13.07.2020 Views

Dutton - Medical Malpractice in SA

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Causation 73

it may well be that the somewhat radical departure from the clearly established

common law principles which the English courts were, on occasion, prepared to

take in relation to factual causation should be left for legislative consideration.

5.4 Legal causation (remoteness of damage)

There is no serious dispute as to the need for a limitation of liability where factual

causation is established. Fleming, The Law of Torts, 66 sums up this second causal

enquiry as follows: 67

‘The second problem involves the question whether, or to what extent, the defendant

should have to answer for the consequences which his conduct has actually helped to

produce. As a matter of practical politics, some limitation must be placed upon legal

responsibility, because the consequences of an act theoretically stretch into infinity.

There must be a reasonable connection between the harm threatened and the harm

done. This inquiry, unlike the first [into factual causation], presents a much larger area

of choice in which legal policy and accepted value judgments must be the final arbiter

of what balance to strike between the claim to full reparation for the loss suffered by

an innocent victim of another’s culpable conduct and the excessive burden that would

be imposed on human activity if a wrongdoer were held to answer for all the consequences

of his default.

To understand its practical implementation by the courts, it is helpful to accept that

the ‘test of legal causation’ is, in a sense, not a test of causation at all. It is in reality

a decision about the limitation of liability. It is “a policy-based mechanism for eliminating

from the causal net those factual consequences for which it would be unreasonable

or undesirable to impose liability”.’

The implementation of this test is frequently of decisive importance in medical

cases. By virtue of the nature of the ethical issues often raised in this area of

the law, which arise out of the combination of rapid scientific and technological

advances, the intricacies of the human body and the inherently personal nature

of the subject matter, medical cases regularly raise new questions of policy to be

dealt with by the courts.

Radically differing views, however, exist as to the manner of limiting the

defendant’s liability for the factual consequences of his or her conduct. 68 Two

66

7 ed at 173.

67

Quoted with approval in S v Mokgethi 1990 (1) SA 32 (A).

68

In respect of limiting the defendant’s liability once factual causation is established, there are

two main schools of thought amongst academic writers and in the case law. One school, the

‘relative view’ (as expounded by Boberg The Law of Delict vol 1 Aquilian Liability 2 imp (Juta

1984) at 381–382 proposes that one should ‘… see both wrongfulness and culpability, not

in abstracto, but as relative to the actual consequences in issue. The question is not whether

the defendant’s conduct was wrongful and culpable, but whether the harm for which the

plaintiff sues was caused wrongfully and culpably by the defendant. Wrongfulness is determined

by applying the criterion of objective reasonableness ex post facto to the actual harm

and the manner of its occurrence; culpability is satisfied only where the defendant intended

or ought reasonably to have foreseen and guarded against harm of the kind that actually

occurred. Having thus accorded the requirements of wrongfulness and fault an active role

in the limitation of liability, those who adopt this approach have no need to postulate a

further requirement that the plaintiff’s damage be not ‘too remote’. Their finding that the

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!