18.06.2013 Views

TRAGIC RECOGNITION: ACTION AND IDENTITY IN ANTIGONE ...

TRAGIC RECOGNITION: ACTION AND IDENTITY IN ANTIGONE ...

TRAGIC RECOGNITION: ACTION AND IDENTITY IN ANTIGONE ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

<strong>TRAGIC</strong> <strong>RECOGNITION</strong>: <strong>ACTION</strong> <strong>AND</strong> <strong>IDENTITY</strong><br />

<strong>IN</strong> <strong>ANTIGONE</strong> <strong>AND</strong> ARISTOTLE<br />

Patchen Markell<br />

The University of Chicago<br />

Department of Political Science<br />

5828 S. University Ave.<br />

Chicago, IL 60637<br />

p-markell@uchicago.edu<br />

Prepared for the Center for Law, Culture, and Social Thought,<br />

Northwestern University, March 9, 2001.<br />

Comments welcome. Not for citation or circulation without permission.


This unchangeable identity of the person, though disclosing itself<br />

intangibly in act and speech, becomes tangible only in the story of<br />

the actor’s and speaker’s life; but as such it can be known, that<br />

is, grasped as a palpable entity only after it has come to its end.<br />

1. The politics and poetics of recognition.<br />

1<br />

Hannah Arendt 1<br />

In a famous passage in the Letter to D’Alembert, Rousseau proposed a form of<br />

“entertainment” to replace the shadowy corruption of the theatre: “Plant a stake crowned with<br />

flowers in the middle of a square; gather the people together there, and you will have a festival.<br />

Do better yet; let the spectators become an entertainment to themselves; make them actors<br />

themselves; do it so that each sees and loves himself in the others so that all will be better<br />

united.” 2 This is a vision of a society bound together, happily, by mutual recognition.<br />

Contemporary political philosophers have cited it as an exemplary early statement of the now-<br />

familiar ideal of equal and reciprocal recognition: just as Rousseau’s republican citizens exchanged<br />

a love grounded in unimpeded mutual knowledge, so the contemporary discourse of recognition<br />

envisions a world in which citizens extend each other forms of respect grounded in the accurate,<br />

undistorted mutual cognition of their identities. 3


Of course, the tradition of dramatic theatre that Rousseau scorned was no stranger to the<br />

notion of recognition. Against the background of the tradition of “recognition-scenes” in tragic<br />

drama—Oedipus’s shattering moment of self-discovery, for example, or Electra’s recognition of<br />

Orestes via his footprints and hair—Aristotle had introduced the concept of recognition,<br />

anagnôrisis, to name one of the constitutive elements of a fine tragedy; 4 since then, recognition<br />

has been both a crucial element in dramatic plots and a central concept in poetics. 5 On the tragic<br />

stage, however, recognition looks startlingly different. In Rousseau as in contemporary political<br />

theory, successful or adequate recognition is presented as a source of satisfaction, fulfillment, and<br />

emancipation; tragic recognition-scenes, by contrast, are often moments of catastrophic loss and<br />

occasions for mourning. 6<br />

What lies behind this striking difference in valence? What can theories and examples of<br />

tragic anagnôrisis teach contemporary political theory about the concept of recognition? This<br />

paper explores these questions through readings of Sophocles’ Antigone and Aristotle’s Poetics.<br />

In the larger work of which this paper is a part, I argue that contemporary theories and practices<br />

of recognition are grounded in more fundamental, “ontological” misrecognitions—that is,<br />

misrecognitions not of this or that identity, but of certain fundamental features of the social and<br />

political world and our place in it. 7 The Antigone, I suggest, can help us identify and understand<br />

these misrecognitions, because it depicts characters who put into practice some of the same<br />

ontological assumptions that lie behind the contemporary discourse of recognition, and in so<br />

doing, suffer tragic fates. Moreover, since tragedy is not just action but the representation of<br />

action, 8 it keeps its audience or readers a step removed from the immediacy of practice, enabling<br />

us to “see a whole denied to those who enact their parts,” and thereby helping us reflect on the<br />

2


nature, sources, and consequences of the tragic characters’ blind spots—which may also, in other<br />

contexts, be ours. 9<br />

The particular ontological issue that concerns me here is the relationship between identity<br />

and action, although, as I shall suggest, this issue is also tied to larger questions about sovereignty<br />

and finitude. What the central characters in the Antigone share with the contemporary discourse<br />

of recognition, I claim, is a fundamental faith in the capacity of “identities”—regarded in this case<br />

as coherent systems of value and affect, anchored in specific locations in the human world—to<br />

serve as the prior ground of agency, reliably guiding and governing action. This understanding of<br />

the connection between identity and action is especially vivid in contemporary discussions of<br />

multiculturalism. Some theorists argue straightforwardly that the cultural identity of a group<br />

“defines” or “determines” its members’ activities, while others contend that the constitutive<br />

relationship between identity and agency is mediated by choice—but the basic idea remains the<br />

same: we know what we are to do, at least in some significant part, by knowing who we are; and<br />

this is why inadequate or improper recognition of cultural identities can (it’s claimed) “cripple”<br />

those who are subject to it. 10<br />

At one level, of course, this view of the relationship of action to identity, by situating our<br />

agency in social and historical context, reflects an admirable skepticism toward what has<br />

famously been called the idea of the “unencumbered subject.” 11 But to say that subjects are<br />

situated in and constitutively encumbered by contexts and histories beyond their control does not<br />

entail that those encumbrances form coherent, intelligible wholes that determine our action in<br />

absolutely predictable ways, and which could thus be the objects of truthful, and therefore<br />

liberating, acts of recognition. Indeed, that idea too easily sidesteps the most radical implications<br />

of the critique of the unsituated self. Even as it attacks the fantasy of a subject always already at<br />

3


one with itself by virtue of its transcendence of context and history, the discourse of recognition<br />

salvages the wish for sovereign agency that lies at the heart of that fantasy, envisioning a subject<br />

restored to itself through the accurate and respectful cognition of its identity—a subject, in other<br />

words, that wins its sovereignty in the thick of context and history, rather than above it.<br />

As I have said, the antagonists in the Antigone share this view of the relationship between<br />

action and identity, as well as the aspiration to sovereignty that underlies it. Yet this is only<br />

Sophocles’ point of departure: the movement of the tragedy cuts against this view. The next two<br />

sections of this paper trace this movement: in section two, I spell out the idea that the Antigone<br />

can be read as a paradigmatic struggle for recognition, structured by the assumption of the<br />

priority of identity to action; in section 3, I draw out an implicit critique of this assumption in<br />

the action of the play, tracking the ways in which Antigone’s and Creon’s acts exceed the terms<br />

of identity by which they seek to govern their conduct. I call this feature of action its<br />

“impropriety” with respect to identity. In section 4, I turn to Aristotle’s Poetics to develop a<br />

more explicit account of the nature, sources, and consequences of action’s improprieties, tying<br />

the Antigone’s story about the relationship of action to identity to Aristotle’s account of the<br />

relationship of action to êthos or character. 12 And these connections return us, in the end, to the<br />

concept of recognition in Aristotle’s Poetics, as well as to the distinctive recognition-scenes of<br />

the Antigone. The distinctive meaning and valence of “recognition” in tragedy, I shall suggest,<br />

arises out of its unorthodox perspective on the relationship between action and identity: tragic<br />

anagnôrisis involves not getting identity right so that it can ground our action; instead, it involves<br />

acknowledging, often under the weight of failure, the limits to the possibility of doing so.<br />

2. The Antigone as a struggle for recognition.<br />

4


Sophocles’ Antigone is set after the death of Oedipus and in the wake of the deadly<br />

rivalry between his sons, Polyneices and Eteocles. 13 After being exiled by his brother,<br />

Polyneices led an Argive army against Thebes, and the two brothers died at each other’s hands. 14<br />

Since the only surviving descendants of Oedipus were the sisters Antigone and Ismene, the<br />

kingship of Thebes fell to Jocasta’s brother Creon, who faced the task of deciding how to treat<br />

the bodies of the fallen warriors. 15 Creon gives Eteocles a hero’s burial, but orders Polyneices’<br />

corpse left unburied and unlamented, and declares that “anyone who dares attempt the act” of<br />

burial “will die by public stoning in the town” (35–36). As the play opens, Antigone tells<br />

Ismene of Creon’s decree, and asks her to help defy the command and bury their brother’s body.<br />

When Ismene refuses and reminds Antigone of her obligation to obey the city’s leaders, Antigone<br />

does the deed herself. The outraged Creon condemns both sisters to death. Creon’s son<br />

Haemon, to whom Antigone is betrothed, protests his father’s judgment, but to little avail.<br />

Creon relents and releases Ismene, but orders Antigone sealed alive in a cave outside the city.<br />

After Antigone, lamenting her fate, has been led away, Creon is visited by the prophet Teiresias,<br />

who foretells that Creon’s impious acts will be repaid by death in Creon’s own family, and will<br />

bring destruction to Thebes. Frightened, Creon tries to reverse his actions: he rushes to bury<br />

Polyneices’ corpse and then to free Antigone. But Antigone has already hung herself, and<br />

Haemon has already discovered her body. Creon arrives at Antigone’s tomb just in time to<br />

witness his son’s angry, desperate suicide; and when news of Haemon’s death reaches his<br />

mother, Eurydice, she too dies by her own hand, cursing Creon with her final breath. As the play<br />

draws to a close, Creon, acknowledging his guilt, prays for an early death.<br />

5


At first glance, the Antigone doesn’t seem to contain anything like the archetypal<br />

“recognition scenes” of Greek literature: Odysseus gradually revealing himself after returning to<br />

Ithaca in disguise; Oedipus discovering that he himself is the murderer whose identity he has<br />

sworn to discover; Electra finding traces of and finally recognizing Orestes at Agamemnon’s<br />

tomb. 16 Yet even without telltale scars and familiar locks of hair, the Antigone is full of<br />

recognitions. The conflict with which the play begins is essentially a controversy about how to<br />

recognize Polyneices; moreover, that controversy involves two adversaries who ground their<br />

actions in confident claims about who Polyneices is, and also, as we shall see, in claims about<br />

their own identities. In this way, the opening of the Antigone models the theoretical<br />

underpinnings of the contemporary politics of recognition: the antagonists attempt to ground<br />

their own actions in their knowledge of identities, and, on the basis of these properly cognized<br />

identities, to secure respect from others. 17<br />

The question of recognition first arises with respect to the dead Polyneices, whose body<br />

is the principal object of controversy in the Antigone. The idea of a conflict over the burial of<br />

bodies was probably not original with Sophocles. Attic funeral orators often recalled the story of<br />

Thebes’ refusal to allow the burial of the corpses of the invading Argive army, which supposedly<br />

provoked a heroic Athenian expedition to recover the bodies. 18 But these were simple, self-<br />

congratulatory stories of Athenian virtue in the face of sheer impiety, and not the stuff of deep<br />

ethical conflict. 19 Sophocles’ version of the story focuses our attention on problems of identity<br />

and recognition by zeroing in on the disparate treatment of Eteocles and Polyneices. 20 The case<br />

of Polyneices and Eteocles is distinctive, because the question of how to deal with Polyneices’<br />

body seems to hangs on who he is—and he can be recognized under two incompatible<br />

descriptions, each of which highlights one aspect of his relationship to Eteocles. On the one<br />

6


hand, Polyneices is a native of Thebes, a member of the ruling family, the brother of Antigone<br />

and Ismene, and the nephew of Creon himself—all relations that throw his affiliation with<br />

Eteocles into relief. Under this description, Polyneices unquestionably ought to be buried, for it<br />

was not only a right but an obligation to give the proper funeral rites to one’s kin. 21 On the other<br />

hand, Polyneices is a traitor who has just raised an army against Thebes out of jealousy and<br />

vindictiveness toward his brother. 22 This perspective makes the difference between Polyneices<br />

and Eteocles more salient than the fact of their affiliation, and demands that they be treated<br />

differently in death. 23<br />

Here, then, as in the contemporary politics of recognition, cognition and respect are<br />

brought together in a distinctive constellation. The distribution of respect is supposed to be<br />

grounded in knowledge of identity; thus, the disagreement about whether Polyneices is a kinsman<br />

or a traitor engenders a further conflict about whether he ought to be granted a funeral, or left to<br />

rot. Indeed, the theme of burial illustrates the close relationship between these two components<br />

of recognition—cognition and respect—with exceptional clarity. Funeral rites are an expression<br />

of respect: they affirm the membership of the deceased in a cross-generational community, and<br />

they create monuments to the dead that help to preserve traces of this community within the<br />

world of the living. Moreover, funeral rites confer honor and affirmation precisely through the<br />

articulation of the identity of the deceased. The spontaneous lament, the public funeral oration<br />

and the carefully composed elegy all recollect the dead person’s character and actions, and the<br />

epitaph carved on the funeral monument helps to “secure a degree of personal immortality” for<br />

the deceased by delivering at least his name, and sometimes a record of his deeds and virtues, to<br />

posterity. 24 In burial, as in the contemporary politics of recognition, the public visibility of<br />

identity becomes an instrument for securing respect.<br />

7


Yet the Antigone’s struggle is not only about recognizing and respecting Polyneices.<br />

Although his death is the immediate occasion for the conflict between Antigone and Creon, the<br />

significance of their confrontation quickly widens, for both ground their obligations toward the<br />

corpse not only in their descriptions of Polyneices but also in accounts of their own identities. If<br />

we attend again to the significance of the themes of burial and lament in the Antigone, it should<br />

come as no surprise that the identities of Antigone and Creon are drawn into the controversy<br />

over Polyneices, for funeral ritual is at least as much about the living as about the dead. As<br />

psychological studies of mourning emphasize, the same rites of burial and lament that serve to<br />

memorialize the dead also help to reconstitute the agency of the mourner in the face of loss. 25<br />

The linguistic and physical artifacts produced as a part of funeral ritual—laments, eulogies, grave<br />

markers—cannot really replace the lost person. 26 But in the production of such artifacts, and<br />

through participation in the symbolic systems that govern funeral procedure, mourners try to<br />

reconstruct the agency that the intrusive facticity of death had seemed to undermine. 27 Of<br />

course, that agency is never experienced immediately and abstractly, but only by occupying<br />

particular roles and identities in the social world; and since the roles and identities through which<br />

different people experience agency may make incompatible demands in a single case, an instance<br />

of mourning can quickly become the occasion for broader social conflict. In this way, the struggle<br />

over Polyneices turns into a struggle for recognition between Antigone and Creon, as they try<br />

unsuccessfully to compel each other to acknowledge not just some facets of Polyneices’ identity,<br />

but the legitimacy of their own identities—of the locations in the ethical world from which<br />

Antigone and Creon try to address the personal and civic losses Polyneices’ body represents.<br />

Antigone and Creon introduce themselves, and articulate the identities in which they<br />

ground their acts, in the first two episodes of the play: Antigone’s exchange with Ismene, and<br />

8


Creon’s speech to the chorus. These scenes show the audience for the first time who these<br />

characters are, and they do so by locating them within the social world that constitutes the<br />

background to the events of the play. As Simon Goldhill and others have observed, one of the<br />

most important ways Antigone and Creon locate themselves is via their contrasting uses of the<br />

opposition between philos and ekhthros, which both characters employ with reference to<br />

Polyneices. 28 As a concrete noun, philos is usually translated “friend”; as an adjective, the same<br />

word is rendered as “dear,” “beloved” or “loving”; and the related noun philia is translated as<br />

“friendship” or “love.” Correspondingly, ekhthros, as a concrete noun, is translated “enemy”; as<br />

an adjective it is rendered as “hostile” or “hated”; and the abstract noun ekhthra is translated as<br />

“hatred” or “enmity.” 29 Yet these translations do not do justice to the semantic range of the<br />

words, especially in the case of philos and philia, which could be used in the context of nearly<br />

any “positive” reciprocal relationships, including bonds among kin, strategic alliances, the<br />

extension of hospitality to strangers, self-love, and the ties of marriage, as well as the class of<br />

personal relationships of mutual affection and support that we normally call “friendship.” 30<br />

Precisely because of their semantic breadth, these words are well-suited to become the focus of a<br />

struggle over the legitimacy and priority of different kinds of social bond. Antigone and Creon<br />

make good use of this potential, transforming what is initially a debate about Polyneices into a<br />

conflict over the proper sense of philos and ekhthros—and thereby announcing their own deepest<br />

commitments to the audience. 31<br />

Antigone’s exchange with Ismene, for instance, is framed by the theme of philia. In the<br />

opening lines of the play, Antigone approaches Ismene with news of Creon’s edict: “Have you<br />

heard anything?” she asks, “or don’t you know that the foes’ [ekhthrôn] trouble comes upon our<br />

friends [philous]” (10)? Antigone implies that in denying burial not only to the six fallen Argive<br />

9


commanders but also to Polyneices, Creon has brought an evil appropriate to an ekhthros upon a<br />

philos. 32 We do not yet know in virtue of what characteristic or relationship Antigone considers<br />

Polyneices philos, but in the course of her exchange with Ismene, Antigone’s meaning becomes<br />

clear.<br />

First, Antigone indicates that she considers Polyneices philos by virtue of kinship. When<br />

Ismene expresses her surprise at Antigone’s plan of disobedience, Antigone justifies herself<br />

simply by referring to the fact of family ties. Polyneices is “my brother, and yours, though you<br />

may wish he were not,” Antigone says. In this declaration, she also identifies herself by placing<br />

herself in a network of blood ties and expressing her allegiance to the bonds of the family.<br />

Second, Antigone indicates that her obligations of philia to Polyneices arise from what she will<br />

later call the “unwritten and unfailing laws” of “the gods below” (451, 455), which govern<br />

reproduction and death. 33 Ismene introduces the theme, contrasting “them below the earth” with<br />

“the men in power” in the city—but while Ismene declares that she feels compelled to obey the<br />

city (65–67), Antigone responds that she regards the underworld as of greater import than the<br />

world of the living, and suggests that once she has “dared the crime of piety,” she will be able to<br />

lie alongside Polyneices, philos with philos (73–74). Finally, although the gendering of the<br />

conflict between Antigone and Creon is more explicit in Creon’s speeches, Antigone does some<br />

of the work of gender identification in her exchange with Ismene. Although the contrasting case<br />

of Ismene, who submissively cautions her sister to “remember that we two are women” who<br />

should not fight with men (61–62), might be taken to be indirect evidence of Antigone’s<br />

resistance to any identification with conventional gender roles, the truth is more complex. As<br />

Charles Segal has explained, for instance, the vocabulary of kinship with which Antigone refers to<br />

her siblings is itself gendered: it “makes kinship a function of the female procreative power,” in<br />

10


direct contrast to the patrilineal system of kinship on which membership in the polis was based,<br />

and from which women were excluded. The ordinary words for brother and sister, adelphos and<br />

adelphê, literally indicate kinship through the womb (delphus), a variety of kinship to which<br />

Antigone calls attention when she later calls Polyneices homosplanchnos—a less ordinary word<br />

that also means “of the same womb” (511). 34 Should the etymologies seem trivial, recall that the<br />

question of the nature of kinship and its relation to gender was a live issue for the Greek<br />

audience: as Segal points out, Antigone’s use of matrilineal kinship words “reopens, on a<br />

personal level, the debate between Apollo and the Erinyes in Aeschylus’s Oresteia,” where the<br />

issue was precisely whether the father’s seed or the mother’s womb played a more important<br />

role in reproduction. 35<br />

Moreover, Antigone’s identification with (at least some) conventional gender roles is later<br />

borne out by the manner in which she performs her duties of philia to Polyneices. Although she<br />

does initially declare her intention to “pile the burial-mound” for Polyneices (80)—a task that<br />

was generally performed by men—she does not actually bury the body but merely sprinkles dust<br />

on the corpse, “enough to turn the curse,” as the guard says (255). 36 Later, just before being led<br />

away by Creon’s guards, she describes her action in a way that conforms quite precisely to<br />

classical norms governing the role of women in funeral rites: “All three of you have known my<br />

hand in death,” she says, referring to Oedipus, Jocasta, and Polyneices; “I washed your bodies,<br />

dressed them for the grave, poured out the last libation at the tomb” (900–902). And, finally,<br />

Sophocles describes Antigone’s lament over Polyneices’ corpse with a familiar, gendered image<br />

specifically associated with the mourning of mothers for their children: “the sharp and shrill cry<br />

of a bitter bird which sees the nest bare where the young birds lay” (423–24). 37<br />

11


Creon’s first speech sharply contests Antigone’s understanding of philia. Whereas<br />

Antigone regards Polyneices as philos by virtue of kinship, treats her own obligations to him as a<br />

matter of chthonian piety, and expresses a gender identity in the way she grounds and performs<br />

these obligations, Creon explicitly rejects each of these identifications. First, although Polyneices<br />

is Creon’s kinsman too, Creon treats him as ekhthros, not philos, because for Creon the criteria of<br />

philia are exclusively political. “He who counts another greater friend [philon] than his own<br />

fatherland [patra], I put him nowhere,” Creon announces (182–83), already invoking the<br />

principle of patrilineal descent that underlay membership in the polis against Antigone’s<br />

matrilineal vocabulary of kinship. Only the ship of state, “sailing straight,” can make it possible<br />

for us to “have friends [philous] at all,” Creon asserts (189–90). For Creon, Polyneices ceased to<br />

be a philos the moment he raised an army against Thebes, and after she violates the city’s laws,<br />

Antigone too will be called a “false friend” [philos kakos] (652). 38 In identifying himself instead<br />

as a citizen and ruler whose deepest commitment is to the all-important law of the polis, Creon<br />

trumps both the principle of kinship and the eternal and unwritten chthonian law that<br />

supposedly assigns duties within the family.<br />

Creon’s exclusively civic conception of philia is also rigidly masculine. As Creon’s<br />

polemical use of the word patra as a synonym for the polis has already indicated, citizenship and<br />

rulership are properly the business of men, and only men. The intertwining of gender identity<br />

with the distinction between polis and oikos, already implied in Creon’s first speech, runs so<br />

deep that Creon, upon hearing the guard’s report that Polyneices’ corpse has been buried, thinks<br />

only to ask “what man [tis andrôn] has dared to do it” (248). The fact that Antigone has<br />

disobeyed thus turns out to be an especially potent threat to Creon’s authority: it throws into<br />

question not just his authority in this particular case, but his masculinity, the condition of the<br />

12


possibility of his political authority as such. In response, Creon’s gendering of the polis<br />

becomes more explicit, insistent, even hysterical: he repeats in different ways and to various<br />

people that he will never let himself be conquered, ruled, defeated by a woman. 39 In one<br />

remarkable passage Creon ties together his renunciation of the ties of kinship as grounds of philia<br />

and the preservation of his own masculinity:<br />

I am no man and she the man instead<br />

if she can have this conquest without pain.<br />

She is my sister’s [adelphês] child, but were she child<br />

of closer kin than any at my hearth,<br />

she and her sister should not so escape<br />

their death and doom (484–89).<br />

These, then, are Antigone’s and Creon’s representations of their own identities (and Polyneices’)<br />

which they deploy in their efforts to guide their own actions and to influence or control the<br />

actions of others. Their confident self-descriptions fit well with the common view that Antigone<br />

represents the family, the chthonian, and the female, while Creon represents the city, the human,<br />

and the male. 40 Yet by focusing on what Antigone and Creon properly represent, we would<br />

ignore the movement and action of the play. For when Antigone and Creon try to fulfill or enact<br />

their identities in their deeds, they find that their actions do not flow smoothly from their<br />

identities: as we shall see, they commit what I shall call “improprieties” with respect to the<br />

identities they claim to bear, and these improprieties place them at odds with their own deepest<br />

commitments. The fact that Antigone and Creon’s deeds cannot easily be reconciled with (what<br />

they take to be) their identities is not evidence of a failure in Sophocles’ characterization; rather,<br />

it is a comment about the nature of identity, and about the limits of our capacity to deploy<br />

identity to predict and govern the meanings and consequences of our actions.<br />

3. The improprieties of action.<br />

13


What happens when Antigone and Creon attempt to ground their actions in their<br />

identities? Consider Antigone first. Her action exceeds and frustrates her identifications in two<br />

related ways: first, Antigone does more than she intends. Antigone frames her action as an<br />

expression of the pious devotion of sister to brother, and she underscores this identification<br />

through her refusal of the vocabulary of politics. Whenever Antigone is confronted with a claim<br />

about the city, she replies exclusively in the vocabulary of the family, refusing the possibility of<br />

any distinction between her brothers, even one more attenuated than Creon’s. As Martha<br />

Nussbaum puts it, “if one listened only to Antigone, one would not know that a war had taken<br />

place or that anything called ‘city’ was ever in danger.” 41 Despite her refusal of the vocabulary<br />

of politics, however, her expression of family piety turns out also to be an act of political<br />

subversion.<br />

However, Antigone does not merely turn out to have done more than she had intended,<br />

for her act places her into conflict not only with what she disavows but also with her own<br />

deepest commitments. Antigone’s relationship with Ismene is a telling example of this second<br />

kind of impropriety. Although Antigone is willing to suffer death out of loyalty to a blood-<br />

relative, in the pursuit of her goal she behaves toward her sister—her adelphê, born of the same<br />

womb just like Polyneices—with cold, vindictive hostility. When Ismene tries to warn Antigone<br />

that it is foolish to pursue her goal against the irresistible force of the polis, Antigone responds:<br />

“If that’s your saying, I shall hate you first, and next the dead will hate you in all justice”<br />

(93–94). And when Ismene shows her belated support for her sister by falsely declaring to<br />

Creon that she had been an accessory to the deed, Antigone declines the offer of solidarity,<br />

insisting that she “cannot love a friend whose love is words” (543)—and this comes mere<br />

14


moments after Antigone declares to Creon that it is her nature to love, not to hate (523)! 42 In<br />

pursuit of divine justice for her brother, Antigone undermines her own identification with the<br />

principle of devotion to the family by declaring her hatred for the sister whom, on her own<br />

account, she ought to love.<br />

Antigone’s action subverts not only her identification as a member of a family, but also<br />

her identification with conventional gender roles. As we have seen, by preparing Polyneices’<br />

body for burial, scattering dust on the corpse to symbolize the burial that she herself does not<br />

perform, lamenting Polyneices’ death, and pouring a final libation, Antigone follows the norms<br />

governing female participation in funeral ritual. But Antigone acts amid circumstances that make<br />

it impossible for her to conform to this traditional role without also violating equally central<br />

norms of gender.<br />

Antigone’s impropriety with respect to conventional gender roles is most clearly evident<br />

in Creon’s hysterical response to her disobedience, which reminds us that the very appearance of<br />

women in civic space threatened the constitutive boundary between oikos and polis. Thus, for<br />

example, after pronouncing his initial sentence on Antigone and Ismene, Creon orders his slaves<br />

to take them back inside the walls of the palace, insisting: “They must be women now. No more<br />

free running” (578–79). 43 The form of punishment Creon finally chooses for Antigone is an even<br />

more radical enclosure of this improper woman: Antigone herself notices the analogy between the<br />

cave in which she is to be buried and the oikos in which women are confined, for she calls the<br />

cave her “marriage-chamber” and her “hollowed-out house” (891–92). 44 Indeed, although Creon<br />

himself never indicates such a motivation, it is noteworthy that his strategy of burying Antigone<br />

alive rather than having her stoned to death, as originally planned, conveniently sidesteps the<br />

issue of Antigone’s funeral rites: confined to the cave, she will die “with no friend’s mourning”<br />

15


(844). Given the function of the lament and the epitaph in conferring worldly immortality,<br />

perhaps the punishment of an unwitnessed death was intended to prevent Antigone and her acts<br />

of resistance from being memorialized in the city; to keep even her name out of the public<br />

sphere—which would, again, restore a conventional order of gender in which only men were<br />

properly bearers of individual distinction, deserving of public remembrance. 45<br />

Yet we do not need to assume the perspective of the anxiously masculine Creon in order<br />

to understand Antigone’s action as an impropriety with respect to gender identity. Antigone’s<br />

action frustrates her own identification as a woman even from her own perspective, by blocking<br />

the usual trajectory from girlhood to marriage and reproduction—and thereby also shattering her<br />

identification with her mother. In an important recent essay that touches on these themes, Matt<br />

Neuburg shows the importance of the distinction between blood-ties and marriage-ties in the<br />

Antigone. “Antigone will never get to have a marriage-family,” Neuburg observes, because “she is<br />

going to die for the sake of her blood-family: her two roles in the world, daughter and sister on<br />

the one hand, wife and mother on the other, have come into apparently irreconcilable conflict.” 46<br />

And indeed, Antigone’s own lament upon her fate reflects this conflict: “My curse,” she mourns,<br />

“is to die unwed” (869). What Neuburg overlooks is that, because marriage-ties and blood-ties<br />

are not only distinct but interdependent, Antigone’s deed also undermines her identification with<br />

the principle of kinship through blood by depriving her of the opportunity to bear children: as<br />

Antigone herself says, “no marriage-bed, no marriage-song for me, and since no wedding, so no<br />

child to rear” (917–18, emphasis added). 47<br />

Creon’s deeds, too, make him into an improper representative of the identities he initially<br />

claimed as his own. As we have seen, Antigone’s act takes on a political meaning to which she<br />

remains obstinately blind in her commitment to the family and its law. Likewise, Creon’s act<br />

16


turns out to have familial implications that he, focused exclusively on the polis, does not<br />

acknowledge. Creon is, after all, not only the ruler of Thebes but also the head of the oikos to<br />

which Antigone belongs; indeed, he is doubly tied to her both as Jocasta’s brother and as the<br />

father of her fiancé. But in his encounter with Antigone, Creon notably does not explicitly<br />

invoke his familial authority; instead, he continues to assert the political distinction between<br />

Polyneices and Eteocles, just as Antigone repeatedly counters him in the vocabulary of kinship.<br />

When Haemon arrives on the scene, he invites his father to speak the language of family by<br />

offering a conventional expression of filial loyalty: “My father, I am yours. You keep me<br />

straight with your good judgment, which I shall ever follow” (635–36). 48 But Creon refuses the<br />

invitation and quickly shifts the terms of the conversation, swallowing family into polis. He<br />

replies by praising Haemon, but immediately introduces the metaphor of “a soldier posted<br />

behind his leader” to describe the proper relation of son to father (640). 49 Finally, although<br />

Creon nominally acknowledges that Antigone’s disobedience is an instance of disorder within the<br />

oikos, he does so only in order to deny that Antigone’s kinship ought to influence his action, and<br />

to reinforce his subordination of all other concerns to political rule. To permit disobedience<br />

among relatives, Creon says, would compel him to permit it in the city at large; thus, enforcing<br />

the edict against Antigone is just another instance of ensuring “justice in the polis” (662). But<br />

Creon’s act, like Antigone’s, exceeds the identity from which it proceeds. Just as Antigone’s act<br />

of family piety was also an act of political subversion, Creon’s defense of political order also<br />

turns out to be an assault on his own family, first in the person of Haemon, whose love for<br />

Antigone drives him to join her in death, and second in Eurydice, driven to suicide by the loss of<br />

her son.<br />

17


Worse still, Creon’s acts, like Antigone’s, not only exceed but also undermine his own<br />

identifications. Just as Antigone’s ruthless devotion to her family leads her to treat her own<br />

sister cruelly, for instance, Creon’s monomaniacal pursuit of civic order transforms him from a<br />

leader into a tyrant. After Creon shifts the terrain of his exchange with Haemon from family to<br />

city, Haemon criticizes his father’s style of rule, at first gently and then with increasing passion<br />

and frustration. After reminding Creon of the murmurs of support for Antigone among the<br />

citizens of Thebes, Haemon warns his father: “do not have one mind, and one alone,” for<br />

“whoever thinks that he alone is wise” will, “come the unfolding, sho[w] his emptiness” (705–9).<br />

Here already we have a pointed suggestion that Creon is betraying his own values, since he<br />

himself had earlier mocked Antigone for acting in isolation from the rest of the city (510);<br />

Teiresias will confirm the suggestion by insinuating that Creon is not a king but a “tyrant”<br />

(1056), and by forecasting the devastation that Creon’s misrule will bring, not only upon his<br />

family, but upon the entire city (1080–84).<br />

Finally, just as Antigone’s action exceeds and frustrates her identification as a woman,<br />

Creon’s deeds, though meant to secure his masculinity, actually undermine it. For Creon, as we<br />

have seen, masculinity is closely tied to political rule, and therefore (he insists) to the rejection of<br />

the normative force of kinship. But consanguinity was what brought him the political power<br />

through which he expresses his manhood: he rules Thebes by virtue of being Jocasta’s<br />

adelphos—the very same relation in which Polyneices and Antigone stand. His disavowal of the<br />

import of kinship leads to the death of his own son, Haemon, in a violent rush of blood (haima).<br />

As Creon is graphically reminded of the blood-ties he had repressed, his fragile economy of<br />

identification and disavowal collapses like a house of cards. “So insistent earlier on the<br />

separation of gender roles and scornful of the female,” Segal observes, “Creon now performs the<br />

18


characteristically (though not exclusively) female role of lamenting over a ‘child,’” expressing the<br />

destabilizing anguish and bitterness that his edict had tried and failed to keep out of public<br />

view. 50<br />

Perhaps the most powerful image that the Antigone offers of the capacity of actions to<br />

exceed the intentions and control of agents comes near the end of the play, as Creon tries to undo<br />

what he has done. After confronting Teiresias, who finally gives Creon an account of his crimes<br />

and foretells the destruction that await him and his city, Creon yields, and tries to stave off his<br />

fate, announcing that he has “come to fear it’s best to hold to the laws of old tradition to the end<br />

of life” (1113–14). Some of what happens next we witness or learn through the reports of a<br />

messenger before Creon does, but the special force of the sequence of events emerges if we<br />

examine it in strict chronology and from Creon’s perspective. First, as the messenger recounts,<br />

Creon and the chorus went to bury Polyneices’ corpse, hoping to reverse the pollution that the<br />

exposed body had brought upon the city (1197–1200). 51 It’s not clear whether Creon relents in<br />

time to turn the curse or not, since Teiresias has said that other cities, whose hearths have been<br />

polluted by the animals that fed on the exposed corpses, are already preparing to make war on<br />

Thebes (1080–84). 52 With no time to speculate, Creon and his rescue party proceed toward<br />

Antigone’s tomb, from which, at a distance, they hear the “keen lament” of Haemon’s voice<br />

(1208). Antigone has already hanged herself, and while Creon was busy burying Polyneices,<br />

Haemon found the tomb and discovered her fate. When Creon finally reaches the burial chamber,<br />

he finds Haemon mournfully embracing Antigone; Haemon says nothing to his father, but lashes<br />

out at him with his sword, and then turns his weapon on himself, dying in a bloody embrace with<br />

Antigone (1220–40). At this point, the messenger leaves Creon and the rest of the party to<br />

attend to the bodies and rushes back to the palace, where he informs Eurydice (and us) of all the<br />

19


preceding events; she leaves the room without a word, followed in short order by the messenger,<br />

who is concerned that her silence “may portend as great disaster as a loud lament” (1251–52).<br />

Creon arrives shortly thereafter—and just as he is confessing his crimes to the assembled chorus,<br />

the messenger returns to announce that Eurydice, too, has taken her own life (1282–83).<br />

Once Creon has given it life, we might say, his action breaks the bonds of intention and<br />

identity and goes off on its own, wreaking havoc. Creon rushes from the house to the deserted<br />

plain to the rocky cave and back to the house, all in a desperate attempt to chase down and<br />

subdue his errant deed, but the act and its reverberations always remain one tragic step ahead of<br />

its agent. In the case of the messenger’s early departure from the tomb, the deed, or at least its<br />

“signification,” is literally a step ahead of the doer. 53 Here, the character of the messenger vividly<br />

personifies the gap between the actor’s performance of a deed and the imitation or recollection of<br />

the deed in which its significance is expressed, offering tragic confirmation of Hannah Arendt’s<br />

observation that “nobody is the author or producer of his own life story.” 54<br />

4. The acknowledgment of finitude: Aristotle and the Antigone.<br />

In chapter 6 of the Poetics, Aristotle makes a famous claim about the relative importance<br />

of the constituent parts of tragic drama: “The most important of the six [parts of tragedy],” he<br />

says, “is the combination of the incidents of the story,” for “tragedy is essentially an imitation<br />

not of persons but of action and life” (1450a15–17). 55 Thus, for Aristotle, “the first essential,<br />

the life and soul, so to speak, of tragedy is the plot,” while “the characters [êthê] come second”<br />

(1450a38–39); indeed, the characters are included for the sake of the action rather than the other<br />

way around (1450a20–22). 56 Aristotle’s point here is sometimes taken to be wholly formal: it is<br />

20


part of a treatise articulating guidelines to be followed by practitioners of the craft of poetry,<br />

from which modern readers might also glean some insight about how to interpret works of<br />

literature. 57 Yet in the course of elaborating this claim about the priority of action and plot to<br />

character, Aristotle moves, momentarily, into a different register:<br />

Tragedy is essentially an imitation not of persons but of action and life, of<br />

happiness and misery. All human happiness or misery takes the form of action;<br />

the end for which we live is a kind of activity, not a quality. Character gives us<br />

qualities, but it is in our actions—what we do—that we are happy or the reverse.<br />

In a play accordingly they do not act in order to portray the characters; they<br />

include the characters for the sake of the action (1450a16–22, emphasis added). 58<br />

Aristotle’s claims in the emphasized sentences refer not only to the representation of<br />

action and character on the stage, but to action and character simpliciter. 59 As Martha Nussbaum<br />

has suggested in an important discussion of the relationship between the Poetics and Aristotle’s<br />

ethics, these passages suggest that for Aristotle, tragic drama’s formal characteristics are not<br />

merely formal, but reflect and illuminate features of the wider world. 60 Following this lead, I now<br />

turn to Aristotle’s Poetics in order to work out, in greater detail, the nature and sources of the<br />

“improprieties” that characterize Antigone’s and Creon’s actions, as well as to illuminate the<br />

specific meaning of tragic anagnôrisis or recognition. 61 As I have suggested, Sophocles’ text<br />

implies a critique of the assumptions about the relationship of action to identity that informed<br />

Antigone’s and Creon’s practical postures (and which are more explicitly articulated in the<br />

contemporary normative discourse of recognition). Aristotle’s claim that action has a kind of<br />

priority over character, I claim, can be read as a philosophical distillation of that critique.<br />

Moreover, tying Aristotle’s claims about action and character to his discussion of anagnôrisis<br />

later in the Poetics (and also back to the Antigone) will help show that tragic anagnôrisis consists<br />

21


not in the agency-enhancing recognition of an identity but rather in the acknowledgment what<br />

Hannah Arendt calls the “non-sovereign” character of human action. 62<br />

* * *<br />

In order to bring Aristotle’s claims about action and character to bear on the themes of<br />

action and identity we have been discussing so far, however, we need to deal with a<br />

terminological question: what is the relationship between Aristotelian êthos and the notion of<br />

identity? After all, it might be objected that Aristotelian êthos refers not to the full range of<br />

socially contingent characteristics we bear, but to our specifically moral or ethical qualities—that<br />

is, to the virtues and vices Aristotle discusses in his ethical treatises. 63 What does character in<br />

this sense have to do with the “identities” articulated by Antigone and Creon—much less with<br />

the use of “identity” in contemporary politics, with its heavy emphasis on group membership<br />

and ascriptive characteristics rather than the moral states of individual ethical agents?<br />

We can address this question by briefly examining the meaning of êthos, both in broader<br />

context and in Aristotle’s philosophy. In an illuminating discussion of the development of the<br />

term êthos from Homer down to Aristotle, Charles Chamberlain has shown that êthos originally<br />

referred to the “haunts” of an animal—that is, to the places where animals of a particular type<br />

were typically or characteristically found. 64 The term later came to be extended to human beings<br />

and transformed in a number of ways—but far from being used exclusively to refer to the vices<br />

and virtues of individuals, it was also used to refer to “the peculiarities which people of a certain<br />

polis acquire as a result of being brought up under its particular laws and customs”; Thucydides,<br />

for example, has Pericles remind the Athenians that they were brought up in a certain êthos,<br />

which Rex Warner renders as “way of life.” 65 Importantly, then, the line of continuity that<br />

Chamberlain traces from “haunts” to “character” does not suggest some exclusive connection<br />

22


etween êthos and virtue. Instead, it suggests that êthos is simply something like that which<br />

gives rise to a distinctive and stable pattern of behavior on the part of things of a certain kind—a<br />

pattern of behavior whose virtuousness or viciousness is one, but only one, interesting thing<br />

about it. 66<br />

Chamberlain’s broader account of the meaning of êthos fits well with Aristotle’s own use<br />

of the term. In the Nicomachean Ethics, Aristotle does not define êthos as such. But in book 2<br />

of the Eudemian Ethics, Aristotle says that êthos is a “quality” [poiotês] that we possess in<br />

respect of our “capacities for affections” [dunameis tôn pathêmatôn] such as anger, fear, shame,<br />

or desire; as well as in respect of the states or habits [hexeis] that determine how we experience<br />

and respond to those affections (1220b5–20). 67 A quality, in turn, is a “differentia” [diaphora]<br />

(Metaph. 5.14, 1020a33); it is simply “that in virtue of which people are said to be such and<br />

such” (Cat. 8, 8b25). And because the states or habits that differentiate us are “lasting and firmly<br />

established” (Cat. 8, 8b27), when we give accounts of the êthos of a person, we are saying<br />

something about what we take to be that person’s persistent qualities with respect to affection,<br />

rather than their momentary attributes. In sum, as Nancy Sherman says, Aristotelian character<br />

“has to do with a person’s enduring traits; that is, with the attitudes, sensibilities, and beliefs that<br />

affect how a person sees, acts, and indeed lives.” 68<br />

What do these genealogies and definitions show? There are two possible conclusions to<br />

be drawn, either of which would be adequate to establish a productive connection between the<br />

themes of action and character in the Poetics, and the themes of action and identity in the<br />

Antigone and elsewhere. The first conclusion is stronger. If Aristotelian êthos, far from being<br />

limited in meaning to the various qualities of virtuousness or viciousness we possess, actually<br />

includes the whole range of “enduring traits” that influence our behavior (arguably excluding<br />

23


those relating to thought or intellect), then êthos is capacious enough to include “identity”—for<br />

“identity,” as I have been using it here, refers not simply to a set of personal or social<br />

characteristics, but to a set of such characteristics that have practical force. So, for example,<br />

when Creon, through his speeches, demonstrates how heavily his sense of the meaning of philia<br />

(and therefore his understanding of his obligations and responsibilities) has been shaped by his<br />

status as citizen and king, it makes sense to say that he has shown us something of his êthos: he<br />

has laid out the terms that govern his action. 69<br />

The second conclusion is a bit weaker. Even if we remain skeptical that êthos can<br />

encompass identity, there is nevertheless an important analogy to be drawn between character<br />

and identity on the basis of the way each relates to action. The preceding discussion should at<br />

least have brought into the foreground the fact that êthos—even êthos narrowly construed—is<br />

typically taken to be prior to action in the same way that Antigone and Creon (and the<br />

contemporary normative discourse of recognition) take identity to be prior to action. Our<br />

qualities of character are stable and persistent attributes that help to determine the actions we<br />

perform (NE 2.2, 1104a27; 3.5, 1114b25), and for this reason, as Sherman says, character helps<br />

us explain “not merely why someone acted this way now, but why someone can be counted on<br />

to act in certain ways”; it introduces predictability, “pattern,” and order into our doings. 70<br />

Indeed, this basic view of êthos has been understandably central to contemporary neo-<br />

Aristotelian revivals of virtue ethics, which focus on the underlying qualities, formed through<br />

practice, habituation, and education, that dispose people to act well: in his account of Aristotle’s<br />

ethics, for example, MacIntyre writes that “the immediate outcome of the exercise of a virtue is a<br />

choice which issues in right action,” and again that “the virtues are precisely those qualities the<br />

possession of which will enable an individual to achieve eudaimonia and the lack of which will<br />

24


frustrate movement toward that telos.” 71 And this, ultimately, is what enables Aristotle’s<br />

consideration of character and action in the Poetics to shed light on the relationship between<br />

identity and action, both in the Antigone and in general.<br />

* * *<br />

We began this section with Aristotle’s claim, in chapter 6 of the Poetics, that tragedy is an<br />

imitation of action rather than of persons, and that in tragedy the plot and its constituent actions<br />

have a certain kind of priority over character. But after the account of the meaning of êthos we<br />

have just developed, this claim might seem puzzling: how can action have priority over character<br />

if character is that set of stable qualities that governs and determines our actions? On some<br />

accounts, this apparent contradiction can only be addressed by positing a deep gulf between<br />

Aristotle’s action-centered account of tragic drama in the Poetics and his character-centered<br />

undestanding of “real life” in his ethical works; if this is right, then it can only be misleading to<br />

look to the Poetics for insight into the real-life relationship between character and action. 72<br />

Such a conclusion might be inevitable if Aristotle’s account of the relationship between<br />

character and action in “real life” were reducible to the thought that êthos determines action. But<br />

important parts of the Nicomachean Ethics, including the discussions of habituation and the<br />

acquisition of virtue in chapter 2, suggest that Aristotle holds a more complex view. It’s not only<br />

that the virtue of bravery causes or is actualized in courageous acts, for example, but also that<br />

bravery itself is formed through the doing of brave deeds (NE 2.2, 1104a28–b4); this, Aristotle<br />

maintains, “is why we must perform the right activities” (NE 2.1, 1103b23). 73 For Aristotle,<br />

then, action and character form a circuit of mutual constitution: character pushes out into the<br />

world by shaping the kinds of things we do; and it is at the same time formed and reformed by<br />

our worldly activity. Against this background, it becomes possible to find in the Poetics an<br />

25


argument that is consistent with, though perhaps different in emphasis from, Aristotle’s broader<br />

ethical views. The point of the Poetics’ claim about the priority of action over character, we<br />

might say, is that this circuit of mutual constitution is not closed. While character influences<br />

action, it does not perfectly determine it; and this means both that “being of a certain good human<br />

character [may fall] short of sufficiency for eudaimonia,” and that character itself is<br />

constitutively vulnerable to the various forms of worldly contingency that are transmitted,<br />

through our activity, back to our being. 74<br />

What are these “various forms of worldly contingency” that afflict activity? And how do<br />

they relate to what, in the context of the Antigone, I have called action’s “impropriety” with<br />

respect to identity? 75 The first question of these questions is, of course, enormous; I will merely<br />

mention two very general considerations here. First, action projects human beings into a world of<br />

causality, initiating sequences of events that, once begun, proceed without necessarily respecting<br />

the agent’s intentions. This fact of the causality of human action most obviously threatens our<br />

capacity to control the consequences of our actions. But it also limits our capacity to control the<br />

significance of our actions, insofar as it prevents us from locating a natural and uncontroversial<br />

boundary between our actions and the events that follow from them. To be sure, we rely on such<br />

boundaries all the time, particularly in the law, where we often need to decide whether an event is<br />

to be imputed to an agent as his act, for which he may be held responsible. But although these<br />

conceptions of the limits of responsibility or imputability may represent themselves as<br />

reflections of some sheerly factual line of demarcation between, say, the willed and the caused, it<br />

is in a way the very absence of such a line that allows imputability to arise as a problem in the<br />

first place. Will and agency only become possible sources of injury or damage because they are<br />

not isolated from a separate world of causes and effects, but are themselves sources of<br />

26


causation 76 —and this absence of a firm qualitative distinction between will and causation makes<br />

it difficult to fix, once and for all, the limits of what may be imputed to us as “our” doing. 77<br />

The fact that our action inserts us into chains of causality not wholly under our control<br />

can, of course, manifest itself in numerous ways, and is perhaps most strikingly visible in cases<br />

of natural disaster in which nonhuman forces undermine our plans (and often destroy us<br />

altogether) in unpredictable, perhaps even utterly meaningless ways. 78 Still, the sheer<br />

contingency of nature is not quite the stuff of tragedy—the abuse of the term “tragedy” in the<br />

modern media notwithstanding. 79 A bit closer to tragedy’s concerns lies the fact that human<br />

beings act into a world inhabited by a plurality of other acting persons: the fact of human<br />

freedom, which is the condition of the possibility of the effective agency, also limits our practical<br />

capacities because it is not exclusively ours but is mirrored in others. 80 At one level, of course,<br />

this reference to the fact of human plurality can be subsumed under the point I have just made<br />

about causality: one of the central reasons we cannot perfectly determine the consequences of our<br />

actions is that we never act altogether in isolation but in interaction both with sometimes<br />

uncooperative or intransigent others as well as with powerful, large-scale human institutions.<br />

But the point is not merely that human plurality limits our control over the consequences of our<br />

actions; here, too, it’s also that the meaning of our deeds is not wholly at our disposal, for the<br />

very terms through which we make assessments of significance are not exclusively our own, but<br />

intersubjective—as Creon and Antigone discover in their clash over the sense of philos and<br />

ekhthros. 81<br />

Notice that these general features of action share a distinctive structure: they involve the<br />

doubling back of some human capacity upon itself—a recursivity, in which a source of<br />

possibility also operates as its own limitation. If human beings were not themselves parts of the<br />

27


causal order of the world, the will would be impotent; yet the very fact of our implication in the<br />

causal order of the world both connects our deeds to chains of events that lie beyond our control,<br />

and blurs the boundaries between action and event that might help us fix and master the meaning<br />

of our actions. Likewise, the idea of freedom depends upon the human capacity to<br />

spontaneously initiate the new and the unexpected—and yet the fact of human freedom inhibits<br />

our ability to do as we will, since the new and unexpected actions of others may throw<br />

unforeseen obstacles in our path. This peculiar structure of enabling conditions that are always<br />

also limitations places human actors in an ontological double bind, rendering us dependent on the<br />

very forces that, in action, we seek to transcend.<br />

The instances of “impropriety” that we have observed in the action of the Antigone, I<br />

suggest, can be understood as consequences of analogous double binds. 82 Antigone and Creon<br />

work to recognize and be recognized in certain ways in part as response to the shattering losses<br />

they have experienced: for them, the pursuit of recognition promises a satisfying restoration of a<br />

sense of agency and independence in the face of the unpredictability and capriciousness of the<br />

world. The categories of identity they claim and assert make it possible for them to know what<br />

to do. At the same time, those categories of identity facilitate a sense of agency not by<br />

accurately mirroring the social world, but by distorting it, abstracting away from the very facts of<br />

complexity and interdependence that lead us to grasp for such categories in the first place. Recall<br />

Antigone’s identifications, for example. Those identifications are secured as much by her<br />

deliberate refusal of the vocabulary of the polis as by her invocation of the obligations of kinship.<br />

For Antigone, to be a representative of the family, the divine law, and woman means not to be<br />

compelled by the claims of the city and the human law, and not to be identified with masculinity;<br />

and the converse is true for Creon. But it is precisely because identity emerges in this way out of<br />

28


distinctions and oppositions that it remains tied to that from which it seeks to distinguish itself.<br />

The practical possibilities and ways of being we disavow in the course of ordering ourselves into<br />

the bearers of coherent “identities” do not, simply by virtue of that disavowal, cease to bear on<br />

what we do: hence Antigone’s action takes on political significance at the very moment that she<br />

attempts to fix its meaning firmly within the sphere of kinship. Antigone’s and Creon’s<br />

blindness to parts of the meanings of their acts is no accident; it is a structural ignorance,<br />

imposed by the nature of identification itself. It is the distinctive form of misrecognition<br />

(Aristotle might have called it a hamartia) that afflicts the pursuit of recognition. 83<br />

* * *<br />

We are now in a position to return to the theme of tragic anagnôrisis. Aristotle first<br />

defines the concept in chapter 11 of the Poetics, in the course of elaborating the nature and<br />

components of the tragic plot: “A recognition is, as the very word implies, a change from<br />

ignorance [agnoias] to knowledge [gnosin], and thus to either love or hate, in the personages<br />

marked for good or evil fortune.” 84 Aristotle proceeds (both in this chapter and later) to list<br />

some examples of recognition, including the recognition of Odysseus by his scar (1454b25–8);<br />

Electra’s recognition of Orestes by “reasoning” in Aeschylus’s Choephori (1455a4–6); and<br />

Oedipus’s recognition that he himself is his father’s killer (1452a32–3). It is tempting to<br />

conclude on the basis of these examples that “recognition” in the Poetics has the same sense that<br />

it did in the preceding account of the Antigone as a “struggle for recognition” (and hence the same<br />

sense that it has in the contemporary normative discourse of recognition). After all, the examples<br />

all seem to suggest that recognition is the recognition of an identity, either one’s own or<br />

another’s. 85<br />

29


This is not altogether wrong, but it is misleading. A somewhat different view emerges if<br />

we situate the concept of recognition within Aristotle’s larger account of the structure of tragedy,<br />

and tie it back to the account of êthos and action we have been developing. 86 First, it is<br />

important to acknowledge that for Aristotle, recognition is closely linked to another component<br />

of what he calls “complex” tragic plots, peripeteia or “reversal”; indeed, Aristotle says that the<br />

“finest form” of recognition is that accompanied by reversal (1452a32–33). And reversal, in turn,<br />

is a particular form of change (metabolê) in the fortune or circumstances of an actor; specifically,<br />

it is a change that takes place through a relatively abrupt shift in the apparent trajectory of the<br />

action. 87 The presence of such abrupt shifts or reversals in the action, in turn, can be understood<br />

as Aristotle’s way of spelling out what it means for the events that make up a tragic plot to occur<br />

“unexpectedly and at the same time in consequence of one another” (para tên doxan di’ allêla,<br />

1452a4), which is a feature that he says characterizes the most effective tragic plots. 88 And this,<br />

finally, bring us back to êthos and action, for it is precisely the gap between who we are and what<br />

we do—what Halliwell calls the “disparity between the knowledge or intentions of the dramatic<br />

characters and the underlying nature of their actions”—that drives this sort of plot, thick with<br />

surprise but not merely accidental. Aristotle’s original claim about the order of priority of action<br />

and êthos, and our parallel understanding of the impropriety of action with respect to identity,<br />

thus turn out to be intimately connected to recognition: action’s impropriety is the one of the<br />

central occasions for tragic anagnôrisis.<br />

This way of situating recognition suggests a different account of its meaning. If the<br />

priority of action over êthos and identity is the occasion for reversal and thus for recognition,<br />

then perhaps we can understand recognition’s “shift from ignorance to knowledge” not only as<br />

the discovery of someone’s true identity, but also and more fundamentally as what I would call<br />

30


an “ontological” discovery, a shift from ignorance to knowledge about the real conditions of one’s<br />

own existence and activity, and especially about the very relationship between êthos or identity<br />

and action. On this account of tragic anagnôrisis, to be sure, recognition may indeed take place<br />

through the discovery of something about one’s own or someone else’s “identity,” at least in the<br />

ordinary sense that we have in mind when we say that Oedipus discovered the identity of his<br />

father’s killer. But what differentiates this account of recognition from the contemporary<br />

normative discourse of recognition (and from recognition as Antigone and Creon pursued it) is<br />

that this sort of recognition does not satisfyingly consolidate and strengthen a practical identity,<br />

or an identity in the thick sense we have been using here—that is, a coherent set of commitments<br />

and values that enable an agent to know what to do. To the contrary, tragic recognition comes<br />

after action, exposing the limits of practical identity, and shattering without yet reconstituting the<br />

coherence of the identificatory scheme with which the agent has tried to govern his activity.<br />

Tragic recognition, we might say, is the acknowledgment of finitude under the weight of a (failed)<br />

effort to become sovereign through the recognition of identity.<br />

This understanding of tragic anagnôrisis is borne out by the text of the Antigone, for<br />

while the Antigone’s struggles for recognition do indeed fail, the play nevertheless contains<br />

moments of “successful” (though unhappy) recognition in this second sense. The Antigone’s<br />

tragic recognitions are not satisfying recognitions of authentic identities; instead, they are<br />

mournful acknowledgments of human finitude, prompted by first-hand experience with the risks<br />

and dangers that accompany the pursuit of satisfaction through recognition. We might at first<br />

expect such moments of tragic recognition to consist in straightforward acknowledgments of guilt,<br />

as for instance when Creon, frightened by Teiresias’s prophecies, accepts the chorus’s counsel<br />

and rushes off to bury Polyneices and free Antigone. But if Creon’s reversal of his decision were<br />

31


the paradigmatic recognition scene in the Antigone, we would look in vain for a corresponding<br />

moment of recognition involving Antigone herself. The only parallel episode comes near the end<br />

of Antigone’s self-lament, and is more equivocal than Creon’s plain reversal: “Should the gods<br />

think that this [i.e., her punishment] is righteousness, in suffering I’ll see my error clear,” she<br />

says. “But if it is the others who are wrong, I wish them no greater punishment than mine”<br />

(926–29). To say that she confesses her guilt here would be to overstate the case, for she only<br />

professes uncertainty about whether the gods will find her righteous or culpable. 89<br />

Yet to suppose on these grounds that only Creon experiences a moment of recognition is<br />

both to overlook something important about Antigone’s words and to misunderstand what this<br />

moment of tragic recognition involves. In the first place, we must be careful to avoid a false<br />

choice between an Antigone who straightforwardly confesses her guilt and an Antigone who<br />

remains as resolute as ever to the end. In fact, both are untrue to the text. Both Antigone’s self-<br />

lament and her admission of the possibility that the gods will judge her guilty represent real<br />

transformations of Antigone’s earlier rigidity. In her opening speeches, Antigone had defiantly<br />

welcomed the prospect of death (70–72), but now she mourns her fate, and in so doing, explicitly<br />

acknowledges that her act has deprived her of the very goods she pursued, including philia and<br />

motherhood (878–81, 918). And, in fact, by acknowledging that the question of the real<br />

significance of her act is out of her hands and rests instead with the gods, Antigone expresses a<br />

more sophisticated recognition of human finitude, of the gap between identity and action, than a<br />

simple avowal of guilt would have indicated. After all, even after Creon changes his tune, he is no<br />

more master of his fate than he had been earlier; in fact, his worst suffering is still to come.<br />

Creon’s real moment of recognition comes after the deaths of his son and wife. As he laments his<br />

fate and prays for a quick death, Creon’s own words reflect his belated awareness not of his<br />

32


wrongdoing, exactly (for he has already seen that) but of the gap between his intentions and his<br />

actions: “Take me away at once,” he pleads, “the frantic man who killed my son, against my<br />

meaning” (1339–41). What Antigone and Creon have recognized, in different ways, is a version<br />

of the predicament described by the Chorus in its famous closing words (1343–52): to avoid the<br />

catastrophes that action’s improprieties bring, we would need to possess as actors a practical<br />

wisdom that we acquire only in retrospect, and too late. 90<br />

NOTES<br />

I owe special thanks to Danielle Allen, Seyla Benhabib, Peter Euben, Jill Frank, Bonnie Honig,<br />

and Patrick Riley for their generous and helpful comments on earlier drafts. This is still a work<br />

in progress, and I have not yet been able to respond as fully as I intend to all the suggestions these<br />

readers have made.<br />

1. Hannah Arendt, The Human Condition (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1953), 193.<br />

2. Jean-Jacques Rousseau, Politics and the Arts: Letter to M. D’Alembert on the Theatre, ed. and<br />

trans. Allan Bloom (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1960), 126.<br />

3. The passage is quoted by Charles Taylor, “The Politics of Recognition,” in Multiculturalism:<br />

Examining the Politics of Recognition, ed. Amy Gutmann (Princeton: Princeton University Press,<br />

1994), 47–48.<br />

4. On recognition, see Aristotle Poet. 1452a29–b8; on its importance to “the finest form of<br />

tragedy,” Poet. 1452b30–34. Except where otherwise noted, quoted passages from the Poetics in<br />

this essay follow Ingram Bywater’s translation, in Aristotle, On the Art of Poetry (Oxford:<br />

Clarendon, 1909). I do make two consistent and small changes in Bywater’s translation without<br />

further notice: I reverse his practice of capitalizing the first letters of such words as “tragedy,”<br />

“plot,” and “character”; and I change his idiosyncratic and less literal rendering of anagnôrisis as<br />

“Discovery,” substituting “recognition.” In working with the Poetics I have also benefited from<br />

the texts, translations, and/or commentaries contained in: Aristotle, Poetics, ed. D. W. Lucas<br />

(Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1972); Stephen Halliwell, The Poetics of Aristotle: Translation and<br />

Commentary (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1987); Gerald F. Else, Aristotle’s<br />

Poetics: The Argument (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1957); Aristotle, Poetics, ed.<br />

and trans. Gerald F. Else (Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 1970).<br />

5. For this history, see Terence Cave, Recognitions: A Study in Poetics (Oxford: Clarendon Press,<br />

1990).<br />

33


6. This ambivalence is registered in Aristotle’s definition of anagnôrisis, which he says is a<br />

“change from ignorance to knowledge, and thus to either love or hate, in the personages marked<br />

for good or evil fortune” (Poet. 1452a29–32). It is also nicely reflected in Jocasta’s next-to-last<br />

words to Oedipus, “May you never know who you are!” (Soph. Oed. Tyr. 1068). Our tendency<br />

to regard recognition as an unequivocal good makes it impossible to grasp this exclamation as an<br />

expression of concern and goodwill, as it seems to be.<br />

7. For analogous uses of “ontological” see Stephen K. White, Sustaining Affirmation: The<br />

Strengths of Weak Ontology in Political Theory (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2000);<br />

and the discussion of “ontopolitical interpretation” in Connolly, “Nothing is Fundamental,”<br />

chap. 1 in The Ethos of Pluralization (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1995).<br />

8. In Aristotle’s terms, tragedy is an “imitation of an action”: Poet. 1450a16.<br />

9. Cf. J. Peter Euben, The Tragedy of Political Theory: The Road Not Taken (Princeton:<br />

Princeton University Press, 1990), 56.<br />

10. Both Axel Honneth (The Fragmented World of the Social [Albany: SUNY Press, 1995], 250)<br />

and Taylor (“The Politics of Recognition,” 26) say that misrecognition can “cripple” its victims.<br />

For the unmediated connection between identity and agency, see Avishai Margalit and Moshe<br />

Halbertal, “Liberalism and the Right to Culture,” Social Research 61, no. 3 (Fall 1994): 491–510;<br />

498); for the mediated connection, see Will Kymlicka, Multicultural Citizenship: A Liberal Theory<br />

of Minority Rights (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1995), chap. 5 (though I believe Kymlicka is pushed<br />

further toward Margalit’s and Halbertal’s position than he acknowledges in his effort to justify<br />

not only a right to culture in general but a right to “one’s own” culture: since what the latter idea<br />

adds is the notion of cultures as plural and to at least some degree mutually exclusive, it demands<br />

a shift in focus away from the choices culture contains (which it might well share with others)<br />

and toward the options it excludes (which are what marks it off as unique).<br />

11. Michael J. Sandel, Liberalism and the Limits of Justice (Cambridge: Cambridge University<br />

Press, 1982).<br />

12. Of course, not only the Poetics is implicated here: the Nicomachean Ethics (especially the<br />

discussion of virtue, misfortune, and eudaimonia in book 1, ch. 10); the Metaphysics (esp. book<br />

9); and the Politics are also all important, as are (for me) Arendt’s uses of some of these<br />

Aristotelian texts in her account of action in The Human Condition, I intend to expand the<br />

discussion of these other texts in a future version of this paper.<br />

13. Parenthetical citations to the Antigone refer to line numbers, and unless otherwise noted,<br />

quotations from the play follow Elizabeth Wyckoff’s translation, in the first edition (only) of<br />

David Grene and Richard Lattimore, eds., The Complete Greek Tragedies, vol. II, Sophocles<br />

(Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1959).<br />

34


14. Polyneices’ grievance is discussed in Aesch. Septem 631–52 and Soph. Oed. Col.<br />

1284–1307. On the death of the brothers see Aesch. Septem 808–14.<br />

15. In Aeschylus’s version of the story, Eteocles and Polyneices died childless; see G. O.<br />

Hutchinson’s discussion in his note to line 903 in Aeschylus, Septem contra Thebas (Oxford:<br />

Clarendon Press, 1985). In other accounts, Polyneices left a son, Thersander, who, together with<br />

the other sons of the Seven (the “Epigoni”) later successfully conquered Thebes. For a summary<br />

of sources see Timothy Gantz, Early Greek Myth: A Guide to Literary and Artistic Sources<br />

(Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins University Press, 1993), 522–25.<br />

16. Terence Cave has even suggested that the burst of interest in the Antigone that began in the<br />

late eighteenth century, and which found its most influential expression in Hegel, helped bring<br />

about “the eclipse of anagnorisis as a central tragic concept” in modern poetics. Recognitions,<br />

154.<br />

17. Indeed, the Antigone is not only full of claims to recognition; it is also surrounded by them.<br />

Readers of the play commonly make claims to recognize Antigone and Creon—to know who<br />

they are and what they stand for. In a classic essay, Jean Bethke Elshtain argues that Antigone is<br />

a representative of “primordial family morality”—an identity that, in the form of “maternal<br />

thinking,” is still available to be taken up in acts of resistance to modern Creons (“Antigone’s<br />

Daughters,” democracy 2, no. 2 [April 1982]: 53, 58–59). In a response to Elshtain, Mary Dietz<br />

claims instead that Antigone represents “the customs and traditions of a collective civil life, an<br />

entire political ethos” (“Citizenship with a Feminist Face: The Problem with Maternal<br />

Thinking,” Political Theory 13, no. 1 [February 1985]: 29). Rather than taking sides in this<br />

debate about what Antigone, properly understood, represents, I suggest that we try to account<br />

for the fact that Elshtain’s and Dietz’s seemingly incompatible accounts of Antigone’s identity<br />

are both partly persuasive. We can do so by focusing less exclusively on who Antigone is and<br />

attending instead to how who she is relates to what she does. This angle can help us understand<br />

how Antigone’s deeds do not smoothly flow from and reinforce, but exceed and disturb our (and<br />

her) conception of her identity.<br />

18. See Larry J. Bennett and William Blake Tyrrell, “Sophocles’ Antigone and Funeral Oratory,”<br />

American Journal of Philology 111, no. 4 (Winter 1990): 442. On the question of whether this<br />

topos preceded Sophocles, see Christiane Sourvinou-Inwood, “Assumptions and the Creation of<br />

Meaning: Reading Sophocles’ Antigone,” Journal of Hellenic Studies 109 (1989): 134–48, arguing<br />

that Sophocles introduced the idea that “the total denial of burial offends against the gods” (143),<br />

but also the response by Helene Foley, “Tragedy and Democratic Ideology: The Case of<br />

Sophocles’ Antigone,” in History, Tragedy, Theory: Dialogues on Athenian Drama, ed. Barbara<br />

Goff (Austin: University of Texas Press, 1995), arguing that the topos of the recovery of the<br />

bodies “could well have been in place before the Antigone was composed” (140). For a summary<br />

of versions of the story and textual evidence concerning norms of burial, see appendix C to D. A.<br />

Hester, “Sophocles the Unphilosophical: A Study in the Antigone,” Mnemosyne, 4th ser., 24<br />

(1971): 54–55.<br />

35


19. See for instance Lysias 2.7–10 and the discussion in Bennett and Tyrrell, “Sophocles’<br />

Antigone and Funeral Oratory,” 443.<br />

20. The focus on the brothers may not be wholly original with Sophocles, since the ending of<br />

Aeschylus’s Seven against Thebes also describes an edict concerning Polyneices and Eteocles,<br />

and depicts Antigone’s resolve to bury Polyneices despite the edict (1010–78). But the<br />

authenticity of the ending is contested, and some argue it to have been a late addition based upon,<br />

not preceding, the Antigone; for a discussion of the issue see Hutchinson’s edition of Aeschylus,<br />

Septem contra Thebas, 209–11.<br />

21. See W. K. Lacey, The Family in Classical Greece (Auckland: University of Auckland, 1980),<br />

148; on the legal obligation see S. C. Humphries, The Family, Women, and Death: Comaprative<br />

Studies, 2nd ed. (Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 1993), 83.<br />

22. The text of the Antigone does nothing to contradict Creon’s view of Polyneices as traitor and<br />

Eteocles as patriot; even the chorus describes Polyneices as pursuing a “dubious quarrel” (110).<br />

23. Thucydides, for instance, notes that Athenian law prohibited the burial of traitors in Attic<br />

soil (1.10); see the discussion of this law in Sourvinou-Inwood, “Assumptions and the Creation<br />

of Meaning,” 137–38, esp. n. 20; and Hester, “Sophocles the Unphilosophical,” 55.<br />

24. Donna C. Kurtz and John Boardman, Greek Burial Customs (London: Thames and Hudson,<br />

1971), 260; see also Christiane Sourvinou-Inwood, ‘Reading’ Greek Death: To the End of the<br />

Classical Period (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1995), 177–79; Gail Holst-Warhaft, Dangerous<br />

Voices: Women’s Laments and Greek Literature (London: Routledge, 1992), chap. 4; for a<br />

modern parallel see Arendt, “On Humanity in Dark Times: Thoughts about Lessing,” in Men in<br />

Dark Times (New York: Harvest/HBJ, 1968), 20–22. Hegel’s discussion of the work of<br />

immortalization performed by burial in his discussion of Greek ethical life in The Phenomenology<br />

of Spirit, trans. A. V. Miller (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1977), 270–71, is also useful here.<br />

25. The locus classicus is Sigmund Freud, “Mourning and Melancholia,” in Collected Papers,<br />

vol. 4 (New York: Basic Books, 1959). See also Eric L. Santner, Stranded Objects: Mourning,<br />

Memory and Film in Postwar Germany (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1990), chap. 1; Peter<br />

M. Sacks, The English Elegy: Studies in the Genre from Spenser to Yeats (Baltimore: The Johns<br />

Hopkins University Press, 1985), chap. 1. Arendt borrows a line from Isak Dinesen that<br />

captures the importance of lament to the mourner: “All sorrows can be borne if you put them<br />

into a story or tell the story about them.” Arendt used these words as the epigraph to her<br />

chapter on “Action” in The Human Condition (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1953), but<br />

she also quotes them in her essay “Isak Dinesen, 1885–1963,” and adds her own gloss: “The<br />

story reveals the meaning of what otherwise would remain an unbearable sequence of sheer<br />

happenings” (Men in Dark Times, 104). Notably, the final sentence of Arendt’s essay on<br />

Dinesen reads like a loose translation of the chorus’s closing words in the Antigone: “Wisdom is a<br />

virtue of old age, and it seems to come only to those who, when young, were neither wise nor<br />

prudent” (109).<br />

36


26. See here Sacks’s discussion of consolation and substitution in The English Elegy, 6–7.<br />

27. This aspect of funeral ritual is reflected in Hegel’s gloss on the practice of burial in Greece as<br />

a way of humanizing death by supplementing a natural and “irrational” event with “an action<br />

consciously done” G. W. F. Hegel, Phenomenology of Spirit, trans. A. V. Miller (Oxford: Oxford<br />

University Press, 1977), 270.<br />

28. The significance of philos and ekhthros in the Antigone has been extensively discussed. I<br />

have benefited most from Simon Goldhill, Reading Greek Tragedy (Cambridge: Cambridge<br />

University Press, 1986), 79–106, to whom I owe in particular the insight into the connection<br />

between philia and recognition (85). See also Mary Whitlock Blundell, Helping Friends and<br />

Harming Enemies: A Study in Sophocles and Greek Ethics (Cambridge: Cambridge University<br />

Press, 1989), 106–48; David Konstan, “Greek Friendship,” American Journal of Philology 117<br />

(1996): 82–85; Charles Segal, Tragedy and Civilization: An Interpretation of Sophocles<br />

(Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1981), 185–86; and Matt Neuburg, “How Like a<br />

Woman: Antigone’s ‘Inconsistency,’” Classical Quarterly 40, no. 1 (1990): 70–76.<br />

29. See the sources in the preceding note as well as the relevant entries in Henry George Liddell<br />

and Robert Scott, A Greek-English Lexicon, 9th ed., rev. Henry Stuart Jones and Roderick<br />

McKenzie (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1968).<br />

30. See here especially Goldhill, Reading Greek Tragedy, 79–83. The connection I draw here<br />

between philia and recognition should shed some light on the long-running debate over whether<br />

the use of philos indicates subjective “affection” or an objective, “ascribed status”—which I<br />

believe to be a false choice. David Konstan, for instance, has recently argued against Goldhill and<br />

others that when Antigone calls Polyneices philos, she does not thereby “indicat[e] kinship as<br />

the grounds for [her] behavior,” but merely expresses her affection for him. Her use of philos<br />

could not possibly refer to the ascribed status of kinship, Konstan argues, because this would<br />

make “nonsense of Antigone’s description of Ismene as an enemy.” Konstan admits, however,<br />

that Antigone’s harshness toward her sister may be intended by Sophocles to express “the irony<br />

by which a sister, normally dear, is rendered inimical”—and the emphasized phrase contains the<br />

key to the problem. Contra Konstan, this irony only works if Antigone’s use of philos not only<br />

indicates affection but also implies some view about why that affection is owed—for instance, the<br />

view that kin are “normally dear.” This need not mean, in Konstan’s terms, that philos simply<br />

“signifies” kin—the way philos works cannot be understood from within a simply designative<br />

theory of language. Rather, the use of philos—like “recognition” itself—is both epistemic and<br />

normative; it both makes reference to objective relationships and announces a feeling of affection<br />

grounded in those relationships. See Konstan, “Greek Friendship,” 83–84. [read Belfiore,<br />

Murder among Friends, ch. 1]<br />

31. This relationship between the use of philia and the recognition of identity is corollary to the<br />

relationship Aristotle describes in his definition of anagnôrisis in the Poetics. There, Aristotle<br />

says that recognition is, “as the very word implies, a change from ignorance to knowledge, and<br />

37


thus either to love [philian] or hate [ekhthran] in the personages marked for good or evil fortune.”<br />

Poet. 1452a29–32. In the Antigone, saying who one is takes the form of locating oneself in a<br />

certain network of relationships of philia and ekhthra; likewise, in the Poetics, discovering who<br />

one is has the effect of transforming one’s understanding of who is philos and who<br />

ekhthros—although, as I will suggest in the last section of this essay, tragic anagnorisis is not<br />

simply the recognition of one’s identity, at least as the contemporary politics of recognition<br />

encourages us to understand that phrase.<br />

32. On the interpretation of this line see R. C. Jebb’s note in his edition of Sophocles, The<br />

Antigone, part 3 of The Plays and Fragments, 3rd ed. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,<br />

1900), 10–11, as well as Blundell, Helping Friends and Harming Enemies, 107 n. 5.<br />

33. On the distinction between the chthonian and Olympian in the context of the Antigone, see<br />

Segal, Tragedy and Civilization, 171.<br />

34. Ibid., 183–84. When contested, citizenship was established by demonstration of enrollment<br />

in the phratry, a patrilineal kinship organization into which daughters were not introduced.<br />

35. Ibid., 184.<br />

36. See Foley, “Tragedy and Democratic Ideology,” 146 n. 11 (responding to Sourvinou-<br />

Inwood, “Assumptions and the Creation of Meaning,” 140). On the roles of men and women at<br />

funerals see Robert Garland, The Greek Way of Death (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1985),<br />

chap. 3; Humphries, The Family, Women and Death, 83–88.<br />

37. See Foley, “Tragedy and Democratic Ideology,” 146 n. 11 (responding to Sourvinou-<br />

Inwood, “Assumptions and the Creation of Meaning,” 140). On the roles of men and women at<br />

funerals see Robert Garland, The Greek Way of Death (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1985),<br />

chap. 3; Humphries, The Family, Women and Death, 83–88.<br />

38. Jebb’s and Grene’s translation; Wyckoff translates philos kakos as “a friend no friend.”<br />

39. See his statements to the chorus (484–85), to Antigone (525), and to Haemon (678–80).<br />

40. This view is often associated with Hegel, and has provoked critics of Hegel to complain that<br />

by reducing Creon and especially Antigone too completely to personifications of opposed social<br />

forces, he overlooks the ways in which, for example, Antigone “breaks out of her assigned<br />

sphere” (Mills, Woman, Nature and Psyche, 35). In fact, as I argue in a detailed reading of Hegel<br />

elsewhere, these criticisms ignore a sharp and meaningful break (which occurs between<br />

paragraphs 463 and 464) in Hegel’s discussion of the Antigone in the Phenomenology. In the<br />

passages up to and including par. 463, Hegel describes the background structure of ancient Greek<br />

Sittlichkeit, laying out the various ethical powers as though they formed a “whole [which] is a<br />

stable equilibrium of all the parts” (par. 462). Characteristically, however, Hegel’s point is<br />

precisely to reveal the limitations of what initially appears to be a satisfactory view or a coherent<br />

38


practice; so beginning in par. 464, he moves from offering a general account of the structure of<br />

Greek ethical life to personifying its constituent powers: here, Antigone and Creon, as individual<br />

agents who commit “deeds,” come on the scene, and in so doing, they “disturb the peaceful<br />

organization and movement of the ethical world”—that is, they reveal, precisely by their<br />

improprieties, the contradictions and limitations that afflict Greek ethical life. So while Hegel<br />

does indeed assign Antigone and Creon to different spheres, he also highlights the ways in which<br />

they do break out of the spheres to which they are assigned; indeed, his reading depends on it.<br />

41. Martha C. Nussbaum, The Fragility of Goodness: Luck and Ethics in Greek Tragedy and<br />

Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1986), 63–64.<br />

42. On Antigone’s treatment of Ismene see Blundell, Helping Friends and Harming Enemies,<br />

111–15.<br />

43. On the gendered architecture of the oikos, see Eva C. Keuls, The Reign of the Phallus: Sexual<br />

Politics in Ancient Athens (New York: Harper and Row, 1985), 93–97.<br />

44. Emily Vermeule notes that in Sophocles’ description the cave has all the architectural<br />

features of a Bronze age chamber tomb, which was itself called an “oikos for the dead”; see<br />

Aspects of Death in Early Greek Art and Poetry (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1979),<br />

54. On the tomb as bedroom or “bridal-chamber” in the Antigone, see Rush Rehm, Marriage to<br />

Death: The Conflation of Wedding and Funeral Rituals in Greek Tragedy (Princeton: Princeton<br />

University Press, 1994), chap. 4, and Richard Seaford, “The Imprisonment of Women in Greek<br />

Tragedy,” Journal of Hellenic Studies 110 (1990): 76–90.<br />

45. Nicole Loraux shows a distinction between men’s epitaphs, which acknowledged and<br />

recorded distinctiveness, with women’s epitaphs, which praised women (if at all) by assimilating<br />

them to a generic type; the “orthodox form” of a woman’s epitaph, Loraux says, is indicated by<br />

the example: “Supposing that feminine virtue still exists in the human race, she partook of it.”<br />

Tragic Ways of Killing a Woman, trans. Anthony Forster (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University<br />

Press, 1987), 27. On the avoidance and suppression of living women’s names, see John Gould,<br />

“Law, Custom and Myth: Aspects of the Social Position of Women in Classical Athens,”<br />

Journal of Hellenic Studies 100 (1980): 45.<br />

46. Neuburg, “How Like a Woman,” 66–67. See also Sheila Murnaghan, “Antigone 904–20 and<br />

the Institution of Marriage,” American Journal of Philology 107, no. 2 (Summer 1986): 192–207.<br />

47. As Christina Elliot Sorum puts it, “in choosing to perpetuate her alliance with her origin,<br />

Antigone rejects her own potential as an origin.” See “The Family in Sophocles’ Antigone and<br />

Electra,” Classical World 75, no. 4 (March–April 1982): 206. Antigone’s grouping of children<br />

with husbands as among the “replaceable” kin (909–10) might seem to undermine my association<br />

of children with blood-ties, since the distinction between blood-ties and marriage-ties is taken by<br />

both Neuburg (73) and Murnaghan (198) to correspond to the distinction between irreplaceable<br />

and replaceable kin. The point, however, is that children represent the point of intersection<br />

39


etween (and therefore the inseparability of) the two kinds of tie: even Neuburg refers to<br />

Haemon, for instance, as bound to Creon by blood (74), even though according to Antigone’s<br />

distinctions, Haemon (as a child) should be replaceable. The problem here is that “blood-tie vs.<br />

marriage-tie” does not correspond perfectly to “irreplaceable vs. replaceable,” because blood and<br />

marriage ties are interrelated in a way that the terms of the latter distinction, which really is a<br />

simple opposition, are not. But even if lines 904–20 involve the issue of replaceability more than<br />

an opposition between ties of blood and marriage, this does not render the lines nonsensical:<br />

given the function of mourning in restoring agency in the face of loss, the fact of the<br />

irreplaceability of a loved one may make the imperative of mourning unconditional, since the<br />

investment in the lost person cannot as easily be transferred to a surrogate object. As<br />

Murnaghan cautions, though, “we should not search for an interpretation that would eliminate<br />

our dissatisfaction with Antigone’s words” (207); they are the words of a woman who is herself<br />

dissatisfied, lamenting the losses imposed upon her by an impossible choice that no<br />

rationalization can clarify without remainder.<br />

48. On this as an expression of specifically filial devotion, see Nussbaum, The Fragility of<br />

Goodness, 62; Joan V. O’Brien, Guide to Sophocles’ Antigone (Carbondale: Southern Illinois<br />

University Press, 1978), 77.<br />

49. On the military language, see Jebb’s note to line 640 and O’Brien, Guide to Sophocles’<br />

Antigone, 79, from which the quoted words are taken.<br />

50. Segal, “Lament and Closure in Antigone,” 131.<br />

51. As many commentators have observed, the actual order of Creon’s actions reverses the order<br />

in which the Chorus recommends he proceed (1100–1101); for a discussion of this “blemish” see<br />

Jebb’s introduction to his edition of The Antigone, xviii–xx.<br />

52. The reference of these lines to the bodies of the sons of “the cities that you fought in war” as<br />

a source of pollution forgivably conflates Polyneices’ corpse with the other Argive dead.<br />

53. In fact, Sophocles has already introduced the theme of the difference between the actor and<br />

the significance of the act in another episode involving a messenger: the guard who first informs<br />

Creon that Polyneices’ corpse has been buried is initially suspected of having committed the<br />

crime himself, though he protests that he “never did the deed” (321).<br />

54. Arendt, The Human Condition, 184. Arendt specifically mentions the use of messengers<br />

within tragedy as an illustration of the gap between perspective of the actor and the perspective<br />

of the narrator in “The Concept of History,” in Between Past and Future (New York: Penguin,<br />

1968), 45.<br />

55. On the translation of the Poetics used here see note 3 above. For a good discussion of<br />

Aristotle’s vocabulary, see Stephen Halliwell, Aristotle’s Poetics (Chapel Hill: University of<br />

North Carolina Press, 1986), 138–42. Aristotle sometimes uses praxis or praxeis to refer to the<br />

40


action or actions of persons in an ordinary sense; at other times, he uses praxis in the singular to<br />

refer to the whole course of action that is imitated in the plot (muthos) of a drama; and the<br />

muthos, in turn, is said to be a combination or arrangement of pragmata—itself cognate with<br />

praxis, and which is usually translated as “incidents” or “events.”<br />

56. This claim has sometimes been a source of consternation because it runs counter to our post-<br />

Romantic preoccupation with what Hegel called the “subjective inner life” of dramatic characters<br />

(Aesthetics: Lectures on Fine Art, trans. T. M. Knox, vol. 2 [Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1975],<br />

1223). As one of Aristotle’s editors writes:<br />

A[ristotle]’s preference for plot as opposed to character has won little approval<br />

from most of the critics from the late nineteenth century onwards. To the<br />

generations which were profoundly influenced by Bradley’s Shakespearian<br />

Studies it was common doctrine that, as Granville Barker once put it, the purpose<br />

of drama was to portray character. Interest in the inner life of the individual,<br />

which had been developed by the great novelists of late Victorian times in<br />

England, France, and Russia, caused exaggerated attention to traits of personality<br />

which could be perceived in Shakespeare and contributed to the spread of the<br />

belief that they must be contained, could one but find them, in all great drama.<br />

D. W. Lucas, “Commentary” to Aristotle, Poetics (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1972), 109–110.<br />

For a critique of anachronistic tendencies (such as the focus on the “tragic hero”) on the part of<br />

modern readers of the Poetics and of Greek tragedy, see John Jones, On Aristotle and Greek<br />

Tragedy (London: Chatto and Windus, 1962), chap. 1.<br />

57. For one interesting example of such a reading see Elizabeth Belfiore’s treatment of the<br />

relationship between the Poetics and modern narrative theory: “Narratological Plots and<br />

Aristotle’s Mythos,” Arethusa 33, no. 1 (Winter 2000): 37–70. In an earlier work, however,<br />

Belfiore argues that Aristotle’s prioritization of action in the Poetics is evidence of a split<br />

between his dramatic theory and his understanding of “real life,” where êthos does indeed have<br />

priority over action; I discuss and criticize this claim in more detail below.<br />

58. On controversies surrounding the text of this passage see Nussbaum, The Fragility of<br />

Goodness, 378–79 and accompanying notes.<br />

59. They echo, for example, the discussion of eudaimonia as an activity in NE 1.7, 1098a15–20,<br />

as has been noted by Amelie Oksenberg Rorty, “The Psychology of Aristotelian Tragedy,” in<br />

Essays on Aristotle’s Poetics (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1992), 20 n. 12.<br />

60. Nussbaum, The Fragility of Goodness, 379–82; cf. Halliwell, Aristotle’s Poetics, 157.<br />

Another way of putting this point is to say that tragedy is the “imitation of an action” not only<br />

in the obvious sense that it represents some sequence of events on the stage, but also because its<br />

very structure mirrors something important about the nature of action itself.<br />

41


61. This use of Aristotle’s Poetics might be thought to follow through on Nussbaum’s suggestion<br />

that insights drawn from the discussion of action and character in book 6 could provide the basis<br />

for a reinterpretation of the concept of anagnôrisis: see The Fragility of Goodness, 382.<br />

62. Arendt, The Human Condition, 244. The following account is heavily informed by Arendt’s<br />

account of action (especially 188–92, 236–47). For a good synoptic discussion of Arendt’s<br />

concept of action, see Maurizio Passerin d’Entrèves, The Political Philosophy of Hannah Arendt<br />

(New York: Routledge, 1994), 64–100.<br />

63. This might be taken to be the implication of Elizabeth Belfiore’s claim that “in the Poetics,<br />

êthos as a part of tragedy is always an indication of choice”—i.e., of prohairesis—“and never<br />

includes a broader set of ‘characteristic peculiarities,’ as êthos sometimes does in the Rhetoric”<br />

(Tragic Pleasures: Aristotle on Plot and Emotion [Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1992],<br />

97). Blundell has suggested that even in the Rhetoric, such attributes as age, sex, and nationality<br />

are not to be understood as aspects of êthos but as influences upon and potenial indicators of it:<br />

“Êthos and Dianoia Reconsidered,” in Amelie Oksenberg Rorty, ed., Essays on Aristotle’s<br />

Poetics (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1992), 164.<br />

64. Charles Chamberlain, “From ‘Haunts’ to ‘Character’: The Meaning of Êthos and its Relation<br />

to Ethics,” Helios 11, no. 2 (Winter 1984): 97–108.<br />

65. Ibid., 101; the passage from Thucydides (2.61.4) is cited at 106 n. 44; see Thucydides,<br />

History of the Peloponnesian War, ed. M. I. Finley, trans. Rex Warner (London: Penguin, 1972),<br />

160.<br />

66. Chamberlain also notes that “êthos comes from the Indo-European root *swedh, see also in<br />

the Latin suus and suesco, meaning ‘one’s own’ or ‘proper’” (104 n. 8). Exploiting this<br />

connection, we might say that something’s êthos is just that which leads it to do what is proper<br />

to it, as the sort of thing it is.<br />

67. I am bracketing controversies over the complicated relationship of êthos to thought or<br />

intellect (dianoia) both in the Poetics and in Aristotelian ethics, since these aren’t relevant to the<br />

aspects of êthos I’m emphasizing here. For discussion and bibliography, see Mary Whitlock<br />

Blundell, “Êthos and Dianoia Reconsidered,” in Amelie Oksenberg Rorty, ed., Essays on<br />

Aristotle’s Poetics (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1992).<br />

68. Nancy Sherman, The Fabric of Character: Aristotle’s Theory of Virtue (Oxford: Clarendon<br />

Press, 1989), 1.<br />

69. The Poetics itself says that êthos (here used in the at-one-remove sense of<br />

“characterization,” or the dramatic depiction of “character”—on this see Halliwell, Aristotle’s<br />

Poetics, 150–51) is that which “shows us the nature of a prohairesis”; certainly Antigone’s and<br />

Creon’s efforts to ground their actions in their identities show us aspects of the nature of their<br />

choices. (Poet. 1450b8–9; I have used Halliwell’s translation because Bywater unfortunately<br />

42


translates prohairesis as “moral purpose.”) Indeed, in the speech quoted above in which Haemon<br />

exhorts his father not to “have one mind, and one alone/that only your opinion can be right”<br />

(705), “mind” renders “êthos.”<br />

70. Sherman, The Fabric of Character, 1.<br />

71. Alasdair MacIntyre, After Virtue, 2nd ed. (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press,<br />

1984), 149, 148.<br />

72. Elizabeth S. Belfiore, Tragic Pleasures: Aristotle on Plot and Emotion (Princeton: Princeton<br />

University Press, 1992). In “real-life situations,” Belfiore says, “action is caused by êthos and<br />

thought”; in drama, on the other hand, where the action is devised by the poet and the êthos is<br />

added later to flesh out the meaning of the action, the order of priority is reversed (89). On this<br />

basis, Belfiore criticizes Nussbaum’s claim that for Aristotle “the great tragic plots explore the<br />

gap between our goodness and our good living,” claiming that this represents a “charactercentered<br />

view of tragedy opposed to Aristotle’s plot-centered view” (91). But, as I shall suggest,<br />

Nussbaum’s view and ones like it are hardly character-centered in the relevant sense of granting<br />

priority to character; quite to the contrary, Nussbaum focuses on exactly those aspects of<br />

tragedy that demonstrate the limits of character’s capacity to determine action.<br />

73. I owe my understanding of this point to conversations with Jill Frank; for an excellent and<br />

concise discussion of the relationships among dunamis, energeia, hexis, and praxis, see her<br />

“Democracy and Distribution: Aristotle on Just Desert,” Political Theory 26, no. 6 (December<br />

1998), esp. 795–96.<br />

74. Nussbaum, The Fragility of Goodness, 382; on vulnerability, see 380–81, as well as<br />

Halliwell, Aristotle’s Poetics, chap. 7.<br />

75. For some other discussions of the first question in the context of Aristotle, see Nussbaum,<br />

The Fragility of Goodness, esp. chaps. 11–12; Rorty, “The Psychology of Aristotelian Tragedy;<br />

Aryeh Kosman, “Acting: Drama as the Mimêsis of Praxis,” in Rorty, ed., Essays on Aristotle’s<br />

Poetics; Sherman, “Hamartia and Virtue,” in Rorty, ed., Essays on Aristotle’s Poetics; and<br />

Halliwell, Aristotle’s Poetics, chap. 7.<br />

76. Though this does not mean that will and agency are only possible sources of injury and<br />

damage because of the unpredictability of action. Often enough, of course, injury and damage are<br />

the result of successful, deliberate projects.<br />

77. On this see Thomas Nagel’s discussion (in the context of an argument about luck and<br />

responsibility in ethics) of the apparently irresolvable split between the “internal” and “external”<br />

perspectives on our actions, in “Moral Luck,” in Mortal Questions (Cambridge: Cambridge<br />

University Press, 1979), esp. 37; as well as Kosman, “Acting,” 65. On how concepts of<br />

responsibility can be regarded as socially constructed but nevertheless effective and non-<br />

43


arbitrary, see Marion Smiley, Moral Responsibility and the Boundaries of Community (Chicago:<br />

University of Chicago Press, 1992).<br />

78. This is not to say that natural disasters are always properly understood as the entirely<br />

arbitrary action of wholly external forces upon blameless human beings: what we experience as<br />

the sheer contingency of nature is sometimes closely related to our own activity and modes of<br />

interaction with nonhuman forces—as, for example, when homes built on “former” floodplains<br />

are destroyed by floods; or when the overprescription of highly successful antibiotics contributes<br />

to the development and spread of drug-resistant strains of bacteria. For more detailed examples<br />

of such tragic interactions between human beings and nature, especially in modern scientific<br />

forestry and agriculture, see James C. Scott, Seeing Like a State: How Certain Schemes to<br />

Improve the Human Condition Have Failed (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1998).<br />

79. On the inferiority of tragic plots based on “mere chance,” see Arist. Poet. 9, 1452a1–11;<br />

good discussions can be found in Sherman, “Hamartia and Virtue”; Rorty, “Psychology of<br />

Aristotelian Tragedy”; Bernard Yack, The Problems of a Political Animal: Community, Justice,<br />

and Conflict in Aristotelian Political Thought (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1993),<br />

chap. 8.<br />

80. On this implication of freedom, see Arendt, The Human Condition, 244, and “What is<br />

Freedom,” in Between Past and Future, 169–71. Amelie Rorty mentions that “reversals” of<br />

action are “most likely to occur in the interaction among several characters, each acting from his<br />

or her own intentions”: “The Psychology of Aristotelian Tragedy,” 11.<br />

81. Seyla Benhabib, also referring to Arendt, calls this the “interpretive indeterminacy” of<br />

action. See her Critique, Norm, and Utopia (New York: Columbia University Press, 1986), 136.<br />

82. Although causal contingency also plays a role in the tragedy, I think the account of<br />

impropriety and identity I give below can ultimately be described as a specific modality or<br />

manifestation of the way in which human plurality deprives us of sovereignty over the<br />

significance of our actions.<br />

83. Aristotle’s use of hamartia occurs in Poet. 13, 1453a10; for a good discussion see Sherman,<br />

“Hamartia and Virtue”; and for an account parallel to mine of hamartia as a kind of blindness or<br />

ignorance that arises precisely from an agent’s own virtues of character, see Rorty, “Psychology<br />

of Aristotelian Tragedy,” 11. Rorty’s account seems distinctive to me in suggesting that the<br />

vulnerabilities of character may arise precisely from the best moments of character itself; other<br />

accounts of character’s vulnerability, such as Nussbaum’s, focus on the ways in which<br />

circumstances external to character itself may render character insufficient for eudaimonia; for<br />

example, Nussbaum (334–35, 380–81) focuses on the cases like Priam’s (in which misfortune<br />

deprives someone of the resources or objects necessary for good activity); Oedipus’s (in which<br />

the “luck of circumstances” makes it the case that the description under which someone intended<br />

his act was, through no fault of his own, not the “morally salient description of what took<br />

place”); and Agamemnon’s (in which circumstances require someone to choose, in full knowledge<br />

44


of all the dimensions of his act, to do something that is in one sense good and in another sense<br />

terrible). Rorty’s account, and the cases of Antigone and Creon, seem to suggest another<br />

possibility, in which it is precisely in becoming and being a person of a certain êthos, or in<br />

ordering one’s activity in accord with a certain identity, that someone becomes, perhaps<br />

culpably, ignorant of the other potentially salient descriptions of his action.<br />

84. Arist. Poet. 11, 1452a29–32.<br />

85. Here I dissent from John Jones’s effort to correct the overemphasis on character in the<br />

interpretation of tragedy by claiming that “the text makes it plain that we can’t” read anagnôrisis<br />

as the recognition of an individual’s identity. In my view, it’s too strong to say that “the centre<br />

of gravity of Aristotle’s terms is situational and not personal,” for Aristotle is concerned with<br />

both, or more precisely with the relationship between them: we might say that he is concerned<br />

with what becomes of persons under the weight of certain distinctive types of situation. (On<br />

Aristotle and Greek Tragedy, 15–16). As the examples indicate, there is some sense in which it’s<br />

impossible not to say that recognition is the recognition of a person (on this see Else, Aristotle’s<br />

Poetics: The Argument, 352–53); the point will be that this is not the recognition of a coherent<br />

practical identity in the sense (and with the unambiguously positive valence) presupposed by the<br />

politics of recognition.<br />

86. Textually, the following account works roughly backward from the definition of anagnôrisis<br />

in chap. 11 to the immediately preceding definition of peripeteia, also in ch. 11; and finally to the<br />

account of plots that occur “unexpectedly and at the same time in consequence of one another” in<br />

chap. 9.<br />

87. On the suddenness of peripeteia, see Else, Aristotle’s Poetics: The Argument, 345; Else<br />

persuasively interprets peripeteia as a subset of metabolê at 343.<br />

88. On the importance of this phrase and its connection to peripeteia and anagnôrisis, see Else,<br />

Aristotle’s Poetics: The Argument, 329ff; Halliwell, Aristotle’s Poetics, 212.<br />

89. On this point see Patricia Jagentowicz Mills, Woman, Nature and Psyche (New Haven: Yale<br />

University Press, 1987), 28–29; Mills seems to me, however, to be trapped by the false choice I<br />

identify in the next paragraph.<br />

90. For an interesting reading of the Antigone in terms of belatedness, see Ulf Heuner,<br />

“Sophokles’ Antigone—zur tragischen Ironie von Zeit und Handlung,” Poetica 29, nos. 1–2<br />

(1997): 1–25.<br />

45

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!