05.10.2015 Views

Fall 2015

Vol_42_1

Vol_42_1

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS
  • No tags were found...

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

6 I n t e r p r e t a t i o n Volume 42 / Issue 1<br />

of the possibility of rationality achieving victory over the irrational or subrational.<br />

On the other hand it would also seem to mean that we are not morally<br />

responsible for our failings in the way that we often believe ourselves to be.<br />

Aristotle’s putative agreement with Socrates would seem not only to further<br />

the depreciation of moral virtue, but also and more importantly to replace<br />

moral virtue with a new kind of virtue, governed by knowledge. This new virtue<br />

promises to be the source of right and good action, thereby pointing to an<br />

intellectual life that is superior to and distinct from the life of moral virtue.<br />

The analysis provided in our essay takes a different approach. While we<br />

too think that Aristotle affirms the Socratic thesis as having these implications<br />

for incontinence, we also think that Aristotle’s argument contains a<br />

subtle questioning of continence itself; his discussion offers little reason to<br />

think that continence can be achieved or that it is good. Aristotle shows that a<br />

continence that is superior or identical to virtue would require the possession<br />

of a scientific knowledge (epistēmē). This scientific knowledge would allow for<br />

continence insofar as “we all suppose that what we know scientifically does<br />

not admit of being otherwise” (1139b20). And if such a precise knowledge is<br />

possible, then it could become the foundation of right human action, for it<br />

could perfect the formerly less than exacting judgment of moral virtue under<br />

the guidance of prudence. 5 It is therefore fitting that Aristotle begins and<br />

ends his presentation of continence and incontinence with a discussion of<br />

the place of the human in relation to the divine, for if a scientific knowledge<br />

of human action could be achieved, then it might even provide the grounds<br />

for human action to reach completion in a way that permits it to become an<br />

object of contemplation.<br />

We will show, however, that although Aristotle’s analysis of the Socratic<br />

thesis means to raise these possibilities, it is ultimately designed to demonstrate<br />

the difficulty of human beings achieving this scientific knowledge, or of<br />

using it to direct their actions. In other words, while we agree that his account<br />

of incontinence sides with the Socratic position insofar as it shows the impossibility<br />

of acting against scientific knowledge, we argue that his analysis<br />

also suggests the need to question the continence that that same scientific<br />

knowledge would require. Aristotle shows the need to question not only<br />

incontinence, but also the possibility of continence, and therefore to wonder<br />

whether our desire to bind science to human action is good. Underscoring and<br />

5<br />

Schaefer writes: “The start of Book VII entails not only a consideration of moral possibilities other<br />

than virtue and vice, but also a reconsideration of moral virtue itself, taking into account its newly<br />

articulated connection with prudence” (“Wisdom and Morality,” 225).

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!