12.07.2015 Views

The Space-Time Image: the Case of Bergson, Deleuze, and Memento

The Space-Time Image: the Case of Bergson, Deleuze, and Memento

The Space-Time Image: the Case of Bergson, Deleuze, and Memento

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS
  • No tags were found...

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

170MELISSA CLARKEcouplings <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> present <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> past, but <strong>the</strong>ir interrelation is more a pluralitythan simply a bifurcation, partly because <strong>the</strong>re are many pasts in relation withmany presents. In order to explain <strong>the</strong> heterogeneity <strong>of</strong> time, one might perhapssay <strong>the</strong>re are multiple tw<strong>of</strong>old relations .What provides <strong>the</strong> continuity <strong>of</strong> time, or its duration, has to do with memoryrelating present to past. To put it differently, <strong>the</strong> continuity <strong>of</strong> time has todo with duration <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> past in <strong>the</strong> present. In fact, <strong>Bergson</strong> views memory <strong>and</strong>duration as coextensive, at least in principle: “In principle, consciousness iscoextensive with life” (1920, 13–14). Inasmuch as memory is consciousness<strong>and</strong> material life (spatiality) endures, <strong>Bergson</strong> is pointing to <strong>the</strong>ir parity.Duration is <strong>the</strong> principle <strong>of</strong> memory. So <strong>the</strong>re is a difference between duration<strong>and</strong> memory, since duration is a pure time relation that is necessary for <strong>the</strong> experience<strong>of</strong> time, while memory is <strong>the</strong> individuated or psychological functionbetween present <strong>and</strong> past. It should also be noted that without memory <strong>the</strong>re isstill duration, according to <strong>Bergson</strong>, because he is careful not to psychologize<strong>the</strong> experience <strong>of</strong> time. 3Let me now briefly enumerate several aspects <strong>of</strong> time as divergent, <strong>and</strong> verybriefly highlight <strong>the</strong> way memory <strong>and</strong>/or duration function in each. First, <strong>the</strong>reis <strong>the</strong> actual present. But <strong>the</strong> present is always already passing, so <strong>the</strong> presentmight more aptly be termed <strong>the</strong> “passing-present.” <strong>The</strong>re is thus a function <strong>of</strong>becoming-past in <strong>the</strong> actual present. That is to say that <strong>the</strong>re is always a durationoperating in <strong>the</strong> present for <strong>the</strong> present to become past. Experience alwaysalready presupposes extended time (or enduring time, or “duration”) because<strong>the</strong>re must be some continuity between <strong>the</strong> present <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> next moment; in o<strong>the</strong>rwords, a past must be somehow present in order for <strong>the</strong> present to move to <strong>the</strong>next present moment. That continuity is provided by <strong>the</strong> aspect <strong>of</strong> duration thatis past, <strong>and</strong> this functions on <strong>the</strong> individual level, as memory. <strong>Bergson</strong> observes:“<strong>the</strong> following moment always contains, over <strong>and</strong> above <strong>the</strong> preceding one, <strong>the</strong>memory <strong>the</strong> latter has left it” (1946, 193). But that is also to say that memory<strong>and</strong>/or duration <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> past is implicit in any real experience, <strong>the</strong>n, since <strong>the</strong>y are<strong>the</strong> continuous relations <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> past subtending <strong>the</strong> present. Once <strong>Bergson</strong> hasmade <strong>the</strong> point that <strong>the</strong> present is always becoming, that is, it is always becomingpast, he confronts a common confusion with respect to time. <strong>The</strong> commonunderst<strong>and</strong>ing <strong>of</strong> time is that <strong>the</strong> present has ontological status, while <strong>the</strong> past isconsidered to “be” no longer. Traditionally speaking, <strong>the</strong> present “is” <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>past “was.” In contradistinction to this, <strong>Bergson</strong> points out that precisely <strong>the</strong>opposite is <strong>the</strong> case, that it is more reasonable to claim that <strong>the</strong> past is, in an ontologicalsense, while <strong>the</strong> present more precisely becomes: “When we think <strong>the</strong>present as going to be, it exists not yet; <strong>and</strong> when we think <strong>of</strong> it as existing it isalready past” (1959, 143). 4 <strong>Bergson</strong> is attempting to reorient our underst<strong>and</strong>ingfrom what he calls its usual “confusion,” in this case to show <strong>the</strong> difference inkind between present <strong>and</strong> past.


<strong>The</strong> <strong>Space</strong>-<strong>Time</strong> <strong>Image</strong> 171We are thus already addressing ano<strong>the</strong>r divergent relation <strong>of</strong> time by discussing<strong>the</strong> past, which we must consider in addition to <strong>the</strong> present. Properlyunderstood, <strong>the</strong> past diverges into both <strong>the</strong> past <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> present that it was, constitutingano<strong>the</strong>r tw<strong>of</strong>old relation. In order for each present to become a past, wesaw that <strong>the</strong>re must be an element <strong>of</strong> past in each present. This also means, conversely,that each past must still contain an element <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> present that it was,that it had been. An alternate way <strong>of</strong> saying <strong>the</strong> same thing is that pasts each havea “now” or present that <strong>the</strong>y were.Fur<strong>the</strong>r, what we commonly call “<strong>the</strong>” past is simultaneously many levels <strong>of</strong>past, possibly even extending back to an ultimately contracted “whole” past.<strong>The</strong>re are innumerable layers <strong>of</strong> past, all <strong>of</strong> which coexist. As an illustration <strong>of</strong>this, consider <strong>Bergson</strong>’s notable drawing, in which <strong>the</strong> present is represented asa plane, with a cone <strong>of</strong> layers balanced on its point on that plane (1959, 156):<strong>The</strong> present is represented as a plane, with a cone <strong>of</strong> layers balanced on its pointon that plane. <strong>The</strong> cone represents layers <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> past supporting <strong>the</strong> present. <strong>The</strong>way to access <strong>the</strong>se levels <strong>of</strong> past from <strong>the</strong> present is through memory <strong>and</strong>/orduration. Memory relates between all <strong>the</strong>se levels <strong>of</strong> past, performing <strong>the</strong> operations<strong>of</strong> selectivity <strong>and</strong> interpretation required for each layer <strong>of</strong> past.We now see that <strong>the</strong>re are multiple pasts. However, <strong>the</strong> implication <strong>of</strong><strong>Bergson</strong>’s descriptions is that <strong>the</strong>re are multiple possible presents as well. Thisis because each present moment is contingent on which past is connected to thatpresent moment. In addition, <strong>the</strong>n, pasts can be accessed by memory <strong>and</strong> becomeactual, thus influencing <strong>the</strong> present. Finally, while <strong>the</strong> past in most senses is virtual,it can be accessed in present memory, so in that particular way <strong>the</strong> past canbe actual as well. Memory can bring <strong>the</strong> past to bear on <strong>the</strong> present, <strong>and</strong> also simplybring <strong>the</strong> past to <strong>the</strong> present. Thus <strong>the</strong> past can be actually relevant, <strong>and</strong> memorycan actualize it.For <strong>the</strong>se divergencies <strong>of</strong> time to be possible, <strong>the</strong>n, <strong>the</strong> present <strong>and</strong> past mustbe coextensive. <strong>The</strong> past must be somehow real, albeit necessarily in a way differentfrom <strong>the</strong> actual present. <strong>The</strong> only possible explanation for this is that <strong>the</strong>past must be virtual <strong>and</strong> that <strong>the</strong> virtual must be a form <strong>of</strong> reality. Sheets <strong>of</strong> pastare always really existent whe<strong>the</strong>r or not <strong>the</strong>y are actual. <strong>The</strong> real, <strong>the</strong>n, is dividedinto <strong>the</strong> actual <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> virtual. All <strong>the</strong> levels <strong>of</strong> past are consequently real. As weshall see below, this turns out to be <strong>the</strong> keystone for <strong>the</strong> explanation <strong>of</strong> how timecan be evoked in film.In sum, <strong>the</strong>n, time is <strong>the</strong> present, which is always already passing, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>(virtually) present pasts, all levels <strong>of</strong> which are simultaneously real for ourexperience. <strong>Time</strong> has two aspects: <strong>the</strong> present, which is actual, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> past,which, although it is virtual, is also real. Duration facilitates <strong>the</strong> connectionbetween present <strong>and</strong> layers <strong>of</strong> past, <strong>and</strong> duration also has two aspects. <strong>The</strong>reis duration properly understood, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>re is memory. Duration proper is <strong>the</strong>logical relation that necessarily functions between <strong>the</strong> actual present <strong>and</strong> all


Chapter 1 Introduction to LabVIEW <strong>and</strong> APTLabVIEWLabVIEW is a graphical programming language that uses icons instead <strong>of</strong> lines <strong>of</strong> text tocreate applications. In contrast to text-based programming languages, where instructionsdetermine program execution, LabVIEW uses dataflow programming, where <strong>the</strong> flow <strong>of</strong> datadetermines execution.In LabVIEW, you build a user interface with a set <strong>of</strong> tools <strong>and</strong> objects.<strong>The</strong> user interface is known as <strong>the</strong> front panel. You <strong>the</strong>n add code using graphicalrepresentations <strong>of</strong> functions to control <strong>the</strong> front panel objects.<strong>The</strong> block diagram contains this code. In some ways, <strong>the</strong> block diagram resembles aflowchart.Refer to <strong>the</strong> National Instruments web site at www.ni.com for more general information aboutLabVIEW.APT<strong>The</strong> apt Suite <strong>of</strong> controllers includes a range <strong>of</strong> compact drivers, high power bench topcontrollers <strong>and</strong> 19" rack based units that, toge<strong>the</strong>r control our range <strong>of</strong> precision stages <strong>and</strong>actuators, support motion control from <strong>the</strong> 10’s <strong>of</strong> cm to <strong>the</strong> nm regime. <strong>The</strong> product <strong>of</strong>feringcomprises stepper motor <strong>and</strong> DC motor controllers, closed loop <strong>and</strong> open loop piezocontrollers, strain gauge readers, <strong>and</strong> solenoid drivers, toge<strong>the</strong>r with a sophisticated feedbackcontroller (NanoTrak) that fully optimizes coupled optical powers in a wide range <strong>of</strong>alignment scenarios. All <strong>of</strong> our controllers are supported by unified PC based user <strong>and</strong>programming utilities (<strong>the</strong> apt s<strong>of</strong>tware suite) that enables higher level custom applicationsto be constructed extremely effectively <strong>and</strong> quickly. Thanks to <strong>the</strong> USB connectivityimplemented on all <strong>of</strong> our controller units, it is extremely easy to link multiple units toge<strong>the</strong>r torealize a multiaxis motion control solution for many positioning <strong>and</strong> alignment needs.APT within LabVIEWProgrammers <strong>of</strong> LabVIEW through <strong>the</strong> use <strong>of</strong> ActiveX technology, used within <strong>the</strong> APTplatform, can communicate <strong>and</strong> control any APT controller. By simply specifying whichcontroller to be used within code function calls, properties <strong>and</strong> events can be used to exposea controllers functionality.Guide to LabVIEW <strong>and</strong> APT Page 6


<strong>The</strong> <strong>Space</strong>-<strong>Time</strong> <strong>Image</strong> 173between scenes, or even by <strong>the</strong> dissonance between sounds <strong>and</strong> visual imageryall <strong>of</strong> which are so commonplace in today’s films. Whenever <strong>the</strong>se mechanismsportray undecidability between <strong>the</strong> real <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> imaginary, <strong>the</strong> relation <strong>of</strong> actualvs. virtual is evoked. But direct time-images are even more clearly produced when<strong>the</strong> film is about peculiarities unsettling <strong>the</strong> viewer’s expectations <strong>of</strong> “reality”;<strong>and</strong>, I would argue, this is compounded when <strong>the</strong> film itself is also concerned withmemory. In an interesting passage in Cinema 2, <strong>Deleuze</strong> describes <strong>the</strong> way inwhich <strong>the</strong> conflict between <strong>the</strong> actual <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> virtual can be represented by a“strangely obscure criminal or justice-bringing activity” (72). <strong>Deleuze</strong> is claimingthat oddities with respect to <strong>the</strong> character (such as inabilities to fit <strong>the</strong> characterin with a definite categorization, a “type,” a determinate kind) present adissonance between a “real” image <strong>of</strong> what that type should be <strong>and</strong> an “imaginary”image. <strong>The</strong> greater <strong>the</strong> degree <strong>of</strong> indiscernibility between what <strong>the</strong> character’srole intuitively “should be” <strong>and</strong> what that character is “really” like, <strong>the</strong> moreblurred <strong>the</strong> distinction between <strong>the</strong> real <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> imaginary becomes. <strong>Deleuze</strong> citesAlfred Hitchcock’s Murder <strong>and</strong> Todd Browning’s <strong>The</strong> Unholy Three as examples.<strong>The</strong> Unholy Three, he notes, features a character’s role taking on two simultaneouslevels: an intuitively consonant one, <strong>and</strong> ano<strong>the</strong>r, darker role:A fake limbless man has his arms cut <strong>of</strong>f for <strong>the</strong> love <strong>of</strong> a woman who couldnot bear a man’s h<strong>and</strong>s, but tries to recover his dignity by ordering <strong>the</strong> murder<strong>of</strong> a rival who is whole. . . . <strong>The</strong> virtual image <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> public role becomesactual, but in relation to a private crime, which becomes actual in turn <strong>and</strong>replaces <strong>the</strong> first image. (<strong>Deleuze</strong> 1959, 72)What is <strong>of</strong> interest is that <strong>the</strong>re is a shifting between <strong>the</strong> publicly accepted role<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> private role <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> character, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>re is a ra<strong>the</strong>r mysterious <strong>and</strong> perpetualcognitive dissonance as to which is <strong>the</strong> “real” <strong>and</strong> which is <strong>the</strong> “imaginary”role <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> character; <strong>the</strong> character moves into <strong>and</strong> out <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> roles. Thiscreates <strong>the</strong> experience <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> simultaneous qualities <strong>of</strong> actuality <strong>and</strong> virtuality <strong>of</strong>which time is composed.As an exemplification <strong>of</strong> this, however, <strong>Memento</strong>’s protagonist serves evenbetter than <strong>the</strong>se examples. <strong>The</strong> oddly malfunctioning Leonard becomes <strong>the</strong> quintessentiallyobscure criminal. Throughout <strong>the</strong> film, <strong>the</strong>re are several scenes inwhich it becomes apparent that o<strong>the</strong>r characters have manipulated Leonard intohurting or killing someone for <strong>the</strong>m. Yet Leonard starts to wear suspiciously niceclo<strong>the</strong>s <strong>and</strong> to drive a suspiciously nice car. He also attacks <strong>and</strong> kills all alone,based only on cryptic notes. Although it is disturbing to think <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> impairedLeonard as a pawn in o<strong>the</strong>r characters’ killing games, it is equally disturbing toconsider that Leonard could be relatively unaffected by his own acts <strong>of</strong> violence.We are never sure to what extent Leonard might be able to control his decisionsin this regard, <strong>and</strong> this blurs our attempts to distinguish between <strong>the</strong> real <strong>and</strong>imaginary with respect to his character.


174MELISSA CLARKE<strong>The</strong> most troubling scene, <strong>the</strong> one in which <strong>the</strong> conflict over <strong>the</strong> criminality<strong>of</strong> this nebulous character comes to a head, is, <strong>of</strong> course, at <strong>the</strong> end <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> film,which is supposed to be <strong>the</strong> earliest point in <strong>the</strong> story that has unfolded. Leonardhas an acquaintance (we are unsure whe<strong>the</strong>r he is a friend or foe) named Ted,<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>re is an argument between <strong>the</strong>m. Ted tells Leonard that he has alreadykilled <strong>the</strong> person he was looking for, a “John G.,” <strong>the</strong> one who injured Leonard<strong>and</strong> killed his wife. Ted shows Leonard a picture that was taken <strong>of</strong> him just after<strong>the</strong> vengeful murder. <strong>The</strong>n Ted begins to accuse Leonard <strong>of</strong> having become akiller, <strong>of</strong> having begun to like to kill people, <strong>and</strong> even <strong>of</strong> needing to kill in orderto give his life meaning. This brings our fear <strong>of</strong> Leonard into sharper focus; wehave thought he was only a hapless victim <strong>and</strong> we have watched him beingmanipulated, but now he appears to be a deranged killer. How many people hashe killed or will he kill? His affliction only makes his status as a criminal moredisturbing.Leonard is also preoccupied throughout with justice <strong>and</strong> vengeance. Itbecomes increasingly clear that Leonard can, will, <strong>and</strong> has hurt or killed peopleaccording to his desire for revenge. Because <strong>of</strong> his condition, he makes for a verycounterintuitive, unreal vigilante character, unlike those we would imagine to bemore “realistic” possible c<strong>and</strong>idates. It is precisely because Leonard is an obscurecriminal, <strong>and</strong> precisely because his control <strong>of</strong> his pursuit <strong>of</strong> justice is in question,that <strong>the</strong> film is so adept at producing <strong>the</strong> time image.In addition, because <strong>the</strong> film features memory aiding <strong>the</strong> obscurity, it evenmore clearly connotes <strong>the</strong> relation between present <strong>and</strong> past. <strong>The</strong> relation <strong>of</strong>memory (or its absence) is always in question; it is always a specific part <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>obscurity.Of course, since <strong>the</strong> characters in films are already imaginary, this exerciseis reflected back on us <strong>and</strong> on our basic assumptions about what is actual <strong>and</strong>what is virtual. When that which is virtual can become actual, or is shown to beindistinct from that which might be actually real, <strong>the</strong>n we have found <strong>the</strong> structure<strong>of</strong> time, with its virtually real past <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> fluidity <strong>of</strong> exchange between it<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> actually real present.In addition to arising from an indiscernibility between <strong>the</strong> real <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> imaginary,<strong>the</strong> time-image can be directly produced through various o<strong>the</strong>r relationson <strong>the</strong> screen, among characters, <strong>and</strong> in <strong>the</strong> viewer, when <strong>the</strong>se relations producetriggers that <strong>Deleuze</strong> has termed “chronosigns.” He defines a chronosign as “animage where time ceases to be subordinate <strong>and</strong> appears for itself” (1989, 335).This is similar to what Rol<strong>and</strong> Bar<strong>the</strong>s has called a “trace,” i.e., it is that whichis evoked by <strong>the</strong> image. <strong>Bergson</strong> calls this a “mediating image” or “phantom.”Traces are signs <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> “in-between” that marks <strong>the</strong> divergence <strong>of</strong> time, that is,<strong>the</strong> precise movement or moment when <strong>the</strong> present becomes past, or what inDeleuzian terms is <strong>the</strong> “event” <strong>of</strong> divergence.<strong>Deleuze</strong> has provided a useful organizational schema, suggesting that <strong>the</strong>reare two identifiable ways in which <strong>the</strong>se signs can be categorized: as “order <strong>of</strong>


<strong>The</strong> <strong>Space</strong>-<strong>Time</strong> <strong>Image</strong> 175time” (l’ordre du temps) signs <strong>and</strong> as “time as series” (le temps comme série)signs. What is interesting is that both <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>m support a <strong>Bergson</strong>ian underst<strong>and</strong>ing<strong>of</strong> time as <strong>the</strong> contemporaneity <strong>of</strong> pasts with <strong>the</strong> present ra<strong>the</strong>r than a succession<strong>of</strong> “now”s.A consideration <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se chronosigns will shift our focus from indiscernibility<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> imaginary <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> real to questions <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> undecidability <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> true<strong>and</strong> false, thus from metaphysical questions to epistemological ones. <strong>The</strong> first<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se types <strong>of</strong> signs, <strong>the</strong> order sign, can have at least two manifestations. <strong>The</strong>first concerns undecidable alternate truths in <strong>the</strong> present, whereas <strong>the</strong> secondfocusses on ambiguity <strong>of</strong> truth in <strong>the</strong> past.When we are perpetually uncertain as to <strong>the</strong> truth <strong>of</strong> several alternate interpretations<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> present, we are directly confronting time. <strong>The</strong> characteristics <strong>of</strong>time reveal <strong>the</strong>mselves because indiscernibility among <strong>the</strong> truths <strong>of</strong> presentsshows that <strong>the</strong>re can be multiple possible presents informed by various pasts.This shows time to be continuously manifest <strong>and</strong> shifting ra<strong>the</strong>r than a succession.This <strong>of</strong> course works only when <strong>the</strong> feeling <strong>of</strong> indecisiveness remains,because to resolve <strong>the</strong> issue definitively would be to fall back into traditionalunderst<strong>and</strong>ings, viz., <strong>of</strong> time as a linear progression.<strong>Memento</strong> is characterized by a chronic undecidability between what is true<strong>and</strong> false in <strong>the</strong> present; in fact, in each scene we are presented with a simultaneity<strong>of</strong> possible interpretations <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> present. Because Leonard can’t formshort-term memories, his given situation is frequently indecipherable, <strong>and</strong> italways contains <strong>the</strong> most extreme potential to be deceiving. In each scene, <strong>the</strong>reis an encounter between Leonard <strong>and</strong> someone whom he, <strong>of</strong> course, doesn’tremember, <strong>and</strong> we are shown a plausible explanation <strong>of</strong> his connection with thatperson. But as <strong>the</strong> film moves to a new scene prior in time, we may be shownthat what appeared to be <strong>the</strong> truth <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> present that we just experienced was notas it appeared. This continues in scene after scene.Let us consider Leonard’s relationship with Ted. In <strong>the</strong> first scene Ted is beingkilled by Leonard. But in <strong>the</strong> next scene in which Ted appears (<strong>and</strong> this scene isclearly understood to have taken place prior in time), he is telling Leonard he ishis friend <strong>and</strong> asking him whe<strong>the</strong>r he is “ready to go” somewhere. But in a subsequentscene (prior in time) someone is telling Leonard that Ted is “<strong>the</strong> one”—<strong>the</strong> one who killed Leonard’s wife. And <strong>the</strong>n in <strong>the</strong> next scene (earlier), we againsee Ted telling Leonard that <strong>the</strong>y are friends. We see that <strong>the</strong>y may or may notbe friends. <strong>The</strong> same thing happens with ano<strong>the</strong>r character, Natalie. Is NatalieLeonard’s friend? In one scene she appears to be helping, in ano<strong>the</strong>r she is shownto be annoyed with him. In still ano<strong>the</strong>r scene Ted tells Leonard not to trust her.We cannot decide; we do not know whe<strong>the</strong>r Ted is Leonard’s friend nor do weknow whe<strong>the</strong>r Natalie is his friend. But <strong>the</strong>re really is no characterizing ei<strong>the</strong>rTed or Natalie as friend or foe. It is essentially a question <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> utter indiscernibility<strong>of</strong> truth or falsity in <strong>the</strong> present. Throughout <strong>the</strong> film, with <strong>the</strong> continualjuxtaposition <strong>of</strong> contrary images, <strong>the</strong> aporias <strong>of</strong> truth <strong>and</strong> falsity in <strong>the</strong>


176MELISSA CLARKEpresent become more <strong>and</strong> more urgently revealed. In <strong>the</strong> end, some <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> questionsas to truth <strong>and</strong> falsity in <strong>the</strong> present are never resolved, leaving only <strong>the</strong>unequivocal sense that <strong>the</strong>re is no resolving <strong>the</strong>se questions. This “sense” we areleft with is precisely <strong>the</strong> order sign indicating time’s characteristics. <strong>The</strong> irresolvability<strong>of</strong> truth in <strong>the</strong> presents shows each is contingent on its connectionwith one among several alternate, coexisting pasts. Without any past to consult,<strong>the</strong>re is no way to interpret <strong>the</strong> presents at all. <strong>The</strong> structure <strong>of</strong> a present is evidentlypure becoming. Moreover, an ongoing paralysis <strong>of</strong> veridicality shows thatwe expect <strong>the</strong> past to exist <strong>and</strong> be newly relevant to <strong>the</strong> present.At <strong>the</strong> same time, <strong>the</strong> problem is not simply that <strong>of</strong> Leonard’s condition.<strong>The</strong> indeterminacy <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> viewer’s own memory <strong>of</strong> what definitively happenedis also evidenced. For after all, it is we who cannot discern what is happeningor what <strong>the</strong> definite nature <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> relationships are. So it is not just in <strong>the</strong> case<strong>of</strong> a malfunctioning memory that time is revealed, although having no memorycapabilities is a shortcut to showing some <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> aspects <strong>of</strong> a time-image.<strong>The</strong> audience has to respond to <strong>the</strong> same irresolvability <strong>of</strong> present “truths,” astate <strong>of</strong> irresolution that shows <strong>the</strong> contingency <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> present on whicheveramong several pasts is subtending it, regardless <strong>of</strong> whe<strong>the</strong>r we can access oneto provide interpretive support.<strong>The</strong> second way <strong>the</strong> time-image can be revealed under <strong>the</strong> “order” categoryis through representation <strong>of</strong> undecidable alternative truths concerning layers <strong>of</strong>past. <strong>The</strong> way this reveals time is very similar to that which characterizes <strong>the</strong>problem <strong>of</strong> truth <strong>and</strong> falsity in <strong>the</strong> presents, viz., in indiscernibility between truth<strong>and</strong> falsity, <strong>the</strong> multiplicity <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> pasts <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir simultaneous realities are bothdisclosed.<strong>Memento</strong> continually moves into <strong>and</strong> out <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> past. <strong>The</strong>re is a continualindiscernibility between what “happened” in <strong>the</strong> immediate past, in <strong>the</strong> time sinceLeonard’s problem began, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>n, overall. It is difficult to differentiate clearlybetween <strong>the</strong> previous discussion <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> presents <strong>and</strong> that <strong>of</strong> irresolvability in <strong>the</strong>near past <strong>and</strong> in <strong>the</strong> past since Leonard’s accident, since it is merely <strong>the</strong> samephenomenon seen from a different perspective. With no memory, <strong>the</strong>re are necessarilygaps between <strong>the</strong> crime <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> present. But what is immediately elicitedin <strong>the</strong> moments when <strong>the</strong>se gaps become obvious is already <strong>the</strong> time-image,because it is clear that <strong>the</strong>re should be a near past to consult in order to interpret.This is a simple testament to <strong>Bergson</strong>’s claims that <strong>the</strong> past remains, <strong>and</strong> is thatwhich drives <strong>the</strong> present.At <strong>the</strong> same time, those gaps in Leonard’s memory are part <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> universalsocial past <strong>and</strong> as such are none<strong>the</strong>less real, even for Leonard because <strong>the</strong>y willstill be pasts <strong>of</strong> his present whe<strong>the</strong>r or not he explicitly accesses <strong>the</strong>m throughmemory. That is to say, when individual memory fails, <strong>the</strong>re is still duration. Thisrealization again supports <strong>Bergson</strong>’s underst<strong>and</strong>ing <strong>of</strong> time.As an example <strong>of</strong> this, let us consider <strong>the</strong> scene where Leonard gets out <strong>of</strong> acar, reading a note he wrote himself that says “Meet Natalie. Cafe. 1:00.” He


<strong>The</strong> <strong>Space</strong>-<strong>Time</strong> <strong>Image</strong> 177goes to <strong>the</strong> place <strong>and</strong> walks in, <strong>and</strong> is walking right past Natalie, who stops himas he walks by to say that it is she whom he is supposed to meet. Leonard’s memoryis malfunctioning, but <strong>the</strong>re is Natalie—<strong>the</strong>ir interaction is part <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> duration<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> general past.But it is a different case when we consider <strong>the</strong> past overall with respect to<strong>Memento</strong>. For <strong>the</strong>re is even a perpetual indiscernibility as to <strong>the</strong> truth <strong>of</strong>Leonard’s memory <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> past prior to <strong>the</strong> commencement <strong>of</strong> his affliction.Distant memories accessed by Leonard in <strong>the</strong> present are conflicting <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>irtruths are indeterminate. In o<strong>the</strong>r words, at a certain point Leonard does notknow, <strong>and</strong> cannot know with absolute certainty, what <strong>the</strong> truth <strong>of</strong> his pre-injurypast was, <strong>and</strong> nei<strong>the</strong>r do we.Consider, for example, that in order to keep straight his “condition” Leonardconstantly tells anyone <strong>and</strong> everyone about a certain “Sammy Jankis,” who hada similar condition <strong>and</strong> for whom Leonard had denied insurance coverage, priorto his own accident. Sammy’s wife, Leonard tells everyone, had essentially killedherself in an desperate attempt to try to prove that Sammy was “faking” his condition.But <strong>the</strong>n Ted, someone who at least knows Leonard, casts aspersions on<strong>the</strong> story. Was <strong>the</strong> story about Sammy “true”? Or was <strong>the</strong> story ra<strong>the</strong>r aboutLeonard, <strong>and</strong> was it Leonard’s wife ra<strong>the</strong>r than Sammy’s wife who was diabetic<strong>and</strong> killed herself to try to snap Leonard out <strong>of</strong> it? Was Leonard’s wife even reallykilled in <strong>the</strong> accident? <strong>The</strong>se questions are raised by Ted, but can Ted be trustedto tell <strong>the</strong> truth? In any event, Ted himself does not necessarily know <strong>the</strong> truth<strong>and</strong> claims to be only speculating. And so on. <strong>The</strong> “truth” <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> past is undecidablefor <strong>the</strong>se <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r issues; for example, we never do find out whe<strong>the</strong>rLeonard did or did not kill “John G.”At this level, <strong>the</strong> viewer becomes aware <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> indiscernibility between <strong>the</strong>truth or falsity <strong>of</strong> layers <strong>of</strong> past. And again, <strong>the</strong> structure <strong>of</strong> time is directlyrevealed. If instead we were confident in a single determinate truth <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> past,we would be falling into <strong>the</strong> more traditional underst<strong>and</strong>ing <strong>of</strong> time as linearprogress, <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> present as <strong>the</strong> only reality, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> past as no longer existent.<strong>The</strong> power <strong>of</strong> recognizing indiscernibility between truth <strong>and</strong> falsity in <strong>the</strong>past, on <strong>the</strong> contrary, is that it reminds us <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> contingency <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> present onone among several pasts, <strong>and</strong> even those are interpreted. So it also reminds us<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> shifting, multilayered character <strong>of</strong> that past <strong>and</strong>, <strong>the</strong>refore, <strong>of</strong> time’s nonlinearity.This directly elicits a recognition <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> reality <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> virtual, whichchallenges <strong>the</strong> confused view that <strong>the</strong> virtual is not, or is not real. It also showsthat time is not linear. When we accept <strong>the</strong>se views, <strong>the</strong>n we are accepting <strong>the</strong><strong>Bergson</strong>ian paradigm <strong>of</strong> time.<strong>The</strong>se two examples (<strong>the</strong> indiscernibility between true <strong>and</strong> false in ei<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>present or <strong>the</strong> past) <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> “order” sign are complemented by a second kind <strong>of</strong>sign that produces <strong>the</strong> time-image; <strong>Deleuze</strong> names this <strong>the</strong> “time as series” sign.This sign is triggered when a depiction <strong>of</strong> time as an orderly progression isreplaced by focus on a progressive sequence <strong>of</strong> changes. This, like <strong>the</strong> “order <strong>of</strong>


178MELISSA CLARKEtime” signs, reveals <strong>the</strong> reality <strong>of</strong> multiple virtual pasts <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> multiplicity <strong>of</strong>alternative presents; it also reveals that time is not an orderly progression.<strong>The</strong> <strong>Bergson</strong>ian underst<strong>and</strong>ing <strong>of</strong> time emerges when a sequence <strong>of</strong> imagesproduces <strong>the</strong> sense that <strong>the</strong>re is a passage <strong>of</strong> power in an event or a character ina certain way. Consider a series <strong>of</strong> images in which a character metamorphizes:ra<strong>the</strong>r than time progressing, what progresses will be <strong>the</strong> character’s becomingsomeone or something else; as <strong>Deleuze</strong> says, <strong>the</strong> character “crosses a limit”whereupon he or she undergoes some sort <strong>of</strong> transformation. This elicits a timeimagewhen, while <strong>the</strong> character is shown to progress throughout <strong>the</strong> duration<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> film, <strong>the</strong> events in <strong>the</strong> film are not progressing chronologically. When<strong>the</strong>re is a juxtaposing <strong>of</strong> recollections <strong>and</strong> previous events, a nonlinear depiction<strong>of</strong> time facilitates precisely a revelation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> linear progression <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>character’s development. Ra<strong>the</strong>r than events taking place in a present constantlyprogressing toward a future with a nonpresent past, it is <strong>the</strong> character who progressesor “becomes”; this reveals that shifting layers <strong>of</strong> past subtend <strong>the</strong> becoming<strong>of</strong> an individual, <strong>and</strong> that <strong>the</strong> past is really bearing on <strong>the</strong> presents <strong>and</strong> isaccessible. Moreover, time does not appear as a progression, but ra<strong>the</strong>r as a layeredsimultaneity.In <strong>the</strong> case <strong>of</strong> <strong>Memento</strong>, once again we have a paradigm illustration <strong>of</strong> this signindicating time. Leonard becomes a killer. <strong>The</strong> film shows him moving from whenhe kills Ted, backward in time, tracing <strong>the</strong> indefinite shifting causes that led up to<strong>the</strong> event. But <strong>the</strong> reason <strong>Memento</strong> is paradigmatic is that all <strong>the</strong> while time is movingbackward, Leonard is depicted as progressively becoming a criminal.Let us reconsider <strong>the</strong> confrontation in <strong>the</strong> penultimate (<strong>and</strong> most prior) scene,to take note <strong>of</strong> Leonard’s progression toward becoming a definite criminal. Ted<strong>and</strong> Leonard are arguing, <strong>and</strong> we sense here, as we have throughout, that Leonardis an obscure vigilante. But much more is revealed in this scene. Ted goes fur<strong>the</strong>rthan accusing Leonard <strong>of</strong> enjoying <strong>the</strong> killing; he accuses him <strong>of</strong> making upo<strong>the</strong>r stories, <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> changing <strong>the</strong> original police report just so he could keep tryingto find <strong>the</strong> killer in perpetuity. Ted says: “You make up your own truth. Whathappened to <strong>the</strong> police report? It was complete when I gave it to you. Who tookout <strong>the</strong> twelve pages? It was you. To make up a puzzle you couldn’t solve.” Tedis threatening Leonard’s neat puzzle. “You have a nice story for yourself,” Tedcontinues, “a wife to pine for, a sense <strong>of</strong> purpose in life.” Leonard responds, “Ishould kill you.” <strong>The</strong>n, to compound <strong>the</strong> situation, Leonard gets in his car <strong>and</strong>burns <strong>the</strong> picture <strong>of</strong> himself that Ted took <strong>of</strong> Leonard after he (supposedly) killed<strong>the</strong> real “John G.” We hear Leonard thinking, “You think I lie to myself to behappy? Well, you’re a ‘John G.’ So you can be my ‘John G.’ Do I lie to myselfto make myself happy? In your case Teddy, yes I will.” <strong>The</strong>n he writes downTed’s license plate number, <strong>and</strong> goes <strong>of</strong>f to get it tattooed on his leg, <strong>of</strong> courseforgetting whose license plate number it was as he is driving.<strong>The</strong> transition has taken place. Leonard has become, by this final scene, a criminal.Yet <strong>the</strong> scene was prior in time to <strong>the</strong> opening scene. <strong>The</strong> becoming-criminal


<strong>The</strong> <strong>Space</strong>-<strong>Time</strong> <strong>Image</strong> 179took place linearly while time did not progress linearly. In fact it was through goingbackward in time that <strong>the</strong> character’s becoming was revealed. So we are againshown time to be a multiply layered reality, with a still-influential past.At this point I would like to make explicit some fur<strong>the</strong>r connections betweenthis film <strong>and</strong> <strong>Bergson</strong>’s revelations as an addition to <strong>the</strong> questions <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> real vs.<strong>the</strong> imaginary <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> two types <strong>of</strong> signs outlined by <strong>Deleuze</strong>. <strong>The</strong> first is merelyto state explicitly that <strong>Bergson</strong>’s idea <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> ontological status <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> past in contrastto <strong>the</strong> becoming <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> present is exemplified in <strong>Memento</strong>. As Bert <strong>the</strong> hotelclerk says to Leonard about his condition: “It’s all backward for you. Maybe yougot an idea about what you wanna do, but you don’t know what you just did.”In one sense, this is to say that in this bizarre condition, <strong>the</strong> past “is not” ontologically.What should be virtually in <strong>the</strong> background, accessible, isn’t.Yet, on closer inspection, <strong>the</strong> question <strong>of</strong> whe<strong>the</strong>r or not <strong>the</strong> memory is malfunctioningis in itself unresolvable. <strong>The</strong>refore a second connection <strong>of</strong> this filmto <strong>Bergson</strong>’s description is <strong>the</strong> consideration <strong>of</strong> memory <strong>and</strong> its ability to function“accurately” <strong>and</strong> with precision. In one sense, Leonard’s memory malfunctions,which should be a constant reminder <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> contrast to our functioningmemory. But in ano<strong>the</strong>r sense, Leonard’s memory is really just like all <strong>of</strong> ours:he wants to create meaning for his life, which is what happens with our functioningmemories. We connect to <strong>the</strong> past to interpret or give meaning to (or t<strong>of</strong>ind truth <strong>and</strong> falsity in) <strong>the</strong> present. <strong>Memento</strong>, <strong>the</strong>n, is simply a reminder thatmemory serves to indicate <strong>the</strong> same time relation, viz., that <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> reality <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>past <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> shifting layers <strong>of</strong> that reality.IV<strong>The</strong>re are a few more conclusions to be drawn from this that haven’t been explicitlyaddressed in discussing <strong>the</strong> time-image relation. We should consider whydescribing time as primary <strong>and</strong> space as secondary would be philosophicallyinteresting. <strong>Deleuze</strong> claims that cinema moved to prioritizing this time-imageafter its initial emphasis on <strong>the</strong> movement-image (which was spatially oriented)prior to World War II, precisely out <strong>of</strong> concerns resulting from <strong>the</strong> war. He alsomakes <strong>the</strong> claim that film was retracing <strong>the</strong> path that philosophy took over severalcenturies. In ei<strong>the</strong>r event, <strong>the</strong> movement was away from universal truths. 8<strong>The</strong>re certainly is no universal truth awaiting ei<strong>the</strong>r Leonard or <strong>the</strong> audienceat <strong>the</strong> end <strong>of</strong> <strong>Memento</strong>. <strong>The</strong>re is no way to verify ei<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> real vs. <strong>the</strong> imaginaryor any <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> many questions as to <strong>the</strong> true vs. <strong>the</strong> false. At <strong>the</strong> same time,<strong>the</strong> past is always virtually present (even when it appears not to be for <strong>the</strong>individual), <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> present is always already passing. As we have seen, <strong>the</strong>seare inescapable products <strong>of</strong> <strong>Memento</strong>, which is to say that <strong>Memento</strong> produces<strong>the</strong> direct time-image.


180MELISSA CLARKEBut it is to say more than this. Consider <strong>the</strong> question <strong>of</strong> universal truth <strong>and</strong>verifiability. What <strong>Memento</strong> shows, along with everything that <strong>the</strong> discussion <strong>of</strong>actual <strong>and</strong> virtual <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> shifting reality <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> past <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> present implies, isprecisely that reality <strong>and</strong> truth are <strong>the</strong> very complex results <strong>of</strong> shifting, multiplyvariant possible connections between <strong>the</strong> present <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> sheets <strong>of</strong> past.Moreover, depending on which past layer is subtending <strong>the</strong> present or actualizedin <strong>the</strong> present, <strong>the</strong> present truth will vary. <strong>Memento</strong> shows that <strong>the</strong> past, while itmay “be” <strong>and</strong> have a virtual reality, is not a firm reliable source <strong>of</strong> determinateinformation with or without memory. Consequently, nei<strong>the</strong>r is <strong>the</strong> present,whe<strong>the</strong>r or not Leonard’s or our own memories are functioning. As LeonardShelby says, sounding very Nietzschean, “Memories are interpretations, not <strong>the</strong>facts,” <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> individual subject can nei<strong>the</strong>r control <strong>the</strong> interpretation nor relyon <strong>the</strong> “facts.” <strong>The</strong> reality is ra<strong>the</strong>r that we must interpret. We are “condemnedto interpret,” or perhaps more precisely, interpretation happens.This has political implications regarding <strong>the</strong> production <strong>of</strong> subjects, or as aquasi-metaphysical question in consideration <strong>of</strong> meaning <strong>and</strong> value in <strong>the</strong>sociopolitical world. Destabilizing <strong>the</strong> subject, <strong>the</strong> present, <strong>the</strong> past, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> actualallows philosophers <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>orists a starting-point from which to question<strong>the</strong> status quo <strong>and</strong> consider alternatives to it.Prioritizing time reveals <strong>the</strong> indeterminacy <strong>of</strong> both time <strong>and</strong> space, <strong>and</strong>emphasizing <strong>the</strong> continuity <strong>of</strong> time (<strong>the</strong> simultaneity <strong>of</strong> presents <strong>and</strong> pasts) dispelsmyths <strong>of</strong> a progression <strong>of</strong> truth, knowledge, history, <strong>and</strong> facts. Inverting <strong>the</strong>traditional preference for a unitary subject, a single true present, <strong>and</strong> a linear progression<strong>of</strong> time <strong>and</strong> an overemphasis on space, science, <strong>and</strong> determinate concepts,can thus have pr<strong>of</strong>ound implications for our underst<strong>and</strong>ing <strong>of</strong> ourselves,our world, <strong>and</strong> most <strong>of</strong> our sociopolitical philosophy.Notes1. Ultimately, <strong>the</strong>se two different elements reconnect, so that it is not in <strong>the</strong> end accurate toclaim that time is an intensive relation. For purposes <strong>of</strong> this discussion, however, let me just say thatat least in this initial respect, time is understood as an internal subjective relation. For a moredetailed summary <strong>of</strong> this, one might consult Maurice Merleau-Ponty 1964 (184) where he claimsthat “absolute knowledge is not detachment, it is inherence” for <strong>Bergson</strong>.2. In addition to being <strong>the</strong> main point <strong>of</strong> <strong>Bergson</strong> 1946, one can also find this discussion in<strong>Bergson</strong> 1959, Chapter II, especially <strong>the</strong> sections: “Homogeneous <strong>Time</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Space</strong>,” “Duration,Succession <strong>and</strong> <strong>Space</strong>,” <strong>and</strong> “Pure Duration.”3. For a very useful discussion <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> relation between memory <strong>and</strong> duration, see <strong>Bergson</strong> 1946(187–237) or <strong>the</strong> beginning <strong>of</strong> <strong>Bergson</strong> 1920. In addition, one might also see <strong>Deleuze</strong> 1991, chap.3.4. For fur<strong>the</strong>r discussion <strong>of</strong> this <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> subsequent points, one might generally consider<strong>Bergson</strong> 1959, chap. 3, especially <strong>the</strong> section on “Relation <strong>of</strong> Past <strong>and</strong> Present.”5. <strong>Bergson</strong> has a more complex set <strong>of</strong> relations in mind here, involving also consciousness <strong>and</strong>freedom. But since in <strong>the</strong> end consciousness <strong>and</strong> freedom are essentially “produced by” memory,for purposes <strong>of</strong> this discussion I am eliding <strong>the</strong>se aspects.6. Unfortunately, <strong>the</strong> term “image” must be used despite its failure to denote <strong>the</strong> relationsearched for herein. <strong>Time</strong> eludes conceptualization, precisely because conceptualizations reify <strong>and</strong>


<strong>The</strong> <strong>Space</strong>-<strong>Time</strong> <strong>Image</strong> 181time defies reification. <strong>The</strong> term “image” connotes some degree <strong>of</strong> a perceptible spatiality, but forlack <strong>of</strong> a better term, I will use “time-image” to connote those combined images that can produce asense <strong>of</strong> time.7. One must be cautious to avoid equivocation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> term “real” here. In an ordinary sense, weare discussing <strong>the</strong> difference between real <strong>and</strong> imaginary <strong>and</strong> relating it to <strong>the</strong> difference betweenactual (present) <strong>and</strong> virtual (past). In ano<strong>the</strong>r context, however, <strong>the</strong> virtual past is still entirely real.This is a problem with language <strong>and</strong> use <strong>of</strong> terms, but I hope that <strong>the</strong> different discussions are clearlydelimited here.8. <strong>Deleuze</strong> maintains <strong>the</strong> first in <strong>the</strong> Preface to Cinema 1, p. ix, while he claims <strong>the</strong> second in<strong>the</strong> Preface to Cinema 2, p. xi.Works CitedBar<strong>the</strong>s, Rol<strong>and</strong>. 1993. Camera Lucida. London: Vintage.<strong>Bergson</strong>, Henri. 1946. <strong>The</strong> Creative Mind. Trans. Mabelle L. Andison. Connecticut: Greenwood Press.———. 1999. Duration <strong>and</strong> Simultaneity. Trans. Mark Lewis <strong>and</strong> Robin Durie. Manchester:Clinamen Press.———. 1959. Matter <strong>and</strong> Memory. Trans. Nancy Margaret Paul <strong>and</strong> W. Scott Palmer. New York:Doubleday.———. 1920. Mind-Energy. Trans. H. Wildon Carr. London: Macmillan.———. 1959. <strong>Time</strong> <strong>and</strong> Free Will. Trans. F. L. Pogson. New York: Macmillan.<strong>Deleuze</strong>, Gilles. 1991. <strong>Bergson</strong>ism. Trans. Hugh Tomlinson <strong>and</strong> Barbara Habberjam. New York:Zone Books.———. 1986. Cinema 1. Trans. Hugh Tomlinson <strong>and</strong> Barbara Habberjam. Minneapolis: MinnesotaUniversity Press.———. 1989. Cinema 2. Trans. Hugh Tomlinson <strong>and</strong> Robert Galeta. Minneapolis: MinnesotaUniversity Press.———. 1994. Difference <strong>and</strong> Repetition. Trans. Paul Patton. New York: Columbia University Press.———. 1985. L’image-temps. Paris: Les Editions de Minuit.Gill, Carolyn Bailey. ed. 2000. <strong>Time</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Image</strong>. Manchester: Manchester University Press.Merleau-Ponty, Maurice. 1964. “<strong>Bergson</strong> in <strong>the</strong> Making,” in Signs, trans. Richard C. McCleary.Evanston: Northwestern University Press.Nolan, Christopher. 2000. <strong>Memento</strong>. I Remember Productions, Llc.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!