03.02.2018 Views

Introduction to Religious Theories of Morality

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

e important <strong>to</strong> its survival. Given these facts, it seems that diversity must have a significant<br />

role <strong>to</strong> play in moral judgment, but NLT does not provide any obvious way <strong>of</strong> accommodating it.<br />

Indeed, NLT seems <strong>to</strong> suggest that we morality requires that we should avoid diversity and<br />

novelty and instead focus on uniformity and sameness. But how far should we take adherence<br />

<strong>to</strong> what we perceive <strong>to</strong> be the natural moral law? Would it require us <strong>to</strong> s<strong>to</strong>p discovering new<br />

technologies or innovative practices because they are “unnatural”?<br />

Finally, the emphasis <strong>of</strong> law and regularity in NLT does little <strong>to</strong> explain supereroga<strong>to</strong>ry or<br />

heroic moral action. Moral monsters commit evils that are unusual and seem “unnatural” for<br />

their singularity. But the same can be said <strong>of</strong> moral saints who perform acts that are just as<br />

unusual and hence seemingly “unnatural.” Great moral heroes like Mahatma Gandhi behaved<br />

(and encouraged others <strong>to</strong> behave) in ways that are hardly commonplace in our observations <strong>of</strong><br />

nature or even <strong>of</strong> what we might regards as “natural” human behavior, and yet we see positive<br />

moral significance in saintly behavior—indeed, moral significance that many would regard as<br />

even more powerful and righteous than that which stems from obedience <strong>to</strong> law. Arguably the<br />

most laudable moral action is in some sense “unnatural” because it is so out <strong>of</strong> the ordinary and<br />

goes above and beyond what natural law asks <strong>of</strong> us. This suggests that NLT is <strong>to</strong>o limited a<br />

theory <strong>to</strong> express the full range <strong>of</strong> moral action and consequence.<br />

Lessons <strong>of</strong> DCT and NLT<br />

DCT and NLT share in common the basic idea that morality is primarily about obligation<br />

and adherence <strong>to</strong> law. Hence these theories frame moral action in terms <strong>of</strong> obedience and<br />

conformity. But the fact that we recognize and value diversity and creativity in moral life<br />

suggests that this theoretical approach <strong>to</strong> morality is <strong>to</strong>o narrow. While DCT and NLT may<br />

contribute something <strong>to</strong> our understanding <strong>of</strong> the relationship between religion and morality,<br />

they are not adequate accounts <strong>of</strong> moral and ethical life.<br />

When we examine both DCT and NLT, we can see that both theories connect moral<br />

righteousness with authority—in the sense that there is an author <strong>of</strong> the creation that authorizes<br />

actions so that they will align with the author’s intent. When we think <strong>of</strong> authority we tend <strong>to</strong><br />

assume a source <strong>of</strong> power and rules or a plan that stem from that source <strong>of</strong> power. This leads<br />

us <strong>to</strong> think in terms <strong>of</strong> obedience. Hence DCT and NLT frame morality in terms <strong>of</strong> power and<br />

obedience—and we see that this framing seems inadequate and dis<strong>to</strong>rted. What is missing? If<br />

we think more closely about the concept <strong>of</strong> an author we see that it is not simply about power<br />

and control. Authors <strong>of</strong> fiction will sometimes talk about the characters they create as having<br />

lives <strong>of</strong> their own and say that sometimes these characters will surprise them! Many writers<br />

start a s<strong>to</strong>ry without knowing how it will end, and discover the conclusion in the process <strong>of</strong><br />

creating the s<strong>to</strong>ry. Authors who have these experiences value them despite the lack <strong>of</strong> control<br />

they feel—in some case, because they lack this control and are free <strong>to</strong> enjoy the surprise.<br />

These descriptions <strong>of</strong> the act <strong>of</strong> creation and creativity suggest that the idea that it is about<br />

intent and control is <strong>to</strong>o narrow an understanding <strong>of</strong> the concept <strong>of</strong> authority.<br />

If this is so, then perhaps thinking about God as author <strong>of</strong> the universe should include<br />

the possibility that God may be surprised at what happens. Perhaps God is not best unders<strong>to</strong>od<br />

as a lawgiver who tells human beings what <strong>to</strong> do, but rather as a crea<strong>to</strong>r who calls upon<br />

creatures <strong>to</strong> creatively participate in the unfolding <strong>of</strong> the creation. This would provide a<br />

plausible explanation <strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> free will. DCT and NLT interpret free will as the capacity <strong>to</strong>

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!