13.07.2015 Views

Après une Lecture de Liszt: Virtuosity and ... - Free

Après une Lecture de Liszt: Virtuosity and ... - Free

Après une Lecture de Liszt: Virtuosity and ... - Free

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

composer-as-butterfly had finally metamorphosedfrom virtuoso-as-caterpillar; the theatricalperformer had represented only an embryonicstage in artistic <strong>de</strong>velopment. <strong>Liszt</strong> thusappeared to reflect a well-documented shift invalues. His emphasis moved from virtuosity tointerpretation, from what Wagner in 1840 hadtermed the “vulgar somersaults” of merepianism to the genius of the artist, 2 from theephemeral performance to the immutable work.In a different sense, the reference to Dante’sDivine Comedy also implied that <strong>Liszt</strong> sawhimself as having earlier wan<strong>de</strong>red down thewrong path: “Nel mezzo <strong>de</strong>l cammin di nostravita / mi ritrovai per una selva oscura, / che ladiritta via era smarrita” (Midway in the journeyof our life / I found myself within a darkforest, / for the straight way was lost.) By quotingthe first line, <strong>Liszt</strong> (who at thirty-five hadgiven his final public concert at Elisavetgrad inSeptember 1847) drew a parallel with Dantemarking his thirty-fifth year in A.D. 1300—the“midpoint” in life’s biblically allotted span aswell as the beginning of Dante’s divine awakening.Yet the strange logic of <strong>Liszt</strong>’s poeticallusion gives us pause. The vision of the unfetteredbutterfly clashes with Dante’s midlifeepiphany, since the butterfly lives for only afew weeks after months of gestation. In<strong>de</strong>ed,the butterfly’s flight is a traditional symbol ofthe soul’s flight after <strong>de</strong>ath, hence <strong>Liszt</strong>’s latemetamorphosis suggests a valedictory coup <strong>de</strong>théâtre—an incongruity not untypical of whatLawrence Kramer dubbed a virtuoso “riddledwith ambivalence.” 3St<strong>and</strong>ing at the crossroads between the rolesof virtuoso <strong>and</strong> composer, <strong>Liszt</strong> in his lettersexpressed this ambivalence most acutely in hisreflections on Werktreue. On the one h<strong>and</strong>, he2“Was sollte euch gelingen, wolltet ihr’ ihm [the virtuosoin a concert hall] es nachthum? Ein schnö<strong>de</strong>r Purzelbaum,nichts An<strong>de</strong>res” (Richard Wagner, “Der Virtuos und <strong>de</strong>rKünstler,” Gesammelte Schriften und Dichtungen von RichardWagner, vol. 1 [Leipzig: E. W. Fritzsch, 1871/1880],p. 212). The essay title’s pejorative distinction implicitly<strong>de</strong>nies “artistic” stature to the virtuosity that <strong>Liszt</strong> representedin 1841. At the time, <strong>Liszt</strong> was reaping praise fromthe Berlin press amid the popular frenzy associated withHeine’s 1844 catchphrase: “<strong>Liszt</strong>omania.”3Lawrence Kramer, Musical Meaning: Toward a CriticalHistory (Berkeley: University of California Press, 2002), p.69.donned the garb of the penitent performer,claiming publicly in 1837: “I even went so faras to add a host of rapid runs <strong>and</strong> ca<strong>de</strong>nzas. . . .You cannot believe . . . how I <strong>de</strong>plore thoseconcessions to bad taste, those sacrilegious violationsof the SPIRIT <strong>and</strong> the LETTER.” 4 Onthe other h<strong>and</strong>, the virtuoso’s blood continuedto run in <strong>Liszt</strong>’s veins, leading him to <strong>de</strong>clareas late as 1853 that “the letter killeth the spirit,a thing to which I will never subscribe, howeverspecious in their hypocritical impartialitymay be the attacks to which I am exposed.” 5As Susan Bernstein has argued, historical conceptsof virtuosity are <strong>de</strong>fined by such contradictions,which can account equally for tawdrypyrotechnics <strong>and</strong> transcen<strong>de</strong>ntal expression:“[<strong>Liszt</strong>’s] consistent inconsistency forms thevery consistency of the virtuoso—an inconsistency<strong>de</strong>termined by the oscillation betweenegoistic protrusion <strong>and</strong> transmissive self-effacement.”6 This fluidity illuminates <strong>Liszt</strong>’sstruggle to change his artistic i<strong>de</strong>ntity on the4From <strong>Liszt</strong>, Lettres d’un bachelier ès musique; <strong>Liszt</strong> toGeorge S<strong>and</strong>, Paris, 12 February 1837, Gazette musicale,pp. 53–56. Quoted <strong>and</strong> translated in Charles Suttoni, AnArtist’s Journey: Lettres d’un bachelier ès musique 1835–1841 (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1989), pp. 17–18.5This second complaint concerned time, accentuation, <strong>and</strong>rhythm in Beethoven’s late style. <strong>Liszt</strong> is responding tocriticism of his conducting during the Calsruhe Festival of1853, explaining to Richard Pohl that “in many cases eventhe rough, literal maintenance of the time <strong>and</strong> of eachcontinuous measure | 1, 2, 3, 4, | 1, 2, 3, 4, | clashes withthe sense <strong>and</strong> expression.” <strong>Liszt</strong> to Richard Pohl, 1 August1853, in The Letters of Franz <strong>Liszt</strong>, ed. La Mara, trans. C.Bache (2 vols., London: H. Grevel, 1894), I, 175–76. Whiletoying with tempo is surely a lesser “infi<strong>de</strong>lity” than activelyembellishing a given text, concert reviews from the1840s continued to record <strong>Liszt</strong>’s “<strong>de</strong>liciously fanciful amplifications”(Franz <strong>Liszt</strong> Selected Letters, p. 136)—actsexemplifying his later dictum that “virtuosity is not asubmissive h<strong>and</strong>mai<strong>de</strong>n to the composition.” The latterremark appears in <strong>Liszt</strong>’s essay on Clara Schumann [1855];see Gesammelte Schriften von Franz <strong>Liszt</strong>, ed. LinaRamann (Leipzig: Breitkopf <strong>and</strong> Härtel, 1881–99), vol. IV(1882), p. 193. See also <strong>Liszt</strong>’s assertion in The Gypsy inMusic [1859] that the virtuoso is not merely a passivepurveyor of an extant creation, a conscientious <strong>and</strong> precise“mason,” but the sole means of accessing a world of feelingto which the work is only a window. The Gypsy inMusic, trans. Edwin Evans, 2 vols. (London: W. Reeves,1926), II, 267.6Susan Bernstein, <strong>Virtuosity</strong> of the Nineteenth Century:Performing Music <strong>and</strong> Language in Heine, <strong>Liszt</strong>, <strong>and</strong>Bau<strong>de</strong>laire (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1998), p.112.DAVIDTRIPPETT<strong>Virtuosity</strong> inthe “Dante”Sonata53


19THCENTURYMUSICroad to Weimar amid the “most intense periodof anti-virtuosity backlash in the history ofinstrumental music,” 7 which in turn gave riseto a “strengthening forcefield between virtuosity<strong>and</strong> the work.” 8 If <strong>Liszt</strong> compared thevirtuoso’s career with a caterpillar’s confinement,did this disqualify “virtuosity” per se orwas it merely a response to public criticism?The comparison prompts another question thatcritics of many stripes have asked of authorshipwithin text- <strong>and</strong> score-based criticism:Who is speaking? 9 <strong>Liszt</strong>’s liquidation of hisperformer’s “self” testifies to his <strong>de</strong>sire to managehis public i<strong>de</strong>ntity strategically, to narratehis own story in a self-styled Künstlerroman,<strong>and</strong> thus to both publicize <strong>and</strong> legitimize hisnew i<strong>de</strong>ntity as a composer <strong>and</strong> ex-virtuoso. 10But as he entered into the service of a patronfor the first time in his professional career—not exactly the unfettered freedom of a butterfly—didthis transformation <strong>une</strong>quivocally representa <strong>de</strong>dicated commitment to a new causeor did it arise, at least in part, from his anxietyover the diminishing status of the virtuoso?In this article I would like to consi<strong>de</strong>r thesequestions in light of <strong>Liszt</strong>’s <strong>Après</strong> <strong>une</strong> lecturedu Dante: Fantasie quasi Sonata. Written between1839 <strong>and</strong> 1858, the Sonata survives inthree full manuscripts <strong>and</strong> four fragments <strong>and</strong>,I contend, interweaves hours <strong>and</strong> hours of improvisationwith a gradual process of revisionon a more abstracted, conceptual level. As apiece born expressly from acts of performance,the Sonata appears not to be regulated exclusivelyby the i<strong>de</strong>a that a work is an enduring,7Dana Gooley, The Virtuoso <strong>Liszt</strong> (Cambridge: CambridgeUniversity Press, 2004), p. 13. As Gooley observes, an antivirtuosostance was propoun<strong>de</strong>d by both Schumann’s NeueZeitschrift <strong>and</strong> Schlesinger’s Revue et Gazette musicale.8Jim Samson, <strong>Virtuosity</strong> <strong>and</strong> the Musical Work (Cambridge:Cambridge University Press, 2003), p. 74.9To cite two notable examples: Edward T. Cone, TheComposer’s Voice (Berkeley: University of California Press,1974), p. 1; Rol<strong>and</strong> Barthes, “The Death of the Author,” inImage—Music—Text, trans. Stephen Heath (Glasgow:Fontana/Collins, 1977), pp. 142–49.10Within the European press, <strong>Liszt</strong>’s compound nationalities,mobile class status, <strong>and</strong> musical competencies wereall <strong>de</strong>bated among writers <strong>and</strong> listeners as part of whatincreasingly became an unstable <strong>and</strong> over-<strong>de</strong>termined publici<strong>de</strong>ntity. See Gooley’s discussion of the multiple symbolici<strong>de</strong>ntities that <strong>Liszt</strong> fulfilled for his audiences in TheVirtuoso <strong>Liszt</strong>, pp. 2ff.immutable product. It thus subverts what CarolynAbbate calls the “performance network” inwhich performers more or less obey the centripetalforce of a “composed” work. 11 <strong>Liszt</strong>’spredisposition toward virtuosity ensured thatcertain musical i<strong>de</strong>as came to him through improvisationrather than prior to it. At first blushthis seems unsurprising, yet it nevertheless presentsa problem for the i<strong>de</strong>ology of a workconcept that separates <strong>Liszt</strong> hierarchicallyinto pianist <strong>and</strong> composer. In contrast to contemporarieslike Felix Men<strong>de</strong>lssohn or RobertSchumann, <strong>Liszt</strong> in his virtuosity continuallychallenges the aesthetic boundaries of composition,improvisation, <strong>and</strong> performance.Such categories imply a distinction betweenmusical thought in the physical immediacy ofimprovisation <strong>and</strong> musical thought in<strong>de</strong>pen<strong>de</strong>ntof physical enactment (even if the composerworks at the piano). But this distinctionappears increasingly weak in light of <strong>Liszt</strong>ianpractices that seemed to recognize a mutuallyinvertible relation between the fingers’ tactilediscovery of i<strong>de</strong>as at the keyboard <strong>and</strong> the cognitiongoverning those fingers <strong>and</strong> i<strong>de</strong>as. SirJohn Russell even reports that Beethoven continuedto improvise “tactilely” as late as 1821<strong>de</strong>spite being almost totally <strong>de</strong>af, 12 <strong>and</strong> in ourown time, research into brain activity has establisheda substantial anatomical overlap betweenexecuting <strong>and</strong> imaging motor tasks. 1311Carolyn Abbate, In Search of Opera (Princeton: PrincetonUniversity Press, 2001), pp. 9ff.12Russell’s account is reproduced in Oscar G. T. Sonneck,Beethoven: Impressions by His Contemporaries (New York:Dover, 1967), pp. 114–16.13Marc Jeannerod, “Neural Simulation of Action: A UnifyingMechanism for Motor Cognition,” NeuroImage 14(2001), 103–09; Marc Jeannerod, V. Frak, “Mental Imagingof Motor Activity in Humans,” Current Opinion in Neurobiology9 (2001), 735–39; M. Lotze, P. Montoya, M. Erb,E. Hulsmann, H. Flor, U. Klose, N. Birbaumer, W. Grodd,“Activation of Cortical <strong>and</strong> Cerebellar Motor Areas duringExecuted <strong>and</strong> Imagined H<strong>and</strong> Movements: An fMRI Study,”Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience 11 (1999), 491–501. Astudy specific to professional pianists suggests that, exceptin the primary sensorimotor area of the left hemisphere<strong>and</strong> the right cerebellum, playing music in one’shead <strong>and</strong> physically playing at the keyboard activate essentiallythe same cortical regions. There is, in other words,“a subliminal activation of the motor system in motorimagery.” See I. G. Meister, T. Krings, H. Foltys, B.Boroojerdi, M. Müller, R. Töpper, A. Thron, “Piano Playingin the Mind—an fMRI Study on Music Imagery <strong>and</strong>Performance in Pianists,” Cognitive Brain Research 1954


Playing <strong>and</strong> imagining music are not as distinctneurologically as they are behaviourally.Nor is this insight confined to mo<strong>de</strong>rn science.Back in 1852, the Berliner Musik-Zeitung Echotreated as an open secret the fact that thekeyboard’s physical properties functioned as acompositional <strong>de</strong>terminant in the improvisationof operatic fantasies: “In the end, we knowonly too well that the piano forms a covertmemory hook [Eselsbrücke], by means of whichmany composers—who are not in a position towrite at the <strong>de</strong>sk—bungle together their operatichack jobs.” 14By softening, if not quite collapsing, the distinctionbetween the physical/tactile <strong>and</strong> mental/imaginaryin music, we might come to regardall composition as “slowed down improvisation.”15 Yet given that these distinctions <strong>de</strong>lineatedcategories of i<strong>de</strong>ntity in press reportsrooted in the twin ascen<strong>de</strong>ncies of virtuosity<strong>and</strong> Werktreue in nineteenth-century Europe,they remain a historical reality. There isthus a corresponding need to maintain a distinctionbetween improvisation <strong>and</strong> composition,the former connoting a performativity inapplicableto concepts of the latter within thesemiotics of the self-contained work. 16(2004), 219–28, here 224. Only the extent of the activationin these regions (measured using functional magnetic resonanceimaging) in two areas specific to physical movement(the primary sensorimotor cortices <strong>and</strong> posterior parietalregions) differentiates imaging <strong>and</strong> executing pianoperformance.14“Wir wissen endlich nur zu gut, daß das Piano dieheimliche Eselsbrücke bil<strong>de</strong>t, mittelst <strong>de</strong>ren vieleComponisten, welche nicht am Pulte zu schreiben imStan<strong>de</strong> sind, ihre Opernsachen zusammenstümpern”(E. K., “Einige Worte über Improvisation,” Berlin Musik-Zeitung Echo 41 [10 Oct. 1852], 323).15Schoenberg famously expressed this opinion in “Brahmsthe Progressive”: “Composition is a kind of slowed downimprovisation; often one cannot write fast enough to keeppace with the torrent of i<strong>de</strong>as” (Komponieren ist eine Artverlangsamte Improvisation; oft kann man nicht schnellgenug schreiben, um mit <strong>de</strong>m Strom <strong>de</strong>r Gedanken Schrittzu halten) (Stil und Gedanke [Frankfurt am Main: S.Fischer, 1976], p. 69).16Beethoven certainly maintained such a distinction in hisadvice to his stu<strong>de</strong>nt, Archduke Rudolph, tasking him withexercises in composition “when sitting at the pianoforte[where] you should jot down your i<strong>de</strong>as in the form ofsketches,” adding later that “you should also composewithout a pianoforte” (Susan Kagan, Archduke Rudolph,Beethoven’s Patron, Pupil, <strong>and</strong> Friend: His Life <strong>and</strong> Music[Stuyvesant: Pendragon Press, 1988], p. 32. Briefwechsel,no.1686).<strong>Liszt</strong>’s position with respect to this distinctionwas in<strong>de</strong>terminate. Not all nineteenthcenturyimprovisation was virtuosic, but <strong>Liszt</strong>’sparticular virtuosity during the 1830s was inherentlyimprovisatory. Its theme-driven,“physical” textures appear to have fed into thegenesis of the “Dante” Sonata in a way thatren<strong>de</strong>rs this particular work a kind of archeologicalsite documenting <strong>Liszt</strong>’s shifting professionali<strong>de</strong>ntity. Although there is a limit towhat we can know about an improvisation withno acoustic trace, <strong>Liszt</strong>’s apparent incorporationof characteristically improvised traits intohis “compositional” process nevertheless embodiesa tension between passionate sentiment,in what Edward Said termed the “extreme occasion”17 of performance, <strong>and</strong> the potential ofironic critique introduced by aesthetic distance.This tension bears witness to a collision between<strong>Liszt</strong>’s twin i<strong>de</strong>ntities as virtuoso <strong>and</strong>composer.Fragments of a FRAGMENT DANTESQUEThe two earliest extant fragments of whatwould become the “Dante” Sonata are in <strong>Liszt</strong>’sh<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> can be dated within a few months ofhis first-documented performance of it (25 October1839). They capture two characteristicmusical elements that he would retain—bothmodified—as bookends in the final publishedsonata. The blank staves <strong>and</strong> paper types indicatethat these remarkable sketches were notsurviving shards from a full manuscript; on thecontrary, I would speculate that they were neverinten<strong>de</strong>d to be “complete” for the purposes ofhis performances in 1839–40. Instead, while<strong>Liszt</strong> always conceived of this work as his “composition,”these sketches may well have functionedrespectively as an ai<strong>de</strong>-mémoire <strong>and</strong> asa memento for two essential components ofwhat was initially more akin to an improvisedfree fantasy: a rhetorical introduction <strong>and</strong> aprincipal diatonic thematic progression presentedhere as the fantasy’s coda. In other words,the sketches might be a mnemonic frame for a17Edward Said, “Performance as an Extreme Occasion,”Musical Elaborations (New York: Columbia UniversityPress, 1991), pp. 1–34.DAVIDTRIPPETT<strong>Virtuosity</strong> inthe “Dante”Sonata55


19THCENTURYMUSICplanned improvisation. MS I 18, no.1 (plate 1),ca.1839, presents the opening tritones, whichestablish a <strong>de</strong>monic topic of <strong>de</strong>scent whollyappropriate to the journey into hell that initiallyinspired the artistic conception. 18 Laterrevisions to this passage in manuscripts from1840 to 1858 are cosmetic. 19 Dated 11 March1840, MS 1C.51 (plate 2), a manuscript hithertounconnected to the “Dante” Sonata, shows asketch of the Sonata’s characteristic majorchordprogression written in the Stammbuchof a female admirer in Prague, suggesting that<strong>Liszt</strong> may have performed it there <strong>and</strong>, on request,copied this music after the fact. 20 Curiously,the progression is notated in C whereasit occurs (substantively) in both F ♯ <strong>and</strong> D in theearliest complete manuscript ca.1840 (MS I 76),where it forms the basis of a thematic <strong>and</strong>modal contrast with the main chromatic themein the Sonata’s later versions (compare with ex.6). This discrepancy of key could represent akindly simplification by <strong>Liszt</strong> for an admiringamateur, but it may also suggest a characteristicallyimprovisatory performance in Praguethat was more tonally discursive than MS I 76records.The final version of the Sonata, entitled <strong>Après</strong><strong>une</strong> lecture du Dante—Fantasie quasi Sonata,was first published by Schott in 1858 as theseventh <strong>and</strong> final piece in the second volume(Deuxième Année, Italie) of <strong>Liszt</strong>’s collection18MS I 18, no.1 is in the Goethe- und Schiller-Archiv,Weimar. A transcription of this fragment was first publishedin the Journal of the British <strong>Liszt</strong> Society 28 (2003),34.19See Appendix A for a stemmatological study of theSonata’s extant sources.20<strong>Liszt</strong> wrote to Marie d’Agoult the same day he signed themanuscript (Wednesday, 11 March 1840), explaining thathe had just given his fifth concert in Prague that morning.His comment that “the Bohemian aristocracy . . . havebeen most charming to me. Here, as elsewhere, the womenare on my si<strong>de</strong>,” makes it plausible that the notated chordprogression from the “Dante” Sonata may have been writtenfor a female aristocrat following a performance(L’aristocratie <strong>de</strong> Bohême . . . a été charmantissime pourmoi. Ici comme ailleurs, les femmes sont pour moi). SeeCorrespondance / Franz <strong>Liszt</strong>, Marie d’Agoult, ed. SergeGut <strong>and</strong> Jacqueline Bellas (Paris: Fayard, 2001), p. 551. In1962 a facsimile of this, MS 1C.51, was published in acollection of facsimiles with the text: “Ein Adagio, das<strong>Liszt</strong> einer unbekannten Prager Verehrerin ins Stammbuchschrieb.” See Alexan<strong>de</strong>r Buchner, Franz <strong>Liszt</strong> in Böhmen(Prague: Artia, 1962), p. 83.Années <strong>de</strong> Pèlerinage. 21 All four principalsources for the Sonata are now housed in theGoethe- und Schiller-Archiv in Weimar; 22 the1840 fragment from Prague, plate 2, is in thePrague State Conservatoire. <strong>Liszt</strong>’s original exemplarfor MS I 76 from ca. 1840 is lost, <strong>and</strong> allbut one of the sources from which I have workedare copyist’s versions; all show his corrections,alterations, <strong>and</strong> revisions. By studying thesedocuments, <strong>and</strong> following extensive researchby Rena Mueller into <strong>Liszt</strong>’s manuscripts, Ihave been able to update Sharon Winklhofer’sstudy from 1977 <strong>and</strong> chart the evolution of theSonata from its origins in 1839 as a sketchentitled Fragment dantesque. 23 The genetic <strong>and</strong>stemmatological information is presented inAppendix A (pp. 92–93), <strong>and</strong> Table 1; fig. 1gives a chronology of the copyists in the productionof the known manuscripts.The revisions <strong>and</strong> evi<strong>de</strong>nt preparation ofmanuscripts between 1839 <strong>and</strong> 1840, 1849 <strong>and</strong>21<strong>Liszt</strong> used four different titles in the preparation of hismanuscripts, all of which suggest an explicitly literaryconception: “Fragment dantesque” connotes an unfinishedform that, for Romantic poetry in particular, pointed tothe infinite by its very incompleteness; “Paralipomènes àla Divina Comedia” means material omitted from the bodyof a text, appen<strong>de</strong>d as a supplement; “Prolégomènes à laDivina Comedia” indicates that <strong>Liszt</strong> changed his mind,preferring not to append but to preface his music to areading of the text; “<strong>Après</strong> <strong>une</strong> lecture du Dante: Fantasiequasi Sonata” is <strong>de</strong>rived from Victor Hugo’s poem of almostthe same name from the collection Les Voixintérieures (1837) <strong>and</strong> allowed <strong>Liszt</strong> to characterize hisrelation to Beethoven with the subtitle. <strong>Liszt</strong>’s use of “du”rather than Hugo’s “<strong>de</strong>” in the final title is most likely<strong>de</strong>liberate, drawing on the German practice of using the<strong>de</strong>finite article to refer to a famous person or thing, <strong>and</strong>attempting to translate this into French. In a letter toJoachim Raff from 1 August 1849, <strong>Liszt</strong> refers to his pieceas Fantasia quasi Sonata (Prologomènes [sic] zu DantesGöttlicher Comödie), but this title is not, to my knowledge,recor<strong>de</strong>d in any of the extant manuscripts. Raff’sletter is cited in Sharon Winklhofer, “<strong>Liszt</strong>, Marie d’Agoult<strong>and</strong> the ‘Dante’ Sonata,” this journal 1 (1977), 30.22In chronological or<strong>de</strong>r, these are MSS I 18, no.1; I 18,no.3; I 76; I 17; I 18, no.2; I 137 7 . See Appendix A for anexplanation of the sources, the findings of which are presentedschematically here as fig. 1.23Rena Mueller, <strong>Liszt</strong>’s “Tasso” Sketchbook: Studies inSources <strong>and</strong> Revisions (Michigan: UMI, 1986), pp. 147–54.See also Sharon Winklhofer, <strong>Liszt</strong>’s Sonata in B Minor: AStudy of Autograph Sources <strong>and</strong> Documents (Ph.D. diss.,University of California, Los Angeles, 1978), subsequentlypublished (Ann Arbor: UMI Research Press, 1980), pp. 53–84, <strong>and</strong> Winklhofer’s shorter study of the “Dante” Sonata,“<strong>Liszt</strong>, Marie d’Agoult, <strong>and</strong> the ‘Dante’ Sonata.”56


DAVIDTRIPPETT<strong>Virtuosity</strong> inthe “Dante”SonataPlate 1: <strong>Liszt</strong>’s first sketch for the opening of the “Dante” Sonata, ca. 1839; MS I 18, no. 1.Courtesy of Goethe- und Schiller-Archiv Weimar. Foto: Klassik Stiftung Weimar.57


19THCENTURYMUSICPlate 2: A sketch of the “Dante” Sonata’s diatonic theme, dated 11 March 1840; MS 1C.51.Courtesy of the Prague State Conservatoire Archive.Date / MS / copyist9/1839 —> I-18, n.1 (<strong>Liszt</strong>)3/11/1840 —> IC-51 “Prague fragment” (<strong>Liszt</strong>)ca. 1840 —> I-18, n.3 (<strong>Liszt</strong>)ca. 1840 —> <strong>Liszt</strong>’s exemplar (lost)ca. 1840 —> I-76 (Gaetano Belloni + Adolph Stahr) revised by <strong>Liszt</strong>ca. 1849 —> I-17 (Eduard Henschke) revised by <strong>Liszt</strong>ca. 1853 —> I-18, n.2 (<strong>Liszt</strong>)ca. 1854 —> I-13 7 (Joachim Raff) corrected by <strong>Liszt</strong>ca. 1857 —> Stichvorlage1858 —> Schott’s editionFigure 158


Table 1Transmission of the “Dante” SonataDate Title MS Folia Watermark H<strong>and</strong>DAVIDTRIPPETT<strong>Virtuosity</strong> inthe “Dante”Sonata9/26/1839 Fragment . . . I-18, n.1 - G. Eck <strong>Liszt</strong>3/11/1840 - IC-51 - - <strong>Liszt</strong>ca. 1840 - I-18, n.3 - Blacons/Shield Bellonica. 1840–41 - I-76 3–17 Blacons/Shield Bellonica. 1848–49 Paralipomènes . . . I-76 1–2 G. Eck Stahrca. 1848–49 - I-76 18–22, + collettes G. Eck <strong>Liszt</strong>ca. 7/1849 - I-17 2–23a, 25a-l, 26–31a, 36–37 No watermark Henschkeca. 1851 - I-17 32–35 No watermark <strong>Liszt</strong>ca. 1852 Prolégomènes . . . I-17 1 No watermark Henschke/<strong>Liszt</strong>ca. 1852–53 - I-17 10a, 15a, + 24–25 No watermark <strong>Liszt</strong>ca 1853–54 - I-18, n.2 - No watermark <strong>Liszt</strong>ca. 1853–56 <strong>Après</strong> <strong>une</strong> Lec . . . I-13 7 Complete No watermark Raff1853, <strong>and</strong> ca.1854 <strong>and</strong> 1858 suggest that <strong>Liszt</strong>was working toward publication at three differentstages. 24 Contemporary with the first twostages, a letter to Marie d’Agoult, a concertreview in the Allgemeine Theaterzeitung, <strong>and</strong>a letter from the Hungarian violinist EduardReményi report that <strong>Liszt</strong> performed the workin at least three different versions. 25 Given that24There is no doubt <strong>Liszt</strong> inten<strong>de</strong>d his Fragment dantesqueto be published in late 1840. Writing to the portrait artistHenri Lehmann, <strong>Liszt</strong> asks: “Have I never played you myFragment dantesque? I don’t believe so. I will publish itwilly-nilly at the beginning of Winter with the first of myYears of Pilgrimage” (Vous ai-je jamais joué mon FragmentDantesque? Je ne crois pas. Bon gré mal gré je lepublierai à l’entrée <strong>de</strong> l’hivera avec la première <strong>de</strong> Mesannées <strong>de</strong> pèlerinage). <strong>Liszt</strong> to Lehmann, 20 September1840, Engl<strong>and</strong>, in Une Correspondance romantique: Madamed’Agoult, <strong>Liszt</strong>, Henri Lehmann, ed. Solange Joubert(Paris: Flammarion, 1947), p. 128. Beyond this evi<strong>de</strong>nce,the presence of <strong>Liszt</strong>’s manuscript markings in red crayon—which he ten<strong>de</strong>d to use for final corrections—suggests thepreparation of a publishable version. Only red crayon couldbe seen clearly above the often <strong>de</strong>nsely layered revisionsin pencil or pen.25<strong>Liszt</strong> performed the “Dante” Sonata in different forms atthe Hôtel <strong>de</strong> l’Europe on 25 October 1839, at his fourthmorning concert (of six) in Vienna on 5 December 1839,<strong>and</strong> in Weimar during J<strong>une</strong> 1853, when he performed alater version entitled Prolégomènes à la Divina Commediato Reményi. <strong>Liszt</strong> mentions his private performance toMarie d’Agoult on October 25; see Correspondance / Franz<strong>Liszt</strong>’s own letters make no reference to the1853 performance, it seems likely that althoughhe publicly programmed the Sonata only oncein Vienna, he may have performed it privatelyto Weimar guests on numerous occasions. Thisopens up the possibility that the stages of compositionrepresented in the early manuscriptsmay have been directed less toward the completionof a final, immutable version than towardan evolving collection of musical i<strong>de</strong>as subjectto continual reworking. Composition, at leastwith regard to this music, would thus havebecome an open-en<strong>de</strong>d process of refinement.It is revealing that, for <strong>Liszt</strong>, this was at notime incongruous with his conception of theSonata as a composed work.I will argue that the relation of the two earlyfragmentary sketches to the completed score isanalogous to the relation of <strong>Liszt</strong>’s i<strong>de</strong>ntity as avirtuoso improviser to his i<strong>de</strong>ntity as a com-<strong>Liszt</strong>, Marie d’Agoult, p. 388. Heinrich Adami published areview of <strong>Liszt</strong>’s performance in Allgemeine Theaterzeitung(7 Dec. 1839), 1197. Reményi reports in a letter that <strong>Liszt</strong>played a version of his sonata for him in J<strong>une</strong> 1853: “Thisscribbler allows himself to address a great man—after havingheard . . . la Fantasie d’après Dante, etc.” (Briefehervorrangen<strong>de</strong>r Zeitgenossen an Franz <strong>Liszt</strong>, ed. La Mara[Leipzig: Breitkopf <strong>and</strong> Härtel, 1895], I, 283).59


19THCENTURYMUSICposer. Not surprisingly, the manuscripts forthe “Dante” Sonata indicate that his workingmethods did not alter <strong>de</strong>cisively as <strong>Liszt</strong> assumedhis duties as Kapellmeister in 1848 <strong>and</strong>began to change his goals <strong>and</strong> aspirations aswell as his instrument (from piano to orchestra).When his professional i<strong>de</strong>ntity changed,<strong>Liszt</strong> intensified his revision of the Sonata, revisitingthe work at least twice; but, as I willsuggest, the methods by which he continuallyrecomposed this music remain essentially themethods of a virtuoso improviser, lending thepiece a problematic status within the normativecategories of work <strong>and</strong> improvisation. Wecan extrapolate from this that the various stagesof revision to the “Dante” Sonata—like theletter to Carl Alexan<strong>de</strong>r—document <strong>Liszt</strong>’s <strong>de</strong>sireto exceed the category of virtuoso <strong>and</strong> gainacceptance as a composer within the post-Beethovenian canon.Debating Musical Legitimacy:PHANTASIEREN <strong>and</strong> KOMPONIERENAs a composer, <strong>Liszt</strong> had endured acrimony inthe press ever since 1837, when he lambastedthe music of his rival Sigismond Thalberg as“pretentiously empty <strong>and</strong> mediocre . . . supremelymonotonous <strong>and</strong> therefore supremelyboring” in the Revue et Gazette musicale <strong>de</strong>Paris. 26 At the time, he misjudged the severityof responses this would elicit from the Parisianbeau mon<strong>de</strong>, anticipating Fétis’s vengeful articlewith the throwaway remark to Maried’Agoult that the journalistic ping pong “couldall become very amusing.” 27 Recent studies of26“Prétentleusement vi<strong>de</strong>s et médiocres . . . souverainementmonotone, et partant souverainement ennuyeuse” (<strong>Liszt</strong>,“Revue critique: M. Thalberg.—Gr<strong>and</strong> Fantasie, oeuvre22.—1 er et 2 e Caprices, œuvres 15 et 19,” La Revue etGazette musicale <strong>de</strong> Paris 4 [8 Jan. 1837], 17–20, here 19).27“Cela pourra <strong>de</strong>venir amusant” (<strong>Liszt</strong> to Marie d’Agoult,13 Feb. 1837, Paris, in Correspondance / Franz <strong>Liszt</strong>, Maried’Agoult, p. 265). Fétis’s first response to <strong>Liszt</strong>’s public<strong>de</strong>nigration of Thalberg’s Gran<strong>de</strong> Fantasie, op. 22, appearedin Vert-vert on 16 January 1837. His more exten<strong>de</strong>d, comparativearticle—“MM. Thalberg et <strong>Liszt</strong>”—was publishedin La Revue et Gazette musicale 17 (23 April 1837), pp.135–42. <strong>Liszt</strong> failed to avert a thorny public dialogue byresponding: “A M. le Professeur Fétis,” Revue 20 (14 May1837), 169–72; <strong>and</strong> he was in turn answered by Fétis asecond time: “A monsieur le directeur <strong>de</strong> la Gazette Musicale<strong>de</strong> Paris,” Revue 21 (21 May 1837), 173–75.the <strong>Liszt</strong>-Thalberg rivalry showed the extent towhich <strong>Liszt</strong> had miscalculated, 28 <strong>and</strong> in thislight his appointment a <strong>de</strong>ca<strong>de</strong> later as Hof-Kapellmeister to the court of Weimar can beviewed as a much-nee<strong>de</strong>d public endorsementof his status as a composer through the court’sinstitutional pedigree. Schumann’s oft-citedcomment on the <strong>Liszt</strong> “problem,” however,remains typical in its marking of a disjuncturebetween i<strong>de</strong>ntities: “While [<strong>Liszt</strong>] <strong>de</strong>veloped hispiano playing to an extraordinary <strong>de</strong>gree, thecomposer in him lagged behind; this alwaysleads to disparity [Mißverhältnis], the consequencesof which are felt in his most recentworks.” 29 Charles Rosen articulates the mo<strong>de</strong>rnequivalent of this influential view when hei<strong>de</strong>ntifies a passage from <strong>Liszt</strong>’s tenth HungarianRhapsody as “the zero <strong>de</strong>gree of musicalinvention if we insist that invention must consistof melody, rhythm, harmony, <strong>and</strong> counterpoint.”For Rosen, <strong>Liszt</strong>’s music is “conceivedabsolutely for public performance,” 30 <strong>and</strong> thepersuasiveness of his remarks <strong>de</strong>rives partlyfrom their congruity with <strong>Liszt</strong>’s documente<strong>de</strong>xperience as an improvising <strong>and</strong> embellishingperformer as opposed to a formally trained composer.Back in 1839, Schumann explicitly un<strong>de</strong>rscoredthis point, reminding his Neue Zeitschriftrea<strong>de</strong>rs that <strong>Liszt</strong> had received scantformal instruction in composition. 31 This lack28See Rainer Kleinertz, “Subjektivität und Öffentlichkeit:<strong>Liszt</strong>s Rivalität mit Thalberg und ihre Folgen,” in Derjunge <strong>Liszt</strong>: Referate <strong>de</strong>s 4. Europäischen <strong>Liszt</strong>-Symposions:Wien 1991, ed. Gottfried Scholz (Munich: Musikverlag E.Katzbichler, 1993); Gooley, “<strong>Liszt</strong>, Thalberg <strong>and</strong> the ParisianPublics,” in The Virtuoso <strong>Liszt</strong>, pp. 18–77; ChristopherH. Gibbs, “‘Just Two Words. Enormous Success’:<strong>Liszt</strong>’s 1838 Vienna Concerts,” in Franz <strong>Liszt</strong> <strong>and</strong> HisWorld, ed. Gooley <strong>and</strong> Gibbs (Princeton: Princeton UniversityPress, 2006), pp. 167–230.29“Brachte er [<strong>Liszt</strong>] es nun als Spieler auf eine erstaunlicheHöhe, so war doch <strong>de</strong>r Komponist zurückgeblieben, undhier wird immer ein Mißverhältnis entstehen, das sichauffallend auch bis in seine letzten Werke fortgerächt hat.”Schumann’s comment occurs in his 1839 review of pianoétu<strong>de</strong>s, including <strong>Liszt</strong>’s Étu<strong>de</strong> en douze exercices (op. 1)<strong>and</strong> their recomposition as twelve Gran<strong>de</strong>s étu<strong>de</strong>s. Translationadapted from Schumann, On Music <strong>and</strong> Musicians,trans. Paul Rosenfeld, ed. Konrad Wolff (New York: Pantheon,1946), p. 147.30Charles Rosen, The Romantic Generation (Bath: Fontana,1996), p. 507.31“Zu anhalten<strong>de</strong>n Studien in <strong>de</strong>r Komposition scheint er[<strong>Liszt</strong>] keine Ruhe, vielleicht auch keinen ihm gewachsenenMeister gefun<strong>de</strong>n zu haben; <strong>de</strong>sto mehr studierte er als60


was a leitmotif of <strong>Liszt</strong>’s reception as a composerin the 1830s, a time when he chose not topublicize that, in his teens, he had in fact studiedwith Ferdin<strong>and</strong> Paër, Antonin Reicha, <strong>and</strong>briefly with Salieri. 32Two competing paradigms of artistic creationare concealed here. For Schumann, composing(or improvising) with an innate but unnurturedtalent inevitably produced results inferior tothose of a properly educated mind endowedwith similar artistic gifts. For <strong>Liszt</strong>, real talent(or perhaps just genius) had the power to nurtureitself. While many Romantic composers—Schumann <strong>and</strong> <strong>Liszt</strong> inclu<strong>de</strong>d—sought to cometo terms with the <strong>de</strong>licate relationship betweenlearning <strong>and</strong> inspiration, craft <strong>and</strong> genius, <strong>Liszt</strong>’sartistic credo at this time seems to have beenformed according to a blend of pragmatism <strong>and</strong>i<strong>de</strong>alism. He could no more undo his years ofimprovisatory practice than he could integratea training he never fully absorbed. UnlikeSchumann, therefore, he appears to lean towardthe notion that the fruits of creation inVirtuos” (“Etü<strong>de</strong>n für das Pianoforte,” [1839], rpt. inSchumann, Gesammelte Schriften über Musik und Musikervon Robert Schumann, ed. Martin Kreisig, vol. 1 [5th edn.Leipzig: Breitkopf <strong>and</strong> Härtel, 1914], p. 439).32Gooley’s <strong>de</strong>tailed study of Parisian concert reviews has<strong>de</strong>monstrated that by 1835 the complex textures of <strong>Liszt</strong>’spublished original works—Apparitions, the Harmoniespoétiques et réligieuses, <strong>and</strong> the Clochette fantasy—hadonly served to convince audiences that, in spite of receivingwi<strong>de</strong> acclaim as a pianist, he was in fact a <strong>de</strong>ficientcomposer. See Gooley, The Virtuoso <strong>Liszt</strong>, p. 24. See alsoDieter Torkewitz discussion of G. Schilling’s article of1836 in “Die Erfassung <strong>de</strong>r ‘Harmonies poétiques etréligieuses’ von <strong>Liszt</strong>,” <strong>Liszt</strong> Studien II (Munich: EmilKatzbichler, 1981), p. 228.Joseph d’Ortigue’s early biography of <strong>Liszt</strong> (in the Gazettemusicale <strong>de</strong> Paris from 14 J<strong>une</strong> 1835) downplays thesignificance of <strong>Liszt</strong>’s music teachers with witheringdismissiveness: <strong>Liszt</strong> was “humiliated to find himself treatedlike a school boy <strong>and</strong> . . . took a dislike to [Czerny, thoughlater recognized his] tact <strong>and</strong> personality”; he studied only“clefs [<strong>and</strong>] religious music” with Salieri, <strong>and</strong> later on, just“counterpoint” with Reicha. No further elaboration or gratitu<strong>de</strong>is given to <strong>Liszt</strong>’s music pedagogues, <strong>and</strong>, if anything,d’Ortigue emphasizes the autodidactic aspects of the boy’sschooling. See “Joseph d’Ortigue: Franz <strong>Liszt</strong>,” trans. VincentGiroud, in <strong>Liszt</strong> <strong>and</strong> His World, pp. 313–15. The extent towhich this may be creative self-fashioning on <strong>Liszt</strong>’s part is<strong>de</strong>batable, but as Benjamin Walton points out, both ofd’Ortigue’s earlier biographies of musician friends (Berlioz,George Onslow) had used material “supplied directly bytheir subjects. . . . It is not unreasonable to suppose thatsomething similar happened [with <strong>Liszt</strong>]” (Walton, “TheFirst Biography: Joseph d’Ortigue on Franz <strong>Liszt</strong> at AgeTwenty-Three,” in <strong>Liszt</strong> <strong>and</strong> His World, p. 305).the instant of inspiration, unmediated by criticalreflection—whether in the exten<strong>de</strong>d formof methodical study or the momentary form ofabstraction from improvisation—would surpassthe “mediated” efforts of more schooled composers.33In opposing critical self-reflection, <strong>Liszt</strong>’sview resonates with a distinguished Romantictradition of subliminal artistic invention, fromShelley, who in his Defense of Poetry (1840)observed: “The mind in creation is as a fadingcoal, which some invisible influence, like aninconstant wind, awakens to transitory brightness.. . . When composition begins, inspirationis already on the <strong>de</strong>cline, <strong>and</strong> the most gloriouspoetry that has ever been communicated to theworld is probably a feeble shadow of the originalconceptions of the poet.” 34 To Schopenhauer,for whom “the sketches of great mastersare often more effective than their finishedpaintings . . . the work done at one stroke . . .[is] perfected in the inspiration of the first conception<strong>and</strong> drawn unconsciously as it were;likewise the melody that comes entirely withoutreflection <strong>and</strong> wholly as if by inspiration. . . [has] the great merit of . . . free impulse ofgenius, without any admixture of <strong>de</strong>liberation.”35Writing from a pedagogical perspective in1841, however, A. B. Marx ma<strong>de</strong> an antitheticalclaim when he spoke of a creative processthat proceeds conversely from intuitive conceptionto action, Anschauung to Tat. Marximplies that views like Shelley’s were out ofdate, already ossified by the time of what Heinewould call <strong>Liszt</strong>omania:If anyone still <strong>de</strong>sired to return to that old misun<strong>de</strong>rst<strong>and</strong>ingabout the dreamlike unconsciousness of33We may speculate that, for Schumann, education <strong>and</strong>the requisite qualities of a “legitimate” composer musthave been an ambiguous issue. He felt himselfun<strong>de</strong>reducated in comparison with Men<strong>de</strong>lssohn, for example,yet was doubtless aware of Forkel’s claim that J. S.Bach was a “self taught genius.” I am grateful to John Buttfor bringing this observation to my attention.34Percy Bysshe Shelley, Literary <strong>and</strong> Philosophical Criticism,ed. John Shawcross (London: Henry Frow<strong>de</strong>, 1909),p. 153.35Arthur Schopenhauer, “On the Inner Nature of Art,” inPhilosophical Writings, ed. Wolfgang Schirmacher (NewYork: Continuum, 1994), pp. 100, 102.DAVIDTRIPPETT<strong>Virtuosity</strong> inthe “Dante”Sonata61


19THCENTURYMUSICgenial creativity, he would find himself correctednot only by the words of Goethe but by the works<strong>and</strong> words of the musical masters, namely by Mozarthimself—who reveals a remarkably clear consciousnessof his intentions <strong>and</strong> their execution in hisletters. But principally speaking, this consciousnesscan be nothing other than an artistic consciousness,one that sets out from contemplation [Anschauung]<strong>and</strong> leads to action [Tat]. 36Though he later i<strong>de</strong>alized this progressioninto a “completely integral [einheitsvoll] processof contemplation <strong>and</strong> act,” 37 Marx, likeSchumann, regar<strong>de</strong>d a lack of training as thefirst stumbling block for a ragged composersuch as <strong>Liszt</strong>. Not surprisingly, in 1854 Hanslickcodified the necessity of music training as partof a compositional mo<strong>de</strong>l hostile to virtuosoimprovisation, thereby cementing a paradigmfor composition that would increasingly <strong>de</strong>finethe dominant critical aesthetics of the nineteenthcentury. Schumann, too, seemed sympatheticto this trend in 1848 <strong>and</strong> advised astu<strong>de</strong>nt: “Above all things, persevere in composingmentally, not with the help of the instrument,<strong>and</strong> keep on twisting <strong>and</strong> turning theprincipal melodies about in your head untilyou can say to yourself: ‘Now they will do’.” 38In this view, the authority of historical consciousness<strong>de</strong>feats that of momentary ecstasyin an i<strong>de</strong>alist hierarchy of mind over body: “Thecomposer works slowly <strong>and</strong> intermittently,”Hanslick insisted pace <strong>Liszt</strong>, “forming the musicalartwork . . . for posterity.” 39 Even Wagner,writing to Hanslick about Tannhäuser eightyears earlier, had voiced a similar, historicallyconscious view: “Do not un<strong>de</strong>restimate thepower of reflection; the unconsciously createdwork of art belongs to periods remote from ourown: the work of art of the most advanced36Cited in, <strong>and</strong> adapted from, A. B. Marx, Musical Form inthe Age of Beethoven, trans. Scott Burnham (Cambridge:Cambridge University Press, 1997), p. 19.37Ibid., p. 31.38“Vor Allem beharren Sie dabei, innerlich—nicht mit Hülfe<strong>de</strong>s Instruments—zu erfin<strong>de</strong>n, die melodischen Hauptmotiveim Kopfe so lange zu drehen und zu wen<strong>de</strong>n, bisSie sich sagen können: ‘nun ist es gut’” (Schumann toLudwig Meinardus, 16 September 1848, Dres<strong>de</strong>n, in RobertSchumanns Briefe, ed. Gustav Jansen [2nd edn. Leipzig:Breitkopf <strong>and</strong> Härtel, 1904], p. 289).39Eduard Hanslick, On the Musically Beautiful, trans. an<strong>de</strong>d. Geoffrey Payzant (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1986), p. 49.period of culture can be produced only by aprocess of conscious creation.” 40By following the “outmo<strong>de</strong>d” beliefs ofShelley <strong>and</strong> Schopenhauer, however, <strong>Liszt</strong> inhis early improvisatory fragments <strong>and</strong> free fantasieswould appear—indirectly—to have takenGoethe at his word: Im Anfang war die Tat! 41In a <strong>de</strong>fensive comment on his musical proceduresdating from 1856, <strong>Liszt</strong> explicitly celebratesa musical structure that is sinnlichrather than geistig. Writing to Louis Köhler,who had <strong>de</strong>dicated a treatise on piano playing<strong>and</strong> composition to him, <strong>Liszt</strong> eschews all formalistdogma:However others may judge of these things, [my works]are for me the necessary <strong>de</strong>velopment of my innerexperiences, which have brought me to the convictionthat invention <strong>and</strong> feeling are not so entirelyevil in Art. Certainly you very rightly observe thatthe forms (which are too often changed by quiterespectable people into formulas) “First Subject,Middle Subject, Closing Subject, etc., may very muchgrow into a habit, because they must be so thoroughlynatural, primitive, <strong>and</strong> very easily intelligible.”Without making the slightest objection tothis opinion, I only beg for permission to be allowedto <strong>de</strong>ci<strong>de</strong> upon the forms by the contents, <strong>and</strong> evenshould this permission be withheld from me fromthe si<strong>de</strong> of the most commendable criticism, I shallnonetheless go on in my own mo<strong>de</strong>st way quitecheerfully. After all, in the end it comes principallyto this—what the i<strong>de</strong>as are, <strong>and</strong> how they are carriedout <strong>and</strong> worked up—<strong>and</strong> that leads us always backto the feeling <strong>and</strong> invention, if we would not scramblein the rut of a mere tra<strong>de</strong>. 42The fulcrum on which this comment pivots isthe outward, or let us say readily perceivable,structures of music. In 1856 <strong>Liszt</strong> was thinkingabout these matters in the context of the symphonicpoem: a project of serious composition.But even before this new conception of large-40Wagner to Eduard Hanslick, 1 January 1847, Dres<strong>de</strong>n, inSelected Letters of Richard Wagner, ed. <strong>and</strong> trans. StewartSpencer <strong>and</strong> Barry Millington (New York: W. W. Norton,1988), p. 134.41Goethe’s Faust famously rejects the word, meaning, <strong>and</strong>mental power before stating: “Mir hilft <strong>de</strong>r Geist! Aufeinmal seh’ ich Rat / Und schreibe getrost: Im Anfang wardie Tat” (J. W. von Goethe, Faust, part I).42<strong>Liszt</strong> to Louis Köhler, 9 July 1856, Weimar, in La Mara,Letters of Franz <strong>Liszt</strong>, I, 273–74.62


scale form, the sense of “form” contra “formula”evi<strong>de</strong>ntly sat <strong>une</strong>asily at the intersectionof music criticism <strong>and</strong> composition forboth <strong>Liszt</strong> <strong>and</strong> Schumann. As early as the mid-1830s it also characterized a virulent line ofcriticism leveled at virtuoso improvisers, <strong>and</strong><strong>Liszt</strong>’s belief in the primacy of literature—thatmusical forms should be <strong>de</strong>termined entirelyby their poetic contents—ma<strong>de</strong> him especiallyvulnerable. Carl Gollmick’s 1842 invectiveagainst the “fallen angels” of contemporary virtuosity,for example, seems like a thinly veiledassault on the practices that <strong>Liszt</strong> represented,if not on the man himself. Gollmick’s principalcomplaint was the impossibility of comprehendingimprovised forms with reference to priormo<strong>de</strong>ls:Give us gol<strong>de</strong>n unity in your performance, <strong>and</strong> theintellectual sympathy of any good composition, yetun<strong>de</strong>stroyed, uninterrupted through bizarre, lugubriouspassions or symptoms of world-weariness.Give us—since you are a pianist—once a free Fantasiewith an elegant <strong>and</strong> securely performed fugal themeas our simple fathers did—but what do I hear! Nothingof these? And you’ve been playing for half anhour! For the sake of the book’s good contents Iwant to forgive you the long confused prelu<strong>de</strong>. Butat last give us something. Begin at long last mynoble-min<strong>de</strong>d artist. But how? You have already finished,wiping the sweat from your brow, <strong>and</strong> st<strong>and</strong>up exhausted. You can hardly respond to the barbaricscream with which the mass goes wild aboutyou. Is then the beloved art on the rack for you? . . .the men shout: “God Damn! He is a <strong>de</strong>vil!”—thewomen whisper <strong>de</strong>lightedly: “He is an angel!”—Iagree with the latter. An angel of music—but onewho has fallen! 4343“Gieb uns in <strong>de</strong>inem Vortrage die goldne Einheit, unddie geistige Sympathie irgend einer guten Composition,aber unzerstört, ununterbrochen durch Bizarrien, lugubereLei<strong>de</strong>nschaften o<strong>de</strong>r Weltschmerz-Symptome. Gieb uns—bist du ein Klavierspieler—einmal eine freie Phantasie miteinem elegant und sicher durchgeführten Fugenthema, wiees unsre einfachen Väter taten.—Aber was höre ich! Von<strong>de</strong>m allen nichts? Und du spielst schon eine halbe Stun<strong>de</strong>!Ich will dir die lange bunte Vorre<strong>de</strong> um <strong>de</strong>s guten Inhalts<strong>de</strong>s Buches willen gern verzeihen. Aber gieb uns endlicheinen solchen. Beginne endlich, mein edler Künstler. Dochwie? Du bist schon zu En<strong>de</strong>, wischest dir <strong>de</strong>n Schweiß von<strong>de</strong>r Stirne, und stehst erschöpft auf. Das barbarischeGeschrei, das dir die Menge entgegentobt, kannst du kaumerwie<strong>de</strong>rn vor Ermattung. Wird dir <strong>de</strong>nn die hol<strong>de</strong> Kunstzur Folterbank? . . . Die Männer rufen: ‘God dam! er ist einThe gefallener Engel metaphor is potent notonly for its geistliche connotations <strong>and</strong> its ironicinversion of the infamous adulation of <strong>Liszt</strong> bywomen, but also for its invocation of history. Itsuggests that before the shallow virtuosity of apostlapsarian present there were prelapsarian“artists” (“our simple fathers,” like biblical patriarchs),the paradigm for which is Beethoven.The latter’s celebrated virtuoso improvisationsinvited comparison—evi<strong>de</strong>ntly unflattering onoccasion—with <strong>Liszt</strong>’s, whose efforts Gollmicksought to “<strong>de</strong>monize” in the gr<strong>and</strong> but corruptedform of the fallen angel.Similarly, if more tolerantly, Carl Czerny inhis treatise Systematische Anleitung zum Fantasierenauf <strong>de</strong>m Pianoforte (1829) explains thatif a composed work may be compared to asymmetrical architectural edifice, an improvisedFantasy is like an English gar<strong>de</strong>n: “seeminglyirregular, but full of surprising variety, <strong>and</strong> executed. . . according to a plan.” 44 Yet Czerny isalso pragmatic in emphasizing that the distinctionbetween a “work” <strong>and</strong> an “improvisation”ultimately <strong>de</strong>pends on the listener’s perception:“When the practicing musician possessesthe capability not only of executing at his instrumentthe i<strong>de</strong>as that his inventive power,inspiration, or mood have evoked in him at theinstant of their conception but of so combiningthem that the coherence can have the effect onthe listener of an actual composition—this iswhat is called: Improvising or Extemporizing[Fantasieren. (Improvisieren, Extemporieren.)].”45 Instating the listener as a barometer ofTeufel!’—die Frauen flüstern entzückt: ‘Es ist ein Engel!’—Ich stimme <strong>de</strong>m letztern bei. Ein Engel <strong>de</strong>r Tonkunst,aber—ein gefallener!” (Carl Gollmick, “Das heutigeVirtuosenwesen,” Neue Zeitschrift für Musik 45 [2 Dec.1842], 185).44Carl Czerny, Systematische Anleitung zum Fantasierenauf <strong>de</strong>m Pianoforte, Op. 200 (Vienna: Diabelli, 1829), p. 3;trans. Alice Michell as A Systematic Introduction to Improvisationon the Pianoforte (New York: Longman, 1983),p. 2.45“Wenn <strong>de</strong>r ausüben<strong>de</strong> Tonkünstler die Fähigkeit besitzt,die I<strong>de</strong>ed, welche seine Erfindungsgabe, Begeisterung, o<strong>de</strong>rLa<strong>une</strong> ihm eingiebt, sogleich, im Augenblick <strong>de</strong>sEntstehens, auf seinem Instrument nicht auszuführen,son<strong>de</strong>rn so zu verbin<strong>de</strong>n, dass <strong>de</strong>r Zusammenhang auf <strong>de</strong>nHörer die Wirkung eines eigentlichen Tonstückes habenkann,—so nennt man dieses: Fantasieren. (Improvisieren,Extemporieren)” (Czerny, Systematische Anleitung, p. 3;Michell, A Systematic Introduction, p. 1).DAVIDTRIPPETT<strong>Virtuosity</strong> inthe “Dante”Sonata63


19THCENTURYMUSICformal coherence ascribes the unity of a performancenot to the origin of the performance (atext or a sketch) but to its <strong>de</strong>stination. Thelistener qua <strong>de</strong>stination becomes a space inwhich a dazzling multiplicity of rhetorical effectscan con<strong>de</strong>nse into a “work.” But such awork remains a text without an inscription,irrespective of whether the improvising performer(after Czerny) or the able listener (afterGollmick) is held to be the agent of cohesion. 46With its implicit emphasis on <strong>de</strong>stination,Czerny’s textbook <strong>de</strong>finition expounds a synonymybetween “Fantasieren,” “Improvisieren,”<strong>and</strong> “Extemporieren,” although the lattertwo terms are largely dropped for the remain<strong>de</strong>rof the treatise. 47 While Czerny explainsmethods practicing improvisation in differentstyles, with different types <strong>and</strong> numbers ofthemes, <strong>and</strong> even with different audiences inmind, he offers no discussion of formal organizationexcept as it is <strong>de</strong>termined by the themes<strong>and</strong> their strategically varied appearances. Inother words, Czerny’s emphasis is on the thematicinvention of the moment rather than onany premeditated <strong>de</strong>sign. Of course, this resultedin formal organization of a kind, although“in a much freer form than a written work,” forCzerny emphasized the listener qua <strong>de</strong>stinationby insisting that an improvisation “mustbe fashioned into an organized totality [only] asfar as is necessary to remain comprehensible<strong>and</strong> interesting.” 48In two separate critiques of Czerny’s treatise,Hamburg’s Blätter für Musik und Literaturquestioned whether a “systematic” approachto improvisation might ren<strong>de</strong>r a free Fantasy“only a piece [Musikstück] falling un<strong>de</strong>r the46The mo<strong>de</strong>l for shifting the locus of meaning from originto <strong>de</strong>stination comes from Barthes, “The Death of theAuthor,” which empowers the agency of the rea<strong>de</strong>r postmortem. Barthes, “The Death of the Author,” p. 148.47Like Czerny, Hummel appears to regard “Phantasiren”<strong>and</strong> “Extemporiren” as synonymous in his Clavierschule;although he uses the term “Phantasiren” only in the text,the title of his seventh chapter from volume 3 is given as:“Vom freien Phantasiren. (Extemporiren).” See Hummel,Ausführliche theoretisch-practische Anweisung zumPiano-Forte-Spiel, vol. 3 (Vienna: Tobias Haslinger, 1828),p. 444.48“Obschon in viel freyeren Formen, als eine geschriebene,doch in soweit ein geordnetes Ganzes bil<strong>de</strong>n muss, alsnöting ist, um verständlich und interessant zu bleiben”(Czerny, Systematische Anleitung, p. 3 [Michell, p. 1]).h<strong>and</strong>s ex tempore.” 49 Similarly an anonymousViennese critic drew a distinction betweenImprovisieren/Extemporieren, <strong>and</strong> Phantasieren,arguing that the terms should differentiatethe levels of formal coherence in an improvisation.Whereas Phantasieren was essentially unboundfrom prior conceptions of form, the othertwo expressions: “connote simply the fusion ofinvention <strong>and</strong> formal realization”—that is, theyrelate to recognizably “composed” forms: “Onecan improvise a regular sonata, an overture, astrict fugue etc. This, however, cannot be calleda “Fantasie” by any means.” 50A review of <strong>Liszt</strong>’s earliest public improvisation—datingfrom his tutelage un<strong>de</strong>r Czerny—records a similar differentiation. The elevenyear-old’sViennese <strong>de</strong>but took place on 1 December1822, <strong>and</strong> his concluding “free fantasy”performance at this concert elicited a correctivein the Allgemeine Zeitung: “We shouldprefer to call the fantasy a ‘capriccio,’ for severalthemes united by voluntary passages donot <strong>de</strong>serve that magnificent title, too often49“Und die freie Phantasie ist jetzt nur ein unter <strong>de</strong>nHän<strong>de</strong>n gesetztes Musikstück ex tempore” (Christern,“Vom musikalischen Phantasie,” Blätter für Musik undLiteratur 4 [Oct. 1840], 21–22, here 21).50The full comment reads: “We regard the expressionsFantasieren, <strong>and</strong> subsequently Improvisieren <strong>and</strong>Extemporieren, however, not quite as synonymous as theauthor suggests, rather we hold that the latter two expressionsconnote simply the fusion of invention <strong>and</strong> formalrealization, whereas in the concept of ‘Fantasie’ the powersof the imagination predominate over form so that, inthe latter, the artist immediately lends form to i<strong>de</strong>as whichhis mood, enthusiasm <strong>and</strong> inventiveness have just inspired,<strong>and</strong> he only follows formal requirements in so far as theyare essential for an artistic creation. One can improvise aregular sonata, an overture, a strict fugue etc. This, however,cannot be called a ‘Fantasie’ by any means.” (Wirhalten die Ausdrücke Fantasieren, dann Improvisieren undExtemporieren jedoch nicht so ganz gleichbe<strong>de</strong>utend, wiediess <strong>de</strong>r Verfasser [Czerny] an<strong>de</strong>utet, son<strong>de</strong>rn glauben,daß die bei<strong>de</strong>n letzen Ausdrücke nur das gleichzeitigeZusammentreffen <strong>de</strong>r Erfindung mit <strong>de</strong>r Ausführungbezeichnen, daß aber im Begriffe <strong>de</strong>r Fantasie auch dasVorherrschen <strong>de</strong>r Einbildungskraft über die Form liegt, so,daß in <strong>de</strong>r letzteren <strong>de</strong>r Künstler I<strong>de</strong>en, welche seine La<strong>une</strong>,Begeisterung, und Erfindungsgabe ihm eben eingibt,sogleich ausführet, und die Formen nur soweit beachten,als sie zu einer Kunstleistung <strong>une</strong>rläßlich, sind. Man kanneine regelmäßige Sonate, eine Overtüre, eine strenge Fugeu.s.w. improvisieren. Allein diess nennt man noch keineFantasie.) (“Über die systematische Anleitung zumPhantasieren auf <strong>de</strong>m Pianoforte con Carl Czerny,” Monatbericht<strong>de</strong>r Gesellschaft <strong>de</strong>r Musikfreun<strong>de</strong> <strong>de</strong>s ÖsterreichischenKaiserstaates [1830]).64


misused in our day.” 51 Seven years later, Czernywould categorize the Capriccio as the freest,most humorous form of fantasy-style improvisation:“an arbitrary linking of individual i<strong>de</strong>aswithout any particular <strong>de</strong>velopment, a whimsical<strong>and</strong> swift shifting from one motive to theother without further relationship than thatbestowed by chance.” If <strong>Liszt</strong>’s reviewer had asimilar i<strong>de</strong>a, he was criticizing the boy’s apparentlyun<strong>de</strong>r<strong>de</strong>veloped ability to relate or transformthemes. 52From this we can <strong>de</strong>duce, first, that duringthe 1820s Improvisieren, while not un<strong>de</strong>rstoodto belong exclusively to genre-based musicalcategories, could conjure the formal traits ofrecognizable sonatas <strong>and</strong> other structures publiclyaccepted as musical “works,” <strong>and</strong>, second,that some contemporary musicians differentiatedbetween different kinds of improvisation,the <strong>de</strong>cisive criterion for which was theconstructive element, that is, its form. Phantasieren,specifically, was reserved for the voicingof a momentary muse, a commingling ofinstant <strong>and</strong> i<strong>de</strong>a in a Shelleyan attempt to capturethe fire of creative inspiration. 53 Czerny’sViennese reviewer articulated this i<strong>de</strong>al mostexplicitly: “The powers of the imagination predominateover form so that . . . the artist immediatelylends form to i<strong>de</strong>as which his mood,enthusiasm <strong>and</strong> inventiveness have just inspired,<strong>and</strong> he only follows formal requirementsin so far as they are essential for an artistic51Allgemeine Zeitung (Jan. 1823), cited in Alan Walker,Franz <strong>Liszt</strong>: The Virtuoso Years 1811–1847 (London: Faber,1983), p. 78.52Czerny, Systematische Anleitung, p. 105 (Michell, p. 121).53A small number of nineteenth-century piano compositionspublished un<strong>de</strong>r the title of “Phantasie”—notablyBeethoven’s op. 27 <strong>and</strong> op. 77, Schubert’s Wan<strong>de</strong>rerfantasie<strong>and</strong> “Graz” Fantasia, Hummel’s op. 123, Men<strong>de</strong>lssohn’sop. 28, <strong>and</strong> Schumann’s ops. 12 <strong>and</strong> 17—elevate this pursuitof momentary inspiration to the status of a work.These crafted “improvisations” reverse Czerny’s notion ofan unnotated Improvisation that attains the semblance ofa work by its vestige of formal coherence, for they areworks by virtue of being printed <strong>and</strong> they attain “improvisatory”status through overt compositional artifice. These“Phantasie” works are thus distinct from the more prevalentopera “fantasies” of the period; they can be viewed asdirect outgrowths of the improvisatory tradition un<strong>de</strong>r discussion.By contrast, it seems that almost no pieces werepublished with the title “Improvisation” because any suchimprovisation, if published, would simply have been givenits appropriate formal title—sonata, variations, etc.creation.” 54 Performers could thus distinguishbetween the Phantasieren of a loose-limbed,fantasy-like work distinguished principally bythematic transformation, <strong>and</strong> Improvisieren/Extemporieren distinguished principally by referenceto an established formal mo<strong>de</strong>l.How does this discourse relate to <strong>Liszt</strong>’s practices?In light of the emerging opposition betweenPhantasieren <strong>and</strong> spontaneous form, itis perhaps no coinci<strong>de</strong>nce that Heinrich Adami,writing in Vienna’s Allgemeine Theaterzeitung,called the premiere of <strong>Liszt</strong>’s Fragmentdantesque late in 1839 “something like an improvisation[Improvisation] to which <strong>Liszt</strong> hadfelt inspired after a reading of the ‘divine comedy’.”In contrast to or<strong>de</strong>rly sonata structures,the music was “a collection of colorfully chaotici<strong>de</strong>as chasing each other, often breakingoff quickly, exchanging one mood with another,bold in outline, aphoristic in execution.” 55Within a month of the premiere, a subsequentconcert review in Pressburg <strong>de</strong>scribed <strong>Liszt</strong>’s54“Das Vorherrschen <strong>de</strong>r Einbildungskraft über die Formliegt, so, daß in <strong>de</strong>r letzteren <strong>de</strong>r Künstler I<strong>de</strong>en, welcheseine La<strong>une</strong>, Begeisterung, und Erfindungsgabe ihm ebeneingibt, sogleich ausführet, und die Formen nur soweitbeachten, als sie zu einer Kunstleistung <strong>une</strong>rläßlich, sind”(“Über die systematische Anleitung zum Phantasieren auf<strong>de</strong>m Pianoforte con Carl Czerny,” in Monatbericht <strong>de</strong>rGesellschaft <strong>de</strong>r Musikfreun<strong>de</strong> <strong>de</strong>s ÖsterreichischenKaiserstaates).An article entitled “Vom muskalischen Phantasieren” a<strong>de</strong>ca<strong>de</strong> later argues similarly that fantasy-style improvisationis neither arbitrary passagework nor preconceived form,but draws its character from the performer’s inner imagination<strong>and</strong> is predicated on keyboard mastery: “Die Phantasieerhält ihre Nahrung, ihre Stoffe sowohl durch die äußere alsdurch die innere Anschauung. Bei<strong>de</strong> kann die Poesie inihrem Bereiche wie<strong>de</strong>rgeben; erstere allein, objectiv undohne Symbole, kann nur die bil<strong>de</strong>n<strong>de</strong> Kunst darstellen;letztere bleibt <strong>de</strong>r Musik anheimgegeben. Zum Phantasierenbedarf es also <strong>de</strong>r inneren Anschauung, <strong>de</strong>r lebendigenAufregung <strong>de</strong>s Gemüths zu Gefühlen, Eindrücken undlei<strong>de</strong>nschaftlichen, mehr o<strong>de</strong>r weniger schaften Affecten.Der Künstler, welcher phantasieren will, soll seiner Fertigkeitso sehr Meister sein, daß alle Gradationen und Nüancen <strong>de</strong>rTöne, Melodien und Akkor<strong>de</strong> sich zu bestimmtenEmpfindungs-Ausdrücken run<strong>de</strong>n” (Christern, “Vommusikalischen Phantasie,” Blätter für Musik und Literatur[Oct. 1840], 22).55“Ungefähr wie eine Improvisation, zu welcher sich <strong>Liszt</strong>nach <strong>de</strong>m Durchlesen <strong>de</strong>r ‘göttlichen Komödie’ begeistertgefühlt hatte, ein Aggregat von bunt durcheinan<strong>de</strong>rsagen<strong>de</strong>n I<strong>de</strong>en, oft schnell abbrechend, eine Gemüthstimmungmit <strong>de</strong>r an<strong>de</strong>ren vertauschend, im Entwurfekühn, in <strong>de</strong>r Ausführing aphoristisch” (Heinrich Adami’sreview in the Allgemeine Theaterzeitung [7 Dec. 1839],1197).DAVIDTRIPPETT<strong>Virtuosity</strong> inthe “Dante”Sonata65


19THCENTURYMUSICmost recent compositions similarly: “now <strong>and</strong>then bizarre . . . not without thoroughness, butstill more <strong>de</strong>eply felt than thought, they almostseem more born from the momentarysentiment of the soul, more like one of theFantasies mocking customary bounds than likecalm conception.” Without specifying whetheror not <strong>Liszt</strong> performed his new Fragment inPressburg, the author (“J. R.”) contributes tothe discourse on Phantasieren by referring the“composed” to a calm aesthetic while construing<strong>Liszt</strong>ian “Phantasie” as more fractured, uncontrollable,<strong>and</strong> volatile: “now [these pieces]spread light <strong>and</strong> warmth—now wildly flaringflames—consuming for their own hearth.” 56In his first known private performance ofthe Fragment, given at the Hôtel <strong>de</strong> l’Europe on25 October 1839, <strong>Liszt</strong> boasted that the solelistener “was taken aback” by the experience. 57And as late as the 1887 English premiere of themuch revised final version, performed by <strong>Liszt</strong>’sstu<strong>de</strong>nt Walter Bache, a baffled critic for theMusical Times wrote: “The most conspicuousof <strong>Liszt</strong>’s works was a so-called Fantasia quasiSonata, ‘<strong>Après</strong> <strong>une</strong> lecture <strong>de</strong> [sic] Dante.’ Thisis a most extraordinary composition, of whichit is absolutely impossible to form any i<strong>de</strong>a at afirst hearing . . . we could not trace any <strong>de</strong>finitemeaning in the constant progression of discordsof which the piece is ma<strong>de</strong> up.” 58 In view56The full paragraph reads: “Was die Compositionen diesesmusikalischen Byron [<strong>Liszt</strong>] anbelangt, so sind sie meisteine Mischung <strong>de</strong>s lyrisch-episch und romantischen Styles,doch ist letzterer bei Weitem vorherrschen<strong>de</strong>r,—oft weich—nie weichlich, bisweilen bizarre,—immer großartig,—nichtohne Gründlichkeit, doch noch tiefer gefühlt als gedacht,scheinen sie fast mehr Geburten momentaner Seelenstimmungund einer <strong>de</strong>r gewöhnlichen Schrankenspotten<strong>de</strong>n Phantasie, als ruhiger Konception—sie sind baldLicht und Wärme verbreitend—bald wild auflo<strong>de</strong>rn<strong>de</strong>Flammen,—verzehrend für ihren eignen Herd” (“Correspon<strong>de</strong>nz-Nachrichten:Preussburg, <strong>de</strong>n 23. Dez. 1839”).This is contained in a small collection of thus-far uni<strong>de</strong>ntifiableGerman press articles about <strong>Liszt</strong> between 1838<strong>and</strong> 1847, which are held in the Nationalarchiv <strong>de</strong>r Richard-Wagner-Stiftungin Bayreuth as: II C b 3.57“À midi chez Fanna auquel je [<strong>Liszt</strong>] joue mes nouveauxmorceaux. Il est surprise du Fragment dantesque” (<strong>Liszt</strong> toMarie d’Agoult, 25 Oct. 1839, Venice, in Correspondance/ Franz <strong>Liszt</strong>, Marie d’Agoult, p. 112).58See “Mr. Walter Bache’s Pianoforte Recital,” MusicalTimes 28 (1 March 1887), 154. See also analytical critiquesof the “Dante” Sonata by William Newman, The Sonatasince Beethoven (3rd edn. New York: Norton, 1983), p.369; Wolfgang Dömling, Franz <strong>Liszt</strong> und seine Zeit (Laaber:of these protests against confusion <strong>and</strong> disor<strong>de</strong>r,it is revealing that in his review article of1839 Schumann compared <strong>Liszt</strong>’s compositionalaesthetic unfavorably to that of Chopin, an<strong>de</strong>xplained that the latter “always has structure. . . there always runs the thread of a melody.” 59Similar criticisms were common in this period—evenfrom would-be supporters—<strong>and</strong>some commentators merely assumed that asense of unity had to be <strong>de</strong>termined by thelistener’s ascription of a unified subjectivity tothe performer. Thus in 1838 another Viennesecritic speculated: “The exemplariness of theform leaves something to be wished . . . [<strong>Liszt</strong>]has perhaps not found the time to make hisworks more vocal <strong>and</strong> more comprehensible tothe general public. . . . Perhaps it is simplybecause of his all-powerful subjectivity thatthey are in their perfection only comprehensible<strong>and</strong> playable by him.” 60Laaber-Verlag, 1985), p. 129; Rudolph Kokai, Franz <strong>Liszt</strong>in seinen frühen Klavierwerken (Budapest: Bärenreiter,1969), pp. 13ff.; Humphrey Searle, The Music of <strong>Liszt</strong> (London:Williams & Norgate, 1954), p. 32; Alan Walker, <strong>Liszt</strong>(London: Faber & Faber, 1971), pp. 42–45; Louis Kentner,“Solo Piano Music: 1827–61,” in <strong>Liszt</strong>: The Man <strong>and</strong> HisMusic, ed. Alan Walker (London: Barrie & Jenkins, 1970),pp. 79–133; Derek Watson, <strong>Liszt</strong> (London: Dent & Sons,1989), pp. 247–48.59“Chopin hat doch Formen; unter <strong>de</strong>n wun<strong>de</strong>rlichenGebil<strong>de</strong>n seiner Musik zieht sich doch immer <strong>de</strong>r rosigeFa<strong>de</strong>n einer Melodie fort” (rpt. in Gesammelte Schriftenüber Musik und Musiker von Robert Schumann, p. 440).English trans. Paul Rosenfeld, On Music <strong>and</strong> Musicians,ed. Konrad Wolff (New York: Pantheon, 1946), pp. 147–48.60Carl Tausenau, “<strong>Liszt</strong> und Thalberg,” Allgemeinemusikalische Anzeiger, 7 February 1838; cited in Gooley,The Virtuoso <strong>Liszt</strong>, p. 47. When the twenty-two-year-oldFelix Men<strong>de</strong>lssohn improvised in public, by contrast, theresult was reportedly “as fluent <strong>and</strong> well planned as awritten work,” according to Sir George Macfarren. SeeGeorge Grove, “Men<strong>de</strong>lssohn,” in Dictionary of Music<strong>and</strong> Musicians (1st edn. London: Macmillan, 1882), vol. 2,p. 300. The composer’s correspon<strong>de</strong>nce is peppered withhis complaints of feeling ill at ease at the pressure thisentailed; he once <strong>de</strong>scribed the illusion of creating worksextempore in public as “madness . . . I rarely feel so foolishas when I sat down there to serve up my fantasy to thepublic. . . . It is inappropriate [ein Missbrauch] <strong>and</strong> absurdat the same time” (ein Unsinn . . . Mir ist selten so närrischzu Muthe gewesen, als wenn ich mich da hinsetzte, ummeine Phantasie <strong>de</strong>m Publikum zu produciren . . . es istein Mißbruch, und ein Unsinn zugleich). See FelixMen<strong>de</strong>lssohn Bartholody, Reisebriefe von Felix Men<strong>de</strong>lssohnBartholody aus <strong>de</strong>n Jahren 1830 bis 1832, ed. PaulMen<strong>de</strong>lssohn (Leipzig: Hermann Men<strong>de</strong>lssohn, 1863), p.289. The differing attitu<strong>de</strong>s of <strong>Liszt</strong> <strong>and</strong> Men<strong>de</strong>lssohn toimprovisation are surely idiosyncratic to an extent, but66


The broa<strong>de</strong>r reception of <strong>Liszt</strong>’s virtuosity ascomposition in the 1840s was equally equivocal.Critics were troubled by the discrepancybetween his aspirations <strong>and</strong> his compositionalabilities, between harmonic experimentation<strong>and</strong> formal mastery. For a virtuoso improvisationto attain the status of a composition, thecritical <strong>de</strong>finition of a “composer” would havehad to exp<strong>and</strong> to accommodate the <strong>de</strong>liberateintroduction of musical instabilities. It wasprobably for this very reason that Schumann,referring globally to the practice of virtuosoextempore playing, cautioned Clara Wieckagainst improvising too frequently just a yearbefore he diagnosed <strong>Liszt</strong>’s unhappy “disparity.”Phantasieren uses up too much creativeenergy, Schumann protested, which could bebetter employed otherwise: “be sure to writeeverything down immediately.” 61 The loss ofwritten music that improvisation entails wenth<strong>and</strong> in h<strong>and</strong> with an emergent conception ofcomposition as a largely documentary, monumentalen<strong>de</strong>avor. Schumann’s fear of creative<strong>de</strong>pletion speaks to the growing anomaly of ayoung virtuoso whose compositional “output”seemed to transgress the hitherto unproblematicboundaries of notation <strong>and</strong> sound. Given thisperceived loss of parity, we may suspect that inobeying “feeling <strong>and</strong> invention,” in seeking toloosen the grip of established musical formulae,<strong>Liszt</strong> the improviser occasionally severe<strong>de</strong>very last “thread” to recognizable forms. Thiseffect has provoked a continuing discourse aboutmusical legitimacy. Bernstein put it memorablyin 1998: “<strong>Liszt</strong> is an error that answers tono correction.” 62nevertheless speak to a psychological division between<strong>Liszt</strong>’s relish of relative imaginative license <strong>and</strong>Men<strong>de</strong>lssohn’s downright fear of exposing the artifice ofextempore forms. What Men<strong>de</strong>lssohn found “inappropriate<strong>and</strong> absurd,” we can surmise, is the stage trick ofcreating musical forms that ought to—<strong>and</strong> might as well—have been pre-formed (i.e., composed). The un<strong>de</strong>rlying distinctionin these firsth<strong>and</strong> accounts is therefore the <strong>de</strong>greeto which Men<strong>de</strong>lssohn’s approach appears to measure extemporeplaying against the expectations of a composedtext; <strong>Liszt</strong>’s perceived weakness was that he did not.61“Nimm Dir immer vor, alles gleich auf das Papier zubrigen” (Schumann to Clara, 3 December 1838, in Robertund Clara Schumann Briefe einer Liebe, ed. Hanns-JosefOrtheil [Königstein: Athenäum, 1982], p. 155).62Bernstein, <strong>Virtuosity</strong> of the Nineteenth Century, p. 109.Views of <strong>Liszt</strong>-as-problem have recently taken a number<strong>Liszt</strong>’s DÉDOUBLEMENT<strong>Liszt</strong>’s letters from the late 1830s show that—in opposition to the task of an éxécutant—he,too, felt the need for “great artistes” to betrained in “the rules of composition,” for themto be well versed “in counterpoint <strong>and</strong> fugue,”(even though he would later reflect that “I wasalways on bad terms with canon. I always remaineda stupid man of feeling”). 63 Yet giventhat he increasingly differentiates between hisown dual i<strong>de</strong>ntities in precisely this way, <strong>Liszt</strong>of forms. The <strong>Liszt</strong> of Bernstein’s “error” runs <strong>de</strong>eper thanan over-<strong>de</strong>termined i<strong>de</strong>ntity allied to amorphous free fantasies,however, for it challenges our very notion of categoricalthought. A corresponding critique can be ma<strong>de</strong> ofSchumann’s categorical distinction between “<strong>Liszt</strong>” thecomposer <strong>and</strong> “<strong>Liszt</strong>” the pianist. The incessantly fluid“confusion of distinctions” Bernstein cites (p. 109) may, inthis instance, be taken equally as a critique of rigid mo<strong>de</strong>sof un<strong>de</strong>rst<strong>and</strong>ing that have difficulty accounting for suchheterogeneity. If <strong>Liszt</strong> is a pianist, then he is also a composer,hence he becomes a hybrid. If we accept what increasinglybecame a hierarchical separation, however, thereseems to be no possibility of fusing the differentiated partsinto the unified subjectivity of one “<strong>Liszt</strong>.” In<strong>de</strong>ed,Alexan<strong>de</strong>r Rehding has even proposed the historical momentat which the public transition between “virtuosocareer” <strong>and</strong> “self-consciously great composer” took place,namely the unveiling of the Beethoven monument at Bonnon 10–13 August 1845. See “Inventing <strong>Liszt</strong>’s Life: EarlyBiography <strong>and</strong> Autobiography,” in The Cambridge Companionto <strong>Liszt</strong>, ed. Kenneth Hamilton (Cambridge: CambridgeUniversity Press, 2005), pp. 14–27. Several critiquesof the “<strong>Liszt</strong> Problem” have been published recently.Bernstein’s “<strong>Liszt</strong>’s Bad Style” addresses <strong>Liszt</strong>’s culturali<strong>de</strong>ntity in the postmo<strong>de</strong>rn present through critiques ofcontemporary writings about <strong>Liszt</strong>, in <strong>Virtuosity</strong> of theNineteenth Century, pp. 109–30; James Deaville’s “<strong>Liszt</strong>in the Twentieth Century” addresses <strong>Liszt</strong>’s precariousposition on the margins of a Western classical mainstreamthrough an examination of writings, research, recordings,<strong>and</strong> film, in The Cambridge Companion to <strong>Liszt</strong>, ed. KennethHamilton (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,2006), pp. 28–56; Gooley’s “<strong>Liszt</strong>, Thalberg, <strong>and</strong> the ParisianPublics” examines the historical over<strong>de</strong>terminationof <strong>Liszt</strong>’s image in the French <strong>and</strong> German press between1834 <strong>and</strong> 1848, in The Virtuoso <strong>Liszt</strong>, pp. 18–77. Of greaterrelevance historically is Béla Bartók’s noted critique of the<strong>Liszt</strong> problem, “<strong>Liszt</strong> zenéje és a mai közönseg,” Népmvel [ü vel] es 6 (1911), 359–62.63<strong>Liszt</strong> to Marie d’Agoult, London, 14 May 1840, inCorrespondance / Franz <strong>Liszt</strong>, Marie d’Agoult, p. 584.<strong>Liszt</strong>’s comment concerns the famous Norwegian violinistOle Bull, whom <strong>Liszt</strong> met in London during 1840 <strong>and</strong>with whom he performed Beethoven’s “Kreutzer” Sonata.Bull evi<strong>de</strong>ntly impressed <strong>Liszt</strong> as a performer, but <strong>Liszt</strong>also notes that he “is a kind of savage, very ignorant ofcounterpoint <strong>and</strong> fugue” (Franz <strong>Liszt</strong>: Selected Letters, pp.137–38). Göllerich, Franz <strong>Liszt</strong> (Berlin: Marquardt, 1908),p. 160.DAVIDTRIPPETT<strong>Virtuosity</strong> inthe “Dante”Sonata67


19THCENTURYMUSICseems to be speaking for a nature divi<strong>de</strong>d againstitself, an ironic nature characterized by selfduplicationor self-multiplication: dédoublement.This splitting <strong>de</strong>scribes the particularpsychology of a retired but not entirely “reformed”virtuoso.In an examination of irony in Bau<strong>de</strong>laire’sessay De l’essence du rire (1855), Paul <strong>de</strong> Manindirectly characterizes <strong>Liszt</strong>’s condition by articulatingthe difference between an intersubjectiverelationship <strong>and</strong> a relationship betweentwo “selves” within a single consciousness—adédoublement such as I argue characterizes<strong>Liszt</strong>’s persona at this time:Within the realm of intersubjectivity one would in<strong>de</strong>edspeak of difference [as between subjects—critic<strong>and</strong> composer or composer <strong>and</strong> listener] in terms ofthe superiority of one subject over another, with allthe implications of will to power, of violence, <strong>and</strong>possession which come into play when a person islaughing at someone else—including the will to educate<strong>and</strong> to improve. But, when the concept of “superiority”is still being used when the self is engagedin a relationship not to other subjects, but to what isprecisely not a self [<strong>Liszt</strong>’s lack of unified i<strong>de</strong>ntity],then the so-called superiority merely <strong>de</strong>signates thedistance constitutive of all acts of reflection. Superiority<strong>and</strong> inferiority then become spatial metaphorsto indicate a discontinuity <strong>and</strong> a plurality of levelswithin a subject that comes to know itself by anincreasing differentiation from what is not. 64By retiring from the stage to pursue a morelofty compositional mission, <strong>Liszt</strong> effectivelyadopted a state of permanent parabasis, 65 bywhich I mean he became the self-consciousnarrator of his own musical en<strong>de</strong>avors, the authorof an exten<strong>de</strong>d self-critique of his earliermusical i<strong>de</strong>ntity in the public eye. This critiquetook the form of the revision of earlierwork as well as original composition <strong>and</strong> abstinencefrom concert tours. But it is not easy todifferentiate between a true authorial voice <strong>and</strong>the persona of a fictional narrator in this selfcritique.<strong>Liszt</strong>’s quixotic assertion to LinaRamann that “my biography is more to be inventedthan to be written after the fact” 66 indicates,perhaps intentionally, a dangerously unstablethreshold between fact <strong>and</strong> fiction.Whether we regard <strong>Liszt</strong>’s renunciation of virtuosityas the expression of an authorial I or afictional character <strong>de</strong>pends on how much sinceritywe ascribe to his shift of i<strong>de</strong>ntity. In thiscase, that means how much mobility we findin his allegiance to the hierarchies of professionalmusical life.This condition of two “selves” within a singleconsciousness allows <strong>Liszt</strong>’s ironic rhetoric toelevate the composer over the virtuoso. Butgiven <strong>Liszt</strong>’s evi<strong>de</strong>nt ambivalence toward virtuosity,a counter impulse might well cry “imposture”to this dichotomy <strong>and</strong> seek an alternativerole reversal of the sort that VladimirJankelevitch <strong>de</strong>scribes sardonically as “insolent”rather than “revolutionary”: “The performerwants to advance on the composer; theone that was first will be second; the one thatwas second wants to live his life. . . . Nothing ischanged. . . . There will again be a thinkinghead, <strong>and</strong> at the service of this head the twoarms of the performer, but the occupiers of theroles have exchanged posts with each other.” 67The fulcrum on which this false dichotomypivots is <strong>Liszt</strong>’s practice of Phantasieren. Forgiven <strong>Liszt</strong>’s well-documented skills as an improviser,just how meaningful can Schumann’srigid distinction between <strong>Liszt</strong>’s performing <strong>and</strong>64See Paul <strong>de</strong> Man, “The Rhetoric of Temporality,” inBlindness <strong>and</strong> Insight (Minneapolis: University of MinnesotaPress, 1983), pp. 212–13. To a certain extent, thispsychology is also evi<strong>de</strong>nt in <strong>Liszt</strong>’s manipulation of hismultiple i<strong>de</strong>ntities during his virtuoso career, as Gooleyhas explained: “<strong>Liszt</strong>’s goals were fundamentally negative.He transformed himself, diversified his affiliations, <strong>and</strong>intervened in the formation of his reputation in reactionto a major crisis in the musical life of his time” (Gooley,The Virtuoso <strong>Liszt</strong>, p. 13).65Schlegel’s <strong>de</strong>finition of irony: “eine permanenteParekbase.” See “Fragment 668,” in Kritische Ausgabe,B<strong>and</strong> 18, Philosophische Lehrjahre (1796–1806), ed. ErnstBehler (Pa<strong>de</strong>rborn: Ferdin<strong>and</strong> Schöningh, 1962), p. 85.66“Meine Biographie ist mehr zu erfin<strong>de</strong>n <strong>de</strong>nn nachzuschreiben”(Ramann, <strong>Liszt</strong>iana: Erinnerungen an Franz<strong>Liszt</strong> in Tagebuchblättern, Briefen und Dokumenten aus<strong>de</strong>n Jahren 1873–1886/87 [Mainz: Schott, 1983], p. 407).67“L’exécutant veut avoir le pas sur le compositeur; celuiqui était premier sera second; celui qui était second veutvivre sa vie . . . rien n’est changé . . . il y aura encore <strong>une</strong>tête pensante, et au service <strong>de</strong> cette tête les <strong>de</strong>ux bras <strong>de</strong>l’exécutant, mais les titulaires <strong>de</strong>s rôles ont permuté l’unavec l’autre” (in Vladimir Jankelevitch, De la Musique auSilence: <strong>Liszt</strong> et la Rhapsodie [Paris: Plon, 1979], pp. 121–22).68


composing be before the latter’s move toWeimar? 68Jankelevitch took this entanglement of action<strong>and</strong> i<strong>de</strong>ntity to its reductio ad absurdumwhen he protested: “It would be necessary tosay that virtuosic music is a music withoutcomposer.” 69 In this abstract reading of keyboardvirtuosity, the “thinking head” controllingthe fingers can belong—in different ways—to either a performer or composer. But if thesefigures occupy the poles of a continuum, thecontinuum is asymmetrical: only the mobilevirtuoso is capable of traversing the span ofpossibilities in either direction, even to thepoint of usurping either pole. Thus the dichotomyof performer <strong>and</strong> composer becomesfalse in the context of <strong>Liszt</strong>ian virtuosity.To what extent does the biographical evi<strong>de</strong>ncesupport the view that <strong>Liszt</strong> himself observed,or at least acted on, this recognition?George S<strong>and</strong>’s diary reports that as a touringvirtuoso <strong>Liszt</strong> wrote his music directly at thepiano. S<strong>and</strong> <strong>de</strong>scribes his labors on a new projectat Nohant in 1837: “Perhaps it is some compositionaltask that he [<strong>Liszt</strong>] tries out in fragmentsat the piano; besi<strong>de</strong> him is his pipe, hisruled paper <strong>and</strong> quill pens. . . . It seems to methat while passing before the piano he must bechurning out these capricious phrases unconsciouslyobedient to his instinct of feeling ratherthan to the labor of reason.” 70 While it is not68By way of historical evi<strong>de</strong>nce for <strong>Liszt</strong>’s improvisations,the journal Le Corsaire, reflecting the typical reception of<strong>Liszt</strong>’s concert etiquette, records that, after listening to atrio for cello, piano, <strong>and</strong> oboe: “<strong>Liszt</strong>’s natural impulsesthen took over, <strong>and</strong> he rushed towards the piano <strong>de</strong>spitehimself, took one of the motifs from the trio just executed,varied it, <strong>and</strong> gave it a new charm . . . every transfixedlistener thought himself transported by a dream into aplace inhabited by the god of harmony.” Thereafter LeCorsaire referred to <strong>Liszt</strong> as the “famous improviser.” SeeMaurice Henri Cecourcelle, La Société académiques <strong>de</strong>senfants d’Apollon (Paris: Schoenewerk & cie, 1881), p.137.69“Il faudrait dire . . . que la musique virtuose est <strong>une</strong>musique sans compositeur” (Jankelevitch, <strong>Liszt</strong> et laRhapsodie, p. 122).70“C’est peut-être un travail <strong>de</strong> composition qu’il essayepar fragments sur le piano; à côté <strong>de</strong> lui est sa pipe, sonpapier réglé et ses plumes . . . Il me semble qu’en passant<strong>de</strong>vant son piano, il doit jeter ces phrases capricieuses àson insu en obéissant à son instinct <strong>de</strong> sentiment plutôtqu’à un travail d’intelligence” (George S<strong>and</strong>, “Entretiensjournaliers,” in Œuvres autobiographiques, ed. GeorgesLubin, 2 vols. [Paris: Gallimard, 1971], II, 981).uncommon for composers to work at, or atleast within reach of, a piano, <strong>Liszt</strong> had honed<strong>and</strong> <strong>de</strong>veloped his instinctive abilities at thekeyboard to the extent that he seemed able toimprovise a passage rapidly on specific musicalmaterial 71 without feeling bound by whatHaydn—in the context of improvisation—hadcalled “the rules of art.” 72 By beginning withphysical performance, <strong>Liszt</strong> could generate animmediate realization of the music, producingmusical passages first as sonic objects ratherthan as intentional objects. This practice mayhave led the “Dante” Sonata—charged by onecritic in 1887, we may recall, as lacking any“<strong>de</strong>finite meaning in the constant progressionof discords”—to fall victim to <strong>Liszt</strong>’s own earliercapacity for Phantasieren. Schumann anticipatedthis situation with sly irony when he71This probably gave <strong>Liszt</strong> the freedom to realize instantlycertain particular textures of harmony, counterpoint,melody, <strong>and</strong> rhythm, or the lack thereof (Rosen’s “zero<strong>de</strong>gree of musical invention”), presenting the sound imageof a virtuoso performance at the point of the music’s inception.At the end of his Clavierschule, Hummel’s commentson improvisation lend cre<strong>de</strong>nce to this view. Aprerequisite for free Phantasieren, he asserts, is that “theh<strong>and</strong>s perform what the mind thinks without constraintregardless of which key the player is in, <strong>and</strong> to be precise,[they] perform without needing to be clearly conscious ofthe mechanical actions” (die Hän<strong>de</strong> ohne Zwang, gleichvielin welcher Tonart sich <strong>de</strong>r Spieler befin<strong>de</strong>t, das ausführen,was <strong>de</strong>r Geist <strong>de</strong>nkt, und zwar es ausführen, ohne dass es<strong>de</strong>s klaren Bewusstseins über diese mechanischenVerrichtungen bedarf). It is precisely this skill that <strong>Liszt</strong>relied on in part—I am suggesting—when “composing” atthe piano during the later 1830s. See Johann NepomukHummel, Ausführliche theoretisch-practische Anweisungzum Piano-Forte-Spiel, vol. 3 (Vienna: Tobias Haslinger,1828), p. 444. For a cultural study of the intersection <strong>and</strong>correspon<strong>de</strong>nces between doctrines of sensation <strong>and</strong> pedagogicalpiano methods in the late eighteenth <strong>and</strong> the earlynineteenth century, see Leslie David Blasius, “The Mechanicsof Sensation <strong>and</strong> the Construction of the RomanticMusical Experience,” in Music Theory in the Age ofRomanticism, ed. Ian Bent (Cambridge: Cambridge UniversityPress, 1996), pp. 3–24.72Reading “rules” as synonymous with “formal procedure”in this context further distinguishes <strong>Liszt</strong>’s attitu<strong>de</strong> tofantasy improvisation from late-eighteenth-century extemporepractice, for which adherence to certain “rules”seemed <strong>de</strong> rigueur. Haydn’s full statement reads: “I satdown, began to improvise, sad or happy according to mymood, serious or trifling. Once I had seized upon an i<strong>de</strong>a,my whole en<strong>de</strong>avor was to <strong>de</strong>velop <strong>and</strong> sustain it in keepingwith the rules of art” (Georg August Griesinger,Biographische Notizen über Joseph Haydn [Leipzig:Breitkopf <strong>and</strong> Härtel, 1810], trans. Vernon Gotwals, Haydn:Two Contemporary Portraits [Madison: University of WisconsinPress, 1963], p. 61).DAVIDTRIPPETT<strong>Virtuosity</strong> inthe “Dante”Sonata69


19THCENTURYMUSIC73“Desto mehr studierte er als Virtuos, wie <strong>de</strong>nn lebhaftemusikalische Naturen <strong>de</strong>n schnellberedten Ton <strong>de</strong>mtrocknen Arbeiten auf <strong>de</strong>m Papier vorziehen” (rpt.Gesammelte Schriften über Musik und Musiker von RobertSchumann, I, 439.74“Denn hier kann er seimen Gedankenflug (obschon ineiner konsequenten Form) volle Freyheit lassen; und oftkommen, während <strong>de</strong>m Spielen ungesucht, interessanteMotive in die Finger . . . Auch kann in dieser Gattung <strong>de</strong>sFantasierens die momentane Stimmung <strong>de</strong>s Spielen (sie seynun lustig, heiterm ernst o<strong>de</strong>r melancholisch) sich amungezwungensten aussprechen” (Carl Czerny: SystematischeAnleitung, p. 63 [Michell, p. 74]).75Franz <strong>Liszt</strong> letter to Louis Köhler, 9 July 1856, in Lettersof Franz <strong>Liszt</strong>, p. 273.said that <strong>Liszt</strong>’s “lively musical nature prefersexpeditiously eloquent tones to dull scoring onpaper.” 73Although S<strong>and</strong>’s testimony rehearses theRomantic cliché of the unconsciously inspiredcomposer, it also i<strong>de</strong>ntifies <strong>Liszt</strong>’s fractured processof composition <strong>and</strong> lends cre<strong>de</strong>nce to thehypothesis that he tried out the phrases onwhich he was working before notating them.Furthermore, S<strong>and</strong> speaks of the governance of<strong>Liszt</strong>’s “composition” by the spontaneous “instinctof feeling” rather than by the calculated“labour of reason”—an observation that, thoughit too is born of a Romantic commonplace,bears a striking resemblance to Czerny’s advicein his treatise for improvising with severalthemes. An improviser, Czerny states, shoul<strong>de</strong>mploy a variety of <strong>de</strong>velopmental procedures:“[for] here he can give free reign to his flights offancy (albeit in rational form); <strong>and</strong> <strong>une</strong>xpected,interesting motives . . . frequently enter thefingers while playing. . . . The performer’s momentarymood (be it now cheerful, now serene,serious or melancholy) can be expressed in themost ab<strong>and</strong>oned manner.” 74 Czerny’s <strong>de</strong>scriptionalso anticipates the procedure of <strong>Liszt</strong>’sthematically driven sonata in striking fashion.If we accept that thematic transformation generatesformal coherence in works such as <strong>Liszt</strong>’s“quasi Sonata,” <strong>and</strong> that this coherence arisesfrom what <strong>Liszt</strong> <strong>de</strong>scribes as the “necessary<strong>de</strong>velopments of . . . inner experiences . . .feeling <strong>and</strong> invention,” 75 it may be that the“compositional” technique of thematic transformationis, at root, a product of an improvisatorytechnique. 76 There thus seems good reasonto trace it back through Czerny to Beethovenin an exten<strong>de</strong>d pedagogical lineage.Czerny’s influence on <strong>Liszt</strong> as a tutor <strong>and</strong>technical taskmaster is well documented, buthis role in the <strong>de</strong>velopment of <strong>Liszt</strong>’s capacityfor free improvisation has attracted less scholarlyattention. 77 Apparently Phantasieren wasintrinsic to their work together. As Czerny recallsin his autobiography: “I en<strong>de</strong>avored toteach [<strong>Liszt</strong>] Phantasieren by frequently givinghim a theme on which to improvise [improvisieren].”78 Equally, <strong>Liszt</strong> mused in his later yearson this aspect of study with his second—<strong>and</strong>last—piano teacher: “[Czerny] ma<strong>de</strong> me sightreadall the good music of the time <strong>and</strong> alsoma<strong>de</strong> me improvise in fantasy-style [Phantasieren]frequently.” 79 There seems little doubt thatthe improvised transformation of musicalthemes characterized the daily contact the twomusicians shared in Vienna over fourteenmonths between 1822 <strong>and</strong> 1823.With this in mind, let us compare <strong>Liszt</strong>’sthematic transformation in the “Dante” Sonata(ex. 1) with Czerny’s illustrated advice76In this context, it is important to note that <strong>Liszt</strong> transcribedBerlioz’s Symphonie fantastique in 1833. AsJonathan Kregor has suggested, his keyboard study ofBerlioz’s idée fixe <strong>and</strong> its accompanimental figures mayhave provi<strong>de</strong>d an additional stimulus for <strong>Liszt</strong>’s explorationof thematic manipulation in the late 1830s. The successof a symphonic mo<strong>de</strong>l based on thematic unity islikely to have given <strong>Liszt</strong> the confi<strong>de</strong>nce <strong>and</strong> impetus toapply what, for him, had been largely an improvisatorytechnique to the i<strong>de</strong>a of more lofty compositional structures.See Kregor, “Collaboration <strong>and</strong> Content in theSymphonie fantastique Transcription,” Journal of Musicology24 (2007), 203.77The only published study is Zsuzanna Domokus’s examinationof “Fantasy” in <strong>Liszt</strong>’s operatic paraphrases. See“Carl Czernys Einfluss Auf Franz <strong>Liszt</strong>: Die Kunst DesPhantasierens,” in <strong>Liszt</strong> Studien IV, ed. Serge Gut (Munich:Katzbichler, 1993), pp. 19–28. For a general survey of improvisationin the nineteenth century, see also Lutz Felbick,“Vom Einfluss <strong>de</strong>r Improvisation auf das mitteleuropäischeMusikleben <strong>de</strong>s 19. Jahrhun<strong>de</strong>rts,” Musik Theorie 20 (2005),166–82.78“Ebenso bestrebte ich mich, ihm [<strong>Liszt</strong>] das Phantasierenanzueignen, in<strong>de</strong>m ich ihm häufig das Thema zum Improvisierenaufgab” (Carl Czerny, Erinnerungen aus meinemLeben, ed. Walter Kolne<strong>de</strong>r [Strasbourg: Éditions P. H.Heitz, 1968], p. 28).79“Er [Czerny] legte mir alle guten Musikalien <strong>de</strong>rdamaligen Zeit à vista vor und ließ mich auch gerne phantasieren”(August Göllerich, Franz <strong>Liszt</strong>, p. 160).70


a.35Presto agitato assai ♯ ♭ ♯ ♭ ♮ ♯ ♮ ♯ ♭ ♯ ♮ ♯ ♮ ♭ ♯ ♮ ♯ ♮ ♭ lamentoso ♯ ♭ ♮ ♯ ♮ ♯ ♮ ♭ ♯ ♭ Example 1: Transformations of the “Dante” Sonata’s principal theme.DAVIDTRIPPETT<strong>Virtuosity</strong> inthe “Dante”Sonatab. ̇ ̇ ̇ ̇ ♮ ̇ ̇ ̇ ♯ ♯ ̇ ♮ ̇ ̇ ♮ ̇ ♮ ̇ ̇ ♯ ♯ ♮ ̇♮ ̇ ̇ ̇ ♯ ̇ ̇ ♮ ♮ ♯ ♮ ̇ ̇ ̇ ♮ ̇ ̇ ̇ ♯ ♯ ♯ ♯ ♯♯ dolcissimo con intimo sentimento ♯ ♯ ♯ ♯ ♯♯ ♯ una corda ̇ ̇ ̇ ̇ ̇157̇ ̇ ̇ ̇ ̇ ̇ ̇ ♯ ♯ ♯ ♮ ♮ ̇ ̇ ̇ ♯ ♯ ♯ ♯ ♮ ♮ dolcissimo con amore ♯ ♯ ♯ ♯ ♯ ♯ una corda 124Andante (quasi improvisato)c.̇più tosto ritenuo e rubato quasi improvisatȯ̇̇̇̇̇̇71


19THCENTURYMUSICd.199 ♭ ♭ ♭ ♭ ♭ ♭ ♭ ♭ ♭ agitato poco a poco cresc.♮ ♯ ♯ ♮ ♯ ♯ ♯ ♭ ♮ ♭ ♭ ♭ ♮ ♭ ♯ ♭ ♯ ♮ ♮ ♭ ♭ ♮ ♭ ♯ ♭ ♯ ♮ 'e.273 ̇ ̇ ♭ ̇ ̇ ̇ ̇ ♭ ̇ ̇♯ ♯ ♯ ♯ lamentoso ♭ ♯ ♯ Tempo rubato e molto ritenuto♮♮ ♯♯ ♮♮ ♭♭ ♯♯ ♭♭ ♮♮ ♭ ♯ ♮ ♯♯f. Allegro Vivace 327♯ ♯ ♯ ♯ ♯ ♯♯ ↓ ♭ff ♭ ♭♯ ♯ ♮ Example 1 (continued) ♮ ♮ ♯ ♯ ' ' '♯ ♮ ' ''''♮ ♯molto appassionato ↑72


Theme ♭ ♭ ♭ ̇̇ ̇ ̇ ̇ ̇ ̇ ♮ ̇̇ ♮ DAVIDTRIPPETT<strong>Virtuosity</strong> inthe “Dante”Sonata“As Allegro”Allegro con brio ♭ ♭ ♭ ̇ ♮ ̇ ̇ff ♭ ♭ ♭ ̇ ̇ ̇ ♭ ♭ ♭ ♮ fḟ♮ ♯ ♭ ♭ ♭ ♮ ̇ ♮ “As Adagio serioso”Adagio serioso ♭ ♭ ♭ ♭ 2 4 ̇ ♭ ♭ ♭ ♭ 2 4 dolce ̇ ̇̇ ̇̇ ̇ ̇ ♮ ♭ ♮ ̇ ̇ ̇̇̇ ̇ ̇ ̇ ̇̇ ̇ ̇ ̇ ̇̇ ̇ etc. ♭ ♭ ♭ ♭ ̇ ♭ ♭ ♭ ♭ ♯ ̇♮ ̇ ♭ ♮ ♭etc.Example 2: Carl Czerny: Systematische Anleitung zumFantasieren auf <strong>de</strong>m Pianoforte, op. 200, example 38.concerning improvisation on a theme (ex. 2).The “Dante” Sonata employs thematic transformationas both an arbiter of form <strong>and</strong> as asource of musical <strong>de</strong>velopment throughout, asmay be illustrated briefly by the episodic recurrencesof the principal chromatic theme in thepublished version from 1858. These transformationsappear to follow closely Czerny’s observationthat “every theme . . . can serve bymeans of several modifications in meter <strong>and</strong>rhythm as . . . [in] all species of compositions”<strong>and</strong> the prescription that follows: “The performermust <strong>de</strong>vote time <strong>and</strong> practice to achievethe capability of transforming each motive thatcomes his way into all . . . styles.” 80 A brief80Michell, A Systematic Introduction, pp. 43, 50. Monothematicphantasieren held specific connotations for a Romantictheory of the creative imagination. In the NeueZeitschrift, an 1839 article on “Phantasie” by the young73


19THCENTURYMUSIC ♭ 6 8 ̇Allegretto graziosȯ ̇ ̇ ♮ dolce ♭ 6 8 ♭ ̇ ♯̇ ♯ ̇ ̇♮ ̇ ̇ ♭“As Allegretto grazioso”“As Rondo”Rondo vivace ♭ ♭ ♭ 2 4 ̇̇ ♮ ↓↓ ↓↓↓↓ ♮ ♮ ↓ ♭ ♭ ♭ 2 ↓↓↓↓↓↓↓↓ ↓4 ↓ ↓ ↓ ↓ ↓ ↓ ♭ ̇ ♯̇ ̇ ♮ ̇ ♭ ̇ ̇↓etc.♭ ♭ ♭̇ ♮ ♯ ♭ ↓↓↓♮ ♭ ♭ ↓↓↓↓↓♭ ↓ ↓ ↓ ↓ ↓ ↓ ↓ ♮ etc.Example 2 (continued)look at Czerny’s written-out examples forFantasy-like Improvisation (Phantasieren) witha single theme makes the likeness clear. AlthoughCzerny’s musical language operateswithin stylistic boundaries such as antece<strong>de</strong>ntconsequentstructures <strong>and</strong> accords with eigh-Königsburg Kapellmeister Eduard Sobolewski cites the infiniteexploration of a single theme/i<strong>de</strong>a as the criticaldifference between artists <strong>and</strong> normal educated citizens:“The reason why [an intelligent person] never learns tocomprehend life [is] that an i<strong>de</strong>a, a small, petty i<strong>de</strong>a issufficient to relieve all the worry <strong>and</strong> trouble of this world./ One i<strong>de</strong>a, often even an i<strong>de</strong>a from an i<strong>de</strong>a, [or] what wemusicians call motive, outline. . . . If one steals everythingfrom [an artist] he nevertheless remains rich” (Das ist dieUrsache, weshalb jener nie das Leben . . . recht begreifenlernt, daß eine I<strong>de</strong>e, eine kleine, winzige I<strong>de</strong>e hinreichendist, ihn all’ <strong>de</strong>r Sorgen und Mühen dieser Welt zu entheben./ Eine I<strong>de</strong>e, ja oft nur eine I<strong>de</strong>e von einer I<strong>de</strong>e, was wirMusiker Motiv, Umriß nennen . . . Raubt ihm alles, erbleibt <strong>de</strong>nnoch reich). See Sobolewski “Phantasie,” NeueZeitschrift für Musik 51 (24 Dec. 1839), 201–03, here 201.Writing in the same journal twenty-three years later,Richard Pohl similarly emphasizes the infinite capacity of74


teenth-century harmonic expectations, his conceptis strikingly similar to the principle behind<strong>Liszt</strong>’s improvisatory thematic transformation.In terms of the ironic relationship betweenthe two halves of <strong>Liszt</strong>’s divi<strong>de</strong>d i<strong>de</strong>ntity, thiskind of improvisation would call into questionthe metamorphic space between composer <strong>and</strong>performer enunciated so explicitly in <strong>Liszt</strong>’sletter to Carl Alexan<strong>de</strong>r in Weimar. For <strong>Liszt</strong>,the performer’s craft was to work themes into acoherent improvisation; the composer’s craft,conversely, was to make themes cohere into animprovisational work. Over <strong>and</strong> above the dialecticor dédoublement between performer <strong>and</strong>composer, <strong>Liszt</strong> the “improvising performer”creates form through what we might call theintuition of “thematic potential,” whereas <strong>Liszt</strong>the composer intuits thematic transformationthrough the creation of form. Any distinctionbetween these actions is one of <strong>de</strong>gree, notkind.A Pedagogical LineageFor <strong>Liszt</strong> in Weimar, the relationship betweenform <strong>and</strong> thematic transformation <strong>de</strong>fined hisconnection with the music of the past. 81 HisPhantasie, hinting at the incessant permutation of figures—geometric, musical—in the context of his survey of earlyacoustic theory: “The imagination follows no other laws butits own; it is limitless <strong>and</strong> unbound, <strong>and</strong> knows neither spacenor time. We gladly let it prevail, we <strong>de</strong>light in its majesticcolors, its wealth of shapes” (Die Phantasie folgt keinenan<strong>de</strong>ren Gesetzen, als ihren eigenen; sie ist schrankenlosund fessellos, und kennt we<strong>de</strong>r Zeit noch Raum. Wir lassensie gern walten, wir lassen uns durch ihrer Farben-Pracht,durch ihren Gestalten-Reichthum entzücken) (Pohl,“Akustische Briefe: Achter Brief,” Neue Zeitschrift für Musik3 [15 July 1853], 25–28, 33–37, 65–67, 73–74, here 26).81The concept of thematic transformation as the arbiter ofform relates directly to <strong>Liszt</strong>’s Weimar reforms. Such aconception was born of a shifting musical syntax in whichthe tonal regulation of greatly expan<strong>de</strong>d musical formsgave some ground to their thematic integration—a processAugust Halm i<strong>de</strong>ntified as a conception of form principallydriven by a theme; or, as he puts it, one in whichform presents “the story of a musical theme.” See AugustHalm, Von zwei Kulturen <strong>de</strong>r Musik (3rd edn. Stuttgart:Ernst Klett, 1947), p. 227. Historically, thematic transformationwas first formulated in relation to <strong>Liszt</strong> by AlfredHeuß in his influential study of <strong>Liszt</strong>’s symphonic poems,“Eine motivisch-thematische Studie über <strong>Liszt</strong>s sinfonischeDichtung ‘Ce qu’on entend sur la montagne’,” Zeitschrift<strong>de</strong>r Internationalen Musikgesellschaft 13 (1911), 10–21.See discussion of the term in Alexan<strong>de</strong>r Rehding, “<strong>Liszt</strong>’sagenda for compositional reform involvedclearly advancing beyond earlier forms so thatit became possible to “discern the stagesthrough which [the new] form was graduallyproduced.” 82 The “Dante” Sonata offers a readyexample, in that <strong>Liszt</strong> symbolically invertedBeethoven’s subtitle for the two Sonatas op. 27,turning “Sonata quasi una Fantasia” into hisown “Fantasia quasi Sonata” <strong>and</strong> thereby establishinga historical lineage for his musicwhile at the same time loosening its ties with aClassical conception of sonata form.In his autobiography, Czerny reports thatBeethoven (his teacher) “was unsurpassed in[the] style of fantasy-like improvisation,” shownin ex. 2, adding that Beethoven “could hardlyreconstruct in writing the wealth of his i<strong>de</strong>as<strong>and</strong> harmonies as well as the nobility <strong>and</strong> consistencyof his most highly artistic <strong>de</strong>velopment.”In perhaps his most revealing commenton Beethoven’s improvisations, however,Czerny distinguishes three different formalstyles:1. The form of a first movement or rondo Finale of aSonata. He would play a normal first section,introducing a second melody, etc., in a relatedkey. In a second section, however, he gave fullrein to his inspiration, while retaining the originalmotive, which he used in all possible ways.Allegros were enlivened by bravura passages, manyof which were even more difficult than thosefound in his sonatas.2. <strong>Free</strong> variation forms somewhat like the ChoralFantasy op. 80 or the choral Finale of the NinthSymphony; both these pieces give a true pictureof his improvising in this manner.3. A mixed form, one i<strong>de</strong>a following the other as ina potpourri, like his Solo Fantasy op. 77. 83Employing an original theme “in all possibleways”—Czerny’s first category—would seemto apply to op. 27, no. 1, where both halves ofMusical Monuments,” this journal 26 (2002), 56, nn. 13,14; <strong>and</strong> Jim Samson, <strong>Virtuosity</strong> <strong>and</strong> the Musical Work, p.217, n.29.82<strong>Liszt</strong>, Sämtliche Schriften, ed. Detlef Altenburg(Wiesba<strong>de</strong>n: Breitkopf <strong>and</strong> Härtel, 1989), V, 34–35.83Czerny, On the Proper Performance of All Beethoven’sWorks for the Piano, ed. Paul Badura-Skoda (Vienna: Universal,1970), p. 15.DAVIDTRIPPETT<strong>Virtuosity</strong> inthe “Dante”Sonata75


19THCENTURYMUSICtechniques (<strong>and</strong> in<strong>de</strong>ed they often have been).For example, whereas Beethoven’s variationform at the end of op. 77 is <strong>de</strong>fined by a generic“style,” <strong>Liszt</strong>’s thematic transformations arenot limited to any particular style (as is evi<strong>de</strong>ntfrom <strong>Liszt</strong>’s <strong>and</strong> Czerny’s use of the procedurein their different musical languages). Furthermore,variation form was a musical genre aswell as a mo<strong>de</strong> of invention. Thematic transformationwas not; it could be a generativeprocess within a variety of forms, includingvariation form, but it belonged to no genre outsi<strong>de</strong>of its improvisatory heritage.Nonetheless, the boundaries between thesemusical procedures can become mobile. AsBeethoven himself observed in a sketch from1809, “Real fantasy-like improvisation[Phantasieren] comes only when we are unconcerned[with] what we play, so—if we want toimprovise in the best, truest manner in public—weshould give ourselves over freely towhat comes to mind.” 86 The correspon<strong>de</strong>nce toCzerny’s advice to “give free reign to [one’s]flights of fancy” 87 is unmistakable. Beethoven’scomment further presages <strong>Liszt</strong>’s belief in theprimacy of “feeling <strong>and</strong> invention” in the creativeprocess. In view of this shared belief, wemay say that in op. 27 Beethoven had writtentwo sonatas, parts of whose form gave the impressionof an improvisation, while in his“Dante” Sonata, <strong>Liszt</strong> improvised—at least initheprincipal theme, a “normal first section,”are reprised in diminution. The section is theninterrupted by a fantasy-like passage (thoughone that does not retain the original motive),after which the main section returns with thetreble <strong>and</strong> bass parts reversed. The Sonata alsoallu<strong>de</strong>s to its slow movement just before thecoda of its finale, a more obviously <strong>Liszt</strong>-likeprocedure.Czerny’s second category—“free variation”—is also relevant to <strong>Liszt</strong> because of the similaritybetween this subgenre of classical variationform <strong>and</strong> the principle of thematic transformation.In his discussion of monothematic improvisation,Czerny likened his own musical examples(ex. 2) to the procedure in Beethoven’sChoral Fantasy, op. 80 (containing fifteen variations),where the piano introduction is probablybased on Beethoven’s own extempore performanceat the premiere on 22 December 1808,<strong>and</strong> in the choral finale of the Ninth Symphony,op. 125 (1824). The two works, Czernyadds, form “two glorious monuments of thisstyle [of Phantasieren].” 84Finally, the great textural <strong>and</strong> melodic varietyin the “mixed form” of op. 77 (containingseven stable variations) would seem to justifyCzerny’s observation that, in Phantasieren,Beethoven “trusted to his genius for the constantinvention of new subjects.” 85 If this <strong>and</strong>the other two works cited by Czerny do in<strong>de</strong>edreflect Beethoven’s style of improvisation on atheme, they offer an analytical basis for comparingBeethoven’s approach to Phantasierenwith that of <strong>Liszt</strong>. Pace Czerny, however, theart of thematic improvisation that his treatisedocuments is qualitatively different from thetechnique of theme <strong>and</strong> variation evi<strong>de</strong>nt inBeethoven’s “Fantasy” works. It is of coursepossible that these later works fail to documentthe thematic transformations that characterizedBeethoven’s actual improvisations(<strong>and</strong> such transformations do occasionally surfacein his other works), but this kind of hypothesismust remain speculative. The transformation<strong>and</strong> the variation of a theme cantherefore be teased apart as separate musical84Michell, A Systematic Introduction, p. 52.85Czerny, On the Proper Performance, p. 58.86This is scribbled on a musical sketch from 1809. I takethis reference from Lewis Lockwood, whose chapter“Beethoven at the Keyboard” explores Beethoven’s extemporepractices. Reports about Beethoven’s improvisationfrequently emphasize the freedom of his musical creativity,<strong>and</strong> while such reports are hardly more than subjectivereinterpretations of an event, their consistent emphasisseems to indicate that established formal structureshad little bearing on Beethoven’s mixed form Phantasieren.For example, Sir John Russell witnessed an improvisationin 1821 wherein Beethoven “gradually . . . forgot everythingelse, <strong>and</strong> ran on during half an hour in a fantasy, in astyle extremely varied, <strong>and</strong> marked, above all, by the mostabrupt transitions” (Beethoven: Impressions by His Contemporaries,ed. O. G. Sonneck [New York: Schirmer, 1926],pp. 115–16; see also pp. 13, 22, 51–52, 208–09). Other contemporaryaccounts of Beethoven’s improvisations inclu<strong>de</strong>Czerny, On the Proper Performance of All Beethoven’sWorks for the Piano, ed. Paul Badura-Skoda (Vienna: Universal,1970); <strong>and</strong> J. G. Prod’homme, “The Baron <strong>de</strong>Trémont: Souvenirs of Beethoven <strong>and</strong> Other Contemporaries,”Musical Quarterly 6 (1920), 366–91.87Michell, A Systematic Introduction, p. 74.76


DAVIDTRIPPETT<strong>Virtuosity</strong> inthe “Dante”SonataPlate 3: Josef Kriehuber’s lithograph of himself with Berlioz, Czerny, <strong>Liszt</strong>, <strong>and</strong> Ernst (1846).Courtesy of the Nationalarchiv <strong>de</strong>r Richard-Wagner-Stiftung, Bayreuth.tially—toward the appearance of a sonata.The subtitles are entirely accurate: what inBeethoven was conceptually Sonata quasi unaFantasia, in <strong>Liszt</strong> became quite literallyFantasie quasi sonata. The titles chart a pedagogicallineage regulated by the practice of thematicimprovisation, partially self-fashioned,<strong>and</strong> aptly stylized in Josef Kriehuber’s lithograph“Matinée bei <strong>Liszt</strong>” from 1846 (plate 3).The lithograph <strong>de</strong>picts the adoring, bespectacledpedagogue looking on—with Hector Berlioz (besi<strong>de</strong>Czerny), Heinrich Wilhelm Ernst (violinin h<strong>and</strong>), <strong>and</strong> Kriehuber himself (left)—as theformer stu<strong>de</strong>nt, playing extempore from a closedscore of Beethoven’s op. 26, seems to be revelingin his inheritance.Improvising Revisions,Revising ImprovisationsCarried out over nineteen years, <strong>Liszt</strong>’s extant<strong>de</strong>letions, recompositions, <strong>and</strong> additions to hisquasi Sonata present a vast complex of documents.Extensive revisions were certainly notatypical for <strong>Liszt</strong>, whose compulsive practicemay well originate with his habit of improvising.But improvisation is often modular, onboth the level of the measure <strong>and</strong> the level ofthe section. It is thus necessary to begin uncoveringthe formulaic fillers, the particular techniquesassociated with transitions, openings,progressions, runs, thematic figuration, <strong>and</strong> soforth that <strong>Liszt</strong> may have <strong>de</strong>veloped betweenthe time of his study with Czerny <strong>and</strong> thevarious stages of composition of the “Dante”Sonata. Whereas some of his revisions havenothing to do with improvisatory practice—forexample, the rebarring <strong>and</strong> consi<strong>de</strong>rable excisionsin MS I 17 that reduce 864 measures to amere 373, or the <strong>de</strong>cision to merge two separatemovements into one—others, such as newtransitions, <strong>and</strong> altered musical figures, oftensuggest a physical relation to the instrument.They indicate a preferred way of moving acrossthe keyboard, associated with the visual aspectof virtuosity, which we may suspect influencedthe sonata’s composition at a level of sensation<strong>and</strong> spectacle anterior to i<strong>de</strong>ation.First, consi<strong>de</strong>r <strong>Liszt</strong>’s transitions. Alteringtransitions between themes provi<strong>de</strong>d <strong>Liszt</strong> with77


19THCENTURYMUSICan opportunity for controlling the rhetoric <strong>and</strong>pacing of the “Dante” Sonata’s thematic transformations.The improvisatory aesthetic of thefollowing examples, with their potential interchangeability(modularity), suggests they mayhave been engen<strong>de</strong>red more by intuition inperformance than by premeditation—Marx’sAnschauung. In other words, some of thesetransitions may have originated at the keyboardwithout <strong>Liszt</strong>’s explicitly intending for them toend up in a composition, but at the moment of“composing,” elements of them were at hisfingertips.The transition between two transformationsof the principal chromatic theme is shown inex. 3a/b <strong>and</strong> summarized schematically in ex.4. There are three versions; the earliest (ex. 3afrom MS I 76 <strong>and</strong> <strong>de</strong>leted in <strong>Liszt</strong>’s h<strong>and</strong>) iseight measures shorter than the other two <strong>and</strong>makes an explicit enharmonic shift between E♭<strong>and</strong> D ♯ in the middle measure, compacting theharmonic movement into one-<strong>and</strong>-a-half measures.The directness <strong>and</strong> brevity of the movesuggest an improvised transition to the extentthat it simply employs chords in different inversions,which, on reflection, <strong>Liszt</strong> exten<strong>de</strong>d<strong>and</strong> composed out.The second version (ex. 3b from MS I 76,which remains extant in the manuscript), likethe first, makes both a registral <strong>and</strong> enharmonicconnection between transition <strong>and</strong> thematictransformation. But it extends the falling chromaticmelody for a further five measures, addsa brief recitative, <strong>and</strong> unfolds the half-diminished-seventhchord through flowing eighthnotes rather than block chords. Here <strong>Liszt</strong> leavesout the dominant-seventh harmony on B, allowingthe lone E♭ to pivot between the twoharmonies by implication. All these measurespoint to a more elaborate musical conception.Yet although they signal an improvisationalprocess more mediated by thought distancedfrom the performative impulse, other elementsin ex. 3b can be seen equally as the result of anongoing process of working out material at thekeyboard. The repetition of m. 3 (as m. 4) coul<strong>de</strong>asily result from the improvisatory practice ofgaining time <strong>and</strong> achieving hypermetric balancequickly <strong>and</strong> easily through a literal repeat,<strong>and</strong> the recitative-like passage is a long-st<strong>and</strong>ingtrick of the tra<strong>de</strong> to “speak extempore”—familiar from C. P. E. Bach’s Fantasias to Beethoven’sop. 110—before launching into anothersection.The final version (MS I 17), also shown in ex.3b, is almost i<strong>de</strong>ntical to the second, but differsfrom it in m. 9 by inverting the ascending chord,breaking the registral connection with themelody, <strong>and</strong> creating a new connection withthe harmonic bass note (C ♯ ). Such revisionsrecall Czerny’s advice that the performer must<strong>de</strong>vote time <strong>and</strong> practice to achieve the capabilityof transforming passages “with ease <strong>and</strong>adroitness. . . . He must not be satisfied with asingle attempt . . . since the modifications inherent. . . are infinite.” 88 Plate 4 shows a facsimilecopy (from MS I 17) documenting thelast two versions.There is also a sense in which revisions, forinstance, the extension of the repeated-notechromatic melody in ex. 3a/b <strong>and</strong> <strong>Liszt</strong>’s <strong>de</strong>cisionfirst to isolate a repeated E♭ , then to integrateit three octaves lower through chromaticvoice-leading, are influenced by a slippage betweenthe visual <strong>and</strong> the auditory. In additionto pure sound, there are the enticing spectacleof rapidly swapping h<strong>and</strong>s <strong>and</strong> the rhetoric of alone h<strong>and</strong>, respectively. Traditions of seeingmusic in this way—a phenomenon Kramer hascalled the “listening gaze” 89 —can constitutethe speed of attack, facial expressions, <strong>and</strong> gesturesof the arms (as well as their absence) aspart of the music being performed. The revisionsto the “Dante” Sonata presented heresuggest that when <strong>Liszt</strong> was revising at thekeyboard his awareness of how physical gestureswould be seen by a listener may also havefunctioned as a <strong>de</strong>terminant of “composition,”thus encoding soundless spectacle into thesounding work.A later section, shown as ex. 5a/b, illustratesthat in revision <strong>Liszt</strong> also ma<strong>de</strong> more substantialalterations to the material of a passage,changing the length of a transition, its use <strong>and</strong>reuse of thematic i<strong>de</strong>as, <strong>and</strong> its relation to furtherthematic transformations. Example 5a encompassesa harmonic move from A♭ to vii 7 on88Ibid., p. 50.89Kramer, Musical Meaning: Toward a Critical Theory, p.77.78


DAVIDTRIPPETT<strong>Virtuosity</strong> inthe “Dante”SonataPlate 4: Facsimile of MS I 17, fol. 21 (transcribed as ex. 3b); GS A 60/I 17.Courtesy of the Goethe- und Schiller-Archiv, Weimer. Foto: Klassik Stiftung Weimar.A, with harmonic motion between A♭ , B, <strong>and</strong> D(<strong>de</strong>noted by the letters A–C in ex. 5a), followedby a stepwise <strong>de</strong>scending whole-tone progressionfrom mm. 13ff., given in diminution startingat m 17. <strong>Liszt</strong>’s revisions to this passage(ex. 5b) incorporate <strong>and</strong> modify the dotted open-79


19THCENTURYMUSICa.MS I 76(<strong>de</strong>leted) ♭ ♭ 4 4 ♯♯ ♮ ♮ ♭ ♭ ♯ ♮ ♮ ♭4 () ♭ ♭ ♯♯ ♯♯ ♯ 2 ♯ ♯♯ ♭ ♭ritenuto languendo ♯♯ ♯♮ ♮♮ ♯ ♮ ♯ ♭♭ ♯ ♯♯ ♯ ♯♯più tasto ritenuto e rubato3♯ ♯♯ ♯ ♯♯ ♯ ♯ ♯ ♯ ♯♯ ̇ ̇ ̇ ̇ ̇ ̇ ̇♮ ♯ ♮̇ dolcissimo con amoreb.MS I 76(revised) ♭ ♭ ♭ ♯ ♭ ♯ ♮ ♮ ♭ ♭ ♭ ♮ ♯3 ♮ ♯ ♯ ♭ ♭ ♮ ♯ ♯ ♭ ♭' ' '♭̇ ♭̇ ♮ ♯ ♮ ♯♮ ♯ ♮ ♯ 5 ♭ ♭ ♮poco rinforz<strong>and</strong>o ♭ ♯ ♮ ♭ ♭ ♭ ♭ ̇♭ Example 380


. (continued) ♭ MS I 17 ♭ 7♭' ♭ ♭ ♮ ♯ ♯ ♭ ♮ 10 ♭ ♭ a piacereAdagiȯ♯[cut directly to m. 11]♯ ♯♯ ♯ ♯♯♯ ♯♯ ♯ ♯♯DAVIDTRIPPETT<strong>Virtuosity</strong> inthe “Dante”SonataMS I 17(revised)11♯ ♯ ♯ ♯ ♯♯ ♯ ♯ ♯ ♯ ♯♯ ♯ ♯ ♯ ♯ ♯♯più tasto ritenuto a rubatȯ ̇ ̇̇ ̇̇ ̇̇♯♮ ♯ ♮ dolcissimo con amore 12♯ ♯ ♯ ♯ ♯♯ ♯ ♯ ♯ ♯ ♯♯ ♯ ♯ ♯ ♯ ♯♯̇ ̇ ̇ ̇ ̇ ̇ ̇̇ ♮ Example 3 (continued) ♭ ♯ ♯ ( )♯ ♯ ♯ ♯ ♯Example 4: Un<strong>de</strong>rlying harmonic motion.81


19THCENTURYMUSICa. MS I 76 (1845–48), <strong>de</strong>noting an early version of the passage in ex. 5b, with correlated letter <strong>de</strong>signations(A–G).Tempo giusto (allegro <strong>de</strong>ciso) ♭ A♭ B♭' ♭' ' ♭' ♯ ♭ ♭ ♭ ♯ ♯ ♯ ♯ ♯ ♯ ♯ ♯ ♯ ♯ ♯ ♯marcatissimo energio assai' ♭♭ ♯♭ ♭♭ ♭ ♭ ♭ ♯ ♮ ♯ ♯ ♯ ♯ ♯ ♯ ♭ ' ' ' ' tremol<strong>and</strong>o' ' ' ' ♯ ♮♯♯ C' ' ♯' ♯ ♮ ♯ ♯ ♯ 'D '' ♯'♮ ♭♯ ♯ ♯ 6'' ' ♯ ♮ ♮ ' ( ) ♮ '' ♯ ♭♮ ♮ 12 'E ♭ ♯ ♯ ♭ 18 ♯♯♯ ♮ F ♯ ♭♭() G♭♭ ♭♭ ♭♭♭ ♭♭ ♭ ♭ ♭♭♭♭ ♭♭ ♭ ♭ ♭♭♭♭ Example 5 ♭♭ ♭ ♭♭♭ ♭♭♭ ♭ ♭ ♯ ♭♭♭ ♭ ♯♯ ♯♯♯♯♯ ♯♯ ♯♯♯♯ ♯ ♯ ♯ ♯ loco♯ ♯ ♯ ♯ ♮ ♯ ♮ ♯ ♮ ♯ ♮ ♯infernale♯ ing tritones of the Sonata, resolving them asperfect intervals <strong>and</strong> elaborating <strong>and</strong> extendingthe passage. The same initial harmonic motionof ex. 5a is stretched over every four measuresrather than every three (again <strong>de</strong>noted by lettersA, B, <strong>and</strong> C); the <strong>de</strong>scending dotted figurefrom the Sonata’s opening again extends over afurther six measures with chromatic left-h<strong>and</strong>octaves over a tonic pedal (letters C <strong>and</strong> D);finally, the same rhythmic diminution of thewhole-tone progression begins a measure earlier(at letter F), which leads to another extensionof the <strong>de</strong>scending dotted figure two measuresafter letter G before the diminished octavesreturn to those of ex. 5a <strong>and</strong> both versionsproceed alike. As with ex. 3a/b, the mo<strong>de</strong>stexpansion in ex. 5b of the un<strong>de</strong>rlying harmonicstructure present in ex. 5a suggests that<strong>Liszt</strong> was gradually composing out an improvisation,incorporating examples of thematic sophisticationsuch as the transformation of theopening motif <strong>and</strong> left-h<strong>and</strong> references to thechromatic octaves of the principal D-minortheme. At the same time, ex. 5b can also be82


. MS I 13 7 (1854), <strong>de</strong>noting the final version of the passage in ex. 5a, with correlated letter <strong>de</strong>signations (A–G).♭↓♭ ↓♭ ♭♭ 4 7 ♭ ̇♭ ̇̇ ♭ ♭ ̇♭ ̇̇ ♭ ff♭♭ ̇̇ ♭ ̇̇ ♭ ↓ ♭B♯♯ ♯ ♯ ♯ ♯ ↓♯ ♯ ♯ ↓♯ ♯↑♯ ♯ ↑A ♯ ♯ ↓ ♯ ♯ ♮ ♯ ♮ più moso♯♯ '̇̇̇̇̇ '♭ ♭↓ ♭ ' ♭ ♭ ̇̇ ̇♯ ̇̇ ̇ ♯ ♯↓ ♭ ' ̇̇ ♭ ↑ ↓ ' ♯ ̇̇♮♮ ' ̇̇♯ ♯ ̇̇♯ ♯ ̇̇ ♯ ♯ ̇̇ C ♯ ♯̇̇ ♯ ♯ ♯ ♭ ♯ ♭ ↓ '↓ ♯ ♭ ♯ ♭ ♯ ↓ ̇̇ ̇̇ ̇ sempre♮♮ ff ♭ ♭ ♯ ♭ ♯ ↓ ♭ ↑ ♭ ̇̇ ♭ '↑♯ ♯♯♯♯♯♯ DAVIDTRIPPETT<strong>Virtuosity</strong> inthe “Dante”Sonata ̇̇̇ ↓ ̇̇ ̇̇'10 ̇̇ 13 ̇̇̇ ̇̇ ↓ ♯ ♯ ↓ ̇ ↓ ̇̇' ̇̇ ↓↓ ↓↓♯♯ ♯♯ ↓̇ ♭♭ ♯♯ ↓ ♯ ♯ ♭ ♮ ♭ ♮ ♯ ↓ ♯ ♭ ♮ ♭ ♮ ♯ ♭ ♭ ♭ ♭ ♯ ♯ E♯♯ D ̇̇ ̇̇ ̇ ♯ ♯ ♯ ♭ ♮ ♮ ♯ ♯ ♯ ♯ ♭ ♮ ♮ ♯ Example 5 (continued)83


19THCENTURYMUSICb. (continued)16 ♭♭ ♮♮♮♮♯♯♯♯♭♭♮♮ 19↓♯ ♯ ♯ 22 24 () ♭ ♭ ♭ ♭ ♭ ♭ ♭ ♮ ♮ ↓♭ ♭ ♯ ♯ ♯ ♯ ♭ ♭ ↓ ♯♯♮↓♯ ↓ ♮ ↓ ↓ ♭ ↓ ♭ ↓ ♯♮ ♮ ♭ ♭♯♯ ♯ ♯ ♯ ♮ ♮ ♭ ♭ ♯ ♮ ♮ ♭♭ ♭♭ ♭ ♭ ♭ ♭ ♭ ♭ ♭ ♭♭ ♭ ♭ ♭ ♭ ♭♭ ♮ ♭ ♭ con strepito♮ ♭ ♭ ♯ ♮ ♭ ♯♯ FG♭ ♭ ♭♭ ♭♭ ♭ ♭ ♭♭ ↑♭♭ ♯ ♯♯♯↑♯ ♯♯ ↓ ♭♭ ♯♯♯♯♭ ♭ ♭♭ ♭♭̇̇ ̇̇♭ ̇̇ ̇̇♭ ♭♭ ♯♯ ♭ ♯ ♮♮ ♯♯ ♯ ♯ ♯♯ ♭ ♭ Example 5 (continued)viewed as an increasingly elaborate improvisationin its patterned chordal <strong>and</strong> octave texturesbetween A <strong>and</strong> C, its reliance on repetition,<strong>and</strong> its recourse to “<strong>de</strong>fault” chromatic ordiminished octaves before moments of harmonicarrival (mm. 5, 8, 12, 15–17, 25). Becausethe relationship between composition-as-improvisation<strong>and</strong> improvisation-as-compositionremains fluid in the “Dante” Sonata, it wouldseem wrong-hea<strong>de</strong>d to i<strong>de</strong>ntify any precise pointat which improvisation “becomes” composition.The in<strong>de</strong>terminacy is wholly in keepingwith <strong>Liszt</strong>’s conception as projected in his finaltitle.Much of <strong>Liszt</strong>’s virtuosity resi<strong>de</strong>s in a worldof exp<strong>and</strong>ing keyboard idioms that have traditionallybelonged to the execution of preexistingmaterial rather than to the thematic-har-monic substance of composition. This i<strong>de</strong>alistdivision becomes increasingly difficult to maintainin the “Dante” Sonata, in part due to thework’s complex genesis. To conceive <strong>Liszt</strong>’spatterning of figures as the scripting of physical,visually virtuosic gestures is to draw attentionto him as the performing agent in contrastto the customary invisibility of a work’s creator.90 The two reports that document <strong>Liszt</strong>90In neat summary of the work-condition un<strong>de</strong>r scrutinyhere, Lydia Goehr writes that composers “should be neitherseen nor heard, to un<strong>de</strong>rscore the mystery both ofabsence <strong>and</strong> of genius.” Continuing this mo<strong>de</strong>l, the statusesof performers <strong>and</strong> audience are to be complementary:“Performers <strong>and</strong> their instruments should be heardbut not seen, but ‘heard’ only as imperfect pointers towardsthe transcen<strong>de</strong>nt. And audiences, to complete thetriad, should be seen but not heard, but ‘seen’ only in the84


sense that each listener being present to grasp the work inthe privacy of his or her own contemplative experience”(Lydia Goehr, The Quest for Voice: Music, Politics, <strong>and</strong>the Limits of Philosophy [Oxford: Oxford University Press,1998], p. 144).91The occasion on which <strong>Liszt</strong> allegedly disguised his playingas Chopin’s was first recor<strong>de</strong>d publicly by CharlesRollinet in Le Temps (1 Sept. 1874), thirty years after thefact. Rollinet’s account was disputed in 1888 by FriedrichNiecks, who reports that the aging <strong>Liszt</strong> <strong>de</strong>clared he hadno recollection of this occasion. Further <strong>de</strong>tails of the disputeare given by Rena Mueller in “The Ramann-<strong>Liszt</strong>Questionnaires,” Franz <strong>Liszt</strong> <strong>and</strong> His World, p. 420, n. 1.In 1837 Berlioz <strong>de</strong>scribes <strong>Liszt</strong>’s invisible performance ofBeethoven’s “Moonlight” Sonata in audiovisual terms: “Itwas the sha<strong>de</strong> of Beethoven himself, his great voice thatwe heard, called forth by the virtuoso” (Journal <strong>de</strong>s Débats,12 March 1837). This anecdote is discussed in relation tothe sonata’s aesthetics of mystery in Lawrence Kramer,“H<strong>and</strong>s On, Lights Off,” from Musical Meaning: Toward aCritical History, p. 37; <strong>and</strong> in relation to Berlioz’s ownaesthetics in Katherine Kolb Reeve, “Primal Scenes:Smithson, Pleyel, <strong>and</strong> <strong>Liszt</strong> in the Eyes of Berlioz,” thisjournal 18 (1995), 228–29.92“Aber man muß das hören und auch sehen, <strong>Liszt</strong> dürftedurchaus nicht hinter <strong>de</strong>n Kulissen spielen; ein großesStück Poesie ginge dadurch verloren” (Neue Zeitschriftfür Musik 12 [1840], 102–03).93The difficult status of such keyboard figures predates<strong>Liszt</strong>’s dédoublement, extending arguably to early-nineteenth-centurypianists including J. N. Hummel, whosekeyboard manuscript for the Concerto in C, op. 34a, forexample, still retained a figured-bass shorth<strong>and</strong> ready forrealization in the moment, leading Joel Sachs to argue thatHummel “conceived of music as the <strong>de</strong>coration of harmonicprogressions” (Joel Sachs, “Johann NepomukHummel,” Grove Music Online, ed. L. Macy, accessed 4J<strong>une</strong> 2007, http://www.grovemusic.com).disappearing entirely behind the musical i<strong>de</strong>ntityof other composers—Chopin, Beethoven—emphasize that he began playing only after extinguishingall c<strong>and</strong>les <strong>and</strong> lamps <strong>and</strong> loweringthe curtains; in total darkness, his auralprosopopoeia reportedly <strong>de</strong>ceived listeners(there were no viewers) to the extent that “itwas impossible not to mistake him [for Chopin];<strong>and</strong> in<strong>de</strong>ed, everyone was mistaken.” 91 (Schumannfamously reinforced the point when herecor<strong>de</strong>d <strong>Liszt</strong>’s own ocular <strong>de</strong>pen<strong>de</strong>ncies in1840: “[if <strong>Liszt</strong>] played behind a screen, a great<strong>de</strong>al of poetry would be lost.” 92 )Hyperbole asi<strong>de</strong>, the visual contingency of<strong>Liszt</strong>’s i<strong>de</strong>ntity would seem to suspend the gesturesassociated with his idiomatic figures in alimbo between professional i<strong>de</strong>ntities: the gesturesdraw the “listening gaze,” yet as inseparablefrom the figures they also contribute tothe thematic substance of a work. 93 <strong>Liszt</strong>’s revisionsillustrate the extent to which his presentationof thematic material <strong>de</strong>pen<strong>de</strong>d onmodular, idiomatic figures. His use of revised<strong>and</strong> reinvented figurations suggests that he wascontinually reworking <strong>and</strong> improvising on different“i<strong>de</strong>al sound images” at the keyboard,resulting in several actualizations, multiple“versions.” Features consi<strong>de</strong>red substantive(structural rather than ornamental) by mainstreamanalysis—harmonic motion, voice-leading,contrapuntal framework, registral disposition—remainunchanged in such revisions, buttheir realization tends to favor the performer’sprerogative to adopt <strong>and</strong> adapt textures to suitthe “momentary mood,” as Czerny put it, or tofollow “feeling <strong>and</strong> invention,” as <strong>Liszt</strong> remarked,in <strong>de</strong>termining “what the i<strong>de</strong>as are,<strong>and</strong> how they are carried out <strong>and</strong> worked up.” 94Because idiomatic figures are by nature irreducibleas patterning components, they operateas basic formal units that can be repeated toform larger paragraphs, which themselves canbe sequentially repeated. 95 In <strong>Liszt</strong>’s case, theinvention <strong>and</strong> constant morphing of figurationsare gui<strong>de</strong>d by a highly <strong>de</strong>veloped intuition forsound images that Rosen calls “the greatest ofany keyboard composer’s between Scarlatti <strong>and</strong>Debussy.” 96 This view can be measured againstthe figural reworking of the F ♯ -major theme(shown in ex. 6), in which <strong>Liszt</strong> revises thetheme’s realization three times with differentfiguration. Although the figural patterns remainrooted in mechanical piano methods, they areemployed in this context to alter the lyricalcharacter of the theme. In a weakening field ofopposition between performer <strong>and</strong> composer,the figures that realize <strong>Liszt</strong>’s theme increas-94<strong>Liszt</strong> to Louis Köhler, 9 July 1856, in Letters of Franz<strong>Liszt</strong>, trans. C. Bache (New York: Charles Scribner’s Sons,1894), I, 274.95See the <strong>de</strong>tailed study of <strong>Liszt</strong>’s figures <strong>and</strong> figurations inJim Samson’s <strong>Virtuosity</strong> <strong>and</strong> the Musical Work. For a studyof figurations at both foreground <strong>and</strong> middleground levels,see Thomas Hitzberger, “Zwischen Tonalität undRationalität: Anmerkungen zur Sequenz- und Figurationstechnik<strong>Liszt</strong>s,” in Virtuosität und Avantgar<strong>de</strong>: Untersuchungenzum Klavierwerk Franz <strong>Liszt</strong> (Mainz: Schott,1988), pp. 32–59; <strong>and</strong> Wilhelm Sei<strong>de</strong>l “Über Figurationsmotivevon Chopin und <strong>Liszt</strong>,” in Report on the InternationalMusicological Society Congress 1972, ed. HenrikGlahn (Copenhagen: Hansen, 1974), pp. 647–51.96Charles Rosen, The Romantic Generation, p. 508.DAVIDTRIPPETT<strong>Virtuosity</strong> inthe “Dante”Sonata85


19THCENTURYMUSICMS I 76 ♯ ♯ ♯ ♯ ♯♯ ̇ ♯ ♯ ♯ ♯ ♯♯ ̇ ♮ ♮ ♮ ♮ ♮ [covered up hereafter]MS I 17(revised) ♯ ♯ ♯ ♯ ♯♯ ♮ ♮ ♮ ♮ ♮ ♮ ♮ ♮ ♯ ♯ ♯ ♯ ♯♯ ̇ ♮♮ MS I 13♯ ♯ ♯ ♯ ♯♯ ♮ ♮ ♯ ♯ ♯ ♯ ♯♯ ♮ ♮ ̇MS I 17(revised)♯ ♯ ♯ ♯ ♯♯ 3 ♯♯ ♯ ♯ ♯ ♯ ♯ ♯♯ ̇ MS I 13♯ ♯ ♯ ♯ ♯♯ ♯ ♯ ♯ ♯ ♯♯ ♮♮ ♮♮ ̇̇ ♮ ♮ ♭ MS I 17(revised)MS I 13 ♯ ♯♯ ♯ ♯♯♭♮ ♭♮ ♯ ♯ ♯ ♯ ♯♯ ♮ ♭♮ ♭5♮ ♮ ♭ ♮ ♭♭ ♭ ♮ ♭ ♭ ♮ ♮♭ ♮ ♭ ♮ ♮ ♯ ♯ ♯ ♯ ♯♯ ♭♮ ♭ ♮ ♮ ♮ ♯ ♯ ♯ ''''♯ ♯♯ ♮ ♮ ♭ ♮ ♭ ♮̇♭ ♮ ♭ ♮ ♭ ̇ ♮♭ ♮ ♮♭ ♭ ♭♮ ♮ ♮̇ ♮ ♭ ♮ 86Example 6: Presentation of theme through differing idiomatic figures.


MS I 17(revised)MS I 13MS I 17(revised)MS I 13♯ ♯♯ ♯ ♯♯♯ ♯ ♯ ♯ ♯♯ ♭ ♮♮ ♮ ♮ ♭ ♮ ♮ ♭ ♮ ♮ ♮ ♮ ♮♮ ♭̇ ̇♮ ♮ ♯ ♮♮♭ ♮ ♮♭♯ ♯ ♮♮ ♮ ♮ ♯ ♯♯ ♯ ♯♯ ♭ ♮ ♮ ♮ ♮ ♮♮ ♮ (♮)♭̇ ̇ ♯ ♯ ♯ ' ' ' ''♯ ♯♯ ♮ ♮ ♯ ♮ ♮ ♭♯ ♮9♯ ♯♯ ♯ ♯♯ ♮♮♮ 7♯ ♯ ♯ ♯ ♯♯♯ ♯♯ ♯ ♯♯♯ ♯♯ ♯ ♯♯♮ ♮ ̇♮ ♮ ♮ ̇ ♮♮ ♮♮ ♮ ♮♮ ♮ ♮ ♮ ̇ '♮♮♯ ♮ ♮♮ [etc.][etc.] ♮ DAVIDTRIPPETT<strong>Virtuosity</strong> inthe “Dante”SonataExample 6 (continued)ingly become constitutive of the fixed workcharacter while the theme’s harmonic <strong>and</strong> melodici<strong>de</strong>ntity remains essentially consistent inall manuscripts.Putting my argument in its most extreme terms,the consi<strong>de</strong>rable revisions to the “Dante” Sonatasuggest a shift in its status from a notatedai<strong>de</strong>-mémoire sketch to a post-Beethovenianwork, a shift that shadows the mise-en-scèneof <strong>Liszt</strong>’s explicit metamorphosis from virtuosoas-caterpillarto composer-as-butterfly. By resigningpublicly as a professional performeramid a flurry of antivirtuoso criticism, 97 <strong>Liszt</strong>ren<strong>de</strong>red his self-critique an act of self-effacement.He effectively <strong>de</strong>termined the negativereception of his earlier portfolio of virtuoso97The most recent analysis of antivirtuoso criticism is thatof Gooley, “The Battle Against Instrumental <strong>Virtuosity</strong> inthe Early Nineteenth Century,” <strong>Liszt</strong> <strong>and</strong> His World, pp.75–112.works by seeking, as Hanslick put it, to writein Weimar “for posterity” rather than to continueto perform for the gratifying heights ofthe instant alone.Because musicological scholarship has ten<strong>de</strong>dto rely on documentary evi<strong>de</strong>nce, improvisationhas remained elusive, relegated to the si<strong>de</strong>linesof conjecture <strong>and</strong> imagination. 98 Method-98Adopting a more analytical approach to the problem ofimprovisation, John Rink has aimed to quantify improvisationwithin Chopin’s Polonaise-Fantaisie, op. 61, througha Schenkerian graphing of different structural levels. Rinksupports his modus oper<strong>and</strong>i with the observation that“certain features of Chopin’s style appear to <strong>de</strong>rive fromthe improvisation tradition . . . at a <strong>de</strong>eper level—at thestructural level, however, the influence improvisation hadon his music . . . is far more difficult to assess precisely.. . . To grasp the essence of Chopin’s music, one mustun<strong>de</strong>rst<strong>and</strong> how improvisation affected its structure”(“Chopin <strong>and</strong> Schenker: Improvisation <strong>and</strong> Musical Structure,”in Chopin Studies: The International MusicologicalSymposium “Chopin <strong>and</strong> Romanticism” Warsaw, 17–23October 1986, vol. 3 [Warsaw: Fre<strong>de</strong>rick Chopin Society,1990], pp. 219–23, here 219).87


19THCENTURYMUSICologically, it is by <strong>de</strong>finition impossible to provethrough documents that the “Dante” Sonatawas the result of Phantasieren during its earlyphases. Yet given the evi<strong>de</strong>nce that traces thepath of an anomalous composition fromuntexted performance to crafted sonata, the finalscore can still—with the requisite historicalimagination—be consi<strong>de</strong>red a distilled amalgamof momentariness, a tissue of recalled improvisations<strong>and</strong> performance i<strong>de</strong>as, a text archetypeof which Rol<strong>and</strong> Barthes observes: “thewriter [or composer] can only imitate a gesturethat is always anterior, never original.” 99 <strong>Liszt</strong>’sstatus as the composer of his work is unstableonly if it is consi<strong>de</strong>red mutually exclusive tohis role as the work’s performer. This exclusivityis a prerequisite of an i<strong>de</strong>alist aesthetic thatdivi<strong>de</strong>s the artwork from its realization an<strong>de</strong>nables the “disparity” lamented by Schumann.Barthes’s critique of the festishizing of texts<strong>and</strong> authors leads him to draw a useful distinctionbetween the author <strong>and</strong> “the mo<strong>de</strong>rnscriptor,” whereby the former is “always conceivedof as the past of his own book” <strong>and</strong> thelatter, more akin to <strong>Liszt</strong> as composer, “is bornsimultaneously with the text, is in no wayequipped with a being preceding or exceedingthe writing, is not the subject with the book aspredicate; there is no other time than that ofthe enunciation <strong>and</strong> every text is eternally writtenhere <strong>and</strong> now.” 100Imagining the unwritten musical text of<strong>Liszt</strong>’s improvisation in these terms creates anuncomfortable condition of absence for textbasedscholarship, particularly though perhapsnot exclusively for <strong>Liszt</strong> studies. The music inquestion was of course always “present” in afinal form through its performance—Barthes’scondition of being eternally “written here <strong>and</strong>now”—but the extent to which stemmatologycan illuminate this <strong>de</strong>pends on the fortuitoustransmission of fragments such as I suggest forMSS I 18, no.1, <strong>and</strong> 1C.51. Positivist methodologyplays a crucial role in this study, but asBernstein suggests, this documentary approachto examining <strong>Liszt</strong>—the “error that answers to99Barthes, “The Death of the Author,” p. 146.100Ibid., p. 145.no correction”—only presents a kind of Heisenbergproblem: “the greater the accuracy of theresearch, the greater, finally, the <strong>de</strong>viance fromwhat is meant by ‘<strong>Liszt</strong>’.” 101 Like the “Dante”Sonata, the aggregate impression of “<strong>Liszt</strong>” remainsin<strong>de</strong>cipherable except as an always retrospectivenarrative that, at least in this case,allows for the permanent over-extension of asingle ego. Philological scrutiny in this articlehas provi<strong>de</strong>d the facts about a musical sketchre<strong>de</strong>fined as a full-fledged work. Ironically, thisinformation has allowed us to see that the consistentinconsistency of the work’s “authorship,”<strong>and</strong> <strong>Liszt</strong>’s reliance on a music that is“performative” in the sense of reaching its i<strong>de</strong>alconception <strong>and</strong> completion only through successiveacts of <strong>de</strong>livery, un<strong>de</strong>rmines the authorityof the mo<strong>de</strong>l of i<strong>de</strong>ntity to which <strong>Liszt</strong>himself sought to subscribe.<strong>Liszt</strong> as mo<strong>de</strong>rn scriptor only adds to the“confusions of distinctions” 102 surrounding himas a historical figure. What benefit is there inapplying such a label if “<strong>Liszt</strong>” is already anover-<strong>de</strong>termination that has reached its momentof saturation? One answer is that theapplication can support a rereading of the compositionaltechnique of thematic transformation.Since Alfred Heuß’s study in 1911, 103 thematictransformation has been associated primarilywith the symphonic poems of theWeimar ex-virtuoso. But as the comparison withCzerny’s treatise shows, the technique was adocumented strategy for Phantasieren that canbe traced via Czerny back to Beethoven.But was the “Dante” Sonata not an anomaly?The answer is: not entirely. Lina Ramann’sbiographical questioning of <strong>Liszt</strong> from the years1875–76 suggests that other potentially similarworks existed, <strong>and</strong> that at least one fell on thewrong si<strong>de</strong> of <strong>Liszt</strong>’s self-critique. Although a101Bernstein, <strong>Virtuosity</strong> of the Nineteenth Century, p. 109.102Ibid.103Daniel Gregory Mason discussed the concept in 1906,but offers only a cursory account of thematic transformation.See The Romantic Composers (New York: Macmillan,1906), pp. 340ff. Following Heuß’s study Erläuterungen zuFranz <strong>Liszt</strong>s Sinfonien und sinfonischen Dichtungen, theterm proliferated.88


substantial fragment, perhaps akin to a sketchedimprovisation, it never reached completion:Ramann: A Berlin reporter indicated that on 11 January1843, you played a “New Fantasy onThemes from Le Nozze di Figaro.” Of yourworks on Mozartian themes, I know onlythe Don Juan fantasy. Was this Figaro fantasywritten out, or was it improvised? Ifit was written out, where can it be found?Has is been published? By whom?<strong>Liszt</strong>: It remained only in sketches, <strong>and</strong> has beenlost. 104In fact, the sketches were found in Weimar <strong>and</strong>have been “completed” three times: in 1912 byBusoni, who suppressed all thematic materialfrom Don Giovanni (245 measures) <strong>and</strong> ad<strong>de</strong>dthirty-seven measures of his own as well asseveral ca<strong>de</strong>nzas; 105 in 1989 by Kenneth Hamilton,who excised nothing <strong>and</strong> ad<strong>de</strong>d a merefifteen measures in or<strong>de</strong>r to complete gaps in atransitional passage <strong>and</strong> at the coda; 106 <strong>and</strong> in1994 by Leslie Howard, who similarly ad<strong>de</strong>dsixteen measures. 107 Given that <strong>Liszt</strong> performedthe Mozart Fantasy in the absence of a completescore in 1843, he almost certainly improvisedsome sections in his performance, though104Ramann’s question dates from December 1875; it wasanswered by <strong>Liszt</strong> in April 1876. See “The Ramann-<strong>Liszt</strong>Questionaires,” trans. Susan Hohl, in <strong>Liszt</strong> <strong>and</strong> His World,p. 411.105Busoni’s excision was possibly carried out in or<strong>de</strong>r toaccord with Ramann’s report that the sketches were for aFantasy on Le nozze alone. The passage quoted above in“The Ramann-<strong>Liszt</strong> Questionaires” first appeared in 1887giving Busoni easy access to it. See Lina Ramann, Franz<strong>Liszt</strong>: Als Künstler und Mensch, vol. 2/1 (Leipzig: Breitkopf<strong>and</strong> Härtel, 1887), p. 202. Busoni’s work was published byBreitkopf <strong>and</strong> Härtel in Leipzig as “Fantasie / über zweiMotive aus W. A. Mozarts / Die Hochzeit <strong>de</strong>s Figaro /nach <strong>de</strong>m fast vollen<strong>de</strong>ten Originalmanuscript / ergänztund Moriz Rosenthal zugeeignet von Ferruccio Busoni /Erste Ausgabe 1912” (Plate no.: V. A. 3830).106Hamilton’s unpublished completion occurs in appendixIV of his doctoral dissertation: The Opera Fantasies <strong>and</strong>Transcriptions of Franz <strong>Liszt</strong>: A Critical Study (BalliolCollege, Oxford University, 1989).107Howard’s edition was published in 1997 by Editio MusicaBudapest un<strong>de</strong>r the title “Fantasie / über Theman ausMozarts Figaro / und Don Giovanni / For piano solo—fürKlavier / Op. post. / First Edition—Erstausgabe (Z. 14,135).” A recording of the piece was released prior to thescore in 1994: <strong>Liszt</strong> at the Opera III (Hyperion: CDA66861/2).the extent to which his playing excee<strong>de</strong>d thesurviving notation cannot be known. 108Manuscript sources are lacking altogetherfor another fantasy-work <strong>Liszt</strong> performed duringthis period. The Gazette musicale reportsthat <strong>Liszt</strong> performed “<strong>une</strong> nouvelle fantaisiecomposée par lui [<strong>Liszt</strong>] sur <strong>de</strong>s mélodies duGuitarrero, <strong>de</strong> M. Halévy” in the Gr<strong>and</strong> Théâtreat Kassel on 19 November 1841 (ten monthsafter the Opera premiered in Paris). 109 There isno mention of this particular performance in<strong>Liszt</strong>’s correspon<strong>de</strong>nce, <strong>and</strong> in the absence ofmanuscript sources two competing hypothesesseem plausible: either the work was writtendown to some extent <strong>and</strong> lost, or—perhaps morelikely—it may never have been notated <strong>and</strong>was consi<strong>de</strong>red a composition only to the extentthat the Gazette reviewer’s impressionswere conditioned through his experience of<strong>Liszt</strong>’s performance.This reasoning may become dangerously hypothetical,but it nevertheless serves to dislocateour notion of composition by separating itfrom the notion of a text. The dislocation furthercomplicates the inherited i<strong>de</strong>alism thatrequires a “work” to be an a priori form precedingany realization in performance. It is tellingin this connection that, contrary to his earlierten<strong>de</strong>ncy to perform from memory (with allthe attendant associations of spontaneous creation),<strong>Liszt</strong>’s rule of thumb in Weimar—asWilliam Mason recounts—was always to playfrom scores, presumably to indicate that whathe was playing were serious, texted compositionsrather than fleeting improvisations. 110 Yet108As Hamilton’s <strong>and</strong> Howard’s completions indicate, the“sketches” are arguably more complete than <strong>Liszt</strong>’s recollectionto Ramann might imply, but this does not mitigatetheir fractional status. Hamilton certainly takes theview that the surviving sources for the Mozart Fantasieare “almost complete.” See The Cambridge Companionto <strong>Liszt</strong>, p. 83.109See “Chronique étrangère” in Gazette musicale 6 (12Dec. 1841), p. 560. For an itinerary of ninety-five “lost”pieces by <strong>Liszt</strong>, see Friedrich Schnapp “VerscholleneKompositionen Franz <strong>Liszt</strong>s,” in Von Deutscher Tonkunst:Festschrift zu Peter Raabes 70. Geburtstag, ed. AlfredMorgenroth (Leipzig: C. F. Peters, 1942), pp. 119–53.110Mason’s memoirs record this particularly through a contrastiveanecdote about Johann Peter Pixis, who performedtogether with <strong>Liszt</strong> before the latter’s move to Weimar<strong>and</strong> begged him to use sheet music on stage, which he didnot: “Later on [<strong>Liszt</strong>] very rarely played even his ownDAVIDTRIPPETT<strong>Virtuosity</strong> inthe “Dante”Sonata89


19THCENTURYMUSICcompositions without having the music before him,” Masonrecalls, “<strong>and</strong> during most of the time I was [in Weimar]copies of his later publications were always lying on thepiano, <strong>and</strong> among them a copy of the ‘Bénédiction <strong>de</strong> Dieudans la Solitu<strong>de</strong>,’ which <strong>Liszt</strong> had used so many timeswhen playing to his guests that it became associated withmemories of Berlioz, Rubinstein, Vieuxtemps, Wieniawski,Joachim, <strong>and</strong> our immediate circle” (William Mason,Memories of a Musical Life [New York: Century, 1901], p.118).111Rosen, Romantic Generation, p. 507.even remaining cautious, we can confirm that<strong>Liszt</strong> performed at least three partially unwritten“works” during the 1840s, that his sketcheswere roughly coeval with their improvisation/performance, <strong>and</strong> that their performance prece<strong>de</strong>dtheir final “composition,” or rather, thatat this stage in <strong>Liszt</strong>’s life, performance <strong>and</strong>composition were effectively synonymous processeswithin the economy of his creative production.This condition un<strong>de</strong>rmines the unqualifiedaspiration of Werktreue in performance by invertingconventional i<strong>de</strong>as about what it is thatis inscribed by a classical score. For <strong>Liszt</strong>’s earlywork on the “Dante” Sonata, notation seemsto function, not as the basis for future performance,but at least in part as the recordingmedium of past performance. This status ismost apparent in plate 2, written as a mementofor an admirer ex post facto. The changes betweenthis manuscript <strong>and</strong> ex. 6 are suggestiveof the consi<strong>de</strong>rable distance traversed betweenimprovisatory performance <strong>and</strong> final notation.We may therefore think of the successive revisionsas “virtual” performances that inscribehypothetical (or perhaps real) improvisationsthat may or may not have originated in concert.Rosen may have been thinking along theselines when he stated that <strong>Liszt</strong>’s music wasconceived absolutely for performance <strong>and</strong> thatits “realization . . . took prece<strong>de</strong>nce over theun<strong>de</strong>rlying compositional structure.” 111 In thisrepertoire, a performer ascends in the normativemusical hierarchy, assuming aspects ofwhat conceptually is a compositional prerogative:to prescribe the notes <strong>and</strong> their or<strong>de</strong>r.This late-twentieth-century viewpoint reflectsa performance-centered aesthetic that mayadd another facet to our assessment of certainof <strong>Liszt</strong>’s pre-Weimar piano works. Seen originallyas transcriptions or amalgams of performanceevents in which the composer <strong>and</strong> performerare one, these “compositions” may beginto assume a new <strong>and</strong> perhaps unfamiliarintegrity. For rather than measuring themagainst the “covert i<strong>de</strong>ological agenda,” 112 asSamson has called it, of the German sonatasymphonictradition, we can view them as productsof a different i<strong>de</strong>ology: that of the improviser-virtuoso.This revisionist perspective resonatessuggestively with an early-nineteenthcenturysentiment perhaps most eloquently—if hyperbolically—formulated in the mid-1840sby an anonymous Darmstadt correspon<strong>de</strong>ntwho dispelled any ambivalence about <strong>Liszt</strong>’sWerktreue <strong>and</strong> his stature as a composer byexplicitly construing performance <strong>and</strong> compositionas synonymous acts in the mind of thegenius:His performance is never a mechanical utterance[Vonsichgeben], rather a composition in the truestsense of the word, an artistic creation existing entirelyfor itself, reborn through fire <strong>and</strong> passion fromwithin. In general he regards every piece he plays asa theme on which to improvise <strong>and</strong> almost alwayscreates anew something won<strong>de</strong>rful, in doing so [he]simultaneously <strong>de</strong>clares the aspiration of the truegenius: always to loosen his art more from all formal<strong>and</strong> frightening shackles, <strong>and</strong> with true enthusiasm<strong>and</strong> unconstrained by all external rules, to reproducein a carefree manner what his inner eye has intuited.113112Samson, <strong>Virtuosity</strong> <strong>and</strong> the Musical Work, p. 112.113“Sein Vortrag ist niemals ein mechanisches Vonsichgeben,son<strong>de</strong>rn im eigentlichsten Sinne <strong>de</strong>s Wortes eineComposition, eine ganz für sich bestehen<strong>de</strong> Schöpfung <strong>de</strong>rKunst, durch Feuer und Lei<strong>de</strong>nschaft von innen herauswie<strong>de</strong>rgeboren. Je<strong>de</strong>s Stück, das er spielt, betrachtet er imAllgemeinen als ein Thema, über welches er phantasirtund fast immer etwas Wun<strong>de</strong>rvolles neu erschafft, undwobei sich zugleich die wahrhaft geniale Strebung kundgibt:seine Kunst immer mehr von allen formellen undbeängstigen<strong>de</strong>n Fesseln loszumachen und in wirklicherBegeisterung und unbekümmert um allen äußerenRegelzwang, das sorglos nachzubil<strong>de</strong>n, was sein inneresAuge geschaut hat” (“Franz <strong>Liszt</strong> [in Darmstadt]” [6 Oct.1845], 1499. This is contained in a small collection ofthus-far uni<strong>de</strong>ntifiable German press articles about <strong>Liszt</strong>between 1838 <strong>and</strong> 1847, which are held in the Nationalarchiv<strong>de</strong>r Richard-Wagner-Stiftung in Bayreuth as: II C b3.Hummel’s comments on the prestige of improvisationalign him with this view <strong>and</strong> offer a complementary perspectiveto the listener-based quotation above. In the final90


Regardless of the music’s elusive history <strong>and</strong>genesis, a mo<strong>de</strong>rn performer can hardly treatthe published “Dante” Sonata from 1858 asimprovisatory. Rather, in a final ironic turn, itis a fixed work to be played “quasi improvisato”(mm. 124, 157), a layering of artifice that finallyconsigns the in<strong>de</strong>cipherable virtuoso tohistory. The work’s fluid formative stages congealinto a compositional topic—a mannerrather than a mo<strong>de</strong> of <strong>de</strong>livery, the i<strong>de</strong>ntity ofwhich must remain “un<strong>de</strong>cidable” within thesemiotics of virtuosity <strong>and</strong> Werktreue.lines of his Clavierschule, Hummel i<strong>de</strong>ntified his publicartistry more with improvisatory performance than what heperceived as a text-based, reproductive practice: “I confessthat, from that moment on [when he was fully proficient atimprovisation], I was less embarrassed to improvise[phantasiren] before an audience of 2000–3000 listene rsthan to play a notated composition I was menially bound to”(Ich gestehe, ich war von <strong>de</strong>m Augenblick an wenigerverlegen, vor einem Publikum von 2–3000 Zuhörern zuphantasiren, als eine nie<strong>de</strong>rgeschriebene Komposizion, <strong>and</strong>ie ich knechtisch gebun<strong>de</strong>n war, zu spielen) (Hummel,Ausführliche theoretisch-practische Anweisung zumPiano-Forte-Spiel, vol. 3 [Vienna: Tobias Haslinger, 1828], p.444).Abstract.The European press of the late 1830s indicates aglaring disparity between <strong>Liszt</strong>’s questionable statusas a composer <strong>and</strong> his eminence as a virtuoso performer.The staggered compositional history of oneparticular piano work, <strong>Après</strong> <strong>une</strong> lecture du Dante—Fantasie quasi Sonata (1839–58), straddles thisschism uniquely in that it bridged two distinct periodsof <strong>Liszt</strong>’s life: the Glanzzeit of immensely successfulEuropean concert tours, <strong>and</strong> the predominantlycompositional span as Kapellmeister inWeimar. As such, it documents the mise-en-scène of<strong>Liszt</strong>’s self-fashioned metamorphosis from virtuosoto composer.As a work borne expressly of improvisational acts,the “Dante” Sonata exhibits paradoxical traits thatbind it to both performance <strong>and</strong> compositional traditions.Through a study of Carl Czerny’s influence on<strong>Liszt</strong>, <strong>and</strong> the latter’s own improvisational practices,I take a medium-sensitive approach to the “Dante”Sonata by interrogating the historical concept ofPhantasieren as part of a rereading of the compositionaltechnique of thematic transformation.Based on the excised material from the extantmanuscripts, I reconstruct the genesis of the “Dante”Sonata <strong>and</strong> chart its compositional history <strong>and</strong> genericevolution. A comparative presentation of selectedrevisions, alternatives, <strong>and</strong> variants from thework illustrates the problematic juncture betweenimprovisation <strong>and</strong> composition, the extent to whichself-borrowing <strong>and</strong> the interchangeability of textsraise questions about our mo<strong>de</strong>rn work-concept, thenotion of a musical text, <strong>and</strong> the functions of performancewithin a text. Key words: <strong>Virtuosity</strong>,Phantasieren, “Dante” Sonata, <strong>Liszt</strong>, compositionalprocess.DAVIDTRIPPETT<strong>Virtuosity</strong> inthe “Dante”Sonata91


19THCENTURYMUSIC1839 (February)<strong>Liszt</strong> first refers to the projected work in hisdiary—Journal <strong>de</strong>s Zÿi—as a symphony, whichhe would complete separately in 1855–56 asEine Symphonie zu Dantes Divina Commedia:If I feel within me the strength <strong>and</strong> life, I will attempta symphonic composition based on Dante,then another on Faust—within three years—meanwhileI will make three sketches: the Triumph ofDeath (Orcagna), the Comedy of Death (Holbein),<strong>and</strong> a Fragment dantesque. 11839 (September)Marie d’Agoult’s letter to Henri Lehmann revealsthat written work on the Fragmentdantesque (for keyboard) had only just begunon 26 September 1839:Le bravo suonatore began this morning a Fragmentdantesque which is sending him to the very Devil.He is so consumed by it that he won’t go to Naplesin or<strong>de</strong>r to be able to complete this work (<strong>de</strong>stined toremain in his sketch portfolio!). 2Paper-type analysis, the fact that this sketchwas in <strong>Liszt</strong>’s h<strong>and</strong>, the spacious use of threestaves, the occasionally wayward spacing, <strong>and</strong>d’Agoult’s <strong>de</strong>monic reference (suggestive of<strong>Liszt</strong>’s opening tritones) indicate that thissketch is most likely MS I 18, No.1, 3 containingthe first twenty-four measures of the Sonata.No further notation survives prior eitherto <strong>Liszt</strong>’s private performance of the piece amonth later on 25 October 1839 at the Hôtel <strong>de</strong>l’Europe or to his public performance of it inAppendix A:Chronology of Revisions for the “Dante” SonataVienna on 5 December 1839 in the fourth morningconcert he gave there. 4The extent to which the music had beenwritten out at this stage, whether as a continuitydraft or collection of sketches, remains unknown.1840The appearance of the Prague fragment (MS1C.51), dated 11 March 1840, <strong>and</strong> the differencesbetween this fragment <strong>and</strong> the first fullMS suggest both that <strong>Liszt</strong> performed the workon his tour of Bohemia <strong>and</strong> that it may stillhave remained largely unwritten at this stage.Whatever <strong>Liszt</strong> performed in 1839–40 musthave resulted in the written exemplar of a completepiece (now lost) that was copied byGeatano Belloni as the original portions of MS I76. In a letter to d’Agoult dated 22 September1840, <strong>Liszt</strong> explains that he had been revisingseveral sections of Belloni’s manuscript. 5 Theresults of these revisions appear to be containedin MS I 76 in graphite pencil <strong>and</strong> reflect thefirst extant (notated) version of the piece, asource thought by Walker <strong>and</strong> Winklhofer nolonger to exist.MS I 18 No. 3—a more concise ending to theSonata—is also in Belloni’s h<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> on thesame “Blacons” paper <strong>and</strong> seems to have beendiscar<strong>de</strong>d from MS I 76. For this reason, MS I18 No. 3 is likely to be the very first notatedconclusion to the Fragment dantesque, if weaccept that the Prague fragment from 11 March1840—also a concluding fragment—was not<strong>Liszt</strong>’s own manuscript.1“Si je me sens force et vie, je tenterai <strong>une</strong> compositionsymphonique d’après Dante, puis <strong>une</strong> autre d’après Faust—dans trois ons—d’ici-là, je ferai trois esquisse: le Triomphe<strong>de</strong> la mort (Orcagna), la Comédie <strong>de</strong> la mort (Holbein), et<strong>une</strong> Fragment dantesque” (<strong>Liszt</strong>, Journal <strong>de</strong>s Zÿi ind’Agoult, Mémories par Daniel Stern [pseud.], ed. DanielOllivier [Paris, 1927], p. 180).2Solange Joubert, Une Correspondance romantique: Madamd’Agoult, <strong>Liszt</strong>, Henri Lehmann (Paris, 1947), p. 33.3A transcription of this fragment was published in the Journalof the British <strong>Liszt</strong> Society, as “Dante fragment, S701e,”28 (2003), 34. The date given in this publication was ca.1837, which is almost certainly incorrect, for it predatesany mention of the work in <strong>Liszt</strong>’s correspon<strong>de</strong>nce by twoyears.1848–49The title page of MS I 76—“Paralopomènes à la‘Divina Comedia’”—must have been ad<strong>de</strong>d be-4Christopher Gibbs’s study of <strong>Liszt</strong>’s concert tours ofVienna in 1838 <strong>and</strong> 1839 provi<strong>de</strong>s the most <strong>de</strong>tailed pictureof <strong>Liszt</strong> at this time to date. See “‘Just Two Words:Enormous Success’: <strong>Liszt</strong>’s 1838 Vienna Concerts,” in <strong>Liszt</strong><strong>and</strong> His World, pp. 167–230.5“Je vais bien – j’ai corrigé ces jours <strong>de</strong>rniers quelquesparties du fragment Dantesque,” <strong>Liszt</strong> to Marie d’Agoult,22 September 1840, Ipswich, in Correspondance / Franz<strong>Liszt</strong>, Marie d’Agoult (Paris: Fayard, 2001), p. 645.92


tween 1848 <strong>and</strong> 1849, however, for the firstbifolium of MS I 76 is a different paper-type<strong>and</strong> is in the h<strong>and</strong> of Adoph Stahr, who was in<strong>Liszt</strong>’s employ between 1848 <strong>and</strong> 1851. 6The next stage of revision saw two furthersessions of correcting <strong>and</strong> amending MS I 76 by<strong>Liszt</strong>, in purple ink <strong>and</strong> red crayon, respectively.The use of red markings strongly suggeststhat he was again preparing the MS forpublication. Additionally, correction leaveswere inserted at the end of the MS on the samepaper as that used by Stahr for the openingbifoluim.Following these extensive revisions, it wasevi<strong>de</strong>ntly impossible for <strong>Liszt</strong> to make furtherprogress on the Sonata using MS I 76, <strong>and</strong> hecontracted Eduard Henschke to prepare a faircopy. Henschke evi<strong>de</strong>ntly went through MS I76 adding acci<strong>de</strong>ntals <strong>and</strong> clefs (on pp. 5–8, <strong>and</strong>11) before transcribing the work as it then existedonto paper that Mueller has associatedwith the post-1848 period in Weimar. 7Winklhofer dates this, MS I 17, prior to 1 August1849 on the basis of its altered title, thusnarrowing the time frame:In the earliest extant manuscript source [sic] for the“Dante” sonata, an undated Abschrift with numerouscorrections in <strong>Liszt</strong>’s h<strong>and</strong>, the title is“Paralipomènes à la Divina Commedia. FantasieSymphonique pour Piano par F. <strong>Liszt</strong>.” Later, <strong>Liszt</strong>crossed out the first word, replacing it with“Prolegomèmes.” This alteration can be dated priorto August 1, 1849, for when <strong>Liszt</strong> wrote to Raff onthat date the score was completely finished, the titlehe used had an additional ingredient probably drawnfrom Beethoven’s “Moonlight” Sonata. He now callsthe work. “Fantasie quasi Sonata (Proligomènes [sic]zu Dantes Göttlicher Comödie).” 8The result is MS I 17, the h<strong>and</strong>-ma<strong>de</strong> paper ofwhich is without watermark but can be datedbetween January <strong>and</strong> August 1849. 9 <strong>Liszt</strong> subsequentlyrevised this MS in stages using variouswriting implements, collettes, <strong>and</strong> inserts.The results were stitched together, concealingall the excised material, in a copy that maywell initially have been inten<strong>de</strong>d, though laterretracted, as a Stichvorlage. Fortunately thestitching was subsequently undone <strong>and</strong> thecollettes released, which has allowed scholarsto investigate this complex stage of revision.<strong>Liszt</strong>’s final title after Victor Hugo—<strong>Après</strong> <strong>une</strong><strong>Lecture</strong> du Dante – Fantasie quasi Sonata—iswritten for the first time in graphite pencil onthis title page.1853A separate correction leaf, MS I 18, n. 2, contains<strong>Liszt</strong>’s reworking of the opening transitioninto the Presto agitato toward the end ofthe Sonata. It was copied into the final manuscriptsource (MS I 13 7 ), but is not in MS I 17<strong>and</strong> therefore seems to have been written ca.1853–54 in between the last additions to I 17<strong>and</strong> its being copied out as I 13 7 .ca. 1853–56The final stage in the genesis of the work wasJoachim Raff’s fair copy—MS I 13 7 —preparedfrom the extensive revisions to MS I 17 forinclusion in the Années.ca. 1857–58Following <strong>Liszt</strong>’s corrections, MS I 13 7 formedthe Stichvorlage for the 1858 Schott edition<strong>and</strong> represents the work as it was published inthe New <strong>Liszt</strong> Edition in 1974. The originationof the notated work in all its known sources ispresented diagrammaticallyas figure 1.l6Mueller, <strong>Liszt</strong>’s “Tasso” Sketchbook: Studies in Sources<strong>and</strong> Revisions (Michigan: UMI, 1986), p. 363.7Ibid., p. 378.8Sharon Winklhofer, “<strong>Liszt</strong>, Marie d’Agoult, <strong>and</strong> the ‘Dante’Sonata,” this journal 1 (1977), 30. 9Mueller, “Tasso,” p. 379; Winklhofer, “Dante,” p. 30.DAVIDTRIPPETT<strong>Virtuosity</strong> inthe “Dante”Sonata93

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!