05.10.2015 Views

Fall 2015

Vol_42_1

Vol_42_1

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS
  • No tags were found...

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

3 2 I n t e r p r e t a t i o n Volume 42 / Issue 1<br />

because his activity as a philosopher was believed to be harmful to the city.<br />

Socrates’s unusual defense mitigated the public’s hostility toward him by<br />

making the audience believe in his virtue. Through this tactic, he was aiming<br />

to preserve philosophy’s position in Athens after his death. The present<br />

study aims to clarify the notion of virtue that Socrates claimed to possess. It<br />

further explains how he employed a rhetorical technique called megalēgoria<br />

(literally, “big talk” or boasting) to attain a good reputation for himself and<br />

for philosophy via his death sentence.<br />

In recent scholarship on Socrates, the value of Xenophon’s works has<br />

often been underestimated. 1 The root of the popular neglect of Xenophon’s<br />

works is his alleged lack of comprehension for and appreciation of Socrates’s<br />

philosophy. It is commonly thought that Xenophon’s limited understanding—owed<br />

to the fact that he was, at most, a country gentleman—trivialized<br />

the teachings of Socrates. His Socrates is regarded as a banal moralist who<br />

merely repeats commonplace sermons. 2<br />

This view is reflected in the common interpretation of the Apology,<br />

according to which Xenophon’s Socrates preferred death to life before the<br />

trial began, because he was anticipating the burdens of old age. Hence, he<br />

intentionally brought about capital punishment by provoking the jury. 3 Here<br />

Xenophon’s account seems to focus on corporeal pleasure and pain, missing<br />

the core of Socratic philosophy. John Burnet attributes this misapprehension<br />

to the shallowness of Xenophon, who could not accept the forensic failure of<br />

his teacher or understand the philosophical depth of Socrates’s conduct. Burnet<br />

argues that Xenophon could not comprehend the loftiness of the Socratic<br />

1<br />

Robert C. Bartlett, editor’s introduction to Xenophon: The Shorter Socratic Writings (Ithaca, NY:<br />

Cornell University Press, 1996), 1–8.<br />

2<br />

John Burnet, Plato’s Phaedo (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1925), xii–xxxviii; Coleman Phillipson,<br />

The Trial of Socrates (London: Stevens, 1928), 26, 31; Anton-Hermann Chroust, Socrates,<br />

Man and Myth: The Two Socratic Apologies of Xenophon (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame<br />

Press, 1957), 1–16; W. K. C. Guthrie, Socrates (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1971), 14–15;<br />

Victorino Tejera, “Ideology and Literature: Xenophon’s Defense of Socrates and Plato’s Apology,” in<br />

New Essays on Socrates, ed. Eugene Kelly (Lanham, MD: University Press of America, 1984), 156;<br />

John M. Cooper, “Notes on Xenophon’s Socrates,” in Reason and Emotion: Essays on Ancient Moral<br />

Psychology and Ethical Theory (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1999), 4–9, 22; C. D. C. Reeve,<br />

ed., The Trials of Socrates (Indianapolis, IN: Hackett, 2002), 177. Cf. Luis E. Navia, “A Reappraisal of<br />

Xenophon’s Apology,” in New Essays on Socrates, ed. Kelly, 47–48; Donald Morrison, “On Professor<br />

Vlastos’ Xenophon,” Ancient Philosophy 7 (1987): 9.<br />

3<br />

R. E. Allen, Socrates and Legal Obligation (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1980), 35;<br />

Navia, “A Reappraisal of Xenophon’s Apology,” 59–62; Thomas C. Brickhouse and Nicholas D. Smith,<br />

Socrates on Trial (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1989), 60–61; Cooper, “Notes on Xenophon’s<br />

Socrates,” 12.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!