01.12.2012 Views

Languages of Fate: Semantic Fields in Chinese and Greek

Languages of Fate: Semantic Fields in Chinese and Greek

Languages of Fate: Semantic Fields in Chinese and Greek

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

<strong>Languages</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Fate</strong>: <strong>Semantic</strong> <strong>Fields</strong> <strong>in</strong> Ch<strong>in</strong>ese <strong>and</strong> <strong>Greek</strong><br />

Paper presented <strong>in</strong> the Workshop "Heaven's Will <strong>and</strong> Life's Lot: Dest<strong>in</strong>y <strong>and</strong> Determ<strong>in</strong>ism <strong>in</strong> Ch<strong>in</strong>ese<br />

Culture," Sponsored by the Chiang Ch<strong>in</strong>g-kuo Foundation, Breckenridge Center, Brunswick ME, May<br />

18-21, 2000<br />

Lisa Raphals<br />

University <strong>of</strong> California at Riverside<br />

A.Introduction: The Rest <strong>of</strong> Your Life<br />

I beg<strong>in</strong>, anachronistically, <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> keep<strong>in</strong>g with the theme <strong>of</strong> this year's sem<strong>in</strong>ar series, with a look<br />

<strong>in</strong>to the future, specifically <strong>in</strong>to the future envisioned <strong>in</strong> a science fiction story titled "Story <strong>of</strong> Your Life"<br />

by Ted Chiang, published <strong>in</strong> the 1999 Best Science Fiction anthology. That story is a complex<br />

narrative <strong>of</strong> two major threads. One concerns the life (<strong>and</strong> death) <strong>of</strong> the narrator's daughter; the other<br />

concerns her efforts as a l<strong>in</strong>guist Shanghaied by the government to decipher the alien language<br />

Heptapod B. I must pass over many fasc<strong>in</strong>at<strong>in</strong>g details. Suffice it to say that these seven-limbed aliens<br />

have two dist<strong>in</strong>ct languages, the spoken language dubbed "Heptapod A" <strong>and</strong> a totally separate written<br />

language, Heptapod B, whose script is not word-divided, allow<strong>in</strong>g for a "semasiographic," rather than<br />

"glottographic" writ<strong>in</strong>g system, than has no relation at all to the order <strong>of</strong> spoken language, not only with<strong>in</strong><br />

the word, but with<strong>in</strong> the sentence. 1 As the narrator ga<strong>in</strong>s pr<strong>of</strong>iciency <strong>in</strong> a l<strong>in</strong>guistic but non-phonological<br />

mode, she realizes that the organization <strong>of</strong> Heptapod B has consequences for thought, beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g with<br />

the <strong>in</strong>terchangeability <strong>of</strong> premises <strong>and</strong> conclusions! 2 Whilst humans <strong>in</strong>terpret events causally <strong>and</strong><br />

chronologically, heptapods select attributes that were mean<strong>in</strong>gful only a period <strong>of</strong> time. 3 The most<br />

important consequence for purposes <strong>of</strong> the present discussion are the implications for free will: human<br />

notions <strong>of</strong> free will are <strong>in</strong>compatible with the heptapod "simultaneous mode <strong>of</strong> consciousness" that, by its<br />

very simultaneity, knows the future. 4 I leave for another day the complexities <strong>of</strong> this story, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g the<br />

possibility that the first thread is translated from Heptapod B, <strong>and</strong> turn to my own subject by ask<strong>in</strong>g<br />

whether the story manages to depict an "alien" sensibility by us<strong>in</strong>g language <strong>and</strong> language acquisition as a<br />

metaphor. It may prove an <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g reflection po<strong>in</strong>t for some <strong>of</strong> the important differences between<br />

<strong>Greek</strong> <strong>and</strong> Ch<strong>in</strong>ese views <strong>of</strong> the <strong>in</strong>terrelations <strong>of</strong> fate <strong>and</strong> free will.<br />

B.Prelim<strong>in</strong>ary Considerations<br />

Questions on the nature <strong>of</strong> fate or dest<strong>in</strong>y <strong>and</strong> how it could be realized, negotiated or averted<br />

<strong>in</strong>formed a wide range <strong>of</strong> reflective thought <strong>in</strong> both Ch<strong>in</strong>a <strong>and</strong> Greece. In many <strong>of</strong> the Ch<strong>in</strong>ese texts,<br />

1


underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g fate is the def<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g characteristic <strong>of</strong> a sage; Classical Confucian authors made the<br />

underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> m<strong>in</strong>g a prerequisite for self-cultivation. On the <strong>Greek</strong> side, it is well known that<br />

determ<strong>in</strong>ism (asserted <strong>and</strong> denied <strong>in</strong> both physical <strong>and</strong> ethical contexts) became a central problem <strong>of</strong><br />

post-Aristotelian <strong>Greek</strong> philosophy, but with some exceptions, the Hellenistic debate tended to eclipse<br />

questions <strong>of</strong> fate, fatalism <strong>and</strong> necessity that engaged earlier <strong>Greek</strong> speculative th<strong>in</strong>kers s<strong>in</strong>ce Homer.<br />

Let me beg<strong>in</strong> with a few methodological considerations. An <strong>in</strong>itial obstacle to comparative<br />

study <strong>of</strong> beliefs <strong>in</strong> fate or fatalism is simply the modern tendency to give both short shrift as objects <strong>of</strong><br />

serious consideration. On the one h<strong>and</strong>, histories <strong>of</strong> religion have situated belief <strong>in</strong> fate (undist<strong>in</strong>guished<br />

from fatalism) as an early stages <strong>in</strong> a teleological evolution toward Christianity. 5 Other treatments<br />

oppose belief <strong>in</strong> fate to free will, a cornerstone <strong>of</strong> modernity; <strong>and</strong> forget to dist<strong>in</strong>guish fate <strong>and</strong> fatalism<br />

from determ<strong>in</strong>ism, the doctr<strong>in</strong>e that every event has a cause ( which implies neither fatalism nor that<br />

events can be predicted.)<br />

In The Consequences <strong>of</strong> Modernity, the sociologist Anthony Giddens suggests another<br />

possibility: that new notions <strong>of</strong> risk <strong>and</strong> trust are a dist<strong>in</strong>ctly modern development that supplants earlier<br />

notions <strong>of</strong> fate, fortune <strong>and</strong> fortuna. Giddens notes that "trust" appears frequently <strong>in</strong> everyday<br />

language, but, some uses <strong>in</strong>voke deeper mean<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> "faith," <strong>in</strong>s<strong>of</strong>ar as trust presupposes a relation to<br />

risk <strong>and</strong> the unanticipated results <strong>of</strong> action. Nowadays, the unexpected comes, not from div<strong>in</strong>e<br />

<strong>in</strong>tervention, but from risk. 6<br />

Giddens' displaced notions <strong>of</strong> fate <strong>and</strong> fortune are <strong>in</strong> turn dist<strong>in</strong>ct from fatalism, the idea that<br />

whatever happens must happen. Fatalism has been an object <strong>of</strong> discussion <strong>and</strong> critique from the first<br />

Mohist attacks on Ruist "fatalism" <strong>in</strong> the Fei M<strong>in</strong>g chapters <strong>of</strong> the Mohist Canon to modern<br />

attacks on theological fatalism <strong>and</strong> scientific determ<strong>in</strong>ism. Even more than belief <strong>in</strong> fate, it seems to<br />

enjoy particular disrepute <strong>in</strong> the modern world:<br />

If time confers respectability on philosophical problems, there are few issues <strong>in</strong> the history<br />

<strong>of</strong> philosophy with more right to be carefully <strong>and</strong> charitably considered than fatalism.<br />

Yet <strong>in</strong> the twentieth century, at least, this approach has certa<strong>in</strong>ly not been adopted.<br />

Contemporary discussions <strong>of</strong> fatalism have been scattered <strong>and</strong> perfunctory, almost always<br />

conclud<strong>in</strong>g with a summary dismissal <strong>of</strong> the fatalist's argument. Typically, the<br />

fatalist is seen as mak<strong>in</strong>g some rather sophomoric blunder — mistak<strong>in</strong>g a tautology for a<br />

substantive thesis about necessity, misunderst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g the scope <strong>of</strong> a `model operator',<br />

2


misrepresent<strong>in</strong>g facts about the future as facts about the past, <strong>and</strong> the like. 7<br />

My approach to the methodological problem <strong>of</strong> comparison is much <strong>in</strong>fluenced by the<br />

comparative work <strong>of</strong> Sir Ge<strong>of</strong>frey Lloyd on Ch<strong>in</strong>ese <strong>and</strong> <strong>Greek</strong> science. He emphasizes the need to<br />

avoid two approaches he refers to as "generalization," the disregard <strong>of</strong> differences <strong>in</strong> time, place, <strong>and</strong><br />

subject matter, <strong>and</strong> "piecemeal," project<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> simple equivalents derived from one tradition onto the<br />

other. 8 Univocal <strong>and</strong> undifferentiated formulations <strong>of</strong> "fatalism" or "belief <strong>in</strong> fate" ignore the contexts <strong>in</strong><br />

which concepts <strong>of</strong> fate, fatalism <strong>and</strong> necessity arose, the problems they were <strong>in</strong>tended to address, <strong>and</strong><br />

the "work" they were <strong>in</strong>tended to do, the systems <strong>of</strong> metaphors <strong>of</strong> which they were elements, <strong>and</strong> the<br />

systems <strong>of</strong> beliefs <strong>and</strong> practices toward which they stood <strong>in</strong> relations <strong>of</strong> contrast or opposition, for<br />

example, notions <strong>of</strong> luck <strong>and</strong> fortune (both good <strong>and</strong> bad). Today (<strong>and</strong> this is work <strong>in</strong> progress!) I<br />

focus on their respective semantic fields <strong>and</strong> the systems <strong>of</strong> metaphors <strong>of</strong> which they were elements, <strong>and</strong><br />

the systems <strong>of</strong> beliefs <strong>and</strong> metaphors toward which they stood <strong>in</strong> relations <strong>of</strong> contrast or opposition, for<br />

example, notions <strong>of</strong> luck, fortune, risk <strong>and</strong> chance. 9<br />

Consider the truism that free will (<strong>and</strong> rationality) are peculiarly <strong>Greek</strong> <strong>and</strong> that Ch<strong>in</strong>ese<br />

philosophy is passive, quietistic or fatalistic. If such generalities can be made at all, the label <strong>of</strong> fatalism<br />

may better fit the <strong>Greek</strong> evidence than the Ch<strong>in</strong>ese. Homer presents a fair consensus that fate cannot<br />

be ga<strong>in</strong>said — whatever we make <strong>of</strong> the relation between Moira (<strong>Fate</strong>) <strong>and</strong> the will <strong>of</strong> Zeus. By<br />

contrast, the accounts <strong>of</strong> fate <strong>in</strong> pre-Buddhist texts share a slightly unnerv<strong>in</strong>g focus on strategy, efficacy,<br />

<strong>and</strong> "setup." 10 Put <strong>in</strong> such overly general terms, strategies toward fate may be an area <strong>of</strong> considerable<br />

difference between Ch<strong>in</strong>ese <strong>and</strong> <strong>Greek</strong> philosophical speculation (to the extent that such generalities<br />

can be used at all), <strong>and</strong> notions <strong>of</strong> strategy may be alternatives to fatalistic accounts <strong>of</strong> dest<strong>in</strong>y.<br />

I approach this problem by explor<strong>in</strong>g some <strong>of</strong> the complex semantics <strong>of</strong> Ch<strong>in</strong>ese m<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>Greek</strong> mo›ra before either were assimilated <strong>in</strong>to later hegemonic discourses: Confucian, Buddhist,<br />

Neo-Confucian, Hellenistic, Christian, etc., start<strong>in</strong>g from the premise that "fate" is not a unified, univocal<br />

or unchang<strong>in</strong>g notion. By fate or dest<strong>in</strong>y I mean the notion that there is a set or immutable pattern to<br />

the world: whether humanly knowable or ultimately <strong>in</strong>scrutable; whether personified as a God (.e.g. the<br />

<strong>Greek</strong> Moirai or Lat<strong>in</strong> Fortuna), under the power <strong>of</strong> one (Si M<strong>in</strong>g , Director <strong>of</strong> Dest<strong>in</strong>ies, or the<br />

will <strong>of</strong> Zeus), or as an agency or power <strong>in</strong>dependent <strong>of</strong>, <strong>and</strong> beyond, the wills <strong>of</strong> gods (Homeric Moira<br />

3


<strong>and</strong>, arguably, Tian M<strong>in</strong>g , the M<strong>and</strong>ate <strong>of</strong> Heaven), <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g the constancies <strong>of</strong> Nature.<br />

A.Ch<strong>in</strong>a<br />

I. The <strong>Semantic</strong> <strong>Fields</strong><br />

Much <strong>of</strong> what follows focuses on different <strong>in</strong>terpretations <strong>of</strong> one word, m<strong>in</strong>g ,fate or<br />

dest<strong>in</strong>y. The Shang oracle bone <strong>in</strong>scriptions present no separate graph for m<strong>in</strong>g. Instead we f<strong>in</strong>d the<br />

graph l<strong>in</strong>g , comm<strong>and</strong> or decree, used <strong>in</strong> two arguably dist<strong>in</strong>ct senses: (1) l<strong>in</strong>g comm<strong>and</strong> or<br />

decree <strong>and</strong> (2) m<strong>in</strong>g as noun, possibly a deity M<strong>in</strong>g or Si M<strong>in</strong>g, who received di sacrifice. 11 Note that<br />

there is no separate graph for the two dist<strong>in</strong>ct concepts. They are separated through context.<br />

The oracle bone evidence suggests that, <strong>in</strong> the Shang view, events reflected the will <strong>of</strong> deities,<br />

such as Si M<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> other ancestors, who could be approached through sacrificial <strong>of</strong>fer<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>and</strong> whose<br />

comm<strong>and</strong>s could be <strong>in</strong>terpreted. 12 (The Shang deity may not be same as the Zhou deity Si M<strong>in</strong>g or<br />

"Director <strong>of</strong> Dest<strong>in</strong>ies," who had power over life <strong>and</strong> death.) These beliefs were <strong>in</strong>separable from<br />

div<strong>in</strong>ation. Most oracle texts were div<strong>in</strong>ations about the future, whether assertive <strong>of</strong> human preference<br />

or <strong>in</strong>terrogative toward div<strong>in</strong>e will. Note also that there is no notion <strong>of</strong> fixed or bl<strong>in</strong>d fate, or <strong>of</strong><br />

predeterm<strong>in</strong>ism here.<br />

1.Zhou <strong>and</strong> Warr<strong>in</strong>g States<br />

1) In the late Zhou <strong>and</strong> Warr<strong>in</strong>g States we f<strong>in</strong>d both a broader semantic field for words concerned with<br />

fate, fatalism <strong>and</strong> dest<strong>in</strong>y <strong>and</strong> an <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>gly complex range <strong>of</strong> concepts associated (<strong>and</strong> debated)<br />

with the word m<strong>in</strong>g. Let me mention a few: The word m<strong>in</strong>g overstood several dist<strong>in</strong>ct mean<strong>in</strong>gs.<br />

i) The first <strong>of</strong> these was life <strong>and</strong> death, the extent <strong>of</strong> one's life span. Xunzi quotes Confucius as<br />

averr<strong>in</strong>g that life <strong>and</strong> death are matters <strong>of</strong> fate<br />

"life <strong>and</strong> death are decreed<br />

13 Accord<strong>in</strong>g to Zhuangzi 6:<br />

14 In this sense people could "make their m<strong>in</strong>g long-lived"<br />

shou m<strong>in</strong>g . 15 And Xunzi refers to soldiers who flee for their lives as literally "runn<strong>in</strong>g<br />

towards their m<strong>in</strong>g, ben m<strong>in</strong>g . 16<br />

ii) fate <strong>in</strong> the sense <strong>of</strong> what has been decreed. Zhuangzi has Confucius advise that "noth<strong>in</strong>g is as<br />

good as br<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>g about what has been decreed" or "noth<strong>in</strong>g is as good as realiz<strong>in</strong>g one's dest<strong>in</strong>y"<br />

. 17<br />

iii) Si M<strong>in</strong>g Director <strong>of</strong> Dest<strong>in</strong>ies (<strong>and</strong> other local div<strong>in</strong>ities)<br />

4


iv) Shang Di m<strong>in</strong>g , the decree <strong>of</strong> Shang Di, the High Lord.<br />

v) tian m<strong>in</strong>g , the m<strong>and</strong>ate or decree <strong>of</strong> heaven. The Odes <strong>and</strong> Documents frequently<br />

repeat the idea that Heaven's decree is not constant, mean<strong>in</strong>g that a ruler cannot count on it<br />

unless he is worthy <strong>of</strong> it. Thus the Duke <strong>of</strong> Zhou tells Pr<strong>in</strong>ce Shi that, even though the Shang has<br />

lost the M<strong>and</strong>ate, he "does not dare to rest [certa<strong>in</strong>] <strong>in</strong> the m<strong>and</strong>ate <strong>of</strong> the Lord on High (Shang<br />

Di m<strong>in</strong>g ) because "Heaven's m<strong>and</strong>ate is not easy [to preserve]; Heaven is hard to<br />

depend on" (tianm<strong>in</strong>g bu yi; tian nan chen ); <strong>and</strong> because people let its<br />

m<strong>and</strong>ate fall (zhui m<strong>in</strong>g ) because they cannot ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong> the virtue <strong>of</strong> their predecessors. 18<br />

vi) shi m<strong>in</strong>g the fate <strong>of</strong> the times. 19 Also shi timel<strong>in</strong>ess, the idea that personal dest<strong>in</strong>y is<br />

l<strong>in</strong>ked with the times<br />

vii) guo zhi m<strong>in</strong>g , the fate <strong>of</strong> a state, as <strong>in</strong> Xunzi's claim that "a person's fate lies with<br />

Heaven; a country's fate lies <strong>in</strong> its rites" . 20<br />

viii) A number <strong>of</strong> verb-object compounds reflect<strong>in</strong>g Warr<strong>in</strong>g States debates, discussed below.<br />

2) fen allotments called "fates" (m<strong>in</strong>g) 21 variously understood as life span, longevity, prosperity, or<br />

specific <strong>in</strong>dividual dest<strong>in</strong>y, to be used <strong>and</strong> cherished, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g by the force <strong>of</strong> human effort<br />

3) jie , fate as decree or opportunity. Xunzi uses jie, literally a node or jo<strong>in</strong>t <strong>of</strong> bamboo, but more<br />

broadly unexpected circumstance or opportunity, to def<strong>in</strong>e fate: "harm<strong>in</strong>g one's nature is called<br />

illness; meet<strong>in</strong>g the node (jie) is called fate . 22<br />

4) bian hua , change <strong>and</strong> transformation, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g the cycles <strong>of</strong> life, death <strong>and</strong> the seasons. In<br />

the Zhuangzi the sage Wang Tai: "takes it as fated that th<strong>in</strong>gs change m<strong>in</strong>g wu zhi hua<br />

. 23 Elsewhere the Zhuangzi has Lao Dan admonish Confucius that "m<strong>in</strong>g cannot be<br />

transformed" . 24 Similarly the Zhuangzi refers to the transformations <strong>of</strong> affairs as "the<br />

movements <strong>of</strong> dest<strong>in</strong>y" m<strong>in</strong>g zhi x<strong>in</strong>g . 25<br />

5) shi configuration or "setup" A wide range <strong>of</strong> texts stress the importance <strong>of</strong> timel<strong>in</strong>ess (shi )<br />

<strong>and</strong> configuration or "setup" (shi ) <strong>in</strong> response to one's times <strong>and</strong> to fate, by underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g<br />

whether or not the times or even more local strategic "configurations" <strong>of</strong> time <strong>and</strong> place held good or<br />

malauspice.<br />

6) sheng or sagacity, the notion that the activities <strong>of</strong> the sage or sheng ren prom<strong>in</strong>ently<br />

5


<strong>in</strong>cluded underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g, <strong>and</strong> com<strong>in</strong>g to some k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> accommodation with, fate. (What this mean<br />

varied widely.)<br />

7) ji xiong , notions <strong>of</strong> good <strong>and</strong> malauspice<br />

8) yi duty, a form <strong>of</strong> "comm<strong>and</strong>."<br />

9) gu purpose or cause<br />

10) chang constancy [<strong>in</strong> nature]<br />

To these we can add a range <strong>of</strong> verb-object compounds, express<strong>in</strong>g Warr<strong>in</strong>g States doctr<strong>in</strong>es<br />

regard<strong>in</strong>g m<strong>in</strong>g, fate <strong>and</strong> heaven. In his discussion <strong>of</strong> these terms <strong>in</strong> a series <strong>of</strong> papers between 1957<br />

<strong>and</strong> 1962, Tang Junyi took the view that all <strong>of</strong> them orig<strong>in</strong>ated <strong>in</strong> the Zhou religion <strong>of</strong> the Odes <strong>and</strong><br />

Documents (<strong>and</strong> thus were not Warr<strong>in</strong>g States products) 26<br />

i) the "underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g m<strong>in</strong>g" (zhi m<strong>in</strong>g ) <strong>of</strong> Confucius, echoed by Xunzi as "those who<br />

underst<strong>and</strong> themselves do not begrudge others; those who underst<strong>and</strong> fate (zhi m<strong>in</strong>g) do not<br />

begrudge Heaven. 27 Though the skeptical thread <strong>in</strong> Zhuangzi questions even whether we can<br />

know whether our lives are fated:: "S<strong>in</strong>ce we do not know the end <strong>of</strong> th<strong>in</strong>gs, how can we say<br />

they have no fates? S<strong>in</strong>ce we do not know the beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> th<strong>in</strong>gs, how can we say they have<br />

fates? 28<br />

ii) the "aga<strong>in</strong>st m<strong>in</strong>g" (fei m<strong>in</strong>g ) <strong>of</strong> the Mohists, attacks on Ruist "fatalism" <strong>in</strong> the three Fei<br />

M<strong>in</strong>g chapters (35-37) <strong>of</strong> the Mohist Canon.<br />

iii) Mengzi's "establish<strong>in</strong>g m<strong>in</strong>g" (li m<strong>in</strong>g , e.g. 7A/1 ), 29<br />

iv) "conform<strong>in</strong>g to fate" (shun m<strong>in</strong>g ) <strong>of</strong> the Zhuangzi 30<br />

v) "return<strong>in</strong>g to m<strong>in</strong>g" (fu m<strong>in</strong>g ) <strong>in</strong> the Zhuangzi (discussed below) <strong>and</strong> Dao de j<strong>in</strong>g<br />

vi) the Xunzi's "controll<strong>in</strong>g" or "caus<strong>in</strong>g m<strong>in</strong>g" (zhi m<strong>in</strong>g , e.g. 16/23),<br />

vii) Zou Yan's "omen <strong>of</strong> receiv<strong>in</strong>g m<strong>in</strong>g" (shou m<strong>in</strong>g zhi fu ), 31<br />

viii) the Zhong yong's "what heaven has decreed is called nature" tian m<strong>in</strong>g zhi wei x<strong>in</strong>g<br />

, <strong>and</strong><br />

ix) "arriv<strong>in</strong>g at [awareness <strong>of</strong>] m<strong>in</strong>g" zhi yu m<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> the Xici commentary to the<br />

Changes. 32<br />

x) penetrat<strong>in</strong>g fate. Accord<strong>in</strong>g to the Zhuangzi, fate is <strong>in</strong> part a matter <strong>of</strong> strategy; <strong>and</strong> the<br />

6


wise assess their times <strong>and</strong> decide how to act: "those <strong>of</strong> penetrat<strong>in</strong>g [<strong>in</strong>sight] <strong>in</strong>to fate (da m<strong>in</strong>g)<br />

do not trouble about what knowledge cannot remedy. 33 Or <strong>in</strong> the couplet "to grasp great fate<br />

(da da m<strong>in</strong>g) is true conformity / to grasp small fate (da xiao m<strong>in</strong>g) is happenstance 34<br />

xi) complet<strong>in</strong>g fate. Accord<strong>in</strong>g to the Zhuangzi, for someone who underst<strong>and</strong>s it, fate is<br />

a means to let th<strong>in</strong>gs come to completion, for example the adroit swimmer, who expla<strong>in</strong>s his skill<br />

to Confucius "I beg<strong>in</strong> with what is <strong>in</strong>born, grow it by essential nature, <strong>and</strong> complete it by means<br />

<strong>of</strong> fate" (cheng hu m<strong>in</strong>g) ... I don't know why I do what I do; that is fate! 35<br />

xii) return<strong>in</strong>g to fate, as <strong>in</strong> the Zhuangzi "Sages who return to fate <strong>and</strong> take heaven as their<br />

teacher become models for others. 36<br />

xiii) sui m<strong>in</strong>g or follow<strong>in</strong>g dest<strong>in</strong>y. The sage-k<strong>in</strong>g Huang Di says that "sages are those who<br />

penetrate <strong>in</strong>to true form <strong>and</strong> follow [the dictates <strong>of</strong>] fate. 37<br />

xiv)shun m<strong>in</strong>g conform<strong>in</strong>g to fate, for example Xunzi's account <strong>of</strong> the junzi, who "conforms<br />

to the decrees [<strong>of</strong> dest<strong>in</strong>y] <strong>and</strong> thereby preserves his authentic s<strong>in</strong>gularity" 38<br />

These debates can be classified <strong>in</strong>to five broadly compet<strong>in</strong>g theories <strong>of</strong> the relations <strong>of</strong> virtue,<br />

practical wisdom <strong>and</strong> chance: (1) m<strong>in</strong>g received at birth predest<strong>in</strong>es most or all acts dur<strong>in</strong>g life, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g<br />

its length; (2) that prior virtue determ<strong>in</strong>es present m<strong>in</strong>g, which is granted for a fixed period <strong>of</strong> time,<br />

without regard to conduct dur<strong>in</strong>g that time; (3) that virtue <strong>and</strong> wisdom somehow determ<strong>in</strong>e m<strong>in</strong>g,<br />

whether through the rewards <strong>of</strong> a conscious Heaven, the spontaneous generation <strong>of</strong> good <strong>and</strong> bad luck,<br />

<strong>and</strong> (4) that the practice <strong>of</strong> virtue <strong>and</strong> wisdom predispose, but do not guarantee, a good life. Beyond<br />

the practice, one can only "await fate" with serenity. F<strong>in</strong>ally, (5) that there is no m<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> no<br />

predeterm<strong>in</strong>ed connection between virtue, wisdom <strong>and</strong> the good life. 39 The relationship <strong>of</strong> these ideas to<br />

each other, to Zhou (<strong>and</strong> Shang religion), their <strong>in</strong>debtedness to mantic practices, their views <strong>of</strong> free will<br />

<strong>and</strong> fixed fate, <strong>and</strong> how they should best be classified, are all subjects <strong>of</strong> considerable scholarly dispute.<br />

The consolidation <strong>of</strong> orthodox "Confucianism dur<strong>in</strong>g the Han saw a cont<strong>in</strong>uation <strong>of</strong> this <strong>in</strong>terest,<br />

with particular concern for the idea that k<strong>in</strong>gs received m<strong>and</strong>ate <strong>of</strong> heaven (di wang shou tian m<strong>in</strong>g<br />

). Other ideas about fate <strong>and</strong> m<strong>in</strong>g from this period <strong>in</strong>clude a "m<strong>and</strong>ate <strong>of</strong> good fortune" (lu<br />

m<strong>in</strong>g ), a "m<strong>and</strong>ate <strong>of</strong> life" (zheng m<strong>in</strong>g ), a "m<strong>and</strong>ate <strong>of</strong> suffer<strong>in</strong>g" (zao m<strong>in</strong>g ), a<br />

7


"m<strong>and</strong>ate <strong>of</strong> correspondence" (sui m<strong>in</strong>g ), as well as correspondence theories <strong>of</strong> y<strong>in</strong>-yang <strong>and</strong><br />

wux<strong>in</strong>g; 40 <strong>and</strong> the notion <strong>of</strong> sui m<strong>in</strong>g , follow<strong>in</strong>g or master<strong>in</strong>g fate, someth<strong>in</strong>g the virtuous can<br />

accomplish by effective response Life span may be fated, but not what is <strong>in</strong> it; a virtuous person might<br />

underst<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> master fate, <strong>and</strong>, by harmoniz<strong>in</strong>g with it, contrive to live out his or her own.<br />

Ideas about m<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> fate were also part <strong>of</strong> the discourse <strong>of</strong> Song (960-1279) <strong>and</strong> M<strong>in</strong>g<br />

Neo-Confucianism. Zhang Hengqu viewed m<strong>in</strong>g as the "ceaselessness <strong>of</strong> heaven" <strong>and</strong> the<br />

"operation <strong>of</strong> cosmic energy. Cheng Yi (1013-1107) <strong>and</strong> Zhu Xi (1130-1200) thought<br />

that heaven sent down m<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> endowed humanity with the li that completed human nature. Liu<br />

Jiuyuan (1139-1193) <strong>and</strong> Wang Yangm<strong>in</strong>g's (1473-1529) views that m<strong>in</strong>d is the<br />

universe culm<strong>in</strong>ated <strong>in</strong> the views <strong>of</strong> Wang Longqi <strong>and</strong> Luo J<strong>in</strong>qi that orig<strong>in</strong>al human<br />

nature is m<strong>in</strong>g. 41 M<strong>in</strong>g also became a concern <strong>of</strong> the Q<strong>in</strong>g (1644-1911) scholars Yan Xizhai ,<br />

Dai Dongyuan , Jiao Xun , Qian Daj<strong>in</strong> <strong>and</strong> Ruan Yuan .<br />

2.Later Ch<strong>in</strong>ese philosophical term<strong>in</strong>ology<br />

Now let me turn to the question <strong>of</strong> Ch<strong>in</strong>ese philosophical term<strong>in</strong>ology for the discussion <strong>of</strong> fate<br />

<strong>and</strong> fatalism. Fu S<strong>in</strong>ian's Exam<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>of</strong> the Evidence on X<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> M<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> Ancient<br />

Teach<strong>in</strong>gs was published <strong>in</strong> 1952. His purpose, like that <strong>of</strong> Ruan Yuan, was to oppose Song scholars'<br />

views. His focus was on the philology <strong>of</strong> m<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> on compet<strong>in</strong>g doctr<strong>in</strong>es <strong>of</strong> m<strong>in</strong>g dur<strong>in</strong>g the Warr<strong>in</strong>g<br />

States. He identified five doctr<strong>in</strong>es, which he described as: 42<br />

i) m<strong>in</strong>g d<strong>in</strong>g or "predeterm<strong>in</strong>ism," the view that personal heaven controls predeterm<strong>in</strong>ed<br />

fate <strong>and</strong> cannot be altered;<br />

ii) m<strong>in</strong>g zheng or "moral determ<strong>in</strong>ism," the view that a moral heaven rewards virtue, with the<br />

corollary that humans can determ<strong>in</strong>e their dest<strong>in</strong>y through moral choices;<br />

iii) si m<strong>in</strong>g or "await<strong>in</strong>g dest<strong>in</strong>y," the Ruist view that heaven rewards virtue overall, but<br />

unpredictably, with the implied recommendation to practice self-cultivation <strong>and</strong> await the<br />

M<strong>and</strong>ate <strong>of</strong> Heaven. Fu considered Xunzi as the orthodox representative <strong>of</strong> Confucianism,<br />

thereby attack<strong>in</strong>g Neo-Confucian attribution <strong>of</strong> this role to Confucius <strong>and</strong> Mencius alone.<br />

iv) m<strong>in</strong>g yun or "fatalism," the view that dest<strong>in</strong>y is fixed <strong>and</strong> controlled by mechanical <strong>and</strong><br />

predictable regularities,<br />

8


v) fei m<strong>in</strong>g or antifatalism, the specifically Mohist opposition to any belief <strong>in</strong> fixed fate Thus<br />

the Mohist claim that [the doctr<strong>in</strong>e <strong>of</strong>] fatalism is not fate, but to reject fatalism is to reject [the<br />

reality <strong>of</strong>] fate [ ] 43<br />

Before turn<strong>in</strong>g to Greece, let me mention a few more important elements to the Ch<strong>in</strong>ese picture.<br />

3. <strong>Fate</strong>, luck, fortune, chance <strong>and</strong> skill<br />

These terms <strong>and</strong> concepts, so far, have clearly come out <strong>of</strong> Classical literary <strong>and</strong> philosophical<br />

uses. Before turn<strong>in</strong>g to Greece, let me broaden out to modern uses, to add a few more Ch<strong>in</strong>ese terms<br />

for notions <strong>of</strong> luck, fortune, etc.<br />

1) luck or fortune. The root mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> Ch<strong>in</strong>ese yun is to carry, transport, or use, also to revolve.<br />

The derivative mean<strong>in</strong>g is fortune, luck, fate, for example <strong>in</strong> the phrases yun qi or luck, hao<br />

yun or good luck.<br />

2) A second term for luck, good fortune, or happ<strong>in</strong>ess is x<strong>in</strong>g . These two senses <strong>of</strong> "lucky"<br />

comb<strong>in</strong>e <strong>in</strong> x<strong>in</strong>g yun very fortunate, or x<strong>in</strong>g yun er , "fortune's favorite" <strong>and</strong> x<strong>in</strong>g<br />

yun zhi shen , "Lady Luck." 44<br />

3) I am not readily able to f<strong>in</strong>d a clear equivalent <strong>in</strong> Ch<strong>in</strong>ese to the notion <strong>of</strong> chance, <strong>in</strong> the sense <strong>of</strong><br />

r<strong>and</strong>omness or accident. Perhaps x<strong>in</strong>g , "luck," is closer to "chance," as <strong>in</strong> the phrases jiao x<strong>in</strong>g<br />

, luckily or by a fluke, or x<strong>in</strong>g de , to obta<strong>in</strong> by chance <strong>and</strong> x<strong>in</strong>g shi , "someth<strong>in</strong>g<br />

that happened out <strong>of</strong> sheer luck." 45 My searches for Ch<strong>in</strong>ese translations for English "r<strong>and</strong>om"<br />

referred more to the emotional disposition to be willful (e.g. sui yi , as one pleases or ren yi<br />

, willful or arbitrary) than to the notion <strong>of</strong> r<strong>and</strong>omness.<br />

4) Risk. Similarly I am not readily able to f<strong>in</strong>d a clear semantic equivalent. The phrase mao xian<br />

means to emit what is vicious, venomous, malicious or dangerous.<br />

4.Summary<br />

Let me attempt to sum this up. A problem <strong>in</strong> talk<strong>in</strong>g about the semantic field <strong>of</strong> fate <strong>in</strong> Ch<strong>in</strong>ese<br />

texts is the considerable range associated with one term, m<strong>in</strong>g. In particular, the word m<strong>in</strong>g reta<strong>in</strong>s the<br />

l<strong>in</strong>ked senses <strong>of</strong> comm<strong>and</strong>, <strong>and</strong> fate ("comm<strong>and</strong>ed," as it were). They must be separated by context.<br />

After a brief discussion <strong>of</strong> the Shang oracle bone <strong>in</strong>scriptions, I began with a semantic field <strong>of</strong><br />

approximately Zhou <strong>and</strong> Warr<strong>in</strong>g States provenance, closely l<strong>in</strong>ked to or derived from m<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g a<br />

9


group <strong>of</strong> verb-object compounds that reflected Warr<strong>in</strong>g States debated about fate, followed by several<br />

post-Han additions. Mov<strong>in</strong>g forward <strong>in</strong> time, I mentioned Ch<strong>in</strong>ese philosophical term<strong>in</strong>ology <strong>and</strong><br />

surveyed a range <strong>of</strong> terms for beliefs <strong>and</strong> practices than closely bear on any study <strong>of</strong> fate, most<br />

particularly those related to div<strong>in</strong>ation. In concluded with a brief discussion <strong>of</strong> some more<br />

contemporary terms for luck, <strong>and</strong> their imperfect fit with a range <strong>of</strong> English-language concepts<br />

concern<strong>in</strong>g luck, chance, r<strong>and</strong>omness <strong>and</strong> risk. Now let me turn to Greece.<br />

B.The <strong>Greek</strong> <strong>Semantic</strong> Field<br />

<strong>Greek</strong> accounts <strong>of</strong> fate fall <strong>in</strong>to two fairly dist<strong>in</strong>ct historical strata, before <strong>and</strong> after the fourth<br />

century. 46 Pre-fourth-century texts, beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g with Homer, describe "fate" <strong>in</strong> several fairly dist<strong>in</strong>ct terms<br />

<strong>and</strong> metaphors: (1) mo›ra or α‰σα, transparent metaphors <strong>of</strong> division, lots or portions, <strong>of</strong> dest<strong>in</strong>y,<br />

death or <strong>of</strong> allotted life span. Over time, these were replaced by (2) metaphors <strong>of</strong> sp<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g,<br />

<strong>in</strong> which fate is a thread spun about the "sp<strong>in</strong>dle" <strong>of</strong> each life. In later works, moira <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>gly<br />

becomes personified as the "Sp<strong>in</strong>ners," the Three <strong>Fate</strong>s or Mo›rai. (3) the attribution <strong>of</strong> misfortune to<br />

da¤mvnew, who variously gave out misfortune or guided <strong>in</strong>dividual dest<strong>in</strong>ies; (4) the problem <strong>of</strong> the<br />

relation <strong>of</strong> fate <strong>and</strong> the gods, most specifically to the will <strong>of</strong> Zeus, k<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> most powerful <strong>of</strong> the gods. 47<br />

To these we may add (5) the appearances <strong>of</strong> the Moirai <strong>of</strong> <strong>Fate</strong>s as objects <strong>of</strong> cult as birth goddesses<br />

(Hesiod, Pausanius, etc. Lat<strong>in</strong> Parcae ("childbear<strong>in</strong>g") were equivalent to the Moirai). (6) After the<br />

fourth century, fate was viewed as pr<strong>in</strong>ciple rul<strong>in</strong>g both the world overall <strong>and</strong> the lives <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividuals,<br />

expressed by the term efimarm°nh.<br />

Today I sample three strata <strong>of</strong> the pre-fourth-century picture: Homer, Parmenides <strong>and</strong> Plato.<br />

Each text def<strong>in</strong>es one or more "problems <strong>of</strong> fate"; they precede, <strong>in</strong>form <strong>and</strong> significantly differ from later<br />

uses <strong>of</strong> fate as a dramatic element <strong>in</strong> tragedy <strong>and</strong> Hellenistic debates on fate <strong>and</strong> fatalism. The Homeric<br />

corpus first poses, <strong>and</strong> conspicuously does not resolve, problems <strong>of</strong> fate <strong>and</strong> fatalism. The relation <strong>of</strong><br />

fate to both the will <strong>of</strong> Zeus <strong>and</strong> the free will <strong>of</strong> mortals is ambiguous. Pre-Socratic philosophy "is<br />

divided <strong>in</strong>to two halves by the name <strong>of</strong> Parmenides," (b. 515-510) who ab<strong>and</strong>ons cosmogony <strong>in</strong> favor<br />

<strong>of</strong> div<strong>in</strong>e <strong>in</strong>struction on the "true" world <strong>of</strong> unchang<strong>in</strong>g reality (<strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g fate), <strong>and</strong> makes fate a vivid<br />

aspect <strong>of</strong> unchang<strong>in</strong>g be<strong>in</strong>g. <strong>Fate</strong> figures <strong>in</strong> Plato's (427-347) account <strong>of</strong> the soul <strong>and</strong> the defense <strong>and</strong><br />

10


self-representation <strong>of</strong> the Platonic Socrates. As an aspect <strong>of</strong> div<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>and</strong> discourses <strong>of</strong><br />

prognostication, it is also an <strong>in</strong>direct issue <strong>in</strong> the history <strong>of</strong> <strong>Greek</strong> medic<strong>in</strong>e, the "<strong>in</strong>quiry concern<strong>in</strong>g<br />

nature," <strong>and</strong> the creation <strong>of</strong> the category <strong>of</strong> rationality. These texts, images <strong>and</strong> metaphors precede<br />

Hellenistic rejections <strong>of</strong> determ<strong>in</strong>ism by Aristotle (384-322) <strong>and</strong> Epicurus (341-270) <strong>and</strong> defenses <strong>of</strong> it<br />

by the Stoa, for whom fate assumed central prom<strong>in</strong>ence as a philosophical problem 48<br />

1.<strong>Fate</strong> <strong>in</strong> Homer<br />

Just as a range <strong>of</strong> mean<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>in</strong>formed Ch<strong>in</strong>ese m<strong>in</strong>g, a range <strong>of</strong> forms <strong>and</strong> mean<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>in</strong>form<br />

<strong>Greek</strong> moira. Let me <strong>in</strong>troduce the basic terms.<br />

1) mo›ra, merow <strong>and</strong> α‰σα: lots or portions, <strong>of</strong> dest<strong>in</strong>y, death or <strong>of</strong> allotted life span (Note the<br />

transparent metaphor <strong>of</strong> division, as with Ch<strong>in</strong>ese fen.)<br />

i) the verb me¤romai, "to receive a portion"<br />

ii) êmorow, êmoirow or êmmorow, to be bereft <strong>of</strong> a th<strong>in</strong>g, unfortunate, or to be without a lot or<br />

share. Demosthenes (On the Halonnesus 7.40) refers to a piece <strong>of</strong> l<strong>and</strong> as "no man's l<strong>and</strong>"<br />

(émmor¤ow).<br />

iii) émor¤a (or émmor¤a), to be "fate-less" for example the statement that "Zeus knows well "the<br />

Od. 20.76).<br />

The oldest terms for fate, mo›ra (from me¤romai, "to receive a portion") <strong>and</strong> α‰σα referred to<br />

a share, lot, or portion, most immediately <strong>of</strong> death, hence dest<strong>in</strong>y as allotted life span. These shares<br />

could be simple fact or special dest<strong>in</strong>y, the result <strong>of</strong> the anger <strong>of</strong> a specific god or a decree <strong>of</strong> fate<br />

beyond the will <strong>of</strong> the gods, or a comb<strong>in</strong>ations. Thus Achilles' tells Thetis that, once he has killed<br />

Hector he will accept his own death at the h<strong>and</strong>s <strong>of</strong> Zeus <strong>and</strong> the other immortals, for even Herakles<br />

was conquered by his fate (moira), <strong>and</strong> the anger <strong>of</strong> Hera;<br />

Œw ka‹ §g≈n, efi dÆ moi ımo¤h mo›ra t°tuktai,<br />

ke¤som' §pe¤ ke yãnv.<br />

<strong>and</strong> so, too, shall I lie, if a like fate has been worked for me<br />

when I die (Il. 18.1190-21).<br />

To be êmorow, êmoirow or êmmorow is to be bereft <strong>of</strong> a th<strong>in</strong>g, unfortunate, or to be without<br />

11


a lot or share. 49 And émor¤a (or émmor¤a) is to be "fate-less," for example the statement that "Zeus<br />

knows well "the portions <strong>and</strong> bereftnesses <strong>of</strong> mortals" mo›rãn t' émmor¤hn te kataynht«n<br />

ényr≈pvn (Od. 20.76).<br />

For the most part, moira occupies a place apart from social status, the share <strong>of</strong> wealth, rank<br />

<strong>and</strong> privilege that results from birth, though Iliad 3 describes Agamemnon as "born <strong>of</strong> good moira <strong>and</strong><br />

happy <strong>in</strong> [the protection <strong>of</strong>] a daimon" (moirhgen°w, ÙlbiÒdaimon, ll. 3.182)<br />

Nor is moira the share that results from the "just deserts" <strong>of</strong> virtuous or unvirtuous action. It<br />

referred rather to sudden reversals <strong>and</strong> situations that threaten to the order decreed by the gods. As<br />

Hector boasts to Andromache that no man can kill him prematurely because fate is a power that cannot<br />

be ga<strong>in</strong>said by god or man.<br />

oÈ gãr t¤w m' Íp¢r a‰san énØr ÖAÛdi proÛãcei<br />

mo›ran d' oÎ t<strong>in</strong>ã fhmi pefugm°non ¶mmenai éndr«n,<br />

No man will hurl me to Hades beyond my portion,<br />

but fate I say no one <strong>of</strong> mank<strong>in</strong>d can flee (Il. 6:487-89)<br />

iv) katå mo›ran "accord<strong>in</strong>g to fate" <strong>and</strong> kat'a‰san "accord<strong>in</strong>g to measure" <strong>and</strong><br />

v) Íp¢r mo›ran <strong>and</strong> Íp¢r a‰san<br />

The above passage raises the problem <strong>of</strong> how or whether action "beyond fate" could occur.<br />

The phrases katå mo›ran "accord<strong>in</strong>g to fate" <strong>and</strong> kat' a‰san "accord<strong>in</strong>g to measure" occur<br />

frequently <strong>in</strong> the Homeric corpus; "beyond fated measure" — Íp¢r mo›ran <strong>and</strong> Íp¢r a‰san — are<br />

relatively rare. More important, they are always <strong>in</strong> counterfactual <strong>in</strong> one <strong>of</strong> several senses, with a range<br />

<strong>of</strong> mean<strong>in</strong>gs from physical to moral "impossibility." 50 The one <strong>in</strong>stance <strong>of</strong> the phrase Íp¢r mo›ran <strong>in</strong><br />

the Homeric corpus occurs when Poseidon <strong>in</strong>tervenes to save A<strong>in</strong>eas from Achilles, ostensibly to avoid<br />

the wrath <strong>of</strong> Zeus, s<strong>in</strong>ce he is fated (mÒrimon) to survive the war (Il. 20.301-2). Poseidon uses an<br />

appeal to dest<strong>in</strong>y to deter him from any further encounter with Achilles<br />

mØ ka‹ Íp¢r mo›ran dÒmon ÖAÛdow e¤saf¤khai<br />

lest, beyond fate, you go down to the house <strong>of</strong> Hades (Il. 20.336).<br />

Apollo also <strong>in</strong>tervenes to prevent the Argives from w<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g victory "beyond the portion <strong>of</strong> Zeus" (Íp¢r<br />

12


DiÚw a‰san, Il. 17.321). We may read these <strong>in</strong>stances <strong>in</strong> two ways. Taken at face value, the gods<br />

<strong>in</strong>tervene to preserve the decreed order <strong>and</strong> prevent mortals from act<strong>in</strong>g outside it. Read rhetorically,<br />

appeals to fate provide a powerful rationale for the gods to <strong>in</strong>tervene accord<strong>in</strong>g to their own wishes<br />

(presumably, with<strong>in</strong> the limits <strong>of</strong> fate).<br />

In battle, "beyond fate" or "beyond measure" clearly refers to premature <strong>and</strong> violent death. In<br />

other contexts, "beyond measure" has the broader connotations <strong>of</strong> impropriety or even impiety. On two<br />

occasions, Paris agrees that Hector's reproaches are "accord<strong>in</strong>g to measure" (kat'a‰san) <strong>and</strong> "not<br />

beyond measure" (oÈd' Íp¢r a‰san, Il. 3.59 <strong>and</strong> 6.333). Excess also can verge on impiety. After a<br />

pitched battle, the <strong>Greek</strong>s prevailed "beyond measure" (huper aisan), when they captured the body <strong>of</strong><br />

Kebriones <strong>and</strong> stripped him <strong>of</strong> his armor (Il. 16.780). In these cases, "beyond measure" labels an act<br />

as morally, rather than physically "impossible."<br />

In all these <strong>in</strong>stances, it is noteworthy that moira does not seem to be l<strong>in</strong>ked to either div<strong>in</strong>ation<br />

— attempts to underst<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> perhaps conform to a fated future — or to m∞ti˚, the skills <strong>and</strong> wiles<br />

that <strong>Greek</strong> society so prized for deal<strong>in</strong>g with unpredictable <strong>and</strong> rapidly shift<strong>in</strong>g situations. 51 Metis, it<br />

appears, was not used to thwart the decrees <strong>of</strong> fate.<br />

2.<strong>Fate</strong> as spun bonds<br />

We also see fate personified as several goddesses l<strong>in</strong>ked to notions <strong>of</strong> dest<strong>in</strong>y, punishment,<br />

retribution <strong>and</strong> justice, typically , revealed by oracles, omens, prodigies <strong>and</strong> signs. They also pose the<br />

problem <strong>of</strong> the relation <strong>of</strong> fate <strong>and</strong> the gods:<br />

i) The Goddesses Themis or Dike <strong>and</strong><br />

ii) Themis <strong>and</strong> Dike (Justice).<br />

iii) Aνãγκη or Necessity,<br />

iv) <strong>Fate</strong> or Mo›ra <strong>and</strong><br />

v) The Three <strong>Fate</strong>s or Mo›rai,<br />

The Three fates are variously represented as h<strong>and</strong>maidens <strong>of</strong> Dike <strong>and</strong> as the "Sp<strong>in</strong>ners" <strong>of</strong><br />

human fates. The fates appear <strong>in</strong>frequently <strong>in</strong> Homer as three figures who sp<strong>in</strong> the thread <strong>of</strong> dest<strong>in</strong>y<br />

13


around each <strong>in</strong>dividual. Alk<strong>in</strong>oos describes the fates as "Heavy Sp<strong>in</strong>ners" Kl«yew, when he speaks<br />

<strong>of</strong> the unusual dest<strong>in</strong>y (aisa) <strong>of</strong> Odysseus, who, once he returns safely to Ithaka<br />

will bear as much as his dest<strong>in</strong>y <strong>and</strong> the Heavy Sp<strong>in</strong>ners<br />

spun for him at birth with thread, when his mother bore him<br />

pe¤setai ëssa <strong>of</strong>l α‰σα katå Kl«y°w te bare›ai<br />

ge<strong>in</strong>om°nƒ nÆsato l¤nƒ, ˜te m<strong>in</strong> t°ke mÆthr (Od. 7.197)<br />

This "sp<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g" takes place primarily at birth, but also at marriage (Od. 4.207), where the Moirai<br />

could be bearers <strong>of</strong> good fortune, <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> some accounts, s<strong>in</strong>g for the bridal couple. 52 In Homer, the<br />

gods are also "sp<strong>in</strong>ners" <strong>of</strong> fate. In Iliad 24 "the gods spun life thus for afflicted mortals" (Õw går<br />

§pekl≈santo yeo‹ deilo›si broto›si, Il. 24.525). The Odyssey beg<strong>in</strong>s when "the gods had spun<br />

for him his return home" (t“ <strong>of</strong>l §pekl≈santo yeo‹ o‰kÒnde n°esyai Od. 1.17). The gods spun<br />

the destruction <strong>of</strong> Troy (Od. 3.208), the fate <strong>of</strong> Odysseus (Od. 11.139), <strong>and</strong> his beggar persona (Od.<br />

16.64)<br />

The division <strong>and</strong> personification <strong>of</strong> Moira <strong>in</strong>to the Three <strong>Fate</strong>s or Mo‰rai, who sp<strong>in</strong>, weave,<br />

<strong>and</strong> cut <strong>of</strong>f the thread <strong>of</strong> each life, first appears <strong>in</strong> Hesiod (Theog. 904-6). Here the <strong>Fate</strong>s are the<br />

daughters <strong>of</strong> Zeus <strong>and</strong> Themis: Clotho, Lachesis ("gett<strong>in</strong>g by lot") <strong>and</strong> Atropos (from which one cannot<br />

turn), <strong>and</strong> only reappear together <strong>in</strong> Plato.<br />

In the climactic passage <strong>of</strong> fragment 8, Parmenides uses specifically Homeric language <strong>and</strong><br />

diction to describe "what-is" (¶st<strong>in</strong>) <strong>and</strong> to frame the claim that the truly real is unchang<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong><br />

immobile. 53<br />

kraterØ gãr Anãgkh<br />

pe¤ratow §n desmo›s<strong>in</strong> ¶xei, tÒ m<strong>in</strong> émf‹w §°rgei<br />

For strong Ananke holds it <strong>in</strong> bonds <strong>of</strong> cha<strong>in</strong> that b<strong>in</strong>ds it all around (fr. 8, 30-31)<br />

oÊd¢n går °st<strong>in</strong> ≥ ¶stai<br />

êllo pãrej toË °Òntow, §pe‹ tÒ ge Mo›r §p°dhsen<br />

oÔlon ãk¤nhtÒn t' ¶mmenai.<br />

For noth<strong>in</strong>g exists or will exist<br />

other than what is, s<strong>in</strong>ce Moira has fettered it<br />

so as to be whole <strong>and</strong> immovable (fr. 8, 36-38).<br />

Here the powers <strong>of</strong> Moira <strong>and</strong> Ananke come together to b<strong>in</strong>d reality <strong>in</strong> strongly Homeric<br />

14


diction: krateros (used <strong>of</strong> Zeus) <strong>and</strong> peiratos en desmoisi.<br />

Plato's fullest account <strong>of</strong> the Moirai is <strong>in</strong> the Republic (Rep. 617b-621a), where they s<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong><br />

harmony at a common task Their activity is liked to Ananke <strong>and</strong> to the daimons that guide the fates <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>in</strong>dividuals. In the passage, Socrates expla<strong>in</strong>s how souls choose their lives <strong>in</strong> the order <strong>of</strong> the lots they<br />

draw. They are then brought before Lachesis, first <strong>of</strong> the Moirai, who:<br />

§ke¤nhn d' •kãstƒ ˘n e·leto da¤mona, toËton fÊlaka sump°mpe<strong>in</strong> toË<br />

b¤ou ka‹ époplhrvtØn t«n aflrey°ntvn.<br />

sends forth a daimon for each [soul] to guard his life <strong>and</strong> to br<strong>in</strong>g to pass what he has<br />

chosen (Rep 620e)<br />

The daimon next leads the soul to Clotho. The turn<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> her sp<strong>in</strong>dle, ratifies the dest<strong>in</strong>y<br />

(mo›ran) the soul has chosen. F<strong>in</strong>ally, the daimon leads the soul to Atropos, "she who cannot be<br />

turned," who "fixes the web so as to be irreversible" (émetãstr<strong>of</strong>a tå §piklvsy°nta<br />

poioËnta). From there, with no look back, it goes beneath the seat <strong>of</strong> Necessity (ÍpÚ tÚn t∞w<br />

énãgkhw fi°nai yrÒnon). <strong>and</strong> f<strong>in</strong>ally to the Pla<strong>in</strong> <strong>of</strong> Lethe (ı t∞w LÆyhw ped¤on, Rep. 621a).<br />

3.Daimons<br />

Psychopompic da¤mvnew or guides <strong>of</strong> the soul (from the root da- da¤v, dat°omai, to<br />

divide, especially to cut up portions <strong>of</strong> meat, <strong>in</strong> sacrifice). These figures variously gave out misfortune or<br />

guided <strong>in</strong>dividual dest<strong>in</strong>ies. Da¤mvnew were orig<strong>in</strong>ally "sharers" who shared out allotments to<br />

humank<strong>in</strong>d. As such they are l<strong>in</strong>ked to the metaphor <strong>of</strong> apportionment that underl<strong>in</strong>es the terms moira<br />

<strong>and</strong> aisa. Like them, they were powers beyond human will, older than the anthropomorphic Olympian<br />

gods <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>comprehensible, daimÒniow. 54 They are not major presences <strong>in</strong> Homer, where they usually<br />

cause illness (Od. 5.396) <strong>and</strong> such misfortunes as Odysseus' imprisonment on Ogygia:<br />

éll' §m¢ tÚn dÊsthnon §f°stion ≥gage da¤mvn<br />

only my unhappy self did the daimon lead to her hearth (Od. 7.248) 55<br />

To some extent, the activity <strong>of</strong> daimons can be contrasted to that <strong>of</strong> the gods (yeÒi) as<br />

thwart<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> aid<strong>in</strong>g human purposes, respectively.<br />

In the poem <strong>of</strong> Parmenides, it is a beneficent daimon who guides the possibly shamanic journey<br />

<strong>of</strong> a young man toward discovery <strong>of</strong> truth 56<br />

15


‡ppoi ta¤ me f°rous<strong>in</strong>, ˜son t' §p‹ yumÚw flkãnoi,<br />

p°mpon, §pe¤ m' §w ıdÚn b∞san polÊfhmon êgousai<br />

da¤monow<br />

The mares that bear me as far as my heart aspires<br />

sent me on, when once they set me on the much-spoken road<br />

<strong>of</strong> the daimon (Parm fr. 1, 1-3)<br />

He reaches the gates <strong>of</strong> the paths <strong>of</strong> Night <strong>and</strong> Day, filled with huge doors, <strong>and</strong> Dike the<br />

avenger (D¤kh polÊpo<strong>in</strong>ow) holds the keys (9) 57 A goddess welcomes him <strong>and</strong> tells him to<br />

xa›r', §pe‹ oÎti se Mo›ra kakØ proÎpempe ne°syai<br />

Rejoice, for it is no ill <strong>Fate</strong> that sends you to travel<br />

here (26).<br />

Daimons play a major role <strong>in</strong> the self-representation <strong>of</strong> the Platonic Socrates, who claimed<br />

repeatedly that a daimon guided his dest<strong>in</strong>y, which he describes as unusual <strong>and</strong> remarkable. His<br />

daimon figures <strong>in</strong> his defense <strong>in</strong> the Apology:<br />

˜ti moi ye›Òn ti ka‹ daimÒnion g¤gnetai [fvnÆ] ... §mo‹ d¢ toËt' ¶st<strong>in</strong> §k<br />

paidÚw érjãmenon, fvnÆ tiw gignom°nh, ∂ tan g°nhtai, ée‹ épotr°pei<br />

me toËto ˘ ín m°llv prãtte<strong>in</strong>, protr°pei d¢ oÎpote.<br />

that someth<strong>in</strong>g div<strong>in</strong>e <strong>and</strong> daemonic would befall me ... ever s<strong>in</strong>ce my early childhood a<br />

voice <strong>of</strong> sorts would come to me, which, when it came, always turned me back from<br />

what I was <strong>in</strong>tend<strong>in</strong>g to do, <strong>and</strong> turned me toward what I was not... (Apol 31d )<br />

He remarks to the jury that someth<strong>in</strong>g marvelous (yaumãsiÒn) had happened to him. That<br />

very morn<strong>in</strong>g, he had met with the approval <strong>of</strong>:<br />

≤ går efivyu›ã moi mantikØ ≤ toË daimon¤ou §n m¢n t“ prÒsyen xrÒnƒ<br />

pant‹ pãnu puknØ ée‹ ∑n ka‹ pãnu §p‹ smikro›w §nantioum°nh, e‡ ti<br />

m°lloimi mØ Ùry«w prãje<strong>in</strong>.<br />

the mantic voice <strong>of</strong> the daimon, to which I had become accustomed , <strong>in</strong> times past was<br />

always close at h<strong>and</strong> to oppose the smallest th<strong>in</strong>g I might <strong>in</strong>tend <strong>in</strong> error (Apol 40a)<br />

Socrates' account is reflected <strong>in</strong> the Euthyphro gives a quasi-humorous account <strong>of</strong> these charges:<br />

manyãnv, Œ S≈kratew: ˜ti dØ sÁ tÚ daimÒnion fØ|w saut“ •kãstote<br />

g¤gnesyai.<br />

Socrates, it is because you say that someth<strong>in</strong>g daimonic is always <strong>in</strong> attendance upon<br />

you (Euth 3b)<br />

The Theaetetus also makes clear that Socrates' daimon attends to the f<strong>in</strong>e details <strong>of</strong> his life. In<br />

his account <strong>of</strong> the midwifery <strong>of</strong> the soul, he describes how he chooses his association:<br />

16


§n¤oiw m¢n tÚ gignÒmenÒn moi daimÒnion épokvlÊei sune›nai, §n¤oiw d¢ §ò,<br />

with some, the daimonic [presence] comes <strong>and</strong> forbids me to associate, with others, it<br />

permits it (Tht 151a)<br />

Daimons also figure prom<strong>in</strong>ently <strong>in</strong> Plato is as guides <strong>of</strong> the soul before birth <strong>and</strong> after death. In<br />

the Phaedo, <strong>in</strong>dividual daimons appear as psychopompoi after death:<br />

l°getai d¢ oÏtvw, …w êra teleutÆsanta ßkaston ı •kãstou da¤mvn,<br />

˜sper z«nta efilÆxei, oappletow êge<strong>in</strong> §pixeire› efiw dÆ t<strong>in</strong>a tÒpon, o de›<br />

toÁw sulleg°ntaw diadikasam°nouw efiw<br />

It is said that, when each person dies, the daimon <strong>of</strong> each, who had charge <strong>of</strong> him while<br />

he was alive, this same one tries to lead him to a certa<strong>in</strong> place (Phaedo 107d)<br />

The wise soul follows the guide, but a soul overly attached to the body l<strong>in</strong>gers <strong>and</strong> "only after<br />

much resistance <strong>and</strong> much suffer<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>and</strong> with excessive force, can it be led away by its guid<strong>in</strong>g daimon<br />

(toË prostetagm°nou da¤monow Phaedo 108b), who leads it to judgment<br />

4.The Dios Boule<br />

§peidån éf¤kvntai <strong>of</strong>l teteleuthkÒtew efiw tÚn tÒpon o ı da¤mvn ßkaston<br />

kom¤zei<br />

when the dead come to the place to which the daimon leads each (Phaedo 113d).<br />

The Diow boulh or "Plan <strong>of</strong> Zeus," most specifically the relation <strong>of</strong> fate to the will <strong>of</strong> Zeus,<br />

k<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> most powerful <strong>of</strong> the gods. Homer never resolves the question <strong>of</strong> the relation <strong>of</strong> moira to the<br />

will <strong>of</strong> the gods, <strong>and</strong> they coexist ambiguously. 58 Human affairs "lie on the knees <strong>of</strong> the gods" (Od.<br />

1.267). The "destructive plan <strong>of</strong> the gods" (ye«n Ùloåw diå boulãw) causes the suffer<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong><br />

Oedipus (Od. 11.276), <strong>and</strong> "the will <strong>of</strong> the gods" (ye«n fiÒthti) causes the death <strong>of</strong> Patroklos (Il.<br />

19.9), the toils <strong>of</strong> Odysseus (Od. 7.214) <strong>and</strong> the Trojan War (Od. 12.190 <strong>and</strong> 17.119). Yet the gods<br />

acknowledge a fate beyond their power to alter. For example, Poseidon grudg<strong>in</strong>gly acknowledges that<br />

it is Odysseus' aisa to escape death (Od. 5.288ff).<br />

While fate appears not to be a problem for the gods <strong>in</strong> general, it poses a more particular, <strong>and</strong><br />

also unresolved, problem for the plan <strong>of</strong> Zeus (DiÚw boulÆ). As k<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the gods, Zeus is more<br />

powerful than all the other gods comb<strong>in</strong>ed, <strong>and</strong> his will has a unique status. The beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the Iliad<br />

makes it clear that the will <strong>of</strong> Zeus is brought to completion with the sack <strong>of</strong> Troy. In the Odyssey Zeus<br />

is more accommodat<strong>in</strong>g to the will <strong>of</strong> the other gods, e.g. <strong>in</strong> the return <strong>of</strong> Odysseus. Nevertheless, Zeus<br />

17


has no more power than the other gods to determ<strong>in</strong>e the span <strong>of</strong> an <strong>in</strong>dividual life. Zeus, as the<br />

"steward <strong>of</strong> war for mank<strong>in</strong>d" (Il. 19.224) may weigh the fates <strong>of</strong> antagonists <strong>in</strong> battle, <strong>and</strong> may even<br />

attempt to defer the moira <strong>of</strong> a hero <strong>in</strong> battle (Il. 16.431-43 <strong>and</strong> 22.167-81), but his will <strong>in</strong>evitably <strong>and</strong><br />

seamlessly conforms to the fate <strong>of</strong> that <strong>in</strong>dividual. As Terence Irw<strong>in</strong> po<strong>in</strong>ts out, Zeus <strong>and</strong> the fates po<strong>in</strong>t<br />

to two dist<strong>in</strong>ct notions <strong>of</strong> (partial) order with<strong>in</strong> the Homeric universe: the impersonal, <strong>in</strong>exorable, amoral<br />

(<strong>and</strong> usually <strong>in</strong>scrutable) order <strong>of</strong> the fates, <strong>and</strong> the <strong>in</strong>telligent, moral justice-based rulership <strong>of</strong> Zeus. 59<br />

The moraliz<strong>in</strong>g retrospective accounts <strong>of</strong> Hesiod, P<strong>in</strong>dar <strong>and</strong> Aeschylus l<strong>in</strong>ked the power <strong>of</strong> the Moirai<br />

with government <strong>of</strong> Zeus; <strong>and</strong> led to the worship <strong>of</strong> Zeus as Moirag°thw, "leader <strong>of</strong> the Moirai" <strong>in</strong> the<br />

fifth century.<br />

<strong>Greek</strong> philosophical reflection on fate moves away from the Homeric problem <strong>of</strong> the limits <strong>of</strong><br />

the will <strong>of</strong> Zeus. As we have seen, Plato takes it up with the role <strong>of</strong> daimons <strong>and</strong> the dest<strong>in</strong>ies <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>in</strong>dividual souls (Republic <strong>and</strong> Timaeus). Aristotle takes <strong>in</strong> up <strong>in</strong> the Nichomachean Ethics, De<br />

Interpretatione, the Metaphysics <strong>and</strong> the Physics.<br />

5.Hellenistic Greece<br />

After the fourth century, the Moirai where <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>gly replaced by the term efimarm°nh.<br />

After the fourth century, fate was viewed as pr<strong>in</strong>ciple rul<strong>in</strong>g both the world overall <strong>and</strong> the lives <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>in</strong>dividuals. It is well known that determ<strong>in</strong>ism (asserted <strong>and</strong> denied <strong>in</strong> both physical <strong>and</strong> ethical contexts)<br />

became a central problem <strong>of</strong> post-Aristotelian <strong>Greek</strong> philosophy. From the late second century B.C.E.<br />

to the third century C.E., discussions <strong>of</strong> fate became part <strong>of</strong> a philosophical repertoire common to all the<br />

philosophical schools. It was central to the Stoa for 400 years, though no Stoic treatise on it has<br />

survived. Discussions <strong>of</strong> the topics <strong>of</strong> fate <strong>and</strong> providence appear <strong>in</strong> texts variously titled On <strong>Fate</strong>, On<br />

Nature, On the Possible, On Providence <strong>and</strong> On the Gods. Surviv<strong>in</strong>g text titled On <strong>Fate</strong> beg<strong>in</strong> with<br />

Chrysippus <strong>of</strong> Soli (280-207 B.C.E.), followed by Cicero (106-43 B.C.E.) <strong>and</strong> Alex<strong>and</strong>er <strong>of</strong><br />

Aphrodisias (2nd-3rd century C.E.). Surviv<strong>in</strong>g accounts refer to the views <strong>of</strong> Epicurus (341-270<br />

B.C.E.), the skeptic Carneades (214-129 B.C.E.), <strong>and</strong> several figures associated with the Stoa: its<br />

founder Zeno <strong>of</strong> Citium (335-263), Boethus <strong>of</strong> Sidon (2nd century B.C.E.), Posidonius (135-51<br />

B.C.E.) <strong>and</strong> Epictetus (c.55-135 C.E.). Lost texts are attributed to the Platonist Plutarch (1st century<br />

18


C.E.), Tertullian (2nd century C.E.), <strong>and</strong> second century Peripatetics <strong>and</strong> Stoics. There were also<br />

fourth century Christian works titled "Aga<strong>in</strong>st <strong>Fate</strong>" by Gregory <strong>of</strong> Nyssa <strong>and</strong> Diodorus <strong>of</strong> Tarsus.<br />

II. Skills <strong>and</strong> Practices<br />

Religious views <strong>of</strong> fate assumed vary<strong>in</strong>g degrees <strong>of</strong> human agency, rang<strong>in</strong>g from "passive"<br />

attempts to ascerta<strong>in</strong> div<strong>in</strong>e will to attempts to align <strong>in</strong>dividual dest<strong>in</strong>y with the pattern <strong>of</strong> the cosmos or<br />

even to trick, compel or negotiate with the gods. Relevant religious practices <strong>in</strong>cluded div<strong>in</strong>ation by<br />

various methods, the <strong>in</strong>terpretation <strong>of</strong> signs (dreams, omens, anomalies, etc.), <strong>and</strong> the efforts <strong>of</strong><br />

specialists (oracles, mediums, etc.) to ascerta<strong>in</strong> div<strong>in</strong>e comm<strong>and</strong>s. A central problem <strong>in</strong> both traditions<br />

was mantic access: who had access to this <strong>in</strong>formation <strong>and</strong> these techniques?<br />

The semantic fields for fate <strong>and</strong> dest<strong>in</strong>y were <strong>in</strong>tertw<strong>in</strong>ed with the practice <strong>of</strong> a range <strong>of</strong><br />

techniques that furthered personal welfare through personal access to mantic knowledge," a formulation<br />

I owe to Mu-chou Poo. 60 By the term mantic access I mean a range <strong>of</strong> techniques <strong>of</strong> prediction <strong>and</strong><br />

div<strong>in</strong>ation. Start<strong>in</strong>g from our earliest written records (literally), a range <strong>of</strong> Ch<strong>in</strong>ese techniques have been<br />

used for prediction <strong>and</strong> div<strong>in</strong>ation. There is evidence that mantic access was far greater <strong>in</strong> 'Ch<strong>in</strong>a than <strong>in</strong><br />

Greece. A detailed description <strong>of</strong> these, their provenance, local variations, etc. is beyond the scope <strong>of</strong><br />

today's discussion. Techniques <strong>in</strong>cluded: (1) the <strong>in</strong>terpretation <strong>of</strong> omens, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g dreams <strong>and</strong> other<br />

signs <strong>and</strong> prodigies. (2) Shamanism, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g the activities <strong>of</strong> Ch<strong>in</strong>ese wu shamans <strong>and</strong> other<br />

shaman <strong>of</strong>fice-holders <strong>and</strong> other shaman <strong>and</strong> mediums, probably <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g a fair range <strong>of</strong> practitioners<br />

at the popular level <strong>and</strong> (3) Div<strong>in</strong>ation methods. In contrast to passive receipt <strong>of</strong> omens, specific<br />

div<strong>in</strong>ation methods allowed the div<strong>in</strong>er to actively seek answers <strong>and</strong> ascerta<strong>in</strong> (or direct) the will <strong>of</strong><br />

specific deities. This range <strong>of</strong> beliefs <strong>and</strong> practices is also an important part <strong>of</strong> any Ch<strong>in</strong>ese discourse on<br />

fate <strong>and</strong> fatalism.<br />

Ch<strong>in</strong>ese techniques began with the read<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> oracle bone "cracks." Shang div<strong>in</strong>ation covered a<br />

wide variety <strong>of</strong> subject matter: sacrifice, military campaigns, hunt<strong>in</strong>g, excursions, calendrics, agriculture,<br />

weather, illness, childbirth, dreams, construction, tribute <strong>and</strong> requests for div<strong>in</strong>e or ancestral approval<br />

<strong>and</strong> assistance. 61 Other techniques <strong>of</strong> prediction <strong>and</strong> div<strong>in</strong>ation were based on "read<strong>in</strong>g" <strong>of</strong> the clouds<br />

<strong>and</strong> stars, Yi j<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> milfoil div<strong>in</strong>ation, the use <strong>of</strong> daybooks, such as those unearthed <strong>in</strong> the tombs at<br />

Shuihudi, to determ<strong>in</strong>e auspicious times for events such as marriages, campaigns, etc.; prediction <strong>of</strong><br />

19


<strong>in</strong>dividual dest<strong>in</strong>y based on physiognomy (<strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g by mothers <strong>of</strong> their children), the <strong>in</strong>terpretation <strong>of</strong><br />

dreams <strong>and</strong> anomalies <strong>in</strong> nature, geomantic techniques such as feng shui, horoscopes, div<strong>in</strong>ation<br />

boards, <strong>and</strong> the manipulation <strong>of</strong> personal names to avoid adverse fate.<br />

<strong>Greek</strong> religion also <strong>in</strong>cluded figures <strong>and</strong> techniques with special skills <strong>in</strong> div<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>and</strong> the<br />

<strong>in</strong>terpretation <strong>of</strong> signs, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g seers (mantis), omens <strong>and</strong> oracles. Some <strong>of</strong> these religious beliefs<br />

takes fate as the comm<strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> one or more deities who can be petitioned or whose will can be<br />

ascerta<strong>in</strong>ed. In this sense, belief <strong>in</strong> fate is <strong>in</strong>extricably connected with beliefs about mantic access.<br />

III. Root Metaphors<br />

There are four areas <strong>of</strong> common or contrast<strong>in</strong>g metaphors between the Ch<strong>in</strong>ese <strong>and</strong> <strong>Greek</strong><br />

semantic fields <strong>of</strong> fate: (1) <strong>Fate</strong> as div<strong>in</strong>e comm<strong>and</strong>, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>volvement <strong>of</strong> div<strong>in</strong>ities, problem <strong>of</strong> the<br />

relation <strong>of</strong> fate to the power <strong>of</strong> the gods, <strong>and</strong> the possibility <strong>of</strong> predictive div<strong>in</strong>ation; (2) <strong>Fate</strong> as division<br />

<strong>and</strong> allotment. A common metaphor <strong>of</strong> division or allotment <strong>in</strong>forms the semantic fields <strong>of</strong> both Ch<strong>in</strong>ese<br />

m<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> <strong>Greek</strong> mo›ra; (3) fate as change or constancy <strong>in</strong> nature, <strong>and</strong> (4) the figure <strong>of</strong> the sage as<br />

someone know knows how to act vis a vis fate.<br />

<strong>Fate</strong> was also a powerful trope <strong>in</strong> a wide range <strong>of</strong> literature <strong>and</strong> rhetoric. Narratives <strong>of</strong> the<br />

action <strong>of</strong> fate are prom<strong>in</strong>ent <strong>in</strong> such early canonical literature as the Homeric poems <strong>and</strong> the Classic <strong>of</strong><br />

Poetry (Shi j<strong>in</strong>g). <strong>Fate</strong> was also a potent rhetorical device <strong>in</strong> Han dynasty memorials to errant<br />

emperors <strong>and</strong> <strong>Greek</strong> tragedy. F<strong>in</strong>ally, views on fate figured as a potential limit<strong>in</strong>g factor on some<br />

technical skills (e.g. medic<strong>in</strong>e, military strategy) <strong>and</strong> as an impetus to several sciences (astronomy,<br />

medic<strong>in</strong>e).<br />

There are, however, important differences <strong>in</strong> what "work" the concept <strong>of</strong> fate did <strong>in</strong> each <strong>of</strong><br />

these areas. (1) <strong>Fate</strong> <strong>and</strong> div<strong>in</strong>e comm<strong>and</strong>. Important differences <strong>in</strong> the purpose <strong>and</strong> techniques for<br />

div<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>and</strong> availability <strong>of</strong> mantic access. (2) <strong>Fate</strong> as division. what was apportioned, by whom, to<br />

whom, <strong>and</strong> to what end differed both between <strong>and</strong> with<strong>in</strong> the two cultural contexts. (3) <strong>Fate</strong> <strong>and</strong><br />

change. Here we f<strong>in</strong>d considerably disagreement. (4) <strong>Fate</strong>, sagacity <strong>and</strong> freewill. On the <strong>Greek</strong> side we<br />

f<strong>in</strong>d metaphors <strong>of</strong> sp<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> expressions <strong>of</strong> human powerlessness. On the Ch<strong>in</strong>ese side<br />

we f<strong>in</strong>d underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> <strong>and</strong> harmony with fate (accord<strong>in</strong>g to very different formulae) as a def<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g<br />

20


characteristic <strong>of</strong> the sage.<br />

A.Metaphor <strong>of</strong> div<strong>in</strong>e comm<strong>and</strong><br />

Ch<strong>in</strong>ese metaphors concern the division <strong>and</strong> allotment <strong>of</strong> shares accord<strong>in</strong>g to the comm<strong>and</strong>s <strong>of</strong><br />

the gods (or ancestors) whose orders had the force <strong>of</strong> fate. <strong>Greek</strong> fate metaphors shifted from shares<br />

to sp<strong>in</strong>ners, who spun <strong>and</strong> bound the courses <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual human lives with the threads <strong>of</strong> fate. Other<br />

more general senses <strong>of</strong> fate, such as punishment, retribution, the fruit <strong>of</strong> past actions (<strong>in</strong> this <strong>and</strong> former<br />

lives), <strong>and</strong> more abstract notions <strong>of</strong> causality <strong>and</strong> constancy <strong>in</strong> nature, seem absent from both Ch<strong>in</strong>a <strong>and</strong><br />

Greece.<br />

B.Metaphors <strong>of</strong> division <strong>and</strong> Allotment<br />

Both M<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> moira portray fate as a lot or allotment <strong>of</strong> life span <strong>and</strong> as an autonomous<br />

power <strong>of</strong> dest<strong>in</strong>y. Both words partake <strong>of</strong> a root metaphor <strong>of</strong> division <strong>and</strong> allotment, from which it is<br />

tempt<strong>in</strong>g, but dangerous, to overgeneralize. What was apportioned, by whom, to whom, <strong>and</strong> to what<br />

end differed both between <strong>and</strong> with<strong>in</strong> the two cultural contexts. The <strong>Greek</strong>s described the moira <strong>of</strong><br />

epic heroes <strong>and</strong> dramatic figures. Homer tells us little about what commoners believed about fate. By<br />

contrast, Ch<strong>in</strong>ese m<strong>in</strong>g appears <strong>in</strong> discussions <strong>of</strong> the lives <strong>of</strong> commoners, as soldiers flee<strong>in</strong>g battle or as<br />

ord<strong>in</strong>ary people try<strong>in</strong>g to live out their lifespans undisturbed; some are even attributed to the commoners<br />

themselves, albeit <strong>in</strong> texts <strong>of</strong> elite authorship.<br />

C.<strong>Fate</strong> <strong>and</strong> change<br />

The specific association <strong>of</strong> fate with <strong>in</strong>evitable change <strong>in</strong> the universe seems particular to the<br />

pre-Buddhist Ch<strong>in</strong>ese accounts, where fate or allotment <strong>in</strong>cludes life span, wealth <strong>and</strong> fortune <strong>in</strong><br />

explicitly chang<strong>in</strong>g times. <strong>Fate</strong> <strong>in</strong> this sense may apply to <strong>in</strong>dividuals, families, nations, empires or<br />

polities. By contrast, Parmenides uses fate as a metaphor for the specifically unchang<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> immobile<br />

nature <strong>of</strong> "what-is." Other <strong>Greek</strong> th<strong>in</strong>kers associated change with the action <strong>of</strong> fate (<strong>in</strong> association with<br />

justice, necessity <strong>and</strong> retribution), but <strong>in</strong> rhetorical <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>tellectual contexts very different from the<br />

Ch<strong>in</strong>ese. Anaxim<strong>and</strong>er describes a balance between com<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>to <strong>and</strong> pass<strong>in</strong>g out <strong>of</strong> be<strong>in</strong>g based on<br />

necessity <strong>and</strong> mutual "penalty <strong>and</strong> retribution" (d¤khn ka‹ t¤s<strong>in</strong>), but it is based, not on fate, but on<br />

"the assessment <strong>of</strong> time" (katå t∞n toË xrÒnou tãj<strong>in</strong>, KR 103, DK 12A9). Heraclitus speaks <strong>of</strong><br />

all th<strong>in</strong>gs "undergo<strong>in</strong>g alteration" (élloioËtai) <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> even the sun be<strong>in</strong>g subject to the retribution <strong>of</strong><br />

21


the <strong>Fate</strong>s, the h<strong>and</strong>maidens <strong>of</strong> Dike, but his focus is the <strong>in</strong>tegrity <strong>of</strong> the order <strong>of</strong> nature <strong>and</strong> the physical<br />

world (KR 207 <strong>and</strong> 229, DK 22B90 <strong>and</strong> 94). References to the action <strong>of</strong> fate or justice became part<br />

<strong>of</strong> the rhetoric <strong>of</strong> appeals to Nature (fÊsiw), expressed <strong>in</strong> legal <strong>and</strong> moral language, that appealed to a<br />

wide range <strong>of</strong> fifth-century <strong>Greek</strong>s. These were used to justify diverse positions. 62 Pre-Buddhist<br />

Ch<strong>in</strong>ese accounts, by contrast, <strong>in</strong>clude but do not emphasize notions <strong>of</strong> causality <strong>and</strong> constancy <strong>in</strong><br />

nature.<br />

D.<strong>Fate</strong> <strong>and</strong> sagacity, or <strong>Fate</strong> <strong>and</strong> Fatalism<br />

This prelim<strong>in</strong>ary Ch<strong>in</strong>ese <strong>and</strong> <strong>Greek</strong> evidence suggests some common notions <strong>of</strong> fate, but very<br />

different attitudes toward fatalism. Pre-Buddhist Ch<strong>in</strong>ese accounts comb<strong>in</strong>e acceptance <strong>of</strong> fate with<br />

strong antifatalism <strong>and</strong> well developed notions <strong>of</strong> strategy or maneuver<strong>in</strong>g room with<strong>in</strong> its decrees. Life<br />

span may be fated, but with<strong>in</strong> it, free will reigns. Change <strong>and</strong> resilience are the order <strong>of</strong> the day <strong>and</strong><br />

open to human strategy <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>genuity. A wide range <strong>of</strong> texts stress the importance <strong>of</strong> timel<strong>in</strong>ess (shi )<br />

<strong>and</strong> configuration or "setup" (shi ) <strong>in</strong> response to one's times <strong>and</strong> to one's fate. Thus longevity <strong>and</strong><br />

good auspice were fated <strong>and</strong> unknowable, but could be cherished <strong>and</strong> cultivated through knowledge<br />

<strong>and</strong> sagacity. In this sense, both the Zhuangzi <strong>and</strong> the Xunzi take "strategic" attitudes toward<br />

omnipresent m<strong>in</strong>g.<br />

<strong>Greek</strong> accounts <strong>of</strong> fate conta<strong>in</strong> a significant fatalist element. <strong>Greek</strong> fates were variously<br />

personified: as Moira, the Moirai, the power <strong>of</strong> Themis or Dike, as the will <strong>of</strong> Zeus or the activity <strong>of</strong><br />

daimons. These div<strong>in</strong>ities alternatively hold fate <strong>in</strong> their power <strong>and</strong> coexisted with an autonomous<br />

"fate" beyond their control. The decrees <strong>and</strong> comm<strong>and</strong>s <strong>of</strong> these div<strong>in</strong>ities <strong>and</strong> div<strong>in</strong>e agencies were<br />

consistently portrayed as fixed, b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>exorable.<br />

22


Summary Table<br />

Greece Ch<strong>in</strong>a<br />

SIMILARITIES<br />

1) Div<strong>in</strong>e comm<strong>and</strong>/m<strong>and</strong>ate 1) Div<strong>in</strong>e comm<strong>and</strong>/m<strong>and</strong>ate<br />

mantic access restricted wide range <strong>of</strong> techniques for mantic access<br />

2) Apportionment <strong>and</strong> division 2) Apportionment: <strong>and</strong> division<br />

<strong>of</strong> lots <strong>and</strong> chance subject to change <strong>and</strong> transformation<br />

life <strong>and</strong> death <strong>in</strong> battle, the "lots" <strong>of</strong> heroes the "full" span <strong>of</strong> life fated at birth<br />

daimons as "sharers" attribute <strong>of</strong> persons, times, places, states<br />

DIFFERENCES<br />

3) <strong>Fate</strong> <strong>and</strong> change 3) <strong>Fate</strong> <strong>and</strong> change<br />

Parmenides' l<strong>in</strong>kage <strong>of</strong> fate with unchang<strong>in</strong>g Ch<strong>in</strong>ese l<strong>in</strong>kage <strong>of</strong> fate with change<br />

4) fate, sagacity <strong>and</strong> freewill 4) fate, sagacity <strong>and</strong> freewill<br />

metaphor <strong>of</strong> sp<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g problem <strong>of</strong> sagacity<br />

human powerlessness object <strong>of</strong> underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> mastery<br />

discourse on free will <strong>and</strong> Dios boule discourse on sagacity<br />

23


Bibliography<br />

Aust<strong>in</strong>, Scott. 1986. Parmenides: Be<strong>in</strong>g, Bounds <strong>and</strong> Logic. New Haven: Yale University Press.<br />

Bernste<strong>in</strong>, Mark H 1992. Fatalism. L<strong>in</strong>coln: University <strong>of</strong> Nebraska Press.<br />

Bobzien, Susanne. 1998. Determ<strong>in</strong>ism <strong>and</strong> Freedom <strong>in</strong> Stoic Philosophy. Oxford: Clarendon<br />

Press.<br />

Burkert, Walter. 1977. <strong>Greek</strong> Religion. Translated by John Raffan, London: Basil Blackwell, 1985.<br />

Chen, N<strong>in</strong>g. 1994. Concepts <strong>of</strong> <strong>Fate</strong> <strong>in</strong> Ancient Ch<strong>in</strong>a. Ph.D. Dissertation. University <strong>of</strong><br />

Pittsburgh.<br />

Chiang, Ted. 1999. "Story <strong>of</strong> Your Life." In The Year's Best Science Fiction: Sixteenth Annual<br />

Collection, ed. Gardner Dozois. New York: St. Mart<strong>in</strong>'s Press.<br />

Detienne, Marcel, <strong>and</strong> Jean-Pierre Vernant. 1978. Cunn<strong>in</strong>g Intelligence <strong>in</strong> <strong>Greek</strong> Culture <strong>and</strong><br />

Society, trans. Janet Lloyd. Atlantic Highl<strong>and</strong>s, NJ: Humanities Press.<br />

Eliade, Mircea, editor <strong>in</strong> chief. The Encyclopedia <strong>of</strong> Religion. 1987. editors, Charles J. Adams et al.<br />

New York: Macmillan; London: Collier Macmillan. pp. 290-98<br />

Fu S<strong>in</strong>ian . 1952. "X<strong>in</strong>gm<strong>in</strong>g gushun bianzheng" [Analysis <strong>of</strong> Ancient Views<br />

<strong>of</strong> X<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> M<strong>in</strong>g]. <strong>in</strong> Fu Mengzhen xian sheng ji vol 3. Taibei.<br />

Giddens, Anthony. 1990. The Consequences <strong>of</strong> Modernity. Stanford, CA: Stanford University<br />

Press.<br />

Graham, Angus. C. 1978. Later Mohist Logic, Ethics <strong>and</strong> Science. Hong Kong: Ch<strong>in</strong>ese University<br />

Press, <strong>and</strong> London: School <strong>of</strong> Oriental <strong>and</strong> African Studies.<br />

Graham, Angus. C. 1981. Chuang-tzu: The Inner Chapters. London: George Allen & Unw<strong>in</strong>; Unw<strong>in</strong><br />

paperbacks.<br />

Greene, William Chace. 1944. Moira: <strong>Fate</strong>, Good, <strong>and</strong> Evil <strong>in</strong> <strong>Greek</strong> Thought. Cambridge Mass:<br />

Harvard University Press.<br />

Guthrie, W. K. C. 1962-1981. A History <strong>of</strong> <strong>Greek</strong> Philosophy. Vols. 1-6, Cambridge: Cambridge<br />

University Press.<br />

Hast<strong>in</strong>gs, James, with John A. Selbie <strong>and</strong> Louis H. Gray. 1961. Encyclopaedia <strong>of</strong> Religion <strong>and</strong><br />

Ethics. New York : Scribner. Orig<strong>in</strong>al edition 1875, revised editions 1955 <strong>and</strong> 1961.<br />

Irw<strong>in</strong>, Terence. 1989. A History <strong>of</strong> Western Philosophy I: Classical Thought. Oxford: Oxford<br />

University Press.<br />

Jaeger, Werner. 1939. Paideia: The Ideals <strong>of</strong> <strong>Greek</strong> Culture. Translated by Gilbert Hight. 3 vols.<br />

New York: Oxford University Press, 1939; 2nd edition, with notes, l945; paperback rpt. l973.<br />

Jullien, François. 1995. The Propensity <strong>of</strong> Th<strong>in</strong>gs: Toward a History <strong>of</strong> Efficacy <strong>in</strong> Ch<strong>in</strong>a.<br />

Translated by Janet Lloyd. New York: Zone Books. Orig<strong>in</strong>ally published as La propension des<br />

24


choses: Pour une histoire de l'efficacité en Ch<strong>in</strong>e. Paris: Editions du Seuil, 1992.<br />

Keightley, David N. 1978. Sources <strong>of</strong> Shang history: the Oracle-bone Inscriptions <strong>of</strong> Bronze Age<br />

Ch<strong>in</strong>a. Berkeley; Los Angeles: University <strong>of</strong> California Press.<br />

Lak<strong>of</strong>f, George <strong>and</strong> Mark Johnson. 1980. Metaphors We Live By. Chicago: University <strong>of</strong> Chicago<br />

Press.<br />

Lloyd, G.E.R. 1996. Adversaries <strong>and</strong> Authorities: Investigations <strong>in</strong>to ancient <strong>Greek</strong> <strong>and</strong> Ch<strong>in</strong>ese<br />

science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.<br />

Lü Shi chunqiu (LSCQ) [Spr<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>and</strong> Autumns <strong>of</strong> Master Lü] SBBY.<br />

Mozi y<strong>in</strong>de (Mo) [A Concordance to the Mozi]. Shanghai: Guji chubanshe, 1982.<br />

Poo, Mu-chou. 1998. In Search <strong>of</strong> Personal Welfare: A View <strong>of</strong> Ancient Ch<strong>in</strong>ese Religion. New<br />

York: State University <strong>of</strong> New York Press.<br />

Raphals, Lisa 1992. Know<strong>in</strong>g Words: Wisdom <strong>and</strong> Cunn<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> the Classical Traditions <strong>of</strong> Ch<strong>in</strong>a<br />

<strong>and</strong> Greece. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.<br />

Red<strong>in</strong>g, Jean-Paul. 1996. "Light <strong>and</strong> the Mirror: Elements <strong>of</strong> Comparative Metaphorology. Paper<br />

Presented at the Association for Asian Studies, Honolulu, Hawai'i, April 11-14, 1996.<br />

Red<strong>in</strong>g, Jean-Paul. 1997. "L'Utilisation Philosophique de la Métaphore en Grèce et en Ch<strong>in</strong>e." Revue<br />

de Théologie et de Philosophie 129:1-30.<br />

Rescher, Nicholas. 1995. Luck: the Brilliant R<strong>and</strong>omness <strong>of</strong> Everyday Life New York : Farrar,<br />

Straus <strong>and</strong> Giroux, 1995.<br />

Ruan Yuan . "X<strong>in</strong>g m<strong>in</strong>g gu xun." [X<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> M<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> the Ancient Classics] Yanj<strong>in</strong>gshi<br />

ji, vol. 10. SBCK.<br />

Shang shu zhengyi (Shu j<strong>in</strong>g) Shisan j<strong>in</strong>g zhushu .<br />

Tang Junyi . 1957. "Xian Q<strong>in</strong> sixiang zhong zhi tian m<strong>in</strong>g guan."<br />

[The concept <strong>of</strong> tian m<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> Pre-Ch'<strong>in</strong> Ch<strong>in</strong>a.] X<strong>in</strong>ya xuebao 2.2:1-33.<br />

Tang Junyi . 1962. "The Tien-m<strong>in</strong>g (Heavenly Ord<strong>in</strong>ance) <strong>in</strong> Pre-Ch'<strong>in</strong> Ch<strong>in</strong>a." Philosophy<br />

East & West 11 (1962): 195-218.<br />

Tang Junyi . 1963. "The Tien-m<strong>in</strong>g (Heavenly Ord<strong>in</strong>ance) <strong>in</strong> Pre-Ch'<strong>in</strong> Ch<strong>in</strong>a." Philosophy<br />

East & West 12 (1963) 29-42.<br />

Topley, Marjorie. 1973. "Cosmic Antagonisms: A Mother-Child Syndrome." In Religion <strong>and</strong> Ritual<br />

<strong>in</strong> Ch<strong>in</strong>ese Society. Arthur P. Wolf, ed. Stanford: Stanford University Press, pp. 233-49.<br />

Von Falkenhausen, Lothar. 1999. Review <strong>of</strong> Mu-chou Poo's In Search <strong>of</strong> Personal Welfare: A<br />

View <strong>of</strong> Ancient Ch<strong>in</strong>ese Religion. Havard Journal <strong>of</strong> Asiatic Studies 59.2 (December 1999):<br />

598-613.<br />

Xia Lu . 1980. "Buci zhong de tian, shen, m<strong>in</strong>g." [Tian, Sheng <strong>and</strong><br />

25


M<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> Oracle Bone Inscriptions]. Wuhan daxue xuebao no 2.<br />

Xunzi y<strong>in</strong>de (X). Shanghai: Guji chubanshe, 1986.<br />

Zhuangzi y<strong>in</strong>de (Zz) . Shanghai: Guji chubanshe, 1982.<br />

26


1 Chiang 1999, pp. 314-15.<br />

2 Chiang 1999, p. 327.<br />

3 Chiang 1999, p. 329.<br />

4 Chiang 1999, pp. 330-32.<br />

5 Cf. Hast<strong>in</strong>gs, Selbie <strong>and</strong> Gray 1961, p. 774.<br />

6 Giddens 1990, p. 29-31.<br />

7 Bernste<strong>in</strong> 1992, p. 1.<br />

8 Lloyd 1996:3-6.<br />

9 See Lak<strong>of</strong>f <strong>and</strong> Johnson 1980 (on metaphor) <strong>and</strong> Red<strong>in</strong>g 1996 <strong>and</strong> 1997 (on Ch<strong>in</strong>ese<br />

metaphorology).<br />

10 See François Jullien's (1995) study <strong>of</strong> Ch<strong>in</strong>ese notions <strong>of</strong> efficacy.<br />

11 Cf. Xia Lu 1980.<br />

12 Cf. Chen, 1994 144. Chen argues that there was not yet a belief <strong>in</strong> fixed fate, despite modern <strong>and</strong><br />

Zhou accounts.<br />

13 X 103/28/39<br />

14 Zz 6:241. Translations are my own unless otherwise specified. I use both the terms decree <strong>and</strong> fate<br />

to translate m<strong>in</strong>g, to avoid <strong>in</strong>troduc<strong>in</strong>g a k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> crypto-fatalism <strong>in</strong>to the texts.<br />

15 Zz 29:998<br />

16 X 55/15/60<br />

17 Zz 4:160<br />

18 Shang shu, Zhou shu, Pr<strong>in</strong>ce Shi (16):18b-19a, cf. Legge 475-7. Cf. Tang Junyi 1962:199.<br />

19 Cf. Zz 16:555, Zz 17:596<br />

20 Xunzi 58/16/4 (Strengthen<strong>in</strong>g the State, Jiang guo) <strong>and</strong> 64/17/43 (Discourse on Heaven, Tian lun)<br />

21 The formless had allotments (fen ) but they were still not divided out, <strong>and</strong> they were called decrees<br />

(m<strong>in</strong>g, Zz 12:424).<br />

22 X 83/22/6<br />

23 Zz 5:189. Graham (1986, p. 76) takes m<strong>in</strong>g as nam<strong>in</strong>g rather than as order<strong>in</strong>g dest<strong>in</strong>y: "he does his<br />

own nam<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the transformations <strong>of</strong> th<strong>in</strong>gs".<br />

24 Zz 14:532<br />

25 Zz 5:212<br />

26 Tang Junyi 1957:1-2 <strong>and</strong> 1962:196-7.<br />

27


27 Xunzi 9/4/21. .<br />

28 Zz 27:958. The translation <strong>of</strong> this passage depends on whether we read <strong>and</strong> as<br />

referr<strong>in</strong>g to the cycles <strong>of</strong> heaven <strong>and</strong> earth described earlier <strong>in</strong> the passage or to the span <strong>of</strong> human lives.<br />

I have taken it <strong>in</strong> the former sense. In the latter sense the passage would read: "S<strong>in</strong>ce we do not know<br />

our ends, how can we say we are not fated [to die]; s<strong>in</strong>ce we do not know how we began, how can we<br />

say we are fated?"<br />

29 Note also zheng m<strong>in</strong>g at 7A/2<br />

30 Tang Junyi 1957:1. This formulation is Tang Junyi's. I can f<strong>in</strong>d no <strong>in</strong>stance <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong> the Zhuangzi,<br />

despite several concordance searches. Shun m<strong>in</strong>g is discussed below.<br />

31 Cf. Tang Junyi 1957:1-2 <strong>and</strong> 1962:196-7.<br />

32 49/Shuo/1.<br />

33 Zz 19:630<br />

34 Zz 30:1059 /<br />

35 Zz 19:657-8<br />

36 Zz 25:880<br />

37 Zz 14:507. . Note also: "People<br />

who do not follow their dest<strong>in</strong>ies distort their natural abilities <strong>and</strong> ru<strong>in</strong> their lives" (Zz 19:663).<br />

38 X 7/3/30<br />

39 The schema is <strong>in</strong>debted to, but not identical to the first major twentieth-century study on the subject<br />

by Fu S<strong>in</strong>ian, which classified Warr<strong>in</strong>g States views <strong>of</strong> fate <strong>in</strong>to five compet<strong>in</strong>g doctr<strong>in</strong>es. In her<br />

discussion <strong>of</strong> these, Michael Nylan (1993) restates <strong>and</strong> modfies Fu's schema. My discussion is<br />

<strong>in</strong>debted to both. Unlike Fu or Nylan, my account focuses on the issue <strong>of</strong> predeterm<strong>in</strong>ation, on which,<br />

more later.<br />

40 Tang 1962: 196-7.<br />

41 Tang 197-8.<br />

42 Fu S<strong>in</strong>ian 1952:305-8.<br />

43 Mo 79/46/20-21. Mozi, Names <strong>and</strong> Objects 16 (Graham 1978, p. 489-90). The Lü Shi chunqiu<br />

chapter "Liv<strong>in</strong>g Out One's Lot" (J<strong>in</strong> shu ) provides an apt example <strong>of</strong> this argument It describes<br />

how sages use knowledge <strong>of</strong> y<strong>in</strong> <strong>and</strong> yang to underst<strong>and</strong> what benefits the myriad creatures <strong>and</strong> live<br />

out their allotted lifespans, without either augment<strong>in</strong>g or cutt<strong>in</strong>g them <strong>of</strong>f (LSCQ 3.2, pp. 3b-5a).<br />

44 Far East Ch<strong>in</strong>ese-English Dictionary, p. 424<br />

45 Far East Ch<strong>in</strong>ese-English Dictionary, p. 424<br />

46 These themes appear consistently <strong>in</strong> treatments <strong>of</strong> the subject <strong>in</strong> Classics (e.g. Greene 1944), history<br />

<strong>of</strong> philosophy (Guthrie 1962-81 passim <strong>and</strong> Irw<strong>in</strong> 1989:16, 157, 171 <strong>and</strong> 180) <strong>and</strong> religion (Burkert<br />

28


1977:129-30).<br />

47 These <strong>in</strong>clude Themis or Dike (In addition to their later roles as deities <strong>of</strong> Justice <strong>and</strong> Punishment,<br />

Dike is associated with an orderly flow <strong>of</strong> time, as is Moira with the orderly division <strong>of</strong> space) <strong>and</strong><br />

éνãγκη (Necessity), revealed by oracles, omens, prodigies <strong>and</strong> signs.<br />

48 For Parmenides' dates see Guthrie II, pp. 1-2, based on Plato's (Parm 127a-c) description <strong>of</strong> a<br />

meet<strong>in</strong>g between the old Parmenides <strong>and</strong> the young Socrates. For the <strong>in</strong>quiry concern<strong>in</strong>g nature see<br />

Lloyd 1987, pp. 1-4 <strong>and</strong> 38-49. Conspicuously absent from this prelim<strong>in</strong>ary study are medical <strong>and</strong><br />

other scientific works. For discussion <strong>of</strong> fate as an area <strong>of</strong> speculation that <strong>of</strong>fers "some <strong>of</strong> the greatest<br />

problems for, or the maximum resistance to, any scientific takeover," see Lloyd 1987, pp. 4 <strong>and</strong> 38-49.<br />

As he po<strong>in</strong>ts out, much <strong>of</strong> the discourse on prediction <strong>in</strong> medic<strong>in</strong>e <strong>and</strong> astronomy concerned prognosis<br />

<strong>of</strong> the course <strong>of</strong> disease or the prediction <strong>of</strong> the positions <strong>of</strong> the sun, moon <strong>and</strong> planets. These<br />

predictions did not significantly <strong>in</strong>volve the operative notions <strong>of</strong> fate.<br />

49 Demosthenes (On the Halonnesus 7.40) refers to a piece <strong>of</strong> l<strong>and</strong> as "no man's l<strong>and</strong>" (émmor¤ow).<br />

50 Of the 101 <strong>in</strong>stances <strong>of</strong> mo›ra <strong>in</strong> the Iliad <strong>and</strong> Odyssey, only one is <strong>in</strong> the phrase huper moiran.<br />

Uper aisan occurs five times out <strong>of</strong> 40 <strong>in</strong>stances <strong>of</strong> aisa.<br />

51 Detienne <strong>and</strong> Vernant 1978. For "metic <strong>in</strong>telligence" <strong>in</strong> Ch<strong>in</strong>a see Raphals 1992.<br />

52 For example, at the marriage <strong>of</strong> Peleus <strong>and</strong> Thetis <strong>and</strong> Zeus <strong>and</strong> Themis.<br />

53 Parmenides also wrote <strong>in</strong> Homeric hexameter <strong>and</strong> began his poem, <strong>in</strong> the Homeric manner, with a<br />

claim for div<strong>in</strong>e <strong>in</strong>spiration.<br />

54 Greene 1944, p. 12.<br />

55 For other examples see Il. 9.600 <strong>and</strong> Od. 3.166, 5.396, <strong>and</strong> 12.295<br />

56 Guthrie considers the daimon to be Helios, the sun, Aust<strong>in</strong> takes her as "the goddess."<br />

57 For discussion See Aust<strong>in</strong> 156-57 <strong>and</strong> Guthrie vol. 2, pp. 7-9.<br />

58 e.g. Il. 1.5, Od. 11.297<br />

59 Irw<strong>in</strong> 1989, pp. 16-17.<br />

60 Poo 3ff.<br />

61 Keightley 1978, pp. 33-35.<br />

62 Accord<strong>in</strong>g to Greene (1944, p. 228), these <strong>in</strong>cluded naive <strong>in</strong>dividualists, super-patriots (<strong>in</strong> defense <strong>of</strong><br />

the state's right to exist), democrats (<strong>in</strong> defense <strong>of</strong> the status quo), aristocrats (<strong>in</strong> defense <strong>of</strong> a<br />

reactionary coup), <strong>and</strong> the Athenian empire itself (<strong>in</strong> defense <strong>of</strong> the conscription <strong>of</strong> Melian neutrals).<br />

29

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!