12.07.2015 Views

Road sharing - does it matter what road users think of each other?

Road sharing - does it matter what road users think of each other?

Road sharing - does it matter what road users think of each other?

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

<strong>Road</strong> SharingDoes <strong>it</strong> <strong>matter</strong> <strong>what</strong> <strong>road</strong> <strong>users</strong><strong>think</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>each</strong> <strong>other</strong>?Dr Simon Christmas (Simon Christmas Ltd)Dr Shaun Helman (TRL Ltd)January 2011


BThe Royal Automobile Club Foundation for Motoring Ltd is a char<strong>it</strong>y whichexplores the economic, mobil<strong>it</strong>y, safety and environmental issues relating to<strong>road</strong>s and responsible <strong>road</strong> <strong>users</strong>. Independent and author<strong>it</strong>ative research,carried out for the public benef<strong>it</strong>, is central to the Foundation’s activ<strong>it</strong>ies.RAC Foundation89–91 Pall MallLondonSW1Y 5HSTel no: 020 7747 3445www.racfoundation.orgRegistered Char<strong>it</strong>y No. 1002705January 2011 © Copyright Royal Automobile Club Foundation for Motoring LtdThis report has been prepared for the RAC Foundation by Dr Simon Christmas,Simon Christmas Ltd and Dr Shaun Helman, TRL. The report content is theview <strong>of</strong> the authors and <strong>does</strong> not necessarily represent the views <strong>of</strong> theRAC Foundation.


C<strong>Road</strong> SharingDoes <strong>it</strong> <strong>matter</strong> <strong>what</strong> <strong>road</strong> <strong>users</strong><strong>think</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>each</strong> <strong>other</strong>?Dr Simon Christmas (Simon Christmas Ltd)Dr Shaun Helman (TRL Ltd)January 2011


iAcknowledgementsWe are extremely grateful to the following, who have generously given their timeand expertise to us during the development <strong>of</strong> the ideas presented in this report:Ellie Besley (PACTS); Andrew Burr (DfT); Andrew Colski (DfT); Rob Gifford(PACTS); Joanne Hill (EuroRAP); Stephen Lawson (EuroRAP); Chris Lines(Transport Consultant); Lilli Matson (TfL); Paul O’Sullivan (DfT); Fiona Seymour(DfT); Louise Taylor (DfT); Adrian Walsh (<strong>Road</strong>Safe).While our views do not necessarily reflect theirs, our better ideas owe much totheir input.About the AuthorsSimon Christmas is an independent social researcher w<strong>it</strong>h wide private andpublic sector experience. Past research in the transport sector has includedstudies <strong>of</strong> young drivers and pre-drivers, motorcyclists, cyclists, van drivers,freight operators and drivers in general (in relation to seat-belt wearing andCO 2 reduction).Shaun Helman is a principal psychologist at TRL, and a Fellow <strong>of</strong> the TRLAcademy. His research interests include the factors impacting on the safety<strong>of</strong> new drivers, driver hazard perception skill and <strong>it</strong>s training and testing,perceptual processes relating to motorcyclist conspicu<strong>it</strong>y, driver distraction,and the evaluation <strong>of</strong> <strong>road</strong> safety interventions.


iiContentsForewordExecutive Summaryiiiv123456Introduction11.1 Context 11.2 Introducing moral models 21.3 The structure <strong>of</strong> this document 4What is a moral model? 62.1 What is a model <strong>of</strong> <strong>other</strong> <strong>road</strong> <strong>users</strong>? 72.2 What makes a model a moral model? 11Where do moral models come from? 183.1 Emergence 183.2 Social Ident<strong>it</strong>y Theory 203.3 Combining the two frameworks 21Why study moral models? 234.1 Changing behaviour 234.2 Understanding the ‘customer’ 274.3 Understanding the evolving culture <strong>of</strong> <strong>road</strong> use 28Conclusion30References 32


iiiForewordSome rivalries are enduring. ManchesterUn<strong>it</strong>ed fans despise Manchester C<strong>it</strong>y fans.Die-hard Labour supporters cannot abideConservatives. And <strong>it</strong> seems many cardrivers loathe cyclists – a feeling which is<strong>of</strong>ten mutual.Why is this so? Why do drivers considerthe typical cyclist to be reckless and bythe same token cyclists view ‘the motorist’as inconsiderate and malicious?Questions like these cannot be ignored inthe fields <strong>of</strong> transport policy and planning,since prejudice leads to antagonism thatcan seriously jeopardise <strong>road</strong> safety.To help address these <strong>matter</strong>s, the RAC Foundation commissioned SimonChristmas and Shaun Helman to explain some <strong>of</strong> the psychology behind<strong>road</strong> user interaction, and how perceptions and att<strong>it</strong>udes translate into actualbehaviour.The authors conclude that analysing the number <strong>of</strong> collisions on the <strong>road</strong>s isnot the only way interaction can and should be measured. They point to thequal<strong>it</strong>y <strong>of</strong> experience as an<strong>other</strong> yardstick. So too is the attainment <strong>of</strong> a <strong>road</strong>user’s goal. But these are more subjective areas involving value judgments andrequire an understanding <strong>of</strong> people’s so-called moral models.Moral models help explain how one set <strong>of</strong> <strong>road</strong> <strong>users</strong> views an<strong>other</strong> set. Themodels encapsulate how we expect <strong>other</strong> tribes on the <strong>road</strong>s to actuallybehave and how we <strong>think</strong> they ought to behave.Typifying ‘rival’ <strong>road</strong> <strong>users</strong> allows us to take mental shortcuts when weencounter them, maximising the speed at which we anticipate <strong>what</strong> is going tohappen around us.The trouble is our assumptions might well be wrong. This is becausestereotypes are generalisations, yet we all retain tra<strong>it</strong>s and characteristics thatdictate how we behave. Even as part <strong>of</strong> a herd we remain individuals.If the psychological processes employed by <strong>road</strong> <strong>users</strong> were better understood,allowance could be made for them when <strong>road</strong> systems and transport policiesare designed.


ivBy <strong>of</strong>fering some theoretical foundations this report provides a usefulcontribution to advancing the debate on <strong>road</strong> <strong>sharing</strong>. As the <strong>road</strong> networkbecomes ever more crowded, understanding how we share space – beyond<strong>what</strong> might be required by formal rules and regulations – becomesincreasingly cr<strong>it</strong>ical.Stephen Glaister CBEDirector, RAC Foundation


vExecutive SummaryThe aim <strong>of</strong> this report is to inform the RAC Foundation about the existingknowledge base on <strong>road</strong> <strong>sharing</strong>.We propose that the idea <strong>of</strong> a <strong>road</strong> user’s ‘moral model’ <strong>of</strong> <strong>other</strong> <strong>road</strong> <strong>users</strong>provides a sensible focus for research w<strong>it</strong>hin this b<strong>road</strong> field. This moral model,we suggest, has two parts:• A part which attributes psychological characteristics – things like goals,motivations, intentions, att<strong>it</strong>udes or character tra<strong>it</strong>s – to types <strong>of</strong> <strong>road</strong> user(defined by observable characteristics, which could include vehicle type,or behaviour).• A part which attributes moral characteristics – things like rights,responsibil<strong>it</strong>ies, and leg<strong>it</strong>imate claims – to different types <strong>of</strong> <strong>road</strong> user, in thecontext <strong>of</strong> different types <strong>of</strong> place.We make use <strong>of</strong> such a moral model when explaining and evaluating <strong>other</strong><strong>road</strong> <strong>users</strong>’ behaviour. (Whether moral models also have an impact on ouranticipation <strong>of</strong> <strong>other</strong> <strong>road</strong> <strong>users</strong>’ behaviour is a difficult question on which, forthe time being, we remain neutral.)In particular, moral models play a role in an individual’s judgement <strong>of</strong> thesuccess <strong>of</strong> their interaction w<strong>it</strong>h <strong>other</strong> <strong>road</strong> <strong>users</strong>. From the individual’sperspective, <strong>it</strong> seems reasonable to distinguish three levels <strong>of</strong> success ininteraction: avoidance <strong>of</strong> collisions, achievement <strong>of</strong> goals, and qual<strong>it</strong>y <strong>of</strong>experiences. Success at the first <strong>of</strong> these levels is a simple <strong>matter</strong> <strong>of</strong> fact, butat the second and third levels moral models are invoked. Because people havedifferent goals and different experiential needs and responses, and becausenot everyone can have everything they want, the best that can be achieved isa fair distribution <strong>of</strong> goal-achievement and experience-qual<strong>it</strong>y; a judgement <strong>of</strong>fairness rests in turn on an assessment <strong>of</strong> how reasonable and leg<strong>it</strong>imate theclaims made by <strong>each</strong> <strong>road</strong> user are.Research into moral models has a number <strong>of</strong> potential impacts on policyand practice.• Behaviour change. Moral models could play an important role in efforts totackle undesirable behaviours (such as aggression), as well as the promotion<strong>of</strong> behavioural choices to support wider objectives such as better publichealth, improved mobil<strong>it</strong>y, enhanced economic efficiency and reducedenvironmental impact. Whether they also have a potential role in <strong>road</strong> safetyremains an open question.


vi• Understanding the ‘customer’. Moral models <strong>of</strong>fer a new framework for<strong>think</strong>ing about consultation and research w<strong>it</strong>h commun<strong>it</strong>ies. A betterunderstanding <strong>of</strong> people’s moral models could help policy-makers andpract<strong>it</strong>ioners <strong>think</strong> about the acceptabil<strong>it</strong>y <strong>of</strong> interventions and anticipatecertain kinds <strong>of</strong> objections or misunderstandings.• Understanding the evolving culture <strong>of</strong> <strong>road</strong> use. Moral models, allied w<strong>it</strong>htheoretical understandings <strong>of</strong> emergent properties and social ident<strong>it</strong>y,provide a way to <strong>think</strong> about and track the culture <strong>of</strong> <strong>road</strong> use. A betterunderstanding <strong>of</strong> moral trends and conflicts could help policy-makers andpract<strong>it</strong>ioners spot both opportun<strong>it</strong>ies to nudge the system in a desireddirection and threats to be tracked and managed.In order to realise this potential, a first prior<strong>it</strong>y for any research in this area mustbe to start addressing the gaps in evidence and theory and, in so doing, refineand replace the working framework we put forward in this scoping report. W<strong>it</strong>ha firmer defin<strong>it</strong>ion and understanding <strong>of</strong> moral models in place, further researchwould be valuable in the following areas:• Identifying key dimensions which can be used to distinguish between moralmodels.• Investigating how differences along these dimensions correlate w<strong>it</strong>h <strong>other</strong>key differences (such as age or primary mode <strong>of</strong> transport).• Building the evidence base for the behavioural consequences <strong>of</strong> differentmoral models.• Tracking how moral models change over time – in individuals and acrossentire populations.While these tasks are clearly beyond the scope <strong>of</strong> any single piece <strong>of</strong> research,however large, we do believe that an in<strong>it</strong>ial qual<strong>it</strong>ative study could start toaddress objective 1 and suggest some in<strong>it</strong>ial hypotheses for objectives 2 and 3.


1<strong>Road</strong> <strong>sharing</strong> - <strong>does</strong> <strong>it</strong> <strong>matter</strong> <strong>what</strong> <strong>road</strong> <strong>users</strong> <strong>think</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>each</strong> <strong>other</strong>?1. Introduction1.1ContextThe aim <strong>of</strong> this report is to inform the RACFoundation about the existing knowledge baseon <strong>road</strong> <strong>sharing</strong>. A number <strong>of</strong> b<strong>road</strong> areas <strong>of</strong>potential research interest were identified:• Understand how behaviours <strong>of</strong> different <strong>road</strong> <strong>users</strong> can bemore successfully co-ordinated so that ‘conflicts’ are reliablyand successfully resolved.• Shed light on how different <strong>road</strong> <strong>users</strong> see and judge <strong>each</strong><strong>other</strong> to help policy and practice to take action on themisunderstandings that happen between <strong>road</strong> <strong>users</strong>, whichcan lead to ‘conflict’.• Understand how traffic law and infrastructure designed tohelp resolve conflict between <strong>users</strong> can be improved bytaking account <strong>of</strong> the ‘lore’ <strong>of</strong> the <strong>road</strong>.• Establish how views on and perceptions <strong>of</strong> fairnessinfluence user att<strong>it</strong>udes about <strong>other</strong> modes and theprovision <strong>of</strong> infrastructure.• Establish how efficiency is viewed by the different types<strong>of</strong> <strong>road</strong> user and <strong>what</strong> implications this has for developingshared networks.


Introduction2In our response, we have sought to find a sensible focus for research w<strong>it</strong>hinthis b<strong>road</strong> field.In preparing this report, we have conducted an informal scan <strong>of</strong> the l<strong>it</strong>eratureand conducted pilot conversations/interviews w<strong>it</strong>h <strong>road</strong> <strong>users</strong> to test whetherthe idea <strong>of</strong> a ‘moral model’ proved a useful theoretical framework in practicefor the design and interpretation <strong>of</strong> qual<strong>it</strong>ative research.1.2Introducing moral models<strong>Road</strong>s are a s<strong>it</strong>e <strong>of</strong> intense interaction between people.An event as simple and everyday as two cars passing in oppos<strong>it</strong>e directions,<strong>each</strong> keeping to their own side <strong>of</strong> a <strong>road</strong>, requires coordination andcollaboration between people who may never encounter <strong>each</strong> <strong>other</strong> againw<strong>it</strong>hin a similar context provided by the environment, social norms andconventions, and, <strong>of</strong> course, the vehicles they are driving.At the <strong>other</strong> end <strong>of</strong> the scale <strong>of</strong> complex<strong>it</strong>y, many urban <strong>road</strong>s see largenumbers <strong>of</strong> people using many different modes <strong>of</strong> transport (includingpedestrians) and simultaneously interacting w<strong>it</strong>h one an<strong>other</strong>. As a recentreport by PACTS (Besley, 2010) puts <strong>it</strong>, these are spaces in which ‘thespectrum <strong>of</strong> public life is carried out.’How successful is this interaction?To answer that question, we need first to <strong>of</strong>fer some kind <strong>of</strong> defin<strong>it</strong>ion <strong>of</strong>success; to do that, we need first to decide from whose point <strong>of</strong> view we areassessing <strong>it</strong>. Let’s start by considering the question from the perspective <strong>of</strong>those who are out on the <strong>road</strong> interacting. From this perspective, <strong>it</strong> seemsreasonable to distinguish three levels <strong>of</strong> success:


3<strong>Road</strong> <strong>sharing</strong> - <strong>does</strong> <strong>it</strong> <strong>matter</strong> <strong>what</strong> <strong>road</strong> <strong>users</strong> <strong>think</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>each</strong> <strong>other</strong>?• Avoidance <strong>of</strong> collisions. While there are probably exotic exceptions, <strong>it</strong> seemsreasonable to assume that everyone interacting on the <strong>road</strong>s is trying toavoid bumping into everyone else.• Achievement <strong>of</strong> goals. By contrast, different <strong>road</strong> <strong>users</strong> have many differentgoals in their use <strong>of</strong> the <strong>road</strong>, not all <strong>of</strong> them related to getting to a destination.• Qual<strong>it</strong>y <strong>of</strong> experience. Again, <strong>road</strong> <strong>users</strong> are likely to differ, responding indifferent ways whether pos<strong>it</strong>ively (relaxation, exc<strong>it</strong>ement, well-being) ornegatively (stress, fear, anger) to different aspects <strong>of</strong> their experience.It is worth making an immediate observation on this basic structure whichfollows from the simple observation that the desire to avoid collisions isuniversally shared, while goals and experiences are not.At the first level, interaction is successful to the extent that people are avoidingcollisions. If no-one ever collides, everyone gets <strong>what</strong> they want. Whether ornot an interaction is successful is a purely factual question, and one for whichquantification <strong>of</strong> the answer is relatively straightforward, through access torecorded collision statistics.At the second and third levels, by contrast, <strong>it</strong> is not possible for everyone toget everything they want. The best we can hope for is a fair distribution <strong>of</strong>goal-achievement and experience-qual<strong>it</strong>y among those who are interacting.To establish whether an outcome is fair, we have to ask whether <strong>what</strong> peoplewanted was reasonable in the first place. The success <strong>of</strong> interaction at theselevels is not just a <strong>matter</strong> <strong>of</strong> quantifiable fact: <strong>it</strong> introduces an unavoidablemoral dimension.For instance, in one <strong>of</strong> the research workshops conducted as part <strong>of</strong> our recentresearch w<strong>it</strong>h cyclists and <strong>other</strong> <strong>road</strong> <strong>users</strong> (Christmas et al., 2010), some <strong>of</strong>the participants complained about the tendency <strong>of</strong> some cyclists to ride ingroups, two or more abreast, making <strong>it</strong> hard for car drivers to get past.‘There’s normally a group, they’re just well up the <strong>road</strong>, there arecars going about 20 miles an hour behind them. Move over, I <strong>think</strong><strong>it</strong>’s selfish.’In one <strong>of</strong> the groups, however, a participant who himself cycled in this waylaunched a spir<strong>it</strong>ed defence <strong>of</strong> the practice in the face <strong>of</strong> oppos<strong>it</strong>ion andquestioning from the rest <strong>of</strong> the group.‘You got a group <strong>of</strong> 20; you can’t keep pulling in to single file all thetime because <strong>it</strong>’s just not practical. [They can’t ride single file allthe time] because they’re talking and training, you know. They’reworking as a team. [It’s] exactly the same as a slow car. You haveto… everybody’s ent<strong>it</strong>led; you know… <strong>it</strong>’s not against the law.’


Introduction4These two responses differ fundamentally. For the first respondent, teamcyclists are selfishly making unreasonable claims on the <strong>road</strong>. For the secondrespondent, team cyclists are doing something that is perfectly reasonable,and justified by the practical requirements <strong>of</strong> training: if anything, <strong>it</strong> is theexpectation <strong>of</strong> drivers that they should always be able to get past cyclists (in away they cannot always get past <strong>other</strong> cars) that is unreasonable.These two different participants have different moral models <strong>of</strong> the people theyinteract w<strong>it</strong>h on the <strong>road</strong>s: different stories about why these people do <strong>what</strong>they do, different views on whether their claims on the <strong>road</strong> are reasonable,and – as a result – different judgements <strong>of</strong> whether the outcome is fair.Put simply, an individual’s judgement <strong>of</strong> the success <strong>of</strong> their interaction w<strong>it</strong>h<strong>other</strong> <strong>road</strong> <strong>users</strong> depends not just on the facts <strong>of</strong> <strong>what</strong> happens, but also ontheir moral model.Perhaps this insight helps to explain an observation – although, like much elsein this report, the observation, the insight and the explanation all remain stuckat the level <strong>of</strong> anecdote and conjecture until more research <strong>of</strong> the kind we willbe arguing for is undertaken.The observation is as follows. Ask some <strong>road</strong> <strong>users</strong> in London – some cyclists,for instance – how successfully people are interacting on the <strong>road</strong>s, and youmay get surprisingly different answers. We, for instance, have heard everythingfrom ‘<strong>it</strong>’s war out there’ to ‘drivers in London are very considerate’.What explains this divergence? It’s possible, <strong>of</strong> course, that these two cyclistsuse consistently different routes, or that one has been luckier than the <strong>other</strong>.Maybe, however, the difference lies in their having different moral models.1.3The structure <strong>of</strong> this documentSo far have we been considering the question <strong>of</strong> successful interaction from theperspective <strong>of</strong> those interacting. Those whose job <strong>it</strong> is to make policies, designinterventions and commission research have a (necessarily) different perspective– along w<strong>it</strong>h their own goals and defin<strong>it</strong>ions <strong>of</strong> successful interaction.Even if the above is all true, therefore, <strong>it</strong> is leg<strong>it</strong>imate to ask: is <strong>it</strong> somethingthat policy-makers and pract<strong>it</strong>ioners need to worry about? Do moral modelsrepresent just a (we would say interesting) theoretical framework, or woulda better understanding <strong>of</strong> that framework enable policy-makers to do thingsdifferently, and in such a way as to increase the ‘success’ <strong>of</strong> <strong>road</strong> <strong>sharing</strong>?To answer this question, we first need to provide some more detail about<strong>what</strong> is meant by the term ‘moral model’; for although, as shall be seen, theconstruct draws on familiar theories (such as Attribution Theory) and concepts


5<strong>Road</strong> <strong>sharing</strong> - <strong>does</strong> <strong>it</strong> <strong>matter</strong> <strong>what</strong> <strong>road</strong> <strong>users</strong> <strong>think</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>each</strong> <strong>other</strong>?(such as att<strong>it</strong>udes to <strong>other</strong> people), <strong>it</strong> puts those pieces together in a way whichis some<strong>what</strong> innovative.As a result, the early sections <strong>of</strong> this report, necessarily, may seem to somereaders to err on the ‘theoretical’ side, and to leave the ‘so <strong>what</strong>?’ questionunanswered. Readers keen for a ‘so <strong>what</strong>?’ could start w<strong>it</strong>h Section 4, but mayfind elements <strong>of</strong> the argument presented therein hard to follow w<strong>it</strong>hout thefoundation provided by Sections 2 and 3.• Section 2 provides an overview <strong>of</strong> the constructs <strong>of</strong> a ‘model’ and, morespecifically, a ‘moral model’, relating <strong>each</strong> to existing theory and ways <strong>of</strong><strong>think</strong>ing about human psychology, and some existing research that webelieve sheds light on some aspects <strong>of</strong> the construct. W<strong>it</strong>hout addressing<strong>it</strong> head on, this section provides a basis for tackling the question: ‘Whatdifference do moral models make?’• Section 3 <strong>of</strong>fers some theoretical perspectives on the ways in which moralmodels may arise, persist or change in the context <strong>of</strong> interaction. W<strong>it</strong>houtaddressing <strong>it</strong> head on, this section provides a basis for tackling the question:‘What makes a difference to moral models?’• Section 4 returns to the question <strong>of</strong> <strong>what</strong> this may mean at the levels <strong>of</strong>policy and practice. Why is <strong>it</strong> worth studying moral models, and <strong>what</strong> kinds<strong>of</strong> studies would be valuable?


6<strong>Road</strong> <strong>sharing</strong> - <strong>does</strong> <strong>it</strong> <strong>matter</strong> <strong>what</strong> <strong>road</strong> <strong>users</strong> <strong>think</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>each</strong> <strong>other</strong>?2. What is a moral model?In this section, we <strong>of</strong>fer an overview <strong>of</strong> theconstructs <strong>of</strong> a ‘model’ and, more specifically, a‘moral model’, relating <strong>each</strong> to existing theoreticalapproaches and research where possible.Our aim is to <strong>of</strong>fer a conceptual construct thatis robust enough to enable us, and <strong>other</strong>s, tobegin the v<strong>it</strong>al tasks <strong>of</strong> gathering evidence andbuilding a more robust theoretical framework.We have, <strong>of</strong> course, drawn on existingevidence and theory where we have found<strong>it</strong>; where such evidence and theory seemsto be lacking, we have used common senseto fill in gaps for the time being, signallingthese points w<strong>it</strong>h expressions like ‘<strong>it</strong> seemsreasonable to <strong>think</strong> that…’ All research has tostart somewhere, and we believe the concept<strong>of</strong> a ‘moral model’ is a sensible place to startfor the time being. We look forward to refiningor replacing both the overall concept and thedetails <strong>of</strong> <strong>it</strong>s elucidation in the light <strong>of</strong> evidence.


What is a moral model?7For ease <strong>of</strong> presentation, we begin w<strong>it</strong>h a brief discussion <strong>of</strong> the idea <strong>of</strong> a‘model <strong>of</strong> <strong>other</strong> <strong>road</strong> <strong>users</strong>’ in the (non-moral) area <strong>of</strong> collision-avoidance inSection 2.1, before plunging into the murkier waters <strong>of</strong> the ‘moral’ in Section 2.2.2.1What is a model <strong>of</strong> <strong>other</strong> <strong>road</strong> <strong>users</strong>?A working model <strong>of</strong> physical objectsHow do people on the <strong>road</strong>s, in or on a variety <strong>of</strong> wheeled vehicles, feet oreven animals, avoid bumping into <strong>each</strong> <strong>other</strong>?There are many different variables in this picture, but one important capabil<strong>it</strong>ywhich the people themselves bring to the mix (perhaps aided or hindered bytheir vehicles or features <strong>of</strong> the environment) is the abil<strong>it</strong>y not just to see where<strong>other</strong> people are now, but also to anticipate <strong>what</strong> they may do and where theymay go next.Let’s focus on this one small element <strong>of</strong> people avoiding bumping into <strong>each</strong><strong>other</strong>. When I am on the <strong>road</strong>, how do I anticipate <strong>what</strong> <strong>other</strong>s may do andwhere they may go next?To some extent, this capabil<strong>it</strong>y is down to knowledge <strong>of</strong> the behaviour <strong>of</strong>physical objects, including vehicles, based on my previous experience <strong>of</strong>them. 1 If I see a stationary bus on the <strong>road</strong> ahead <strong>of</strong> me, I can anticipate that <strong>it</strong>won’t suddenly rotate or start moving very fast. This is not to say I consciouslyor unconsciously represent these possibil<strong>it</strong>ies in order to rule them out, butI would be extremely surprised if e<strong>it</strong>her <strong>of</strong> them happened. I work on theassumption <strong>of</strong> a range <strong>of</strong> physical possibil<strong>it</strong>ies and likelihoods for differentkinds <strong>of</strong> objects in different kinds <strong>of</strong> s<strong>it</strong>uations.1 Part <strong>of</strong> this will be <strong>what</strong> my experience tells me about <strong>what</strong> is allowed by the more accessible laws<strong>of</strong> physics (for example, objects do not spontaneously disappear). The focus here, however, is onmy experience <strong>of</strong> objects and their likely movements w<strong>it</strong>hin some b<strong>road</strong>ly predictable context – the<strong>road</strong> system.


8<strong>Road</strong> <strong>sharing</strong> - <strong>does</strong> <strong>it</strong> <strong>matter</strong> <strong>what</strong> <strong>road</strong> <strong>users</strong> <strong>think</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>each</strong> <strong>other</strong>?In <strong>other</strong> words I anticipate the future <strong>road</strong> s<strong>it</strong>uation using a working model<strong>of</strong> the behaviour <strong>of</strong> the physical objects on the <strong>road</strong>, based on my previousexperience <strong>of</strong> them. The abil<strong>it</strong>y to anticipate hazards in this way is one thingthat seems to differentiate between accident-involved and accident-freedrivers, and <strong>it</strong> is certainly a skill that increases w<strong>it</strong>h on-<strong>road</strong> experience (for areview, see Horswill & McKenna, 2004).A working model <strong>of</strong> <strong>other</strong> <strong>road</strong> <strong>users</strong>In a similar way, my capabil<strong>it</strong>y to anticipate <strong>what</strong> is going to happen on the<strong>road</strong> may also depend on knowledge <strong>of</strong> the behaviour <strong>of</strong> human beings –assumptions about psychological possibil<strong>it</strong>ies and likelihoods.For instance, if the stationary bus is at a bus stop, in the hours when busservices run, I may both anticipate that the bus is likely to start moving againat some point, and be wary that <strong>it</strong> will do so w<strong>it</strong>hout indicating, again possiblybecause I have experienced this before.It is not, however, a bus that communicates (or <strong>does</strong> not communicate)<strong>it</strong>s intentions by indicating: <strong>it</strong> is a bus driver. In anticipating the future <strong>road</strong>s<strong>it</strong>uation in this case, I seem to use a working model <strong>of</strong> the behaviour, not <strong>of</strong>physical objects, but <strong>of</strong> <strong>other</strong> <strong>road</strong> <strong>users</strong> – based, as before, on my previousexperience <strong>of</strong> them.As well as drawing on a working model <strong>of</strong> the behaviour <strong>of</strong> physical objects,our abil<strong>it</strong>y to avoid bumping into <strong>each</strong> <strong>other</strong> on the <strong>road</strong>s seems likely to relyon such a working model <strong>of</strong> <strong>other</strong> <strong>road</strong> <strong>users</strong>. 2Consider, by way <strong>of</strong> contrast, the familiar s<strong>it</strong>uation when two people walkingtowards <strong>each</strong> <strong>other</strong> engage in a moment <strong>of</strong> synchronised sidestepping beforeworking out how to get past <strong>each</strong> <strong>other</strong>. In this case, one might argue that<strong>it</strong> is precisely the lack <strong>of</strong> a working model that causes the problems: ne<strong>it</strong>herperson has an expectation <strong>of</strong> the direction in which the <strong>other</strong> will step. (Thereis more to be said about this example: for instance, the relationship betweenanticipation and convention, a point to which we shall return in Section 3.)How can we best conceptualise working models?For the immediate purposes <strong>of</strong> this paper, we are going to use a deliberatelysimplistic approach which sees a model as comprising a large number <strong>of</strong>2 An<strong>other</strong> example <strong>of</strong> this is an anecdote from one <strong>of</strong> the report authors (SH), who a number <strong>of</strong> yearsago was privy to details <strong>of</strong> a commentary drive from some police pursu<strong>it</strong> drivers in Oxford, England. Onturning down a street on which one <strong>of</strong> Oxford Univers<strong>it</strong>y’s colleges stood, the police driver commentedthat a major hazard in this <strong>road</strong> was pedestrians looking the wrong way when they stepped into thestreet; this, he reasoned, was due to that fact that the college in question held mainly overseas students,whose experience in their own countries tended to be that vehicles drove on the right. Again the ‘priming’<strong>of</strong> his anticipation was partly based on an understanding <strong>of</strong> the people involved – at least subjectively <strong>it</strong>went beyond just a description <strong>of</strong> the behaviour.


What is a moral model?9generalised types 3 (e.g. ‘bus driver’) <strong>each</strong> associated w<strong>it</strong>h and/or defined bya number <strong>of</strong> characteristics (e.g. ‘s<strong>it</strong>s in the driver’s seat <strong>of</strong> a bus’, ‘stops atbus stops to pick up passengers, then continues on route’, ‘may not alwaysindicate before pulling out’).These types – which may nest or intersect – serve as heuristics, or mentalshortcuts, which maximise the scope and speed <strong>of</strong> our understanding, albe<strong>it</strong>at the risk <strong>of</strong> getting things wrong some <strong>of</strong> the time.The use <strong>of</strong> a model can be seen as comprising two steps:• Identification <strong>of</strong> a person as a member <strong>of</strong> type X on the basis <strong>of</strong> one ormore characteristics.• Attribution to that person <strong>of</strong> <strong>other</strong> characteristics associated w<strong>it</strong>h type X.For instance, in the example above, I identify a person as a ‘bus driver’ on thebasis <strong>of</strong> the only characteristic that is actually visible to me: the fact that theyare s<strong>it</strong>ting in the driving seat <strong>of</strong> a bus. On this basis, I attribute to them thecharacteristic ‘may not always indicate before pulling out’.For all I actually know, the person in the driving seat might actually be amember <strong>of</strong> a gang <strong>of</strong> bank-robbers, about to turn as suddenly as he caninto the traffic to create a diversion. The heuristic types in my working modelusefully spare me from wasting valuable processing time and energy on bizarre(and, crucially, really unlikely) possibil<strong>it</strong>ies like this – usefully, that is, until theday I encounter said gang <strong>of</strong> bank-robbers.Caveat: abstractions and brainsIt is very important to stress that this simplistic description <strong>of</strong> a model ascomprising a large number <strong>of</strong> types is a theoretical abstraction – one <strong>of</strong> themany elements <strong>of</strong> the discussion that stands in need <strong>of</strong> future improvement.In real<strong>it</strong>y, our abil<strong>it</strong>y to anticipate the behaviour <strong>of</strong> <strong>other</strong> <strong>road</strong> <strong>users</strong> almostcertainly depends not on a single model lodged somewhere in our brains, buton the interaction <strong>of</strong> many different systems and the knowledge they embody.It seems reasonable to assume that these systems, collectively, produceresults that are some<strong>what</strong> like the results <strong>of</strong> the simplistic model describedabove. This assumption is <strong>what</strong> makes the simplistic approach good enoughfor current purposes.3 There is a fairly obvious connection here between our concept <strong>of</strong> a ‘type’ and the psychologicalconcept <strong>of</strong> a ‘schema’. Nevertheless, we will continue using the term ‘type’. The concept <strong>of</strong> a ‘schema’covers a far b<strong>road</strong>er range <strong>of</strong> cogn<strong>it</strong>ive structures containing generalised knowledge; and in this contextthe everyday term ‘type’ is more self-explanatory.


10<strong>Road</strong> <strong>sharing</strong> - <strong>does</strong> <strong>it</strong> <strong>matter</strong> <strong>what</strong> <strong>road</strong> <strong>users</strong> <strong>think</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>each</strong> <strong>other</strong>?In actual interactions, however, the devil may lie in the details; and even smalldifferences – in response time, for instance – could make a crucial difference towhether two people avoid a collision or not. Moreover, the types <strong>of</strong> processinginvolved (that may lead to these differences in response time) may depend ona number <strong>of</strong> factors.One example comes from Walker (2005a) who found that, when describingpictures <strong>of</strong> <strong>road</strong> scenes containing cyclists and pedestrians people used‘personalised’ words in their descriptions almost 100% <strong>of</strong> the time (e.g. ‘a ladyis wa<strong>it</strong>ing to cross the <strong>road</strong>’ or ‘a cyclist is turning right’). On the <strong>other</strong> hand,words referring to vehicles were almost always used when cars and <strong>other</strong>motor vehicles were present (e.g. ‘a car is turning left’). When motorcyclistswere in scenes, they were referred to approximately half <strong>of</strong> the time w<strong>it</strong>hpersonalised words, and half <strong>of</strong> the time w<strong>it</strong>h ‘vehicle referent’ words. Walkersuggests that this difference in the language used by people hints at afundamental difference in the way in which they view different types <strong>of</strong> <strong>road</strong>user, depending on how easy <strong>it</strong> is to conceptualise them as a ‘person’.Of course <strong>it</strong> is one thing to claim that people hold different att<strong>it</strong>udes towardsand models <strong>of</strong> different <strong>road</strong> <strong>users</strong>. It is an<strong>other</strong> to claim that these have adirect impact on interactions. However, there is evidence that this is the case,and there are psychological mechanisms that explain why. Walker (2005a)argues that when <strong>road</strong> <strong>users</strong> are viewed and interpreted as ‘people’, automaticbrain processes related to social cogn<strong>it</strong>ion (e.g. face and gaze processing) areinvoked in the viewer. Other work by Walker and his colleagues (2005b) hasshown that such processing may slow the decisions made by drivers wheninterpreting the intentions <strong>of</strong> vulnerable <strong>road</strong> <strong>users</strong> such as cyclists; when visualattention is focused on the face <strong>of</strong> cyclists and on establishing eye contact andgaze direction, decisions about whether or not the cyclist is turning across thedriver’s path are slower than when such processes are not involved.Walker’s research is one example from a disparate body <strong>of</strong> work that hasrelevance to the concept <strong>of</strong> moral models. However, this body <strong>of</strong> research hasnot previously been drawn together into a theoretical framework.Identification and attributionThe simple example <strong>of</strong> a model used to anticipate <strong>other</strong>s’ behaviour allows usto make some useful observations about the operation <strong>of</strong> working models.If we first focus on the identification step, <strong>it</strong> seems reasonable to assume thatthere are two basic types <strong>of</strong> observable characteristics on the basis <strong>of</strong> which aperson may be identified as <strong>of</strong> a particular type (although context can also playa cr<strong>it</strong>ical role):• Observed behaviour; and• Physical attributes.


What is a moral model?11Physical attributes obviously include things like the way people look, how theyare dressed, and so forth. On the <strong>road</strong>, however, the most salient physicalattribute is likely to be the type <strong>of</strong> vehicle (if any) the person is using. In manycases, this will be the only visible characteristic <strong>of</strong> the <strong>other</strong> person – as in theexample <strong>of</strong> the bus driver above.Unlike the identification step, attribution is not lim<strong>it</strong>ed to observablecharacteristics. Having identified a person as belonging to type X, we mayattribute to them all sorts <strong>of</strong> characteristics that are unobservable in principleas well as practice, such as:• Psychological characteristics – things like goals, motivations, intentions,att<strong>it</strong>udes or character tra<strong>it</strong>s; and• Moral characteristics – things like rights and responsibil<strong>it</strong>ies.It is attributed characteristics such as these that make up a moral model.2.2What makes a model a moral model?Psychological characteristics: attribution and stereotypesExplaining and evaluating <strong>other</strong> people’s behaviour by attributing psychologicalcharacteristics to them is an everyday human activ<strong>it</strong>y, not the preserve<strong>of</strong> psychologists, and one that is studied by an area <strong>of</strong> psychology calledAttribution Theory.The evidence suggests that the mechanisms employed in making suchattributions go far beyond the kind <strong>of</strong> simplistic model <strong>of</strong> types we have beendiscussing. Kelley’s covariation model (1967), for instance, suggests thatpeople also consider information such as whether the same person <strong>does</strong> thesame thing in similar or different circumstances.In our interactions on the <strong>road</strong>, however, we typically lack this kind <strong>of</strong>information about <strong>other</strong> people, whom we encounter, for the most part,fleetingly and anonymously. It is only at the level <strong>of</strong> types that we couldconsider consistency across s<strong>it</strong>uations.And in fact, even when we do have more information to work w<strong>it</strong>h, theevidence for our use <strong>of</strong> types – or stereotypes as they are better known inthis context – in attributing psychological characteristics is compelling. One<strong>of</strong>ten-c<strong>it</strong>ed example is the influence <strong>of</strong> factors such as physical attractivenessand race on assessments by mock jurors regarding guilt and recommendedpunishments for mock crimes. It has been shown that in terms <strong>of</strong> the likelihood<strong>of</strong> being found not guilty, defendants are at an advantage if they are physicallyattractive; in add<strong>it</strong>ion, racial characteristics can lead to harsher punishmentsfor some types <strong>of</strong> crime (Mazzella & Feingold, 1994).


12<strong>Road</strong> <strong>sharing</strong> - <strong>does</strong> <strong>it</strong> <strong>matter</strong> <strong>what</strong> <strong>road</strong> <strong>users</strong> <strong>think</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>each</strong> <strong>other</strong>?That stereotypes <strong>of</strong> different kinds <strong>of</strong> <strong>road</strong> <strong>users</strong> exist is unquestionable:indeed, the one type that <strong>does</strong> not exist in everyday parlance is that <strong>of</strong> theundifferentiated ‘<strong>road</strong> user’, a phrase that had to be invented.Desp<strong>it</strong>e the intu<strong>it</strong>ive appeal <strong>of</strong> the idea <strong>of</strong> different <strong>road</strong> user stereotypes,we know surprisingly l<strong>it</strong>tle about which people, and how many, hold <strong>what</strong>stereotypes about whom, although some research has been done.Basford et al. (2002: 1) for example found, amongst <strong>other</strong> things, that ‘whendrivers encounter cyclists in circumstances that cause them to slow ordeviate… their estimation <strong>of</strong> the cyclist’s discourtesy increases, regardless <strong>of</strong>the cyclist’s actual behaviour’. Even this relatively rare piece <strong>of</strong> research onstereotypes, however, concludes that the best framework for future researchin this area is the Theory <strong>of</strong> Planned Behaviour, a theory that puts att<strong>it</strong>udes tobehaviour, not att<strong>it</strong>udes to people, at the heart <strong>of</strong> explanation.More recently Musselwh<strong>it</strong>e et al. (2010) have carried out a large qual<strong>it</strong>ative study<strong>of</strong> att<strong>it</strong>udes towards <strong>road</strong> user safety. Musselwh<strong>it</strong>e et al. found that althoughpeople have multiple ident<strong>it</strong>ies as <strong>road</strong> <strong>users</strong> (pedestrian, cyclist, car driver etc.)they tend to hold only one <strong>road</strong> user ‘ident<strong>it</strong>y’ at a time (usually ‘car driver’).In add<strong>it</strong>ion, different risk-increasing behaviours were attributed to differenttypes <strong>of</strong> <strong>road</strong> user; cyclists, for example, were viewed by car drivers as one<strong>of</strong> the most unsafe <strong>road</strong> <strong>users</strong>, partly due to perceptions <strong>of</strong> their ‘aggressive’behaviour such as weaving in and out <strong>of</strong> traffic. Interestingly, <strong>it</strong> was also foundthat car drivers categorised cyclists into three distinct types (pr<strong>of</strong>essionalcyclists such as couriers, commuters, and those cycling for fun) and attributeddifferent behaviours to these; pr<strong>of</strong>essional cyclists, for example, were seen asthe greatest risk, due to their excessive rule breaking and risk taking.Anticipation vs evaluationClearly, <strong>road</strong> user stereotypes exist. Why then have they not received moreresearch attention? Part <strong>of</strong> the answer may lie in the combination <strong>of</strong> tw<strong>of</strong>actors: (i) a justifiable focusing <strong>of</strong> research energy on <strong>road</strong> safety, and (ii)serious questions about whether stereotypes are actually relevant to this topic.Earlier, in order to introduce the idea <strong>of</strong> a model <strong>of</strong> <strong>other</strong> <strong>road</strong> <strong>users</strong>, weused the example <strong>of</strong> a bus driver. In anticipating that a bus driver might notindicate before pulling out, <strong>it</strong> was argued, I seem to use a working model <strong>of</strong> thebehaviour <strong>of</strong> <strong>other</strong> <strong>road</strong> <strong>users</strong>.But do I actually use one?So long as we are concerned only w<strong>it</strong>h models as a theoretical abstraction, thisquestion can be set to one side. But, as we also noted earlier, when <strong>it</strong> comesto the details <strong>of</strong> real interactions, the devil is in the details. The processing thatgoes on in the moments that can be cr<strong>it</strong>ical to avoiding a collision could indeedinvolve activation <strong>of</strong> a model <strong>of</strong> the behaviour <strong>of</strong> bus drivers. However, <strong>it</strong> might


What is a moral model?13be that we form a more direct connection between a bus and a likely event, andso behave as if we activated such a model w<strong>it</strong>hout actually having to do so?There appears to be an important distinction to be made here between the role<strong>of</strong> models in the activ<strong>it</strong>y <strong>of</strong> anticipation (before the event) as opposed to theactiv<strong>it</strong>ies <strong>of</strong> explanation and evaluation (after the event).The attributions studied by Attribution Theory are part <strong>of</strong> the process <strong>of</strong>consciously explaining and evaluating behaviour (as were most <strong>of</strong> thestereotypes explored by Basford et al. (2002)). By contrast, the anticipation<strong>of</strong> future <strong>road</strong> s<strong>it</strong>uations that underpins skills like hazard perception seemsfar more likely to involve implic<strong>it</strong>, almost unconscious processes – processeswhich may be very different in their operation from the explanations given bythe same person after the event.It is not hard to see how stereotypes can play a part in decisions which allowtime for processes such as explanation and evaluation to be involved, suchas who to hire for a job, whether someone is a criminal, or who was at faultin an accident. It is much less obvious that they play a role in the mechanics<strong>of</strong> avoiding collisions; they seem more likely to play a role in our recording <strong>of</strong>collisions – for instance, the ‘contributory factors’ in STATS19 (Department forTransport, 2010b).This is not to say that they defin<strong>it</strong>ely do not play a role. For instance, stereotypescan be linked to powerful emotions (imagine your feelings meeting different kinds<strong>of</strong> people in a dark alley at night) which in turn might have direct consequencesfor behaviour about which we understand l<strong>it</strong>tle in a <strong>road</strong> safety context.The question has not yet been settled e<strong>it</strong>her way by research, though somefascinating studies have been carried out. That our behavioural responses to


14<strong>Road</strong> <strong>sharing</strong> - <strong>does</strong> <strong>it</strong> <strong>matter</strong> <strong>what</strong> <strong>road</strong> <strong>users</strong> <strong>think</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>each</strong> <strong>other</strong>?different types <strong>of</strong> <strong>road</strong> user can be influenced by characteristics <strong>of</strong> that <strong>road</strong>user is amply illustrated by a now famous study by Walker (2005a), whichestablished that when a male cyclist was wearing a blonde wig (so as to appearfemale), drivers passing him afforded him more room than when he appearedmale (by not wearing the wig). Even if stereotypical attribution <strong>of</strong> characteristicsby gender is not directly involved in this behaviour, the research raises importantquestions. How and why <strong>does</strong> the link between assessment <strong>of</strong> gender andresponse arise in the first place? Are stereotypes involved in <strong>it</strong>s genesis and/ormaintenance, even if they play no direct role in <strong>it</strong>s actual operation?Equally ambiguous from the point <strong>of</strong> view <strong>of</strong> interpretation are various findingsthat relate to drivers’ observation skills around motorcyclists. Brooks andGuppy (1996), for instance, found that car drivers who had relatives who rodea motorcycle were less likely than average to be involved in a collision w<strong>it</strong>h amotorcyclist. Recent data from Crundall et al. at the Univers<strong>it</strong>y <strong>of</strong> Nottingham(in press) are also relevant here: car drivers who also have experience asmotorcyclists have a qual<strong>it</strong>atively different scanning behaviour w<strong>it</strong>h regardto motorcyclists at junctions when compared w<strong>it</strong>h <strong>other</strong> experienced cardrivers and novices. On the basis <strong>of</strong> findings such as these, the Departmentfor Transport (DfT) Think! team has argued that ‘empathy w<strong>it</strong>h motorcyclists isimportant’ and, in the Named Riders campaign <strong>of</strong> 2010 (DfT, 2010a), soughtto encourage drivers to see the individual human being behind the stereotype.This is a plausible reading <strong>of</strong> the findings on which <strong>it</strong> is based, but <strong>it</strong> is notthe only possible one; there are likely to be multiple mechanisms by whichexperience w<strong>it</strong>h (and as) different types <strong>of</strong> <strong>road</strong> user can affect interactionsw<strong>it</strong>h those <strong>road</strong> <strong>users</strong>.For example Crundall et al. (2008a) explored the ways in which att<strong>it</strong>udes tomotorcyclists changed w<strong>it</strong>h both general on-<strong>road</strong> experience and also ‘dualuse’experience (i.e. experience as both a car driver and a motorcyclist). Ascale was developed to measure different aspects <strong>of</strong> these att<strong>it</strong>udes, and howthey varied w<strong>it</strong>h experience. Four different aspects <strong>of</strong> att<strong>it</strong>udes were measured:negative att<strong>it</strong>udes towards motorcyclists (e.g. ‘When a car and a motorcyclecollide <strong>it</strong> is typically the fault <strong>of</strong> the motorcyclist.’), empathic att<strong>it</strong>udes towardsmotorcyclists (e.g. ‘I have similar personal characteristics to the averagemotorcyclist.’), awareness <strong>of</strong> the perceptual problems car drivers mayexperience when looking for motorcyclists (‘Motorcycles are easily hidden fromview by parked vehicles and <strong>other</strong> parts <strong>of</strong> the <strong>road</strong> environment, e.g. buildingsor overgrown vegetation.’), and knowledge <strong>of</strong> the spatial requirements <strong>of</strong>motorcyclists (e.g. ‘When a motorcyclist overtakes a car at 40 mph <strong>what</strong> size<strong>of</strong> gap should be left between the car and the passing motorcycle in order toremain safe?’). Although only based on an in<strong>it</strong>ial version <strong>of</strong> the scale, evidencewas found that the effect <strong>of</strong> experience was different for these different aspects<strong>of</strong> att<strong>it</strong>udes, and for different types <strong>of</strong> driver. For example, female driversshowed improvements in negative att<strong>it</strong>udes w<strong>it</strong>h general driving experience,but males showed only modest improvements w<strong>it</strong>h general driving experienceand instead showed large changes w<strong>it</strong>h motorcycling experience. Although


What is a moral model?15an extremely relevant area when <strong>it</strong> comes to moral models, more researchwill be needed to establish the impact, and mechanism <strong>of</strong> impact, <strong>of</strong> having amotorcycling relative (or motorcycling experience) on car drivers’ interactionsw<strong>it</strong>h motorcyclists.In this paper, we remain neutral on the question <strong>of</strong> the wider role potentiallyplayed by moral models in anticipation and <strong>other</strong> areas in which automaticprocessing seems likely to play a dominant role. Similar questions to thoseraised here about stereotypes may be raised about the relevance <strong>of</strong> the moralevaluations we will discuss in the next section to <strong>road</strong> safety. As one cyclistcommented on a presentation <strong>of</strong> our earlier research w<strong>it</strong>h cyclists and <strong>other</strong><strong>road</strong> <strong>users</strong>: ‘I don’t care if they <strong>think</strong> I should be there, so long as they see meand don’t h<strong>it</strong> me.’ We will not explore possible but speculative responses tothis challenge here.Instead, we would like to focus on the role played by a moral model, includingthe part that concerns the psychological characteristics <strong>of</strong> different types <strong>of</strong><strong>road</strong> user, in explaining and evaluating <strong>other</strong> <strong>road</strong> <strong>users</strong>’ behaviour. Indeed thisuse is for us the defining feature <strong>of</strong> a moral model.Moral characteristicsThe attribution <strong>of</strong> psychological characteristics – things like goals, motivations,intentions, att<strong>it</strong>udes or character tra<strong>it</strong>s – delivers one part <strong>of</strong> <strong>what</strong> we need toevaluate <strong>other</strong> <strong>road</strong> <strong>users</strong>’ behaviour: an answer to the question <strong>of</strong> why theydid <strong>what</strong> they did. That leaves the question <strong>of</strong> <strong>what</strong> they ought to have done.The natural way <strong>of</strong> conceptualising people’s views on <strong>what</strong> ought to be doneis in the form <strong>of</strong> rules, and at first sight there may not seem to be muchconnection between the structure <strong>of</strong> the rules and our account <strong>of</strong> a workingmodel <strong>of</strong> types <strong>of</strong> <strong>road</strong> user.Rules, one might argue, are all about the rightness or wrongness <strong>of</strong> behaviours:they are more like the att<strong>it</strong>udes in the Theory <strong>of</strong> Planned Behaviour than theatt<strong>it</strong>udes that underpin stereotypes. If we want a simple picture <strong>of</strong> how peoplestore their views on <strong>what</strong> ought to be done, wouldn’t <strong>it</strong> make more sense toimagine a sort <strong>of</strong> private Highway Code in their heads?The best response to this line <strong>of</strong> argument is provided by the contents page <strong>of</strong>the real Highway Code, the online version <strong>of</strong> which starts as follows:‘Rules for pedestriansRules for <strong>users</strong> <strong>of</strong> powered wheelchairs and mobil<strong>it</strong>y scootersRules about animalsRules for cyclistsRules for motorcyclistsRules for drivers and motorcyclists’


16<strong>Road</strong> <strong>sharing</strong> - <strong>does</strong> <strong>it</strong> <strong>matter</strong> <strong>what</strong> <strong>road</strong> <strong>users</strong> <strong>think</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>each</strong> <strong>other</strong>?Our contention is simply that <strong>it</strong> is reasonable to imagine that people’s views onwho ought to be where and doing <strong>what</strong> are structured in a similar way, aroundtypes <strong>of</strong> <strong>road</strong> user. The types in question may, <strong>of</strong> course, be more granularthan those above: for instance, observed behaviour suggests that the models<strong>of</strong> drivers <strong>of</strong> black taxi cabs in London contain a number <strong>of</strong> prescriptions whichapply only to their interactions w<strong>it</strong>h <strong>other</strong> such taxi drivers. In principle, <strong>it</strong> ispossible that some types may not be linked to vehicle types at all, though <strong>it</strong> isharder to imagine examples here.Of course, the rules that any individual attaches to different types <strong>of</strong> <strong>road</strong> userin their ‘private Highway Code’ may coincide only partially w<strong>it</strong>h the actualHighway Code.It seems highly probable that this part <strong>of</strong> the moral model also employsan<strong>other</strong> kind <strong>of</strong> typology – types <strong>of</strong> place. Just as planners distinguish betweenurban rooms and urban corridors, or public spaces and highways, so we mayassume that people apply different rules in different places. Again, these rulesmay not coincide w<strong>it</strong>h the actual infrastructure: consider, for example, thede facto semi-pedestrianisation <strong>of</strong> parts <strong>of</strong> Soho and Covent Garden inCentral London.As well as prescribing behaviour, we suggest that this part <strong>of</strong> a moral modelcan be seen as establishing the relative rights and responsibil<strong>it</strong>ies <strong>of</strong> different<strong>road</strong> <strong>users</strong> that underpin those prescriptions. At the beginning <strong>of</strong> this report, westated that to establish whether the outcome <strong>of</strong> interaction is fair, we first have toask whether <strong>what</strong> people wanted was reasonable in the first place. We suggestthat <strong>it</strong> is this part <strong>of</strong> the moral model that underpins an individual’s evaluation <strong>of</strong>the claims made by all those <strong>road</strong> <strong>users</strong> on the <strong>road</strong> they are all using.Moral characteristics and automatic processingAs noted above, we remain neutral on the question<strong>of</strong> the wider impact <strong>of</strong> a person’s moral modelin areas such as automatic processing:and this neutral<strong>it</strong>y applies asmuch to moral evaluations as topsychological explanations.At first sight, the case for moralevaluations having an impact on automaticprocessing seems even weaker than thecase for stereotypes having such an impact.As one cyclist commented on a presentation <strong>of</strong>our earlier research w<strong>it</strong>h cyclists and<strong>other</strong> <strong>road</strong> <strong>users</strong>: ‘I don’t care if they<strong>think</strong> I should be there, so long asthey see me and don’t h<strong>it</strong> me.’


What is a moral model?17Nevertheless, there are interesting questions to explore here. There is goodreason to believe that our sense <strong>of</strong> <strong>what</strong> people should do is shaped by ourobservation <strong>of</strong> <strong>what</strong> people do in fact do (a point to which we will returnlater); even if our moral expectations do not directly influence our predictiveexpectations, they may share a common cause w<strong>it</strong>h them. Like stereotypes,moral evaluations may also have an impact on emotions, w<strong>it</strong>h unknown furtherconsequences on the <strong>road</strong>.Saints, villains and victimsA moral model, we have suggested, comprises two parts:• The first links types <strong>of</strong> people to psychological characteristics which can beinvoked in the explanation <strong>of</strong> their behaviour.• The second links types <strong>of</strong> <strong>road</strong> user to rules, responsibil<strong>it</strong>ies, rights andleg<strong>it</strong>imate claims, in the context <strong>of</strong> different types <strong>of</strong> place.There is no reason to suppose that these two typologies coincide perfectly: infact there are good reasons to suppose they will not. Car driver stereotypes,for instance, may be influenced by factors such as the make <strong>of</strong> car, but <strong>it</strong> ishard to imagine someone <strong>other</strong> than Jeremy Clarkson arguing that the drivers<strong>of</strong> some makes <strong>of</strong> car have different rights or responsibil<strong>it</strong>ies as a result. Othertypes, such as a hybrid car driver, may cut across both typologies for somepeople but not for <strong>other</strong>s.Nevertheless, the two typologies clearly intersect, and in their intersection liesthe potential for a range <strong>of</strong> saints, villains and victims.Consider an obvious example: the wh<strong>it</strong>e van man. Back in 1999, in responseto research commissioned by Renault UK which sought to expose this‘gross caricature <strong>of</strong> real<strong>it</strong>y’, the BBC helpfully decided to find some driverswho demurred:One driver told the BBC (1999): ‘They come right up behind youfrom behind and flash at you if you don’t move out <strong>of</strong> the way.’An<strong>other</strong> said: ‘They tend to be on the whole chauvinist pigs thatdon’t look out for cars and pull out at every opportun<strong>it</strong>y.’Caricatures such as these describe attributed psychological characteristics <strong>of</strong>the <strong>road</strong> <strong>users</strong> being described and the behaviour that is seen from them in thecontexts <strong>of</strong> actual responsibil<strong>it</strong>ies and rights. They s<strong>it</strong> across the two halves <strong>of</strong>the moral model.


18<strong>Road</strong> <strong>sharing</strong> - <strong>does</strong> <strong>it</strong> <strong>matter</strong> <strong>what</strong> <strong>road</strong> <strong>users</strong> <strong>think</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>each</strong> <strong>other</strong>?3. Where do moralmodels come from?This section <strong>of</strong>fers some theoreticalperspectives on the ways in which moralmodels may arise, persist or change in thecontext <strong>of</strong> interaction, drawing on relevanttheoretical perspectives.3.1EmergenceEmergence, consistent behaviour and normsEarlier, we discussed the common s<strong>it</strong>uation in which twopeople walking towards <strong>each</strong> <strong>other</strong> are caught in synchronisedsidestepping. Our working model <strong>of</strong> <strong>other</strong> pedestrians, weargued, tells us nothing about which way <strong>other</strong> people arelikely to step.An<strong>other</strong> way <strong>of</strong> diagnosing the problem here is to say thatwe lack a shared protocol for resolving this s<strong>it</strong>uation. Onthe <strong>road</strong>, by contrast, shared protocols play a fundamentalrole in ensuring that interactions <strong>of</strong> this kind can proceedw<strong>it</strong>hout ‘sidestepping’, for which there may not be time, or<strong>other</strong> failures <strong>of</strong> co-ordination. The most obvious such sharedprotocol in the UK is that everyone drives on the left – but thereare many <strong>other</strong>s.How do people come to share protocols? Recent yearshave seen a growing recogn<strong>it</strong>ion <strong>of</strong> the ways in whichsocial behaviour (along w<strong>it</strong>h the behaviour <strong>of</strong> many <strong>other</strong>complex, interacting systems) spontaneously organises<strong>it</strong>self into patterns. Thanks to basic tendencies amongindividuals to im<strong>it</strong>ate and conform, sometimes backed upw<strong>it</strong>h social mechanisms to punish non-conform<strong>it</strong>y, shared


Where do moral models come from?19protocols emerge w<strong>it</strong>hout anyone setting out to create or promote them. Thephenomenon is ubiqu<strong>it</strong>ous across human behaviour, w<strong>it</strong>h language, culture andfashion being some <strong>of</strong> the more obvious examples.It is in this context that we can talk about norms. Through the mechanismsabove, norms link <strong>what</strong> is normal (<strong>what</strong> most people do) to <strong>what</strong> is normative(<strong>what</strong> people should do). This is why we can explain synchronised sidesteppingin two apparently different ways. Caught in the s<strong>it</strong>uation, I knowne<strong>it</strong>her <strong>what</strong> the <strong>other</strong> person will do (<strong>what</strong> is normal) nor <strong>what</strong> I should do(<strong>what</strong> is normative): there is no norm.A useful concept here is that <strong>of</strong> a dynamic equilibrium: a persistent state <strong>of</strong> asystem in which the individual parts are constantly in flux. The innumerablecomplex interactions that occur on the <strong>road</strong>s every day occur in such a state <strong>of</strong>dynamic equilibrium, which the norms <strong>of</strong> the <strong>road</strong> describe. Such equilibria canarise w<strong>it</strong>hout the need for any intervention by an ‘author<strong>it</strong>y’, after which theymay persist, change steadily, or suddenly collapse in response to apparentlysmall changes w<strong>it</strong>hin them.It is plausible, if unproven, that the spontaneous emergence and maintenance<strong>of</strong> norms lies behind much <strong>of</strong> the consistent behaviour we see in humans. It isequally plausible that the same processes are at work on the <strong>road</strong>s.Emergence and moral modelsHow <strong>does</strong> this relate to moral models?Norms do not have to require all people involved to do the same thing, as wasthe case in the example <strong>of</strong> driving on the left. A simple example <strong>of</strong> a norm(or set <strong>of</strong> norms) which <strong>does</strong> not is ‘giving way’, which works preciselybecause the two people involved do different things. Many norms have roles,and so long as <strong>each</strong> party makes the same allocation <strong>of</strong> all the <strong>other</strong> playersto those roles (aided, for instance, by wh<strong>it</strong>e lines on the <strong>road</strong>), then the normserves as the shared protocol necessary to make the interaction work.


20<strong>Road</strong> <strong>sharing</strong> - <strong>does</strong> <strong>it</strong> <strong>matter</strong> <strong>what</strong> <strong>road</strong> <strong>users</strong> <strong>think</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>each</strong> <strong>other</strong>?Cr<strong>it</strong>ically, for our current purposes, norms may also discriminate (in the morallyneutral sense) between different types <strong>of</strong> <strong>road</strong> user. Indeed, given that they arederived from <strong>what</strong> is normal, they cannot fail to do so: the normal behaviour <strong>of</strong>pedestrians is very unlike the normal behaviour <strong>of</strong> those in cars, for instance.Given this, <strong>it</strong> is not unreasonable to <strong>think</strong> <strong>of</strong> the norms that describe thedynamic equilibrium state <strong>of</strong> interaction on the <strong>road</strong>s as a form <strong>of</strong> collectivemoral model.Strengths and weaknessesThis account has a lot <strong>of</strong> intu<strong>it</strong>ive plausibil<strong>it</strong>y. It has two apparentconsequences which might give us pause for thought, however:• On the one hand, the account seems to imply that – at least so long as adynamic equilibrium state is maintained – everyone using the <strong>road</strong>s will havethe same moral model.• If the dynamic equilibrium state collapsed or fragmented, and people startedbehaving in many different ways, this would imply not the existence <strong>of</strong> manydifferent sets <strong>of</strong> norms but the existence <strong>of</strong> none: there would be no ‘normal’behaviour any more.Ideas around emergence help to explain how the behaviour <strong>of</strong> people on the<strong>road</strong> can be coordinated through the existence <strong>of</strong> common norms and moralmodels, but they do not seem well su<strong>it</strong>ed to explaining how people might endup w<strong>it</strong>h different moral models.3.2Social Ident<strong>it</strong>y TheoryIn-groups and out-groupsSocial Ident<strong>it</strong>y Theory provides an alternative account <strong>of</strong> how moral modelsmight emerge which potentially addresses some <strong>of</strong> the gaps in the accountbased on emergence.At the heart <strong>of</strong> the theory lies the experimental observation that people have astrong tendency to classify groups to which they belong (in-groups) as beingbetter than groups to which they do not belong (out-groups).This effect is manifest in a number <strong>of</strong> ways, and can occur even when groups aredefined by much looser characteristics than those that bind <strong>road</strong> user groupstogether. For example <strong>it</strong> has been shown that group membership can influencevarious behaviours towards out-groups (for example assignment <strong>of</strong> winnings ingames) even when such membership is based on random assignment at thebeginning <strong>of</strong> the study; participants are aware <strong>of</strong> the accidental manner in which‘their group’ has been formed and yet they still show preferential behaviourtowards members <strong>of</strong> their group, and adverse behaviour towards <strong>other</strong>s.


Where do moral models come from?21Findings from Musselwh<strong>it</strong>e et al. (2008) are again relevant here; <strong>it</strong> was foundthat although almost all car drivers sometimes have a non-driver ident<strong>it</strong>y onthe <strong>road</strong> (e.g. pedestrian, cyclist), in terms <strong>of</strong> their views about <strong>road</strong> safetyand behaviours they tend to default to seeing things from a car driver’s point<strong>of</strong> view, and in any case only activate one <strong>of</strong> their ‘ident<strong>it</strong>ies’ (or in-groups) atany one time. Musselwh<strong>it</strong>e et al. also found that people tend to <strong>think</strong> that <strong>road</strong>safety decreases w<strong>it</strong>h increasing interaction between different types <strong>of</strong> <strong>road</strong>user, and that the <strong>road</strong> space is seen almost universally as a place for cars.Interestingly, people were also asked about particular interventions to increase<strong>road</strong> safety, and the ‘shared-space’ concept was one <strong>of</strong> these. In general,people were sceptical <strong>of</strong> the practical<strong>it</strong>y <strong>of</strong> shared-space approaches, on thegrounds that such a concept could not work w<strong>it</strong>hin the driving culture in theUK: the idea that drivers who were unwilling to give up their ‘dominance’ <strong>of</strong> the<strong>road</strong> space could turn <strong>it</strong> into a ‘free for all’ was <strong>of</strong>fered as one example <strong>of</strong> this.Musselwh<strong>it</strong>e et al. suggested that the reason for this lack <strong>of</strong> support for theconcept is rooted partly in the mindset that safety is all about segregation <strong>of</strong>different types <strong>of</strong> <strong>road</strong> <strong>users</strong>.Such evidence is – we would argue – one reason why we need furtherunderstanding <strong>of</strong> moral models. How can we promote cross-modal moralmodels that are not built on an assumption <strong>of</strong> a level <strong>of</strong> segregation which isimpractical on modern urban <strong>road</strong>s?Emergence and Social Ident<strong>it</strong>y Theory comparedUnlike the account based on emergence, Social Ident<strong>it</strong>y Theory points towarda world in which different moral models would be the rule. In fact, on thisaccount, <strong>it</strong> is the possibil<strong>it</strong>y <strong>of</strong> different groups having the same moral modelthat seems in need <strong>of</strong> explanation.As a theory, Social Ident<strong>it</strong>y Theory also seems better su<strong>it</strong>ed to describing somegroups <strong>of</strong> <strong>road</strong> <strong>users</strong> than <strong>other</strong>s, owing to the importance <strong>it</strong> places on anindividual identifying as a member <strong>of</strong> a specific group. It is plausible to suggestthat drivers <strong>of</strong> black cabs in London, for instance, strongly identify as such,and that this might help to explain their preferential treatment <strong>of</strong> <strong>other</strong> such taxidrivers (by letting them out, for instance). There are clearly also some peoplewho identify in an equally strong way as cyclists, or motorcyclists, or cardrivers. But there are surely many <strong>other</strong>s – a major<strong>it</strong>y, we would argue – whodo not identify in this way w<strong>it</strong>h their mode <strong>of</strong> transport.3.3Combining the two frameworksA plausible storyGiven their respective strengths and weaknesses, a combination <strong>of</strong> emergenceand Social Ident<strong>it</strong>y Theory holds out some promise as a theoretical frameworkfor understanding the origins <strong>of</strong> moral models. The easiest way to present thiscombined theory is as a simple story.


22<strong>Road</strong> <strong>sharing</strong> - <strong>does</strong> <strong>it</strong> <strong>matter</strong> <strong>what</strong> <strong>road</strong> <strong>users</strong> <strong>think</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>each</strong> <strong>other</strong>?Imagine a c<strong>it</strong>y in which, thanks to the processes <strong>of</strong> emergence, a stabledynamic equilibrium exists on the <strong>road</strong>s. While stable, however, there isnothing to say that a dynamic equilibrium has to be especially fair – as theexistence <strong>of</strong> hierarchical and unequal societies throughout human historyattests. Norms can discriminate in the morally charged sense too.Of course, most people w<strong>it</strong>hin that equilibrium, judging <strong>it</strong>s outcomes by themoral model that derives from <strong>it</strong>, will judge that <strong>it</strong> is fair – by defin<strong>it</strong>ion. But afew may be unhappy: the overall equilibrium <strong>of</strong> the system is consistent w<strong>it</strong>hnoise and irregular<strong>it</strong>y w<strong>it</strong>hin <strong>it</strong>.Now suppose that something happens to destabilise the equilibrium state. Forinstance, there might be an increase in the numbers <strong>of</strong> a type <strong>of</strong> <strong>road</strong> useramong whom unhappiness is more common. At this point, <strong>it</strong> seems qu<strong>it</strong>epossible that the processes described by Social Interaction Theory might kickin to bind a number <strong>of</strong> unhappy individuals into a cohesive ‘in-group’ w<strong>it</strong>h theirown distinctive and different moral model.What would happen next? The theories themselves do not tell us: a newdynamic equilibrium state (new norms) might appear, or the old one mightsuddenly collapse w<strong>it</strong>hout anything replacing <strong>it</strong>, or any <strong>of</strong> a number <strong>of</strong>possibil<strong>it</strong>ies. Of course, if the account above is an accurate description <strong>of</strong>London, w<strong>it</strong>h the part <strong>of</strong> unhappy <strong>road</strong> <strong>users</strong> played by cyclists, then we willfind out in the years ahead.What about the law?One piece <strong>of</strong> the jigsaw that is obviously missing from the account above is thedefin<strong>it</strong>ive statement <strong>of</strong> <strong>what</strong> people should actually do on the <strong>road</strong>s: the law.Nor is the law just wr<strong>it</strong>ten down: <strong>road</strong> <strong>users</strong> get trained in the rules, marketedat to encourage conform<strong>it</strong>y w<strong>it</strong>h them, and punished if they break them. Theyare surrounded by infrastructure and signage which reinforces the rules andcommunicates <strong>what</strong> they are meant to do.It seems unlikely that all this activ<strong>it</strong>y has no effect at all on people’s moralmodels. Some norms today may have started out life as laws – though thereverse also holds true: we drove on the left before anyone thought <strong>of</strong> turningthe norm into a law.What kind <strong>of</strong> effect such activ<strong>it</strong>y has may depend on whether <strong>it</strong>s prevailingdirection runs w<strong>it</strong>h or against the grain <strong>of</strong> people’s existing moral models. Justas moral models underpin judgements about the claims <strong>of</strong> <strong>other</strong> <strong>road</strong> <strong>users</strong>and the success <strong>of</strong> interaction, <strong>it</strong> seems reasonable to assume they will alsoinfluence people’s response to and acceptance <strong>of</strong> new interventions.


23<strong>Road</strong> <strong>sharing</strong> - <strong>does</strong> <strong>it</strong> <strong>matter</strong> <strong>what</strong> <strong>road</strong> <strong>users</strong> <strong>think</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>each</strong> <strong>other</strong>?4. Why study moral models?Moral models are clearly involved in individuals’evaluations <strong>of</strong> the success <strong>of</strong> interaction on the<strong>road</strong>. As we noted in the Introduction, however,those whose job <strong>it</strong> is to make policies, designinterventions and commission research havetheir own goals and defin<strong>it</strong>ions <strong>of</strong> successfulinteraction. Even if the ideas presented inSections 2 and 3 were substantiated in theirentirety, we would still have to ask: ‘so <strong>what</strong>?’In this section, we turn to question <strong>of</strong> whethermoral models are things that policy-makers andpract<strong>it</strong>ioners need to worry about. Is <strong>it</strong> worthstudying moral models, and <strong>what</strong> kinds <strong>of</strong>studies would be valuable?4.1Changing behaviourChanging moral models to change behaviourOne obvious rationale for studying moral models would be tosupply the evidence base for behaviour change interventionsfocused on changing moral models. Such interventions wouldrequire both understanding <strong>of</strong> how moral models influencebehaviour, and understanding <strong>of</strong> how moral models in turn canbe influenced.


Why study moral models?24While the term ‘moral model’ may be a new one, there are precedents forinterventions which operate at least in part in this kind <strong>of</strong> terr<strong>it</strong>ory. The Think!Named Riders campaign mentioned earlier, for example, aims to get drivers to<strong>think</strong> differently about motorcyclists, drawing on evidence <strong>of</strong> how this will inturn influence behaviour. This general approach is not new. For example the AAworked in the 1990s, w<strong>it</strong>h the Cyclists’ Touring Club and the UK Departmentfor Transport, to develop a leaflet called ‘Drive Safe, Cycle Safe’ (1994). Thiswork was built on the observation that many drivers are also cyclists.More widely, there are a number <strong>of</strong> examples <strong>of</strong> campaigns which have soughtto change behaviour by changing a perception <strong>of</strong> the rights and responsibil<strong>it</strong>iessurrounding that behaviour – for instance, the Julie campaign to encourageseatbelt wearing in the rear seat or, outside the world <strong>of</strong> <strong>road</strong> safety, the shiftin anti-smoking campaigning to an emphasis on the impact <strong>of</strong> smoke on<strong>other</strong> people.The idea <strong>of</strong> changing moral models as a way <strong>of</strong> changing behaviour should not,we believe, be a controversial one in principle.The more difficult question is: in which areas is this a promising approach tobehaviour change in practice, one that seems likely to have impact and istherefore worthy <strong>of</strong> attention and investment?<strong>Road</strong> safetyAs the discussion in Section 2 made clear, our view is that the case for oragainst studying moral models in a purely <strong>road</strong> safety context remains to bemade. Making such a case will require a better understanding <strong>of</strong> how moralmodels are actually realised in the brain, and how and when they are used.It may also depend on our asking different questions about the causes <strong>of</strong>accidents when we track them. For instance, we noted in Section 2 that oneroute through which moral models might have an influence on <strong>road</strong> safety


25<strong>Road</strong> <strong>sharing</strong> - <strong>does</strong> <strong>it</strong> <strong>matter</strong> <strong>what</strong> <strong>road</strong> <strong>users</strong> <strong>think</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>each</strong> <strong>other</strong>?issues is via emotion, but we know l<strong>it</strong>tle about the direct role played byemotions in accidents, beyond a general acceptance that some emotionalstates (e.g. anger) are incompatible w<strong>it</strong>h <strong>road</strong> safety outcomes because theycan lead to unsafe behaviours such as speeding. The prior<strong>it</strong>isation <strong>of</strong> <strong>road</strong>safety issues at the practical level is (sensibly) driven by <strong>road</strong> safety statistics;statistics about <strong>road</strong> accidents are (necessarily) confined to those things whichcan be recorded at the crash scene. As a result, factors which are harder orimpossible to record in such a way as to link them to crash outcomes (suchas emotion) are much less likely to be studied except w<strong>it</strong>hin the commun<strong>it</strong>y <strong>of</strong>scientists engaged in more basic research.It is worth noting, <strong>of</strong> course, that the same points could have been madeabout many <strong>other</strong> ‘basic research’ issues in the past – and that work on theseissues has since led to practical outcomes. For example, an understanding<strong>of</strong> the basic perceptual processing challenges faced when looking out formotorcyclists at junctions has led to meaningful practical interventions in terms<strong>of</strong> media campaigns designed to raise awareness <strong>of</strong> these issues in motorists.Examples include the current Think! Named Riders Campaign, and a Transportfor London (TfL) campaign <strong>of</strong> 2008 based on Horswill et al. (2005). (SeeCrundall et al. (2008b) for a review <strong>of</strong> the different perceptual and att<strong>it</strong>udinalprocesses around this issue.)Note also that the study <strong>of</strong> moral models has a far more straightforwardapplication when we turn to the acceptabil<strong>it</strong>y <strong>of</strong> interventions intended toimprove <strong>road</strong> safety, such as improvements to infrastructure. We discuss thispoint further in Section 4.2.Undesirable behaviourWhereas the impact <strong>of</strong> moral models on the mechanics <strong>of</strong> avoiding collisionsis questionable, there is a stronger prima facie case that moral models areimplicated in various kinds <strong>of</strong> behaviours that are undesirable in themselves –such as aggression and anti-social behaviour on the <strong>road</strong>.Changing moral models therefore seems promising as a route to changing thiskind <strong>of</strong> behaviour. The kind <strong>of</strong> studies required to underpin such interventionsis also relatively clear-cut: research which correlates moral models and actualbehaviours.Of course, that leaves unanswered the question <strong>of</strong> which behaviours oneactually wants to change. This question raises issues about the correct scope<strong>of</strong> intervention by author<strong>it</strong>ies – the lim<strong>it</strong>s <strong>of</strong> their responsibil<strong>it</strong>ies and rightsas one <strong>of</strong> the agents involved in the interaction on the <strong>road</strong>s – that clearly gobeyond the scope <strong>of</strong> e<strong>it</strong>her this report or research into moral models.An understanding <strong>of</strong> moral models <strong>does</strong>, however, provide a useful frameworkfor <strong>think</strong>ing about a familiar challenge that arises in this area: deciding <strong>what</strong>counts as anti-social in the first place. Different people w<strong>it</strong>h different moral


Why study moral models?26models will take different views on this (consider the example <strong>of</strong> team cyclingin the Introduction). In the absence <strong>of</strong> unanim<strong>it</strong>y, author<strong>it</strong>ies face the difficultchallenge <strong>of</strong> fixing their own moral model, in the firm knowledge that <strong>it</strong> cannotpossibly please everyone. While having an understanding <strong>of</strong> <strong>what</strong> <strong>road</strong> <strong>users</strong>currently <strong>think</strong> <strong>does</strong> not solve this challenge, <strong>it</strong> <strong>does</strong> provide crucial evidenceagainst which a judgement can be made. We discuss this point further inSection 4.2.What is also clear is that author<strong>it</strong>ies cannot simply duck the issue <strong>of</strong> fixingtheir own moral model. Every time the lights are re-phased or the streets laidout differently, the changes communicate (implic<strong>it</strong>ly) an evaluation (coherent or<strong>other</strong>wise) <strong>of</strong> the relative claims <strong>of</strong> different <strong>road</strong> <strong>users</strong> on the street. A betterunderstanding <strong>of</strong> the moral models held by different <strong>road</strong> <strong>users</strong> will help inthe planning <strong>of</strong> such changes, and the explic<strong>it</strong> communications that may beneeded to help facil<strong>it</strong>ate a better public acceptance.Health, environment and mobil<strong>it</strong>yA second area where the study <strong>of</strong> moral models seems promising is as part <strong>of</strong>the effort to achieve b<strong>road</strong>er policy objectives – better public health, improvedmobil<strong>it</strong>y, enhanced economic efficiency, reduced environmental impact – bychanging patterns <strong>of</strong> <strong>road</strong> use.For instance, mode choice is cr<strong>it</strong>ical across all <strong>of</strong> the above areas, and modechoice, unlike the mechanics <strong>of</strong> avoiding collisions, is a decision that caninvolve deliberation, creating plenty <strong>of</strong> time for moral models to come into play.Moreover, there are highly plausible ways in which they do have such animpact. Imagine, for example, that I am making a decision about whether tostart cycling. We know from many different studies that perceptions <strong>of</strong> safetywill rank high in my decision; one factor in my perception <strong>of</strong> safety is myevaluation <strong>of</strong> the behaviour <strong>of</strong> <strong>other</strong> <strong>road</strong> <strong>users</strong>. Moral models impact on thisevaluation in two distinct ways:• First, the moral models <strong>of</strong> <strong>other</strong> <strong>road</strong> <strong>users</strong> will influence their behaviourin ways which shape my evaluation <strong>of</strong> them. Put simply, if I see cases<strong>of</strong> drivers behaving aggressively towards cyclists or cutting them <strong>of</strong>f atjunctions, I may be less likely to start cycling myself. Note that <strong>it</strong> <strong>does</strong>not <strong>matter</strong> whether these s<strong>it</strong>uations are actually unsafe, because <strong>it</strong> is myperception <strong>of</strong> safety – whether I <strong>think</strong> I would feel unsafe if I were on thebike – that <strong>matter</strong>s.• Secondly, my own moral model will shape how I interpret the behaviour <strong>of</strong><strong>other</strong>s <strong>what</strong>ever they are actually doing. If I believe that ‘<strong>it</strong>’s war out there’,I am more likely to anticipate interacting w<strong>it</strong>h aggressive and selfish driversthan if I believe that ‘drivers in London are very considerate’.


27<strong>Road</strong> <strong>sharing</strong> - <strong>does</strong> <strong>it</strong> <strong>matter</strong> <strong>what</strong> <strong>road</strong> <strong>users</strong> <strong>think</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>each</strong> <strong>other</strong>?Changing moral models could be a powerful tool for those seeking b<strong>road</strong>erchanges in patterns <strong>of</strong> <strong>road</strong> use. In this case, however, the tricky question maybe establishing whose moral model needs to change.Research implicationsTo identify opportun<strong>it</strong>ies to change behaviour by changing moral models, weneed evidence <strong>of</strong> the behavioural consequences <strong>of</strong> different moral models.At the simplest level, this means investigating the connections between havinga moral model and particular behaviours – such as driving aggressively, orchoosing to travel by bicycle. Note that, as well as establishing correlations, <strong>it</strong>would also be important to investigate the direction <strong>of</strong> any causal relationship.As the examples above make clear, however, there would also be valuein investigating the consequences <strong>of</strong> behaviours which are themselvesconsequences <strong>of</strong> moral models: for instance, <strong>does</strong> the aggressive behaviourdeter <strong>other</strong>s from choosing to travel by bicycle?4.2Understanding the ‘customer’What <strong>road</strong> <strong>users</strong> wantBehaviour-change approaches conceptualise <strong>road</strong>s as the s<strong>it</strong>e <strong>of</strong> policyrelevantbehaviour. But <strong>road</strong>s are also a service, provided for <strong>road</strong> <strong>users</strong> andpaid for by them through various forms <strong>of</strong> taxation. From this service-provisionstandpoint, knowing <strong>what</strong> <strong>road</strong> <strong>users</strong> want is an end in <strong>it</strong>self.The trad<strong>it</strong>ional consultation approach – sending people plans and askingwhether they would prefer a speed hump or a bollard – expects ordinaryc<strong>it</strong>izens to make expert judgements about the potential impact <strong>of</strong> various types<strong>of</strong> infrastructure or intervention on the thing they are more likely to care about:the success <strong>of</strong> their everyday interactions w<strong>it</strong>h the <strong>road</strong> system, and w<strong>it</strong>h<strong>other</strong> <strong>road</strong> <strong>users</strong>. It seems to us that people are ne<strong>it</strong>her equipped nor (<strong>of</strong>ten)motivated to respond to questions such as these.So why not ask about the thing people care about instead?Moral models provide a framework for asking people questions that mightactually make sense to them. Rather than asking <strong>what</strong> a <strong>road</strong> should look like,we should ask how people should interact on <strong>it</strong> – who should and shouldn’t bewhere, <strong>what</strong> they should and shouldn’t be doing. Consultation approaches thatfocus on these topics are, essentially, researching people’s moral models.Of course, the experts would still be left w<strong>it</strong>h the challenge <strong>of</strong> developingsolutions that would deliver <strong>what</strong> people wanted. In this they might fail. But atleast they would then be cr<strong>it</strong>icised for failing to get the solution right – and notfor failing to listen to <strong>what</strong> people want in the first place.


Why study moral models?28Acceptance <strong>of</strong> interventionsAs noted in Section 4.1, author<strong>it</strong>ies – and the individual policy-makers andpract<strong>it</strong>ioners that work in them – have their own more or less explic<strong>it</strong> andcoherent moral models, articulated to <strong>road</strong> <strong>users</strong> by the phasing <strong>of</strong> lights,the lay-out <strong>of</strong> the street, the prior<strong>it</strong>ies <strong>of</strong> traffic police, the semiotics <strong>of</strong>communications, and in countless <strong>other</strong> ways.Understanding the different moral models <strong>of</strong> <strong>road</strong> <strong>users</strong> gives all <strong>of</strong> us, asindividuals working w<strong>it</strong>h our own moral models, a way <strong>of</strong> seeing the <strong>road</strong>sfrom <strong>other</strong> perspectives, and anticipating things that to us seem obvious butto <strong>other</strong>s prove objectionable.Research implicationsAs part <strong>of</strong> the process <strong>of</strong> understanding <strong>what</strong> <strong>road</strong> <strong>users</strong> want and will accept,we need a better understanding <strong>of</strong> the different moral models that exist andwho holds them.This means identifying key dimensions which can be used to distinguishbetween moral models, and investigating how differences along thesedimensions correlate w<strong>it</strong>h <strong>other</strong> key differences (such as age or primary mode<strong>of</strong> transport).In the longer term, <strong>it</strong> could mean developing a segmentation based on thesedimensions and differences.4.3Understanding the evolving culture <strong>of</strong> <strong>road</strong> useOne reason why undesirable behaviour on the <strong>road</strong> might <strong>matter</strong>is that some <strong>of</strong> <strong>it</strong> may prove, almost l<strong>it</strong>erally, ‘infectious’.Consider, for example, recent experiments by Keizer inthe Netherlands (Keizer et al., 2008). In one experiment,passers-by were tempted w<strong>it</strong>h a 5 note protruding froman envelope which was <strong>it</strong>self sticking out <strong>of</strong> a letterbox.Twice as many passers-by stole the money if the mailboxwas daubed w<strong>it</strong>h graff<strong>it</strong>i or surrounded w<strong>it</strong>h l<strong>it</strong>ter. Similareffects were observed when the researchers left shoppingtrolleys around or padlocked cycles to railings illegally, w<strong>it</strong>hpeople more likely to do things like l<strong>it</strong>ter or take an illegalshort-cut. Cialdini’s work (2003) on descriptive norms is alsorelevant here: the basic argument is that if people perceive thatan undesirable behaviour (e.g. l<strong>it</strong>tering) is nonetheless common,people are more likely to do <strong>it</strong>.


29<strong>Road</strong> <strong>sharing</strong> - <strong>does</strong> <strong>it</strong> <strong>matter</strong> <strong>what</strong> <strong>road</strong> <strong>users</strong> <strong>think</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>each</strong> <strong>other</strong>?This is still a relatively new field <strong>of</strong> research, and <strong>it</strong> would be rash to draw firmconclusions. It seems reasonable, however, to link evidence like this to thediscussion, in Section 3, <strong>of</strong> how norms link the normal w<strong>it</strong>h the normative. Inthat section, we considered two theoretical perspectives on how moral models(and, w<strong>it</strong>h them, behaviour) might change over time across an entire population<strong>of</strong> interacting <strong>road</strong> <strong>users</strong>.We will almost certainly never be able to predict how the culture <strong>of</strong> interaction onthe <strong>road</strong>s will evolve over time, but a better understanding <strong>of</strong> the moral trendsand conflicts that already exist may enable us to spot both opportun<strong>it</strong>ies tonudge the system in a desired direction, and threats to be tracked and managed.Is the behaviour <strong>of</strong> cyclists crossing red lights in London creating a new set <strong>of</strong>norms which more equ<strong>it</strong>ably shares the <strong>road</strong> between different types <strong>of</strong> <strong>road</strong><strong>users</strong>, or dangerously eroding the rule <strong>of</strong> law on the <strong>road</strong>? Only time will tell.But if we knew how the moral models <strong>of</strong> everyone on the <strong>road</strong> were evolvingas a result, we might have some clues as to which outcome is more likely, andsome indication <strong>of</strong> <strong>what</strong> to do.Research implicationsAs a contribution to our understanding <strong>of</strong> the evolving culture <strong>of</strong> <strong>road</strong> use, weneed to track how moral models change over time – in individuals and acrossentire populations.


30<strong>Road</strong> <strong>sharing</strong> - <strong>does</strong> <strong>it</strong> <strong>matter</strong> <strong>what</strong> <strong>road</strong> <strong>users</strong> <strong>think</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>each</strong> <strong>other</strong>?5. ConclusionThe aim <strong>of</strong> this report is to inform the RACFoundation about the existing knowledge baseon <strong>road</strong> <strong>sharing</strong>. Potential areas for researchidentified in advance were:• Understand how behaviours <strong>of</strong> different <strong>road</strong> <strong>users</strong> can bemore successfully co-ordinated so that ‘conflicts’ are reliablyand successfully resolved.• Shed light on how different <strong>road</strong> <strong>users</strong> see and judge <strong>each</strong><strong>other</strong> to help policy and practice to take action on themisunderstandings that happen between <strong>road</strong> <strong>users</strong>, whichcan lead to ‘conflict’.• Understand how traffic law and infrastructure designed tohelp resolve conflict between <strong>users</strong> can be improved bytaking account <strong>of</strong> the ‘lore’ <strong>of</strong> the <strong>road</strong>.• Establish how views on and perceptions <strong>of</strong> fairnessinfluence user att<strong>it</strong>udes about <strong>other</strong> modes and theprovision <strong>of</strong> infrastructure• Establish how efficiency is viewed by the different <strong>road</strong><strong>users</strong> and <strong>what</strong> implications this has for developingshared networks.


Conclusion31In this report we have identified the topic <strong>of</strong> <strong>road</strong> <strong>users</strong>’ moral models as asensible focus for research w<strong>it</strong>hin this b<strong>road</strong> field. We hope that, in doing so,we have made <strong>it</strong> clear both why this would represent innovation in research,and how studying this topic would have implications for practice.Our discussion <strong>of</strong> moral models, while based on evidence and theory where wehave found <strong>it</strong>, has had to draw on common sense to fill in gaps where evidenceand theory are lacking. A prior<strong>it</strong>y for any research in this area has to be to startaddressing these gaps and, in so doing, refine and replace the framework wehave presented in this report.Over and above that, we have identified a number <strong>of</strong> <strong>other</strong> areas in whichresearch would be valuable:• Identifying key dimensions which can be used to distinguish betweenmoral models.• Investigating how differences along these dimensions correlate w<strong>it</strong>h <strong>other</strong>key differences (such as age or primary mode <strong>of</strong> transport).• Building the evidence base for the behavioural consequences <strong>of</strong> differentmoral models.• Tracking how moral models change over time – in individuals and acrossentire populations.While these tasks are clearly beyond the scope <strong>of</strong> any single piece <strong>of</strong> research,however large, we do believe that an in<strong>it</strong>ial qual<strong>it</strong>ative study could start toaddress objective 1 and suggest some in<strong>it</strong>ial hypotheses against objectives2 and 3.


32<strong>Road</strong> <strong>sharing</strong> - <strong>does</strong> <strong>it</strong> <strong>matter</strong> <strong>what</strong> <strong>road</strong> <strong>users</strong> <strong>think</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>each</strong> <strong>other</strong>?6ReferencesAA, Cyclists’ Touring Club & Department for Transport (1994). Drive Safe, CycleSafe. (Leaflet available from the Department for Transport.)Basford, L., Reid, S., Lester, T., Thomson, J. & Tolmie, A. (2002). Drivers’perceptions <strong>of</strong> cyclists (TRL549).Br<strong>it</strong>ish B<strong>road</strong>casting Corporation (1999). Rude wh<strong>it</strong>e van man ‘a myth’. BBCNews Online, 13 January. Retrieved 15 December 2010 from http://news.bbc.co.uk/1/hi/uk/254271.stmBesley, E. (2010). Kerb Your Enthusiasm. Why shared space <strong>does</strong>n’t alwaysmean shared surface, and <strong>other</strong> stories. PACTS.Brooks, P. & Guppy, A. (1996). Driver awareness and motorcycle accidents.Proceedings <strong>of</strong> the International Motorcycle Safety Conference, 2(10): 27–56.Christmas, S., Helman, S., Buttress, S., Newman, C. & Hutchens, R. (2010).Cycling, Safety and Sharing the <strong>Road</strong>: Qual<strong>it</strong>ative Research w<strong>it</strong>h Cyclists andOther <strong>Road</strong> Users, DfT <strong>Road</strong> Safety Web Publication No.17.Cialdini (2003). Crafting messages to protect the environment. CurrentDirections in Psychological Science, 12: 105–109.Crundall, D., Crundall, E., Clarke, D., & Shahar, A. (in press). Why do car driversviolate the right-<strong>of</strong>-way <strong>of</strong> motorcycles at t-junctions? Accident Analysis andPrevention.Crundall, D. Bibby, P., Clarke, D., Ward, P., & Bartle, C. (2008a). Car drivers’att<strong>it</strong>udes towards motorcyclists: a survey. Accident Analysis and Prevention,40: 983–993.Crundall, D., Clarke, D., Ward, P., and Bartle, C. (2008b). Car drivers’ skills andatt<strong>it</strong>udes to motorcycle safety. London: Department for Transport.Department for Transport (DfT) (2010a). Named Riders campaign. Retrieved 15December 2010 from http://www.dft.gov.uk/<strong>think</strong>/focusareas/motorcycling?page=Campaign.DfT (2010b). <strong>Road</strong> Casualties Great Br<strong>it</strong>ain: 2009. London: DfT.Horswill, M. S. & McKenna, F. P. (2004). Drivers’ hazard perception abil<strong>it</strong>y:s<strong>it</strong>uation awareness on the <strong>road</strong>. In S. Banbury & S. Tremblay (eds.) A cogn<strong>it</strong>iveapproach to s<strong>it</strong>uation awareness: Theory and application (155–175). Aldershot:Ashgate Publishing.


References33Horswill, M. S., Helman, S., Ardiles, P. & Wann, J. P. (2005). Motorcycleaccident risk could be inflated by a time to arrival illusion. Optometry andVision Science, 82(8): 740–746.Kelley, H.H. (1967), Attribution theory in social psychology. In D. Levine (ed.),Nebraska Symposium on Motivation, 15.Keizer, K., Lindenberg, S. & Steg, L. (2008). The Spreading <strong>of</strong> Disorder. Science,322(5908): 1681–1685.Mazzella, R. & Feingold, A. (1994). The Effects <strong>of</strong> Physical Attractiveness, Race,Socioeconomic Status, and Gender <strong>of</strong> Defendants and Victims on Judgments<strong>of</strong> Mock Jurors: A Meta-Analysis. Journal <strong>of</strong> Applied Social Psychology, 24(15):1315–1338.Musselwh<strong>it</strong>e, C., Avineri, E., Susilo, Y., Fulcher, E., Bhattachary, D., Hunter, A. &Stockley, R. (2010). Understanding public att<strong>it</strong>udes to <strong>road</strong> user safety. <strong>Road</strong>Safety Research Report No. 111. London: Department for Transport.Transport for London (2005). Give motorcyclists a second thought campaign.Retrieved 15 December 2010 from http://www.tfl.gov.uk/tfl/corporate/media/newscentre/motorcyclists.shtml.Walker, I. (2005a). <strong>Road</strong> <strong>users</strong>’ perceptions <strong>of</strong> <strong>other</strong> <strong>road</strong> <strong>users</strong>: do differenttransport modes invoke qual<strong>it</strong>atively different concepts in observers?Advances in Transportation Studies an International Journal: Section A, 6.Walker, I. (2005b). Signals are informative but slow down responses whendrivers meet bicyclists at <strong>road</strong> junctions. Accident Analysis and Prevention,37: 1074–1085.


The Royal Automobile Club Foundation for Motoring Lim<strong>it</strong>ed is a char<strong>it</strong>y whichexplores the economic, mobil<strong>it</strong>y, safety and environmental issues relating to <strong>road</strong>sand responsible <strong>road</strong> <strong>users</strong>. Independent and author<strong>it</strong>ative research, carried outfor the public benef<strong>it</strong>, is central to the Foundation’s activ<strong>it</strong>ies.RAC Foundation89-91 Pall MallLondonSW1Y 5HSTel no: 020 7747 3445www.racfoundation.orgRegistered Char<strong>it</strong>y No. 1002705January 2011 © Copyright Royal Automobile Club Foundation for Motoring Lim<strong>it</strong>edDesigned byThe Javelin Partnership LtdTel: 01189 303 123

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!