21.07.2015 Views

on conceptual analysis as the primary qualitative approach to ... - IASE

on conceptual analysis as the primary qualitative approach to ... - IASE

on conceptual analysis as the primary qualitative approach to ... - IASE

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

124pedagogical developments promoting student “engagement” and have joined <strong>the</strong>educati<strong>on</strong>al shift in focus from <strong>the</strong> merely “epistemological” (what students will know) <strong>to</strong>including <strong>the</strong> “<strong>on</strong><strong>to</strong>logical” (what students will become) (cf. Barnett, 2007; Pe<strong>to</strong>cz &Reid, 2010). One major problem is that teachers and students diverge <strong>on</strong> <strong>the</strong> specific<strong>on</strong><strong>to</strong>logical goal; <strong>the</strong>y both want <strong>to</strong> focus <strong>on</strong> what students will become, but, where<strong>as</strong>students want <strong>to</strong> become psychologists and help people, <strong>the</strong>ir teachers want <strong>the</strong>m <strong>to</strong>become competent researchers and evalua<strong>to</strong>rs of <strong>the</strong> psychological research of o<strong>the</strong>rs, so<strong>as</strong> <strong>to</strong> become competent scientist-practiti<strong>on</strong>ers.Teaching in psychology follows <strong>the</strong> North American scientist-practiti<strong>on</strong>er model(established at <strong>the</strong> Boulder c<strong>on</strong>ference in 1949, cf. Belar & Perry, 1991). Psychology<strong>to</strong>day is defined <strong>as</strong> <strong>the</strong> science of human behaviour and mental life, and is distinguishedfrom pop psychology and its ubiqui<strong>to</strong>us extensi<strong>on</strong>s and applicati<strong>on</strong>s by <strong>the</strong> latter’spseudo-scientific grounding. The discipline’s success <strong>as</strong> an applied field rests <strong>on</strong> <strong>the</strong>putative scientific status of <strong>the</strong> research findings from which are derived its variouspractical applicati<strong>on</strong>s (psychological tests, me<strong>as</strong>urement scales, types of clinicalinterventi<strong>on</strong>, etc.). Accordingly, students are taught <strong>to</strong> be scientists first, and <strong>the</strong>npractiti<strong>on</strong>ers; <strong>the</strong>ir practice must be scientifically-b<strong>as</strong>ed; it must implement <strong>on</strong>ly thoseinterventi<strong>on</strong>s that are evidence-b<strong>as</strong>ed and derived from sound <strong>the</strong>ory and rigorousempirical research. And <strong>the</strong> hallmarks of rigorous empirical research are held inpsychology <strong>to</strong> be experimentati<strong>on</strong>, me<strong>as</strong>urement, and quantitative statistical data <strong>analysis</strong>.The use of statistics in psychology arose c<strong>on</strong>currently with <strong>the</strong> use of me<strong>as</strong>urement andquantitative techniques. The latter became c<strong>on</strong>solidated in<strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> post-sec<strong>on</strong>d world warmethodological c<strong>on</strong>sensus (Michell, 2002, 2010), which w<strong>as</strong> fuelled by <strong>the</strong> introducti<strong>on</strong>of government funding (and subsequent m<strong>on</strong>i<strong>to</strong>ring) of scientific research (Leahey, 2004;Solovey, 2004), in <strong>the</strong> c<strong>on</strong>text of a rapidly expanding identificati<strong>on</strong> of quantificati<strong>on</strong> withobjectivity (Porter, 1995). Since <strong>the</strong>n, quantitative methods have become entrenchedwithin mainstream psychology, and almost universally regarded <strong>as</strong> c<strong>on</strong>stitutive of science.Given <strong>the</strong> challenging situati<strong>on</strong> of trying <strong>to</strong> teach something that is c<strong>on</strong>sideredessential in science <strong>to</strong> students who struggle with its c<strong>on</strong>tent and relevance, it is notsurprising that research in this area is burge<strong>on</strong>ing. Until recently most of this research h<strong>as</strong>used quantitative methods. Never<strong>the</strong>less, because statistics educati<strong>on</strong> c<strong>on</strong>tinues <strong>to</strong> need all<strong>the</strong> help it can get, it is understandable—even encouraging—that <strong>the</strong>re h<strong>as</strong> been a move<strong>to</strong>wards <strong>qualitative</strong> and mixed-methods <strong>approach</strong>es <strong>to</strong> statistics educati<strong>on</strong> research.2. THE RISE OF QUALITATIVE APPROACHES TO STATISTICSEDUCATION RESEARCHThe recent move <strong>to</strong>wards <strong>qualitative</strong> and mixed methods <strong>approach</strong>es <strong>to</strong> statisticseducati<strong>on</strong> research h<strong>as</strong> occurred in <strong>the</strong> c<strong>on</strong>text of a general reinvigorati<strong>on</strong> of <strong>qualitative</strong>methods within <strong>the</strong> social sciences, described <strong>as</strong> a “quiet methodological revoluti<strong>on</strong>”(Denzin & Lincoln, 1994, p. ix). Qualitative methods draw up<strong>on</strong> a variety of broadphilosophical <strong>approach</strong>es identified <strong>as</strong> post-Kuhnian “paradigms” (Lincoln & Guba,2000) or “axiomatic positi<strong>on</strong>s” (Potter, 1996), such <strong>as</strong> social c<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong>ism,phenomenology, symbolic interacti<strong>on</strong>ism, hermeneutics, structuralism, post-structuralism,and ethogenics (Richards<strong>on</strong>, 1996). The specific techniques or methods (grounded <strong>the</strong>ory,discourse <strong>analysis</strong>, ethnography, phenomenography, participant observati<strong>on</strong>, pro<strong>to</strong>col<strong>analysis</strong>, c<strong>as</strong>e study, narrative <strong>analysis</strong>, etc.) are typically c<strong>on</strong>cerned with “<strong>the</strong> meaning ofexperience, acti<strong>on</strong>s and events <strong>as</strong> <strong>the</strong>se are interpreted through <strong>the</strong> eyes of particularparticipants, researchers and (sub)cultures” (Henwood, 1996, p. 27), and <strong>the</strong>ir aim is <strong>to</strong>


125“do more justice <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> objects of research than is possible in quantitative research” (Flick,2002, p. 8; cf. also, Janesick, 2000).There are two good re<strong>as</strong><strong>on</strong>s for statistics educati<strong>on</strong> researchers <strong>to</strong> adopt <strong>qualitative</strong>(and mixed) methods. First, <strong>as</strong> Pe<strong>to</strong>cz & Reid (2010) remind us, “while statistics isessentially a quantitative discipline, it c<strong>on</strong>tains a necessary core of <strong>qualitative</strong>comp<strong>on</strong>ents” (p. 272), such <strong>as</strong> definiti<strong>on</strong>s, categories, and forms of linguistic structure (cf.Bowker & Star, 2000; Pe<strong>to</strong>cz & Sowey, 2010). Sec<strong>on</strong>dly, <strong>qualitative</strong> methods can alloweduca<strong>to</strong>rs <strong>to</strong> discover and address students’ c<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong>s of statistics. Pe<strong>to</strong>cz and Reidargue that, despite some pressure <strong>to</strong> use statistics <strong>to</strong> investigate statistics educati<strong>on</strong>,<strong>qualitative</strong> <strong>approach</strong>es can give us something that cannot be acquired from quantitative<strong>approach</strong>es. For instance, <strong>the</strong>y can clarify <strong>the</strong> variety of ways in which statistics cogniti<strong>on</strong>processes can go awry. Kalinowski, Lai, Fidler, and Cumming (this issue) point out that,where quantitative methods may reveal, say, frequencies of false beliefs about somestatistical c<strong>on</strong>cept, <strong>qualitative</strong> methods can illuminate how students have arrived at thosefalse beliefs, helping us <strong>to</strong> access <strong>the</strong> re<strong>as</strong><strong>on</strong>ing processes and <strong>as</strong>sumpti<strong>on</strong>s at work in <strong>the</strong>formati<strong>on</strong> of misc<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong>s.These views are justified. There is incre<strong>as</strong>ing evidence that <strong>the</strong> use of <strong>qualitative</strong><strong>approach</strong>es <strong>to</strong> statistics educati<strong>on</strong> research h<strong>as</strong> indeed extended and enriched ourunderstanding of statistical cogniti<strong>on</strong> processes, and thus facilitated improvements instatistics educati<strong>on</strong> and practices. For example, Kalinowski et al. (this issue) report <strong>as</strong>eries of studies that succeeded in capturing subtleties of statistical cognitive re<strong>as</strong><strong>on</strong>ingprocesses c<strong>on</strong>cerning c<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong>s (and misc<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong>s) of <strong>the</strong> difference between usingc<strong>on</strong>fidence intervals (CIs) and null hypo<strong>the</strong>sis significance tests (NHST). In <strong>on</strong>e c<strong>as</strong>e, <strong>the</strong>results suggest that <strong>the</strong> seemingly successful statistical reform in medicine (in comparis<strong>on</strong><strong>to</strong> psychology), <strong>as</strong> evidenced by <strong>the</strong> incre<strong>as</strong>ed reporting of CIs, is merely superficial inthat <strong>the</strong> correct understanding and interpreting of CIs lags far behind <strong>the</strong> reporting of<strong>the</strong>m. In ano<strong>the</strong>r study, <strong>qualitative</strong> data allowed <strong>the</strong> researchers <strong>to</strong> test and c<strong>on</strong>firm <strong>the</strong>irhypo<strong>the</strong>ses about specific misc<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong>s, and <strong>the</strong>n <strong>to</strong> develop more effective methods ofteaching <strong>the</strong> relevant statistical principles. Pe<strong>to</strong>cz and Reid (2010) review a series of <strong>the</strong>irown studies that used phenomenography, a form of grounded <strong>the</strong>ory furnishingdescripti<strong>on</strong>s of cogniti<strong>on</strong> processes from <strong>the</strong> learner’s perspective, derived from semistructuredinterview data, and obtained via a Piagetian style of answer-c<strong>on</strong>tingentquesti<strong>on</strong>ing. Syn<strong>the</strong>sising <strong>the</strong> results of <strong>the</strong>ir research, <strong>the</strong>y identify hierarchicallystructured <strong>qualitative</strong> variability in students’ understanding of statistical issues, from“narrow” c<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong>s <strong>to</strong> “broader” c<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong>s. Within that c<strong>on</strong>text, <strong>the</strong>y identify six<strong>qualitative</strong>ly distinct c<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong>s both of statistics and of learning statistics, ranging from<strong>the</strong> most limiting (mere techniques) <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> most expansive (helping <strong>to</strong> make sense of <strong>the</strong>world and foster pers<strong>on</strong>al transformati<strong>on</strong>). These findings inform <strong>the</strong>ir variousrecommendati<strong>on</strong>s c<strong>on</strong>cerning <strong>the</strong> pedagogical c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s in which student motivati<strong>on</strong> canbe fostered and movements <strong>to</strong>wards <strong>the</strong> more expansive end of <strong>the</strong> c<strong>on</strong>tinuum can occur.The recogniti<strong>on</strong> of <strong>the</strong> centrality of motivati<strong>on</strong> is also found in <strong>the</strong> work of Bijker,Wynants and van Buuren (2006), who showed <strong>the</strong> value of an integrated teaching andlearning design for fostering optimal motivati<strong>on</strong>, more favourable attitudes and moreadequate learning strategies in studying statistics (cf. also van Buuren, 2006; Wiberg,2009).More recently, Gal and Ograjenšek (2010) have extended <strong>the</strong> core messagec<strong>on</strong>cerning <strong>the</strong> value of <strong>qualitative</strong> <strong>approach</strong>es by reporting results from a number ofo<strong>the</strong>r studies (<strong>qualitative</strong> and mixed), such <strong>as</strong> naturalistic observati<strong>on</strong>al studiesaccompanied by follow-up structured interviews, pro<strong>to</strong>col <strong>analysis</strong> of thinking-aloudwhile-solving-problems,ethnographic participant observati<strong>on</strong>al studies, focus groups


126combined with in-depth interviews, and c<strong>on</strong>tent <strong>analysis</strong> of data derived from CIT(Critical Incident Technique) studies. They offer, am<strong>on</strong>gst o<strong>the</strong>r c<strong>on</strong>clusi<strong>on</strong>s, threerecommendati<strong>on</strong>s. First, “<strong>qualitative</strong> thinking and knowledge of relevant <strong>qualitative</strong>methods should be c<strong>on</strong>sidered part of <strong>the</strong> c<strong>on</strong>ceptual and methodological preparati<strong>on</strong> ofstatisticians” (p. 293). Sec<strong>on</strong>dly, “students should be made aware of <strong>the</strong> existence of<strong>qualitative</strong> techniques during <strong>the</strong> introducti<strong>on</strong> of <strong>the</strong> standard research process (e.g.problem formulati<strong>on</strong> and research planning) at <strong>the</strong> beginning of a statistics course” (p.293). Thirdly, “a solid exposure not <strong>on</strong>ly <strong>to</strong> advantages but also <strong>to</strong> limitati<strong>on</strong>s ofquantitative methods should be provided” (p. 294).We agree wholeheartedly with <strong>the</strong>se three recommendati<strong>on</strong>s, and we find <strong>the</strong> generaldirecti<strong>on</strong> of <strong>qualitative</strong> <strong>approach</strong>es <strong>to</strong> be very encouraging, <strong>as</strong> far <strong>as</strong> it goes. But it needs<strong>to</strong> go much fur<strong>the</strong>r. For <strong>the</strong>re is <strong>on</strong>e <strong>qualitative</strong> <strong>approach</strong> that, we feel, h<strong>as</strong> been largelyoverlooked. This is <strong>the</strong> method of c<strong>on</strong>ceptual <strong>analysis</strong>, whose special place <strong>as</strong> <strong>primary</strong>within scientific methods in general h<strong>as</strong> also been overlooked. As we hope <strong>to</strong> show, this is<strong>the</strong> <strong>on</strong>ly method that allows us <strong>to</strong> identify and tackle a number of issues in statisticseducati<strong>on</strong> that have crucial <strong>the</strong>oretical and practical implicati<strong>on</strong>s, but which are leftunexamined by o<strong>the</strong>r methods, whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>qualitative</strong>, quantitative or mixed.3. CONCEPTUAL ANALYSIS AND ITS NEGLECT IN PSYCHOLOGYC<strong>on</strong>ceptual <strong>analysis</strong> is <strong>analysis</strong> of c<strong>on</strong>cepts, terms, variables, c<strong>on</strong>structs, definiti<strong>on</strong>s,<strong>as</strong>serti<strong>on</strong>s, hypo<strong>the</strong>ses, and <strong>the</strong>ories. It involves examining <strong>the</strong>se for clarity andcoherence, critically scrutinising <strong>the</strong>ir logical relati<strong>on</strong>s, and identifying <strong>as</strong>sumpti<strong>on</strong>s andimplicati<strong>on</strong>s. Sometimes called <strong>the</strong>oretical research, and closely related <strong>to</strong> criticalthinking, c<strong>on</strong>ceptual <strong>analysis</strong> is not merely a matter of language or language use (cf.Bennett & Hacker, 2003); it is also a matter of <strong>the</strong> c<strong>on</strong>tent of our linguistic expressi<strong>on</strong>s,that is, what we claim <strong>to</strong> be thinking and talking about. And sometimes c<strong>on</strong>ceptual<strong>analysis</strong> serves <strong>to</strong> expose (typically unc<strong>on</strong>scious) practical inc<strong>on</strong>sistency (B<strong>as</strong>sham,Irwin, Nard<strong>on</strong>e, & Wallace, 2008), such <strong>as</strong> when some<strong>on</strong>e rejects logic by means of avalid deductive argument (cf. Triplett, 1988), or behaves like a realist in <strong>the</strong>ir researchwhile explicitly claiming allegiance <strong>to</strong> antirealist perspectives (cf. Lambie, 1991; Levitt,2001).In a recent paper entitled “Toward a richer view of <strong>the</strong> scientific method: The role ofc<strong>on</strong>ceptual <strong>analysis</strong>,” Machado and Silva (2007) point <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> neglect of c<strong>on</strong>ceptual<strong>analysis</strong> in psychology, <strong>as</strong> evidenced by <strong>the</strong> general lack of space and attenti<strong>on</strong> given <strong>to</strong> itin teaching courses and curricula, textbooks, c<strong>on</strong>ference presentati<strong>on</strong>s, published papers,and book chapters. Scientific method, <strong>the</strong>y say, h<strong>as</strong> always included three discerniblesubsets or clusters of activity: experimentati<strong>on</strong> (performing c<strong>on</strong>trolled experiments,systematic observati<strong>on</strong>s and correlati<strong>on</strong>al studies); ma<strong>the</strong>matisati<strong>on</strong> (framingma<strong>the</strong>matical or statistical laws and models <strong>on</strong> <strong>the</strong> b<strong>as</strong>is of data collected viaexperimentati<strong>on</strong>); and c<strong>on</strong>ceptual <strong>analysis</strong> (clarifying c<strong>on</strong>cepts, exposing c<strong>on</strong>ceptualproblems in models, revealing unacknowledged <strong>as</strong>sumpti<strong>on</strong>s and steps in arguments,evaluating <strong>the</strong> c<strong>on</strong>sistency of <strong>the</strong>oretical accounts). Psychology, however, regards <strong>on</strong>ly<strong>the</strong> first two of <strong>the</strong>se three activities <strong>as</strong> central <strong>to</strong> science, and so operates with animpoverished view of scientific method. Moreover, psychologists c<strong>on</strong>tinue <strong>to</strong> devaluec<strong>on</strong>ceptual <strong>analysis</strong> <strong>on</strong> various (ir<strong>on</strong>ically, inc<strong>on</strong>sistent) grounds: that it is “obvious” andan inherent part of scientific activity; that it is a form of verbal tyranny, stifling scientificcreativity; and that it is purely negative and destructive, failing <strong>to</strong> offer c<strong>on</strong>structiveavenues of progress.


127To counter <strong>the</strong>se misc<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong>s, Machado and Silva (2007) illustrate <strong>the</strong>intertwining of all three activities within <strong>the</strong> work of <strong>the</strong> quintessential scientist of <strong>the</strong>scientific revoluti<strong>on</strong>, Galileo. They <strong>the</strong>n show <strong>the</strong> applicability and value of c<strong>on</strong>ceptual<strong>analysis</strong> <strong>to</strong> a number of research problems across various are<strong>as</strong> in c<strong>on</strong>temporarypsychology. For example, c<strong>on</strong>ceptual <strong>analysis</strong> solves <strong>the</strong> age-old “problem” of <strong>the</strong>inversi<strong>on</strong> of retinal images, by clarifying that it rests <strong>on</strong> <strong>the</strong> unacknowledged incoherent<strong>as</strong>sumpti<strong>on</strong> that <strong>the</strong> object of percepti<strong>on</strong> is <strong>the</strong> retinal image: “The problem of how objectsare seen upright if <strong>the</strong>ir retinal images are inverted is not <strong>to</strong> be solved empirically but <strong>to</strong>be dissolved c<strong>on</strong>ceptually” (p. 675, emph<strong>as</strong>is added). Bennett and Hacker (2003) providesimilar c<strong>on</strong>ceptual analyses of this and many o<strong>the</strong>r “problems” in current experimentalcognitive neuroscience. Machado and Silva c<strong>on</strong>clude that, because “Observati<strong>on</strong>s andexperiments, <strong>on</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>on</strong>e hand, and c<strong>on</strong>ceptual <strong>analysis</strong>, <strong>on</strong> <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r hand, are filtersthrough which all scientific hypo<strong>the</strong>ses, models and <strong>the</strong>ories must p<strong>as</strong>s” (p. 679), itfollows that “psychologists should replace <strong>the</strong> currently dominant view of <strong>the</strong> scientificmethod with <strong>on</strong>e that <strong>as</strong>signs c<strong>on</strong>ceptual <strong>analysis</strong> its proper weight” (p. 680).Here, <strong>to</strong>o, we wholeheartedly agree. But again we feel that <strong>the</strong>re is a str<strong>on</strong>ger c<strong>as</strong>e <strong>to</strong>be made. This c<strong>as</strong>e emerges from a closer examinati<strong>on</strong> of scientific method. As we shallattempt <strong>to</strong> show, c<strong>on</strong>ceptual <strong>analysis</strong>, far from sitting al<strong>on</strong>gside experimentati<strong>on</strong> andma<strong>the</strong>matisati<strong>on</strong> <strong>as</strong> <strong>on</strong>e of three separate activities c<strong>on</strong>stituting science, is logically andtemporally prior <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r two, is resp<strong>on</strong>sible <strong>on</strong> occ<strong>as</strong>i<strong>on</strong> for precluding <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r twowhen it reveals <strong>the</strong>m <strong>to</strong> be scientifically inappropriate, and is indispensable during <strong>the</strong>o<strong>the</strong>r two. Therefore, c<strong>on</strong>ceptual <strong>analysis</strong> is, in <strong>the</strong>se three senses, <strong>the</strong> <strong>primary</strong> method.4. LOCATING CONCEPTUAL ANALYSIS WITHIN SCIENTIFIC METHODAS CRITICAL INQUIRYIn order <strong>to</strong> locate c<strong>on</strong>ceptual <strong>analysis</strong> clearly within scientific method, we begin withfour points that are generally accepted within <strong>the</strong> scientific community, includingmainstream psychology: (a) Science is a human social activity aimed at <strong>the</strong> investigati<strong>on</strong>of natural systems (including, of course, human and psychological systems); (b) Thesesystems are comprised (<strong>as</strong> is all reality) of complex, dynamic, interrelated and interactingspatio-temporal situati<strong>on</strong>s; (c) These situati<strong>on</strong>s can (in principle) be known by humans (orany o<strong>the</strong>r cognising organisms), and many of <strong>the</strong>m are known (although, of course, given<strong>the</strong>ir infinite complexity, we cannot know everything about a situati<strong>on</strong>); (d) Our cognitiveand perceptual apparatus is limited and fallible; we can, and do, make mistakes.These four facts underpin <strong>the</strong> broad c<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong> of science that w<strong>as</strong> introduced by <strong>the</strong>ancient Greeks and developed throughout <strong>the</strong> European traditi<strong>on</strong> (cf. Crombie, 1994;Haack, 2003; Machado & Silva, 2007). This is <strong>the</strong> view of science <strong>as</strong> critical inquiry; thatis, critical inquiry is <strong>the</strong> core method of science. This view c<strong>on</strong>tr<strong>as</strong>ts with mainstreampsychology’s much narrower view of science, <strong>on</strong>e which (<strong>as</strong> will become clear from <strong>the</strong><strong>analysis</strong> that follows) not <strong>on</strong>ly excludes c<strong>on</strong>ceptual <strong>analysis</strong> but which, <strong>as</strong> a c<strong>on</strong>sequenceof that exclusi<strong>on</strong>, c<strong>on</strong>sists of a scientistic package of dis<strong>to</strong>rti<strong>on</strong>s and misc<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong>s,involving implicit lapses from explicit commitments <strong>to</strong> science and realism (Bickhard,1992; Green, 1992; Mackay & Pe<strong>to</strong>cz, in press; Pe<strong>to</strong>cz, 2004, in press).So, where exactly does c<strong>on</strong>ceptual <strong>analysis</strong> fit within scientific method <strong>as</strong> criticalinquiry? This can be clarified via a hierarchical cl<strong>as</strong>sificati<strong>on</strong> of methods, which includes<strong>the</strong> stages of scientific inquiry (see Figure 1 for a diagrammatic representati<strong>on</strong> of <strong>the</strong><strong>the</strong>mes discussed here).


128Figure 1. Cl<strong>as</strong>sificati<strong>on</strong> of methods showing <strong>the</strong> <strong>primary</strong> role ofc<strong>on</strong>ceptual <strong>analysis</strong> in <strong>the</strong> stages of scientific inquiryOur initial divisi<strong>on</strong> of methods is in<strong>to</strong> two b<strong>as</strong>ic categories: mechanical methods andinquiry methods. Mechanical methods involve doing something <strong>to</strong> achieve a particularoutcome, and <strong>the</strong>y can be fur<strong>the</strong>r divided in<strong>to</strong> performance methods (e.g., how <strong>to</strong> ride a


129bike, how <strong>to</strong> hit a tennis forehand) and producti<strong>on</strong> methods (e.g., recipes for cooking,procedures for building, techniques for sewing). The result of a successful performancemethod is that we can do something that we could not previously do (e.g., we can hit atennis forehand). The result of a successful producti<strong>on</strong> method is that something whichdid not exist before exists now (e.g., we now have a cake, a house, a dress).In c<strong>on</strong>tr<strong>as</strong>t <strong>to</strong> mechanical methods, <strong>the</strong> fundamental aim of methods of inquiry isdiscovery. The result of a successful inquiry method is that something which w<strong>as</strong>previously not known is now known. The something that is discovered may be <strong>the</strong> natureor structure of some situati<strong>on</strong> (its properties, processes, etc.), such that we havediscovered <strong>the</strong> answer <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> “what?” or “how?” (including <strong>the</strong> “how does it work?”)questi<strong>on</strong>s, and we can <strong>the</strong>refore provide a descripti<strong>on</strong> of that situati<strong>on</strong>. Alternatively, <strong>the</strong>something that is discovered may be <strong>the</strong> situati<strong>on</strong>’s causal antecedents, <strong>the</strong> necessary andsufficient c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s for <strong>the</strong> situati<strong>on</strong>’s occurrence, such that we have discovered <strong>the</strong>answer <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> “why?” questi<strong>on</strong>, and we can <strong>the</strong>refore provide an explanati<strong>on</strong> of <strong>the</strong>situati<strong>on</strong>. Hence, <strong>the</strong> goals of descripti<strong>on</strong> and explanati<strong>on</strong> are made possible by achieving<strong>the</strong> inquiry method’s aim of discovery. These findings are communicated by variousforms (sometimes called “methods”) of representati<strong>on</strong>.Now, leaving <strong>as</strong>ide mechanical methods and remaining with methods of inquiry, <strong>the</strong>secan be divided in<strong>to</strong> two b<strong>as</strong>ic categories: scientific and n<strong>on</strong>-scientific. The differencebetween <strong>the</strong>m is that scientific inquiry is critical inquiry in that it is premised <strong>on</strong> <strong>the</strong>recogniti<strong>on</strong> of our cognitive and perceptual fallibility. Because we might be wr<strong>on</strong>g, wedirect our efforts <strong>to</strong> applying <strong>the</strong> best available error-detecti<strong>on</strong> mechanisms, so that, ifpossible, we can identify and correct our errors. Science “bends over backwards” <strong>to</strong> useprocedures that can be self-corrective. This attitude is what unites <strong>the</strong> various specificforms of scientific investigati<strong>on</strong>. To repeat, <strong>the</strong>n, critical inquiry is <strong>the</strong> single corescientific method (cf. Cohen & Nagel, 1934; Haack, 2003; Michell, 2010), whe<strong>the</strong>r it bein <strong>the</strong> “c<strong>on</strong>text of discovery” or in <strong>the</strong> “c<strong>on</strong>text of justificati<strong>on</strong>” (Herschel, 1987). Inc<strong>on</strong>tr<strong>as</strong>t, n<strong>on</strong>-scientific inquiry is not critical or self-critical; it does not focus <strong>on</strong> <strong>the</strong>possibility of being wr<strong>on</strong>g, and does not welcome criticism. Faith, intuiti<strong>on</strong>, appeal <strong>to</strong>authority—<strong>the</strong>se may well lead <strong>to</strong> knowledge, but <strong>the</strong>y are not c<strong>on</strong>cerned withchallenging <strong>the</strong>ir own knowledge claims and subjecting <strong>the</strong>m <strong>to</strong> critical testing.Insofar <strong>as</strong> it rests <strong>on</strong> critical inquiry, scientific inquiry overlaps with ordinaryeveryday inquiry. In that respect, scientific method “does not differ in its nature from <strong>the</strong>normal activity of thought” (Freud, 1933/1975, p. 170), and is “merely a potentiati<strong>on</strong> ofcomm<strong>on</strong> sense, exercised with a specially firm determinati<strong>on</strong> not <strong>to</strong> persist in error if anyexerti<strong>on</strong> of hand or mind can deliver us from it” (Medawar, 1969, p. 59). As such, itdraws up<strong>on</strong> no special c<strong>on</strong>cepts of evidence or mode of inference:Respect for evidence, care in weighing it, and persistence in seeking it out, so far frombeing exclusively scientific desiderata, are <strong>the</strong> standards by which we judge allinquirers, detectives, his<strong>to</strong>rians, investigative journalists, etc., <strong>as</strong> well <strong>as</strong> scientists …Scientific inquiry is c<strong>on</strong>tinuous with <strong>the</strong> most ordinary of everyday empirical inquiry.There is no mode of inference, no ‘scientific method,’ exclusive <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> sciences andguaranteed <strong>to</strong> produce true, probably true, more nearly true, or more empiricallyadequate, results. (Haack, 2003, pp. 23–24)The critical inquiry that is <strong>the</strong> core method of science can be fur<strong>the</strong>r divided in<strong>to</strong> twodifferent methods, depending <strong>on</strong> its focus. These are c<strong>on</strong>ceptual (or logical) <strong>analysis</strong> andobservati<strong>on</strong>al (or empirical) <strong>analysis</strong>. When we pose questi<strong>on</strong>s about <strong>the</strong> nature and waysof working of <strong>the</strong> systems that we are investigating, and when we offer answers <strong>to</strong> thosequesti<strong>on</strong>s, critical inquiry requires that we subject <strong>the</strong>se <strong>to</strong> testing; that is, we c<strong>on</strong>siderwhe<strong>the</strong>r we could be wr<strong>on</strong>g.


130In c<strong>on</strong>ceptual <strong>analysis</strong>, we are c<strong>on</strong>ducting <strong>the</strong>oretical research and applying logicaltests. We examine logical structures, including <strong>as</strong>sumpti<strong>on</strong>s and implicati<strong>on</strong>s, and applytests of clarity, intelligibility, coherence, and so <strong>on</strong> <strong>to</strong> our c<strong>on</strong>cepts, questi<strong>on</strong>s, hypo<strong>the</strong>ses,and <strong>the</strong>ories. This shows <strong>the</strong> first sense in which c<strong>on</strong>ceptual <strong>analysis</strong> is <strong>primary</strong>; it is <strong>the</strong>first step in scientific inquiry (Step 1 in Figure 1); it is that part of scientific research thatmust be applied prior <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> choice of any specific observati<strong>on</strong>al method. For, if we arefaced with a supposed field of inquiry or a research questi<strong>on</strong>, <strong>on</strong>ly c<strong>on</strong>ceptual <strong>analysis</strong>will establish whe<strong>the</strong>r or not our questi<strong>on</strong> is clear, logically coherent, and so <strong>on</strong>, and thusadmits of fur<strong>the</strong>r investigati<strong>on</strong>. This is what is meant by saying that <strong>the</strong> testing of <strong>as</strong>cientific <strong>the</strong>ory involves first subjecting it <strong>to</strong> logical tests. If <strong>the</strong> logical tests are failed, ifour c<strong>on</strong>ceptual <strong>analysis</strong> reveals c<strong>on</strong>fusi<strong>on</strong>s, ambiguities, c<strong>on</strong>tradicti<strong>on</strong>s, implicit<strong>as</strong>sumpti<strong>on</strong>s, and so forth, <strong>the</strong>n we know without going any fur<strong>the</strong>r (i.e., without taking<strong>the</strong> next step in<strong>to</strong> any specific observati<strong>on</strong>al <strong>analysis</strong>) that <strong>the</strong> situati<strong>on</strong> <strong>as</strong> envisaged isei<strong>the</strong>r not yet clear enough or could not possibly be <strong>the</strong> c<strong>as</strong>e. We are <strong>the</strong>n c<strong>on</strong>strained, inaccordance with <strong>the</strong> requirements of scientific investigati<strong>on</strong>, <strong>to</strong> rec<strong>on</strong>sider <strong>the</strong> questi<strong>on</strong>,reformulate it, clarify it, adjust it, or aband<strong>on</strong> it. This reveals <strong>the</strong> sec<strong>on</strong>d sense in whichc<strong>on</strong>ceptual <strong>analysis</strong> is <strong>primary</strong>; it h<strong>as</strong> <strong>the</strong> power <strong>to</strong> preclude observati<strong>on</strong>al inquiry,where<strong>as</strong> observati<strong>on</strong>al <strong>analysis</strong> can never reveal that c<strong>on</strong>ceptual <strong>analysis</strong> is inappropriate.If <strong>the</strong> results of c<strong>on</strong>ceptual <strong>analysis</strong> show that <strong>the</strong> initial logical tests are p<strong>as</strong>sed, <strong>the</strong>n<strong>the</strong> next step (Step 2) is <strong>to</strong> move <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r form of scientific inquiry, observati<strong>on</strong>al(empirical) <strong>analysis</strong>. The first step in this venture (Step 2a) is obviously <strong>to</strong> c<strong>on</strong>siderexisting observati<strong>on</strong>s, and, if those existing observati<strong>on</strong>s are judged <strong>to</strong> be sufficient, <strong>the</strong>inquiry can end <strong>the</strong>re. In o<strong>the</strong>r words, from a scientific point of view (in c<strong>on</strong>tr<strong>as</strong>t, perhaps,<strong>to</strong> a social or political point of view), <strong>the</strong>re is no point in w<strong>as</strong>ting time and resourcesmaking observati<strong>on</strong>s that have already been satisfac<strong>to</strong>rily made, so it is incumbent up<strong>on</strong>scientific researchers <strong>to</strong> be familiar with research that h<strong>as</strong> already been successfullyc<strong>on</strong>ducted. If, however, existing observati<strong>on</strong>s are insufficient, or <strong>the</strong>re are no existingobservati<strong>on</strong>s, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> next step is <strong>to</strong> make new observati<strong>on</strong>s. These new observati<strong>on</strong>s arefur<strong>the</strong>r categorised in<strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> familiar “research methods”: quantitative methods, <strong>qualitative</strong>(i.e., n<strong>on</strong>-quantitative) methods, and mixed methods.And here we come <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> third sense in which c<strong>on</strong>ceptual <strong>analysis</strong> is <strong>primary</strong>. Even ifwe have established via c<strong>on</strong>ceptual <strong>analysis</strong> that our <strong>the</strong>ory or research questi<strong>on</strong> islogically clear and coherent in all relevant <strong>as</strong>pects, we do not <strong>the</strong>n leave c<strong>on</strong>ceptual<strong>analysis</strong> behind <strong>as</strong> we move in<strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> various empirical observati<strong>on</strong>al methods. C<strong>on</strong>ceptual<strong>analysis</strong> c<strong>on</strong>tinues <strong>to</strong> be required all al<strong>on</strong>g <strong>the</strong> way, up <strong>to</strong> and including <strong>the</strong> finalinterpretati<strong>on</strong> of our results and suggesti<strong>on</strong>s for future research directi<strong>on</strong>s. For example,logic is needed in order <strong>to</strong> derive testable hypo<strong>the</strong>ses from <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory via <strong>the</strong> standardhypo<strong>the</strong>tico-deductive method. Then it proceeds via recognising <strong>the</strong> logical point thatquantity and quality are not interchangeable, and that <strong>the</strong> grounds for choice betweenquantitative or <strong>qualitative</strong> methods is an empirical issue. That is, from a realist perspective(and most scientific psychologists claim <strong>to</strong> be realists) scientific observati<strong>on</strong>al inquiryrequires attunement of <strong>the</strong> specific method or technique <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> nature of what is beinginvestigated or focused <strong>on</strong>. Therefore, <strong>the</strong> choice of quantitative or <strong>qualitative</strong> methodmust be determined not by a priori ideological commitment (e.g., “I subscribe <strong>to</strong> socialc<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong>ism, so I do <strong>qualitative</strong> research,” or “I am a scientist, so I do quantitativeresearch”), nor by imposing <strong>on</strong>e type of structure <strong>on</strong><strong>to</strong> ano<strong>the</strong>r (e.g., “If I apply numbers<strong>to</strong> this material, that will render <strong>the</strong> material quantitative”), but by <strong>the</strong> nature of <strong>the</strong>material under investigati<strong>on</strong>. If we are investigating structures or <strong>as</strong>pects of structures thatare quantitative in nature (whe<strong>the</strong>r discrete or c<strong>on</strong>tinuous), <strong>the</strong>n quantitative methods willbe appropriate, where<strong>as</strong> if we are investigating structures or <strong>as</strong>pects of structures that are


131not quantitative in nature, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>qualitative</strong> methods are scientifically demanded andquantitative methods will be scientifically inappropriate. And if we are interested in bothquantitative and <strong>qualitative</strong> features, <strong>the</strong>n mixed methods will be warranted. Next, <strong>on</strong>ce<strong>the</strong> specific observati<strong>on</strong>al method h<strong>as</strong> been appropriately determined, c<strong>on</strong>ceptual <strong>analysis</strong>is required <strong>to</strong> identify appropriate methods of c<strong>on</strong>trol, <strong>to</strong> determine <strong>the</strong> mode of data<strong>analysis</strong>, and <strong>to</strong> interpret <strong>the</strong> results in <strong>the</strong> light of <strong>the</strong> underlying <strong>as</strong>sumpti<strong>on</strong>s of that<strong>analysis</strong>. For example, <strong>the</strong> value of experimentati<strong>on</strong> (<strong>as</strong> opposed <strong>to</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r observati<strong>on</strong>almethods) will depend not <strong>on</strong>ly <strong>on</strong> how much c<strong>on</strong>trol of variables is possible but also <strong>on</strong>how much c<strong>on</strong>trol is appropriate under <strong>the</strong> circumstances (<strong>as</strong> is indicated by <strong>the</strong> justifiablec<strong>on</strong>cern in psychology with ecological validity). Similarly, <strong>the</strong> value of analysing data viaparametric or n<strong>on</strong>-parametric statistics is directly related <strong>to</strong> logical c<strong>on</strong>siderati<strong>on</strong>s of <strong>the</strong>fit between <strong>the</strong> nature of <strong>the</strong> collected data and <strong>the</strong> <strong>as</strong>sumpti<strong>on</strong>s and implicati<strong>on</strong>s of <strong>the</strong>statistical <strong>analysis</strong>. In <strong>the</strong>se ways, c<strong>on</strong>ceptual <strong>analysis</strong> remains an essentialaccompaniment <strong>to</strong> observati<strong>on</strong>al (empirical) <strong>analysis</strong>, and indispensable if <strong>the</strong> c<strong>on</strong>clusi<strong>on</strong>sdrawn from <strong>the</strong> research findings are <strong>to</strong> be sound.Against this background of locating c<strong>on</strong>ceptual <strong>analysis</strong> <strong>as</strong> <strong>primary</strong> within scientificmethod, we can now highlight four important implicati<strong>on</strong>s that are uncomfortably at oddswith current views and practices in mainstream psychology, and which are relevant <strong>to</strong> oursubsequent scrutiny of statistics educati<strong>on</strong>.5. IMPLICATIONS FOR PSYCHOLOGY OF THE PLACE OF CONCEPTUALANALYSIS AS PRIMARY WITHIN SCIENTIFIC METHODTo begin with, scientific psychology subscribes explicitly <strong>to</strong> realism. However,mistakenly believing that positivism and realism are equivalent, it h<strong>as</strong> acceptedpositivism’s versi<strong>on</strong> of <strong>the</strong> distincti<strong>on</strong> between logical and empirical inquiry, according <strong>to</strong>which <strong>on</strong>ly empirical inquiry can be regarded <strong>as</strong> scientific, and logical inquiry is <strong>to</strong> berelegated <strong>to</strong> philosophy. Hence, psychology came <strong>to</strong> regard logical or c<strong>on</strong>ceptual <strong>analysis</strong><strong>as</strong> part of <strong>the</strong> philosophy package that needed <strong>to</strong> be dismissed in <strong>the</strong> name of science. Bu<strong>the</strong>re (<strong>as</strong> in o<strong>the</strong>r crucial respects) positivism is anti<strong>the</strong>tical <strong>to</strong> realism (cf. Friedman, 1991,1999; Hibberd, 2005). Thus, c<strong>on</strong>trary <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> received view in mainstream psychology,nei<strong>the</strong>r experimentati<strong>on</strong> nor me<strong>as</strong>urement nor <strong>the</strong> use of statistics (let al<strong>on</strong>e all threecombined) is necessary for science. Nor does scientific research begin with <strong>the</strong>quantitative or <strong>qualitative</strong> methods adopted <strong>to</strong> make new observati<strong>on</strong>s. Instead, according<strong>to</strong> realism, scientific research begins with c<strong>on</strong>ceptual <strong>analysis</strong>, and what is necessary is“<strong>the</strong> persistent applicati<strong>on</strong> of logic <strong>as</strong> <strong>the</strong> comm<strong>on</strong> feature of all re<strong>as</strong><strong>on</strong>ed knowledge … inessence scientific method is simply <strong>the</strong> pursuit of truth <strong>as</strong> determined by logicalc<strong>on</strong>siderati<strong>on</strong>s” (Cohen & Nagel, 1934, p. 192).Sec<strong>on</strong>dly, because <strong>the</strong> realism <strong>to</strong> which scientific psychology is explicitly committedentails that it is a questi<strong>on</strong> of <strong>the</strong> way things are in <strong>the</strong> world whe<strong>the</strong>r any particularattribute is quantitative or <strong>qualitative</strong> in structure, it follows that <strong>qualitative</strong> methods arejust <strong>as</strong> scientifically legitimate (indeed, warranted) <strong>as</strong> are quantitative methods. Nature isfull of n<strong>on</strong>-quantitative structures (e.g., semantic, categorical, logical), all of which areappropriately investigated by n<strong>on</strong>-quantitative methods, typically included under <strong>the</strong>umbrella term <strong>qualitative</strong>. Qualitative methods are scientific when <strong>the</strong>y are appropriatelyapplied and applied carefully and critically. C<strong>on</strong>versely, quantitative methods areunscientific when <strong>the</strong>y are misapplied. Here, again, psychology h<strong>as</strong> been misled by <strong>the</strong>antirealist <strong>as</strong>pects of positivism. The positivist c<strong>on</strong>venti<strong>on</strong>alism of mainstreampsychological practices adopts <strong>the</strong> view that “<strong>the</strong> difference between quality and quantityis not a difference in nature, but a difference in our c<strong>on</strong>ceptual schema— in our language”


132(Carnap, 1966, p. 58). But, again from <strong>the</strong> point of view of <strong>the</strong> realism <strong>to</strong> whichpsychology explicitly subscribes, it is a point of logic, discovered via c<strong>on</strong>ceptual <strong>analysis</strong>,that it is not possible that “data collecti<strong>on</strong> procedures are independent of data <strong>analysis</strong>techniques … [such that] collected data may be transformed at any point, and may beanalysed both quantitatively and <strong>qualitative</strong>ly” (T<strong>as</strong>hakkori & Teddlie, 2003a, p. 696,emph<strong>as</strong>is added). In o<strong>the</strong>r words, it is not possible <strong>to</strong> “quantitize” <strong>qualitative</strong> data or“qualitize” quantitative data (Teddlie & T<strong>as</strong>hakkori, 2003, p. 9).This leads in<strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> third implicati<strong>on</strong>. To believe that we can make somethingquantitative merely by throwing numbers at it is <strong>to</strong> c<strong>on</strong>flate mechanical methods withinquiry methods; it is <strong>to</strong> treat a mechanical method (e.g., applying a recipe) <strong>as</strong> if it werean inquiry method. Though it is true that mechanical methods rest <strong>on</strong> facts about <strong>the</strong>world that have been discovered, and though it is true that in pursuing inquiry <strong>on</strong>e maymake use of mechanical procedures (operating a microscope, making calculati<strong>on</strong>s via acomputer, following <strong>the</strong> “recipe” for performing a particular statistical <strong>analysis</strong>, etc.),<strong>the</strong>se methods of performance and producti<strong>on</strong> cannot replace methods of inquiry. Tothink that <strong>the</strong>y can is <strong>to</strong> engage in a form of scientific practicalism, which begins withsubordinating <strong>the</strong> (realist) search for truth <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> goal of achieving specific practical(performance or producti<strong>on</strong>) outcomes, and ends with believing that <strong>the</strong> essence ofscience lies in simply adopting quantitative methods and performing statistical <strong>analysis</strong>.Finally, insofar <strong>as</strong> c<strong>on</strong>ceptual <strong>analysis</strong> is a method that focuses <strong>on</strong> n<strong>on</strong>-quantitativestructures, namely, logical, semantic and categorical structures, it is clearly not aquantitative method. As such, it bel<strong>on</strong>gs under <strong>the</strong> umbrella term <strong>qualitative</strong> <strong>on</strong> <strong>the</strong> samegrounds <strong>as</strong> are all o<strong>the</strong>r so-called <strong>qualitative</strong> methods. When this is combined with <strong>the</strong>primacy of c<strong>on</strong>ceptual <strong>analysis</strong> within scientific research, according <strong>to</strong> which sometimes<strong>the</strong> inquiry will end without going <strong>on</strong> <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r specific observati<strong>on</strong>al methods, whereat o<strong>the</strong>r times c<strong>on</strong>ceptual <strong>analysis</strong> will be needed al<strong>on</strong>gside those o<strong>the</strong>r methods, it can bec<strong>on</strong>cluded that c<strong>on</strong>ceptual <strong>analysis</strong> is <strong>the</strong> <strong>primary</strong> <strong>qualitative</strong> method in scientificresearch.6. APPLYING CONCEPTUAL ANALYSIS TO STATISTICS EDUCATION INPSYCHOLOGYPrevious <strong>qualitative</strong> research h<strong>as</strong> focused <strong>on</strong> students’ percepti<strong>on</strong>s of statistics and itsrelevance, <strong>on</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir statistical cogniti<strong>on</strong> processes, and, in particular, <strong>on</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir c<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong>sand misc<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong>s of various statistical issues. Our c<strong>on</strong>ceptual <strong>analysis</strong> of statisticseducati<strong>on</strong> goes deeper; it addresses <strong>the</strong> b<strong>as</strong>es from which we derive our evaluative criteriaregarding students’ c<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong>s and misc<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong>s, and for this we turn <strong>the</strong> spotlightback <strong>on</strong><strong>to</strong> ourselves <strong>as</strong> teachers, and our own understandings of statistical issues. We alsoadopt <strong>the</strong> scientist-practiti<strong>on</strong>er model; we examine first <strong>the</strong> scientific c<strong>on</strong>tent and <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong>various practices. As we hope <strong>to</strong> show, c<strong>on</strong>ceptual <strong>analysis</strong> highlights a number of majorproblems that have “flown under <strong>the</strong> radar” in standard statistics educati<strong>on</strong> research. Withrespect <strong>to</strong> scientific c<strong>on</strong>tent, <strong>the</strong>se problems include unacknowledged and c<strong>on</strong>flicting<strong>as</strong>sumpti<strong>on</strong>s about <strong>the</strong> nature of quantity, quality, me<strong>as</strong>urement, probability, evidence,and inference. Many of <strong>the</strong>se <strong>as</strong>sumpti<strong>on</strong>s are c<strong>on</strong>troversial, unwarranted, likely <strong>to</strong> befalse (<strong>on</strong> <strong>the</strong> b<strong>as</strong>is of available evidence), or known <strong>to</strong> be false. With respect <strong>to</strong> practice,<strong>the</strong> problems include <strong>the</strong> existence of l<strong>on</strong>g-entrenched practices that are at odds withpsychology’s stated scientific goals. That is, from a c<strong>on</strong>ceptual <strong>analysis</strong> perspective <strong>the</strong>yare forms of practical inc<strong>on</strong>sistency. Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, <strong>the</strong>se practices preclude access <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong><strong>to</strong>ols necessary for statistics educati<strong>on</strong> reform.


1336.1. CONCEPTUAL ANALYSIS OF STATISTICS EDUCATION CONTENTWith respect <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> c<strong>on</strong>tent of statistics, we can divide it for purposes of discussi<strong>on</strong>in<strong>to</strong> two separate clusters of unexamined and c<strong>on</strong>flicting <strong>as</strong>sumpti<strong>on</strong>s. The first clusterc<strong>on</strong>cerns <strong>the</strong> nature of me<strong>as</strong>urement, quantity, quality, <strong>the</strong> distincti<strong>on</strong> betweenquantitative and <strong>qualitative</strong> methods, test scores, and test validity. The sec<strong>on</strong>d clusterc<strong>on</strong>cerns <strong>the</strong> nature of probability, evidence, and <strong>the</strong> evidential role of statisticalinference.Taking <strong>the</strong> first cluster, <strong>the</strong>re are three different uses of <strong>the</strong> term me<strong>as</strong>urement. Inloose colloquial language it can mean “<strong>as</strong>sess,” “examine,” “observe” or even “describe.”Many psychology students have difficulty in letting go of this usage (e.g., “How can we‘me<strong>as</strong>ure’ <strong>the</strong> mind?”). But, in science, <strong>the</strong> c<strong>on</strong>cept of me<strong>as</strong>urement is more specific andtechnical. The physical sciences (which psychology h<strong>as</strong> l<strong>on</strong>g attempted <strong>to</strong> emulate) follow<strong>the</strong> standard, cl<strong>as</strong>sical realist definiti<strong>on</strong> of me<strong>as</strong>urement, according <strong>to</strong> which me<strong>as</strong>urementis “<strong>the</strong> estimati<strong>on</strong> or discovery of <strong>the</strong> ratio of some magnitude of a quantitative attribute<strong>to</strong> a unit of <strong>the</strong> same attribute” (Michell, 1997, p. 358, emph<strong>as</strong>is in original). That is, inscience, me<strong>as</strong>urement is <strong>the</strong> <strong>as</strong>sessment of (c<strong>on</strong>tinuous) quantitative structure and sorequires and presupposes quantitative structure. If <strong>the</strong> variable that we are c<strong>on</strong>sidering isnot by nature quantitative, <strong>the</strong>n me<strong>as</strong>urement is impossible; attempting me<strong>as</strong>urementwould be like trying <strong>to</strong> drink a loaf of bread or discover <strong>the</strong> width of <strong>on</strong>e’s coughing;bread just doesn’t have drinkable properties and coughs just d<strong>on</strong>’t come in widths.However, <strong>as</strong> me<strong>as</strong>ure is not coextensive with “describe,” “observe,” “investigate” or“<strong>as</strong>sess,” we can still legitimately do any of <strong>the</strong>se o<strong>the</strong>r things <strong>to</strong> our variable, and so itdoes not follow that, if we cannot me<strong>as</strong>ure it, we must ignore it (cf. Pe<strong>to</strong>cz & Sowey,2010, p. 61); we can explore what kind of n<strong>on</strong>-quantitative structure it h<strong>as</strong>, and investigateit via whatever <strong>qualitative</strong> methods are appropriate.Now, mainstream psychology’s treatment of me<strong>as</strong>urement c<strong>on</strong>flicts with thisscientific view, and with psychology’s own explicit commitment <strong>to</strong> scientific realism.This <strong>the</strong>me h<strong>as</strong> been most thoroughly and cogently explored in <strong>the</strong> work of Michell over<strong>the</strong> l<strong>as</strong>t two decades (e.g., Michell, 1990, 1999, 2010, and especially 1997, which is hisseminal paper in this area and which includes peer resp<strong>on</strong>ses and discussi<strong>on</strong>). Tosummarise this work, psychology’s commitment <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> quantitative imperative (<strong>the</strong> falsebelief that me<strong>as</strong>urement is a necessary c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong> of science—see Michell, 2003) h<strong>as</strong> led<strong>to</strong> a psychometric <strong>approach</strong> that c<strong>on</strong>stitutes a “pathology of science” (Michell, 2000,2008), a form of “methodological thought-disorder” (Michell, 1997). This involves a twostagebreakdown in scientific practice. At <strong>the</strong> first stage, <strong>the</strong> underlying empiricalhypo<strong>the</strong>sis that <strong>the</strong> psychological attribute being <strong>as</strong>sessed is quantitative is not subject <strong>to</strong>empirical test. In o<strong>the</strong>r words, psychologists merely <strong>as</strong>sume that <strong>the</strong> variables of interest(abilities, intelligence, attitudes, pers<strong>on</strong>ality traits, etc.) are indeed quantitative and henceme<strong>as</strong>urable. At <strong>the</strong> sec<strong>on</strong>d stage, this failure <strong>to</strong> test <strong>the</strong> empirical hypo<strong>the</strong>sis is <strong>the</strong>ndisguised. The disguise is effected by psychology’s aband<strong>on</strong>ing <strong>the</strong> cl<strong>as</strong>sical realistdefiniti<strong>on</strong> of me<strong>as</strong>urement and adopting its own special definiti<strong>on</strong> of me<strong>as</strong>urement,following S. S. Stevens (Stevens, 1946; cf. Michell, 2002), according <strong>to</strong> whichme<strong>as</strong>urement is <strong>the</strong> “<strong>as</strong>signment of numerals <strong>to</strong> objects or events according <strong>to</strong> rule”(Michell, 1997, p. 360, emph<strong>as</strong>is in original). This n<strong>on</strong>realist, operati<strong>on</strong>ist definiti<strong>on</strong> ofme<strong>as</strong>urement allows psychologists <strong>to</strong> claim <strong>to</strong> be me<strong>as</strong>uring any variable of interest,regardless of whe<strong>the</strong>r or not it actually h<strong>as</strong> a quantitative structure; <strong>the</strong>y think <strong>the</strong>y canmake something quantitative simply by throwing numerals at it. And this is howme<strong>as</strong>urement is (mis)taught in psychology (Michell, 2001).


134The inference from order <strong>to</strong> quantity, which Michell (2009a) labels <strong>the</strong>psychometricians’ fallacy, and <strong>the</strong> underlying <strong>as</strong>sumpti<strong>on</strong> of quantitativity, leadc<strong>on</strong>sequentially <strong>to</strong> standard treatments of psychological test scores. In resp<strong>on</strong>se <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong>objecti<strong>on</strong> that his arguments do not apply <strong>to</strong> probabilistic item resp<strong>on</strong>se models, Michell(2004a) points out that <strong>the</strong> same untested <strong>as</strong>sumpti<strong>on</strong> underlies <strong>the</strong>m, insofar <strong>as</strong> <strong>the</strong> issueof whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> relevant psychological attribute is quantitative is never raised <strong>as</strong> a sourceof model misfit. Moreover, “<strong>the</strong> locus of quantitativity in probabilistic models derives notfrom anything known directly about <strong>the</strong> relevant attribute but from <strong>the</strong> postulated shape of‘error’” (pp. 125–6), with <strong>the</strong> result that “if <strong>the</strong> attribute is not quantitative, <strong>the</strong> supposedshape of ‘error’ <strong>on</strong>ly projects <strong>the</strong> image of a fictitious quantitativity” (p. 126). In general,<strong>the</strong>n, psychology appears <strong>to</strong> be dealing with ordered attributes whose degrees ofdifference are intrinsically n<strong>on</strong>metric because <strong>the</strong>y are <strong>qualitative</strong>ly heterogeneous(Michell, 2010). Therefore, “transforming” test scores (whe<strong>the</strong>r in<strong>to</strong> fac<strong>to</strong>r scores viafac<strong>to</strong>r <strong>analysis</strong> or in<strong>to</strong> ability scores via item resp<strong>on</strong>se models) does not transform <strong>the</strong>min<strong>to</strong> me<strong>as</strong>ures of anything when <strong>the</strong>re is no evidence that <strong>the</strong> hypo<strong>the</strong>sised fac<strong>to</strong>rs orabilities are quantitative.The same problem extends <strong>to</strong> psychology’s c<strong>on</strong>cept of test validity, which w<strong>as</strong>introduced nearly a century ago, and which is typically unders<strong>to</strong>od and taught <strong>to</strong> students<strong>as</strong> being <strong>the</strong> extent <strong>to</strong> which a test me<strong>as</strong>ures what it is supposed <strong>to</strong> me<strong>as</strong>ure. Being acrucial c<strong>on</strong>cept in psychology by virtue of <strong>the</strong> widespread use of tests and scales, and<strong>the</strong>re being nothing analogous for me<strong>as</strong>urement in <strong>the</strong> physical sciences (where <strong>the</strong>structure of <strong>the</strong> attribute is identified before <strong>the</strong> me<strong>as</strong>uring instrument is devised), validityh<strong>as</strong> been <strong>the</strong> subject of much discussi<strong>on</strong> and many attempts at unificati<strong>on</strong> (cf. Lissitz,2009). But here, again, <strong>as</strong> Michell (2009b) points out, <strong>the</strong> definiti<strong>on</strong> of validity rests <strong>on</strong>two untested <strong>as</strong>sumpti<strong>on</strong>s: that <strong>the</strong> test me<strong>as</strong>ures something, and that whatever it issupposed <strong>to</strong> be me<strong>as</strong>uring can be me<strong>as</strong>ured. However, “Few testers realize thatknowledge of <strong>the</strong> structure of attributes is necessary <strong>to</strong> provide a scientific b<strong>as</strong>e for testingpractice” (p. 123). As “no scientific evidence h<strong>as</strong> been collected capable of sustaining <strong>the</strong>hypo<strong>the</strong>sis that such attributes are quantitative” (Michell, 2010, p. 48), it follows that “<strong>the</strong>presumpti<strong>on</strong>s underlying <strong>the</strong> c<strong>on</strong>cept of validity are invalidly endorsed” (Michell, 2009b,p. 111).Taking <strong>the</strong> sec<strong>on</strong>d cluster, <strong>the</strong> problems of <strong>as</strong>sumed quantitativity and illegitimateme<strong>as</strong>urement are exacerbated by <strong>the</strong> applicati<strong>on</strong> of statistical techniques that rest <strong>on</strong>c<strong>on</strong>fused <strong>as</strong>sumpti<strong>on</strong>s c<strong>on</strong>cerning <strong>the</strong> nature of probability and <strong>the</strong> evidential role ofstatistical inference. Psychologists are generally unaware that <strong>the</strong>re are competing views<strong>on</strong> <strong>the</strong> nature of probability, and that those who developed <strong>the</strong> statistical techniques nowwidely applied in psychology advised against <strong>the</strong>ir use and debated <strong>the</strong> implicati<strong>on</strong>s of<strong>the</strong>ir disagreements. Psychologists are generally unaware that what is taught in <strong>the</strong>irtextbooks is <strong>the</strong> result of an “inference revoluti<strong>on</strong>” (Gigerenzer & Murray, 1987) tha<strong>to</strong>ccurred in <strong>the</strong> middle of <strong>the</strong> twentieth century and “saw <strong>the</strong> widespread adopti<strong>on</strong> of ahybrid of frequently c<strong>on</strong>tradic<strong>to</strong>ry Fisherian and Neyman-Pears<strong>on</strong> statistical c<strong>on</strong>cepts <strong>as</strong> <strong>as</strong>ingle, unc<strong>on</strong>troversial method of inductive inference” (Hubbard & Ryan, 2000, p. 666).Specifically, this hybrid cobbled <strong>to</strong>ge<strong>the</strong>r Fisherian NHST with <strong>the</strong> competing views ofNeyman and Pears<strong>on</strong>, <strong>to</strong>ge<strong>the</strong>r with <strong>the</strong>ir ide<strong>as</strong> about an alternative hypo<strong>the</strong>sis, Type 1and Type 2 errors, and statistical power, in a manner that nei<strong>the</strong>r camp would havec<strong>on</strong>d<strong>on</strong>ed. As Hubbard and Ryan summarise it, “Despite serious misgivings <strong>on</strong> both sides,this hybrid methodology, with its emph<strong>as</strong>is <strong>on</strong> <strong>the</strong> rejecti<strong>on</strong> of <strong>the</strong> null hypo<strong>the</strong>sis at p


135use and abuse of SST [statistical significance testing] h<strong>as</strong> failed <strong>to</strong> reduce its visibility in<strong>the</strong> psychological literature” (p. 672).O<strong>the</strong>rs have g<strong>on</strong>e deeper in <strong>the</strong>ir analyses. For example, Grays<strong>on</strong> (1998) arguesc<strong>on</strong>vincingly that <strong>the</strong> major statistical c<strong>on</strong>fusi<strong>on</strong> in psychology (and o<strong>the</strong>r social sciences)is <strong>the</strong> blurring of <strong>the</strong> distincti<strong>on</strong> between <strong>the</strong> Neyman frequentist view of l<strong>on</strong>g-runprobability (which disallows <strong>the</strong> evidential use of probabilistic informati<strong>on</strong> in <strong>the</strong> singlec<strong>as</strong>e) and <strong>the</strong> scientific issue of evidential inference. According <strong>to</strong> Neyman and Pears<strong>on</strong>(1933), in terms of <strong>the</strong> nature of scientific evidence, <strong>the</strong>re is nothing <strong>to</strong> be gained in <strong>as</strong>ingle piece of research by performing a statistical <strong>analysis</strong> and computing a single p-value; that is, <strong>the</strong>re is no point at all <strong>to</strong> how we routinely perform statistical analysesfollowing single experiments. Never<strong>the</strong>less, psychologists are unwilling <strong>to</strong> give up <strong>the</strong>objective (yet scientifically sterile) l<strong>on</strong>g-run frequency view of probability in exchangefor <strong>on</strong>e that seems <strong>to</strong>o subjective, insofar <strong>as</strong> it treats probabilities <strong>as</strong> numbers thatrepresent degrees of belief that can be quantified <strong>on</strong> single occ<strong>as</strong>i<strong>on</strong>s (<strong>as</strong> in <strong>the</strong> Bayesian<strong>approach</strong>) (cf. also Gigerenzer, 1987). Yet <strong>the</strong> attracti<strong>on</strong> of <strong>the</strong> Bayesian <strong>approach</strong> lies inits allowing for evidential inference in a single experiment. So, psychologists want <strong>to</strong>have <strong>the</strong>ir cake and eat it. Following Gigerenzer’s (1993) Freudian analogy, Grays<strong>on</strong>(1998) agrees that, in mainstream psychology’s statistical psyche, <strong>the</strong> superego isrepresented by rigorous, socially-desirable frequentism, <strong>the</strong> ego is <strong>the</strong> c<strong>on</strong>fused yetpragmatic Fisherian significance testing, and <strong>the</strong> id is <strong>the</strong> Bayesian lustful desire forevidential inference, allowing us <strong>to</strong> draw c<strong>on</strong>clusi<strong>on</strong>s about <strong>the</strong> probability of ourhypo<strong>the</strong>ses given <strong>the</strong> data. Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, Grays<strong>on</strong> dem<strong>on</strong>strates that <strong>the</strong> unavoidable issueof evidential inference in a single c<strong>as</strong>e is left unaddressed by <strong>the</strong> incre<strong>as</strong>ingly popularrecommendati<strong>on</strong>s <strong>to</strong> avoid <strong>the</strong> problem by moving <strong>to</strong> CIs, effect sizes, meta-analyses, and<strong>the</strong> like (even if <strong>the</strong>se do bring o<strong>the</strong>r genuine advantages). The current <strong>as</strong>sumpti<strong>on</strong> is thatreplacing NHST with CIs, properly unders<strong>to</strong>od, c<strong>on</strong>stitutes statistical reform and progress,partly because it challenges <strong>the</strong> dicho<strong>to</strong>mous thinking <strong>as</strong>sociated with <strong>the</strong> accept/rejectdecisi<strong>on</strong> rule in NHST. However, if <strong>the</strong> arguments presented by Gigerenzer and Grays<strong>on</strong>are correct, <strong>the</strong>n this is a band-aid remedy for a life-threatening wound.Psychology’s statistical psyche is populated by numerous o<strong>the</strong>r c<strong>on</strong>fusi<strong>on</strong>s andmisc<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong>s (cf. also Grays<strong>on</strong>, 1988; Rosnow & Rosenthal, 1989; Rozeboom, 1960),such <strong>as</strong> those c<strong>on</strong>cerning “negative” results, against <strong>the</strong> reporting of which <strong>the</strong>re iswidespread scientific prejudice (Furedy, 1978; Rosenthal, 1979); <strong>the</strong> use of “protecti<strong>on</strong>”methods in multiple-inference procedures (Grays<strong>on</strong> & Oliphant, 1996); <strong>the</strong>misunderstanding of post-hoc testing (Oliphant & Grays<strong>on</strong>, 1996); and <strong>the</strong> widespreadpractice of HARKing (hypo<strong>the</strong>sising after <strong>the</strong> results are known) by adjusting predicti<strong>on</strong>sin <strong>the</strong> light of results (Kerr, 1998).Grays<strong>on</strong>’s (1998) c<strong>on</strong>clusi<strong>on</strong>s can be generalised <strong>to</strong> all of <strong>the</strong>se: The issues typicallyare scientific, not statistical; each of us h<strong>as</strong> <strong>the</strong> resp<strong>on</strong>sibility of understanding andcoming <strong>to</strong> a (possibly uncertain) point of view <strong>on</strong> <strong>the</strong>m; <strong>the</strong> evaluati<strong>on</strong> of statisticalevidence is <strong>on</strong>ly <strong>on</strong>e small part of “<strong>the</strong> whole scientific enterprise of re<strong>as</strong><strong>on</strong>ing about andevaluati<strong>on</strong> of evidence” (p. 342); and, finally, “if nothing else comes from <strong>the</strong> presentdebate, it will be immensely valuable if it destroys <strong>the</strong> sanguine reliance <strong>on</strong> ‘statisticalexperts’ that h<strong>as</strong> characterized <strong>the</strong> attitudes of many social scientists in <strong>the</strong> p<strong>as</strong>t” (p. 341).6.2. CONCEPTUAL ANALYSIS OF STATISTICS EDUCATION PRACTICEFrom a c<strong>on</strong>ceptual <strong>analysis</strong> point of view, <strong>the</strong> nature of our reliance <strong>on</strong> “experts” instatistics educati<strong>on</strong> is part of a general package that can best be described <strong>as</strong> a c<strong>as</strong>e ofpractical inc<strong>on</strong>sistency. Of course, practical inc<strong>on</strong>sistency within psychology is not


136restricted <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> teaching of statistics. For example, it appears also in <strong>the</strong> discrepancywithin <strong>qualitative</strong> methods between what is explicitly preached (antirealist relativism,including <strong>the</strong> rejecti<strong>on</strong> of <strong>the</strong> “procrustean” quantitative “psychometric trinity” of validity,generalisability, and reliability) and what is actually practised (implicit methodologicalrealism, adherence <strong>to</strong> <strong>qualitative</strong> counterparts of <strong>the</strong> psychometric trinity—viz. credibility,transferability, and dependability) (Lincoln & Guba, 2000). Any brief survey of <strong>the</strong>various handbooks of <strong>qualitative</strong> or mixed research methods (e.g., Denzin & Lincoln,2000; Flick, 2002; Potter, 1996; Richards<strong>on</strong>, 1996; T<strong>as</strong>hakkori & Teddlie, 2003b) willc<strong>on</strong>firm <strong>the</strong> existence of this discrepancy (Hammersley, 1989; but see Bryman, 1988, fora comprehensive and perceptive discussi<strong>on</strong> of <strong>the</strong> issues). This h<strong>as</strong> c<strong>on</strong>tributed <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong>reluctance of scientific psychologists pursuing quantitative methods <strong>to</strong> embrace<strong>qualitative</strong> methods <strong>as</strong> being of equal scientific merit and <strong>to</strong> integrate <strong>the</strong>m appropriatelyin <strong>the</strong>ir research methods courses. Within quantitative psychology in general and statisticseducati<strong>on</strong> in particular a similar (albeit c<strong>on</strong>verse and more disguised) discrepancy exists.Here, <strong>the</strong> philosophy that is explicitly preached is scientific realism, where<strong>as</strong> <strong>the</strong>methodology that is practised is an antirealist and unscientific form of scientificpracticalism.Scientific practicalism includes an instrumentalist view of science <strong>as</strong> directed <strong>to</strong>wardspractical ends, a c<strong>on</strong>cern with “what works.” In terms of our earlier cl<strong>as</strong>sificati<strong>on</strong> ofmethods, practicalism blurs <strong>the</strong> distincti<strong>on</strong> between methods of inquiry and mechanicalmethods. In statistics educati<strong>on</strong> in psychology, we pay lip service <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> scientistpractiti<strong>on</strong>ermodel and <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> goal of developing students in<strong>to</strong> critical c<strong>on</strong>sumers andc<strong>on</strong>duc<strong>to</strong>rs of psychological research. For example, <strong>the</strong> Australian PsychologyAccreditati<strong>on</strong> Council (APAC), <strong>the</strong> professi<strong>on</strong>al body that accredits psychology teachingprograms within universities, b<strong>as</strong>es its required standards <strong>on</strong> <strong>the</strong> scientist-practiti<strong>on</strong>ermodel. Am<strong>on</strong>gst <strong>the</strong>se standards, critical thinking skills are emph<strong>as</strong>ised (APAC, 2010;Tanner & Daniels<strong>on</strong>, 2007). However, we do not follow this in practice. In additi<strong>on</strong> t<strong>on</strong>eglecting c<strong>on</strong>ceptual <strong>analysis</strong> in <strong>the</strong> ways we have discussed, we typically train andreinforce students <strong>to</strong> treat statistical and data-analytic methods <strong>as</strong> a set of practicalrecipes, <strong>the</strong> blind implementati<strong>on</strong> of which ipso fac<strong>to</strong> guarantees <strong>the</strong> scientific credentialsof <strong>the</strong> researchers and <strong>the</strong> scientific value of any results.Moreover, unfortunately, we become role models for our students. We do <strong>as</strong> we are<strong>to</strong>ld—by journal edi<strong>to</strong>rs, psychological <strong>as</strong>sociati<strong>on</strong>s, accreditati<strong>on</strong> bodies, and so <strong>on</strong>. Weallow <strong>the</strong>se m<strong>as</strong>ters <strong>to</strong> dictate <strong>the</strong> f<strong>as</strong>hi<strong>on</strong>s that we follow, and make <strong>the</strong> decisi<strong>on</strong>s for us.For example, <strong>as</strong> Schmidt (1992) complains, “it h<strong>as</strong> been remarkably difficult <strong>to</strong> weansocial science researchers away from <strong>the</strong>ir entrancement with significance testing.… Thepsychology of addicti<strong>on</strong> <strong>to</strong> significance testing would be a f<strong>as</strong>cinating research area” (p.1176). Ir<strong>on</strong>ically, <strong>the</strong> terms “wean” and “addicti<strong>on</strong>” are appropriate, for <strong>the</strong>y imply aninfantile state of dependence. Accordingly, a t<strong>as</strong>k force w<strong>as</strong> created in 1996 by <strong>the</strong>American Psychological Associati<strong>on</strong> (APA) Board of Scientific Affairs <strong>to</strong> determinewhe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>to</strong> proscribe <strong>the</strong> use of NHST and replace it with CIs, that is, <strong>to</strong> “ph<strong>as</strong>e out”NHST from course texts and journal articles, thus c<strong>on</strong>straining teachers <strong>to</strong> change <strong>the</strong>ircourses, authors <strong>to</strong> revise <strong>the</strong>ir textbooks, and journal article authors <strong>to</strong> modify <strong>the</strong>irinference strategies (Hubbard, Parsa, & Luthy, 1997; Kirk, 1996). In <strong>the</strong> event, <strong>the</strong> t<strong>as</strong>kforce (quite re<strong>as</strong><strong>on</strong>ably) refused <strong>to</strong> ban NHST or p-values. Never<strong>the</strong>less, <strong>the</strong> pressuresc<strong>on</strong>tinue.For example, in a recent paper “Challenges for quantitative psychology andme<strong>as</strong>urement in <strong>the</strong> 21st century,” Osbourne (2010) notes,At this, <strong>the</strong> dawn of <strong>the</strong> 21st century, <strong>the</strong>re are remarkably promising signs.Researchers are beginning <strong>to</strong> understand that strict null hypo<strong>the</strong>sis statistical testing


137(NHST) is limiting and provides an incomplete picture of results. More journals nowrequire effect sizes, c<strong>on</strong>fidence intervals, and o<strong>the</strong>r practices <strong>on</strong>e might argue are welloverdue. (p. 2, emph<strong>as</strong>is added)He urges that <strong>on</strong>ly by challenging <strong>as</strong>sumpti<strong>on</strong>s can we be <strong>as</strong>sured of following <strong>the</strong>path of “best practice”:The world doesn’t need ano<strong>the</strong>r journal promulgating 20th century thinking,genuflecting at <strong>the</strong> altar of p < 0.05. I challenge us <strong>to</strong> challenge traditi<strong>on</strong>. Shrug off<strong>the</strong> shackles of 20th century methodology and thinking, and <strong>the</strong> next time you sitdown <strong>to</strong> examine your hard-earned data, challenge yourself <strong>to</strong> implement <strong>on</strong>e newmethodology that represents best practice. Use R<strong>as</strong>ch me<strong>as</strong>urement or IRT ra<strong>the</strong>r thanaveraging items <strong>to</strong> form scale scores. Calculate p (rep) in additi<strong>on</strong> <strong>to</strong> power and p. UseHLM <strong>to</strong> study change over time, or use propensity scores <strong>to</strong> create more soundcomparis<strong>on</strong> groups. Use meta-<strong>analysis</strong> <strong>to</strong> leverage <strong>the</strong> findings of dozens of studiesra<strong>the</strong>r than merely adding <strong>on</strong>e more <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> literature. Choose just <strong>on</strong>e best practice,and use it. (p. 3)This advice is proffered in <strong>the</strong> c<strong>on</strong>text of <strong>the</strong> author’s warning that “To blindly accept<strong>the</strong> dogma of <strong>the</strong> field without scholarly examinati<strong>on</strong> is <strong>to</strong> diminish what we do,” so “Wemust be vigilant, <strong>as</strong> researchers … <strong>to</strong> c<strong>on</strong>tinue questi<strong>on</strong>ing and examining our tacit<strong>as</strong>sumpti<strong>on</strong>s” (p. 1).Here, practical inc<strong>on</strong>sistency is enshrined in <strong>the</strong> message. C<strong>on</strong>ceptual <strong>analysis</strong> doesindeed require us <strong>to</strong> test our <strong>as</strong>sumpti<strong>on</strong>s. But which <strong>as</strong>sumpti<strong>on</strong>s? In this enthusi<strong>as</strong>ticrallying of <strong>the</strong> quantitative troops, <strong>the</strong>re is no awareness of <strong>the</strong> widespread failure <strong>to</strong>recognise, let al<strong>on</strong>e test, <strong>the</strong> b<strong>as</strong>ic <strong>as</strong>sumpti<strong>on</strong> underlying psychological me<strong>as</strong>urement ingeneral. Nor is <strong>the</strong>re any apparent awareness that <strong>the</strong> “promising signs” at <strong>the</strong> dawn of <strong>the</strong>21st century were already presented and discussed nearly a century earlier, sometimeseven by those who invented <strong>the</strong> techniques. There is no awareness of <strong>the</strong> invalidity at <strong>the</strong>heart of psychology’s c<strong>on</strong>cept of psychometric test validity. There is no acknowledgmentthat <strong>the</strong> altars of effect sizes, c<strong>on</strong>fidence intervals, R<strong>as</strong>ch me<strong>as</strong>urements, and <strong>the</strong> like areno more deserving of genuflecti<strong>on</strong> than that of p < 0.05.Psychology’s failure <strong>to</strong> engage in c<strong>on</strong>ceptual <strong>analysis</strong> “all <strong>the</strong> way down” means thatin <strong>the</strong> future it may become just <strong>as</strong> hard <strong>to</strong> “wean” researchers from <strong>the</strong>ir addicti<strong>on</strong> <strong>to</strong>meta-<strong>analysis</strong> and c<strong>on</strong>fidence intervals, or from any o<strong>the</strong>r statistical technique c<strong>on</strong>sideredat <strong>the</strong> time <strong>to</strong> be “best practice.” Those who are aware of <strong>the</strong> problems never<strong>the</strong>lessc<strong>on</strong>tinue <strong>to</strong> succumb <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> pressure <strong>to</strong> engage in a flawed practice; it guaranteespublicati<strong>on</strong>, c<strong>on</strong>tinued employment, professi<strong>on</strong>al development, and <strong>the</strong> respect of <strong>the</strong>scientific psychological community. According <strong>to</strong> Hubbard and Ryan (2000), “This al<strong>on</strong>eunderscores <strong>the</strong> degree <strong>to</strong> which SST h<strong>as</strong> attained <strong>the</strong> status of a methodologicalimprimatur that even <strong>the</strong> staunchest critics of its use must occ<strong>as</strong>i<strong>on</strong>ally bow down before”(p. 673).Hence, <strong>the</strong> replacement of inquiry methods with mechanical methods leads <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong>courting of error, in direct c<strong>on</strong>tr<strong>as</strong>t <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> aim of <strong>the</strong> core scientific method of criticalinquiry <strong>to</strong> address <strong>the</strong> possibility of error in order <strong>to</strong> reduce it. The teaching of statistics,just like <strong>the</strong> teaching of psychometrics, “actually subverts <strong>the</strong> scientific method” (Michell,2001, p. 211).The teaching of statistics in psychology also subverts our explicit ethical aims. AsFuredy (1978) points out in his discussi<strong>on</strong> of <strong>the</strong> prejudice against “negative” or “null”results, “<strong>the</strong> effect of such scientific prejudice <strong>on</strong> <strong>the</strong> progress of knowledge can be …every bit <strong>as</strong> dev<strong>as</strong>tating <strong>as</strong> <strong>the</strong> effects of racial prejudice <strong>on</strong> <strong>the</strong> life of a politicalcommunity” (p. 169). For example, it can lead <strong>to</strong> “<strong>the</strong> birth of seemingly indestructibleempirical generalizati<strong>on</strong>s which actually have little or no evidential b<strong>as</strong>is” (p. 177). The


138result is unc<strong>on</strong>scious double standards in our ethics. Fudging data is universallyc<strong>on</strong>demned; allowing our psychological “me<strong>as</strong>ures” <strong>to</strong> determine social or educati<strong>on</strong>alpolicies is not.Part of <strong>the</strong> problem lies in <strong>the</strong> fact that <strong>the</strong> various c<strong>on</strong>tributi<strong>on</strong>s in <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory andhis<strong>to</strong>ry of statistics, including <strong>the</strong> c<strong>on</strong>troversial issues c<strong>on</strong>cerning me<strong>as</strong>urement,probability, evidential inference, and so <strong>on</strong>, are omitted from our statistics and researchmethods textbooks, making it even more difficult <strong>to</strong> include <strong>the</strong>m in <strong>the</strong> curriculum and <strong>to</strong>examine <strong>the</strong>m critically. Psychologists in general are simply not exposed <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> debatesand criticisms relating <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir own statistical practices (cf. Halpin & Stam, 2006). Ofcourse, many of <strong>the</strong>m may be thankful for this. But it precludes access <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>to</strong>olsnecessary for implementing reform in <strong>the</strong> teaching of statistics.7. RECOMMENDATIONSIn <strong>the</strong> light of <strong>the</strong> results of our c<strong>on</strong>ceptual <strong>analysis</strong>, we offer three recommendati<strong>on</strong>sfor statistics educati<strong>on</strong> in psychology.First, statistics educati<strong>on</strong> should include a much broader c<strong>on</strong>text, both c<strong>on</strong>ceptual andsocio-his<strong>to</strong>rical. As indicated in our cl<strong>as</strong>sificati<strong>on</strong> of methods, statistics must first beappropriately c<strong>on</strong>textualised within scientific method in general, and specific empiricalresearch methods (quantitative, <strong>qualitative</strong>, and mixed) in particular (cf. Bryman, 1988). Itmust also encomp<strong>as</strong>s not <strong>on</strong>ly <strong>the</strong> underlying core c<strong>on</strong>cepts but also some of <strong>the</strong>c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s under which particular c<strong>on</strong>cepts and practices (including <strong>the</strong> use of variousstatistical techniques) were adopted and o<strong>the</strong>rs rejected, and <strong>the</strong>ir different implicati<strong>on</strong>s. Itmight be objected that this is an unrealistic counsel of perfecti<strong>on</strong>, for we simply do nothave <strong>the</strong> time or space <strong>to</strong> cover all <strong>the</strong> (admittedly useful) c<strong>on</strong>textual fac<strong>to</strong>rs. Just <strong>as</strong> it h<strong>as</strong>been argued that students cannot re<strong>as</strong><strong>on</strong>ably be expected <strong>to</strong> absorb and understand <strong>the</strong>complex ma<strong>the</strong>matical calculati<strong>on</strong>s that are involved in statistics, so it might equally beobjected that <strong>the</strong>y cannot re<strong>as</strong><strong>on</strong>ably be expected <strong>to</strong> understand <strong>the</strong> difficult c<strong>on</strong>ceptualc<strong>on</strong>tent involved in <strong>the</strong> various c<strong>on</strong>troversies regarding <strong>the</strong> nature of me<strong>as</strong>urement,probability, evidential inference, and so <strong>on</strong>. In any c<strong>as</strong>e, <strong>as</strong>sumpti<strong>on</strong>s are always involvedin any field of inquiry, and <strong>on</strong>e cannot be expected <strong>to</strong> commit <strong>on</strong>eself <strong>to</strong> a potentiallyinfinite regress of questi<strong>on</strong>ing and examining <strong>as</strong>sumpti<strong>on</strong>s. Our reply <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong>se objecti<strong>on</strong>sis that any awareness is better than n<strong>on</strong>e, and that all <strong>as</strong>sumpti<strong>on</strong>s are not equal. Some<strong>as</strong>sumpti<strong>on</strong>s are warranted and unc<strong>on</strong>troversial, o<strong>the</strong>rs are not; some are relevant, o<strong>the</strong>rsare not. Where an <strong>as</strong>sumpti<strong>on</strong> is c<strong>on</strong>troversial, relevant, and appears <strong>to</strong> be unwarranted, <strong>as</strong>cientific investiga<strong>to</strong>r cannot afford not <strong>to</strong> examine it. Just <strong>as</strong> Socrates claimed that, froman ethical point of view, an unexamined life is not worth leading, so, <strong>to</strong>o, from a scientificpoint of view, unexamined <strong>as</strong>sumpti<strong>on</strong>s are not worth holding, and unexamined practicesnot worth pursuing.Our sec<strong>on</strong>d recommendati<strong>on</strong> flows from <strong>the</strong> first and from our discussi<strong>on</strong> of scientificmethod <strong>as</strong> critical inquiry. Appropriate c<strong>on</strong>textualising of statistics within scientificmethod means that nei<strong>the</strong>r quantitative methods nor statistics can be taught <strong>as</strong> having aprivileged place within science or scientific research methods. As scientific methods mustbe attuned <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> nature of <strong>the</strong> phenomena being investigated, and because <strong>the</strong> phenomenaof interest will vary from <strong>on</strong>e scientific field <strong>to</strong> ano<strong>the</strong>r (e.g., physics deals moreobviously with quantitative structures), <strong>on</strong>e cannot legislate a priori <strong>on</strong> <strong>the</strong> relevance andvalue of quantitative methods. Clearly, <strong>as</strong> Michell (2004b) points out, “<strong>the</strong> fixati<strong>on</strong> up<strong>on</strong>quantitative methods that characterizes modern psychology really h<strong>as</strong> no justificati<strong>on</strong>given <strong>the</strong> realist understanding of science” (p. 307). Therefore, it is antiscientific forpsychology <strong>to</strong> c<strong>on</strong>tinue <strong>to</strong> insist that quantitative methods are somehow more scientific


139than are <strong>qualitative</strong> methods. Instead, nature c<strong>on</strong>tains a potentially infinite number ofpossible alternatives <strong>to</strong> quantitative structure, and so <strong>the</strong> mainstream psychologicalresearcher, no less than <strong>the</strong> student of psychology, should be prepared <strong>to</strong> explore novelempirical structures and appropriate ways of investigating <strong>the</strong>m, including ma<strong>the</strong>matically(Michell, 2001; cf. Resnick, 1997). It might be objected that, c<strong>on</strong>trary <strong>to</strong> this newmessage, quantitative and statistical methods just are accorded a privileged place, and it isuseless <strong>to</strong> protest. However, social privilege is not logical privilege. To c<strong>on</strong>flate <strong>the</strong>sociology with <strong>the</strong> logic of science is <strong>to</strong> join postmodernism and scientific irrati<strong>on</strong>alismand <strong>to</strong> retreat from <strong>the</strong> realist self-understanding of scientific psychology (Haack, 1996;Lambie, 1991; S<strong>to</strong>ve, 1991). Where statistics and quantitative methods have beenmistakenly allocated a privileged logical place, students will come <strong>to</strong> appreciate that thish<strong>as</strong> arisen not from <strong>the</strong> requirements of science per se but from social, political, and o<strong>the</strong>rforces.Our third recommendati<strong>on</strong> is that <strong>the</strong> current prescriptive teaching and researchpractices, being unjustified, need <strong>to</strong> be replaced by practices more in keeping with <strong>the</strong>spirit of <strong>the</strong> core scientific method of critical inquiry. Even if we cannot prevent <strong>the</strong>prescripti<strong>on</strong>s that appear in textbooks and are issued by t<strong>as</strong>k forces, professi<strong>on</strong>al<strong>as</strong>sociati<strong>on</strong>s, accreditati<strong>on</strong> bodies, and <strong>the</strong> like, we can pursue <strong>the</strong> scientific job of treating<strong>the</strong>m critically. We can follow Osbourne’s (2010) call <strong>to</strong> challenge <strong>as</strong>sumpti<strong>on</strong>s bychallenging also <strong>the</strong> implicit <strong>as</strong>sumpti<strong>on</strong>s <strong>on</strong> which his recommendati<strong>on</strong>s rest.Prescripti<strong>on</strong> in statistics educati<strong>on</strong> substitutes mechanical methods for methods of inquiry.Prescripti<strong>on</strong>s are appropriate for cooking recipes and building guidelines (although, evenin those c<strong>as</strong>es, <strong>the</strong>y are always c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>al—if you want <strong>to</strong> produce a cake that rises, <strong>the</strong>nyou must use self-raising flour or baking powder). It might be objected that this would be<strong>to</strong>o disillusi<strong>on</strong>ing for students, shaking <strong>the</strong>ir c<strong>on</strong>fidence in psychological science.However, <strong>as</strong> <strong>the</strong> term suggests, disillusi<strong>on</strong>ing students involves challenging and dispelling<strong>the</strong>ir illusi<strong>on</strong>s. Surely no h<strong>on</strong>est scientist knowingly aims <strong>to</strong> instil or reinforce illusi<strong>on</strong>s,including <strong>the</strong> illusi<strong>on</strong> that <strong>the</strong>re is a royal road <strong>to</strong> scientific certainty that comes fromdoing <strong>as</strong> <strong>on</strong>e is <strong>to</strong>ld. In any c<strong>as</strong>e, this move would be c<strong>on</strong>sistent with <strong>the</strong> “<strong>on</strong><strong>to</strong>logical”goal of educati<strong>on</strong>, helping students <strong>to</strong> gain <strong>the</strong> self-c<strong>on</strong>fidence that comes from becomingau<strong>the</strong>ntic. In our experience, students are quite resilient enough, and even enjoyic<strong>on</strong>ocl<strong>as</strong>m and its wake of creative opportunities, especially if <strong>the</strong>y perceive that <strong>the</strong>irteachers are compani<strong>on</strong>s <strong>on</strong> <strong>the</strong> same journey.It should be clear that we see our recommendati<strong>on</strong>s not <strong>as</strong> competing with some of <strong>the</strong>pedagogical c<strong>on</strong>clusi<strong>on</strong>s that are emerging from recent <strong>qualitative</strong> <strong>approach</strong>es <strong>to</strong> statisticseducati<strong>on</strong> research but <strong>as</strong> both supporting and supplementing <strong>the</strong>m. C<strong>on</strong>ceptual <strong>analysis</strong>reveals that <strong>the</strong> field of statistics is not <strong>as</strong> rigid and exact <strong>as</strong> it is typically portrayed, andits variability and uncertainty cannot be magically spirited away. Our recommendati<strong>on</strong> <strong>to</strong>teach statistics within its broader c<strong>on</strong>text reinforces <strong>the</strong> three recommendati<strong>on</strong>s made byGal and Ograjenšek (2010), and also sits comfortably al<strong>on</strong>gside calls (e.g., Pe<strong>to</strong>cz & Reid,2010) <strong>to</strong> broaden <strong>the</strong> learning c<strong>on</strong>text <strong>to</strong> include <strong>the</strong> student <strong>as</strong> pers<strong>on</strong> and <strong>as</strong> professi<strong>on</strong>al,and c<strong>on</strong>sider <strong>the</strong> value and meaning of statistics for <strong>the</strong> pers<strong>on</strong> and <strong>the</strong>ir life. We believethat, in a very profound way, exposure <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> uncertainty, variability, and inc<strong>on</strong>sistenciesin <strong>as</strong>sumpti<strong>on</strong>s about <strong>the</strong> c<strong>on</strong>tent and use of statistics will mirror and validate <strong>the</strong><strong>qualitative</strong> variability in <strong>the</strong> meanings of statistics for individuals. Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, usingc<strong>on</strong>ceptual <strong>analysis</strong> <strong>as</strong> a <strong>qualitative</strong> <strong>approach</strong> <strong>to</strong> statistics educati<strong>on</strong> research will result inpromoting c<strong>on</strong>ceptual <strong>analysis</strong> <strong>as</strong> a learner strategy, and, <strong>the</strong>reby, c<strong>on</strong>tributing <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong><strong>on</strong><strong>to</strong>logical goals of educati<strong>on</strong>, namely <strong>the</strong> transformati<strong>on</strong> of <strong>the</strong> pers<strong>on</strong> in<strong>to</strong> anaut<strong>on</strong>omous thinker.


1408. SOME CONCLUDING REMARKSWe are acutely aware that we have insufficient space here <strong>to</strong> detail and substantiate<strong>the</strong>se claims and explore <strong>the</strong> underlying issues <strong>as</strong> fully <strong>as</strong> <strong>the</strong>y warrant (that would be at<strong>as</strong>k for our several statistics and research methods courses). It would be nice if we could,via some quick-and-e<strong>as</strong>y summary, save <strong>the</strong> reader <strong>the</strong> time and effort required by <strong>the</strong>challenging t<strong>as</strong>k of examining all of <strong>the</strong> <strong>primary</strong> source material (e.g., <strong>the</strong> work ofMichell) from which we have built our c<strong>as</strong>e. But, even if that were possible, it wouldc<strong>on</strong>travene what we are proposing—that psychologists and <strong>the</strong>ir students should be in apositi<strong>on</strong> <strong>to</strong> examine <strong>the</strong> material carefully and critically for <strong>the</strong>mselves, before coming <strong>to</strong><strong>the</strong>ir own c<strong>on</strong>clusi<strong>on</strong>s. Having said that, we hope our sketch h<strong>as</strong> been sufficient <strong>to</strong> make<strong>the</strong> main point. The results of our c<strong>on</strong>ceptual <strong>analysis</strong> of statistics educati<strong>on</strong> inpsychology suggest that, if we wish <strong>to</strong> do more than merely pay lip service <strong>to</strong>c<strong>on</strong>temporary educati<strong>on</strong>al goals, we shall need <strong>to</strong> supplement our <strong>qualitative</strong>investigati<strong>on</strong>s in<strong>to</strong> our students’ c<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong>s and misc<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong>s of statistics by turning<strong>the</strong> research spotlight back <strong>on</strong><strong>to</strong> ourselves, our own understandings, and our teachingpractices.We have restricted our discussi<strong>on</strong> <strong>to</strong> statistics educati<strong>on</strong> in psychology, and leave it <strong>to</strong>o<strong>the</strong>rs <strong>to</strong> c<strong>on</strong>sider whe<strong>the</strong>r or not <strong>as</strong>pects of our <strong>analysis</strong> might extend bey<strong>on</strong>d psychologyin<strong>to</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r disciplines. Perhaps psychology is a special c<strong>as</strong>e; perhaps <strong>on</strong>ly in psychology is<strong>the</strong>re “c<strong>on</strong>fusi<strong>on</strong> and barrenness” that are attributable <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> combinati<strong>on</strong> of “experimentalmethods and c<strong>on</strong>ceptual c<strong>on</strong>fusi<strong>on</strong>” (Wittgenstein, 1953, p. 232); perhaps <strong>on</strong>ly inpsychology does <strong>the</strong> “powerful impact of disciplinary socializati<strong>on</strong> practices” (Good,2007, p. 286) c<strong>on</strong>stitute an almost insurmountable obstacle <strong>to</strong> scientific progress; perhaps<strong>on</strong>ly in psychology does <strong>the</strong> aversi<strong>on</strong> <strong>to</strong> examining <strong>as</strong>sumpti<strong>on</strong>s mean that “a great deal ofpsychological research might well rest <strong>on</strong> philosophical quicksand” (Green, 1992, p. 292);perhaps <strong>on</strong>ly in psychology does it happen that “Galloping empiricism, which is ourpresent occupati<strong>on</strong>al dise<strong>as</strong>e, d<strong>as</strong>hes forth like a headless horseman” (Allport, 1966, p. 3),such that “We find ourselves c<strong>on</strong>fused by our intemperate empiricism, which often yieldsunnameable fac<strong>to</strong>rs, arbitrary codes, unintelligible interacti<strong>on</strong> effects, and sheer flatulencefrom our computers” (p. 8).If we have given <strong>the</strong> impressi<strong>on</strong> that statistics educati<strong>on</strong> in psychology is sometimes ac<strong>as</strong>e of <strong>the</strong> unaware leading <strong>the</strong> naïve in<strong>to</strong> error, <strong>the</strong>n we make no apologies. For, <strong>on</strong> anythorough and disp<strong>as</strong>si<strong>on</strong>ate scrutiny, <strong>the</strong> evidence is overwhelming. Mainstreampsychology’s obsessi<strong>on</strong> with being “scientific” h<strong>as</strong> led, ir<strong>on</strong>ically, via its marriage-ofc<strong>on</strong>veniencewith statistics and quantitative methods and its devaluing of <strong>qualitative</strong><strong>approach</strong>es (including c<strong>on</strong>ceptual <strong>analysis</strong>) <strong>to</strong> an instituti<strong>on</strong>alised disguising of <strong>the</strong>problems and misc<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong>s in its psychometric, data-analytic, and statistics educati<strong>on</strong>practices.But we cannot h<strong>on</strong>estly claim <strong>to</strong> be surprised by this. As psychologists, we are all <strong>to</strong>oaware of <strong>the</strong> fact that <strong>the</strong> mind is not a unity but a society of competing impulses, and thatgenuinely scientific c<strong>on</strong>cerns can so e<strong>as</strong>ily be displaced or subverted by social, political,and ec<strong>on</strong>omic interests, especially if <strong>the</strong> latter are indeed well-served by <strong>the</strong> currentpractices of <strong>the</strong> profit-driven academic instituti<strong>on</strong>s (Nussbaum, 2010). It is <strong>the</strong>refore quiteunderstandable that so much of mainstream psychology is engaged in what Chomsky(1959/1964) identified <strong>as</strong> “a kind of play acting at science” (p. 559).Never<strong>the</strong>less, we are cautiously optimistic. For, <strong>as</strong> Bennett and Hacker (2003) poin<strong>to</strong>ut in <strong>the</strong>ir exhaustive critique of c<strong>on</strong>temporary cognitive neuroscience, “C<strong>on</strong>ceptualentanglement can coexist with flourishing science.… Hidden reefs do not imply that <strong>the</strong>reefs are not navigable, <strong>on</strong>ly that <strong>the</strong>y are dangerous. The moot questi<strong>on</strong> is how running


141<strong>on</strong> <strong>the</strong>se reefs is manifest” (p. 5). Our positive message emerges from three of <strong>the</strong> manyir<strong>on</strong>ies in this s<strong>to</strong>ry. First, c<strong>on</strong>ceptual <strong>analysis</strong> of statistics educati<strong>on</strong> in psychologyproduces evidence that <strong>on</strong>e of <strong>the</strong> major problems h<strong>as</strong> been <strong>the</strong> neglect of c<strong>on</strong>ceptual<strong>analysis</strong> within <strong>the</strong> research methods teaching programs. Because critical inquiry is <strong>the</strong>core method of science, c<strong>on</strong>ceptual <strong>analysis</strong> could perhaps be “re-marketed” byharnessing <strong>the</strong> motivati<strong>on</strong>s of psychologists; it could be gently reintroduced <strong>as</strong> a way ofreinforcing and enriching psychology’s scientific goal and its commitments <strong>to</strong> evidenceb<strong>as</strong>edpractice (Machado & Silva, 2007). Next, if it is <strong>the</strong> c<strong>as</strong>e, <strong>as</strong> <strong>the</strong> evidence suggests,that methodological thinking in psychology h<strong>as</strong> g<strong>on</strong>e <strong>as</strong>tray over <strong>the</strong> l<strong>as</strong>t 60 years(Toomela & Valsiner, 2010), it may turn out that, in bringing it back <strong>on</strong> track, we come <strong>to</strong>agree that <strong>the</strong> marriage between psychology and statistics w<strong>as</strong> indeed made in hell and isbest off heading for <strong>the</strong> divorce court—albeit not for <strong>the</strong> student-percepti<strong>on</strong> re<strong>as</strong><strong>on</strong>s wec<strong>on</strong>sidered at <strong>the</strong> outset; ra<strong>the</strong>r, in terms of <strong>the</strong> subject matter of <strong>the</strong> two disciplines, <strong>the</strong>relati<strong>on</strong>ship is more appropriately that of acquaintances who are occ<strong>as</strong>i<strong>on</strong>al fruitfulcollabora<strong>to</strong>rs than that of intimate l<strong>on</strong>g-term bedfellows. Finally, c<strong>on</strong>ceptual <strong>analysis</strong>reveals an additi<strong>on</strong>al way in which statistics educati<strong>on</strong> can move bey<strong>on</strong>d <strong>the</strong> mere“epistemological” focus and achieve <strong>the</strong> deepest possible form of “<strong>on</strong><strong>to</strong>logical” goal.Here, <strong>the</strong> self-transformati<strong>on</strong> of its students (no less than its teachers) will come in <strong>the</strong>shape of <strong>the</strong> familiar Socratic ir<strong>on</strong>y: The greater <strong>the</strong> field of our awareness andunderstanding, <strong>the</strong> more we can transform from mute followers of rigid authoritarianprescripti<strong>on</strong>s in<strong>to</strong> au<strong>the</strong>ntic and willing embracers of aporia and enlightened ignorance.REFERENCESAllport, G. (1966). Traits revisited. American Psychologist, 21(1), 1–10.Australian Psychology Accreditati<strong>on</strong> Council (2010). Rules for accreditati<strong>on</strong> andaccreditati<strong>on</strong> standards for psychology courses.[Online:http://www.apac.psychology.org.au/Assets/Files/APAC_Rules_for%20_Accreditati<strong>on</strong>_and_Accreditati<strong>on</strong>_Standards_for%20_Psychology_Courses_Ver_10_June_2010.pdf ]Barnett, R. (2007). A will <strong>to</strong> learn: Being a student in an age of uncertainty. Buckingham,UK: Society for research in Higher Educati<strong>on</strong>, Open University Press.B<strong>as</strong>sham, G., Irwin, W., Nard<strong>on</strong>e, H., & Wallace, J. M. (2008). Critical thinking: Astudent’s introducti<strong>on</strong> (3 rd ed.). Bost<strong>on</strong>: McGraw Hill.Belar, C. D., & Perry, N. W. (Eds.). (1991). Proceedings: Nati<strong>on</strong>al c<strong>on</strong>ference <strong>on</strong>scientist-practiti<strong>on</strong>er educati<strong>on</strong>. Sar<strong>as</strong>ota, FL: Professi<strong>on</strong>al Resource Exchange.Bennett, M. R., & Hacker, P. M. S. (2003). Philosophical foundati<strong>on</strong>s of neuroscience.Oxford: Blackwell.Bickhard, M. H. (1992). Myths of science. Theory & Psychology, 2(3), 321–337.Bijker, M., Wynants, G., & van Buuren, H. (2006). A comparative study of <strong>the</strong> effects ofmotivati<strong>on</strong>al and attitudinal fac<strong>to</strong>rs <strong>on</strong> studying statistics. In A. Rossman & B. Chance(Eds.), Working cooperatively in statistics educati<strong>on</strong>: Proceedings of <strong>the</strong> SeventhInternati<strong>on</strong>al C<strong>on</strong>ference <strong>on</strong> Teaching Statistics, Salvador, Brazil. [CDROM].Voorburg, The Ne<strong>the</strong>rlands: Internati<strong>on</strong>al Statistical Institute.[Online: http://www.stat.auckland.ac.nz/~i<strong>as</strong>e/publicati<strong>on</strong>s/17/5H2_BIJK.pdf ]Bowker, G., & Star, S. (2000). Sorting things out: Cl<strong>as</strong>sificati<strong>on</strong> and its c<strong>on</strong>sequences.Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.Bryman, A. (1988). Quantity and quality in social research. L<strong>on</strong>d<strong>on</strong>: Unwin Hyman.Carnap, R. (1966). Philosophical foundati<strong>on</strong>s of physics. New York: B<strong>as</strong>ic Books.Chiesi, F., & Primi, C. (2010). Cognitive and n<strong>on</strong>-cognitive fac<strong>to</strong>rs related <strong>to</strong> students’statistics achievement. Statistics Educati<strong>on</strong> Research Journal, 9(1), 6–26.[Online: http://www.stat.auckland.ac.nz/~i<strong>as</strong>e/serj/SERJ9%281%29_Chiesi_Primi.pdf ]


142Chomsky, N. (1964). A review of B. F. Skinner’s Verbal behavior. In J. A. Fodor & J. J.Katz (Eds.), The structure of language: Readings in <strong>the</strong> philosophy of language (pp.547–578). Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall. (Reprinted from Language, 1959, 35,26–58)Cohen, M. R., & Nagel, E. (1934). An introducti<strong>on</strong> <strong>to</strong> logic and scientific method.L<strong>on</strong>d<strong>on</strong>: Routledge & Kegan Paul.Crombie, A. C. (1994). Styles of scientific thinking in <strong>the</strong> European traditi<strong>on</strong>. L<strong>on</strong>d<strong>on</strong>:Duckworth.Denzin, N. K., & Lincoln, Y. S. (Eds.). (1994). Handbook of <strong>qualitative</strong> research.Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.Denzin, N. K., & Lincoln, Y. S. (Eds.). (2000). Handbook of <strong>qualitative</strong> research (2 nded.). Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.Flick, U. (2002). An introducti<strong>on</strong> <strong>to</strong> <strong>qualitative</strong> research (2 nd ed.). L<strong>on</strong>d<strong>on</strong>: Sage.Freud, S. (1975). Lecture XXXV. The questi<strong>on</strong> of a Weltanschauung. In J. Strachey (Ed.& Trans.), The standard editi<strong>on</strong> of <strong>the</strong> complete psychological works of SigmundFreud (Vol. 22, pp. 158–182). L<strong>on</strong>d<strong>on</strong>: Hogarth Press. (Original work published1933)Friedman, M. (1991). The re-evaluati<strong>on</strong> of logical positivism. Journal of Philosophy,88(10), 505–19.Friedman, M. (1999). Rec<strong>on</strong>sidering logical positivism. Cambridge, MA: CambridgeUniversity Press.Furedy, J. J. (1978). Negative results: Abolish <strong>the</strong> name but h<strong>on</strong>our <strong>the</strong> same. In J. P.Sutcliffe (Ed.), C<strong>on</strong>ceptual <strong>analysis</strong> and method in psychology. Essays in h<strong>on</strong>our ofW. M. O’Neil. Sydney: Sydney University Press.Gal, I., & Ograjenšek, I. (2010). Qualitative research in <strong>the</strong> service of understandinglearners and users of statistics. Internati<strong>on</strong>al Statistical Review, 78(2), 287–296.Gigerenzer, G. (1987). Probabilistic thinking and <strong>the</strong> fight against subjectivity. In L.Krüger, G. Gigerenzer, & M. Morgan (Eds.), The probabilistic revoluti<strong>on</strong> (Vol. 2, pp.11–36). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Gigerenzer, G. (1993). The superego, <strong>the</strong> ego, and <strong>the</strong> id in statistical re<strong>as</strong><strong>on</strong>ing. In G.Keren & C. Lewis (Eds.), A handbook for data <strong>analysis</strong> in <strong>the</strong> behavioral sciences:Methodological issues (pp. 311–339). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.Gigerenzer, G., & Murray, D. J. (1987). Cogniti<strong>on</strong> <strong>as</strong> intuitive statistics. Hillsdale, NJ:Lawrence Erlbaum.Good, J. M. M. (2007). The affordances for social psychology of <strong>the</strong> ecological <strong>approach</strong><strong>to</strong> social knowing. Theory & Psychology, 17(2), 265–295.Grays<strong>on</strong>, D. A. (1988). Limitati<strong>on</strong> <strong>on</strong> <strong>the</strong> use of scales in psychiatry. Australian & NewZealand Journal of Psychiatry, 22(1), 99–108.Grays<strong>on</strong>, D. A. (1998). The frequentist façade and <strong>the</strong> flight from evidential inference.British Journal of Psychology, 83(2), 325–45.Grays<strong>on</strong>, D. A., & Oliphant, G. W. (1996). Multiple inference procedures: Problems andsoluti<strong>on</strong>s. In C. R. Latimer & J. Michell (Eds.), At <strong>on</strong>ce scientific and philosophic: AFestschrift for John Philip Sutcliffe (pp. 23–46). Brisbane: Boombana Publicati<strong>on</strong>s.Green, C. D. (1992). Of immortal mythological be<strong>as</strong>ts. Theory & Psychology, 2(3), 291–320.Haack, S. (1996). Towards a sober sociology of science. In P. R. Gross (Ed.), The flightfrom science and re<strong>as</strong><strong>on</strong> (pp. 259–65). New York: Annals of <strong>the</strong> New York Academyof Sciences.Haack, S. (2003). Defending science—within re<strong>as</strong><strong>on</strong>: Between scientism and cynicism.New York: Prome<strong>the</strong>us Books.


143Halpin, P. F., & Stam, H. J. (2006). Inductive inference or inductive behavior: Fisher andNeyman-Pears<strong>on</strong> <strong>approach</strong>es <strong>to</strong> statistical testing in psychological research. AmericanJournal of Psychology, 119(4), 625–653.Hammersley, M. (1989). The dilemma of <strong>qualitative</strong> method: Herbert Blumer and <strong>the</strong>Chicago traditi<strong>on</strong>. L<strong>on</strong>d<strong>on</strong>: Routledge.Henwood, K. (1996). Qualitative inquiry: perspectives, methods and psychology. In J. T.E. Richards<strong>on</strong> (Ed.), Handbook of <strong>qualitative</strong> research methods (pp. 25–40). Oxford:BPS Blackwell.Herschel, J. F. W. (1987). A preliminary discourse <strong>on</strong> <strong>the</strong> study of natural philosophy.Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Hibberd, F. J. (2005). Unfolding social c<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong>ism. New York: Springer.Hubbard, R., Parsa, R. A., & Luthy, M. R. (1997). The spread of statistical significancetesting in psychology. The c<strong>as</strong>e of <strong>the</strong> Journal of Applied Psychology, 1917–1994.Theory & Psychology, 7(4), 545–554.Hubbard, R., & Ryan, P. (2000). The his<strong>to</strong>rical growth of statistical significance testing inpsychology—and its future prospects. Educati<strong>on</strong>al and Psychological Me<strong>as</strong>urement,60(5), 661–681.Janesick, V. J. (2000). The choreography of <strong>qualitative</strong> research design. In N. K. Denzin& Y. S. Lincoln (Eds.), Handbook of <strong>qualitative</strong> research (2 nd ed.) (pp. 379–399).Thousand Oaks: Sage.Kalinowski, P., Lai, J., Fidler, F., & Cumming, G. (2010). Qualitative research: Anessential part of statistical cogniti<strong>on</strong>. Statistics Educati<strong>on</strong> Research Journal, 9(2), 22-34.[Online: http://www.stat.auckland.ac.nz/~i<strong>as</strong>e/serj/SERJ9%282%29_Kalinowski.pdf ]Kerr, N. L. (1998). HARKing: Hypo<strong>the</strong>sizing after <strong>the</strong> results are known. Pers<strong>on</strong>ality andSocial Psychology Review, 2(3), 196–217.Kirk, R. E. (1996). Practical significance: A c<strong>on</strong>cept whose time h<strong>as</strong> come. Educati<strong>on</strong>aland Psychological Me<strong>as</strong>urement, 56(5), 746–759.Lal<strong>on</strong>de, R. N., & Gardner, R. C. (1993). Statistics <strong>as</strong> a sec<strong>on</strong>d language? A model forpredicting performance in psychology students. Canadian Journal of BehaviouralScience, 25(1), 108–125.Lambie, J. (1991). The misuse of Kuhn in psychology. The Psychologist: Bulletin of <strong>the</strong>British Psychological Society, 1, 6–11.Leahey, T. H. (2004). A his<strong>to</strong>ry of psychology. Main currents in psychological thought(6 th ed.). New Jersey: Pears<strong>on</strong> Educati<strong>on</strong>.Levitt, N. (2001). The sources and dangers of postmodern anti-science: Do <strong>the</strong>seintellectual popguns matter? Free Inquiry, 21(2), 44–47.Lincoln, Y. S., & Guba, E. G. (2000). Paradigmatic c<strong>on</strong>troversies, c<strong>on</strong>tradicti<strong>on</strong>s, andemerging c<strong>on</strong>fluences. In N. K. Denzin & Y. S. Lincoln (Eds.), Handbook of<strong>qualitative</strong> research (2 nd ed., pp. 163–188). Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.Lissitz, R. W. (Ed.). (2009). The c<strong>on</strong>cept of validity. Revisi<strong>on</strong>s, new directi<strong>on</strong>s, andapplicati<strong>on</strong>s. Charlotte, NC: Informati<strong>on</strong> Age Publishing Inc.Machado, A., & Silva, F. J. (2007). Toward a richer view of <strong>the</strong> scientific method. Therole of c<strong>on</strong>ceptual <strong>analysis</strong>. American Psychologist, 62(7), 671–681.Mackay, N., & Pe<strong>to</strong>cz, A. (Eds.). (in press). Realism and psychology: Collected essays.Leiden: Brill.Medawar, P. B. (1969). Inducti<strong>on</strong> and intuiti<strong>on</strong> in scientific thought. L<strong>on</strong>d<strong>on</strong>: Methuen &Co Ltd.Michell, J. (1990). An introducti<strong>on</strong> <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> logic of psychological me<strong>as</strong>urement. Hillsdale,NJ: Erlbaum.


144Michell, J. (1997). Quantitative science and <strong>the</strong> definiti<strong>on</strong> of me<strong>as</strong>urement in psychology.British Journal of Psychology, 88(3), 355–83.Michell, J. (1999). Me<strong>as</strong>urement in psychology: A critical his<strong>to</strong>ry of a methodologicalc<strong>on</strong>cept. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Michell, J. (2000). Normal science, pathological science and psychometrics. Theory &Psychology, 10(5), 639–667.Michell, J. (2001). Teaching and misteaching me<strong>as</strong>urement in psychology. AustralianPsychologist, 36(3), 211–217.Michell, J. (2002). Stevens’s <strong>the</strong>ory of scales of me<strong>as</strong>urement and its place in modernpsychology. Australian Journal of Psychology, 54(2), 99–104.Michell, J. (2003). The quantitative imperative: Positivism, naïve realism and <strong>the</strong> place of<strong>qualitative</strong> methods in Psychology. Theory & Psychology, 13(1), 5–31.Michell, J. (2004a). Item resp<strong>on</strong>se models, pathological science and <strong>the</strong> shape of error:Reply <strong>to</strong> Boorsboom and Mellenbergh. Theory & Psychology, 14(1), 121–129.Michell, J. (2004b). The place of <strong>qualitative</strong> research in psychology. Qualitative Researchin Psychology, 1(4), 307–319.Michell, J. (2008). Is psychometrics pathological science? Me<strong>as</strong>urement:Interdisciplinary Research and Perspectives, 6(1 & 2), 7–24.Michell, J. (2009a). The psychometricians’ fallacy: Too clever by half? British Journal ofMa<strong>the</strong>matical and Statistical Psychology, 62(1), 41–55.Michell, J. (2009b). Invalidity in validity. In R. W. Lissitz (Ed.), The c<strong>on</strong>cept of validity.Revisi<strong>on</strong>s, new directi<strong>on</strong>s, and applicati<strong>on</strong>s (pp. 111–133). Charlotte, NC:Informati<strong>on</strong> Age Publishing Inc.Michell, J. (2010). The quantity/quality interchange. A blind spot <strong>on</strong> <strong>the</strong> highway ofscience. In A. Toomela & J. Valsiner (Eds.), Methodological thinking in psychology:60 years g<strong>on</strong>e <strong>as</strong>tray? (pp. 45–68). Charlotte, NC: Informati<strong>on</strong> Age Publishing Inc.Neyman, J., & Pears<strong>on</strong>, E. S. (1933). On <strong>the</strong> problem of most efficient tests of statisticalhypo<strong>the</strong>ses. Philosophical Transacti<strong>on</strong>s of <strong>the</strong> Royal Society of L<strong>on</strong>d<strong>on</strong>, A, 231, 289–337.Nussbaum, M. (2010, April 30). Skills for life. Why cuts in humanities teaching pose athreat <strong>to</strong> democracy itself. Times Literary Supplement, pp. 13–15.Oliphant, G. W., & Grays<strong>on</strong>, D. A. (1996). Some misc<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong>s c<strong>on</strong>cerning post hocstatistical hypo<strong>the</strong>sis testing. In C. R. Latimer & J. Michell (Eds.), At <strong>on</strong>ce scientificand philosophic: A Festschrift for John Philip Sutcliffe (pp. 47–56). Brisbane:Boombana Publicati<strong>on</strong>s.Osborne, J. W. (2010). Challenges for quantitative psychology and me<strong>as</strong>urement in <strong>the</strong>21st century. Fr<strong>on</strong>tiers in Psychology, 1(1), 1–3.Pe<strong>to</strong>cz, A. (2004). Science, meaning and <strong>the</strong> scientist-practiti<strong>on</strong>er model of treatment. InD. J<strong>on</strong>es (Ed.), Working with dangerous people (pp. 25–42). Oxford: RadcliffeMedical Press.Pe<strong>to</strong>cz, A. (in press). Re-thinking <strong>the</strong> place of semiotics in psychology and itsimplicati<strong>on</strong>s for psychological research. In S. C. Hamel (Ed.), Semiotics: Theory andapplicati<strong>on</strong>s. New York: Nova Science.Pe<strong>to</strong>cz, P., & Reid, A. (2010). On becoming a statistician: A <strong>qualitative</strong> view.Internati<strong>on</strong>al Statistical Review, 78(2), 271–286.Pe<strong>to</strong>cz, P., & Sowey, E. (2010). Statistical diversi<strong>on</strong>s. Teaching Statistics, 32(2), 60–64.Porter, T. M. (1995). Trust in numbers: The pursuit of objectivity in science and publiclife. Princet<strong>on</strong>: Princet<strong>on</strong> University Press.Potter, W. J. (1996). An <strong>analysis</strong> of thinking and research about <strong>qualitative</strong> methods.Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.


145Resnick, M. D. (1997). Ma<strong>the</strong>matics <strong>as</strong> a science of patterns. Oxford: Oxford UniversityPress.Richards<strong>on</strong>, J. T. E. (1996). Handbook of <strong>qualitative</strong> research methods. Oxford: BPSBlackwell.Rosenthal, R. (1979). The “file drawer problem” and <strong>to</strong>lerance for null results.Psychological Bulletin, 86(3), 638–641.Rosnow, R. L., & Rosenthal, R. (1989). Statistical procedures and <strong>the</strong> justificati<strong>on</strong> ofknowledge in psychological science. American Psychologist, 44(10), 1276–84.Rozeboom, W. (1960). The fallacy of <strong>the</strong> null hypo<strong>the</strong>sis significance test. PsychologicalBulletin, 57(5), 416–428.Schmidt, F. L. (1992). What do data really mean? Research findings, meta-<strong>analysis</strong>, andcumulative knowledge in psychology. American Psychologist, 47(10), 1173–1181.Solovey, M. (2004). Riding natural scientists’ coattails <strong>on</strong><strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> endless fr<strong>on</strong>tier: TheSSRC and <strong>the</strong> quest for scientific legitimacy. Journal of <strong>the</strong> His<strong>to</strong>ry of <strong>the</strong> BehavioralSciences, 40(4), 393–422.Stevens, S. S. (1946). On <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory of scales of me<strong>as</strong>urement. Science, 103(2684), 667–680.S<strong>to</strong>ve, D. C. (1991). The Pla<strong>to</strong> cult and o<strong>the</strong>r philosophical follies. Oxford: Blackwell.Tanner, P. L., & Daniels<strong>on</strong>, M. L. (2007). Comp<strong>on</strong>ents necessary for <strong>the</strong> preparati<strong>on</strong> of<strong>the</strong> scientist-practiti<strong>on</strong>er. American Behavioral Scientist, 50(6), 772–777.T<strong>as</strong>hakkori, A., & Teddlie, C. (2003a). The p<strong>as</strong>t and future of mixed methods research:From data triangulati<strong>on</strong> <strong>to</strong> mixed model designs. In A. T<strong>as</strong>hakkori & C. Teddlie(Eds.), Handbook of mixed methods in social and behavioral research (pp. 671–701).Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.T<strong>as</strong>hakkori, A., & Teddlie, C. (Eds.). (2003b). Handbook of mixed methods in social andbehavioral research. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.Teddlie, C., & T<strong>as</strong>hakkori, A. (2003). Major issues and c<strong>on</strong>troversies in <strong>the</strong> use of mixedmethods in <strong>the</strong> social and behavioural sciences. In A. T<strong>as</strong>hakkori & C. Teddlie (Eds.),Handbook of mixed methods in social and behavioral research (pp. 3–50). ThousandOaks, CA: Sage.Toomela, A., & Valsiner, J. (Eds.). (2010). Methodological thinking in psychology: 60years g<strong>on</strong>e <strong>as</strong>tray? Charlotte, NC: Informati<strong>on</strong> Age Publishing Inc.Triplett, T. (1988). Azande logic versus Western logic? British Journal for <strong>the</strong> Philosophyof Science, 39(3), 361–366.van Buuren, H. (2006). Teaching statistics and research methods: An integrated <strong>approach</strong>.In A. Rossman & B. Chance (Eds.), Working cooperatively in statistics educati<strong>on</strong>:Proceedings of <strong>the</strong> Seventh Internati<strong>on</strong>al C<strong>on</strong>ference <strong>on</strong> Teaching Statistics, Salvador,Brazil. [CDROM]. Voorburg, The Ne<strong>the</strong>rlands: Internati<strong>on</strong>al Statistical Institute.[Online: http://www.stat.auckland.ac.nz/~i<strong>as</strong>e/publicati<strong>on</strong>s/17/3H1_VANB.pdf ]Wiberg, M. (2009). Teaching statistics in integrati<strong>on</strong> with psychology. Journal ofStatistics Educati<strong>on</strong>, 17(1).[Online: http://www.amstat.org/publicati<strong>on</strong>s/jse/v17n1/wiberg.html ]Wittgenstein, L. (1953). Philosophical investigati<strong>on</strong>s (G. E. M. Anscombe, Trans.).Oxford: Blackwell.AGNES PETOCZSchool of Psychology, University of Western Sydney - Banks<strong>to</strong>wnLocked Bag 1797, South Penrith DC NSW 1797Australia

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!