13.07.2015 Views

Right click here to get the supersized ... - Stephen Kinsella

Right click here to get the supersized ... - Stephen Kinsella

Right click here to get the supersized ... - Stephen Kinsella

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

EC4024 Financial Economics Course PackJan 14, 2008Dr <strong>Stephen</strong> <strong>Kinsella</strong>


Reflections_Leibowitz.fm Page 32 Monday, September 12, 2005 10:56 AMAlpha Hunters and Beta GrazersMartin L. LeibowitzActive alphas arederived fromexploiting acuteand chronicinefficiencies. Theyare hard <strong>to</strong> capture,but <strong>the</strong> greatinves<strong>to</strong>rs have beenable <strong>to</strong> do so overmany, many years.T<strong>here</strong> is a great philosophical divide between passive, efficiencybased“beta grazers” and active “alpha hunters.” The explosivegrowth of hedge funds, of both <strong>the</strong> traditional and <strong>the</strong> long-onlyformat, has contributed <strong>to</strong> this widening chasm between intenselyproactive inves<strong>to</strong>rs and those funds that are indexed or semi-indexed.This Reflections article presents my personal observations on<strong>the</strong> general subject of active investing and on <strong>the</strong> nature, persistence,and discernibility of various market inefficiencies that could give rise<strong>to</strong> such investment opportunities. Ironically, <strong>the</strong>se behavioral biasescan act as frictions as well as opportunities, and this ambiguity mayhelp explain why a few notable inves<strong>to</strong>rs appear <strong>to</strong> be almost continuouslysuccessful while o<strong>the</strong>r active inves<strong>to</strong>rs fall well short of<strong>the</strong>ir alpha tar<strong>get</strong>s.At <strong>the</strong> outset, we should note that t<strong>here</strong> is a middle ground w<strong>here</strong>relatively passive, non-zero-sum forms of alpha return can be found.As described in a series of articles (Leibowitz 2004; Leibowitz andBova 2005a, 2005c), <strong>the</strong>se “allocation alphas” arise because <strong>the</strong> volatilityrisk of typical institutional portfolios is overwhelmingly dominatedby <strong>the</strong>ir home-market equity exposure. By tilting <strong>the</strong>ir strategicallocations <strong>to</strong>ward a more balanced allocation, institutions can oftengarner enhanced expected returns with only modest increases inmarginal volatility. The level of expected benefit obviously dependson <strong>the</strong> institution’s specific return–risk assumptions.Unlike truly active alphas, allocation alphas are broadly accessiblethrough a semipassive process of moving <strong>to</strong>ward an effectivestrategic allocation. As such, <strong>the</strong>y are akin <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> civilized sort ofprotein-seeking found in shopping at <strong>the</strong> local supermarket, with <strong>the</strong>selections determined by personal taste and dietary constraints.These readily available allocation alphas serve a critical and valuablerole in moving a fund <strong>to</strong>ward optimal strategic allocation. Allocationalphas are quite distinct, however, from <strong>the</strong> truly active alphasderived from tracking down—and bagging—<strong>the</strong> fleeting and elusiveopportunities that arise from market inefficiencies. Both forms ofalpha offer <strong>the</strong> potential for enhanced return, and <strong>the</strong>y can sometimesbe combined <strong>to</strong> create exceptional opportunities. They arequite different concepts, however, and are pursued in different ways.Having made this distinction, I focus <strong>the</strong> remainder of this article on<strong>the</strong> truly active-skill-based investments that are intended <strong>to</strong> addalpha above and beyond <strong>the</strong> returns passively available in any assetclass or strategic portfolio.Martin L. Leibowitz is a managing direc<strong>to</strong>r at Morgan Stanley, New York City.32 www.cfapubs.org ©2005, CFA Institute


Reflections_Leibowitz.fm Page 33 Friday, September 9, 2005 4:12 PMTruly Active AlphasMuch of <strong>the</strong> literature on truly active investing hasfocused on so-called anomalies—sources of incrementalreturn that appear <strong>to</strong> have some degree ofpersistence. In addition, a number of elegant formalizationshave been developed for incorporatingactive return–risk prospects in<strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> investmentdecision process (Sharpe 1991; Grinold and Kahn2000; Waring and Siegel 2003; Asness 2004). Thisdiscussion should be broadened, however, <strong>to</strong>include consideration of all frictions and behavioralbiases—persistent as well as occasional—thatmight serve as fundamental sources of inefficiency.Such inefficiencies are not always exploitable: Theymay take <strong>the</strong> form of overshoots at certain timesand undershoots at o<strong>the</strong>r times, <strong>the</strong>ir exploitationmay be blocked by counterforces or technicalrestrictions of various sorts, or <strong>the</strong>y may resolve<strong>the</strong>mselves very slowly—or never.We need <strong>to</strong> understand, however, that <strong>the</strong>sesources of inefficiency are multifold, broad based,and continually renewing <strong>the</strong>mselves. Most importantly,we need <strong>to</strong> understand that <strong>the</strong>y really doexist—even if <strong>the</strong>y are not always available, discernible,or directionally consistent. Such pockets of inefficiencyat times become reasonably discernible andactionable—<strong>to</strong> certain active inves<strong>to</strong>rs. Thus, <strong>the</strong>irvery existence becomes one facet of an argument(albeit an admittedly still incomplete argument) for<strong>the</strong> possibility of successful active investing.Ano<strong>the</strong>r argument (also incomplete) is <strong>the</strong> his<strong>to</strong>ricalfact that a handful of inves<strong>to</strong>rs has producedextraordinary performance over a span of manyyears—often <strong>to</strong><strong>get</strong>her with equally extraordinarycross-sectional success in <strong>the</strong>ir choices of disparateinvestments. The approaches of <strong>the</strong>se greatinves<strong>to</strong>rs—Warren Buffett, Bill Miller, Leon Levy,Dave Swensen, Jack Meyer—differ in numerousaspects, but as pointed out by Peter Bernstein(2005), <strong>the</strong> inves<strong>to</strong>rs share <strong>the</strong> common feature ofnot being in <strong>the</strong> mainstream (i.e., <strong>the</strong>y are all contrariansin one way or ano<strong>the</strong>r). The great onesshare a number of positive characteristics—focus,patience, a clear-cut philosophy, a willingness <strong>to</strong> gobeyond <strong>the</strong> diversification mantra and accept highconcentration risks, an innovation-prone attitude,<strong>the</strong> organizational sponsorship and personal fortitude<strong>to</strong> endure significant periods of underperformance,and a disciplined process for pursuing <strong>the</strong>irgoals. And in various ways and at various pointsin time, <strong>the</strong>y have all been willing <strong>to</strong> stake significantchips on <strong>the</strong>ir convictions.With respect <strong>to</strong> this latter point, one might wellrecall Charles Ellis’s (1998) wonderful characterizationof most inves<strong>to</strong>rs as playing what in tennisparlance is called “<strong>the</strong> loser’s game.” In <strong>the</strong> loser’sgame, weekend players, with <strong>the</strong>ir readily returnableforehands and backhands, square off againsteach o<strong>the</strong>r and <strong>the</strong> one who misses <strong>the</strong> last returnloses. The message is <strong>to</strong> play a consistent game and<strong>to</strong> avoid miss-hits. It is generally good advice for Bplayers—and beta grazers!The great ones, however—in tennis and ininvesting—go one big step beyond. They play adisciplined game until <strong>the</strong> moment <strong>the</strong>y see whatlooks like a grand opportunity. At that moment,<strong>the</strong>y move in<strong>to</strong> carpe diem mode, ga<strong>the</strong>r up <strong>the</strong>irprowess, and take a calculated risk <strong>to</strong> proactivelyand aggressively force a win. 1Even <strong>the</strong> great Fischer Black was fascinated by<strong>the</strong> potential for exploitable inefficiency, althoughhe certainly knew that such opportunities wouldnot be easy, widespread, or available <strong>to</strong> all. He oncefamously answered a question about how his viewof <strong>the</strong> investing world had evolved after movingfrom <strong>the</strong> Massachusetts Institute of Technology <strong>to</strong>Goldman Sachs with “<strong>the</strong> view is much clearerfrom <strong>the</strong> banks of <strong>the</strong> Charles than from <strong>the</strong> banksof <strong>the</strong> Hudson.” Earlier in his career, he had delivereda wonderful talk at <strong>the</strong> University of Chicagounder <strong>the</strong> title “Yes, Virginia, T<strong>here</strong> Is Hope,”which was later published in <strong>the</strong> Financial AnalystsJournal (Black 1973). In that talk, he reported on hisstudy of <strong>the</strong> Value Line Ranking System, whichwould have produced superior performance overa long span of years if followed religiously (andwith transactional-cost efficiency!).Chronic and Acute InefficienciesSome of my pet sources of inefficiencies are behavioraland organizational dis<strong>to</strong>rtions that I haveobserved over <strong>the</strong> years. I certainly do not mean <strong>to</strong>imply that <strong>the</strong>y are exploitable anomalies, but <strong>the</strong>ydo represent <strong>the</strong> raw nuclear material out of whichdiscernible opportunities could arise.In perfectly efficient markets, all informationwould be immediately embedded in prices. Themarket would go through a sequence of quantumleaps from one equilibrium value <strong>to</strong> ano<strong>the</strong>r. Inves<strong>to</strong>rswould have no need <strong>to</strong> trade except for liquiditypurposes. It would be hard <strong>to</strong> make a livingSeptember/Oc<strong>to</strong>ber 2005 www.cfapubs.org 33


Reflections_Leibowitz.fm Page 34 Friday, September 9, 2005 4:12 PMworking in such an idealized world. Fortunately,for those of us in <strong>the</strong> financial arena, <strong>the</strong> reality isthat <strong>the</strong> markets are always in transition from onestate of inefficiency <strong>to</strong> . . . maybe equilibrium but,more likely, a new state of inefficiency.Inefficiencies come in many forms and subforms,but <strong>the</strong>y can be roughly classified as ei<strong>the</strong>rchronic or acute. Acute inefficiencies are <strong>the</strong> discernibleopportunities that can be exploited by accessiblearbitrages. With acute inefficiencies, <strong>the</strong>surrounding uncertainties can be hedged or minimized.Their resolution occurs quickly, well within<strong>the</strong> relevant time frame of arbitraging participants.Chronic inefficiencies tend <strong>to</strong> be less discernible,more ambiguous, more resistant <strong>to</strong> rapid resolutionfrom available market forces, and generallylonger term in nature. This distinction relates <strong>to</strong>Jack Treynor’s (1976) wonderfully suggestive concep<strong>to</strong>f “fast ideas versus slow ideas.”Obviously, one would prefer <strong>to</strong> hurl fast ideasat acute inefficiencies, but by <strong>the</strong>ir very nature,fast ideas have a short half-life. And that half-lifemay be condensing with <strong>the</strong> explosive growth inhedge funds. But even in this era of <strong>the</strong> hedgefund, only a small minority of market participantsspend <strong>the</strong>ir days in a high-performance hunt foracute inefficiencies. The vast majority of inves<strong>to</strong>rs,and certainly <strong>the</strong> bulk of <strong>the</strong> assets, swim with <strong>the</strong>broad currents, while looking for less-fleetingincremental opportunities.Within this mainstream, one has expanses ofapparent efficiency coexisting with pockets ofchronic inefficiencies. Chronic inefficiencies arisefrom structural and behavioral sources, such astrading frictions, organizational barriers, imbalancesin capital flows, valuation ambiguities, lackof catalysts for resolution, convoy or herdingbehavior, artificial peer comparisons, rebalancinginconsistencies, compulsive confirmation seeking,filtering of conflicting data, misreading of marketsignals, inertia, formulaic action plans, and overlyrigid “policy portfolios.” These types of chronicinefficiencies can be quite persistent. Few arbitrageurshave mandates that allow <strong>the</strong>m <strong>to</strong> pursuelong-term opportunities, and <strong>the</strong>ir absence contributes<strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> longevity of such inefficiencies. As <strong>the</strong>well-known saying goes: The market can remainirrational far longer than you can hang on<strong>to</strong> yourposition—or your career.Process vs. Outcome. A much-discussedbehavioral bias is <strong>the</strong> tendency <strong>to</strong> overemphasizerecent his<strong>to</strong>rical results. As every mutual fund prospectusstates, “Past performance should not betaken as a guide <strong>to</strong> future performance.” Thatwarning, although true, is not much help when fewo<strong>the</strong>r hard facts are available. A more ominousrephrasing would be, “Past performance is noteven a good guide <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> quality of <strong>the</strong> decisions thatwent in<strong>to</strong> that past performance.” Yet, <strong>the</strong> ultimateissue is <strong>the</strong> soundness of <strong>the</strong> decision process itself:Was all knowable information incorporated? Was<strong>the</strong> reasoning thorough and sound? Were alternativescenarios considered and contrary viewssought? Was a well-planned implementation andmoni<strong>to</strong>ring program established—and <strong>the</strong>n followed?Was t<strong>here</strong> a routine postmortem analysis oflessons learned? And are organizational disciplineand staff continuity sufficient <strong>to</strong> achieve consistencyin <strong>the</strong> decision process itself?Unfortunately, <strong>the</strong> sort of retrospective analysisthat includes <strong>the</strong>se questions occurs more oftenwhen <strong>the</strong> outcomes are bad than when <strong>the</strong>y aregood. Participants would be well advised <strong>to</strong> conductsuch postmortems even when <strong>the</strong> outcomesare happy ones, however, and <strong>to</strong> ask what really led<strong>to</strong> success. Was <strong>the</strong> positive result achieved for t<strong>here</strong>asons thought, or was it simply good fortune inthis particular instance?Even when presented with a regime that hasevery evidence of success—but only a probabilisticsuccess—few inves<strong>to</strong>rs are able <strong>to</strong> bring <strong>the</strong>mselvesor <strong>the</strong>ir organizations <strong>to</strong> consistently follow its path.The pressures of benchmarks, peer comparisons,standard accounting, liability and expendituredemands, limited organizational risk <strong>to</strong>lerance,managerial self-doubt—all can lead <strong>to</strong> lurchingdepartures from prescribed disciplines, even oneswith a high—but probabilistic—success prospect.After all, even a strategy whose success is ma<strong>the</strong>maticallyprovable will generate long runs ofunderperformance. Indeed, a <strong>to</strong>pic in probability<strong>the</strong>ory deals specifically with <strong>the</strong> risk of ruin—and<strong>the</strong> ultimate odds of ruin always favor <strong>the</strong> infinitelyresourced casino.Convoy Behavior. Traditional modes ofinvesting in <strong>the</strong> financial markets involve absoluteor relative valuations of various market segmentsor securities—a process in which ambiguities, complexities,and externalities abound. Inefficienciesand opportunities do exist in this area, but <strong>the</strong>y arefar from clearly discernible and can only be seen“through a glass darkly.”34 www.cfapubs.org ©2005, CFA Institute


Reflections_Leibowitz.fm Page 35 Friday, September 9, 2005 4:12 PMMany chronic inefficiencies have <strong>the</strong>ir roots in<strong>the</strong> behavioral biases of mainstream participants.For example, consider <strong>the</strong> herding behavior ofinstitutional funds. Participants in <strong>the</strong> financialmarkets find <strong>the</strong>mselves on a sea of ambiguity.They may try <strong>to</strong> climb up <strong>the</strong> mast <strong>to</strong> see what liesahead, <strong>to</strong> look for islands of opportunity, but <strong>the</strong>yare always battered by <strong>the</strong> waves, <strong>the</strong> wea<strong>the</strong>r, and<strong>the</strong> uncertainties of navigating in unchartedwaters. Is t<strong>here</strong> any surprise that one sees so manysailing in convoys?It is no coincidence that most institutional portfoliosare tightly clustered, with <strong>to</strong>tal volatilitiesfalling in <strong>the</strong> 10–11 percent range—regardless of<strong>the</strong> fund’s mission, liability structure, sponsorstrength, or funding status (Leibowitz and Bova2004). When such ambiguity abounds, people naturallyassume that <strong>the</strong>ir peer groups might justhave <strong>the</strong> right idea. This behavior is not <strong>to</strong>tallyirrational w<strong>here</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory is more art than science andw<strong>here</strong> <strong>the</strong> expertise-<strong>to</strong>-luck ratio is often tilted infavor of luck. Moreover, a sufficient critical mass ofinves<strong>to</strong>rs with a common belief, even an erroneousone, can forge a pricing consensus that becomes ade fac<strong>to</strong> reality that must be taken seriously.Ano<strong>the</strong>r issue is <strong>the</strong> valuation horizon of <strong>the</strong>average inves<strong>to</strong>r. The true efficient marketeermight argue that <strong>the</strong> market is continuously efficien<strong>to</strong>ver time. It is interesting <strong>to</strong> speculate, however,whe<strong>the</strong>r most inves<strong>to</strong>rs have some specificspan of time—perhaps from six months <strong>to</strong> threeyears—on which <strong>the</strong>y focus <strong>the</strong>ir investment andvaluation decisions. If so, <strong>the</strong>n inves<strong>to</strong>rs withlonger horizons may reap a somewhat larger riskpremium than average inves<strong>to</strong>rs do. In terms ofTreynor’s fast–slow dicho<strong>to</strong>my, <strong>the</strong> advantagemight go <strong>to</strong> inves<strong>to</strong>rs who are ei<strong>the</strong>r faster orslower than this hypo<strong>the</strong>tical norm.Ano<strong>the</strong>r behavioral bias is <strong>the</strong> tendency <strong>to</strong> seek<strong>the</strong> opinions of o<strong>the</strong>r “experts” who can confirmone’s own views, which results in what might becalled a “compounding consensus.” Actually,instead of seeking confirmation, one shouldactively solicit contrary views, hear <strong>the</strong>m out, consider<strong>the</strong>m objectively, and <strong>the</strong>n try <strong>to</strong> recognizethat <strong>the</strong> financial markets <strong>the</strong>mselves always reflectsome balance of conflicting views. In <strong>the</strong>ory, oneshould always start with <strong>the</strong> hypo<strong>the</strong>sis that <strong>the</strong>market is well priced. Then, before acting on anypotential opportunity, one should (1) try <strong>to</strong> ascertainwhy <strong>the</strong> market is priced w<strong>here</strong> it is, (2) becomeconvinced that <strong>the</strong> basis for this current price doesnot fully reflect <strong>the</strong> true opportunities, (3) believethat t<strong>here</strong> is some process w<strong>here</strong>by one’s views of<strong>the</strong> true state of affairs will eventually come <strong>to</strong> bewidely discernible (and in a more compelling fashionthan has obviously happened <strong>to</strong> date), and (4)conclude that this “discernment” will transpirewithin a relevant time span.Bayesian Rigidity. The compulsion <strong>to</strong> seekconfirmation also relates <strong>to</strong> how <strong>the</strong> unfolding ofevents is interpreted. The “rigid Bayesians” willrelentlessly try <strong>to</strong> retain <strong>the</strong>ir old views in <strong>the</strong> faceof new information. To help counter this all-<strong>to</strong>ohumaninclination, one could write down <strong>the</strong>explicit reasoning behind a projected outcome and<strong>the</strong>n establish <strong>the</strong> miles<strong>to</strong>nes that would have <strong>to</strong>occur if events <strong>to</strong>ok <strong>the</strong> anticipated path. Such awrite-up would be akin <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> contingency plansmilitary establishments routinely create for a widespectrum of geopolitical scenarios.A French marquis once said:He who makes detailed plans about everypotential course of action, and <strong>the</strong>n decides—in advance and in great detail—how <strong>to</strong>respond <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> various contingencies thatmight arise, and <strong>the</strong>n fur<strong>the</strong>r proceeds <strong>to</strong>address <strong>the</strong> subsequent situations that couldfollow each possible outcome, etc., etc.—thisman will make very few mistakes [actually, I’mnot sure that this part is true], but he will alsodo very little [I am sure that this part is true].Yet, although <strong>the</strong> market’s fast pace may limit howmuch contingency planning makes sense, <strong>the</strong>investment management profession surely coulddevote more effort in this direction.Price-Tar<strong>get</strong> Revisionism. Ano<strong>the</strong>r area ofcurious behavior has <strong>to</strong> do with price tar<strong>get</strong>s. Whena long position is taken and <strong>the</strong> market movesfavorably, <strong>the</strong> price rise tends <strong>to</strong> be taken as aconfirmation of <strong>the</strong> wisdom of <strong>the</strong> purchase decision.To <strong>the</strong> extent that a price tar<strong>get</strong> was establishedat <strong>the</strong> outset, <strong>the</strong> inves<strong>to</strong>r may <strong>the</strong>n betempted <strong>to</strong> find some rationale for revising <strong>the</strong>tar<strong>get</strong> upward. This revisionism has some ra<strong>the</strong>robvious dangers. A more rational approach wouldbe <strong>to</strong> assume that as <strong>the</strong> price moves <strong>to</strong>ward <strong>the</strong>original tar<strong>get</strong>, <strong>the</strong> prospect for fur<strong>the</strong>r incrementalreturn decreases while <strong>the</strong> risk increases. So, as afirst cut, one should think in terms of selling off aportion of <strong>the</strong> position as it moves up. Thus, inves<strong>to</strong>rswould be well advised <strong>to</strong> have a plan <strong>to</strong> reduceSeptember/Oc<strong>to</strong>ber 2005 www.cfapubs.org 35


Reflections_Leibowitz.fm Page 36 Friday, September 9, 2005 4:12 PM<strong>the</strong> positions as <strong>the</strong> original tar<strong>get</strong> is approached—<strong>the</strong> burden of proof (or at least <strong>the</strong> burden of argument)being placed on <strong>the</strong> inves<strong>to</strong>r who wishes <strong>to</strong>maintain <strong>the</strong> original position and/or revise <strong>the</strong>price tar<strong>get</strong> upward.When <strong>the</strong> market moves against one’s position,one might reasonably conclude that <strong>the</strong> market isgiving a clear signal that one is wrong. A morecommon belief is that <strong>the</strong> market is wrong and thatgreater return is <strong>to</strong> be expected from <strong>the</strong> lower price.To counter <strong>the</strong> natural tendency <strong>to</strong> avoid a frontallook at deteriorating positions, a help, again, mightbe <strong>to</strong> have a series of adverse-event miles<strong>to</strong>nes thatcould act as trip wires <strong>to</strong> signal serious reconsideration.A substantive adverse move should be <strong>the</strong>basis for asking what <strong>the</strong> market is trying <strong>to</strong> revealand for vigorously seeking those contrary views.The Ebullience Cycle. Ano<strong>the</strong>r commonbehavior is <strong>the</strong> “unopened envelope” syndrome.Back in <strong>the</strong> old days when physical envelopes were<strong>the</strong> primary delivery vehicle for individuals’ portfoliostatements, a persistently dreary marketwould lead <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong>se envelopes being redelivered—unopened—in<strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> “circular file.” Such a state ofdenial when <strong>the</strong> market moves against one is <strong>to</strong>tallyhuman, especially when deciding what <strong>to</strong> do aboutit, if anything, is not easy. The unopened envelopereinforces individuals’ propensity for inaction in<strong>the</strong> face of losing positions.The opposite phenomenon is, of course, thatwhen <strong>the</strong> markets are moving up, <strong>the</strong> incomingenvelope is eagerly awaited and ripped open withgreat vigor. High spirits are rampant, and risks aremore comfortable. In this ebullient atmosp<strong>here</strong>,both individual and institutional inves<strong>to</strong>rs areinclined <strong>to</strong> hold on firmly <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir winning positions,which are shining examples of <strong>the</strong>ir brilliance.They may even invest more aggressively,leading <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> phenomenon that Jack Bogle (2005)cited of markets providing one return, <strong>the</strong> mutualfunds providing something less, and <strong>the</strong> inves<strong>to</strong>rs<strong>get</strong>ting even less (a number that is rarely measured,except by <strong>the</strong> individuals in pain). This problem ofmaking ever-greater investments as <strong>the</strong> marketrises is a classic cycle that is not likely <strong>to</strong> abate.Rebalancing Behavior. Market movementstypically elicit different responses from four typesof ac<strong>to</strong>rs: holders, rebalancers, valua<strong>to</strong>rs, andshifters (Leibowitz and Hammond 2004).■ Holders. As noted, in a deteriorating market,individuals tend <strong>to</strong> leave <strong>the</strong>ir envelopesunopened and positions unchanged. This “holdingpattern” effectively reduces <strong>the</strong>ir equity allocations.■ Rebalancers. Institutions behave very differentlyfrom holders. When <strong>the</strong> market pushes aninstitutional fund away from its policy portfolioallocation, it usually quickly rebalances back <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong>original percentage weights. In essence, institutionsact as “formulaic rebalancers.”■ Valua<strong>to</strong>rs. Valua<strong>to</strong>rs take positions basedon <strong>the</strong> belief that <strong>the</strong> market is ei<strong>the</strong>r cheap (or rich)or that it will continue (or reverse) its recent direction.Valua<strong>to</strong>rs can obviously play in two directions.As <strong>the</strong> market moves down, <strong>the</strong>y may, basedon <strong>the</strong> belief that <strong>the</strong> market has become cheap andwill reverse itself, act as contrarians. As momentumplayers, <strong>the</strong>y may view <strong>the</strong> market’s decline—onei<strong>the</strong>r a technical or a fundamental basis—as aharbinger of fur<strong>the</strong>r downward pressure.■ Shifters. This category really represents atransient reaction ra<strong>the</strong>r than an ongoing style.Inves<strong>to</strong>rs in any of <strong>the</strong> first three categories mayfind <strong>the</strong>mselves becoming shifters at some point intime. Shifting occurs when a fundamental changein asset allocation is required because of circumstancesintrinsic <strong>to</strong> a fund’s or an individual’s situationra<strong>the</strong>r than because of <strong>the</strong>ir assessment of <strong>the</strong>market’s valuation. 2 That is, shifting is a fundamentalmove from one strategic stance <strong>to</strong> ano<strong>the</strong>r. Forexample, individuals may increase <strong>the</strong>ir short-termfixed-income allocations when suddenly faced withan imminent liquidity need—loss of a job, anupcoming move, a looming major purchase, medicalcontingencies, and so on.Institutions are more resistant <strong>to</strong> shifting behavior.Most institutional funds have a policy portfoliothat serves as an anchor for <strong>the</strong>ir overall strategy.The policy portfolio is intended <strong>to</strong> be <strong>the</strong> best possiblepassive portfolio that encapsulates all relevantinformation about <strong>the</strong> nature of <strong>the</strong> fund, its purpose,and how it interacts with prospective returnsand risks in <strong>the</strong> financial markets. Policy portfolioshave great organizational value in forming a baselinefor structuring and controlling <strong>the</strong> investmentmanagement process. Following normal marketmovements, institutions try <strong>to</strong> rebalance back <strong>to</strong><strong>the</strong>ir policy portfolios. Significant shifts tend <strong>to</strong> takeplace only after a major reallocation study or underextreme organizational duress. A downside <strong>to</strong> policyportfolios is that <strong>the</strong>y tend <strong>to</strong> be defined somewhatarbitrarily, <strong>to</strong> be specified in greater detail than36 www.cfapubs.org ©2005, CFA Institute


Reflections_Leibowitz.fm Page 37 Friday, September 9, 2005 4:13 PMis justified, <strong>to</strong> be sustained over a longer time thanis appropriate, and <strong>to</strong> form a high barrier for anytactical departure. Bill Jahnke (1999), Rob Arnott(2004), and Bernstein (2004) have written eloquentlyabout <strong>the</strong> behavioral dis<strong>to</strong>rtions that can arise froman overly rigid commitment <strong>to</strong> policy portfolios.Market ImpactThese different responses may ei<strong>the</strong>r exacerbate ormoderate market movements. Obviously, <strong>the</strong> holderswill have little effect on <strong>the</strong> market; <strong>the</strong>y are ou<strong>to</strong>f <strong>the</strong> game, so <strong>to</strong> speak. The rebalancers will tend<strong>to</strong> have a smoothing effect: As <strong>the</strong> market goesdown, <strong>the</strong>y buy more; as <strong>the</strong> market goes up, <strong>the</strong>ysell. Within <strong>the</strong> valua<strong>to</strong>r category, <strong>the</strong> contrariansand “reversionists” will act as modera<strong>to</strong>rs w<strong>here</strong>asthose pursuing momentum strategies will have anexacerbating effect. Because shifting tends <strong>to</strong>become more urgent (and probably more widespread)in adverse conditions, shifters will generallyexacerbate market moves.This four-part categorization also indicatessomething about how new flows are invested.Holders and rebalancers will usually invest <strong>the</strong>irnew funds congruently with <strong>the</strong>ir existing allocations.(However, individuals do seem <strong>to</strong> exhibitsomewhat more proactive flexibility in investing<strong>the</strong>ir new funds than with <strong>the</strong>ir existing allocations.This behavior is ra<strong>the</strong>r curious.) Valua<strong>to</strong>rs,of course, will make fresh decisions about w<strong>here</strong><strong>to</strong> deploy new funds, but this type represents arelatively small part of overall new fund flows. Thebulk of flows is concentrated in holders and rebalancers—thosewith relatively rigid channels whotend <strong>to</strong> direct new investments largely <strong>to</strong>ward<strong>the</strong>ir current allocations. 3Rebalancing and Market EfficiencyThe rebalancing behaviors <strong>the</strong>mselves may becomesources of market inefficiency. Consider which of<strong>the</strong> behaviors really make sense. Suppose a fundstarts with a portfolio that mirrors <strong>the</strong> market as awhole. One could argue that, in a strictly efficientmarket, price movements would move <strong>the</strong> fund’sportfolio in concert with <strong>the</strong> evolving equilibrium,and in this case, holding behavior might make eminentsense. Most funds do not, however, have aportfolio that reflects <strong>the</strong> market as a whole (certainlynot on purpose). Moreover, at least in <strong>the</strong> caseof individuals, holding behavior is more likely <strong>to</strong>be <strong>the</strong> result of inertia, not sophisticated reasoning.Some formulaic rebalancers believe <strong>the</strong>y areadhering <strong>to</strong> an appropriate response in an efficientmarket. T<strong>here</strong> is some inconsistency, however, inreestablishing <strong>the</strong> same allocation after an “efficientmarket” has made a major alteration in global assetweights. After all, a downward move reduces <strong>the</strong>asset’s weight in <strong>the</strong> market portfolio, which arguesfor rebalancing back <strong>to</strong> an allocation somewhatlower than <strong>the</strong> original policy portfolio weight.One sometimes hears <strong>the</strong> rationale for formulaicrebalancing presented in terms of buyingcheaper after a decline and selling expensiveassets after a rise. But if one really believes that <strong>the</strong>market has become discernibly cheaper as a resul<strong>to</strong>f a decline, shouldn’t <strong>the</strong> right move be <strong>to</strong> establishan even larger position ra<strong>the</strong>r than <strong>to</strong> rebalanceback <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> original position? After all, if <strong>the</strong>policy allocation were done afresh, <strong>the</strong>n (given <strong>the</strong>newly cheaper valuation) <strong>the</strong> revised allocationshould be even more aggressive than before. Thus,one can reasonably argue that rebalancing should,in general, lead not <strong>to</strong> a resurrection of <strong>the</strong> originalallocation but, ra<strong>the</strong>r, <strong>to</strong> a higher or lower percentageweighting!Ideally, rational rebalancing should not be rigidlytet<strong>here</strong>d <strong>to</strong> a fixed policy portfolio but shouldrespond more fluidly <strong>to</strong> market signals—<strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong>extent <strong>the</strong>y are interpreted ei<strong>the</strong>r as an efficientrestructuring of <strong>the</strong> global portfolio or as a discerniblechange in valuation. The problem, of course, is thatlarge investment organizations are not designed <strong>to</strong>facilitate such judgmental flexibility. And as oneastute chief investment officer put it, “Better <strong>to</strong> havea rigid rebalancing by prior agreement than a portfoliothat deteriorates in<strong>to</strong> a holding pattern because<strong>the</strong> organization lacks <strong>the</strong> confidence or <strong>the</strong> will <strong>to</strong>reestablish <strong>the</strong> policy portfolio weightings—or <strong>to</strong>even move back in that direction.”The behavior of valua<strong>to</strong>rs is integrally tied in<strong>to</strong><strong>the</strong> issue of discernibility. To <strong>the</strong> extent that discerniblevaluation opportunities truly exist, why not try<strong>to</strong> take advantage of <strong>the</strong>m? Of course, with valua<strong>to</strong>rs,<strong>the</strong> big question is whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>ir businessmodels compel <strong>the</strong>m <strong>to</strong> make tactical and timingdecisions even when no market opportunities meetthis test of “reasonable discernibility.”September/Oc<strong>to</strong>ber 2005 www.cfapubs.org 37


Reflections_Leibowitz.fm Page 38 Friday, September 9, 2005 4:13 PMRisk as Risk <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> Policy PortfolioA fund’s strong reluctance <strong>to</strong> being forced <strong>to</strong> shiftaway from its policy portfolio may play an underappreciatedrole in setting <strong>the</strong> fund’s risk <strong>to</strong>leranceand in shaping its policy portfolio in <strong>the</strong> first place.When an institution shifts <strong>to</strong> a lower-risk allocation,it departs from <strong>the</strong> policy portfolio that was previouslyconsidered <strong>to</strong> represent an optimal allocation.Institutional funds are understandablyreluctant <strong>to</strong> move away from pre-established policyportfolios. Indeed, <strong>the</strong>ir rebalancing behavior isspecifically geared <strong>to</strong>ward sustaining this portfoliostructure. Most institutional managers view it asmost unfortunate if <strong>the</strong> fund is forced by an extrememarket movement—or by <strong>the</strong> fund’s investmentcommittee—<strong>to</strong> abandon <strong>the</strong> presumably optimalapproach and shift in<strong>to</strong> a lower-risk strategy.Potential trigger points for such mandatedshifts lurk in <strong>the</strong> background of every inves<strong>to</strong>r’smind, however, acting as fence posts that define <strong>the</strong>outer limits of <strong>to</strong>lerable risk. These fence posts mayalso play a feedback role in setting <strong>the</strong> policy portfolio’soverall risk level in <strong>the</strong> first place. For example,suppose adverse movements of 15–20 percentare considered <strong>to</strong> be <strong>the</strong> <strong>to</strong>lerable outer limit of <strong>the</strong>risk envelope. Then, a fund might reasonably wish<strong>to</strong> control <strong>the</strong> prospect of any such triggering eventby reducing its probability <strong>to</strong> a minimal level (say,10 percent). This shortfall constraint implies a portfoliovolatility (risk) level in <strong>the</strong> 10–11 percentrange, which happens <strong>to</strong> be exactly w<strong>here</strong> mostinstitutional funds are clustered.Two fur<strong>the</strong>r observations on this issue of risk.One is that <strong>the</strong> standard measure of risk, volatility,is an estimate of <strong>the</strong> range of returns at a givenhorizon. As pointed out by Mark Kritzman (2000)and by Kritzman and Don Rich (2002), this end-ofhorizondistribution is not <strong>the</strong> same as <strong>the</strong>distribution of outcomes that could occur at someintermediary time. That distribution is muchwider. And logically, this “riskier” intermediarydistribution should determine when triggerpoints might be activated. 4The Illusion of Growth EternalParticipants in <strong>the</strong> financial markets are intrinsicallyoriented <strong>to</strong>ward an optimistic view of a worldwith a continuously compounding growth ofvalue. Reality reminds us, however, that wealth canalso be destroyed—both by “whimpers” and by“bangs.” Sidney Homer and I (2004) once posed <strong>the</strong>following question: If a Roman soldier put just onedrachma in a savings account and let it compoundat 4 percent throughout <strong>the</strong> ages, how much moneywould his descendants have <strong>to</strong>day? The answerturned out <strong>to</strong> be so many drachmas that, at virtuallyany exchange rate, it would amount <strong>to</strong> far morethan <strong>the</strong> <strong>to</strong>tal existing wealth in <strong>the</strong> world. Thisoutcome led <strong>to</strong> a follow-up question: What happened<strong>to</strong> it all? The sobering answer is that wealthis destroyed by war, inflation, devaluation, pandemic,political collapse, repudiation, obsolescence,virulent competition, bankruptcy, financialdebacle, revolutionary technology, nonproductiveinvestment, and so on. The natural inclination <strong>to</strong>deny <strong>the</strong> phan<strong>to</strong>m of such discontinuities may benecessary for moving things forward, but it mayalso be a chronic source of inefficiency.ConclusionParticipants in <strong>the</strong> financial markets often find<strong>the</strong>mselves sailing on a sea of ambiguity throughbroad patches of fog, bouts of heavy wea<strong>the</strong>r, andoccasional balmy periods that may prove only <strong>to</strong> be<strong>the</strong> center of passing s<strong>to</strong>rms. One can elect <strong>the</strong>passive approach—fly <strong>the</strong> beta flag and allow one’sportfolio <strong>to</strong> float on <strong>the</strong> “index currents.” Or onecan choose <strong>to</strong> be an active alpha-seeking inves<strong>to</strong>rand try <strong>to</strong> chip away at <strong>the</strong> many chronic inefficienciesand behavioral biases that we know exist, eventhough we can’t clearly discern how <strong>the</strong>y are pricedand whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>y will profitably regress <strong>to</strong>wardequilibrium within a reasonable time. With chronicinefficiencies, by <strong>the</strong>ir very definition, discernibilitywill always be somewhat clouded. (O<strong>the</strong>rwise,<strong>the</strong>y would become acute—and would be longgone.) So, with <strong>the</strong>se opportunities, one is alwaysacting on imperfect knowledge and playing <strong>the</strong>odds. But without actively scanning <strong>the</strong> horizonand being poised <strong>to</strong> move on reasonably discernibleopportunities, inves<strong>to</strong>rs will surely have nochance of reaping <strong>the</strong> incremental return in<strong>here</strong>ntin <strong>the</strong> grand continuous march <strong>to</strong>ward efficiency.The great inves<strong>to</strong>rs are like <strong>the</strong> great sailors:They have <strong>the</strong> courage <strong>to</strong> set forth, <strong>the</strong>y know w<strong>here</strong><strong>the</strong>y want <strong>to</strong> go, <strong>the</strong>y have a strong gyroscope <strong>to</strong>keep <strong>the</strong>m on course, <strong>the</strong>y have appropriate respectfor <strong>the</strong> dangers of <strong>the</strong> sea and its potential for radicalshifts in wea<strong>the</strong>r and currents, and <strong>the</strong>y are notafraid <strong>to</strong> be alone for long stretches.38 www.cfapubs.org ©2005, CFA Institute


Reflections_Leibowitz.fm Page 39 Friday, September 9, 2005 4:13 PMNotes1. Although I argue for <strong>the</strong> possibility of successful activeinvesting, I do not wish <strong>to</strong> suggest that everyone can be awinner. Indeed, <strong>the</strong>y cannot. And <strong>the</strong> narrowness of <strong>the</strong> lis<strong>to</strong>f great inves<strong>to</strong>rs attests <strong>to</strong> that dour fact. The great mass ofinves<strong>to</strong>rs should treat <strong>the</strong> market as being highly efficientand should start with <strong>the</strong> null hypo<strong>the</strong>sis that all assets arefairly priced.2. In some cases, market movements do ultimately lead <strong>to</strong> aportfolio shift. For example, a rule of thumb says that manyindividuals will let <strong>the</strong>ir allocations drift until a 15–20 percentdecline from some high-water mark forces <strong>the</strong>m <strong>to</strong>seriously reconsider <strong>the</strong>ir risk <strong>to</strong>lerances. I am drawing adistinction, however, between shifts based on a marketdrivenchange in risk <strong>to</strong>lerance and those reallocations thatare directly valuation motivated.3. The large majority of existing dollar assets are also controlledby holders and formulaic rebalancers, which leads<strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> interesting question of whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> key risk premiumsbetween asset classes are being priced by a relativelyminor segment of <strong>the</strong> investing universe.4. An even more severe criterion would be based on <strong>the</strong>range of declines from a high-water mark (Leibowitz andBova 2005b).ReferencesArnott, Robert D. 2004. “Managing Assets in a World of HigherVolatility and Lower Returns.” In Points of Inflection: NewDirections for Portfolio Management (Charlottesville, VA: CFAInstitute):39–52.Asness, Clifford. 2004. “An Alternative Future.” Journal ofPortfolio Management (Special Anniversary Issue):94–103.Bernstein, Peter L. 2004. “Overview: A Fifth Point of Inflection.”In Points of Inflection: New Directions for Portfolio Management(Charlottesville, VA: CFA Institute):1–5.———. 2005. “Alpha: The Real Thing, or Chimerical?” Economicsand Portfolio Strategy (15 March).Black, Fischer. 1973. “Yes, Virginia, T<strong>here</strong> Is Hope: Tests of <strong>the</strong>Value Line Ranking System.” Financial Analysts Journal, vol. 29,no. 5 (September/Oc<strong>to</strong>ber):10–14.Bogle, Jack. 2005. “The Mutual Fund Industry 60 Years Later:For Better or Worse?” Financial Analysts Journal, vol. 61, no. 1(January/February):15–24.Ellis, Charles. 1998. Winning <strong>the</strong> Loser’s Game. New York:McGraw-Hill.Grinold, Richard C., and Ronald N. Kahn. 2000. Active PortfolioManagement. 2nd ed. New York: McGraw-Hill.Homer, Sidney, and Martin L. Leibowitz. 2004. Inside <strong>the</strong> YieldBook. Prince<strong>to</strong>n, NJ: Bloomberg Press.Jahnke, William. 1999. “Why Setting an Asset Allocation PolicyIs a Bad Idea.” Journal of Financial Planning (February).Available online at www.fpanet.org/journal/articles/1999_Issues/jfp0299-art5.cfm.Kritzman, Mark P. 2000. Puzzles of Finance. New York: JohnWiley & Sons.Kritzman, Mark P., and Don Rich. 2002. “The Mismeasuremen<strong>to</strong>f Risk.” Financial Analysts Journal, vol. 58, no. 3 (May/June):91–99.Leibowitz, Martin L. 2004. “The !-Plus Measure in AssetAllocation.” Journal of Portfolio Management, vol. 30, no. 3(Spring):26–36Leibowitz, Martin L., and Anthony Bova. 2004. “StructuralBetas: The Key Risk Fac<strong>to</strong>r in Asset Allocation.” Morgan StanleyResearch Notes (21 June).———. 2005a. “The Efficient Frontier Using ‘Alpha Cores’.”Morgan Stanley Research Notes (7 January).———. 2005b. “Convergence of Risk.” Morgan Stanley ResearchNote (April).———. 2005c. “Allocation Betas.” Financial Analysts Journal,vol. 61, no. 4 (July/August):70–82.Leibowitz, Martin L., and P. Brett Hammond. 2004. “TheChanging Mosaic of Investment Patterns.” Journal of PortfolioManagement, vol. 30, no. 3 (Spring):10–25.Sharpe, William F. 1991. “From <strong>the</strong> Board: The Arithmetic ofActive Management.” Financial Analysts Journal, vol. 47, no. 1(January/February):7–9.Treynor, Jack L. 1976. “Long-Term Investing.” Financial AnalystsJournal, vol. 32, no. 3 (May/June):56–59.Waring, M. Bar<strong>to</strong>n, and Laurence B. Siegel. 2003. “TheDimensions of Active Management.” Journal of PortfolioManagement, vol. 29, no. 3 (Spring):35–52.September/Oc<strong>to</strong>ber 2005 www.cfapubs.org 39


Behavioral FinanceJay R. RitterCordell Professor of FinanceUniversity of FloridaP.O. Box 117168Gainesville FL 32611-7168http://bear.cba.ufl.edu/ritterjay.ritter@cba.ufl.edu(352) 846-2837Published, with minor modifications, in <strong>the</strong>Pacific-Basin Finance Journal Vol. 11, No. 4, (September 2003) pp. 429-437.AbstractThis article provides a brief introduction <strong>to</strong> behavioral finance. Behavioral finance encompassesresearch that drops <strong>the</strong> traditional assumptions of expected utility maximization with rationalinves<strong>to</strong>rs in efficient markets. The two building blocks of behavioral finance are cognitivepsychology (how people think) and <strong>the</strong> limits <strong>to</strong> arbitrage (when markets will be inefficient).The growth of behavioral finance research has been fueled by <strong>the</strong> inability of <strong>the</strong> traditionalframework <strong>to</strong> explain many empirical patterns, including s<strong>to</strong>ck market bubbles in Japan, Taiwan,and <strong>the</strong> U.S.JEL classification: G14; D81Keywords: Behavioral finance; arbitrage; psychology; market efficiencyA modified version of this paper was given as a keynote address at <strong>the</strong> July, 2002APFA/PACAP/FMA meetings in Tokyo. I would like <strong>to</strong> thank Ken Froot and Andrei Shleiferfor sharing <strong>the</strong>ir data and ideas, and Rongbing Huang for research assistance.


Behavioral Finance1. IntroductionBehavioral finance is <strong>the</strong> paradigm w<strong>here</strong> financial markets are studied using models thatare less narrow than those based on Von Neumann-Morgenstern expected utility <strong>the</strong>ory andarbitrage assumptions. Specifically, behavioral finance has two building blocks: cognitivepsychology and <strong>the</strong> limits <strong>to</strong> arbitrage. Cognitive refers <strong>to</strong> how people think. T<strong>here</strong> is a hugepsychology literature documenting that people make systematic errors in <strong>the</strong> way that <strong>the</strong>y think:<strong>the</strong>y are overconfident, <strong>the</strong>y put <strong>to</strong>o much weight on recent experience, etc. Their preferencesmay also create dis<strong>to</strong>rtions. Behavioral finance uses this body of knowledge, ra<strong>the</strong>r than taking<strong>the</strong> arrogant approach that it should be ignored. Limits <strong>to</strong> arbitrage refers <strong>to</strong> predicting in whatcircumstances arbitrage forces will be effective, and when <strong>the</strong>y won't be.Behavioral finance uses models in which some agents are not fully rational, ei<strong>the</strong>rbecause of preferences or because of mistaken beliefs. An example of an assumption aboutpreferences is that people are loss averse - a $2 gain might make people feel better by as much asa $1 loss makes <strong>the</strong>m feel worse. Mistaken beliefs arise because people are bad Bayesians.Modern finance has as a building block <strong>the</strong> Efficient Markets Hypo<strong>the</strong>sis (EMH). The EMHargues that competition between inves<strong>to</strong>rs seeking abnormal profits drives prices <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir“correct” value. The EMH does not assume that all inves<strong>to</strong>rs are rational, but it does assume thatmarkets are rational. The EMH does not assume that markets can foresee <strong>the</strong> future, but it doesassume that markets make unbiased forecasts of <strong>the</strong> future. In contrast, behavioral financeassumes that, in some circumstances, financial markets are informationally inefficient.Not all misvaluations are caused by psychological biases, however. Some are just due <strong>to</strong>temporary supply and demand imbalances. For example, <strong>the</strong> tyranny of indexing can lead <strong>to</strong>demand shifts that are unrelated <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> future cash flows of <strong>the</strong> firm. When Yahoo was added <strong>to</strong><strong>the</strong> S&P 500 in December 1999, index fund managers had <strong>to</strong> buy <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck even though it had alimited public float. This extra demand drove up <strong>the</strong> price by over 50% in a week and over100% in a month. Eighteen months later, <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck price was down by over 90% from w<strong>here</strong> itwas shortly after being added <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> S&P.2


If it is easy <strong>to</strong> take positions (shorting overvalued s<strong>to</strong>cks or buying undervalued s<strong>to</strong>cks)and <strong>the</strong>se misvaluations are certain <strong>to</strong> be corrected over a short period, <strong>the</strong>n “arbitrageurs” willtake positions and eliminate <strong>the</strong>se mispricings before <strong>the</strong>y become large. But if it is difficult <strong>to</strong>take <strong>the</strong>se positions, due <strong>to</strong> short sales constraints, for instance, or if t<strong>here</strong> is no guarantee that <strong>the</strong>mispricing will be corrected within a reasonable timeframe, <strong>the</strong>n arbitrage will fail <strong>to</strong> correct <strong>the</strong>mispricing. 1 Indeed, arbitrageurs may even choose <strong>to</strong> avoid <strong>the</strong> markets w<strong>here</strong> <strong>the</strong> mispricing ismost severe, because <strong>the</strong> risks are <strong>to</strong>o great. This is especially true when one is dealing with alarge market, such as <strong>the</strong> Japanese s<strong>to</strong>ck market in <strong>the</strong> late 1980s or <strong>the</strong> U.S. market fortechnology s<strong>to</strong>cks in <strong>the</strong> late 1990s. Arbitrageurs that attempted <strong>to</strong> short Japanese s<strong>to</strong>cks in mid-1987 and hedge by going long in U.S. s<strong>to</strong>cks were right in <strong>the</strong> long run, but <strong>the</strong>y lost hugeamounts of money in Oc<strong>to</strong>ber 1987 when <strong>the</strong> U.S. market crashed by more than <strong>the</strong> Japanesemarket (because of Japanese government intervention). If <strong>the</strong> arbitrageurs have limited funds,<strong>the</strong>y would be forced <strong>to</strong> cover <strong>the</strong>ir positions just when <strong>the</strong> relative misvaluations were greatest,resulting in additional buying pressure for Japanese s<strong>to</strong>cks just when <strong>the</strong>y were most overvalued!2. Cognitive BiasesCognitive psychologists have documented many patterns regarding how people behave.Some of <strong>the</strong>se patterns are as follows:HeuristicsHeuristics, or rules of thumb, make decision-making easier. But <strong>the</strong>y can sometimes lead<strong>to</strong> biases, especially when things change. These can lead <strong>to</strong> suboptimal investment decisions.When faced with N choices for how <strong>to</strong> invest retirement money, many people allocate using <strong>the</strong>1/N rule. If t<strong>here</strong> are three funds, one-third goes in<strong>to</strong> each. If two are s<strong>to</strong>ck funds, two-thirdsgoes in<strong>to</strong> equities. If one of <strong>the</strong> three is a s<strong>to</strong>ck fund, one-third goes in<strong>to</strong> equities. Recently,Benartzi and Thaler (2001) have documented that many people follow <strong>the</strong> 1/N rule.OverconfidencePeople are overconfident about <strong>the</strong>ir abilities. Entrepreneurs are especially likely <strong>to</strong> beoverconfident. Overconfidence manifests itself in a number of ways. One example is <strong>to</strong>o littlediversification, because of a tendency <strong>to</strong> invest <strong>to</strong>o much in what one is familiar with. Thus,1Technically, an arbitrage opportunity exists when one can guarantee a profit by, for example, going long in anundervalued asset and shorting an overvalued asset. In practice, almost all arbitrage activity is risk arbitrage—making trades w<strong>here</strong> <strong>the</strong> expected profit is high relative <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> risk involved.3


people invest in local companies, even though this is bad from a diversification viewpointbecause <strong>the</strong>ir real estate (<strong>the</strong> house <strong>the</strong>y own) is tied <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> company’s fortunes. Think of au<strong>to</strong>industry employees in Detroit, construction industry employees in Hong Kong or Tokyo, orcomputer hardware engineers in Silicon Valley. People invest way <strong>to</strong>o much in <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck of <strong>the</strong>company that <strong>the</strong>y work for.Men tend <strong>to</strong> be more overconfident than women. This manifests itself in many ways,including trading behavior. Barber and Odean (2001) recently analyzed <strong>the</strong> trading activities ofpeople with discount brokerage accounts. They found that <strong>the</strong> more people traded, <strong>the</strong> worse<strong>the</strong>y did, on average. And men traded more, and did worse than, women inves<strong>to</strong>rs.Mental AccountingPeople sometimes separate decisions that should, in principle, be combined. Forexample, many people have a household bud<strong>get</strong> for food, and a household bud<strong>get</strong> forentertaining. At home, w<strong>here</strong> <strong>the</strong> food bud<strong>get</strong> is present, <strong>the</strong>y will not eat lobster or shrimpbecause <strong>the</strong>y are much more expensive than a fish casserole. But in a restaurant, <strong>the</strong>y will orderlobster and shrimp even though <strong>the</strong> cost is much higher than a simple fish dinner. If <strong>the</strong>y insteadate lobster and shrimp at home, and <strong>the</strong> simple fish in a restaurant, <strong>the</strong>y could save money. Butbecause <strong>the</strong>y are thinking separately about restaurant meals and food at home, <strong>the</strong>y choose <strong>to</strong>limit <strong>the</strong>ir food at home.FramingFraming is <strong>the</strong> notion that how a concept is presented <strong>to</strong> individuals matters. Forexample, restaurants may advertise “early-bird” specials or “after-<strong>the</strong>atre” discounts, but <strong>the</strong>ynever use peak-period “surcharges.” They <strong>get</strong> more business if people feel <strong>the</strong>y are <strong>get</strong>ting adiscount at off-peak times ra<strong>the</strong>r than paying a surcharge at peak periods, even if <strong>the</strong> prices areidentical. Cognitive psychologists have documented that doc<strong>to</strong>rs make differentrecommendations if <strong>the</strong>y see evidence that is presented as “survival probabilities” ra<strong>the</strong>r than“mortality rates,” even though survival probabilities plus mortality rates add up <strong>to</strong> 100%.RepresentativenessPeople underweight long-term averages. People tend <strong>to</strong> put <strong>to</strong>o much weight on recentexperience. This is sometimes known as <strong>the</strong> “law of small numbers.” As an example, whenequity returns have been high for many years (such as 1982-2000 in <strong>the</strong> U.S. and westernEurope), many people begin <strong>to</strong> believe that high equity returns are “normal.”4


ConservatismWhen things change, people tend <strong>to</strong> be slow <strong>to</strong> pick up on <strong>the</strong> changes. In o<strong>the</strong>r words,<strong>the</strong>y anchor on <strong>the</strong> ways things have normally been. The conservatism bias is at war with t<strong>here</strong>presentativeness bias. When things change, people might underreact because of <strong>the</strong>conservatism bias. But if t<strong>here</strong> is a long enough pattern, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong>y will adjust <strong>to</strong> it and possiblyoverreact, underweighting <strong>the</strong> long-term average.Disposition effectThe disposition effect refers <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> pattern that people avoid realizing paper losses andseek <strong>to</strong> realize paper gains. For example, if someone buys a s<strong>to</strong>ck at $30 that <strong>the</strong>n drops <strong>to</strong> $22before rising <strong>to</strong> $28, most people do not want <strong>to</strong> sell until <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck <strong>get</strong>s <strong>to</strong> above $30. Thedisposition effect manifests itself in lots of small gains being realized, and few small losses. Infact, people act as if <strong>the</strong>y are trying <strong>to</strong> maximize <strong>the</strong>ir taxes! The disposition effect shows up inaggregate s<strong>to</strong>ck trading volume. During a bull market, trading volume tends <strong>to</strong> grow. If <strong>the</strong>market <strong>the</strong>n turns south, trading volume tends <strong>to</strong> fall. As an example, trading volume in <strong>the</strong>Japanese s<strong>to</strong>ck market fell by over 80% from <strong>the</strong> late 1980s <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> mid 1990s. The fact thatvolume tends <strong>to</strong> fall in bear markets results in <strong>the</strong> commission business of brokerage firmshaving a high level of systematic risk. 2One of <strong>the</strong> major criticisms of behavioral finance is that by choosing which bias <strong>to</strong>emphasize, one can predict ei<strong>the</strong>r underreaction or overreaction. This criticism of behavioralfinance might be called "model dredging." In o<strong>the</strong>r words, one can find a s<strong>to</strong>ry <strong>to</strong> fit <strong>the</strong> facts <strong>to</strong>ex post explain some puzzling phenomenon. But how does one make ex ante predictions aboutwhich biases will dominate? T<strong>here</strong> are two excellent articles that address this issue: Barberisand Thaler (2002), and Hirshliefer (2001). Hirshliefer (p. 1547) in particular addresses <strong>the</strong> issueof when we would expect one behavioral bias <strong>to</strong> dominate o<strong>the</strong>rs. He emphasizes that t<strong>here</strong> is atendency for people <strong>to</strong> excessively rely on <strong>the</strong> strength of information signals and under-rely on<strong>the</strong> weight of information signals. This is sometimes described as <strong>the</strong> salience effect.2During <strong>the</strong> bear market beginning in April 2000 in <strong>the</strong> U.S., aggregate s<strong>to</strong>ck market volume has not dropped. Thisis apparently due <strong>to</strong> increased trading by institutions, since s<strong>to</strong>ck trading by individuals has in fact declined. Thesignificant drop in transaction costs associated with <strong>the</strong> move <strong>to</strong> decimalization and technological advances partlyaccounts for this. Ano<strong>the</strong>r reason is that many firms split <strong>the</strong>ir shares in late 1999 and <strong>the</strong> first half of 2000, which,ceteris paribus, would have resulted in higher trading volume. The drop in commission revenue from individuals(predicted by <strong>the</strong> disposition effect) has resulted in revenue declines for retail-oriented brokerage firms such asCharles Schwab & Co.5


3. The limits <strong>to</strong> arbitrageMisvaluations of financial assets are common, but it is not easy <strong>to</strong> reliably makeabnormal profits off of <strong>the</strong>se misvaluations. Why? Misvaluations are of two types: those thatare recurrent or arbitrageable, and those that are nonrepeating and long-term in nature. For t<strong>here</strong>current misvaluations, trading strategies can reliably make money. Because of this, hedgefunds and o<strong>the</strong>rs zero in on <strong>the</strong>se, and keep <strong>the</strong>m from ever <strong>get</strong>ting <strong>to</strong>o big. Thus, <strong>the</strong> market ispretty efficient for <strong>the</strong>se assets, at least on a relative basis. For <strong>the</strong> long-term, nonrepeatingmisvaluations, it is impossible in real time <strong>to</strong> identify <strong>the</strong> peaks and troughs until <strong>the</strong>y havepassed. Getting in <strong>to</strong>o early risks losses that wipe out capital. Even worse, if limited partners oro<strong>the</strong>r inves<strong>to</strong>rs are supplying funds, withdrawals of capital after a losing streak may actuallyresult in buying or selling pressure that exacerbates <strong>the</strong> inefficiency.Just who are <strong>the</strong>se inves<strong>to</strong>rs who make markets efficient? Well, one obvious class ofinves<strong>to</strong>rs who are trying <strong>to</strong> make money by identifying misvaluations are hedge funds. Arelative value hedge fund takes long and short positions, buying undervalued securities and <strong>the</strong>nfinding highly correlated securities that are overvalued, and shorting <strong>the</strong>m. A macro hedge fund,on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r hand, takes speculative positions that cannot be easily hedged, such as shortingNasdaq during <strong>the</strong> last two years.How well do efforts by arbitrageurs <strong>to</strong> make money work in practice at making marketsmore efficient? As Shleifer and Vishny argue in <strong>the</strong>ir 1997 "Limits <strong>to</strong> Arbitrage" article, <strong>the</strong>efforts of arbitrageurs <strong>to</strong> make money will make some markets more efficient, but <strong>the</strong>y won'thave any effect on o<strong>the</strong>r markets.Let's look at an example, that of a giant hedge fund, Long Term Capital Management.LTCM was founded about nine years ago by Myron Scholes, Robert Mer<strong>to</strong>n, John Meriwe<strong>the</strong>r,and o<strong>the</strong>rs. For <strong>the</strong>ir first three or four years, <strong>the</strong>y were spectacularly successful. But <strong>the</strong>n, fouryears ago, <strong>the</strong>y had one bad quarter in which <strong>the</strong>y lost $4 billion, wiping out <strong>the</strong>ir equity capitaland forcing <strong>the</strong> firm <strong>to</strong> liquidate. But <strong>the</strong>y were right in <strong>the</strong> long run!LTCM mainly traded in fixed income and derivative markets. But one of <strong>the</strong> ways that<strong>the</strong>y lost money was on <strong>the</strong> Royal Dutch/Shell equity arbitrage trade.In 1907, Royal Dutch of <strong>the</strong> Ne<strong>the</strong>rlands and Shell of <strong>the</strong> UK agreed <strong>to</strong> merge <strong>the</strong>irinterests on a 60-40 basis, and pay dividends on <strong>the</strong> same basis. It is easy <strong>to</strong> show that whenever<strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck prices are not in a 60-40 ratio, t<strong>here</strong> is an arbitrage profit opportunity. Finance <strong>the</strong>ory6


has a clear prediction. Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, <strong>the</strong>se are large companies. Until July 2002, Royal Dutchwas in <strong>the</strong> S & P 500, and Shell is in <strong>the</strong> FTSE.How well does this prediction work?7


0.20.10-0.1-0.2-0.3Royal Dutch / Shell Deviation1/2/19801/2/19811/2/19821/2/19831/2/19841/2/19851/2/19861/2/19871/2/19881/2/19891/2/19901/2/19911/2/19921/2/19931/2/19941/2/19951/2/19961/2/19971/2/19981/2/19991/2/20001/2/2001Figure 1—Deviations from Royal Dutch/Shell parity from January 1980 <strong>to</strong> December 2001, as computed by Froot and Dabora (1999)and updated by Ken Froot.deviation from <strong>the</strong>oretical value


For <strong>the</strong> last 22 years, from 1980 <strong>to</strong> 2001, figure 1 demonstrates that t<strong>here</strong> have been largedeviations from <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>oretical relation. In 1998, LTCM shorted <strong>the</strong> expensive s<strong>to</strong>ck and bought<strong>the</strong> cheap one. Did <strong>the</strong>y make money? No, <strong>the</strong>y lost money when prices diverged fur<strong>the</strong>r from<strong>the</strong>ir <strong>the</strong>oretical values during <strong>the</strong> third quarter of 1998. To meet liquidity needs, LTCM ando<strong>the</strong>r hedge funds were forced <strong>to</strong> sell out <strong>the</strong>ir positions, and this selling pressure made marketsmore inefficient, ra<strong>the</strong>r than more efficient. So <strong>the</strong> forces of arbitrage failed.The data plotted in figure 1 end in December 2001, with <strong>the</strong> price ratio close <strong>to</strong> its<strong>the</strong>oretical value. Has it stayed t<strong>here</strong>? In July 2002, Standard and Poors announced that RoyalDutch would be dropped from <strong>the</strong> S&P 500 because <strong>the</strong>y were deleting non-Americancompanies. Royal Dutch dropped by 17% in <strong>the</strong> week of <strong>the</strong> announcement, although t<strong>here</strong> is nosuggestion that <strong>the</strong> present value of dividends changed.So what is <strong>the</strong> bot<strong>to</strong>m line on market efficiency? It is useful <strong>to</strong> divide events in<strong>to</strong> twocategories - high-frequency events, which occur often, and low-frequency events, which occuronly infrequently, and may take a long time <strong>to</strong> recover from.The high-frequency evidence supports market efficiency. It is hard <strong>to</strong> find a tradingstrategy that is reliably profitable. And mutual funds have difficulty beating <strong>the</strong>ir benchmarks.The low-frequency evidence, however, does not support market efficiency. Examples ofenormous misvaluations include:1) The undervaluation of world-wide s<strong>to</strong>ck markets from 1974-1982.2) The Japanese s<strong>to</strong>ck price and land price bubble of <strong>the</strong> 1980s.3) The Taiwanese s<strong>to</strong>ck price bubble that peaked in February 1990.4) The Oc<strong>to</strong>ber 1987 s<strong>to</strong>ck market crash.5) The technology, media, and telecom (TMT) bubble of 1999-2000.4. Applications of behavioral financeI would now like <strong>to</strong> talk about some specific applications of behavioral finance. While Icould choose from many applications, I am going <strong>to</strong> briefly discuss two of my recentpublications. The first application concerns inflation and <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck market. I’m going <strong>to</strong> start outwith a simple valuation question. Below, I list some specific assumptions about a hypo<strong>the</strong>ticalfirm, and <strong>the</strong> question is, “How much is <strong>the</strong> equity of this firm worth?”9


Assumptions: The inflation rate is 6%, and <strong>the</strong> equity risk premium is zero, so <strong>the</strong> nominal cos<strong>to</strong>f capital is 10% (a real cost of capital of 4%). The firm wants <strong>to</strong> keep <strong>the</strong> real value of its debtunchanged, so it must increase <strong>the</strong> nominal amount of debt by 6% each year. T<strong>here</strong> is no realgrowth, and all free cash flow (if any) is paid out in dividends.Revenue $1,200,000Cost of Goods Sold $600,000Administrative Expenses $400,000Interest Expense $200,000Taxes $0After-tax profits $0Debt $2,000,000Book Equity $1,500,000Shares outstanding 10,000Interest rate on debt 10%With inflation at 6% and $2 million in debt, <strong>the</strong> firm must issue $120,000 more debt nextyear <strong>to</strong> keep <strong>the</strong> real value of its debt constant. This cash can be used <strong>to</strong> pay dividends. This is$12 per share, and using <strong>the</strong> growing perpetuity formulaP = Div 1 /(r – g)with r = 10% and g = 6%, P = $12/(0.10 – 0.06) = $300 per share.So <strong>the</strong> equity is worth $3 million, or $300 per share. Earnings are zero because <strong>the</strong>accountants treat nominal interest expense as a cost, but <strong>the</strong>y don't treat <strong>the</strong> inflation-induceddecrease in <strong>the</strong> real value of debt as a benefit <strong>to</strong> equity holders. In o<strong>the</strong>r words, <strong>the</strong> trueeconomic earnings are higher than <strong>the</strong> accounting earnings, because accountants measure <strong>the</strong>cost, but not <strong>the</strong> benefit <strong>to</strong> equityholders, of debt financing when t<strong>here</strong> is inflation.This is an example of w<strong>here</strong> framing makes a difference. Nominal interest expenseappears on <strong>the</strong> income statement. The decrease in <strong>the</strong> real value of nominal liabilities due <strong>to</strong>inflation does not appear on <strong>the</strong> income statement. Because it doesn’t appear, I would argue thatinves<strong>to</strong>rs don’t take it in<strong>to</strong> account, and hence undervalue equities when inflation is high. If youfind this implausible, ask yourself “how many finance professors with PhDs <strong>get</strong> <strong>the</strong> valuationcorrect?” If <strong>the</strong> market makes this mistake, <strong>the</strong>n s<strong>to</strong>cks become riskier, because <strong>the</strong>y fall more10


than <strong>the</strong>y should when inflation increases, and <strong>the</strong>y rise more than <strong>the</strong>y should when inflationdecreases. Over a full inflation cycle, <strong>the</strong>se two effects balance out, which is why s<strong>to</strong>cks are lessrisky in <strong>the</strong> long run than <strong>the</strong>y are in <strong>the</strong> short run (Siegel (1998), Chapter 2).Modigliani and Cohn (1979) argued that <strong>the</strong> U.S. s<strong>to</strong>ck market was grossly undervaluedin <strong>the</strong> mid and late 1970s because inves<strong>to</strong>rs had irrational beliefs about earnings, given <strong>the</strong> highinflation that existed <strong>the</strong>n. Richard Warr and I, in our March 2002 JFQA article on <strong>the</strong> decline ofinflation and <strong>the</strong> bull market of 1982-1999, conduct an out-of-sample test of <strong>the</strong> Modigliani-Cohn hypo<strong>the</strong>sis. We argue that part of <strong>the</strong> bull market of <strong>the</strong> 1980s was attributable <strong>to</strong> arecovery from <strong>the</strong> undervaluation. We also argue that <strong>the</strong> continued s<strong>to</strong>ck market rise in <strong>the</strong>1990s was an overshooting - <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck market became overvalued - and we predicted that 2000-2002 would have low s<strong>to</strong>ck returns. Fortunately, I believe in my research, and I've had much ofmy retirement assets in inflation-indexed bonds <strong>the</strong> last three years. These have been <strong>the</strong> bestperformingasset class.The second application of behavioral finance that I would like <strong>to</strong> briefly discuss concerns<strong>the</strong> underpricing of IPOs.Prospect <strong>the</strong>ory is a descriptive <strong>the</strong>ory of choice under uncertainty. This is in contrast <strong>to</strong>expected utility <strong>the</strong>ory, which is normative ra<strong>the</strong>r than descriptive. Prospect <strong>the</strong>ory focuses onchanges in wealth, w<strong>here</strong>as expected utility <strong>the</strong>ory focuses on <strong>the</strong> level of wealth. Gains andlosses are measured relative <strong>to</strong> a reference point. Prospect <strong>the</strong>ory also assumes loss aversion.Prospect <strong>the</strong>ory also incorporates framing—if two related events occur, an individual has achoice of treating <strong>the</strong>m as separate events (segregation) or as one (integration). For example, if aperson goes <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> racetrack and makes two bets, winning one and losing one, <strong>the</strong> person mayintegrate <strong>the</strong> outcome and focus on <strong>the</strong> net payoff. If <strong>the</strong> net payoff is positive, a gain hasoccurred, and focusing on this makes <strong>the</strong> bet<strong>to</strong>r happy. If t<strong>here</strong> is a net loss, segregating <strong>the</strong> twobets allows <strong>the</strong> bet<strong>to</strong>r <strong>to</strong> feel disappointed once, but happy once.Tim Loughran and I use prospect <strong>the</strong>ory in our 2002 RFS paper "Why Don't Issuers GetUpset About Leaving Money on <strong>the</strong> Table in IPOs?" <strong>to</strong> explain <strong>the</strong> severe underpricing of someIPOs. If an IPO is underpriced, pre-issue s<strong>to</strong>ckholders are worse off because <strong>the</strong>ir wealth hasbeen diluted. We argue that if an entrepreneur receives <strong>the</strong> good news that he or she is suddenlyunexpectedly wealthy because of a higher than expected IPO price, <strong>the</strong> entrepreneur doesn'tbargain as hard for an even higher offer price. This is because <strong>the</strong> person integrates <strong>the</strong> good11


news of a wealth increase with <strong>the</strong> bad news of excessive dilution. The individual is better offon net. Underwriters take advantage of this mental accounting and severely underprice <strong>the</strong>sedeals. It is <strong>the</strong>se IPOs w<strong>here</strong> <strong>the</strong> offer price has been raised (a little) that leave a lot of money on<strong>the</strong> table when <strong>the</strong> market price goes up a lot.5. ConclusionsThis brief introduction <strong>to</strong> behavioral finance has only <strong>to</strong>uched on a few points. Moreextensive analysis can be found in Barberis and Thaler (2003), Hirshliefer (2001), Shefrin(2000), and Shiller (2000).It is very difficult <strong>to</strong> find trading strategies that reliably make money. This does notimply that financial markets are informationally efficient, however. Low frequencymisvaluations may be large, without presenting any opportunity <strong>to</strong> reliably make money. As anexample, individuals or institutions who shorted Japanese s<strong>to</strong>cks in 1987-1988 when <strong>the</strong>y weresubstantially overvalued, or Taiwanese s<strong>to</strong>cks in early 1989 when <strong>the</strong>y were substantiallyovervalued, or TMT s<strong>to</strong>cks in <strong>the</strong> U.S., Europe, and Hong Kong in early 1999 when <strong>the</strong>y weresubstantially overvalued, all lost enormous amounts of money as <strong>the</strong>se s<strong>to</strong>cks became even moreovervalued. Most of <strong>the</strong>se shortsellers, who were right in <strong>the</strong> long run, were wiped out before<strong>the</strong> misvaluations started <strong>to</strong> disappear. Thus, <strong>the</strong> forces of arbitrage, which work well for highfrequency events, work very poorly for low frequency events.Behavioral finance is, relatively speaking, in its infancy. It is not a separate discipline,but instead will increasingly be part of mainstream finance.12


ReferencesBarber, Brad, and Terry Odean, 2001. “Boys will be boys: Gender, overconfidence, andcommon s<strong>to</strong>ck investment.” Quarterly Journal of Economics 116, 261-292.Barberis, Nicholas, and Richard Thaler, 2003. “A survey of behavioral finance.” in G.Constantinides, M. Harris, and R. Stulz (edi<strong>to</strong>rs) Handbook of <strong>the</strong> Economics of FinanceNorth-Holland, Amsterdam.Benartzi, Shlomo, and Richard Thaler, 2001. “Naïve diversification strategies in definedcontribution savings plans.” American Economic Review 91, 79-98.Froot, Kenneth A., and Emil A. Dabora, 1999. “How are s<strong>to</strong>ck prices affected by <strong>the</strong> location oftrade?” Journal of Financial Economics 53, 189-216.Hirshleifer, David, 2001. “Inves<strong>to</strong>r psychology and asset pricing.” Journal of Finance 56,1533-1597.Loughran, Tim, and Jay R. Ritter, 2002. "Why don't issuers <strong>get</strong> upset about leaving money on<strong>the</strong> table in IPOs?" Review of Financial Studies 15, 413-443.Modigliani, Franco, and Richard Cohn, 1979. “Inflation, rational valuation and <strong>the</strong> market.”Financial Analysts Journal 35, 24-44.Ritter, Jay R., and Richard Warr, 2002. “The decline of inflation and <strong>the</strong> bull market of 1982-1999.” Journal of Financial and Quantitative Analysis. 37, 29-61.Shefrin, Hersh, 2000. Beyond Greed and Fear Harvard Business School Press, Bos<strong>to</strong>n.Shiller, Robert J., 2000. Irrational Exuberance Prince<strong>to</strong>n University Press, Prince<strong>to</strong>n.Shleifer, Andrei, and Robert Vishny, 1997. “The limits of arbitrage.” Journal of Finance52, 35-55.Siegel, Jeremy J., 1998. S<strong>to</strong>cks for <strong>the</strong> Long Run, Second Edition McGraw-Hill, New York.13


The A Priori Problem of Observed ProbabilitiesNassim Nicholas TalebLife is not a labora<strong>to</strong>ry in which we are suppliedprobabilities. Nor is it an exercise in textbooks onstatistics. Nor is it an urn. Nor is it a casino w<strong>here</strong> <strong>the</strong>state authorities moni<strong>to</strong>r and enforce some probabilistictransparency.Alas we do not observe probabilities; we estimate <strong>the</strong>mfrom observations and samples. This discussionpresents <strong>the</strong> principal problem of empirical probabilisticknowledge and discovery. The central problem is asfollows. Without a strong, necessarily normative, apriori specification of <strong>the</strong> underlying reality of aprocess, epistemic confidence is inversely proportional<strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> consequences of <strong>the</strong> knowledge at hand. Themore events matter, <strong>the</strong> worse our empirical knowledgeabout <strong>the</strong>ir properties. Large deviations, <strong>the</strong> one thatcan have <strong>the</strong> most meaningful effect on <strong>the</strong> <strong>to</strong>talproperties, are far more error-prone in empiricalevaluation than regular ones.This note will also present <strong>the</strong> epistemologicaldifference between <strong>the</strong> nonscalable and scalabledistributions –as well as more minor issues oftenbundled under <strong>the</strong> archaic designation “Knightian”uncertainty.THE TELESCOPE PROBLEMAssume that t<strong>here</strong> are series of discrete “events” i ofmagnitude ! i (taken as departures from a “norm”, a“mean”, or a center) and with probability " i (i can alsobe a “slice”, a discretizing interval for a continuousdistribution, in which case we assume equality in <strong>the</strong>slices). Assume fur<strong>the</strong>r that ! i can take values on t<strong>here</strong>al line, with no known upper bounds or lower bounds,between minus infinity and infinity. (I am not assumingthat an upper or lower bound does not exist, only thatwe do not know w<strong>here</strong> it is.) Assume that you areobserving samples in a finite set, and derivingproperties that are general, applying outside <strong>the</strong> sampleset (you could also be deriving a probability distributionof future events from past events). You observe a se<strong>to</strong>f values ! i and make an inference about <strong>the</strong>ir possiblefrequency outside such set.Let me make it clear: You are not sampling within anurn, <strong>the</strong> composition of which you know. You aremaking statement outside of a sample set. This meansthat you are now subjected <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> problem of induction.Now consider <strong>the</strong> moment contribution of every state of<strong>the</strong> world i, with M i,m = " i ! i m <strong>the</strong> moment contributionof order m. The <strong>to</strong>tal moment of order n would be <strong>the</strong>summation of M over all possible values of i.M m=$" i# imLet us turn <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> estimation of probabilities. How does<strong>the</strong> sample reveals <strong>the</strong> values " i ? Assume that you <strong>get</strong><strong>the</strong>m by simply taking <strong>the</strong> sample of size n, and addingup <strong>the</strong> ! values of observations for a given !, <strong>here</strong> n ! /n ,w<strong>here</strong> n ! are <strong>the</strong> number of observations of <strong>the</strong> even<strong>to</strong>f magnitude !.Let us call <strong>the</strong> “true” probabilities " i *, <strong>the</strong> probabilitiesthat can be obtained by having full knowledge of <strong>the</strong>generating process. We do not observe <strong>the</strong>m, but <strong>the</strong>yare <strong>the</strong> ones that, in a world w<strong>here</strong> <strong>the</strong>y can bedesigned, <strong>the</strong> data is sampled from <strong>the</strong>m.The constraint that all " i add up <strong>to</strong> 1 is not sufficient inmany situations. So <strong>the</strong> central problem is as follows.• The small probability estimationerror:The smaller <strong>the</strong> " i *, <strong>the</strong> larger weneed <strong>the</strong> sample n in order <strong>to</strong> be <strong>to</strong> besatisfied with our inference, and, for agiven sample size, <strong>the</strong> higher <strong>the</strong> error inusing " i as an estima<strong>to</strong>r of "*.• The telescope problem: if <strong>the</strong> |!| issome decreasing function of ", for |!| largeenough, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> smaller <strong>the</strong> probability,<strong>the</strong> more consequential <strong>the</strong> impact of <strong>the</strong>error on <strong>the</strong> <strong>to</strong>tal moment. Effectively thisis <strong>the</strong> case with unimodal distributions.So <strong>the</strong> errors in <strong>the</strong> smaller " are multiplied by a larger!. The pair " i ! i is a rectangle that <strong>get</strong>s thinner as "becomes smaller, but its surface is more s<strong>to</strong>chastic." i" iThe Telescope Problem: Smaller probability "multiplies larger deviation !, with <strong>the</strong> error in <strong>the</strong>! i! i


!estimation of <strong>the</strong> product "! <strong>get</strong>ting larger as " <strong>get</strong>ssmaller.SAINT PETERSBURG COMPOUNDEDBut things can <strong>get</strong> worse for <strong>the</strong> “rectangle”. Let usnow consider <strong>the</strong> shape of <strong>the</strong> probability decrease,how <strong>the</strong> " need <strong>to</strong> drop as |!| rises. It is a fact that<strong>the</strong> " cannot decrease <strong>to</strong>o slowly. The first intuition of<strong>the</strong> problem is in <strong>the</strong> well-known Saint Petersburgparadox (i.e., for n between 1 and infinity, a payoff ! iof 2 i with probability " i =1/2 i ), showing that no matterhow low <strong>the</strong> ", <strong>the</strong> increase in |!| can be such that <strong>the</strong>moment contributions of all M i are equal. Simply, <strong>the</strong>situation in which" i= 1 K , w<strong>here</strong> K is a constant,# imakes <strong>the</strong> computation of all moments >1 impossible.Generalization of <strong>the</strong> Saint Petersburg problem<strong>to</strong> higher ! momentsm. So more generally, for <strong>the</strong>moment M m <strong>to</strong> exist we need (in a unimodaldistribution) <strong>the</strong> slices of M i,m <strong>to</strong> decrease as a certainrate, i.e.,$" i< 1 '& K)%# i (So <strong>the</strong> problem is that it is hard for a probabilitydistribution <strong>to</strong> do <strong>the</strong> job for all moments m unless "falls faster than ! ! m for all m. For that <strong>to</strong> happen, <strong>the</strong>only typical form is one with a characteristic scale, like" i= e #a$ i. It makes <strong>the</strong> product " i ! i m decrease forlarger values of !. What I call non-nonscalable is,simply, <strong>the</strong> situation in which we do not have thatexponential decline. See Note 1 for details.1/ mThe o<strong>the</strong>r solution is <strong>to</strong> give up on moments.THE A PRIORI PROBLEMLet us now look a <strong>the</strong> error rate in <strong>the</strong> estimation of " ,and <strong>the</strong> difficulty that for higher orders of M, t<strong>here</strong> is acompounding effect of a higher error it multiplies largerand larger values of !. This is clearly intractable.This can be solved, of course, with an arbitrary functionthat decreases <strong>the</strong> moment contributions M i of <strong>the</strong> ! as<strong>the</strong>se become larger. In o<strong>the</strong>r words, by assuming apriori a certain class of distributions.Accordingly, we need one of <strong>the</strong> following threesolutions:Solution 1: A metaprobabilistic framework:allowing us <strong>to</strong> estimate <strong>the</strong> errors of <strong>the</strong> observed " isome measure of <strong>the</strong> difference between probabilitiesand perfect information. In o<strong>the</strong>r words, we wouldhave " * i,j for every probability i, making every momentcontribution M i,m s<strong>to</strong>chastic. But <strong>here</strong> again t<strong>here</strong> is <strong>the</strong>risk of regress as <strong>the</strong> metaprobability needs <strong>to</strong> bechecked as well for its own error –we need a model oferror measurement for that.Risk v/s Uncertainty: Note <strong>the</strong> difference between<strong>the</strong> so-called “Knightian” risk and uncertainty can beexpressed as follows: risk is normatively set with*unitary metaprobabilities " i,j = 1 for all j (or nometaprobability). This makes <strong>the</strong> difference between<strong>the</strong> two entirely normative, not empirical. In o<strong>the</strong>rwords, <strong>the</strong> difference does not exist in an environmentw<strong>here</strong> one cannot accept epistemological certaintiesabout probabilities without a priori.Solution 2: Assuming beforehand a probabilitydistribution: If distributions are popular, it is because<strong>the</strong>y allow normatively <strong>to</strong> make inferences aboutprobabilities by analogy with o<strong>the</strong>r probabilities in placeof <strong>the</strong> metaprobabilistic framewor. Here <strong>the</strong> estimationerror concerns some parameters of <strong>the</strong> probabilitydistribution, but not <strong>the</strong> probabilities <strong>the</strong>mselves.This option is problematic because t<strong>here</strong> is nojustification for <strong>the</strong> derivation of probability distributionsinternally from <strong>the</strong> data, i.e. empirically, causingano<strong>the</strong>r infinite regress argument. We need data forprobability distribution and a probability distribution <strong>to</strong>know how much data we need. So we cannot do ameta-probability distribution. This is w<strong>here</strong> it becomesnormative.Note that t<strong>here</strong> are situations in which one can put asubordination: you sample between two probabilitydistributions, say two Gaussians. TheSolution 3: Truncation: of some values of <strong>the</strong> !allowing <strong>the</strong> integration and <strong>the</strong> finiteness of M m . This isnot done by assumption, but, ra<strong>the</strong>r, in eliminating <strong>the</strong>sensitivity of <strong>the</strong> variable above a certain amount.(Note one aspect of Saint-Petersburg: The use of utilityof payoff introduced a soft truncation. But you can set<strong>the</strong> game in a way <strong>to</strong> truncate “organically”.)CONCLUSIONT<strong>here</strong> are no ways <strong>to</strong> deal with unbounded payoffsprobabilistically without making assumptions, andassuming that <strong>the</strong>se assumptions are not subjected <strong>to</strong>probabilistic judgment. This is <strong>the</strong> tragedy ofprobabilistic reasoning in modern domains, for whichwe cannot <strong>to</strong>lerate a priori probabilities.2© Copyright 2007 by N. N. Taleb.


MATHEMATICAL POINTSNote 1: Assume that "(x) is a continuous function.Assume x in <strong>the</strong> positive domain and p mono<strong>to</strong>nic ineach domain “for x large enough”. We need M[n], i.e.,"(!) ! n <strong>to</strong> be a decreasing function of ! for all n. Tosatisfy <strong>the</strong> strict negativity of M’[n] <strong>the</strong> derivative of <strong>the</strong>“moment slice” with respect <strong>to</strong> !, we have! n-1 (n "(!) + ! "’(!))


Can S<strong>to</strong>ck Market Forecasters Forecast?Alfred Cowles 3rdEconometrica, Vol. 1, No. 3. (Jul., 1933), pp. 309-324.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0012-9682%28193307%291%3A3%3C309%3ACSMFF%3E2.0.CO%3B2-SEconometrica is currently published by The Econometric Society.Your use of <strong>the</strong> JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available athttp://www.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/about/terms.html. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtainedprior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in<strong>the</strong> JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use.Please contact <strong>the</strong> publisher regarding any fur<strong>the</strong>r use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained athttp://www.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/journals/econosoc.html.Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain <strong>the</strong> same copyright notice that appears on <strong>the</strong> screen or printedpage of such transmission.The JSTOR Archive is a trusted digital reposi<strong>to</strong>ry providing for long-term preservation and access <strong>to</strong> leading academicjournals and scholarly literature from around <strong>the</strong> world. The Archive is supported by libraries, scholarly societies, publishers,and foundations. It is an initiative of JSTOR, a not-for-profit organization with a mission <strong>to</strong> help <strong>the</strong> scholarly community takeadvantage of advances in technology. For more information regarding JSTOR, please contact support@js<strong>to</strong>r.org.http://www.js<strong>to</strong>r.orgFri Jan 4 10:47:40 2008


CAN STOCK MARKET FORECASTERS FORECAST?A paper read before a joint meeting of <strong>the</strong> Econometric Society and <strong>the</strong>American Statistical Association, Cincinnati, Ohio, December 31, 1932INTRODUCTIONTHISpaper presents results of analyses of <strong>the</strong> forecasting efforts of 45professional agencies which have attempted, ei<strong>the</strong>r <strong>to</strong> select specificcommon s<strong>to</strong>cks which should prove superior in investment merit <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong>general run of equities, or <strong>to</strong> predict <strong>the</strong> future movements of <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ckmarket itself. The paper falls in<strong>to</strong> two main parts. The first deals with<strong>the</strong> attempts of two groups, 20 fire insurance companies and 16 financialservices, <strong>to</strong> foretell which specific securities would prove mostprofitable. The second part deals with <strong>the</strong> efforts of 25 financial publications<strong>to</strong> foretell <strong>the</strong> future course of <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck market. Various statisticaltests of <strong>the</strong>se results are given.These investigations were instituted five years ago as a means oftesting <strong>the</strong> success of applied economics in <strong>the</strong> investment field. Itseemed a plausible assumption that if we could demonstrate <strong>the</strong> existencein individuals or organizations of <strong>the</strong> ability <strong>to</strong> foretell <strong>the</strong> elusivefluctuations, ei<strong>the</strong>r of particular s<strong>to</strong>cks, or of s<strong>to</strong>cks in general, thismight lead <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> identification of economic <strong>the</strong>ories or statistical practiceswhose soundness had been established by successful prediction.The forecasters include well-known organizations in <strong>the</strong> differentfields represented, many of which are large and well financed, employingeconomists and statisticians of unquestioned ability. The names of<strong>the</strong>se organizations are omitted, since <strong>the</strong>ir publication would be likely<strong>to</strong> invite wholesale controversy over <strong>the</strong> interpretation of <strong>the</strong>ir records.Some of <strong>the</strong> forecasters seem <strong>to</strong> have taken a page from <strong>the</strong> book of<strong>the</strong> Delphic Oracle, expressing <strong>the</strong>ir prophecies in terms susceptible ofmore than one construction. It would frequently be possible, t<strong>here</strong>fore,for an edi<strong>to</strong>r, after <strong>the</strong> event, <strong>to</strong> present a plausible challenge of ourinterpretation. Most of <strong>the</strong> forecasts appear through <strong>the</strong> medium ofweekly publications and each of <strong>the</strong>se has been read and recorded on<strong>the</strong> day it became available <strong>to</strong> us, which in practically every case wasbefore <strong>the</strong> event. In this way certain possible elements of bias havebeen eliminated. It was impossible that hindsight could influence ourjudgment, ei<strong>the</strong>r in <strong>the</strong> selection of publications for analysis or in <strong>the</strong>interpretations placed on <strong>the</strong>ir forecasts. In <strong>the</strong> case of <strong>the</strong> fire insurancecompanies, however, <strong>the</strong> analyses were made annually, based on<strong>the</strong> transactions reported in Kimber's Record of Insurance CompanySecurity Pu~chases. The companies were selected as fairly representa-


tive of <strong>the</strong>ir class. The analysis of <strong>the</strong> 26-year forecasting record ofWilliam Peter Hamil<strong>to</strong>n, former edi<strong>to</strong>r of <strong>the</strong> Tt'all Street Journal, alsofalls in a different category, in that it was undertaken because of t<strong>here</strong>putation for successful forecasting which he had established over along period of years.FORECASTING THE COURSE OF INDIVIDUAL STOCK PRICESWe turn first <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> records of two groups, <strong>the</strong> financial services and<strong>the</strong> fire insurance companies, which have attempted <strong>to</strong> select individuals<strong>to</strong>cks that would prove more profitable for investment than <strong>the</strong> averageissue. The first part of this section deals with <strong>the</strong> records, over <strong>the</strong>44 years ending July, 1932, of 16 leading financial services which havemade a practice of regularly submitting <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir subscribers selectedlists of common s<strong>to</strong>cks for investment. Our analysis includes about7,500 separate recommendations, requiring approximately 75,000 entries.The first step was <strong>to</strong> record each week <strong>the</strong> name and price ofeach s<strong>to</strong>ck recommended for purchase or sale by each service. Nextcame <strong>the</strong> tabulation of <strong>the</strong> advice <strong>to</strong> sell or cover <strong>the</strong> commitmentpreviously advised. Reiterated advice was not considered, action beingassumed <strong>to</strong> have been taken as of <strong>the</strong> date when <strong>the</strong> recommendationwas first published. The percentage gain or loss on each such transactionwas recorded and, in a parallel column, <strong>the</strong> gain or loss of <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ckmarket for <strong>the</strong> identical period. A balance was struck every six monthswhich summarized <strong>the</strong> <strong>to</strong>tal results secured by each service as comparedwith <strong>the</strong> action of <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck market. Proper corrections were, ofcourse, made <strong>to</strong> offset <strong>the</strong> effect of changes in capital structure resultingfrom <strong>the</strong> issue of rights, s<strong>to</strong>ck dividends, etc. Since a tendency existedamong some services <strong>to</strong> emphasize <strong>the</strong>ir conspicuously successful s<strong>to</strong>ckrecommendations and ignore more unfortunate commitments, weadopted a practice of au<strong>to</strong>matically dropping a s<strong>to</strong>ck from <strong>the</strong> list sixmonths after it had been last recommended, when specific advice <strong>to</strong>sell was not given.A redistribution of funds in equal amounts among all s<strong>to</strong>cks recommendedhas been assumed for each service at <strong>the</strong> beginning of every sixmonths' period analyzed. It could be maintained, of course, that thisequalizing process should take place as often as once a week, but thiswould increase <strong>the</strong> labor of computation <strong>to</strong> overwhelming proportions.Provisional experiments demonstrated that it would yield conclusionspractically identical with those secured by <strong>the</strong> shorter method. Compounding<strong>the</strong> successive six months' records gives <strong>the</strong> percentage bywhich each service's recommendations have exceeded, or fallen behind,<strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck market, as shown in Table I.Only six of <strong>the</strong> 16 services achieved any success. To arrive at an


ALFRED COWLES ~ R D311average performance, <strong>the</strong> record of each service was reduced <strong>to</strong> an effectiveannual rate which was <strong>the</strong>n weighted in accordance with <strong>the</strong>length of <strong>the</strong> period represented. The average annual effective rate ofall <strong>the</strong> services, thus arrived at, is - 1.43 per cent.TABLEIRESULTSOF COMMITMENTSTOCKSIN RECOMMENDED BY 16 FINANCIALSERVICES (RELATED TO MARKET AVERAGES)Service W e e k s Per cent1. .....................234 ..................... +80.82. ....................234 ..................... +17.23. ....................234 ..................... +15.24. ..................... 234 ..................... f12.35. ..................... 234 ..................... + 8.46. ..................... 26 ..................... + 6.17. .................... 52 ..................... 0.8. .....................104 ..................... - 0.59. ..................... 234 - 1.910. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 52 ..................... - 2.211. ..................... 52 ..................... - 3.012. ..................... 52 ..................... - 8.313. ..................... 78 ..................... -16.114. ..................... 104 ..................... -28.215. ..................... 104 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . -31.216. ..................... 156 ..................... -33.0PROBABILITY TESTSIn an attempt <strong>to</strong> determine whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> service having <strong>the</strong> best recordachieved its result through skill or chance, we resorted <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>oriesof compound and inverse probability. Our conclusion is thusrendered consistent by obtaining approximately <strong>the</strong> same answer intwo different ways.With <strong>the</strong> aid of various checks, involving 1250 computations of <strong>the</strong>action of individual s<strong>to</strong>cks selected at random, we derived a formula,A.D. (t) =5.42+1.5t (A.D. =average deviation, t, in units of 4 weeks,2 I), representing <strong>the</strong> deviation, for all periods from one month up <strong>to</strong>one year, of <strong>the</strong> average individual s<strong>to</strong>ck from <strong>the</strong> average of all s<strong>to</strong>cks.Service Number 1, for <strong>the</strong> 9 six months' periods from January 1,1928 <strong>to</strong> July 1, 1932, was successful 7 times and unsuccessful 2 times.With <strong>the</strong> aid of <strong>the</strong> table referred <strong>to</strong>, <strong>the</strong> averages of "chances in 1000<strong>to</strong> do worse" for <strong>the</strong> 7 periods in which it was successful and <strong>the</strong> 2 periodsin which it was unsuccessful were found <strong>to</strong> be 842 and 66 respectively.By <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory of direct probabilities, <strong>the</strong> probability of asingle service being right at least 7 times in 9 is equal <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> sum of <strong>the</strong>first 3 terms of <strong>the</strong> binomial (9+3)@.p = 1/29+9/2@+36/2@ =46/512 = .090The probability that a single service could in 9 predictions be 7 times


312 ECONOMETRICAon <strong>the</strong> positive side and in <strong>the</strong>se 7 forecasts equal <strong>the</strong> achievement ofService Number 1 is,P=.090 X (1 - .842)= .014However, <strong>the</strong> record of <strong>the</strong> best service is marred by its failure in <strong>the</strong>two negative cases. The average of <strong>the</strong> two chances <strong>to</strong> do worse in <strong>the</strong>secases is .066. We <strong>the</strong>n have,as <strong>the</strong> probability of a single random service having a record worsethan that of Service Number 1. We t<strong>here</strong>fore conclude that <strong>the</strong> probabilitythat a random service can, first, be on <strong>the</strong> right side of <strong>the</strong> market7 times out of 9, and second, equal in performance <strong>the</strong> record of ServiceNumber 1, isP = ,090X (1-.670) =.030.This means that in 16 services we should expect <strong>to</strong> find 16 X.030 = .48services which will equal <strong>the</strong> record of Service Number 1. That is <strong>to</strong> say,<strong>the</strong> chance is even that we should <strong>get</strong> at least one service as good asNumber 1.Because of <strong>the</strong> assumptions implied in this computation, we shall arguethis ano<strong>the</strong>r way. We shall assume that <strong>the</strong> probability that a servicefor its <strong>to</strong>tal forecast shall be on <strong>the</strong> positive side of <strong>the</strong> market is1/2. Then <strong>the</strong> estimate of its success must be made by a differentevaluation of Q. For this purpose we shall adopt a formula suggestedby Bayes' rule in inverse probability in which <strong>the</strong> weights .9l0 and .090instead of 7/9 and 2/9 are used. We <strong>get</strong>Hence, if a service was on <strong>the</strong> right side of <strong>the</strong> market, <strong>the</strong> probabilityof its achieving <strong>the</strong> success of Service Number 1would be 1-Q.Thus <strong>the</strong> compound probability would beP = 1/2 (1 - .901)= .050.Among <strong>the</strong> 16 services <strong>the</strong> probability of <strong>the</strong> most successful one equalling<strong>the</strong> record of Service Number 1would be P= 16X .050 = 30, thatis <strong>to</strong> say, we should expect <strong>to</strong> <strong>get</strong> among 16 random services about oneservice which would equal Number 1. Since this answer is quite consistentwith our previous answer, our analysis suggests <strong>the</strong> conclusionthat <strong>the</strong> record of Service Number 1 could not be definitely attributed<strong>to</strong> skill.


ALFRED COTVLES ~ R D313TWENTY FIRE INSURANCE COhlPANIESThe second analysis deals with <strong>the</strong> common s<strong>to</strong>ck investments, from1028 <strong>to</strong> 1931 inclusive, of 20 of our leading fire insurance companies.Its significance lies in <strong>the</strong> fact that <strong>the</strong>se companies are representativeof a class of common s<strong>to</strong>ck inves<strong>to</strong>r which has had long years of experienceand large amounts of capital at its disposal. Fire insurance datesfrom <strong>the</strong> Great London Fire of 1666, and active investment in s<strong>to</strong>cksdeveloped during <strong>the</strong> nineteenth century. The fire insurance companiesare much older hands at <strong>the</strong> business of investment than ei<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>financial services, which are a twentieth century product, or Americaninvestment trusts, which are largely a development of <strong>the</strong> last fewyears. The investment policies of <strong>the</strong>se companies are based on <strong>the</strong>accumulated knowledge of successive boards of direc<strong>to</strong>rs whose judgmentmight be presumed, over <strong>the</strong> years, <strong>to</strong> have been well above tha<strong>to</strong>f <strong>the</strong> average inves<strong>to</strong>r. The 20 companies which were selected foranalysis hold assets <strong>to</strong>talling several hundred million dollars, and seema fair sample of <strong>the</strong>ir kind.Fire insurance companies carry between 20 and 30 per cent of <strong>the</strong>ir<strong>to</strong>tal investments in common s<strong>to</strong>cks. Their average turnover amounts<strong>to</strong> only some 5 per cent a year. For this reason it was thought best <strong>to</strong>confine our analysis <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> record of <strong>the</strong> actual purchases and salesmade during <strong>the</strong> period under examination, ra<strong>the</strong>r than <strong>to</strong> compute<strong>the</strong> record of <strong>the</strong> entire common s<strong>to</strong>ck portfolio. To simplify <strong>the</strong> labor,all items of s<strong>to</strong>ck purchased were given equal weights, regardless of <strong>the</strong>amounts involved. While <strong>the</strong> conclusion does not exactly reflect <strong>the</strong>actual investment results secured by <strong>the</strong>se companies, it should, however,provide a satisfac<strong>to</strong>ry test of <strong>the</strong> success of <strong>the</strong>se organizationsin selecting s<strong>to</strong>cks which performed better than <strong>the</strong> average.The method employed in <strong>the</strong> analysis is essentially <strong>the</strong> same as thatused in <strong>the</strong> case of <strong>the</strong> investment services. A second purchase of anitem was omitted from <strong>the</strong> record unless a sale of this item intervened.A record of <strong>the</strong> sale of an item, of course, determined <strong>the</strong> date as ofwhich it was dropped from <strong>the</strong> list. Also, any item of which t<strong>here</strong> hadbeen no purchase recorded for 12 months was au<strong>to</strong>matically consideredsold.The compounded records of <strong>the</strong> 20 companies for <strong>the</strong> 4-year periodare shown in Table 11.Six of <strong>the</strong> companies show evidence of success, and <strong>the</strong> average of<strong>the</strong> 20 is -4.72 per cent. The average record of <strong>the</strong> companies in <strong>the</strong>s<strong>to</strong>cks which <strong>the</strong>y selected for investment fell below <strong>the</strong> average of <strong>the</strong>s<strong>to</strong>ck market at <strong>the</strong> effective annual rate of 1.20 per cent. A comparableresult could have been achieved through a purely random selection of


314 ECONOMETRICAs<strong>to</strong>cks. The analysis of <strong>the</strong> fire insurance companies' records thus confirms<strong>the</strong> results secured in appraising <strong>the</strong> records of <strong>the</strong> financial services.TABLEI1RESULTSOF COSIMITSIENTSSTOCKSIN MADEBY TWENTYFIRE INSURANCECOMPANIES (RELATEDTO STOCKMARKETAVERAGES)All companies 1928-31, inc.CompanyPer cent1. ..............................................+27.352. ..............................................$25.113. ..............................................+18.344. .............................................. $10.385. ..............................................+10.126. 3.207. ..............................................- 2.068. ............................................. - 3.639. .............................................- 5.0610. .............................................. - 6.6711. .............................................. -10.4412. .............................................. -10.5513. .............................................. -11.7614. .............................................. -12.9215. .............................................-13.8216. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . -14.9617. .............................................-18.0318. -21.8919. -23.4420. .............................................. -33.72FORECASTING THE STOCK MARKET ACCORDING TO THE DOW THEORYHaving dealt with <strong>the</strong> efficiency of two great groups of professionals,fire insurance companies and financial services, in selecting commons<strong>to</strong>cks for investment, we turn now <strong>to</strong> a consideration of skill inpredicting <strong>the</strong> course of <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck market as a whole. This section alsois in two principal sub-divisions. First we consider <strong>the</strong> record of WilliamPeter Ramil<strong>to</strong>n.This analysis was undertaken because several decades of edi<strong>to</strong>rialsin <strong>the</strong> country's leading financial newspaper have built up a great popularfollowing for <strong>the</strong> Dow Theory, of which Eamil<strong>to</strong>n was <strong>the</strong> principalsponsor. The Dow Theory was <strong>the</strong> creation of Charles H . Dow, founderof <strong>the</strong> Dour Jones financial news service, founder and edi<strong>to</strong>r of <strong>the</strong> WallStred Journal. After Dour's death in 1902 Hamil<strong>to</strong>n succeeded him asedi<strong>to</strong>r of <strong>the</strong> Wall Street Journal, continuing in this position until hisdeath in December, 1929.During 26 years of his incumbency Hamil<strong>to</strong>n wrote 255 edi<strong>to</strong>rialswhich presented forecasts for <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck market based on <strong>the</strong> Dow Theory.These were sufficiently definite <strong>to</strong> permit scoring as bullish, bearish,or doubtful. This we did by a majority vote of five readers. When


ALFRED COWLES ~ R D315doubtful we assumed that he abstained from trading. When bullish itwas assumed that he bought equal dollar amounts of <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>cks includedin <strong>the</strong> Dour Jones railroad and industrial averages, and sold<strong>the</strong>m only when he became bearish or doubtful. When bearish we assumedthat he sold short equal dollar amounts of <strong>the</strong>se s<strong>to</strong>cks andcovered only when he became doubtful or bullish. The percentage gainor loss on each such transaction has been calculated, and <strong>the</strong> resultscompounded through <strong>the</strong> 26 years. Since <strong>the</strong> Dow Jones averages haveonly recently been corrected <strong>to</strong> offset <strong>the</strong> effect of s<strong>to</strong>ck rights, s<strong>to</strong>ckdividends, and s<strong>to</strong>ck splits, such adjustments have been made for all<strong>the</strong> previous years on <strong>the</strong> basis of tables published by Dwight C. Rosein his book Investment Management. Corrections have also been made<strong>to</strong> allow for <strong>the</strong> effect of brokerage charges, cash dividends, and <strong>the</strong>interest presumably earned by Hamil<strong>to</strong>n's funds when <strong>the</strong>y were notin <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck market. The fully adjusted figures were <strong>the</strong>n reduced <strong>to</strong>an effective annual rate of gain which is presented as a measure of t<strong>here</strong>sult accomplished.From December 1903 <strong>to</strong> December 1929, Hamil<strong>to</strong>n, through <strong>the</strong> applicationof his forecasts <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>cks composing <strong>the</strong> Dour Jones industrialaverages, would have earned a return, including dividend andinterest income, of 12 per cent per annum. In <strong>the</strong> same period <strong>the</strong>s<strong>to</strong>cks composing <strong>the</strong> industrial averages showed a return of 15.5 percent per annum. Hamil<strong>to</strong>n t<strong>here</strong>fore failed by an appreciable margin<strong>to</strong> gain as much through his forecasting as he would have made by acontinuous outright investment in <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>cks composing <strong>the</strong> industrialaverages. He exceeded by a wide margin, however, a supposedly normalinvestment return of about 5 per cent. Applying his forecasts <strong>to</strong><strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>cks composing <strong>the</strong> Dow Jones railroad averages, <strong>the</strong> result isan annual gain of 5.7 per cent while <strong>the</strong> railroad averages <strong>the</strong>mselvesshow a return of 7.7 per cent.Hamil<strong>to</strong>n was long of s<strong>to</strong>cks 55 per cent, short 16 per cent, and ou<strong>to</strong>f <strong>the</strong> market 29 per cent, of <strong>the</strong> 26 years under review. Counting onlychanges of position, he made bullish forecasts 29 times. Applying <strong>the</strong>se<strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> industrial averages, 16 were profitable, 13 unprofitable. He announcedbearish forecasts 23 times, 10 were profitable, 13 unprofitable.He advised 38 times that funds be withdrawn from <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck market,19 of <strong>the</strong>se withdrawals being profitable, 19 unprofitable. In all, 45 ofhis changes of position were unsuccessful, 45 successful. The applicationof <strong>the</strong> forecasts <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> railroad averages confirms <strong>the</strong>se conclusionsexcept that in this case 41 changes of position were successful and 49unsuccessful. For <strong>the</strong> period from 1909 <strong>to</strong> 1914 inclusive, when <strong>the</strong> industrialaverages displayed what, in effect, was a horizontal trend, hishypo<strong>the</strong>tical fund shrank 7.8 per cent Der annum below what it would


316 ECONOMETRICAhave been if loaned at 5 per cent interest. The result of applying hisforecasts <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> railroad averages deserves attention in view of <strong>the</strong> factthat this group displayed an almost horizontal secular trend for <strong>the</strong>26 years under consideration. His average annual pain of 5.7 per centin this group would have been approximately equalled, in <strong>the</strong> case ofa continuous outright investment, by <strong>the</strong> dividend income.STOCK NARKET FORECASTS OF TWENTY-FOUR FINANCIALPUBLICATIONSFor <strong>the</strong> analysis of o<strong>the</strong>r results secured in forecasting <strong>the</strong> course of<strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck market, we selected during <strong>the</strong> period from January 1, 1928,<strong>to</strong> June 1, 1932, 24 publications (among which were 18 professionalfinancial services, 4 financial weeklies, one bank letter, and one investmenthouse letter). More than 3,300 forecasts were tabulated. Themethod used has been for each reader <strong>to</strong> ask himself <strong>the</strong> question, "In<strong>the</strong> light of what this particular bulletin says, would one be led <strong>to</strong> buys<strong>to</strong>cks with all <strong>the</strong> funds at his disposal, or place a portion only of hisfunds in s<strong>to</strong>cks, or withdraw entirely from <strong>the</strong> market?" The readergraded <strong>the</strong> advice in each instance by means of one of nine possibleentries, namely 100 per cent of funds in <strong>the</strong> market, 87$, 75, 62$, 50,374, 25, 124, or 0 per cent. The great majority of forecasters confine<strong>the</strong>mselves <strong>to</strong> general discussions of <strong>the</strong> investment situation, leaving<strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> reader <strong>the</strong> decision as <strong>to</strong> what proportion of his funds he shallplace in <strong>the</strong> market. The tabulation, t<strong>here</strong>fore, cannot be ma<strong>the</strong>maticallyconclusive. Our method, in general, has been <strong>to</strong> have <strong>the</strong> vote ofthree readers of c~mpetent intelligence determine <strong>the</strong> interpretation ofeach forecast. Marginal commitments have not been incorporated inour tabulations because in no case have <strong>the</strong>y been advised by any of<strong>the</strong> forecasters. Similarly, short commitments are not in general assumedbecause, of <strong>the</strong> entire 24 forecasters, only one recommended<strong>the</strong>m. His record has been computed on a special basis.The tabulated forecasts have been tested in <strong>the</strong> light of <strong>the</strong> actualfluctuations of <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck market as reflected by <strong>the</strong> Standard StatisticsCompany index of 90 representative s<strong>to</strong>cks. If a forecast is 100 per centbullish and <strong>the</strong> market rises 10 per cent in <strong>the</strong> subsequent week, <strong>the</strong>forecaster is scored as +10 per cent. If <strong>the</strong> forecaster, after weighing<strong>the</strong> favorable and unfavorable fac<strong>to</strong>rs, leaves <strong>the</strong> decision hanging in<strong>the</strong> balance, <strong>the</strong> score is $5 per cent or one-half of <strong>the</strong> market advance.This is on <strong>the</strong> assumption that <strong>the</strong> inves<strong>to</strong>r, being in doubt as <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong>future course of <strong>the</strong> market and being, by definition, committed <strong>to</strong>common s<strong>to</strong>cks as a possible investment medium, would be led <strong>to</strong>adopt a hedged position with half of his funds in s<strong>to</strong>cks and half inreserve. If <strong>the</strong> forecast is 100 per cent bearish, <strong>the</strong> score is zero, regard-


ALFRED COWLES ~ R D317less of <strong>the</strong> subsequent action of <strong>the</strong> mnrket, on <strong>the</strong> assumption that,under such conditions, <strong>the</strong> inves<strong>to</strong>r would withdraw all of his fundsfrom s<strong>to</strong>cl\s. On <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r hand, if <strong>the</strong> forecast is 100 per cent hullis11and <strong>the</strong> market drops 10 per cent in <strong>the</strong> ensuing weeli, <strong>the</strong> score is-10 per cent. If <strong>the</strong> forecast is doubtful when <strong>the</strong> market drops 10 percent, <strong>the</strong> score is -5 per cent. The compounding of all <strong>the</strong>se weeklyscores for <strong>the</strong> period covered gives a cumulative record for each forecaster.This permits comparisons which reveal relative success andaverage performance. While it may be thought that accurate week-<strong>to</strong>weekforecasting is a hopeless ideal, it should be emphasized that ouranalysis of weekly results also measures accurately <strong>the</strong> efficiency oflong swing forecasts.A figure representing <strong>the</strong> average of all possible forecasting resultsfor <strong>the</strong> period was arrived at by compounding one-half of every weeklypercentage change in <strong>the</strong> level of <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck market. The final scoresgiven below for <strong>the</strong> 24 forecasters were computed by dividing <strong>the</strong>actual performance of each by <strong>the</strong> average of all possible results referred<strong>to</strong> above, and subtracting 100.TABLEI11RESULTSOF STOCKMARKETFORECASTSForecaster Weeks Per cent1. .....................105 ..................... f72.42. ..................... 230 ..................... +31.53. .....................230 ..................... +28.34. ..................... 21 ..................... $24.25. ..................... 157 ..................... + 9.06. ..................... 53 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . + 3.07. ..................... 126 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . + 2.48. ..................... 53 ..................... + 1.39. ..................... 105 ..................... - 1.710. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 157 ..................... - 2.111. ..................... 230 ..................... - 3.612. ..................... 43 ..................... - 6.013. ..................... 53 ..................... - 6.714. ..................... 131 ..................... - 6.915. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 230 ..................... -12.516. .....................230 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . -13.517. ..................... 53 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . -17.218. .....................230 ..................... -21.519. ..................... 69 ..................... -29.420. ..................... 230 ..................... -83.021. ..................... 230 ..................... -35.322. ..................... 230 ..................... -41.523. ..................... 157 ..................... -45.324. ..................... 230 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . -49.1The records show that only one-third of <strong>the</strong> list met with any success.In order <strong>to</strong> derive a significant average of <strong>the</strong> performance of <strong>the</strong>


entire group <strong>the</strong> results listed above have been reduced <strong>to</strong> effectiveannual rates, and each has been given a weight <strong>to</strong> conform with <strong>the</strong>length of <strong>the</strong> record analysed. After <strong>the</strong>se adjustments, we are enabled<strong>to</strong> conclude that <strong>the</strong> average forecasting agency fell approximately4 per cent per annum below a record representing <strong>the</strong> average of allperformances achievable by pure chance. This would seem <strong>to</strong> indicatethat, in general, <strong>the</strong>se s<strong>to</strong>ck market forecasters failed <strong>to</strong> accomplish<strong>the</strong>ir objective. The most that can be said in extenuation is that <strong>the</strong>long-continued decline in securities has been, naturally, a handicap <strong>to</strong>a group which, taking warning from <strong>the</strong> experience of Cassandra, usuallyseems constrained <strong>to</strong> look on <strong>the</strong> bright side. During <strong>the</strong> 43 yearperiod under analysis <strong>the</strong> number of weeks in which <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck marketdeclined almost exactly equalled <strong>the</strong> number of weeks in which advanceswere recorded, and <strong>the</strong> <strong>to</strong>tal amount of <strong>the</strong> declines considerablyexceeded <strong>the</strong> <strong>to</strong>tal amount of <strong>the</strong> advances. Yet we recordedduring this period 2033 bullish, 804 bearish, and 479 doubtful forecasts.Fur<strong>the</strong>r, we note that in 1028, <strong>the</strong> only year <strong>the</strong> market showeda net gain, <strong>the</strong> excess of bullish over bearish forecasts was smaller thanin any succeeding year. Taking a glaring example, in <strong>the</strong> rising marke<strong>to</strong>f 1928 <strong>the</strong> ratio of bullish <strong>to</strong> bearish forecasts was only four <strong>to</strong> three.In 1931, when <strong>the</strong> market declined 54 per cent, t<strong>here</strong> were sixteenbullish forecasts <strong>to</strong> every three bearish.STATISTICAL INTERPRETATIONS OF RESULTSIn an attempt <strong>to</strong> illuminate <strong>the</strong> problem of whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> records of all<strong>the</strong>se forecasters lay within <strong>the</strong> limits of pure chance, we compiled24 records, identical with those of <strong>the</strong> 24 forecasters as <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>to</strong>talperiod covered, but having purely fortui<strong>to</strong>us advices applied <strong>to</strong> randomintervals within <strong>the</strong>se perids. For example, <strong>to</strong> compile a purely chancerecord <strong>to</strong> compare with <strong>the</strong> actual record of a forecaster whose operationscovered 230 weeks from January 1,1928, <strong>to</strong> June 1,1932, we firstdetermined <strong>the</strong> average number of changes of advice for such a period,which was 33. Cards numbered from 1<strong>to</strong> 229 were shuffled, drawn, reshuffled,drawn, in all 33 times. Thus 33 random dates were selectedas of which forecasts were <strong>to</strong> be changed. The investment policieswhich were <strong>to</strong> apply <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> intervals between those dates were derivedin similar fortui<strong>to</strong>us fashion, by drawing 33 times from nine cards oneach of which a different one of <strong>the</strong> nine possible investment policieswas noted.It only remained <strong>to</strong> relate <strong>the</strong>se random advices <strong>to</strong> a s<strong>to</strong>ck marketindex, cumulate <strong>the</strong> results, relate <strong>the</strong>m, as we had done with t<strong>here</strong>cords of <strong>the</strong> actual forecasters, <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> average of all chances for <strong>the</strong>period, and subtract 100. Thus we had a list of 21 purely chance fore-


ALFRED COWLES ~ R D 319casting records, shown in Table IV, <strong>to</strong> compare with <strong>the</strong> records of <strong>the</strong>actual prophet's.TABLEIVRESULTSOF RANDOMFORECASTSForecaster Weeks Per cent1. ..................... 230 ..................... f 7 1 . 12. .....................230 ..................... +37.23. .....................230 ..................... +24.24. ....................157 ..................... +19.15. ..................... 230 ..................... f 1 3 . 26. ..................... 105 .................... + 9.27. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 230 ..................... + 2 . 78. ..................... 53 ..................... + 2.59. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 131 .....................+ 1.3lo. .....................230 .................... f 1.111. ..................... 53 ..................... - .112. ..................... 54 ..................... - .613. ..................... 157 ..................... - 2.514. .....................230 ..................... - 4.615. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 43 ..................... - 5.416. ..................... 53 ..................... - 6.117. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 230 ..................... -10.518. ..................... 21 .................... -10.919. .....................157 ..................... -11.020. ..................... 105 ..................... -13.021. ..................... 230 ..................... -13.122. ..................... 230 ..................... -14.223. ..................... 69 -18.724. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 126 ..................... -27.1For easy comparison of <strong>the</strong> two groups we have prepared Figure 1showing all <strong>the</strong> records, actual and hypo<strong>the</strong>tical. The chart indicatesthat w<strong>here</strong> forecasting agencies made gains, even <strong>the</strong> greatest of <strong>the</strong>selay within limits equalled by <strong>the</strong> best of our 24 imaginary recordsrepresenting random action at random intervals. But <strong>the</strong> extremerlosses of <strong>the</strong> forecasters tended <strong>to</strong> exceed <strong>the</strong> losses registered by <strong>the</strong>least successful of our 2-1 records of purely chance operations.In any attempt at interpreting <strong>the</strong> significance of <strong>the</strong> performancesof <strong>the</strong> various s<strong>to</strong>ck market forecasters we are embarrased by our inability<strong>to</strong> determine how often economic developments occur of sufficientimportance <strong>to</strong> justify <strong>the</strong> revision of forecasts. This is tantamount<strong>to</strong> admitting that we do not know <strong>the</strong> true number of independentcases, or items, in <strong>the</strong> time series representing <strong>the</strong> various forecastingrecords. In <strong>the</strong>se circumstances, probable errors for correlation coefficients,or for normal distributions, cannot constitute very exact measuresof probability JVe do know, however, since we are dealing withweekly publications, that <strong>the</strong> maximum possible number of forecastingopportunities is 32 a year. 5Ve also know that forecasts, on <strong>the</strong> average,undergo some degree of revision about 7 times a year. The correlation


320 ECONOMETRICAcoefficients and probable errors, which constitute one of our tests ofprobability, have been worked out on both of <strong>the</strong>se bases.The record of Forecaster Kumber 1 was available <strong>to</strong> us for a periodof only two years, during which he did not once change his advice. Tiret<strong>here</strong>fore omitted his record from consideration in our statistical interpretationon <strong>the</strong> ground that inferences based on it would be relativelyinconclusive. For <strong>the</strong> correlation test t<strong>here</strong>fore, Forecasters Number2, 3, 22 and 24 were chosen as representing <strong>the</strong> best and <strong>the</strong> worstwhose records covered <strong>the</strong> entire period under analysis. The weeklyforecasts of each of <strong>the</strong>se four were correlated with <strong>the</strong> first differencesSTOCK MARKET FORECASTING1 24 professional Agenctes 1 ( 24 Random Records 1of <strong>the</strong> logarit'hms of t'he s<strong>to</strong>ck market averages over 44 years. ForecasterNumber 2 had a correlation coefficient of .I51 ;Forecaster Number3, of .107; and Forecast'ers Number 22 and 24, of -.I24 and -.I32respect'ively. The probable error of <strong>the</strong> best correlation coefficient, withn =230, was .043. The difference in r between Forecast'ers Numbers 1and 3 is about equal t'o this probable error, and r =.I97 is greater t'har4 times <strong>the</strong> probable error of .043. We have interpreted <strong>the</strong>se data bj<strong>the</strong> use of R. A. Fisher's technique, w<strong>here</strong> z= tan h-lr. The best cor.relation r = .197, n =230, was first compared with a t'heoretical r = .000n =230; and <strong>the</strong>n compared with r = -.132, n =230, t'hat is <strong>the</strong> loweslcorrelat'ion coefficient,.1' z n -3 1/n -31st sample .I97 .200 227 .0044 12nd sample ,000 ,000 227 .00441-Difference .200 Sum ,00882


ALFRED COWLES ~ R D321,188 is <strong>to</strong> be compared with .200. Since <strong>the</strong>se figures are approximatelyequal, <strong>the</strong> presumption of skill is slight although <strong>the</strong> presumption doesexist because of <strong>the</strong> fact that .I88 is less than .200, <strong>the</strong> difference between<strong>the</strong> two values for =. Using R. A. Fisher's technique in <strong>the</strong> secondcase, that is, comparing <strong>the</strong> best correlation coefficient r = .I97 with<strong>the</strong> lowest correlation coefficient r= -.132, seems <strong>to</strong> indicate thatt<strong>here</strong> is a real difference between <strong>the</strong> two samples. If ano<strong>the</strong>r samplewere taken from each of <strong>the</strong>se two forecasters, we should expect <strong>to</strong> findn similar difference between <strong>the</strong>m in favor of <strong>the</strong> first forecaster within<strong>the</strong> limits of <strong>the</strong> probable error.We <strong>the</strong>n computed correlation coefficients and probd)le errors for<strong>the</strong> data arrived at by taking as our items <strong>the</strong> periods during whicheach forecast was in force. We thus had 30 items for Forecaster Xumher2, which equalled <strong>the</strong> number of changes he made in his forecasts,instead of <strong>the</strong> 230 items which represented <strong>the</strong> number of weeks fortvhich his record was tabulated. On this basis Forecaster Sumber 2had a correlation coefficient of .479; Forecaster Kumber 3 had a correlationcoefficient of ,245; and Forecasters Number 22 and 24 had correlationcoefficients of -313 and -.206 respectively. The probable errorof <strong>the</strong> best correlation coefficient, with n=30, was found <strong>to</strong> be .095.Thus r =.479 was about five times <strong>the</strong> probable error of .005. The bestrandom forecast had r =.356$- .102, when his changes of position weretaken as <strong>the</strong> items of <strong>the</strong> series. When <strong>the</strong> number of weeks (230), overwhich his random record extends, was used, and this record correlatedwith <strong>the</strong> first differences of <strong>the</strong> logarithms of <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck market averages,r =.I25f,044.Deductions as <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> significance of <strong>the</strong> relationships of <strong>the</strong> variouscorrelation coefficients <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> probable errors are rendered inconclusive,not only by our inability <strong>to</strong> identify <strong>the</strong> true number of independentcases in each series, but also by <strong>the</strong> fact that we have not computed asufficient number of <strong>the</strong> correlation coefficients <strong>to</strong> enable us <strong>to</strong> determine<strong>the</strong> character of <strong>the</strong>ir distribution.Having thus experimented with various correlation tests we <strong>the</strong>nresorted <strong>to</strong> measuring <strong>the</strong> spread of <strong>the</strong> performances of <strong>the</strong> individualforecasters by means of frequency distributions of <strong>the</strong> percentage~~eekly gains and losses of each of six forecasters divided by <strong>the</strong> averageresult of all possible forecasts. The six chosen were two of <strong>the</strong> bestactual records, two of <strong>the</strong> worst actual records, and <strong>the</strong> best andalmost <strong>the</strong> worst random records. The series thus arrived at were eachdistributed in<strong>to</strong> several classes ranging from 92.50 per cent <strong>to</strong> 108.50per cent; <strong>the</strong>se frequencies were plotted and appeared <strong>to</strong> be reasonablynormal. (See Figure 2.) Averages of each of <strong>the</strong> percentage frequencydistributions were computed and compared with a <strong>the</strong>oretical average


322 ECOXOMETRICAFREQUENCY OlSTRlBUTlONSForecaster 2 _ Forecaster 3125 - -<strong>to</strong>o- 50rnqmwr-WOO -~m=3-nQtcao m=$v,~rcooo-arr,~v,~r-rnomaaoaoa""ppooppgA o o o o a o m p ~ g ~ p g p p ~ AForecaster 22 Forecaster 24 -I25100. 75m cn ~ on w r ~ namao m -~ N mg vg m~ a g + ~ w~ og g A%d%%6888szsdZ3h$%


ALFRED COWLES ~ R D323of 100, which represented <strong>the</strong> average of all random frequency distributions.The probable error of <strong>the</strong> latter was found <strong>to</strong> be .086. ForecastersNumber 2 and 3 showed averages of 100.098 and 100.103 respectively;each deviating from <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>oretical average by amounts which wereslightly greater than <strong>the</strong> probable error .086, but considerably less thantwice this probable error. Forecasters Number 22 and 24 had averagesof 99.674 and 99.711 respectively; less than <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>oretical average by3 2 6 and .289. Each of <strong>the</strong>se differences was more than three, and lessthan four, times greater than <strong>the</strong> probable error .086. When a similarfrequency distribution is made for <strong>the</strong> best purely random forecaster,it is found that <strong>the</strong> average was equal <strong>to</strong> 100.213, which is greaterthan that of Forecasters 2 and 3. The deviation from <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>oreticalaverage lies within three times <strong>the</strong> probable error of this <strong>the</strong>oreticalaverage.1. Sixteen financial services, in making some 7500 recommendationsof individual common s<strong>to</strong>cks for investment during <strong>the</strong> period fromJanuary 1, 1928, <strong>to</strong> July 1, 1932, compiled an average record that wasworse than that of <strong>the</strong> average common s<strong>to</strong>ck by 1.43 per cent annually.Statistical tests of <strong>the</strong> best individual records failed <strong>to</strong> demonstratethat <strong>the</strong>y exhibited skill, and indicated that <strong>the</strong>y more probablywere results of chance.2. Twenty fire insurance companies in making a similar selection ofsecurities during <strong>the</strong> years 1928 <strong>to</strong> 1931, inclusive, achieved an averagerecord 1.20 per cent annually worse than that of <strong>the</strong> general run ofs<strong>to</strong>cks. The best of <strong>the</strong>se records, since it is not very much more impressivethan <strong>the</strong> record of <strong>the</strong> most successful of <strong>the</strong> sixteen financialservices, fails <strong>to</strong> exhibit definitely <strong>the</strong> existence of any skill in investment.3. William Peter Hamil<strong>to</strong>n, edi<strong>to</strong>r of <strong>the</strong> U'all Street Journal, publishingforecasts of <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck market based on <strong>the</strong> Dow Theory over aperiod of 26 years, from 1904 <strong>to</strong> 1929, inclusive, achieved a result betterthan what would ordinarily be regarded as a normal investment return,but poorer than <strong>the</strong> result of a continuous outright investment in representativecommon s<strong>to</strong>cks for this period. On 90 occasions he announcedchanges in <strong>the</strong> outlook for <strong>the</strong> market. Forty-five of <strong>the</strong>sepredictions were successful and 45 unsuccessful.4. Twenty-four financial publications engaged in forecasting <strong>the</strong>s<strong>to</strong>ck market during <strong>the</strong> 4$ years from January 1,1928, <strong>to</strong> June 1,1932,failed as a group by 4 per cent per annum <strong>to</strong> achieve a result as good as<strong>the</strong> average of all purely random performances. A review of <strong>the</strong> variousstatistical tests, applied <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> records for this period, of <strong>the</strong>se 24 fore-


324 ECOBOMETRICAcasters, indicates that <strong>the</strong> most successful records are little, if any,better than what might be expected <strong>to</strong> result from pure chance. T<strong>here</strong>is some evidence, on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r hand, <strong>to</strong> indicate that <strong>the</strong> least successfulrecords are worse than what could reasonably be attributed <strong>to</strong>chance.Cowles Commission foi. Research in Economics


1EFFICIENT MARKETS HYPOTHESISAndrew W. LoTo appear in L. Blume and S. Durlauf, The New Palgrave: A Dictionary of Economics,Second Edition, 2007. New York: Palgrave McMillan.The efficient markets hypo<strong>the</strong>sis (EMH) maintains that market prices fullyreflect all available information. Developed independently by Paul A.Samuelson and Eugene F. Fama in <strong>the</strong> 1960s, this idea has been appliedextensively <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong>oretical models and empirical studies of financial securitiesprices, generating considerable controversy as well as fundamental insightsin<strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> price-discovery process. The most enduring critique comes frompsychologists and behavioural economists who argue that <strong>the</strong> EMH is basedon counterfactual assumptions regarding human behaviour, that is,rationality. Recent advances in evolutionary psychology and <strong>the</strong> cognitiveneurosciences may be able <strong>to</strong> reconcile <strong>the</strong> EMH with behaviouralanomalies.T<strong>here</strong> is an old joke, widely <strong>to</strong>ld among economists, about an economist strolling down <strong>the</strong>street with a companion. They come upon a $100 bill lying on <strong>the</strong> ground, and as <strong>the</strong>companion reaches down <strong>to</strong> pick it up, <strong>the</strong> economist says, ‘Don’t bo<strong>the</strong>r – if it were agenuine $100 bill, someone would have already picked it up’. This humorous example ofeconomic logic gone awry is a fairly accurate rendition of <strong>the</strong> efficient markets hypo<strong>the</strong>sis(EMH), one of <strong>the</strong> most hotly contested propositions in all <strong>the</strong> social sciences. It isdisarmingly simple <strong>to</strong> state, has far-reaching consequences for academic <strong>the</strong>ories andbusiness practice, and yet is surprisingly resilient <strong>to</strong> empirical proof or refutation. Even afterseveral decades of research and literally thousands of published studies, economists have notyet reached a consensus about whe<strong>the</strong>r markets – particularly financial markets – are, in fact,efficient.The origins of <strong>the</strong> EMH can be traced back <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> work of two individuals in <strong>the</strong> 1960s:Eugene F. Fama and Paul A. Samuelson. Remarkably, <strong>the</strong>y independently developed <strong>the</strong>same basic notion of market efficiency from two ra<strong>the</strong>r different research agendas. Thesedifferences would propel <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>m along two distinct trajec<strong>to</strong>ries leading <strong>to</strong> several o<strong>the</strong>rbreakthroughs and miles<strong>to</strong>nes, all originating from <strong>the</strong>ir point of intersection, <strong>the</strong> EMH.


2Like so many ideas of modern economics, <strong>the</strong> EMH was first given form by PaulSamuelson (1965), whose contribution is neatly summarized by <strong>the</strong> title of his article: ‘Proofthat Properly Anticipated Prices Fluctuate Randomly’. In an informationally efficient market,price changes must be unforecastable if <strong>the</strong>y are properly anticipated, that is, if <strong>the</strong>y fullyincorporate <strong>the</strong> information and expectations of all market participants. Having developed aseries of linear-programming solutions <strong>to</strong> spatial pricing models with no uncertainty,Samuelson came upon <strong>the</strong> idea of efficient markets through his interest in temporal pricingmodels of s<strong>to</strong>rable commodities that are harvested and subject <strong>to</strong> decay. Samuelson’s abidinginterest in <strong>the</strong> mechanics and kinematics of prices, with and without uncertainty, led him andhis students <strong>to</strong> several fruitful research agendas including solutions for <strong>the</strong> dynamic assetallocationand consumption-savings problem, <strong>the</strong> fallacy of time diversification and logoptimalinvestment policies, warrant and option-pricing analysis and, ultimately, <strong>the</strong> Blackand Scholes (1973) and Mer<strong>to</strong>n (1973) option-pricing models.In contrast <strong>to</strong> Samuelson’s path <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> EMH, Fama’s (1963; 1965a; 1965b, 1970)seminal papers were based on his interest in measuring <strong>the</strong> statistical properties of s<strong>to</strong>ckprices, and in resolving <strong>the</strong> debate between technical analysis (<strong>the</strong> use of geometric patternsin price and volume charts <strong>to</strong> forecast future price movements of a security) and fundamentalanalysis (<strong>the</strong> use of accounting and economic data <strong>to</strong> determine a security’s fair value).Among <strong>the</strong> first <strong>to</strong> employ modern digital computers <strong>to</strong> conduct empirical research infinance, and <strong>the</strong> first <strong>to</strong> use <strong>the</strong> term ‘efficient markets’ (Fama, 1965b), Fama operationalized<strong>the</strong> EMH hypo<strong>the</strong>sis – summarized compactly in <strong>the</strong> epigram ‘prices fully reflect all availableinformation’ – by placing structure on various information sets available <strong>to</strong> marketparticipants. Fama’s fascination with empirical analysis led him and his students down a verydifferent path from Samuelson’s, yielding significant methodological and empiricalcontributions such as <strong>the</strong> event study, numerous econometric tests of single- and multi-fac<strong>to</strong>rlinear asset-pricing models, and a host of empirical regularities and anomalies in s<strong>to</strong>ck, bond,currency and commodity markets.The EMH’s concept of informational efficiency has a Zen-like, counter-intuitiveflavour <strong>to</strong> it: <strong>the</strong> more efficient <strong>the</strong> market, <strong>the</strong> more random <strong>the</strong> sequence of price changesgenerated by such a market, and <strong>the</strong> most efficient market of all is one in which price changesare completely random and unpredictable. This is not an accident of nature, but is in fact <strong>the</strong>direct result of many active market participants attempting <strong>to</strong> profit from <strong>the</strong>ir information.Driven by profit opportunities, an army of inves<strong>to</strong>rs pounce on even <strong>the</strong> smallestinformational advantages at <strong>the</strong>ir disposal, and in doing so <strong>the</strong>y incorporate <strong>the</strong>ir information


3in<strong>to</strong> market prices and quickly eliminate <strong>the</strong> profit opportunities that first motivated <strong>the</strong>irtrades. If this occurs instantaneously, which it must in an idealized world of ‘frictionless’markets and costless trading, <strong>the</strong>n prices must always fully reflect all available information.T<strong>here</strong>fore, no profits can be garnered from information-based trading because such profitsmust have already been captured (recall <strong>the</strong> $100 bill on <strong>the</strong> ground). In ma<strong>the</strong>matical terms,prices follow martingales.Such compelling motivation for randomness is unique among <strong>the</strong> social sciences and isreminiscent of <strong>the</strong> role that uncertainty plays in quantum mechanics. Just as Heisenberg’suncertainty principle places a limit on what we can know about an electron’s position andmomentum if quantum mechanics holds, this version of <strong>the</strong> EMH places a limit on what wecan know about future price changes if <strong>the</strong> forces of economic self-interest hold.A decade after Samuelson’s (1965) and Fama’s (1965a; 1965b; 1970) landmark papers,many o<strong>the</strong>rs extended <strong>the</strong>ir framework <strong>to</strong> allow for risk-averse inves<strong>to</strong>rs, yielding a‘neoclassical’ version of <strong>the</strong> EMH w<strong>here</strong> price changes, properly weighted by aggregatemarginal utilities, must be unforecastable (see, for example, LeRoy, 1973; M. Rubinstein,1976; and Lucas, 1978). In markets w<strong>here</strong>, according <strong>to</strong> Lucas (1978), all inves<strong>to</strong>rs have‘rational expectations’, prices do fully reflect all available information and marginal-utilityweightedprices follow martingales. The EMH has been extended in many o<strong>the</strong>r directions,including <strong>the</strong> incorporation of non-traded assets such as human capital, state-dependentpreferences, heterogeneous inves<strong>to</strong>rs, asymmetric information, and transactions costs. But <strong>the</strong>general thrust is <strong>the</strong> same: individual inves<strong>to</strong>rs form expectations rationally, marketsaggregate information efficiently, and equilibrium prices incorporate all available informationinstantaneously.The random walk hypo<strong>the</strong>sisThe importance of <strong>the</strong> EMH stems primarily from its sharp empirical implications many ofwhich have been tested over <strong>the</strong> years. Much of <strong>the</strong> EMH literature before LeRoy (1973) andLucas (1978) revolved around <strong>the</strong> random walk hypo<strong>the</strong>sis (RWH) and <strong>the</strong> martingale model,two statistical descriptions of unforecastable price changes that were initially taken <strong>to</strong> beimplications of <strong>the</strong> EMH. One of <strong>the</strong> first tests of <strong>the</strong> RWH was developed by Cowles andJones (1937), who compared <strong>the</strong> frequency of sequences and reversals in his<strong>to</strong>rical s<strong>to</strong>ckreturns, w<strong>here</strong> <strong>the</strong> former are pairs of consecutive returns with <strong>the</strong> same sign, and <strong>the</strong> latterare pairs of consecutive returns with opposite signs. Cootner (1962; 1964), Fama (1963;1965a), Fama and Blume (1966), and Osborne (1959) perform related tests of <strong>the</strong> RWH and,


4with <strong>the</strong> exception of Cowles and Jones (who subsequently acknowledged an error in <strong>the</strong>iranalysis – Cowles, 1960), all of <strong>the</strong>se articles indicate support for <strong>the</strong> RWH using his<strong>to</strong>ricals<strong>to</strong>ck price data.More recently, Lo and MacKinlay (1988) exploit <strong>the</strong> fact that return variances scalelinearly under <strong>the</strong> RWH – <strong>the</strong> variance of a two-week return is twice <strong>the</strong> variance of a oneweekreturn if <strong>the</strong> RWH holds – and construct a variance ratio test which rejects <strong>the</strong> RWH forweekly US s<strong>to</strong>ck returns indexes from 1962 <strong>to</strong> 1985. In particular, <strong>the</strong>y find that variancesgrow faster than linearly as <strong>the</strong> holding period increases, implying positive serial correlationin weekly returns. Oddly enough, Lo and MacKinlay also show that individual s<strong>to</strong>cksgenerally do satisfy <strong>the</strong> RWH, a fact that we shall return <strong>to</strong> below.French and Roll (1986) document a related phenomenon: s<strong>to</strong>ck return variances overweekends and exchange holidays are considerably lower than return variances over <strong>the</strong> samenumber of days when markets are open. This difference suggests that <strong>the</strong> very act of tradingcreates volatility, which may well be a symp<strong>to</strong>m of Black’s (1986) noise traders.For holding periods much longer than one week – fcor example, three <strong>to</strong> five years –Fama and French (1988) and Poterba and Summers (1988) find negative serial correlation inUS s<strong>to</strong>ck returns indexes using data from 1926 <strong>to</strong> 1986. Although <strong>the</strong>ir estimates of serialcorrelation coefficients seem large in magnitude, t<strong>here</strong> is insufficient data <strong>to</strong> reject <strong>the</strong> RWHat <strong>the</strong> usual levels of significance. Moreover, a number of statistical artifacts documented byKim, Nelson and Startz (1991) and Richardson (1993) cast serious doubt on <strong>the</strong> reliability of<strong>the</strong>se longer-horizon inferences.Finally, Lo (1991) considers ano<strong>the</strong>r aspect of s<strong>to</strong>ck market prices long thought <strong>to</strong> havebeen a departure from <strong>the</strong> RWH: long-term memory. Time series with long-term memoryexhibit an unusually high degree of persistence, so that observations in <strong>the</strong> remote past arenon-trivially correlated with observations in <strong>the</strong> distant future, even as <strong>the</strong> time span between<strong>the</strong> two observations increases. Nature’s predilection <strong>to</strong>wards long-term memory has beenwell-documented in <strong>the</strong> natural sciences such as hydrology, meteorology, and geophysics,and some have argued that economic time series must t<strong>here</strong>fore also have this property.However, using recently developed statistical techniques, Lo (1991) constructs a test forlong-term memory that is robust <strong>to</strong> short-term correlations of <strong>the</strong> sort uncovered by Lo andMacKinlay (1988), and concludes that, despite earlier evidence <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> contrary, t<strong>here</strong> is littlesupport for long-term memory in s<strong>to</strong>ck market prices. Departures from <strong>the</strong> RWH can be fullyexplained by conventional models of short-term dependence.


5Variance bounds testsAno<strong>the</strong>r set of empirical tests of <strong>the</strong> EMH starts with <strong>the</strong> observation that in a world withoutuncertainty <strong>the</strong> market price of a share of common s<strong>to</strong>ck must equal <strong>the</strong> present value of allfuture dividends, discounted at <strong>the</strong> appropriate cost of capital. In an uncertain world, one cangeneralize this dividend-discount model or present-value relation in <strong>the</strong> natural way: <strong>the</strong>market price equals <strong>the</strong> conditional expectation of <strong>the</strong> present value of all future dividends,discounted at <strong>the</strong> appropriate risk-adjusted cost of capital, and conditional on all availableinformation. This generalization is explicitly developed by Grossman and Shiller (1981).LeRoy and Porter (1981) and Shiller (1981) take this as <strong>the</strong>ir starting point incomparing <strong>the</strong> variance of s<strong>to</strong>ck market prices <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> variance of ex post present values offuture dividends. If <strong>the</strong> market price is <strong>the</strong> conditional expectation of present values, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong>difference between <strong>the</strong> two, that is, <strong>the</strong> forecast error, must be uncorrelated with <strong>the</strong>conditional expectation by construction. But this implies that <strong>the</strong> variance of <strong>the</strong> ex postpresent value is <strong>the</strong> sum of <strong>the</strong> variance of <strong>the</strong> market price (<strong>the</strong> conditional expectation) and<strong>the</strong> variance of <strong>the</strong> forecast error. Since volatilities are always non-negative, this variancedecomposition implies that <strong>the</strong> variance of s<strong>to</strong>ck prices cannot exceed <strong>the</strong> variance of ex postpresent values. Using annual US s<strong>to</strong>ck market data from various sample periods, LeRoy andPorter (1981) and Shiller (1981) find that <strong>the</strong> variance bound is violated dramatically.Although LeRoy and Porter are more circumspect about <strong>the</strong> implications of such violations,Shiller concludes that s<strong>to</strong>ck market prices are <strong>to</strong>o volatile and <strong>the</strong> EMH must be false.These two papers ignited a flurry of responses which challenged Shiller’s controversialconclusion on a number of fronts. For example, Flavin (1983), Kleidon (1986), and Marshand Mer<strong>to</strong>n (1986) show that statistical inference is ra<strong>the</strong>r delicate for <strong>the</strong>se variance bounds,and that, even if <strong>the</strong>y hold in <strong>the</strong>ory, for <strong>the</strong> kind of sample sizes Shiller uses and underplausible data-generating processes <strong>the</strong> sample variance bound is often violated purely due <strong>to</strong>sampling variation. These issues are well summarized in Gilles and LeRoy (1991) andMer<strong>to</strong>n (1987).More importantly, on purely <strong>the</strong>oretical grounds Marsh and Mer<strong>to</strong>n (1986) andMichener (1982) provide two explanations for violations of variance bounds that are perfectlyconsistent with <strong>the</strong> EMH. Marsh and Mer<strong>to</strong>n (1986) show that if managers smooth dividends– a well-known empirical phenomenon documented in several studies of dividend policy –and if earnings follow a geometric random walk, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> variance bound is violated in<strong>the</strong>ory, in which case <strong>the</strong> empirical violations may be interpreted as support for this versionof <strong>the</strong> EMH.


6Alternatively, Michener constructs a simple dynamic equilibrium model along <strong>the</strong> linesof Lucas (1978) in which prices do fully reflect all available information at all times butw<strong>here</strong> individuals are risk averse, and this risk aversion is enough <strong>to</strong> cause <strong>the</strong> variancebound <strong>to</strong> be violated in <strong>the</strong>ory as well.These findings highlight an important aspect of <strong>the</strong> EMH that had not been emphasizedin earlier studies: tests of <strong>the</strong> EMH are always tests of joint hypo<strong>the</strong>ses. In particular, <strong>the</strong>phrase ‘prices fully reflect all available information’ is a statement about two distinct aspectsof prices: <strong>the</strong> information content and <strong>the</strong> price formation mechanism. T<strong>here</strong>fore, any test ofthis proposition must concern <strong>the</strong> kind of information reflected in prices, and how thisinformation comes <strong>to</strong> be reflected in prices.Apart from issues regarding statistical inference, <strong>the</strong> empirical violation of variancebounds may be interpreted in many ways. It may be a violation of EMH, or a sign thatinves<strong>to</strong>rs are risk averse, or a symp<strong>to</strong>m of dividend smoothing. To choose among <strong>the</strong>sealternatives, more evidence is required.Overreaction and underreactionA common explanation for departures from <strong>the</strong> EMH is that inves<strong>to</strong>rs do not always react inproper proportion <strong>to</strong> new information. For example, in some cases inves<strong>to</strong>rs may overreact <strong>to</strong>performance, selling s<strong>to</strong>cks that have experienced recent losses or buying s<strong>to</strong>cks that haveenjoyed recent gains. Such overreaction tends <strong>to</strong> push prices beyond <strong>the</strong>ir ‘fair’ or ‘rational’market value, only <strong>to</strong> have rational inves<strong>to</strong>rs take <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r side of <strong>the</strong> trades and bring pricesback in line eventually. An implication of this phenomenon is price reversals: what goes upmust come down, and vice versa. Ano<strong>the</strong>r implication is that contrarian investmentstrategies – strategies in which ‘losers’ are purchased and ‘winners’ are sold – will earnsuperior returns.Both of <strong>the</strong>se implications were tested and confirmed using recent US s<strong>to</strong>ck marketdata. For example, using monthly returns of New York S<strong>to</strong>ck Exchange (NYSE) s<strong>to</strong>cks from1926 <strong>to</strong> 1982, DeBondt and Thaler (1985) document <strong>the</strong> fact that <strong>the</strong> winners and losers inone 36-month period tend <strong>to</strong> reverse <strong>the</strong>ir performance over <strong>the</strong> next 36-month period.Curiously, many of <strong>the</strong>se reversals occur in January (see <strong>the</strong> discussion below on <strong>the</strong> ‘Januaryeffect’). Chopra, Lakonishok and Ritter (1992) reconfirm <strong>the</strong>se findings after correcting formarket risk and <strong>the</strong> size effect. And Lehmann (1990) shows that a zero-net-investmentstrategy in which long positions in losers are financed by short positions in winners almostalways yields positive returns for monthly NYSE/AMEX s<strong>to</strong>ck returns data from 1962 <strong>to</strong>


71985.However, Chan (1988) argues that <strong>the</strong> profitability of contrarian investment strategiescannot be taken as conclusive evidence against <strong>the</strong> EMH because t<strong>here</strong> is typically noaccounting for risk in <strong>the</strong>se profitability calculations (although Chopra, Lakonishok andRitter, 1992 do provide risk adjustments, <strong>the</strong>ir focus was not on specific trading strategies).By risk-adjusting <strong>the</strong> returns of a contrarian trading strategy according <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> capital assetpricing model, Chan (1988) shows that <strong>the</strong> expected returns are consistent with <strong>the</strong> EMH.Moreover, Lo and MacKinlay (1990c) show that at least half of <strong>the</strong> profits reported byLehmann (1990) are not due <strong>to</strong> overreaction but ra<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> result of positive crossau<strong>to</strong>correlationsbetween s<strong>to</strong>cks. For example, suppose <strong>the</strong> returns of two s<strong>to</strong>cks A and B areboth serially uncorrelated but are positively cross-au<strong>to</strong>correlated. The lack of serialcorrelation implies no overreaction (which is characterized by negative serial correlation), butpositive cross-au<strong>to</strong>correlations yields positive expected returns <strong>to</strong> contrarian tradingstrategies. The existence of several economic rationales for positive cross-au<strong>to</strong>correlation thatare consistent with EMH suggests that <strong>the</strong> profitability of contrarian trading strategies is notsufficient evidence <strong>to</strong> conclude that inves<strong>to</strong>rs overreact.The reaction of market participants <strong>to</strong> information contained in earningsannouncements also has implications for <strong>the</strong> EMH. In one of <strong>the</strong> earliest studies of <strong>the</strong>information content of earnings, Ball and Brown (1968) show that up <strong>to</strong> 80 per cent of <strong>the</strong>information contained in <strong>the</strong> earnings ‘surprises’ is anticipated by market prices.However, <strong>the</strong> more recent article by Bernard and Thomas (1990) argues that inves<strong>to</strong>rssometimes underreact <strong>to</strong> information about future earnings contained in current earnings.This is related <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> ‘post-earnings announcement drift’ puzzle first documented by Ball andBrown (1968), in which <strong>the</strong> information contained in earnings announcement takes severaldays <strong>to</strong> become fully impounded in<strong>to</strong> market prices. Although such effects are indeedtroubling for <strong>the</strong> EMH, <strong>the</strong>ir economic significance is often questionable – while <strong>the</strong>y mayviolate <strong>the</strong> EMH in frictionless markets, very often even <strong>the</strong> smallest frictions – for example,positive trading costs, taxes – can eliminate <strong>the</strong> profits from trading strategies designed <strong>to</strong>exploit <strong>the</strong>m.AnomaliesPerhaps <strong>the</strong> most common challenge <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> EMH is <strong>the</strong> anomaly, a regular pattern in anasset’s returns which is reliable, widely known, and inexplicable. The fact that <strong>the</strong> pattern isregular and reliable implies a degree of predictability, and <strong>the</strong> fact that <strong>the</strong> regularity is


8widely known implies that many inves<strong>to</strong>rs can take can advantage of it.For example, one of <strong>the</strong> most enduring anomalies is <strong>the</strong> ‘size effect’, <strong>the</strong> apparentexcess expected returns that accrue <strong>to</strong> s<strong>to</strong>cks of small-capitalization companies – in excess of<strong>the</strong>ir risks – which was first discovered by Banz (1981). Keim (1983), Roll (1983), andRozeff and Kinney (1976) document a related anomaly: small capitalization s<strong>to</strong>cks tend <strong>to</strong>outperform large capitalization s<strong>to</strong>cks by a wide margin over <strong>the</strong> turn of <strong>the</strong> calendar year.This so-called ‘January effect’ seems robust <strong>to</strong> sample period, and is difficult <strong>to</strong> reconcilewith <strong>the</strong> EMH because of its regularity and publicity. O<strong>the</strong>r well-known anomalies include<strong>the</strong> Value Line enigma (Copeland and Mayers, 1982), <strong>the</strong> profitability of short-term returnreversalstrategies in US equities (Rosenberg, Reid and Lanstein,1985; Chan, 1988;Lehmann, 1990; and Lo and MacKinlay, 1990c), <strong>the</strong> profitability of medium-termmomentum strategies in US equities (Jegadeesh, 1990; Chan, Jegadeesh and Lakonishok,1996; and Jegadeesh and Titman, 2001), <strong>the</strong> relation between price/earnings ratios andexpected returns (Basu, 1977), <strong>the</strong> volatility of orange juice futures prices (Roll, 1984), andcalendar effects such as holiday, weekend, and turn-of-<strong>the</strong>-month seasonalities (Lakonishokand Smidt, 1988).What are we <strong>to</strong> make of <strong>the</strong>se anomalies? On <strong>the</strong> one hand, <strong>the</strong>ir persistence in <strong>the</strong> faceof public scrutiny seems <strong>to</strong> be a clear violation of <strong>the</strong> EMH. After all, most of <strong>the</strong>seanomalies can be exploited by relatively simple trading strategies, and, while <strong>the</strong> resultingprofits may not be riskless, <strong>the</strong>y seem unusually profitable relative <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir risks (see,especially, Lehmann, 1990).On <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r hand, EMH supporters might argue that such persistence is in factevidence in favour of EMH or, more <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> point, that <strong>the</strong>se anomalies cannot be exploited <strong>to</strong>any significant degree because of fac<strong>to</strong>rs such as risk or transactions costs. Moreover,although some anomalies are currently inexplicable, this may be due <strong>to</strong> a lack of imaginationon <strong>the</strong> part of academics, not necessarily a violation of <strong>the</strong> EMH. For example, recentevidence suggests that <strong>the</strong> January effect is largely due <strong>to</strong> ‘bid–ask bounce’, that is, closingprices for <strong>the</strong> last trading day of December tend <strong>to</strong> be at <strong>the</strong> bid price and closing prices for<strong>the</strong> first trading day of January tend <strong>to</strong> be at <strong>the</strong> ask price. Since small-capitalization s<strong>to</strong>cksare also often low-price s<strong>to</strong>cks, <strong>the</strong> effects of bid-ask bounce in percentage terms are muchmore pronounced for <strong>the</strong>se s<strong>to</strong>cks – a movement from bid <strong>to</strong> ask for a $5.00 s<strong>to</strong>ck on <strong>the</strong>NYSE (w<strong>here</strong> <strong>the</strong> minimum bid-ask spread was $0.125 prior <strong>to</strong> decimalization in 2000)represents a 2.5 per cent return.Whe<strong>the</strong>r or not one can profit from anomalies is a question unlikely <strong>to</strong> be settled in an


9academic setting. While calculations of ‘paper’ profits of various trading strategies comeeasily <strong>to</strong> academics, it is virtually impossible <strong>to</strong> incorporate in a realistic manner importantfeatures of <strong>the</strong> trading process such as transactions costs (including price impact), liquidity,rare events, institutional rigidities and non-stationarities. The economic value of anomaliesmust be decided in <strong>the</strong> labora<strong>to</strong>ry of actual markets by investment professionals, over longperiods of time, and even in <strong>the</strong>se cases superior performance and simple luck are easilyconfused.In fact, luck can play ano<strong>the</strong>r role in <strong>the</strong> interpretation of anomalies: it can account foranomalies that are not anomalous. Regular patterns in his<strong>to</strong>rical data can be found even if noregularities exist, purely by chance. Although <strong>the</strong> likelihood of finding such spuriousregularities is usually small (especially if <strong>the</strong> regularity is a very complex pattern), itincreases dramatically with <strong>the</strong> number of ‘searches’ conducted on <strong>the</strong> same set of data. Suchdata-snooping biases are illustrated in Brown et al. (1992) and Lo and MacKinlay (1990b) –even <strong>the</strong> smallest biases can translate in<strong>to</strong> substantial anomalies such as superior investmentreturns or <strong>the</strong> size effect.Behavioural critiquesThe most enduring critiques of <strong>the</strong> EMH revolve around <strong>the</strong> preferences and behaviour ofmarket participants. The standard approach <strong>to</strong> modelling preferences is <strong>to</strong> assert that inves<strong>to</strong>rsoptimize additive time-separable expected utility functions from certain parametric families –for example, constant relative risk aversion. However, psychologists and experimentaleconomists have documented a number of departures from this paradigm, in <strong>the</strong> form ofspecific behavioural biases that are ubiqui<strong>to</strong>us <strong>to</strong> human decision-making under uncertainty,several of which lead <strong>to</strong> undesirable outcomes for an individual’s economic welfare – forexample, overconfidence (Fischoff and Slovic, 1980; Barber and Odean, 2001; Gervais andOdean, 2001), overreaction (DeBondt and Thaler, 1985), loss aversion (Kahneman andTversky, 1979; Shefrin and Statman, 1985; Odean, 1998), herding (Huberman and Regev,2001), psychological accounting (Tversky and Kahneman, 1981), miscalibration ofprobabilities (Lichtenstein, Fischoff and Phillips, 1982), hyperbolic discounting (Laibson,1997), and regret (Bell, 1982). These critics of <strong>the</strong> EMH argue that inves<strong>to</strong>rs are often – if notalways – irrational, exhibiting predictable and financially ruinous behaviour.To see just how pervasive such behavioural biases can be, consider <strong>the</strong> followingexample which is a slightly modified version of an experiment conducted by twopsychologists, Kahneman and Tversky (1979). Suppose you are offered two investment


10opportunities, A and B: A yields a sure profit of $240,000, and B is a lottery ticket yielding$1 million with a 25 per cent probability and $0 with 75 per cent probability. If you had <strong>to</strong>choose between A and B, which would you prefer? Investment B has an expected value of$250,000, which is higher than A’s payoff, but this may not be all that meaningful <strong>to</strong> youbecause you will receive ei<strong>the</strong>r $1 million or zero. Clearly, t<strong>here</strong> is no right or wrong choice<strong>here</strong>; it is simply a matter of personal preferences. Faced with this choice, most subjectsprefer A, <strong>the</strong> sure profit, <strong>to</strong> B, despite <strong>the</strong> fact that B offers a significant probability ofwinning considerably more. This behaviour is often characterized as ‘risk aversion’ forobvious reasons. Now suppose you are faced with ano<strong>the</strong>r two choices, C and D: C yields asure loss of $750,000, and D is a lottery ticket yielding $0 with 25 per cent probability and aloss of $1 million with 75 per cent probability. Which would you prefer? This situation is notas absurd as it might seem at first glance; many financial decisions involve choosing between<strong>the</strong> lesser of two evils. In this case, most subjects choose D, despite <strong>the</strong> fact that D is morerisky than C. When faced with two choices that both involve losses, individuals seem <strong>to</strong> be‘risk seeking’, not risk averse as in <strong>the</strong> case of A versus B.The fact that individuals tend <strong>to</strong> be risk averse in <strong>the</strong> face of gains and risk seeking in<strong>the</strong> face of losses can lead <strong>to</strong> some very poor financial decisions. To see why, observe that <strong>the</strong>combination of choices A and D is equivalent <strong>to</strong> a single lottery ticket yielding $240,000 with25 per cent probability and ! $760,000 with 75 per cent probability, w<strong>here</strong>as <strong>the</strong>combination of choices B and C is equivalent <strong>to</strong> a single lottery ticket yielding $250,000 with25 per cent probability and ! $750,000 with 75 per cent probability. The B and Ccombination has <strong>the</strong> same probabilities of gains and losses, but <strong>the</strong> gain is $10,000 higher and<strong>the</strong> loss is $10,000 lower. In o<strong>the</strong>r words, B and C is formally equivalent <strong>to</strong> A and D plus asure profit of $10,000. In light of this analysis, would you still prefer A and D?A common response <strong>to</strong> this example is that it is contrived because <strong>the</strong> two pairs ofinvestment opportunities were presented sequentially, not simultaneously. However, in atypical global financial institution <strong>the</strong> London office may be faced with choices A and B and<strong>the</strong> Tokyo office may be faced with choices C and D. Locally, it may seem as if t<strong>here</strong> is noright or wrong answer – <strong>the</strong> choice between A and B or C and D seems <strong>to</strong> be simply a matterof personal risk preferences – but <strong>the</strong> globally consolidated financial statement for <strong>the</strong> entireinstitution will tell a very different s<strong>to</strong>ry. From that perspective, t<strong>here</strong> is a right and wronganswer, and <strong>the</strong> empirical and experimental evidence suggests that most individuals tend <strong>to</strong>select <strong>the</strong> wrong answer. T<strong>here</strong>fore, according <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> behaviouralists, quantitative models of


11efficient markets – all of which are predicated on rational choice – are likely <strong>to</strong> be wrong aswell.Impossibility of efficient marketsGrossman and Stiglitz (1980) go even far<strong>the</strong>r – <strong>the</strong>y argue that perfectly informationallyefficient markets are an impossibility for, if markets are perfectly efficient, t<strong>here</strong> is no profit<strong>to</strong> ga<strong>the</strong>ring information, in which case t<strong>here</strong> would be little reason <strong>to</strong> trade and marketswould eventually collapse. Alternatively, <strong>the</strong> degree of market inefficiency determines <strong>the</strong>effort inves<strong>to</strong>rs are willing <strong>to</strong> expend <strong>to</strong> ga<strong>the</strong>r and trade on information, hence a nondegeneratemarket equilibrium will arise only when t<strong>here</strong> are sufficient profit opportunities,that is, inefficiencies, <strong>to</strong> compensate inves<strong>to</strong>rs for <strong>the</strong> costs of trading and informationga<strong>the</strong>ring. The profits earned by <strong>the</strong>se attentive inves<strong>to</strong>rs may be viewed as ‘economic rents’that accrue <strong>to</strong> those willing <strong>to</strong> engage in such activities. Who are <strong>the</strong> providers of <strong>the</strong>se rents?Black (1986) gave us a provocative answer: ‘noise traders’, individuals who trade on what<strong>the</strong>y consider <strong>to</strong> be information but which is, in fact, merely noise.The supporters of <strong>the</strong> EMH have responded <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong>se challenges by arguing that, whilebehavioural biases and corresponding inefficiencies do exist from time <strong>to</strong> time, t<strong>here</strong> is alimit <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir prevalence and impact because of opposing forces dedicated <strong>to</strong> exploiting suchopportunities. A simple example of such a limit is <strong>the</strong> so-called ‘Dutch book’, in whichirrational probability beliefs give rise <strong>to</strong> guaranteed profits for <strong>the</strong> savvy inves<strong>to</strong>r. Consider,for example, an event E , defined as ‘<strong>the</strong> S&P 500 index drops by five per cent or more nextMonday’, and suppose an individual has <strong>the</strong> following irrational beliefs: t<strong>here</strong> is a 50 per centprobability that E will occur, and a 75 per cent probability that E will not occur. This isclearly a violation of one of <strong>the</strong> basic axioms of probability <strong>the</strong>ory – <strong>the</strong> probabilities of twomutually exclusive and exhaustive events must sum <strong>to</strong> 1 – but many experimental studieshave documented such violations among an overwhelming majority of human subjects.These inconsistent subjective probability beliefs imply that <strong>the</strong> individual would bewilling <strong>to</strong> take both of <strong>the</strong> following bets B1and B2:B 1 =" $1 if E#$ ! $1 o<strong>the</strong>rwise, B 2 =c" $1 if E#$ ! $3 o<strong>the</strong>rwisew<strong>here</strong>cE denotes <strong>the</strong> event ‘not E ’. Now suppose we take <strong>the</strong> opposite side of both bets,placing $50 on B1and $25 on B2. If E occurs, we lose $50 on B1but gain $75 on B2,yielding a profit of $25. IfcE occurs, we gain $50 on B1and lose $25 on B2, also yielding a


12profit of $25. Regardless of <strong>the</strong> outcome, we have secured a profit of $25, an ‘arbitrage’ thatcomes at <strong>the</strong> expense of <strong>the</strong> individual with inconsistent probability beliefs. Such beliefs arenot sustainable, and market forces – namely, arbitrageurs such as hedge funds and proprietarytrading groups – will take advantage of <strong>the</strong>se opportunities until <strong>the</strong>y no longer exist, that is,until <strong>the</strong> odds are in line with <strong>the</strong> axioms of probability <strong>the</strong>ory. (Only when <strong>the</strong>se axioms aresatisfied is arbitrage ruled out. This was conjectured by Ramsey, 1926, and proved rigorouslyby de Finetti, 1937, and Savage, 1954.) T<strong>here</strong>fore, proponents of <strong>the</strong> classical EMH arguethat t<strong>here</strong> are limits <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> degree and persistence of behavioural biases such as inconsistentprobability beliefs, and substantial incentives for those who can identify and exploit suchoccurrences. While all of us are subject <strong>to</strong> certain behavioural biases from time <strong>to</strong> time,according <strong>to</strong> EMH supporters market forces will always act <strong>to</strong> bring prices back <strong>to</strong> rationallevels, implying that <strong>the</strong> impact of irrational behaviour on financial markets is generallynegligible and, t<strong>here</strong>fore, irrelevant.But this last conclusion relies on <strong>the</strong> assumption that market forces are sufficientlypowerful <strong>to</strong> overcome any type of behavioural bias, or equivalently that irrational beliefs arenot so pervasive as <strong>to</strong> overwhelm <strong>the</strong> capacity of arbitrage capital dedicated <strong>to</strong> takingadvantage of such irrationalities. This is an empirical issue that cannot be settled<strong>the</strong>oretically, but must be tested through careful measurement and statistical analysis. Theclassic reference by Kindleberger (1989) – w<strong>here</strong> a number of speculative bubbles, financialpanics, manias, and market crashes are described in detail – suggests that <strong>the</strong> forces ofirrationality can overwhelm <strong>the</strong> forces of arbitrage capital for months and, in several wellknowncases, years.So what does this imply for <strong>the</strong> EMH?The current state of <strong>the</strong> EMHGiven all of <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>oretical and empirical evidence for and against <strong>the</strong> EMH, what can weconclude? Amazingly, t<strong>here</strong> is still no consensus among economists. Despite <strong>the</strong> manyadvances in <strong>the</strong> statistical analysis, databases, and <strong>the</strong>oretical models surrounding <strong>the</strong> EMH,<strong>the</strong> main result of all of <strong>the</strong>se studies is <strong>to</strong> harden <strong>the</strong> resolve of <strong>the</strong> proponents of each side of<strong>the</strong> debate.One of <strong>the</strong> reasons for this state of affairs is <strong>the</strong> fact that <strong>the</strong> EMH, by itself, is not awell-defined and empirically refutable hypo<strong>the</strong>sis. To make it operational, one must specifyadditional structure, for example, inves<strong>to</strong>rs’ preferences or information structure. But <strong>the</strong>n atest of <strong>the</strong> EMH becomes a test of several auxiliary hypo<strong>the</strong>ses as well, and a rejection of


13such a joint hypo<strong>the</strong>sis tells us little about which aspect of <strong>the</strong> joint hypo<strong>the</strong>sis is inconsistentwith <strong>the</strong> data. Are s<strong>to</strong>ck prices <strong>to</strong>o volatile because markets are inefficient, or due <strong>to</strong> riskaversion, or dividend smoothing? All three inferences are consistent with <strong>the</strong> data. Moreover,new statistical tests designed <strong>to</strong> distinguish among <strong>the</strong>m will no doubt require auxiliaryhypo<strong>the</strong>ses of <strong>the</strong>ir own which, in turn, may be questioned.More importantly, tests of <strong>the</strong> EMH may not be <strong>the</strong> most informative means of gauging<strong>the</strong> efficiency of a given market. What is often of more consequence is <strong>the</strong> efficiency of aparticular market relative <strong>to</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r markets – for example, futures vs. spot markets, auctionvs. dealer markets. The advantages of <strong>the</strong> concept of relative efficiency, as opposed <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> allor-nothingnotion of absolute efficiency, are easy <strong>to</strong> spot by way of an analogy. Physicalsystems are often given an efficiency rating based on <strong>the</strong> relative proportion of energy or fuelconverted <strong>to</strong> useful work. T<strong>here</strong>fore, a pis<strong>to</strong>n engine may be rated at 60 per cent efficiency,meaning that on average 60 per cent of <strong>the</strong> energy contained in <strong>the</strong> engine’s fuel is used <strong>to</strong>turn <strong>the</strong> crankshaft, with <strong>the</strong> remaining 40 per cent lost <strong>to</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r forms of work, such as heat,light or noise.Few engineers would ever consider performing a statistical test <strong>to</strong> determine whe<strong>the</strong>r ornot a given engine is perfectly efficient – such an engine exists only in <strong>the</strong> idealizedfrictionless world of <strong>the</strong> imagination. But measuring relative efficiency – relative, that is, <strong>to</strong><strong>the</strong> frictionless ideal – is commonplace. Indeed, we have come <strong>to</strong> expect such measurementsfor many household products: air conditioners, hot water heaters, refrigera<strong>to</strong>rs, and so on.T<strong>here</strong>fore, from a practical point of view, and in light of Grossman and Stiglitz (1980), <strong>the</strong>EMH is an idealization that is economically unrealizable, but which serves as a usefulbenchmark for measuring relative efficiency.The desire <strong>to</strong> build financial <strong>the</strong>ories based on more realistic assumptions has led <strong>to</strong>several new strands of literature, including psychological approaches <strong>to</strong> risk-taking behaviour(Kahneman and Tversky, 1979; Thaler, 1993; Lo, 1999), evolutionary game <strong>the</strong>ory(Friedman, 1991), agent-based modelling of financial markets (Arthur et al., 1997; Chan etal., 1998), and direct applications of <strong>the</strong> principles of evolutionary psychology <strong>to</strong> economicsand finance (Lo, 1999; 2002; 2004; 2005; Lo and Repin, 2002). Although substantiallydifferent in methods and style, <strong>the</strong>se emerging sub-fields are all directed at newinterpretations of <strong>the</strong> EMH. In particular, psychological models of financial markets focus on<strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong> manner in which human psychology influences <strong>the</strong> economic decision-makingprocess as an explanation of apparent departures from rationality. Evolutionary game <strong>the</strong>orystudies <strong>the</strong> evolution and steady-state equilibria of populations of competing strategies in


14highly idealized settings. Agent-based models are meant <strong>to</strong> capture complex learningbehaviour and dynamics in financial markets using more realistic markets, strategies, andinformation structures. And applications of evolutionary psychology provide a reconciliationof rational expectations with <strong>the</strong> behavioural findings that often seem inconsistent withrationality.For example, in one agent-based model of financial markets (Farmer, 2002), <strong>the</strong> marketis modelled using a non-equilibrium market mechanism, whose simplicity makes it possible<strong>to</strong> obtain analytic results while maintaining a plausible degree of realism. Market participantsare treated as computational entities that employ strategies based on limited information.Through <strong>the</strong>ir (sometimes suboptimal) actions <strong>the</strong>y make profits or losses. Profitablestrategies accumulate capital with <strong>the</strong> passage of time, and unprofitable strategies lose moneyand may eventually disappear. A financial market can thus be viewed as a co-evolvingecology of trading strategies. The strategy is analogous <strong>to</strong> a biological species, and <strong>the</strong> <strong>to</strong>talcapital deployed by agents following a given strategy is analogous <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> population of thatspecies. The creation of new strategies may alter <strong>the</strong> profitability of pre-existing strategies, insome cases replacing <strong>the</strong>m or driving <strong>the</strong>m extinct.Although agent-based models are still in <strong>the</strong>ir infancy, <strong>the</strong> simulations and related<strong>the</strong>ory have already demonstrated an ability <strong>to</strong> understand many aspects of financial markets.Several studies indicate that, as <strong>the</strong> population of strategies evolves, <strong>the</strong> market tends <strong>to</strong>become more efficient, but this is far from <strong>the</strong> perfect efficiency of <strong>the</strong> classical EMH. Pricesfluctuate in time with internal dynamics caused by <strong>the</strong> interaction of diverse tradingstrategies. Prices do not necessarily reflect ‘true values’; if we view <strong>the</strong> market as a machinewhose job is <strong>to</strong> set prices properly, <strong>the</strong> inefficiency of this machine can be substantial.Patterns in <strong>the</strong> price tend <strong>to</strong> disappear as agents evolve profitable strategies <strong>to</strong> exploit <strong>the</strong>m,but this occurs only over an extended period of time, during which substantial profits may beaccumulated and new patterns may appear.The adaptive markets hypo<strong>the</strong>sisThe methodological differences between mainstream and behavioural economics suggest thatan alternative <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> traditional deductive approach of neoclassical economics may benecessary <strong>to</strong> reconcile <strong>the</strong> EMH with its behavioural critics. One particularly promisingdirection is <strong>to</strong> view financial markets from a biological perspective and, specifically, withinan evolutionary framework in which markets, instruments, institutions and inves<strong>to</strong>rs interactand evolve dynamically according <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> ‘law’ of economic selection. Under this view,


15financial agents compete and adapt, but <strong>the</strong>y do not necessarily do so in an optimal fashion(see Farmer and Lo, 1999; Farmer, 2002; Lo, 2002; 2004; 2005).This evolutionary approach is heavily influenced by recent advances in <strong>the</strong> emergingdiscipline of ‘evolutionary psychology’, which builds on <strong>the</strong> seminal research of E.O. Wilson(1975) in applying <strong>the</strong> principles of competition, reproduction, and natural selection <strong>to</strong> socialinteractions, yielding surprisingly compelling explanations for certain kinds of humanbehaviour, such as altruism, fairness, kin selection, language, mate selection, religion,morality, ethics and abstract thought (see, for example, Barkow, Cosmides and Tooby, 1992;Gigerenzer, 2000). ‘Sociobiology’ is <strong>the</strong> rubric that Wilson (1975) gave <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong>se powerfulideas, which generated a considerable degree of controversy in <strong>the</strong>ir own right, and <strong>the</strong> sameprinciples can be applied <strong>to</strong> economic and financial contexts. In doing so, we can fullyreconcile <strong>the</strong> EMH with all of its behavioural alternatives, leading <strong>to</strong> a new syn<strong>the</strong>sis: <strong>the</strong>adaptive markets hypo<strong>the</strong>sis (AMH).Students of <strong>the</strong> his<strong>to</strong>ry of economic thought will no doubt recall that Thomas Malthusused biological arguments – <strong>the</strong> fact that populations increase at geometric rates w<strong>here</strong>asnatural resources increase at only arithmetic rates – <strong>to</strong> arrive at ra<strong>the</strong>r dire economicconsequences, and that both Darwin and Wallace were influenced by <strong>the</strong>se arguments (seeHirshleifer, 1977, for fur<strong>the</strong>r details). Also, Joseph Schumpeter’s view of business cycles,entrepreneurs and capitalism have an unmistakeable evolutionary flavour <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong>m; in fact, hisnotions of ‘creative destruction’ and ‘bursts’ of entrepreneurial activity are similar in spirit <strong>to</strong>natural selection and Eldredge and Gould’s (1972) notion of ‘punctuated equilibrium’. Morerecently, economists and biologists have begun <strong>to</strong> explore <strong>the</strong>se connections in several veins:direct extensions of sociobiology <strong>to</strong> economics (Becker, 1976; Hirshleifer, 1977);evolutionary game <strong>the</strong>ory (Maynard Smith, 1982); evolutionary economics (Nelson andWinter, 1982); and economics as a complex system (Anderson, Arrow and Pines, 1988). Andpublications like <strong>the</strong> Journal of Evolutionary Economics and <strong>the</strong> Electronic Journal ofEvolutionary Modeling and Economic Dynamics now provide a home for research at <strong>the</strong>intersection of economics and biology.Evolutionary concepts have also appeared in a number of financial contexts. Forexample, Luo (1995) explores <strong>the</strong> implications of natural selection for futures markets, andHirshleifer and Luo (2001) consider <strong>the</strong> long-run prospects of overconfident traders in acompetitive securities market. The literature on agent-based modelling pioneered by Arthur etal. (1997), in which interactions among software agents programmed with simple heuristicsare simulated, relies heavily on evolutionary dynamics. And at least two prominent


16practitioners have proposed Darwinian alternatives <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> EMH. In a chapter titled ‘TheEcology of Markets’, Niederhoffer (1997, ch. 15) likens financial markets <strong>to</strong> an ecosystemwith dealers as ‘herbivores’, specula<strong>to</strong>rs as ‘carnivores’, and floor traders and distressedinves<strong>to</strong>rs as ‘decomposers’. And Bernstein (1998) makes a compelling case for activemanagement by pointing out that <strong>the</strong> notion of equilibrium, which is central <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> EMH, israrely realized in practice and that market dynamics are better explained by evolutionaryprocesses.Clearly <strong>the</strong> time is now ripe for an evolutionary alternative <strong>to</strong> market efficiency.To that end, in <strong>the</strong> current context of <strong>the</strong> EMH we begin, as Samuelson (1947) did, with<strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory of <strong>the</strong> individual consumer. Contrary <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> neoclassical postulate that individualsmaximize expected utility and have rational expectations, an evolutionary perspective makesconsiderably more modest claims, viewing individuals as organisms that have been honed,through generations of natural selection, <strong>to</strong> maximize <strong>the</strong> survival of <strong>the</strong>ir genetic material(see, for example, Dawkins, 1976). While such a reductionist approach can quicklydegenerate in<strong>to</strong> useless generalities – for example, <strong>the</strong> molecular biology of economicbehaviour – never<strong>the</strong>less, t<strong>here</strong> are valuable insights <strong>to</strong> be gained from <strong>the</strong> broader biologicalperspective. Specifically, this perspective implies that behaviour is not necessarily intrinsicand exogenous, but evolves by natural selection and depends on <strong>the</strong> particular environmentalthrough which selection occurs. That is, natural selection operates not only upon geneticmaterial but also upon social and cultural norms in homo sapiens; hence Wilson’s term‘sociobiology’.To operationalize this perspective within an economic context, consider <strong>the</strong> idea of ‘boundedrationality’ first espoused by Nobel-prize-winning economist Herbert Simon. Simon (1955)suggested that individuals are hardly capable of <strong>the</strong> kind of optimization that neoclassicaleconomics calls for in <strong>the</strong> standard <strong>the</strong>ory of consumer choice. Instead, he argued that,because optimization is costly and humans are naturally limited in <strong>the</strong>ir computationalabilities, <strong>the</strong>y engage in something he called ‘satisficing’, an alternative <strong>to</strong> optimization inwhich individuals make choices that are merely satisfac<strong>to</strong>ry, not necessarily optimal. In o<strong>the</strong>rwords, individuals are bounded in <strong>the</strong>ir degree of rationality, which is in sharp contrast <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong>current orthodoxy – rational expectations – w<strong>here</strong> individuals have unbounded rationality(<strong>the</strong> term ‘hyper-rational expectations’ might be more descriptive). Unfortunately, althoughthis idea garnered a Nobel Prize for Simon, it had relatively little impact on <strong>the</strong> economicsprofession. (However, his work is now receiving greater attention, thanks in part <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong>growing behavioural literature in economics and finance. See, for example, Simon, 1982;


17Sargent, 1993; A. Rubinstein, 1998; Gigerenzer and Selten, 2001.) Apart from <strong>the</strong>sociological fac<strong>to</strong>rs discussed above, Simon’s framework was commonly dismissed becauseof one specific criticism: what determines <strong>the</strong> point at which an individual s<strong>to</strong>ps optimizingand reaches a satisfac<strong>to</strong>ry solution? If such a point is determined by <strong>the</strong> usual cost–benefitcalculation underlying much of microeconomics (that is, optimize until <strong>the</strong> marginal benefitsof <strong>the</strong> optimum equals <strong>the</strong> marginal cost of <strong>get</strong>ting t<strong>here</strong>), this assumes <strong>the</strong> optimal solution isknown, which would eliminate <strong>the</strong> need for satisficing. As a result, <strong>the</strong> idea of boundedrationality fell by <strong>the</strong> wayside, and rational expectations has become <strong>the</strong> de fac<strong>to</strong> standard formodelling economic behaviour under uncertainty.An evolutionary perspective provides <strong>the</strong> missing ingredient in Simon’s framework.The proper response <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> question of how individuals determine <strong>the</strong> point at which <strong>the</strong>iroptimizing behaviour is satisfac<strong>to</strong>ry is this: such points are determined not analytically butthrough trial and error and, of course, natural selection. Individuals make choices based onpast experience and <strong>the</strong>ir ‘best guess’ as <strong>to</strong> what might be optimal, and <strong>the</strong>y learn byreceiving positive or negative reinforcement from <strong>the</strong> outcomes. If <strong>the</strong>y receive no suchreinforcement, <strong>the</strong>y do not learn. In this fashion, individuals develop heuristics <strong>to</strong> solvevarious economic challenges, and, as long as those challenges remain stable, <strong>the</strong> heuristicswill eventually adapt <strong>to</strong> yield approximately optimal solutions <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong>m.If, on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r hand, <strong>the</strong> environment changes, <strong>the</strong>n it should come as no surprise that<strong>the</strong> heuristics of <strong>the</strong> old environment are not necessarily suited <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> new. In such cases, weobserve ‘behavioural biases’ – actions that are apparently ill-advised in <strong>the</strong> context in whichwe observe <strong>the</strong>m. But ra<strong>the</strong>r than labelling such behaviour ‘irrational’, it should berecognized that suboptimal behaviour is not unlikely when we take heuristics out of <strong>the</strong>irevolutionary context. A more accurate term for such behaviour might be ‘maladaptive’. Theflopping of a fish on dry land may seem strange and unproductive, but under water <strong>the</strong> samemotions are capable of propelling <strong>the</strong> fish away from its preda<strong>to</strong>rs.By coupling Simon’s notion of bounded rationality and satisficing with evolutionarydynamics, many o<strong>the</strong>r aspects of economic behaviour can also be derived. Competition,cooperation, market-making behaviour, general equilibrium, and disequilibrium dynamics areall adaptations designed <strong>to</strong> address certain environmental challenges for <strong>the</strong> human species,and by viewing <strong>the</strong>m through <strong>the</strong> lens of evolutionary biology we can better understand <strong>the</strong>apparent contradictions between <strong>the</strong> EMH and <strong>the</strong> presence and persistence of behaviouralbiases.Specifically, <strong>the</strong> adaptive markets hypo<strong>the</strong>sis can be viewed as a new version of <strong>the</strong>


18EMH, derived from evolutionary principles. Prices reflect as much information as dictated by<strong>the</strong> combination of environmental conditions and <strong>the</strong> number and nature of ‘species’ in <strong>the</strong>economy or, <strong>to</strong> use <strong>the</strong> appropriate biological term, <strong>the</strong> ecology. By ‘species’ I mean distinctgroups of market participants, each behaving in a common manner. For example, pensionfunds may be considered one species; retail inves<strong>to</strong>rs, ano<strong>the</strong>r; market-makers, a third; andhedge-fund managers, a fourth. If multiple species (or <strong>the</strong> members of a single highlypopulous species) are competing for ra<strong>the</strong>r scarce resources within a single market, thatmarket is likely <strong>to</strong> be highly efficient – for example, <strong>the</strong> market for 10-Year US TreasuryNotes reflects most relevant information very quickly indeed. If, on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r hand, a smallnumber of species are competing for ra<strong>the</strong>r abundant resources in a given market, that marketwill be less efficient – for example, <strong>the</strong> market for oil paintings from <strong>the</strong> Italian Renaissance.Market efficiency cannot be evaluated in a vacuum, but is highly context-dependent anddynamic, just as insect populations advance and decline as a function of <strong>the</strong> seasons, <strong>the</strong>number of preda<strong>to</strong>rs and prey <strong>the</strong>y face, and <strong>the</strong>ir abilities <strong>to</strong> adapt <strong>to</strong> an ever-changingenvironment.The profit opportunities in any given market are akin <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> amount of food and waterin a particular local ecology – <strong>the</strong> more resources present, <strong>the</strong> less fierce <strong>the</strong> competition. Ascompetition increases, ei<strong>the</strong>r because of dwindling food supplies or an increase in <strong>the</strong> animalpopulation, resources are depleted which, in turn, causes a population decline eventually,decreasing <strong>the</strong> level of competition and starting <strong>the</strong> cycle again. In some cases cyclesconverge <strong>to</strong> corner solutions, that is, certain species become extinct, food sources arepermanently exhausted, or environmental conditions shift dramatically. By viewing economicprofits as <strong>the</strong> ultimate food source on which market participants depend for <strong>the</strong>ir survival, <strong>the</strong>dynamics of market interactions and financial innovation can be readily derived.Under <strong>the</strong> AMH, behavioural biases abound. The origins of such biases are heuristicsthat are adapted <strong>to</strong> non-financial contexts, and <strong>the</strong>ir impact is determined by <strong>the</strong> size of <strong>the</strong>population with such biases versus <strong>the</strong> size of competing populations with more effectiveheuristics. During <strong>the</strong> autumn of 1998, <strong>the</strong> desire for liquidity and safety by a certainpopulation of inves<strong>to</strong>rs overwhelmed <strong>the</strong> population of hedge funds attempting <strong>to</strong> arbitragesuch preferences, causing those arbitrage relations <strong>to</strong> break down. However, in <strong>the</strong> years prior<strong>to</strong> August 1998 fixed-income relative-value traders profited handsomely from <strong>the</strong>se activities,presumably at <strong>the</strong> expense of individuals with seemingly ‘irrational’ preferences (in fact,such preferences were shaped by a certain set of evolutionary forces, and might be quiterational in o<strong>the</strong>r contexts). T<strong>here</strong>fore, under <strong>the</strong> AMH, investment strategies undergo cycles


19of profitability and loss in response <strong>to</strong> changing business conditions, <strong>the</strong> number ofcompeti<strong>to</strong>rs entering and exiting <strong>the</strong> industry, and <strong>the</strong> type and magnitude of profi<strong>to</strong>pportunities available. As opportunities shift, so <strong>to</strong>o will <strong>the</strong> affected populations. Forexample, after 1998 <strong>the</strong> number of fixed-income relative-value hedge funds declineddramatically – because of outright failures, inves<strong>to</strong>r redemptions, and fewer start-ups in thissec<strong>to</strong>r – but many have reappeared in recent years as performance for this type of investmentstrategy has improved.Even fear and greed – <strong>the</strong> two most common culprits in <strong>the</strong> downfall of rationalthinking according <strong>to</strong> most behaviouralists – are <strong>the</strong> product of evolutionary forces, adaptivetraits that enhance <strong>the</strong> probability of survival. Recent research in <strong>the</strong> cognitive neurosciencesand economics, now coalescing in<strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> discipline known as ‘neuroeconomics’, suggests animportant link between rationality in decision-making and emotion (Grossberg and Gu<strong>to</strong>wski,1987; Damasio, 1994; Elster, 1998; Lo and Repin, 2002; and Loewenstein, 2000), implyingthat <strong>the</strong> two are not anti<strong>the</strong>tical but in fact complementary. For example, contrary <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong>common belief that emotions have no place in rational financial decision-making processes,Lo and Repin (2002) present preliminary evidence that physiological variables associatedwith <strong>the</strong> au<strong>to</strong>nomic nervous system are highly correlated with market events even for highlyexperienced professional securities traders. They argue that emotional responses are asignificant fac<strong>to</strong>r in <strong>the</strong> real-time processing of financial risks, and that an importantcomponent of a professional trader’s skills lies in his or her ability <strong>to</strong> channel emotion,consciously or unconsciously, in specific ways during certain market conditions.This argument often surprises economists because of <strong>the</strong> link between emotion andbehavioural biases, but a more sophisticated view of <strong>the</strong> role of emotions in human cognitionshows that <strong>the</strong>y are central <strong>to</strong> rationality (see, for example, Damasio, 1994; Rolls, 1999). Inparticular, emotions are <strong>the</strong> basis for a reward-and-punishment system that facilitates <strong>the</strong>selection of advantageous behaviour, providing a numeraire for animals <strong>to</strong> engage in a ‘cost–benefit analysis’ of <strong>the</strong> various actions open <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong>m (Rolls, 1999, ch. 10.3). From anevolutionary perspective, emotion is a powerful adaptation that dramatically improves <strong>the</strong>efficiency with which animals learn from <strong>the</strong>ir environment and <strong>the</strong>ir past (see Damasio,1994). These evolutionary underpinnings are more than simple speculation in <strong>the</strong> context offinancial market participants. The extraordinary degree of competitiveness of global financialmarkets and <strong>the</strong> outsize rewards that accrue <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> ‘fittest’ traders suggest that Darwinianselection – ’survival of <strong>the</strong> richest’, <strong>to</strong> be precise – is at work in determining <strong>the</strong> typicalprofile of <strong>the</strong> successful trader. After all, unsuccessful traders are eventually eliminated from


20<strong>the</strong> population after suffering a certain level of losses.The new paradigm of <strong>the</strong> AMH is still under development, and certainly requires agreat deal more research <strong>to</strong> render it ‘operationally meaningful’ in Samuelson’s sense.However, even at this early stage it is clear that an evolutionary framework is able <strong>to</strong>reconcile many of <strong>the</strong> apparent contradictions between efficient markets and behaviouralexceptions. The former may be viewed as <strong>the</strong> steady-state limit of a population with constantenvironmental conditions, and <strong>the</strong> latter involves specific adaptations of certain groups thatmay or may not persist, depending on <strong>the</strong> particular evolutionary paths that <strong>the</strong> economyexperiences. More specific implications may be derived through a combination of deductiveand inductive inference – for example, <strong>the</strong>oretical analysis of evolutionary dynamics,empirical analysis of evolutionary forces in financial markets, and experimental analysis ofdecision-making at <strong>the</strong> individual and group level.For example, one implication is that, <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> extent that a relation between risk andreward exists, it is unlikely <strong>to</strong> be stable over time. Such a relation is determined by t<strong>here</strong>lative sizes and preferences of various populations in <strong>the</strong> market ecology, as well asinstitutional aspects such as <strong>the</strong> regula<strong>to</strong>ry environment and tax laws. As <strong>the</strong>se fac<strong>to</strong>rs shif<strong>to</strong>ver time, any risk–reward relation is likely <strong>to</strong> be affected. A corollary of this implication isthat <strong>the</strong> equity risk premium is also time-varying and path-dependent. This is not sorevolutionary an idea as it might first appear – even in <strong>the</strong> context of a rational expectationsequilibrium model, if risk preferences change over time, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> equity risk premium mustvary <strong>to</strong>o. The incremental insight of <strong>the</strong> AMH is that aggregate risk preferences are notimmutable constants, but are shaped by <strong>the</strong> forces of natural selection. For example, untilrecently US markets were populated by a significant group of inves<strong>to</strong>rs who had neverexperienced a genuine bear market – this fact has undoubtedly shaped <strong>the</strong> aggregate riskpreferences of <strong>the</strong> US economy, just as <strong>the</strong> experience since <strong>the</strong> bursting of <strong>the</strong> technologybubble in <strong>the</strong> early 2000s has affected <strong>the</strong> risk preferences of <strong>the</strong> current population ofinves<strong>to</strong>rs. In this context, natural selection determines who participates in marketinteractions; those inves<strong>to</strong>rs who experienced substantial losses in <strong>the</strong> technology bubble aremore likely <strong>to</strong> have exited <strong>the</strong> market, leaving a markedly different population of inves<strong>to</strong>rs.Through <strong>the</strong> forces of natural selection, his<strong>to</strong>ry matters. Irrespective of whe<strong>the</strong>r prices fullyreflect all available information, <strong>the</strong> particular path that market prices have taken over <strong>the</strong>past few years influences current aggregate risk preferences. Among <strong>the</strong> three fundamentalcomponents of any market equilibrium – prices, probabilities, and preferences – preferencesis clearly <strong>the</strong> most fundamental and least unders<strong>to</strong>od. Several large bodies of research have


21developed around <strong>the</strong>se issues – in economics and finance, psychology, operations research(also called ‘decision sciences’) and, more recently, brain and cognitive sciences – and manynew insights are likely <strong>to</strong> flow from syn<strong>the</strong>sizing <strong>the</strong>se different strands of research in<strong>to</strong> amore complete understanding of how individuals make decisions (see Starmer, 2000, for anexcellent review of this literature). Simon’s (1982) seminal contributions <strong>to</strong> this literature arestill remarkably timely and <strong>the</strong>ir implications have yet <strong>to</strong> be fully explored.ConclusionsMany o<strong>the</strong>r practical insights and potential breakthroughs can be derived from shifting ourmode of thinking in financial economics from <strong>the</strong> physical <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> biological sciences.Although evolutionary ideas are not yet part of <strong>the</strong> financial mainstream, <strong>the</strong> hope is that <strong>the</strong>ywill become more commonplace as <strong>the</strong>y demonstrate <strong>the</strong>ir worth – ideas are also subject <strong>to</strong>‘survival of <strong>the</strong> fittest’. No one has illustrated this principal so well as Harry Markowitz, <strong>the</strong>fa<strong>the</strong>r of modern portfolio <strong>the</strong>ory and a Nobel laureate in economics in 1990. In describinghis experience as a Ph.D. student on <strong>the</strong> eve of his graduation, he wrote in his Nobel address(Markowitz, 1991, p. 476):. . . [W]hen I defended my dissertation as a student in <strong>the</strong> Economics Department of<strong>the</strong> University of Chicago, Professor Mil<strong>to</strong>n Friedman argued that portfolio <strong>the</strong>ory wasnot Economics, and that <strong>the</strong>y could not award me a Ph.D. degree in Economics for adissertation which was not Economics. I assume that he was only half serious, since<strong>the</strong>y did award me <strong>the</strong> degree without long debate. As <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> merits of his arguments, atthis point I am quite willing <strong>to</strong> concede: at <strong>the</strong> time I defended my dissertation,portfolio <strong>the</strong>ory was not part of Economics. But now it is.In light of <strong>the</strong> sociology of <strong>the</strong> EMH controversy (see, for example, Lo, 2004), <strong>the</strong>debate is likely <strong>to</strong> continue. However, despite <strong>the</strong> lack of consensus in academia and industry,<strong>the</strong> ongoing dialogue has given us many new insights in<strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> economic structure of financialmarkets. If, as Paul Samuelson has suggested, financial economics is <strong>the</strong> crown jewel of <strong>the</strong>social sciences, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> EMH must account for half <strong>the</strong> facets.Andrew W. LoSee also asset price anomalies; bounded rationality; financial market anomalies; information


22economics; rational expectationsI thank John Cox, Gene Fama, Bob Mer<strong>to</strong>n, and Paul Samuelson for helpful discussions.BibliographyAnderson, P. Arrow, K. and Pines, D.eds. 1988. The Economy as an Evolving ComplexSystem. Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley Publishing Company.Arthur, B. Holland, J. LeBaron, B. Palmer R. and P. Tayler. 1997. Asset pricing underendogenous expectations in an artificial s<strong>to</strong>ck market. In The Economy as an EvolvingComplex System II, ed. B. Arthur, S. Durlauf, and D. Lane Reading, MA: Addison Wesley.Ball, R. and Brown, P. 1968. An empirical evaluation of accounting income numbers.Journal of Accounting Research 6, 159–78.Banz, R. 1981. The relationship between return and market value of common s<strong>to</strong>ck. Journalof Financial Economics 9, 3–18.Barber, B. and Odean, T. 2001. Boys will be boys: gender, overconfidence, and commons<strong>to</strong>ck investment. Quarterly Journal of Economics 116, 261–29.Barkow, J. Cosmides, L. and Tooby, J. 1992. The Adapted Mind: Evolutionary Psychologyand <strong>the</strong> Generation of Culture. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Basu, S. 1977. The investment performance of common s<strong>to</strong>cks in relation <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir price–earnings ratios: a test of <strong>the</strong> efficient market hypo<strong>the</strong>sis. Journal of Finance 32, 663–82.Becker, G. 1976. Altruism, egoism, and genetic fitness: economics and sociobiology.Journal of Economic Literature 14, 817–26.Bell, D. 1982. Risk premiums for decision regret. Management Science 29, 1156–66.Bernard, V. and Thomas, J. 1990. Evidence that s<strong>to</strong>ck prices do not fully reflect <strong>the</strong>implications of current earnings for future earnings. Journal of Accounting and Economics13, 305–40.Bernstein, P. 1998. Why <strong>the</strong> efficient market offers hope <strong>to</strong> active management. InEconomics and Portfolio Strategy, 1 Oc<strong>to</strong>ber. New York: Peter Bernstein, Inc.Black, F. 1986. Noise. Journal of Finance 41, 529–44.Black, F. and Scholes, M. 1973. Pricing of options and corporate liabilities. Journal ofPolitical Economy 81, 637–54.


23Brown, S. Goetzmann, W. Ibbotson, R. and Ross, S. 1992. Survivorship bias in performancestudies. Review of Financial Studies 5, 553–80.Campbell, J. and Shiller, R. 1988. The dividend–price ratio and expectations of futuredividends and discount fac<strong>to</strong>rs. Review of Financial Studies 1, 195–228.Chan, K. 1988. On <strong>the</strong> contrarian investment strategy. Journal of Business 61, 147–64.Chan, L., Jegadeesh, N. and Lakonishok, J. 1996. Momentum strategies. Journal of Finance51, 1681–713.Chan, N., LeBaron, B., Lo, A. and Poggio, T. 1998. Information Dissemination andAggregation in Asset Markets with Simple Intelligent Traders. Labora<strong>to</strong>ry TechnicalMemorandum No. 1646. Cambridge, MA: MIT Artificial Intelligence.Chopra, N. Lakonishok, J. and Ritter, J. 1992. Measuring Abnormal Performance: Do S<strong>to</strong>cksOverreact? Journal of Financial Economics 31, 235–86.Cootner, P. 1962. S<strong>to</strong>ck prices: random vs. systematic changes. Industrial ManagementReview 3, 24–45.Cootner, P. 1964. The Random Character of S<strong>to</strong>ck Market Prices. London: RiskPublications.Copeland, T. and Mayers, D. 1982. The Value Line enigma (1965–1978): a case study ofperformance evaluation issues. Journal of Financial Economics 10, 289–322.Cowles, A. 1960. A revision of previous conclusions regarding s<strong>to</strong>ck price behavior.Econometrica 28, 909–15.Cowles, A. and Jones, H. 1937. Some a posteriori probabilities in s<strong>to</strong>ck market action.Econometrica 5, 280–294.Damasio, A. 1994. Descartes’ Error: Emotion, Reason, and <strong>the</strong> Human Brain. New York:Avon Books.Dawkins, R. 1976. The Selfish Gene. Oxford: Oxford University Press.de Finetti, B. 1937. La Prévision: Ses Lois Logiques, Ses Sources Subjectives. Annales del’Institut Henri Poincaré 7, 1–68. English translation in Studies in Subjective Probability, ed.H. Kyburg and H. Smokler. New York: John Wiley & Sons, 1964.DeBondt, W. and Thaler, R. 1985. Does <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck market overreact?. Journal of Finance 40,793–807.Eldredge, N. and Gould, S. 1972. Punctuated equilibria: an alternative <strong>to</strong> phyletic gradualism.In Models in Paleobiology, ed. T. Schopf. San Francisco: Freeman, Cooper.Elster, J. 1998. Emotions and economic <strong>the</strong>ory. Journal of Economic Literature 36, 47–74.Fama, E. 1963. Mandelbrot and <strong>the</strong> stable Paretian hypo<strong>the</strong>sis. Journal of Business 36, 420–


2429.Fama, E. 1965a. The behavior of s<strong>to</strong>ck market prices. Journal of Business 38, 34–105.Fama, E. 1965b. Random walks in s<strong>to</strong>ck market prices. Financial Analysts Journal 21, 55–9.Fama, E. 1970. Efficient capital markets: a review of <strong>the</strong>ory and empirical work. Journal ofFinance 25, 383–417.Fama, E. and Blume, M. 1966. Filter rules and s<strong>to</strong>ck market trading profits. Journal ofBusiness 39, 226–41.Fama, E. and French, K.1988. Permanent and temporary components of s<strong>to</strong>ck prices.Journal of Political Economy 96, 246–73.Farmer, D. 2002. Market force, ecology and evolution. Industrial and Corporate Change11, 895–953.Farmer, D. and Lo, A. 1999. Frontiers of finance: evolution and efficient markets.Proceedings of <strong>the</strong> National Academy of Sciences 96, 9991–2.Fischoff, B. and Slovic, P. 1980. A little learning...: confidence in multicue judgment tasks.In Attention and Performance, VIII, ed. R. Nickerson Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.Flavin, M. 1983. Excess volatility in <strong>the</strong> financial markets: a reassessment of <strong>the</strong> empiricalevidence. Journal of Political Economy 91, 929–56.French, K. and Roll, R. 1986. S<strong>to</strong>ck return variances: <strong>the</strong> arrival of information and t<strong>here</strong>action of traders. Journal of Financial Economics 17, 5–26.Friedman, D. 1991. Evolutionary games in economics. Econometrica 59, 637–66.Gervais, S. and Odean, T. 2001. Learning <strong>to</strong> be overconfident. Review of Financial Studies14, 1–27.Gigerenzer, G. 2000, Adaptive Thinking: Rationality in <strong>the</strong> Real World. Oxford: OxfordUniversity Press.Gigerenzer, G. and Selten, R. 2001, Bounded Rational: The Adaptive Toolbox. Cambridge,MA: MIT Press.Gilles, C. and LeRoy, S. 1991. Econometric aspects of <strong>the</strong> variance-bounds tests: a survey.Review of Financial Studies 4, 753–92.Grossberg, S. and Gu<strong>to</strong>wski, W. 1987. Neural dynamics of decision making under risk:affective balance and cognitive-emotional interactions. Psychological Review 94, 300–18.Grossman, S. and Shiller, R. 1981. The determinants of <strong>the</strong> variability of s<strong>to</strong>ck market prices.American Economic Review 71, 222–7.Grossman, S. and Stiglitz, J. 1980. On <strong>the</strong> impossibility of informationally efficient markets.


25American Economic Review 70, 393–408.Hirshleifer, J. 1977. Economics from a biological viewpoint. Journal of Law and Economics20, 1–52.Hirshleifer, D. and Luo, G. 2001. On <strong>the</strong> survival of overconfident traders in a competitivesecurities market. Journal of Financial Markets 4, 73–84.Huberman, G. and Regev, T. 2001. Contagious speculation and a cure for cancer: a noneventthat made s<strong>to</strong>ck prices soar. Journal of Finance 56, 387–96.Jegadeesh, N. 1990. Evidence of predictable behavior of security returns. Journal ofFinance 45, 881–98.Jegadeesh, N. and Titman, S. 2001. Profitability of momentum strategies: an evaluation ofalternative explanations. Journal of Finance 56, 699–720.Kahneman, D. and Tversky, A. 1979. Prospect <strong>the</strong>ory: an analysis of decision under risk.Econometrica 47, 263–91.Keim, D. 1983. Size-related anomalies and s<strong>to</strong>ck return seasonality: fur<strong>the</strong>r empiricalevidence. Journal of Financial Economics 12, 13–32.Kim, M., Nelson, C. and Startz, R. 1991. Mean reversion in s<strong>to</strong>ck prices? a reappraisal of <strong>the</strong>empirical evidence. Review of Economic Studies 58, 515–28.Kindleberger, C. 1989. Manias, Panics, and Crashes: A His<strong>to</strong>ry of Financial Crises. NewYork: Basic Books.Kleidon, A. 1986. Variance bounds tests and s<strong>to</strong>ck price valuation models. Journal ofPolitical Economy 94, 953–1001.Laibson, D. 1997. Golden eggs and hyperbolic discounting. Quarterly Journal of Economics62, 443–77.Lakonishok, J. and Smidt, S. 1988. Are seasonal anomalies real? A ninety-year perspective.Review of Financial Studies 1, 403–25.Lehmann, B. 1990. Fads, martingales, and market efficiency. Quarterly Journal ofEconomics 105, 1–28.Leroy, S. 1973. Risk aversion and <strong>the</strong> martingale property of s<strong>to</strong>ck returns. InternationalEconomic Review 14, 436–46.LeRoy, S. and Porter, R.1981. The present value relation: tests based on variance bounds.Econometrica 49, 555–74.Lichtenstein, S., Fischoff, B. and Phillips, L. 1982. Calibration of probabilities: <strong>the</strong> state of<strong>the</strong> art <strong>to</strong> 1980. In Judgment Under Uncertainty: Heuristics and Biases, ed. D. Kahneman, P.Slovic and A. Tversky. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.


26Lo, A. 1991. Long-term memory in s<strong>to</strong>ck market prices. Econometrica 59, 1279–313.Lo, A., ed. 1997. Market Efficiency: S<strong>to</strong>ck Market Behavior in Theory and Practice, 2 vols.Cheltenham: Edward Elgar Publishing Company.Lo, A. 1999. The three P’s of <strong>to</strong>tal risk management. Financial Analysts Journal 55, 87–129.Lo, A. 2001. Risk management for hedge funds: introduction and overview. <strong>to</strong> appear inFinancial Analysts Journal 57, 16–33.Lo, A. 2002. Bubble, rubble, finance in trouble? Journal of Psychology and FinancialMarkets 3, 76–86.Lo, A. 2004. The adaptive markets hypo<strong>the</strong>sis: market efficiency from an evolutionaryperspective. Journal of Portfolio Management 30, 15–29.Lo, A. 2005. Reconciling efficient markets with behavioral finance: <strong>the</strong> adaptive marketshypo<strong>the</strong>sis. Journal of Investment Consulting 7, 21–44.Lo, A. and MacKinlay, C. 1988. S<strong>to</strong>ck market prices do not follow random walks: evidencefrom a simple specification test. Review of Financial Studies 1, 41–66.Lo, A. and MacKinlay, C. 1990a. An econometric analysis of nonsynchronous trading.Journal of Econometrics 45, 181–212.Lo, A. and MacKinlay, C. 1990b. Data snooping biases in tests of financial asset pricingmodels. Review of Financial Studies 3, 431–68.Lo, A. and MacKinlay, C. 1990c. When are contrarian profits due <strong>to</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck marke<strong>to</strong>verreaction? Review of Financial Studies 3, 175–206.Lo, A. and MacKinlay, C. 1999. A Non-Random Walk Down Wall Street. Prince<strong>to</strong>n, NJ:Prince<strong>to</strong>n University Press.Lo, A. and Repin, D. 2002. The psychophysiology of real-time financial risk processing.Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience 14, 323–39.Loewenstein, G. 2000. Emotions in economic <strong>the</strong>ory and economic behavior. AmericanEconomic Review 90, 426–32.Lucas, R. 1978. Asset prices in an exchange economy. Econometrica 46, 1429–46.Luo, G. 1995. Evolution and market competition. Journal of Economic Theory 67, 223–50.Markowitz, H. 1991. Foundations of portfolio <strong>the</strong>ory. Journal of Finance 46, 469–77.Marsh, T. andMer<strong>to</strong>n, R. 1986. Dividend variability and variance bounds tests for <strong>the</strong>rationality of s<strong>to</strong>ck market prices. American Economic Review 76, 483–98.Maynard Smith, J. 1982, Evolution and <strong>the</strong> Theory of Games. Cambridge: CambridgeUniversity Press.


27Mer<strong>to</strong>n, R. 1973. Theory of rational option pricing. Bell Journal of Economics andManagement Science 4, 141–83.Mer<strong>to</strong>n, R. 1987. On <strong>the</strong> current state of <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck market rationality hypo<strong>the</strong>sis. InMacroeconomics and Finance: Essays in Honor of Franco Modigliani, ed. R. Dornbusch, S.Fischer and J. Bossons. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Michener, R. 1982. Variance bounds in a simple model of asset pricing. Journal of PoliticalEconomy 90, 166–75.Nelson, R. and Winter, S. 1982. An Evolutionary Theory of Economic Change. Cambridge,MA: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.Niederhoffer, V. 1997. Education of a Specula<strong>to</strong>r. New York: John Wiley & Sons.Odean, T. 1998. Are inves<strong>to</strong>rs reluctant <strong>to</strong> realize <strong>the</strong>ir losses?. Journal of Finance 53,1775–98.Osborne, M. 1959. Brownian motion in <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck market. Operations Research 7, 145–73.Poterba, J. and Summers, L. 1988. Mean reversion in s<strong>to</strong>ck returns: evidence andimplications. Journal of Financial Economics 22, 27–60.Ramsey, F. 1926. Truth and probability. In Foundations of Ma<strong>the</strong>matics and O<strong>the</strong>r LogicalEssays, ed. R. Braithwaite. New York: Harcourt Brace & Co.Richardson, M. 1993. Temporary components of s<strong>to</strong>ck prices: a skeptic’s view. Journal ofBusiness and Economics Statistics 11, 199–207.Roberts, H. 1959. S<strong>to</strong>ck-market ‘patterns’ and financial analysis: methodologicalsuggestions. Journal of Finance 14, 1–10.Roberts, H. 1967. Statistical versus clinical prediction of <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck market. Unpublishedmanuscript, Center for Research in Security Prices, University of Chicago.Roll, R. 1983. Vas is das? The turn-of-<strong>the</strong>-year effect and <strong>the</strong> return premia of small firms.Journal of Portfolio Management 9, 18–28.Roll, R. 1984. Orange juice and wea<strong>the</strong>r. American Economic Review 74, 861–80.Rolls, E. 1999. The Brain and Emotion. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Rosenberg, B., Reid, K. and Lanstein, R. 1985. Persuasive evidence of market inefficiency.Journal of Portfolio Management 11, 9–17.Rozeff, M. and Kinney, W., Jr. 1976. Capital market seasonality: <strong>the</strong> case of s<strong>to</strong>ck returns.Journal of Financial Economics 3, 379–402.Rubinstein, A. 1998. Modeling Bounded Rationality. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Rubinstein, M. 1976. The valuation of uncertain income streams and <strong>the</strong> pricing of options.Bell Journal of Economics 7, 407–25.


28Samuelson, P. 1947. Foundations of Economics Analysis. Cambridge, MA: HarvardUniversity Press.Samuelson, P. 1965. Proof that properly anticipated prices fluctuate randomly. IndustrialManagement Review 6, 41–9.Sargent, T. 1993. Bounded Rationality in Macroeconomics. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Savage, L. 1954. Foundations of Statistics. New York: John Wiley & Sons.Schumpeter, J. 1939. Business Cycles: A Theoretical, His<strong>to</strong>rical, And Statistical Analysis of<strong>the</strong> Capitalist Process. New York: McGraw-Hill.Shefrin, M. and Statman, M. 1985. The disposition <strong>to</strong> sell winners <strong>to</strong>o early and ride losers<strong>to</strong>o long: <strong>the</strong>ory and evidence. Journal of Finance 40, 777–90.Shiller, R. 1981. Do s<strong>to</strong>ck prices move <strong>to</strong>o much <strong>to</strong> be justified by subsequent changes individends? American Economic Review 71, 421–36.Simon, H. 1955. A behavioral model of rational choice. Quarterly Journal of Economics 69,99–118.Simon, H. 1982. Models of Bounded Rationality, 2 vols. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Starmer, C. 2000. Developments in non-expected utility <strong>the</strong>ory: <strong>the</strong> hunt for a descriptive<strong>the</strong>ory of choice under risk. Journal of Economic Literature 38, 332–82.Thaler, R., ed. 1993, Advances in Behavioral Finance. New York: Russell Sage Foundation.Tversky, A. and Kahneman, D.1981. The framing of decisions and <strong>the</strong> psychology of choice.Science 211, 453–8.Wilson, E. 1975, Sociobiology: The New Syn<strong>the</strong>sis. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press ofHarvard University Press.


Maps of Bounded Rationality: Psychology for Behavioral EconomicsDaniel KahnemanThe American Economic Review, Vol. 93, No. 5. (Dec., 2003), pp. 1449-1475.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0002-8282%28200312%2993%3A5%3C1449%3AMOBRPF%3E2.0.CO%3B2-%23The American Economic Review is currently published by American Economic Association.Your use of <strong>the</strong> JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available athttp://www.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/about/terms.html. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtainedprior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in<strong>the</strong> JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use.Please contact <strong>the</strong> publisher regarding any fur<strong>the</strong>r use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained athttp://www.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/journals/aea.html.Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain <strong>the</strong> same copyright notice that appears on <strong>the</strong> screen or printedpage of such transmission.The JSTOR Archive is a trusted digital reposi<strong>to</strong>ry providing for long-term preservation and access <strong>to</strong> leading academicjournals and scholarly literature from around <strong>the</strong> world. The Archive is supported by libraries, scholarly societies, publishers,and foundations. It is an initiative of JSTOR, a not-for-profit organization with a mission <strong>to</strong> help <strong>the</strong> scholarly community takeadvantage of advances in technology. For more information regarding JSTOR, please contact support@js<strong>to</strong>r.org.http://www.js<strong>to</strong>r.orgMon Jan 14 13:57:31 2008


Maps of Bounded Rationality:Psychology for Behavioral ~conomics~The work cited by <strong>the</strong> Nobel committee wasdone jointly with Amos Tversky (1937-1996)during a long and unusually close collaboration.To<strong>get</strong>her, we explored <strong>the</strong> psychology of intuitivebeliefs and choices and examined <strong>the</strong>irbounded rationality. Herbert A. Simon (1955,1979) had proposed much earlier that decisionmakers should be viewed as boundedly rational,and had offered a model in which utility maximizationwas replaced by satisficing. Our researchattempted <strong>to</strong> obtain a map of boundedrationality, by exploring <strong>the</strong> systematic biasesthat separate <strong>the</strong> beliefs that people have and <strong>the</strong>choices <strong>the</strong>y make from <strong>the</strong> optimal beliefs andchoices assumed in rational-agent models. Therational-agent model was our starting point and<strong>the</strong> main source of our null hypo<strong>the</strong>ses, butTversky and I viewed our research primarily asa contribution <strong>to</strong> psychology, with a possiblecontribution <strong>to</strong> economics as a secondary benefit.We were drawn in<strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> interdisciplinaryconversation by economists who hoped thatpsychology could be a useful source of assumptionsfor economic <strong>the</strong>orizing, and indirectly asource of hypo<strong>the</strong>ses for economic research(Richard H. Thaler, 1980, 1991, 1992). TheseThis article is a revised version of <strong>the</strong> lecture DanielKahneman delivered in S<strong>to</strong>ckholm, Sweden, on December8, 2002, when he received <strong>the</strong> Bank of Sweden Prize inEconomic Sciences in Memory of Alfred Nobel. The articleis copyright 0The Nobel Foundation 2002 and is published<strong>here</strong> with <strong>the</strong> permission of <strong>the</strong> Nobel Foundation.* Woodrow Wilson School, Prince<strong>to</strong>n University,Prince<strong>to</strong>n, NJ 08544 (e-mail: Kahneman@prince<strong>to</strong>n.edu).This essay revisits problems that Amos Tversky and Istudied <strong>to</strong><strong>get</strong>her many years ago, and continued <strong>to</strong> discuss ina conversation that spanned several decades. It builds on ananalysis of judgment heuristics that was developed in collaborationwith Shane Frederick (Kahneman and Frederick,2002). A different version was published in American Psychologistin September 2003. For detailed comments on thisversion I am grateful <strong>to</strong> Angus Dea<strong>to</strong>n, David Laibson,Michael Rothschild, and Richard Thaler. The usual caveatsapply. Geoffrey Goodwin, Amir Goren, and Kurt Schoppeprovided helpful research assistance.hopes have been realized <strong>to</strong> some extent, givingrise <strong>to</strong> an active program of research by behavioraleconomists (Thaler, 2000; Colin Camereret al., forthcoming; for o<strong>the</strong>r examples, seeKahneman and Tversky, 2000).My work with Tversky comprised three separateprograms of research, some aspects ofwhich were carried out with o<strong>the</strong>r collabora<strong>to</strong>rs.The first explored <strong>the</strong> heuristics that people useand <strong>the</strong> biases <strong>to</strong> which <strong>the</strong>y are prone in varioustasks of judgment under uncertainty, includingpredictions and evaluations of evidence(Kahneman and Tversky, 1973; Tversky andKahneman, 1974; Kahneman et al., 1982). Thesecond was concerned with prospect <strong>the</strong>ory, amodel of choice under risk (Kahneman andTversky, 1979; Tversky and Kahneman, 1992)and with loss aversion in riskless choice (Kahnemanet al., 1990, 1991 ; Tversky and Kahneman,1991). The third line of research dealt withframing effects and with <strong>the</strong>ir implications forrational-agent models (Tversky and Kahneman,1981, 1986). The present essay revisits <strong>the</strong>sethree lines of research in light of recent advancesin <strong>the</strong> psychology of intuitive judgmentand choice. Many of <strong>the</strong> ideas presented <strong>here</strong>were anticipated informally decades ago, but<strong>the</strong> attempt <strong>to</strong> integrate <strong>the</strong>m in<strong>to</strong> a co<strong>here</strong>ntapproach <strong>to</strong> judgment and choice is recent.Economists often criticize psychological researchfor its propensity <strong>to</strong> generate lists oferrors and biases, and for its failure <strong>to</strong> offer aco<strong>here</strong>nt alternative <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> rational-agent model.This complaint is only partly justified: psychological<strong>the</strong>ories of intuitive thinking cannotmatch <strong>the</strong> elegance and precision of formal normativemodels of belief and choice, but this isjust ano<strong>the</strong>r way of saying that rational modelsare psychologically unrealistic. Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore,<strong>the</strong> alternative <strong>to</strong> simple and precise models isnot chaos. Psychology offers integrative conceptsand mid-level generalizations, which gaincredibility from <strong>the</strong>ir ability <strong>to</strong> explain ostensiblydifferent phenomena in diverse domains. Inthis spirit, <strong>the</strong> present essay offers a unified


1450 THE AMERICAN ECONOMIC REVIEW DECEMBER 2003treatment of intuitive judgme'nt and choice,which builds on an earlier study of <strong>the</strong> relationshipbetween preferences and attitudes (Kahnemanet al., 1999) and extends a model ofjudgment heuristics recently proposed by Kahnemanand Shane Frederick (2002). The guidingideas are (i) that most judgments and mostchoices are made intuitively; (ii) that <strong>the</strong> rulesthat govern intuition are generally similar <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong>rules of perception. Accordingly, <strong>the</strong> discussionof <strong>the</strong> rules of intuitive judgments and choiceswill rely extensively on visual analogies.Section I introduces a distinction betweentwo generic modes of cognitive function, correspondingroughly <strong>to</strong> intuition and reasoning.Section 11 describes <strong>the</strong> fac<strong>to</strong>rs that determine<strong>the</strong> relative accessibility of different judgmentsand responses. section-111 relates prospect <strong>the</strong>ory<strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> general proposition that changes anddifferences are more accessible than absolutevalues. Section IV explains framing effects interms of differential salience and accessibility.Section V reviews an attribute substitutionmodel of heuristic judgment. Section VI describesa particular family of heuristics, calledpro<strong>to</strong>type heuristics. Section VII discusses <strong>the</strong>interactions between intuitive and deliberatethought. Section VIII concludes.I. The Architecture of Cognition: Two SystemsThe present treatment distinguishes twomodes of thinking and deciding, which correspondroughly <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> everyday concepts of reasoningand intuition. Reasoning is what we dowhen we compute <strong>the</strong> product of 17 by 258, fillan income tax form, or consult a map. Intuitionis at work when we read <strong>the</strong> sentence "BillClin<strong>to</strong>n is a shy man" as mildly amusing, orwhen we find ourselves reluctant <strong>to</strong> eat a pieceof what we know <strong>to</strong> be chocolate that has beenformed in <strong>the</strong> shape of a cockroach (Paul Rozinand Carol Nemeroff, 2002). Reasoning is donedeliberately and effortfully, but intuitive thoughtsseem <strong>to</strong> come spontaneously <strong>to</strong> mind, withoutconscious search or computation, and withouteffort. Casual observation and systematic researchindicate that most thoughts and actionsare normally intuitive in this sense (Daniel T.Gilbert, 1989, 2002; Timothy D. Wilson, 2002;Seymour Epstein, 2003).Although effortless thought is <strong>the</strong> norm,some moni<strong>to</strong>ring of <strong>the</strong> quality of mental oper-ations and overt behavior also goes on. We donot express every passing thought or act onevery impulse. But <strong>the</strong> moni<strong>to</strong>ring is normallylax, and allows many intuitive judgments <strong>to</strong> beexpressed, including some that &e erroneous(Kahneman and Frederick, 2002). Ellen J.Langer et al. (1978) provided a well-knownexample of what she called "mindless behavior."In her experiment, a confederate tried <strong>to</strong>cut in line at a copying machine, using variouspreset "excuses." The conclusion was that statementsthat had <strong>the</strong> form of an unqualified requestwere rejected (e.g., "Excuse me, may I use<strong>the</strong> Xerox machine?')), but almost any statementthat had <strong>the</strong> general form of an explanation wasaccepted, including "Excuse me, may I use <strong>the</strong>Xerox machine because I want <strong>to</strong> make copies?"The superficiality is striking.Frederick (2003, personal communication)has used simple puzzles <strong>to</strong> study cognitive selfmoni<strong>to</strong>ring,as in <strong>the</strong> following example: "A batand a ball cost $1.10 in <strong>to</strong>tal. The bat costs $1more than <strong>the</strong> ball. How much does <strong>the</strong> ballcost?'AAlmost everyone reports an initial tendency<strong>to</strong> answer "10 cents" because <strong>the</strong> sum$1.10 separates naturally in<strong>to</strong> $1 and 10 cents,and 10 cents is about <strong>the</strong> right magnitude. Frederickfound that many intelligent people yield <strong>to</strong>this immediate impulse: 50 percent (47193) of agroup of Prince<strong>to</strong>n students and 56 percent(1641293) of students at <strong>the</strong> University of Michigangave <strong>the</strong> wrong answer. Clearly, <strong>the</strong>se respondentsoffered <strong>the</strong>ir response without firstchecking it. The surprisingly high rate of errorsin this easy problem illustrates how lightly <strong>the</strong>output of effortless associative thinking is moni<strong>to</strong>red:people are not accus<strong>to</strong>med <strong>to</strong> thinkinghard. and are often content <strong>to</strong> trust a plausiblejudgment that quickly comes <strong>to</strong> mind. Remarkably,Frederick has found that errors inthis puzzle and in o<strong>the</strong>rs of <strong>the</strong> same typewere- significant predic<strong>to</strong>rs of high discountrates.In <strong>the</strong> examples discussed so far, intuitionwas associated with poor performance, but intuitivethinking can also be powerful and accurate.High skill is acquired by prolongedpractice, and <strong>the</strong> performance of skills is rapidand effortless. The proverbial master chessplayer who walks past a game and declares"white mates in three" without slowing is performingintuitively (Simon and William G.Chase, 1973), as is <strong>the</strong> experienced nurse who


VOL. 93 NO. 5KAHNEMAN: MAPS OF BOUNDED RATIONALITYEPERCEPTIONSYSTEMFastParallelAu<strong>to</strong>maticEffortlessAssociativeSlow-learningEmotional1- --rSYSTEM 2SerialControlledEffortfulRule-governedFlexibleNeutralPerceptsCurrent stimulationStimulus-boundConceptual representationsPast, Present and FutureCan be evoked by languagedetects subtle signs of impending heart failure(Gary Klein, 1998; Atul Gawande, 2002).The distinction between intuition and reasoninghas recently been a <strong>to</strong>pic of considerableinterest <strong>to</strong> psychologists (see, e.g., ShellyChaiken and Yaacov Trope, 1999; Gilbert,2002; Steven A. Sloman, 2002; Keith E.Stanovich and Richard F. West, 2002). T<strong>here</strong> issubstantial agreement on <strong>the</strong> characteristics thatdistinguish <strong>the</strong> two types of cognitive processes,for which Stanovich and West (2000) proposed<strong>the</strong> neutral labels of System 1 and System 2.The scheme shown in Figure 1 summarizes<strong>the</strong>se characteristics. The operations of System1 are fast, au<strong>to</strong>matic, effortless, associative, andoften emotionally charged; <strong>the</strong>y are also governedby habit, and are t<strong>here</strong>fore difficult <strong>to</strong>control or modify. The operations of System 2are slower, serial, effortful, and deliberatelycontrolled; <strong>the</strong>y are also relatively flexible andpotentially rule-governed.The difference in effort provides <strong>the</strong> mostuseful indications of whe<strong>the</strong>r a given mentalprocess should be assigned <strong>to</strong> System 1 or System2. Because <strong>the</strong> overall capacity for mentaleffort is limited, effortful processes tend <strong>to</strong> disrupteach o<strong>the</strong>r, w<strong>here</strong>as effortless processesnei<strong>the</strong>r cause nor suffer much interference whencombined with o<strong>the</strong>r tasks. For example, a driver'sability <strong>to</strong> conduct a conversation is a sensitiveindica<strong>to</strong>r of <strong>the</strong> amount of attentioncurrently demanded by <strong>the</strong> driving task. Dualtasks have been used in hundreds of psychologicalexperiments <strong>to</strong> measure <strong>the</strong> attentional demandsof different mental activities (for areview, see Harold E. Pashler, 1998). Studiesusing <strong>the</strong> dual-task method suggest that <strong>the</strong> selfmoni<strong>to</strong>ringfunction belongs with <strong>the</strong> effortfuloperations of System 2. People who are occupiedby a demanding mental activity (e.g., attempting<strong>to</strong> hold in mind several digits) aremuch more likely <strong>to</strong> respond <strong>to</strong> ano<strong>the</strong>r task byblurting out whatever comes <strong>to</strong> mind (Gilbert,1989). The phrase that "System 2 moni<strong>to</strong>rs <strong>the</strong>activities of System 1" will be used <strong>here</strong> asshorthand for a hypo<strong>the</strong>sis about what wouldhappen if <strong>the</strong> operations of System 2 were disrupted.For example, it is safe <strong>to</strong> predict that <strong>the</strong>percentage of errors in <strong>the</strong> bat-and-ball questionwill increase, if <strong>the</strong> respondents are asked thisquestion while attempting <strong>to</strong> keep a list ofwords in <strong>the</strong>ir active memory.In <strong>the</strong> language that will be used <strong>here</strong>, <strong>the</strong>perceptual system and <strong>the</strong> intuitive operations


1452 THE AMERICAN ECONOMIC REVIEW DECEMBER 2003of System 1 generate impressions of <strong>the</strong> attributesof objects of perception and thought.These impressions are not voluntary and neednot be verbally explicit. In contrast, judgmentsare always explicit and intentional, whe<strong>the</strong>r ornot <strong>the</strong>y are overtly expressed. Thus, System 2is involved in all judgments, whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>y originatein impressions or in deliberate reasoning.The label "intuitive" is applied <strong>to</strong> judgmentsthat directly reflect impressions.Figure 1 illustrates an idea that guided t<strong>here</strong>search that Tversky and I conducted from itsearly days: that intuitive judgments occupy aposition-perhaps corresponding <strong>to</strong> evolutionaryhis<strong>to</strong>ry-between <strong>the</strong> au<strong>to</strong>matic operationsof perception and <strong>the</strong> deliberate operations ofreasoning. All <strong>the</strong> characteristics that studentsof intuition have attributed <strong>to</strong> System 1 are alsoproperties of perceptual operations. Unlike perception,however, <strong>the</strong> operations of System 1are not restricted <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> processing of currentstimulation. Like System 2, <strong>the</strong> operations ofSystem 1 deal with s<strong>to</strong>red concepts as well aswith percepts, and can be evoked by language.This view of intuition suggests that <strong>the</strong> vasts<strong>to</strong>re of scientific knowledge available aboutperceptual phenomena can be a source of usefulhypo<strong>the</strong>ses about <strong>the</strong> workings of intuition. Thestrategy of drawing on analogies from perceptionis applied in <strong>the</strong> following section.11. The Accessibility DimensionA defining property of intuitive thoughts isthat <strong>the</strong>y come <strong>to</strong> mind spontaneously, like percepts.The technical term for <strong>the</strong> ease withwhich mental contents come <strong>to</strong> mind is accessibility(E. Tory Higgins, 1996). To understandintuition, we must understand why somethoughts are accessible and o<strong>the</strong>rs are not. T<strong>here</strong>mainder of this section introduces <strong>the</strong> concep<strong>to</strong>f accessibility by examples drawn from visualperception.Consider Figures 2a and 2b. As we look at<strong>the</strong> object in Figure 2a, we have immediateimpressions of <strong>the</strong> height of <strong>the</strong> <strong>to</strong>wer, <strong>the</strong> areaof <strong>the</strong> <strong>to</strong>p block, and perhaps <strong>the</strong> volume of <strong>the</strong><strong>to</strong>wer. Translating <strong>the</strong>se impressions in<strong>to</strong> unitsof height or volume requires a deliberate operation,but <strong>the</strong> impressions <strong>the</strong>mselves are highlyaccessible. For o<strong>the</strong>r attributes, no perceptualimpression exists. For example, <strong>the</strong> <strong>to</strong>tal areathat <strong>the</strong> blocks would cover if <strong>the</strong> <strong>to</strong>wer were,' /F~gurc 2a Figt~rc ?b Figure 2cdismantled is not perceptually accessible,though it can be estimated by a deliberate procedure,such as multiplying <strong>the</strong> area of a blockby <strong>the</strong> number of blocks. Of course, <strong>the</strong> situationis reversed with Figure 2b. Now <strong>the</strong> blocksare laid out and an impression of <strong>to</strong>tal area isimmediately accessible, but <strong>the</strong> height of <strong>the</strong><strong>to</strong>wer that could be constructed with <strong>the</strong>seblocks is not.Some relational properties are accessible.Thus, it is obvious at a glance that Figures 2aand 2c are different, but also that <strong>the</strong>y are moresimilar <strong>to</strong> each o<strong>the</strong>r than ei<strong>the</strong>r is <strong>to</strong> Figure2b. And some statistical properties of ensemblesare accessible, while o<strong>the</strong>rs are not. For anexample, consider <strong>the</strong> question "What is <strong>the</strong>average length of <strong>the</strong> lines in Figure 3?' Thisquestion is easy. When a set of objects of <strong>the</strong>same general kind is presented <strong>to</strong> an observerwhe<strong>the</strong>rsimultaneously or successively-a representationof <strong>the</strong> set is computed au<strong>to</strong>matically,which includes quite precise information about<strong>the</strong> average (Dan Ariely, 2001; Sang-ChulChong and Anne Treisman, 2003). The representationof <strong>the</strong> pro<strong>to</strong>type is highly accessible,and it has <strong>the</strong> character of a percept: we fo'im animpression of <strong>the</strong> typical line without choosing<strong>to</strong> do so. The only role for System 2 in this taskis <strong>to</strong> map <strong>the</strong> impression of typical length on<strong>to</strong><strong>the</strong> appropriate scale. In contrast, <strong>the</strong> answer <strong>to</strong><strong>the</strong> question "What is <strong>the</strong> <strong>to</strong>tal length of <strong>the</strong>lines in <strong>the</strong> display?' does not come <strong>to</strong> mindwithout considerable effort.As <strong>the</strong> example of averages and sums illustrates,some attributes are more accessible thano<strong>the</strong>rs, both in perception and in judgment. Attributesthat are routinely and au<strong>to</strong>maticallyproduced by <strong>the</strong> perceptual system or by System


VOL. 93 NO. 5KAHNEMAN: MAPS OF BOUNDED RATIONALITY14531, without intention or effort, have been callednatural assessments (Tversky and Kahneman,1983). Kahneman and Frederick (2002) compileda partial list of <strong>the</strong>se natural assessments.In addition <strong>to</strong> physical properties such as size,distance, and loudness, <strong>the</strong> list includes moreabstract properties such as similarity, causalpropensity, surprisingness, affective valence,and mood.The evaluation of stimuli as good or bad is aparticularly important natural assessment. Theevidence, both behavioral (John A. Bargh,1997; Robert B. Zajonc, 1998) and neurophysiological(e.g., Joseph E. LeDoux, 2000), isconsistent with <strong>the</strong> idea that <strong>the</strong> assessment ofwhe<strong>the</strong>r objects are good (and should be approached)or bad (should be avoided) is carriedout quickly and efficiently by specialized neuralcircuitry. A remarkable experiment reported byBargh (1997) illustrates <strong>the</strong> speed of <strong>the</strong> evaluationprocess, and its direct link <strong>to</strong> approach andavoidance. Participants were shown a series ofstimuli on a screen, and instructed <strong>to</strong> respond <strong>to</strong>each stimulus as soon as it appeared, by movinga lever that blanked <strong>the</strong> screen. The stimuli wereaffectively charged words, some positive (e.g.,LOVE) and some aversive (e.g., VOMIT), butthis feature was irrelevant <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> participant'stask. Half <strong>the</strong> participants responded by pulling<strong>the</strong> lever <strong>to</strong>ward <strong>the</strong>mselves, half responded bypushing <strong>the</strong> lever away. Although <strong>the</strong> responsewas initiated within a fraction of a second, wellbefore <strong>the</strong> meaning of <strong>the</strong> stimulus was consciouslyregistered, <strong>the</strong> emotional valence of <strong>the</strong>word had a substantial effect. Participants wererelatively faster in pulling a lever <strong>to</strong>ward <strong>the</strong>mselves(approach) for positive words, and relativelyfaster pushing <strong>the</strong> lever away when <strong>the</strong>word was aversive. The tendencies <strong>to</strong> approachor avoid were evoked by an au<strong>to</strong>matic processthat was not under conscious voluntary control.Several psychologists have commented on <strong>the</strong>influence of this primordial evaluative system(<strong>here</strong> included in System 1) on <strong>the</strong> attitudes andpreferences that people adopt consciously anddeliberately (Zajonc, 1998; Kahneman et al.,1999; Paul Slovic et al., 2002; Epstein, 2003).The preceding discussion establishes a dimensionof accessibility. At one end of thisdimension we find operations that have <strong>the</strong>characteristics of perception and of <strong>the</strong> intuitiveSystem 1: <strong>the</strong>y are rapid, au<strong>to</strong>matic, and effortless.At <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r end are slow. serial. andeffortful operations that people need a specialreason <strong>to</strong> undertake. Accessibility is a continuum,not a dicho<strong>to</strong>my, and some effortful operationsdemand more effort than o<strong>the</strong>rs. Someof <strong>the</strong> determinants of accessibility are probablygenetic; o<strong>the</strong>rs develop through experience. Theacquisition of skill gradually increases <strong>the</strong> accessibilityof useful responses and of productiveways <strong>to</strong> organize information, until skilled performancebecomes almost effortless. This effec<strong>to</strong>f practice is not limited <strong>to</strong> mo<strong>to</strong>r skills. Amaster chess player does not see <strong>the</strong> same boardas <strong>the</strong> novice, and visualizing <strong>the</strong> <strong>to</strong>wer in anmay of blocks would also become virtuallyeffortless with prolonged practice.The impressions that become accessible inany particular situation are mainly determined,of course, by <strong>the</strong> actual properties of <strong>the</strong> objec<strong>to</strong>f judgment: it is easier <strong>to</strong> see a <strong>to</strong>wer in Figure2a than in Figure 2b, because <strong>the</strong> <strong>to</strong>wer in <strong>the</strong>latter is only virtual. Physical salience also determinesaccessibility: if a large green letter anda small blue letter are shown at <strong>the</strong> same time,"green" will come <strong>to</strong> mind first. However, saliencecan be overcome by deliberate attention:an instruction <strong>to</strong> look for <strong>the</strong> small object willenhance <strong>the</strong> accessibility of all its features.Analogous effects of salience and of spontaneousand voluntary attention occur with moreabstract stimuli. For example, <strong>the</strong> statements"Team A beat team B" and "Team B lost <strong>to</strong>


1454 THE AMERICAN ECONOMIC REVIEW DECEMBER 2003team A" convey <strong>the</strong> same information, but becauseeach sentence draws attention <strong>to</strong> its grammaticalsubject, <strong>the</strong>y make different thoughtsaccessible. Accessibility also reflects temporarystates of associative activation. For example, <strong>the</strong>mention of a familiar social category temporarilyincreases <strong>the</strong> accessibility of <strong>the</strong> traits associatedwith <strong>the</strong> category stereotype, as indicated by alowered threshold for recognizing behaviors asindications of <strong>the</strong>se traits (Susan T. Fiske, 1998).As designers of billboards know well, motivationallyrelevant and emotionally arousingstimuli spontaneously attract attention. Billboardsare useful <strong>to</strong> advertisers because payingattention <strong>to</strong> an object makes all its featuresaccessible-including those that are not linked<strong>to</strong> its primary motivational or emotional significance.The "hot" states of high emotional andmotivational arousal greatly increase <strong>the</strong> accessibilityof thoughts that relate <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> immediateemotion and <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> current needs, and reduce <strong>the</strong>accessibility of o<strong>the</strong>r thoughts (George Loewenstein.1996. 2000: Jon Elster. 1998). Aneffect of emotional significance on accessibilitywas demonstrated in an important study by YuvalRottenstreich and Chris<strong>to</strong>pher K. Hsee(2001), which showed that people are less sensitive<strong>to</strong> variations of probability when valuingchances <strong>to</strong> receive emotionally loaded outcomes(kisses and electric shocks) than when<strong>the</strong> outcomes are monetary.Figure 4 (adapted from Jerome S. Bruner andA. Leigh Minturn, 1955) includes a standarddemonstration of <strong>the</strong> effect of context on accessibility.An ambiguous stimulus that is perceivedas a letter within a context of letters isinstead seen as a number when placed within acontext of numbers. More generally, expectations(conscious or not) are a powerful determinan<strong>to</strong>f accessibility.Ano<strong>the</strong>r important point that Figure 4 illustratesis <strong>the</strong> complete suppression of ambiguityin conscious perception. This aspect of <strong>the</strong> demonstrationis spoiled for <strong>the</strong> reader who sees <strong>the</strong>two versions in close proximity, but when <strong>the</strong>two lines are shown separately, observers willnot spontaneously become aware of <strong>the</strong> alternativeinterpretation. They "see" <strong>the</strong> interpretationof <strong>the</strong> object that is <strong>the</strong> most likely in its context,but have no subjective indication that itcould be seen differently. Ambiguity and uncertaintyare suppressed in intuitive judgment aswell as in perception. Doubt is a phenomenon ofSystem 2, an awareness of one's ability <strong>to</strong> thinkincompatible thoughts about <strong>the</strong> same thing.The central finding in studies of intuitive decisions,as described by Klein (1998), is thatexperienced decision makers working underpressure (e.g., firefighting company captains)rarely need <strong>to</strong> choose between options because,in most cases, only a single option comes <strong>to</strong> mind.The compound cognitive system that hasbeen sketched <strong>here</strong> is an impressive computationaldevice. It is well-adapted <strong>to</strong> its environmentand has two ways of adjusting <strong>to</strong> changes:a short-term process that is flexible and effortful,and a long-term process of skill acquisitionthat eventually produces highly effective responsesat low cost. The system tends <strong>to</strong> seewhat it expects <strong>to</strong> see-a form of Bayesianadaptation-and it is also capable of respondingeffectively <strong>to</strong> surprises. However, this marvelouscreation differs in important respects fromano<strong>the</strong>r paragon, <strong>the</strong> rational agent assumed ineconomic <strong>the</strong>ory. Some of <strong>the</strong>se differences areexplored in <strong>the</strong> following sections, which reviewseveral familiar results as effects of accessibility.Possible implications for <strong>the</strong>orizing in behavioraleconomics are explored along <strong>the</strong> way.111. Changes or States: Prospect TheoryA general property of perceptual systems isthat <strong>the</strong>y are designed <strong>to</strong> enhance <strong>the</strong> accessibilityof changes and differences. Perception isreference-dependent: <strong>the</strong> perceived attributesof a focal stimulus reflect <strong>the</strong> contrast betweenthat stimulus and a context of prior and concurrentstimuli. This section will show that


VOL. 93 NO. 5 XAHNEMAN: MAPS OF BOUNDED RATIONALITY 1455FIGURE 5. REFERENCE-DEPENDENCE IN THE PERCEF'TION OF BRIGHTNESSintuitive evaluations of outcomes are alsoreference-dependent.The role of ~rior stimulation is familiar in <strong>the</strong>domain of temperature. Immersing <strong>the</strong> hand inwater at 20°C will feel pleasantly warm afterprolonged immersion in much colder water, andpleasantly cool after immersion in muchwarmer water. Figure 5 illustrates referencedependencein vision. The two enclosed squareshave <strong>the</strong> same luminance, but <strong>the</strong>y do not appearequally bright. The point of <strong>the</strong> demonstrationis that <strong>the</strong> brightness of an area is not asingle-parameter function of <strong>the</strong> light energythat reaches <strong>the</strong> eye from that area, just as <strong>the</strong>experience of temperature is not a single-parameterfunction of <strong>the</strong> temperature <strong>to</strong> which one iscurrently exposed. An account of perceivedbrightness ortemperature also requires a parameterfor a reference value (often called adaptationlevel), which is influenced by <strong>the</strong> context ofcurrent and prior stimulation.From <strong>the</strong> vantage point of a student of perception,it is quite surprising that in standardeconomic analyses <strong>the</strong> utility of decision outcomesis assumed <strong>to</strong> be determined entirely by<strong>the</strong> final state of endowment, and is t<strong>here</strong>forereference-independent. In <strong>the</strong> context of riskychoice, this assumption can be traced <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong>brilliant essay that first defined a <strong>the</strong>ory of expectedutility (Daniel Bernoulli, 1738). Bernoulliassumed that states of wealth have aspecified utility, and proposed that <strong>the</strong> decisionrule for choice under risk is <strong>to</strong> maximize <strong>the</strong>expected utility of wealth (<strong>the</strong> moral expectation).The language of Bernoulli's essay is prescriptive-itspeaks of what is sensible orreasonable <strong>to</strong> do-but <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory was also intendedas a description of <strong>the</strong> choices of reasonablemen (Gerd Gigerenzer et al., 1989). As inmost modem treatments of decision-making,Bernoulli's essay does not acknowledge anytension between prescription and description.The proposition that decision makers evaluateoutcomes by <strong>the</strong> utility of final asset positionshas been retained in economic analyses for almost300 vears. This is ra<strong>the</strong>r remarkable. because<strong>the</strong> idea is easily shown <strong>to</strong> be wrong; Icall it Bernoulli's error.Tversky and I constructed numerous thoughtexperiments when we began <strong>the</strong> study of riskychoice that led <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> formulation of prospect<strong>the</strong>ory (Kahneman and Tversky, 1979). Examplessuch as Problems 1 and 2 below convincedus of <strong>the</strong> inadequacy of <strong>the</strong> utility function forwealth as an explanation of choice.Problem 1Would you accept this gamble?50% chance <strong>to</strong> win $15050% chance <strong>to</strong> lose $100Would your choice change if youroverall wealth were lower by $loo?


1456 THE AMERICAN ECONOMIC REVIEW DECEMBER 2003T<strong>here</strong> will be few takers of <strong>the</strong> gamble in Problem1. The experimental evidence shows thatmost people will reject a gamble with evenchances <strong>to</strong> win and lose, unless <strong>the</strong> possible winis at least twice <strong>the</strong> size of <strong>the</strong> possible loss(e.g., Tversky and Kahneman, 1992). The answer<strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> second question is, of course, negative.Next consider Problem 2:1OSst.SVALUECAMProblem 2Which would you choose?lose $100 with certaintyor50% chance <strong>to</strong> win $5050% chance <strong>to</strong> lose $200Would your choice change if youroverall wealth were higher by $loo?In Problem 2, <strong>the</strong> gamble appears much moreattractive than <strong>the</strong> sure loss. Experimental resultsindicate that risk-seeking preferences areheld by a large majority of respondents in problemsof this kind (Kahneman and Tversky,1979). Here again, <strong>the</strong> idea that a change of$100 in <strong>to</strong>tal wealth would affect preferencescannot be taken seriously.We examined many choice pairs of thistype in our early explorations, and concludedthat <strong>the</strong> very abrupt switch from risk aversion<strong>to</strong> risk seeking could not plausibly be explainedby a utility function for wealth. Preferencesappeared <strong>to</strong> be determined byattitudes <strong>to</strong> gains and losses, defined relative<strong>to</strong> a reference point, but Bernoulli's <strong>the</strong>oryand its successors did not incorporate a referencepoint. We t<strong>here</strong>fore proposed an alternative<strong>the</strong>ory of risk, in which <strong>the</strong> carriers ofutility are gains and losses-changes ofwealth ra<strong>the</strong>r than states of wealth. One noveltyof prospect <strong>the</strong>ory was that it was explicitlypresented as a formal descriptive <strong>the</strong>oryof <strong>the</strong> choices that people actually make, notas a normative model. This was a departurefrom a long his<strong>to</strong>ry of choice models thatserved double duty as normative logics and asidealized descriptive models.The distinctive predictions of prospect <strong>the</strong>oryfollow from <strong>the</strong> shape of <strong>the</strong> value function,which is shown in Figure 6. The valuefunction is defined on gains and losses and isIFIGURE 6. ASCHEMATICVALUEFUNCTION FOR CHANGEScharacterized by three features: (1) it is concavein <strong>the</strong> domain of gains, favoring riskaversion; (2) it is convex in <strong>the</strong> domain oflosses, favoring risk seeking; (3) most important,<strong>the</strong> function is sharply kinked at t<strong>here</strong>ference point, and loss-averse-steeper forlosses than for gains by a fac<strong>to</strong>r of about2-2.5 (Kahneman et al., 1991; Tversky andKahneman, 1992).If Bernoulli's formulation is transparentlyincorrect as a descriptive model of riskychoices, as has been argued <strong>here</strong>, whyhas this model been retained for so long?The answer appears <strong>to</strong> be that <strong>the</strong> assignmen<strong>to</strong>f utility <strong>to</strong> wealth is an aspect of rationality,and t<strong>here</strong>fore compatible with <strong>the</strong>general assumption of rationality in economic<strong>the</strong>orizing (Kahneman, 2003a). ConsiderProblem 3:Problem 3Two persons <strong>get</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir monthly reportfrom a broker:A is <strong>to</strong>ld that her wealth went from4M <strong>to</strong> 3MB is <strong>to</strong>ld that her wealth went fromIM <strong>to</strong> I.1MWho of <strong>the</strong> two individuals has morereason <strong>to</strong> be satisfied with her financialsituation?Who is happier <strong>to</strong>day?


VOL. 93 NO. 5KAHNEMAN: MAPS OF BOUNDED RATIONAUTY1457Problem 3 highlights <strong>the</strong> contrasting interpretationsof utility in <strong>the</strong>ories that define outcomesas states or as changes. In Bernoulli's analysisonly <strong>the</strong> first of <strong>the</strong> two questions of Problem 3is relevant, and only long-term consequencesmatter. Prospect <strong>the</strong>ory, in contrast, is concernedwith short-term outcomes, and <strong>the</strong> valuefunction presumably reflects an anticipation of<strong>the</strong> valence and intensity of <strong>the</strong> emotions thatwill be experienced at moments of transitionfrom one state <strong>to</strong> ano<strong>the</strong>r (Kahneman, 2000a, b;Barbara Mellers, 2000). Which of <strong>the</strong>se conceptsof utility is more useful? The culturalnorm of reasonable decision-making favors <strong>the</strong>long-term view over a concern with transient emotions.Indeed, <strong>the</strong> adoption of a broad perspectiveand a long-term view is an aspect of <strong>the</strong> meaningof rationality in everyday language. The finalstatesinterpretation of <strong>the</strong> utility of outcomes ist<strong>here</strong>fore a good fit for a rational-agent model.These considerations support <strong>the</strong> normativeand prescriptive status of <strong>the</strong> Bernoullian definitionof outcomes. On <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r hand, an exclusiveconcern with <strong>the</strong> long term may beprescriptively sterile, because <strong>the</strong> long term isnot w<strong>here</strong> life is lived. Utility cannot be divorcedfrom emotion, and emotions are triggeredby changes. A <strong>the</strong>ory of choice thatcompletely ignores feelings such as <strong>the</strong> pain oflosses and <strong>the</strong> regret of mistakes is not onlydescriptively unrealistic, it also leads <strong>to</strong> prescriptionsthat do not maximize <strong>the</strong> utility ofoutcomes as <strong>the</strong>y are actually experiencedthatis, utility as Bentham conceived it (Kahneman,1994, 2000a; Kahneman et al., 1997).Bernoulli's error-<strong>the</strong> idea that <strong>the</strong> carriersof utility are final states-is not restricted <strong>to</strong>decision-making under risk. Indeed, <strong>the</strong> incorrectassumption that initial endowments do notmatter is <strong>the</strong> basis of Coase's <strong>the</strong>orem and of itsmultiple applications (Kahneman et al., 1990).The error of reference-independence is builtin<strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> standard representation of indifferencemaps. It is puzzling <strong>to</strong> a psychologist that <strong>the</strong>semaps do not include a representation of <strong>the</strong>decision maker's current holdings of variousgoods-<strong>the</strong> counterpart of <strong>the</strong> reference point inprospect <strong>the</strong>ory. The parameter is not included,of course, because consumer <strong>the</strong>ory assumesthat it does not matter.The core idea of prospect <strong>the</strong>ory-that <strong>the</strong>value function is kinked at <strong>the</strong> reference pointand loss averse-became useful <strong>to</strong> economicswhen Thaler (1980) used it <strong>to</strong> explain risklesschoices. In particular, loss aversion explained aviolation of consumer <strong>the</strong>ory that Thaler identifiedand labeled <strong>the</strong> "endowment effect": <strong>the</strong> sellingprice for consumption goods is much higher than<strong>the</strong> buying price, often by a fac<strong>to</strong>r of 2 or more.The value of a good <strong>to</strong> an individual appears <strong>to</strong> behigher when <strong>the</strong> good is viewed as something thatcould be lost or given up than when <strong>the</strong> same goodis evaluated as a potential gain (Kahneman et al.,1990, 1991; Tversky and Kahneman, 1991).When half <strong>the</strong> participants in an experimentalmarket were randomly chosen <strong>to</strong> be endowedwith a good (a mug) and trade was allowed, <strong>the</strong>volume of trade was about half <strong>the</strong> amount thatwould be predicted by assuming that value wasindependent of initial endowment (Kahnemanet al., 1990). Transaction costs did not explainthis counterexample <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> Coase <strong>the</strong>orem, because<strong>the</strong> same institution produced no indicationof reluctance <strong>to</strong> trade when <strong>the</strong> objects oftrade were money <strong>to</strong>kens. The results suggestthat <strong>the</strong> participants in <strong>the</strong>se experiments did notvalue <strong>the</strong> mug as an object <strong>the</strong>y could have andconsume, but as something <strong>the</strong>y could <strong>get</strong>, orgive up. Interestingly, John A. List (2003a, b)found that <strong>the</strong> magnitude of <strong>the</strong> endowmenteffect was substantially reduced for participantswith intense experience in <strong>the</strong> trading of sportscards.Experienced traders (who are also consumers)showed less reluctance <strong>to</strong> trade onegood for ano<strong>the</strong>r-not only sportscards, but alsomugs and o<strong>the</strong>r goods-as if <strong>the</strong>y had learned <strong>to</strong>base <strong>the</strong>ir choice on long-term value, ra<strong>the</strong>r thanon <strong>the</strong> immediate emotions associated with <strong>get</strong>tingor giving up objects.Reference-dependence and loss aversion helpaccount for several phenomena of choice. Thefamiliar observation that out-of-pocket lossesare valued much more than opportunity costs isreadily explained, if <strong>the</strong>se outcomes are evaluatedon different limbs of <strong>the</strong> value function.The distinction between "actual" losses andlosses of opportunities is recognized in manyways in <strong>the</strong> law (David Cohen and Jack L.Knetsch, 1992) and in lay intuitions about rulesof fairness in <strong>the</strong> market (Kahneman et al.,1986). Loss aversion also contributes <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong>well-documented status-quo bias (WilliamSamuelson and Richard Zeckhauser, 1988). Because<strong>the</strong> reference point is usually <strong>the</strong> statusquo, <strong>the</strong> properties of alternative options areevaluated as advantages or disadvantages


1458 THE AMERICAN ECONOMIC REVIEW DECEMBER 2003relative <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> current situation, and <strong>the</strong> disadvantagesof <strong>the</strong> alternatives loom larger than<strong>the</strong>ir advantages. O<strong>the</strong>r applications of <strong>the</strong> concep<strong>to</strong>f loss aversion are documented in severalchapters in Kahneman and Tversky (2000).IV. Framing EffectsIn <strong>the</strong> display of blocks in Figure 2, <strong>the</strong> sameproperty (<strong>the</strong> <strong>to</strong>tal height of a set of blocks) washighly accessible in one display and not in ano<strong>the</strong>r,although both displays contained <strong>the</strong>same information. This observation is entirelyunremarkable-it does not seem shocking thatsome attributes of a stimulus are au<strong>to</strong>maticallyperceived while o<strong>the</strong>rs must be computed, orthat <strong>the</strong> same attribute is perceived in one displayof an object but must be computed inano<strong>the</strong>r. In <strong>the</strong> context of decision-making,however, similar observations raise a significantchallenge <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> rational-agent model.The assumption that preferences are not affectedby inconsequential variations in <strong>the</strong>description of outcomes has been called extensionality(Kenneth J. Arrow, 1982) and invariance(Tversky and Kahneman, 1986), and isconsidered an essential aspect of rationality.Invariance is violated in framing effects, w<strong>here</strong>extensionally equivalent descriptions lead <strong>to</strong>different choices by altering <strong>the</strong> relative salienceof different aspects of <strong>the</strong> problem. Tversky andKahneman (1981) introduced <strong>the</strong>ir discussion offraming effects with <strong>the</strong> following problem:The Asian diseaseImagine that <strong>the</strong> United States is preparingfor <strong>the</strong> outbreak of an unusualAsian disease, which is expected <strong>to</strong> kill600 people. Two alternative programs <strong>to</strong>combat <strong>the</strong> disease have been proposed.Assume that <strong>the</strong> exact scientific estimatesof <strong>the</strong> consequences of <strong>the</strong> programs areas follows:If Program A is adopted, 200 peoplewill be savedIf Program B is adopted, t<strong>here</strong> is aone-third probability that 600 people willbe saved and a two-thirds probability thatno people will be savedIn this version of <strong>the</strong> problem, a substantialmajority of respondents favor Program A, indicatingrisk aversion. O<strong>the</strong>r respondents, selectedat random, receive a question in which<strong>the</strong> same cover s<strong>to</strong>ry is followed by a differentdescription of <strong>the</strong> options:If Program A' is adopted, 400 people willdieIf Program B' is adopted, t<strong>here</strong> is a onethirdprobability that nobody will die anda two-thirds probability that 600 peoplewill dieA substantial majority of respondents nowfavor Program B', <strong>the</strong> risk-seeking option. Althought<strong>here</strong> is no substantive difference between<strong>the</strong> versions, <strong>the</strong>y evoke differentassociations and evaluations. This is easiest <strong>to</strong>see in <strong>the</strong> certain option, because outcomes thatare certain are overweighted relative <strong>to</strong> outcomesof high or intermediate probability (Kahnemanand Tversky, 1979). Thus, <strong>the</strong> certaintyof saving people is disproportionately attractive,while accepting <strong>the</strong> certain death of people isdisproportionately aversive. These immediateaffective responses respectively favor A over Band B' over A'. As in Figures 2a and 2b, <strong>the</strong>different representations of <strong>the</strong> outcomes highlightsome features of <strong>the</strong> situation and masko<strong>the</strong>rs.In an essay about <strong>the</strong> ethics of policy,Thomas C. Schelling (1984) presented a compellinglyrealistic example of <strong>the</strong> dilemmasraised by framing. Schelling reports asking hisstudents <strong>to</strong> evaluate a tax policy that wouldallow a larger child exemption <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> rich than<strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> poor. Not surprisingly, his students foundthis proposal outrageous. Schelling <strong>the</strong>n pointedout that <strong>the</strong> default case in <strong>the</strong> standard tax tableis a childless family, with special adjustmentsfor families with children, and led his class <strong>to</strong>agree that <strong>the</strong> existing tax schedule could berewritten with a family with two children as <strong>the</strong>default case. In this formulation, childless familieswould pay a surcharge. Should this surchargebe as large for <strong>the</strong> poor as for <strong>the</strong> rich?Of course not. The two versions of <strong>the</strong> questionabout how <strong>to</strong> treat <strong>the</strong> rich and <strong>the</strong> poor bothtrigger an intuitive preference for protecting <strong>the</strong>


VOL. 93 NO. 5KAHNEMAN: MAPS OF BOUNDED RATIONAWTY1459poor, but <strong>the</strong>se preferences are inco<strong>here</strong>nt.Schelling's problem highlights an importantpoint. Framing effects are not a labora<strong>to</strong>ry curiosity,but a ubiqui<strong>to</strong>us reality. The tax tablemust be framed one way or ano<strong>the</strong>r, and eachframe will increase <strong>the</strong> accessibility of someresponses and make o<strong>the</strong>r responses less likely.T<strong>here</strong> has been considerable interest amongbehavioral economists in a particular type offraming effect, w<strong>here</strong> a choice between twooptions A and B is affected by designatingei<strong>the</strong>r A or B as a default option. The optiondesignated as <strong>the</strong> default has a large advantagein such choices, even for decisions that haveconsiderable significance. Eric J. Johnson et al.(1993) described a compelling example. Thestates of Pennsylvania and New Jersey bothoffer drivers a choice between an insurancepolicy that allows an unconstrained right <strong>to</strong> sue,and a less expensive policy that restricts <strong>the</strong>right <strong>to</strong> sue. The unconstrained right <strong>to</strong> sue is<strong>the</strong> default in Pennsylvania, <strong>the</strong> opposite is <strong>the</strong>default in New Jersey, and <strong>the</strong> takeup of fullcoverage is 79 percent and 30 percent in <strong>the</strong> twostates, respectively. Johnson and Daniel G.Goldstein (2003) estimate that Pennsylvaniadrivers spend 450 million dollars annually onfull coverage that <strong>the</strong>y would not purchase if<strong>the</strong>ir choice were framed as it is for New Jerseydrivers.Johnson and Goldstein (2003) also compared<strong>the</strong> proportions of <strong>the</strong> population enrolled inorgan donation programs in seven Europeancountries in which enrollment was <strong>the</strong> defaultand four in which nonenrollment was <strong>the</strong> default.Averaging over countries, enrollment indonor programs was 97.4 percent when thiswas <strong>the</strong> default option, 18 percent o<strong>the</strong>rwise.The passive acceptance of <strong>the</strong> formulationgiven has significant consequences in thiscase. as it does in o<strong>the</strong>r recent studies w<strong>here</strong><strong>the</strong> selection of <strong>the</strong> default on <strong>the</strong> form thatworkers completed <strong>to</strong> set <strong>the</strong>ir 401(k) contributionsdominated <strong>the</strong>ir ultimate choice(Brigitte Madrian and Dennis Shea, 2001;James J. Choi et al., 2002).The basic principle of framing is <strong>the</strong> passiveacceptance of <strong>the</strong> formulation given. Because ofthis passivity, people fail <strong>to</strong> construct a canonicalrepresentation for all extensionally equivalentdescriptions of a state of affairs. They donot spontaneously compute <strong>the</strong> height of a<strong>to</strong>wer that could be built from an array ofblocks, and <strong>the</strong>y do not spontaneously transform<strong>the</strong> representation of puzzles or decisionproblems. Obviously, no one is able <strong>to</strong> recognize"137 X 24" and "3,288" as "<strong>the</strong> same"number without going through some elaboratecomputations. Invariance cannot be achieved bya finite mind.The impossibility of invariance raises significantdoubts about <strong>the</strong> descriptive realism ofrational-choice models (Tversky and Kahneman,1986). Absent a system that reliably generatesappropriate canonical representations,intuitive decisions will be shaped by <strong>the</strong> fac<strong>to</strong>rsthat determine <strong>the</strong> accessibility of different featuresof <strong>the</strong> situation. Highly accessible featureswill influence decisions, while features of lowaccessibility will be largely ignored-and <strong>the</strong>correlation between accessibility and reflectivejudgments of relevance in a state of completeinformation is not necessarily high.A particularly unrealistic assumption of <strong>the</strong>rational-agent model is that agents make <strong>the</strong>irchoices in a comprehensively inclusive context,which incorporates all <strong>the</strong> relevant details of <strong>the</strong>present situation, as well as expectations aboutall future opportunities and risks. Much evidencesupports <strong>the</strong> contrasting claim that people'sviews of decisions and outcomes arenormally characterized by "narrow framing"(Kahneman and Daniel Lovallo, 1993), and by<strong>the</strong> related notions of "mental accounting"(Thaler, 1985, 1999) and "decision bracketing"(Daniel Read et al., 1999).The following are some examples of <strong>the</strong>prevalence of narrow framing. The decision ofwhe<strong>the</strong>r or not <strong>to</strong> accept a gamble is normallyconsidered as a response <strong>to</strong> a single opportunity,not as an occasion <strong>to</strong> apply a general policy(Gideon Keren and Willem A. Wagenaar, 1987;Tversky and Donald A. Redelmeier, 1992; Kahnemanand Lovallo, 1993; Shlomo Benartzi andThaler, 1999). Inves<strong>to</strong>rs' decisions about particularinvestments appear <strong>to</strong> be considered inisolation from <strong>the</strong> remainder of <strong>the</strong> inves<strong>to</strong>r'sportfolio (Nicholas Barberis et al., 2003). Thetime horizon that inves<strong>to</strong>rs adopt for evaluating<strong>the</strong>ir investments appears <strong>to</strong> be unreasonablyshort-an observation that helps explain <strong>the</strong>equity-premium puzzle (Benartzi and Thaler,1995). Finally, <strong>the</strong> prevalence of <strong>the</strong> gain~lossframing of outcomes over <strong>the</strong> wealth frame,which was discussed in <strong>the</strong> previous section,can now be seen as an instance of narrow


1460 THE AMERICAN ECONOMIC REVIEW DECEMBER 2003framing. A shared feature of all <strong>the</strong>se examplesis that decisions made in narrow frames departfar more from risk neutrality than decisions thatare made in a more inclusive context.The prevalence of narrow frames is an effec<strong>to</strong>f accessibility, which can be unders<strong>to</strong>od byreferring <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> displays of blocks in Figure2. The same set of blocks is framed as a <strong>to</strong>werin Figure 2a, and as a flat array in Figure 2b. Althoughit is possible <strong>to</strong> "see" a <strong>to</strong>wer in Figure2b, it is much easier <strong>to</strong> do so in Figure 2a. Narrowframes generally reflect <strong>the</strong> structure of <strong>the</strong>environment in which decisions are made. Thechoices that people face arise one at a time, and<strong>the</strong> principle of passive acceptance suggests that<strong>the</strong>y will be considered as <strong>the</strong>y arise. The problemat hand and <strong>the</strong> immediate consequences of<strong>the</strong> choice will be far more accessible than allo<strong>the</strong>r considerations, and as a result decisionproblems will be framed far more narrowly than<strong>the</strong> rational model assumes.V. Attribute Substitution: A Model of JudgmentHeuristicsThe first research program that Tversky and Iunder<strong>to</strong>ok <strong>to</strong><strong>get</strong>her consisted of a series of studiesof various types of judgment about uncertainevents, including numerical predictions and assessmentsof <strong>the</strong> probabilities of hypo<strong>the</strong>ses.Our conclusion in a review of this work was that"people rely on a limited number of heuristicprinciples which reduce <strong>the</strong> complex tasks ofassessing probabilities and predicting values <strong>to</strong>simpler judgmental operations. In general, <strong>the</strong>seheuristics are quite useful, but sometimes <strong>the</strong>ylead <strong>to</strong> severe and systematic errors" (Tverskyand Kahneman, 1974, p. 1124). The article introducedthree heuristics-representativeness,availability, and anchoring-that were used <strong>to</strong>explain a dozen systematic biases in judgmentunder uncertainty, including nonregressive prediction,neglect of base-rate information, overconfidence,and overestimates of <strong>the</strong> frequencyof events that are easy <strong>to</strong> recall. Some of <strong>the</strong>biases were identified by systematic errors inestimates of known quantities and statisticalfacts. O<strong>the</strong>r biases were defined by discrepanciesbetween <strong>the</strong> regularities of intuitivejudgments and <strong>the</strong> principles of probability<strong>the</strong>ory, Bayesian inference, and regressionanalysis.FIGURE 7. AN ILLUSION OF ATTRIBUTE SUBSTITUTIONSource: Pho<strong>to</strong> by Lenore Shoharn, 2003.Kahneman and Frederick (2002) recently revisited<strong>the</strong> early studies of judgment heuristics,and proposed a formulation in which <strong>the</strong> reductionof complex tasks <strong>to</strong> simpler operations isachieved by an operation of attribute substitution."Judgment is said <strong>to</strong> be mediated by aheuristic when <strong>the</strong> individual assesses a specifiedtar<strong>get</strong> attribute of a judgment object bysubstituting ano<strong>the</strong>r property of that object-<strong>the</strong>heuristic attribute-which comes more readily<strong>to</strong> mind" (p. 53). Unlike <strong>the</strong> early work, Kahnemanand Frederick's conception of heuristicsis not restricted <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> domain of judgmentunder uncertainty.For a perceptual example of attribute substitution,consider <strong>the</strong> question: "What are <strong>the</strong>sizes of <strong>the</strong> two horses in Figure 7, as <strong>the</strong>y aredrawn on <strong>the</strong> page?' The images are in factidentical in size, but <strong>the</strong> figure produces a compellingillusion. The tar<strong>get</strong> attribute that 0bse~ersintend <strong>to</strong> evaluate is objective twodimensionalsize, but <strong>the</strong>y are unable <strong>to</strong> do thisveridically. Their judgments map an impressionof three-dimensional size (<strong>the</strong> heuristic attribute)on<strong>to</strong> units of length that are appropriate<strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> tar<strong>get</strong> attribute, and scaled <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> sizeof <strong>the</strong> page. This illusion is caused by <strong>the</strong>differential accessibility of competing interpretationsof <strong>the</strong> image. An impression of three-


VOL. 93 NO. 5KAHNEMAN: MAPS OF BOUNDED RATIONAWTY1461dimensional size is <strong>the</strong> only impression of sizethat comes <strong>to</strong> mind for ndive observers-paintersand experienced pho<strong>to</strong>graphers are able <strong>to</strong>do better-and it produces an illusion in <strong>the</strong>perception of picture size.A study by Fritz Strack et al. (1988) illustrates<strong>the</strong> role of attribute substitution in a differentcontext. College students responded <strong>to</strong> asurvey which included <strong>the</strong> two following questionsin immediate succession: "How happy areyou with your life in general?" and "How manydates did you have last month?" The correlationbetween <strong>the</strong> two questions was 0.12 when <strong>the</strong>yappeared in <strong>the</strong> order shown. Among respondentswho received <strong>the</strong> same questions in reverseorder, <strong>the</strong> correlation was 0.66. Thepsychological interpretation of <strong>the</strong> high correlation'is inferential, but straightforward. The datingquestion undoubtedly evoked in manyrespondents an emotionally charged evaluationof <strong>the</strong>ir romantic life. This evaluation washighly accessible when <strong>the</strong> question abouthappiness was encountered next, and it wasmapped on<strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> scale of general happiness.In <strong>the</strong> interpretation offered <strong>here</strong>, <strong>the</strong> respondentsanswered <strong>the</strong> happiness question by reportingwhat came <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir mind, and failed <strong>to</strong>notice that <strong>the</strong>y were answering a questionthat had not been asked-a cognitive illusionthat is analogous <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> visual illusion ofFigure 7.The most direct evidence for attribute substitutionwas reported by Kahneman and Tversky(1973), in a task of categorical prediction. T<strong>here</strong>were three experimental groups in <strong>the</strong>ir experiment.Participants in a base-rate group evaluated<strong>the</strong> relative frequencies of graduatestudents in nine categories of ~pecialization.~Mean estimates ranged from 20 percent for Humanitiesand Education <strong>to</strong> 3 percent for LibraryScience.Two o<strong>the</strong>r groups of participants were shown<strong>the</strong> same list of areas of graduate specialization,and <strong>the</strong> following description of a fictitiousgraduate student.' The observed value of 0.66 underestimates <strong>the</strong> truecorrelation between <strong>the</strong> variables of interest, because ofmeasurement error in all variables.The categories were Business Administration; ComputerScience; Engineering; Humanities and Education;Law; Library Science; Medicine; Physical and Life Sciences;Social Sciences and Social Work.Tom W. is of high intelligence, althoughlacking in true creativity. He has a needfor order and clarity, and for neat andtidy systems in which every detail findsits appropriate place. His writing isra<strong>the</strong>r dull and mechanical, occasionallyenlivened by somewhat corny punsand by flashes of imagination of <strong>the</strong>sci-ji type. He has a strong drive forcompetence. He seems <strong>to</strong> have little feeland little sympathy for o<strong>the</strong>r people anddoes not enjoy interacting with o<strong>the</strong>rs.Self-centered, he none<strong>the</strong>less has a deepmoral sense.Participants in a similarity group ranked <strong>the</strong>nine fields by <strong>the</strong> degree <strong>to</strong> which Tom W."resembles a typical graduate student" (in thatfield). The description of Tom W, was deliberatelyconstructed <strong>to</strong> make him more representativeof <strong>the</strong> less populated fields, and thismanipulation was successful: <strong>the</strong> correlation between<strong>the</strong> averages of representativeness rank-ing~ and of estimated base rates was -0.62.Participants in <strong>the</strong> probabilily group ranked <strong>the</strong>nine fields according <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> likelihood that TomW. would have specialized in each. The respondentsin <strong>the</strong> latter group were graduate studentsin psychology at major universities. They were<strong>to</strong>ld that <strong>the</strong> personality sketch had been writtenby a psychologist when Tom W. was in highschool, on <strong>the</strong> basis of personality tests of dubiousvalidity. This information was intended <strong>to</strong>discredit <strong>the</strong> description as a source of validinformation.The statistical logic is straightforward. A descriptionbased on unreliable information mustbe given little weight, and predictions made in<strong>the</strong> absence of valid evidence must revert <strong>to</strong>base rates. This reasoning implies that judgmentsof probability should be highly correlatedwith <strong>the</strong> corresponding base rates in <strong>the</strong> TomW. problem.The psychology of <strong>the</strong> task is also straightforward.The similarity of Tom W. <strong>to</strong> variousstereotypes is a highly accessible natural assessment,w<strong>here</strong>as judgments of probability are difficult.The respondents are t<strong>here</strong>fore expected <strong>to</strong>substitute a judgment of similarity (representa-tiveness) for <strong>the</strong> required judgment of probability.The two instructions-<strong>to</strong> rate similarity or


THE AMERICAN ECONOMIC REVIEW DECEMBER 2003(4 (b)Tom W.Lindamean rank (similarity)mean rank (similarity)probability-should t<strong>here</strong>fore elicit similarjudgments.The scatterplot of <strong>the</strong> mean judgments of <strong>the</strong>two groups is presented in Figure 8a. As <strong>the</strong>figure shows, <strong>the</strong> correlation between judgmentsof probability and similarity is nearlyperfect (0.98). The correlation between judgmentsof probability and base rates is -0.63.The results are in perfect accord with <strong>the</strong> hypo<strong>the</strong>sisof attribute substitution. They also confirma bias of base-rate neglect in thisprediction task. The results are especially compellingbecause <strong>the</strong> responses were rankings.The large variability of <strong>the</strong> average rankings ofboth attributes indicates highly consensual responses,and nearly <strong>to</strong>tal overlap in <strong>the</strong> systematicvariance.Figure 8b shows <strong>the</strong> results of ano<strong>the</strong>r studyin <strong>the</strong> same design, in which respondents wereshown <strong>the</strong> description of a woman namedLinda, and a list of eight possible outcomesdescribing her present employment and activities.The two critical items in <strong>the</strong> list were #6("Linda is a bank teller") and <strong>the</strong> conjunctionitem #8 ("Linda is a bank teller and active in<strong>the</strong> feminist movement"). The o<strong>the</strong>r six possibilitieswere unrelated and miscellaneous(e.g., elementary school teacher, psychiatricsocial worker). As in <strong>the</strong> Tom W. problem,some respondents ranked <strong>the</strong> eight outcomesby <strong>the</strong> similarity of Linda <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> categorypro<strong>to</strong>types; o<strong>the</strong>rs ranked <strong>the</strong> same outcomesby probability.Linda is 31 years old, single, outspokenand very bright. She majored in philosophy.As a student she was deeply concernedwith issues of discrimination andsocial justice and also participated in antinucleardemonstrations.As might be expected, 85 percent of respondentsin <strong>the</strong> similarity group ranked <strong>the</strong> conjunctionitem (#8) higher than its constituent,indicating that Linda resembles <strong>the</strong> image of afeminist bank teller more than she resembles astereotypical bank teller. This ordering of <strong>the</strong>two items is quite reasonable for judgments ofsimilarity. However, it is much more problematicthat 89 percent of respondents in <strong>the</strong> probabilitygroup also ranked <strong>the</strong> conjunction higherthan its constituent. This pattern of probabilityjudgments violates mono<strong>to</strong>nicity, and has beencalled <strong>the</strong> "conjunction fallacy" (Tversky andKahneman, 1983).The observation that biases of judgment aresystematic was quickly recognized as relevant<strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> debate about <strong>the</strong> assumption of rationality


VOL. 93 NO. 5KAHNEMAN: MAPS OF BOUNDED RATIONALITY1463in economics (see, e.g., Peter A. Diamond,1977; David M. Gre<strong>the</strong>r, 1978; Howard Kunreu<strong>the</strong>r,1979; Arrow, 1982). T<strong>here</strong> has alsobeen some discussion of <strong>the</strong> role of specificjudgment biases in economic phenomena, especiallyin finance (e.g., Werner F. M. De Bondtand Thaler, 1985; Robert J. Shiller, 2000; AndreiShleifer, 2000; Mat<strong>the</strong>w Rabin, 2002). Recentextensions of <strong>the</strong> notion of heuristics <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong>domain of affect may be of particular relevance<strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> conversation between psychology andeconomics, because <strong>the</strong>y bear on <strong>the</strong> core concep<strong>to</strong>f a preference. As was noted earlier, affectivevalence is a natural assessment, which isau<strong>to</strong>matically computed and always accessible.This basic evaluative attribute (good/bad, like/dislike, approachfavoid) is t<strong>here</strong>fore a candidatefor substitution in any task that calls for a favorableor unfavorable response. Slovic and hiscolleagues (see, e.g., ~lovic et al., 2002) introduced<strong>the</strong> concept of an aSfect heuristic. Theyshowed that affect (liking or disliking) is <strong>the</strong>heuristic attribute for numerous tar<strong>get</strong> attributes,including <strong>the</strong> evaluation of <strong>the</strong> costsand benefits of various technologies, <strong>the</strong> safeconcentration of chemicals, and even <strong>the</strong> predictedeconomic performance of various industries.In an article aptly titled "Risk asFeelings," Loewenstein et al. (2001) documented<strong>the</strong> related proposition that beliefs aboutrisk are often expressions of emotion.If different tar<strong>get</strong> attributes are strongly influencedby <strong>the</strong> same affective reaction, <strong>the</strong>dimensionality of decisions and judgmentsabout valued objects may be expected <strong>to</strong> beunreasonably low. Indeed, Melissa L. Finucaneet al. (2000) found that people's judgments of<strong>the</strong> costs and benefits of various technologiesare negatively correlated, especially when <strong>the</strong>judgments are made under time pressure. Atechnology that is liked is judged <strong>to</strong> have lowcosts and large benefits. These judgments aresurely biased, because <strong>the</strong> correlation betweencosts and benefits is generally positive in <strong>the</strong>world of real choices. In <strong>the</strong> same vein, Kahnemanet al. (1997) presented evidence that differentresponses <strong>to</strong> public goods (e.g.,willingness <strong>to</strong> pay, ratings of moral satisfactionfor contributing) yielded essentially interchangeablerankings of a set of policy issues.Here again, a basic affective response appeared<strong>to</strong> be <strong>the</strong> common fac<strong>to</strong>r.Kahneman et al. (1997) suggested that peo-ple's decisions often express affective evaluations(attitudes), which do not conform <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong>logic of economic preferences. To understandpreferences, <strong>the</strong>n, we may need <strong>to</strong> understand<strong>the</strong> psychology of emotions. And we cannottake it for granted that preferences that are controlledby <strong>the</strong> emotion of <strong>the</strong> moment will beinternally co<strong>here</strong>nt, or even reasonable by <strong>the</strong>cooler criteria of reflective reasoning. In o<strong>the</strong>rwords, <strong>the</strong> preferences of System 1 are notnecessarily consistent with <strong>the</strong> preferences ofSystem 2. The next section will show that somechoices are not appropriately sensitive <strong>to</strong> variationsof quantity and cost-and are better describedas expressions of an affective responsethan as economic preferences.VI. Pro<strong>to</strong>type HeuristicsThe results summarized in Figure 8 showedthat <strong>the</strong> judgments that subjects made about <strong>the</strong>Tom W. and Linda problems substituted <strong>the</strong>more accessible attribute of similarity (representativeness)for <strong>the</strong> required tar<strong>get</strong> attribute ofprobability. The goal of <strong>the</strong> present section is <strong>to</strong>embed <strong>the</strong> representativeness heuristic in abroader class of pro<strong>to</strong>type heuristics, whichshare a common psychological mechanismt<strong>here</strong>presentation of categories by <strong>the</strong>ir pro<strong>to</strong>types-anda remarkably consistent pattern ofbiases.In <strong>the</strong> display of lines in Figure 3, <strong>the</strong> average(typical) length of <strong>the</strong> lines was highly accessible,but <strong>the</strong> sum of <strong>the</strong>ir lengths was not. Bothobservations are quite general. Classic psychologicalexperiments have established <strong>the</strong> followingproposition: whenever we look at orthink about a set (ensemble, category) which issufficiently homogeneous <strong>to</strong> have a pro<strong>to</strong>type,information about <strong>the</strong> pro<strong>to</strong>type is au<strong>to</strong>maticallyaccessible (Michael I. Posner and <strong>Stephen</strong>W. Keele, 1968; Eleanor Rosch and Carolyn B.Mewis, 1975). The pro<strong>to</strong>type of a set is characterizedby <strong>the</strong> average values of <strong>the</strong> salientproperties of its members. The high accessibilityof pro<strong>to</strong>type information serves an importantadaptive function. It allows new stimuli <strong>to</strong> becategorized efficiently, by comparing <strong>the</strong>ir features<strong>to</strong> those of category pro<strong>to</strong>types.3 ForS<strong>to</strong>red information about individual exemplars alsocontributes <strong>to</strong> categorization.


1464 THE AMERICAN ECONOMIC REVIEW DECEMBER 2003example, <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>red pro<strong>to</strong>type of a set of linesallows a quick decision about a new line-doesit belong with <strong>the</strong> set? T<strong>here</strong> is no equallyobvious function for <strong>the</strong> au<strong>to</strong>matic computationof sums.The low accessibility of sums and <strong>the</strong> highaccessibility of pro<strong>to</strong>types have significant consequencesin tasks that involve judgments ofsets, as in <strong>the</strong> following examples:(i) category prediction (e.g., <strong>the</strong> probabilitythat <strong>the</strong> category of bank tellers containsLinda as a member);(ii) pricing a quantity of public or privategoods (e.g., <strong>the</strong> personal dollar value ofsaving a certain number of migra<strong>to</strong>ry birdsfrom drowning in oil ponds);(iii) global evaluation of a past experience thatextended over time (e.g., <strong>the</strong> overall aversivenessof a painful medical procedure);(iv) assessment of <strong>the</strong> support that a sample ofobservations provides for a hypo<strong>the</strong>sis(e.g., <strong>the</strong> probability that a sample of coloredballs has been drawn from one specijiedurn ra<strong>the</strong>r than ano<strong>the</strong>r).The objects of judgment in <strong>the</strong>se tasks aresets or categories, and <strong>the</strong> tar<strong>get</strong> attributes havea common logical structure. Extensional attributesare governed by a general principle ofconditional adding, which dictates that each elementwithin <strong>the</strong> set adds <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> overall value anamount that depends on <strong>the</strong> elements alreadyincluded. In simple cases, <strong>the</strong> value is additive:<strong>the</strong> <strong>to</strong>tal length of <strong>the</strong> set of lines in Figure 3 isjust <strong>the</strong> sum of <strong>the</strong>ir separate lengths. In o<strong>the</strong>rcases, each positive element of <strong>the</strong> set increases<strong>the</strong> aggregate value, but <strong>the</strong> combination rule isnonadditive (typically ~ubadditive).~ The attributesof <strong>the</strong> category pro<strong>to</strong>type are not extensional-<strong>the</strong>yare averages, w<strong>here</strong>as extensionalattributes are alun <strong>to</strong> sums.The preceding argument leads <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> hypo<strong>the</strong>sisthat tasks that require <strong>the</strong> assessment ofIf <strong>the</strong> judgment is mono<strong>to</strong>nically related <strong>to</strong> an additivescale (such as <strong>the</strong> underlying count of <strong>the</strong> number of birds),<strong>the</strong> formal structure is known in <strong>the</strong> measurement literatureas an "extensive structure" (R. Duncan Luce et at., 1990,Ch. 3). T<strong>here</strong> also may be attributes that lack an underlyingadditive scale, in which case <strong>the</strong> structure is known in <strong>the</strong>literature as a "positive concatenation structure" (Luce etal., 1990, Ch. 19, volume 3, p. 38).extensional variables will be relatively difficult,and that intuitive responses may be generatedby substituting an attribute of <strong>the</strong> pro<strong>to</strong>type for<strong>the</strong> extensional tar<strong>get</strong> attribute. Pro<strong>to</strong>type heuristicsinvolve a tar<strong>get</strong> attribute that is extensional,and a heuristic attribute which is acharacteristic of <strong>the</strong> category pro<strong>to</strong>type. Pro<strong>to</strong>typeheuristics are associated with two majorbiases, which generalize <strong>the</strong> biases of representativenessthat were introduced in <strong>the</strong> precedingsection:(i) Violations of mono<strong>to</strong>nicity. Adding elements<strong>to</strong> a set may lower <strong>the</strong> average andcause <strong>the</strong> judgment of <strong>the</strong> tar<strong>get</strong> variable <strong>to</strong>decrease, contrary <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> logic of extensionalvariables. The prevalent judgmentthat Linda is less likely <strong>to</strong> be a bank tellerthan <strong>to</strong> be a feminist bank teller illustratesthis bias.(ii) Extension neglect. O<strong>the</strong>r things equal, anincrease in <strong>the</strong> extension of a category willincrease <strong>the</strong> value of its extensional attributes,but leave unchanged <strong>the</strong> values ofits pro<strong>to</strong>type attributes. The apparent neglec<strong>to</strong>f <strong>the</strong> base rates of areas of specializationin judgments about Tom W, is anexample.Studies that have examined <strong>the</strong> two biases indifferent contexts are described next.A. Pricing GoodsThe price of a set of goods is an extensionalvariable. If price is evaluated by <strong>the</strong> attractivenessof a pro<strong>to</strong>typical element of <strong>the</strong> set, violationsof mono<strong>to</strong>nicity and extension neglect arepredicted.Scope Neglect.-Complete or almost completeneglect of extension has often been observedin studies of <strong>the</strong> willingness <strong>to</strong> pay forpublic goods, w<strong>here</strong> <strong>the</strong> effect is called "neglec<strong>to</strong>f scope." The best known example is a studyby William H. Desvousges et al. (1993) inwhich respondents indicated <strong>the</strong>ir willingness <strong>to</strong>contribute money <strong>to</strong> prevent <strong>the</strong> drowning ofmigra<strong>to</strong>ry birds. The number of birds that wouldbe saved was varied for different subsamples.The estimated amounts that households werewilling <strong>to</strong> pay were $80, $78, and $88, <strong>to</strong> save2,000, 20,000, or 200,000 birds, respectively.


VOL. 93 NO. 5KAHNEMAN. MAPS OF BOUNDED RATIONAUTY1465The tar<strong>get</strong> attribute in this case is willingness <strong>to</strong>pay (WTP), and <strong>the</strong> heuristic attribute appears<strong>to</strong> be <strong>the</strong> emotion associated with <strong>the</strong> image ofa bird drowning in oil, or perhaps with <strong>the</strong>image of a bird being saved from drowning(Kahneman et al., 1999).Frederick and Baruch Fischhoff (1998) reviewednumerous demonstrations of such scopeneglect in studies of willingness <strong>to</strong> pay for publicgoods. For example, Kahneman and Knetschfound that survey respondents in Toron<strong>to</strong> werewilling <strong>to</strong> pay almost as much <strong>to</strong> clean up <strong>the</strong>lakes in a small region of Ontario or <strong>to</strong> clean upall <strong>the</strong> lakes in that province (reported by Kahneman,1986). The issue of scope neglect iscentral <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> application of <strong>the</strong> contingent valuationmethod (CVM) in <strong>the</strong> assessment of <strong>the</strong>economic value of public goods, and it has beenhotly debated (see, e.g., Richard T. Carson,1997). The proponents of CVM have reportedexperiments in which t<strong>here</strong> was some sensitivity<strong>to</strong> scope, but even <strong>the</strong>se effects are minute,far <strong>to</strong>o small <strong>to</strong> satisfy <strong>the</strong> economic logic ofpricing (Diamond, 1996; Kahneman et al.,1999).Violations of Mono<strong>to</strong>nicity.-List (2002) reportedan experiment that confirmed, in a realmarket setting, violations of dominance thatHsee (1998) had previously reported in a hypo<strong>the</strong>ticalpricing task. In List's experiment, tradersof sportscards assigned significantly highervalue <strong>to</strong> a set of ten sportscards labeled "Mint1near mint condition" than <strong>to</strong> a set that included<strong>the</strong> same ten cards and three additional cardsdescribed as "poor condition." In a series offollow-up experiments, Jonathan E. Alevy et al.(2003) also confirmed an important difference(originally suggested by Hsee) between <strong>the</strong>prices that people will pay when <strong>the</strong>y see onlyone of <strong>the</strong> goods (separate evaluation), or when<strong>the</strong>y price both goods at <strong>the</strong> same time (jointevaluation). The goods were similar <strong>to</strong> thoseused in List's experiment. The predicted violationof dominance was observed in separateevaluation, especially for relatively inexperiencedmarket participants. These individualsbid an average of $4.05 for <strong>the</strong> small set ofcards, and only $1.82 for <strong>the</strong> larger set. Theviolations of dominance were completelyeliminated in <strong>the</strong> joint evaluation condition,w<strong>here</strong> <strong>the</strong> bids for <strong>the</strong> small and large setsaveraged $2.89 and $3.32, respectively.Alevy et al. (2003) noted that System 1 appears<strong>to</strong> dominate responses in separate evaluation,w<strong>here</strong>as System 2 conforms <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong>dominance rule when given a chance <strong>to</strong> do so.T<strong>here</strong> was a definite effect of market experience,both in this study and in List (2002): <strong>the</strong>bids of highly experienced traders alsoshowed violations of mono<strong>to</strong>nicity in separateevaluation, but <strong>the</strong> effect was much smaller.B. Evaluations of Extended EpisodesThe global utility of an experience that extendsover time is an extensional attribute (Kahneman,1994,20OOa, b; Kahneman et al., 1997),and <strong>the</strong> duration of <strong>the</strong> experience is a measureof its extension. The corresponding pro<strong>to</strong>typeattribute is <strong>the</strong> experienced utility associatedwith a representative moment of <strong>the</strong> episode. Aspredicted by attribute substitution, global evaluationsof <strong>the</strong> episode exhibit both durationneglect and violations of mono<strong>to</strong>nicity.Duration Neglect.-In a study described byRedelmeier and Kahneman (1996), patients undergoingcolonoscopy reported <strong>the</strong> intensity ofpain every 60 seconds during <strong>the</strong> procedure (seeFigure 9), and subsequently provided a globalevaluation of <strong>the</strong> pain <strong>the</strong>y had suffered. Thecorrelation of global evaluations with <strong>the</strong> durationof <strong>the</strong> procedure (which ranged from 4 <strong>to</strong>66 minutes in that study) was 0.03. On <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rhand global evaluations were correlated (r =0.67) with an average of <strong>the</strong> pain reported attwo points of time: when pain was at its peak,and just before <strong>the</strong> procedure ended. For example,patient A in Figure 9 reported a more negativeevaluation of <strong>the</strong> procedure than patient B.The same pattern of duration neglect and PeaklEnd evaluations has been observed in o<strong>the</strong>rstudies (Barbara L. Fredrickson and Kahneman,1993; see Kahneman, 2000a, for a discussion).These results are consistent with <strong>the</strong> hypo<strong>the</strong>sisthat <strong>the</strong> extended episode (which can be consideredan ordered set of moments) is representedin memory by a typical moment of <strong>the</strong>experience.Violations of Dominance.-A randomizedclinical experiment was conducted following<strong>the</strong> colonoscopy study described above. For half<strong>the</strong> patients, <strong>the</strong> instrument was not immediatelyremoved when <strong>the</strong> clinical examination


1466 THE AMERICAN ECONOMIC REVIEW DECEMBER 2003Patlent APatient B0 10 20 0Tlrne (minutes)10 20Tlrne (rnlnuter)FIGURE 9. PAIN INTENSITY REPORTED BY TWO COLONOSCOPY PATIENTSended. Instead, <strong>the</strong> physician waited for about aminute, leaving <strong>the</strong> instrument stationary. Theexperience during <strong>the</strong> extra period was uncomfortable,but <strong>the</strong> procedure guaranteed that <strong>the</strong>colonoscopy never ended in severe pain. Patientsreported significantly more favorableglobal evaluations in this experimental conditionthan in <strong>the</strong> control condition (Redelmeier etal., 2003).Violations of dominance have also beenconfirmed in choices. Kahneman et al. (1993)exposed participants <strong>to</strong> two cold-pressor experiences,one with each hand: a "short" episode(immersion of one hand in 14°C waterfor 60 seconds), and a "long" episode (<strong>the</strong>short episode, plus an additional 30 secondsduring which <strong>the</strong> water was gradually warmed<strong>to</strong> 15°C). When <strong>the</strong>y were later asked whichof <strong>the</strong> two experiences <strong>the</strong>y preferred <strong>to</strong> repeat,a substantial majority chose <strong>the</strong> longtrial. This pattern of choices is predicted from<strong>the</strong> PeaklEnd rule of evaluation that was describedearlier. Similar violations of dominancewere observed with unpleasant soundsof variable loudness and duration (Charles A.Schreiber and Kahneman, 2000). These violationsof dominance suggest that choices betweenfamiliar experiences are made in anintuitive process of "choosing by liking." Extendedepisodes are represented in memory bya typical moment-and <strong>the</strong> desirability oraversiveness of <strong>the</strong> episode is dominated by<strong>the</strong> remembered utility of that moment (Kah-neman, 1994). When a choice is <strong>to</strong> be made,<strong>the</strong> option that is associated with <strong>the</strong> higherremembered utility (more liked) is chosen.This mode of choice is likely <strong>to</strong> yield choicesthat do not maximize <strong>the</strong> utility that willactually be experienced (Kahneman et al.,1997).C. O<strong>the</strong>r Pro<strong>to</strong>type HeuristicsThe pattern of results observed in diversestudies of pro<strong>to</strong>type heuristics suggests <strong>the</strong> needfor a unified interpretation, and raises a significantchallenge <strong>to</strong> treatments that deal only withone domain. A number of authors have offeredcompeting interpretations of base-rate neglect(Leda Cosmides and John Tooby, 1996;Jonathan Jay Koehler, 1996), insensitivity <strong>to</strong>scope in WTP (Raymond Kopp, 1992), andduration neglect (Ariely and Loewenstein,2000). In general however, <strong>the</strong>se interpretationsare specific <strong>to</strong> a particular task, and would notcarry over <strong>to</strong> demonstrations of extension neglectin <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r tasks that have been discussed.In contrast, <strong>the</strong> account offered <strong>here</strong>(and developed in greater detail by Kahnemanand Frederick, 2002) is equally applicable <strong>to</strong>diverse tasks that require an assessment of anextensional tar<strong>get</strong> attribute.The cases that have been discussed are onlyillustrations, not a comprehensive list of pro<strong>to</strong>typeheuristics. For example, <strong>the</strong> same form ofnonextensional thinking explains why <strong>the</strong> me-


VOL. 93 NO. 5KAHNEMAN: MAPS OF BOUNDED RATIONALITY1467dian estimate of <strong>the</strong> annual number of murdersin Detroit is twice as high as <strong>the</strong> estimate of <strong>the</strong>number of murders in Michigan (Kahnemanand Frederick, 2002). It also explains whyprofessional forecasters assigned a higherprobability <strong>to</strong> "an earthquake in Californiacausing a flood in which more than 1,000people will drown" than <strong>to</strong> "a flood somew<strong>here</strong>in <strong>the</strong> United States in which more than1,000 people will drown" (Tversky and Kahneman,1983).As <strong>the</strong>se examples illustrate, t<strong>here</strong> is no guaranteeddefense against violations of mono<strong>to</strong>nicity.How could a forecaster who assigns aprobability <strong>to</strong> a lethal flood ensure (in finitetime) that t<strong>here</strong> is no subset of that event whichwould have appeared even more probable?More generally, <strong>the</strong> results reviewed in thissection suggest a profound incompatibility between<strong>the</strong> capabilities and operational rules ofintuitive judgment and choice and <strong>the</strong> normativestandards for beliefs and preferences. Thelogic of belief and choice requires accurateevaluation of extensional variables. In contrast,intuitive thinking operates with exemplars orpro<strong>to</strong>types that have <strong>the</strong> dimensionality of individualinstances and lack <strong>the</strong> dimension ofextension.VII. The Boundaries of Intuitive ThinkingThe judgments that people express, <strong>the</strong> actions<strong>the</strong>y take, and <strong>the</strong> mistakes <strong>the</strong>y commitdepend on <strong>the</strong> moni<strong>to</strong>ring and corrective functionsof System 2, as well as on <strong>the</strong> impressionsand tendencies generated by system 1. Thissection reviews a selection of findings and ideasabout <strong>the</strong> functioning of System 2. A moredetailed treatment is given in Kahneman andFrederick (2002) and Kahneman (2003b).Judgments and choices are normally intuitive,skilled, unproblematic, and reasonablysuccessful (Klein, 1998). The prevalence offraming effects, and o<strong>the</strong>r indications of superficialprocessing such as <strong>the</strong> bat-and-ball problem,suggest that people mostly do not thinkvery hard and that System 2 moni<strong>to</strong>rs judgmentsquite lightly. On some occasions, however,<strong>the</strong> moni<strong>to</strong>ring of System 2 will detect apotential error, and an effort will be made <strong>to</strong>correct it. The question for this section can beformulated in terms of accessibility: when dodoubts about one's intuitive judgments come <strong>to</strong>mind? The answer, as usual in psychology, is alist of relevant fac<strong>to</strong>rs.Research has established that <strong>the</strong> ability <strong>to</strong>avoid errors of intuitive judgment is impairedby time pressure (Finucane et al., 2000), byconcurrent involvement in a different cognitivetask (Gilbert, 1989, 1991, 2002), by performing<strong>the</strong> task in <strong>the</strong> evening for "morning people"and in <strong>the</strong> morning for "evening people" (GalenV. Bodenhausen, 1990), and, surprisingly, bybeing in a good mood (Alice M. Isen et al.,1988; Herbert Bless et al., 1996). Conversely,<strong>the</strong> facility of System 2 is positively correlatedwith intelligence (Stanovich and West, 2002),with <strong>the</strong> trait that psychologists have labeled"need for cognition" (which is roughly whe<strong>the</strong>rpeople find thinking fun) (Eldar Shafir andRobyn A. LeBoeuf, 2002), and with exposure <strong>to</strong>statistical thinking (Richard E. Nisbett et al.,1983; Franca Agnoli and David H. Krantz,1989; Agnoli, 1991).The question of <strong>the</strong> precise conditions underwhich errors of intuition are most likely <strong>to</strong> beprevented is of methodological interest <strong>to</strong> psychologists,because some controversies in <strong>the</strong>literature on cognitive illusions are resolvedwhen this fac<strong>to</strong>r is considered (see Kahnemanand Frederick, 2002; Kahneman, 2003b). Oneof <strong>the</strong>se methodological issues is also of considerablesubstantive interest: this is <strong>the</strong> distinctionbetween separate evaluation and jointevaluation (Hsee, 1996).In <strong>the</strong> separate evaluation condition of List'sstudy of dominance violations, for example,different groups of traders bid on two sets ofbaseball cards; in joint evaluation each traderevaluated both sets at <strong>the</strong> same time. The resultswere drastically different. Violations of mono<strong>to</strong>nicity,which were very pronounced in <strong>the</strong>between-groups comparison, were eliminated in<strong>the</strong> joint evaluation condition. The participantsin <strong>the</strong> latter condition evidently realized that oneof <strong>the</strong> sets of goods included <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r, and wast<strong>here</strong>fore worth more. Once <strong>the</strong>y had detected<strong>the</strong> dominance relation, <strong>the</strong> participants constrained<strong>the</strong>ir bids <strong>to</strong> follow <strong>the</strong> rule. Thesedecisions are mediated by System 2. Thus, t<strong>here</strong>appear <strong>to</strong> be two distinct modes of choice:"choosing by liking" selects <strong>the</strong> most attractiveoption; "choosing by rule" conforms <strong>to</strong> an explicitconstraint.Prospect <strong>the</strong>ory introduced <strong>the</strong> same distinctionbetween modes of choice (Kahneman and


1468 THE AMERICAN ECONOMIC REVIEW DECEMBER 2003Tversky, 1979). The normal process corresponds<strong>to</strong> choice by liking: <strong>the</strong> decision makerevaluates each gamble in <strong>the</strong> choice set, <strong>the</strong>nselects <strong>the</strong> gamble of highest value. In prospect<strong>the</strong>ory, this mode of choice can lead <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong>selection of a dominated option5 However, <strong>the</strong><strong>the</strong>ory also introduced <strong>the</strong> possibility of choiceby rule: if one option transparently dominates<strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r, <strong>the</strong> decision maker will select <strong>the</strong>dominant option without fur<strong>the</strong>r evaluation. Totest this model, Tversky and Kahneman (1986)constructed a pair of gambles that satisfied threecriteria: (i) !gamble A dominated gamble B; (ii)<strong>the</strong> prospect-<strong>the</strong>ory value of B was higher than<strong>the</strong> value of A; (iii) <strong>the</strong> gambles were complex,and <strong>the</strong> dominance relation only became apparentafter grouping outcomes. As expected fromo<strong>the</strong>r framing results, most participants in <strong>the</strong>experiment evaluated <strong>the</strong> gambles as originallyformulated, failed <strong>to</strong> detect <strong>the</strong> relation between<strong>the</strong>m, chose <strong>the</strong> option <strong>the</strong>y liked most, andexhibited <strong>the</strong> predicted violation of dominance.The cold-pressor experiment that was describedearlier (Kahneman et al., 1993) isclosely analogous <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> study of nontransparentdominance that Tversky and Kahneman (1986)reported. A substantial majority of participantsviolated dominance in a direct and seeminglytransparent choice between cold-pressor experiences.However, postexperimental debriefingsindicated that <strong>the</strong> dominance was not in facttransparent. The participants in <strong>the</strong> experimentdid not realize that <strong>the</strong> long episode included <strong>the</strong>short one, although <strong>the</strong>y did notice that <strong>the</strong>episodes differed- in duration. Because <strong>the</strong>yfailed <strong>to</strong> detect that one option dominated <strong>the</strong>o<strong>the</strong>r, <strong>the</strong> majority of participants chose as peoplecommonly do when <strong>the</strong>y select an experience<strong>to</strong> be repeated: <strong>the</strong>y "chose by liking,"selected <strong>the</strong> option that had <strong>the</strong> higher rememberedutility, and t<strong>here</strong>by agreed <strong>to</strong> expose<strong>the</strong>mselves <strong>to</strong> a period of unnecessary pain(Kahneman, 1994; Kahneman et al., 1997).The complex pattern of results in <strong>the</strong> studiesof dominance in <strong>the</strong> joint-evaluation designsuggests three general conclusions: (i) choicesthat are governed by rational rules do exist, but(ii) <strong>the</strong>se choices are restricted <strong>to</strong> unusual circumstances,and (iii) <strong>the</strong> activation of <strong>the</strong> rulesCumulative prospect <strong>the</strong>ory (Tversky and Kahneman,1992) does not have this feature.depends on <strong>the</strong> fac<strong>to</strong>rs of attention and accessibility.The fact that System 2 "knows" <strong>the</strong> dominancerule and "wants" <strong>to</strong> obey it onlyguarantees that <strong>the</strong> rule will be followed if apotential violation is explicitly detected.System 2 has <strong>the</strong> capability of correctingo<strong>the</strong>r errors, besides violations of dominance. Inparticular, <strong>the</strong> substitution of one attribute forano<strong>the</strong>r in judgment inevitably leads <strong>to</strong> errorsin <strong>the</strong> weights assigned <strong>to</strong> different sourcesof information, and <strong>the</strong>se could-at least inprinciple-be detected and corrected. For example,a participant in <strong>the</strong> Tom W. study (seeFigure 8a) could have reasoned as follows:"Tom W. looks very much like a library sciencestudent, but t<strong>here</strong> are very few of those. I shouldt<strong>here</strong>fore adjust my impression of probabilitydownward." Although this level of reasoningshould not have been beyond <strong>the</strong> reach of <strong>the</strong>graduate students who answered <strong>the</strong> Tom W.question, <strong>the</strong> evidence shown in Figure 8 showsthat few, if any, of <strong>the</strong>se respondents had <strong>the</strong>idea of adjusting <strong>the</strong>ir predictions <strong>to</strong> allow for<strong>the</strong> different base rates of <strong>the</strong> alternative outcomes.The explanation of this result in terms ofaccessibility is straightforward: <strong>the</strong> experimentprovided no explicit cues <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> relevance ofbase rates.Base-rate information was not completely ignoredin experiments that provided strongercues, though <strong>the</strong> effects of this variable wereconsistently <strong>to</strong>o small relative <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> effect of<strong>the</strong> case-specific information (Jonathan St. B. T.Evans et al., 2002). The evidence of numerousstudies supports <strong>the</strong> following conclusions: (i)<strong>the</strong> likelihood that <strong>the</strong> subject will detect a misweightingof some aspect of <strong>the</strong> informationdepends on <strong>the</strong> salience of cues <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> relevanceof that fac<strong>to</strong>r; (ii) if <strong>the</strong> misweighting is detected,t<strong>here</strong> will be an effort <strong>to</strong> correct it; (iii)<strong>the</strong> correction is likely <strong>to</strong> be insufficient, and <strong>the</strong>final judgments are t<strong>here</strong>fore likely <strong>to</strong> remainanchored on <strong>the</strong> initial intuitive impression(Gretchen B. Chapman and Johnson, 2002).Economists may be struck by <strong>the</strong> emphasison salient cues and by <strong>the</strong> absence of financialincentives from <strong>the</strong> list of major fac<strong>to</strong>rs thatinfluence <strong>the</strong> quality of decisions and judgments.However, <strong>the</strong> claim that high stakeseliminate departures from rationality is not supportedby a careful review of <strong>the</strong> experimentalevidence (Camerer and Robin M. Hogarth,1999). A growing literature of field research and


VOL. 93 NO. 5KAHNEMAN: MAPS OF BOUNDED RATIONALITY1469field experiments documents large and systematicmistakes in some of <strong>the</strong> most consequentialfinancial decisions that people make, includingchoices of investments (Brad M. Barber andTerrance Odean, 2000; Benartzi and Thaler,2001), and actions in <strong>the</strong> real estate market(David Genesove and Chris<strong>to</strong>pher J. Mayer,2001). The daily paper provides fur<strong>the</strong>r evidenceof poor decisions with large outcomes.The present analysis helps explain why <strong>the</strong>effects of incentives are nei<strong>the</strong>r large nor robust.High stakes surely increase <strong>the</strong> amount of attentionand effort that people invest in <strong>the</strong>irdecisions. But attention and effort by <strong>the</strong>mselvesdo not purchase rationality or guaranteegood decisions. In particular, cognitive effortexpended in bolstering a decision already madewill not improve its quality, and <strong>the</strong> evidencesuggests that <strong>the</strong> share of time and effort devoted<strong>to</strong> such bolstering may increase when <strong>the</strong>stakes are high (Jennifer S. Lerner and Philip E.Tetlock, 1999). Effort and concentration arelikely <strong>to</strong> bring <strong>to</strong> mind a more complete set ofconsiderations, but <strong>the</strong> expansion may yield aninferior decision unless <strong>the</strong> weighting of <strong>the</strong>secondary considerations is appropriately low.In some instances-including tasks that requirepredictions of one's future tastes-<strong>to</strong>o muchcognitive effort actually lowers <strong>the</strong> quality ofperformance (Wilson and Jonathan W.Schooler, 1991). Klein (2003, Ch. 4) has arguedthat t<strong>here</strong> are o<strong>the</strong>r situations in which skilleddecision makers do better when <strong>the</strong>y trust <strong>the</strong>irintuitions than when <strong>the</strong>y engage in detailedanalysis.VIII. Concluding RemarksThe rational agent of economic <strong>the</strong>ory wouldbe described, in <strong>the</strong> language of <strong>the</strong> presenttreatment, as endowed with a single cognitivesystem that has <strong>the</strong> logical ability of a flawlessSystem 2 and <strong>the</strong> low computing costs of System1. Theories in behavioral economics havegenerally retained <strong>the</strong> basic architecture of <strong>the</strong>rational model, adding assumptions about cognitivelimitations designed <strong>to</strong> account for specificanomalies. For example, <strong>the</strong> agent may berational except for discounting hyperbolically,evaluating outcomes as changes, or a tendency<strong>to</strong> jump <strong>to</strong> conclusions.The model of <strong>the</strong> agent that has been presented<strong>here</strong> has a different architecture, whichmay be more difficult <strong>to</strong> translate in<strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>oreticallanguage of economics. The core ideasof <strong>the</strong> present treatment are <strong>the</strong> two-systemstructure, <strong>the</strong> large role of System 1 and <strong>the</strong>extreme context-dependence that is implied by<strong>the</strong> concept of accessibility. The central characteristicof agents is not that <strong>the</strong>y reason poorlybut that <strong>the</strong>y often act intuitively. And <strong>the</strong> behaviorof <strong>the</strong>se agents is not guided by what<strong>the</strong>y are able <strong>to</strong> compute, but by what <strong>the</strong>yhappen <strong>to</strong> see at a given moment.These propositions suggest heuristic questionsthat may guide attempts <strong>to</strong> predict or explainbehavior in a given setting: "What wouldan impulsive agent be tempted <strong>to</strong> do?"'Whatcourse of action seems most natural in thissituation?" The answers <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong>se questions willoften identify <strong>the</strong> judgment or course of action<strong>to</strong> which most people will be attracted. Forexample, it is more natural <strong>to</strong> join a group ofstrangers running in a particular direction than<strong>to</strong> adopt a contrarian destination. However, <strong>the</strong>two-system view also suggests that o<strong>the</strong>r questionsshould be raised: "Is <strong>the</strong> intuitively attractivejudgment or course of action in conflictwith a rule that <strong>the</strong> agent would endorse?" If <strong>the</strong>answer <strong>to</strong> that question is positive, <strong>the</strong>n "Howlikely is it in <strong>the</strong> situation at hand that t<strong>here</strong>levant rule will come <strong>to</strong> mind in time <strong>to</strong> overrideintuition?" Of course, this mode of analysisalso allows for differences between individuals,and between groups. What is natural and intuitivein a given situation is not <strong>the</strong> same foreveryone: different cultural experiences favordifferent intuitions about <strong>the</strong> meaning of situations,and new behaviors become intuitive asskills are acquired. Even when <strong>the</strong>se complexitiesare taken in<strong>to</strong> account, <strong>the</strong> approach <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong>understanding and prediction of behavior thathas been sketched <strong>here</strong> is simple and easy <strong>to</strong>apply, and likely <strong>to</strong> yield hypo<strong>the</strong>ses that aregenerally plausible and often surprising. Theorigins of this approach are in an importantintellectual tradition in psychology, which hasemphasized "<strong>the</strong> power of <strong>the</strong> situation" (LeeRoss and Nisbett, 1991).The present treatment has developed several<strong>the</strong>mes: that intuition and reasoning are alternativeways <strong>to</strong> solve problems, that intuition resemblesperception, that people sometimesanswer a difficult question by answering aneasier one instead, that <strong>the</strong> processing of informationis often superficial, that categories are


1470 THE AMERICAN ECONOMIC REVIEW DECEMBER 2003represented by pro<strong>to</strong>types. All <strong>the</strong>se features of<strong>the</strong> cognitive system were in our minds in someform when Amos Tversky and I began our jointwork in 1969, and most of <strong>the</strong>m were in HerbertSimon's mind much earlier. However, <strong>the</strong> roleof emotion in judgment and decision makingreceived less attention in that work than it hadreceived before <strong>the</strong> beginning of <strong>the</strong> cognitiverevolution in psychology in <strong>the</strong> 1950's. Morerecent developments have res<strong>to</strong>red a central role<strong>to</strong> emotion, which is incorporated in <strong>the</strong> view ofintuition that was presented <strong>here</strong>. Findingsabout <strong>the</strong> role of optimism in risk taking, <strong>the</strong>effects of emotion on decision weights, <strong>the</strong> roleof fear in predictions of harm, and <strong>the</strong> role ofliking and disliking in factual predictions-allindicate that <strong>the</strong> traditional separation betweenbelief and preference in analyses of decisionmaking is psychologically unrealistic.Incorporating a common sense psychology of<strong>the</strong> intuitive agent in<strong>to</strong> economic models willpresent difficult challenges, especially for formal<strong>the</strong>orists. It is encouraging <strong>to</strong> note, however,that <strong>the</strong> challenge of incorporating <strong>the</strong> firstwave of psychological findings in<strong>to</strong> economicsappeared even more daunting 20 years ago, andthat challenge has been met with considerablesuccess.REFERENCESAgnoli, Franca. "Development of JudgmentalHeuristics and Logical Reasoning: TrainingCounteracts <strong>the</strong> Representativeness Heuristic."Cognitive Development, April-June1991, 6(2), pp. 195-217.Agnoli, Franca and Krantz, David H. "SuppressingNatural Heuristics by Formal Instruction:The Case of <strong>the</strong> Conjunction Fallacy." CognitivePsychology, Oc<strong>to</strong>ber 1989, 21(4), pp.515-50.Alevy, Jonathan E.; List, John A. and Adamowicz,Wik<strong>to</strong>r. "More is Less: Preference Reversalsand Non-Market valuations." Workingpaper, University of Maryland, 2003.Ariely, Dan. "Seeing Sets: Representation byStatistical Properties." Psychological Science,March 2001, 12(2), pp. 157-62.Ariely, Dan and Loewenstein, George. "WhenDoes Duration Matter in Judgment and DecisionMaking?" Journal of ExperimentalPsychology: General, December 2000,129(4), pp. 508-23.Arrow, Kenneth J. "Risk Perception in Psychologyand Economics." Economic Inquiry, January1982, 20(1), pp. 1-9.Barber, Brad M. and Odean, Terrance. "Tradingis Hazardous <strong>to</strong> Your Wealth: The CommonS<strong>to</strong>ck Investment Performance of IndividualInves<strong>to</strong>rs." Journal of Finance, April 2000,55(2), pp. 773-806.Barberis, Nicholas; Huang, Ming and Thaler,Richard H. "Individual Preferences, MonetaryGambles and <strong>the</strong> Equity Premium." NationalBureau of Economic Research(Cambridge, MA) Working Paper No.W9997, May 2003.Bargh, John A. "The Au<strong>to</strong>maticity of EverydayLife," in Robert S. Wyer, Jr., ed., The au<strong>to</strong>maticityof everyday life: Advances in socialcognition, Vol. 10. Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum,1997, pp. 1-61.Benartzi, Shlomo and Thaler, Richard H. "MyopicLoss Aversion and <strong>the</strong> Equity PremiumPuzzle." Quarterly Journal of Economics,February 1995, 110(1), pp. 73-92.."Risk Aversion or Myopia? Choices inRepeated Gambles and Retirement Investments."Management Science, March 1999,47(3), pp. 364-81.. "NaYve Diversification Strategies inDefined Contribution Saving Plans." ArnericanEconomic Review, March 2001, 91(1),pp. 79-98.Bernoulli, Daniel. "Exposition of a New Theoryon <strong>the</strong> Measurement of Risk." Econometrica,January 1954, 22(1), pp. 23-36. (Originalwork published 1738.)Bless, Herbert; Clore, Gerald L.; Schwarz, Norbert;Golisano, Verana; Rabe, Christian andWolk, Marcus. "Mood and <strong>the</strong> Use of Scripts:Does a Happy Mood Really Lead <strong>to</strong> Mindlessness?'Journalof Personality and SocialPsychology, Oc<strong>to</strong>ber 1996, 71(4), pp. 665-79.Bodenhausen, Galen V. "Stereotypes as JudgmentalHeuristics: Evidence of CircadianVariations in Discrimination." PsychologicalScience, September 1990, 1(5), pp. 3 19-22.Bruner, Jerome S. and Minturn, A. Leigh. "PerceptualIdentification and Perceptual Organization."Journal of General Psychology, July1955, 53, pp. 21-28.Camerer, Colin F. and Hogarth, Robin M. "TheEffect of Financial Incentives." Journal ofRisk and Uncertainty, December 1999,19(1-3), pp. 7-42.


VOL. 93 NO. 5KAHNEMAN: MAPS OF BOUNDED RATIONALITY1471Camerer, Colin F.; Loewenstein, George andRabin, Mat<strong>the</strong>w, eds. Advances in behavioraleconomics. Prince<strong>to</strong>n, NJ: Prince<strong>to</strong>n UniversityPress (forthcoming).Carson, Richard T. "Contingent Valuation Surveysand Tests of Insensitivity <strong>to</strong> Scope," inR. J. Kopp, W. W. Pommerhene, and N.Schwartz, eds., Determining <strong>the</strong> value of nonmarketedgoods: Economic, psychological,and policy relevant aspects of contingent valuationmethods. Bos<strong>to</strong>n, MA: Kluwer, 1997,pp. 127-63.Chaiken, Shelly and Trope, Yaacov, eds. Dualprocess<strong>the</strong>ories in social psychology. NewYork: Guilford Press, 1999.Chapman, Gretchen B. and Johnson, Eric J. "Incorporating<strong>the</strong> Irrelevant: Anchors in Judgmentsof Belief and Value," in ThomasGilovich, Dale Griffin, and Daniel Kahneman,eds., Heuristics and biases: The psychologyof intuitive thought. New York:Cambridge University Press, 2002, pp. 120-38.Choi, James J.; Laibson, David; Madrian, Brigitteand Metrick, Andrew. "Defined ContributionPensions: Plan Rules, Participant Decisionsand <strong>the</strong> Path of Least Resistance," in JamesM. Poterba, ed., Tax policy and <strong>the</strong> economy,Vol. 16. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2002,pp. 67-113.Chong, Sang-Chul and Treisman, Anne. "Representationof Statistical Properties." Vision Research,February 2003, 43(4), pp. 393-404.Cohen, David and Knetsch, Jack L. "JudicialChoice &d Disparities Between Measures ofEconomic Value." Osgoode Hall Law Review,1992, 30(3), pp. 737-70.Cosmides, Leda and Tooby, John. "Are HumansGood Intuitive Statisticians After All? RethinkingSome Conclusions From <strong>the</strong> Literatureon Judgment and Uncertainty."Cognition, January 1996, 58(1), pp. 1-73.De Bondt, Werner F. M. and Thaler, Richard H."Does <strong>the</strong> S<strong>to</strong>ck Market Overreact?'Journalof Finance, July 1985, 40(3), pp. 793-808.Desvousges, William H.; Johnson, F. Reed; Dunford,Richard W.; Hudson, Sara P.; Wilson, K.Nichole and Boyle, Kevin J. "Measuring NaturalResource Damages with Contingent Valuation:Tests of Validity and Reliability," inJeny A. Hausman, ed., Contingent valuation:A critical assessment. Amsterdam: North-Holland, 1993, pp. 91-164.Diamond, Peter A. "A Framework for SocialSecurity Analysis." Journal of Public Economics,December 1977, 8(3), pp. 275-98.. "Testing <strong>the</strong> Internal Consistency ofContingent Valuation Surveys." Journal ofEnvironmental Economics and Management,May 1996, 30(3), pp. 155-73.Elster, Jon. "Emotions and Economic Theory."Journal of Economic Literature, March 1998,26(1), pp. 47-74.Epstein, Seymour. "Cognitive-Experiential Self-Theory of Personality," in Theodore Millonand Melvin J. Lerner, eds., Comprehensivehandbook of psychology, volume 5: Personalityand social psychology. Hoboken, NJ:Wiley & Sons, 2003, pp. 159-84.Evans, Jonathan St. B. T.; Handley, Simon J.;Over, David E. and Perham, Nicholas. "BackgroundBeliefs in Bayesian Inference." Memoryand Cognition, March 2002, 30(2), pp.179 -90.Finucane, Melissa L.; Alhakami, Ali; Slovic, Pauland Johnson, <strong>Stephen</strong> M. "The Affect Heuristicin Judgments of Risks and Benefits."Journal of Behavioral Decision Making, JanuaryMarch2000, 13(1), pp. 1-17.Fiske, Susan T. "Stereotyping, Prejudice, andDiscrimination," in Daniel T. Gilbert, SusanT. Fiske, and Gardner Lindzey, eds., Thehandbook of social psychology, 4th Ed., Vol.1. New York: McGraw-Hill, 1998, pp. 357-41 1.Frederick, Shane W. and Fischhoff, Baruch."Scope (1n)sensitivity in Elicited Valuations."Risk, Decision, and Policy, August1998, 3(2), pp. 109-23.Fredrickson, Barbara L. and Kahneman, Daniel."Duration Neglect in Retrospective Evaluationsof Affective Episodes." Journal of Personalityand Social Psychology, July 1993,65(1), pp. 45-55.Gawande, AN. Complications: A surgeon'snotes on an imperfect science. New York:Metropolitan Books, 2002.Genesove, David and Mayer, Chris<strong>to</strong>pher J."Loss Aversion and Seller Behavior: Evidencefrom <strong>the</strong> Housing Market." QuarterlyJournal of Economics, November 2001,II6(4), pp. 1233-60.Gigerenzer, Gerd; Swijtink, Zeno; Porter, Theodore;Das<strong>to</strong>n, Lorraine; Beatty, John andKmger, Lorenz. The empire of chance: Howprobability changed science and everyday


1472 THE AMERICAN ECONOMIC REVIEW DECEMBER 2003life. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,1989.Gilbert, Daniel T. "Thinlung Lightly About O<strong>the</strong>rs:Au<strong>to</strong>matic Components of <strong>the</strong> Social InferenceProcess," in James S. Uleman andJohn A. Bargh, eds., Unintended thought.Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall, 1989,pp. 189-211.. "How Mental Systems Believe."American Psychologist, February 199 1,46(2),pp. 107-19.. "Inferential Correction," in ThomasGilovich, Dale Griffin, and Daniel Kahneman,eds., Heuristics and biases: The psychologyof intuitive thought. New York:Cambridge University Press, 2002, pp. 167-84.Gre<strong>the</strong>r, David M. "Recent Psychological Studiesof Behavior Under Uncertainty." AmericanEconomic Review, May 1978 (Papersand Proceedings), 68(2), pp. 70-74.Higgins, E. Tory. "Knowledge Activation: Accessibility,Applicability, and Salience," in E.Tory Higgins and Arie W. Kruglanski, eds.,Social psychology: Handbook of basic principles.New York: Guilford Press, 1996, pp.133-68.Hsee, Chris<strong>to</strong>pher K. "The Evaluability Hypo<strong>the</strong>sis:An Explanation of Preference ReversalsBetween Joint and Separate Evaluations ofAlternatives." Organizational Behavior andHuman Decision Processes, September 1996,67(3),pp. 247-57.."Less is Better: When Low-Value Op-tions are Valued More Highly Than High-Value Options." Journal of BehavioralDecision Making, June 1998, 11(2), pp. 107-21.Isen, Alice M.; Nygren, Thomas E. and Ashby, F.Gregory. "Influence of Positive Affect on <strong>the</strong>Subjective Utility of Gains and Losses: It isJust Not Worth <strong>the</strong> Risk." Journal of Personalityand Social Psychology, November1988, 55(5), pp. 710-17.Johnson, Eric J. and Goldstein, Daniel G. "DoDefaults Save Lives?'Working paper, Centerfor Decision Sciences, Columbia University,2003.Johnson, Eric J.; Hershey, John; Meszaros, Jacquelineand Kunreu<strong>the</strong>r, Howard. "Framing,Probability Dis<strong>to</strong>rtions, and Insurance Decisions."Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, August1993, 7(1), pp. 35-51.Kahneman, Daniel. "Comment," in Ronald G.Cumrnings, David S. Brookshire, and WilliamD. Schultze, eds., Valuing environmen-tal goods. To<strong>to</strong>wa, NJ: RowmanandAllenheld, 1986, pp. 185-93.. "New Challenges <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> RationalityAssumption." Journal of Institutional andTheoretical Economics, March 1994, 150(1),pp. 18-36.. "Evaluation by Moments: Past and Future,"in Daniel Kahneman and Amos Tversky,eds., Choices, values, and frames. NewYork: Cambridge University Press, 2000a,pp. 693-708.."Experienced Utility and Objective Happiness:A Moment-Based Approach," in DanielKahneman and Amos Tversky, eds., Choices,values, and frames. New York: CambridgeUniversity Press, 2000b, pp. 673-92.. "A Psychological Perspective on Economics."American Economic Review, May2003a (Papers and Proceedings), 93(2), pp.162-68.. "A Perspective on Judgment andChoice: Mapping Bounded Rationality."American Psychologist, September 2003b,56(9),pp. 697-720.Kahneman, Daniel and Frederick, Shane. "RepresentativenessRevisited: Attribute Substitutionin Intuitive Judgment," in ThomasGilovich, Dale Griffin, and Daniel Kahneman,eds., Heuristics and biases: The psychologyof intuitive thought. New York:Cambridge University Press, 2002, pp. 49-81.Kahneman, Daniel; Fredrickson, Barbara L.;Schreiber, Charles A. and Redelmeier, DonaldA. "When More Pain is Preferred <strong>to</strong> Less:Adding a Better End." Psychological Science,November 1993, 4(6), pp. 401-05.Kahneman, Daniel; Knetsch, Jack and Thaler,Richard. "Fairness as a Constraint on Profitseeking:Entitlements in <strong>the</strong> Market." AmericanEconomic Review, September 1986,76(4),pp. 728-41.. "Experimental Tests of <strong>the</strong> EndowmentEffect and <strong>the</strong> Coase Theorem." Journalof Political Economy, December 1990,98(6),pp. 1325-48.. "The Endowment Effect, Loss Aversion,and Status Quo Bias: Anomalies." Journalof Economic Perspectives, Winter 1991,5(1),pp. 193-206.


VOL. 93 NO. 5KAHNEMAN: MAPS OF BOUNDED RATIONALITY1473Kahneman, Daniel and Lovallo, Daniel. "TimidChoices and Bold Forecasts: A CognitivePerspective on Risk Taking." ManagementScience, January 1993, 39(1), pp. 17-31.Kahneman, Daniel; Ri<strong>to</strong>v, Ilana and Schkade,David. "Economic Preferences or AttitudeExpressions? An Analysis of Dollar Responses<strong>to</strong> Public Issues." Journal of Riskand Uncertainty, December 1999, 19(1-3),pp. 203-35.Kahneman, Daniel; Slovic, Paul and Tversky,Amos, eds. Judgment under uncertainty: Heuristicsand biases. New York: CambridgeUniversity Press, 1982.Kahneman, Daniel and Tversky, Amos. "On <strong>the</strong>Psychology of Prediction." PsychologicalReview, July 1973, 80(4), pp. 237-51.. "Prospect Theory: An Analysis of DecisionsUnder Risk." Econometrica, March1979, 47(2), pp. 263-91.-, eds. Choices, values, andframes. NewYork: Cambridge University Press, 2000.Kahneman, Daniel; Wakker, Peter P. and Sarin,Rakesh. "Back <strong>to</strong> Bentham? Explorations ofExperienced Utility." Quarterly Journal ofEconomics, May 1997,112(2), pp. 375-405.Keren, Gideon and Wagenaar, Willem A. "Violationsof Utility Theory in Unique and RepeatedGambles." Journal of ExperimentalPsychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition,July 1987, 13(3), pp. 387-91.Klein, Gary. Sources of power: How peoplemake decisions. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press,1998.. Intuition at work: Why developingyour gut instincts will make you better atwhat you do. New York: Doubleday, 2003.Koehler, Jonathan Jay. "The Base-Rate FallacyReconsidered: Descriptive, Normative, andMethodological Challenges." Behavioral andBrain Sciences, March 1996, 19, pp. 1-53.Kopp, Raymond. "Why Existence Value Shouldbe Used in Cost-Benefit Analysis." Journalof Policy Analysis and Management, Winter1992, 11(1), pp. 123-30.Kunreu<strong>the</strong>r, Howard. "The Changing SocietalConsequences of Risks From Natural Hazards."Annals of <strong>the</strong> American Academy ofPolitical and Social Science, May 1979,443(443), pp. 104-16.Langer, Ellen J.; Blank, Arthur and Chanowitz,Benzion. "The Mindlessness of OstensiblyThoughtful Action: The Role of 'Placebic'Information in Interpersonal Interaction."Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,June 1978, 36(6), pp. 635-42.LeDow, Joseph E. "Emotion Circuits in <strong>the</strong>Brain." Annual Review of Neuroscience,March 2000, 23, pp. 155-84.Lerner, Jennifer S. and Tetlock, Philip E. "Accountingfor <strong>the</strong> Effects of Accountability."Psychological Bulletin, March 1999, 125(2),pp. 255-75.List, John A. "Preference Reversals of a DifferentKind: The 'More Is Less' Phenomenon."American Economic Review, December2002, 92(5), pp. 1636-43.. "Does Market Experience EliminateMarket Anomalies?'Quarterly Journal ofEconomics, February 2003a, 118(1), pp. 47-71.. "Neoclassical Theory Versus ProspectTheory: Evidence From <strong>the</strong> Marketplace."National Bureau of Economic Research(Cambridge, MA) Working Paper No.W9736, 2003b; Econometrica, 2004 (forthcoming).Loewenstein, George. "Out of Control: VisceralInfluences on Behavior." Organizational Behaviorand Human Decision Processes,March 1996, 65(3), pp. 272-92.. "Emotions in Economic Theory andEconomic Behavior." American EconomicReview, May 2000 (Papers and Proceedings),90(2), pp. 426-32.Loewenstein, George; Weber, Elke U.; Hsee,Chris<strong>to</strong>pher K. and Welch, N. "Risk as Feelings."Psychological Bulletin, March 2001,127(2), pp. 267-86.Luce, R. Duncan; Krantz, David H.; Suppes,Patrick and Tversky, Amos. Foundations ofmeasurement, volume 3: Representation, axiomatization,and invariance. San Diego, CA:Academic Press, 1990.Madrian, Brigitte and Shea, Dennis. "The Powerof Suggestion: Inertia in 40 1 (k) Participationand Savings Behavior." Quarterly Journal ofEconomics, November 200 1, 116(4), pp.1149-87.Mellers, Barbara. "Choice and <strong>the</strong> RelativePleasure of Consequences." PsychologicalBulletin, November 2000, 126(6), pp. 910-24.Nisbett, Richard E.; Krantz, David H.; Jepson,Chris<strong>to</strong>pher and Kunda, Ziva. "The Use ofStatistical Heuristics in Everyday Inductive


1474 THE AMERICAN ECONOMIC REVIEW DECEMBER 2003Reasoning." Psychological Review, Oc<strong>to</strong>ber1983, 90(4), pp. 339-63.Pashler, Harold E. The psychology of attention.Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1998.Posner, Michael I. and Keele, <strong>Stephen</strong> W. "On <strong>the</strong>Genesis of Abstract Ideas." Journal of ExperimentalPsychology, Pt. 1, 1968, 77(3), pp.353-63.Rabin, Mat<strong>the</strong>w. "Inference by Believers in <strong>the</strong>Law of Small Numbers." Quarterly Journalof Economics, August 2002, 17(3), pp. 775-816.Read, Daniel; Loewenstein, George and Rabin,Mat<strong>the</strong>w. "Choice Bracketing." Journal ofRisk and Uncertainty, December 1999,19(1-3), pp. 171-97.Redelmeier, Donald A. and Kahneman, Daniel."Patients' Memories of Painful MedicalTreatments: Real-time and RetrospectiveEvaluations of Two Minimally Invasive Procedures."Pain, July 1996, 66(1), pp. 3-8.Redelmeier, Donald A.; Katz, Joel and Kahneman,Daniel. "Memories of Colonoscopy: ARandomized Trial." Pain, July 2003, 104(1-2), pp. 187-94.Rosch, Eleanor and Mervis, Carolyn B. "FamilyResemblances: Studies in <strong>the</strong> Internal Structureof Categories." Cognitive Psychology,Oc<strong>to</strong>ber 1975, 7(4), pp. 573-605.Ross, Lee and Nisbett, Richard E. The person and<strong>the</strong> situation. New York: McGraw-Hill,1991.Rottenstreich, Yuval and Hsee, Chris<strong>to</strong>pher K."Money, Kisses and Electric Shocks: On <strong>the</strong>Affective Psychology of Risk." PsychologicalScience, May 2001, 12(3), pp. 185-90.Rozin, Paul and Nemeroff, Carol. "Sympa<strong>the</strong>ticMagical Thinking: The Contagion and SimilarityHeuristics," in Thomas Gilovich, DaleGriffin, and Daniel Kahneman, eds., Heuristicsand biases: The psychology of intuitivethought. New York: Cambridge UniversityPress, 2002, pp. 201-16.Samuelson, William and Zeckhauser, Richard."Status Quo Bias in Decision Making." Journalof Risk and Uncertainty, March 1988,](I), pp. 7-59.Schelling, Thomas C. Choice and consequence:Perspectives of an errant economist.Cambridge, MA: Harvard UniversityPress, 1984.Schreiber, Charles A. and Kahneman, Daniel."Determinants of <strong>the</strong> Remembered Utility ofAversive Sounds." Journal of ExperimentalPsychology: General, March 2000, 129(1),pp. 27-42.Shafir, Eldar and LeBoeuf, Robyn A. "Rationality."Annual Review of Psychology, February2002, 53(1), pp. 419-517.Shiller, Robert J. Irrational exuberance. Prince<strong>to</strong>n,NJ: Prince<strong>to</strong>n University Press, 2000.Shleifer, Andrei. InefJicient markets: An introduction<strong>to</strong> behavioral jnance. New York:Oxford University Press, 2000.Simon, Herbert A. "A Behavioral Model of RationalChoice." Quarterly Journal of Economics,February 1955, 69(1), pp. 99-1 18.. "Information Processing Models ofCognition." Annual Review of Psychology,February 1979, 30, pp. 363-96.Simon, Herbert A. and Chase, William G. "Skillin Chess." American Scientist, July 1973,61(4), pp. 394-403.Sloman, Steven A. "Two Systems of Reasoning,"in Thomas Gilovich, Dale Griffin, and DanielKahneman, eds., Heuristics and biases: Thepsychology of intuitive thought. New York:Cambridge University Press, 2002, pp. 379-96.Slovic, Paul; Finucane, Melissa; Peters, Ellen andMacGregor, Donald G. "The Affect Heuristic,"in Thomas Gilovich, Dale Griffin, andDaniel Kahneman, eds., Heuristics and biases:The psychology of intuitive thought.New York: Cambridge University Press,2002, pp. 397-420.Stanovich, Keith E. and West, Richard F. "IndividualDifferences in Reasoning: Implicationsfor <strong>the</strong> Rationality Debate?" Behavioraland Brain Sciences, Oc<strong>to</strong>ber 2000,23(5), pp.645-65.. "Individual Differences in Reasoning:Implications for <strong>the</strong> Rationality Debate?" inThomas Gilovich, Dale Griffin, and DanielKahneman, eds., Heuristics and biases: Thepsychology of intuitive thought. New York:Cambridge University Press, 2002, pp. 421-40.Strack, Fritz; Martin, Leonard and Schwarz,Norbert. "Priming and Communication: SocialDeterminants of Information Use inJudgments of Life Satisfaction." EuropeanJournal of Social Psychology, Oc<strong>to</strong>ber-November 1988, 18(5), pp. 429-42.Thaler, Richard H. "Toward a Positive Theoryof Consumer Choice." Journal of Economic


VOL. 93 NO. 5KAHNEMAN: MAPS OF BOUNDED RATlONALITY1475Behavior and Organization, March 1980,1(1), pp. 36-90.. "Mental Accounting and ConsumerChoice." Marketing Science, Summer 1985,4(3), pp. 199-214.. Quasi rational economics. New York:Russell Sage Foundation, 1991.. The winner's curse: Paradoxes andanomalies of economic life. New York: FreePress, 1992.."Mental Accounting Matters." Journalof Behavioral Decision Making, July 1999,12(3), pp. 183-206.. "Toward a Positive Theory of ConsumerChoice," in Daniel Kahneman andAmos Tversky, eds., Choices, values, andframes. New York: Cambridge UniversityPress, 2000, pp. 268-87.Tversky, Amos and Kahneman, Daniel. "Judgmentunder Uncertainty: Heuristics andBiases." Science, September 1974,185(4157), pp. 1124-31.. "The Framing of Decisions and <strong>the</strong>Psychology of Choice." Science, January1981,211(4481), pp. 453-58.-."Extensional Versus Intuitive Reasoning:The Conjunction Fallacy in ProbabilityJudgment." Psychological Review, Oc<strong>to</strong>ber1983, 90(4), pp. 293-315.. "Rational Choice and <strong>the</strong> Framing ofDecisions." Journal of Business, Oc<strong>to</strong>ber1986, 59(4), pp. S251-78.. "Loss Aversion in Riskless Choice: AReference-Dependent Model." QuarterlyJournal of Economics, November 1991,106(4), pp. 1039-61.. "Advances in Prospect Theory: CumulativeRepresentation of Uncertainty." Journalof Risk and Uncertainty, Oc<strong>to</strong>ber 1992,5(4), pp. 297-323.Tversky, Amos and Redelmeier, Donald A. "On<strong>the</strong> Framing of Multiple Prospects." PsychologicalScience, May 1992, 3(3), pp. 191-93.Wilson, Timothy D. Strangers <strong>to</strong> ourselves:Discovering <strong>the</strong> adaptive unconscious.Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press,2002.Wilson, Timothy D. and Schooler, Jonathan W."Thinking Too Much: Introspection Can Reduce<strong>the</strong> Quality of Preferences and Decisions."Journal of Personality and SocialPsychology, ~ebn&y 1991, 60(2), pp. 181-92.Zajonc, Robert B. "Emotions," in Daniel T. Gilbert,Susan T. Fiske, and Gardner Lindzey,eds., Handbook of socialpsychology, 4th Ed.,Vol. 1. New York: Oxford University Press,1998, pp. 591-632.


http://www.js<strong>to</strong>r.orgLINKED CITATIONS- Page 1 of 5 -You have printed <strong>the</strong> following article:Maps of Bounded Rationality: Psychology for Behavioral EconomicsDaniel KahnemanThe American Economic Review, Vol. 93, No. 5. (Dec., 2003), pp. 1449-1475.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0002-8282%28200312%2993%3A5%3C1449%3AMOBRPF%3E2.0.CO%3B2-%23This article references <strong>the</strong> following linked citations. If you are trying <strong>to</strong> access articles from anoff-campus location, you may be required <strong>to</strong> first logon via your library web site <strong>to</strong> access JSTOR. Pleasevisit your library's website or contact a librarian <strong>to</strong> learn about options for remote access <strong>to</strong> JSTOR.ReferencesTrading Is Hazardous <strong>to</strong> Your Wealth: The Common S<strong>to</strong>ck Investment Performance ofIndividual Inves<strong>to</strong>rsBrad M. Barber; Terrance OdeanThe Journal of Finance, Vol. 55, No. 2. (Apr., 2000), pp. 773-806.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0022-1082%28200004%2955%3A2%3C773%3ATIHTYW%3E2.0.CO%3B2-FMyopic Loss Aversion and <strong>the</strong> Equity Premium PuzzleShlomo Benartzi; Richard H. ThalerThe Quarterly Journal of Economics, Vol. 110, No. 1. (Feb., 1995), pp. 73-92.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0033-5533%28199502%29110%3A1%3C73%3AMLAATE%3E2.0.CO%3B2-TRisk Aversion or Myopia? Choices in Repeated Gambles and Retirement InvestmentsShlomo Benartzi; Richard H. ThalerManagement Science, Vol. 45, No. 3. (Mar., 1999), pp. 364-381.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0025-1909%28199903%2945%3A3%3C364%3ARAOMCI%3E2.0.CO%3B2-UNaive Diversification Strategies in Defined Contribution Saving PlansShlomo Benartzi; Richard H. ThalerThe American Economic Review, Vol. 91, No. 1. (Mar., 2001), pp. 79-98.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0002-8282%28200103%2991%3A1%3C79%3ANDSIDC%3E2.0.CO%3B2-8


http://www.js<strong>to</strong>r.orgLINKED CITATIONS- Page 2 of 5 -Exposition of a New Theory on <strong>the</strong> Measurement of RiskDaniel BernoulliEconometrica, Vol. 22, No. 1. (Jan., 1954), pp. 23-36.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0012-9682%28195401%2922%3A1%3C23%3AEOANTO%3E2.0.CO%3B2-XDoes <strong>the</strong> S<strong>to</strong>ck Market Overreact?Werner F. M. De Bondt; Richard ThalerThe Journal of Finance, Vol. 40, No. 3, Papers and Proceedings of <strong>the</strong> Forty-Third Annual MeetingAmerican Finance Association, Dallas, Texas, December 28-30, 1984. (Jul., 1985), pp. 793-805.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0022-1082%28198507%2940%3A3%3C793%3ADTSMO%3E2.0.CO%3B2-QEmotions and Economic TheoryJon ElsterJournal of Economic Literature, Vol. 36, No. 1. (Mar., 1998), pp. 47-74.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0022-0515%28199803%2936%3A1%3C47%3AEAET%3E2.0.CO%3B2-9Loss Aversion and Seller Behavior: Evidence from <strong>the</strong> Housing MarketDavid Genesove; Chris<strong>to</strong>pher MayerThe Quarterly Journal of Economics, Vol. 116, No. 4. (Nov., 2001), pp. 1233-1260.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0033-5533%28200111%29116%3A4%3C1233%3ALAASBE%3E2.0.CO%3B2-JRecent Psychological Studies of Behavior under UncertaintyDavid M. Gre<strong>the</strong>rThe American Economic Review, Vol. 68, No. 2, Papers and Proceedings of <strong>the</strong> Ninetieth AnnualMeeting of <strong>the</strong> American Economic Association. (May, 1978), pp. 70-74.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0002-8282%28197805%2968%3A2%3C70%3ARPSOBU%3E2.0.CO%3B2-Z


http://www.js<strong>to</strong>r.orgLINKED CITATIONS- Page 3 of 5 -A Psychological Perspective on EconomicsDaniel KahnemanThe American Economic Review, Vol. 93, No. 2, Papers and Proceedings of <strong>the</strong> One HundredFifteenth Annual Meeting of <strong>the</strong> American Economic Association, Washing<strong>to</strong>n, DC, January 3-5,2003. (May, 2003), pp. 162-168.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0002-8282%28200305%2993%3A2%3C162%3AAPPOE%3E2.0.CO%3B2-5Fairness as a Constraint on Profit Seeking: Entitlements in <strong>the</strong> MarketDaniel Kahneman; Jack L. Knetsch; Richard ThalerThe American Economic Review, Vol. 76, No. 4. (Sep., 1986), pp. 728-741.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0002-8282%28198609%2976%3A4%3C728%3AFAACOP%3E2.0.CO%3B2-IExperimental Tests of <strong>the</strong> Endowment Effect and <strong>the</strong> Coase TheoremDaniel Kahneman; Jack L. Knetsch; Richard H. ThalerThe Journal of Political Economy, Vol. 98, No. 6. (Dec., 1990), pp. 1325-1348.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0022-3808%28199012%2998%3A6%3C1325%3AETOTEE%3E2.0.CO%3B2-WAnomalies: The Endowment Effect, Loss Aversion, and Status Quo BiasDaniel Kahneman; Jack L. Knetsch; Richard H. ThalerThe Journal of Economic Perspectives, Vol. 5, No. 1. (Winter, 1991), pp. 193-206.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0895-3309%28199124%295%3A1%3C193%3AATEELA%3E2.0.CO%3B2-VTimid Choices and Bold Forecasts: A Cognitive Perspective on Risk TakingDaniel Kahneman; Dan LovalloManagement Science, Vol. 39, No. 1. (Jan., 1993), pp. 17-31.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0025-1909%28199301%2939%3A1%3C17%3ATCABFA%3E2.0.CO%3B2-IProspect Theory: An Analysis of Decision under RiskDaniel Kahneman; Amos TverskyEconometrica, Vol. 47, No. 2. (Mar., 1979), pp. 263-292.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0012-9682%28197903%2947%3A2%3C263%3APTAAOD%3E2.0.CO%3B2-3


http://www.js<strong>to</strong>r.orgLINKED CITATIONS- Page 4 of 5 -Back <strong>to</strong> Bentham? Explorations of Experienced UtilityDaniel Kahneman; Peter P. Wakker; Rakesh SarinThe Quarterly Journal of Economics, Vol. 112, No. 2, In Memory of Amos Tversky (1937-1996).(May, 1997), pp. 375-405.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0033-5533%28199705%29112%3A2%3C375%3ABTBEOE%3E2.0.CO%3B2-FWhy Existence Value Should Be Used in Cost-Benefit AnalysisRaymond J. KoppJournal of Policy Analysis and Management, Vol. 11, No. 1. (Winter, 1992), pp. 123-130.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0276-8739%28199224%2911%3A1%3C123%3AWEVSBU%3E2.0.CO%3B2-VThe Changing Societal Consequences of Risks from Natural HazardsHoward Kunreu<strong>the</strong>rAnnals of <strong>the</strong> American Academy of Political and Social Science, Vol. 443, Risks and Its Treatment:Changing Societal Consequences. (May, 1979), pp. 104-116.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0002-7162%28197905%29443%3C104%3ATCSCOR%3E2.0.CO%3B2-WPreference Reversals of a Different Kind: The "More Is Less" PhenomenonJohn A. ListThe American Economic Review, Vol. 92, No. 5. (Dec., 2002), pp. 1636-1643.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0002-8282%28200212%2992%3A5%3C1636%3APROADK%3E2.0.CO%3B2-UEmotions in Economic Theory and Economic BehaviorGeorge LoewensteinThe American Economic Review, Vol. 90, No. 2, Papers and Proceedings of <strong>the</strong> One HundredTwelfth Annual Meeting of <strong>the</strong> American Economic Association. (May, 2000), pp. 426-432.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0002-8282%28200005%2990%3A2%3C426%3AEIETAE%3E2.0.CO%3B2-LThe Power of Suggestion: Inertia in 401(k) Participation and Savings BehaviorBrigitte C. Madrian; Dennis F. SheaThe Quarterly Journal of Economics, Vol. 116, No. 4. (Nov., 2001), pp. 1149-1187.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0033-5533%28200111%29116%3A4%3C1149%3ATPOSII%3E2.0.CO%3B2-%23


http://www.js<strong>to</strong>r.orgLINKED CITATIONS- Page 5 of 5 -A Behavioral Model of Rational ChoiceHerbert A. SimonThe Quarterly Journal of Economics, Vol. 69, No. 1. (Feb., 1955), pp. 99-118.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0033-5533%28195502%2969%3A1%3C99%3AABMORC%3E2.0.CO%3B2-AMental Accounting and Consumer ChoiceRichard ThalerMarketing Science, Vol. 4, No. 3. (Summer, 1985), pp. 199-214.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0732-2399%28198522%294%3A3%3C199%3AMAACC%3E2.0.CO%3B2-8Judgment under Uncertainty: Heuristics and BiasesAmos Tversky; Daniel KahnemanScience, New Series, Vol. 185, No. 4157. (Sep. 27, 1974), pp. 1124-1131.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0036-8075%2819740927%293%3A185%3A4157%3C1124%3AJUUHAB%3E2.0.CO%3B2-MThe Framing of Decisions and <strong>the</strong> Psychology of ChoiceAmos Tversky; Daniel KahnemanScience, New Series, Vol. 211, No. 4481. (Jan. 30, 1981), pp. 453-458.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0036-8075%2819810130%293%3A211%3A4481%3C453%3ATFODAT%3E2.0.CO%3B2-3Rational Choice and <strong>the</strong> Framing of DecisionsAmos Tversky; Daniel KahnemanThe Journal of Business, Vol. 59, No. 4, Part 2: The Behavioral Foundations of Economic Theory.(Oct., 1986), pp. S251-S278.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0021-9398%28198610%2959%3A4%3CS251%3ARCATFO%3E2.0.CO%3B2-CLoss Aversion in Riskless Choice: A Reference-Dependent ModelAmos Tversky; Daniel KahnemanThe Quarterly Journal of Economics, Vol. 106, No. 4. (Nov., 1991), pp. 1039-1061.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0033-5533%28199111%29106%3A4%3C1039%3ALAIRCA%3E2.0.CO%3B2-O


Theory of Finance from <strong>the</strong> Perspective of Continuous TimeRobert C. Mer<strong>to</strong>nThe Journal of Financial and Quantitative Analysis, Vol. 10, No. 4, 1975 Proceedings. (Nov.,1975), pp. 659-674.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0022-1090%28197511%2910%3A4%3C659%3ATOFFTP%3E2.0.CO%3B2-5The Journal of Financial and Quantitative Analysis is currently published by University of Washing<strong>to</strong>n School of BusinessAdministration.Your use of <strong>the</strong> JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available athttp://www.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/about/terms.html. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtainedprior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in<strong>the</strong> JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use.Please contact <strong>the</strong> publisher regarding any fur<strong>the</strong>r use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained athttp://www.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/journals/uwash.html.Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain <strong>the</strong> same copyright notice that appears on <strong>the</strong> screen or printedpage of such transmission.The JSTOR Archive is a trusted digital reposi<strong>to</strong>ry providing for long-term preservation and access <strong>to</strong> leading academicjournals and scholarly literature from around <strong>the</strong> world. The Archive is supported by libraries, scholarly societies, publishers,and foundations. It is an initiative of JSTOR, a not-for-profit organization with a mission <strong>to</strong> help <strong>the</strong> scholarly community takeadvantage of advances in technology. For more information regarding JSTOR, please contact support@js<strong>to</strong>r.org.http://www.js<strong>to</strong>r.orgThu Nov 1 06:11:33 2007


JOURNAL OF FINANCIAL AND QUANTITATIVE ANALYSISNovember 1975THEORY OF FINANCE FROM THE PERSPECTIVE OF CONTINUOUS TIMERobert C. Mer<strong>to</strong>n*It is not uncommon on occasions such as this <strong>to</strong> talk about <strong>the</strong> shortcomings in <strong>the</strong><strong>the</strong>ory of Finance, and <strong>to</strong> emphasize how little progress has been made in answering <strong>the</strong>basic questions in Finance, despite enormous research efforts. Indeed, it is not uncommonon such occasions <strong>to</strong> attack our basic "mythodology," particularly <strong>the</strong> "Ivory Tower" natureof our assumptions, as <strong>the</strong> major reasons for our lack of progress. Like a Sunday morningsermon, such talks serve many useful functions. For one, <strong>the</strong>y serve <strong>to</strong> deflate our professionalegos. For ano<strong>the</strong>r, <strong>the</strong>y serve <strong>to</strong> remind us that <strong>the</strong> importance of a contributionas judged by our professional peers (<strong>the</strong> gold we really work for) is often not closelyaligned with its operational importance in <strong>the</strong> outside world. Also, such talks serve <strong>to</strong>comfort those just entering <strong>the</strong> field, by letting <strong>the</strong>m know that t<strong>here</strong> is much left <strong>to</strong> dobecause so little has been done. While such talks are not uncommon, this is not what mytalk is about. Ra<strong>the</strong>r, my discussion centers on <strong>the</strong> positive progress made in <strong>the</strong> developmen<strong>to</strong>f a <strong>the</strong>ory of Finance using <strong>the</strong> continuous-time mode of analysis.Hearing this in 1975, amidst an economic recession with a baffling new disease called"stagflation" and with our financial markets only beginning <strong>to</strong> recover from <strong>the</strong> worstturmoil in almost 40 years, some will say that I am embarked on a fool's errand. Perhaps.At any rate, on this errand, I shall discuss <strong>the</strong> continuous-time solutions <strong>to</strong> some of <strong>the</strong>basic problems of Finance: portfolio selection, capital market equilibrium, and <strong>the</strong> pricingof capital assets; <strong>the</strong> derived functions of financial intermediaries and instruments;and <strong>the</strong> pricing of corporate liabilities. Ra<strong>the</strong>r than dwelling on <strong>the</strong> technical aspectsof obtaining <strong>the</strong>se solutions, I will discuss <strong>the</strong> substantive results and why <strong>the</strong>y seem <strong>to</strong>differ from those obtained in o<strong>the</strong>r modes of analysis. While my main interest is in <strong>the</strong>substantive results, some methodological discussion is necessary because <strong>the</strong> continuoustimemode is relatively new. However, I will attempt <strong>to</strong> keep this discussion <strong>to</strong> a minimumby emphasizing only those assumptions that differ from its discrete-time counterpart, andleave those assumptions common <strong>to</strong> both types of analysis as unders<strong>to</strong>od.The natural beginning point for <strong>the</strong> development of a <strong>the</strong>ory of Finance is <strong>the</strong> problemof lifetime consumption and portfolio selection for <strong>the</strong> individual consumer or householdunder uncertainty. T<strong>here</strong> is a long standing tradition in economic <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>to</strong> take <strong>the</strong> existenceof households and <strong>the</strong>ir tastes as 'tgivens," as exogenous <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory. But thistradition does not extend <strong>to</strong> economic organizations and institutions: that is, <strong>the</strong>y areregarded as existing primarily because of <strong>the</strong> functions <strong>the</strong>y serve instead of functioningprimarily because <strong>the</strong>y exist. Economic organizations and institutions, unlike householdsand <strong>the</strong>ir tastes, are endogenous <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory. To derive <strong>the</strong> functions of <strong>the</strong>se financial* Massachusetts Institute of Technology. Aid from <strong>the</strong> Natural Science Foundation isqra tef ull y acknowledged.


organizations and institutions, t<strong>here</strong>fore, we must first derive <strong>the</strong> behavior of individualhouseholds.The basic lifetime consumption-portfolio selection problem can be stated as follows:at each point in time, <strong>the</strong> consumer must make two types of decisions: (1) How much ofhis wealth <strong>to</strong> consume (<strong>the</strong> "consumption choice"); (2) How <strong>to</strong> allocate that part of hiswealth that he does not consume, across alternative assets (<strong>the</strong> "portfolio choice"). Itis assumed that he makes <strong>the</strong>se decisions so as <strong>to</strong> maximize <strong>the</strong> expected value of hisutility of lifetime consumption. This function is usually represented as a sum (or in<strong>the</strong> case of continuous-time, a time integral) of strictly concave von-Neumann-Morgensternutility functions for consumption at each date plus possibly an end-of-life utility func-tion of wealth representing any bequest motives.So formulated, a set of s<strong>to</strong>chastic processes for <strong>the</strong> state variables, typically t<strong>here</strong>turns on assets, are posited, ei<strong>the</strong>r as objective probability distributions for <strong>the</strong>future course of returns or as representations of <strong>the</strong> inves<strong>to</strong>r's subjective beliefs, and<strong>the</strong> problem is solved by s<strong>to</strong>chastic dynamic programming. A complete solution contains<strong>the</strong> individual's demands for consumption and assets as a function of age, wealth, and <strong>the</strong>o<strong>the</strong>r relevant state variables. To this point, of course, <strong>the</strong> discussion is consistentwith ei<strong>the</strong>r a discrete-time or continuous-time formulation.While t<strong>here</strong> are differing assumptions about <strong>the</strong> continuous-time formulation of <strong>the</strong>problem depending upon <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>chastic processes posited, t<strong>here</strong> are three assumptions com-mon <strong>to</strong> all such formulations: Namely,(1) The capital markets are assumed <strong>to</strong> be open all <strong>the</strong> time, and t<strong>here</strong>fore economicagents have <strong>the</strong> opportunity <strong>to</strong> trade continuously.(2) Prices of assets traded in speculative markets satisfy <strong>the</strong> "Efficient Markets Hypo-<strong>the</strong>sis" of Fama and samue1son.l Namely, assets are priced so that <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>chasticprocesses describing <strong>the</strong> unanticipated parts of <strong>the</strong>ir returns (i.e.1 <strong>the</strong> actual returnsminus <strong>the</strong>ir expected value) are a martingale. This assumption does not imply an independentincrements process although such a process satisfies this assumption.(3) The s<strong>to</strong>chastic processes generating <strong>the</strong> state variables can be described as ei<strong>the</strong>r:[I] Diffusion processes with continuous sample paths. Simply described,<strong>the</strong> state variables generated by <strong>the</strong>se processes are changing all <strong>the</strong>time but <strong>the</strong> magnitude of such changes are small over a short timeperiod.[2] Compound Poisson processes with step function type sample paths.Simply described, <strong>the</strong> state variables generated by <strong>the</strong>se processeswill, almost certainly, over a short enough time interval have nochange, or with a very small probability, a radical change or"jump" will occur.[31 A mixture of both types.While all three types have been used in <strong>the</strong> Finance literaturet2 most of <strong>the</strong> best-known'see Fama [51 and Samuelson [23].*see Mer<strong>to</strong>n [lo-171 ; Black and Scholes [I, 21 ; Cox and Ross [41; Mer<strong>to</strong>n and Samuelson[181.


esults from continuous-time analysis have come from restricting <strong>the</strong> state variabledynamics <strong>to</strong> being diffusion processes with continuous sample paths. Indeed, since vir-tually any reasonable s<strong>to</strong>chastic process arising in an economics context can be adequatelyapproximated by some mixture of <strong>the</strong>se two types, I would expect any serious disagreementwith <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>chastic process assumption would be on <strong>the</strong> use of a special form of <strong>the</strong>seprocesses, ra<strong>the</strong>r than with <strong>the</strong> processes <strong>the</strong>mselves.The basic assumptions established, let us return <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> consumption-portfolio prob-lem, leaving for later <strong>the</strong> discussion of <strong>the</strong> merits of <strong>the</strong> assumptions. In its simplestfoAI3 <strong>the</strong> continuous-time version of <strong>the</strong> problem assumes that <strong>the</strong> only source of uncer-tainty facing <strong>the</strong> consumer is <strong>the</strong> rate of return on assets. It is fur<strong>the</strong>r assumed that<strong>the</strong>se returns are generated by diffusion processes with continuous sample paths and thatreturns are serially independent and identically distributed through time, i.e., thatprices follow a geometric Brownian motion and hence,<strong>the</strong> prices are lognormally distributed.Also, it is assumed that t<strong>here</strong> is a single consumption good.In solving this problem, as in more general forms of <strong>the</strong> continuous time analysis,<strong>the</strong> first-order conditions for optimal demands for assets are linear, and hence <strong>the</strong> demandfunctions can be solved for explicitly by matrix inversion. Moreover, in this problem,<strong>the</strong> relative demands for risky assets, i.e., <strong>the</strong> demand for, say, risky asset i dividedby <strong>the</strong> demand for risky asset j, is independent of <strong>the</strong> inves<strong>to</strong>r's preferences of wealthlevel, and indeed, depend only on <strong>the</strong> instantaneous means, variances, and covariances of<strong>the</strong> returns. From this, it is a short step <strong>to</strong> prove a mutual fund or separation <strong>the</strong>orem:namely, that all inves<strong>to</strong>rs agreeing on <strong>the</strong> distribution of returns will be indifferentbetween choosing <strong>the</strong>ir portfolios from among <strong>the</strong> basic securities or from just two mutualfunds. Fur<strong>the</strong>r, <strong>the</strong> separation is complete because <strong>the</strong> compositions of two funds can bedetermined solely from <strong>the</strong> "technological" data about returns without knowledge of inves-<strong>to</strong>rs' preferences, wealth levels, or time horizons. Moreover, if one of <strong>the</strong> assets isriskless, <strong>the</strong>n one fund can be that asset and <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r need only have risky assets, andin this case, <strong>the</strong> risky fund is called <strong>the</strong> "optimal combination of risky assets."though <strong>the</strong>se results are identical in structure <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> classic Markowitz-Tobin mean-variance findings, <strong>the</strong>ir derivation <strong>here</strong> comes from a quite different set of assumptions.The classic mean-variance results are deduced in a static framework by hypo<strong>the</strong>sizingthat mean and variance are sufficient statistics for making decisions. Indeed, when itwas shown that <strong>the</strong> only conditions under which this hypo<strong>the</strong>sis is consistent with expectedutility maximization are if returns are normally distributed or if utility functions arequadratic, economists (with <strong>the</strong> exception of those in Finance) lost interest in this ap-proach (except for example purposes) and returned <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> more general framework of expectedutility maximization.In contrast, <strong>the</strong> continuous-time results come from an intertemporal model, are con-sistent with any concave utility function, and assume a return structure consistent withlimited liability: namely, <strong>the</strong> lognormal distribution which has for a long time been a4pro<strong>to</strong>type distribution for security returns.3~eeMer<strong>to</strong>n [I01 and [ll, section 51.*~tshould be emphasized that <strong>the</strong> lognormality assumption applies only in <strong>the</strong> simpleform of <strong>the</strong> continuous time formulation, and is not essential <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> basic simplificationsgained from this mode of analysis.Al-


The natural question <strong>to</strong> ask is: "Why does it work <strong>here</strong>, when it didn't in discretetime?" What rabbits went in<strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> hat? Indeed, one should be suspicious about any resultsthat obtain in a continuous-time formulation but not in its discrete counterpart.T<strong>here</strong> are two "rabbits": one, <strong>the</strong> assumption that inves<strong>to</strong>rs can revise <strong>the</strong>ir portfoliosfrequently, and two, that prices can only change by small amounts in short periods oftime. Moreover, <strong>the</strong> continuous-time result is consistent with <strong>the</strong> discrete-time solutionwhen <strong>the</strong> appropriate comparison is made.To see this, I make a short digression: T<strong>here</strong> are three time intervals or horizonsinvolved in <strong>the</strong> consumption-portfolio problem. (1) The trading horizon, is <strong>the</strong> minimumlength of time between which successive transactions by economic agents can be made in<strong>the</strong> market. This is determined by <strong>the</strong> structure of <strong>the</strong> markets in <strong>the</strong> economy. For example,how frequently <strong>the</strong> market is open, and this time scale is not determined by <strong>the</strong>individual inves<strong>to</strong>r. (2) The decision horizon, is <strong>the</strong> length of time between which <strong>the</strong>inves<strong>to</strong>r makes successive decisions. So, for example, an inves<strong>to</strong>r with a fixed decisioninterval of one month, who makes a consumption decision and portfolio allocation <strong>to</strong>daywill under no conditions make any new decisions or take any action prior <strong>to</strong> one monthfrom now. (3) The planning horizon, is <strong>the</strong> maximum length of time for which <strong>the</strong> inves<strong>to</strong>rgives any weight in his utility function. Typically, this time period would correspond<strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> balance of <strong>the</strong> consumer's lifetime. Actually, t<strong>here</strong> is a fourth time interval,not directly related <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> problem's solution but related <strong>to</strong> empirical testing of <strong>the</strong>derived behavior. I call this <strong>the</strong> observation horizon. It is <strong>the</strong> length of time betweensuccessive observations of <strong>the</strong> data by <strong>the</strong> tester, and is typically, ei<strong>the</strong>r daily, weekly,monthly, quarterly, or annually. It is useful <strong>to</strong> keep <strong>the</strong>se three or four different timeintervals in mind when evaluating <strong>the</strong> relative merits of alternative formulations for <strong>the</strong>same problem. Indeed, <strong>the</strong> choice of time intervals has a significant impact on <strong>the</strong> derivedbehavior: a fact <strong>to</strong>o often neglected in many analyses.The one-period or static approach <strong>to</strong> portfolio selection implicitly assumes that <strong>the</strong>decision and planning horizons are <strong>the</strong> same: "one-period." Moreover, when such modelsare aggregated <strong>to</strong> determine market equilibrium relationships, it is fur<strong>the</strong>r implicitlyassumed that <strong>the</strong>se intervals are <strong>the</strong> same for all inves<strong>to</strong>rs, and t<strong>here</strong>fore, correspond<strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> trading interval. Fur<strong>the</strong>r, when such models are tested, <strong>the</strong> tester usually assumesthat <strong>the</strong>se three intervals are in turn equal <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> observation interval from whichhe has chosen his data.In <strong>the</strong> typical multiperiod, discrete-time analysis, <strong>the</strong> trading and decision intervalsare assumed equal and <strong>the</strong> same for all participants. However, <strong>the</strong> actual time lengthof <strong>the</strong>se intervals is left unspecified. Hence, while usually not recognized explicitly,every such solution derived has as an implicit argument <strong>the</strong> length of <strong>the</strong> time interval,denoted <strong>here</strong> by "h." Clearly, if one were <strong>to</strong> vary <strong>the</strong> "h" in such solutions, <strong>the</strong> derivedbehavior of <strong>the</strong> inves<strong>to</strong>rs would change, as indeed would any deduced equilibrium relationship.Moreover, for any derived behavior <strong>to</strong> be true for an arbitrary discrete-time model(i.e., one w<strong>here</strong> "h" is not specified), it would have <strong>to</strong> be invariant <strong>to</strong> "h." Think aboutwhat this means: such a result would have <strong>to</strong> obtain whe<strong>the</strong>r inves<strong>to</strong>rs had <strong>the</strong> opportunity<strong>to</strong> revise <strong>the</strong>ir portfolios every day or were "frozen" in<strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir investments for tenyears. In this light, it is not surprising that t<strong>here</strong> are few results from <strong>the</strong>se arbitrary


discrete-time models, and those that do obtain are for <strong>the</strong> most part a qualitative na-ture such as: "risk-averse inves<strong>to</strong>rs diversify."By contrast, <strong>the</strong> continuous-time model is very explicit about <strong>the</strong> value of "h":namely, h = 0.Of course, this is only a <strong>the</strong>oretical abstraction since actual continuoustrading is not possible. However, with a few technical exceptions <strong>the</strong> continuous-timesolution is <strong>the</strong> valid continuous limit of <strong>the</strong> discrete-time solution as <strong>the</strong> trading in-terval h tends <strong>to</strong> zero. I.e., given a delta, I can always find an "h" small enough sothat <strong>the</strong> difference between <strong>the</strong> continuous-time solution and its discrete counterpartfor that h is less than delta, using a reasonable metric for measuring "difference."Thus, <strong>the</strong> continuous-time solution is a valid approximation <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> discrete-time solu-tion, and its accuracy is a function of <strong>the</strong> actual structure of returns and <strong>the</strong> lengthof <strong>the</strong> "true" discrete time interval. And it is in this sense that <strong>the</strong> continuous-timeand discrete-time results are consistent.While I thought this correspondence was clear from <strong>the</strong> derivations in my papers, ithas periodically been rediscovered. Indeed, six years after my first paper appeared inprint, a new twist in its rediscovery has been <strong>to</strong> use it <strong>to</strong> argue for <strong>the</strong> superiority ofdiscrete-time analysis over <strong>the</strong> continuous analysis because discrete-time includes con-5tinuous time as a limiting case.While I am on <strong>the</strong> subject of such comparisons, <strong>the</strong> major substantive results ob-tained in discrete-time analysis have required <strong>the</strong> assumption of a specific utility func-tion or family of functions (for example, <strong>the</strong> HARA family). Quite aside from <strong>the</strong> issueof whe<strong>the</strong>r assuming a specific family of utility functions is superior <strong>to</strong> assuming aspecific family of s<strong>to</strong>chastic processes, <strong>the</strong> limited results of sharing rules and separa-tion <strong>the</strong>orems in <strong>the</strong> discrete case not only require inves<strong>to</strong>rs <strong>to</strong> have <strong>the</strong> same utilityfunctions but <strong>the</strong>y also must have <strong>the</strong> same decision interval (what I have called "h").Indeed, for such results <strong>to</strong> be empirically testable, <strong>the</strong> tester will have <strong>to</strong> settle onwhat that interval is. In this sense, <strong>the</strong> discrete analysis is operationally no moregeneral than <strong>the</strong> continuous analysis. Moreover, having looked at <strong>the</strong> data on s<strong>to</strong>ck andbond returns, if that interval is less than a month, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> discrete and continuoussolutions will be virtually <strong>the</strong> same.A more serious criticism of <strong>the</strong> realism of <strong>the</strong> continuous-model is that with trans-actions costs inves<strong>to</strong>rs cannot trade continuously. This is certainly true. Indeed, onereason often given for finite trading-intervals is <strong>to</strong> give implicit, if not explicit,recognition <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong>se costs. I have argued that this is unsatisfac<strong>to</strong>ry because <strong>the</strong>length of time between trades in <strong>the</strong> presence of such costs will almost certainly be"action-oriented" and t<strong>here</strong>fore s<strong>to</strong>chastic in nature, and <strong>the</strong> proper way <strong>to</strong> handle thisproblem is <strong>to</strong> start with <strong>the</strong> continuous-time model and deduce <strong>the</strong> optimal intervals. Ina recent paper, Magill and Constantinides [9] have deduced such solutions, and <strong>the</strong> op-timal trading intervals are discrete and s<strong>to</strong>chastic. Indeed, <strong>the</strong> inves<strong>to</strong>r could end uptrading more than once in a day or not for many months, depending on <strong>the</strong> ex-post timepath followed by prices. The derived behavior for inves<strong>to</strong>rs is <strong>to</strong> trade when <strong>the</strong> gainfrom better diversification offsets <strong>the</strong> cost of transactinq. Their analysis also castslight on an issue raised earlier: namely, t<strong>here</strong> are some cases w<strong>here</strong> <strong>the</strong> limit of <strong>the</strong>discrete-time solution is not <strong>the</strong> continuous solution. For example, if an inves<strong>to</strong>r has5~ee Rubinstein [22, p. 51.


an isoelastic utility function and if security returns are lognormally distributed,<strong>the</strong>n in a standard discrete-time analysis, such an inves<strong>to</strong>r will never choose <strong>to</strong> borrowor shortHowever, in a continuous-time analysis, <strong>the</strong> same inves<strong>to</strong>r may wellchoose <strong>to</strong> borrow or short sell. Which is <strong>the</strong> more "reasonable" description? The Magill-Constantinides analyses demonstrate that even though <strong>the</strong> trading intervals are discretewith probability one, inves<strong>to</strong>rs with utility functions in <strong>the</strong> HARA family may wellchoose <strong>to</strong> borrow or short sell. The reason for <strong>the</strong> difference in derived behavior be-tween <strong>the</strong> standard discrete-time and <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>chastic discrete-time analyses is clear.In <strong>the</strong> former, <strong>the</strong> inves<strong>to</strong>r is "frozen" in<strong>to</strong> holding his portfolio until <strong>the</strong> end of <strong>the</strong>period, and hence by shortselling, or borrowing, risks ruin. In <strong>the</strong> latter, <strong>the</strong> inves<strong>to</strong>rcan revise his portfolio at any time (although he incurs a cost <strong>to</strong> do so) and hence hewill readjust his portfolio, when necessary, <strong>to</strong> avoid ruin. I submit that <strong>the</strong> latter be-havior is a better description of how inves<strong>to</strong>rs behave, and it illustrates why using dis-crete-time analysis as an implicit method of recognizing transactions costs is a poorsubstitute for its explicit recognition in a continuous-time framework.In summary, <strong>the</strong> continuous-time solution is consistent with its discrete-timecounterpart when <strong>the</strong> trading interval is "small," and <strong>to</strong> my mind, <strong>the</strong> assumptions re-quired are descriptive of capital markets as <strong>the</strong>y actually function. Moreover, <strong>the</strong>continuous-time analysis has all <strong>the</strong> virtues of simplicity and empirical tractabilityfound in <strong>the</strong> classic mean-variance analysis but without its objectionable assumptions.~eturning <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> substantive findings of <strong>the</strong> basic consumption-portfolio selec-tion problem, once <strong>the</strong> separation or mutual fund <strong>the</strong>orem is proven, it is straight-forward <strong>to</strong> derive a continuous-time version of <strong>the</strong> Capital Asset Pricing Model. Indeed,in any model w<strong>here</strong> all inves<strong>to</strong>rs hold risky assets in <strong>the</strong> same relative proportions,it follows immediately that this "optimal combination of risky assetso' must be <strong>the</strong> marketportfolio for equilibrium <strong>to</strong> obtain. For if all inves<strong>to</strong>rs want <strong>to</strong> hold risky assetsin <strong>the</strong> same relative proportions, <strong>the</strong>n t<strong>here</strong> is only one way in which this is possible:namely, <strong>the</strong>se relative proportions must he identical <strong>to</strong> those in <strong>the</strong> market portfolio.It t<strong>here</strong>fore follows that among all possible investment strategies, <strong>the</strong> only one thatall inves<strong>to</strong>rs could follow is <strong>the</strong> one that says hold all assets in proportion <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong>irmarket value.Let me remark, somewhat paren<strong>the</strong>tically, that if among <strong>the</strong> soothsayers and strate-gists of Wall Street, t<strong>here</strong> were one best investment strategy, and if this "best" strate-gy became widely known, <strong>the</strong>n whatever <strong>the</strong> original statement of <strong>the</strong> strategy, it mustlead <strong>to</strong> simply this imperative: hold all assets in proportion <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir market value.For suppose such a strategy required that <strong>the</strong> inves<strong>to</strong>r hold equal amounts of Ford andGeneral Mo<strong>to</strong>rs. How could all inves<strong>to</strong>rs following this best strategy do so, unless <strong>the</strong><strong>to</strong>tal value of each were <strong>the</strong> same?Having established that <strong>the</strong> optimal combination of risky assets is <strong>the</strong> market portfolio,<strong>the</strong> Security Market Line relationship follows directly. However, in <strong>the</strong> continuous-6~<strong>here</strong>ason is that <strong>the</strong> lognormal distribution has <strong>the</strong> full range of nonnegativeoutcomes and <strong>the</strong> expected value of <strong>the</strong> marginal utility of an isoelastic utility functionis infinite if t<strong>here</strong> is a positive probability of zero wealth, and undefined fornegative wealth.


time model, it will only hold for short observation intervals, while in <strong>the</strong> originalstatic version, <strong>the</strong> observation interval is never specified.This simple version of <strong>the</strong> continuous-time model has been attacked on <strong>the</strong> groundsthat it is not consistent with intertemporal eq~ilibrium:~ namely, it is claimed thatif all risky assets are held in <strong>the</strong> same proportions throughout time, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> only waythis is possible is if <strong>the</strong> ex-post returns on all assets are <strong>the</strong> same. Of course, thisis nonsense. For this criticism <strong>to</strong> follow, one must make some ra<strong>the</strong>r absurd assumptionsabout <strong>the</strong> supplies of assets. Namely, it must be assumed that firms cannot raise addi-tional investment capital except through internally-generated profits and that firmsmust reinvest all such profits in <strong>the</strong>ir own technology. In o<strong>the</strong>r words, a firm cannotdistribute profits through dividends or share repurchase and it cannot invest in <strong>the</strong>technologies of o<strong>the</strong>r firms. So, for example, in <strong>the</strong> early part of this century, buggywhip manufacturers would have had <strong>to</strong> reinvest all <strong>the</strong>ir profits in fur<strong>the</strong>r production ofbuggy whips, while au<strong>to</strong>mobile manufacturers could not have raised new capital <strong>to</strong> produceau<strong>to</strong>mobiles. Given that a purported major function of <strong>the</strong> capital markets is <strong>the</strong> effi-cient allocation of resources <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> most productive investments, it is not surprisinqthat strange results would follow from such a set of restrictions.I would point out <strong>the</strong> positive results that <strong>the</strong> posited structure of returns in thissimple version of <strong>the</strong> continuous-time model is consistent with intertemporal equilibriumfor a simple wheat economy w<strong>here</strong> <strong>the</strong> different risky assets 'correspond <strong>to</strong> alternative(uncertain) harvest technologies which remain <strong>the</strong> same through time. Indeed, in thiseconomy, equilibrium is achieved through time by a pure quantity adjustment in <strong>the</strong> amoun<strong>to</strong>f wheat allocated <strong>to</strong> each technology.I would also point out that <strong>the</strong> behavior implied by this model is consistent witha changing investment opportunity set if such changes are purely random.That is, evenif <strong>the</strong> expected returns and covariances among those returns do change over time, <strong>the</strong>behavior at each point in time will be as if <strong>the</strong>y are fixed at <strong>the</strong> current levels pro-vided that such changes are completely random. The proof follows along lines used byFama in his 1970 AER article [6].In a closely related interpretation, <strong>the</strong> simple version of <strong>the</strong> model is also con-sistent with an inves<strong>to</strong>r who does not know <strong>the</strong> period-by-period, transi<strong>to</strong>ry expectedreturn and covariance structure, but who does know <strong>the</strong> long-run or steady-state equili-brium structure of returns. For example, an inves<strong>to</strong>r may not know <strong>the</strong> ex-ante expectedreturn on <strong>the</strong> market for <strong>the</strong> next six months, but he may know that his<strong>to</strong>rically, <strong>the</strong>risk premium on <strong>the</strong> market has averaged 7 percent. If he believes that this structureis constant (at least in real terms), <strong>the</strong>n his optimal behavior will be generated byusing this model. Of course, he will still have reason <strong>to</strong> adjust his portfolio overtime <strong>to</strong> achieve <strong>the</strong> appropriate pattern of consumption, <strong>to</strong> maintain diversification,and <strong>to</strong> maintain <strong>the</strong> optimal risk-return mix.This simple version of <strong>the</strong> continuous-time model forms a point of connection be-tween <strong>the</strong> models based on <strong>the</strong> maximization of single-period expected utility of terminalwealth and <strong>the</strong> more general, multiperiod consumption-portfolio models, and t<strong>here</strong>fore is7See Rosenberg and Ohlson [21].


important. However, I view it more as a beginning ra<strong>the</strong>r than a final model.In a recent paper,8 I extended this basic continuous-time model by allowing formultiple sources of uncertainty in addition <strong>to</strong> end-of-period return uncertainty. While<strong>the</strong> concrete examples in that paper focus on <strong>the</strong> impact of a changing investment opportunityset (i.e., <strong>the</strong> case w<strong>here</strong> <strong>the</strong> per period expected returns and covariance structureare changing s<strong>to</strong>chastically over time), I also indicated in a general derivation thatsimilar results would obtain for o<strong>the</strong>r sources of uncertainty, for example, multiple consumptiongoods with uncertain relative prices or when <strong>the</strong> inves<strong>to</strong>r has uncertain wageincome. The changing opportunity set is a particularly important type of uncertaintybecause it only affects intertemporal inves<strong>to</strong>rs and t<strong>here</strong>fore, its impact would nevershow itself in a one-period analysis. For example, an inves<strong>to</strong>r with a one-period planninghorizon facing a specified one-period rate of return structure which includes aninterest rate of 8 percent will not change his optimal portfolio if informed that nextperiod's return structure might have an interest rate of ei<strong>the</strong>r 5 percent or 11 percent,instead of <strong>the</strong> same 8 percent as this period. However, a multiperiod maximizer facing<strong>the</strong> same specified one-period rate of return structure will change his current portfolioholdings upon being informed of <strong>the</strong> changed beliefs about future investment rates. Andthis is so, even though both inves<strong>to</strong>rs are making an investment decision for one periodat a time.In analyzing this model, it was found that, in contrast <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> basic continuous-timemodel, all inves<strong>to</strong>rs will not hold <strong>the</strong> same relative proportions of risky assets, andt<strong>here</strong>fore <strong>the</strong> standard separation or mutual fund <strong>the</strong>orem of Markowitz and Tobin will no<strong>to</strong>btain. However, <strong>the</strong> first-order conditions are still linear in <strong>the</strong> demand functionsfor risky assets, and can, t<strong>here</strong>fore, be solved by matrix inversion. Inspection of <strong>the</strong>sedemand functions reveals a ra<strong>the</strong>r interesting structure. Namely, <strong>the</strong> demand for eachasset can be written as a sum of terms: <strong>the</strong> first term is identical <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> demand derivedin <strong>the</strong> basic model w<strong>here</strong> <strong>the</strong> only source of uncertainty is end-of-period returns. Eacho<strong>the</strong>r term can be identified with a specific additional source of uncertainty. Moreover,differential demand terms have <strong>the</strong> interpretation of being "hedges" by <strong>the</strong> inves<strong>to</strong>ragainst <strong>the</strong>se o<strong>the</strong>r sources of uncertainty. To'see why "hedge" is an appropriate terminology:consider <strong>the</strong> following.The actual path of optimal consumption will be a s<strong>to</strong>chastic process because optimalconsumption is a function of wealth and <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r state variables (e.g., interest rates,prices, and time) which <strong>the</strong>mselves follow s<strong>to</strong>chastic processes. This consumption s<strong>to</strong>chasticprocess will have an expected time path and a variance around that path. In essence,<strong>the</strong> derived differential demands for <strong>the</strong> risky assets are such as <strong>to</strong> minimize <strong>the</strong> varianceof consumption for a given expected time path. So, for example, if an unanticipateddecline in interest rates produces an unanticipated decline in consumption for a givenlevel of wealth, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> inves<strong>to</strong>r will tend <strong>to</strong> hold more of those securities that willproduce higher realized returns in <strong>the</strong> event interest rates do decline. So, in this case,he may hold long maturity bonds. For by doing so, if an unanticipated decline in interestrates does occur, <strong>the</strong>n he will also find himself with an unanticipated higher wealthwhich will tend <strong>to</strong> offset <strong>the</strong>'negative impact of <strong>the</strong> interest rate decline on consumption.


Indeed, this general pattern repeats itself for each additional source of uncer-tainty for which securities can be used <strong>to</strong> hedqe. Moreover, <strong>the</strong> two-mutual fund orseparation <strong>the</strong>orem of <strong>the</strong> basic model generalizes <strong>to</strong> a multifund <strong>the</strong>orem w<strong>here</strong> in addi-tion <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> two funds, t<strong>here</strong> is a fund for each additional source of uncertainty. Ofcourse, <strong>the</strong> term "mutual fund" is used broadly since simple financial instruments likebonds may serve <strong>the</strong> function of some of <strong>the</strong> funds.Thus, in this more general modeL securities have, in addition <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir manifestfunction of providing an "efficient" risk-return tradeoff for end-of-period wealth, alatent function of allowing consumers <strong>to</strong> "hedge" against o<strong>the</strong>r uncertainties.9These findings suggest what I call a "Consumer Services" model of asset pricingwhich falls somew<strong>here</strong> in between a model that considers only <strong>the</strong> uncertainty associatedwith end-of-period wealth (for example, <strong>the</strong> Capital Asset Pricing Model) and <strong>the</strong> completemarkets model of Arrow and Debreu. The model is rich enough <strong>to</strong> explain <strong>the</strong> functions offinancial intermediaries and financial instruments while maintaining sufficient specifi-cation <strong>to</strong> be empirically testable. The basic ideas behind <strong>the</strong> model go as follows below.If we start with <strong>the</strong> Arrow-Debreu model with complete markets w<strong>here</strong> t<strong>here</strong> are moresecurities than states of nature n, <strong>the</strong>n Cass and Stiglitz [3] have proven a "mutualfund" or "separation" <strong>the</strong>orem which states that t<strong>here</strong> can be constructed n mutual fundsor (composite) securities made up of linear combinations of all <strong>the</strong> securities such that(1) all consumer-inves<strong>to</strong>rs would be indifferent between having available just <strong>the</strong>se nmutual funds or all <strong>the</strong> securities; (2) <strong>the</strong> construction of <strong>the</strong>se composite securitiesrequires no knowledge of consumer preferences, wealth allocations, or <strong>the</strong>ir subjectiveprobabilities for each of <strong>the</strong> states of nature.While <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>orem states "indifferent" when t<strong>here</strong> are no transactions costs andinformation is freely available <strong>to</strong> everyone, it is reasonable <strong>to</strong> presume strict prefer-ence for <strong>the</strong> mutual funds if <strong>the</strong> number of securities greatly exceeds <strong>the</strong> number ofstates. Economies of scale in transactions costs and information ga<strong>the</strong>rinq and process-ing make it more sensible <strong>to</strong> have a centralized compilation of <strong>the</strong> distributions foreach of <strong>the</strong> primary securities ra<strong>the</strong>r than have each inves<strong>to</strong>r do it for himself. For<strong>the</strong> same reason, it would make sense for each mutual fund <strong>to</strong> have <strong>the</strong> property of payinga positive amount in one state of nature and zero o<strong>the</strong>rwise (i.e., a set of basic con-tingent claims) ra<strong>the</strong>r than some o<strong>the</strong>r more complicated combination which in <strong>the</strong>orywould be equivalent.Since <strong>the</strong> number of possible states of nature, n, is very large, such a completeset of markets is economically infeasible. T<strong>here</strong> are three basic reasons: (1) t<strong>here</strong> are<strong>the</strong> direct costs of operation of so many separate mutual funds; (2) that despite <strong>the</strong> re-duction in <strong>the</strong> number of securities <strong>to</strong> be analyzed, <strong>the</strong> large size of n would make <strong>the</strong>consumer's information processing costs very larqe; (3) <strong>the</strong> occurrence of certain statesmay be controllable by some consumers (i.e., <strong>the</strong> moral hazard problem). Hence, some"compromise" is obviously required. TO do so, we retain <strong>the</strong> notion that <strong>the</strong> mutual fundapproach is preferred when t<strong>here</strong> are large numbers of securities and large numbers ofrelatively small economic units (e.g., consumers), but we restrict <strong>the</strong> number of funds.Consumers have access <strong>to</strong> limited amounts of information and have limited abilities <strong>to</strong>process <strong>the</strong> information that <strong>the</strong>y have. Fur<strong>the</strong>r, because of <strong>the</strong> costs of informationhis section was originally presented as a part of "A Reexamination of <strong>the</strong> CapitalAsset Pricing Model;' (mimeo) July 1973.


ga<strong>the</strong>ring and processing, one would expect <strong>the</strong> consumer <strong>to</strong> center his attentions on <strong>the</strong>major sources of uncertainty which affect his consumption plan. Hence, it is reasonable<strong>to</strong> assume that <strong>the</strong>se sources of uncertainty can be represented by a finite and not verylarge number of state variables. Fur<strong>the</strong>r, one would expect <strong>the</strong> number and type of mutualfunds that would be created would correspond roughly <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> number and type of major uncertaintieswhich consumers face. The primary prerequisites for such a fund <strong>to</strong> becreated are: (1) <strong>the</strong> source of uncertainty must be important <strong>to</strong> a sufficient number ofconsumers; (2) it must be possible <strong>to</strong> have a standardized contract with payoffs in contingencieswhich are easily recognizable; (3) <strong>the</strong> source of uncertainty must not be controllableby <strong>the</strong> consumer(s). Thus, for some of <strong>the</strong> major uncertainties, it is virtuallyimpossible <strong>to</strong> construct a financial security which would allow <strong>the</strong> consumer <strong>to</strong> hedgeagainst <strong>the</strong>m. Broadly, we would expect <strong>to</strong> find two types of securities traded: (1) "natural"or primary securities, such as common s<strong>to</strong>cks, which are issued by firms <strong>to</strong> financeproduction of real output; (2) financial securities or financial intermediaries created<strong>to</strong> serve <strong>the</strong> purposes of <strong>the</strong> "mutual funds" <strong>to</strong> be derived [namely, <strong>to</strong> aid <strong>the</strong> consumerin achieving a higher (expected) consumption level (through a return <strong>to</strong> capital), abetter intertemporal allocation of resources (by not requiring that savings equals investmentat each point in time), a lower level of risk (by providing hedges against <strong>the</strong>major (common) sources of uncertainty faced by <strong>the</strong> consumer)].The individual consumer's demand for assets can be partitioned as follows: forthose important sources of uncertainty which he faces in common with o<strong>the</strong>r consumers, hewill take positions in <strong>the</strong> mutual funds or financial securities created for that purpose.For those important sources of uncertainty for which no mutual fund exists (ei<strong>the</strong>r becauseit is specialized <strong>to</strong> him or t<strong>here</strong> is in<strong>here</strong>nt moral hazard), he will take positionsin those primary securities, if <strong>the</strong>y exist, <strong>to</strong> hedge. For those sources of uncertaintyfor which no security is a hedge and for those sources which he simply neglects in hisanalysis, no security position can help so his (differential) demand for securities willbe unaffected.As an example, if <strong>the</strong> consumers are one-period maximizers of <strong>the</strong> utility of meanand variance of end-of-period wealth, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> well-known separation or two-fund <strong>the</strong>oremobtains. Namely, each inves<strong>to</strong>r will be indifferent between selecting a portfolio fromall <strong>the</strong> primary securities and from two funds: (1) <strong>the</strong> market portfolio of risky assetsand (2) a riskless asset. Presumably, such funds or financial instruments would becreated since t<strong>here</strong> is an obvious common demand. However, consider an inves<strong>to</strong>r who alsohas (uncertain) labor income which he cannot sell forward <strong>to</strong> eliminate its risk becauseof <strong>the</strong> moral hazard problem. Suppose fur<strong>the</strong>r that it is a very highly-specialized formof labor which can only be used by one company (or a small number of similar companies).Then, from risk-aversion, it would be natural <strong>to</strong> suppose that this inves<strong>to</strong>r would want<strong>to</strong> hold less of this company's s<strong>to</strong>ck <strong>to</strong> hedge aqainst unfavorable changes in his laborincome. If, on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r hand, t<strong>here</strong> were no security whose outcome was correlated withthis particular source of uncertainty, he can do nothing <strong>to</strong> hedge, and his optimal portfoliowould be generated by <strong>the</strong> two mutual funds alone.Thus, <strong>to</strong> a reasonable approximation, most of <strong>the</strong> aggregate demand for <strong>the</strong> individualprimary securities can be viewed as coming in an "indirect" way through mutual funds,


i.e., individual consumers for <strong>the</strong> most part only purchase a relatively small number ofcomposite financial securities or mutual funds. Mutual fund managers serve <strong>the</strong> functionof purchasing <strong>the</strong> primary securities <strong>to</strong> form <strong>the</strong> portfolio necessary <strong>to</strong> perform <strong>the</strong>seservices. T<strong>here</strong>fore, <strong>the</strong> aggregate demand for a primary security will depend on how itsreturn contributes <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> formation of <strong>the</strong>se "service" portfolios.Since <strong>the</strong> equilibrium expected return on an asset is "determined" in part by <strong>the</strong>aggregate demand for it, one would expect <strong>to</strong> find a correspondence between its expectedreturn and <strong>the</strong> statistical dependence between <strong>the</strong> asset's return and <strong>the</strong> various majorsources of uncertainty. All risk-averse consumers would prefer <strong>to</strong> have less uncertaintyfor <strong>the</strong> same expected consumption stream, and t<strong>here</strong>fore would "give up" some (expected)return on an asset in return for that asset providing a hedqe against some of <strong>the</strong>se uncertainties.Hence, <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> extent that any asset's return contributes <strong>to</strong> (or aggravates)<strong>the</strong> consumers' attempts <strong>to</strong> hedge against <strong>the</strong>se uncertainties, one would expect <strong>the</strong>equilibrium return on that asset <strong>to</strong> be affected. If, on average, a particular asset'sreturn contributes <strong>to</strong> consumers' attempts <strong>to</strong> hedge against a common source of uncertainty,<strong>the</strong>n one would expect <strong>the</strong> equilibrium expected return on that asset <strong>to</strong> be differentiallylower than on a similar asset which does not provide that "service." This negative differentialin expected return can be interpreted as <strong>the</strong> market "cost" <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> consumerfor <strong>the</strong> hedging service provided by this asset. If, on average, an asset's returnaggravates consumers' attempts <strong>to</strong> hedqe, than its equilibrium expected return would bedifferentially higher, and this positive differential in expected return can be interpretedas <strong>the</strong> market "premium" <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> consumer in return for bearing <strong>the</strong> extra riskcaused by holding this asset. A simple illustration of this principle can be found in<strong>the</strong> CAPM. Since <strong>the</strong> only source of uncertainty is end-of-period wealth and all inves<strong>to</strong>rsare assumed <strong>to</strong> be risk-averse, a given inves<strong>to</strong>r would view an asset as providing a("diversification") service if it lowers <strong>the</strong> variance of his end-of-period wealth andhence, would accept a lower expected return on this asset than on one which did not providethis service. However, since all inves<strong>to</strong>rs' optimal portfolios are perfectly correlated,an asset which aids diversification for one inves<strong>to</strong>r does so for all inves<strong>to</strong>rs,and t<strong>here</strong>fore, all inves<strong>to</strong>rs would accept a lower expected return on this asset. Inspectionof <strong>the</strong> Security Market Line, indeed shows this is <strong>the</strong> case.However, with respect <strong>to</strong> most sources of uncertainty, such unanimity among inves<strong>to</strong>rs'views of whe<strong>the</strong>r an asset contributes <strong>to</strong> risk or not will be <strong>the</strong> exception. Thus, onegroup of consumers may consider a long position in an asset as contributing <strong>to</strong> a reductionof <strong>the</strong> risks it perceives, while ano<strong>the</strong>r group may view a short position as contributing<strong>to</strong> a reduction in its risks. Thus, whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> equilibrium expected return on <strong>the</strong>asset reflects a differential cost or premium will depend on <strong>the</strong> aggregation of inves<strong>to</strong>rs'demands, and unless t<strong>here</strong> is a systematic "weak side" <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> market, <strong>the</strong> sign of <strong>the</strong> differentialmay fluctuate through time. One example of this type is <strong>the</strong> Modigliani-Sutch[I91 Habitat <strong>the</strong>ory of bond pricing. If a consumer has preferences which induce riskaversionwith respect <strong>to</strong> wealth, <strong>the</strong>n he will view long-term bonds as risky and wouldrequire a market premium over short-term bonds <strong>to</strong> hold <strong>the</strong>m. However, if a consumerhas preferences which induce risk-aversion with respect <strong>to</strong> income, <strong>the</strong>n short-term bondsare risky <strong>to</strong> him, and he would require a market premium over long-term bonds <strong>to</strong> hold <strong>the</strong>m.


Thus, with respect <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> uncertainty about future interest rates, <strong>the</strong> differential expectedreturn between long- and short-term bonds could be of ei<strong>the</strong>r sign.To determine <strong>the</strong> types of securities one would expect <strong>to</strong> find and <strong>the</strong> sources ofdifferentials in expected returns, it is necessary <strong>to</strong> establish what <strong>the</strong> important uncertaintiesare for a typical consumer in making his plan. Although not a complete listing,<strong>the</strong>following seven items would seem <strong>to</strong> cover most of <strong>the</strong> important common sourcesof uncertainty for a consumer:(S.1) Uncertainty about his own future tastes;(S.2) Uncertainty about <strong>the</strong> menu of possible consumption goods that will beavailable <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> future;(5.3) Uncertainty about relative prices of consumption goods;(S.4) Uncertainty about his labor income;(S.5) Uncertainty about future values of nonhuman assets;(S.6) Uncertainty about <strong>the</strong> future investment opportunity set; i.e., <strong>the</strong>future rates of return which can be earned on capital;(5.7) Uncertainty about <strong>the</strong> age of death.While all of <strong>the</strong>se have been considered in one model or ano<strong>the</strong>r, it is important <strong>to</strong> notethat those models based on <strong>the</strong> criterion of maximizing <strong>the</strong> expected utility of end-ofperiodwealth explicitly take in<strong>to</strong> account only <strong>the</strong> uncertainty associated with nonhumanwealth. Included in this class of models is <strong>the</strong> CAPM.Even though all <strong>the</strong>se uncertainties are important <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> consumer, not all willdifferentially affect security prices'or returns. It is difficult <strong>to</strong> imagine a financialsecurity which could reduce <strong>the</strong> uncertainties associated with one's own future tastes or<strong>the</strong> menu of possible consumption goods in <strong>the</strong> future. While uncertainty about <strong>the</strong> ageof death is an important problem for all consumers and life insurance was created inresponse <strong>to</strong> this demand, <strong>the</strong> event of death is probably reasonably statistically independentacross people, and it is unlikely that <strong>the</strong> returns on securities (o<strong>the</strong>r than lifeinsurance policies) would be statistically dependent on <strong>the</strong> event of an individual'sdeath. Hence, one would not expect this source of uncertainty <strong>to</strong> have differential effectson security prices. The risks associated with labor income can be completelyeliminated if <strong>the</strong> consumer could sell forward his wage income in <strong>the</strong> same way shares areissued on nonhuman capital. But, because of <strong>the</strong> moral hazard problem, it is difficultfor <strong>the</strong> consumer <strong>to</strong> do so. While some of <strong>the</strong> individual risk can be eliminated by disabilityand life insurance and by "investing" in education <strong>to</strong> make his labor more substitutableacross finns, t<strong>here</strong> still will be systemath risk due <strong>to</strong> (unanticipated)shifts in capital and labor's relative shares (i.e., <strong>the</strong> wage-rental ratio). This uncertaintycould produce a differential demand for shares in labor-intensive versus capitalintensiveindustries. Similarly, inflation risk may cause differentials in demand betweendifferent maturity "money" securities. Although information costs and <strong>the</strong> uncertaintiesabout tastes and future products prohibit complete future markets for consumption goods,it is reasonable <strong>to</strong> expect consumers <strong>to</strong> differentiate broad classes of consumption (e.g.,housing, food, transportation, clothing, and recreation) and hence, differentials indemand for shares in different industries could occur as <strong>the</strong> result of uncertainty aboutrelative consumption good prices. The standard end-of-period wealth uncertainty will


induce differential demands for those securities which aid diversification. Finally,if t<strong>here</strong> is uncertainty about <strong>the</strong> rates of return which will be available in <strong>the</strong> future,differential demands may occur between long- and short-term bonds and between shares offirms whose returns are sensitive <strong>to</strong> shifts in capitalization rates versus ones thatare not.If <strong>the</strong>se are <strong>the</strong> sources of uncertainty common <strong>to</strong> most inves<strong>to</strong>rs, <strong>the</strong>n we canidentify a set of mutual funds which would be (approximately) sufficient <strong>to</strong> span <strong>the</strong>space of consumers' optimal portfolios. Specifically, we might identify <strong>the</strong>se funds <strong>to</strong>be: (1) <strong>the</strong> "market" portfolio; (2) a (short-term) riskless asset; hedging portfoliosfor unanticipated; (3) shifts in rates of return; (4) shifts in <strong>the</strong> wage-rental ratio;(5) changes in prices for basic groups of consumption goods. Fur<strong>the</strong>r, consumer demandsfor individual securities can be written as if <strong>the</strong>y came indirectly through <strong>the</strong> demandsfor <strong>the</strong>se mutual funds. Hence, <strong>the</strong> equilibrium expected return on a security will be afunction of <strong>the</strong> expected return on each of <strong>the</strong>se funds and <strong>the</strong> statistical dependencebetween <strong>the</strong> security's return and <strong>the</strong> return on each of <strong>the</strong>se funds.Indeed, this model is testable in its continuous-time formulation because, inequilibrium, <strong>the</strong> expected excess return on an individual security will be equal <strong>to</strong> aweighted sum of <strong>the</strong> excess returns on <strong>the</strong> mutual funds w<strong>here</strong> <strong>the</strong> weights will equal <strong>the</strong>instantaneous multiple regression coefficients between <strong>the</strong> return on <strong>the</strong> individualsecurity and <strong>the</strong> returns on <strong>the</strong> funds. This result is a natural generalization of <strong>the</strong>standard Security Market Line <strong>to</strong> a Security Market Hyperplane:For my last <strong>to</strong>pic, I turn <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory for pricing financial instruments and inparticular <strong>the</strong> pricing of corporate liabilities. It is <strong>here</strong> w<strong>here</strong> <strong>the</strong> continuous-timeanalysis has had its greatest impact. In what may be one of <strong>the</strong> most important contri-10butions <strong>to</strong> Finance in this decade, Fischer Black and Myron Scholes used <strong>the</strong> continuous-time analysis <strong>to</strong> deduce a formula for common s<strong>to</strong>ck options. In essence, <strong>the</strong>y were able<strong>to</strong> demonstrate that by following a specified dynamic portfolio policy consisting of mix-tures of positions in <strong>the</strong> underlying common s<strong>to</strong>ck and riskless borrowing or lending,<strong>the</strong>y could exactly replicate <strong>the</strong> payoff structure associated with a call option.Given this demonstration, it is immediately obvious that this portfolio strategyis a perfect substitute for <strong>the</strong> option, and indeed, any two of <strong>the</strong> three securities in-volved can be combined in an appropriate portfolio strategy <strong>to</strong> exactly replicate <strong>the</strong>payoff structure of <strong>the</strong> third. Hence, given <strong>the</strong> prices of any two of <strong>the</strong> securities(for example, <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck and riskless bond), <strong>the</strong> third security's price (in this case <strong>the</strong>option) is uniquely determined, i.e., <strong>the</strong>ir analysis is clearly a relative pricinq <strong>the</strong>ory.Having solved <strong>the</strong> call option case, it is straightforward <strong>to</strong> see that <strong>the</strong> same tech-nique can be used <strong>to</strong> price o<strong>the</strong>r types of options, and from t<strong>here</strong>, it is not a long step<strong>to</strong> recognize that <strong>the</strong>ir approach is equally valid when applied <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> firm as a whole <strong>to</strong>price its entire capital structure. As a result, <strong>the</strong>ir analysis has led <strong>to</strong> a unified10 See Black and Scholes [I]. For fur<strong>the</strong>r discussion, see Mer<strong>to</strong>n [121.


<strong>the</strong>ory for pricing of virtually any financial claim on <strong>the</strong> firm.'I view <strong>the</strong> Black-Scholes contribution in three parts. The first and most importantpart is <strong>the</strong> initial insight in setting up <strong>the</strong> problem. The second part is <strong>the</strong> developmen<strong>to</strong>f a quantitative formula based for <strong>the</strong> most part on observable br reasonably estimatedvariables. In particular, ra<strong>the</strong>r surprisingly, consumer preferences and <strong>the</strong> expectedreturn on <strong>the</strong> underlying s<strong>to</strong>ck do not enter <strong>the</strong> formula. Moreover, one need noteven assume that <strong>the</strong> market is in equilibrium. Of course, a quantitative formula is importantbecause it allows for empirical testing and for its direct use in applications.This is one of those rare cases w<strong>here</strong> a piece of analysis conceived entirely in <strong>the</strong>oryhas had an immediate and important impact on actual operations. Indeed, <strong>the</strong> Black-Scholesformula is widely used by most firms trading in <strong>the</strong> option market. The third part isthat <strong>the</strong> Black-Scholes analysis has led <strong>to</strong> some important qualitative propositions. Forexample, it is widely held that <strong>the</strong> Modigliani-Miller irrelevance-of-financing <strong>the</strong>oremdoes not hold when t<strong>here</strong> is a positive probability of bankruptcy because in such cases,personal borrowing and corporate borrowing are no longer perfect substitutes for oneano<strong>the</strong>r. The Black-Scholes type analysis can be used <strong>to</strong> demonstrate that this conclusionis false. Namely, while no fixed portfolio strategy can replicate <strong>the</strong> nonlinear payoffstructure of such corporate debt, a continuous-time, dynamic portfolio strategy can.Also, some earlier studiesL2 attempted <strong>to</strong> use warrant price and s<strong>to</strong>ck price comparisons<strong>to</strong> estimate inves<strong>to</strong>r's expectations for <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck or inves<strong>to</strong>r's risk preferences.But since <strong>the</strong> Black-Scholes formula requires nei<strong>the</strong>r as inputs for pricing warrants, itclearly demonstrates that such attempts are doomed <strong>to</strong> failure.Since <strong>the</strong> pricing formula does not depend upon knowledge of <strong>the</strong> expected return on<strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck, both Bulls and Bears who agree on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r inputs, will agree on <strong>the</strong> priceof <strong>the</strong> option relative <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck, or <strong>the</strong> prices of <strong>the</strong> individual elements of <strong>the</strong>capital structure relative <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>to</strong>tal value of <strong>the</strong> firm. This demonstrates that <strong>the</strong>inves<strong>to</strong>r's decision as <strong>to</strong> what investment action <strong>to</strong> take in regard <strong>to</strong> a specific firmcan be separated in<strong>to</strong> two parts. First, in an evaluation of <strong>the</strong> firm as a whole, is ita good or bad investment? Second, given this decision, what financial claim on <strong>the</strong> firmis <strong>the</strong> best vehicle for ei<strong>the</strong>r being long or short in <strong>the</strong> firm? Since <strong>the</strong> Black-Scholesformula requires an estimate of <strong>the</strong> variance on <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck, it has created a demand forfur<strong>the</strong>r research in<strong>to</strong> estimation techniques for variances.While much of <strong>the</strong> research in this area is still in progress,13 I believe that beforelong we will have answers <strong>to</strong> many of <strong>the</strong> long outstanding questions about corporate financingpolicy including a rationale for debt tar<strong>get</strong>s and debt capacity, and a quantitativeanalysis of <strong>the</strong> optimal debt structure when interest payments are deductible.Moreover, most of <strong>the</strong> assumptions required in <strong>the</strong> original Black-Scholes derivationhave been substantially weakened in more recent research with no significant changes in<strong>the</strong>ir more important conclusions.While time does not permit me <strong>to</strong> cover all <strong>the</strong> continuous-time research going on in'seMer<strong>to</strong>n [12, 151 and Ingersoll [a].12See Sprenkle [861.13~nexcellent survey can be found in Smith [25].


Finance, I will simply mention <strong>the</strong> Solnik [271 analysis in international capital markets,<strong>the</strong> Richard [201 analysis of <strong>the</strong> demand for insurance, <strong>the</strong> Fischer [71 analysis of indexlinkedbonds, and Scheffman [24] analysis of <strong>the</strong> optimal investment decision by firms.In summary, <strong>the</strong> continuous-time mode of analysis has proved fruitful in analyzingsome of <strong>the</strong> basic problems in Finance. The costs associated with <strong>get</strong>ting <strong>the</strong>se resultsare <strong>the</strong> twin assumptions that markets are open most of <strong>the</strong> time and that <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>chasticprocesses can be described by ei<strong>the</strong>r diffusion or compound Poisson processes. The benefitsare generally sharper results that are easier <strong>to</strong> interpret than in <strong>the</strong> discretetimecase, and an enormous literature on <strong>the</strong>se s<strong>to</strong>chastic processes which allows one <strong>to</strong>analyze ra<strong>the</strong>r complex models and still <strong>get</strong> quantitative results.REFERENCES[I] Black, F., and M. Scholes. "The Pricing of Options and Corporate Liabilities."Journal of Political Economy, vol. 81 (1973), pp. 637-659.[21 . "The Valuation of Option Contracts and a Test of Market Efficiency."Journal of Finance,vol. 27 (1972), pp. 399-417.[3] Cass, D., and J. Stiglitz. "The Structure of Inves<strong>to</strong>r Preferences and Asset Returns,and Separability in Portfolio Allocation: A Contribution <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> Pure Theoryof Mutual Funds." Journal of Economic Theory, vol. 2 (1970), pp. 122-160.[4] Cox, J., and S. Ross. "The Pricing of Options for Jump Processes." Journal ofFinancial Economics, (forthcoming).[51 Farna, E. "Efficient Capital Markets: A Review of Theory and Empirical Work."Journal of Finance, vol. 25 (19701, pp. 383-417.[GI. "Multiperiod Consumption-Investment Decisions." American EconomicReview, vol. 60 (1970), pp. 163-174.[71 Fischer, S. "The Demand for Index Bonds." Journal of Political Economy, vol. 83(1975), pp. 509-534.[81 Ingersoll, J. "A Theoretical and Empirical Investigation of <strong>the</strong> Dual Purpose Funds:An Application of Contingent Claims Analysis." Journal of Financial Economics,(forthcoming).[91 Magill, M., and G. Constantinides. "Portfolio Selection with Transactions Costs."Journal of Economic Theory, (forthcoming).[lo] Mer<strong>to</strong>n, R. C. "Lifetime Portfolio Selection under Uncertainty: The Continuous-TimeCase." Review of Economics and Statistics, vol. 51 (1969), pp. 247-257.[Ill. "Optimum Consumption and Portfolio Rules in a Continuous Time Model."Journal of Economic Theory, vol. 3 (1971), pp. 373-413.[I21 . "Theory of Rational Option Pricing." Bell Journal of Economics andManagement Science, vol. 4 (19731, pp. 141-183.[131 . "An Intertemporal Capital Asset Pricing Model." Econometrica, vol. 41(1973), pp. 867-887.[I41 . "Appendix: Continuous-Time Speculative Processes." In P. A. Samuelson,"Ma<strong>the</strong>matics of Speculative Price," SIAM Review.[I51 . "On <strong>the</strong> Pricing of Corporate Debt: The Risk Structure of InterestRates." Journal of Finance, vol. 29 (1974) , pp. 449-470.


[161 . "Option Pricing when Underlying S<strong>to</strong>ck Returns Are Discontinuous."Journal of Financial Economics, (forthcoming).[18] Mer<strong>to</strong>n, R. C., and P. A. Samuelson. "Fallacy of <strong>the</strong> Log-Normal ~pproximation <strong>to</strong>Optimal Portfolio Decision-Making over Many Periods." Journal of Financial Economics,vol. 1 (1974), pp. 67-94.[191 Modigliani, F., and R. Sutch. "Innovations in Interest Rate Policy." AmericanEconomic Review, vol. 56 (1966), pp. 178-197.[20] Richard, S. "Optimal Consumption, Portfolio and Life Insurance Rules for an UncertainLived Individual in a Continuous-Time Model." Journal of Financial Economics,vol 2 (1975), pp. 187-204.[21] Rosenberg, B., and J. Ohlson. "The Stationary Distribution of Returns and PortfolioSeparation in Capital Markets: A Fundamental Contradiction." University ofCalifornia, Berkeley (unpublished, 1973).[221 Rubinstein, M. "The Strong Case for <strong>the</strong> Generalized Logarithmic Utility Model as<strong>the</strong> Premier Model of Financial Markets." W. P. #34, Institute of Business and EconomicResearch, University of California, Berkeley (1975).[23] Samuelson, P. A. "Proof that Properly Anticipated Prices Fluctuate Randomly."Industrial Management Review, vol. 6 (1965), pp. 41-49.[241 Scheffman, D. "'Optimal' Investment under Uncertainty." University of WesternOntario (unpublished, 1975).[25] Smith, C. "Option Pricing: A Review." Journal of Financial Economics,(forthcoming).[26] Sprenkle, C. "Warrant Prices as Indica<strong>to</strong>rs of Expectations and Preferences." InThe Random Character of S<strong>to</strong>ck Market Prices, edited by P. Cootner. Cambridge:M.I.T. Press, pp. 412-474.[271 Solnik, B. European Capital Markets. Lexing<strong>to</strong>n, Mass: Lexing<strong>to</strong>n Books (1973).


The Capital Asset Pricing ModelAndré F. PeroldThe Journal of Economic Perspectives, Vol. 18, No. 3. (Summer, 2004), pp. 3-24.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0895-3309%28200422%2918%3A3%3C3%3ATCAPM%3E2.0.CO%3B2-ZThe Journal of Economic Perspectives is currently published by American Economic Association.Your use of <strong>the</strong> JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available athttp://www.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/about/terms.html. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtainedprior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in<strong>the</strong> JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use.Please contact <strong>the</strong> publisher regarding any fur<strong>the</strong>r use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained athttp://www.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/journals/aea.html.Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain <strong>the</strong> same copyright notice that appears on <strong>the</strong> screen or printedpage of such transmission.The JSTOR Archive is a trusted digital reposi<strong>to</strong>ry providing for long-term preservation and access <strong>to</strong> leading academicjournals and scholarly literature from around <strong>the</strong> world. The Archive is supported by libraries, scholarly societies, publishers,and foundations. It is an initiative of JSTOR, a not-for-profit organization with a mission <strong>to</strong> help <strong>the</strong> scholarly community takeadvantage of advances in technology. For more information regarding JSTOR, please contact support@js<strong>to</strong>r.org.http://www.js<strong>to</strong>r.orgMon Dec 17 05:49:47 2007


Journal of Economic Perspectives-Volume 18, Number 3-Summer 2004 -Pages 3-24The Capital Asset Pricing ModelAndr6 F. Peroldfundamental question in finance is how <strong>the</strong> risk of an investment shouldaffect its expected return. The Capital Asset Pricing Model (CAPM)provided <strong>the</strong> first co<strong>here</strong>nt framework for answering this question. TheCAPM was developed in <strong>the</strong> early 1960s by William Sharpe (1964),Jack Treynor(1962),John Lintner (1965a, b) and Jan Mossin (1966).The CAPM is based on <strong>the</strong> idea that not all risks should affect asset prices. Inparticular, a risk that can be diversified away when held along with o<strong>the</strong>r investmentsin a portfolio is, in a very real way, not a risk at all. The CAPM gives usinsights about what kind of risk is related <strong>to</strong> return. This paper lays out <strong>the</strong> key ideasof <strong>the</strong> Capital Asset Pricing Model, places its development in a his<strong>to</strong>rical context,and discusses its applications and enduring importance <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> field of finance.His<strong>to</strong>rical BackgroundIn retrospect, it is striking how little we unders<strong>to</strong>od about risk as late as <strong>the</strong>1960s-whe<strong>the</strong>r in terms of <strong>the</strong>ory or empirical evidence. After all, s<strong>to</strong>ck andoption markets had been in existence at least since 1602 when shares of <strong>the</strong> EastIndia Company began trading in Amsterdam (de la Vega, 1688); and organizedinsurance markets had become well developed by <strong>the</strong> 1700s (Bernstein, 1996). By1960, insurance businesses had for centuries been relying on diversification <strong>to</strong>spread risk. But despite <strong>the</strong> long his<strong>to</strong>ry of actual risk-bearing and risk-sharing inorganized financial markets, <strong>the</strong> Capital Asset Pricing Model was developed at atime when <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>oretical foundations of decision making under uncertainty wererelatively new and when basic empirical facts about risk and return in <strong>the</strong> capitalmarkets were not yet known.Andre' F. Perold is <strong>the</strong> George Gund Professor of Finance and Banking, Harvard BusinessSchool, Bos<strong>to</strong>n, Massachusetts. His e-mail address is (aperoldQhbs.edu).


4 Journal of Economic PerspectivesRigorous <strong>the</strong>ories of inves<strong>to</strong>r risk preferences and decision-making underuncertainty emerged only in <strong>the</strong> 1940s and 1950s, especially in <strong>the</strong> work of vonNeumann and Morgenstern (1944) and Savage (1954). Portfolio <strong>the</strong>ory, showinghow inves<strong>to</strong>rs can create portfolios of individual investments <strong>to</strong> optimally trade offrisk versus return, was not developed until <strong>the</strong> early 1950s by Harry Markowitz(1952, 1959) and Roy (1952).Equally noteworthy, <strong>the</strong> empirical measurement of risk and return was in itsinfancy until <strong>the</strong> 1960s, when sufficient computing power became available so thatresearchers were able <strong>to</strong> collect, s<strong>to</strong>re and process market data for <strong>the</strong> purposes ofscientific investigation. The first careful study of returns on s<strong>to</strong>cks listed on <strong>the</strong> NewYork S<strong>to</strong>ck Exchange was that of Fisher and Lorie (1964) in which <strong>the</strong>y note: "It issurprising <strong>to</strong> realize that t<strong>here</strong> have been no measurements of <strong>the</strong> rates of returnon investments in common s<strong>to</strong>cks that could be considered accurate and definitive."In that paper, Fisher and Lorie report average s<strong>to</strong>ck market returns overdifferent holding periods since 1926, but not <strong>the</strong> standard deviation of thosereturns. They also do not report any particular estimate of <strong>the</strong> equity risk premium-thatis, <strong>the</strong> average amount by which <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck market outperformedrisk-free investments-although <strong>the</strong>y do remark that rates of return on commons<strong>to</strong>cks were "substantially higher than safer alternatives for which data are available."Measured standard deviations of broad s<strong>to</strong>ck market returns did not appearin <strong>the</strong> academic literature until Fisher and Lorie (1968). Carefully constructedestimates of <strong>the</strong> equity risk premium did not appear until Ibbotson and Sinquefield(1976) published <strong>the</strong>ir findings on long-term rates of return. They found that over<strong>the</strong> period 1926 <strong>to</strong> 1974, <strong>the</strong> (arithmetic) average return on <strong>the</strong> Standard andPoor's 500 index was 10.9 percent per annum, and <strong>the</strong> excess return over U.S.Treasury bills was 8.8 percent per annum.' The first careful study of <strong>the</strong> his<strong>to</strong>ricalequity risk premium for UK s<strong>to</strong>cks appeared in Dimson and Brealey (19'78) with anestimate of 9.2 percent per annum over <strong>the</strong> period 1919-19'77.In <strong>the</strong> 1940s and 1950s, prior <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> development of <strong>the</strong> Capital Asset PricingModel, <strong>the</strong> reigning paradigm for estimating expected returns presupposed that<strong>the</strong> return that inves<strong>to</strong>rs would require (or <strong>the</strong> "cost of capital") of an assetdepended primarily on <strong>the</strong> manner in which that asset was financed (for example,Bierman and Smidt, 1966). T<strong>here</strong> was a "cost of equity capital" and a "cost of debtcapital," and <strong>the</strong> weighted average of <strong>the</strong>se-based on <strong>the</strong> relative amounts of debtand equity financing-represented <strong>the</strong> cost of capital of <strong>the</strong> asset.The costs of debt and equity capital were inferred from <strong>the</strong> long-term yields ofthose instruments. The cost of debt capital was typically assumed <strong>to</strong> be <strong>the</strong> rate ofinterest owed on <strong>the</strong> debt, and <strong>the</strong> cost of equity capital was backed out from <strong>the</strong>cash flows that inves<strong>to</strong>rs could expect <strong>to</strong> receive on <strong>the</strong>ir shares in relation <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong>current price of <strong>the</strong> shares. A popular method of estimating <strong>the</strong> cost of equity thisway was <strong>the</strong> Gordon and Shapiro (1956) model, in which a company's dividends areThese are arithmetic average returns. Ibbotson and Sinquefield (1976) were also <strong>the</strong> first <strong>to</strong> report <strong>the</strong>term premium on long-term bonds: 1.1 percent per annum average return in excess of Treasury billsover <strong>the</strong> period 1926-1974.


Andre' F. Perold5assumed <strong>to</strong> grow in perpetuity at a constant rate g. In this model, if a firm's currentdividend per share is D, and <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck price of <strong>the</strong> firm is P, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> cost of equitycapital r is <strong>the</strong> dividend yield plus <strong>the</strong> dividend growth rate: r = D/P + g.2From <strong>the</strong> perspective of modern finance, this approach <strong>to</strong> determining <strong>the</strong>cost of capital was anchored in <strong>the</strong> wrong place. At least in a frictionless world, <strong>the</strong>value of a firm or an asset more broadly does not depend on how it is financed, asshown by Modigliani and Miller (1958). This means that <strong>the</strong> cost of equity capitallikely is determined by <strong>the</strong> cost of capital of <strong>the</strong> asset, ra<strong>the</strong>r than <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r wayaround. Moreover, this process of inferring <strong>the</strong> cost of equity capital from futuredividend growth rates is highly subjective. T<strong>here</strong> is no simple way <strong>to</strong> determine <strong>the</strong>market's forecast of <strong>the</strong> growth rate of future cash flows, and companies with highdividend growth rates will be judged by this method <strong>to</strong> have high costs of equitycapital. Indeed, <strong>the</strong> Capital Asset Pricing Model will show that t<strong>here</strong> need not beany connection between <strong>the</strong> cost of capital and future growth rates of cash flows.In <strong>the</strong> pre-CAPM paradigm, risk did not enter directly in<strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> computation of <strong>the</strong>cost of capital. The working assumption was often that a firm that can be financedmostly with debt is probably safe and is thus assumed <strong>to</strong> have a low cost of capital; whilea firm that cannot support much debt is probably risky and is thus assumed <strong>to</strong>command a high cost of capital. These rules-of-thumb for incorporating risk in<strong>to</strong>discount rates were ad hoc at best. As Modigliani and Miller (1958) noted: "Nosatisfac<strong>to</strong>ry explanation has yet been provided . . . as <strong>to</strong> what determines <strong>the</strong> size of <strong>the</strong>risk [adjustment] and how it varies in response <strong>to</strong> changes in o<strong>the</strong>r variables."In short, before <strong>the</strong> arrival of <strong>the</strong> Capital Asset Pricing Model, <strong>the</strong> question of howexpected returns and risk were related had been posed, but was still awaiting an answer.Why Inves<strong>to</strong>rs Might Differ in Their Pricing of RiskIntuitively, it would seem that inves<strong>to</strong>rs should demand high returns forholding high-risk investments. That is, <strong>the</strong> price of a high-risk asset should be bidsufficiently low so that <strong>the</strong> future payoffs on <strong>the</strong> asset are high (relative <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong>price). A difficulty with this reasoning arises, however, when <strong>the</strong> risk of an investmentdepends on <strong>the</strong> manner in which it is held.To illustrate, consider an entrepreneur who needs <strong>to</strong> raise $1million for a riskynew venture. T<strong>here</strong> is a 90 percent chance that <strong>the</strong> venture will fail and end upworthless; and t<strong>here</strong> is a 10 percent chance that <strong>the</strong> venture will succeed within ayear and be worth $40 million. The expected value of <strong>the</strong> venture in one year ist<strong>here</strong>fore $4 million, or $4 per share assuming that <strong>the</strong> venture will have a millionshares outstanding.Case I: If a single risk-averse individual were <strong>to</strong> fund <strong>the</strong> full $1 million-w<strong>here</strong>'The cost of equity capital in this model is <strong>the</strong> "internal rate of return," <strong>the</strong> discount rate that equates <strong>the</strong>present value of future cash flows <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> current s<strong>to</strong>ck price. In <strong>the</strong> GordonShapiro model, <strong>the</strong> projecteddividend stream is D, D(l + g),D ( l + g)2. . . The present value of <strong>the</strong>se cash flows when discounted at rater is D / ( r - g),which when set equal <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> current s<strong>to</strong>ck price, P, establishes r = D/P + g.


6 Journal of Economic Perspectives<strong>the</strong> investment would represent a significant portion of <strong>the</strong> wealth of thatindividual-<strong>the</strong> venture would have <strong>to</strong> deliver a very high expected return, say100 percent. To achieve an expected return of 100 percent on an investment of $1million, <strong>the</strong> entrepreneur would have <strong>to</strong> sell <strong>the</strong> inves<strong>to</strong>r a 50 percent stake:300,000 shares at a price per share of $2.Case 11: If <strong>the</strong> funds could be raised from someone who can diversify acrossmany such investments, <strong>the</strong> required return might be much lower. Consider aninves<strong>to</strong>r who has $100 million <strong>to</strong> invest in 100 ventures with <strong>the</strong> same payoffs andprobabilities as above, except that <strong>the</strong> outcomes of <strong>the</strong> ventures are all independen<strong>to</strong>f one ano<strong>the</strong>r. In this case, <strong>the</strong> probability of <strong>the</strong> inves<strong>to</strong>r sustaining a largepercentage loss is small-for example, <strong>the</strong> probability that all 100 ventures fail is aminiscule .003 percent (= 0.9~")-and <strong>the</strong> diversified inves<strong>to</strong>r might consequentlybe satisfied <strong>to</strong> receive an expected return of only, say, 10 percent. If so, <strong>the</strong>entrepreneur would need <strong>to</strong> sell a much smaller stake <strong>to</strong> raise <strong>the</strong> same amount ofmoney, <strong>here</strong> 27.5 percent (= $1.1 million/$4 million); and <strong>the</strong> inves<strong>to</strong>r would paya higher price per share of $3.64 (= $1 million/275,000 shares).Cases I and I1 differ only in <strong>the</strong> degree <strong>to</strong> which <strong>the</strong> inves<strong>to</strong>r is diversified; <strong>the</strong>stand-alone risk and <strong>the</strong> expected future value of any one venture is <strong>the</strong> same inboth cases. Diversified inves<strong>to</strong>rs face less risk per investment than undiversifiedinves<strong>to</strong>rs, and <strong>the</strong>y are t<strong>here</strong>fore willing <strong>to</strong> receive lower expected returns (and <strong>to</strong>pay higher prices). For <strong>the</strong> purpose of determining required returns, <strong>the</strong> risks ofinvestments t<strong>here</strong>fore must be viewed in <strong>the</strong> context of <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r risks <strong>to</strong> whichinves<strong>to</strong>rs are exposed. The CAPM is a direct outgrowth of this key idea.Diversification, Correlation and RiskThe notion that diversification reduces risk is centuries old. In eighteenth-centuryEnglish language translations of Don Quixote, Sancho Panza advises his master, "It is <strong>the</strong>part of a wise man <strong>to</strong> . . . not venture all his eggs in one basket." According <strong>to</strong> Herbison(2003), <strong>the</strong> proverb "Do not keep all your eggs in one basket" actually appeared as farback as Torriano's (1666) Common Place ofItalian Proverbs.However, diversification was typically thought of in terms of spreading your wealthacross many ind@endent risks that would cancel each o<strong>the</strong>r if held in sufficient number(as was assumed in <strong>the</strong> newventures example). Harry Markowitz (1952) had <strong>the</strong> insightthat, because of broad economic influences, risks across assets were correlated <strong>to</strong> adegree. As a result, inves<strong>to</strong>rs could eliminate some but not all risk by holding adiversified portfolio. Markowitz wrote: "This presumption, that <strong>the</strong> law of large numbersapplies <strong>to</strong> a portfolio of securities, cannot be accepted. The returns from securitiesare <strong>to</strong>o intercorrelated. Diversification cannot eliminate all variance."Markowitz (1952) went on <strong>to</strong> show analytically how <strong>the</strong> benefits of diversificationdepend on correlation. The correlation between <strong>the</strong> returns of two assetsmeasures <strong>the</strong> degree <strong>to</strong> which <strong>the</strong>y fluctuate <strong>to</strong><strong>get</strong>her. Correlation coefficientsrange between -1.0 and 1.0. When <strong>the</strong> correlation is 1.0, <strong>the</strong> two assets areperfectly positively correlated. They move in <strong>the</strong> same direction and in fixed


The Capital Asset Pricing i\/lodel 7proportions (plus a constant). In this case, <strong>the</strong> two assets are substitutes for oneano<strong>the</strong>r. When <strong>the</strong> correlation is -1.0, <strong>the</strong> returns are perfectly negatively correlatedmeaning that when one asset goes up, <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r goes down and in a fixedproportion (plus a constant). In this case, <strong>the</strong> two assets act <strong>to</strong> insure one ano<strong>the</strong>r.When <strong>the</strong> correlation is zero, knowing <strong>the</strong> return on one asset does not help youpredict <strong>the</strong> return on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r.To show how <strong>the</strong> correlation among individual security returns affects portfoliorisk, consider investing in two risky assets, A and B. Assume that <strong>the</strong> risk of anasset is measured by its standard deviation of return, which for assets A and B isdenoted by a, and a,, respectively. Let p denote <strong>the</strong> correlation between t<strong>here</strong>turns on assets A and B; let x be <strong>the</strong> fraction invested in Asset A and y (= 1 -x) be <strong>the</strong> fraction invested in Asset B.When <strong>the</strong> returns on assets within a portfolio are perfectly positively correlated(p = l),<strong>the</strong> portfolio risk is <strong>the</strong> weighted average of <strong>the</strong> risks of <strong>the</strong> assets in <strong>the</strong>portfolio. The risk of <strong>the</strong> portfolio <strong>the</strong>n can be expressed asap= xa, + yu~.The more interesting case is when <strong>the</strong> assets are not perfectly correlated (p < 1).Then t<strong>here</strong> is a nonlinear relationship between portfolio risk and <strong>the</strong> risks of <strong>the</strong>underlying assets. In this case, at least some of <strong>the</strong> risk from one asset will be offsetby <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r asset, so <strong>the</strong> standard deviation of <strong>the</strong> portfolio upis always less than<strong>the</strong> weighted average of a, and a,.3 Thus, <strong>the</strong> risk of a portfolio is less than <strong>the</strong>average risk of <strong>the</strong> underlying assets. Moreover, <strong>the</strong> benefit of diversification willincrease <strong>the</strong> far<strong>the</strong>r away that <strong>the</strong> correlation p is from 1.These are Harry Markowitz's important insights: 1) that diversification does notrely on individual risks being uncorrelated, just that <strong>the</strong>y be imperfectly correlated; and2) that <strong>the</strong> risk reduction from diversification is limited by <strong>the</strong> extent <strong>to</strong> whichindividual asset returns are correlated. If Markowitz were restating Sancho Panza'sadvice, he might say: It is safer <strong>to</strong> spread your eggs among imperfectly correlatedbaskets than <strong>to</strong> spread <strong>the</strong>m among perfectly correlated baskets.Table 1 illustrates <strong>the</strong> benefits of diversifying across international equity markets.The table lists <strong>the</strong> world's largest s<strong>to</strong>ck markets by market capitalization as ofDecember 31, 2003, <strong>the</strong> combination of which we will call <strong>the</strong> world equity market"he portfolio standard deviation, up,can be expressed in terms of <strong>the</strong> standard deviations of assets Aand B and <strong>the</strong>ir correlation using <strong>the</strong> variance formula:This expression can be algebraically manipulated <strong>to</strong> obtainWhen p = 1,<strong>the</strong> final term disappears, gibing <strong>the</strong> formula in <strong>the</strong> text. When p < 1,<strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> size of <strong>the</strong> secondterm will increase as p declines, and so <strong>the</strong> standard deviation of <strong>the</strong> portfolio hill fall as p declines.


- -8 Journal of Economic PerspectivesTable 1Market Capitalizations and His<strong>to</strong>rical Risk Estimates for 24 Countries,January 1994-December 2003'MarketCapztalzzatzonBeta($ Bzllzons, Capztalzzatzon S.D. of us. Correlatzon12/31/O?) H'ezght Return TI.IEIMP us 'IIELWU.S. $14,266 47.8%Japan 2,953 9.9%UK 2,426 8.1%France 1,403 4.7%Germany 1,079 3.6%Canada 910 3.0%Switzerland 727 2.4%Spain 726 2.4%Hong Kong 715 2.4%Italy 615 2.1%Australia 586 2.0%China 513 1.7%Taiwan 379 1.3%Ne<strong>the</strong>rlands 368 1.2%Sweden 320 1.1%South Korea 298 1.0%India 279 0.9%South Africa 261 0.9%Brazil 235 0.8%Russia 198 0.7%Belgium 174 0.6%Mala! sia 168 0.6%Singapore 149 0.5%Mexico 123 0.4%U'EMP $29,870 100%S.D. of MEMP assuming perfect correlationS.D. of MEMP assuming zero correlation'Ihtes: M'EMP stands for World Equity Market Portfolio. S.D. is standard de~iation expressed on anannualized basis. Calculations are based on his<strong>to</strong>rical monthly returns obtained from Global FinancialData Inc.portfolio, labeled in <strong>the</strong> table as MTMP. The capitalization of <strong>the</strong> world equitymarket portfolio was about $30 trillion-comprising over 95 percent of all publiclytraded equities-with <strong>the</strong> United Statese representing by far <strong>the</strong> largest fraction.Table 1 includes <strong>the</strong> standard deviation of monthly <strong>to</strong>tal returns for each country over<strong>the</strong> ten-year period ending December 31, 2003, expressed on an annualized basis.Assuming that <strong>the</strong> his<strong>to</strong>rical standard deviations and correlations of return aregood estimates of future standard deviations and correlations, we can use this data<strong>to</strong> calculate that <strong>the</strong> standard deviation of return of <strong>the</strong> W'EMP-given <strong>the</strong> capitalizationweights as of December 20034s 15.3 percent per annum. If <strong>the</strong> countryreturns were all perfectly correlated with each o<strong>the</strong>r, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> standard deviation of<strong>the</strong> WEMP would be <strong>the</strong> capitalization-weighted average of <strong>the</strong> standard deviations,


Andre' F. Perold9which is 19.9 percent per annum. The difference of 4.6 percent per annumrepresents <strong>the</strong> diversification benefit-<strong>the</strong> risk reduction stemming from <strong>the</strong> factthat <strong>the</strong> world's equity markets are imperfectly correlated. Also shown in Table 1 isthat <strong>the</strong> standard deviation of <strong>the</strong> WEMP would be only 8.4 percent per annum if <strong>the</strong>country returns were uncorrelated with one ano<strong>the</strong>r. The amount by which this figureis lower than <strong>the</strong> actual standard deviation of 15.3 percent per annum is a measure of<strong>the</strong> extent <strong>to</strong> which <strong>the</strong> world's equity markets share common influences.Portfolio Theory, Riskless Lending and Borrowing and FundSeparationTo arrive at <strong>the</strong> CAPM, we need <strong>to</strong> examine how imperfect correlation amongasset returns affects <strong>the</strong> inves<strong>to</strong>r's tradeoff between risk and return. MThile riskscombine nonlinearly (because of <strong>the</strong> diversification effect), expected returns combinelinearly. That is, <strong>the</strong> expected return on a portfolio of investments is just <strong>the</strong>weighted average of <strong>the</strong> expected returns of <strong>the</strong> underlying assets. Imagine twoassets with <strong>the</strong> same expected return and <strong>the</strong> same standard deviation of return. Byholding both assets in a portfolio, one obtains an expected return on <strong>the</strong> portfoliothat is <strong>the</strong> same as ei<strong>the</strong>r one of <strong>the</strong>m, but a portfolio standard deviation that islower than any one of <strong>the</strong>m individually. Diversification thus leads <strong>to</strong> a reduction inrisk without any sacrifice in expected return.Generally, t<strong>here</strong> will be many combinations of assets with <strong>the</strong> same portfolioexpected return but different portfolio risk; and t<strong>here</strong> will be many combinationsof assets with <strong>the</strong> same portfolio risk but different portfolio expected return. Usingoptimization techniques, we can compute what Markowitz coined <strong>the</strong> "efficientfrontier." For each level of expected return, we can solve for <strong>the</strong> portfolio combinationof assets that has <strong>the</strong> lowest risk. Or for each level of risk, we can solve for<strong>the</strong> combination of assets that has <strong>the</strong> highest expected return. The efficientfrontier consists of <strong>the</strong> collection of <strong>the</strong>se optimal portfolios, and each inves<strong>to</strong>r canchoose which of <strong>the</strong>se best matches <strong>the</strong>ir risk <strong>to</strong>lerance.The initial development of portfolio <strong>the</strong>ory assumed that all assets were risky.James Tobin (1958) showed that when inves<strong>to</strong>rs can borrow as well as lend at <strong>the</strong>risk-free rate, <strong>the</strong> efficient frontier simplifies in an important way. (A "risk-free"instrument pays a fixed real return and is default free. U.S. Treasury bonds thatadjust au<strong>to</strong>matically with inflation-called Treasury inflation-protected instruments,or TIPS-and short-term U.S. Treasury bills are considered close approximationsof risk-free instruments.)To see how riskless borrowing and lending affects inves<strong>to</strong>rs' decision choices,consider investing in <strong>the</strong> following three instruments: risky assets M and H, and <strong>the</strong>riskless asset, w<strong>here</strong> <strong>the</strong> expected returns and risks of <strong>the</strong> assets are shown in Table 2.Suppose first that you had <strong>the</strong> choice of investing all of your wealth in just one of<strong>the</strong>se assets. Which would you choose? The answer depends on your risk <strong>to</strong>lerance.Asset Hhas <strong>the</strong> highest risk and also <strong>the</strong> highest expected return. You would choose


10 Journal of Economic PerspectivesTable 2How Riskless Borrowing and Lending AffectInves<strong>to</strong>rs' ChoicesExpected returnRisk (S.D.)Riskless asset 3% (r,) 0%Asset ,Vl 10% ( E M ) 20% (alw)Asset H 12% (E,) 40% (a,)Asset H if you had a high <strong>to</strong>lerance for risk. The riskless asset has no risk but also<strong>the</strong> lowest expected return. You would choose <strong>to</strong> lend at <strong>the</strong> risk-free rate if you hada very low <strong>to</strong>lerance for risk. Asset M has an intermediate risk and expected return,and you would choose this asset if you had a moderate <strong>to</strong>lerance for risk.Suppose next that you can borrow and lend at <strong>the</strong> risk-free rate, that you wish<strong>to</strong> invest some of your wealth in Asset H and <strong>the</strong> balance in riskless lending orborrowing. If x is <strong>the</strong> fraction of wealth invested in Asset H, <strong>the</strong>n 1 - x is <strong>the</strong>fraction invested in <strong>the</strong> risk-free asset. When x < 1,you are lending at <strong>the</strong> risk-freerate; when x > 1, you are borrowing at <strong>the</strong> risk-free rate. The expected return ofthis portfolio is (1 - x) rf + xE, which equals rf + x(EH - rf) , and <strong>the</strong> risk of <strong>the</strong>portfolio is xa,. The risk of <strong>the</strong> portfolio is proportional <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> risk of Asset H,since Asset H i s <strong>the</strong> only source of risk in <strong>the</strong> portfolio.Risk and expected return thus both combine linearly, as shown graphically inFigure 1. Each point on <strong>the</strong> line connecting <strong>the</strong> risk-free asset <strong>to</strong> Asset H representsa particular allocation ( x) <strong>to</strong> Asset Hwith <strong>the</strong> balance in ei<strong>the</strong>r risk-free lending orrisk-free borrowing. The slope of this line is called <strong>the</strong> Sharpe Ratio-<strong>the</strong> riskpremium of Asset H divided by <strong>the</strong> risk of Asset H:Sharpe Ratio = (EH- rf)/aH.The Sharpe Ratio of Asset H evaluates <strong>to</strong> 0.175 (= (12 percent - 5 percent)/40 percent) and all combinations of Asset H with risk-free borrowing or lendinghave this same Sharpe Ratio.Also shown in Figure 1 are <strong>the</strong> risks and expected returns that can be achievedby combining Asset M with riskless lending and borrowing. The Sharpe Ratio ofAsset M is 0.25, which is higher than that of Asset H, and any level of risk and returnthat can be obtained by investing in Asset H along with riskless lending or borrowingis dominated by some combination of Asset M and riskless lending or borrowing.For example, for <strong>the</strong> same risk as Asset H, you can obtain a higher expectedreturn by investing in Asset Mwith 2:l leverage. As shown in Figure 1, <strong>the</strong> expectedreturn of a 2:l leveraged position in Asset M is 15 percent (that is, (2 X 10 percent)- (1 X 5 percent)), which is higher than <strong>the</strong> 12 percent expected return ofAsset H. If you could hold only one risky asset along with riskless lending orborrowing, it unambiguously would be Asset M.Being able <strong>to</strong> lend and borrow at <strong>the</strong> risk-free rate thus dramatically changes


The Capital Asset Pricing ModelI IFigure 1Combining a Risky Asset with Risk-Free Lending and BorrowingCombinations of Combinations ofasset 121 invol~ing asset 121 involving14 risk-free risk-free2:l Leverage-I--+-I ---)Coinbinations of Combinations ofasset H involving asset H invol~ingrisk-freerisk-freelendingborrowing0 5 10 15 20 25 30 35 40 45 50Risk (standard de~lation)our investment choices. The asset of choice-if you could choose only one riskyasset-is <strong>the</strong> one with <strong>the</strong> highest Sharpe Ratio. Given this choice of risky asset, youneed <strong>to</strong> make a second decision, which is how much of it <strong>to</strong> hold in your portfolio.The answer <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> latter question depends on your risk <strong>to</strong>lerance.Figure 2 illustrates <strong>the</strong> approach in <strong>the</strong> case w<strong>here</strong> we can invest in combinationsof two risky assets, M and H, plus riskless lending and borrowing. Thecorrelation between <strong>the</strong> returns of assets M and H is assumed <strong>to</strong> be zero. In <strong>the</strong>figure, <strong>the</strong> curve connecting assets M and H represents all expected return/standard deviation pairs that can be attained through combinations of assets M andH. The combination of assets M and H that has <strong>the</strong> highest Sharpe Ratio is74 percent in Asset M and 26 percent in Asset H (<strong>the</strong> tangency point). Theexpected return of this combination is 10.52 percent, and <strong>the</strong> standard deviation is18.09 percent. The Sharpe Ratio evaluates <strong>to</strong> 0.305, which is considerably higherthan <strong>the</strong> Sharpe Ratios of assets M and H (0.25 and 0.175, respectively). Inves<strong>to</strong>rswho share <strong>the</strong> same estimates of expected return and risk all will locate <strong>the</strong>irportfolios on <strong>the</strong> tangency line connecting <strong>the</strong> risk-free asset <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> frontier. Inparticular, <strong>the</strong>y all will hold assets M and H in <strong>the</strong> proportions 74/26.The optimal portfolio of many risky assets can be found similarly. Figure 3offers a general illustration. Use Markowitz's algorithm <strong>to</strong> obtain <strong>the</strong> efficientfrontier of portfolios of risky assets. Find <strong>the</strong> portfolio on <strong>the</strong> efficient frontier thathas <strong>the</strong> highest Sharpe Ratio, which will be <strong>the</strong> point w<strong>here</strong> a ray stretching up from<strong>the</strong> risk-free point is just tangent <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> efficient frontier. Then, in accordance withyour risk <strong>to</strong>lerance, allocate your wealth between this highest Sharpe Ratio portfolioand risk-free lending or borrowing.This characterization of <strong>the</strong> efficient frontier is referred <strong>to</strong> as "fund separation."Inves<strong>to</strong>rs with <strong>the</strong> same beliefs about expected returns, risks and correlationsall will invest in <strong>the</strong> portfolio or "fund" of risky assets that has <strong>the</strong> highest Sharpe


12 Journal of Economic PerspectiuesFigure 2Efficient Frontier with Two Risky Assets15I0 3 10 15 20 25 30 35 40 45Risk (standard de~lation)Figure 3Efficient Frontier with Many Risky AssetsHighest SharpemmIImEfficient frontierof risky assets-IndividualassetsRisk (standard deviation)Ratio, but <strong>the</strong>y will differ in <strong>the</strong>ir allocations between this fund and risk-freelending or borrowing based on <strong>the</strong>ir risk <strong>to</strong>lerance. Notice in particular that <strong>the</strong>composition of <strong>the</strong> optimal portfolio of risky assets does not depend on <strong>the</strong>inves<strong>to</strong>r's <strong>to</strong>lerance for risk.Market-Determined Expected Returns and Stand-Alone RiskPortfolio <strong>the</strong>ory prescribes that inves<strong>to</strong>rs choose <strong>the</strong>ir portfolios on <strong>the</strong> efficientfrontier, given <strong>the</strong>ir beliefs about expected returns and risks. The Capital


Asset Pricing Model, on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r hand, is concerned with <strong>the</strong> pricing of assets inequilibrium. CAPM asks: What are <strong>the</strong> implications for asset prices if everyoneheeds this advice? In equilibrium, all assets must be held by someone. For <strong>the</strong>market <strong>to</strong> be in equilibrium, <strong>the</strong> expected return of each asset must be such thatinves<strong>to</strong>rs collectively decide <strong>to</strong> hold exactly <strong>the</strong> supply of shares of <strong>the</strong> asset. TheCapital Asset Pricing Model will tell us how inves<strong>to</strong>rs determine those expectedreturns-and t<strong>here</strong>by asset prices-as a function of risk.In thinking about how expected return and risk might be related, let us askwhe<strong>the</strong>r, as a rule, <strong>the</strong> expected return on an investment could possibly be afunction of its stand-alone risk (measured by standard deviation of return). Theanswer turns out <strong>to</strong> be "no." Consider <strong>the</strong> shares of two firms with <strong>the</strong> samestand-alone risk. If <strong>the</strong> expected return on an investment was determined solely byits stand-alone risk, <strong>the</strong> shares of <strong>the</strong>se firms would have <strong>the</strong> same expected return,say 10 percent. Any portfolio combination of <strong>the</strong> two firms would also have anexpected return of 10 percent (since <strong>the</strong> expected return of a portfolio of assets is<strong>the</strong> weighted average of <strong>the</strong> expected returns of <strong>the</strong> assets that comprise <strong>the</strong>portfolio). However, if <strong>the</strong> shares of <strong>the</strong> firms are not perfectly correlated, <strong>the</strong>n aportfolio invested in <strong>the</strong> shares of <strong>the</strong> two firms will be less risky than ei<strong>the</strong>r onestand-alone. T<strong>here</strong>fore, if expected return is a function solely of stand-alone risk,<strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> expected return of this portfolio must be less than 10 percent, contradicting<strong>the</strong> fact that <strong>the</strong> expected return of <strong>the</strong> portfolio is 10 percent. Expectedreturns, t<strong>here</strong>fore, cannot be determined solely by stand-alone risk.Accordingly, any relationship between expected return and risk must be basedon a measure of risk that is not stand-alone risk. As we will soon see, that measureof risk is given by <strong>the</strong> incremental risk that an asset provides when added <strong>to</strong> aportfolio, as discussed in <strong>the</strong> next section.Improving <strong>the</strong> Sharpe Ratio of a PortfolioSuppose you were trying <strong>to</strong> decide whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>to</strong> add a particular s<strong>to</strong>ck <strong>to</strong> yourinvestment portfolio of risky assets. If you could borrow and lend at <strong>the</strong> risk-freerate, you would add <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck if it improved <strong>the</strong> portfolio's Sharpe Ratio. It turnsout t<strong>here</strong> is a simple rule <strong>to</strong> guide <strong>the</strong> decision-a rule that can be derived byunderstanding <strong>the</strong> two special cases: 1) when <strong>the</strong> additional s<strong>to</strong>ck is uncorrelatedwith <strong>the</strong> existing portfolio, and 2) when <strong>the</strong> additional s<strong>to</strong>ck is perfectly correlatedwith <strong>the</strong> existing portfolio. The rule will lead us directly <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> equilibriumrisk-return relationship specified by <strong>the</strong> Capital Asset Pricing Model.In what follows, it will be helpful <strong>to</strong> think in terms of "excess return," t<strong>here</strong>turn of an instrument in excess of <strong>the</strong> risk-free rate. The expected excess returnis called <strong>the</strong> risk premium.Adding a S<strong>to</strong>ck that is Uncorrelated with <strong>the</strong> Existing PortfolioWhen should a portfolio be diversified in<strong>to</strong> an uncorrelated s<strong>to</strong>ck? If <strong>the</strong>excess returns on <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck and existing portfolio are uncorrelated, adding a small


14 Journal of Economic Perspectivesamount of <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck has almost no effect on <strong>the</strong> risk of <strong>the</strong> portfolio.4 At <strong>the</strong>margin, t<strong>here</strong>fore, <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck is a substitute for investing in <strong>the</strong> risk-free asset.Including <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck will increase <strong>the</strong> portfolio's Sharpe Ratio if <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck's expectedreturn Es exceeds <strong>the</strong> risk-free rate rf. Said ano<strong>the</strong>r way, <strong>the</strong> additional s<strong>to</strong>ck shouldbe included in <strong>the</strong> portfolio if its risk premium Es - rf is positive.Adding a S<strong>to</strong>ck that is Perfectly Correlated with <strong>the</strong> Existing PortfolioIf <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck and portfolio excess returns are perfectly correlated, investing in<strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck becomes a substitute for investing in <strong>the</strong> portfolio itself. To see this, recallthat a perfect correlation means that <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck and <strong>the</strong> portfolio excess returnsmove <strong>to</strong><strong>get</strong>her in a fixed ratio plus a constant. The fixed ratio is called beta,denoted by P, and <strong>the</strong> constant is called alpha, denoted by a. In o<strong>the</strong>r words, <strong>the</strong>excess return of <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck is equal <strong>to</strong> alpha plus beta times <strong>the</strong> excess return of <strong>the</strong>portfolio. It also follows that <strong>the</strong> expected excess return of <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck is alpha plus betatimes <strong>the</strong> expected excess return on <strong>the</strong> portfolio-that is, Es - r- = a + P(EP -rf)The constant alpha is t<strong>here</strong>fore given by <strong>the</strong> difference between <strong>the</strong> riskpremium of <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck and beta times <strong>the</strong> risk premium of <strong>the</strong> portfolio. Since <strong>the</strong>s<strong>to</strong>ck and <strong>the</strong> portfolio move <strong>to</strong><strong>get</strong>her in a fixed proportion, beta is given by <strong>the</strong>ratio of s<strong>to</strong>ck <strong>to</strong> portfolio standard deviations of excess return: P = as/a,.Compare now an investment of $1 in <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck with <strong>the</strong> following "mimicking"strategy: invest $P in <strong>the</strong> portfolio and <strong>the</strong> balance $(1 - P) in <strong>the</strong> risk-free asset,assuming that p < 1. For example, if beta is 0.5, <strong>the</strong>n investing $0.50 in <strong>the</strong> portfolioand $0.50 in <strong>the</strong> riskless asset is a strategy that will gain or lose 0.5 percent of excessreturn for every 1 percent gain or loss in <strong>the</strong> portfolio excess return. The excess returnof <strong>the</strong> mimicking strategy is beta times <strong>the</strong> excess return of <strong>the</strong> portfolio. The mimickingstrategy will behave just like <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck up <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> constant difference alpha. Themimicking strategy can be thought of as a "s<strong>to</strong>ck" with <strong>the</strong> given beta but an alpha of zero.Similarly, if P > 1, <strong>the</strong> mimicking strategy involves investing $P in <strong>the</strong> portfolioof which $(P - 1) is borrowed at <strong>the</strong> riskless rate. For example, if beta is 3, <strong>the</strong>mimicking portfolio involves investing $3 in <strong>the</strong> portfolio of which $2 is borrowedat <strong>the</strong> risk-free rate. This strategy will gain or lose 3 percent of excess return forevery 1 percent gain or loss in <strong>the</strong> portfolio excess return. Again, <strong>the</strong> mimickingstrategy will behave just like <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck up <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> constant difference alpha.When should a s<strong>to</strong>ck be added <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> portfolio if its return is perfectly correlatedwith that of <strong>the</strong> portfolio? Since, up <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> constant alpha, <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck is just a substitutefor <strong>the</strong> portfolio, adding $1 of <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> portfolio amounts <strong>to</strong> owning $P moreof <strong>the</strong> portfolio. But owning more of <strong>the</strong> portfolio by itself does not change its SharpeRatio. T<strong>here</strong>fore, adding <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck will increase <strong>the</strong> portfolio's Sharpe Ratio if <strong>the</strong>Assume that you have $1 ofwealth invested in <strong>the</strong> portfolio. Then, adding an investment of $x in sharesof <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck increases <strong>the</strong> portfolio variance <strong>to</strong> u; + x2uz, w<strong>here</strong> u: is <strong>the</strong> variance of <strong>the</strong> portfolio andx2uz is <strong>the</strong> variance of <strong>the</strong> additional s<strong>to</strong>ck, weighted by <strong>the</strong> number of dollars invested in <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck.Remember, <strong>the</strong> variance of a combination of uncorrelated risks equals <strong>the</strong> sum of <strong>the</strong> variances of <strong>the</strong>indi~ldual risks. The increase in portfolio risk (standard deviation as well as variance) is proportional <strong>to</strong>x2, which implies that <strong>the</strong> change in portfolio risk is negligible for small x. The $x needed <strong>to</strong> purchase<strong>the</strong> shares can come from holding less of <strong>the</strong> risk-free asset or by borrowing at <strong>the</strong> risk-free rate.


The Capital Asset Pricing Model 15s<strong>to</strong>ck's expected excess return exceeds that of <strong>the</strong> mimicking portfolio. This occurs ifa > 0 or equivalently if Es - rf > P(Ep - 9,meaning that <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck's risk premiummust exceed beta times <strong>the</strong> portfolio risk premium.The General Case: Adding a S<strong>to</strong>ck that is Imperfectly Correlated with <strong>the</strong>Existing PortfolioSuppose next that <strong>the</strong> returns on <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck and <strong>the</strong> portfolio are correlated <strong>to</strong>some degree (0 < p < 1). In this case, <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck's return can be separated in<strong>to</strong> a returncomponent that is perfectly correlated with <strong>the</strong> portfolio and a return component that isuncorrelated with <strong>the</strong> portfolio. Since <strong>the</strong> standard deviation of <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck is a,, <strong>the</strong>standard deviation of <strong>the</strong> perfectly correlated component of <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck's return isThus, <strong>the</strong> beta of <strong>the</strong> perfectly correlated component of <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck's excess return <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong>portfolio's excess return is given by <strong>the</strong> ratio of standard deviations: P = pada,As just discussed, <strong>the</strong> component of <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck's return that is perfectly correlatedwith <strong>the</strong> portfolio is a substitute for <strong>the</strong> portfolio itself and can be mimickedthrough an investment of /3 in <strong>the</strong> portfolio and (1- P) in <strong>the</strong> riskless asset. Thecomponent of <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck's excess return that is uncorrelated with <strong>the</strong> portfolio can,at <strong>the</strong> margin, be diversified away and will thus have no effect on <strong>the</strong> risk of <strong>the</strong>portfolio. This component of return can be mimicked through an investment in<strong>the</strong> risk-free asset. We can t<strong>here</strong>fore conclude that adding <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> portfoliowill improve <strong>the</strong> Sharpe Ratio if <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck's risk premium exceeds <strong>the</strong> sum of <strong>the</strong>risk premia of <strong>the</strong> two mimicking portfolios: P (E, - rf) for <strong>the</strong> perfectly correlatedreturn component and zero for <strong>the</strong> uncorrelated return component.This insight establishes a rule for improving <strong>the</strong> portfolio. Adding a marginalshare of s<strong>to</strong>ck <strong>to</strong> a portfolio will increase <strong>the</strong> portfolio's Sharpe Ratio if <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck'salpha is positive, that is, if its risk premium satisfiesConversely, selling short a marginal share of <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck will increase <strong>the</strong> portfolio'sSharpe Ratio if <strong>the</strong> alpha is negative, E, - rf < P (E, - rf) . The portfolio has <strong>the</strong>highest attainable Sharpe Ratio if Es - rf = P(Ep - rf) for every s<strong>to</strong>ck-that is, if<strong>the</strong> risk premium for each s<strong>to</strong>ck is equal <strong>to</strong> beta times <strong>the</strong> risk premium for <strong>the</strong>portfolio as a whole.The Capital Asset Pricing ModelThe rule for improving <strong>the</strong> Sharpe Ratio of a portfolio allows us <strong>to</strong> derive <strong>the</strong>Capital Asset Pricing Model in a straightforward and intuitive way. We begin with fourassumptions. First, inves<strong>to</strong>rs are risk averse and evaluate <strong>the</strong>ir investment portfoliosThe correlation coefficient p is <strong>the</strong> "R in "R-squared"--<strong>the</strong> fraction of <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck's variance that isattributable <strong>to</strong> movements in <strong>the</strong> portfolio. If p < 0, <strong>the</strong> standard deviation of <strong>the</strong> perfectly correlatedcomponent is Ipla,.


16 Journal of Economic Perspectivessolely in terms of expected return and standard deviation of return measured over <strong>the</strong>same single holding period. Second, capital markets are perfect in several senses: allassets are infinitely divisible; t<strong>here</strong> are no transactions costs, short selling restrictions ortaxes; information is costless and available <strong>to</strong> everyone; and all inves<strong>to</strong>rs can borrowand lend at <strong>the</strong> risk-free rate. Third, inves<strong>to</strong>rs all have access <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> same investmen<strong>to</strong>pportunities. Fourth, inves<strong>to</strong>rs all make <strong>the</strong> same estimates of individual asset expectedreturns, standard deviations of return and <strong>the</strong> correlations among asset returns.These assumptions represent a highly simplified and idealized world, but areneeded <strong>to</strong> obtain <strong>the</strong> W M in its basic form. The model has been extended in manyways <strong>to</strong> accommodate some of <strong>the</strong> complexities manifest in <strong>the</strong> real world. But under<strong>the</strong>se assumptions, given prevailing prices, inves<strong>to</strong>rs all will determine <strong>the</strong> same highestSharpe Ratio portfolio of risky assets. Depending on <strong>the</strong>ir risk <strong>to</strong>lerance, each inves<strong>to</strong>rwill allocate a portion of wealth <strong>to</strong> this optimal portfolio and <strong>the</strong> remainder <strong>to</strong> risk-freelending or borrowing. Inves<strong>to</strong>rs all will hold risky assets in <strong>the</strong> same relative proportions.For <strong>the</strong> market <strong>to</strong> be in equilibrium, <strong>the</strong> price (that is, <strong>the</strong> expected return) ofeach asset must be such that inves<strong>to</strong>rs collectively decide <strong>to</strong> hold exactly <strong>the</strong> supply of<strong>the</strong> asset. If inves<strong>to</strong>rs all hold risky assets in <strong>the</strong> same proportions, those proportionsmust be <strong>the</strong> proportions in which risky assets are held in <strong>the</strong> market portfolio-<strong>the</strong>portfolio comprised of all available shares of each risky asset. In equilibrium, t<strong>here</strong>fore,<strong>the</strong> portfolio of risky assets with <strong>the</strong> highest Sharpe Ratio must be <strong>the</strong> market portfolio.If <strong>the</strong> market portfolio has <strong>the</strong> highest attainable Sharpe Ratio, t<strong>here</strong> is no way<strong>to</strong> obtain a higher Sharpe Ratio by holding more or less of any one asset. Applying<strong>the</strong> portfolio improvement rule, it follows that <strong>the</strong> risk premium of each asset mustsatisfy Es - r- = /3 (ElM- rf) , w<strong>here</strong> E, and E , are <strong>the</strong> expected return on <strong>the</strong> assetand <strong>the</strong> market portfolio, respectively, and /3 is <strong>the</strong> sensitivity of <strong>the</strong> asset's return<strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> return on <strong>the</strong> market portfolio.We have just established <strong>the</strong> Capital Asset Pricing Model: In equilibrium, <strong>the</strong>expected return of an asset is given byThis formula is <strong>the</strong> one that Sharpe, Treynor, Lintner and Mossin successfully se<strong>to</strong>ut <strong>to</strong> find. It is <strong>the</strong> relationship between expected return and risk that is consistentwith inves<strong>to</strong>rs behaving according <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> prescriptions of portfolio <strong>the</strong>ory. If thisrule does not hold, <strong>the</strong>n inves<strong>to</strong>rs will be able <strong>to</strong> outperform <strong>the</strong> market (in <strong>the</strong>sense of obtaining a higher Sharpe Ratio) by applying <strong>the</strong> portfolio improvementrule, and if sufficiently many inves<strong>to</strong>rs do this, s<strong>to</strong>ck prices will adjust <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> pointw<strong>here</strong> <strong>the</strong> CAPM becomes true.Ano<strong>the</strong>r way of expressing <strong>the</strong> CAPM equation isSharpe Ratio of Asset S = p X Sharpe Ratio of <strong>the</strong> Market ~ o r t f o l i o . ~Using <strong>the</strong> fact that that P = pa Ju,, <strong>the</strong> equation E, = ,rf + P(EM - rf) can be rearranged <strong>to</strong> give( E , - rf)/u, = p (E, - rf)/uW,which is <strong>the</strong> expression in <strong>the</strong> text.


Andre' F. Perold 17In o<strong>the</strong>r words, in equilibrium, <strong>the</strong> Sharpe Ratio of any asset is no higher than <strong>the</strong>Sharpe Ratio of <strong>the</strong> market portfolio (since p 5 1). Moreover, assets having <strong>the</strong>same correlation with <strong>the</strong> market portfolio will have <strong>the</strong> same Sharpe Ratio.The Capital Asset Pricing Model tells us that <strong>to</strong> calculate <strong>the</strong> expected returnof a s<strong>to</strong>ck, inves<strong>to</strong>rs need know two things: <strong>the</strong> risk premium of <strong>the</strong> overall equitymarket EM - rf (assuming that equities are <strong>the</strong> only risky assets) and <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck'sbeta versus <strong>the</strong> market. The s<strong>to</strong>ck's risk premium is determined by <strong>the</strong> componen<strong>to</strong>f its return that is perfectly correlated with <strong>the</strong> market-that is, <strong>the</strong> extent <strong>to</strong> which<strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck is a substitute for investing in <strong>the</strong> market. The component of <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck'sreturn that is uncorrelated with <strong>the</strong> market can be diversified away and does notcommand a risk premium.The Capital Asset Pricing Model has a number of important implications. First,perhaps <strong>the</strong> most striking aspect of <strong>the</strong> CAPM is what <strong>the</strong> expected return of anasset does not depend on. In particular, <strong>the</strong> expected return of a s<strong>to</strong>ck does notdepend on its stand-alone risk. It is true that a high beta s<strong>to</strong>ck will tend <strong>to</strong> have ahigh stand-alone risk because a portion of a s<strong>to</strong>ck's stand-alone risk is determinedby its beta, but a s<strong>to</strong>ck need not have a high beta <strong>to</strong> have a high stand-alone risk.A s<strong>to</strong>ck with high stand-alone risk t<strong>here</strong>fore will only have a high expected return<strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> extent that its stand-alone risk is derived from its sensitivity <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> broad s<strong>to</strong>ckmarket.Second, beta offers a method of measuring <strong>the</strong> risk of an asset that cannot bediversified away. We saw earlier that any risk measure for determining expectedreturns would have <strong>to</strong> satisfy <strong>the</strong> requirement that <strong>the</strong> risk of a portfolio is <strong>the</strong>weighted average of <strong>the</strong> risks of <strong>the</strong> holdings in <strong>the</strong> portfolio. Beta satisfies thisrequirement. For example, if two s<strong>to</strong>cks have market betas of 0.8 and 1.4, respectively,<strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> market beta of a 50/50 portfolio of <strong>the</strong>se s<strong>to</strong>cks is 1.1, <strong>the</strong> averageof <strong>the</strong> two s<strong>to</strong>ck betas. Moreover, <strong>the</strong> capitalization weighted average of <strong>the</strong> marketbetas of all s<strong>to</strong>cks is <strong>the</strong> beta of <strong>the</strong> market versus itself. The average s<strong>to</strong>ck t<strong>here</strong>forehas a market beta of 1 .O.On a graph w<strong>here</strong> <strong>the</strong> risk of an asset as measured by beta is on <strong>the</strong> horizontalaxis and return is on <strong>the</strong> vertical axis, all securities lie on a single line-<strong>the</strong> so-calledSecurities Market Line shown in Figure 4. If <strong>the</strong> market is in equilibrium, all assetsmust lie on this line. If not, inves<strong>to</strong>rs will be able <strong>to</strong> improve upon <strong>the</strong> marketportfolio and obtain a higher Sharpe Ratio. In contrast, Figure 3 presented earliermeasured risk on <strong>the</strong> horizontal axis as stand-alone risk, <strong>the</strong> standard deviation ofeach s<strong>to</strong>ck, and so s<strong>to</strong>cks were scattered over <strong>the</strong> diagram. But remember that notall of <strong>the</strong> stand-alone risk of an asset is priced in<strong>to</strong> its expected return, just thatportion of its risk, pa,, that is correlated with <strong>the</strong> market portfolio.Third, in <strong>the</strong> Capital Asset Pricing Model, a s<strong>to</strong>ck's expected return does notdepend on <strong>the</strong> growth rate of its expected future cash flows. To find <strong>the</strong> expectedreturn of a company's shares, it is thus not necessary <strong>to</strong> carry out an extensive financialanalysis of <strong>the</strong> company and <strong>to</strong> forecast its future cash flows. According <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> CAPM,all we need <strong>to</strong> know about <strong>the</strong> specific company is <strong>the</strong> beta of its shares, a parameterthat is usually much easier <strong>to</strong> estimate than <strong>the</strong> expected future cash flows of <strong>the</strong> firm.


18 Journal of Economic PerspectivesFigure 4The Securities Market Line (SML)ISMLLBeta of market = 1.0BetaIs <strong>the</strong> CAPM Useful?The Capital Asset Pricing Model is an elegant <strong>the</strong>ory with profound implicationsfor asset pricing and inves<strong>to</strong>r behavior. But how useful is <strong>the</strong> model gven <strong>the</strong> idealizedworld that underlies its derivation? T<strong>here</strong> are several ways <strong>to</strong> answer this question. First,we can examine whe<strong>the</strong>r real world asset prices and inves<strong>to</strong>r portfolios conform <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong>predictions of <strong>the</strong> model, if not always in a strict quantitative sense, and least in a strongqualitative sense. Second, even if <strong>the</strong> model does not describe our current worldparticularly well, it might predict future inves<strong>to</strong>r behavior-for example, as a consequenceof capital market frictions being lessened through financial innovation, improvedregulation and increasing capital market integration. Third, <strong>the</strong> CAPM canserve as a benchmark for understanding <strong>the</strong> capital market phenomena that causeasset prices and inves<strong>to</strong>r behavior <strong>to</strong> deviate from <strong>the</strong> prescriptions of <strong>the</strong> model.Suboptimal DiversificationConsider <strong>the</strong> W M prediction that inves<strong>to</strong>rs all will hold <strong>the</strong> same (market)portfolio of risky assets. One does not have <strong>to</strong> look far <strong>to</strong> realize that inves<strong>to</strong>rs donot hold identical portfolios, which is not a surprise since taxes alone will causeidiosyncratic inves<strong>to</strong>r behavior. For example, optimal management of capital gainstaxes involves early realization of losses and deferral of capital gains, and so taxableinves<strong>to</strong>rs might react very differently <strong>to</strong> changes in asset values depending on when<strong>the</strong>y purchased <strong>the</strong> asset (Constantinides, 1983).Never<strong>the</strong>less, it will still be a positivesign for <strong>the</strong> model if most inves<strong>to</strong>rs hold broadly diversified portfolios. But even <strong>here</strong><strong>the</strong> evidence is mixed. On one hand, popular index funds make it possible for inves<strong>to</strong>rs<strong>to</strong> obtain diversification at low cost. On <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r hand, many workers hold concentratedownership of company s<strong>to</strong>ck in employee retirement savings plans and manyexecutives hold concentrated ownership of company s<strong>to</strong>ck options.One of <strong>the</strong> most puzzling examples of suboptimal diversification is <strong>the</strong> so-


The Capital Asset Pricing Model 19called home bias in international investing. In almost all countries, foreign ownershipof assets is low, meaning that inves<strong>to</strong>rs tend <strong>to</strong> hold predominantly homecountry assets. For example, in 2003, foreign ownership accounted for only10 percent of publicly traded U.S. equities and 21 percent of publicly tradedJapanese equities. Japanese inves<strong>to</strong>r portfolios t<strong>here</strong>fore deviate significantly from<strong>the</strong> world equity market portfolio: <strong>the</strong>y own <strong>the</strong> vast majority of <strong>the</strong>ir home countryequities, but only a tiny share of U.S. equities. By contrast, and as shown inTable 1, an inves<strong>to</strong>r holding <strong>the</strong> world equity market portfolio would be invested48 percent in U.S. equities and only 10 percent in Japanese equities.Why is suboptimal diversification so pervasive? Common explanations are tha<strong>to</strong>btaining broad diversification can be costly, in terms of direct expenses and taxes,and that inves<strong>to</strong>rs are subject <strong>to</strong> behavioral biases and lack of sophistication. Noneof <strong>the</strong>se reasons, if valid, would mean that <strong>the</strong> CAPM is not useful. The CAPM tellsus that inves<strong>to</strong>rs pay a price for being undiversified in that <strong>the</strong>y are taking risks forwhich <strong>the</strong>y are not being compensated. Thus, t<strong>here</strong> exists <strong>the</strong> potential for portfolioimprovement, which in turn creates opportunities for inves<strong>to</strong>r education andfinancial innovation. Indeed, foreign ownership of equities in many countries hasmore than doubled over <strong>the</strong> last 20 years, most likely due <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> increasedavailability of low-cost vehicles <strong>to</strong> invest globally and greater inves<strong>to</strong>r appreciationof <strong>the</strong> need for diversification. Inves<strong>to</strong>rs <strong>to</strong>day seem <strong>to</strong> be much better diversifiedthan in decades past, a trend that appears likely <strong>to</strong> continue.Performance MeasurementOne of <strong>the</strong> earliest applications of <strong>the</strong> Capital Asset Pricing Model was <strong>to</strong>performance measurement of fund managers (Treynor, 1965; Sharpe, 1966;Jensen, 1968). Consider two funds, A and B, that are actively managed in <strong>the</strong> hopeof outperforming <strong>the</strong> market. Suppose that <strong>the</strong> funds obtained returns of 12 percentand 18 percent, respectively, during a period when <strong>the</strong> risk-free rate was5 percent and <strong>the</strong> overall market returned 15 percent. Assume fur<strong>the</strong>r that <strong>the</strong>standard deviation of funds A and B were 40 percent per annum and 30 percentper annum, respectively. Which fund had <strong>the</strong> better performance?At first glance, fund A had greater risk and a lower return than fund B, so fundB would appear <strong>to</strong> have been <strong>the</strong> better performing fund. However, we know from<strong>the</strong> CAPM that focusing on stand-alone risk is misleading if inves<strong>to</strong>rs can holddiversified portfolios. To draw a firmer conclusion, we need <strong>to</strong> know how <strong>the</strong>sefunds are managed: Suppose that fund A consists of a high-risk but "marketneutral"portfolio that has long positions in some shares and short positions ino<strong>the</strong>rs, with a portfolio beta of zero. Fund B, on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r hand, invests in selectedhigh beta s<strong>to</strong>cks, with a portfolio beta of 1.5.Instead of investing in funds A and/or B, inves<strong>to</strong>rs could have held correspondingmimicking or "benchmark portfolios. For fund A, since its beta is zero,<strong>the</strong> benchmark portfolio is an investment in <strong>the</strong> risk-free asset; for fund B, <strong>the</strong>benchmark is a position in <strong>the</strong> market portfolio leveraged 1.5:l with borrowing at<strong>the</strong> risk-free rate. The benchmark portfolios respectively would have returned5 percent and 20 percent (= 5 percent + 1.5 X (15 percent - 5 percent)). Fund


20 Journal of Economic PerspectivesTable 3Evaluating Portfolio Managers with <strong>the</strong> CAPM&turn Rzsk (S.D.) Beta AlphaRiskless asset 5% 0% 0.0 05%Market portfolio 15% 20% 1 .O 05%Fund A 12% 40% 0.0 7%Fund B 18% 30% 1.5 -2%A thus outperformed its benchmark by 7 percent, while fund B underperformed itsbenchmark by 2 percent, as shown in Table 3.In terms of <strong>the</strong> CAPM framework, funds A and B had alphas of 7 percent and-2 percent, respectively, w<strong>here</strong> alpha is <strong>the</strong> difference between a fund's performanceand that predicted given <strong>the</strong> beta of <strong>the</strong> fund. Appropriately risk adjusted,fund A's performance (alpha = 7 percent) exceeded that of fund B (alpha =-2 percent). An inves<strong>to</strong>r who held <strong>the</strong> market portfolio would, at <strong>the</strong> margin, haveobtained a higher return for <strong>the</strong> same risk by allocating money <strong>to</strong> fund A ra<strong>the</strong>rthan <strong>to</strong> fund B.'The key idea <strong>here</strong> is that obtaining high returns by owning high beta s<strong>to</strong>cksdoes not take skill, since inves<strong>to</strong>rs can passively create a high beta portfolio simplythrough a leveraged position in <strong>the</strong> market portfolio. Obtaining high returns withlow beta s<strong>to</strong>cks is much harder, however, since such performance cannot bereplicated with a passive strategy. Inves<strong>to</strong>rs t<strong>here</strong>fore need <strong>to</strong> assess performancebased on returns that have been appropriately risk adjusted. The CAPM provides aclear framework for thinking about this issue.The CAPM and Discounted Cash Flow AnalysisAccording <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> CAPM,<strong>the</strong> appropriate discount rate for valuing <strong>the</strong> expectedfuture cash flows of a company or of a new investment project is determinedby <strong>the</strong> risk-free rate, <strong>the</strong> market risk premium and <strong>the</strong> beta versus <strong>the</strong> market of <strong>the</strong>company or project. Accuracy in estimating <strong>the</strong>se parameters matters greatly forreal world decisionmaking since, for long-dated cash flows, an error in <strong>the</strong> discountrate is magnified manyfold when calculating <strong>the</strong> net present value.Beta is usually estimated with use of linear regression analysis applied <strong>to</strong> his<strong>to</strong>ricals<strong>to</strong>ck market returns data. Beta can in many circumstances be accurately measured thisway even over a relatively short period of time, provided that t<strong>here</strong> is sufficienthigh-frequency data. MThen <strong>the</strong> company or project being valued is not publicly tradedor t<strong>here</strong> is no relevant return his<strong>to</strong>ry, it is cus<strong>to</strong>mary <strong>to</strong> infer beta from comparableentities whose betas can be estimated. But measurement issues can arise even if <strong>the</strong>availability of market returns data is not an issue, for example when <strong>the</strong> covariance with' This assumes that <strong>the</strong> beta of <strong>the</strong> overall portfolio is held constant-bv holding more of <strong>the</strong> marketportfolio if money is allocated <strong>to</strong> fund A and less of <strong>the</strong> market portfolio if money is allocated <strong>to</strong> fund B.


Andre' F. Pprold 21<strong>the</strong> market is time varying and when local s<strong>to</strong>ck market indexes are used as proxies for<strong>the</strong> broad market portfolio because <strong>the</strong> latter is not well specified.The hardest of all parameters <strong>to</strong> estimate is usually <strong>the</strong> market risk premium.The his<strong>to</strong>rical risk premium is estimated from <strong>the</strong> average of past returns and,unlike variance-related measures like beta, average returns are very sensitive <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong>beginning and ending level of s<strong>to</strong>ck prices. The risk premium must t<strong>here</strong>fore bemeasured over long periods of time, and even this may not be sufficient if <strong>the</strong> riskpremium varies over time.None of <strong>the</strong>se measurement questions poses a problem for <strong>the</strong> CAPM per se,however. The market risk premium is common <strong>to</strong> all models of cash flow valuation,and its estimation needs <strong>to</strong> be performed regardless of <strong>the</strong> difficulty of <strong>the</strong> task.Provided that <strong>the</strong> W M is <strong>the</strong> "right" model, beta <strong>to</strong>o needs <strong>to</strong> be estimated,irrespective of difficulty.Extensions of <strong>the</strong> CAPMThe Capital Asset Pricing Model has been extended in a variety of ways. Some of<strong>the</strong> best-known extensions include allowing heterogenous beliefs (Lintner, 1969; Mer<strong>to</strong>n,1987); eliminating <strong>the</strong> possibility of risk-free lending and borrowing (Black, 1972);having some assets be nonmarketable (Mayers, 1973); allowing for multiple timeperiods and investment opportunities that change from one period <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> next(Mer<strong>to</strong>n, 1973; Breeden, 1979); extensions <strong>to</strong> international investing (Solnik, 1974;Stulz, 1981; Adler and Dumas, 1983) ;and employing weaker assumptions by relying onarbitrage pricing (Ross, 1976). In most extensions of <strong>the</strong> CAPM, no single portfolio ofrisky assets is optimal for everyone. Ra<strong>the</strong>r, inves<strong>to</strong>rs allocate <strong>the</strong>ir wealth differentiallyamong several risky portfolios, which across all inves<strong>to</strong>rs aggregate <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> marketportfolio.To illustrate, consider <strong>the</strong> International Capital Asset Pricing Model. Thismodel takes in<strong>to</strong> account that inves<strong>to</strong>rs have consumption needs particular <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong>country in which <strong>the</strong>y are resident. Thus, British inves<strong>to</strong>rs will worry about <strong>the</strong>purchasing power of pounds while American inves<strong>to</strong>rs worry about <strong>the</strong> purchasingpower of dollars, which means that British and American inves<strong>to</strong>rs will differentlyassess <strong>the</strong> incremental contribution that any particular asset makes <strong>to</strong> portfolio risk.As a result, <strong>the</strong>y will hold somewhat different portfolios.8 In <strong>the</strong> basic CAPM,inves<strong>to</strong>rs care about only one risk fac<strong>to</strong>r-<strong>the</strong> overall market. In this internationalversion of <strong>the</strong> model, <strong>the</strong>y are also concerned about real currency fluctuations. Thisinsight leads <strong>to</strong> a model of expected returns involving not only <strong>the</strong> beta of an assetversus <strong>the</strong> overall market, but also <strong>the</strong> betas of <strong>the</strong> asset versus currency movementsand any o<strong>the</strong>r risk that is viewed differently by different inves<strong>to</strong>r segments.Almost all variants of <strong>the</strong> CAPM have a multi-beta expression for expected"ritish inves<strong>to</strong>rs who own American assets will hedge a portion of <strong>the</strong>ir real pound/dollar exchangerate exposure by borrowing in dollars and lending in pounds, and American inves<strong>to</strong>rs who own Britishassets will hedge a portion of <strong>the</strong>ir real dollar/pound exchange rate exposure by borrowing in poundsand lending in dollars. British and American inves<strong>to</strong>rs thus will lend <strong>to</strong> and borrow from each o<strong>the</strong>r, and<strong>the</strong>y will have opposite exposures <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> dollar/pound exchange rate.


22 Journal of Economic Perspectivesreturn. They are derived from <strong>the</strong> same basic notions: 1) inves<strong>to</strong>rs will holdportfolios that are optimized given <strong>the</strong>ir specific needs, constraints and risk preferences;2) in equilibrium, asset prices reflect <strong>the</strong>se demands; and 3) assets withhigh expected returns are those that are correlated with any risk that a significantgroup of inves<strong>to</strong>rs has been unable <strong>to</strong> eliminate from <strong>the</strong>ir portfolios.Whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> basic CAPM or one of its multifac<strong>to</strong>r extensions is <strong>the</strong> "correct"model of asset prices is ultimately an empirical question, one that is discussed indetail by Fama and French in <strong>the</strong>ir companion paper in this journal. Initial tests of<strong>the</strong> CAPM by Black, Jensen and Scholes (1972) and Fama and MacBeth (1973)supported <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory in that high beta s<strong>to</strong>cks were found <strong>to</strong> have had higherreturns than low beta s<strong>to</strong>cks. However, <strong>the</strong> relationship between beta and averagereturns was not as steep as indicated by <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>oretical Securities Market Line.Since this early work, a vast body of research has looked for additional riskfac<strong>to</strong>rs that affect expected returns. Most notably, Fama and French (1992) findthat adding a "value" fac<strong>to</strong>r and a "size" fac<strong>to</strong>r (in addition <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> overall market)greatly improves upon <strong>the</strong> explana<strong>to</strong>ry power of <strong>the</strong> CAPM. The pervasiveness of<strong>the</strong>se findings in follow-up research across time and o<strong>the</strong>r countries provides strongevidence that more than one systematic risk fac<strong>to</strong>r is at work in determining assetprices. However, <strong>the</strong> value and size fac<strong>to</strong>rs are not explicitly about risk; at best, <strong>the</strong>yare proxies for risk. For example, size per se cannot be a risk fac<strong>to</strong>r that affectsexpected returns, since small firms would <strong>the</strong>n simply combine <strong>to</strong> form large firms.Ano<strong>the</strong>r criticism of <strong>the</strong> Fama-French findings is that <strong>the</strong>ir value effect is based ongiving equal weight <strong>to</strong> small and large companies and is much stronger thanobserved in capitalization-weighted value indexes. Until <strong>the</strong> risks that underlie <strong>the</strong>Fama-French fac<strong>to</strong>rs are identified, <strong>the</strong> forecast power of <strong>the</strong>ir model will be indoubt and <strong>the</strong> applications will be limited.ConclusionThe Capital Asset Pricing Model is a fundamental contribution <strong>to</strong> our understandingof <strong>the</strong> determinants of asset prices. The CAPM tells us that ownership ofassets by diversified inves<strong>to</strong>rs lowers <strong>the</strong>ir expected returns and raises <strong>the</strong>ir prices.Moreover, inves<strong>to</strong>rs who hold undiversified portfolios are likely <strong>to</strong> be taking risksfor which <strong>the</strong>y are not being rewarded. As a result of <strong>the</strong> model, and despite itsmixed empirical performance, we now think differently about <strong>the</strong> relationshipbetween expected returns and risk; we think differently about how inves<strong>to</strong>rs shouldallocate <strong>the</strong>ir investment portfolios; and we think differently about questions suchas performance measurement and capital bud<strong>get</strong>ing.m I thank Josh Coval, Mihir Desai, Craig French, Ken Froot, Jim Hines, Elon Kohlberg,Adam Perold, Melissa Perold, Andrei Shleifer, Bill Sharpe, Rene' Stulz, Timothy Taylor, LuisViceira and Michael Waldman for he@ful discussions and comments.


The Capital Asset Pricing Model 23ReferencesAdler, Michael and Bernard Dumas. 1983. "InternationalPortfolio Choice and CorporationFinance: A Syn<strong>the</strong>sis." Journal of Fznance. June,38, pp. 92.5-84.Bernoulli, Daniel. 1738 [19.54]. "SpecimenTheoriae Novae de Mensura Sortis (Expositionof a New Theory on <strong>the</strong> Measurement ofRisk)." Louise Sommer, trans. Econometrica. 22,pp. 23-36.Bernstein, Peter L. 1996. Against <strong>the</strong> Gods: TheRemarkable S<strong>to</strong>y of Risk. New York: John Wiley &Sons, Inc.Bierman, Harold and Seymour Smidt. 1966.The Capital Bud<strong>get</strong>ing Decision-Economic Analysisand Financing of Investment Projects. New York:Macmillan Company.Black, Fischer. 1972. "Capital Market Equilibriumwith Restricted Borrowing." Journal of Business.July, 45:3, pp. 444-55.Black, Fischer, Michael C. Jensen and MyronScholes. 1972. "The Capital Asset Pricing Model:Some Empirical Tests," in Studies in <strong>the</strong> Theoy ofCapitalLMarkets.Michael C. Jensen, ed. New York:Praeger, pp. 79-121.Breeden, Douglas T. 1979. "An IntertemporalAsset Pricing Model with S<strong>to</strong>chastic Consumptionand Investment Opportunities." Journal ofFinancial Economics. September, 7, pp. 265-96.Constantinides, George M. 1983. "CapitalMarket Equilibrium with Personal Tax." Econometric~.May,.51:3, pp. 611-36.Dimson, Elroy and R. A. Brealey. 1978. "TheRisk Premium on UK Equities." The InvestmentAnabst. December, 52, pp. 14-18,Fama, Eugene F. and Kenneth R. French.1992. "The Cross-Section of Expected S<strong>to</strong>ckReturns." Journal of Finance. June, 47, pp. 427-65.Fama, Eugene F. and James D. MacBeth. 1973."Risk, Return, and Equilibrium: EmpiricalTests." Journal of Political Economy. May/June, 3,pp. 753-55.Fisher, L. and J. H. Lorie. 1964. "Rates ofReturn on Investments in Common S<strong>to</strong>cks." JournalofBusiness. Januarv, 37, pp. 1-21.Fisher, L. and J. H. Lorie. 1968. "Rates ofReturn on Investments in Common S<strong>to</strong>ck: TheYear-by-Year Record, 1926-1965." Journal of Buszness.July, 41, pp. 291-316.Gordon, Myron J. and Eli Shapiro. 1956. "CapitalEquipment Analysis: The Required Rateof Profit." Management Sczence. Oc<strong>to</strong>ber, 3:1,pp. 102-10.Ibbotson, Robert G. and Rex A. Sinquefield.1976. "S<strong>to</strong>cks, Bonds, Bills, and Inflation: Year-by-Year His<strong>to</strong>rical Returns ( 1926-1974) ."Journalof Business. January, 49, pp. 11-47.Herbison, B. J. 2003. "Notes on <strong>the</strong> TranslationofDon Quixote."Available at (\nnv.herbison.com/herbison/broken-eggs-quixote.htm1).Jensen, Michael C. 1968. "The Performance ofMutual Funds in <strong>the</strong> Period 1945-1964." JournalofFinance. May, 23, pp. 389-416.Lintner, John. 196.5a. "The Valuation of RiskAssets and <strong>the</strong> Selection of Risky Investmentsin S<strong>to</strong>ck Portfolios and Capital Bud<strong>get</strong>s." Reviewof Economics and Statistics. February, 47,pp. 13-37.Lintner, John. 1965b. "Security Prices, Riskand Maximal Gains from Diversification." Journalof Finance. December, 20, pp. 587-615.Lintner, John. 1969. "The Aggregation of Inves<strong>to</strong>rsDiverse Judgments and Preferences inPurely Competitive Security Markets." Journal ofFinancial and Quantitative Analysis. December, 4,pp. 347-400.Markowitz, Harry. 19.52. "Portfolio Selection."Journal of Finance. March, 7, pp. 77-91.Markowitz, Harry. 1959. Portfolio Selection: EfficientDivprsz$cations of Investments. Cowles FoundationMonograph No. 16. New York: JohnWiley & Sons, Inc.Mayers, David. 1973. "Nonmarketable Assetsand <strong>the</strong> Determination of Capital Asset Prices in<strong>the</strong> Absence of a Riskless Asset." Journal of Business.April, 46, pp. 2.58-67.Mer<strong>to</strong>n, Robert C. 1973. "An IntertermporalCapital Asset Pricing Model." Econometrica. September,41, pp. 867-87.Mer<strong>to</strong>n, Robert C. 1987. "A Simple Model ofCapital Market Equilibrium with Incomplete Information."Journal ofFinance. July, 42, pp. 483-510.Modigliani, Franco and Mer<strong>to</strong>n H. Mier.1958. "The Cost of Capital, Corporation Finance,and <strong>the</strong> Theory of Investment." AmericanEconomic him.June, 48:3, pp. 261-97.Mossin, Jan. 1966. "Equilibrium in a CapitalAsset Market." Econometrica. Oc<strong>to</strong>ber, 3.5,pp. 768-83.Ross, <strong>Stephen</strong> A. 1976. "Arbitrage Theory ofCapital Asset Pricing." Journal of Economic Theov.December, 13, pp. 341-60.Roy, Andrew D. 1952. "Safety First and <strong>the</strong>Holding of Assets." Econometnca. July, 20,pp. 431-39.Savage, Leonard J. 1954. The Foundations ojStatistics. New York: John Wiley & Sons, Inc.Sharpe,Wiiam F. 1964. "Capital Asset Prices:A Theory of Market Equilibrium Under Condi-


24 Journal of Economic Perspectivesrions of ksk " Journal ofFznance September, 19,pp 425-42Sharpe, Wiiam F. 1966 "Mutual Fund Performance" Journal of Buszness Januarv, 39,pp 119-38Solnik, Bruno H. 1974 ''An Equilibriumhfodcl of <strong>the</strong> International Capital Market "JournalofEconomlc Theoq kugust, 8, pp 500-24Stulz, Rene M. 1981 "A Model of Internationalhsct Pricing "Jou7rzal ofhnanczal Econom-1c5 Septetnber, 9, pp 383-406Tobin, James. 1958 liquidi it^ Preference asBchalior Towards ksk " Rczlzew ofEconomzc StudlesFcbruan, 25, pp 68-85Treynor, J. L. 1962 "To~\ard a Theorv of hfarkerValue of Rlsk~ Assets " Unpublished mnnuscript.Final version in Asset Pricing and PortfolioPerfo~mance1999, Robert A. Korajczyk, ed., London:Risk Books, pp. 15-22.Treynor, J. L. 1965. "How <strong>to</strong> Rate <strong>the</strong> Performanceof Mutual Funds." Haward Business Review.January/February,43, pp. 63-75.de la Vega, Joseph P. 1688 [1957]. Confusionde Confusiones. English translation by H. Kallenbenz,No. 13. Cambridge, Mass.: The KressLibrary Series of Publications, The Kress Libraryof Business and Economics, HarvardUniversity.von Neumann, John L. and Oskar Morgenstern.1944. The09 of Games and Economic Behavior.Prince<strong>to</strong>n, N.J.: Prince<strong>to</strong>n UniversityPress.


http://www.js<strong>to</strong>r.orgLINKED CITATIONS- Page 1 of 5 -You have printed <strong>the</strong> following article:The Capital Asset Pricing ModelAndré F. PeroldThe Journal of Economic Perspectives, Vol. 18, No. 3. (Summer, 2004), pp. 3-24.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0895-3309%28200422%2918%3A3%3C3%3ATCAPM%3E2.0.CO%3B2-ZThis article references <strong>the</strong> following linked citations. If you are trying <strong>to</strong> access articles from anoff-campus location, you may be required <strong>to</strong> first logon via your library web site <strong>to</strong> access JSTOR. Pleasevisit your library's website or contact a librarian <strong>to</strong> learn about options for remote access <strong>to</strong> JSTOR.[Footnotes]1 S<strong>to</strong>cks, Bonds, Bills, and Inflation: Year-by-Year His<strong>to</strong>rical Returns (1926-1974)Roger G. Ibbotson; Rex A. SinquefieldThe Journal of Business, Vol. 49, No. 1. (Jan., 1976), pp. 11-47.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0021-9398%28197601%2949%3A1%3C11%3ASBBAIY%3E2.0.CO%3B2-2ReferencesInternational Portfolio Choice and Corporation Finance: A Syn<strong>the</strong>sisMichael Adler; Bernard DumasThe Journal of Finance, Vol. 38, No. 3. (Jun., 1983), pp. 925-984.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0022-1082%28198306%2938%3A3%3C925%3AIPCACF%3E2.0.CO%3B2-UExposition of a New Theory on <strong>the</strong> Measurement of RiskDaniel BernoulliEconometrica, Vol. 22, No. 1. (Jan., 1954), pp. 23-36.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0012-9682%28195401%2922%3A1%3C23%3AEOANTO%3E2.0.CO%3B2-XNOTE: The reference numbering from <strong>the</strong> original has been maintained in this citation list.


http://www.js<strong>to</strong>r.orgLINKED CITATIONS- Page 2 of 5 -Capital Market Equilibrium with Restricted BorrowingFischer BlackThe Journal of Business, Vol. 45, No. 3. (Jul., 1972), pp. 444-455.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0021-9398%28197207%2945%3A3%3C444%3ACMEWRB%3E2.0.CO%3B2-GCapital Market Equilibrium with Personal TaxGeorge M. ConstantinidesEconometrica, Vol. 51, No. 3. (May, 1983), pp. 611-636.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0012-9682%28198305%2951%3A3%3C611%3ACMEWPT%3E2.0.CO%3B2-IThe Cross-Section of Expected S<strong>to</strong>ck ReturnsEugene F. Fama; Kenneth R. FrenchThe Journal of Finance, Vol. 47, No. 2. (Jun., 1992), pp. 427-465.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0022-1082%28199206%2947%3A2%3C427%3ATCOESR%3E2.0.CO%3B2-NRisk, Return, and Portfolio Analysis: ReplyEugene F. FamaThe Journal of Political Economy, Vol. 81, No. 3. (May - Jun., 1973), pp. 753-755.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0022-3808%28197305%2F06%2981%3A3%3C753%3ARRAPAR%3E2.0.CO%3B2-LRates of Return on Investments in Common S<strong>to</strong>cksL. Fisher; J. H. LorieThe Journal of Business, Vol. 37, No. 1. (Jan., 1964), pp. 1-21.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0021-9398%28196401%2937%3A1%3C1%3AROROII%3E2.0.CO%3B2-TRates of Return on Investments in Common S<strong>to</strong>ck: The Year-by-Year Record, 1926-65Lawrence Fisher; James H. LorieThe Journal of Business, Vol. 41, No. 3. (Jul., 1968), pp. 291-316.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0021-9398%28196807%2941%3A3%3C291%3AROROII%3E2.0.CO%3B2-8NOTE: The reference numbering from <strong>the</strong> original has been maintained in this citation list.


http://www.js<strong>to</strong>r.orgLINKED CITATIONS- Page 3 of 5 -Capital Equipment Analysis: The Required Rate of ProfitMyron J. Gordon; Eli ShapiroManagement Science, Vol. 3, No. 1. (Oct., 1956), pp. 102-110.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0025-1909%28195610%293%3A1%3C102%3ACEATRR%3E2.0.CO%3B2-XS<strong>to</strong>cks, Bonds, Bills, and Inflation: Year-by-Year His<strong>to</strong>rical Returns (1926-1974)Roger G. Ibbotson; Rex A. SinquefieldThe Journal of Business, Vol. 49, No. 1. (Jan., 1976), pp. 11-47.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0021-9398%28197601%2949%3A1%3C11%3ASBBAIY%3E2.0.CO%3B2-2The Performance of Mutual Funds in <strong>the</strong> Period 1945-1964Michael C. JensenThe Journal of Finance, Vol. 23, No. 2, Papers and Proceedings of <strong>the</strong> Twenty-Sixth AnnualMeeting of <strong>the</strong> American Finance Association Washing<strong>to</strong>n, D.C. December 28-30, 1967. (May,1968), pp. 389-416.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0022-1082%28196805%2923%3A2%3C389%3ATPOMFI%3E2.0.CO%3B2-GThe Valuation of Risk Assets and <strong>the</strong> Selection of Risky Investments in S<strong>to</strong>ck Portfolios andCapital Bud<strong>get</strong>sJohn LintnerThe Review of Economics and Statistics, Vol. 47, No. 1. (Feb., 1965), pp. 13-37.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0034-6535%28196502%2947%3A1%3C13%3ATVORAA%3E2.0.CO%3B2-7Security Prices, Risk, and Maximal Gains From DiversificationJohn LintnerThe Journal of Finance, Vol. 20, No. 4. (Dec., 1965), pp. 587-615.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0022-1082%28196512%2920%3A4%3C587%3ASPRAMG%3E2.0.CO%3B2-UNOTE: The reference numbering from <strong>the</strong> original has been maintained in this citation list.


http://www.js<strong>to</strong>r.orgLINKED CITATIONS- Page 4 of 5 -The Aggregation of Inves<strong>to</strong>r's Diverse Judgments and Preferences in Purely CompetitiveSecurity MarketsJohn LintnerThe Journal of Financial and Quantitative Analysis, Vol. 4, No. 4. (Dec., 1969), pp. 347-400.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0022-1090%28196912%294%3A4%3C347%3ATAOIDJ%3E2.0.CO%3B2-SPortfolio SelectionHarry MarkowitzThe Journal of Finance, Vol. 7, No. 1. (Mar., 1952), pp. 77-91.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0022-1082%28195203%297%3A1%3C77%3APS%3E2.0.CO%3B2-1Nonmarketable Assets and <strong>the</strong> Determination of Capital Asset Prices in <strong>the</strong> Absence of aRiskless AssetDavid MayersThe Journal of Business, Vol. 46, No. 2. (Apr., 1973), pp. 258-267.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0021-9398%28197304%2946%3A2%3C258%3ANAATDO%3E2.0.CO%3B2-UAn Intertemporal Capital Asset Pricing ModelRobert C. Mer<strong>to</strong>nEconometrica, Vol. 41, No. 5. (Sep., 1973), pp. 867-887.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0012-9682%28197309%2941%3A5%3C867%3AAICAPM%3E2.0.CO%3B2-EA Simple Model of Capital Market Equilibrium with Incomplete InformationRobert C. Mer<strong>to</strong>nThe Journal of Finance, Vol. 42, No. 3, Papers and Proceedings of <strong>the</strong> Forty-Fifth Annual Meetingof <strong>the</strong> American Finance Association, New Orleans, Louisiana, December 28-30, 1986. (Jul., 1987),pp. 483-510.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0022-1082%28198707%2942%3A3%3C483%3AASMOCM%3E2.0.CO%3B2-7NOTE: The reference numbering from <strong>the</strong> original has been maintained in this citation list.


http://www.js<strong>to</strong>r.orgLINKED CITATIONS- Page 5 of 5 -The Cost of Capital, Corporation Finance and <strong>the</strong> Theory of InvestmentFranco Modigliani; Mer<strong>to</strong>n H. MillerThe American Economic Review, Vol. 48, No. 3. (Jun., 1958), pp. 261-297.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0002-8282%28195806%2948%3A3%3C261%3ATCOCCF%3E2.0.CO%3B2-3Equilibrium in a Capital Asset MarketJan MossinEconometrica, Vol. 34, No. 4. (Oct., 1966), pp. 768-783.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0012-9682%28196610%2934%3A4%3C768%3AEIACAM%3E2.0.CO%3B2-3Safety First and <strong>the</strong> Holding of AssetsA. D. RoyEconometrica, Vol. 20, No. 3. (Jul., 1952), pp. 431-449.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0012-9682%28195207%2920%3A3%3C431%3ASFATHO%3E2.0.CO%3B2-SCapital Asset Prices: A Theory of Market Equilibrium under Conditions of RiskWilliam F. SharpeThe Journal of Finance, Vol. 19, No. 3. (Sep., 1964), pp. 425-442.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0022-1082%28196409%2919%3A3%3C425%3ACAPATO%3E2.0.CO%3B2-OMutual Fund PerformanceWilliam F. SharpeThe Journal of Business, Vol. 39, No. 1, Part 2: Supplement on Security Prices. (Jan., 1966), pp.119-138.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0021-9398%28196601%2939%3A1%3C119%3AMFP%3E2.0.CO%3B2-6Liquidity Preference as Behavior Towards RiskJ. TobinThe Review of Economic Studies, Vol. 25, No. 2. (Feb., 1958), pp. 65-86.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0034-6527%28195802%2925%3A2%3C65%3ALPABTR%3E2.0.CO%3B2-8NOTE: The reference numbering from <strong>the</strong> original has been maintained in this citation list.


Capital Asset Prices: A Theory of Market Equilibrium under Conditions of RiskWilliam F. SharpeThe Journal of Finance, Vol. 19, No. 3. (Sep., 1964), pp. 425-442.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0022-1082%28196409%2919%3A3%3C425%3ACAPATO%3E2.0.CO%3B2-OThe Journal of Finance is currently published by American Finance Association.Your use of <strong>the</strong> JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available athttp://www.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/about/terms.html. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtainedprior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in<strong>the</strong> JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use.Please contact <strong>the</strong> publisher regarding any fur<strong>the</strong>r use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained athttp://www.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/journals/afina.html.Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain <strong>the</strong> same copyright notice that appears on <strong>the</strong> screen or printedpage of such transmission.The JSTOR Archive is a trusted digital reposi<strong>to</strong>ry providing for long-term preservation and access <strong>to</strong> leading academicjournals and scholarly literature from around <strong>the</strong> world. The Archive is supported by libraries, scholarly societies, publishers,and foundations. It is an initiative of JSTOR, a not-for-profit organization with a mission <strong>to</strong> help <strong>the</strong> scholarly community takeadvantage of advances in technology. For more information regarding JSTOR, please contact support@js<strong>to</strong>r.org.http://www.js<strong>to</strong>r.orgThu Dec 20 06:47:48 2007


Tlze Journal of FINANCEVOL.XIX SEPTEMBER1964 No. 3CAPITAL ASSET PRICES: A THEORY OF MARKETEQUILIBRIUM UNDER CONDITIONS OF RISK*ONEOF THE PROBLEMS which has plagued those attempting <strong>to</strong> predict <strong>the</strong>behavior of capital markets is <strong>the</strong> absence of a body of positive microeconomic<strong>the</strong>ory dealing with conditions of risk. Although many usefulinsights can be obtained from <strong>the</strong> traditional models of investment underconditions of certainty, <strong>the</strong> pervasive influence of risk in financial transactionshas forced those working in this area <strong>to</strong> adopt models of pricebehavior which are little more than assertions. A typical classroom explanationof <strong>the</strong> determination of capital asset prices, for example,usually begins with a careful and relatively rigorous description of <strong>the</strong>process through which individual preferences and physical relationshipsinteract <strong>to</strong> determine an equilibrium pure interest rate. This is generallyfollowed by <strong>the</strong> assertion that somehow a market risk-premium is alsodetermined, with <strong>the</strong> prices of assets adjusting accordingly <strong>to</strong> account fordifferences in <strong>the</strong>ir risk.A useful representation of <strong>the</strong> view of <strong>the</strong> capital market implied insuch discussions is illustrated in Figure 1. In equilibrium, capital assetprices have adjusted so that <strong>the</strong> inves<strong>to</strong>r, if he follows rational procedures(primarily diversification), is able <strong>to</strong> attain any desired point along acapital market line.l He may obtain a higher expected rate of return onhis holdings only by incurring additional risk. In effect, <strong>the</strong> marketpresents him with two prices: <strong>the</strong> price of time, or <strong>the</strong> pure interest rate(shown by <strong>the</strong> intersection of <strong>the</strong> line with <strong>the</strong> horizontal axis) and <strong>the</strong>Me of risk, <strong>the</strong> additional expected return per unit of risk borne (t<strong>here</strong>ciprocal of <strong>the</strong> slope of <strong>the</strong> line).* A great many people provided comments on early versions of this paper which led<strong>to</strong> major improvements in <strong>the</strong> exposition. In addition <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> referees, who were mos<strong>the</strong>lpful, <strong>the</strong> author wishes <strong>to</strong> express his appreciation <strong>to</strong> Dr. Harry Markowitz of <strong>the</strong>RAND Corporation, Professor Jack Hirshleifer of <strong>the</strong> University of California at LosAngeles, and <strong>to</strong> Professors Yoram Barzel, George Brabb, Bruce Johnson, Walter Oi andR. Haney Scott of <strong>the</strong> University of Washing<strong>to</strong>n.t Associate Professor of Operations Research, University of Washing<strong>to</strong>n.1. Although some discussions are also consistent with a non-linear (but mono<strong>to</strong>nic) curve.425


426 The Journal of FinanceAt present t<strong>here</strong> is no <strong>the</strong>ory describing <strong>the</strong> manner in which <strong>the</strong> priceof risk results from <strong>the</strong> basic influences of inves<strong>to</strong>r preferences, <strong>the</strong> physicalattributes of capital assets, etc. Moreover, lacking such a <strong>the</strong>ory, it isdifficult <strong>to</strong> give any real meaning <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> relationship between <strong>the</strong> priceof a single asset and its risk. Through diversification, some of <strong>the</strong> riskin<strong>here</strong>nt in an asset can be avoided so that its <strong>to</strong>tal risk is obviously not<strong>the</strong> relevant influence on its price; unfortunately little has been saidconcerning <strong>the</strong> particular risk component which is relevant.O- Expected Rate of Returnpure Interest'RateFIGURE1In <strong>the</strong> last ten years a number of economists have developed normativemodels dealing with asset choice under conditions of risk. Markowitz?following Von Neumann and Morgenstern, developed an analysis basedon <strong>the</strong> expected utility maxim and proposed a general solution for <strong>the</strong>portfolio selection problem. Tobin3 showed that under certain conditionsMarkowitz's model implies that <strong>the</strong> process of investment choice can bebroken down in<strong>to</strong> two phases: first, <strong>the</strong> choice of a unique optimumcombination of risky assets; and second, a separate choice concerning <strong>the</strong>allocation of funds between such a combination and a single riskless2. Harry M. Markowitz, Portfolio Selection, Eficient Diversification of Investments(New York: John Wiley and Sons, Inc., 1959). The major elements of <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory firstappeared in his article "Portfolio Selection," The Journal of Finance, XI1 (March 1952),77-91.3. James Tobin, "Liquidity Preference as Behavior Towards Risk," The Review ofEconomic Studies, XXV (February, 1958), 65-86.


Capital Asset Prices427asset. Recently, Hicks4 has used a model similar <strong>to</strong> that proposed byTobin <strong>to</strong> derive corresponding conclusions about individual inves<strong>to</strong>rbehavior, dealing somewhat more explicitly with <strong>the</strong> nature of <strong>the</strong> conditionsunder which <strong>the</strong> process of investment choice can be dicho<strong>to</strong>mized.An even more detailed discussion of this process, including a rigorousproof in <strong>the</strong> context of a choice among lotteries has been presented byGordon and Gang~lli.~Although all <strong>the</strong> authors cited use virtually <strong>the</strong> same model of inves<strong>to</strong>rbeha~ior,~ none has yet attempted <strong>to</strong> extend it <strong>to</strong> construct a marketequilibrium <strong>the</strong>ory of asset prices under conditions of risk.7 We will showthat such an extension provides a <strong>the</strong>ory with implications consistent with<strong>the</strong> assertions of traditional financial <strong>the</strong>ory described above. Moreover,it sheds considerable light on <strong>the</strong> relationship between <strong>the</strong> price of anasset and <strong>the</strong> various components of its overall risk. For <strong>the</strong>se reasonsit warrants consideration as a model of <strong>the</strong> determination of capital assetprices.Part I1 provides <strong>the</strong> model of individual inves<strong>to</strong>r behavior under conditionsof risk. In Part I11 <strong>the</strong> equilibrium conditions for <strong>the</strong> capitalmarket are considered and <strong>the</strong> capital market line derived. The implicationsfor <strong>the</strong> relationship between <strong>the</strong> prices of individual capital assetsand <strong>the</strong> various components of risk are described in Part IV.The Inves<strong>to</strong>r's Preference FunctionAssume that an individual views <strong>the</strong> outcome of any investment inprobabilistic terms; that is, he thinks of <strong>the</strong> possible results in terms ofsome probability distribution. In assessing <strong>the</strong> desirability of a particularinvestment, however, he is willing <strong>to</strong> act on <strong>the</strong> basis of only two para-4. John R. Hicks, "Liquidity," The Economic Journal, LXXII (December, 1962), 787-802.5. M. J. Gordon and Ramesh Gangolli, "Choice Among and Scale of Play on LotteryType Alternatives," College of Business Administration, University of Rochester, 1962.For ano<strong>the</strong>r discussion of this relationship see W. F. Sharpe, "A Simplified Model forPortfolio Analysis," Management Science, Vol. 9, No. 2 (January 1963), 277-293. Arelated discussion can be found in F. Modigliani and M. H. Miller, "The Cost of Capital,Corporation Finance, and <strong>the</strong> Theory of Investment," The American Economic Review,XLVIII (June 1958), 261-297.6. Recently Hirshleifer has suggested that <strong>the</strong> mean-variance approach used in <strong>the</strong>articles cited is best regarded as a special case of a more general formulation due <strong>to</strong>Arrow. See Hirshleifer's "Investment Decision Under Uncertainty," Papers and Proceedingsof <strong>the</strong> Seventy-Sixth Annual Meeting of <strong>the</strong> American Economic Association, Dec. 1963,or Arrow's lLLe Role des Valeurs Boursieres pour la Repartition la Meilleure des Risques,"Inter~tational Colloquium on Econometrics, 1952.7. After preparing this paper <strong>the</strong> author learned that Mr. Jack L. Treynor, of ArthurD. Little, Inc., had independently developed a model similar in many respects <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> onedescribed <strong>here</strong>. Unfortunately Mr. Treynor's excellent work on this subject is, at present,unpublished.


428 The Journal of Financemeters of this distribution-its expected value and standard deviation.'This can be represented by a <strong>to</strong>tal utility function of <strong>the</strong> form:U = f(Ew, ow)w<strong>here</strong> Ew indicates expected future wealth and ow <strong>the</strong> predicted standarddeviation of <strong>the</strong> possible divergence of actual future wealth from Ew.Inves<strong>to</strong>rs are assumed <strong>to</strong> prefer a higher expected future wealth <strong>to</strong> alower value, ceteris paribus (dU/dEw > 0). Moreover, <strong>the</strong>y exhibitrisk-aversion, choosing an investment offering a lower value of ow <strong>to</strong>one with a greater level, given <strong>the</strong> level of Ew (dU/do, < 0). These assumptionsimply that indifference curves relating Ew and OW will beupward-sloping?To simplify <strong>the</strong> analysis, we assume that an inves<strong>to</strong>r has decided <strong>to</strong>commit a given amount (Wi) of his present wealth <strong>to</strong> investment. LettingWt be his terminal wealth and R <strong>the</strong> rate of return on his investment:we haveWt = R Wi $. Wi.This relationship makes it possible <strong>to</strong> express <strong>the</strong> inves<strong>to</strong>r's utility interms of R, since terminal wealth is directly related <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> rate of return:U = ~ (ER,CR).Figure 2 summarizes <strong>the</strong> model of inves<strong>to</strong>r preferences in a family ofindifference curves; successive curves indicate higher levels of utility asone moves down and/or <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> right.1°8. Under certain conditions <strong>the</strong> mean-variance approach can be shown <strong>to</strong> lead <strong>to</strong>unsatisfac<strong>to</strong>ry predictions of behavior. Markowitz suggests that a model based on <strong>the</strong>semi-variance (<strong>the</strong> average of <strong>the</strong> squared deviations below <strong>the</strong> mean) would be preferable;in light of <strong>the</strong> formidable computational problems, however, he bases his analysis on <strong>the</strong>variance and standard deviation.9. While only <strong>the</strong>se characteristics are required for <strong>the</strong> analysis, it is generally assumedthat <strong>the</strong> curves have <strong>the</strong> property of diminishing marginal rates of substitution betweenE, and a,, as do those in our diagrams.10. Such indifference curves can also be derived by assuming that <strong>the</strong> inves<strong>to</strong>r wishes<strong>to</strong> maximize expected utility and that his <strong>to</strong>tal utility can be represented by a quadraticfunction of R with decreasing marginal utility. Both Markowitz and Tobin present sucha derivation. A similar approach is used by Donald E. Farrar in The Investment DecisionUnder Uncertainty (Prentice-Hall, 1962). Unfortunately Farrar makes an error in hisderivation; he appeals <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> Von-Neumann-Morgenstern cardinal utility axioms <strong>to</strong> transforma function of <strong>the</strong> form:E(U) = a+ bER - cER2 - coR2in<strong>to</strong> one of <strong>the</strong> form:E (U) =klER -k2aR2.That such a transformation is not consistent with <strong>the</strong> axioms can readily be seen in thisform, since <strong>the</strong> first equation implies non-linear indifference curves in <strong>the</strong> ER, aR2 planewhile <strong>the</strong> second implies a linear relationship. Obviously no three (different) points canlie on both a line and a non-linear curve (with a mono<strong>to</strong>nic derivative). Thus <strong>the</strong> twofunctions must imply different orderings among alternative choices in at least someinstance.


Capital Asset PricesThe Investment Opportunity CurveThe model of inves<strong>to</strong>r behavior considers <strong>the</strong> inves<strong>to</strong>r as choosing froma set of investment opportunities that one which maximizes his utility.Every investment plan available <strong>to</strong> him may be represented by a point in<strong>the</strong> En, OR plane. If all such plans involve some risk, <strong>the</strong> area composedof such points will have an appearance similar <strong>to</strong> that shown in Figure 2.The inves<strong>to</strong>r will choose from among all possible plans <strong>the</strong> one placinghim on <strong>the</strong> indifference curve representing <strong>the</strong> highest level of utility(point F). The decision can be made in two stages: first, find <strong>the</strong> set ofefficient investment plans and, second choose one from among this set.A plan is said <strong>to</strong> be efficient if (and only if) t<strong>here</strong> is no alternative wi<strong>the</strong>i<strong>the</strong>r (1) <strong>the</strong> same ERand a lower on, (2) <strong>the</strong> same OR and a higher EBor (3) a higher En and a lower on. Thus investment Z is inefficient sinceinvestments B, C, and D (among o<strong>the</strong>rs) dominate it. The only planswhich would be chosen must lie along <strong>the</strong> lower right-hand boundary(AFBDCX)-<strong>the</strong> investment opportunity curve.To understand <strong>the</strong> nature of this curve, consider two investment plans-A and B, each including one or more assets. Their predicted expectedvalues and standard deviations of rate of return are shown in Figure 3.


430 The Journal of FinanceIf <strong>the</strong> proportion a of <strong>the</strong> individual's wealth is placed in plan A and t<strong>here</strong>mainder (1-a) in B, <strong>the</strong> expected rate of return of <strong>the</strong> combination willlie between <strong>the</strong> expected returns of <strong>the</strong> two plans:The predicted standard deviation of return of <strong>the</strong> combination is:Note that this relationship includes Tab, <strong>the</strong> correlation coefficient between<strong>the</strong> predicted rates of return of <strong>the</strong> two investment plans. A value of f 1would indicate an inves<strong>to</strong>r's belief that t<strong>here</strong> is a precise positive relationshipbetween <strong>the</strong> outcomes of <strong>the</strong> two investments. A zero value wouldindicate a belief that <strong>the</strong> outcomes of <strong>the</strong> two investments are completelyindependent and -1 that <strong>the</strong> inves<strong>to</strong>r feels that t<strong>here</strong> is a precise inverserelationship between <strong>the</strong>m. In <strong>the</strong> usual case r,b will have a value between0 and +l.Figure 3 shows <strong>the</strong> possible values of ER~and OR, obtainable withdifferent combinations of A and B under two different assumptions about


Capital Asset Prices 431<strong>the</strong> value of Tab. If <strong>the</strong> two investments are perfectly correlated, <strong>the</strong>combinations will lie along a straight line between <strong>the</strong> two points, sincein this case both ER~and OR, will be linearly related <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> proportionsinvested in <strong>the</strong> two plans.ll If <strong>the</strong>y are less than perfectly positively correlated,<strong>the</strong> standard deviation of any combination must be less than tha<strong>to</strong>btained with perfect correlation (since lab will be less) ; thus <strong>the</strong> combinationsmust lie along a curve below <strong>the</strong> line AB.12 AZB shows such acurve for <strong>the</strong> case of complete independence (r,b = 0); with negativecorrelation <strong>the</strong> locus is even more U-shaped.13The manner in which <strong>the</strong> investment opportunity curve is formed isrelatively simple conceptually, although exact solutions are usually quitedifficult.14 One first traces curves indicating ER, OR values available withsimple combinations of individual assets, <strong>the</strong>n considers combinations ofcombinations of assets. The lower right-hand boundary must be ei<strong>the</strong>rlinear or increasing at an increasing rate (d2O R/~E~R > 0). AS suggestedearlier, <strong>the</strong> complexity of <strong>the</strong> relationship between <strong>the</strong> characteristics ofindividual assets and <strong>the</strong> location of <strong>the</strong> investment opportunity curvemakes it difficult <strong>to</strong> provide a simple rule for assessing <strong>the</strong> desirabilityof individual assets, since <strong>the</strong> effect of an asset on an inves<strong>to</strong>r's over-allinvestment opportunity curve depends not only on its expected rate ofreturn (ER~) and risk (ORi), but also on its correlations with <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>ravailable opportunities (ril, ri2, ... . ,ri,). However, such a rule is impliedby <strong>the</strong> equilibrium conditions for <strong>the</strong> model, as we will show in part IV.The Pure Rate of InterestWe have not yet dealt with riskless assets. Let P be such an asset; itsrisk is zero ( a = ~ 0) ~ and its expected rate of return, ER*, is equal (bydefinition) <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> pure interest rate. If an inves<strong>to</strong>r places a of his wealthbut rab = 1, t<strong>here</strong>fore <strong>the</strong> expression under <strong>the</strong> square root sign can be fac<strong>to</strong>red:bRc= dEabRa+ (1 - a) oRbI2= a bRa+ (1 - a) bRb= oRb+ (bRa-bRb)a12. This curvature is, in essence, <strong>the</strong> rationale for diversification.'Ra13. When rab = 0, <strong>the</strong> slope of <strong>the</strong> curve at point A is - , at point B it isE ~ b-E ~ abRb. When r,,=-1, -- <strong>the</strong> curve degenerates <strong>to</strong> two straight lines <strong>to</strong> a pointE ~ b-E ~ aon <strong>the</strong> horizontal axis.14. Markowitz has shown that this is a problem in parametric quadratic programming.An efficient solution technique is described in his article, "The Optimization of a QuadraticFunction Subject <strong>to</strong> Linear Constraints," Naval Research Logistics Quarterly, Vol. 3(March and June, 1956), 111-133. A solution method for a special case is given in <strong>the</strong>author's iiA Simplified Model for Portfolio Analysis," op. cit.


432 The Journal of Financein P and <strong>the</strong> remainder in some risky asset A, he would obtain an expectedrate of return:ERe =aE~p+ ( 1 -a) ER~The standard deviation of such a combination would be:but since a~,= 0, this reduces <strong>to</strong>:This implies that all combinations involving any risky asset or combinationof assets plus <strong>the</strong> riskless asset must have values of ER~ and URCwhich lie along a straight line between <strong>the</strong> points representing <strong>the</strong> twocomponents. Thus in Figure 4 all combinations of ERand OR lying along<strong>the</strong> line PA are attainable if some money is loaned at <strong>the</strong> pure rate andsome placed in A. Similarly, by lending at <strong>the</strong> pure rate and investing inB, combinations along PB can be attained. Of all such possibilities, however,one will dominate: that investment plan lying at <strong>the</strong> point of <strong>the</strong>original investment opportunity curve w<strong>here</strong> a ray from point P is tangent<strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> curve. In Figure 4 all investments lying along <strong>the</strong> original curve


Capital Asset Prices433from X <strong>to</strong> + are dominated by some combination of investment in 9 andlending at <strong>the</strong> pure interest rate.Consider next <strong>the</strong> possibility of borrowing. If <strong>the</strong> inves<strong>to</strong>r can borrowat <strong>the</strong> pure rate of interest, this is equivalent <strong>to</strong> disinvesting in P. Theeffect of borrowing <strong>to</strong> purchase more of any given investment than ispossible with <strong>the</strong> given amount of wealth can be found simply by lettinga take on negative values in <strong>the</strong> equations derived for <strong>the</strong> case of lending.This will obviously give points lying along <strong>the</strong> extension of line PA ifborrowing is used <strong>to</strong> purchase more of A; points lying along <strong>the</strong> extensionof PB if <strong>the</strong> funds are used <strong>to</strong> purchase B, etc.As in <strong>the</strong> case of lending, however, one investment plan will dominateall o<strong>the</strong>rs when borrowing is possible. When <strong>the</strong> rate at which funds canbe borrowed equals <strong>the</strong> lending rate, this plan will be <strong>the</strong> same one whichis dominant if lending is <strong>to</strong> take place. Under <strong>the</strong>se conditions, <strong>the</strong> investmen<strong>to</strong>pportunity curve becomes a line (P+Z in Figure 4). Moreover,if <strong>the</strong> original investment opportunity curve is not linear at point +,<strong>the</strong>process of investment choice can be dicho<strong>to</strong>mized as follows: first select<strong>the</strong> (unique) optimum combination of risky assets (point +), and secondborrow or lend <strong>to</strong> obtain <strong>the</strong> particular point on PZ at which an indifferencecurve is tangent <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> line.16Before proceeding with <strong>the</strong> analysis, it may be useful <strong>to</strong> consider alternativeassumptions under which only a combination of assets lying at <strong>the</strong>point of tangency between <strong>the</strong> original investment opportunity curve anda ray from P can be efficient. Even if borrowing is impossible, <strong>the</strong> inves<strong>to</strong>rwill choose + (and lending) if his risk-aversion leads him <strong>to</strong> a pointbelow + on <strong>the</strong> line P+. Since a large number of inves<strong>to</strong>rs choose <strong>to</strong> placesome of <strong>the</strong>ir funds in relatively risk-free investments, this is not an unlikelypossibility. Alternatively, if borrowing is possible but only up <strong>to</strong>some limit, <strong>the</strong> choice of + would be made by all but those inves<strong>to</strong>rswilling <strong>to</strong> undertake considerable risk. These alternative paths lead <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong>main conclusion, thus making <strong>the</strong> assumption of borrowing or lendingat <strong>the</strong> pure interest rate less onerous than it might initially appear <strong>to</strong> be.In order <strong>to</strong> derive conditions for equilibrium in <strong>the</strong> capital market weinvoke two assumptions. First, we assume a common pure rate of interest,with all inves<strong>to</strong>rs able <strong>to</strong> borrow or lend funds on equal terms. Second,we assume homogeneity of inves<strong>to</strong>r expectation^:'^ inves<strong>to</strong>rs are assumed15. This proof was first presented by Tobin for <strong>the</strong> case in which <strong>the</strong> pure rate ofinterest is zero (cash). Hicks considers <strong>the</strong> lending situation under comparable conditionsbut does not allow borrowing. Both authors present <strong>the</strong>ir analysis using maximizationsubject <strong>to</strong> constraints expressed as equalities. Hicks' analysis assumes independence andthus insures that <strong>the</strong> solution will include no negative holdings of risky assets; Tobin'scovers <strong>the</strong> general case, thus his solution would generally include negative holdings ofsome assets. The discussion in this paper is based on Markowitz' formulation, whichincludes non-negativity constraints on <strong>the</strong> holdings of all assets.16. A term suggested by one of <strong>the</strong> referees.


434 The Journal of Finance<strong>to</strong> agree on <strong>the</strong> prospects of various investrnents-<strong>the</strong> expected values,standard deviations and correlation coefficients described in Part 11.Needless <strong>to</strong> say, <strong>the</strong>se are highly restrictive and undoubtedly unrealisticassumptions. However, since <strong>the</strong> proper test of a <strong>the</strong>ory is not <strong>the</strong> realismof its assumptions but <strong>the</strong> acceptability of its implications, and since <strong>the</strong>seassumptions imply equilibrium conditions which form a major par<strong>to</strong>f classical financial doctrine, it is far from clear that this formulationshould be rejected--especially in view of <strong>the</strong> dearth of alternative modelsleading <strong>to</strong> similar results.Under <strong>the</strong>se assumptions, given some set of capital asset prices, eachinves<strong>to</strong>r will view his alternatives in <strong>the</strong> same manner. For one set ofprices <strong>the</strong> alternatives might appear as shown in Figure 5. In this situa-tion, an inves<strong>to</strong>r with <strong>the</strong> preferences indicated by indifference curves A1through A4 would seek <strong>to</strong> lend some of his funds at <strong>the</strong> pure interest rateand <strong>to</strong> invest <strong>the</strong> remainder in <strong>the</strong> combination of assets shown by point+,since this would give him <strong>the</strong> preferred over-all position A*. An inves<strong>to</strong>rwith <strong>the</strong> preferences indicated by curves B1 through B4 would seek <strong>to</strong> investall his funds in combination +, while an inves<strong>to</strong>r with indifferencecurves C1 through C4 would invest all his funds plus additional (borrowed)


Capital Asset Prices 435funds in combination 9 in order <strong>to</strong> reach his preferred position (C*). Inany event, all would attempt <strong>to</strong> purchase only those risky assets whichenter combination 9.The attempts by inves<strong>to</strong>rs <strong>to</strong> purchase <strong>the</strong> assets in combination 9 and<strong>the</strong>ir lack of interest in holding assets not in combination 9 would, ofcourse, lead <strong>to</strong> a revision of prices. The prices of assets in 9 will rise and,since an asset's expected return relates future income <strong>to</strong> present price,<strong>the</strong>ir expected returns will fall. This will reduce <strong>the</strong> attractiveness of combinationswhich include such assets; thus point 9 (among o<strong>the</strong>rs) willmove <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> left of its initial position.17 On <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r hand, <strong>the</strong> prices ofassets not in 9 will fall, causing an increase in <strong>the</strong>ir expected returns anda rightward movement of points representing combinations which include<strong>the</strong>m. Such price changes will lead <strong>to</strong> a revision of inves<strong>to</strong>rs' actions; somenew combination or combinations will become attractive, leading <strong>to</strong> differentdemands and thus <strong>to</strong> fur<strong>the</strong>r revisions in prices. As <strong>the</strong> process continues,<strong>the</strong> investment opportunity curve will tend <strong>to</strong> become more linear,with points such as 9 moving <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> left and formerly inefficient points(such as F and G) moving <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> right.Capital asset prices must, of course, continue <strong>to</strong> change until a set ofprices is attained for which every asset enters at least one combinationlying on <strong>the</strong> capital market line. Figure 6 illustrates such an equilibriumcondition.'' All possibilities in <strong>the</strong> shaded area can be attained with combinationsof risky assets, while points lying along <strong>the</strong> line PZ can be attainedby borrowing or lending at <strong>the</strong> pure rate plus an investment insome combination of risky assets. Certain possibilities (those lying alongPZ from point A <strong>to</strong> point B) can be obtained in ei<strong>the</strong>r manner. For example,<strong>the</strong> ER, OR values shown by point A can be obtained solely by somecombination of risky assets; alternatively, <strong>the</strong> point can be reached by acombination of lending and investing in combination C of risky assets.It is important <strong>to</strong> recognize that in <strong>the</strong> situation shown in Figure 6many alternative combinations of risky assets are efficient (i.e., lie alongline PZ), and thus <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory does not imply that all inves<strong>to</strong>rs will hold<strong>the</strong> same combination.lQ On <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r hand, all such combinations mustbe perfectly (positively) correlated, since <strong>the</strong>y lie along a linear border of17. If inves<strong>to</strong>rs consider <strong>the</strong> variability of future dollar returns unrelated <strong>to</strong> presentprice, both E, and a, will fall; under <strong>the</strong>se conditions <strong>the</strong> point representing an assetwould move along a ray through <strong>the</strong> origin as its price changes.18. The area in Figure 6 representing ER, uR values attained with only risky assetshas been drawn at some distance from <strong>the</strong> horizontal axis for emphasis. It is likely thata more accurate representation would place it very close <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> axis.19. This statement contradicts Tobin's conclusion that t<strong>here</strong> will be a unique optimalcombination of risky assets. Tobin's proof of a unique optimum can be shown <strong>to</strong> beincorrect for <strong>the</strong> case of perfect correlation of efficient risky investment plans if <strong>the</strong>line connecting <strong>the</strong>ir ER, aR points would pass through point P. In <strong>the</strong> graph on page 83of this article (09. cit.) <strong>the</strong> constant-risk locus would, in this case, degenerate from afamily of ellipses in<strong>to</strong> one of straight lines parallel <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> constant-return loci, thus givingmultiple optima.


436 The Journal of Finance<strong>the</strong> ER, OR region.20 This provides a key <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> relationship between <strong>the</strong>prices of capital assets and different types of risk.IV. THEPRICESOF CAPITALASSETSWe have argued that in equilibrium t<strong>here</strong> will be a simple linear relationshipbetween <strong>the</strong> expected return and standard deviation of return forefficient combinations of risky assets. Thus far nothing has been saidabout such a relationship for individual assets. Typically <strong>the</strong> ER,OR valuesassociated with single assets will lie above <strong>the</strong> capital market line, reflecting<strong>the</strong> inefficiency of undiversified holdings. Moreover, such points maybe scattered throughout <strong>the</strong> feasible region, with no consistent relationshipbetween <strong>the</strong>ir expected return and <strong>to</strong>tal risk (OR). However, t<strong>here</strong>will be a consistent relationship between <strong>the</strong>ir expected returns and whatmight best be called systematic risk, as we will now show.Figure 7 illustrates <strong>the</strong> typical relationship between a single capital20. ER, bR values given by combinations of any two combinations must lie within<strong>the</strong> region and cannot plot above a straight line joining <strong>the</strong> points. In this case <strong>the</strong>y cannotplot below such a straight line. But since only in <strong>the</strong> case of perfect correlation will <strong>the</strong>yplot along a straight line, <strong>the</strong> two combinations must be perfectly correlated. As shownin Part IV, this does not necessarily imply that <strong>the</strong> individual securities <strong>the</strong>y containare perfectly correlated.


Capita2 Asset Prices 437asset (point i) and an efficient combination of assets (point g) of whichit is a part. The curve igg' indicates all ER,an values which can be obtainedwith feasible combinations of asset i and combination g. As before, wedenote such a combination in terms of a proportion a of asset i and(1 -a) of combination g. A value of a = 1 would indicate pure invest-ment in asset i while a = 0 would imply investment in combination g.Note, however, that a = .5 implies a <strong>to</strong>tal investment of more than half<strong>the</strong> funds in asset i, since half would be invested in i itself and <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rhalf used <strong>to</strong> purchase combination g, which also includes some of asset i.This means that a combination in which asset i does not appear at all mustbe represented by some negative value of a. Point g' indicates such acombination.In Figure 7 <strong>the</strong> curve igg' has been drawn tangent <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> capital marketline (PZ) at point g. This is no accident. All such curves must be tangent<strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> capital market line in equilibrium, since (1) <strong>the</strong>y must <strong>to</strong>uch it at<strong>the</strong> point representing <strong>the</strong> efficient combination and (2) <strong>the</strong>y are continuousat that point.21 Under <strong>the</strong>se conditions a lack of tangency would21. Only if rig=-1 will <strong>the</strong> curve be discontinuous over <strong>the</strong> range in question.


438 The Journal of Financeimply that <strong>the</strong> curve intersects PZ. But <strong>the</strong>n some feasible combination ofassets would lie <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> right of <strong>the</strong> capital market line, an obvious impossibilitysince <strong>the</strong> capital market line represents <strong>the</strong> efficient boundary offeasible values of En and OR.The requirement that curves such as igg' be tangent <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> capitalmarket line can be shown <strong>to</strong> lead <strong>to</strong> a relatively simple formula whichrelates <strong>the</strong> expected rate of return <strong>to</strong> various elements of risk for all assetswhich are included in combination g.22Its economic meaning can bestbe seen if <strong>the</strong> relationship between <strong>the</strong> return of asset i and that of combinationg is viewed in a manner similar <strong>to</strong> that used in regression analy-~ i s Imagine . ~ ~ that we were given a number of (ex post) observations of<strong>the</strong> return of <strong>the</strong> two investments. The points might plot as shown in Fig.8. The scatter of <strong>the</strong> Ri observations around <strong>the</strong>ir mean (which will approximateERI)is, of course, evidence of <strong>the</strong> <strong>to</strong>tal risk of <strong>the</strong> asset -o ~i.But part of <strong>the</strong> scatter is due <strong>to</strong> an underlying relationship with <strong>the</strong> returnon combination g, shown by Big, <strong>the</strong> slope of <strong>the</strong> regression line. The responseof Ri <strong>to</strong> changes in R, (and variations in Rg itself) account for22. The standard deviation of a combination of g and i will be:= dh20Ri2+ (1 - a12 bRg2 + Prig a(l - a) aRiaRg4but a = aRg at a = 0. Thus:The expected return of a combination will be:E = aE,, $ (1- a) ERgThus, at all values of a:and, at a = 0:do a, -rigb~i-=dE ER, -ERiLet <strong>the</strong> equation of <strong>the</strong> capital market line be:aR = s(ER - P)w<strong>here</strong> P is <strong>the</strong> pure interest rate. Since igg' is tangent <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> line when u = 0, and since(ERg, oRg) lies on <strong>the</strong> line:~ R P-rigo~i '=R,_- -ER~-ERI E R ~-Por:[-I [-I'igb~i P 1-~ R P= - + E ~ ~ .23. This model has been called <strong>the</strong> diagonal model since its portfolio analysis solutioncan be facilitated by re-arranging <strong>the</strong> data so that <strong>the</strong> variance-covariance matrix becomesdiagonal. The method is described in <strong>the</strong> author's article, cited earlier.


Capital Asset PricesReturn on Asset i (Ri)Return on Combination g (R )gmuch of <strong>the</strong> variation in Ri. It is this component of <strong>the</strong> asset's <strong>to</strong>tal riskwhich we term <strong>the</strong> systematic risk. The remainder? being uncorrelatedwith R,, is <strong>the</strong> unsystematic component. This formulation of <strong>the</strong> relationshipbetween Ri and Rg can be employed ex ante as a predictive model. Bigbecomes <strong>the</strong> predicted response of Ri <strong>to</strong> changes in Rg. Then, given OR,(<strong>the</strong> predicted risk of Rg), <strong>the</strong> systematic portion of <strong>the</strong> predicted riskof each asset can be determined.This interpretation allows us <strong>to</strong> state <strong>the</strong> relationship derived from<strong>the</strong> tangency of curves such as igg' with <strong>the</strong> capital market line in <strong>the</strong>form shown in Figure 9. All assets entering efficient combination g musthave (predicted) Big and ER~values lying on <strong>the</strong> line PQ.26 Prices will24. ex post, <strong>the</strong> standard error.25.and:The expression on <strong>the</strong> right is <strong>the</strong> expression on <strong>the</strong> left-hand side of <strong>the</strong> last equation infootnote 22. ~ hus:P 1


A440 The Journal of Financeadjust so that assets which are more responsive <strong>to</strong> changes in R, will havehigher expected returns than those which are less responsive. This accordswith common sense. Obviously <strong>the</strong> part of an asset's risk which is due <strong>to</strong>its correlation with <strong>the</strong> return on a combination cannot be diversified awaywhen <strong>the</strong> asset is added <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> combination. Since Big indicates <strong>the</strong> magnitudeof this type of risk it should be directly related <strong>to</strong> expected return.The relationship illustrated in Figure 9 provides a partial answer <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong>question posed earlier concerning <strong>the</strong> relationship between an asset's riskPure Rate of InterestFIGURE9and its expected return. But thus far we have argued only that <strong>the</strong> relationshipholds for <strong>the</strong> assets which enter some particular efficient combination(g). Had ano<strong>the</strong>r combination been selected, a different linearrelationship would have been derived. Fortunately this limitation is easilyovercome. As shown in <strong>the</strong>we may arbitrarily select any one26. Consider <strong>the</strong> two assets i and i*, <strong>the</strong> former included in efficient combination gand <strong>the</strong> latter in combination g*. As shown above:P 1and:[-I = - + [-] E ~ g I?E ~ i


Capital Asset Prices 441of <strong>the</strong> efficient combinations, <strong>the</strong>n measure <strong>the</strong> predicted responsivenessof every asset's rate of return <strong>to</strong> that of <strong>the</strong> combination selected; and<strong>the</strong>se coefficients will be related <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> expected rates of return of <strong>the</strong>assets in exactly <strong>the</strong> manner pictured in Figure 9.The fact that rates of return from all efficient combinations will beperfectly correlated provides <strong>the</strong> justification for arbitrarily selecting anyone of <strong>the</strong>m. Alternatively we may choose instead any variable perfectlycorrelated with <strong>the</strong> rate of return of such combinations. The vertical axisin Figure 9 would <strong>the</strong>n indicate alternative levels of a coefficient measuring<strong>the</strong> sensitivity of <strong>the</strong> rate of return of a capital asset <strong>to</strong> changes in <strong>the</strong>variable chosen.This possibility suggests both a plausible explanation for <strong>the</strong> implicationthat all efficient combinations will be perfectly correlated and a usefulinterpretation of <strong>the</strong> relationship between an individual asset's expectedreturn and its risk. Although <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory itself implies only thatrates of return from efficient combinations will be perfectly correlated,we might expect that this would be due <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir common dependence on<strong>the</strong> over-all level of economic activity. If so, diversification enables <strong>the</strong>inves<strong>to</strong>r <strong>to</strong> escape all but <strong>the</strong> risk resulting from swings in economic activity-thistype of risk remains even in efficient combinations. And, sinceall o<strong>the</strong>r types can be avoided by diversification, only <strong>the</strong> responsivenessof an asset's rate of return <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> level of economic activity is relevant inBi*g* = -[ P ] + [ 1 ] ERi*.ER,* - ER,* -Since Rgand Rgr are perfectly correlated:- riagThus:Since both g and g* lie on a line which intercepts <strong>the</strong> E-axis at P:and:ER, -PBi*.* = Bi*, [ ]ER,* -PThus:P 1 ER, -P- [ ERg*-P] + [ ] 'Ri* = 'i*g 1ER,* -P ,ER,*- ]from which we have <strong>the</strong> desired relationship between K,and g:P 1Bi,,ER, -Pmust t<strong>here</strong>fore plot on <strong>the</strong> same line as does Big.


442 The Journal of Financeassessing its risk. Prices will adjust until t<strong>here</strong> is a linear relationshipbetween <strong>the</strong> magnitude of such responsiveness and expected return. Assetswhich are unaffected by changes in economic activity will return <strong>the</strong>pure interest rate; those which move with economic activity will promiseappropriately higher expected rates of return.This discussion provides an answer <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> second of <strong>the</strong> two questionsposed in this paper. In Part 111 it was shown that with respect <strong>to</strong> equilibriumconditions in <strong>the</strong> capital market as a whole, <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory leads <strong>to</strong>results consistent with classical doctrine (i.e., <strong>the</strong> capital market line).We have now shown that with regard <strong>to</strong> capital assets considered individually,it also yields implications consistent with traditional concepts:it is common practice for investment counselors <strong>to</strong> accept a lower expectedreturn from defensive securities (those which respond little <strong>to</strong> changes in<strong>the</strong> economy) than <strong>the</strong>y require from aggressive securities (which exhibitsignificant response). As suggested earlier, <strong>the</strong> familiarity of <strong>the</strong> implicationsneed not be considered a drawback. The provision of a logical frameworkfor producing some of <strong>the</strong> major elements of traditional financial<strong>the</strong>ory should be a useful contribution in its own right.


http://www.js<strong>to</strong>r.orgLINKED CITATIONS- Page 1 of 2 -You have printed <strong>the</strong> following article:Capital Asset Prices: A Theory of Market Equilibrium under Conditions of RiskWilliam F. SharpeThe Journal of Finance, Vol. 19, No. 3. (Sep., 1964), pp. 425-442.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0022-1082%28196409%2919%3A3%3C425%3ACAPATO%3E2.0.CO%3B2-OThis article references <strong>the</strong> following linked citations. If you are trying <strong>to</strong> access articles from anoff-campus location, you may be required <strong>to</strong> first logon via your library web site <strong>to</strong> access JSTOR. Pleasevisit your library's website or contact a librarian <strong>to</strong> learn about options for remote access <strong>to</strong> JSTOR.[Footnotes]3 Liquidity Preference as Behavior Towards RiskJ. TobinThe Review of Economic Studies, Vol. 25, No. 2. (Feb., 1958), pp. 65-86.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0034-6527%28195802%2925%3A2%3C65%3ALPABTR%3E2.0.CO%3B2-84 LiquidityJ. R. HicksThe Economic Journal, Vol. 72, No. 288. (Dec., 1962), pp. 787-802.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0013-0133%28196212%2972%3A288%3C787%3AL%3E2.0.CO%3B2-P5 A Simplified Model for Portfolio AnalysisWilliam F. SharpeManagement Science, Vol. 9, No. 2. (Jan., 1963), pp. 277-293.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0025-1909%28196301%299%3A2%3C277%3AASMFPA%3E2.0.CO%3B2-75 The Cost of Capital, Corporation Finance and <strong>the</strong> Theory of InvestmentFranco Modigliani; Mer<strong>to</strong>n H. MillerThe American Economic Review, Vol. 48, No. 3. (Jun., 1958), pp. 261-297.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0002-8282%28195806%2948%3A3%3C261%3ATCOCCF%3E2.0.CO%3B2-3NOTE: The reference numbering from <strong>the</strong> original has been maintained in this citation list.


http://www.js<strong>to</strong>r.orgLINKED CITATIONS- Page 2 of 2 -14 A Simplified Model for Portfolio AnalysisWilliam F. SharpeManagement Science, Vol. 9, No. 2. (Jan., 1963), pp. 277-293.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0025-1909%28196301%299%3A2%3C277%3AASMFPA%3E2.0.CO%3B2-719 Liquidity Preference as Behavior Towards RiskJ. TobinThe Review of Economic Studies, Vol. 25, No. 2. (Feb., 1958), pp. 65-86.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0034-6527%28195802%2925%3A2%3C65%3ALPABTR%3E2.0.CO%3B2-8NOTE: The reference numbering from <strong>the</strong> original has been maintained in this citation list.


From Efficient Markets Theory <strong>to</strong> Behavioral FinanceRobert J. ShillerThe Journal of Economic Perspectives, Vol. 17, No. 1. (Winter, 2003), pp. 83-104.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0895-3309%28200324%2917%3A1%3C83%3AFEMTTB%3E2.0.CO%3B2-JThe Journal of Economic Perspectives is currently published by American Economic Association.Your use of <strong>the</strong> JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available athttp://www.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/about/terms.html. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtainedprior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in<strong>the</strong> JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use.Please contact <strong>the</strong> publisher regarding any fur<strong>the</strong>r use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained athttp://www.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/journals/aea.html.Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain <strong>the</strong> same copyright notice that appears on <strong>the</strong> screen or printedpage of such transmission.The JSTOR Archive is a trusted digital reposi<strong>to</strong>ry providing for long-term preservation and access <strong>to</strong> leading academicjournals and scholarly literature from around <strong>the</strong> world. The Archive is supported by libraries, scholarly societies, publishers,and foundations. It is an initiative of JSTOR, a not-for-profit organization with a mission <strong>to</strong> help <strong>the</strong> scholarly community takeadvantage of advances in technology. For more information regarding JSTOR, please contact support@js<strong>to</strong>r.org.http://www.js<strong>to</strong>r.orgTue Jan 15 08:07:41 2008


Journal of Economic Perspectives-Volume 17, Number 1-Winter 2003-Pages 83-1 04From Efficient Markets Theory <strong>to</strong>Behavioral FinanceRobert J. Shillercademic finance has evolved a long way from <strong>the</strong> days when <strong>the</strong> efficientmarkets <strong>the</strong>ory was widely considered <strong>to</strong> be proved beyond doubt. Behavioralfinance-that is, finance from a broader social science perspectiveincluding psychology and sociology-is now one of <strong>the</strong> most vital research programs,and it stands in sharp contradiction <strong>to</strong> much of efficient markets <strong>the</strong>ory.The efficient markets <strong>the</strong>ory reached its height of dominance in academiccircles around <strong>the</strong> 1970s. At that time, <strong>the</strong> rational expectations revolution ineconomic <strong>the</strong>ory was in its first blush of enthusiasm, a fresh new idea that occupied<strong>the</strong> center of attention. The idea that speculative asset prices such as s<strong>to</strong>ck pricesalways incorporate <strong>the</strong> best information about fundamental values and that priceschange only because of good, sensible information meshed very well with <strong>the</strong>oreticaltrends of <strong>the</strong> time. Prominent finance models of <strong>the</strong> 1970s related speculativeasset prices <strong>to</strong> economic fundamentals, using rational expectations <strong>to</strong> tie <strong>to</strong><strong>get</strong>herfinance and <strong>the</strong> entire economy in one elegant <strong>the</strong>ory. For example, RobertMer<strong>to</strong>n published "An Intertemporal Capital Asset Pricing Model" in 1973, whichshowed how <strong>to</strong> generalize <strong>the</strong> capital asset pricing model <strong>to</strong> a comprehensiveintertemporal general equilibrium model. Robert Lucas published "Asset Prices inan Exchange Economy" in 1978, which showed that in a rational expectationsgeneral equilibrium, rational asset prices may have a forecastable element that isrelated <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> forecastability of consumption. Douglas Breeden published his<strong>the</strong>ory of "consumption betas" in 1979, w<strong>here</strong> a s<strong>to</strong>ck's beta (which measures <strong>the</strong>sensitivityof its return compared <strong>to</strong> some index) was determined by <strong>the</strong> correlationRobertJ. Shiller is <strong>the</strong> Stanley B. Resor Professor of Economics and also afJiliated with <strong>the</strong>Cowles Foundation and <strong>the</strong> International Centerfor Finance, Yale C'niuersitj, N m Haven,Connecticut. He is a Research Associate at <strong>the</strong> National Bureau of Economic Research,Cambridge, Massachusetts. His e-mail address is (robert.shiller@jale.edu).


84 Journal of Economic Perspectivesof <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck's return with per capita consumption. These were exciting <strong>the</strong>oreticaladvances at <strong>the</strong> time. In 1973, <strong>the</strong> first edition of Bur<strong>to</strong>n Malkiel's acclaimed book,A Random Walk Down Wall Street, appeared, which conveyed this excitement <strong>to</strong> awider audience.In <strong>the</strong> decade of <strong>the</strong> 1970s, I was a graduate student writing a Ph.D. dissertationon rational expectations models and an assistant and associate professor, and I wasmostly caught up in <strong>the</strong> excitement of <strong>the</strong> time. One could easily wish that <strong>the</strong>semodels were true descriptions of <strong>the</strong> world around us, for it would <strong>the</strong>n be awonderful advance for our profession. We would have powerful <strong>to</strong>ols <strong>to</strong> study and<strong>to</strong> quantiQ <strong>the</strong> financial world around us.Wishful thinking can dominate much of <strong>the</strong> work of a profession for a decade,but not indefinitely. The 1970s already saw <strong>the</strong> beginnings of some disquiet over<strong>the</strong>se models and a tendency <strong>to</strong> push <strong>the</strong>m somewhat aside in favor of a moreeclectic way of thinking about financial markets and <strong>the</strong> economy. Browsing <strong>to</strong>dayagain through finance journals from <strong>the</strong> 1970s, one sees some beginnings ofreports of anomalies that didn't seem likely <strong>to</strong> square with <strong>the</strong> efficient markets<strong>the</strong>ory, even if <strong>the</strong>y were not presented as significant evidence against <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory.For example, Eugene Fama's 1970 article, "Efficient Capital Markets: A Review ofEmpirical M'ork," while highly enthusiastic in its conclusions for market efficiency,did report some anomalies like slight serial dependencies in s<strong>to</strong>ck market returns,though with <strong>the</strong> <strong>to</strong>ne of pointing out how small <strong>the</strong> anomalies were.The 1980s and Excess VolatilityFrom my perspective, <strong>the</strong> 1980s were a time of important academic discussionof <strong>the</strong> consistency of <strong>the</strong> efficient markets model for <strong>the</strong> aggregate s<strong>to</strong>ck marketwith econometric evidence about <strong>the</strong> time series properties of prices, dividends andearnings. Of particular concern was whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>se s<strong>to</strong>cks show excess volatilityrelative <strong>to</strong> what would be predicted by <strong>the</strong> efficient markets model.The anomalies that had been discovered might be considered at worst smalldepartures from <strong>the</strong> fundamental truth of market efficiency, but if most of <strong>the</strong>volatility in <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck market was unexplained, it would call in<strong>to</strong> question <strong>the</strong> basicunderpinnings of <strong>the</strong> entire efficient markets <strong>the</strong>ory. The anomaly represented by<strong>the</strong> notion of excess volatility seems <strong>to</strong> be much more troubling for efficiencymarkets <strong>the</strong>ory than some o<strong>the</strong>r financial anomalies, such as <strong>the</strong> January effect or<strong>the</strong> day-of-<strong>the</strong>-week effect.' The volatility anomaly is much deeper than thoserepresented by price stickiness or ta<strong>to</strong>nnement or even by exchange-rate overshooting.The evidence regarding excess volatility seems, <strong>to</strong> some observers at least, <strong>to</strong>imply that changes in prices occur for no fundamental reason at all, that <strong>the</strong>y occurbecause of such things as "sunspots" or "animal spirits" or just mass psychology.The efficient markets model can be stated as asserting that <strong>the</strong> price P, of a'A good discussion of <strong>the</strong> major anomalies, and <strong>the</strong> evidence for <strong>the</strong>m, is in Siege1 (2002)


Robert J. Shiller 85share (or of a portfolio of shares representing an index) equals <strong>the</strong> ma<strong>the</strong>maticalexpectation, conditional on all information available at <strong>the</strong> time, of <strong>the</strong> presentvalue eof actual subsequent dividends accruing <strong>to</strong> that share (or portfolio ofshares). Eis not known at time t and has <strong>to</strong> be forecasted. Efficient markets say thatprice equals <strong>the</strong> optimal forecast of it.Different forms of <strong>the</strong> efficient markets model differ in <strong>the</strong> choice of <strong>the</strong>discount rate in <strong>the</strong> present value, but <strong>the</strong> general efficient markets model can bewritten just as P, = E,P"I; w<strong>here</strong> E, refers <strong>to</strong> ma<strong>the</strong>matical expectation conditionalon public information available at time t. This equation asserts that any surprisingmovements in <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck market must have at <strong>the</strong>ir origin some new informationabout <strong>the</strong> fundamental value e.It follows from <strong>the</strong> efficient markets model that E = P, + C;, w<strong>here</strong> C; is aforecast error. The forecast error U, must be uncorrelated with any informationvariable available at time t, o<strong>the</strong>rwise <strong>the</strong> forecast would not be optimal; it wouldnot be taking in<strong>to</strong> account all information. Since <strong>the</strong> price P, itself is informationat time t, P, and C; must be uncorrelated with each o<strong>the</strong>r. Since <strong>the</strong> variance of <strong>the</strong>sum of two uncorrelated variables is <strong>the</strong> sum of <strong>the</strong>ir variances, it follows that <strong>the</strong>variance of emust equal <strong>the</strong> variance of P, plus <strong>the</strong> variance of C;, and hence,since <strong>the</strong> variance of U,cannot be negative, that <strong>the</strong> variance of emust be greaterthan or equal <strong>to</strong> that of P,.Thus, <strong>the</strong> fundamental principle of optimal forecasting is that <strong>the</strong> forecastmust be less variable than <strong>the</strong> variable forecasted. Any forecaster whose forecastconsistently varies through time more than <strong>the</strong> variable forecasted is making aserious error, because <strong>the</strong>n high forecasts would <strong>the</strong>mselves tend <strong>to</strong> indicateforecast positive errors, and low forecasts indicate negative errors. The maximumpossible variance of <strong>the</strong> forecast is <strong>the</strong> variance of <strong>the</strong> variable forecasted, and thiscan occur only if <strong>the</strong> forecaster has perfect foresight and <strong>the</strong> forecasts correlateperfectly with <strong>the</strong> variable forecasted.If one computes for each year since 1871 <strong>the</strong> present value subsequent <strong>to</strong> thatyear of <strong>the</strong> real dividends paid on <strong>the</strong> Standard & Poor's Composite S<strong>to</strong>ck PriceIndex, discounted by a constant real discount rate equal <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> geometric averagereal return 1871-2002 on <strong>the</strong> same Standard & Poor Index, one finds that <strong>the</strong>present value, if plotted through time, behaves remarkably like a stable trend.2 Incontrast, <strong>the</strong> Standard & Poor's Composite S<strong>to</strong>ck Price Index gyrates wildly up anddown around this trend. Figure 1 illustrates <strong>the</strong>se patterns.How, <strong>the</strong>n, can we take it as received doctrine that, according <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> simplestefficient markets <strong>the</strong>ory, <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck price represents <strong>the</strong> optimal forecast of thispresent value, <strong>the</strong> price responding only <strong>to</strong> objective information about it? I arguedin Shiller (1981), as did also <strong>Stephen</strong> LeRoy and Richard Porter (1981), that <strong>the</strong>stability of <strong>the</strong> present value through time suggests that t<strong>here</strong> is excess volatility in'The present ralue, constant discount rate, is computed for each year t as PT,,,,,~,~ = ELI+, p"llD,,w<strong>here</strong> p is a constant discount fac<strong>to</strong>r, and D, is <strong>the</strong> real dividend at time t. .kn assumption was madeabout real di~ldends after 2002. See note <strong>to</strong> Figure 1.


86 Journal of Economic PerspectivesFig-ure 1Real S<strong>to</strong>ck Prices and Present Values of Subsequent Real Dividends(annual data)Real S<strong>to</strong>ck Price (S&P 500)1000 -PD\: Interest Rates..-u ic'PDV, Constant Discount Rate100 -PD\: ConsumptionAVotes:The heaviest line is <strong>the</strong> Standard & Poor 500 Index for Januan of year shown. The less-heayline is <strong>the</strong> present value for each year of subsequent real didends accruing <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> index discountedby <strong>the</strong> geometric-average real return for <strong>the</strong> entire sample, 6.61 percent. Di~idends after 2002 wereassumed equal <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> 2002 dividend times 1.25 (<strong>to</strong> correct for recent lower dividend payout) andgrowing at <strong>the</strong> geometric-average his<strong>to</strong>rical growth rate for di~idends, 1.11 percent. The thin line is<strong>the</strong> present value for each year of subsequent real di~idends discounted by one-year interest ratesplus a risk premium equal <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> geometric average real return on <strong>the</strong> market minus <strong>the</strong> geometricaverage real one-year interest rate. The dashed line is <strong>the</strong> present value for each year of subsequentreal di~idends discounted by marginal rates of substitution in consumption for a representativeindi~idualwith a coefficient of relative risk aversion of 3 who consumes <strong>the</strong> real per capitanondurable and senice consumption from <strong>the</strong> U. S. National Income and Product Accounts.Real values were computed from nominal values by dividing by <strong>the</strong> consumer price index (CPI-LTsince 1913, linked <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> Warren and Pearson producer price index before 1913) and rescaling <strong>to</strong>Januan 2003 = 100. Some of <strong>the</strong> ven latest obsen~ations of underlying series were estimated basedon data available as of this writing; for example, <strong>the</strong> consumer price index forJanwan 2003 wasestimated based on data from previous months. Source data are available on (http://x\uw.econ.yale.edu/-shiller), and <strong>the</strong> fur<strong>the</strong>r descriptions of some of <strong>the</strong> data are in Shiller (1989). See alsofootnotes 1, 5 and 6.<strong>the</strong> aggregate s<strong>to</strong>ck market, relative <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> present value implied by <strong>the</strong> efficientmarkets model. Our work launched a remarkable amount of controversy, fromwhich I will recall <strong>here</strong> just a few highlights.The principal issue regarding our original work on excess volatility was inregard <strong>to</strong> thinking about <strong>the</strong> stationarity of dividends and s<strong>to</strong>ck prices. My ownwork in <strong>the</strong> early 1980s had followed a tradition in <strong>the</strong> finance literature of


From Eficient 1Tfarkets Theory <strong>to</strong> Behavioral Finance 87assuming that dividends fluctuated around a known trend.' However, one mightalso argue, as do Marsh and Mer<strong>to</strong>n (1986), that dividends need not stay close <strong>to</strong>a trend and that even if earnings followed a trend, share issuance or repurchasecould make dividends depart from a trend indefinitely. In addition, if businessmanagers use dividends <strong>to</strong> provide a smoo<strong>the</strong>d flow of payouts from <strong>the</strong>ir businesses,<strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck prices might be expected <strong>to</strong> shift more rapidly than dividends.Marsh and Mer<strong>to</strong>n argued that such dividend smoothing could make s<strong>to</strong>ckprices unstationary in such a way that in finite samples prices appear more volatilethan <strong>the</strong> present values.Thus, <strong>the</strong> challenge became how <strong>to</strong> construct a test for expected volatility thatmodeled dividends and s<strong>to</strong>ck prices in a more general way. ill., such tests weredeveloped, <strong>the</strong>y tended <strong>to</strong> confirm <strong>the</strong> overall hypo<strong>the</strong>sis that s<strong>to</strong>ck prices hadmore volatility than an efficient markets hypo<strong>the</strong>sis could explain. For example,West (1988) derived an inequality that <strong>the</strong> variance of innovations (that is, surprises)in s<strong>to</strong>ck prices must be less than or equal <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> variance of <strong>the</strong> innovations in <strong>the</strong>forecasted present value of dividends based on a subset of information available <strong>to</strong><strong>the</strong> market. This inequality is quite general: it holds even when dividends and s<strong>to</strong>ckprices have infinite variances so long as <strong>the</strong> variance of <strong>the</strong> innovation (<strong>the</strong>unexpected change) in <strong>the</strong>se is finite. Using long-term annual data on s<strong>to</strong>ck prices,MTest found that <strong>the</strong> variance of innovations in s<strong>to</strong>ck prices was four <strong>to</strong> 20 times its<strong>the</strong>oretical upper bound.4 ~ ohn Campbell and I (1988) recast <strong>the</strong> time series modelin terms of a cointegrated model of real prices and real dividends, while alsorelaxing o<strong>the</strong>r assumptions about <strong>the</strong> time series, and again found evidence ofexcess volatility." Campbell (1991) provided a variance decomposition for s<strong>to</strong>ckreturns that indicated that most of <strong>the</strong> variability of <strong>the</strong> aggregate s<strong>to</strong>ck marketconveyed information about future returns, ra<strong>the</strong>r than about future dividends.Ano<strong>the</strong>r contested issue regarding <strong>the</strong> early work on excess volatility questioned<strong>the</strong> assumption of <strong>the</strong> early work that <strong>the</strong> efficient markets model was bestconveyed through an expected present value model in which <strong>the</strong> real discount rateis constant through time. The assumption of a constant discount rate over time canonly be considered a first step, for <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory suggests more complex relationships.'It should be pointed out that dividend payouts as a fraction of earnings have shown a gradualdowntrend over <strong>the</strong> period since 1871 and that di~idend payouts have increasingly been substituted byshare repurchases. Set share repurchases reached approximately 1percent of shares outstanding by <strong>the</strong>late 1990s. However, share repurchases do not invalidate <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>oretical model that s<strong>to</strong>ck prices shouldequal <strong>the</strong> present ralue of dividends. See Cole, Helwege and Laster (1996).'In more technical terms, this argument is over whe<strong>the</strong>r dividends could be viewed as a stationan series.The discussion was often phrased in terms of <strong>the</strong> "unit root" properh of <strong>the</strong> time series, tv<strong>here</strong> a unitroot refers <strong>to</strong> notion that when a variable is regressed on its otvn lags, <strong>the</strong> characteristic equation of <strong>the</strong>difference equation has a root on <strong>the</strong> unit circle. \Vest (1988) can be vietved as a \cay of addressing <strong>the</strong>unit root issue. In our 1988 paper, Campbell and I handled nonstationarity by using a vec<strong>to</strong>r au<strong>to</strong>regressivemodel including <strong>the</strong> log dividend-price ratio and <strong>the</strong> change in log di~idends as elements.Barsky and De Long (1993), hotvever, later shotved that if one assumes that real dividends must be twicedifferenced <strong>to</strong> induce stationarity (so that dividends are even more unstationan in <strong>the</strong> sense thatdi~idendgroruth rates, not just levels, are unstationan), <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> efficient markets model looks ra<strong>the</strong>rmore consistent with <strong>the</strong> data.


88 Journal of Economic PerspectiuesOne such efficient markets model makes <strong>the</strong> discount rate correspond <strong>to</strong>interest rates. The line in Figure 1 labeled "PDV, Interest Rates" illustrates thisconcept.%owever, allowing time-varying interest rates in <strong>the</strong> present value formuladoes little <strong>to</strong> support <strong>the</strong> efficient markets model. The actual price is stillmore volatile than <strong>the</strong> present value, especially for <strong>the</strong> latest half century. Moreover,what changes through time t<strong>here</strong> are in <strong>the</strong> present value bear little resemblance<strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> changes through time in <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck prices, Note for example that <strong>the</strong>present value is extremely high throughout <strong>the</strong> depression years of <strong>the</strong> 1930s, notlow as was <strong>the</strong> actual s<strong>to</strong>ck market. The present value is high <strong>the</strong>n because realinterest rates were at extreme lows after 1933, in<strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> early 195Os, and since realdividends really did not fall much after 1929. After 1929, real Standard & Poor'sdividends fell <strong>to</strong> around 1925 levels for just a few years, 1933-1935 and 1938, but,contrary <strong>to</strong> popular impressions, were generally higher in <strong>the</strong> 1930s than <strong>the</strong>y werein <strong>the</strong> 1920s.'An alternative approach <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> possibility of varying real discount rates looks at<strong>the</strong> intertemporal marginal rate of substitution for consumption, which is shown inFigure 1 with <strong>the</strong> line labeled "PDV, ~onsum~tion."~he models of efficientfinancial markets from <strong>the</strong> 1970s like Mer<strong>to</strong>n (1973), Lucas (1978) and Breeden(1979) concluded that s<strong>to</strong>ck prices are <strong>the</strong> expected present value of futuredividends discounted using marginal rates of substitution of consumption, and in<strong>the</strong>se models <strong>the</strong> equations for s<strong>to</strong>ck returns were derived in <strong>the</strong> context of a modelmaximizing <strong>the</strong> utility of consumption. Grossman and Shiller (1981) produced aplot of that present value since 1881, using Standard & Poor dividend data andusing aggregate consumption data <strong>to</strong> compute <strong>the</strong> marginal rates of substitution asdiscount fac<strong>to</strong>rs, and this plot is updated <strong>here</strong>, and this is what is shown in Figure 1. We"hepresent value, discounted by interest rates, is a plot for each year t ofSee note <strong>to</strong> Figure 1.' Campbell and I (1989) recast <strong>the</strong> argument in terms of a vec<strong>to</strong>r au<strong>to</strong>regressive model of real s<strong>to</strong>ckprices, real interest rates and real dividends, in tshich each of <strong>the</strong>se variables tsas regressed on lags ofitself and lags of <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r variables. TVe found that <strong>the</strong> di~idend-price ratio not only shows excessvolatilit!, but shows ven little correlation with <strong>the</strong> dividend divided by <strong>the</strong> forecast of <strong>the</strong> present valueof future dividends."he present value, consumption discounted, is a plot for each year t ofw<strong>here</strong> C, is real per cafiita real consumption at time t. This expression is inspired by Lucas (1978) andderived in &ossman and Shiller (1981) assuming a coefficient of relative risk aversion of 3. See note <strong>to</strong>Figure 1.


RobertJ. Shiller 89found, as can also be seen <strong>here</strong> in Figure 1, that <strong>the</strong> present value of dividends asdiscounted in this model had only a tenuous relation <strong>to</strong> actual s<strong>to</strong>ck prices, and didnot appear volatile enough <strong>to</strong> justify <strong>the</strong> price movements unless we pushed <strong>the</strong>coefficient of relative risk aversion <strong>to</strong> ridiculously high levels, higher than <strong>the</strong> valueof three that was used for <strong>the</strong> plot.Grossman and Shiller (1981) stressed that t<strong>here</strong> were some similarities between<strong>the</strong> present value and <strong>the</strong> actual real price, notably <strong>the</strong> present value peaksin 1929 and bot<strong>to</strong>ms out in 1933, close <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> actual peak and trough of <strong>the</strong> market.But <strong>the</strong> present value does this because consumption peaked in 1929 and <strong>the</strong>ndropped very sharply, bot<strong>to</strong>ming out in 1933, and <strong>the</strong> present value takes accoun<strong>to</strong>f this, as if people had perfect foresight of <strong>the</strong> coming depression. But in fact itappears very unlikely that people saw this outcome in 1929, and if <strong>the</strong>y did not, <strong>the</strong>n<strong>the</strong> efficient model does not predict that <strong>the</strong> actual real price should have tracked<strong>the</strong> present value over this period.Actually, <strong>the</strong> consumption discount model, while it may show some comovementsat times with actual s<strong>to</strong>ck prices, does not work well because it does notjustify<strong>the</strong> volatility of s<strong>to</strong>ck prices. I showed (1982) that <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>oretical model implies alower bound on <strong>the</strong> volatility of <strong>the</strong> marginal rate of substitution, a bound which iswith <strong>the</strong> U.S. data much higher than could be observed unless risk aversion wereimplausibly high. Hansen and Jagannathan later generalized this lower bound andelaborated on its implications, and <strong>to</strong>day <strong>the</strong> apparent violation of this "Hansen-Jagannathan lower bound" is regarded as an important anomaly in finance."Some very recent research has emphasized that, even though <strong>the</strong> aggregates<strong>to</strong>ck market appears <strong>to</strong> be wildly inefficient, individual s<strong>to</strong>ck prices do show somecorrespondence <strong>to</strong> efficient markets <strong>the</strong>ory. That is, while <strong>the</strong> present value modelfor <strong>the</strong> aggregate s<strong>to</strong>ck market seems unsupported by <strong>the</strong> data, t<strong>here</strong> is someevidence that cross-sectionalvariations in s<strong>to</strong>ck prices relative <strong>to</strong> accounting measuresshow some relation <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> present value model. Paul Samuelson some years agoposited that <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck market is "micro efficient but macro inefficient," since t<strong>here</strong>is considerable predictable variation across firms in <strong>the</strong>ir predictable future pathsof dividends but little predictable variation in aggregate dividends. Hence, Samuelsonasserted, movements among individual s<strong>to</strong>cks make more sense than domovements in <strong>the</strong> market as a whole. T<strong>here</strong> is now evidence <strong>to</strong> back up thisassertion.Vuolteenaho (2002) showed, using vec<strong>to</strong>r-au<strong>to</strong>regressive methods, that <strong>the</strong>ratio of book-<strong>to</strong>-market-value of U.S. firms explains a substantial fraction of changesin future firms' earnings. Cohen, Polk and Vuolteenaho (2002) concluded that 75<strong>to</strong> 80 percent of <strong>the</strong> variation across firms in <strong>the</strong>ir book-<strong>to</strong>-market ratios can beexplained in terms of future variation in profits. Jung and Shiller (2002) show that,cross-sectionally, for U.S. s<strong>to</strong>cks that have been continually traded since 1926, <strong>the</strong>price-dividend ratio is a strong forecaster of <strong>the</strong> present value of future dividend"ee, for example, John Cochrane's (2001)book As.rrt Pnczng tvhich sun.eys this literature. Much of <strong>the</strong>older literature is summarized in my 1989 book 114nrkrt 1701ntilitj.


90 Journal of Economic Perspectiveschanges. So, dividend-price ratios on individual s<strong>to</strong>cks do serve as forecasts oflong-term future changes in <strong>the</strong>ir future dividends, as efficient markets assert.This does not mean that t<strong>here</strong> are not substantial bubbles in individual s<strong>to</strong>ckprices, but that <strong>the</strong> predictable variation across firms in dividends has often been solarge as <strong>to</strong> largely swamp out <strong>the</strong> effect of <strong>the</strong> bubbles. A lot of this predictablevariation across firms takes <strong>the</strong> form of firms' paying zero dividends for many yearsand inves<strong>to</strong>rs correctly perceiving that eventually dividends will be coming, and offirms in very bad shape with inves<strong>to</strong>rs correctly perceiving <strong>the</strong>y will not be payingsubstantial dividends much longer. Wen it comes <strong>to</strong> individual s<strong>to</strong>cks, suchpredictable variations, and <strong>the</strong>ir effects on price, are often far larger than <strong>the</strong>bubble component of s<strong>to</strong>ck prices.T<strong>here</strong> is a clear sense that <strong>the</strong> level of volatility of <strong>the</strong> overall s<strong>to</strong>ck marketcannot be well explained with any variant of <strong>the</strong> efficient markets model in whichs<strong>to</strong>ck prices are formed by looking at <strong>the</strong> present discounted value of futurereturns. T<strong>here</strong> are many ways <strong>to</strong> tinker with <strong>the</strong> discount rates in <strong>the</strong> present valueformulas, and someday someone may find some definition of discount rates thatproduces a present value series that "fits" <strong>the</strong> actual price better than any of <strong>the</strong>series shown in Figure 1.loBut it is unlikely that <strong>the</strong>y will do so convincingly, given<strong>the</strong> failure of our efforts <strong>to</strong> date <strong>to</strong> capture <strong>the</strong> volatility of s<strong>to</strong>ck prices. To justify<strong>the</strong> volatility in terms of such changes in <strong>the</strong> discount rates, one will have <strong>to</strong> arguethat inves<strong>to</strong>rs also had a great deal of information about changes in <strong>the</strong> fac<strong>to</strong>rsinfluencing <strong>the</strong>se future discount rates.After all <strong>the</strong> efforts <strong>to</strong> defend <strong>the</strong> efficient markets <strong>the</strong>ory, t<strong>here</strong> is still everyreason <strong>to</strong> think that, while markets are not <strong>to</strong>tally crazy, <strong>the</strong>y contain quite substantialnoise, so substantial that it dominates <strong>the</strong> movements in <strong>the</strong> aggregatemarket. The efficient markets model, for <strong>the</strong> aggregate s<strong>to</strong>ck market, has still neverbeen supported by any study effectively linking s<strong>to</strong>ck market fluctuations withsubsequent fundamentals. By <strong>the</strong> end of <strong>the</strong> 1980s, <strong>the</strong> restless minds of manyacademic researchers had turned <strong>to</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>ories.The Blossoming of Behavioral FinanceIn <strong>the</strong> 1990s, a lot of <strong>the</strong> focus of academic discussion shifted away from <strong>the</strong>seeconometric analyses of time series on prices, dividends and earnings <strong>to</strong>warddeveloping models of human psychology as it relates <strong>to</strong> financial markets. The fieldof behavioral finance developed. Researchers had seen <strong>to</strong>o many anomalies, <strong>to</strong>olo O<strong>the</strong>r fac<strong>to</strong>rs are considered by hlcGrattan and Prescott (2001),who emphasize tax rate changes, andSiege1 (2002),who considers not only tax rate changes hut also changes in <strong>the</strong> volatility of <strong>the</strong> economy,changes in <strong>the</strong> inflation rate, and changes in transactions costs. Nei<strong>the</strong>r of <strong>the</strong>se studies sho~vs a "fit"between present due and prices over <strong>the</strong> long sample, however. Notably, <strong>the</strong> fac<strong>to</strong>rs <strong>the</strong>y use do notgo through sudden changes at <strong>the</strong> time of <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck market booms and crashes surrounding 1929 and2000.


From Efficient 1Varkets The09 <strong>to</strong> Behavioral Finance 91little inspiration that our <strong>the</strong>oretical models captured important fluctuations. Anextensive body of empirical work, summarized in Campbell, Lo and MacKinlay's1996 book The Econometm'cs ofFznanczal lVarkets, laid <strong>the</strong> foundation for a revolutionin finance.Richard Thaler and I started our National Bureau of Economic Researchconference series on behavioral finance in 1991, extending workshops that Thalerhad organized at <strong>the</strong> Russell Sage Foundation a few years earlier.'' Many o<strong>the</strong>rworkshops and seminars on behavioral finance followed. T<strong>here</strong> is so much goingon in <strong>the</strong> field that it is impossible <strong>to</strong> summarize in a short space. Here, I willillustrate <strong>the</strong> progress of behaxioral finance with two salient examples from recentresearch: feedback models and obstacles <strong>to</strong> smart money. For overall surveys of <strong>the</strong>field of behavioral finance, <strong>the</strong> interested reader might begin with Hersh Shefrin'sByond Greed and Fear: Understanding Behavzoral Finance and <strong>the</strong> Psycholog?: of Investing(2000) or Andrei Shleifer's InefJiczent Markets (2000). T<strong>here</strong> are also some newbooks of collected papers in behavioral finance, including a three-volume set,Behavzoral Fznance, edited by Hersh Shefrin (2001), and Advances zn BehavzoralFznance 11, edited by Richard H. Thaler (2003).Feedback ModelsOne of <strong>the</strong> oldest <strong>the</strong>ories about financial markets, expressed long ago innewspapers and magazines ra<strong>the</strong>r than scholarly journals, is, if translated in<strong>to</strong>academic words, a price-<strong>to</strong>-price feedback <strong>the</strong>ory. Maen speculative prices go up,creating successes for some inves<strong>to</strong>rs, this may attract public attention, promoteword-of-mouth enthusiasm, and heighten expectations for fur<strong>the</strong>r price increases.The talk attracts attention <strong>to</strong> "new era" <strong>the</strong>ories and "popular models" that justify<strong>the</strong> price increases.12 This process in turn increases inves<strong>to</strong>r demand and thusgenerates ano<strong>the</strong>r round of price increases. If <strong>the</strong> feedback is not interrupted, itmay produce after many rounds a speculative "bubble," in which high expectationsfor fur<strong>the</strong>r price increases support very high current prices. The high prices areultimately not sustainable, since <strong>the</strong>y are high only because of expectations offur<strong>the</strong>r price increases, and so <strong>the</strong> bubble eventually bursts, and prices come fallingdown. The feedback that propelled <strong>the</strong> bubble carries <strong>the</strong> seeds of its own destruction,and so <strong>the</strong> end of <strong>the</strong> bubble may be unrelated <strong>to</strong> news s<strong>to</strong>ries aboutfundamentals. The same feedback may also produce a negative bubble, downwardprice movements propelling fur<strong>the</strong>r downward price movements, promoting wordof-mouthpessimism, until <strong>the</strong> market reaches an unsustainably low level.Such a feedback <strong>the</strong>ory is very old. As long ago as 1841, Charles MacKay in his" For a list of our programs since 1991, with links <strong>to</strong> authors' websites, see (http://colrles.eco~yale.edu/hel~fin).l2 Descriptions of nen. era <strong>the</strong>ories attending mrious speculative bubhles are described in my book(2000). Popular models that acconlpanied <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck market crash of 1987, <strong>the</strong> real estate buhblespeaking around 1990 and various initial public offering booms are discussed in my paper in this journal(1990).


92 ~Joz~rnal of Economic Perspectivesinfluential book Memoirs of Extraordina~ Popular Delusions described <strong>the</strong> famoustulipmania in Holland in <strong>the</strong> 1630s, a speculative bubble in tulip flower bulbs, withwords that suggest feedback and <strong>the</strong> ultimate results of <strong>the</strong> feedback (pp. 118-119):Many individuals grew suddenly rich. A golden bait hung temptingly outbefore <strong>the</strong> people, and one after ano<strong>the</strong>r, <strong>the</strong>y rushed <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> tulip marts, likeflies around a honey-pot . . . .At last, however, <strong>the</strong> more prudent began <strong>to</strong> seethat this folly could not last forever. Rich people no longer bought <strong>the</strong> flowers<strong>to</strong> keep <strong>the</strong>m in <strong>the</strong>ir gardens, but <strong>to</strong> sell <strong>the</strong>m again at cent per cent profit.It was seen that somebody must lose fearfully in <strong>the</strong> end. As this convictionspread, prices fell, and never rose again.13The feedback <strong>the</strong>ory seems <strong>to</strong> be even much older than this. Note of such feedback,and <strong>the</strong> role of word-of-mouth communications in promoting it, was in fact madeat <strong>the</strong> time of <strong>the</strong> tulipmania itself. One anonymous observer publishing in 1637(<strong>the</strong> year of <strong>the</strong> peak of <strong>the</strong> tulipmania) gives a fictional account of a conversationbetween two people, Gaergoedt and Waermondt, that illustrates this author'simpression of <strong>the</strong> word-of-mouth communications of that time:Gaergoedt: "You can hardly make a return of 10% with <strong>the</strong> money that youinvest in your occupation [as a weaver], but with <strong>the</strong> tulip trade, you can makereturns of lo%, loo%, yes, even 1000%.Waerrnondt: " . . . . But tell me, should I believe you?"Gaergoedt: "I hill tell you again, what I just said."Waermondt: "But I fear that, since I would only start now, it's <strong>to</strong>o late, becausenow <strong>the</strong> tulips are very expensive, and I fear that I'll be hit uith <strong>the</strong> spit rod,before tasting <strong>the</strong> roast."Gaergoedt: "It's never <strong>to</strong>o late <strong>to</strong> make a profit, you make money whilesleeping. I've been away from home for four or five days, and I came homejust last night, but now I know that <strong>the</strong> tulips I have have increased in valueby three or four thousand guilder; w<strong>here</strong> do you have profits like that fromo<strong>the</strong>r goods?"Waermondt: "I am perplexed when I hear you talking like that, I don't knowwhat <strong>to</strong> do; has anybody become rich with this trade?"Gaergoedt: "What kind of question is this? Look at all <strong>the</strong> gardeners that used<strong>to</strong> wear white-gray outfits, and now <strong>the</strong>y're wearing new clo<strong>the</strong>s. Many weavers,that used <strong>to</strong> wear patched up clo<strong>the</strong>s, that <strong>the</strong>y had a hard time putting"' Garher questions hlacIiay's facts about <strong>the</strong> tulipmania in his 1990 article in this journal and in hisbook Famous Erst Bubbles. For example, <strong>the</strong> crash was not absolutely final; Garber documents very hightulip prices in 1643. The actual course of <strong>the</strong> bubble is ambiguous, as all contracts were suspended by<strong>the</strong> states of Holland in 1637just after <strong>the</strong> peak, and no price data are available from that date.


on, now wear <strong>the</strong> glitteriest clo<strong>the</strong>s. Yes, many who trade in tulips are ridinga horse, have a carriage or a wagon, and during winter, an ice carriage, . . . ."I4Casual observations over <strong>the</strong> years since <strong>the</strong>n are plentiful evidence that such talk,provoking a sense of relative futility of one's day-<strong>to</strong>-day work and envy of <strong>the</strong>financial successes of o<strong>the</strong>rs, and including some vacuous answer <strong>to</strong> doubts that <strong>the</strong>price rise may be over, is effective in overcoming rational doubts among somesubstantial number of people and tends <strong>to</strong> bring successive rounds of <strong>the</strong>m in<strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong>market.In my book Irrational Exuberanre, published (with some luck) at <strong>the</strong> ver) peakof <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck market bubble in March 2000, I argued that very much <strong>the</strong> samefeedback, transmitted by word-of-mouth as well as <strong>the</strong> media, was at work inproducing <strong>the</strong> bubble we were seeing <strong>the</strong>n. I fur<strong>the</strong>r argued that <strong>the</strong> naturalself-limiting behavior of bubbles, and <strong>the</strong> possibility of downward feedback after <strong>the</strong>bubble was over, suggested a dangerous outlook for s<strong>to</strong>cks in <strong>the</strong> future.One might well also presume that such simple feedback, if it operates sodramatically in events like <strong>the</strong> tulip bubble or <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck market boom until 2000,ought often <strong>to</strong> recur at a smaller scale and <strong>to</strong> play an important if lesser role inmore normal day-<strong>to</strong>-day movements in speculative prices. Feedback models, in <strong>the</strong>form of difference equations, can of course produce complicated dynamics. Thefeedback may be an essential source of much of <strong>the</strong> apparently inexplicable"randomness" that we see in financial market prices.But <strong>the</strong> feedback <strong>the</strong>ory is very hard <strong>to</strong> find expressed in finance or economicstextbooks, even <strong>to</strong>day. Since <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>or) has appeared mostly in popular discourse,and not in <strong>the</strong> textbooks, one might well infer that it has long been discredited bysolid academic research. In fact, academic research has until recently hardlyaddressed <strong>the</strong> feedback model.The presence of such feedback is supported by some experimental evidence.Psychologists Andreassen and Kraus (1988) found that when people are shown realhis<strong>to</strong>rical s<strong>to</strong>ck prices in sequence (and which <strong>the</strong>y knew were real s<strong>to</strong>ck prices) andinvited <strong>to</strong> trade in a simulated market that displays <strong>the</strong>se prices, <strong>the</strong>y tended <strong>to</strong>behave as if <strong>the</strong>y extrapolate past price changes when <strong>the</strong> prices appear <strong>to</strong> exhibita trend relative <strong>to</strong> period-<strong>to</strong>-period variability. Smith, Suchanek and Williams(1988) were able <strong>to</strong> create experimental markets that generated bubbles that areconsistent with feedback trading. Marimon, Spear and Sunder (1993) showedexperiments in which repeating bubbles were generated if subjects were preconditionedby past experience <strong>to</strong> form expectations of bubbles.The presence of such feedback is also supported by research in cognitivepsychology, which shows that human judgments of <strong>the</strong> probability of future eventsshow systematic biases. For example, psychologists Tversky and Kahneman haveshown that judgments tend <strong>to</strong> be made using a representativeness heuristic,"Anommous (1637) Bjorn Tuypens translated this passage


94 journal of Economic Perspectivesw<strong>here</strong>by people try <strong>to</strong> predict by seeking <strong>the</strong> closest match <strong>to</strong> past patterns, withoutattention <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> obsesved probability of matching <strong>the</strong> pattern. For example, whenasked <strong>to</strong> guess <strong>the</strong> occupations of people whose personality and interests aredescribed <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong>m, subjects tended <strong>to</strong> guess <strong>the</strong> occupation that seemed <strong>to</strong> match<strong>the</strong> description as closely as possible, without regard <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> rarity of <strong>the</strong> occupation.Rational subjects would have chosen humdrum and unexceptional occupationsmore because more people are in <strong>the</strong>se occupations. (Kahneman and Tversky,1974). By <strong>the</strong> same principle, people may tend <strong>to</strong> match s<strong>to</strong>ck price patterns in<strong>to</strong>salient categories such as dramatic and persistent price trends, thus leading <strong>to</strong>feedback dynamics, even if <strong>the</strong>se categories may be rarely seen in fundamentalunderlying fac<strong>to</strong>rs.Daniel, Hirschleifer and Subramanyam (1999) have shown that <strong>the</strong> psychologicalprinciple of "biased self-attribution" can also promote feedback. Biasedself-attribution, identified by psychologist Daryl Bem (1965), is a pattern of humanbehavior w<strong>here</strong>by individuals attribute events that confirm <strong>the</strong> validity of <strong>the</strong>iractions <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir own high ability and attribute events that disconfirm <strong>the</strong>ir actions<strong>to</strong> bad luck or sabotage. Upon reading <strong>the</strong> above passage from <strong>the</strong> time of <strong>the</strong>tulipmania, one easily imagines that Gaergoedt is basking in self-esteem andrelishing <strong>the</strong> telling of <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ry. Many readers <strong>to</strong>day can probably easily recallsimilar conversations, and similar ego-involvement by <strong>the</strong> spreaders of <strong>the</strong> word, in<strong>the</strong> 1990s. Such human interactions, <strong>the</strong> essential cause of speculative bubbles,appear <strong>to</strong> recur across centuries and across countries: <strong>the</strong>y reflect fundamentalparameters of human behavior.T<strong>here</strong> is also evidence supportive of feedback from natural experiments, whichmay be more convincing than <strong>the</strong> lab experiments when <strong>the</strong>y occur in real time,with real money, with real social networks and associated interpersonal support andemotions, with real and visceral envy of friends' investment successes, and withcommunications-media presence. Ponzi schemes may be thought of as representingsuch natural experiments. A Ponzi scheme (or pyramid scheme or moneycirculation scheme) involves a superficially plausible but unverifiable s<strong>to</strong>r) abouthow money is made for inves<strong>to</strong>rs and <strong>the</strong> fraudulent creation of high returns forinitial inves<strong>to</strong>rs by giving <strong>the</strong>m <strong>the</strong> money invested by subsequent inves<strong>to</strong>rs. Initialinves<strong>to</strong>r response <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> scheme tends <strong>to</strong> be weak, but as <strong>the</strong> rounds of high returnsgenerates excitement, <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>r) becomes increasingly believable and enticing <strong>to</strong>inves<strong>to</strong>rs. These schemes are often ver) successful in generating extraordinar)enthusiasms among some inves<strong>to</strong>rs. We have seen some spectacular Ponzi schemesrecently in countries that do not have effective regulation and surveillance <strong>to</strong>prevent <strong>the</strong>m. A number of Ponzi schemes in Albania 1996-1997 were so large that<strong>to</strong>tal liabilities reached half a year's GDP; <strong>the</strong>ir collapse brought on a period ofanarchy and civil war in which 2000 people were killed (Janis, 1999). Real worlds<strong>to</strong>ck-market speculative bubbles, I argued in my 2000 book Iwational Exuberance,resemble Ponzi schemes in <strong>the</strong> sense that some "new era" s<strong>to</strong>ry becomes attached<strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> bubble and acquires increasing plausibility and inves<strong>to</strong>r enthusiasm as <strong>the</strong>market continues <strong>to</strong> achieve high returns. Given <strong>the</strong> obvious success of Ponzi


From Effirient Markets The09 <strong>to</strong> Behavioral Finanre 95schemes when <strong>the</strong>y are not s<strong>to</strong>pped by <strong>the</strong> law, we would need a good reason <strong>to</strong>think that analogous phenomena of speculative bubbles are not also likely.The s<strong>to</strong>ck market boom that ended in early 2000 is ano<strong>the</strong>r relevant episode.According <strong>to</strong> my survey data, now expressed in <strong>the</strong> form of s<strong>to</strong>ck market confidenceindexes produced by <strong>the</strong> Yale School of Management and available at (http:,l/icf.som.yale.edu/confidence.index),<strong>the</strong> confidence of individual inves<strong>to</strong>rs that <strong>the</strong>s<strong>to</strong>ck market will go up in <strong>the</strong> next year, and will rebound from any drop, rosedramatically 1989-2000. As in <strong>the</strong> tulipmania centuries before, t<strong>here</strong> was a focusingof public attention and talk on <strong>the</strong> speculative market and a proliferation ofwishful-thinking <strong>the</strong>ories about a "new era" that would propel <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck market ona course that, while uneven, is relentlessly upward, <strong>the</strong>ories that were spread byword of mouth as well as <strong>the</strong> media.It is widely thought that t<strong>here</strong> is a problem with <strong>the</strong> feedback <strong>the</strong>ories: <strong>the</strong><strong>the</strong>ories would seem <strong>to</strong> imply that speculative price changes are strongly seriallycorrelated through time, that prices show strong momentum, continuing uniformlyin one direction day after day. This seems inconsistent with <strong>the</strong> evidence that s<strong>to</strong>ckprices are approximately a random walk.But simple feedback models do not imply strong serial correlation, as I stressedin Shiller (1990). T<strong>here</strong>, I presented a model of <strong>the</strong> demand for a speculative assetas equaling a distributed lag with exponentially declining weights on past pricechanges through time (<strong>the</strong> distributed lag representing feedback distributed overtime), plus o<strong>the</strong>r fac<strong>to</strong>rs that affect demand. The model asserts that people reactgradually <strong>to</strong> price changes over months or years, not just <strong>to</strong> yesterday's pricechange. A his<strong>to</strong>ry of price increases over <strong>the</strong> last year may encourage buying <strong>to</strong>dayeven if yesterday's price change was down. Also, <strong>the</strong> model recognizes that t<strong>here</strong> areo<strong>the</strong>r shocks, besides feedback, influencing price.In such a model, a disturbance in some demand fac<strong>to</strong>r o<strong>the</strong>r than feedbackcan in certain cases be amplified, at least for a time, because it changes <strong>the</strong> priceand thus affects future prices through <strong>the</strong> distributed lag.15 However, unless weknow something about <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r fac<strong>to</strong>rs that drive demand, such a distributed lagmodel does not imply anything at all about <strong>the</strong> serial correlation properties ofspeculative price changes. The feedback model does not imply that t<strong>here</strong> is muchserial correlation in day-<strong>to</strong>-day s<strong>to</strong>ck price changes, since <strong>the</strong> noise in <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rfac<strong>to</strong>rs feeds directly in<strong>to</strong> short-run changes, and <strong>the</strong> effect on <strong>to</strong>day's price oflagged o<strong>the</strong>r fac<strong>to</strong>rs operates at a low frequency that is essentially unrelated <strong>to</strong>day-<strong>to</strong>-day changes and has effects that can be observed only from its cumulativeeffect after a long period of time.Thus, <strong>the</strong> approximate random walk character of s<strong>to</strong>ck prices is not evidence"The feedback model is p, = c J"', eCY('-" dp, + T,, 0 < c < 1, 0 < y. Here, p, is price at timet, and r,is <strong>the</strong> combined effect of o<strong>the</strong>r fac<strong>to</strong>rs on demand. It follo~vs that p, = r,+ (c/(l - c))(r,-is a ~veighted average of lagged T. See Shiller(1990, p. 60). Such a model does not imply that price behaves smoothly through time: price can lookmuch like a random walk if, for example, T, is a random walk.- -T~),w<strong>here</strong> T, = (y/(1- c)) 51, eC(? '('-'""-"T,~T


96 journal of Economic Perspectivesagainst feedback. Moreover, even if feedback did imply some momentum, we canalso note that <strong>the</strong> random walk character of s<strong>to</strong>ck prices is really not fully supportedby <strong>the</strong> evidence anyway, and that in fact t<strong>here</strong> has been more than a little momentum<strong>to</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck prices. Jegadeesh and Titman (1993) found that winning s<strong>to</strong>cks, s<strong>to</strong>cksthat showed exceptionally high six-month returns, beat losing s<strong>to</strong>cks, s<strong>to</strong>cks thatshowed exceptionally low six-month returns, by 12 percent over <strong>the</strong> following year.In contrast, over longer periods of time this momentum seems <strong>to</strong> reverse itself. DeBondt and Thaler (1985) find that over <strong>the</strong> period 1926 <strong>to</strong> 1982, s<strong>to</strong>cks representedon <strong>the</strong> Center for Research in Security Prices data set of <strong>the</strong> University of Chicagowhose returns had been in <strong>the</strong> <strong>to</strong>p decile across firms over three years (thus,"winner" s<strong>to</strong>cks) tended <strong>to</strong> show negative cumulative returns in <strong>the</strong> succeedingthree years. They also found that "loser" s<strong>to</strong>cks whose returns had been in <strong>the</strong>bot<strong>to</strong>m decile over <strong>the</strong> prior three years tended <strong>to</strong> show positive returns over <strong>the</strong>succeeding three years. Thus, t<strong>here</strong> is a tendency for s<strong>to</strong>ck prices <strong>to</strong> continue in <strong>the</strong>same direction over intesvals of six months <strong>to</strong> a year, but <strong>to</strong> reverse <strong>the</strong>mselves overlonger intemals. Campbell, Lo and Mackinlav (1996) document this fact care full^.'^A pattern like this is certainly consistent with some combination of feedback effectsand o<strong>the</strong>r demand fac<strong>to</strong>rs driving <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck market largely independently offundamentals.Smart Money vs. Ordinary Inves<strong>to</strong>rsTheoretical models of efficient financial markets that represent everyone asrational optimizers can be no more than metaphors for <strong>the</strong> world around us.Nothing could be more absurd than <strong>to</strong> claim that everyone knows how <strong>to</strong> solvecomplex s<strong>to</strong>chastic optimization models. For <strong>the</strong>se <strong>the</strong>oretical models <strong>to</strong> have anyrelevance <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck market, it must somehow be <strong>the</strong> case that a smaller elemen<strong>to</strong>f "smart money" or <strong>the</strong> "marginal trader" can offset <strong>the</strong> foolishness of manyinves<strong>to</strong>rs and make <strong>the</strong> markets efficient.The efficient markets <strong>the</strong>ory, as it is commonly expressed, asserts that whenirrational optimists buy a s<strong>to</strong>ck, smart money sells, and when irrational pessimistssell a s<strong>to</strong>ck, smart money buys, t<strong>here</strong>by eliminating <strong>the</strong> effect of <strong>the</strong> irrationaltraders on market price. But finance <strong>the</strong>ory does not necessarily imply that smartmoney succeeds in fully offsetting <strong>the</strong> impact of ordinary inves<strong>to</strong>rs. In recent years,research in behavioral finance has shed some important light on <strong>the</strong> implicationsof <strong>the</strong> presence of <strong>the</strong>se two classes of inves<strong>to</strong>rs for <strong>the</strong>or) and also on somecharacteristics of <strong>the</strong> people in <strong>the</strong> two classes.From a <strong>the</strong>oretical point of view, it is far from clear that smart money has <strong>the</strong>power <strong>to</strong> drive market prices <strong>to</strong> fundamental values. For example, in one modelwith both feedback traders and smart money, <strong>the</strong> smart money tended <strong>to</strong> amplzjj,ra<strong>the</strong>r than diminish, <strong>the</strong> effect of feedback traders, by buying in ahead of <strong>the</strong>'"rinblatt and Han (2001) have argued that this tendency of s<strong>to</strong>ck prices <strong>to</strong> sho~\. nlomentunl for awhile and <strong>the</strong>n reverse <strong>the</strong>mselves might be related <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> phenomenon that inves<strong>to</strong>rs tend <strong>to</strong> hold on<strong>to</strong> losers and sell winners (Statman and Shefrin, 1985; Odean, 1998).


feedback traders in anticipation of <strong>the</strong> price increases <strong>the</strong>y will cause (De Long,Shleifer, Summers and Waldman, 1990b). In a related model, rational, expectedutility-maximizingsmart money never chooses <strong>to</strong> offset all of <strong>the</strong> effects of irrationalinves<strong>to</strong>rs because <strong>the</strong>y are rationally concerned about <strong>the</strong> risk generated by <strong>the</strong>irrational inves<strong>to</strong>rs and do not want <strong>to</strong> assume <strong>the</strong> risk that <strong>the</strong>ir completelyoffsetting <strong>the</strong>se o<strong>the</strong>r inves<strong>to</strong>rs would entail (De Long, Shleifer, Summers andWaldman, 1990b) .IiOften, speculative bubbles appear <strong>to</strong> be common <strong>to</strong> investments of a certain"style," and <strong>the</strong> bubbles may not include many o<strong>the</strong>r investments. For example, <strong>the</strong>s<strong>to</strong>ck market bubble that peaked in <strong>the</strong> year 2000 was strongest in tech s<strong>to</strong>cks orNasdaq s<strong>to</strong>cks. Barberis and Shleifer (2002) present a model in which feedbacktraders' demand for investments within a particular style is related <strong>to</strong> a distributedlag on past returns of that style class. By <strong>the</strong>ir bud<strong>get</strong> constraint, when feedbacktraders are enticed by one style, <strong>the</strong>y must move out of competing styles. The smartmoney are rational utility maximizers. Barberis and Shleifer present a numericalimplementation of <strong>the</strong>ir model and find that smart money did not fully offset <strong>the</strong>effects of <strong>the</strong> feedback traders. Style classes go through periods of boom and bustamplified by <strong>the</strong> feedback.Goetzmann and Massa (1999) provided some direct evidence that it is reasonable<strong>to</strong> suppose that t<strong>here</strong> are c\vo distinct classes of inves<strong>to</strong>rs: feedback traders whofollow trends and <strong>the</strong> smart money who move <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r way. Fidelity Investmentsprovided <strong>the</strong>m with two years of daily account information for 91,000 inves<strong>to</strong>rs ina Standard and Poor's 500 index fund. Goetzmann and Massa were able <strong>to</strong> sort<strong>the</strong>se inves<strong>to</strong>rs in<strong>to</strong> two groups based on how <strong>the</strong>y react <strong>to</strong> daily price changes.T<strong>here</strong> were both momentum inves<strong>to</strong>rs, who habitually bought more after priceswere rising, and contrarian inves<strong>to</strong>rs, or smart money, who habitually sold afterprices were rising. Individual inves<strong>to</strong>rs tended <strong>to</strong> stay as one or <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r, rarelyshifted between <strong>the</strong> two categories.Recent research has focused on an important obstacle <strong>to</strong> smart money'soffsetting <strong>the</strong> effects of irrational inves<strong>to</strong>rs. The smart money can always buy <strong>the</strong>s<strong>to</strong>ck, but if <strong>the</strong> smart money no longer owns <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck and finds it difficult <strong>to</strong> short<strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> smart money may be unable <strong>to</strong> sell <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck. Some s<strong>to</strong>cks couldbe in a situation w<strong>here</strong> zealots have bought in<strong>to</strong> a s<strong>to</strong>ck so much that only zealotsown shares, and trade is only among zealots, and so <strong>the</strong> zealots alone determine <strong>the</strong>price of <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck. The smart money who know that <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck is priced ridiculouslyhigh may well use up all <strong>the</strong> easily available shortable shares and <strong>the</strong>n will bestanding on <strong>the</strong> sidelines, unable <strong>to</strong> short more shares and profit from <strong>the</strong>irknowledge. Miller (1977) pointed out this flaw in <strong>the</strong> argument for market efficiency,and his paper has been discussed ever since.It seems incontrovertible that in some cases s<strong>to</strong>cks have been held primarily byzealots and that short sellers have found it very difficult <strong>to</strong> short. One example is <strong>the</strong>"Shleifer and Summers (1990) present a nice summary of <strong>the</strong>se <strong>the</strong>mes in this journal


98 Journal of Economic Perspectives3Com sale of Palm near <strong>the</strong> peak of <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck market bubble (Lamont and Thaler,2001). In March 2000, Scorn, a profitable provider of network systems and senices,sold <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> general public via an initial public offering 5 percent of its subsidiaryPalm, a maker of handheld computers. 3Com announced at <strong>the</strong> same time that t<strong>here</strong>st of Palm would follow later. The price that <strong>the</strong>se first Palm shares obtained in<strong>the</strong> market was so high, when compared with <strong>the</strong> price of <strong>the</strong> 3Com shares, that ifone subtracts <strong>the</strong> implied value of <strong>the</strong> remaining 95 percent of Palm from <strong>the</strong>3Com market value, one finds that <strong>the</strong> non-Palm part of 3Com had a negativevalue.Since <strong>the</strong> worst possible price for 3Com after <strong>the</strong> Palm sale was completed wouldbe zero, t<strong>here</strong> was thus a strong incentive for inves<strong>to</strong>rs <strong>to</strong> short Palm and buy Scorn.But, <strong>the</strong> interest cost of borrowing Palm shares reached 35 percent by July 2000,putting a damper on <strong>the</strong> advantage <strong>to</strong> exploiting <strong>the</strong> mispricing." Even an inves<strong>to</strong>rwho knew for certain that <strong>the</strong> Palm shares would fall substantially may have beenunable <strong>to</strong> make a profit from this knowledge. The zealots had won with Palm andhad control over its price, for <strong>the</strong> time being.The Palm example is an unusual anomaly. Shorting s<strong>to</strong>cks only rarely becomesso costly. But <strong>the</strong> example proves <strong>the</strong> principle. The question is: How important areobstacles <strong>to</strong> smart money's selling in causing s<strong>to</strong>cks <strong>to</strong> deviate from fundamentalvalue?Of course, in reality, <strong>the</strong> distinction between zealots and smart money is notalways sharp. Instead, t<strong>here</strong> are sometimes all gradations in between, especiallysince <strong>the</strong> objective evidence about <strong>the</strong> fundamental value of individual s<strong>to</strong>cks isalways somewhat ambiguous. If selling short is difficult, a number of individuals<strong>to</strong>cks could become overpriced. It would also appear possible that major segmentsof <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck market, say <strong>the</strong> Nasdaq in 1999, or even <strong>the</strong> entire s<strong>to</strong>ck market, couldwind up owned by, if not zealots, at least relatively optimistic people. Short-saleconstraints could be a fatal flaw in <strong>the</strong> basic efficient markets <strong>the</strong>ory.The problem with evaluating Miller's (1977) <strong>the</strong>ory that a lack of short sellingcan cause financial anomalies like overpricing and bubbles is that t<strong>here</strong> has beenlittle or no data on which s<strong>to</strong>cks are difficult <strong>to</strong> short. T<strong>here</strong> are long time seriesdata series on "short interest," which is <strong>the</strong> <strong>to</strong>tal number of shares that are shorted.Figlewski (1981) found that high levels of short interest for individual s<strong>to</strong>ckspredicts low subsequent returns for <strong>the</strong>m, a direction that would be predicted byMiller's <strong>the</strong>ory. But <strong>the</strong> predictability was weak. On <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r hand, differences inshort interest across s<strong>to</strong>cks do not have an unambiguous connection with difficultyof shorting. S<strong>to</strong>cks differ from each o<strong>the</strong>r in terms of <strong>the</strong> fraction of shares that arein accounts that are shortable. Differences across s<strong>to</strong>cks in short interest can alsoreflect different demand for shorting for hedging needs. Thus, t<strong>here</strong> is a significantl8 Put option prices on Palm also hegan <strong>to</strong> reflect <strong>the</strong> negative opinions and became so experlsive that<strong>the</strong> usual relation between options prices and s<strong>to</strong>ck price, <strong>the</strong> so-called "put-call parih," failed <strong>to</strong> hold.One must remember that options markets are derivative markets that clear separately from s<strong>to</strong>ckmarkets, and overpriced puts have no direct impact on <strong>the</strong> supply and demand for s<strong>to</strong>ck unlessarhitrageurs can exploit <strong>the</strong> overpricing hy shorting <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck.


From EfJicient 1Varkets The09 <strong>to</strong> Behauioral Finance 99errors-in-variables problem when using short interest as an indica<strong>to</strong>r of <strong>the</strong> cost ofshorting.Some recent papers have sought <strong>to</strong> detect <strong>the</strong> presence of barriers that mightlimit short sales indirectly by obsening <strong>the</strong> differences of opinion that can have animpact on price if t<strong>here</strong> is a difficulty shorting s<strong>to</strong>cks. Without obsening barriers <strong>to</strong>shorting s<strong>to</strong>cks directly, we can still infer that when differences of opinion are highabout a s<strong>to</strong>ck, it is more likely that short-sale restrictions will be binding for thats<strong>to</strong>ck, and thus that <strong>the</strong> more pessimistic inves<strong>to</strong>rs hill not prevent <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck frombecoming overpriced and hence subject <strong>to</strong> lower subsequent returns.Scherbina (2000) measured differences of opinion by calculating <strong>the</strong> dispersionof analysts' earnings forecasts. She found that s<strong>to</strong>cks with a high dispersion ofanalysts' forecasts had lower subsequent returns, and she linked <strong>the</strong> low returns <strong>to</strong><strong>the</strong> resolution of <strong>the</strong> uncertainty. Chen, Hong and Stein (2000) measured differenceof opinion by a breadth of ownership measure derived from a database onmutual fund portfolios. The breadth variable for each quarter is <strong>the</strong> ratio of <strong>the</strong>number of mutual funds that hold a long position in <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>to</strong>tal numberof mutual funds for that quarter. They find that firms in <strong>the</strong> <strong>to</strong>p decile by breadthof ownership outperformed those in <strong>the</strong> bot<strong>to</strong>m decile by 4.95 percent per annumafter adjusting for various o<strong>the</strong>r fac<strong>to</strong>rs.What we would really like <strong>to</strong> have <strong>to</strong> test <strong>the</strong> importance of short salesrestrictions on s<strong>to</strong>ck pricing is some evidence on <strong>the</strong> cost of shorting. If those s<strong>to</strong>cksthat have become very costly <strong>to</strong> short tend <strong>to</strong> have poor subsequent returns, <strong>the</strong>nwe will have more direct confirmation of Miller's (1977) <strong>the</strong>ory. T<strong>here</strong> is surprisinglylittle available information about <strong>the</strong> cost of shorting individual s<strong>to</strong>cks. Suchdata have not been available for economic research until recently. A number ofrecent unpublished papers have assembled data on <strong>the</strong> cost of shorting individuals<strong>to</strong>cks, but <strong>the</strong>se papers have assembled data for no more than a year around 2000.Recently, Jones and Lamont (2001) discovered an old source of data on <strong>the</strong>cost of shorting s<strong>to</strong>cks. In <strong>the</strong> 1920s and 1930s in <strong>the</strong> United States, t<strong>here</strong> used <strong>to</strong>be a "loan crowd" on <strong>the</strong> floor of <strong>the</strong> New York S<strong>to</strong>ck Exchange, w<strong>here</strong> one couldlend or borrow shares, and <strong>the</strong> interest rates at which shares were loaned werereported in <strong>the</strong> Wall Street Journal. Jones and Lamont assembled time series of <strong>the</strong>interest rates charged on loans of s<strong>to</strong>cks from 1926 <strong>to</strong> 1933, eight years of data onan average of 80 actively-traded s<strong>to</strong>cks. They found that, after controlling for size,over this period <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>cks that were more expensive <strong>to</strong> short tended <strong>to</strong> be morehighly priced (in terms of market-<strong>to</strong>-book ratios), consistent with <strong>the</strong> Miller (1977)<strong>the</strong>ory. Moreover, <strong>the</strong>y found that <strong>the</strong> more expensive-<strong>to</strong>-short s<strong>to</strong>cks had lowersubsequent returns on average, again consistent with <strong>the</strong> Miller <strong>the</strong>ory. Of course,<strong>the</strong>ir data span only eight years from a remote period in his<strong>to</strong>ry, and so <strong>the</strong>irrelevance <strong>to</strong> <strong>to</strong>day's markets might be questioned.Why has t<strong>here</strong> not been more data on <strong>the</strong> cost of shorting? Why did <strong>the</strong> loancrowd on <strong>the</strong> New York S<strong>to</strong>ck Exchange disappear and <strong>the</strong> loan rates in <strong>the</strong> WallStreetJournalwith it? Perhaps after <strong>the</strong> crash of 1929 <strong>the</strong> widespread hostility <strong>to</strong> shortsellers (who were widely held responsible for <strong>the</strong> crash) forced <strong>the</strong> market <strong>to</strong> go


100 Journal of Eronomir Perspectivesunderground. Jones and Lamont (2001) document a consistent pattern of politicalopposition <strong>to</strong> short sellers after 1929 and point out thatJ. Edgar Hoover, <strong>the</strong> headof <strong>the</strong> Federal Bureau of Investigation, was quoted as saying that he would investigatea conspiracy <strong>to</strong> keep s<strong>to</strong>ck prices low. By 1933, <strong>the</strong> rates shown on <strong>the</strong> loanlist become all zeros, and <strong>the</strong> Wall Street Journal s<strong>to</strong>pped publishing <strong>the</strong> loan list in1934.Fortunately, this long drought of data on <strong>the</strong> cost of shorting s<strong>to</strong>cks may beover, and s<strong>to</strong>cks should become easier <strong>to</strong> short. In 2002, a consortium of financialinstitutions established an electronic market for borrowing and lending s<strong>to</strong>cksonline via a new firm, EquiLend, LLC. The new securities lending platform at(http://uww.equilend.corn)exceeded $11 billion in transactions in its first twoweeks, and daily availability posting exceed $1 trillion.But <strong>the</strong> true cost of shorting s<strong>to</strong>cks is probably much higher than <strong>the</strong> explicitinterest cost of borrowing <strong>the</strong> shares, because of <strong>the</strong> psychological cost that inhibitsshort selling. Most inves<strong>to</strong>rs, even some very smart inves<strong>to</strong>rs, have probably nevereven considered shorting shares. Shorting shares is widely reputed <strong>to</strong> involve somesubstantial risks and nuisances. For example, <strong>the</strong> short-seller always stands <strong>the</strong> riskthat <strong>the</strong> ultimate owner of <strong>the</strong> shares will want <strong>to</strong> sell <strong>the</strong> shares, at which time <strong>the</strong>short-seller is forced <strong>to</strong> return <strong>the</strong> shares. This detail may be little more than anuisance, for <strong>the</strong> short seller can likely borrow <strong>the</strong>m again from ano<strong>the</strong>r lender, butit may figure largely in potential short-sellers' minds.A more important consideration that may weigh on short sellers' minds is <strong>the</strong>unlimited loss potential that short sales entail. When an inves<strong>to</strong>r buys a s<strong>to</strong>ck, <strong>the</strong>potential loss is no greater than <strong>the</strong> original investment. But when an inves<strong>to</strong>rshorts a s<strong>to</strong>ck, <strong>the</strong> potential losses can greatly exceed <strong>the</strong> original investment. Aninves<strong>to</strong>r can always terminate <strong>the</strong>se losses by covering <strong>the</strong> shorts, but this actiontypically brings considerable psychological anguish. Deciding <strong>to</strong> cover one's shortsand <strong>get</strong> out of a short position after losses is psychologically difficult, given <strong>the</strong>evidence on <strong>the</strong> pain of regret. Kahneman and Tversky's prospect <strong>the</strong>ory (1979)suggests that individuals are far more upset by losses than <strong>the</strong>y are pleased byequivalent gains; in fact, individuals are so upset by losses that <strong>the</strong>y will even takegreat risks with <strong>the</strong> hope of avoiding any losses at all. The effects of this pain ofregret have been shown <strong>to</strong> result in a tendency of inves<strong>to</strong>rs in s<strong>to</strong>cks <strong>to</strong> avoid sellinglosers, but <strong>the</strong> same pain of regret ought <strong>to</strong> cause short sellers <strong>to</strong> want <strong>to</strong> avoidcovering <strong>the</strong>ir shorts in a losing situation. People prefer <strong>to</strong> avoid putting <strong>the</strong>mselvesin situations that might confront <strong>the</strong>m with psychologically difficult decisions in <strong>the</strong>future.The s<strong>to</strong>ck market that we have <strong>to</strong>day always limits <strong>the</strong> liability of inves<strong>to</strong>rs. AsMoss (2002) has documented, <strong>the</strong> idea that all publicly traded s<strong>to</strong>cks should havelimited liability for <strong>the</strong>ir inves<strong>to</strong>rs was <strong>the</strong> result of experimenting with differentkinds of s<strong>to</strong>ckholder liability in <strong>the</strong> United States in <strong>the</strong> early nineteenth centuryand <strong>the</strong> discovery of <strong>the</strong> psychological attractiveness of limited liability s<strong>to</strong>cks. Thedebates in <strong>the</strong> early nineteenth century were concerned with <strong>the</strong> balancing of <strong>the</strong>agency costs of limited liability, which encourages businesses <strong>to</strong> take greater risks,


Rob&,J Shiller 101against <strong>the</strong> benefits in terms of peace of mind <strong>to</strong> inves<strong>to</strong>rs. Various alternatives wereconsidered or experimented with, including unlimited liability, unlimited proportionalliability (w<strong>here</strong> individual inves<strong>to</strong>rs in a company are limited <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir proportionateshare of <strong>the</strong> company's losses according <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir share in <strong>the</strong> company),and double liability (w<strong>here</strong> individual inves<strong>to</strong>rs are accountable for <strong>the</strong> capitalsubscribed once again). By around 1830, it was apparent from experiments in NewYork and surrounding states that inves<strong>to</strong>rs found it very appealing that <strong>the</strong>y couldput money down <strong>to</strong> buy a s<strong>to</strong>ck <strong>to</strong>day, and from that day forward face no fur<strong>the</strong>rlosses beyond what <strong>the</strong>y already put down. It allowed <strong>the</strong>m, once having purchaseda s<strong>to</strong>ck, <strong>to</strong> concentrate <strong>the</strong>ir emotions on <strong>the</strong> small probability of <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck doingextremely well, ra<strong>the</strong>r on <strong>the</strong> small probability that someone would come after<strong>the</strong>m for more money. People have always been very attracted <strong>to</strong> lottery tickets, and<strong>the</strong> invention of limited liability, Moss concludes, turned s<strong>to</strong>ck investments psychologicallyin<strong>to</strong> something a lot like lottery tickets. By <strong>the</strong> same <strong>the</strong>ory, <strong>the</strong>n, inves<strong>to</strong>rswill not find short~ng s<strong>to</strong>cks very attractive.Remarkably few shares are in fact sold short. According <strong>to</strong> New York S<strong>to</strong>ckExchange data, from 1977 <strong>to</strong> 2000 year-end short interest ranged from 0.14 percent<strong>to</strong> 1.91 percent of all shares. According <strong>to</strong> Dechow, Hut<strong>to</strong>n, Muelbroek and S<strong>to</strong>ne(2001), less than 2 percent of all s<strong>to</strong>cks had short interest greater than 5 percent ofshares outstanding 1976-1983. Given <strong>the</strong> obviously large difference of opinionabout and difference of public attention <strong>to</strong> different s<strong>to</strong>cks, it is hard <strong>to</strong> see howsuch a small amount of short selling could offset <strong>the</strong> effect on s<strong>to</strong>ck price of <strong>the</strong>extra demand of inves<strong>to</strong>rs who develop an irrational fixation on certain s<strong>to</strong>cks.ConclusionThe collaboration between finance and o<strong>the</strong>r social sciences that has becomeknown as behavioral finance has led <strong>to</strong> a profound deepening of our knowledge offinancial markets. In judging <strong>the</strong> impact of behavioral finance <strong>to</strong> date, it is important<strong>to</strong> apply <strong>the</strong> right standards. Of course, we do not expect such research <strong>to</strong>provide a method <strong>to</strong> make a lot of money off of financial market inefficiency veryfast and reliably. We should not expect market efficiency <strong>to</strong> be so egregiously wrongthat immediate profits should be continually available. But market efficiency can beegregiously wrong in o<strong>the</strong>r senses. For example, efficient markets <strong>the</strong>ory may lead<strong>to</strong> drastically incorrect interpretations of events such as major s<strong>to</strong>ck marketbubbles.In his review of <strong>the</strong> literature on behavioral finance, Eugene Fama (1998)found fault for two basic reasons. The first was that <strong>the</strong> anomalies that werediscovered tended <strong>to</strong> appear <strong>to</strong> be as often underreaction by inves<strong>to</strong>rs as overreaction.The second was that <strong>the</strong> anomalies tended <strong>to</strong> disappear, ei<strong>the</strong>r as timepassed or as methodology of <strong>the</strong> studies improved. His first criticism reflects anincorrect view of <strong>the</strong> psychological underpinnings of behavioral finance. Sincet<strong>here</strong> is no fundamental psychological principle that people tend always <strong>to</strong> over-


102 Journal of Economic Perspectivesreact or always <strong>to</strong> underreact, it is no surprise that research on financial anomaliesdoes not reveal such a principle ei<strong>the</strong>r. His second criticism is also weak. It is <strong>the</strong>nature of scholarly research, at <strong>the</strong> frontier, in all disciplines, that initial claims ofimportant discoveries are often knocked down by later research. The most basicanomaly, of excess volatility, seems hardly <strong>to</strong> have been knocked down, and it is infact graphically reinforced by <strong>the</strong> experience of <strong>the</strong> past few years in <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ckmarkets of <strong>the</strong> world. Moreover, <strong>the</strong> mere fact that anomalies sometimes disappearor switch signs with time is no evidence that <strong>the</strong> markets are fully rational. That isalso what we would expect <strong>to</strong> see happen even in highly irrational markets. (Itwould seem peculiar <strong>to</strong> argue that irrational markets should display regular andlasting patterns!) Even <strong>the</strong> basic relation suggested by market inefficiency, thats<strong>to</strong>cks whose price is bid up by inves<strong>to</strong>rs will tend <strong>to</strong> go back down later, and s<strong>to</strong>cksthat are underpriced by inves<strong>to</strong>rs will tend <strong>to</strong> go up later, is not a relation that canbe easily tested or that should hold in all time periods. The fundamental value ofs<strong>to</strong>cks is hard <strong>to</strong> measure, and, moreover, if speculative bubbles (ei<strong>the</strong>r positivebubbles or negative bubbles) last a long time, <strong>the</strong>n even this fundamental relationmay not be observed except in very long sample periods.In fur<strong>the</strong>r research, it is important <strong>to</strong> bear in mind <strong>the</strong> demonstrated weaknessesof efficient markets <strong>the</strong>ory and maintain an eclectic approach. While <strong>the</strong>oreticalmodels of efficient markets have <strong>the</strong>ir place as illustrations or characterizationsof an ideal world, we cannot maintain <strong>the</strong>m in <strong>the</strong>ir pure form as accuratedescrip<strong>to</strong>rs of actual markets.Indeed, we have <strong>to</strong> distance ourselves from <strong>the</strong> presumption that financialmarkets always work well and that price changes always reflect genuine information.Evidence from behavioral finance helps us <strong>to</strong> understand, for example, that<strong>the</strong> recent worldwide s<strong>to</strong>ck market boom, and <strong>the</strong>n crash after 2000, had its originsin human foibles and arbitrary feedback relations and must have generated a realand substantial misallocation of resources. The challenge for economists is <strong>to</strong> makethis reality a better part of <strong>the</strong>ir models.ReferencesAndreassen, Paul and <strong>Stephen</strong> Kraus. 1988. "Style Investing." NBER Working Paper No.'Yudgmental Prediction by Extrapolation." Un- w8039.published paper, Department of Psycholoa, Barsky, Robert and J. Bradford De Long.Ha1.i-ard University.1993. "Why Does <strong>the</strong> S<strong>to</strong>ck Market Fluctuate?"Anonymous. 1637. Samen-spraeck tusschen Wnw- Qunterb Journal of Economics. May, 108, pp. 291-mondt ende Gawgoedt nopende de opkomste ende on- 311.dergangh van flora. Haerlem: Adriaen Roman, Bern, Daryl J. 1965. "An Experimental Analysisreprinted in Economisch His<strong>to</strong>n'sch Janrboek. 1926, of Self-Persuasion." Journal of Experimental Social12:20-43, pp. 28-29. psycho lo^. 1, pp.199-218.Barberis, Nicholas and Andrei Shleifer. 2000. Breeden, Douglas T. 1979. "AnIntertemporal


From Efficient Markets Theoly <strong>to</strong> Behavioral Finance 103Asset Pricing Model with S<strong>to</strong>chastic Consumptionand Investment Opportunities." Journal ofFinancial Economics. 7:2, pp. 265-96.Campbell, John Y. 1991. "A Variance Decompositionfor S<strong>to</strong>ck Returns." Economic Journal.March, 101:405, pp. 157-79.Campbell, John Y. and Robert J. Shiller. 1988."S<strong>to</strong>ck Prices, Earnings, and Expected Dividends."Journal ofFinance. July, 43:3, pp. 661-76.Campbell, John Y. and Robert J. Shiller. 1989."The Dividend-Price Ratio and Expectations ofFuture Dibldends and Discount Fac<strong>to</strong>rs." RevimofFinancia1 Studies. 1:3, pp. 195-228.Campbell, John Y., Andrew W. Lo and A.Craig MacKinlay. 1996. The Econometrics of FinancialiWarkets. Prince<strong>to</strong>n: Prince<strong>to</strong>n UniversityPress.Qlen, Joseph, Harrison Hong and Jeremy C.Stein. 2000. "Breadth of Ownership and S<strong>to</strong>ck Returns."Unpublished paper, stanford University.Cochrane, John H. 2001. Asset Pricing. Prince<strong>to</strong>n:Prince<strong>to</strong>n University Press.Cohen, Randolph, Chris<strong>to</strong>pher Polk andTuomo Vuolteenaho. 2002. "The Value Spread."Unpublished paper, Harvard Business School.Forthcoming,Journal of Finance.Cole, Kevin, Jean Helwege and David Laster.1996. "S<strong>to</strong>ck Market Valuation Indica<strong>to</strong>rs: IsThis Time Different?" Financial Analysts Journal.May/June, pp. 56-64.Daniel, Kent, David Hihleifer and AvanidharSubramanyam. 1998. "Inves<strong>to</strong>r Psychology andSecurity Market Under- and Overreactions."Journal of Finance. December, 53:6, pp. 1839-885.De Bondt, Werner F. M. and Richard H. Thaler.1985."Does <strong>the</strong> S<strong>to</strong>ck Market Overreact?"Journal of Finance. July, 40:3, pp. 793-805.De Long, J. Bradford, Andrei Shleifer, LawrenceH. Summers and Robert J. Waldmann.1990a. "Noise Trader Risk in Financial Markets."Journal of Political Economy. August, 98:4, pp.703-38.De Long, J. Bradford, Andrei Shleifer, LawrenceH. Summers and Robert J. Waldmann.1990b. "Positive Feedback Investment Strategiesand Destabilizing Rational Speculation." Jouhalof Finance. June, 45:2, pp. 379-95.Dechow, Patricia M., Amy P. Hut<strong>to</strong>n, LisaMuelbroek and Richard G. S<strong>to</strong>ne. 2001. "Short-Selling, Fundamental Analysis and S<strong>to</strong>ck Returns."Journal ofFinancia1 Economics. Forthcoming.Fama, Eugene F. 1970. "Efficient Capital Markets:A Review of Empirical Work." Journal ofFinance. May, 25:2, pp. 383-417.Fama, Eugene F. 1991. "Efficient Capital Mar-kets: 11." Journal of Finance. December, 46:5,pp. 1575-617.Fama, Eugene F. 1998. "Market Efficiency,Long-Term Returns, and Behavioral Finance."Journal of Financial Economics. September, 49:3,pp. 283-306.Figlewski, <strong>Stephen</strong>. 1981. "The InformationalEffects of Restrictions on Short Sales: Some EmpiricalEvidence." Journal of Financial and QuantitativeAnalysis. November, 16:4, pp. 463-76.Figlewski, <strong>Stephen</strong> and Gwendolyn P. Webb.1993. "Options, Short Sales, and Market Completeness."Journal of Finance. June, 48:2, pp.761-77.Garber, Peter M. 1990. "Famous First Bubbles."Journal ofEconomic Pwspectives. Spring, 4:2,pp. 35-54.Garber, Peter M. 2000. Famous First Bubbles.Cambridge: MIT Press.Goetzmann, William N. and Massimo Massa.1999. "Daily Momentum and Contrarian Behaviorof Index Fund Inves<strong>to</strong>rs." Unpublished paper,Yale University.Grinblatt, Mark and Bing Han. 2001. "TheDisposition Effect and Momentum." Unpublished paper, Anderson School, UCLA.Grossman, Sanford J. and Robert J. Shiller.1981. "The Determinants of <strong>the</strong> Variability ofS<strong>to</strong>ck Market Prices." American Economic him.May, 71:2, pp. 222-27.Hansen, Lars P. and Ravi Jagannathan. 1991."Implications of Security Market Data for Modelsof Dynamic Economies." Journal of PoliticalEconomy. April, 99:2, pp. 225-62.Jarvis, Chris. 1999. "The Rise and Fall of <strong>the</strong>Pyramid Schemes in Albania." InternationalMonetary Fund Working Paper No. 99-98.Jegadeesh, Narasimhan and Sheridan Titman.1993. "Returns <strong>to</strong> Buying Winners and SellingLosers: Implications for S<strong>to</strong>ck Market Efficiency."Journal of Finance. March, 48:1, pp.65-91.Jones, Charles M. and Owen A. Lamont.2001."Short-Sale Constraints and S<strong>to</strong>ck Returns."NBER Working Paper No. 8494.Jung, Jeeman and Robert J. Shiller. 2002."One Simple Test of Samuelson's Dictum for <strong>the</strong>S<strong>to</strong>ck Market." NBER Working Paper No.w9348.Kahneman, Daniel and Amos Tversky. 1979."Prospect Theory: An Analysis of Decision UnderRisk." Econometrica. March, 47:2, pp. 263-92.Lamont, Owen A. and Richard H. Thaler.2001. "Can <strong>the</strong> Market Add and Subtract? Mispricingin S<strong>to</strong>ck Market Ca1.i-e-Outs." NationalBureau of Economic Research Working Paper


104 Journal of Economzc PerspectivesNo. 8302, 2000. Forthcoming, Journal of PoliticalEconomy.LeRoy, <strong>Stephen</strong> F. and Richard D. Porter.1981. "The Present-Value Relation: Tests Basedon Implied L'ariance Bounds." Econometn'ca. May,49:3, p p 97-113.Lucas, Robert E. 1978. "Asset Prices in anExchange Economy." Econometn'ca. November,465, pp. 1429-445.MacKay, Charles. 1996. "Memoirs of ExtraordinaryPopular Delusions," 1841, in ExtraordinaqPopular Delusions and <strong>the</strong> ,C3ndness of Crowds andConfusidn de Confusiones. Martin Fridson, ed. NewYork: John Wiley.Malkiel, Bur<strong>to</strong>n G. 1973. A Random Jt'alk DownMrall Street. New York: W. W. Nor<strong>to</strong>n.Marimon, Ramon, <strong>Stephen</strong> E. Spear andShyam Sunder. 1993. "Expectationally DrivenMarket L'olatility: An Experimental Study." JournalofEconomic Theo?. Oc<strong>to</strong>ber, 61:l, pp. 74-103.Marsh, Teny A. and Robert C. Mer<strong>to</strong>n. 1986."Dividend Variability and Variance Bounds Testsfor <strong>the</strong> Rationality of S<strong>to</strong>ck Market Prices." AmericanEconomic Revim. June, 763, pp. 483-98.McGrattan, Wen R. and Edward C. Prescott.2001. "Taxes, Regulation, and Asset Prices." Unpublishedpaper, Federal Reserve Bank of Minneapolis.Mer<strong>to</strong>n, Robert C. 1973. "An IntertemporalCapital Asset Pricing Model." Econometn'ca. September,41:5, pp. 867-87.Miller, Edward M. 1977. "Risk, Uncertaintyand Divergence of Opinion." Journal of Finance.September, 32:4, pp. 1151-168.Moss, David A. 2002. When All Else Fails: Governmentas <strong>the</strong> LJltimate Risk iknager. Cambridge,Mass.: Harvard University Press.Odean, Terrance. 1998. "Are Inves<strong>to</strong>rs Reluctant<strong>to</strong> Realize <strong>the</strong>ir Losses?" Journal of Finance.Oc<strong>to</strong>ber, 53:5, pp. 1775-798.Samuelson, Paul A. 1998. "Summing Up onBusiness Cycles: Opening Address," in BeyondShocks: T.l'hat Causes Business Cycles. Jeffrey C. Fuhrerand Scott Schuh, eds. Bos<strong>to</strong>n: Federal ReserveBank of Bos<strong>to</strong>n, pp. 33-36.Scherbina, Anna. 2000. "S<strong>to</strong>ck Prices and Differencesin Opinion: Empirical Evidence thatPrices Reflect Optimism." Unpublished paper,Northwestern University.Shefrin, Hersh. 2000. Beyond Greed and Fear:Lkderstanding Behavioral Finance and <strong>the</strong> Psycholog?'oflnvesting. Bos<strong>to</strong>n, Mass.: Harvard BusinessSchool Press.Shefrin, Hersh. 2001. Behavioral Finance (TheInternational Libra? of Critical M'ritings in FinancialEconomics), Volumes I through lV Cheltenham,U.K.: Edward Elgar.Shiller, Robert J. 1982. "Consumption, AssetMarkets and Macroeconomic Fluctuations."Carnegze-Rochester Confprence Series on Public Policy.Autumn, 17, pp. 203-38.Shiller, Robert J. 1989. Market Volatility. Cambridge,Mass.: MIT Press.Shiller, Robert J. 1990a. "Speculative Pricesand Popular Models." Journal ofEconomic Perspectives.Spring, 4:2, pp. 55-65.Shiller, Robert J. 1990b. "Market Volatilityand Inves<strong>to</strong>r Behavior." Amm'can Economic Revim.May, 80:2, pp. 58-62.Shiller, Robert J. 2000a. In-ational Exuberance.Prince<strong>to</strong>n, N.J.: Prince<strong>to</strong>n University Press.Shiller, Robert J. 2000b. "Measuring BubbleExpectations and Inves<strong>to</strong>r Confidence." Journalof psycho lo^ and Financial Markets. 1: 1, pp.49-60.Shiller, Robert J. 2002. "Bubbles, HumanJudgment, and Expert Opinion." Financial AnalystsJournal. 58, pp. 18-26.Shleifer, Andrei. 2000. InefJicient ,C3nrkets. Oxford:Oxford University Press.Shielfer, Andrei and Lawrence Summers.1990. "The Noise-Trader Approach <strong>to</strong> Finance."Journal of Economic Perspectzves. Spring, 4:2 pp.19-33.Siegel, Jeremy J. 2002. S<strong>to</strong>cks for <strong>the</strong> Long Run.Third Edition. New York: McGraw-Hill.Smith, Vernon, Geny Suchanek and Arling<strong>to</strong>nWilliams. 1988. "Bubbles, Crashes, and EndogenousExpectations in Experimental Spot AssetMarkets." Econometn'ca. September, 565, pp.1119-153.Statman, Meir and Hersh Shefrin. 1985. "TheDisposition <strong>to</strong> Sell Winners Too Early and RideLosers Too Long: Theory and Evidence." Journalof Finance. July, 40:3, pp. 777-90.Thaler, Richard. 2003. Advances in BehavioralFinance II. New York: Russell Sage.Tversky, Amos and Daniel Kahneman. 1974."Judgment under Uncertainty: Heuristics andBiases." Science. 185:4157, pp. 1124-31.Vuolteenaho, Tuomo. "What Drives Firm-Level S<strong>to</strong>ck Returns?" Journal of Finance. February,57:1, pp. 233-64.West, Kenneth D. 1988. "Dividend Innovationsand S<strong>to</strong>ck Price Volatility." Econometrica.January, 561, pp. 36-71.


http://www.js<strong>to</strong>r.orgLINKED CITATIONS- Page 1 of 7 -You have printed <strong>the</strong> following article:From Efficient Markets Theory <strong>to</strong> Behavioral FinanceRobert J. ShillerThe Journal of Economic Perspectives, Vol. 17, No. 1. (Winter, 2003), pp. 83-104.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0895-3309%28200324%2917%3A1%3C83%3AFEMTTB%3E2.0.CO%3B2-JThis article references <strong>the</strong> following linked citations. If you are trying <strong>to</strong> access articles from anoff-campus location, you may be required <strong>to</strong> first logon via your library web site <strong>to</strong> access JSTOR. Pleasevisit your library's website or contact a librarian <strong>to</strong> learn about options for remote access <strong>to</strong> JSTOR.[Footnotes]4 Dividend Innovations and S<strong>to</strong>ck Price VolatilityKenneth D. WestEconometrica, Vol. 56, No. 1. (Jan., 1988), pp. 37-61.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0012-9682%28198801%2956%3A1%3C37%3ADIASPV%3E2.0.CO%3B2-M5 Why Does <strong>the</strong> S<strong>to</strong>ck Market Fluctuate?Robert B. Barsky; J. Bradford De LongThe Quarterly Journal of Economics, Vol. 108, No. 2. (May, 1993), pp. 291-311.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0033-5533%28199305%29108%3A2%3C291%3AWDTSMF%3E2.0.CO%3B2-I7 The Dividend-Price Ratio and Expectations of Future Dividends and Discount Fac<strong>to</strong>rsJohn Y. Campbell; Robert J. ShillerThe Review of Financial Studies, Vol. 1, No. 3. (Autumn, 1988), pp. 195-228.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0893-9454%28198823%291%3A3%3C195%3ATDRAEO%3E2.0.CO%3B2-O8 Asset Prices in an Exchange EconomyRobert E. Lucas, Jr.Econometrica, Vol. 46, No. 6. (Nov., 1978), pp. 1429-1445.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0012-9682%28197811%2946%3A6%3C1429%3AAPIAEE%3E2.0.CO%3B2-INOTE: The reference numbering from <strong>the</strong> original has been maintained in this citation list.


http://www.js<strong>to</strong>r.orgLINKED CITATIONS- Page 2 of 7 -8 The Determinants of <strong>the</strong> Variability of S<strong>to</strong>ck Market PricesSanford J. Grossman; Robert J. ShillerThe American Economic Review, Vol. 71, No. 2, Papers and Proceedings of <strong>the</strong> Ninety-ThirdAnnual Meeting of <strong>the</strong> American Economic Association. (May, 1981), pp. 222-227.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0002-8282%28198105%2971%3A2%3C222%3ATDOTVO%3E2.0.CO%3B2-815 Market Volatility and Inves<strong>to</strong>r BehaviorRobert J. ShillerThe American Economic Review, Vol. 80, No. 2, Papers and Proceedings of <strong>the</strong> Hundred andSecond Annual Meeting of <strong>the</strong> American Economic Association. (May, 1990), pp. 58-62.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0002-8282%28199005%2980%3A2%3C58%3AMVAIB%3E2.0.CO%3B2-H16 A Theoretical Analysis of Real Estate Returns: DiscussionMeir StatmanThe Journal of Finance, Vol. 40, No. 3, Papers and Proceedings of <strong>the</strong> Forty-Third Annual MeetingAmerican Finance Association, Dallas, Texas, December 28-30, 1984. (Jul., 1985), pp. 719-721.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0022-1082%28198507%2940%3A3%3C719%3AATAORE%3E2.0.CO%3B2-816 Are Inves<strong>to</strong>rs Reluctant <strong>to</strong> Realize Their Losses?Terrance OdeanThe Journal of Finance, Vol. 53, No. 5. (Oct., 1998), pp. 1775-1798.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0022-1082%28199810%2953%3A5%3C1775%3AAIRTRT%3E2.0.CO%3B2-4ReferencesWhy Does <strong>the</strong> S<strong>to</strong>ck Market Fluctuate?Robert B. Barsky; J. Bradford De LongThe Quarterly Journal of Economics, Vol. 108, No. 2. (May, 1993), pp. 291-311.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0033-5533%28199305%29108%3A2%3C291%3AWDTSMF%3E2.0.CO%3B2-INOTE: The reference numbering from <strong>the</strong> original has been maintained in this citation list.


http://www.js<strong>to</strong>r.orgLINKED CITATIONS- Page 3 of 7 -A Variance Decomposition for S<strong>to</strong>ck ReturnsJohn Y. CampbellThe Economic Journal, Vol. 101, No. 405. (Mar., 1991), pp. 157-179.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0013-0133%28199103%29101%3A405%3C157%3AAVDFSR%3E2.0.CO%3B2-XS<strong>to</strong>ck Prices, Earnings, and Expected DividendsJohn Y. Campbell; Robert J. ShillerThe Journal of Finance, Vol. 43, No. 3, Papers and Proceedings of <strong>the</strong> Forty-Seventh AnnualMeeting of <strong>the</strong> American Finance Association, Chicago, Illinois, December 28-30, 1987. (Jul.,1988), pp. 661-676.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0022-1082%28198807%2943%3A3%3C661%3ASPEAED%3E2.0.CO%3B2-1The Dividend-Price Ratio and Expectations of Future Dividends and Discount Fac<strong>to</strong>rsJohn Y. Campbell; Robert J. ShillerThe Review of Financial Studies, Vol. 1, No. 3. (Autumn, 1988), pp. 195-228.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0893-9454%28198823%291%3A3%3C195%3ATDRAEO%3E2.0.CO%3B2-OInves<strong>to</strong>r Psychology and Security Market under- and OverreactionsKent Daniel; David Hirshleifer; Avanidhar SubrahmanyamThe Journal of Finance, Vol. 53, No. 6. (Dec., 1998), pp. 1839-1885.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0022-1082%28199812%2953%3A6%3C1839%3AIPASMU%3E2.0.CO%3B2-%23Does <strong>the</strong> S<strong>to</strong>ck Market Overreact?Werner F. M. De Bondt; Richard ThalerThe Journal of Finance, Vol. 40, No. 3, Papers and Proceedings of <strong>the</strong> Forty-Third Annual MeetingAmerican Finance Association, Dallas, Texas, December 28-30, 1984. (Jul., 1985), pp. 793-805.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0022-1082%28198507%2940%3A3%3C793%3ADTSMO%3E2.0.CO%3B2-QNoise Trader Risk in Financial MarketsJ. Bradford De Long; Andrei Shleifer; Lawrence H. Summers; Robert J. WaldmannThe Journal of Political Economy, Vol. 98, No. 4. (Aug., 1990), pp. 703-738.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0022-3808%28199008%2998%3A4%3C703%3ANTRIFM%3E2.0.CO%3B2-LNOTE: The reference numbering from <strong>the</strong> original has been maintained in this citation list.


http://www.js<strong>to</strong>r.orgLINKED CITATIONS- Page 4 of 7 -Positive Feedback Investment Strategies and Destabilizing Rational SpeculationJ. Bradford de Long; Andrei Shleifer; Lawrence H. Summers; Robert J. WaldmannThe Journal of Finance, Vol. 45, No. 2. (Jun., 1990), pp. 379-395.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0022-1082%28199006%2945%3A2%3C379%3APFISAD%3E2.0.CO%3B2-YEfficient Capital Markets: A Review of Theory and Empirical WorkEugene F. FamaThe Journal of Finance, Vol. 25, No. 2, Papers and Proceedings of <strong>the</strong> Twenty-Eighth AnnualMeeting of <strong>the</strong> American Finance Association New York, N.Y. December, 28-30, 1969. (May,1970), pp. 383-417.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0022-1082%28197005%2925%3A2%3C383%3AECMARO%3E2.0.CO%3B2-VEfficient Capital Markets: IIEugene F. FamaThe Journal of Finance, Vol. 46, No. 5. (Dec., 1991), pp. 1575-1617.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0022-1082%28199112%2946%3A5%3C1575%3AECMI%3E2.0.CO%3B2-LThe Informational Effects of Restrictions on Short Sales: Some Empirical Evidence<strong>Stephen</strong> FiglewskiThe Journal of Financial and Quantitative Analysis, Vol. 16, No. 4, Proceedings of 16th AnnualConference of <strong>the</strong> Western Finance Association, June 18-20, 1981, Jackson Hole, Wyoming. (Nov.,1981), pp. 463-476.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0022-1090%28198111%2916%3A4%3C463%3ATIEORO%3E2.0.CO%3B2-COptions, Short Sales, and Market Completeness<strong>Stephen</strong> Figlewski; Gwendolyn P. WebbThe Journal of Finance, Vol. 48, No. 2. (Jun., 1993), pp. 761-777.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0022-1082%28199306%2948%3A2%3C761%3AOSSAMC%3E2.0.CO%3B2-QNOTE: The reference numbering from <strong>the</strong> original has been maintained in this citation list.


http://www.js<strong>to</strong>r.orgLINKED CITATIONS- Page 5 of 7 -Famous First BubblesPeter M. GarberThe Journal of Economic Perspectives, Vol. 4, No. 2. (Spring, 1990), pp. 35-54.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0895-3309%28199021%294%3A2%3C35%3AFFB%3E2.0.CO%3B2-9The Determinants of <strong>the</strong> Variability of S<strong>to</strong>ck Market PricesSanford J. Grossman; Robert J. ShillerThe American Economic Review, Vol. 71, No. 2, Papers and Proceedings of <strong>the</strong> Ninety-ThirdAnnual Meeting of <strong>the</strong> American Economic Association. (May, 1981), pp. 222-227.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0002-8282%28198105%2971%3A2%3C222%3ATDOTVO%3E2.0.CO%3B2-8Implications of Security Market Data for Models of Dynamic EconomiesLars Peter Hansen; Ravi JagannathanThe Journal of Political Economy, Vol. 99, No. 2. (Apr., 1991), pp. 225-262.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0022-3808%28199104%2999%3A2%3C225%3AIOSMDF%3E2.0.CO%3B2-LReturns <strong>to</strong> Buying Winners and Selling Losers: Implications for S<strong>to</strong>ck Market EfficiencyNarasimhan Jegadeesh; Sheridan TitmanThe Journal of Finance, Vol. 48, No. 1. (Mar., 1993), pp. 65-91.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0022-1082%28199303%2948%3A1%3C65%3ARTBWAS%3E2.0.CO%3B2-YProspect Theory: An Analysis of Decision under RiskDaniel Kahneman; Amos TverskyEconometrica, Vol. 47, No. 2. (Mar., 1979), pp. 263-292.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0012-9682%28197903%2947%3A2%3C263%3APTAAOD%3E2.0.CO%3B2-3The Present-Value Relation: Tests Based on Implied Variance Bounds<strong>Stephen</strong> F. LeRoy; Richard D. PorterEconometrica, Vol. 49, No. 3. (May, 1981), pp. 555-574.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0012-9682%28198105%2949%3A3%3C555%3ATPRTBO%3E2.0.CO%3B2-3NOTE: The reference numbering from <strong>the</strong> original has been maintained in this citation list.


http://www.js<strong>to</strong>r.orgLINKED CITATIONS- Page 6 of 7 -Asset Prices in an Exchange EconomyRobert E. Lucas, Jr.Econometrica, Vol. 46, No. 6. (Nov., 1978), pp. 1429-1445.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0012-9682%28197811%2946%3A6%3C1429%3AAPIAEE%3E2.0.CO%3B2-IDividend Variability and Variance Bounds Tests for <strong>the</strong> Rationality of S<strong>to</strong>ck Market PricesTerry A. Marsh; Robert C. Mer<strong>to</strong>nThe American Economic Review, Vol. 76, No. 3. (Jun., 1986), pp. 483-498.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0002-8282%28198606%2976%3A3%3C483%3ADVAVBT%3E2.0.CO%3B2-CAn Intertemporal Capital Asset Pricing ModelRobert C. Mer<strong>to</strong>nEconometrica, Vol. 41, No. 5. (Sep., 1973), pp. 867-887.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0012-9682%28197309%2941%3A5%3C867%3AAICAPM%3E2.0.CO%3B2-ERisk, Uncertainty, and Divergence of OpinionEdward M. MillerThe Journal of Finance, Vol. 32, No. 4. (Sep., 1977), pp. 1151-1168.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0022-1082%28197709%2932%3A4%3C1151%3ARUADOO%3E2.0.CO%3B2-MAre Inves<strong>to</strong>rs Reluctant <strong>to</strong> Realize Their Losses?Terrance OdeanThe Journal of Finance, Vol. 53, No. 5. (Oct., 1998), pp. 1775-1798.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0022-1082%28199810%2953%3A5%3C1775%3AAIRTRT%3E2.0.CO%3B2-4Speculative Prices and Popular ModelsRobert J. ShillerThe Journal of Economic Perspectives, Vol. 4, No. 2. (Spring, 1990), pp. 55-65.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0895-3309%28199021%294%3A2%3C55%3ASPAPM%3E2.0.CO%3B2-INOTE: The reference numbering from <strong>the</strong> original has been maintained in this citation list.


http://www.js<strong>to</strong>r.orgLINKED CITATIONS- Page 7 of 7 -Market Volatility and Inves<strong>to</strong>r BehaviorRobert J. ShillerThe American Economic Review, Vol. 80, No. 2, Papers and Proceedings of <strong>the</strong> Hundred andSecond Annual Meeting of <strong>the</strong> American Economic Association. (May, 1990), pp. 58-62.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0002-8282%28199005%2980%3A2%3C58%3AMVAIB%3E2.0.CO%3B2-HBubbles, Crashes, and Endogenous Expectations in Experimental Spot Asset MarketsVernon L. Smith; Gerry L. Suchanek; Arling<strong>to</strong>n W. WilliamsEconometrica, Vol. 56, No. 5. (Sep., 1988), pp. 1119-1151.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0012-9682%28198809%2956%3A5%3C1119%3ABCAEEI%3E2.0.CO%3B2-3A Theoretical Analysis of Real Estate Returns: DiscussionMeir StatmanThe Journal of Finance, Vol. 40, No. 3, Papers and Proceedings of <strong>the</strong> Forty-Third Annual MeetingAmerican Finance Association, Dallas, Texas, December 28-30, 1984. (Jul., 1985), pp. 719-721.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0022-1082%28198507%2940%3A3%3C719%3AATAORE%3E2.0.CO%3B2-8Judgment under Uncertainty: Heuristics and BiasesAmos Tversky; Daniel KahnemanScience, New Series, Vol. 185, No. 4157. (Sep. 27, 1974), pp. 1124-1131.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0036-8075%2819740927%293%3A185%3A4157%3C1124%3AJUUHAB%3E2.0.CO%3B2-MWhat Drives Firm-Level S<strong>to</strong>ck Returns?Tuomo VuolteenahoThe Journal of Finance, Vol. 57, No. 1. (Feb., 2002), pp. 233-264.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0022-1082%28200202%2957%3A1%3C233%3AWDFSR%3E2.0.CO%3B2-FDividend Innovations and S<strong>to</strong>ck Price VolatilityKenneth D. WestEconometrica, Vol. 56, No. 1. (Jan., 1988), pp. 37-61.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0012-9682%28198801%2956%3A1%3C37%3ADIASPV%3E2.0.CO%3B2-MNOTE: The reference numbering from <strong>the</strong> original has been maintained in this citation list.


Rationality as Process and as Product of ThoughtHerbert A. SimonThe American Economic Review, Vol. 68, No. 2, Papers and Proceedings of <strong>the</strong> Ninetieth AnnualMeeting of <strong>the</strong> American Economic Association. (May, 1978), pp. 1-16.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0002-8282%28197805%2968%3A2%3C1%3ARAPAAP%3E2.0.CO%3B2-4The American Economic Review is currently published by American Economic Association.Your use of <strong>the</strong> JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available athttp://www.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/about/terms.html. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtainedprior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in<strong>the</strong> JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use.Please contact <strong>the</strong> publisher regarding any fur<strong>the</strong>r use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained athttp://www.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/journals/aea.html.Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain <strong>the</strong> same copyright notice that appears on <strong>the</strong> screen or printedpage of such transmission.The JSTOR Archive is a trusted digital reposi<strong>to</strong>ry providing for long-term preservation and access <strong>to</strong> leading academicjournals and scholarly literature from around <strong>the</strong> world. The Archive is supported by libraries, scholarly societies, publishers,and foundations. It is an initiative of JSTOR, a not-for-profit organization with a mission <strong>to</strong> help <strong>the</strong> scholarly community takeadvantage of advances in technology. For more information regarding JSTOR, please contact support@js<strong>to</strong>r.org.http://www.js<strong>to</strong>r.orgTue Jan 15 08:09:07 2008


RICHARD T. ELY LECTURERationality as Process and as Product of ThoughtThis opportunity <strong>to</strong> deliver <strong>the</strong> RichardT. Ely Lecture affords me some very personalsatisfactions. Ely. unbeknownst <strong>to</strong>him, bore a great responsibility for my economiceducation, and even for my choice ofprofession. The example of my uncle,Harold Merkel, who was a student of Commonsand Ely at Wisconsin before WorldWar I, taught me that human behavior wasa fit subject for scientific study, anddirected me <strong>to</strong> economics and politicalscience instead of high energy physics ormolecular biology. Some would refer <strong>to</strong> thisas satisficing, for I had never heard of highenergy physics or molecular biology. andhence was spared an agonizing weighing ofalternative utiles. I simply picked <strong>the</strong> firstprofession that sounded fascinating.Ely's influence went much fur<strong>the</strong>r thanthat. My older bro<strong>the</strong>r's copy of his Oirtlinesof Er.ono~?~ic.c -<strong>the</strong> 1930 edition-wason our bookshelves when I prepared forhigh school debates on tariffs versus freetrade, and on <strong>the</strong> Single Tax of HenryGeorge. It provided me with a sufficientlygood grounding in principles that I was laterable <strong>to</strong> take Henry Simons' intermediate<strong>the</strong>ory course at <strong>the</strong> University of Chicago.and <strong>the</strong> graduate courses of Frank Knightand Henry Schultz without additionalpreparation.The Ely textbook. in its generation, held<strong>the</strong> place of Samuelson or Bach in ours. If itwould not sound as though I were denyingany progress in economics over <strong>the</strong> pasthalf century, I might suggest that Ely'stextbook could be substituted for any of ourcurrent ones at a substantial reduction inweight. and without students or teacher beingmore than dimly aware of <strong>the</strong> replacement.Of course <strong>the</strong>y would not hear fromEly about marginal propensities <strong>to</strong> do thisCarnegie-Mellon Universityor that, nor about <strong>the</strong> late lamented Phillipscurve. But monetarists could rejoice inEly's uncompromising statement of <strong>the</strong>quantity <strong>the</strong>ory (p. 298, italics). and in hisassertion that "<strong>the</strong> solution of <strong>the</strong> problemof unemployment depends largely upon indirectmeasures, such as monetary andbanking reform"-Ely does go on <strong>to</strong> say,however. that "we shall recognize that societymust offer a willing and able man anopportunity <strong>to</strong> work" (p. 528).I. Rationalit! in and out of EconomicsI have more than personal reasons for directingyour attention <strong>to</strong> Ely's textbook.On page 4. we find a definition of economicsthat is, I think, wholly characteristicof books contemporary with his."Economics," he says, "is <strong>the</strong> sciencewhich treats of those social phenomena thatare due <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> wealth-<strong>get</strong>ting and wealthusingactivities of man." Economics. that is<strong>to</strong> say. concerns itself with a particularsubset of man's behaviors-those having <strong>to</strong>do with <strong>the</strong> production, exchange, andconsumption of goods and services.Many, perhaps most. economists <strong>to</strong>daywould regard that view as <strong>to</strong>o limiting.They would prefer <strong>the</strong> definition proposedin <strong>the</strong> Internationnl Encyt lopedia of tlzeSociril Sciences: "Economics . . . is <strong>the</strong>study of <strong>the</strong> allocation of scarce resourcesamong unlimited and competing uses" (vol.4. p. 472). If beefsteak is scarce. <strong>the</strong>y wouldsay. so are votes, and <strong>the</strong> <strong>to</strong>ols of economicanalysis can be used as readily <strong>to</strong> analyze<strong>the</strong> allocation of <strong>the</strong> one as of <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r.This point of view has launched economicsin<strong>to</strong> many excursions and incursions in<strong>to</strong>political science and her o<strong>the</strong>r sister socialsciences, and has generated a certainamount of hubris in <strong>the</strong> profession withrespect <strong>to</strong> its broader civilizing mission. I


) MIC ASSOCIA TI0 V MAY 1978would suppose that <strong>the</strong> program of thismeeting. hith its emphasis upon <strong>the</strong> relationsbetween economics and <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rsocial sciences. is at least partly a reflectionof that hubris.The <strong>to</strong>pic of allocating scarce resourcescan be approached from ei<strong>the</strong>r its normativeor its positive sicie. Fundamental <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong>approach from ei<strong>the</strong>r side are assumptionsabout <strong>the</strong> adaetation of means <strong>to</strong> ends. ofactions <strong>to</strong> goals and situations. Economics.whe<strong>the</strong>r normative or positive, has notsimply been <strong>the</strong> study of <strong>the</strong> allocation ofscarce resources. it has been <strong>the</strong> study of<strong>the</strong> rrrtional allocation of scarce resources.Moreover, <strong>the</strong> term "rational" has loneuhad in economics a much more specificmeaning than its general dictionarysignification of "agreeable <strong>to</strong> reason; notabsurd. preposterous. extravagant. foolish,fanciful. or <strong>the</strong> like; intelligent. sensible."4s is \bell known. <strong>the</strong> rational man of economic.,is a maximizer. who will \ettle fornothing less than <strong>the</strong> best. Even his expectations,we have learned in <strong>the</strong> past fewyears, are rational (see John Muth, 1961).'And his rationality extends as far as <strong>the</strong>bedroom for. as Gary Becker tells us, "hewould read in bed at night only if <strong>the</strong> valueof reading exceeded <strong>the</strong> value (<strong>to</strong> him) of<strong>the</strong> loss in sleep suffered by his wife"(1974, p. 1078).It is this concept of rationality that is economics'main export commodity in its tradewith <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r social sciences. It is nonovelty in those sciences <strong>to</strong> propose thatpeople behave rationally-if that term istahen in its broader dictionary sense.Assumptions of rationality are essentialcomponents of virtually all <strong>the</strong> sociological.psychological, political. and ~tnthropological<strong>the</strong>ories with which I am familiar.What economics has <strong>to</strong> export, <strong>the</strong>n, is not'The term is ill-chown. for rational expectations in<strong>the</strong> sense of Muth are profit-maximizing expectationsonly under very special circumstances (see belo\+).Perhaps we would mislead o~irselves and o<strong>the</strong>rs less ifwe called <strong>the</strong>n1 by <strong>the</strong> less alluring phrase. "consistentexpectations.''rationality, but a very particular and specialform of it-<strong>the</strong> rationality of <strong>the</strong> utilitymaximizer, and a pretty smart one at that.But international flows have <strong>to</strong> bebalanced. If <strong>the</strong> program of this meetingaims at more active intercourse betweeneconomics and her sister social sciences,<strong>the</strong>n we must ask not only what economicswill export. but also what she will receive inpayment. An economist might well betempted <strong>to</strong> murmur <strong>the</strong> lines of <strong>the</strong>tentmaker: "I wonder often what <strong>the</strong>Vintners buy-One half as precious as <strong>the</strong>stuff <strong>the</strong>y sell."My paper will be much concerned withthat question, and before I proceed, it maybe well <strong>to</strong> sketch in outline <strong>the</strong> path Ipropose <strong>to</strong> follow in answering it. The argumenthas three major steps.First. I would like <strong>to</strong> expand on <strong>the</strong><strong>the</strong>me that almost all human behavior has alarge rational component, but only in termsof <strong>the</strong> broader everyday sense of rationality,not <strong>the</strong> economists' more specializedsense of maximization.Second, I should like <strong>to</strong> show that economicsitself has not by any means limiteditself <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> nar-rower definition of rationality.Much economic literature (forexample. <strong>the</strong> literature of comparative institutionalanalysis) uses weaker definitionsof rationality extensively; and that literaturewould not be greatly. if at all,improved by substituting <strong>the</strong> strongerdefinition for <strong>the</strong> weaker one.' To <strong>the</strong>extent that <strong>the</strong> weaker definition is adeqyatefor purposes of analysis. economicswill find that t<strong>here</strong> is indeed much that isimportable from <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r social sciences.Third, economics has largely been preoccupiedwith <strong>the</strong> resulrs of rational choicera<strong>the</strong>r than <strong>the</strong> proc,c1s.s of choice. Yet aseconomic analysis acquires a broaderconcern with <strong>the</strong> dynamics of choice underuncertainty. it will become more and Inoreessential <strong>to</strong> consider choice processes. In<strong>the</strong> past twenty years, t<strong>here</strong> have been irn-*For an interesting argument in s~ipport of thisproposition from a surprising source. see Becker(1962). What Becker calls "irrationality" in his articleuould be called "hounded rationality'' <strong>here</strong>.


VOL 68 YO 2RICHARD T. EL-Y LtCTURE3portant advances in our understanding ofprocedural rationality. particularly as aresult of research in artificial intelligenceand cognitive psychology. The importationof <strong>the</strong>se <strong>the</strong>ories of <strong>the</strong> processes of choicein<strong>to</strong> economics could provide immensehelp in deepening our understanding of <strong>the</strong>dynamics of rationality. and of <strong>the</strong>influences upon choice of <strong>the</strong> institutionalstructure uithin which it takes place.We begin. <strong>the</strong>n. by looking at <strong>the</strong> broaderconcept of rationality <strong>to</strong> which I have referred.and its social xience applications.Let me provide some examples how rationalitytypically enters in<strong>to</strong> social science<strong>the</strong>ories. Consider first so-called "socialexchange" <strong>the</strong>ories (see, for example.George Homans). The central idea <strong>here</strong> isthat uhen two or more people interact,each expects <strong>to</strong> <strong>get</strong> something from <strong>the</strong>interaction that is valuable <strong>to</strong> him. and ist<strong>here</strong>by motivated <strong>to</strong> give something upthat is valuable <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs. Social exchange,in <strong>the</strong> form of <strong>the</strong> "inducementscontr-ibutionsbalance" of Chester I. Barnardand <strong>the</strong> author (1947). has played animportant role in organization <strong>the</strong>ory. andin even earlier times (see. for example.George Sirnmel) was a central ingredient insociological <strong>the</strong>ories. Much of <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>orizingand empirical work on <strong>the</strong> <strong>to</strong>pic hasbeen concerned with determining whatconstitutes a significant inducement orcontribution in particular classes of exchangesituations-that ih, with <strong>the</strong> actualshape and substance of <strong>the</strong> "utility function."Clearly. <strong>the</strong> man of social exchan<strong>get</strong>heory is a rational man, even if he is neverasked <strong>to</strong> equate things at <strong>the</strong> margin.It is perhaps more surprising <strong>to</strong> discoverhow pervasive assumptions of rationalityare in psychoanalytic <strong>the</strong>ory-confil-ming<strong>the</strong> suhpicion that <strong>the</strong>r-e is indeed method inmadness. In his Fir*c~ 1,c~r.tui.c~~ SigmundFreud has this <strong>to</strong> say about neurotic illnesses:We see that human beings fall illwhen. as a result of external obstaclesor of an internal lack of adaptation. <strong>the</strong>satisfaction of <strong>the</strong>ir erotic needs ittt~jrrlityis frustratect. We see that <strong>the</strong>y<strong>the</strong>n take flight in<strong>to</strong> illilcss in order thatby its help <strong>the</strong>y may find a satisfaction<strong>to</strong> take <strong>the</strong> place of what has beenfrustrated . . . We suspect that ourpatients' resistance <strong>to</strong> recovery is nosimple one. but compounded of severalmotives. Not only does <strong>the</strong> patient'sego rebel against giving up t<strong>here</strong>pressions by means of which it hasrisen above its original disposition. but<strong>the</strong> sexual instincts are unwilling <strong>to</strong>renounce <strong>the</strong>ir substitutive satisfactionso long as it is uncertain whe<strong>the</strong>rreality will offer <strong>the</strong>m anything better.Almost all explanat<strong>to</strong>ns of pathological behaviorin <strong>the</strong> psychoanalytic literature taketh~sform: <strong>the</strong>y explain <strong>the</strong> patient's illnessin terms of <strong>the</strong> functions it performs forhim.The auotation from Freud is illustrativeof a kind of functional reasoning that goesfar beyond psychoan:~lysis and is uidelyused throughout <strong>the</strong> social sciences. andespecially anthropology and sociology. Behaviorsare functional if <strong>the</strong>y contribute <strong>to</strong>certain goals, w<strong>here</strong> <strong>the</strong>se goals may be <strong>the</strong>ple;lsur-e or satisfaction of an individual or<strong>the</strong> guarantee of food or shelter for <strong>the</strong>members of a society. Functional analysisin this sense is concerned with explaininghow "major social patterns operate <strong>to</strong>maintain <strong>the</strong> integration or adaptation of<strong>the</strong> larger system" (see Frank Cancian). Institutionsare functional if reasonable menmight create and maintain <strong>the</strong>m in order <strong>to</strong>meet social needs or achieve social goals.It is not necessary or implled that <strong>the</strong>adaptation of institutions or behavior patterns<strong>to</strong> goals be conscious or ~ntended.When awareness and intention are present.<strong>the</strong> function is usually called intrn(fest.o<strong>the</strong>rwise it is a ltr<strong>to</strong>lt function. The function,whe<strong>the</strong>r it be manifest or latent.provides <strong>the</strong> grounds for <strong>the</strong> reasonablenessor rationalitv of <strong>the</strong> institution or behaviorpattern. As in economics, evolutionaryarguments are often adduced <strong>to</strong>explain <strong>the</strong> persistence and survival of


4 A llLRlC A 1' CCOVO MIC ASSOCIATIOY \IAk I978functional patterns. and <strong>to</strong> avoid assumptionsof deliberate calculation in explaining<strong>the</strong>m.In practice, it is very rarely that <strong>the</strong>existence or character of institutions aretictlirc,c~tlfrom <strong>the</strong> functions that must beperformed for system survival. In almost allcases it is <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r way round: it is empiricalobservation of <strong>the</strong> behavior patternthat raises <strong>the</strong> question of why it persistswhatfunction it performs. Perhaps, in anappropriate axiomatic formulation. it wouldbe possible <strong>to</strong> tt~~t1lrc.rthat every societymust have food-ga<strong>the</strong>ring institutions. Inpoint of fact, such institutions can be ob-.xer~.e~tl in every society. and <strong>the</strong>ir existenceis <strong>the</strong>n rationalized by <strong>the</strong> argument tha<strong>to</strong>btaining food is a functional requisite forall societies. This kind of argument maydemonstrate <strong>the</strong> sufficiency of a particularpattern for performing an essential function,but cannot demonstrate itsnecessity-cannot show that t<strong>here</strong> may notbe alternative, functionally equivalent, behaviorpatterns that would satisfy <strong>the</strong> sameneed.The point may be stated more formally.Functional arguments are arguments about<strong>the</strong> movements of systems <strong>to</strong>ward stableself-maintaining equilibria. But withoutfur<strong>the</strong>r specification, t<strong>here</strong> is no reason <strong>to</strong>suppose that <strong>the</strong> attained equilibria that arereached will be global maxima or minima ofsome function ra<strong>the</strong>r than local. relativemaxima or minima. In fact. we know that<strong>the</strong> conditions that every local maximum ofa system be a global maximum are verystrong (usually some kind of "convexity"conditions).Fur<strong>the</strong>r. when <strong>the</strong> system is complex andits environment continually changing (thatis. in <strong>the</strong> conditions under which biologicaland social evolution actually take place).t<strong>here</strong> is no assurance that <strong>the</strong> system's momentaryposition will lie anyw<strong>here</strong> near apoint of equilibrium, whe<strong>the</strong>r local orglobal. Hence, all that can be concludedfrom a functional argument is that certaincharacteristics (<strong>the</strong> satisfaction of certainfunctional requirements in a particular way)are consistent with <strong>the</strong> survival and fur<strong>the</strong>rdevelopment of <strong>the</strong> system. not that <strong>the</strong>sesame requirements could not be satisfied insome o<strong>the</strong>r way. Thus. for example.societies can satisfy <strong>the</strong>ir functional needsfor food by hunting or fishing activities. byagriculture. or by preda<strong>to</strong>ry exploitation ofo<strong>the</strong>r societies.Functional analysis of exactly this kind.though with a different vocabulary, is commonlyemployed by economists, especiallywhen <strong>the</strong>y seek <strong>to</strong> use economic <strong>to</strong>ols <strong>to</strong>"explain" institutions and behaviors thatlie outside <strong>the</strong> traditional domains ofproduction and distribution. Moreover. i<strong>to</strong>ccurs within those domains. As anexample. <strong>the</strong> fact is observed that individualsfrequently insure against certainkinds of contingencies. Attitudes are <strong>the</strong>npostulated (for example. risk aversion) forwhich buying insurance is a functional andreasonable action. If some people are observed<strong>to</strong> insure. and o<strong>the</strong>rs not. <strong>the</strong>n thisdifference in behavior can be explained bya difference between <strong>the</strong>m in risk aversion.To take a second example. GeorgeStigler and Becker wish <strong>to</strong> explain <strong>the</strong> fact(if it is a fact-<strong>the</strong>ir empiricism is verycasual) that as people hear more music.<strong>the</strong>y want <strong>to</strong> hear still more. They invent acommodity, "music appreciation" (not <strong>to</strong>be confused with time spent in listening <strong>to</strong>music). and suggest that listening <strong>to</strong> musicmight produce not only immediate enjoymentbut also an investment in c,c~pac,ityforappreciating music (i.e.. in amount of enjoymentproduced per listening hour). Once<strong>the</strong>se assumptions are granted. variousconclusions can be drawn about <strong>the</strong> demandfor music appreciation. However.only weak conclusions follow about listeningtime unless additional strong postulatesare introduced about <strong>the</strong> elasticity of demandfor appreciation.A rough "sociological" translation of <strong>the</strong>Stigler-Becker argument would be thatlistening <strong>to</strong> music is functional both in producingpleasure and in enhancing <strong>the</strong>pleasure of subsequent listening-a typicalfunctional argument. It is quite unclearwhat is gained by dressing it in <strong>the</strong> garb of


VOL. 68 .VO. 2RICHARD T. EL-Y LECTURE5marginalism. We might be willing <strong>to</strong>grant that people would be inclined <strong>to</strong> investmore in musical appreciation early inlife than later in life (because <strong>the</strong>y wouldhave a longer time in which <strong>to</strong> amortize <strong>the</strong>investment) without insisting that costs andreturns were being equated at <strong>the</strong> margin.and without gaining any new insights in<strong>to</strong><strong>the</strong> situation from making <strong>the</strong> latterassumption.A sense of fairness compels me <strong>to</strong> take athird example from my own work. In my1951 paper. I defined <strong>the</strong> characteristics ofan employment contract that distinguish itfrom an ordinary sales contract. and <strong>the</strong>nshowed why reasonable men might prefer<strong>the</strong> former <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> latter as <strong>the</strong> basis for establishingan employment relation. Myargument requires a <strong>the</strong>orem and fifteennumbered equations. and assumes thatboth employer and employee maximize<strong>the</strong>ir utilities. Actually, <strong>the</strong> underlyingfunctional argument is very simple. An employeewho didn't care very much which ofseveral alternative tasks he performedwould not require a large inducement <strong>to</strong> accept<strong>the</strong> authority of an employer-that is,<strong>to</strong> permit <strong>the</strong> employer <strong>to</strong> make <strong>the</strong> choiceamong <strong>the</strong>m. The employer in turn wouldbe willing <strong>to</strong> provide <strong>the</strong> necessary inducementin order <strong>to</strong> acquire <strong>the</strong> right <strong>to</strong>postpone his decisions about <strong>the</strong> employee'sagenda, and in this way <strong>to</strong>postpone some of his decisions whose outcomesare contingent on future uncertainevents.' The rigorous economic argument.involving <strong>the</strong> idea of maximizing behaviorby employer and employee. is readily translatablein<strong>to</strong> a simple qualitative argumentthat an employment contract may be afunctional ("reasonable") way of dealingwith certain kinds of uncertainty. The argu-'Recently. Oliver Williamson has pointed out that Iwould have <strong>to</strong> introduce slightly stronger assumptions<strong>to</strong> justify <strong>the</strong> employment contract as rational if one of<strong>the</strong> alternatives <strong>to</strong> it were what he calls a "contingentclaims" contract, but <strong>the</strong> point of my example is notaffected. To exclude <strong>the</strong> contingent claims contract asa viable alternative, we need merely take account of<strong>the</strong> large transaction costs it aould entail under realworld conditions.~nent <strong>the</strong>n explains why employment relationsare so widely used in our society.The translation of <strong>the</strong>se examples of economicreasoning in<strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> language of functionalanalysis could be paralleled by examplesof translation scholarship which run in<strong>the</strong> opposite direction. Political scientists.for example. long ago observed that undercertain circumstances institutions ofrepresentative democracy spawned a multiplicityof political parties. while under o<strong>the</strong>rcircumstances. <strong>the</strong> votes were divided inequilibrium between two major parties.These contrasting equilibria could readilybe shown by functional arguments <strong>to</strong> resultfrom rational voting decisions under differentrules of <strong>the</strong> elec<strong>to</strong>ral game. as wasobserved by Maurice Duverger, in hisclassic work on political parties. as well asby a number of political scientists who precededhim. In recent years. <strong>the</strong>se sameresults have been rederived morerigorously by economists and game<strong>the</strong>orists. employing much strongerassumptions of utility maximization by <strong>the</strong>voters: it was hard <strong>to</strong> see that <strong>the</strong>maximization assumptions have producedany new predictions of b e h a ~ i o r . ~Perhaps <strong>the</strong>se examples suffice <strong>to</strong> showthat t<strong>here</strong> is no such gap as is commonlysupposed between <strong>the</strong> view of manespoused by economics and <strong>the</strong> view foundin <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r social sciences. The view ofman as rational is not peculiar <strong>to</strong> economics.but is endemic, and even ubiqui<strong>to</strong>us,throughout <strong>the</strong> social sciences. Economicstends <strong>to</strong> emphasize a particular4For an introduction <strong>to</strong> this literature. see WilliamH. Riker and Peter C. Ordeshook. and Riker. AnthonyDowns' book belongs <strong>to</strong> an intermediate genre. Whileit employs <strong>the</strong> language of economics, it limits itself <strong>to</strong>verbal. nonrigorous reasoning which certainly doesnot make any essential use of maximizing assumptions(as contra\ted with rationality assumptions in <strong>the</strong>broader sense). and which largely translates in<strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong>economic vocabulary generalizations that were ;:Ireadypart of <strong>the</strong> science and folklore of politics. In thcnext section, o<strong>the</strong>r examples of this kind of informaluse of rationality principles are examined <strong>to</strong> analyzein\titutions and <strong>the</strong>ir behavior.


form of rationality-maximizing behavior-asits preferred engine of explanation.but <strong>the</strong> differences are often differencesin vocabulary more than insubstance. We shall see in a moment that inmuch economic discussion <strong>the</strong> notion ofmaximization is used in a loose sense that isvery close <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> common sense notions ofrationality used elsew<strong>here</strong> in <strong>the</strong> socialsciences.One conclusion we may draw is thateconomists might well exercise a certainamolint of circumspection in <strong>the</strong>irendeavors <strong>to</strong> export economic analysis <strong>to</strong><strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r social sciences. 'They may discoverthat <strong>the</strong>y are sometimes offeringcommodities that are already in generoussupply, and which can t<strong>here</strong>fore be disposedof only at a ruinously low price. On<strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r side of <strong>the</strong> trade. <strong>the</strong>y may findthat t<strong>here</strong> is more of interest in <strong>the</strong> modesand results of inquiry of <strong>the</strong>ir fellow socialscientists than <strong>the</strong>y have generally beenaware.11. On ippljing <strong>the</strong> Principle of Rationalit!What is characteristic of <strong>the</strong> examples offunctional analysis cited in <strong>the</strong> last section.whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>v be dra\vn from economics orfrom <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r socinl sciences, i5 that <strong>the</strong>yare not focu5ed on. or eken muchconcerned with. h o variable\ ~ are eau'itedat <strong>the</strong> margin. or how equilibrium is alteredby marginal shifts in conditions (forexample, shifts in a supply or demandschedule). Ra<strong>the</strong>r, <strong>the</strong>y are focused onqualitative and structural questions. typically.on <strong>the</strong> choice among a small numberof discrete institutional alternatives:Not "how much flood insurance will aman buy?" but "what are <strong>the</strong> structuralconditions that make buying insurance rationalor attractive?"Not "at what levels will wages befixed'?" but "when will work be performed~~nder an employment contract ra<strong>the</strong>r thana sales contract?"If we M ant a natural science analogy <strong>to</strong>this kind of <strong>the</strong>orizing, we can find it ingeology. A geologist notice5 deep scrntchesin rock; he notices that certain hills ofgravel are elongated along a north-southaxis. and that <strong>the</strong> boulders embedded in<strong>the</strong>m are not as smooth as those usuallyfound on beaches. To explain <strong>the</strong>se facts,he evokes a structural. and not at all quantitative.hypo<strong>the</strong>sis: that <strong>the</strong>se phenomenawere produced by <strong>the</strong> process of glaciation.In <strong>the</strong> first instance, he does not try <strong>to</strong>explain <strong>the</strong> depth of <strong>the</strong> glacial till, or estimate<strong>the</strong> weight of <strong>the</strong> ice that procluced it.but simply <strong>to</strong> identify <strong>the</strong> basic causativeprocess. He wants <strong>to</strong> explain <strong>the</strong> role ofglaciation. of erosion. of vulcanization, ofsedimentation in producing <strong>the</strong> land formsthat he observes. His explanations.niorever. are after-<strong>the</strong>-fact, and not predictive.As economics expands beyond its centralcore of price <strong>the</strong>ory, and its central concernwith quantities of commodities and money.we observe in it this same shift from ahighly quantitative analysis. in whichequilibration at <strong>the</strong> margin plays a centralrole, <strong>to</strong> a much more q~lalitative institutionalanalysis, in which discrete structuralalternatives are compared.In <strong>the</strong>se analyses aimed at explaining institutionalstructure, maximizing assumptionsplay a much less significant role than<strong>the</strong>y typically do in <strong>the</strong> analysis of marketequilibria. The rational man who sometimesprefers an employment contract <strong>to</strong> asales contract need not be a maximizer.Even a satisficer will exhibit such apreference whenever <strong>the</strong> difference inrewards between <strong>the</strong> two arrangements issufficiently large and evident.For this same reason. such analyses canoften be carried out without elaboratema<strong>the</strong>matical apparatus or marginal calculation.In general, much cruder andsimpler arguments will suffice <strong>to</strong>demonstrate an inequality between t n oquantities than are required <strong>to</strong> show <strong>the</strong>conditions under which <strong>the</strong>se quantities areequated at <strong>the</strong> margin. Thus. in <strong>the</strong> recentworks of Janos Kornai. Williamson. andJohn Montias on economic organization.we find only ra<strong>the</strong>r modest and simple ap-


VOL. 68 .VO. 2RICHARD T. ELY LECTURE7plications of ma<strong>the</strong>matical analysis. In <strong>the</strong>ways in which <strong>the</strong>y involve principles of rationality.<strong>the</strong> arguments of <strong>the</strong>se authors resembleJames March and <strong>the</strong> author's Orgtrnizntioilsmore closely than PaulSamuelson's Folrntlr~rio/~s.~What is <strong>the</strong> predominant form of reasoningthat we encounter in <strong>the</strong>se <strong>the</strong>oreticaltreatments of social institutions? Do <strong>the</strong>ycontain arguments based on maximizingassumptions? Basically. <strong>the</strong>y rest upon avery simple form of causal analysis.Particular institutional structures orpractices are seen <strong>to</strong> entail certain undesirable(for example, costly) 01- desirable(for example. value-producing) consequences.Cctc1ri.s plit'ihlr.~,situations andpractices will be preferred when importantfavorable conseq~lences are associated with<strong>the</strong>m. and avoided when important unfavorableconsequences are associated with<strong>the</strong>m. A shift in <strong>the</strong> balance of consequences.or in awareness of <strong>the</strong>m. may motivatea change in institutional arrangements.Consider <strong>the</strong> following argument fromMontias typical of this genre of analysis.which relates <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> balance in organizationsbetween centralization anddecentralization.Decentralizing measures are generallyaimed at remedying two shortcom-'A notable exception <strong>to</strong> this generalization about <strong>the</strong>economic literature on organizations is <strong>the</strong> aork ofJacob Marschak and Roy Radner on <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory ofteams. These authors chow <strong>the</strong> strategy of detailed.precise analysis of <strong>the</strong> implications of maximizingassumptions for <strong>the</strong> transmi\\ion of information in organization\.The price <strong>the</strong>y paid for this rigor b%as <strong>to</strong>find <strong>the</strong>m\elves limited <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> highly simplified situationsa<strong>here</strong> wlutions could be found for <strong>the</strong>ma<strong>the</strong>matical problems <strong>the</strong>y posed. We need not. ofcourse. make an ei<strong>the</strong>r-or choice betaeen <strong>the</strong>se taomodes of inquiry. While it may be difficult or impossible<strong>to</strong> extend <strong>the</strong> formal analysis of <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>or) of teams<strong>to</strong> problems of real world complexity. <strong>the</strong> rigorousmicro<strong>the</strong>ory may illuminate <strong>the</strong> workings of importantcomponent mechanisms in <strong>the</strong> complex macrosituations.The methodological i\\ues in choo\ing betweenanalytic tractability and realism are quite parallel <strong>to</strong>thme involved in <strong>the</strong> choice between labora<strong>to</strong>ry andfield methods for ga<strong>the</strong>ring empirical informationabout social phenomena. Nei<strong>the</strong>r one by itself marks<strong>the</strong> exclusive path <strong>to</strong>b%ard truth.ings of an 'overcentralized' systemstructure. (1) Superordinates areoverburdened with responsibility for<strong>the</strong> detailed direction and coordinationof <strong>the</strong>ir subordinates' activities. (3)This 'petty tutelage' deprives subordinatesof <strong>the</strong> opportunity <strong>to</strong> make decisionsthat might increase <strong>the</strong> payoffof <strong>the</strong> organization of which <strong>the</strong>y are apart. . . . Why not loosen controls. . . ? . . . When controls areloosened, unless <strong>the</strong> incentive systemis modified <strong>to</strong> bring about greaterharmony between <strong>the</strong> goals of supervisorsand supervisees. it may induceproducers <strong>to</strong> shift <strong>the</strong>ir input andoutput mix in directions that . . . vitiateany benefits that might be reapedby <strong>the</strong> organization as a whole from <strong>the</strong>exercise of greater initiative at lowertiers. [p. 3151Here two costs or disadvantages ofcentralization (burden on supervisors.restriction of choice-set of subordinates)are set off against a disadvantage ofdecentralization (goals of subordinates divergentfrorn organization goals).What can we learn about organizationfrom an at-gument like this'? Certainly littleor nothing about <strong>the</strong> optirnal balance pointbetween centralization and decentralizationin any particular organization. Ra<strong>the</strong>r, wemight derive conclusions of <strong>the</strong>se kinds:1. That increasing awareness of one of<strong>the</strong> predicted consequences may cause anorganization <strong>to</strong> move in <strong>the</strong> direction ofcentralization 01- decentralization. (Forexample. an egregious case of "suboptimizing"by a subordinate may cause additionalcentralized controls <strong>to</strong> be instituted.)2. That new technical devices may tilt<strong>the</strong> balance between centralization anddecentralization. For example, inventionand adoption of divisionalized profit andloss statements led <strong>to</strong>ward decentralizationof many large America11 business firms in<strong>the</strong> 1950's: while reduction in informationcosts through computerization led at alater date <strong>to</strong> centralization of inven<strong>to</strong>rycontrol decisions in those same firms.Of course Montias' conclusions couldalso be derived from a more formaloptimization analysis-in fact he presents


such an analysis on <strong>the</strong> t~vo pages follo~ving<strong>the</strong> passage quoted above. But it is notclear that anything new is added by <strong>the</strong> formalization.since <strong>the</strong> parameters imputed <strong>to</strong><strong>the</strong> system are largely unmeiisured and unmeasurable.T<strong>here</strong> is something <strong>to</strong> be said for anOckham's Razor that. escheu ing assumptionsof optimization. provictes an explanationof behavior that is consistent withoitl~(~t. optimizing or satisficing procedureson <strong>the</strong> part of <strong>the</strong> human agents. Parsimonyrecommends that bve prefer <strong>the</strong> postulatethat rnen are reasonable <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> postulatethat <strong>the</strong>y are supremely rational whenei<strong>the</strong>r one of <strong>the</strong> tc\o assumptions \ \ i l l doour work of inference as uell as <strong>the</strong>The kind of qualitative analysis I havebeen describing has ano<strong>the</strong>r virtue. In complexsituations t<strong>here</strong> is likely <strong>to</strong> be aconsiderable gap bet~been <strong>the</strong> real environmen<strong>to</strong>f u decision (<strong>the</strong> world as God orsome o<strong>the</strong>r omniscient observer sees it) and<strong>the</strong> environment as <strong>the</strong> ac<strong>to</strong>rs perceive it.The analysis can <strong>the</strong>n address itself ei<strong>the</strong>r<strong>to</strong> normative questions-<strong>the</strong> whole rangeof consequences that .shoi~ltlenter in<strong>to</strong> decisionsin such situations-or descriptivequestions. including <strong>the</strong> q~~estions of whichcomponents of <strong>the</strong> situation are likely <strong>to</strong> betaken in<strong>to</strong> account by <strong>the</strong> ac<strong>to</strong>rs, and how<strong>the</strong> ac<strong>to</strong>rs are likely <strong>to</strong> represent <strong>the</strong> situationas a w hole.In <strong>the</strong> precomputer era. for example. itwas very difficult for managers in businessorganizations <strong>to</strong> pay attention <strong>to</strong> all <strong>the</strong>major variables affected by <strong>the</strong>ir decisions.Company treasurers frequently rnade deci-"Ockharn is usu:~ll) invoked on behalf of <strong>the</strong> parsimonyof optimizing a\\urnption\. and against <strong>the</strong> additional[rtl I~oc.postulates that \ati\ticing mvdel., arethought <strong>to</strong> require in order- <strong>to</strong> guariintee ~~niquene\\ ofsolution\. Rut that :lrgument only :~pplies\+hen\\e aretrying <strong>to</strong> deduce unique equilibl-ia. a ta\k quite differentfr-om <strong>the</strong> one rnost institution:il \triter\ \et for<strong>the</strong>rnselves. Ho~te~er. I h;i\e no urge <strong>to</strong> enlar-ge onthi\ point. kly intent <strong>here</strong> i\ not polemical. on bchalf ofsatisficing po\tulates, but ra<strong>the</strong>r <strong>to</strong> \ho\\ ho\+ large aplot of comnion gro~~nd i\ shzired b! optirniring nilsati\ficing analy sis. Again. compare Beckel- ( 1962).sions about ~vot:king capital with little 01.noattention <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir irnpact on inven<strong>to</strong>rylevels. while production and marketingexecutives rnade decisions about inven<strong>to</strong>rywithout taking in<strong>to</strong> account impacts onliquidity. The introduction of computerschanged <strong>the</strong> hays in which executives bvereable <strong>to</strong> reach decisions: <strong>the</strong>y could nowview <strong>the</strong>m in terms of a much hider set ofinterrelated consequences than before. Theperception of <strong>the</strong> environment of a decisionis a function of-among o<strong>the</strong>r things-<strong>the</strong>information sources and computational capabilitiesof <strong>the</strong> executives ~ v h o make it.[,earning phenomena are also readilyhandled within this frarneuork. A numberof <strong>the</strong> changes introduced in<strong>to</strong> planning andcontrol procedu~.es in eastern Europeancountries during <strong>the</strong> 1960's were instituteduhen <strong>the</strong> governments in question learnedby experience of some of <strong>the</strong> dysfunctionalconsequences of trying <strong>to</strong> control productionby means of crude aggregates ofphysical quantities. An initial distrust ofprices and market mechanisms bvasgradually and partially overcome afterdirect experience of <strong>the</strong> disadvantages ofsome of <strong>the</strong> alternative mechanisms. Theselearning experiences could be paralleledwith experiences of American steel companies.for example. that experimentedwith <strong>to</strong>nnage incentives for mill departmentsuperintendents.'4 general proposition that rnight beasserted about organizations is that <strong>the</strong>number of considerations that arepotentially relevant <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> effectiveness of:in organization design is so large that onlya few of <strong>the</strong> more salient of <strong>the</strong>se lie uithiti<strong>the</strong> circle of awareness at any given time.that <strong>the</strong> rnembership of this subset changescontinually 21s new situations (produced byexternal or internal events) arise, and that"learning" in <strong>the</strong> form of reaction <strong>to</strong>perceived consequences is <strong>the</strong> dominantc\ay in uhich rationality exhibits itself.In a world w<strong>here</strong> <strong>the</strong>se kinds of adjustmentsare prominent. a <strong>the</strong>ory of rationalbehavior must be quite as much concernedwith <strong>the</strong> characteristics of <strong>the</strong> rational ac<strong>to</strong>rs-<strong>the</strong>means <strong>the</strong>y use <strong>to</strong> cope with uncertaintyand cognitive complexity-as


POL 68 \O 2 RICH4RD TELY LE( TUREYwith <strong>the</strong> characteristics of <strong>the</strong> objective environmentin which <strong>the</strong>y make <strong>the</strong>ir decisions.In such a world. ue must give an accountnot only of .rril?.~tcit~tit.cl rnfiotltrlity<strong>the</strong>extent <strong>to</strong> c\ hich appropriate courses ofaction are chosen-but also proc.c~clllrct1 rrrtionrrlity-<strong>the</strong>effectiveness, in light ofhuman cognitive po\+,ers and limitations, of<strong>the</strong> proc.rt1rri.c.v used <strong>to</strong> choose actions. Aseconomics moves out <strong>to</strong>ward situations ofincreasing cognitive complexity, it becomesincreasingly concerned with <strong>the</strong>ability of ac<strong>to</strong>rs <strong>to</strong> cope ~vith <strong>the</strong> complexity.and hence ~vith <strong>the</strong> proceduralaspects of rationality. In <strong>the</strong> remainder ofmy talk. I \zould like <strong>to</strong> develop this concep<strong>to</strong>f procedul-al rationality, and its implicationsfor economic analysis.111. \lincl as <strong>the</strong> Scarce ResourceUntil ra<strong>the</strong>r recently. such limited attentionas was paid by economists <strong>to</strong> pl-ocedural.us distinct from substantive. rationality\\,as mainly motivated by <strong>the</strong> problemsof uncertainty and expectations. Thesimple notion of maximizing utility or profitcould not be applied <strong>to</strong> situations u<strong>here</strong> <strong>the</strong>optitnurn action depended on uncertain environmentalevents. or upon <strong>the</strong> actions ofo<strong>the</strong>r rational agents (for example, imperfectcompetition).The former difficulty was l.emoved <strong>to</strong>some degree by replacing utility rnaxirnizationwith <strong>the</strong> maximization of subjective expectedutility (SEU)as <strong>the</strong> criterion of rationality.In spite of its conceptualelegance. however, <strong>the</strong> SEU solution hassome grave defects us ei<strong>the</strong>r a normative or21 descriptive formulation. In general. <strong>the</strong>optimal solution depends upon all of <strong>the</strong>moments of <strong>the</strong> frequency distributions ofuncertain events. The exceptions are asmall but ilnportant class of cases u<strong>here</strong><strong>the</strong> utility or pt.ofit function is quadratic andall constraints are in <strong>the</strong> form of equationsra<strong>the</strong>r than inequalities.' The empirical-In thi\ caw <strong>the</strong> expccteci v;tlues of <strong>the</strong> en\ironmentalv;ir~able\ xrve as certainty equivalent\. so thatSEU maximiration recluires onl! I-eplacing <strong>the</strong> unkno\\ntr-ue \due\ by <strong>the</strong>\e expected balue\. See <strong>the</strong>author ( l9i7).defect of <strong>the</strong> SEU formulation is that whenit has been subjected <strong>to</strong> test in <strong>the</strong> labora<strong>to</strong>ryor <strong>the</strong> real \\,orld. even in relativelysimple situations. <strong>the</strong> behavior of humansubjects has generally departed ~videlyfrom it.Some of <strong>the</strong> evidence has been surveyedby Ward Ed\vnrds. and more recently byDaniel Kahneman and Amos Tversky.They describe experilnental situations in\\,hich estimates formed on <strong>the</strong> basis ofinitial information are not revised nearly asmuch by subsequent information as ~vouldhe required by Bayes' Theorem. In o<strong>the</strong>rsituations. suhjects respond largely <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong>information received most recently. andtake inadequate account of prior informatlon.Beha~ior that is rad~cally inconsistentuith <strong>the</strong> SEU frame\\ol-k occurs also innaturalistic settings. Ho\rard Kunreu<strong>the</strong>r etal. have recently carried out extensivestudies of behavior and attitudes relating <strong>to</strong><strong>the</strong> purchase of flood insurance by personso\+ning property in lob-lying areas Theyfound that kno\+ledge of <strong>the</strong> ubailability ofinsurance. or rates. and of objective risksuas very imperfect. and that <strong>the</strong> actual deci5ionswhe<strong>the</strong>r or not <strong>to</strong> insure \+ere relatedmuch more <strong>to</strong> personul experienceuith floods than <strong>to</strong> an! objective factsabout <strong>the</strong> situation-or even <strong>to</strong> personalsubjective beliefs about those facts. In <strong>the</strong>face of this evidence. kt is hard <strong>to</strong> tahe Stbseriously as a <strong>the</strong>ory of actual human behatior in <strong>the</strong> face of uncertainty .XFor situations u <strong>here</strong> <strong>the</strong> rationality of anaction depends upon hat o<strong>the</strong>rs (uho arealso striving <strong>to</strong> be ration'll) do again. noconsensus has been reached as <strong>to</strong> \\hatconstitutes optimal behavior. This is one of<strong>the</strong> reasons I have else~b<strong>here</strong> called imperfectcornpetltion "<strong>the</strong> permanent andineradicable scandal of economic <strong>the</strong>ory"(I976b. p. 140). The most ~maginatike andXKunreu<strong>the</strong>r et al. point out that thc <strong>the</strong>ory canno<strong>the</strong> "saved" by ass~~rning utility <strong>to</strong> be radically non-linear in money. In <strong>the</strong> Hood in\urance case. that interpretationof <strong>the</strong> data mould uork only if ue werenilling <strong>to</strong> as\ume that money has strongly itlc.retrsitlr:marginal utility. not a Ler) plausible e\cape route for<strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory.


ambitious attempt <strong>to</strong> resolve <strong>the</strong> difficulty\\as <strong>the</strong> von Neurnanti-Morgenstern <strong>the</strong>oryof garnes, \+,hich is embarrassing in <strong>the</strong>wealth of alternative solutions it offers.While <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory of garnes reveals <strong>the</strong>potential richness of behavior uhen rationalindividuals are faced ~vith conflict ofinterest. <strong>the</strong> capability of reacting <strong>to</strong> eacho<strong>the</strong>r's actions (or expected actions). andpossibilities for coalition. it has provided nounique ancl universally accepted criterionof rationality <strong>to</strong> generalize <strong>the</strong> SEU criterionand extend it <strong>to</strong> this broader range ofsituations.The so-called "rational expectations"models, currently so popular (and due originally<strong>to</strong> hluth). pass over <strong>the</strong>se problemsra<strong>the</strong>r than solving <strong>the</strong>rn. They ignorepotential coalitions and attempted mutualoutguessing behavior. and correspond <strong>to</strong>optitnal solutions only ~vhen <strong>the</strong> losses arequadratic functions of <strong>the</strong> errors of estimate.9Hence <strong>the</strong>y do not correspond <strong>to</strong>any classical criterion of rationality. and labeling<strong>the</strong>m with that term. ra<strong>the</strong>r than <strong>the</strong>more neutral "consistent expectations."provides <strong>the</strong>m ~vith a ra<strong>the</strong>r unwarrantedlegitimation.Finally. it should be retnarkerl that <strong>the</strong>rnain motivation in economics for developing<strong>the</strong>ories of uncertainty and mutual expectationshas not been <strong>to</strong> replace substantivecriteria of rationality with pt-oceduralcriteria. but ra<strong>the</strong>r <strong>to</strong> find substantive criteriabroad enough <strong>to</strong> extend <strong>the</strong> concept ofrationality beyond <strong>the</strong> boundaries of staticoptirnizatioti under certainty. As M ithclassical decision <strong>the</strong>ory. <strong>the</strong> interest liesnot in 11011. tiecisions are made but in n


C'OL. 68 .YO. 2 RIC'HARD T. EL Y LECTURE 1IThe <strong>the</strong>ory of teams, as developed byMarschak and Radner. goes a step far<strong>the</strong>rin specifying <strong>the</strong> procedure of decision.That <strong>the</strong>ory, as is hell known. is concernedwith <strong>the</strong> in~proven~ent that may be realizedin a team's decisions by interchange of informationamong <strong>the</strong> team members. But<strong>here</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory does not limit itself <strong>to</strong> determining<strong>the</strong> aggregate amount of informationthat should be transmitted, but seeks <strong>to</strong> calculateuhat messages should be exchanged,under bvhat conditions. and at what cost.The content of <strong>the</strong> communication as hellas <strong>the</strong> <strong>to</strong>tal amount of information becomesrelevant <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory.In its attitude <strong>to</strong>ward rationality. <strong>the</strong><strong>the</strong>ory of teams is as "classical." houever.as is search <strong>the</strong>ory. The bounds on <strong>the</strong> rationalityof <strong>the</strong> team members are"externalized" and represented as costs ofcommunication. so that <strong>the</strong>y can be foldedin<strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> economic calculation along uith<strong>the</strong> costs and benefits of outcomes.To find <strong>the</strong>ories that compare <strong>the</strong> meritsof alternative search procedures. we mustlook largely outside <strong>the</strong> domain of economics.A number of such <strong>the</strong>ories havebeen developed in <strong>the</strong> past thirty years.mainly by management scientists and researchersin <strong>the</strong> field of artificial intelligence.An important example is <strong>the</strong>body of uork that has been done on integerprogramming.Integer programming problen~s resemblelinear programming problems (<strong>to</strong> maximizesome quantity, subject <strong>to</strong> constraints in <strong>the</strong>form of linear equations and inequalities).uith <strong>the</strong> added condition that certain variablescan only take whole numbers as <strong>the</strong>irvalues. The integer constraint makes inapplicablemost of <strong>the</strong> powerful computationalmethods available for solving linearprogramming problems. uith <strong>the</strong> result thatinteger programming problems are far lesstractable. computationally. than linearprogramming problen~s having comparablenumbers of variables.Solution methods for integer program-mlng problems use various forms of hlghlyselective search-for example branch-andboundmethods that establish successivelynarrobler limits for <strong>the</strong> value of <strong>the</strong> optimum.and hence permit a correspondingnarrow Ing of search <strong>to</strong> promising regions of<strong>the</strong> space. It becomes a matter ofconsiderable practical and <strong>the</strong>oreticalinterest <strong>to</strong> evaluate <strong>the</strong> relative computationalefficiency of competing searchprocedures. and also <strong>to</strong> estimate hob+ <strong>the</strong>cost of search u ill grou I+ith <strong>the</strong> size of <strong>the</strong>problem posed. Until recently. mostevaluation of search algorithms has beenempirical: <strong>the</strong>y have been tested on sampleproblems. Recently. however, a body of<strong>the</strong>ory-called <strong>the</strong>ory of computationalcomplexity-has grown up that begins <strong>to</strong>answer some of <strong>the</strong>se questions in a moresystematic way.I cannot give <strong>here</strong> an account of <strong>the</strong><strong>the</strong>ory of computational con~plexity. or allof its implications for procedural rationality.A good introduction I+i l l be foundin Alfred Aho et al. One important set ofresults that comes out of <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory does requireat least brief mention. These resultshave <strong>to</strong> do hith <strong>the</strong> way In ~hich <strong>the</strong>amount of computation requlred <strong>to</strong> solveproblems of a given class grous wlth <strong>the</strong>size of <strong>the</strong> problems-wlth <strong>the</strong> number ofvariables. say . I0In a domain w<strong>here</strong> computational requirementsgrow rapidly with problem slze,be will be able <strong>to</strong> solve only small problems;in domains u<strong>here</strong> <strong>the</strong> requirementsgrou slowly. b+e ill be able <strong>to</strong> solve muchlarger problems. The problems that <strong>the</strong> realworld presents <strong>to</strong> us are generallyenormous compared 1+1th <strong>the</strong> problems thatwe can solve on even our largest computersHence. our computational modelsare al~bays rough approximations <strong>to</strong> t<strong>here</strong>ality. and be must hope that <strong>the</strong> approximatlonb+ill not be <strong>to</strong>o Inexact <strong>to</strong> be useful."'Most of <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>orems in computational complexityhave <strong>to</strong> do uith <strong>the</strong> "worst case." that is. with <strong>the</strong>maximum amount of computation required <strong>to</strong> solventl? problem of <strong>the</strong> given class. Very feu results areavailable for <strong>the</strong> expected cost. averaged over all problemsof <strong>the</strong> class.


I2 A 1IERIC 4 \ LC0 VO MIC A5SOC14710 "L \lAl 1978We hill be particularly concerned that computationalcosts not increase rapidly ivithprobletn size.It is cus<strong>to</strong>mary in <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory of computationalcomplexity <strong>to</strong> regard problems of agiven size as "tractable" if comp~~tationsdo not grow faster than at some fixed pouerof problem size. Such classes of problemsare known as "polynomial complex."Problems that grow exponentially in cornplexitywith size are not polynomial complex.since <strong>the</strong> rate of grouth of computationcomes <strong>to</strong> exceed any fixed pobver of<strong>the</strong>ir size.A large and important class of probletns~vhich includes <strong>the</strong> general integer programmingproblem. as well as standard schedulingproblems. all have been sho~vn <strong>to</strong> have<strong>the</strong> same level of complexity-if one ispolynomial complex, <strong>the</strong>n all are; if one isnot polynomial complex. <strong>the</strong>n none are.These probletns have been labeled ",YPcomplete."It is conjectured. but not yetproven. that <strong>the</strong> class of IYP-completeprobletns is not polynotnially complex. butprobably exponentially complex.The significance of <strong>the</strong>se findings andconjectures is in sho~ving that computationaldifficulties. and <strong>the</strong> need <strong>to</strong> approximate.are not just a minor annoying featureof our ~vorld <strong>to</strong> be dealt with by rnanufacturinglarger computers or breedingsmarter people. Cornplexity is deep in <strong>the</strong>nature of things. and discovering <strong>to</strong>lerableapproximation procedures and heuristicsthat pertnit huge spaces <strong>to</strong> be searched veryselectively lies at <strong>the</strong> heart of intelligence,uhe<strong>the</strong>r hurnan or artificial. A <strong>the</strong>ory of rationalitythat does not give an account ofprobletn solving in <strong>the</strong> face of cotnplexity issadly incomplete. It is horse than incomplete:it can be seriously misleading by providing"solutions" <strong>to</strong> econornic questionsthat are w i t h o ~ operational ~ t significance.One interesting and important directionof research in cotnp~~tational co~nplexitylies in sho~ving how <strong>the</strong> complexity of problemsmight be decreased by lveakening t<strong>here</strong>quirements for solution-by requiring solutionsonly <strong>to</strong> approximate <strong>the</strong> optimum.or by replacing an optitnality criterion by asatisficing criterion. Results are still frag-mentary. but it is already known that t<strong>here</strong>are some cases w<strong>here</strong> such modificationsreduce exponential or NP-complete problernclasses <strong>to</strong> polynomial-completeclasses.The <strong>the</strong>ory of heuristic search. cultivatedin artificial intelligence and informationprocessing psychology, is concerned withdevising or identifying search proceduresthat hill permit systems of limited computationalcapacity <strong>to</strong> make complex decisionsand solve difficult problems. (For ageneral survey of <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory. see NilsNilsson.) When a task environment has patternedstructure. so that solutions <strong>to</strong> asearch probletn are not scattered randornlythroughout it. but are located in bays related<strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> structure. <strong>the</strong>n an intelligentsystem capable of detecting <strong>the</strong> pattern canexploit it in order <strong>to</strong> search for solutions ina highly selective h a y .One form. for example. of selectiveheuristic search. called best-first search.assigns <strong>to</strong> each node in <strong>the</strong> search space anestimate of <strong>the</strong> distance of that node frorn asolution. At each stage, <strong>the</strong> next incremen<strong>to</strong>f effort is expended in searching frotn <strong>the</strong>node. among those already reached, thathas <strong>the</strong> smallest distance estimate (see. forexample. <strong>the</strong> author and J.B. Kadane). Asano<strong>the</strong>r example. when <strong>the</strong> task is <strong>to</strong> find agood or best solution, it may be possible <strong>to</strong>assign upper and lo~ver bounds on <strong>the</strong>values of <strong>the</strong> solutions that can be obtainedby searching a particular part of <strong>the</strong> space.If <strong>the</strong> upper bound on region A is lowerthan <strong>the</strong> lower bound on some o<strong>the</strong>r region.<strong>the</strong>n region A does not need <strong>to</strong> be searchedat all.I hill leave <strong>the</strong> <strong>to</strong>pics of computationalcotnplexity and heuristic search ~vith <strong>the</strong>sesketchy remarks. What implications <strong>the</strong>sedevelopments in <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory of proceduralrationality will have for econotnics definedas "<strong>the</strong> science ~vhich treats of <strong>the</strong> uealth<strong>get</strong>tingand wealth-using activities of man"remain <strong>to</strong> be seen. That <strong>the</strong>y are an integralpart of economics defined as "<strong>the</strong> sciencewhich treats of <strong>the</strong> allocation of scarceresources" is obvious. The scarce resourceis cotnputational capacity-<strong>the</strong> mind. Theability of tnan <strong>to</strong> solve cotnplex problems,


and <strong>the</strong> m,ignitude of <strong>the</strong> resources thathave <strong>to</strong> be alloc'ited <strong>to</strong> solving <strong>the</strong>m,depend on <strong>the</strong> efficiency \\ith \\hich thisresource. mind. is deployed.Finally. I uould like <strong>to</strong> turn from <strong>the</strong>ra<strong>the</strong>r highly developed approaches <strong>to</strong>procedural rationality that I have been discussingback <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> more qualitative kindsof institutional issues that were consideredin <strong>the</strong> previous section of this paper. Manyof <strong>the</strong> central issues of our time are questionsof hou we use limited information andlimited computation~il capacity <strong>to</strong> deal c\ i<strong>the</strong>normous problems whose shape we barelygrasp.For many purposes. a modern governmentcan be regarded as a parallel computingdevice. While one part of its capabilityfor rational problem solving is directed <strong>to</strong>fire protection. ano<strong>the</strong>r is directed <strong>to</strong> pavinghigh~vays. ancl ano<strong>the</strong>r <strong>to</strong> collectingrefi~se. For o<strong>the</strong>r important purposes. ugovernment. like a human being. is a serialprocessing system. capable of attending <strong>to</strong>only one thing at u time. When importantnew policies must be formulated. publicand official attention must be focused onone or a few matters. O<strong>the</strong>r concerns. nomatter how pressing. must wait <strong>the</strong>ir turnon <strong>the</strong> agenda. When <strong>the</strong> agenda becomescrowded. public life begins <strong>to</strong> appeal moreand more as a succession of crises. Whenproblems become interrelated. as energyand pollution problems have become. t<strong>here</strong>is <strong>the</strong> constant danger that attentiondirected <strong>to</strong> a single facet of <strong>the</strong> c\eb \\illspaun solutions that disregard vital consequencesfor <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r t"icets. When oil isscarce, bve return <strong>to</strong> coal. but for<strong>get</strong> that wemust <strong>the</strong>n deal with vastly increased quantitiesof sulfur oxides in our urban ail.. Orwe outlaw nuclear pouer stations becauseof radiation hazards, but fail <strong>to</strong> make alternativeprovi4ion <strong>to</strong> meet our energyneeds. It is futile <strong>to</strong> talk of substantive rationalityin public affairs without considering\\,hat p~ucedural means are available <strong>to</strong>order issues on <strong>the</strong> public agenda in :t rationaluay. and <strong>to</strong> in5i11-e attention <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> in-direct consequences of actions taken <strong>to</strong>reach specific goals or solve specific problems.In a uot.ld u<strong>here</strong> information is relativelyscarce. and w<strong>here</strong> p~.oblems for decisionare few and simple. information is almostal~vaysa positive good. In a cjorld w<strong>here</strong>attention is a major scarce resource. informationmay be an expensive luxury, forit may turn our attention frorn c\ hat is important<strong>to</strong> uhat is unimportant. We cannotafford <strong>to</strong> attend <strong>to</strong> inforrnation simply becauseit is t<strong>here</strong>. I am not aware that t<strong>here</strong>has been any systematic development of a<strong>the</strong>ory of inforrnation and communicationthat treats attention ra<strong>the</strong>r than information21s <strong>the</strong> scarce resource." Some of <strong>the</strong>practical consequences of attentionscarcity have already been noticed in businessand government. w<strong>here</strong> early designsof so-called "management informationsystems" flooded executives with trivialdata and. until <strong>the</strong>y learned <strong>to</strong> ignore <strong>the</strong>m.dist~.itcted <strong>the</strong>ir attention from more irnportantmatters. It is probably true ofcontemporary organizations that an au<strong>to</strong>matedinformation system that does notconsume and digest vastly more informationthan it produces and distributes harms<strong>the</strong> performance of <strong>the</strong> organization incjhich it is incorporated.The management of attention and tracingindirect consequences of action are two of<strong>the</strong> basic issues of procedural rationalitythat confront a modern society. T<strong>here</strong> areo<strong>the</strong>rs of comparable importance: what decision-makingprocedure is rational when<strong>the</strong> basic quantities for making marginalcomparisons are simply not known? A fewyears ago. I served as chairman of a NationalAcademy of Sciences (,YAS) committeewhose job it Ivas <strong>to</strong> advise <strong>the</strong> Congresson <strong>the</strong> control of au<strong>to</strong>mobile emissions (see,YAS, Coordinating Committee on Ail-Quality Stuclies). It is easy <strong>to</strong> formulate anSEU model <strong>to</strong> conceptualize <strong>the</strong> problem.T<strong>here</strong> is a production function for au<strong>to</strong>mobilesthat associates different costs with differentlevels of emissions. The laws govern-"Somc un\)\tc'matic ~-e~nnrk\ on <strong>the</strong> subject \rill br.found in <strong>the</strong> ;i~tho~.( 107hu. chs. 13. 1.1).


ing <strong>the</strong> chemistry of <strong>the</strong> atmosp<strong>here</strong> determine<strong>the</strong> concentrations of pollutingsubstances in <strong>the</strong> air as a function of <strong>the</strong>levels of emissions. Biomedical sciencetells us uhat effects on life and health canbe expected from various concentrations ofpollutants. ,411 we need do is <strong>to</strong> attach aprice tag <strong>to</strong> life and health. and ue can calculate<strong>the</strong> optimum level of pollution control.T<strong>here</strong> is only one hitch-which will beapparent <strong>to</strong> all of you. None of <strong>the</strong> relevantparameters of <strong>the</strong> various "productionfunctions" are knoun-except. within halfan order of magnitude, <strong>the</strong> cost of reducing<strong>the</strong> emissions <strong>the</strong>mselves. The physics andchemistry of <strong>the</strong> atmosp<strong>here</strong> presents aseries of unsolved problems-particularlyrelating <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> pho<strong>to</strong>chemical reactions affecting<strong>the</strong> oxides of nitrogen and ozone.Medical science is barely able <strong>to</strong> detect thatt<strong>here</strong> trr~health effects from pollutants,much less measure hou large <strong>the</strong>se effectsare. The committee's deliberations led immediately<strong>to</strong> one conclusion-one thatcongressmen are 'tccus<strong>to</strong>med <strong>to</strong> hearingfrom such committees: We need more research.But uhile <strong>the</strong> I-esearch is beingdone. uh'tt provisions should be incorpor-utedin <strong>the</strong> Clean Air Act of 1977 (or <strong>the</strong>Acts of 1978 through 2000. for that matter)''For- research won't give us clear answers<strong>the</strong>n ei<strong>the</strong>r. What constitirtes procedural rationalityin such cir-cumstances?"Reasonable men" reach "reasonable"conclusions in circumstances uher-e <strong>the</strong>yhave no prospect of applying classicalmodels of s~rbstnntive rationality. We knowonly imper-fectly hou <strong>the</strong>y do it. We knoueven less uhe<strong>the</strong>r- <strong>the</strong> ~rocedures <strong>the</strong>v usein place of <strong>the</strong> inapplicable models haveany merit-although most of us wouldchoose <strong>the</strong>m in preference <strong>to</strong> drauing lots.The st~rdy of procedural r-ationality in circumstancesu<strong>here</strong> attention is scarce.uher-e problems are immensely complex.and w<strong>here</strong> crucial information is absentpresents a host of challenging and fundamentalresearch problems <strong>to</strong> anyone uho isinter-ested in <strong>the</strong> rational allocution ofscar-ce resources.IV. ConclusionIn his<strong>to</strong>ries of human civilization, <strong>the</strong>invention of writing and <strong>the</strong> invention ofprinting are always treated as key events.Perhaps in future his<strong>to</strong>ries <strong>the</strong> invention ofelectrical communication and <strong>the</strong> inventionof <strong>the</strong> computer will receive comparableemphasis. What all of <strong>the</strong>se developmentshave in common, and what makes <strong>the</strong>m soimportant, is that <strong>the</strong>y represent basicchanges in man's equipment for making rationalchoices-in his computational capabilities.Problems that are impossible <strong>to</strong>handle with <strong>the</strong> head alone (multiplyinglarge numbers <strong>to</strong><strong>get</strong>her. for example) becometrivial when <strong>the</strong>y can be written downon paper. Interactions of energy and environmentthat almost defy conceptualizationlend <strong>the</strong>mselves <strong>to</strong> at least approximatemodeling with modern computers.The advances in man's capacity forprocedural rationality are not limited <strong>to</strong><strong>the</strong>se obvious examples. The invention ofalgebra. of analytic geometry, of <strong>the</strong> calculuswere such advances. So was <strong>the</strong>invention. if we may call it that. of <strong>the</strong>modern organization, which greatlyincreased man's capacity for coordinatedparallel activity. Changes in <strong>the</strong> productionfunction for information and decisions arecentral <strong>to</strong> any account of changes over <strong>the</strong>centuries of <strong>the</strong> human condition.In <strong>the</strong> past, econornics has largelyignored <strong>the</strong> processes that rational manuses in reaching his resource allocation decisions.This was possibly an acceptablestrategy for explaining rational decision instatic. relatively simple problem situationsu<strong>here</strong> it might be assumed that additionalcomputational time or pouer could notchange <strong>the</strong> outcome. The strategy does notuosk. however. uhen ue are seeking <strong>to</strong>explain <strong>the</strong> decision maker's behavior incomplex. dynamic circumstances that involvea great deal of uncertainty. and thatmake severe demands upon his attention.As economics acquires aspirations <strong>to</strong>explain behavior under <strong>the</strong>se typical conditionsof modern organizational and publiclife, it will have <strong>to</strong> devote major energy <strong>to</strong>


VOL. 68 NO. 2RICHARD 7. ELY LECTURE15building a <strong>the</strong>ory of procedural rationality<strong>to</strong> complement existing <strong>the</strong>ories of substantiverationality. Some elements of such a<strong>the</strong>ory can be borrowed from <strong>the</strong> neighboringdisciplines of operations research.artificial intelligence, and cognitivepsychology; but an enormous job remains<strong>to</strong> be done <strong>to</strong> extend this work and <strong>to</strong> applyit <strong>to</strong> specifically economic problems.Jacob Marschak, throughout his longcareer, had a deep belief in and commitment<strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> interdependencies and complementarityof <strong>the</strong> several social sciences. Ihave shared that belief and commitment,without always agreeing with him in detailas <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> precise route for exploiting it. Thedevelopments I have been describingstreng<strong>the</strong>n greatly, it seems <strong>to</strong> me, <strong>the</strong> rationalgrounds for both belief and commitment.Whe<strong>the</strong>r ue accept <strong>the</strong> morerestricted definition of economics that Iquoted from Ely's textbook, or <strong>the</strong> uiderdefinition that is widely accepted <strong>to</strong>day. Liehave every reason <strong>to</strong> try <strong>to</strong> communicatewith <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r social sciences. both <strong>to</strong> findout what we have <strong>to</strong> 4ay that may be ofinterest <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong>m. and <strong>to</strong> discover what <strong>the</strong>ycan teach us about <strong>the</strong> nature of proceduralrationality.REFERENCESAlfred V. Aho et al., The Design and Analj,.si.soj'Compurer AIgorithm.s, Reading 1974.Chester I. Barnard, Thr Functions of' <strong>the</strong>Executive, Cambridge 1938.G. S. Becker, "Irrational Behavior and EconomicTheory," J. Polir. Econ., Feb.1962, 70, 1-13.. "A Theory of Social Interations,"J. Polit. Econ., Nov./Dec. 1974, (92,1063-93.F. M. Cancian, "Functional Analysis," inInternational Ency~clopedia of' <strong>the</strong> SocialSciences, 1968.6, 29-42.R. M. Cyert and M. H. Degrott, "SequentialStrategies in Dual Control," Theor!,Decn., Apr. 1977,8, 173-92.Anthony Downs, An Econonzic Throrj. ofDemocracj,, New Y ork 1957.Maurice Duverger, Political Parties, rev. ed.,New York 1959, (Les Partis Politiques,Paris 1951).W. Edwards, "Conservation in Human InformationProcessing," in BenjaminKleinmuntz, ed., Forr~al Representationof'Human Thought, New York 1968.Richard T. Ely, Outlines of' Econonzics, rev.ed., New York 1930.S. Freud, "Five Lectures on Psychoanalysis"(originally "The Origin and Developmen<strong>to</strong>f Psychoanalysis" 1910) in The ConzpletePsychological Works of SigrnundFreud, Vol. 11, London 1957.George Homans, Social Behavior: Its Elemmtar),Fornzs, New York 1961.D. Kahneman and A. Tversky, "On <strong>the</strong> Psychologyof Prediction," Psj.cho1. Rrv.,July 1973,80, 237-5 1.Janos Kornai, Anti-Eyuilihriunz, Amsterdam1971.Howard Kunreu<strong>the</strong>r et al., Protecting AgainstHigh-Risk Hazards: Public Polic!. Lrssons,New York 1978.James G. March and Herbert A. Simon, Organizations,New York 1958.Jacob Marschak and Roy Radner, EcononzicTheor, of' Team.s, New Haven 1972.John M. Montias, The Structure of EcononlicSj>.stem.s,New Haven 1976.J. F. Muth, "Rational Expectations and <strong>the</strong>Theory of Price Movements," Econometrica,July 1961, ZY, 315-35.Nils Nilsson, Prohlerrl-Solving Methods inArtificial Intelligmce, New York 1971.A. Rees, "Econon~ics," in IntrrnationalEncj,cloprdiu qf <strong>the</strong> Social Sciences, 1968,4,472.William H. Riker, Thr Throrj oj' PoliticalCoalitions, New Haven 1962.and Peter C. Ordeshook, An Introduction<strong>to</strong> Positit~e Poliric*al Tlleorj,, NewJersey 1973.Paul Samuelson, Foundations of EconomicAnalj,.sis, Cambridge 1947.George Simmel, Soziologir, Berlin 1908.Herbert A. Simon, "A Formal Theory of <strong>the</strong>Employment Relation," Encononzrrrica,July 1951, lY, 293305., "A Behavioral Model of Rational


115 A.MtRIC.AN tC'ONO.ZfIC ASSOC IA7lOl' MAY 1978Choice," Quart. J. Econ., Feb. 1955, 69,99-1 18,, "Dynamic Programming UnderUncertainty with a Quadratic CriterionFunction," Econot~lrtric,a,Jan. 1956, 24,74- 8 1 .,(1976a) Adn~inistrarivr Bcha~*ior, 3ded., New York 1976., (1976b) "From Substantive <strong>to</strong>Procedural Rationality," in Spiro J.Latsis, ed., Mcthod and Appraisal inEconomics, Cambridge 1976.a n d J. B. Kadane, "Optit~iai Problem-Solving Search: All-or-None Solutions,"Artificial Intel., Fall 1975,6, 23548.G. J. Stigler, "The Economics of Information,"J. Polit. Econ., June 1961, 69,213-15.a n d G. S. Becker, "De Gustibus nonest Disputandum," Anlrr. Econ. Rev.,Mar. 1977.67. 76-90.Oliver E. Williamson, Markets and Hierarchies,New York 1975.National Academy of Sciences, (hr,4S ) CoordinatingCommittee on Air QualityStudies, '4ir Qualitj! and Au<strong>to</strong>t~~ohileEttlission Cot?trol, Vol. 1 summary rep.,Washing<strong>to</strong>n 1974.


http://www.js<strong>to</strong>r.orgLINKED CITATIONS- Page 1 of 2 -You have printed <strong>the</strong> following article:Rationality as Process and as Product of ThoughtHerbert A. SimonThe American Economic Review, Vol. 68, No. 2, Papers and Proceedings of <strong>the</strong> Ninetieth AnnualMeeting of <strong>the</strong> American Economic Association. (May, 1978), pp. 1-16.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0002-8282%28197805%2968%3A2%3C1%3ARAPAAP%3E2.0.CO%3B2-4This article references <strong>the</strong> following linked citations. If you are trying <strong>to</strong> access articles from anoff-campus location, you may be required <strong>to</strong> first logon via your library web site <strong>to</strong> access JSTOR. Pleasevisit your library's website or contact a librarian <strong>to</strong> learn about options for remote access <strong>to</strong> JSTOR.[Footnotes]2 Irrational Behavior and Economic TheoryGary S. BeckerThe Journal of Political Economy, Vol. 70, No. 1. (Feb., 1962), pp. 1-13.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0022-3808%28196202%2970%3A1%3C1%3AIBAET%3E2.0.CO%3B2-J6 Irrational Behavior and Economic TheoryGary S. BeckerThe Journal of Political Economy, Vol. 70, No. 1. (Feb., 1962), pp. 1-13.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0022-3808%28196202%2970%3A1%3C1%3AIBAET%3E2.0.CO%3B2-JReferencesIrrational Behavior and Economic TheoryGary S. BeckerThe Journal of Political Economy, Vol. 70, No. 1. (Feb., 1962), pp. 1-13.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0022-3808%28196202%2970%3A1%3C1%3AIBAET%3E2.0.CO%3B2-JNOTE: The reference numbering from <strong>the</strong> original has been maintained in this citation list.


http://www.js<strong>to</strong>r.orgLINKED CITATIONS- Page 2 of 2 -A Theory of Social InteractionsGary S. BeckerThe Journal of Political Economy, Vol. 82, No. 6. (Nov. - Dec., 1974), pp. 1063-1093.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0022-3808%28197411%2F12%2982%3A6%3C1063%3AATOSI%3E2.0.CO%3B2-WRational Expectations and <strong>the</strong> Theory of Price MovementsJohn F. MuthEconometrica, Vol. 29, No. 3. (Jul., 1961), pp. 315-335.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0012-9682%28196107%2929%3A3%3C315%3AREATTO%3E2.0.CO%3B2-GDynamic Programming Under Uncertainty with a Quadratic Criterion FunctionHerbert A. SimonEconometrica, Vol. 24, No. 1. (Jan., 1956), pp. 74-81.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0012-9682%28195601%2924%3A1%3C74%3ADPUUWA%3E2.0.CO%3B2-5The Economics of InformationGeorge J. StiglerThe Journal of Political Economy, Vol. 69, No. 3. (Jun., 1961), pp. 213-225.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0022-3808%28196106%2969%3A3%3C213%3ATEOI%3E2.0.CO%3B2-DDe Gustibus Non Est DisputandumGeorge J. Stigler; Gary S. BeckerThe American Economic Review, Vol. 67, No. 2. (Mar., 1977), pp. 76-90.Stable URL:http://links.js<strong>to</strong>r.org/sici?sici=0002-8282%28197703%2967%3A2%3C76%3ADGNED%3E2.0.CO%3B2-8NOTE: The reference numbering from <strong>the</strong> original has been maintained in this citation list.


Why We Have Never Used <strong>the</strong> Black-Scholes-Mer<strong>to</strong>n Option Pricing FormulaEspen Gaarder Haug & Nassim Nicholas TalebJanuary 2008- Fourth VersionAbstract: Options traders use a pricing formula which <strong>the</strong>y adapt by fudgingand changing <strong>the</strong> tails and skewness by varying one parameter, <strong>the</strong> standarddeviation of a Gaussian. Such formula is popularly called “Black-Scholes-Mer<strong>to</strong>n”owing <strong>to</strong> an attributed eponymous discovery (though changing <strong>the</strong> standarddeviation parameter is in contradiction with it). However we have his<strong>to</strong>ricalevidence that 1) Black, Scholes and Mer<strong>to</strong>n did not invent any formula, justfound an argument <strong>to</strong> make a well known (and used) formula compatible with<strong>the</strong> economics establishment, by removing <strong>the</strong> “risk” parameter through“dynamic hedging”, 2) Option traders use (and evidently have used since 1902)heuristics and tricks more compatible with <strong>the</strong> previous versions of <strong>the</strong> formulaof Louis Bachelier and Edward O. Thorp (that allow a broad choice of probabilitydistributions) and removed <strong>the</strong> risk parameter by using put-call parity. 3) Optiontraders did not use formulas after 1973 but continued <strong>the</strong>ir bot<strong>to</strong>m-up heuristics.The Bachelier-Thorp approach is more robust (among o<strong>the</strong>r things) <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> highimpact rare event. The paper draws on his<strong>to</strong>rical trading methods and 19 th andearly 20 th century references ignored by <strong>the</strong> finance literature. It is time <strong>to</strong> s<strong>to</strong>pcalling <strong>the</strong> formula by <strong>the</strong> wrong name.BREAKING THE CHAIN OF TRANSMISSIONFor us, practitioners, <strong>the</strong>ories should arise frompractice 1 . This explains our concern with <strong>the</strong> “scientific”notion that practice should fit <strong>the</strong>ory. Option hedging,pricing, and trading is nei<strong>the</strong>r philosophy norma<strong>the</strong>matics. It is a rich craft with traders learningfrom traders (or traders copying o<strong>the</strong>r traders) andtricks developing under evolution pressures, in abot<strong>to</strong>m-up manner. It is technë, not ëpistemë. Had itbeen a science it would not have survived – for <strong>the</strong>empirical and scientific fitness of <strong>the</strong> pricing andhedging <strong>the</strong>ories offered are, we will see, at best,defective and unscientific (and, at <strong>the</strong> worst, <strong>the</strong>hedging methods create more risks than <strong>the</strong>y reduce).Our approach in this paper is <strong>to</strong> ferret out his<strong>to</strong>ricalevidence of technë showing how option traders wentabout <strong>the</strong>ir business in <strong>the</strong> past.Options, we will show, have been extremely active in<strong>the</strong> pre-modern finance world. Tricks and heuristicallyderived methodologies in option trading and riskmanagement of derivatives books have been developedover <strong>the</strong> past century, and used quite effectively byopera<strong>to</strong>rs. In parallel, many derivations were producedby ma<strong>the</strong>matical researchers. The economics literature,1 For us, in this discussion, a practitioner is deemed <strong>to</strong> besomeone involved in repeated decisions about option hedging,not a support quant who writes pricing software or anacademic who provides “consulting” advice.however, did not recognize <strong>the</strong>se contributions,substituting <strong>the</strong> rediscoveries or subsequentreformulations done by (some) economists. T<strong>here</strong> isevidence of an attribution problem with Black-Scholes-Mer<strong>to</strong>n option “formula”, which was developed, used,and adapted in a robust way by a long tradition ofresearchers and used heuristically by option bookrunners. Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, in a case of scientific puzzle, <strong>the</strong>exact formula called “Black-Sholes-Mer<strong>to</strong>n” was writtendown (and used) by Edward Thorp which,paradoxically, while being robust and realistic, has beenconsidered unrigorous. This raises <strong>the</strong> following: 1) TheBlack Scholes Mer<strong>to</strong>n was just a neoclassical financeargument, no more than a thought experiment 2 , 2) Weare not aware of traders using <strong>the</strong>ir argument or <strong>the</strong>irversion of <strong>the</strong> formula.It is high time <strong>to</strong> give credit w<strong>here</strong> it belongs.THE BLACK-SCHOLES-MERTON “FORMULA” WAS ANARGUMENTOption traders call <strong>the</strong> formula <strong>the</strong>y use <strong>the</strong> “Black-Scholes-Mer<strong>to</strong>n” formula without being aware that by2 Here we question <strong>the</strong> notion of confusing thoughtexperiments in a hypo<strong>the</strong>tical world, of no predictive power,with ei<strong>the</strong>r science or practice. The fact that <strong>the</strong> Black-Scholes-Mer<strong>to</strong>n argument works in a Pla<strong>to</strong>nic world and appears <strong>to</strong> be“elegant” does not mean anything since one can alwaysproduce a Pla<strong>to</strong>nic world in which a certain equation works, orin which a “rigorous” proof can be provided, a process calledreverse-engineering.


some irony, of all <strong>the</strong> possible options formulas thathave been produced in <strong>the</strong> past century, what is called<strong>the</strong> Black-Scholes-Mer<strong>to</strong>n “formula” (after Black andScholes, 1973, and Mer<strong>to</strong>n, 1973) is <strong>the</strong> one <strong>the</strong>fur<strong>the</strong>st away from what <strong>the</strong>y are using. In fact of <strong>the</strong>formulas written down in a long his<strong>to</strong>ry it is <strong>the</strong> onlyformula that is fragile <strong>to</strong> jumps and tail events.First, something seems <strong>to</strong> have been lost in translation:Black and Scholes (1973) and Mer<strong>to</strong>n (1973) actuallynever came up with a new option formula, but only an<strong>the</strong>oretical economic argument built on a new way of“deriving”, ra<strong>the</strong>r rederiving, an already existing –andwell known –formula. The argument, we will see, isextremely fragile <strong>to</strong> assumptions. The foundations ofoption hedging and pricing were already far more firmlylaid down before <strong>the</strong>m. The Black-Scholes-Mer<strong>to</strong>nargument, simply, is that an option can be hedgedusing a certain methodology called “dynamic hedging”and <strong>the</strong>n turned in<strong>to</strong> a risk-free instrument, as <strong>the</strong>portfolio would no longer be s<strong>to</strong>chastic. Indeed whatBlack, Scholes and Mer<strong>to</strong>n did was “marketing”, findinga way <strong>to</strong> make a well-known formula palatable <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong>economics establishment of <strong>the</strong> time, little else, and infact dis<strong>to</strong>rting its essence.Such argument requires strange far-fetchedassumptions: some liquidity at <strong>the</strong> level of transactions,knowledge of <strong>the</strong> probabilities of future events (in aneoclassical Arrow-Debreu style) 3 , and, more critically,a certain ma<strong>the</strong>matical structure that requires “thintails”,or mild randomness, on which, later. The entireargument is indeed, quite strange and ra<strong>the</strong>rinapplicable for someone clinically and observationdrivenstanding outside conventional neoclassicaleconomics. Simply, <strong>the</strong> dynamic hedging argument isdangerous in practice as it subjects you <strong>to</strong> blowups; itmakes no sense unless you are concerned withneoclassical economic <strong>the</strong>ory. The Black-Scholes-Mer<strong>to</strong>n argument and equation flow a <strong>to</strong>p-downgeneral equilibrium <strong>the</strong>ory, built upon <strong>the</strong> assumptionsof opera<strong>to</strong>rs working in full knowledge of <strong>the</strong> probabilitydistribution of future outcomes –in addition <strong>to</strong> acollection of assumptions that, we will see, are highlyinvalid ma<strong>the</strong>matically, <strong>the</strong> main one being <strong>the</strong> ability <strong>to</strong>cut <strong>the</strong> risks using continuous trading which only worksin <strong>the</strong> very narrowly special case of thin-taileddistributions. But it is not just <strong>the</strong>se flaws that make itinapplicable: option traders do not “buy <strong>the</strong>ories”,particularly speculative general equilibrium ones, which<strong>the</strong>y find <strong>to</strong>o risky for <strong>the</strong>m and extremely lacking in3 Of all <strong>the</strong> misplaced assumptions of Black Scholes thatcause it <strong>to</strong> be a mere thought experiment, though an extremelyelegant one, a flaw shared with modern portfolio <strong>the</strong>ory, is <strong>the</strong>certain knowledge of future delivered variance for <strong>the</strong> randomvariable (or, equivalently, all <strong>the</strong> future probabilities). This iswhat makes it clash with practice –<strong>the</strong> rectification by <strong>the</strong>market fattening <strong>the</strong> tails is a negation of <strong>the</strong> Black-Scholesthought experiment.standards of reliability. A normative <strong>the</strong>ory is, simply,not good for decision-making under uncertainty(particularly if it is in chronic disagreement wi<strong>the</strong>mpirical evidence). People may take decisions basedon speculative <strong>the</strong>ories, but avoid <strong>the</strong> fragility of<strong>the</strong>ories in running <strong>the</strong>ir risks.Yet professional traders, including <strong>the</strong> authors (and,alas, <strong>the</strong> Swedish Academy of Science) have operatedunder <strong>the</strong> illusion that it was <strong>the</strong> Black-Scholes-Mer<strong>to</strong>n“formula” <strong>the</strong>y actually used –we were <strong>to</strong>ld so. Thismyth has been progressively reinforced in <strong>the</strong> literatureand in business schools, as <strong>the</strong> original sources havebeen lost or frowned upon as “anecdotal” (Mer<strong>to</strong>n,1992).Figure 1 The typical "risk reduction" performedby <strong>the</strong> Black-Scholes-Mer<strong>to</strong>n argument. Theseare <strong>the</strong> variations of a dynamically hedgedportfolio. BSM indeed "smoo<strong>the</strong>s" out risks butexposes <strong>the</strong> opera<strong>to</strong>r <strong>to</strong> massive tail events –reminiscent of such blowups as LTCM. O<strong>the</strong>roption formulas are robust <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> rare event andmake no such claims.This discussion will present our real-world, ecologicalunderstanding of option pricing and hedging based onwhat option traders actually do and did for more than ahundred years.This is a very general problem. As we said, optiontraders develop a chain of transmission of technë, likemany professions. But <strong>the</strong> problem is that <strong>the</strong> “chain” isoften broken as universities do not s<strong>to</strong>re <strong>the</strong> acquiredskills by opera<strong>to</strong>rs. Effectively plenty of robus<strong>the</strong>uristically derived implementations have beendeveloped over <strong>the</strong> years, but <strong>the</strong> economicsestablishment has refused <strong>to</strong> quote <strong>the</strong>m oracknowledge <strong>the</strong>m. This makes traders need <strong>to</strong> relearnmatters periodically. Failure of dynamic hedging in1987, by such firm as Leland O’Brien Rubinstein, forinstance, does not seem <strong>to</strong> appear in <strong>the</strong> academicliterature published after <strong>the</strong> event 4 (Mer<strong>to</strong>n, 1992,4 For instance –how mistakes never resurface in<strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong>consciousness, Mark Rubinstein was awarded in 1995 <strong>the</strong>2© Copyright 2007 by N. N. Taleb.


Rubinstein, 1998, Ross, 2005); <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> contrary dynamichedging is held <strong>to</strong> be a standard operation 5 .T<strong>here</strong> are central elements of <strong>the</strong> real world that canescape <strong>the</strong>m –academic research without feedbackfrom practice (in a practical and applied field) can cause<strong>the</strong> diversions we witness between labora<strong>to</strong>ry andecological frameworks. This explains why some manyfinance academics have had <strong>the</strong> tendency <strong>to</strong> makesmooth returns, <strong>the</strong>n blow up using <strong>the</strong>ir own <strong>the</strong>ories 6 .We started <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r way around, first by years ofoption trading doing million of hedges and thousands ofoption trades. This in combination with investigating<strong>the</strong> forgotten and ignored ancient knowledge in optionpricing and trading we will explain some commonmyths about option pricing and hedging.T<strong>here</strong> are indeed two myths:• That we had <strong>to</strong> wait for <strong>the</strong> Black-Scholes-Mer<strong>to</strong>n options formula <strong>to</strong> trade <strong>the</strong> product,price options, and manage option books. Infact <strong>the</strong> introduction of <strong>the</strong> Black, Scholes andMer<strong>to</strong>n argument increased our risks and setus back in risk management. More generally, itis a myth that traders rely on <strong>the</strong>ories, evenless a general equilibrium <strong>the</strong>ory, <strong>to</strong> priceoptions.• That we “use” <strong>the</strong> Black-Scholes-Mer<strong>to</strong>noptions “pricing formula”. We, simply don’t.In our discussion of <strong>the</strong>se myth we will focus on <strong>the</strong>bot<strong>to</strong>m-up literature on option <strong>the</strong>ory that has beenhidden in <strong>the</strong> dark recesses of libraries. And thataddresses only recorded matters –not <strong>the</strong> actualpractice of option trading that has been lost.MYTH 1: PEOPLE DID NOT PROPERLY “PRICE” OPTIONSBEFORE THE BLACK-SCHOLES-MERTON THEORYIt is assumed that <strong>the</strong> Black-Scholes-Mer<strong>to</strong>n <strong>the</strong>ory iswhat made it possible for option traders <strong>to</strong> calculate<strong>the</strong>ir delta hedge (against <strong>the</strong> underlying) and <strong>to</strong> priceoptions. This argument is highly debatable, bothhis<strong>to</strong>rically and analytically.Options were actively trading at least already in <strong>the</strong>1600 as described by Joseph De La Vega –implyingsome form of technë, a heuristic method <strong>to</strong> price <strong>the</strong>mFinancial Engineer of <strong>the</strong> Year award by <strong>the</strong> InternationalAssociation of Financial Engineers. T<strong>here</strong> was no mention ofportfolio insurance and <strong>the</strong> failure of dynamic hedging.6 For a standard reaction <strong>to</strong> a rare event, see <strong>the</strong> following:"Wednesday is <strong>the</strong> type of day people will remember in quantlandfor a very long time," said Mr. Rothman, a University ofChicago Ph.D. who ran a quantitative fund before joiningLehman Bro<strong>the</strong>rs. "Events that models only predicted wouldhappen once in 10,000 years happened every day for threedays." One 'Quant' Sees Shakeout For <strong>the</strong> Ages -- '10,000Years' By Kaja Whitehouse, August 11, 2007; Page B3.and deal with <strong>the</strong>ir exposure. De La Vega describesoption trading in <strong>the</strong> Ne<strong>the</strong>rlands, indicating tha<strong>to</strong>pera<strong>to</strong>rs had some expertise in option pricing andhedging. He diffusely points <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> put-call parity, andhis book was not even meant <strong>to</strong> teach people about <strong>the</strong>technicalities in option trading. Our insistence on <strong>the</strong>use of Put-Call parity is critical for <strong>the</strong> following reason:The Black-Scholes-Mer<strong>to</strong>n’s claim <strong>to</strong> fame is removing<strong>the</strong> necessity of a risk-based drift from <strong>the</strong> underlyingsecurity –<strong>to</strong> make <strong>the</strong> trade “risk-neutral”. But one doesnot need dynamic hedging for that: simple put callparity can suffice (Derman and Taleb, 2005), as we willdiscuss later. And it is this central removal of <strong>the</strong> “riskpremium”that apparently was behind <strong>the</strong> decision by<strong>the</strong> Nobel committee <strong>to</strong> grant Mer<strong>to</strong>n and Scholes <strong>the</strong>(<strong>the</strong>n called) Bank of Sweden Prize in Honor of AlfredNobel: “Black, Mer<strong>to</strong>n and Scholes made a vitalcontribution by showing that it is in fact not necessary<strong>to</strong> use any risk premium when valuing an option. Thisdoes not mean that <strong>the</strong> risk premium disappears;instead it is already included in <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck price.” 7 It isfor having removed <strong>the</strong> effect of <strong>the</strong> drift on <strong>the</strong> valueof <strong>the</strong> option, using a thought experiment, that <strong>the</strong>irwork was originally cited, something that wasmechanically present by any form of trading andconverting using far simpler techniques.Options have a much richer his<strong>to</strong>ry than shown in <strong>the</strong>conventional literature. Forward contracts seems <strong>to</strong>date all <strong>the</strong> way back <strong>to</strong> Mesopotamian clay tabletsdating all <strong>the</strong> way back <strong>to</strong> 1750 B.C. Gelderblom andJonker (2003) show that Amsterdam grain dealers hadused options and forwards already in 1550.In <strong>the</strong> late 1800 and <strong>the</strong> early 1900 t<strong>here</strong> were activeoption markets in London and New York as well as inParis and several o<strong>the</strong>r European exchanges. Markets itseems, were active and extremely sophisticated optionmarkets in 1870. Kairys and Valerio (1997) discuss <strong>the</strong>market for equity options in USA in <strong>the</strong> 1870s, indirectlyshowing that traders were sophisticated enough <strong>to</strong>price for tail events 8 .7 see www.Nobel.se8 The his<strong>to</strong>rical description of <strong>the</strong> market is informativeuntil Kairys and Valerio try <strong>to</strong> gauge whe<strong>the</strong>r options in <strong>the</strong>1870s were underpriced or overpriced (using Black-Scholes-Mer<strong>to</strong>n style methods). T<strong>here</strong> was one tail-event in this period,<strong>the</strong> great panic of September 1873. Kairys and Valerio find thatholding puts was profitable, but deem that <strong>the</strong> market panicwas just a one-time event :“However, <strong>the</strong> put contracts benefit from <strong>the</strong> “financialpanic” that hit <strong>the</strong> market in September, 1873. Viewingthis as a “one-time” event, we repeat <strong>the</strong> analysis for putsexcluding any unexpired contracts written before <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ckmarket panic.”Using references <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> economic literature that also concludethat options in general were overpriced in <strong>the</strong> 1950s 1960s and1970s <strong>the</strong>y conclude: "Our analysis shows that optioncontracts were generally overpriced and were unattractive forretail inves<strong>to</strong>rs <strong>to</strong> purchase”. They add: ”Empirically we findthat both put and call options were regularly overpricedrelative <strong>to</strong> a <strong>the</strong>oretical valuation model."3© Copyright 2007 by N. N. Taleb.


T<strong>here</strong> was even active option arbitrage trading takingplace between some of <strong>the</strong>se markets. T<strong>here</strong> is a longlist of missing treatises on option trading: we traced atleast ten German treatises on options written between<strong>the</strong> late 1800s and <strong>the</strong> hyperinflation episode 9 .One informative extant source, Nelson (1904), speaksvolumes: An option trader and arbitrageur, S.A. Nelsonpublished a book “The A B C of Options and Arbitrage”based on his observations around <strong>the</strong> turn o <strong>the</strong>twentieth century. According <strong>to</strong> Nelson (1904) up <strong>to</strong>500 messages per hour and typically 2000 <strong>to</strong> 3000messages per day w<strong>here</strong> sent between <strong>the</strong> London and<strong>the</strong> New York market through <strong>the</strong> cable companies.Each message was transmitted over <strong>the</strong> wire system inless than a minute. In a heuristic method that wasrepeated in Dynamic Hedging by one of <strong>the</strong> authors,(Taleb,1997), Nelson, describe in a <strong>the</strong>ory-free waymany rigorously clinical aspects of his arbitragebusiness: <strong>the</strong> cost of shipping shares, <strong>the</strong> cost ofinsuring shares, interest expenses, <strong>the</strong> possibilities <strong>to</strong>switch shares directly between someone being longsecurities in New York and short in London and in thisway saving shipping and insurance costs, as well asmany more tricks etc.The formal financial economics canon does not includehis<strong>to</strong>rical sources from outside economics, a mechanismdiscussed in Taleb (2007a). The put-call parity wasaccording <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> formal option literature first fullydescribed by S<strong>to</strong>ll (1969), but nei<strong>the</strong>r he not o<strong>the</strong>rs in<strong>the</strong> field even mention Nelson. Not only was <strong>the</strong> putcallparity argument fully unders<strong>to</strong>od and described indetail by Nelson (1904), but he, in turn, makes frequentreference <strong>to</strong> Higgins (1902). Just as an example Nelson(1904) referring <strong>to</strong> Higgins (1902) writes:“It may be worthy of remark that ‘calls’ are moreoften dealt than ‘puts’ <strong>the</strong> reason probably beingthat <strong>the</strong> majority of ‘punters’ in s<strong>to</strong>cks and sharesare more inclined <strong>to</strong> look at <strong>the</strong> bright side of things,These results are contradicted by <strong>the</strong> practitioner Nelson(1904): “…<strong>the</strong> majority of <strong>the</strong> great option dealers who havefound by experience that it is <strong>the</strong> givers, and not <strong>the</strong> takers, ofoption money who have gained <strong>the</strong> advantage in <strong>the</strong> long run”.9 Here is a partial list:Bielschowsky, R (1892): Ueber die rechtliche Natur derPrämiengeschäfte, Bresl. Genoss.-BuchdrGranichstaedten-Czerva, R (1917): Die Prämiengeschäftean der Wiener Börse, Frankfurt am MainHolz, L. (1905) Die Prämiengeschäfte, Thesis (doc<strong>to</strong>ral)--Universität Ros<strong>to</strong>ckKitzing, C. (1925): Prämiengeschäfte : Vorprämien-,Rückprämien-, Stellagen- u. Nochgeschäfte ; Die solidestenSpekulationsgeschäfte mit Versicherg auf Kursverlust, BerlinLeser, E, (1875): Zur Geschichte der PrämiengeschäfteSzkolny, I. (1883): Theorie und praxis derprämiengeschäfte nach einer originalen methode dargestellt.,Frankfurt am MainAuthor Unknown (1925): Das Wesen derPrämiengeschäfte, Berlin : Eugen Bab & Co., Bankgeschäftand t<strong>here</strong>fore more often ‘see’ a rise than a fall inprices.This special inclination <strong>to</strong> buy ‘calls’ and <strong>to</strong> leave <strong>the</strong>‘puts’ severely alone does not, however, tend <strong>to</strong>make ‘calls’ dear and ‘puts’ cheap, for it can beshown that <strong>the</strong> adroit dealer in options can converta ‘put’ in<strong>to</strong> a ‘call,’ a ‘call’ in<strong>to</strong> a ‘put’, a ‘call o’ more’in<strong>to</strong> a ‘put- and-call,’ in fact any option in<strong>to</strong> ano<strong>the</strong>r,by dealing against it in <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck. We may t<strong>here</strong>foreassume, with <strong>to</strong>lerable accuracy, that <strong>the</strong> ‘call’ of as<strong>to</strong>ck at any moment costs <strong>the</strong> same as <strong>the</strong> ‘put’ ofthat s<strong>to</strong>ck, and half as much as <strong>the</strong> Put-and-Call.”The Put-and-Call was simply a put plus a call with <strong>the</strong>same strike and maturity, what we <strong>to</strong>day would call astraddle. Nelson describes <strong>the</strong> put-call parity over manypages in full detail. Static market neutral delta hedgingwas also known at that time, in his book Nelson forexample writes:“Sellers of options in London as a result of longexperience, if <strong>the</strong>y sell a Call, straightway buy half<strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck against which <strong>the</strong> Call is sold; or if a Put issold; <strong>the</strong>y sell half <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck immediately.”We must interpret <strong>the</strong> value of this statement in <strong>the</strong>light that standard options in London at that time wereissued at-<strong>the</strong>-money (as explicitly pointed out byNelson); fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, all standard options in Londonwere European style. In London in- or out-of-<strong>the</strong>moneyoptions w<strong>here</strong> only traded occasionally andw<strong>here</strong> known as “fancy options”. It is quite clear fromthis and <strong>the</strong> rest of Nelson’s book that that <strong>the</strong> optiondealers w<strong>here</strong> well aware of <strong>the</strong> delta for at-<strong>the</strong>-moneyoptions was approximately 50%. As a matter of fact at<strong>the</strong>-moneyoptions trading in London at that time wereadjusted <strong>to</strong> be struck <strong>to</strong> be at-<strong>the</strong>-money forward, inorder <strong>to</strong> make puts and calls of <strong>the</strong> same price. Weknow <strong>to</strong>day know that options that are at-<strong>the</strong>-moneyforward and not have very long time <strong>to</strong> maturity have adelta very close <strong>to</strong> 50% (naturally minus 50% for puts).The options in London at that time typically had onemonth <strong>to</strong> maturity when issued.Nelson also diffusely points <strong>to</strong> dynamic delta hedging,and that it worked better in <strong>the</strong>ory than practice (seeHaug, 2007). It is clearly from all <strong>the</strong> details describedby Nelson that options in <strong>the</strong> early 1900 traded activelyand that option traders at that time in no way fel<strong>the</strong>lpless in ei<strong>the</strong>r pricing or in hedging <strong>the</strong>m.Herbert Filer was ano<strong>the</strong>r option trader that wasinvolved in option trading from 1919 <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> 1960s.Filler(1959) describes what must be consider areasonable active option market in New York andEurope in <strong>the</strong> early 1920s and 1930s. Filer mentionhowever that due <strong>to</strong> World War II t<strong>here</strong> was no tradingon <strong>the</strong> European Exchanges, for <strong>the</strong>y were closed.Fur<strong>the</strong>r, he mentions that London option trading did notresume before 1958. In <strong>the</strong> early 1900, option tradersin London were considered <strong>to</strong> be <strong>the</strong> mostsophisticated, according <strong>to</strong> Nelson. It could well be thatWorld War II and <strong>the</strong> subsequent shutdown of option4© Copyright 2007 by N. N. Taleb.


trading for many years was <strong>the</strong> reason known robustarbitrage principles about options were forgotten andalmost lost, <strong>to</strong> be partly re-discovered by financeprofessors such as S<strong>to</strong>ll (1969).Earlier, in 1908, Vinzenz Bronzin published a bookderiving several option pricing formulas, and a formulavery similar <strong>to</strong> what <strong>to</strong>day is known as <strong>the</strong> Black-Scholes-Mer<strong>to</strong>n formula. Bronzin based his risk-neutraloption valuation on robust arbitrage principles such as<strong>the</strong> put-call parity and <strong>the</strong> link between <strong>the</strong> forwardprice and call and put options –in a way that wasrediscovered by Derman and Taleb (2005) 10 . Indeed,<strong>the</strong> put-call parity restriction is sufficient <strong>to</strong> remove <strong>the</strong>need <strong>to</strong> incorporate a future return in <strong>the</strong> underlyingsecurity –it forces <strong>the</strong> lining up of options <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong>forward price 11 .Again, 1910 Henry Deutsch describes put-call parity butin less detail than Higgins and Nelson. In 1961 Reinachagain described <strong>the</strong> put-call parity in quite some detail(ano<strong>the</strong>r text typically ignored by academics). Tradersat New York s<strong>to</strong>ck exchange specializing in using <strong>the</strong>put-call parity <strong>to</strong> convert puts in<strong>to</strong> calls or calls in<strong>to</strong>puts was at that time known as Converters. Reinach(1961):“Although I have no figures <strong>to</strong> substantiate myclaim, I estimate that over 60 per cent of allCalls are made possible by <strong>the</strong> existence ofConverters.”In o<strong>the</strong>r words <strong>the</strong> converters (dealers) who basicallyoperated as market makers were able <strong>to</strong> operate andhedge most of <strong>the</strong>ir risk by “statically” hedging optionswith options. Reinach wrote that he was an optiontrader (Converter) and gave examples on how he andhis colleagues tended <strong>to</strong> hedge and arbitrage optionsagainst options by taking advantage of optionsembedded in convertible bonds:“Writers and traders have figured out o<strong>the</strong>rprocedures for making profits writing Puts &10 The argument Derman Taleb(2005) was present inTaleb (1997) but remained unnoticed.11 Ruffino and Treussard (2006) accept that one couldhave solved <strong>the</strong> risk-premium by happenstance, not realizingthat put-call parity was so extensively used in his<strong>to</strong>ry. But <strong>the</strong>yfind it insufficient. Indeed <strong>the</strong> argument may not be sufficientfor someone who subsequently complicated <strong>the</strong> representationof <strong>the</strong> world with some implements of modern finance such as“s<strong>to</strong>chastic discount rates” –while simplifying it at <strong>the</strong> sametime <strong>to</strong> make it limited <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> Gaussian and allowing dynamichedging. They write that “<strong>the</strong> use of a non-s<strong>to</strong>chastic discountrate common <strong>to</strong> both <strong>the</strong> call and <strong>the</strong> put options isinconsistent with modern equilibrium capital asset pricing<strong>the</strong>ory.” Given that we have never seen a practitioner use“s<strong>to</strong>chastic discount rate”, we, like our option tradingpredecessors, feel that put-call parity is sufficient & does <strong>the</strong>job.The situation is akin <strong>to</strong> that of scientists lecturing birds onhow <strong>to</strong> fly, and taking credit for <strong>the</strong>ir subsequent performance–except that <strong>here</strong> it would be lecturing <strong>the</strong>m <strong>the</strong> wrong way.Calls. Most are <strong>to</strong>o specialized for all but <strong>the</strong>seasoned professional. One such procedure is<strong>the</strong> ownership of a convertible bonds and <strong>the</strong>nwriting of Calls against <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck in<strong>to</strong> which <strong>the</strong>bonds are convertible. If <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck is calledconverted and <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck is delivered.”Higgins, Nelson and Reinach all describe <strong>the</strong> greatimportance of <strong>the</strong> put-call parity and <strong>to</strong> hedge optionswith options. Option traders w<strong>here</strong> in no way helplessin hedging or pricing before <strong>the</strong> Black-Scholes-Mer<strong>to</strong>nformula. Based on simple arbitrage principles <strong>the</strong>yw<strong>here</strong> able <strong>to</strong> hedge options more robustly than withBlack- Scholes-Mer<strong>to</strong>n. As already mentioned staticmarket-neutral delta hedging was described by Higginsand Nelson in 1902 and 1904. Also, W. D. Gann (1937)discusses market neutral delta hedging for at-<strong>the</strong>moneyoptions, but in much less details than Nelson(1904). Gann also indicates some forms of auxiliarydynamic hedging.Mills (1927) illustrates how jumps and fat tails werepresent in <strong>the</strong> literature in <strong>the</strong> pre-Modern PortfolioTheory days. He writes: ”A distribution may departwidely from <strong>the</strong> Gaussian type because <strong>the</strong> influence ofone or two extreme price change.”Option Formulas and Delta HedgingWhich brings us <strong>to</strong> option pricing formulas. The firstidentifiable one was Bachelier (1900). Sprenkle (1962)extended Bacheliers work <strong>to</strong> assume lognormal ra<strong>the</strong>rthan normal distributed asset price. It also avoidsdiscounting (<strong>to</strong> no significant effect since manymarkets, particularly <strong>the</strong> U.S., option premia were paidat expiration).James Boness (1964) also assumed a lognormal assetprice. He derives a formula for <strong>the</strong> price of a calloption that is actually identical <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> Black-Scholes-Mer<strong>to</strong>n 1973 formula, but <strong>the</strong> way Black, Scholes andMer<strong>to</strong>n derived <strong>the</strong>ir formula based on continuousdynamic delta hedging or alternatively based on CAPM<strong>the</strong>y were able <strong>to</strong> <strong>get</strong> independent of <strong>the</strong> expected rateof return. It is in o<strong>the</strong>r words not <strong>the</strong> formula itself thatis considered <strong>the</strong> great discovery done by Black,Scholes and Mer<strong>to</strong>n, but how <strong>the</strong>y derived it. This isamong several o<strong>the</strong>rs also pointed out by Rubinstein(2006):“The real significance of <strong>the</strong> formula <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong>financial <strong>the</strong>ory of investment lies not in itself,but ra<strong>the</strong>r in how it was derived. Ten yearsearlier <strong>the</strong> same formula had been derived byCase M. Sprenkle (1962) and A. James Boness(1964).”Samuelson (1969) and Thorp (1969) publishedsomewhat similar option pricing formulas <strong>to</strong> Boness andSprenkle. Thorp (2007) claims that he actually had anidentical formula <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> Black-Scholes-Mer<strong>to</strong>n formula5© Copyright 2007 by N. N. Taleb.


programmed in<strong>to</strong> his computer years before Black,Scholes and Mer<strong>to</strong>n published <strong>the</strong>ir <strong>the</strong>ory.Now, delta hedging. As already mentioned staticmarket-neutral delta hedging was clearly described byHiggins and Nelson 1902 and 1904. Thorp and Kassouf(1967) presented market neutral static delta hedging inmore details, not only for at-<strong>the</strong>-money options, but foroptions with any delta. In his 1969 paper Thorp isshortly describing market neutral static delta hedging,also briefly pointed in <strong>the</strong> direction of some dynamicdelta hedging, not as a central pricing device, but arisk-management <strong>to</strong>ol. Filer also points <strong>to</strong> dynamichedging of options, but without showing muchknowledge about how <strong>to</strong> calculate <strong>the</strong> delta. Ano<strong>the</strong>r“ignored” and “forgotten” text is a book/bookletpublished in 1970 by Arnold Bernhard & Co. Theauthors are clearly aware of market neutral static deltahedging or what <strong>the</strong>y name “balanced hedge” for anylevel in <strong>the</strong> strike or asset price. This book has multipleexamples of how <strong>to</strong> buy warrants or convertible bondsand construct a market neutral delta hedge by shorting<strong>the</strong> right amount of common shares. Arnold Bernhard &Co also published deltas for a large number of warrantsand convertible bonds that <strong>the</strong>y distributed <strong>to</strong> inves<strong>to</strong>rson Wall Street.Referring <strong>to</strong> Thorp and Kassouf (1967), Black, Scholesand Mer<strong>to</strong>n <strong>to</strong>ok <strong>the</strong> idea of delta hedging one stepfur<strong>the</strong>r, Black and Scholes (1973):“If <strong>the</strong> hedge is maintained continuously, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong>approximations mentioned above become exact, and<strong>the</strong> return on <strong>the</strong> hedged position is completelyindependent of <strong>the</strong> change in <strong>the</strong> value of <strong>the</strong> s<strong>to</strong>ck. Infact, <strong>the</strong> return on <strong>the</strong> hedged position becomescertain. This was pointed out <strong>to</strong> us by Robert Mer<strong>to</strong>n.”This may be a brilliant ma<strong>the</strong>matical idea, but optiontrading is not ma<strong>the</strong>matical <strong>the</strong>ory. It is not enough <strong>to</strong>have a <strong>the</strong>oretical idea so far removed from reality thatis far from robust in practice. What is surprising is that<strong>the</strong> only principle option traders do not use and cannotuse is <strong>the</strong> approach named after <strong>the</strong> formula, which is apoint we discuss next.MYTH 2: OPTION TRADERS TODAY “USE” THE BLACK-SCHOLES-MERTON FORMULATraders don’t do “Valuation”First, operationally, a price is not quite “valuation”.Valuation requires a strong <strong>the</strong>oretical framework withits corresponding fragility <strong>to</strong> both assumptions and <strong>the</strong>structure of a model. For traders, a “price” produced <strong>to</strong>buy an option when one has no knowledge of <strong>the</strong>probability distribution of <strong>the</strong> future is not “valuation”,but an expedient. Such price could change. Theirbeliefs do not enter such price. It can also bedetermined by his inven<strong>to</strong>ry.This distinction is critical: traders are engineers,whe<strong>the</strong>r boundedly rational (or even non interested inany form of probabilistic rationality), <strong>the</strong>y are not privy<strong>to</strong> informational transparency about <strong>the</strong> future states of<strong>the</strong> world and <strong>the</strong>ir probabilities. So <strong>the</strong>y do not need ageneral <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>to</strong> produce a price –merely <strong>the</strong>avoidance of Dutch-book style arbitrages against <strong>the</strong>m,and <strong>the</strong> compatibility with some standard restriction: Inaddition <strong>to</strong> put-call parity, a call of a certain strike Kcannot trade at a lower price than a call K+!K(avoidance of negative call and put spreads), a callstruck at K and a call struck at K+2 !K cannot be moreexpensive that twice <strong>the</strong> price of a call struck at K+!K(negative butterflies), horizontal calendar spreadscannot be negative (when interest rates are low), andso forth. The degrees of freedom for traders are thusreduced: <strong>the</strong>y need <strong>to</strong> abide by put-call parity andcompatibility with o<strong>the</strong>r options in <strong>the</strong> market.In that sense, traders do not perform “valuation” withsome “pricing kernel” until <strong>the</strong> expiration of <strong>the</strong>security, but, ra<strong>the</strong>r, produce a price of an optioncompatible with o<strong>the</strong>r instruments in <strong>the</strong> markets, witha holding time that is s<strong>to</strong>chastic. They do not need <strong>to</strong>pdown“science”.When do we value?If you find traders operated solo, in a desert island,having for some <strong>to</strong> produce an option price and hold it<strong>to</strong> expiration, in a market in which <strong>the</strong> forward isabsent, <strong>the</strong>n some valuation would be necessary –but<strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong>ir book would be minuscule. And this thoughtexperiment is a dis<strong>to</strong>rtion: people would not tradeoptions unless <strong>the</strong>y are in <strong>the</strong> business of tradingoptions, in which case <strong>the</strong>y would need <strong>to</strong> have a bookwith offsetting trades. For without offsetting trades, wedoubt traders would be able <strong>to</strong> produce a positionbeyond a minimum (and negligible) size as dynamichedging not possible. (Again we are not aware of manynon-blownup option traders and institutions who havemanaged <strong>to</strong> operate in <strong>the</strong> vacuum of <strong>the</strong> BlackScholes-Mer<strong>to</strong>n argument). It is <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> impossibility ofsuch hedging that we turn next.On <strong>the</strong> Ma<strong>the</strong>matical Impossibility ofDynamic HedgingFinally, we discuss <strong>the</strong> severe flaw in <strong>the</strong> dynamichedging concept. It assumes, nay, requires all momentsof <strong>the</strong> probability distribution <strong>to</strong> exist 12 .12 Mer<strong>to</strong>n (1992) seemed <strong>to</strong> accept <strong>the</strong> inapplicability ofdynamic hedging but he perhaps thought that <strong>the</strong>se ills wouldbe cured thanks <strong>to</strong> his prediction of <strong>the</strong> financial world“spiraling <strong>to</strong>wards dynamic completeness”. Fifteen years later,we have, if anything, spiraled away from it.6© Copyright 2007 by N. N. Taleb.


Assume that <strong>the</strong> distribution of returns has a scale-freeor fractal property that we can simplify as follows: for xlarge enough, (i.e. “in <strong>the</strong> tails”), P[X>n x]/P[X>x]depends on n, not on x. In financial securities, say,w<strong>here</strong> X is a daily return, t<strong>here</strong> is no reason forP[X>20%]/P[X>10%] <strong>to</strong> be different fromP[X>15%]/P[X>7.5%]. This self-similarity at all scalesgenerates power-law, or Paretian, tails, i.e., above acrossover point, P[X>x]=K x -! . It happens, looking atmillions of pieces of data, that such property holds inmarkets –all markets, baring sample error. Foroverwhelming empirical evidence, see Mandelbrot(1963), which predates Black-Scholes-Mer<strong>to</strong>n (1973)and <strong>the</strong> jump-diffusion of Mer<strong>to</strong>n (1976); see alsoStanley et al. (2000), and Gabaix et al. (2003). Theargument <strong>to</strong> assume <strong>the</strong> scale-free is as follows: <strong>the</strong>distribution might have thin tails at some point (sayabove some value of X). But we do not know w<strong>here</strong>such point is –we are epistemologically in <strong>the</strong> dark as <strong>to</strong>w<strong>here</strong> <strong>to</strong> put <strong>the</strong> boundary, which forces us <strong>to</strong> useinfinity.Some criticism of <strong>the</strong>se “true fat-tails” accept that suchproperty might apply for daily returns, but, owing <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong>Central Limit Theorem, <strong>the</strong> distribution is held <strong>to</strong>become Gaussian under aggregation for cases in which! is deemed higher than 2. Such argument does nothold owing <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> preasymp<strong>to</strong>tics of scalabledistributions: Bouchaud and Potters (2003) andMandelbrot and Taleb (2007) argue that <strong>the</strong>presasymp<strong>to</strong>tics of fractal distributions are such that<strong>the</strong> effect of <strong>the</strong> Central Limit Theorem are exceedinglyslow in <strong>the</strong> tails –in fact irrelevant. Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, t<strong>here</strong>is sampling error as we have less data for longerperiods, hence fewer tail episodes, which give an insampleillusion of thinner tails. In addition, <strong>the</strong> pointthat aggregation thins out <strong>the</strong> tails does not hold fordynamic hedging –in which <strong>the</strong> opera<strong>to</strong>r dependsnecessarily on high frequency data and <strong>the</strong>ir statisticalproperties. So long as it is scale-free at <strong>the</strong> time periodof dynamic hedge, higher moments become explosive,“infinite” <strong>to</strong> disallow <strong>the</strong> formation of a dynamicallyhedge portfolio. Simply a Taylor expansion is impossibleas moments of higher order that 2 matter critically –one of <strong>the</strong> moments is going <strong>to</strong> be infinite.The mechanics of dynamic hedging are as follows.Assume <strong>the</strong> risk-free interest rate of 0 with no loss ofgenerality. The canonical Black-Scholes-Mer<strong>to</strong>n packageconsists in selling a call and purchasing shares of s<strong>to</strong>ckthat provide a hedge against instantaneous moves in<strong>the</strong> security. Thus <strong>the</strong> portfolio " locally "hedged"against exposure <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> first moment of <strong>the</strong> distributionis <strong>the</strong> following:Take <strong>the</strong> discrete time change in <strong>the</strong> values of <strong>the</strong>portfolioBy expanding around <strong>the</strong> initial values of S, we have<strong>the</strong> changes in <strong>the</strong> portfolio in discrete time.Conventional option <strong>the</strong>ory applies <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> Gaussian inwhich all orders higher than !S 2 and disappears rapidly.Taking expectations on both sides, we can see <strong>here</strong>very strict requirements on moment finiteness: allmoments need <strong>to</strong> converge. If we include ano<strong>the</strong>r term,of order !S 3 , such term may be of significance in aprobability distribution with significant cubic or quarticterms. Indeed, although <strong>the</strong> n th derivative with respect<strong>to</strong> S can decline very sharply, for options that have astrike K away from <strong>the</strong> center of <strong>the</strong> distribution, itremains that <strong>the</strong> delivered higher orders of !S arerising disproportionately fast for that <strong>to</strong> carry amitigating effect on <strong>the</strong> hedges.So <strong>here</strong> we mean all moments--no approximation. Thelogic of <strong>the</strong> Black-Scholes-Mer<strong>to</strong>n so-called solutionthanks <strong>to</strong> I<strong>to</strong>'s lemma was that <strong>the</strong> portfolio collapsesin<strong>to</strong> a deterministic payoff. But let us see how quicklyor effectively this works in practice.The Actual Replication process is as follows: The payoffof a call should be replicated with <strong>the</strong> following streamof dynamic hedges, <strong>the</strong> limit of which can be seen <strong>here</strong>,between t and TSuch policy does not match <strong>the</strong> call value: <strong>the</strong>difference remains s<strong>to</strong>chastic (while according <strong>to</strong> BlackScholes it should shrink). Unless one lives in a fantasyworld in which such risk reduction is possible 13 .Fur<strong>the</strong>r, t<strong>here</strong> is an inconsistency in <strong>the</strong> works ofMer<strong>to</strong>n making us confused as <strong>to</strong> what <strong>the</strong>ory findsacceptable: in Mer<strong>to</strong>n (1976) he agrees that we canuse Bachelier-style option derivation in <strong>the</strong> presence ofjumps and discontinuities –no dynamic hedging– bu<strong>to</strong>nly when <strong>the</strong> underlying s<strong>to</strong>ck price is uncorrelated <strong>to</strong>w<strong>here</strong> C is <strong>the</strong> call price, and S <strong>the</strong> underlying security.13 We often hear <strong>the</strong> misplaced comparison <strong>to</strong> New<strong>to</strong>nianmechanics. It supposedly provided a good approximation untilwe had relativity. The problem with <strong>the</strong> comparison is that <strong>the</strong>thin-tailed distributions are not approximations for fat-tailedones: t<strong>here</strong> is a deep qualitative difference.7© Copyright 2007 by N. N. Taleb.


<strong>the</strong> market. This seems <strong>to</strong> be an admission thatdynamic hedging argument applies only <strong>to</strong> somesecurities: those that do not jump and are correlated <strong>to</strong><strong>the</strong> market.Figure 2 A 25% Gap in Ericsson, one of <strong>the</strong> MostLiquid S<strong>to</strong>cks in <strong>the</strong> World. Such move candominate hundreds of weeks of dynamichedging.The Robustness of <strong>the</strong> GaussianThe success of <strong>the</strong> “formula” last developed by Thorp,and called “Black-Scholes-Mer<strong>to</strong>n” was due <strong>to</strong> a simpleattribute of <strong>the</strong> Gaussian: you can express anyprobability distribution in terms of Gaussian, even if ithas fat tails, by varying <strong>the</strong> standard deviation # at <strong>the</strong>level of <strong>the</strong> density of <strong>the</strong> random variable. It does notmean that you are using a Gaussian, nor does it meanthat <strong>the</strong> Gaussian is particularly parsimonious (sinceyou have <strong>to</strong> attach a # for every level of <strong>the</strong> price). Itsimply mean that <strong>the</strong> Gaussian can express anythingyou want if you add a function for <strong>the</strong> parameter #,making it function of strike price and time <strong>to</strong> expiration.This “volatility smile”, i.e., varying one parameter <strong>to</strong>produce #(K), or “volatility surface”, varying twoparameter, #(S,t) is effectively what was done indifferent ways by Dupire(1994, 2005) and Derman(1994,1998), see Ga<strong>the</strong>ral(2006). They assume avolatility process not because t<strong>here</strong> is necessarily sucha thing –only as a method of fitting option prices <strong>to</strong> aGaussian. Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, although <strong>the</strong> Gaussian hasfinite second moment (and finite all higher moments aswell), you can express a scalable with infinite varianceusing Gaussian “volatility surface”. One strong constrainon <strong>the</strong> # parameter is that it must be <strong>the</strong> same for aput and call with same strike (if both are Europeanstyle),and <strong>the</strong> drift should be that of <strong>the</strong> forward 14 .Indeed, ironically, <strong>the</strong> volatility smile is inconsistentwith <strong>the</strong> Black-Scholes-Mer<strong>to</strong>n <strong>the</strong>ory. This has lead <strong>to</strong>hundreds if not thousands of papers trying extend(what was perceived <strong>to</strong> be) <strong>the</strong> Black-Scholes-Mer<strong>to</strong>nmodel <strong>to</strong> incorporate s<strong>to</strong>chastic volatility and jumpdiffusion.Several of <strong>the</strong>se researchers have beensurprised that so few traders actually use s<strong>to</strong>chastic14 See Breeden and Litzenberberger (1978), Ga<strong>the</strong>ral(2006). See also Bouchaud and Potters (2001) for hedgingerrors in <strong>the</strong> real world.volatility models. It is not a model that says how <strong>the</strong>volatility smile should look like, or evolves over time; itis a hedging method that is robust and consistent withan arbitrage free volatility surface that evolves overtime.In o<strong>the</strong>r words, you can use a volatility surface as amap, not a terri<strong>to</strong>ry. However it is foolish <strong>to</strong> justifyBlack-Scholes-Mer<strong>to</strong>n on grounds of its use: we repeatthat <strong>the</strong> Gaussian bans <strong>the</strong> use of probabilitydistributions that are not Gaussian –w<strong>here</strong>as nondynamichedging derivations (Bachelier, Thorp) are notgrounded in <strong>the</strong> Gaussian.Order Flow and OptionsIt is clear that option traders are not necessarilyinterested in probability distribution at expiration time –given that this is abstract, even metaphysical for <strong>the</strong>m.In addition <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> put-call parity constrains thataccording <strong>to</strong> evidence was fully developed already in1904, we can hedge away inven<strong>to</strong>ry risk in options witho<strong>the</strong>r options. One very important implication of thismethod is that if you hedge options with options <strong>the</strong>noption pricing will be largely demand and supplybased 15 . This in strong contrast <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> Black-Scholes-Mer<strong>to</strong>n (1973) <strong>the</strong>ory that based on <strong>the</strong> idealized worldof geometric Brownian motion with continuous-timedelta hedging <strong>the</strong>n demand and supply for optionssimply not should affect <strong>the</strong> price of options. Ifsomeone wants <strong>to</strong> buy more options <strong>the</strong> market makerscan simply manufacture <strong>the</strong>m by dynamic delta hedgingthat will be a perfect substitute for <strong>the</strong> option itself.This raises a critical point: option traders do not“estimate” <strong>the</strong> odds of rare events by pricing out-of<strong>the</strong>-moneyoptions. They just respond <strong>to</strong> supply anddemand. The notion of “implied probability distribution”is merely a Dutch-book compatibility type ofproposition.Bachelier-ThorpThe argument often casually propounded attributing<strong>the</strong> success of option volume <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> quality of <strong>the</strong> BlackScholes formula is ra<strong>the</strong>r weak. It is particularlyweakened by <strong>the</strong> fact that options had been sosuccessful at different time periods and places.Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, t<strong>here</strong> is evidence that while both <strong>the</strong>Chicago Board Options Exchange and <strong>the</strong> Black-Scholes-Mer<strong>to</strong>n formula came about in 1973, <strong>the</strong> modelwas "rarely used by traders" before <strong>the</strong> 1980s(O'Connell, 2001). When one of <strong>the</strong> authors (Taleb)became a pit trader in 1992, almost two decades afterBlack-Scholes-Mer<strong>to</strong>n, he was surprised <strong>to</strong> find thatmany traders still priced options “sheets free”, “pricing15See Gârleanu, Pedersen, and Poteshman (2006).8© Copyright 2007 by N. N. Taleb.


off <strong>the</strong> butterfly”, and “off <strong>the</strong> conversion”, withoutrecourse <strong>to</strong> any formula.Even a book written in 1975 by a finance academicappears <strong>to</strong> credit Thorpe and Kassouf (1967) -- ra<strong>the</strong>rthan Black-Scholes (1973), although <strong>the</strong> latter waspresent in its bibliography. Auster (1975):Sidney Fried wrote on warrant hedges before 1950,but it was not until 1967 that <strong>the</strong> book Beat <strong>the</strong>Market by Edward O. Thorp and Sheen T. Kassoufrigorously, but simply, explained <strong>the</strong> “shortwarrant/long common” hedge <strong>to</strong> a wide audience.We conclude with <strong>the</strong> following remark. Sadly, all <strong>the</strong>equations, from <strong>the</strong> first (Bachelier), <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> last pre-Black-Scholes-Mer<strong>to</strong>n (Thorp) accommodate a scalefreedistribution. The notion of explicitly removing <strong>the</strong>expectation from <strong>the</strong> forward was present in Keynes(1924) and later by Blau (1944) –and long a Call shorta put of <strong>the</strong> same strike equals a forward. Thesearbitrage relationships appeared <strong>to</strong> be well known in1904.One could easily attribute <strong>the</strong> explosion in optionvolume <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> computer age and <strong>the</strong> ease of processingtransactions, added <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> long stretch of peacefuleconomic growth and absence of hyperinflation. From<strong>the</strong> evidence (once one removes <strong>the</strong> propaganda), <strong>the</strong>development of scholastic finance appears <strong>to</strong> be anepiphenomenon ra<strong>the</strong>r than a cause of option trading.Once again, lecturing birds how <strong>to</strong> fly does not allowone <strong>to</strong> take subsequent credit.This is why we call <strong>the</strong> equation Bachelier-Thorp. Wewere using it all along and gave it <strong>the</strong> wrong name,after <strong>the</strong> wrong method and with attribution <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong>wrong persons. It does not mean that dynamic hedgingis out of <strong>the</strong> question; it is just not a central part of <strong>the</strong>pricing paradigm. It led <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> writing down of a certains<strong>to</strong>chastic process that may have its uses, some day,should markets “spiral <strong>to</strong>wards dynamic completeness”.But not in <strong>the</strong> present.ReferencesBachelier, L. (1900): Theory of speculation in: P.Cootner, ed., 1964, The random character of s<strong>to</strong>ckmarket prices, MIT Press, Cambridge, Mass.Bernhard, A. (1970): More Profit and Less Risk:Convertible Securities and Warrants. Written and Editedby <strong>the</strong> Publisher and Edi<strong>to</strong>rs of The Value LineConvertible Survey, Arnold Bernhard & Co., IncBlack, F., and M. Scholes (1973): “The Pricing ofOptions and Corporate Liabilities,” Journal of PoliticalEconomy, 81, 637–654.Blau, G. (1944-1945): “Some Aspects of The Theory ofFutures Trading,” The Review of Economic Studies,12(1).Boness, A. (1964): “Elements of a Theory of S<strong>to</strong>ck-Option Value,” Journal of Political Economy, 72, 163–175.Bouchaud J.-P. and M. Potters (2003): Theory ofFinancial Risks and Derivatives Pricing, From StatisticalPhysics <strong>to</strong> Risk Management, 2 nd Ed., CambridgeUniversity Press.Bouchaud J.-P. and M. Potters (2001): “Welcome <strong>to</strong> anon-Black-Scholes world”, Quantitative Finance, Volume1, Number 5, May 01, 2001 , pp. 482-483(2)Breeden, D., and R. Litzenberger (1978): Prices ofstate-contingent claims implicit in option prices, Journalof Business 51, 621–651.Bronzin, V. (1908): Theorie der Prämiengeschäfte.Leipzig und Wien: Verlag Franz Deticke.Cootner, P. H. (1964): The Random Character of S<strong>to</strong>ckMarket Prices. Cambridge, Massachusetts, The M.I.T.Press.De La Vega, J. (1688): Confusión de Confusiones. Reprintedin <strong>the</strong> book: ‘Extraordinary Popular Delusionsand <strong>the</strong> Madness of Crowds & Confusión deConfusiones’ edited by Martin S. Fridson, 1996, NewYork: Wiley Publishing.Derman, Emanuel, and Iraj Kani (1994) “Riding on asmile”, Risk 7, 32–39.Derman, Emanuel (1998), S<strong>to</strong>chastic implied trees:Arbitrage pricing with s<strong>to</strong>chastic term and strikestructure of volatility, International Journal ofTheoretical and Applied Finance 1, 61–110.Derman, E., and N. Taleb (2005): “The Illusion ofDynamic Delta Replication,” Quantitative Finance, 5(4),323–326.Dupire, Bruno (1994): Pricing with a smile, Risk 7, 18–20.Dupire, Bruno (1998): A new approach forunderstanding <strong>the</strong>. impact of volatility on option prices,Discussion paper Nikko Financial Products.Dupire, Bruno (2005): Volatility derivatives modeling,www.math.nyu.edu/ carrp/mfseminar/bruno.ppt.Filer, H. 1959: Understanding Put and Call Option’s,New York: Popular Library.Gabaix, X. , P. Gopikrishnan, V.Plerou & H.E.Stanley,2003, A <strong>the</strong>ory of power-law distributions infinancial market fluctuations, Nature, 423, 267-270.Gann, W. D. (1937) How <strong>to</strong> Make Profits in Puts andCalls.Gârleanu, N., L. H. Pedersen, and Poteshman (2006):“Demand-Based Option Pricing”. Working Paper: New9© Copyright 2007 by N. N. Taleb.


York University - Leonard N. Stern School of Business.Ga<strong>the</strong>ral, Jim (2006), The volatility Surface, WileyGelderblom, O. and Jonker, J. (2003) ” Amsterdam as<strong>the</strong> cradle of modern futures and options trading, 1550-1650” , Working PaperHaug E. G. (1996): The Complete Guide <strong>to</strong> OptionPricing Formulas, New York: McGraw-HillHaug, E. G. (2007): Derivatives Models on Models, NewYork, John Wiley & SonsHiggins, L. R. (1902): The Put-and-Call. London: E. WQ ilson.Kairys and Valerio (1997) “The Market for EquityOptions in <strong>the</strong> 1870s” Journal of Finance, Vol LII, NO.4., Pp 1707 – 1723Keynes, J. M. (1924): A Tract on Monetary Reform. Reprinted2000, Amherst New York: Prome<strong>the</strong>us Books.Mandelbrot, Benoit 1997, Fractals and Scaling inFinance, Springer-Verlag.Mandelbrot, Benoit (2001a):Quantitative Finance, 1,113-123Mandelbrot, Benoit (2001b): Quantitative Finance, 1,124-130Mandelbrot, Benoit (1963): The variation of certainspeculative prices. The Journal of Business, 36(4):394–419.Mandelbrot, B. and N. N. Taleb (2007): “Mild vs. WildRandomness: Focusing on Risks that Matter.”Forthcoming in Frank Diebold, Neil Doherty, andRichard Herring, eds., The Known, <strong>the</strong> Unknown and<strong>the</strong> Unknowable in Financial Institutions. Prince<strong>to</strong>n,N.J.: Prince<strong>to</strong>n University Press.Mer<strong>to</strong>n R. C. (1973): “Theory of Rational OptionPricing,” Bell Journal of Economics and ManagementScience, 4, 141–183.Mer<strong>to</strong>n R. C. (1976): ‘‘Option Pricing When UnderlyingS<strong>to</strong>ck Returns are Discontinuous,’’ Journal of FinancialEconomics, 3, 125–144.Mer<strong>to</strong>n, RC (1992): Continuous-Time Finance, revisededition, BlackwellMills F. (1927) The Behaviour of Prices, National Bureauof Economic ResearchNelson, S. A. (1904): The A B C of Options andArbitrage. New York: The Wall Street Library.O'Connell, Martin, P. (2001): The Business of Options ,New York: John Wiley & Sons.Reinach, A. M. (1961): The Nature of Puts & Calls. NewYork: The Book-mailer.Review of <strong>the</strong> International Statistics Institute, 37(3).Rubinstein M. (1998): Derivatives. www.in-<strong>the</strong>money.comRubinstein M. (2006): A His<strong>to</strong>ry of The Theory ofInvestments. New York: John Wiley & Sons.Ruffino and Treussard (2006) "Derman and Taleb's`The Ilusion of Dynamic Replication': a comment",Quantitative Finance, 6, 5, pp 365-367Samuelson, P. (1965): “Rational Theory of WarrantPricing,” Industrial Management Review, 6, 13–31.Sprenkle, C. (1961): “Warrant Prices as Indica<strong>to</strong>rs ofExpectations and Preferences,” Yale Economics Essays,1(2), 178–231.Stanley, H.E. , L.A.N. Amaral, P. Gopikrishnan, and V.Plerou, 2000, Scale invariance and universality ofeconomic fluctuations”, Physica A, 283,31-41S<strong>to</strong>ll, H. (1969): “The Relationship Between Put AndCall Prices,” Journal of Finance, 24(5), 801–824.Taleb, N. (1997): Dynamic Hedging. New York: JohnWiley & Sons.Taleb, N. (2007a): The Black Swan. New York:Random House.Taleb. N. (2007b): “Scale-Invariance in Practice: SomeQuestions and Workable Patches”, working paperThorp, E. O. (1969): “Optimal Gambling Systems forFavorable Games”,Thorp, E. O., and S. T. Kassouf (1967): Beat <strong>the</strong>Market. New York: Random HouseThorp, E. O. (2002): “What I Knew and When I KnewIt – Part 1, Part 2, Part 3,” Wilmott Magazine, Sep-02,Dec-02, Jan-03Thorp, E. O. (2007): “Edward Thorp on Gambling andTrading,” in Haug (2007)Thorp, E. O., and S. T. Kassouf (1967): Beat <strong>the</strong>Market. New York: Random House10© Copyright 2007 by N. N. Taleb.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!