22.02.2013 Views

Download - Berlin School of Mind and Brain

Download - Berlin School of Mind and Brain

Download - Berlin School of Mind and Brain

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

ISSUES IN PHILOSOPHY AND NEUROSCIENCE<br />

VENICE, 17-21 APRIL 2011<br />

1


Contents<br />

Program schedule……………………………………3<br />

Abstracts………………………………………………..6<br />

List <strong>of</strong> participants………………………….….…19<br />

Accommodation…………………………………….21<br />

3


PANEL 1: CONSCIOUSNESS I<br />

Program<br />

Monday, April 18 th<br />

Chairs: Pr<strong>of</strong>. Michael Pauen <strong>and</strong> Georgina Torbet<br />

9:00 - 9:25<br />

9:25 - 9:50<br />

9:50 - 10:15<br />

On the Influence <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Brain</strong> on the <strong>Brain</strong>: Be “Aware”!<br />

(Sebastian Philipp)<br />

Meditation…? Questions for Neuroscientists<br />

(Arun Singh)<br />

10:15 - 10:30 BREAK<br />

PANEL 2: CONSCIOUSNESS II<br />

The Role <strong>of</strong> Neuroscientific Findings in Ascribing<br />

Intentional States (Joachim Lipski)<br />

Chairs: Pr<strong>of</strong>. Arno Villringer <strong>and</strong> Bianca van Kemenade<br />

10:30 - 10:55<br />

The Mystery <strong>of</strong> the Internal Clock, or What do we Know<br />

about Time Perception? (Sophie Herbst)<br />

10:55 - 11:20 Hypnosis as <strong>and</strong> Neuroscience (Vera Ludwig)<br />

11:20 - 11:45<br />

11:45 - 13:30 LUNCH<br />

13:30<br />

afternoon<br />

Cognitive Neuroscience Approaches to Freudian Repression<br />

(Georgina Torbet)<br />

Boat to Venice<br />

Sightseeing with an organized tour; details tba<br />

4


PANEL 3: ETHICS<br />

Tuesday, April 19 th<br />

Chairs: Pr<strong>of</strong>. Benedikt Grothe <strong>and</strong> Emiliano Zaccarella<br />

9:00 - 9:25<br />

9:25 - 9:50<br />

Ethical Issues in Human-Robot Interaction<br />

(Aleks<strong>and</strong>ra Kupferberg)<br />

Neuroscientific Research on Moral Judgement<br />

(David Kaufmann)<br />

9:50 - 10:15 Neuroscience <strong>and</strong> Morality (Judy Ng)<br />

10:15 - 10:30 BREAK<br />

PANEL 4: SENSE PERCEPTION I<br />

Chairs: Pr<strong>of</strong>. Wilhelm Vossenkuhl <strong>and</strong> Alex<strong>and</strong>er Soutschek<br />

10:30 - 10:55<br />

10:55 - 11:20<br />

Color Vision: From the Outside World via the Cortex to<br />

Consciousness (Christian Kellner)<br />

Recurrent Neural Processing in Somatosensory Awareness<br />

(Ryszard Auksztulewicz)<br />

11:20 - 11:45 Multisensory Integration (Bianca van Kemenade)<br />

11:45 - 13:30 LUNCH<br />

PANEL 5: SENSE PERCEPTION II<br />

Chair: PD Dr. Stephan Sellmaier <strong>and</strong> Ellen Fridl<strong>and</strong><br />

13:30 - 13:55<br />

Orientation Encoding in the FFA is Selective to Faces:<br />

Evidence from Multivoxal Pattern Analysis (Fern<strong>and</strong>o<br />

Ramirez)<br />

13:55 - 14:20 Naturalized Epistemology (Alex<strong>and</strong>er Soutschek)<br />

5


Wedesday, April 19 th<br />

PANEL 6: WILL AND DECISION MAKING<br />

Chairs: Pr<strong>of</strong>. Michael Pauen <strong>and</strong> Ryszard Auksztulewicz<br />

9:00 - 9:25<br />

9:25 - 9:50<br />

The Role <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Brain</strong> in Impulsivity <strong>and</strong> Self-Control<br />

(Saskia Köhler)<br />

Building Blocks in Human Decision Making <strong>and</strong> Cognitive<br />

Control (Rol<strong>and</strong> Nigbur)<br />

9:50 - 10:15 Drosophila <strong>and</strong> Cognitive Functions (Armin Bahl)<br />

10:15 - 10:30 BREAK<br />

PANEL 7: CLINICAL APPLICATIONS<br />

Chairs: Pr<strong>of</strong>. Benedikt Grothe <strong>and</strong> Judy Ng<br />

10:30 - 10:55 Optogenetics (Barbara Trattner)<br />

10:55 - 11:20<br />

11:20 - 11:45<br />

11:45 - 13:30 LUNCH<br />

PANEL 8: LANGUAGE<br />

Reduction <strong>of</strong> Inter-hemispheric Connectivity in Disorders<br />

<strong>of</strong> Consciousness (Smadar Ovadia-Caro)<br />

The Neural Effects <strong>of</strong> Alcohol Bias Modification Training<br />

(Corinde Wiers)<br />

Chairs: Pr<strong>of</strong>. Arno Villringer <strong>and</strong> Aleks<strong>and</strong>ra Kupferberg<br />

13:30 - 13:55<br />

CLOSING SESSION<br />

On the Nature <strong>of</strong> Merge: Neuroanatomical Correlates <strong>of</strong><br />

Local Syntactic Structures in Natural Language Processing<br />

(Emiliano Zaccarella)<br />

6


Aleks<strong>and</strong>ra Kupferberg<br />

Abstracts<br />

Ethical Issues in Human-Robot Interaction<br />

Despite tremendous usefulness <strong>and</strong> great social benefits gained by integrating robots as<br />

helpers <strong>and</strong> interaction partners into human environments, there are a number <strong>of</strong><br />

important ethical problems involved in such developments. These problems require<br />

careful consideration <strong>and</strong> analyses from a perspective <strong>of</strong> applied ethics, since ethical<br />

problems will be noticeable in cases where robots are used in everyday <strong>and</strong> intimate<br />

settings such as the education sector, personal assistance duties <strong>and</strong> the elderly care. In<br />

such settings, the tendency <strong>of</strong> humans to see their interactions with machines in<br />

anthropomorphic terms will be increased <strong>and</strong> people might develop affection towards<br />

machines e.g. because <strong>of</strong> similarities in personality <strong>and</strong> knowledge <strong>and</strong> also affection<br />

shown by the robot towards the human. Another problem might arise in case that a robot<br />

is given two conflicting orders by two different humans. Whom should it obey? Who<br />

should carry the responsibility for a failure in a joint human-robot task? A different issue<br />

deals with the question whether it is ethically <strong>and</strong> morally responsible to manufacture<br />

robot workers <strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong>roids, since the argument is that robot workers take jobs from<br />

human workers. In which way will humanity be transformed if the dangerous,<br />

monotonous <strong>and</strong> hazardous work will be performed by robots <strong>and</strong> the expectations <strong>of</strong><br />

humans will increase towards other humans? The consequences <strong>of</strong> introduction <strong>of</strong> robots<br />

in human environments will also increase the percentages <strong>of</strong> his/her life interfacing with<br />

machines instead <strong>of</strong> real humans. Therefore, ethics must do empirical research to<br />

examine what counts as a good life in the environment that encompasses both humans<br />

<strong>and</strong> robotic companions.<br />

Alex<strong>and</strong>er Soutschek<br />

Naturalized Epistemology: Can empirical science help to answer traditional<br />

epistemological questions?<br />

In traditional philosophy, epistemological questions are investigated by conceptual<br />

analyses <strong>and</strong> a priori arguments. For example, the sceptical question <strong>of</strong> whether<br />

knowledge <strong>of</strong> the external world is possible shall be answered by analysing our intuitive<br />

concepts <strong>of</strong> knowledge <strong>and</strong> reality. In contrast to that program, naturalized epistemology<br />

assumes that the modern empirical sciences like psychology or the neurosciences can<br />

explain better than philosophy how the human mind works <strong>and</strong> how it gains knowledge<br />

about its environment. In consequence, epistemology should give up its traditional project<br />

<strong>of</strong> a conceptual analysis <strong>of</strong> knowledge <strong>and</strong> stick to the results <strong>of</strong> empirical sciences<br />

instead. In my talk, I will deal with the question whether naturalized epistemology really<br />

can find an answer to traditional epistemological problems like scepticism.<br />

7


Armin Bahl<br />

Smarter than One Might Think: Drosophila as a model for higher cognitive<br />

functions<br />

In the fruit fly Drosophila melanogaster, electrophysiological <strong>and</strong> imaging techniques as<br />

well as neuronal genetic modifications can be combined at the same time in the behaving<br />

animal. It is that recent fusion <strong>of</strong> well-established toolsets that makes the fly one <strong>of</strong> the<br />

most popular model organisms for the study <strong>of</strong> developmental biology, brain physiology,<br />

neuronal computation <strong>and</strong> behavior today (Olsen & Wilson, 2010, Seelig et al., 2010). The<br />

Drosophila brain has less than a cubic square millimeter in size <strong>and</strong> approximately<br />

300.000 nerve cells. <strong>Brain</strong>s <strong>of</strong> higher organisms like humans have more than 300.000<br />

times more nerve cells <strong>and</strong> are more than 2 million times larger. These numbers could<br />

lead to the belief that the fly’s behavioral repertoire should be small <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> only minor<br />

interest for human neurobiology. But despite their small brains flies do have amazing<br />

abilities, they possess, for example, an elaborated memory <strong>and</strong> can be trained to associate<br />

colors with objects or odors (Brembs & Heisenberg, 2001). Using visual cues they also<br />

build up spatial memories allowing them to quickly navigate towards a target spot whose<br />

location had be learned before (Foucaud et al., 2010). A well-studied topic in<br />

psychophysics is attention <strong>and</strong> saliency, which is normally attributed only to higher<br />

organisms but it was shown that the ability to attend to a salient object is also present in<br />

flies (Wolf & Heisenberg, 1980). There is an ongoing debate on whether the freedom <strong>of</strong><br />

will might be an illusion <strong>and</strong> that behaviour instead <strong>of</strong> being self-initiated is always<br />

deterministic with variability coming from internal or external noise (Heisenberg 2009).<br />

However there are evidences from research in Drosophila that the manoeuvres during<br />

flight might be self-initiated by internal noise-independent mechanisms (Maye et al.,<br />

2007). These examples demonstrate that Drosophila has a long list <strong>of</strong> exciting <strong>and</strong><br />

elaborated abilities <strong>and</strong> therefore makes it an interesting model organism also for<br />

research in human cognition, physiology <strong>and</strong> psychology. In combination with the<br />

experimental possibilities in flies it is now possible to tackle the neural basis <strong>of</strong> these<br />

behaviors which might shed light on the neural representation <strong>of</strong> learning, attention <strong>and</strong><br />

will - might it be free or not.<br />

Arun Singh<br />

Meditation…? Questions for Neuroscientists<br />

Generally, the aim <strong>of</strong> meditation is modulation <strong>of</strong> awareness. Any effort free from<br />

distraction <strong>of</strong> the mind may work as effective meditation. There are two different<br />

meditation categories: concentrative, <strong>and</strong> non-concentrative. It may be integrated into a<br />

specific spiritual context, but is by itself not specific to religion in general. It includes an<br />

approach to manage stress, anxiety, headache, <strong>and</strong> daily physical pain complaints. Since<br />

1960, more than 1000 research articles have been published trying to explain the benefits<br />

<strong>of</strong> meditation. Richard Davidson <strong>and</strong> Dalai Lama have investigated the effects <strong>of</strong><br />

meditation on the brain. For example, one <strong>of</strong> Davidson’s studies found that long-term<br />

meditators showed high amplitude gamma synchrony during mental practice. All <strong>of</strong> his<br />

studies imply that intensive meditation results in both functional as well as structural<br />

changes in the brain regions. Investigations performed by Lazar et al have demonstrated<br />

that mediation can increase the density <strong>of</strong> grey matter <strong>and</strong> cortical thickness. Meditation<br />

has also been related to alterations <strong>of</strong> sensory perception, as well as metabolic changes,<br />

e.g. <strong>of</strong> heart rate, blood pressure, respiration. Given scientific evidence has proved to be<br />

beneficial for mental <strong>and</strong> physical health, but there is much more left to be yet understood<br />

by neuroscientists.<br />

8


Barbara Trattner<br />

Optogenetics<br />

Optogenetics is an elegant emerging method in neuroscience, which exploits optical <strong>and</strong><br />

genetic tools to precisely control neuronal brain circuits in living animals at a high<br />

temporal <strong>and</strong> spatial resolution. Generally neuronal properties are investigated with the<br />

help <strong>of</strong> selective pharmacological agents targeting certain neuronal structures. These<br />

agents are however disadvantageous in that they have a systemic action, are temporally<br />

imprecise <strong>and</strong> may cause unspecific side-effects. In addition to replacing pharmacology,<br />

optogenetic approaches can also substitute electrical stimulation <strong>of</strong> a neuronal population<br />

for defined light-gated activation. Photosensitive proteins can be artificially expressed in<br />

neurones to alter their firing properties <strong>and</strong> thereby information processing. By exposing<br />

only a certain brain area to light, only the activity <strong>of</strong> those neurones will be modulated by<br />

the photosensitive proteins. Due to the immense possibilities that optogenetics <strong>of</strong>fer in<br />

elucidating neuronal brain circuits, it was selected the method <strong>of</strong> the year 2010 by the<br />

prestigious scientific journal Nature Methods. The principle <strong>of</strong> using optogenetics was<br />

first found around 2000, when photosensitive proteins were expressed in neurones, which<br />

could thereby be sensitised to light. Further research in the field <strong>of</strong> optogenetics led to the<br />

implementation <strong>of</strong> genetically-encoded bacterial <strong>and</strong> algeal photosensitive ion channels<br />

<strong>and</strong> pumps in neurones. Depending on the properties <strong>of</strong> these ion transporters, they can<br />

either hyperpolarise or depolarise neurones. An advantage <strong>of</strong> using photosensitive ion<br />

transporters to targeting endogenous channels with drugs is the fast time constant: Upon<br />

illumination with the correct wavelength, photosensitive channels open <strong>and</strong> close in the<br />

range <strong>of</strong> milliseconds. A lot <strong>of</strong> research is currently going on to develop new artificial<br />

light-gated ion channels or receptors. With the help <strong>of</strong> tissue-specific promoters, these<br />

proteins can be expressed only in a certain neuronal subgroup or at a confined<br />

developmental stage.<br />

Precisely choosing the brain area, which is exposed to light, allows the further refinement<br />

<strong>of</strong> the subgroup <strong>of</strong> modulated neurones. By expressing photosensitive proteins in a<br />

subclass <strong>of</strong> neurones responsible for a defined behaviour, researchers can nowadays<br />

control behaviour by exciting or inhibiting only those neurones with light. Flies for<br />

instance can learn that a certain odour is aversive when the odour is paired with the lightgated<br />

activation <strong>of</strong> a certain receptor class. Mice can be woken up when a certain neuronal<br />

population <strong>of</strong> the hypothalamus, artificially expressing photosensitive proteins, are<br />

stimulated with light.<br />

The therapeutic aim <strong>of</strong> optogenetics for humans is to restore vision after a degeneration <strong>of</strong><br />

photoreceptor cells in the retina. In mice it was shown that equipping retinal neurones<br />

with photosensitive proteins from microbes using a viral delivery can restore visual<br />

responses. In humans this approach is currently investigated in inherited retinal<br />

dysfunctions: In Leber’s congenital amaurosis patient lack a certain pigment protein <strong>of</strong><br />

the retina. Subretinal administration <strong>of</strong> viral vectors encoding the absent pigment, lead to<br />

a long-lasting improvement in vision perception. However optogenetic treatments are not<br />

yet st<strong>and</strong>ard in the therapy <strong>of</strong> blindness, mainly due to the fact that viral gene transfer<br />

bears many risks.<br />

9


Bianca van Kemenade<br />

Multisensory Integration<br />

Our senses are constantly bombarded with information from the different modalities. In<br />

order to interact with our environment in an appropriate manner, we have to select which<br />

information is most important. In the process <strong>of</strong> integrating this information to give rise<br />

to a conscious percept, the different modalities can influence each other: our conscious<br />

perception <strong>of</strong> a stimulus in one modality can be influenced by a stimulus in another<br />

modality. This process is <strong>of</strong>ten referred to as multisensory integration, or cross-modal<br />

processing. Multisensory integration is a broad topic that covers a wide range <strong>of</strong> research;<br />

therefore I will select some <strong>of</strong> the most important findings. I will introduce some<br />

interesting illusions, discuss some studies on the neural mechanisms underlying<br />

multisensory integration, <strong>and</strong> cover some patient studies. With this overview I would like<br />

to introduce this fascinating topic to other scientists working in different fields.<br />

Christian Kellner<br />

Color Vision: From the outside world via the cortex to consciousness<br />

Color <strong>and</strong> color vision has always been a topic that fascinated scholars, ranging from<br />

Dalton's research <strong>of</strong> color blindness over Goethe's "Theory <strong>of</strong> Color" to the "dispute"<br />

between the trichromatic theory <strong>of</strong> Young–Helmholtz theory <strong>and</strong> the opponent process<br />

theory <strong>of</strong> Hering. Color (vision) also became a highly debated topic in the Philosophy <strong>of</strong><br />

mind with the problem <strong>of</strong> "qualia" (<strong>and</strong> its suggested consequence <strong>of</strong> the "explanatory<br />

gap").<br />

At the core <strong>of</strong> a lot <strong>of</strong> those problems lies the fundamental question <strong>of</strong> the relationship<br />

between the outside (physical) world <strong>and</strong> the subjective personal experience. Of course,<br />

nowadays neuroscientists believe that the link is made via the brain. Though (color) vision<br />

is a field that has undergone intensive research by neuroscientists, there are <strong>of</strong> course<br />

some yet fundamental but unsolved problems; two famous ones are the problem <strong>of</strong><br />

dichromats ("what do 'color blind' people see") <strong>and</strong> the problem <strong>of</strong> unique hues (the<br />

elementary chromatic hues: red, green, yellow & blue) <strong>and</strong> their (still missing) neuronal<br />

correlates.<br />

I will mainly focus on the current state <strong>of</strong> the latter problem <strong>and</strong> if there is time/space left<br />

I will also try to present some new insights about the problem <strong>of</strong> color blindness.<br />

10


Corinde Wiers<br />

The Neural Effects <strong>of</strong> Alcohol Bias Modification Training<br />

The pathology <strong>of</strong> alcoholism is associated with maladaptive attention- <strong>and</strong> approach<br />

biases towards substance-related stimuli, i.e. the tendency <strong>of</strong> alcoholic patients to<br />

approach rather than avoid these stimuli, even though they are not rationally inclined to.<br />

From animal studies it is known that limbic areas are structurally <strong>and</strong> functionally altered<br />

after long-term drinking, but the neural mechanisms <strong>of</strong> alcohol biases in humans remain<br />

largely unknown. In this talk I present my currently ongoing research, in which I use fMRI<br />

<strong>and</strong> EEG to study brain regions involved in these biases in alcoholic patients. My<br />

hypothesis is that limbic brain activity predicts performance on a computerised alcohol<br />

bias task. My next step is to underst<strong>and</strong> how bias modification training, a promising<br />

intervention in which patients selectively learn to avoid rather than approach stimuli,<br />

modulates the brain <strong>and</strong> may prevent relapse. Finally I talk about how neuroimaging can<br />

be <strong>of</strong> use for the treatment <strong>of</strong> alcohol addiction directly.<br />

11


David Kaufmann<br />

Neuroscientific Research on Moral Judgement<br />

In my research project at GSN I intend to investigate the overt <strong>and</strong> covert philosophical<br />

conceptual premises <strong>of</strong> the neuroscientific approach to investigating moral judgement <strong>and</strong><br />

the importance <strong>of</strong> these premises for interpreting neuroscientific results in philosophical<br />

terms as well as in ordinary language. The first step in order to do this would be to<br />

investigate the links between philosophical, psychological <strong>and</strong> neuroscientific concepts<br />

employed in the explanation <strong>of</strong> moral judgement <strong>and</strong> their characteristic role in their<br />

theories <strong>of</strong> origin. For the seminar “Current Issues in philosophy <strong>and</strong> neurosciences” I’d<br />

like to propose to give a short introduction on one issue about the neuroscientific research<br />

on moral judgement that this first step could shed some light on <strong>and</strong> which I consider<br />

especially interesting: It has been a striking feature <strong>of</strong> neuroscientific experiments on<br />

moral judgements that they’re most <strong>of</strong>ten „nothing but“ psychological experiments<br />

performed in an fMRI scanner – <strong>and</strong> their results are most <strong>of</strong>ten „only“ used to back up<br />

already quite well confirmed psychological theories on moral judgement. When it comes<br />

to a philosophical or common language interpretation <strong>of</strong> these neuroscientific findings we<br />

must find that from a philosophical point <strong>of</strong> view they seem quite boring. They just<br />

confirm stuff that is already “known” from psychological research. The question that<br />

arises in regard <strong>of</strong> this matter is whether the situation that neuroscientific research on<br />

morality doesn’t seem to give great philosophical insights is owed to „structural“ reasons<br />

(for example due to conceptual constraints) or whether the reasons for that frustrating<br />

situation are just „coincidental“ (due to the fact that just occasionally nobody happened to<br />

do research otherwise).<br />

What does “conceptual constraints” mean here? I’d like to speak <strong>of</strong> “conceptual<br />

constraints” when we can’t talk in philosophical terms or ordinary language about what<br />

the neurosciences tell us about morality in their own scientific jargon. This could mean<br />

concretely that neuroscientific statements cannot be „translated“ in common ways <strong>of</strong><br />

speaking but by „going the long way“ <strong>and</strong> being first translated into psychological terms –<br />

as a mere confirmation <strong>of</strong> already existing psychological hypotheses. According to this line<br />

<strong>of</strong> thought, anything that neuroscience can <strong>of</strong>fer apart from the assertion <strong>of</strong> psychological<br />

hypothesises would be „lost in translation“.<br />

This would not only be a pity for the interested lay person, but also for the neuroscientist<br />

engaged in the investigation <strong>of</strong> moral judgement: It would be quite a blow if she would not<br />

be able to explain her findings to laymen apart from what can be proven by her efforts in<br />

psychological research.<br />

As a philosopher I see it as a thrilling task to investigate whether such constraints exist by<br />

examining the links between philosophical, psychological <strong>and</strong> neuroscientific concepts<br />

that play a role in the philosophical interpretation <strong>of</strong> neuroscientific results on moral<br />

judgement. The resulting findings could in the best case tell us whether <strong>and</strong> to what extent<br />

a direct philosophical or ordinary language interpretation <strong>of</strong> neuroscientific results is<br />

possible – <strong>and</strong> in how far taking “the long way” would really leave everything that doesn’t<br />

derive from psychological hypothesises in limbo. If such a translation (direct or indirect)<br />

should be possible, it will be an even more fascinating next step to check where there is<br />

room for misunderst<strong>and</strong>ings <strong>and</strong> misinterpretations <strong>of</strong> which I daresay that there will be<br />

plenty <strong>of</strong>. But this will be a different story. My short talk or my poster would give an<br />

account <strong>of</strong> how such constraints could look like in theory, my reasons for thinking that<br />

they are at least limited, an outlook what I expect to find <strong>and</strong> possible next steps. I would<br />

set these matters in context <strong>of</strong> an overall presentation <strong>of</strong> my dissertation project.<br />

12


Emiliano Zaccarella<br />

On the Nature <strong>of</strong> Merge: Neuroanatomical Correlates <strong>of</strong> Local Syntactic<br />

Structures in Natural Language Processing<br />

Probabilistic fiber tracking approaches to language-relevant areas have recently identified<br />

a dorsal stream going from pars opercularis (BA 44) to the posterior temporal cortex via<br />

the superior longitudinal fasciculus, <strong>and</strong> a more ventral stream going from the frontal<br />

operculum (FOC) to the anterior temporal cortex via the uncinate fasciculum. According<br />

to the ‘two-pathways’ model, it has been suggested that the former stream supports the<br />

processing <strong>of</strong> non-adjacent elements in hierarchically more complex sentences <strong>and</strong><br />

possibly the identification <strong>of</strong> the constituency structure, while the latter stream supports<br />

the combinations <strong>of</strong> adjacent elements in a sequence. Even though many studies contrast<br />

this view a direct comparison with the stimulus material so far employed will show that<br />

the model above is still adequate <strong>and</strong> preferable over alternative suggestions. A corrected<br />

set <strong>of</strong> stimuli for a following fMRI analysis will be finally discussed.<br />

Fern<strong>and</strong>o Ramirez<br />

Orientation Encoding in the FFA is Selective to Faces: Evidence from<br />

Multivoxal Pattern Analysis<br />

The fusiform face area (FFA) is a region <strong>of</strong> the human ventral visual pathway that exhibits<br />

a stronger response to faces than objects. The role <strong>of</strong> this region within the face perception<br />

network is not well understood, <strong>and</strong> its selectivity has been debated. Furthermore, it is<br />

unclear which properties <strong>of</strong> visual stimuli are reflected in the patterns <strong>of</strong> activation <strong>of</strong> this<br />

region. Here we directly explored the encoding <strong>of</strong> orientation using a combination <strong>of</strong> fMRI<br />

<strong>and</strong> multivoxel pattern analysis. We presented subjects with synthetic images <strong>of</strong> faces <strong>and</strong><br />

cars that were rotated in depth <strong>and</strong> presented either above or below fixation. We explored<br />

orientation related information available in fine-grained activity patterns in FFA <strong>and</strong> early<br />

visual cortex. Distributed signals from the FFA allowed above-chance classification <strong>of</strong><br />

within-category orientation only for faces. This result generalized to faces presented in<br />

different retinotopic positions. In contrast, classification in early visual cortex resulted in<br />

equal, above-chance classification <strong>of</strong> face <strong>and</strong> car orientation, but only when trained <strong>and</strong><br />

tested on corresponding retinotopic positions. Classification across position was<br />

substantially decreased for both categories in early visual cortex. We conclude that<br />

category-selective effects <strong>of</strong> stimulus orientation are reflected in the fine grained patterns<br />

<strong>of</strong> activation in FFA, <strong>and</strong> that the structure <strong>of</strong> these patterns is partially translation<br />

invariant.<br />

13


Georgina Torbet<br />

Cognitive Neuroscience Approaches to Freudian Repression<br />

This presentation will discuss the methods through which the empirical sciences may<br />

investigate psychoanalytic constructs, focusing particularly on repression. While<br />

repression is a well-known clinical phenomenon, it lacks a robust evidence base <strong>and</strong> is<br />

difficult to reconcile with current knowledge <strong>of</strong> experimental psychology. We have<br />

attempted to frame repression in terms <strong>of</strong> mechanisms which are well understood in<br />

cognitive neuroscience, in order to investigate this subject experimentally <strong>and</strong> to gather<br />

empirical data on it.<br />

We have built upon experiments in directed forgetting, in which people intentionally<br />

forget material which they had previously learned when instructed to do so. We have<br />

replicated this well-known effect, <strong>and</strong> exp<strong>and</strong>ed the paradigm to include cues given in a<br />

non-conscious way. Through innovative use <strong>of</strong> subliminal stimuli, we have attempted to<br />

demonstrate that unconscious cues can effect memory <strong>and</strong> induce forgetting. Some<br />

preliminary results will be presented, <strong>and</strong> implications for the empirical study <strong>of</strong><br />

psychoanalytic phenomena will be discussed.<br />

Joachim Lipski<br />

The Role <strong>of</strong> Neuroscientific Findings in Ascribing Intentional States<br />

The role <strong>of</strong> intentional terminology in neuroscientific contexts, one <strong>of</strong> the most crucial<br />

links between philosophy <strong>and</strong> the neurosciences, is still lacking a proper theoretical<br />

foundation. Available proposals range from a simple identification <strong>of</strong> intentional<br />

statements with corresponding neurological statements, to a more-or-less strictly causally<br />

moderated relationship, to denying the neurosciences the use <strong>of</strong> such terminology at all.<br />

Subscribing to any <strong>of</strong> these views will have a significant bearing on the role that<br />

neuroscientific findings play in the potential ascription <strong>of</strong> intentional properties, <strong>and</strong> the<br />

fact that these views are competing has led to many a controversial debate. Personally, I<br />

suggest that many <strong>of</strong> these proposals, while being mutually exclusive in their elaborated<br />

forms, have put forward valuable points which can be constructively integrated into a<br />

theory <strong>of</strong> translation between neuroscientific terms, ins<strong>of</strong>ar as they pertain to intentional<br />

phenomena, <strong>and</strong> intentional terms, such as they are being used in analytic philosophy.<br />

14


Judy Ng<br />

Neuroscience <strong>and</strong> Morality<br />

Where does morality originate? Is it only a social construct or is it hardwired into the<br />

functionings <strong>of</strong> the human brain? Through observation <strong>of</strong> many patients with different<br />

brain damage over the decades <strong>and</strong> their resulting abnormal moral judgments,<br />

neuroscientists have deduced possible links between neuroanatomy <strong>and</strong> moral judgment.<br />

In addition, fMRI studies have shown an association between brain areas that are<br />

involved in emotional processing <strong>and</strong> aspects <strong>of</strong> moral cognition, while other patient<br />

studies have suggested that deficits in moral behavior <strong>and</strong> cognition are associated with<br />

emotional dysfunction. Many <strong>of</strong> these studies utilize test stimuli that range from morally<br />

relevant statements <strong>and</strong> pictures to complex moral scenarios <strong>and</strong> dilemmas. Taken<br />

together, recent studies suggest that morally relevant stimuli may provoke an emotional<br />

response that may influence moral judgment, but the driving force <strong>of</strong> the judgment itself<br />

remains to be investigated.<br />

Rol<strong>and</strong> Nigbur<br />

Building Blocks in Human Decision Making <strong>and</strong> Cognitive Control<br />

Human decision making is based on manifold neuro-cognitive processes that allow goaldirected<br />

predictions <strong>of</strong> the environmental context but also enable flexible adjustments to<br />

monitor perceptual selection or behavioral adaptation. In so-called conflict paradigms<br />

participants have to react to ambiguous information that sometimes induces competing<br />

activations in the brain. Here, cognitive control is needed to amplify the brain activity to<br />

perform the task at h<strong>and</strong> correctly.<br />

In my studies I investigated how these control functions can be tracked via<br />

electrophysiological brain activity (EEG). Several approaches have tried to identify the<br />

neural building blocks <strong>of</strong> executive control functions. The medial frontal cortex (MFC) is<br />

thought to detect conflicts <strong>and</strong> recruit additional resources from other brain areas<br />

including the lateral prefrontal cortices (LPFC). Together with additional task relevant<br />

areas in the brain such as motor or perceptual systems a network for implementing<br />

control functions is assumed.<br />

I will present data from experiments using different conflict paradigms that will<br />

demonstrate how event-related potentials (ERPs) can help to shed light on the cognitive<br />

architecture <strong>of</strong> our brain. Furthermore I will show how spectral decomposition <strong>of</strong> the EEG<br />

signal delivers information about the interaction <strong>of</strong> different brain areas. In a last step I<br />

will refer to current research investigating the role <strong>of</strong> emotion <strong>and</strong> motivation in decision<br />

making <strong>and</strong> cognitive control functions.<br />

15


Ryszard Auksztulewicz<br />

Recurrent Neural Processing in Somatosensory Awareness<br />

The characteristics <strong>of</strong> neural processing underlying conscious stimulus detection, despite<br />

extensive research, remain elusive. As a prominent theoretical account <strong>of</strong> visual<br />

awareness, the recurrent processing hypothesis states that while stimuli generally evoke<br />

feedforward activity propagating through the visual cortex, stimuli which become<br />

consciously detected are further processed in feedforward-feedback loops established<br />

between various stages <strong>of</strong> visual processing.<br />

Although this hypothesis has not been tested directly in modalities other than vision,<br />

monkey studies have provided indirect evidence for feedback processing in somatosensory<br />

detection. Here we applied dynamic causal modelling (DCM) to EEG data acquired from<br />

humans in a somatosensory detection task to test this theory. In the analysis, we focused<br />

on model-based evidence for feedforward, feedback <strong>and</strong> recurrent processing between<br />

primary <strong>and</strong> secondary somatosensory cortices. Our results suggest that increased<br />

recurrent processing within the somatosensory system, dominated by an enhanced cSIcSII<br />

connection, underlies somatosensory awareness.<br />

Saskia Köhler<br />

The Role <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Brain</strong> in Impulsivity <strong>and</strong> Self-Control<br />

Impulsivity is a personality trait that is present in healthy individuals. However, high<br />

impulsivity may also cause problems in social life, such as troubles in partnership, fights,<br />

<strong>and</strong> traffic violations. This is because impulsive actions are <strong>of</strong>ten rapid, unplanned, hasty<br />

<strong>and</strong> without regard to negative consequences. The opposite <strong>of</strong> impulsivity can be<br />

described as self-control, given that people showing high impulsivity have problems<br />

controlling their actions, thoughts <strong>and</strong> emotions. Since an association between impulsivity<br />

<strong>and</strong> mental illness is apparent, neuroscientific research in this field is important. In my<br />

PhD project, I investigate the role <strong>of</strong> the brain in impulsivity <strong>and</strong> self-control with<br />

different approaches: (1) administering different functional magnetic resonance imaging<br />

(fMRI) paradigms, which provoke impulsive or self-controlled behavior, (2) examining<br />

fMRI resting state measurements, (3) examining MRI structural measurements, <strong>and</strong> (4)<br />

determining the influence <strong>of</strong> virtual lesions with transcranial direct current stimulation<br />

(tDCS). I examine psychiatric patients, which are characterized by high impulsivity <strong>and</strong><br />

low self-control competencies (alcohol dependent patients <strong>and</strong> pathological gamblers),<br />

<strong>and</strong> healthy subjects. I will present results from at least one <strong>of</strong> these approaches.<br />

16


Sebastian Philipp<br />

On the Influence <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Brain</strong> on the <strong>Brain</strong>: Be “Aware”!<br />

Altered statistics in external sensory stimuli lead to a change in the neural representation<br />

<strong>of</strong> the respective sensory entity. This is the well investigated phenomenon that the<br />

external world shapes representations in the brain. However, besides some recent studies<br />

it is not yet investigated how internal, mental conditions – such as attention, imagery or<br />

meditation – effect neural sensory representations – which is the question <strong>of</strong> whether <strong>and</strong><br />

how the brain itself shapes representations in the brain. The effects <strong>of</strong> altered external<br />

stimulation <strong>of</strong> the body on somatosensory representations are well investigated by<br />

psychophysically measuring the tactile acuity <strong>of</strong> human subjects. Recent studies report<br />

effects <strong>of</strong> long-term Tai Chi practice on tactile acuity [2]. Tai Chi is a sensory attentional<br />

training where practitioners focus attention on the body's extremities. Study results<br />

showed that Tai Chi practitioners' tactile acuity in the finger tips is superior to that <strong>of</strong> the<br />

matched controls. However, it is questionable if these effects are only due to the subjects'<br />

having focused their attention on their extremities during the long-term practice over<br />

several years or if it is also due to the bodily aspects <strong>of</strong> the long-term Tai Chi practice. In<br />

our study, we investigate the effect <strong>of</strong> a short meditative training – a purely mental<br />

training – on tactile acuity in the finger tips. Tactile acuity <strong>of</strong> subjects with ample<br />

experience in Zazen is measured psychophysically before the training period. During the<br />

training period <strong>of</strong> two hours, subjects are asked to be completely aware <strong>of</strong> the arising<br />

sensory percepts in their fingertips while preventing external stimulation by not moving<br />

their h<strong>and</strong>s. After training, subjects' tactile acuity is measured again. We compare tactile<br />

acuity before <strong>and</strong> after the meditative intervention. In my presentation I will give an<br />

introduction to the topics <strong>of</strong> meditation <strong>and</strong> alterations <strong>of</strong> sensory representations by<br />

external stimulation. Furthermore, I will show preliminary results from our current study<br />

on the effects <strong>of</strong> meditation on tactile acuity <strong>and</strong> I will mention possible philosophical<br />

aspects <strong>of</strong> this study in order to yield an open discussion with the audience.<br />

17


Smadar Ovadia-Caro<br />

Reduction <strong>of</strong> Inter-hemispheric Connectivity in Disorders <strong>of</strong> Consciousness<br />

Disorders <strong>of</strong> consciousness (DOC) pose diagnostic challenges because patients can be<br />

behaviorally unresponsive. A promising new approach towards DOC diagnosis may be<br />

<strong>of</strong>fered by the analysis <strong>of</strong> functional magnetic resonance imaging (fMRI) data acquired in<br />

the absence <strong>of</strong> any task dem<strong>and</strong>s (“resting-state”). Previous work has shown reduced<br />

functional connectivity within the "default network", a subset <strong>of</strong> regions known to be<br />

deactivated during engaging tasks, which correlated with the degree <strong>of</strong> consciousness<br />

impairment. However, it remains unclear whether the breakdown <strong>of</strong> connectivity is<br />

restricted to the "default network", <strong>and</strong> to what degree changes in functional connectivity<br />

can be observed at the single-subject level. Here, we analyzed resting-state interhemispheric<br />

connectivity in three homotopic regions <strong>of</strong> interest, which could reliably be<br />

identified based on distinct anatomical l<strong>and</strong>marks, <strong>and</strong> were part <strong>of</strong> an "externally<br />

oriented network". Resting-state fMRI data were acquired for a group <strong>of</strong> 11 healthy<br />

subjects <strong>and</strong> 8 DOC patients. At the group level, our results indicate decreased interhemispheric<br />

functional connectivity in patients with impaired awareness as compared to<br />

subjects with intact awareness. The single-case statistic by Crawford & Howell (1998)<br />

indicated a significant deviation from the healthy sample in 5/8 patients. Importantly, <strong>of</strong><br />

the three patients whose connectivity indices were comparable to the healthy sample, one<br />

was diagnosed as locked-in. Our results highlight the clinical potential <strong>of</strong> resting-state<br />

fMRI data, <strong>and</strong> suggest further investigation <strong>of</strong> inter-hemispheric connectivity as a<br />

complementary diagnostic measure for DOC patients.<br />

Sophie Herbst<br />

The Mystery <strong>of</strong> the Internal Clock, or What do we Know about Time<br />

Perception?<br />

Time perception is becoming a popular research field again, based on its long-st<strong>and</strong>ing<br />

history that dates back to antique philosophers. In my talk I’ll give a short insight on the<br />

topic from a psychological viewpoint, illustrated by recent discussions in the scientific<br />

community <strong>and</strong> discuss how state-<strong>of</strong>-the-art neuroscience methods can help to uncover<br />

the mysteries <strong>of</strong> which there are still plenty in this field.<br />

Subsequently I will focus on my thesis’ question: how perceptual processes can influence<br />

our internal time keeping mechanisms. Different views exist about whether subjective<br />

duration is based on early perceptual processes or relates to higher-level stimulus<br />

processing requiring attention. In order to distinguish between the influences <strong>of</strong> early <strong>and</strong><br />

late processes perceptual processing on perceived duration, we applied a well-established<br />

paradigm from attention research: the Attentional Blink. Our preliminary findings argue<br />

for a specific influence <strong>of</strong> higher-level cognitive processes on perceived duration, or – in<br />

other words – suggest that simple changes in visual input do not fully explain the<br />

emergence <strong>of</strong> subjective duration.<br />

18


Vera Ludwig<br />

Hypnosis <strong>and</strong> Neuroscience<br />

Hypnosis can influence perception, behaviour, <strong>and</strong> cognition in healthy people. For<br />

example, susceptible individuals may temporarily experience their own movements as<br />

produced by an external source, they may have hallucinations, or they may report a<br />

complete absence <strong>of</strong> pain. Such effects make hypnosis a potentially powerful tool for<br />

cognitive neuroscience; <strong>and</strong> indeed, this method is increasingly being used in<br />

neuroimaging studies. I will explain what hypnosis can do for mind-<strong>and</strong>-brain research by<br />

showing how it has helped to elucidate the neural basis <strong>of</strong> certain subjective phenomena<br />

(e.g., pain, feeling <strong>of</strong> agency). However, I will also consider the limitations <strong>and</strong> challenges<br />

<strong>of</strong> research using hypnosis – in particular, the possibility that hypnotized participants are<br />

merely role-playing. After the presentation, we will discuss to what extent <strong>and</strong> in which<br />

cases hypnosis can be a useful research tool.<br />

19


<strong>Berlin</strong> Faculty<br />

List <strong>of</strong> participants<br />

Ellen Fridl<strong>and</strong>, PhD ellenfridl<strong>and</strong>@gmail.com<br />

Pr<strong>of</strong>. Michael Pauen m@pauen.com<br />

Pr<strong>of</strong>. Arno Villringer villringer@cbs.mpg.de<br />

<strong>Berlin</strong> Participants<br />

Ryszard Auksztulewicz rikismo@gmail.com<br />

Sophie Herbst ksherbst@gmail.com<br />

Bianca van Kemenade biancavankemenade@gmail.com<br />

Saskia Koehler saskia.koehler@psychologie.hu-berlin.de<br />

Vera Ludwig vera.Ludwig@gmx.net<br />

Rol<strong>and</strong> Nigbur rol<strong>and</strong>nigbur@googlemail.com<br />

Smadar Ovadia smadar.ovadia@gmail.com<br />

Milena Rabovsky milena.rabovsky@hu-berlin.de<br />

Fern<strong>and</strong>o Ramirez toporam@yahoo.com<br />

Georgina Torbet gtorbe01@students.bbk.ac.uk<br />

Corinde Wiers corinde@gmail.com<br />

Emiliano Zaccarella zaccarella@cbs.mpg.de<br />

Munich Faculty<br />

Pr<strong>of</strong>. Benedikt Grothe grothe@lmu.de<br />

PD Dr. Stephan Sellmaier stephan.sellmaier@lrz.uni-muenchen.de<br />

Pr<strong>of</strong>. Wilhelm Vossenkuhl vossenkuhl@lmu.de<br />

Munich Participants<br />

Armin Bahl arbahl@gmail.com<br />

Aleks<strong>and</strong>ra Kupferberg aleks<strong>and</strong>ra.kupferberg@gmx.de<br />

David Kaufmann david_kaufmann@gmx.net<br />

Joachim Lipski abt-nihil@gmx.de<br />

Arun Singh arun.singh@med.uni-muenchen.de<br />

Judy Ng judyng@neuro.mpg.de<br />

Barbara Trattner barbaratrattner@hotmail.com<br />

Sebastian Philipp seb.t.p@gmx.de<br />

Christian Kellner kellner@biologie.uni-muenchen.de<br />

Alex<strong>and</strong>ra Soutschek alex.soutschek@web.de<br />

Annette Winkelmann, Manager <strong>Berlin</strong> <strong>School</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Mind</strong> <strong>and</strong> Barin<br />

Dr. Alex<strong>and</strong>ra Stein, Coordinator Graduate <strong>School</strong> <strong>of</strong> Systemic Neurosciences<br />

20


Accomodation <strong>and</strong> transportation<br />

Our accommodation: Don Orione Artigianelli<br />

Website: www.donorione-venezia.it<br />

Zattere Dorsoduro 909/A - 30123 Venezia –<br />

tel +39 0415224077 - fax +39 0415286214<br />

Transportation to San Servolo<br />

From the guesthouse, you need to go to the station "Zaterre" <strong>and</strong> take boat number 51 or<br />

2, leaving at 8:21 / 8:20 to San Zaccaria <strong>and</strong> there change to line 20 to San Servolo.<br />

(http://www.actv.it/; http://www.univiu.org/viu-quick/how-to-get-viu)<br />

21

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!