12.07.2015 Views

is discontinuous bergsonism possible? - Agathos: An International ...

is discontinuous bergsonism possible? - Agathos: An International ...

is discontinuous bergsonism possible? - Agathos: An International ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

IS DISCONTINUOUS BERGSONISM POSSIBLE?TERESA CASTELÃO-LAWLESS ∗Abstract: Gaston Bachelard’s position toward the philosophy of HenriBergson <strong>is</strong> most interesting. In La Dialectique de la durée (1936), Bachelardclaims that “of Bergson<strong>is</strong>m we accept everything but continuity” and that therest of h<strong>is</strong> book will be an attempt to show the possibility of a “d<strong>is</strong>continuousBergson<strong>is</strong>m”. In th<strong>is</strong> paper, I focus on the reaction of Bachelard to works ofBergson such as the Essai sur les données immédiates de la conscience(1889), L’Evolution créatrice (1907), and Durée et simultanéité: à propos dela théorie d’Einstein (1922) and demonstrate that even though the conditionsnecessary for the possibility of a d<strong>is</strong>continuous Bergson<strong>is</strong>m are not the sameones which Bachelard had in mind when he accepted most of Bergson<strong>is</strong>m,their phenomenologies of the scientific spirit were analogous.Keywords: continuity, d<strong>is</strong>continuity, ep<strong>is</strong>temology, scientific creativity,metaphysics, nature of science, nature of physical reality.French ep<strong>is</strong>temolog<strong>is</strong>t Gaston Bachelard (1884-1962) could nothave escaped confronting h<strong>is</strong> philosophy of science with thephilosophy of Henri Bergson (1859-1941). Bachelard’s first book, theEssai sur la conna<strong>is</strong>sance approchée,1 appeared in 1927, the yearBergson received the Nobel Prize for Literature. By then, Bergson hadbeen part of the intellectual landscape of France for almost twodecades. Bergson’s Essai sur les données immédiates de la consciencehad come out in 1889; h<strong>is</strong> “new metaphysics” had been publ<strong>is</strong>hed bythe Revue de métaphysique et de morale in 1903 and in L’Evolutioncréatrice in 1907; and h<strong>is</strong> interpretation of Einstein’s relativity inDurée et simultanéité in 1922 had sparked much controversy in the∗Teresa Castelão-Lawless <strong>is</strong> Ph.D. Professor, Department of Philosophy, GrandValley State University, MI, USA. E-mail: Castelat@gvsu.edu1 Bachelard’s doctoral thes<strong>is</strong>


26 AGATHOS: <strong>An</strong> <strong>International</strong> Review of the Humanities and Social Sciencesacademic community. Bergson had scient<strong>is</strong>ts and intellectuals takingsides on h<strong>is</strong> position regarding the boundaries of science andmetaphysics. He had supporters in Lou<strong>is</strong> de Broglie but detractors inHenri Poincaré, Albert Einstein, and Léon Brunschvicg. The dividewas also sociological, since it coincided with the “competing currentsof philosophical thought and practice in the French universities”2. Forinstance, at the Sorbonne, Le Roy was combining in h<strong>is</strong> courses thephilosophies of Bergson and Poincaré, thus reducing science to asystem of practical conventions, whereas Brunschvicg was doing justthe opposite in order to protect scientific real<strong>is</strong>m against what heperceived as Bergson’s “irrational<strong>is</strong>m”(Chim<strong>is</strong>so 1997, 4-5). Thesefacts were probably enough to motivate Bachelard’s curiosity. Notonly does he mention Bergson in all of h<strong>is</strong> works on ep<strong>is</strong>temology, hedevotes two books to Bergson’s philosophy, L’Intuition de l’instant(1932) and La Dialectique de la durée (1936). These titles suggest thatBachelard opposed Bergson<strong>is</strong>m for, according to h<strong>is</strong> own view,intuition was not composed of instants and duration was notdialectical.Scholars have taken Bachelard’s critic<strong>is</strong>m of Bergson’s philosophyof continuity at face value. Th<strong>is</strong> <strong>is</strong> because it seemed to them that ad<strong>is</strong>continu<strong>is</strong>t philosopher such as Bachelard had necessarily to rejectnot only continuity but Bergson<strong>is</strong>m altogether with it. Myinterpretation diverges from th<strong>is</strong> view. It shows that Bachelardaccepted continuity, with the prov<strong>is</strong>o that it was continuity of scientificexplanation rather than in physical reality, and that Bergson’s andBachelard’s phenomenologies of the mind are analogous.BERGSON AND BACHELARD ON FLEXIBLECONCEPTUALIZATIONBachelard quickly detected the need to accommodate thevocabulary of philosophy to the new sciences in light of their newrequirement that scientific concepts be as flexible and mobile as thedialectical mind which produces them, and which demonstrate atdifferent times and in different situations an alternation betweenrational<strong>is</strong>m and empiric<strong>is</strong>m, continuity and d<strong>is</strong>continuity. He knew2 See Cr<strong>is</strong>tina Chim<strong>is</strong>so’s “Introduction” to The Dialectics of Duration, p. 4. See alsoTeresa Castelão-Lawless, “Gaston Bachelard et le milieu scientifique et intellectuelfrança<strong>is</strong>”, in Nouvel, Pascal (dir.) 1997. Actualité et postérités de Gaston Bachelard.Par<strong>is</strong>: Presses Universitaires de France, pp.101-115


AGATHOS: <strong>An</strong> <strong>International</strong> Review of the Humanities and Social Sciences 27that, especially at the level of quantum mechanics, there wereambiguities in the act of knowing and that one had to replace causalityfor uncertainty and probability. He also claimed that philosophy wasphilosophy or metaphysics of science only3.Bergson too was very critical of empiric<strong>is</strong>m and rational<strong>is</strong>m. Bothof these metaphysics of science could lead one into falsely believingthat “by putting together all the diagrams [we] can reconstitute theobject itself”4. He thought that traditional philosophy had made one toconfuse real problems with lingu<strong>is</strong>tic fallacies, symbols with reality,and to think that symbols represented reality instead of fragments of it.Bergson also wanted to demonstrate that, even though science andmetaphysics are complementary and ought to cross paths at somepoint, they should nevertheless be kept demarcated on grounds ofintention and purpose, on what level of reality they were expected tograsp, and on the methodologies that were used to approachqualitatively different perceptions and levels of reality. In fact, he said,“if consciousness has to split up into intuition and intelligence, it <strong>is</strong>because of the need it had to apply itself to matter at the same time asit had to follow the stream of life. The double form of consciousness <strong>is</strong>due to the double form of the real”5. He had claimed since the Essa<strong>is</strong>ur les données immédiates de la conscience (1889) that ourintelligence grasped “artificial” reality analytically and scientifically,while our intuition grasped “real” reality psychologically andmetaphysically. Physical science gave us knowledge that was practicalfor life and for the study of “dead matter.” But th<strong>is</strong> knowledge was acontrived, static construct of reality in its dynamic completeness. Itwas a m<strong>is</strong>take to expect mechanic<strong>is</strong>t science to be readily capable ofgiving us access to the essence of things. Dialectic was to Bergson anincomplete, fractured tool of analys<strong>is</strong>. It only captured in fragments, asin a “still movie,” a reality and a mind which were in constant flux.To Bergson, metaphysics, if properly used, would give us glimpsesof a reality which tended to escape rational categorization. For th<strong>is</strong> tohappen, we needed to keep our intellectual habits from creating staticimages of duration, such as imagining time as moving in a linearspatial trajectory as it was described abstractly in science, instead of3 Bachelard’s ep<strong>is</strong>temology kept with the French tradition of combining h<strong>is</strong>tory andphilosophy of science4 Henri Bergson (2007). <strong>An</strong> Introduction to Metaphysics. New York: PalgraveMacmillan, p.215 Henri Bergson (1944). Creative Evolution. New York: The Modern Library, p.196


28 AGATHOS: <strong>An</strong> <strong>International</strong> Review of the Humanities and Social Sciencesthe real, concrete time given by intuitive consciousness (Bergson1944,196) . Th<strong>is</strong> was an extremely difficult task. As Bergson pointedout in the Essai, “all dynamic representation <strong>is</strong> d<strong>is</strong>tasteful to reflectiveconsciousness”.6 However, “concepts are necessary [to reachintuition], for all the other sciences work as a rule with concepts, andmetaphysics cannot d<strong>is</strong>pense with other sciences. But it <strong>is</strong> only trulyitself when it goes beyond the concept, or at least when it frees itselffrom rigid and ready-made concepts in order to create a kind verydifferent from those which we habitually use; I mean, supple, mobile,and almost fluid representations”(Bergson 2007, 13). Later in the text,he adds, “Shall we say, then, that duration has unity? Doubtless, acontinuity of elements which prolong themselves into one anotherparticipates in unity as much as in multiplicity….shall we concludethat duration must be defined as unity and multiplicity at the sametime? (…) when I replace myself in duration by an effort of intuition, Iimmediately perceive how it <strong>is</strong> unity, multiplicity, and many otherthings besides. These different concepts, then, were only so manystandpoints from which we could consider duration. Neither separatednor reunited have they made us penetrate it.”(Bergson 2007, 14-15)The mind does fragment reality into dual<strong>is</strong>ms like unity andmultiplicity, continuity and d<strong>is</strong>continuity, real<strong>is</strong>m and ideal<strong>is</strong>m, but italso makes the m<strong>is</strong>take of mixing qualitatively different ones, such aswhen we “make time into a representation imbued with space”7.These passages in Bergson’s texts about metaphysics showinteresting points of intersection with Bachelard’s ep<strong>is</strong>temology ofscience. For, while Bergson was describing the metaphysical functionof thinking and Bachelard talked about the metaphysics of appliedrational<strong>is</strong>m, they referred in similar terms to the value ofrepresentation, to how the mind works, and to what ought to happen tothe shelf-life of concepts. In other words, Bachelard believed that thecapacity for concepts to be flexible testified to their adaptability to aconstantly moving, probabil<strong>is</strong>tic scientific reality and to the dynamicof the scientific spirit in its creative activity, whereas Bergson requiredconceptual flexibility and a variety of standpoints for us to be able tograsp dynamic reality and dynamic consciousness intuitively. Thus, ifBachelard defended conceptual fluidity in good science and the6 Henri Bergson (1889). Essai sur les données immédiates de la conscience. Par<strong>is</strong>:P.U.F, p.77 Gilles Deleuze (1991). Bergson<strong>is</strong>m. New York: Zone Books, p.22


AGATHOS: <strong>An</strong> <strong>International</strong> Review of the Humanities and Social Sciences 29mobility of the mind to adjust to whatever level of reality one wasdealing with, and Bergson defended conceptual flexibility and themobility of the mind to grasp the flux of reality, then they both wouldhave to agree that either continuity or d<strong>is</strong>continuity were incompleteconceptualizations of reality. They also would have to agree thatsometimes there was unity, sometimes d<strong>is</strong>unity, and sometimesmultiplicity in the knowledge of nature and of the self. The same textsof Bergson testify to the fact that he was not without furtherqualification “the philosopher of continuity.” To Bergson, labelingduration a simple “continuity” would be an error, for th<strong>is</strong> would beattempting to conceptualize that which could not be conceptualized atall. As Bergson had said when referring to the study of consciousness,“the inner life <strong>is</strong> all of th<strong>is</strong> at once: variety of qualities, continuity ofprogress, and unity of direction. It cannot be represented by images,and it <strong>is</strong> even less <strong>possible</strong> to represent it by concepts” (Bergson 2007,10).We could still claim that a reason for Bachelard’s critic<strong>is</strong>m ofBergson’s philosophy of continuity was because they defined“intuition” differently. To Bergson, intuition was metaphysicalthinking,8 something that we ought to encourage in ourselves so thatwe could both access immaterial reality and be able to understand theoperations of consciousness. It seems that Bachelard would not agreewith th<strong>is</strong>, since to him intuitions had to be d<strong>is</strong>couraged in sciencebecause they were an ep<strong>is</strong>temological obstacle to its development.However, th<strong>is</strong> <strong>is</strong> not all that Bachelard had to say about intuition. In LaDialectique de la durée he admitted that, besides those “negative”intuitions which were “at the root of our concepts”, “positive”intuitions had an important role in science, since they could “putconcepts together: these essentially secondary intuitions (…) arewrongly thought to be artificial and poor.” They too have an importantrole in the scientific enterpr<strong>is</strong>e.9 Furthermore, Bergson would notd<strong>is</strong>agree with Bachelard that there should be no place for “negative”intuitions in science, for he too claimed that physical science ought to8 Henri Bergson (1938). La Pensée et le mouvant. Par<strong>is</strong>: P.U.F., p.2169 G.Bachelard (2000). The Dialectic of Duration (1950). Manchester: ClinamenPress, p.30. The role given to “irrational” judgments of value which cannot bearticulated lingu<strong>is</strong>tically but are essential to scientific theory assessment and intheory choice receives an incomparably better treatment in works such as MichaelPolanyi’s Personal Knowledge: Towards a Post-Critical Philosophy. Chicago: TheUniversity of Chicago Press, 1958


30 AGATHOS: <strong>An</strong> <strong>International</strong> Review of the Humanities and Social Sciencesbe the product of intelligence only and not of metaphysics. In fact,Bergson affirmed that all intuitions ought to be subjected to empiricalverification just like any other science. So, those of Bergson’sintuitions which could be confirmed by observation were not d<strong>is</strong>similarto Bachelard’s “positive” intuitions which cooperated in theconstruction of conceptual systems. Besides, both Bergson andBachelard believed that metaphysics should interact creatively withscience, and that they should be checked against one another. In fact,the role that Bachelard gave to philosophy of science was operationallyanalogous to the role that Bergson gave to metaphysics: theircombined effect allowed for their mutual progress and development,and enabled us to approximate the essence of reality.EMPIRICALLY VERIFIED METAPHYSICSBergson and Bachelard claimed that metaphysics ought to beempirically confirmed by science itself and by the way we thought.Bachelard spent decades showing that h<strong>is</strong> ep<strong>is</strong>temology fitted scientificevidence perfectly well. In h<strong>is</strong> turn, Bergson had said in L’Evolutioncréatrice that “metaphysics <strong>is</strong> dependent upon the theory ofknowledge”, that“both one and the other depend upon experience,”(Bergson 1944, 196) and in the Essai that “we [can] witness thesuperposition or, even better, the intimate fusion of many ideas that,once d<strong>is</strong>sociated, seem to exclude themselves from each other inlogically contradictory terms” (Bergson 1889, 101). One way forBergson to test the metaphysical hypothes<strong>is</strong> of duration, for instance,was to do so against two of the most important scientific theories of h<strong>is</strong>time, biological evolution and relativity. In L’Evolution créatrice,Bergson tried to demonstrate continuity in the phenomenon of life as itdeveloped through duration. To him, “there <strong>is</strong> an unbroken continuitybetween the evolution of the embryo and that of the completeorgan<strong>is</strong>m….The development of the embryo <strong>is</strong> a perpetual change ofform”(Bergson 1944, 22), so that “evolution implies a real pers<strong>is</strong>tenceof the past in the present, a duration which <strong>is</strong> (…) a connectinglink…Continuity of change, preservation of the past in the present, realduration – the living being seems (…) to share these attributes withconsciousness” (Bergson 1944, 27). As it can be testified by the marksof time in our aging bodies, external time or duration <strong>is</strong> not about staticbeing, as described by non-temporal frames such as mathematics andlogic, but about becoming (Bergson 1944, 324). So, even though wecan find a multiplicity of durations, “there <strong>is</strong> only a current of


AGATHOS: <strong>An</strong> <strong>International</strong> Review of the Humanities and Social Sciences 31ex<strong>is</strong>tence and the opposing current; thence proceeds the wholeevolution of life” (Bergson 1944, 203). It was from the study ofevolution that one can recognize that the two lines of thought providedby the intellect and intuition truly led to one another (Bergson 1944,196). Also, in Durée et simultanéité Bergson tried to demonstrate theempirical validity of “continuity” of duration by inferring it from theconception of time as described in Einstein’s theory of relativity. AsBergson put it, “not only the theses of Einstein do not seem tocontradict, but they even confirm, they (…) are a commencement ofproof in the natural belief that men have of a unique and universaltime”.10Bachelard had tried to infer from relativity an ep<strong>is</strong>temology ofscience that would confirm h<strong>is</strong> longtime belief that d<strong>is</strong>continuityex<strong>is</strong>ted in matter, in h<strong>is</strong>tory, and in consciousness. Bachelard’s firstcritical book on Bergson, L’intuition de l’instant, used the views ofGaston Roupnel against those of Bergson. Roupnel had in the pastcriticized Bergson’s dual<strong>is</strong>tic phenomenology.11 He had alsoattempted to establ<strong>is</strong>h a rapprochement between d<strong>is</strong>continuity and“phenomena of radiation in the quanta hypothes<strong>is</strong>”.12 The musingsover Roupnel’s La Nouvelle Silöe were a license on the part ofBachelard to return to relativity and to prove that continuity in durationdid not ex<strong>is</strong>t except as a rushed, generalized approach to reality. In themidst of profuse literary considerations, Bachelard admitted that “[we]were awoken from our dogmatic dreams [i.e., our confidence in theBergsonian thes<strong>is</strong>] by the Einsteinian critique of objective duration. Itseems (…) to us evident that th<strong>is</strong> critique destroys the absolute of thatwhich lasts, but in keeping (…) the absolute of what <strong>is</strong>, that <strong>is</strong> to say,the absolute of the instant”.(Bachelard 1979, 29)Despite agreements between Bergson and Bachelard on <strong>is</strong>suessuch as the role of intuition, the mobility of the mind, and the need toreform philosophy of science, one would think that Bachelard’srealization that the metaphysics of continuity could not be empiricallycorroborated by relativity would lead him to give up on Bergson<strong>is</strong>maltogether. But in fact, four years later Bachelard publ<strong>is</strong>hed La10 Henri Bergson (1968). Durée et simultanéité: a propos de la théorie d’Einstein(1922). Par<strong>is</strong>: Presses Universitaires de France11 Gaston Roupnel (1871-1946). He <strong>is</strong> seen as anticipating some of the spiritual<strong>is</strong>m ofTeilhard de Chardin, which makes it even stranger that Bachelard never usedevolution theory to test Bergson<strong>is</strong>m12 G.Bachelard (1979). L’Intuition de l’instant (1932). Par<strong>is</strong>: Editions Gonthier, p.53


32 AGATHOS: <strong>An</strong> <strong>International</strong> Review of the Humanities and Social SciencesDialectique de la durée to advance h<strong>is</strong> own agenda of ep<strong>is</strong>temologicald<strong>is</strong>continuity and to further test Bergson<strong>is</strong>m against modern science.As we have seen, Bergson had not rejected d<strong>is</strong>continuity altogether.But he had definitely restricted its use when he claimed in L’Evolutioncréatrice that “of the d<strong>is</strong>continuous alone does the intellect form a clearidea (…) as the intellect <strong>is</strong> characterized by the unlimited power ofdecomposing according to any law and of recomposing into anysystem” (Bergson 1944, 170-173).The problem was that Bachelard continued to be attracted toBergson<strong>is</strong>m but did not agree that d<strong>is</strong>continuity was simply anintellectual tool to be used to capture something that was in realitycontinuous. He wanted to demonstrate that d<strong>is</strong>continuity correspondedapproximately to the ontology of the physical world as described byquantum mechanics. So, h<strong>is</strong> new book was an attempt to test again h<strong>is</strong>d<strong>is</strong>continuity thes<strong>is</strong>. It was also meant to provide another falsifying testof Bergson’s metaphysics, th<strong>is</strong> time by trying “to develop ad<strong>is</strong>continuous Bergson<strong>is</strong>m, showing the need to arithmatizeBergsonian duration so as to give it more fluidity, more numbers, andalso more accuracy in the correspondence the phenomena of thoughtexhibit between themselves and the quantum character<strong>is</strong>tics of reality”(Bachelard 2000, 29). The need that Bachelard had to ‘d<strong>is</strong>continualize’Bergson came from h<strong>is</strong> own belief in the functional futility of “thepostulate of temporal continuity.” He did not think that presupposing acontinuous reality could clarify the descriptions and the enumerationsnecessary for microphenomenology in general or for quantumexperiments in particular (Bachelard 2000, 50). However, even thoughhe could not accept that physical reality was continuous, he stillbelieved that Bergson<strong>is</strong>m helped to legitimize h<strong>is</strong> own views on themobility of the mind and the need for flexibility in conceptualization.The arbitrariness of the separation between the subject and theobject did not demonstrate to Bachelard that our mind was imposingd<strong>is</strong>continuous standpoints to a fluid duration - which would beBergson’s position if he could have tested continuity against quantumtheory -, but that all the mathematical standpoints created by the mindwere as different as the multiple ways in which a d<strong>is</strong>continuous realitycould give itself to us. In other words, where Bachelard d<strong>is</strong>agreed withBergson was not in the use that Bergson had made of continuity as acategory of thought per se, since Bachelard shared the same belief thatone must use multiple plastic concepts to represent <strong>possible</strong> states ofknowledge and of thought. As he pointed out, “from our point of view


AGATHOS: <strong>An</strong> <strong>International</strong> Review of the Humanities and Social Sciences 33(…) continuity – or continuities - can be presented as character<strong>is</strong>tics ofthe psyche, [but] character<strong>is</strong>tics that cannot be regarded as complete,solid, constant (Bachelard 2000, 29). H<strong>is</strong> d<strong>is</strong>agreement was withBergson’s claim that continuity ex<strong>is</strong>ted OUTSIDE of the self thatthinks it. Bachelard said in L’Intuition de l’instant that “we reject th<strong>is</strong>metaphysical extrapolation which affirms a continuous in itself, whenwe are at all times in the face of the d<strong>is</strong>continuous of our experience”(Bachelard 1979, 42). In La Dialectique de la durée, he even claimedthat science, which provided us with “proofs of being,” (Bachelard2000, 33) had not proved at all the ex<strong>is</strong>tence of continuity (Bachelard2000, 43). So, Bachelard was a real<strong>is</strong>t in relation to scientific entitieswhile Bergson was a conventional<strong>is</strong>t in relation to scientific entitiesand a real<strong>is</strong>t in relation to the objects of intuition. But they were both“the philosophers of mobility”, and th<strong>is</strong> might well be why Bachelardkept coming back to Bergson.Bachelard’s recurrent fascination with Bergson could have hadtwo more sources. One was that, contrary to common belief, theinfluence of Bergson<strong>is</strong>m in French academia had not d<strong>is</strong>appearedcompletely after 1922. In fact, five years after La Dialectique de ladurée, Lou<strong>is</strong> de Broglie publ<strong>is</strong>hed “Les Conceptions de la physiquecontemporaine et les idées de Bergson sur le temps et sur lemovement” in the Revue de métaphysique et de morale. There, DeBroglie admitted that one could d<strong>is</strong>agree with some of the ideas ofBergson, including h<strong>is</strong> m<strong>is</strong>interpretation of relativity and h<strong>is</strong> weakargumentations, which were usually hidden by an “admirable style”.13But, now that one knew relativity was not “the last word in science”(De Broglie 1941, 246), one could not help but to be shocked by “theanalogy between certain new conceptions of contemporary physics andsome of the astounding intuitions of the philosopher of duration” (DeBroglie 1941, 242).Contrary to the views of Bachelard, De Broglie had not keptrelativity and quantum theories in the same ep<strong>is</strong>temological bag. So, hecriticized Einstein’s relativity on the grounds that it was unable tointerpret quantum phenomena; that quantum theories allowed us to“penetrate in the deepest layers of reality” in a way that relativity couldnot; that relativity could only give us macroscopic and stat<strong>is</strong>tical views13 Lou<strong>is</strong> De Broglie (1941). «Les Conceptions de la physique contemporaine et lesidées de Bergson sur le temps et sur le mouvement», in Revue de métaphysique et demorale, T.LIII, n.4, p.242


34 AGATHOS: <strong>An</strong> <strong>International</strong> Review of the Humanities and Social Sciencesof phenomena; and so that, contrary to wave mechanics, relativity didnot allow for a detailed description of elementary processes, oneswhich could help us to properly access those d<strong>is</strong>continuities that werelinked to the ex<strong>is</strong>tence of the quantum of action.14 In the same breath,he then asked whether “th<strong>is</strong> new physics would not be in betteraccordance with certain ideas of Bergson than with the relativ<strong>is</strong>ticdoctrine” (De Broglie 1941, 246-247).What intrigued De Broglie the most was the anticipatory nature ofBergson’s speculations on time, duration, and movement. Wave andquantum mechanics showed the impossibility of being able tosimultaneously “attribute to an elementary corpuscle a well definedstate of movement and a completely determined position. Theex<strong>is</strong>tence of the quantum of action (…) opposes every simultaneousdetermination and perfect prec<strong>is</strong>ion of those coordinates which fixatethe position of the corpuscle and the (…) energy and quantity ofmovement which specify its dynamic state. In other words, it wasim<strong>possible</strong> to know at the same time and with prec<strong>is</strong>ion the dynamicaspect of these elementary processes as well as their localization inspace” (De Broglie 1941, 248). To De Broglie, only macroscopicallycould one have the illusion of being able to know these two thingsprec<strong>is</strong>ely and simultaneously and, contrary to what Bachelard thought,only rushed generalizations could make one assume that the world wasas static as its relativ<strong>is</strong>tic descriptions.Bachelard saw our inability to detect position and momentumsimultaneously as definite proof that nature was d<strong>is</strong>continuous, whileDe Broglie believed that our inability to measure it except with thehelp from theories of quantum d<strong>is</strong>continuity was a sign that nature wasfleeting, continuous, and unpredictable. Wave mechanics showed thatphysical entities were constantly “in progress.” Therefore, De Brogliecontinued, “if Bergson could have studied the quantum theories indetail, he would have noted certainly with joy that, in the image thatthey offer us of the evolution of the physical world, they show usnature in all its occasions hesitating between several possibilities, andhe would have undoubtedly repeated, as in La Pensée et le Mouvant,that ‘time <strong>is</strong> that very hesitation or it <strong>is</strong> nothing at all’” (De Broglie14 The quantum of action had been first postulated in 1900 by Max Planck and laterby Einstein


AGATHOS: <strong>An</strong> <strong>International</strong> Review of the Humanities and Social Sciences 351941, 252-253).15 The very need for wave mechanics to renounceindividualization of particles, as well as its inability to follow theevolution of particles throughout time meant that reality was fluid, justlike Bergson had suggested (De Broglie 1941, 255). So, it <strong>is</strong> <strong>possible</strong>that Bachelard did not give up on Bergson prec<strong>is</strong>ely because DeBroglie demonstrated that quantum mechanics verified continuity innature, and thus that Bergson<strong>is</strong>m might be right after all.<strong>An</strong>other reason for why Bachelard would not give up onBergson<strong>is</strong>m had to do with h<strong>is</strong> own work on creative imagination in artand in literature. Contrary to Bergson who believed that science andintuition or instinct were complementary, Bachelard thought thatscience was complementary to poetry. For instance, in LaPsychanalyse du feu, he said that “the ax<strong>is</strong> of poetry and science arefirst of all inverted. The only thing that philosophy should aspire to do<strong>is</strong> to make poetry and science complementary, to unite them as twowell made contraries. One must therefore oppose expansive poeticspirit [and] taciturn scientific spirit (…).”16 In L’Evolution créatrice,Bergson claimed that “instinct and intelligence are two divergentdevelopments of one and the same principle, which in the one caseremains within itself, in the other steps out of itself and becomesabsorbed in the utilization of inert matter”(Bergson 1944, 184). Th<strong>is</strong>means that Bachelard’s role for poetry was analogous to the roleBergson had given to intuition.Bachelard wrote a series of books on rêverie, a state ofconsciousness which <strong>is</strong> prompted by our contemplation of the world ofmatter. The reflections that we make in the state of rêverie are freedfrom those rational and empirical constraints which we must imposeon scientific frames of thinking. There we could give free reign to thewandering mind and to those “negative” intuitions that were obstaclesto the scientific spirit but fruitful to the literary and art<strong>is</strong>ticimagination. Rêverie does not need to be tested, and th<strong>is</strong> <strong>is</strong> probablywhat makes them so open to the Bergsonian metaphysical method.1715 Karl Popper develops th<strong>is</strong> “hesitation” of nature in h<strong>is</strong> theory of propensities,which <strong>is</strong> really an amendment of probability theory. To him, probability did notexplain emergent evolution and other open but predictable acts of nature. Popperknew some of the works of Bergson, but he quickly d<strong>is</strong>m<strong>is</strong>sed Bergson’s élan vital16 G.Bachelard (1985). La Psychanalyse du feu (1938). Par<strong>is</strong>: Gallimard, p.1217 In h<strong>is</strong> studies of the unconscious in science and in art, Bachelard also relies heavilyon the analytic psychology of C.G.Jung


36 AGATHOS: <strong>An</strong> <strong>International</strong> Review of the Humanities and Social SciencesIn L’Air et les songes (1943), which was a study in the imagination ofmovement, Bachelard said that a psychology of the imagination - inother words the study of states of consciousness in rêverie – “cannot bedeveloped with static forms, it must get instruction from those formswhich are in the process of deforming themselves, which are payingmuch more attention to the dynamic principles of deformation. Thepsychology of the aerial element <strong>is</strong> the least “atomic” of all the fourpsychologies that study the material imagination” (Bachelard 1938,30). In the last chapter of the book, he recognized that Bergson hadbeen important when he had advocated a “revolution against thephilosophy of concept,”18 and when he made one realize that theexcesses of geometrization in the physical sciences were obstacles tothe study of movement. (Bachelard 1943, 332) Then, he admitted that“the images that we propose lead us to maintain Bergsonian intuition –which sometimes only offers itself as a mode of enlarged thinking – bypositive experiences (…) of the imagination….One could thenmultiply Bergson<strong>is</strong>m if we could make it adhere to the images ofwhich he <strong>is</strong> so rich, by considering it in matter and in the dynamic ofits own images”. (Bachelard 1943, 333)CONCLUSIONIs a d<strong>is</strong>continuous Bergson<strong>is</strong>m <strong>possible</strong>? Yes, but only if we agreewith De Broglie’s ep<strong>is</strong>temological interpretation of quantum physics.Furthermore, d<strong>is</strong>continuous Bergson<strong>is</strong>m <strong>is</strong> <strong>possible</strong> to Bachelard if hewould agree to restrict Bergson<strong>is</strong>m to the study of conceptualflexibility in knowledge, in the mind, and to poetic states ofconsciousness where intuitions, instincts, and the freedom to dream areprinciples of creative action. In these realms, it does not really matterwhether physical reality <strong>is</strong> continuous or d<strong>is</strong>continuous, or whetherconcepts correspond to reality or simple conventions. What Bachelardcould not accept of Bergson was not continuity tout court, but thecontinuity of physical reality.References:Bachelard, G. (1996). L’Air et les songes: essai sur l’imagination du mouvement(1943). Par<strong>is</strong>: Librairie José CortiBachelard, G. (1985). La Psychanalyse du feu (1938). Par<strong>is</strong>: GallimardBachelard G. (1979). L’Intuition de l’instant (1932). Par<strong>is</strong>: Editions Gonthier18 G.Bachelard (1996). L’Air et les songes: essai sur l’imagination du mouvement(1943). Par<strong>is</strong>: Librairie José Corti, p.331


AGATHOS: <strong>An</strong> <strong>International</strong> Review of the Humanities and Social Sciences 37Bachelard G. (2000). The Dialectic of Duration (1950). Manchester: Clinamen PressBergson, Henri (2007). <strong>An</strong> Introduction to Metaphysics. New York: PalgraveMacmillanBergson, Henri (1944). Creative Evolution. New York: The Modern LibraryBergson, Henri (1968). Durée et simultanéité: à propos de la théorie d’Einstein(1922). Par<strong>is</strong>: Presses Universitaires de FranceBergson, Henri (1889). Essai sur les données immédiates de la conscience. Par<strong>is</strong>:P.U.FBergson, Henri (1938). La Pensée et le mouvant. Par<strong>is</strong>: P.U.F.Castelão-Lawless, Teresa (1997). «Gaston Bachelard et le milieu scientifique etintellectuel frança<strong>is</strong>», in Nouvel, Pascal (dir.) Actualité et postérités de GastonBachelard. Par<strong>is</strong>: Presses Universitaires de France, pp.101-115Chim<strong>is</strong>so, Cr<strong>is</strong>tina (2000). «Introduction» to The Dialectics of Duration, op.cit.De Broglie, Lou<strong>is</strong> (1941). «Les Conceptions de la physique contemporaine et lesidées de Bergson sur le temps et sur le mouvement», in Revue de métaphysique et demorale, T.LIII, n.4Deleuze, Gilles (1991). Bergson<strong>is</strong>m. New York: Zone Books

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!