02.07.2013 Views

Cultural Theory and Popular Culture

Cultural Theory and Popular Culture

Cultural Theory and Popular Culture

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

FIFTH EDITION<br />

CULtUrAL<br />

theoryANd<br />

PoPULAr<br />

CULtUre<br />

AN INTRODUCTION<br />

JohN storey


<strong>Cultural</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Popular</strong> <strong>Culture</strong><br />

An Introduction<br />

Visit the <strong>Cultural</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Popular</strong> <strong>Culture</strong>, fifth edition<br />

Companion Website at www.pearsoned.co.uk/storey to find<br />

valuable student learning material including:<br />

■ Extension activities for each chapter<br />

■ Extra questions to aid revision <strong>and</strong> further underst<strong>and</strong>ing<br />

■ Annotated links to relevant sites on the web <strong>and</strong> further<br />

reading<br />

■ Multiple choice questions to check basic underst<strong>and</strong>ing<br />

■ Glossary of key terms


We work with leading authors to develop the<br />

strongest educational materials in cultural studies,<br />

bringing cutting-edge thinking <strong>and</strong> best learning<br />

practice to a global market.<br />

Under a range of well-known imprints, including<br />

Longman, we craft high quality print <strong>and</strong> electronic<br />

publications which help readers to underst<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong><br />

apply their content, whether studying or at work.<br />

To find out more about the complete range of our<br />

publishing, please visit us on the World Wide Web at:<br />

www.pearsoned.co.uk


<strong>Cultural</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Popular</strong> <strong>Culture</strong><br />

An Introduction<br />

Fifth edition<br />

John Storey<br />

University of Sunderl<strong>and</strong>


Contents<br />

Preface/Acknowledgements ix<br />

Publisher’s acknowledgements xiii<br />

1 What is popular culture? 1<br />

<strong>Culture</strong> 1<br />

Ideology 2<br />

<strong>Popular</strong> culture 5<br />

<strong>Popular</strong> culture as other 13<br />

Further reading 14<br />

2 The ‘culture <strong>and</strong> civilization’ tradition 17<br />

Matthew Arnold 18<br />

Leavisism 22<br />

Mass culture in America: the post-war debate 28<br />

The culture of other people 33<br />

Further reading 35<br />

3 <strong>Cultural</strong>ism 37<br />

Richard Hoggart: The Uses of Literacy 38<br />

Raymond Williams: ‘The analysis of culture’ 44<br />

E.P. Thompson: The Making of the English Working Class 49<br />

Stuart Hall <strong>and</strong> Paddy Whannel: The <strong>Popular</strong> Arts 51<br />

The Centre for Contemporary <strong>Cultural</strong> Studies 57<br />

Further reading 58<br />

4 Marxisms 59<br />

Classical Marxism 59<br />

The Frankfurt School 62<br />

Althusserianism 70<br />

Hegemony 79<br />

Post-Marxism <strong>and</strong> cultural studies 82<br />

Further reading 88<br />

5 Psychoanalysis 91<br />

Freudian psychoanalysis 91<br />

Lacanian psychoanalysis 101


vi<br />

Contents<br />

Cine-psychoanalysis 104<br />

Slavoj yizek <strong>and</strong> Lacanian fantasy 107<br />

Further reading 109<br />

6 Structuralism <strong>and</strong> post-structuralism 111<br />

Ferdin<strong>and</strong> de Saussure 111<br />

Claude Lévi-Strauss, Will Wright <strong>and</strong> the American Western 114<br />

Rol<strong>and</strong> Barthes: Mythologies 118<br />

Post-structuralism 126<br />

Jacques Derrida 126<br />

Discourse <strong>and</strong> power: Michel Foucault 128<br />

The panoptic machine 131<br />

Further reading 133<br />

7 Gender <strong>and</strong> sexuality 135<br />

Feminisms 135<br />

Women at the cinema 136<br />

Reading romance 140<br />

Watching Dallas 147<br />

Reading women’s magazines 153<br />

Men’s studies <strong>and</strong> masculinities 159<br />

Queer theory 160<br />

Further reading 164<br />

8 ‘Race’, racism <strong>and</strong> representation 167<br />

‘Race’ <strong>and</strong> racism 167<br />

The ideology of racism: its historical emergence 168<br />

Orientalism 171<br />

Anti-racism <strong>and</strong> cultural studies 179<br />

Further reading 180<br />

9 Postmodernism 181<br />

The postmodern condition 181<br />

Postmodernism in the 1960s 182<br />

Jean-François Lyotard 184<br />

Jean Baudrillard 186<br />

Fredric Jameson 191<br />

Postmodern pop music 197<br />

Postmodern television 198<br />

Postmodernism <strong>and</strong> the pluralism of value 201<br />

The global postmodern 203<br />

Convergence culture 210<br />

Afterword 211<br />

Further reading 211


Contents vii<br />

10 The politics of the popular 213<br />

A paradigm crisis in cultural studies? 213<br />

The cultural field 216<br />

The economic field 226<br />

Post-Marxist cultural studies: hegemony revisited 232<br />

The ideology of mass culture 234<br />

Further reading 235<br />

Notes 237<br />

Bibliography 241<br />

Index 253<br />

Supporting resources<br />

■ Visit www.pearsoned.co.uk/storey to find valuable online resources<br />

Companion Website for students<br />

■ Extension activities for each chapter<br />

■ Extra questions to aid revision <strong>and</strong> further underst<strong>and</strong>ing<br />

■ Annotated links to relevant sites on the web <strong>and</strong> further reading<br />

■ Multiple choice questions to check basic underst<strong>and</strong>ing<br />

■ Glossary of key terms<br />

For instructors<br />

■ Extension activities for the classroom<br />

■ Discussion topics<br />

■ Homework ideas<br />

Also: The Companion Website provides the following features:<br />

■ Search tool to help locate specific items of content<br />

■ E-mail results <strong>and</strong> profile tools to send results of quizzes to instructors<br />

■ Online help <strong>and</strong> support to assist with website usage <strong>and</strong> troubleshooting<br />

For more information please contact your local Pearson Education sales<br />

representative or visit www.pearsoned.co.uk/storey


Preface/Acknowledgements<br />

Preface to fifth edition<br />

In writing the fifth edition I have revised, rewritten <strong>and</strong> edited throughout. I have also<br />

added new material to most of the chapters (the book has grown from a first edition<br />

of around 65,000 words to a fifth edition that is in excess of 114,000 words). The most<br />

obvious addition is the new chapter ‘Race, racism <strong>and</strong> representation’ <strong>and</strong> the new<br />

sections on the panoptic machine (Chapter 6) <strong>and</strong> convergence culture (Chapter 9).<br />

I have also added more diagrams <strong>and</strong> illustrations.<br />

The fifth edition is best read in conjunction with its companion volume, <strong>Cultural</strong><br />

<strong>Theory</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Popular</strong> <strong>Culture</strong>: A Reader, fourth edition (Pearson, 2009).<br />

Preface to fourth edition<br />

In writing the fourth edition I have revised, rewritten <strong>and</strong> edited throughout. I have<br />

also added new material to most of the chapters (the book has grown from a first edition<br />

of around 65,000 words to a fourth edition that is well in excess of 100,000<br />

words). The most obvious addition is the new chapter on psychoanalysis <strong>and</strong> the<br />

sections on post-Marxism (Chapter 4) <strong>and</strong> the global postmodern (Chapter 8). I have<br />

also added more diagrams <strong>and</strong> illustrations. Finally, I have changed the running order<br />

of the chapters. The chapters are now chronological in terms of where each begins.<br />

However, where each chapter ends may sometimes disrupt chronology. For example,<br />

Marxism begins before post-structuralism, but where the discussion of Marxism ends is<br />

more contemporary than where the discussion of post-structuralism ends. There seems<br />

to be no obvious solution to this problem.<br />

Preface to third edition<br />

In writing the third edition I have sought to improve <strong>and</strong> to exp<strong>and</strong> the material in the<br />

first two editions of this book. To achieve this I have revised <strong>and</strong> I have rewritten much<br />

more extensively than in the second edition. I have also added new material to most<br />

of the chapters. This is most evident in the renamed, <strong>and</strong> reorganized, Chapter 6, where


x<br />

Preface/Acknowledgements<br />

I have added a new section on queer theory, <strong>and</strong> where I have extended the section on<br />

reading women’s magazines. Perhaps the most visible change is the addition of illustrations,<br />

<strong>and</strong> the inclusion of a list of websites useful to the student of cultural theory<br />

<strong>and</strong> popular culture.<br />

Preface to second edition<br />

In writing the second edition I have sought to improve <strong>and</strong> to exp<strong>and</strong> the material in<br />

the first book. To achieve this I have revised <strong>and</strong> I have rewritten. More specifically, I<br />

have added new sections on popular culture <strong>and</strong> the carnivalesque, postmodernism<br />

<strong>and</strong> the pluralism of value. I have also extended five sections, neo-Gramscian cultural<br />

studies, popular film, cine-psychoanalysis <strong>and</strong> cultural studies, feminism as reading,<br />

postmodernism in the 1960s, the cultural field.<br />

Preface to first edition<br />

As the title of this book indicates, my subject is the relationship between cultural<br />

theory <strong>and</strong> popular culture. But as the title also indicates, my study is intended as an<br />

introduction to the subject. This has entailed the adoption of a particular approach. I<br />

have not tried to write a history of the encounter between cultural theory <strong>and</strong> popular<br />

culture. Instead, I have chosen to focus on the theoretical <strong>and</strong> methodological implications<br />

<strong>and</strong> ramifications of specific moments in the history of the study of popular<br />

culture. In short, I have tended to treat cultural theory / popular culture as a discursive<br />

formation, <strong>and</strong> to focus less on historical provenance <strong>and</strong> more on how it functions<br />

ideologically in the present. To avoid misunderst<strong>and</strong>ing <strong>and</strong> misrepresentation, I have<br />

allowed critics <strong>and</strong> theorists, when <strong>and</strong> where appropriate, to speak in their own<br />

words. In doing this, I am in agreement with the view expressed by the American literary<br />

historian Walter E. Houghton: ‘Attitudes are elusive. Try to define them <strong>and</strong> you<br />

lose their essence, their special colour <strong>and</strong> tone. They have to be apprehended in their<br />

concrete <strong>and</strong> living formulation.’ Moreover, rather than simply surveying the field, I<br />

have tried through quotation <strong>and</strong> detailed commentary to give the student of popular<br />

culture a ‘taste’ of the material. However, this book is not intended as a substitute for<br />

reading first-h<strong>and</strong> the theorists <strong>and</strong> critics discussed here. And, although each chapter<br />

ends with suggestions for further reading, these are intended to supplement the reading<br />

of the primary texts discussed in the individual chapters (details of which are<br />

located in the Notes at the end of the book).<br />

Above all, the intention of this book is to provide an introduction to the academic<br />

study of popular culture. As I have already indicated, I am under no illusion that this<br />

is a fully adequate account, or the only possible way to map the conceptual l<strong>and</strong>scape<br />

that is the subject of this study. My hope is that this version of the relationship between


popular culture <strong>and</strong> cultural theory will encourage other students of popular culture to<br />

begin their own mapping of the field.<br />

Finally, I hope I have written a book that can offer something to both those familiar<br />

with the subject <strong>and</strong> those to whom – as an academic subject at least – it is all very new.<br />

Acknowledgements<br />

Preface/Acknowledgements xi<br />

I would like to thank students on the ‘<strong>Cultural</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Popular</strong> <strong>Culture</strong>’ modules<br />

(1990–2008) at the University of Sunderl<strong>and</strong>, with whom I have rehearsed many<br />

of the ideas contained in this book. I would also like to thank colleagues in the<br />

(University of Sunderl<strong>and</strong>) Centre for Research in Media <strong>and</strong> <strong>Cultural</strong> Studies, <strong>and</strong><br />

friends at other institutions, for ideas <strong>and</strong> encouragement. I would also like to thank<br />

Andrew Taylor of Pearson Education for giving me the opportunity to write a fifth edition.


Publisher’s acknowledgements<br />

We are grateful to the following for permission to reproduce copyright material:<br />

Photo 6.1 (Paris Match), with permission from Hachette Filipacchi Associés; the text in<br />

Photo 6.2 from an advertisement recruiting teachers in Empire, for the Department for<br />

Education <strong>and</strong> Skills (1991). Reproduced with permission of the Controller of HMSO;<br />

Figure 9.1 (Daily Express headline) reproduced by permission of Express Newspapers;<br />

Figure 10.1 (Queen’s Theatre playbill) with permission from The Arts Library,<br />

Manchester Central Library.<br />

The following are the author’s own: Photo 2.1 (day trip to Blackpool), Photo 4.3 (two<br />

figures on a beach), Figures 6.1 <strong>and</strong> 6.2 (Rock-a-day Johnny), Photo 9.1 (Cocacolonization<br />

of China), Figure 9.2 (the ‘foreign’), all © John Storey.<br />

In some instances we have been unable to trace the owners of copyright material, <strong>and</strong><br />

we would appreciate any information that would enable us to do so.<br />

We are grateful to all the reviewers who generously gave their comments on this new<br />

edition.


1 What is popular<br />

culture?<br />

Before we consider in detail the different ways in which popular culture has been<br />

defined <strong>and</strong> analysed, I want to outline some of the general features of the debate that<br />

the study of popular culture has generated. It is not my intention to pre-empt the<br />

specific findings <strong>and</strong> arguments that will be presented in the following chapters. Here<br />

I simply wish to map out the general conceptual l<strong>and</strong>scape of popular culture. This is,<br />

in many ways, a daunting task. As Tony Bennett (1980) points out, ‘as it st<strong>and</strong>s, the<br />

concept of popular culture is virtually useless, a melting pot of confused <strong>and</strong> contradictory<br />

meanings capable of misdirecting inquiry up any number of theoretical blind<br />

alleys’ (18). Part of the difficulty stems from the implied otherness that is always absent/<br />

present when we use the term ‘popular culture’. As we shall see in the chapters which<br />

follow, popular culture is always defined, implicitly or explicitly, in contrast to other<br />

conceptual categories: folk culture, mass culture, dominant culture, working-class culture,<br />

etc. A full definition must always take this into account. Moreover, as we shall also<br />

see, whichever conceptual category is deployed as popular culture’s absent other, it will<br />

always powerfully affect the connotations brought into play when we use the term<br />

‘popular culture’.<br />

Therefore, to study popular culture we must first confront the difficulty posed by the<br />

term itself. That is, ‘depending on how it is used, quite different areas of inquiry <strong>and</strong><br />

forms of theoretical definition <strong>and</strong> analytical focus are suggested’ (20). The main argument<br />

that I suspect readers will take from this book is that popular culture is in effect<br />

an empty conceptual category, one that can be filled in a wide variety of often conflicting<br />

ways, depending on the context of use.<br />

<strong>Culture</strong><br />

In order to define popular culture we first need to define the term ‘culture’. Raymond<br />

Williams (1983) calls culture ‘one of the two or three most complicated words in the<br />

English language’ (87). Williams suggests three broad definitions. First, culture can be<br />

used to refer to ‘a general process of intellectual, spiritual <strong>and</strong> aesthetic development’<br />

(90). We could, for example, speak about the cultural development of Western Europe


2<br />

Chapter 1 What is popular culture?<br />

<strong>and</strong> be referring only to intellectual, spiritual <strong>and</strong> aesthetic factors – great philosophers,<br />

great artists <strong>and</strong> great poets. This would be a perfectly underst<strong>and</strong>able formulation. A<br />

second use of the word ‘culture’ might be to suggest ‘a particular way of life, whether<br />

of a people, a period or a group’ (ibid.). Using this definition, if we speak of the cultural<br />

development of Western Europe, we would have in mind not just intellectual <strong>and</strong><br />

aesthetic factors, but the development of, for example, literacy, holidays, sport, religious<br />

festivals. Finally, Williams suggests that culture can be used to refer to ‘the works <strong>and</strong><br />

practices of intellectual <strong>and</strong> especially artistic activity’ (ibid.). In other words, culture<br />

here means the texts <strong>and</strong> practices whose principal function is to signify, to produce or<br />

to be the occasion for the production of meaning. <strong>Culture</strong> in this third definition is<br />

synonymous with what structuralists <strong>and</strong> post-structuralists call ‘signifying practices’<br />

(see Chapter 6). Using this definition, we would probably think of examples such as<br />

poetry, the novel, ballet, opera, <strong>and</strong> fine art. To speak of popular culture usually means<br />

to mobilize the second <strong>and</strong> third meanings of the word ‘culture’. The second meaning<br />

– culture as a particular way of life – would allow us to speak of such practices as the<br />

seaside holiday, the celebration of Christmas, <strong>and</strong> youth subcultures, as examples of<br />

culture. These are usually referred to as lived cultures or practices. The third meaning –<br />

culture as signifying practices – would allow us to speak of soap opera, pop music, <strong>and</strong><br />

comics, as examples of culture. These are usually referred to as texts. Few people would<br />

imagine Williams’s first definition when thinking about popular culture.<br />

Ideology<br />

Before we turn to the different definitions of popular culture, there is another term we<br />

have to think about: ideology. Ideology is a crucial concept in the study of popular culture.<br />

Graeme Turner (1996) calls it ‘the most important conceptual category in cultural<br />

studies’ (182). James Carey (1996) has even suggested that ‘British cultural studies<br />

could be described just as easily <strong>and</strong> perhaps more accurately as ideological studies’<br />

(65). Like culture, ideology has many competing meanings. An underst<strong>and</strong>ing of this<br />

concept is often complicated by the fact that in much cultural analysis the concept is<br />

used interchangeably with culture itself, <strong>and</strong> especially popular culture. The fact that<br />

ideology has been used to refer to the same conceptual terrain as culture <strong>and</strong> popular<br />

culture makes it an important term in any underst<strong>and</strong>ing of the nature of popular culture.<br />

What follows is a brief discussion of just five of the many ways of underst<strong>and</strong>ing<br />

ideology. We will consider only those meanings that have a bearing on the study of<br />

popular culture.<br />

First, ideology can refer to a systematic body of ideas articulated by a particular group<br />

of people. For example, we could speak of ‘professional ideology’ to refer to the ideas<br />

which inform the practices of particular professional groups. We could also speak of<br />

the ‘ideology of the Labour Party’. Here we would be referring to the collection of political,<br />

economic <strong>and</strong> social ideas that inform the aspirations <strong>and</strong> activities of the Party.


Ideology 3<br />

A second definition suggests a certain masking, distortion, or concealment. Ideology<br />

is used here to indicate how some texts <strong>and</strong> practices present distorted images of reality.<br />

They produce what is sometimes called ‘false consciousness’. Such distortions, it is<br />

argued, work in the interests of the powerful against the interests of the powerless.<br />

Using this definition, we might speak of capitalist ideology. What would be intimated<br />

by this usage would be the way in which ideology conceals the reality of domination<br />

from those in power: the dominant class do not see themselves as exploiters or oppressors.<br />

And, perhaps more importantly, the way in which ideology conceals the reality of<br />

subordination from those who are powerless: the subordinate classes do not see themselves<br />

as oppressed or exploited. This definition derives from certain assumptions<br />

about the circumstances of the production of texts <strong>and</strong> practices. It is argued that they<br />

are the superstructural ‘reflections’ or ‘expressions’ of the power relations of the economic<br />

base of society. This is one of the fundamental assumptions of classical<br />

Marxism. Here is Karl Marx’s (1976a) famous formulation:<br />

In the social production of their existence men enter into definite, necessary relations,<br />

which are independent of their will, namely, relations of production corresponding<br />

to a determinate stage of development of their material forces of production.<br />

The totality of these relations of production constitutes the economic structure of<br />

society, the real foundation on which there arises a legal <strong>and</strong> political superstructure<br />

<strong>and</strong> to which there correspond definite forms of social consciousness. The<br />

mode of production of material life conditions the social, political <strong>and</strong> intellectual<br />

life process in general (3).<br />

What Marx is suggesting is that the way a society organizes the means of its economic<br />

production will have a determining effect on the type of culture that society produces<br />

or makes possible. The cultural products of this so-called base/superstructure<br />

relationship are deemed ideological to the extent that, as a result of this relationship,<br />

they implicitly or explicitly support the interests of dominant groups who, socially,<br />

politically, economically <strong>and</strong> culturally, benefit from this particular economic organization<br />

of society. In Chapter 4, we will consider the modifications made by Marx <strong>and</strong><br />

Frederick Engels themselves to this formulation, <strong>and</strong> the way in which subsequent<br />

Marxists have further modified what has come to be regarded by many cultural critics<br />

as a rather mechanistic account of what we might call the social relations of culture <strong>and</strong><br />

popular culture. However, having said this, it is nevertheless the case that<br />

acceptance of the contention that the flow of causal traffic within society is<br />

unequally structured, such that the economy, in a privileged way, influences political<br />

<strong>and</strong> ideological relationships in ways that are not true in reverse, has usually<br />

been held to constitute a ‘limit position’ for Marxism. Ab<strong>and</strong>on this claim, it is<br />

argued, <strong>and</strong> Marxism ceases to be Marxism (Bennett, 1982a: 81).<br />

We can also use ideology in this general sense to refer to power relations outside<br />

those of class. For instance, feminists speak of the power of patriarchal ideology, <strong>and</strong>


4<br />

Chapter 1 What is popular culture?<br />

how it operates to conceal, mask <strong>and</strong> distort gender relations in our society (see<br />

Chapter 7). In Chapter 8 we will examine the ideology of racism.<br />

A third definition of ideology (closely related to, <strong>and</strong> in some ways dependent on,<br />

the second definition) uses the term to refer to ‘ideological forms’ (Marx, 1976a: 5).<br />

This usage is intended to draw attention to the way in which texts (television fiction,<br />

pop songs, novels, feature films, etc.) always present a particular image of the world.<br />

This definition depends on a notion of society as conflictual rather than consensual,<br />

structured around inequality, exploitation <strong>and</strong> oppression. Texts are said to take sides,<br />

consciously or unconsciously, in this conflict. The German playwright Bertolt Brecht<br />

(1978) summarizes the point: ‘Good or bad, a play always includes an image of the<br />

world. . . . There is no play <strong>and</strong> no theatrical performance which does not in some way<br />

affect the dispositions <strong>and</strong> conceptions of the audience. Art is never without consequences’<br />

(150–1). Brecht’s point can be generalized to apply to all texts. Another way<br />

of saying this would be simply to argue that all texts are ultimately political. That is,<br />

they offer competing ideological significations of the way the world is or should be.<br />

<strong>Popular</strong> culture is thus, as Hall (2009a) claims, a site where ‘collective social underst<strong>and</strong>ings<br />

are created’: a terrain on which ‘the politics of signification’ are played out in<br />

attempts to win people to particular ways of seeing the world (122–23).<br />

A fourth definition of ideology is one associated with the early work of the French<br />

cultural theorist Rol<strong>and</strong> Barthes (discussed in more detail in Chapter 6). Barthes argues<br />

that ideology (or ‘myth’ as Barthes himself calls it) operates mainly at the level of connotations,<br />

the secondary, often unconscious meanings that texts <strong>and</strong> practices carry, or<br />

can be made to carry. For example, a Conservative Party political broadcast transmitted<br />

in 1990 ended with the word ‘socialism’ being transposed into red prison bars. What<br />

was being suggested is that the socialism of the Labour Party is synonymous with<br />

social, economic <strong>and</strong> political imprisonment. The broadcast was attempting to fix the<br />

connotations of the word ‘socialism’. Moreover, it hoped to locate socialism in a binary<br />

relationship in which it connoted unfreedom, whilst conservatism connoted freedom.<br />

For Barthes, this would be a classic example of the operations of ideology, the attempt<br />

to make universal <strong>and</strong> legitimate what is in fact partial <strong>and</strong> particular; an attempt<br />

to pass off that which is cultural (i.e. humanly made) as something which is natural<br />

(i.e. just existing). Similarly, it could be argued that in British society white, masculine,<br />

heterosexual, middle class, are unmarked in the sense that they are the ‘normal’, the<br />

‘natural’, the ‘universal’, from which other ways of being are an inferior variation on an<br />

original. This is made clear in such formulations as a female pop singer, a black journalist,<br />

a working-class writer, a gay comedian. In each instance the first term is used to<br />

qualify the second as a deviation from the ‘universal’ categories of pop singer, journalist,<br />

writer <strong>and</strong> comedian.<br />

A fifth definition is one that was very influential in the 1970s <strong>and</strong> early 1980s. It<br />

is the definition of ideology developed by the French Marxist philosopher Louis<br />

Althusser. We shall discuss Althusser in more detail in Chapter 4. Here I will simply<br />

outline some key points about one of his definitions of ideology. Althusser’s main contention<br />

is to see ideology not simply as a body of ideas, but as a material practice. What<br />

he means by this is that ideology is encountered in the practices of everyday life <strong>and</strong>


not simply in certain ideas about everyday life. Principally, what Althusser has in mind<br />

is the way in which certain rituals <strong>and</strong> customs have the effect of binding us to the<br />

social order: a social order that is marked by enormous inequalities of wealth, status<br />

<strong>and</strong> power. Using this definition, we could describe the seaside holiday or the celebration<br />

of Christmas as examples of ideological practices. This would point to the way in<br />

which they offer pleasure <strong>and</strong> release from the usual dem<strong>and</strong>s of the social order, but<br />

that, ultimately, they return us to our places in the social order, refreshed <strong>and</strong> ready to<br />

tolerate our exploitation <strong>and</strong> oppression until the next official break comes along. In<br />

this sense, ideology works to reproduce the social conditions <strong>and</strong> social relations necessary<br />

for the economic conditions <strong>and</strong> economic relations of capitalism to continue.<br />

So far we have briefly examined different ways of defining culture <strong>and</strong> ideology.<br />

What should be clear by now is that culture <strong>and</strong> ideology do cover much the same conceptual<br />

l<strong>and</strong>scape. The main difference between them is that ideology brings a political<br />

dimension to the shared terrain. In addition, the introduction of the concept of<br />

ideology suggests that relations of power <strong>and</strong> politics inescapably mark the culture/<br />

ideology l<strong>and</strong>scape; it suggests that the study of popular culture amounts to something<br />

more than a simple discussion of entertainment <strong>and</strong> leisure.<br />

<strong>Popular</strong> culture<br />

<strong>Popular</strong> culture 5<br />

There are various ways to define popular culture. This book is of course in part about<br />

that very process, about the different ways in which various critical approaches have<br />

attempted to fix the meaning of popular culture. Therefore, all I intend to do for the<br />

remainder of this chapter is to sketch out six definitions of popular culture that in their<br />

different, general ways, inform the study of popular culture. But first a few words about<br />

the term ‘popular’. Williams (1983) suggests four current meanings: ‘well liked by<br />

many people’; ‘inferior kinds of work’; ‘work deliberately setting out to win favour with<br />

the people’; ‘culture actually made by the people for themselves’ (237). Clearly, then,<br />

any definition of popular culture will bring into play a complex combination of the different<br />

meanings of the term ‘culture’ with the different meanings of the term ‘popular’.<br />

The history of cultural theory’s engagement with popular culture is, therefore, a history<br />

of the different ways in which the two terms have been connected by theoretical labour<br />

within particular historical <strong>and</strong> social contexts.<br />

An obvious starting point in any attempt to define popular culture is to say that<br />

popular culture is simply culture that is widely favoured or well liked by many people.<br />

And, undoubtedly, such a quantitative index would meet the approval of many people.<br />

We could examine sales of books, sales of CDs <strong>and</strong> DVDs. We could also examine<br />

attendance records at concerts, sporting events, <strong>and</strong> festivals. We could also scrutinize<br />

market research figures on audience preferences for different television programmes.<br />

Such counting would undoubtedly tell us a great deal. The difficulty might prove to be<br />

that, paradoxically, it tells us too much. Unless we can agree on a figure over which


6<br />

Chapter 1 What is popular culture?<br />

something becomes popular culture, <strong>and</strong> below which it is just culture, we might find<br />

that widely favoured or well liked by many people included so much as to be virtually<br />

useless as a conceptual definition of popular culture. Despite this problem, what is<br />

clear is that any definition of popular culture must include a quantitative dimension.<br />

The popular of popular culture would seem to dem<strong>and</strong> it. What is also clear, however,<br />

is that on its own, a quantitative index is not enough to provide an adequate definition<br />

of popular culture. Such counting would almost certainly include ‘the officially sanctioned<br />

“high culture” which in terms of book <strong>and</strong> record sales <strong>and</strong> audience ratings for<br />

television dramatisations of the classics, can justifiably claim to be “popular” in this<br />

sense’ (Bennett, 1980: 20–1).<br />

A second way of defining popular culture is to suggest that it is the culture that is left<br />

over after we have decided what is high culture. <strong>Popular</strong> culture, in this definition, is<br />

a residual category, there to accommodate texts <strong>and</strong> practices that fail to meet the<br />

required st<strong>and</strong>ards to qualify as high culture. In other words, it is a definition of popular<br />

culture as inferior culture. What the culture/popular culture test might include is a<br />

range of value judgements on a particular text or practice. For example, we might want<br />

to insist on formal complexity. In other words, to be real culture, it has to be difficult.<br />

Being difficult thus ensures its exclusive status as high culture. Its very difficulty literally<br />

excludes, an exclusion that guarantees the exclusivity of its audience. The French<br />

sociologist Pierre Bourdieu argues that cultural distinctions of this kind are often used<br />

to support class distinctions. Taste is a deeply ideological category: it functions as<br />

a marker of ‘class’ (using the term in a double sense to mean both a social economic<br />

category <strong>and</strong> the suggestion of a particular level of quality). For Bourdieu (1984), the<br />

consumption of culture is ‘predisposed, consciously <strong>and</strong> deliberately or not, to fulfil a<br />

social function of legitimating social differences’ (5). This will be discussed in more<br />

detail in Chapters 9 <strong>and</strong> 10.<br />

This definition of popular culture is often supported by claims that popular culture<br />

is mass-produced commercial culture, whereas high culture is the result of an<br />

individual act of creation. The latter, therefore, deserves only a moral <strong>and</strong> aesthetic<br />

response; the former requires only a fleeting sociological inspection to unlock what<br />

little it has to offer. Whatever the method deployed, those who wish to make the case<br />

for the division between high <strong>and</strong> popular culture generally insist that the division<br />

between the two is absolutely clear. Moreover, not only is this division clear, it is transhistorical<br />

– fixed for all time. This latter point is usually insisted on, especially if the<br />

division is dependent on supposed essential textual qualities. There are many problems<br />

with this certainty. For example, William Shakespeare is now seen as the epitome<br />

of high culture, yet as late as the nineteenth century his work was very much a part of<br />

popular theatre. 1 The same point can also be made about Charles Dickens’s work.<br />

Similarly, film noir can be seen to have crossed the border supposedly separating popular<br />

<strong>and</strong> high culture: in other words, what started as popular cinema is now the preserve<br />

of academics <strong>and</strong> film clubs. 2 One recent example of cultural traffic moving in the<br />

other direction is Luciano Pavarotti’s recording of Puccini’s ‘Nessun Dorma’. Even the<br />

most rigorous defenders of high culture would not want to exclude Pavarotti or Puccini<br />

from its select enclave. But in 1990, Pavarotti managed to take ‘Nessun Dorma’ to


<strong>Popular</strong> culture 7<br />

number one in the British charts. Such commercial success on any quantitative analysis<br />

would make the composer, the performer <strong>and</strong> the aria, popular culture. 3 In fact,<br />

one student I know actually complained about the way in which the aria had been supposedly<br />

devalued by its commercial success. He claimed that he now found it embarrassing<br />

to play the aria for fear that someone should think his musical taste was simply<br />

the result of the aria being ‘The Official BBC Gr<strong>and</strong>st<strong>and</strong> World Cup Theme’. Other students<br />

laughed <strong>and</strong> mocked. But his complaint highlights something very significant<br />

about the high/popular divide: the elitist investment that some put in its continuation.<br />

On 30 July 1991, Pavarotti gave a free concert in London’s Hyde Park. About<br />

250,000 people were expected, but because of heavy rain, the number who actually<br />

attended was around 100,000. Two things about the event are of interest to a student<br />

of popular culture. The first is the enormous popularity of the event. We could connect<br />

this with the fact that Pavarotti’s previous two albums (Essential Pavarotti 1 <strong>and</strong> Essential<br />

Pavarotti 2) had both topped the British album charts. His obvious popularity would<br />

appear to call into question any clear division between high <strong>and</strong> popular culture.<br />

Second, the extent of his popularity would appear to threaten the class exclusivity of a<br />

high/popular divide. It is therefore interesting to note the way in which the event was<br />

reported in the media. All the British tabloids carried news of the event on their front<br />

pages. The Daily Mirror, for instance, had five pages devoted to the concert. What the<br />

tabloid coverage reveals is a clear attempt to define the event for popular culture. The<br />

Sun quoted a woman who said, ‘I can’t afford to go to posh opera houses with toffs <strong>and</strong><br />

fork out £100 a seat.’ The Daily Mirror ran an editorial in which it claimed that<br />

Pavarotti’s performance ‘wasn’t for the rich’ but ‘for the thous<strong>and</strong>s . . . who could never<br />

normally afford a night with an operatic star’. When the event was reported on television<br />

news programmes the following lunchtime, the tabloid coverage was included as<br />

part of the general meaning of the event. Both the BBC’s One O’clock News <strong>and</strong> ITV’s<br />

12.30 News, referred to the way in which the tabloids had covered the concert, <strong>and</strong><br />

moreover, the extent to which they had covered the concert. The old certainties of the<br />

cultural l<strong>and</strong>scape suddenly seemed in doubt. However, there was some attempt made<br />

to reintroduce the old certainties: ‘some critics said that a park is no place for opera’<br />

(One O’clock News); ‘some opera enthusiasts might think it all a bit vulgar’ (12.30<br />

News). Although such comments invoked the spectre of high-culture exclusivity, they<br />

seemed strangely at a loss to offer any purchase on the event. The apparently obvious<br />

cultural division between high <strong>and</strong> popular culture no longer seemed so obvious. It<br />

suddenly seemed that the cultural had been replaced by the economic, revealing a division<br />

between ‘the rich’ <strong>and</strong> ‘the thous<strong>and</strong>s’. It was the event’s very popularity that<br />

forced the television news to confront, <strong>and</strong> ultimately to find wanting, old cultural<br />

certainties. This can be partly illustrated by returning to the contradictory meaning<br />

of the term ‘popular’. 4 On the one h<strong>and</strong>, something is said to be good because it is<br />

popular. An example of this usage would be: it was a popular performance. Yet, on<br />

the other h<strong>and</strong>, something is said to be bad for the very same reason. Consider the<br />

binary oppositions in Table 1.1. This demonstrates quite clearly the way in which<br />

popular <strong>and</strong> popular culture carries within its definitional field connotations of inferiority;<br />

a second-best culture for those unable to underst<strong>and</strong>, let alone appreciate, real


8<br />

Chapter 1 What is popular culture?<br />

Table 1.1 <strong>Popular</strong> culture as ‘inferior’ culture.<br />

<strong>Popular</strong> press Quality press<br />

<strong>Popular</strong> cinema Art cinema<br />

<strong>Popular</strong> entertainment Art<br />

culture – what Matthew Arnold refers to as ‘the best that has been thought <strong>and</strong> said in<br />

the world’ (see Chapter 2). Hall (2009b) argues that what is important here is not the<br />

fact that popular forms move up <strong>and</strong> down the ‘cultural escalator’; more significant are<br />

‘the forces <strong>and</strong> relations which sustain the distinction, the difference . . . [the] institutions<br />

<strong>and</strong> institutional processes . . . required to sustain each <strong>and</strong> to continually mark<br />

the difference between them’ (514). This is principally the work of the education system<br />

<strong>and</strong> its promotion of a selective tradition (see Chapter 3).<br />

A third way of defining popular culture is as ‘mass culture’. This draws heavily on<br />

the previous definition. The mass culture perspective will be discussed in some detail<br />

in Chapter 2; therefore all I want to do here is to suggest the basic terms of this<br />

definition. The first point that those who refer to popular culture as mass culture want<br />

to establish is that popular culture is a hopelessly commercial culture. It is massproduced<br />

for mass consumption. Its audience is a mass of non-discriminating consumers.<br />

The culture itself is formulaic, manipulative (to the political right or left,<br />

depending on who is doing the analysis). It is a culture that is consumed with brainnumbed<br />

<strong>and</strong> brain-numbing passivity. But as John Fiske (1989a) points out, ‘between<br />

80 <strong>and</strong> 90 per cent of new products fail despite extensive advertising . . . many films fail<br />

to recover even their promotional costs at the box office’ (31). Simon Frith (1983: 147)<br />

also points out that about 80 per cent of singles <strong>and</strong> albums lose money. Such statistics<br />

should clearly call into question the notion of consumption as an automatic<br />

<strong>and</strong> passive activity (see Chapters 7 <strong>and</strong> 10).<br />

Those working within the mass culture perspective usually have in mind a previous<br />

‘golden age’ when cultural matters were very different. This usually takes one of two<br />

forms: a lost organic community or a lost folk culture. But as Fiske (1989a) points out,<br />

‘In capitalist societies there is no so-called authentic folk culture against which to measure<br />

the “inauthenticity” of mass culture, so bemoaning the loss of the authentic is a<br />

fruitless exercise in romantic nostalgia’ (27). This also holds true for the ‘lost’ organic<br />

community. The Frankfurt School, as we shall see in Chapter 4, locate the lost golden<br />

age, not in the past, but in the future.<br />

For some cultural critics working within the mass culture paradigm, mass culture is<br />

not just an imposed <strong>and</strong> impoverished culture, it is in a clear identifiable sense an<br />

imported American culture: ‘If popular culture in its modern form was invented in any<br />

one place, it was . . . in the great cities of the United States, <strong>and</strong> above all in New York’<br />

(Maltby, 1989: 11; my italics). The claim that popular culture is American culture has<br />

a long history within the theoretical mapping of popular culture. It operates under the<br />

term ‘Americanization’. Its central theme is that British culture has declined under the


<strong>Popular</strong> culture 9<br />

homogenizing influence of American culture. There are two things we can say with<br />

some confidence about the United States <strong>and</strong> popular culture. First, as Andrew Ross<br />

(1989) has pointed out, ‘popular culture has been socially <strong>and</strong> institutionally central<br />

in America for longer <strong>and</strong> in a more significant way than in Europe’ (7). Second,<br />

although the availability of American culture worldwide is undoubted, how what is<br />

available is consumed is at the very least contradictory (see Chapter 9). What is true is<br />

that in the 1950s (one of the key periods of Americanization), for many young people<br />

in Britain, American culture represented a force of liberation against the grey certainties<br />

of British everyday life. What is also clear is that the fear of Americanization is<br />

closely related to a distrust (regardless of national origin) of emerging forms of popular<br />

culture. As with the mass culture perspective generally, there are political left <strong>and</strong><br />

political right versions of the argument. What are under threat are either the traditional<br />

values of high culture, or the traditional way of life of a ‘tempted’ working class.<br />

There is what we might call a benign version of the mass culture perspective. The<br />

texts <strong>and</strong> practices of popular culture are seen as forms of public fantasy. <strong>Popular</strong> culture<br />

is understood as a collective dream world. As Richard Maltby (1989) claims, popular<br />

culture provides ‘escapism that is not an escape from or to anywhere, but an escape<br />

of our utopian selves’ (14). In this sense, cultural practices such as Christmas <strong>and</strong> the<br />

seaside holiday, it could be argued, function in much the same way as dreams: they<br />

articulate, in a disguised form, collective (but repressed) wishes <strong>and</strong> desires. This is a<br />

benign version of the mass culture critique because, as Maltby points out, ‘If it is the<br />

crime of popular culture that it has taken our dreams <strong>and</strong> packaged them <strong>and</strong> sold<br />

them back to us, it is also the achievement of popular culture that it has brought us<br />

more <strong>and</strong> more varied dreams than we could otherwise ever have known’ (ibid.).<br />

Structuralism, although not usually placed within the mass culture perspective, <strong>and</strong><br />

certainly not sharing its moralistic approach, nevertheless sees popular culture as a sort<br />

of ideological machine which more or less effortlessly reproduces the prevailing structures<br />

of power. Readers are seen as locked into specific ‘reading positions’. There is little<br />

space for reader activity or textual contradiction. Part of post-structuralism’s critique of<br />

structuralism is the opening up of a critical space in which such questions can be<br />

addressed. Chapter 6 will consider these issues in some detail.<br />

A fourth definition contends that popular culture is the culture that originates from<br />

‘the people’. It takes issue with any approach that suggests that it is something imposed<br />

on ‘the people’ from above. According to this definition, the term should only be used<br />

to indicate an ‘authentic’ culture of ‘the people’. This is popular culture as folk culture:<br />

a culture of the people for the people. As a definition of popular culture, it is ‘often<br />

equated with a highly romanticised concept of working-class culture construed as the<br />

major source of symbolic protest within contemporary capitalism’ (Bennett, 1980: 27).<br />

One problem with this approach is the question of who qualifies for inclusion in the<br />

category ‘the people’. Another problem with it is that it evades the ‘commercial’ nature<br />

of much of the resources from which popular culture is made. No matter how much<br />

we might insist on this definition, the fact remains that people do not spontaneously<br />

produce culture from raw materials of their own making. Whatever popular culture is,<br />

what is certain is that its raw materials are those which are commercially provided. This


10<br />

Chapter 1 What is popular culture?<br />

approach tends to avoid the full implications of this fact. Critical analysis of pop <strong>and</strong><br />

rock music is particularly replete with this kind of analysis of popular culture. At a conference<br />

I once attended, a contribution from the floor suggested that Levi jeans would<br />

never be able to use a song from The Jam to sell its products. The fact that they had<br />

already used a song by The Clash would not shake this conviction. What underpinned<br />

this conviction was a clear sense of cultural difference – television commercials for Levi<br />

jeans are mass culture, the music of The Jam is popular culture defined as an oppositional<br />

culture of ‘the people’. The only way the two could meet would be through The<br />

Jam ‘selling out’. As this was not going to happen, Levi jeans would never use a song<br />

by The Jam to sell its products. But this had already happened to The Clash, a b<strong>and</strong><br />

with equally sound political credentials. This circular exchange stalled to a stop. The<br />

cultural studies use of the concept of hegemony would have, at the very least, fuelled<br />

further discussion (see Chapter 4).<br />

A fifth definition of popular culture, then, is one that draws on the political analysis<br />

of the Italian Marxist Antonio Gramsci, particularly on his development of the<br />

concept of hegemony. Gramsci (2009) uses the term ‘hegemony’ to refer to the way<br />

in which dominant groups in society, through a process of ‘intellectual <strong>and</strong> moral leadership’<br />

(75), seek to win the consent of subordinate groups in society. This will be discussed<br />

in some detail in Chapter 4. What I want to do here is to offer a general outline<br />

of how cultural theorists have taken Gramsci’s political concept <strong>and</strong> used it to explain<br />

the nature <strong>and</strong> politics of popular culture. Those using this approach see popular culture<br />

as a site of struggle between the ‘resistance’ of subordinate groups <strong>and</strong> the forces<br />

of ‘incorporation’ operating in the interests of dominant groups. <strong>Popular</strong> culture in this<br />

usage is not the imposed culture of the mass culture theorists, nor is it an emerging<br />

from below, spontaneously oppositional culture of ‘the people’ – it is a terrain of<br />

exchange <strong>and</strong> negotiation between the two: a terrain, as already stated, marked by resistance<br />

<strong>and</strong> incorporation. The texts <strong>and</strong> practices of popular culture move within what<br />

Gramsci (1971) calls a ‘compromise equilibrium’ (161). The process is historical<br />

(labelled popular culture one moment, <strong>and</strong> another kind of culture the next), but it is<br />

also synchronic (moving between resistance <strong>and</strong> incorporation at any given historical<br />

moment). For instance, the seaside holiday began as an aristocratic event <strong>and</strong> within<br />

a hundred years it had become an example of popular culture. Film noir started as<br />

despised popular cinema <strong>and</strong> within thirty years had become art cinema. In general<br />

terms, those looking at popular culture from the perspective of hegemony theory tend<br />

to see it as a terrain of ideological struggle between dominant <strong>and</strong> subordinate classes,<br />

dominant <strong>and</strong> subordinate cultures. As Bennett (2009) explains,<br />

The field of popular culture is structured by the attempt of the ruling class to win<br />

hegemony <strong>and</strong> by forms of opposition to this endeavour. As such, it consists not<br />

simply of an imposed mass culture that is coincident with dominant ideology, nor<br />

simply of spontaneously oppositional cultures, but is rather an area of negotiation<br />

between the two within which – in different particular types of popular culture –<br />

dominant, subordinate <strong>and</strong> oppositional cultural <strong>and</strong> ideological values <strong>and</strong> elements<br />

are ‘mixed’ in different permutations (96).


The compromise equilibrium of hegemony can also be employed to analyse different<br />

types of conflict within <strong>and</strong> across popular culture. Bennett highlights class conflict,<br />

but hegemony theory can also be used to explore <strong>and</strong> explain conflicts involving ethnicity,<br />

‘race’, gender, generation, sexuality, disability, etc. – all are at different moments<br />

engaged in forms of cultural struggle against the homogenizing forces of incorporation<br />

of the official or dominant culture. The key concept in this use of hegemony theory,<br />

especially in post-Marxist cultural studies (see Chapter 4), is the concept of ‘articulation’<br />

(the word being employed in its double sense to mean both to express <strong>and</strong> to<br />

make a temporary connection). <strong>Popular</strong> culture is marked by what Chantal Mouffe<br />

(1981) calls ‘a process of disarticulation–articulation’ (231). The Conservative Party<br />

political broadcast, discussed earlier, reveals this process in action. What was being<br />

attempted was the disarticulation of socialism as a political movement concerned with<br />

economic, social <strong>and</strong> political emancipation, in favour of its articulation as a political<br />

movement concerned to impose restraints on individual freedom. Also, as we shall see<br />

in Chapter 7, feminism has always recognized the importance of cultural struggle<br />

within the contested l<strong>and</strong>scape of popular culture. Feminist presses have published<br />

science fiction, detective fiction <strong>and</strong> romance fiction. Such cultural interventions represent<br />

an attempt to articulate popular genres for feminist politics. It is also possible,<br />

using hegemony theory, to locate the struggle between resistance <strong>and</strong> incorporation<br />

as taking place within <strong>and</strong> across individual popular texts <strong>and</strong> practices. Raymond<br />

Williams (1980) suggests that we can identify different moments within a popular text<br />

or practice – what he calls ‘dominant’, ‘emergent’ <strong>and</strong> ‘residual’ – each pulling the<br />

text in a different direction. Thus a text is made up of a contradictory mix of different<br />

cultural forces. How these elements are articulated will depend in part on the social circumstances<br />

<strong>and</strong> historical conditions of production <strong>and</strong> consumption. Hall (1980a)<br />

uses Williams’s insight to construct a theory of reading positions: ‘subordinate’,<br />

‘dominant’, <strong>and</strong> ‘negotiated’. David Morley (1980) has modified the model to take into<br />

account discourse <strong>and</strong> subjectivity: seeing reading as always an interaction between the<br />

discourses of the text <strong>and</strong> the discourses of the reader.<br />

There is another aspect of popular culture that is suggested by hegemony theory.<br />

This is the claim that theories of popular culture are really theories about the constitution<br />

of ‘the people’. Hall (2009b), for instance, argues that popular culture is a contested<br />

site for political constructions of ‘the people’ <strong>and</strong> their relation to ‘the power<br />

bloc’ (see Chapter 4):<br />

‘the people’ refers neither to everyone nor to a single group within society but to<br />

a variety of social groups which, although differing from one another in other<br />

respects (their class position or the particular struggles in which they are most<br />

immediately engaged), are distinguished from the economically, politically <strong>and</strong><br />

culturally powerful groups within society <strong>and</strong> are hence potentially capable of<br />

being united – of being organised into ‘the people versus the power bloc’ – if their<br />

separate struggles are connected (Bennett, 1986: 20).<br />

This is of course to make popular culture a profoundly political concept.<br />

<strong>Popular</strong> culture 11


12<br />

Chapter 1 What is popular culture?<br />

<strong>Popular</strong> culture is a site where the construction of everyday life may be examined.<br />

The point of doing this is not only academic – that is, as an attempt to underst<strong>and</strong><br />

a process or practice – it is also political, to examine the power relations that constitute<br />

this form of everyday life <strong>and</strong> thus reveal the configurations of interests its<br />

construction serves (Turner, 1996: 6).<br />

In Chapter 10, I will consider John Fiske’s ‘semiotic’ use of Gramsci’s concept of<br />

hegemony. Fiske argues, as does Paul Willis from a slightly different perspective (also<br />

discussed in Chapter 10), that popular culture is what people make from the products<br />

of the culture industries – mass culture is the repertoire, popular culture is what people<br />

actively make from it, actually do with the commodities <strong>and</strong> commodified practices<br />

they consume.<br />

A sixth definition of popular culture is one informed by recent thinking around the<br />

debate on postmodernism. This will be the subject of Chapter 9. All I want to do now<br />

is to draw attention to some of the basic points in the debate about the relationship<br />

between postmodernism <strong>and</strong> popular culture. The main point to insist on here is the<br />

claim that postmodern culture is a culture that no longer recognizes the distinction<br />

between high <strong>and</strong> popular culture. As we shall see, for some this is a reason to celebrate<br />

an end to an elitism constructed on arbitrary distinctions of culture; for others it is a<br />

reason to despair at the final victory of commerce over culture. An example of the supposed<br />

interpenetration of commerce <strong>and</strong> culture (the postmodern blurring of the distinction<br />

between ‘authentic’ <strong>and</strong> ‘commercial’ culture) can be found in the relationship<br />

between television commercials <strong>and</strong> pop music. For example, there is a growing list of<br />

artists who have had hit records as a result of their songs appearing in television commercials.<br />

One of the questions this relationship raises is: ‘What is being sold: song or<br />

product?’ I suppose the obvious answer is both. Moreover, it is now possible to buy<br />

CDs that consist of the songs that have become successful, or have become successful<br />

again, as a result of being used in advertisements. There is a wonderful circularity to<br />

this: songs are used to sell products <strong>and</strong> the fact that they do this successfully is then<br />

used to sell the songs. For those with little sympathy for either postmodernism or the<br />

celebratory theorizing of some postmodernists, the real question is: ‘What is such a<br />

relationship doing to culture?’ Those on the political left might worry about its effect<br />

on the oppositional possibilities of popular culture. Those on the political right might<br />

worry about what it is doing to the status of real culture. This has resulted in a sustained<br />

debate in cultural studies. The significance of popular culture is central to this<br />

debate. This, <strong>and</strong> other questions, will be explored in Chapter 9. The chapter will also<br />

address, from the perspective of the student of popular culture, the question: ‘What is<br />

postmodernism?’<br />

Finally, what all these definitions have in common is the insistence that whatever<br />

else popular culture is, it is definitely a culture that only emerged following industrialization<br />

<strong>and</strong> urbanization. As Williams (1963) argues in the ‘Foreword’ to <strong>Culture</strong> <strong>and</strong><br />

Society, ‘The organising principle of this book is the discovery that the idea of culture,<br />

<strong>and</strong> the word itself in its general modern uses, came into English thinking in the period<br />

which we commonly describe as that of the Industrial Revolution’ (11). It is a


definition of culture <strong>and</strong> popular culture that depends on there being in place a capitalist<br />

market economy. This of course makes Britain the first country to produce<br />

popular culture defined in this historically restricted way. There are other ways to<br />

define popular culture, which do not depend on this particular history or these particular<br />

circumstances, but they are definitions that fall outside the range of the cultural<br />

theorists <strong>and</strong> the cultural theory discussed in this book. The argument, which underpins<br />

this particular periodization of popular culture, is that the experience of industrialization<br />

<strong>and</strong> urbanization changed fundamentally the cultural relations within the<br />

l<strong>and</strong>scape of popular culture. Before industrialization <strong>and</strong> urbanization, Britain had<br />

two cultures: a common culture which was shared, more or less, by all classes, <strong>and</strong> a<br />

separate elite culture produced <strong>and</strong> consumed by the dominant classes in society (see<br />

Burke, 1994; Storey, 2003). As a result of industrialization <strong>and</strong> urbanization, three<br />

things happened, which together had the effect of redrawing the cultural map. First of<br />

all, industrialization changed the relations between employees <strong>and</strong> employers. This<br />

involved a shift from a relationship based on mutual obligation to one based solely on<br />

the dem<strong>and</strong>s of what Thomas Carlyle calls the ‘cash nexus’ (quoted in Morris, 1979:<br />

22). Second, urbanization produced a residential separation of classes. For the first<br />

time in British history there were whole sections of towns <strong>and</strong> cities inhabited only by<br />

working men <strong>and</strong> women. Third, the panic engendered by the French Revolution – the<br />

fear that it might be imported into Britain – encouraged successive governments to<br />

enact a variety of repressive measures aimed at defeating radicalism. Political radicalism<br />

<strong>and</strong> trade unionism were not destroyed, but driven underground to organize<br />

beyond the influence of middle-class interference <strong>and</strong> control. These three factors<br />

combined to produce a cultural space outside of the paternalist considerations of<br />

the earlier common culture. The result was the production of a cultural space for the<br />

generation of a popular culture more or less outside the controlling influence of the<br />

dominant classes. How this space was filled was a subject of some controversy for<br />

the founding fathers of culturalism (see Chapter 3). Whatever we decide was its content,<br />

the anxieties engendered by the new cultural space were directly responsible for the<br />

emergence of the ‘culture <strong>and</strong> civilization’ approach to popular culture (see Chapter 2).<br />

<strong>Popular</strong> culture as other<br />

<strong>Popular</strong> culture as other 13<br />

What should be clear by now is that the term ‘popular culture’ is not as definitionally<br />

obvious as we might have first thought. A great deal of the difficulty arises from the<br />

absent other which always haunts any definition we might use. It is never enough to<br />

speak of popular culture; we have always to acknowledge that with which it is being<br />

contrasted. And whichever of popular culture’s others we employ, mass culture, high<br />

culture, working-class culture, folk culture, etc., it will carry into the definition of<br />

popular culture a specific theoretical <strong>and</strong> political inflection. ‘There is’, as Bennett<br />

(1982a) indicates, ‘no single or “correct” way of resolving these problems; only a series


14<br />

Chapter 1 What is popular culture?<br />

of different solutions which have different implications <strong>and</strong> effects’ (86). The main<br />

purpose of this book is to chart the many problems encountered, <strong>and</strong> the many solutions<br />

suggested, in cultural theory’s complex engagement with popular culture. As we<br />

shall discover, there is a lot of ground between Arnold’s view of popular culture as<br />

‘anarchy’ <strong>and</strong> Dick Hebdige’s (1988) claim that, ‘In the West popular culture is no<br />

longer marginal, still less subterranean. Most of the time <strong>and</strong> for most people it simply<br />

is culture.’ Or, as Geoffrey Nowell-Smith (1987) notes, ‘popular cultural forms have<br />

moved so far towards centre stage in British cultural life that the separate existence of<br />

a distinctive popular culture in an oppositional relation to high culture is now in question’<br />

(80). This of course makes an underst<strong>and</strong>ing of the range of ways of theorizing<br />

popular culture all the more important.<br />

This book, then, is about the theorizing that has brought us to our present state of<br />

thinking on popular culture. It is about how the changing terrain of popular culture<br />

has been explored <strong>and</strong> mapped by different cultural theorists <strong>and</strong> different theoretical<br />

approaches. It is upon their shoulders that we st<strong>and</strong> when we think critically about<br />

popular culture. The aim of this book is to introduce readers to the different ways in<br />

which popular culture has been analysed <strong>and</strong> the different popular cultures that have<br />

been articulated as a result of the process of analysis. For it must be remembered that<br />

popular culture is not a historically fixed set of popular texts <strong>and</strong> practices, nor is it a<br />

historically fixed conceptual category. The object under theoretical scrutiny is both historically<br />

variable, <strong>and</strong> always in part constructed by the very act of theoretical engagement.<br />

This is further complicated by the fact that different theoretical perspectives have<br />

tended to focus on particular areas of the popular cultural l<strong>and</strong>scape. The most common<br />

division is between the study of texts (popular fiction, television, pop music, etc.)<br />

<strong>and</strong> lived cultures or practices (seaside holidays, youth subcultures, the celebration of<br />

Christmas, etc.). The aim of this book, therefore, is to provide readers with a map of<br />

the terrain to enable them to begin their own explorations, to begin their own mapping<br />

of the main theoretical <strong>and</strong> political debates that have characterized the study of<br />

popular culture.<br />

Further reading<br />

Storey, John (ed.), <strong>Cultural</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Popular</strong> <strong>Culture</strong>: A Reader, 4th edition, Harlow:<br />

Pearson Education, 2009. This is the companion volume to this book. It contains<br />

examples of most of the work discussed here. This book <strong>and</strong> the companion Reader<br />

are supported by an interactive website (www.pearsoned.co.uk/storey). The website<br />

has links to other useful sites <strong>and</strong> electronic resources.<br />

Agger, Ben, <strong>Cultural</strong> Studies as <strong>Cultural</strong> <strong>Theory</strong>, London: Falmer Press, 1992. As the title<br />

implies, this is a book about cultural studies written from a perspective sympathetic<br />

to the Frankfurt School. It offers some useful commentary on popular culture, especially<br />

Chapter 2: ‘<strong>Popular</strong> culture as serious business’.


Further reading 15<br />

Allen, Robert C. (ed.), Channels of Discourse, Reassembled, London: Routledge, 1992.<br />

Although this collection is specifically focused on television, it contains some excellent<br />

essays of general interest to the student of popular culture.<br />

Bennett, Tony, Colin Mercer <strong>and</strong> Janet Woollacott (eds), <strong>Popular</strong> <strong>Culture</strong> <strong>and</strong> Social<br />

Relations, Milton Keynes: Open University Press, 1986. An interesting collection of<br />

essays, covering both theory <strong>and</strong> analysis.<br />

Brooker, Peter, A Concise Glossary of <strong>Cultural</strong> <strong>Theory</strong>, London: Edward Arnold, 1999. A<br />

brilliant glossary of the key terms in cultural theory.<br />

Day, Gary (ed.), Readings in <strong>Popular</strong> <strong>Culture</strong>, London: Macmillan, 1990. A mixed collection<br />

of essays, some interesting <strong>and</strong> useful, others too unsure about how seriously<br />

to take popular culture.<br />

Du Gay, Paul, Stuart Hall, Linda Janes, Hugh Mackay <strong>and</strong> Keith Negus, Doing <strong>Cultural</strong><br />

Studies: The Story of the Sony Walkman, London: Sage, 1997. An excellent introduction<br />

to some of the key issues in cultural studies. Certainly worth reading for the<br />

explanation of ‘the circuit of culture’.<br />

Fiske, John, Reading the <strong>Popular</strong>, London: Unwin Hyman, 1989. A collection of essays<br />

analysing different examples of popular culture.<br />

Fiske, John, Underst<strong>and</strong>ing <strong>Popular</strong> <strong>Culture</strong>, London: Unwin Hyman, 1989. A clear presentation<br />

of his particular approach to the study of popular culture.<br />

Goodall, Peter, High <strong>Culture</strong>, <strong>Popular</strong> <strong>Culture</strong>: The Long Debate, St Leonards: Allen &<br />

Unwin, 1995. The book traces the debate between high <strong>and</strong> popular culture, with<br />

particular, but not exclusive, reference to the Australian experience, from the eighteenth<br />

century to the present day.<br />

Milner, Andrew, Contemporary <strong>Cultural</strong> Studies, 2nd edn, London: UCL Press, 1994. A<br />

useful introduction to contemporary cultural theory.<br />

Mukerji, Ch<strong>and</strong>ra <strong>and</strong> Michael Schudson (eds), Rethinking <strong>Popular</strong> <strong>Culture</strong>, Berkeley:<br />

University of California Press, 1991. A collection of essays, with an informed <strong>and</strong><br />

interesting introduction. The book is helpfully divided into sections on different<br />

approaches to popular culture: historical, anthropological, sociological <strong>and</strong> cultural.<br />

Naremore, James <strong>and</strong> Patrick Brantlinger, Modernity <strong>and</strong> Mass <strong>Culture</strong>, Bloomington<br />

<strong>and</strong> Indianapolis: Indiana University Press, 1991. A useful <strong>and</strong> interesting collection<br />

of essays on cultural theory <strong>and</strong> popular culture.<br />

Storey, John, Inventing <strong>Popular</strong> <strong>Culture</strong>, Malden, MA: Blackwell, 2003. An historical<br />

account of the concept of popular culture.<br />

Strinati, Dominic, An Introduction to Theories of <strong>Popular</strong> <strong>Culture</strong>, London: Routledge,<br />

1995. A clear <strong>and</strong> comprehensive introduction to theories of popular culture.<br />

Tolson, Andrew, Mediations: Text <strong>and</strong> Discourse in Media Studies, London: Edward<br />

Arnold, 1996. An excellent introduction to the study of popular media culture.<br />

Turner, Graeme, British <strong>Cultural</strong> Studies, 2nd edn, London: Routledge, 1996. Still the<br />

best introduction to British cultural studies.<br />

Walton, David, Introducing <strong>Cultural</strong> Studies: Learning Through Practice, London: Sage,<br />

2008. Another excellent introduction to cultural studies: useful, informative <strong>and</strong><br />

funny.


2 The ‘culture <strong>and</strong><br />

civilization’ tradition<br />

The popular culture of the majority has always been a concern of powerful minorities.<br />

Those with political power have always thought it necessary to police the culture of<br />

those without political power, reading it ‘symptomatically’ (see Chapter 6) for signs of<br />

political unrest; reshaping it continually through patronage <strong>and</strong> direct intervention. In<br />

the nineteenth century, however, there is a fundamental change in this relationship.<br />

Those with power lose, for a crucial period, the means to control the culture of the subordinate<br />

classes. When they begin to recover control, it is culture itself, <strong>and</strong> not culture<br />

as a symptom or sign of something else, that becomes, really for the first time, the<br />

actual focus of concern. As we noted at the end of Chapter 1, two factors are crucial to<br />

an underst<strong>and</strong>ing of these changes: industrialization <strong>and</strong> urbanization. Together they<br />

produce other changes that contribute to the making of a popular culture that marks a<br />

decisive break with the cultural relationships of the past.<br />

If we take early nineteenth-century Manchester as our example of the new industrial<br />

urban civilization, certain points become clear. First of all, the town evolved clear lines<br />

of class segregation; second, residential separation was compounded by the new work<br />

relations of industrial capitalism. Third, on the basis of changes in living <strong>and</strong> working<br />

relations, there developed cultural changes. Put very simply, the Manchester working<br />

class was given space to develop an independent culture at some remove from the<br />

direct intervention of the dominant classes. Industrialization <strong>and</strong> urbanization had<br />

redrawn the cultural map. No longer was there a shared common culture, with an additional<br />

culture of the powerful. Now, for the first time in history, there was a separate<br />

culture of the subordinate classes of the urban <strong>and</strong> industrial centres. It was a culture<br />

of two main sources: (i) a culture offered for profit by the new cultural entrepreneurs,<br />

<strong>and</strong> (ii) a culture made by <strong>and</strong> for the political agitation of radical artisans, the<br />

new urban working class <strong>and</strong> middle-class reformers, all described so well by E.P.<br />

Thompson in The Making of the English Working Class (see Chapter 3). Each of these<br />

developments in different ways threatened traditional notions of cultural cohesion <strong>and</strong><br />

social stability. One threatened to weaken authority through the commercial dismantling<br />

of cultural cohesion; the other offered a direct challenge to all forms of political<br />

<strong>and</strong> cultural authority.<br />

These were not developments guaranteed to hearten those who feared for the continuation<br />

of a social order based on power <strong>and</strong> privilege. Such developments, it was<br />

argued, could only mean a weakening of social stability, a destabilizing of the social


18<br />

Chapter 2 The ‘culture <strong>and</strong> civilization’ tradition<br />

order. It marked the beginning of what Benjamin Disraeli would call the ‘two nations’<br />

(Disraeli, 1980), <strong>and</strong> it eventually gave birth to the first political <strong>and</strong> cultural movement<br />

of the new urban working class – Chartism. It is out of this context, <strong>and</strong> its<br />

continuing aftermath, which the political study of popular culture first emerges.<br />

Matthew Arnold<br />

The study of popular culture in the modern age can be said to begin with the work of<br />

Matthew Arnold. In some ways this is surprising as he had very little to say directly<br />

about popular culture. Arnold’s significance is that he inaugurates a tradition, a particular<br />

way of seeing popular culture, a particular way of placing popular culture within<br />

the general field of culture. The tradition has come to be known as the ‘culture <strong>and</strong><br />

civilization’ tradition. My discussion of Arnold’s contribution to the study of popular<br />

culture will focus mainly (but not exclusively) on <strong>Culture</strong> <strong>and</strong> Anarchy (1867–9), the<br />

work that secured, <strong>and</strong> continues to sustain, his reputation as a cultural critic. Arnold<br />

established a cultural agenda that remained dominant in debate from the 1860s until<br />

the 1950s. His significance, therefore, lies not with any body of empirical work, but<br />

with the enormous influence of his general perspective – the Arnoldian perspective –<br />

on popular culture.<br />

For Arnold (1960), culture begins by meaning two things. First <strong>and</strong> foremost, it is a<br />

body of knowledge: in Arnold’s famous phrase, ‘the best that has been thought <strong>and</strong><br />

said in the world’ (6). Secondly, culture is concerned ‘to make reason <strong>and</strong> the will of<br />

God prevail’ (42). It is in the ‘sweetness <strong>and</strong> light’ of the second claim that ‘the moral,<br />

social, <strong>and</strong> beneficial character of culture becomes manifest’ (46). That is, ‘culture . . .<br />

is a study of perfection . . . perfection which consists in becoming something rather<br />

than in having something, in an inward condition of the mind <strong>and</strong> spirit, not in an<br />

outward set of circumstances’ (48). In other words, culture is the endeavour to know<br />

the best <strong>and</strong> to make this knowledge prevail for the good of all humankind. But how<br />

is culture to be attained? According to Arnold, we shall attain it by ‘the disinterested<br />

<strong>and</strong> active use of reading, reflection, <strong>and</strong> observation, in the endeavour to know the<br />

best that can be known’ (179). <strong>Culture</strong>, therefore, no longer consists in two things, but<br />

in three. <strong>Culture</strong> is now the means to know the best that has been thought <strong>and</strong> said, as<br />

well as that body of knowledge <strong>and</strong> the application of that knowledge to the ‘inward<br />

condition of the mind <strong>and</strong> spirit’ (31). There is, however, a fourth aspect to consider:<br />

Arnold insists that culture seeks ‘to minister to the diseased spirit of our time’ (163).<br />

This would appear to be an example of culture’s third aspect. However, we are quickly<br />

told that culture will play its part ‘not so much by lending a h<strong>and</strong> to our friends <strong>and</strong><br />

countrymen in their actual operations for the removal of certain definite evils, but rather<br />

in getting our countrymen to seek culture’ (163–4; my italics). This is Arnold’s fourth<br />

<strong>and</strong> final definition: culture is the seeking of culture, what Arnold calls ‘cultivated inaction’<br />

(163). For Arnold, then, culture is: (i) the ability to know what is best; (ii) what


Matthew Arnold 19<br />

is best; (iii) the mental <strong>and</strong> spiritual application of what is best, <strong>and</strong> (iv) the pursuit of<br />

what is best.<br />

<strong>Popular</strong> culture is never actually defined. However, it becomes clear when reading<br />

through Arnold’s work that the term ‘anarchy’ operates in part as a synonym for popular<br />

culture. Specifically, anarchy/popular culture is used to refer to Arnold’s conception<br />

of the supposedly disruptive nature of working-class lived culture: the political<br />

dangers that he believes to be inevitably concomitant with the entry of the male urban<br />

working class into formal politics in 1867. The upshot of this is that anarchy <strong>and</strong><br />

culture are for Arnold deeply political concepts. The social function of culture is to<br />

police this disruptive presence: the ‘raw <strong>and</strong> uncultivated . . . masses’ (176); ‘the raw<br />

<strong>and</strong> unkindled masses’ (69); ‘our masses . . . quite as raw <strong>and</strong> uncultivated as the<br />

French’ (76); ‘those vast, miserable unmanageable masses of sunken people’ (193).<br />

The problem is working-class lived culture: ‘The rough [i.e. a working-class political<br />

protester] . . . asserting his personal liberty a little, going where he likes, assembling<br />

where he likes, bawling as he likes, hustling as he likes’ (80–1). Again:<br />

the working class . . . raw <strong>and</strong> half developed . . . long lain half hidden amidst its<br />

poverty <strong>and</strong> squalor . . . now issuing from its hiding place to assert an<br />

Englishman’s heaven born privilege of doing as he likes, <strong>and</strong> beginning to perplex<br />

us by marching where it likes, meeting where it likes, bawling what it likes, breaking<br />

what it likes (105; my italics).<br />

The context of all this is the suffrage agitation of 1866–7. Arnold’s employment of<br />

the phrase ‘beginning to perplex us’ is a clear indication of the class nature of his discourse.<br />

His division of society into Barbarians (aristocracy), Philistines (middle class)<br />

<strong>and</strong> Populace (working class) would seem at first sight to defuse the class nature of this<br />

discourse. This seems to be supported by his claim that under all ‘our class divisions,<br />

there is a common basis of human nature’ (ibid.). However, if we examine what<br />

Arnold means by a common basis, we are forced to a different conclusion. If we imagine<br />

the human race existing on an evolutionary continuum with itself at one end<br />

<strong>and</strong> a common ancestor shared with the ape at the other, what Arnold seems to be<br />

suggesting is that the aristocracy <strong>and</strong> middle class are further along the evolutionary<br />

continuum than the working class. This is shown quite clearly in his example of the<br />

common basis of our human nature. He claims that<br />

every time that we snatch up a vehement opinion in ignorance <strong>and</strong> passion, every<br />

time that we long to crush an adversary by sheer violence, every time that we are<br />

envious, every time that we are brutal, every time that we adore mere power or success,<br />

every time that we add our voice to swell a blind clamour against some<br />

unpopular personage, every time that we trample savagely on the fallen [we have]<br />

found in our own bosom the eternal spirit of the Populace (107).<br />

According to Arnold, it takes only a little help from ‘circumstances’ to make this<br />

‘eternal spirit’ triumph in both Barbarian <strong>and</strong> Philistine. <strong>Culture</strong> has two functions in


20<br />

Chapter 2 The ‘culture <strong>and</strong> civilization’ tradition<br />

this scenario. First, it must carefully guide the aristocracy <strong>and</strong> the middle class from<br />

such circumstances. Second, it must bring to the working class, the class in which this<br />

so-called human nature is said to reside, ‘a much wanted principle . . . of authority, to<br />

counteract the tendency to anarchy that seems to be threatening us’ (82). The principle<br />

of authority, as we shall see, is to be found in a strong centralized State.<br />

Why did Arnold think like this? The answer has a great deal to do with the historical<br />

changes witnessed by the nineteenth century. When he recommends culture ‘as the<br />

great help out of our present difficulties’ (6), it is these changes he has in mind. The<br />

‘present difficulties’ have a double context. On the one h<strong>and</strong>, they are the immediate<br />

‘problems’ raised by the granting of the franchise to the male urban working class. On<br />

the other, they are recognition of a historical process that had been in play from at least<br />

the eighteenth century (the development of industrial capitalism). Arnold believed<br />

that the franchise had given power to men as yet uneducated for power. A working<br />

class which has lost ‘the strong feudal habits of subordination <strong>and</strong> deference’ (76) is a<br />

very dangerous working class. It is the function of education to restore a sense of subordination<br />

<strong>and</strong> deference to the class. In short, education would bring to the working<br />

class a ‘culture’ that would in turn remove the temptations of trade unionism, political<br />

agitation <strong>and</strong> cheap entertainment. In short, culture would remove popular culture.<br />

Against such ‘anarchy’, culture recommends the State: ‘We want an authority . . .<br />

culture suggests the idea of the State’ (96). Two factors make the State necessary. First,<br />

the decline of the aristocracy as a centre of authority; second, the rise of democracy.<br />

Together they create a terrain favourable to anarchy. The solution is to occupy this terrain<br />

with a mixture of culture <strong>and</strong> coercion. Arnold’s cultured State is to function to<br />

control <strong>and</strong> curtail the social, economic <strong>and</strong> cultural aspirations of the working class<br />

until the middle class is sufficiently cultured to take on this function itself. The State<br />

will operate in two ways: (i) through coercion to ensure no more Hyde Park riots, <strong>and</strong><br />

(ii) through the instilling of the ‘sweetness <strong>and</strong> light’ of culture.<br />

<strong>Culture</strong> <strong>and</strong> Anarchy informs its reader that ‘education is the road to culture’ (209).<br />

It is, therefore, worth looking briefly at his vision of education. Arnold does not envisage<br />

working-class, middle-class <strong>and</strong> aristocratic students all walking down the same<br />

road to culture. For the aristocracy, education is to accustom it to decline, to banish it<br />

as a class to history. For the working class, education is to civilize it for subordination,<br />

deference <strong>and</strong> exploitation. Arnold saw working-class schools (primary <strong>and</strong> elementary)<br />

as little more than outposts of civilization in a dark continent of workingclass<br />

barbarism: ‘they civilize the neighbourhood where they are placed’ (1973: 39).<br />

According to Arnold, working-class children had to be civilized before they could be<br />

instructed. In a letter to his mother, written in 1862, he writes: ‘the State has an interest<br />

in the primary school as a civilizing agent, even prior to its interest in it as an<br />

instructing agent’ (1896: 187). It was culture’s task to accomplish this. For the middle<br />

class, education was something quite different. Its essential function is to prepare<br />

middle-class children for the power that is to be theirs. Its aim is to convert ‘a middle<br />

class, narrow, ungenial, <strong>and</strong> unattractive [into] a cultured, liberalised, ennobled,<br />

transformed middle class, [one to which the working class] may with joy direct its<br />

aspirations’ (1954: 343).


Matthew Arnold 21<br />

Arnold (1960) called his various proposals, quoting the Duke of Wellington, ‘a<br />

revolution by due course of law’ (97). What it amounts to is a revolution from above,<br />

a revolution to prevent popular revolution from below. It works on the principle that<br />

a reform given is always better than a reform taken, forced or won. <strong>Popular</strong> dem<strong>and</strong>s<br />

are met, but in such a way as to weaken claims for further dem<strong>and</strong>s. It is not that<br />

Arnold did not desire a better society, one with less squalor, less poverty, less ignorance,<br />

etc., but that a better society could never be envisaged as other than a society in<br />

which the new urban middle class were ‘hegemonic’ (see Chapter 4).<br />

Most of what I have said is a roundabout way of saying that the first gr<strong>and</strong> theorist<br />

of popular culture had in fact very little to say about popular culture, except, that is, to<br />

say that it is symptomatic of a profound political disorder. <strong>Culture</strong> is not the main concern<br />

of Arnold’s work; rather the main concern is social order, social authority, won<br />

through cultural subordination <strong>and</strong> deference. Working-class culture is significant to<br />

the extent that it signals evidence of social <strong>and</strong> cultural disorder <strong>and</strong> decline – a breakdown<br />

in social <strong>and</strong> cultural authority. The fact that working-class culture exists at all is<br />

evidence enough of decline <strong>and</strong> disorder. Working-class ‘anarchy’ is to be suppressed<br />

by the harmonious influences of culture – ‘the best that has been thought <strong>and</strong> said in<br />

the world’.<br />

Many of Arnold’s ideas are derived from the Romantic critique of industrialism (see<br />

Williams, 1963). One writer in particular seems especially relevant, Samuel Taylor<br />

Coleridge. Coleridge (1972) distinguishes between ‘civilisation’ (‘a mixed good, if not<br />

far more a corrupting influence’) <strong>and</strong> ‘cultivation’ (‘the harmonious development of<br />

those qualities <strong>and</strong> faculties which characterise our humanity’) (33). To simplify,<br />

Coleridge suggests that civilization refers to the nation as a whole; cultivation is the<br />

property of a small minority, whom he calls the ‘clerisy’. It is the function of the cultivated<br />

clerisy to guide the progress of civilization:<br />

the objects <strong>and</strong> final intention of the whole order being these – preserve the stores,<br />

<strong>and</strong> to guard the treasures, of past civilisation, <strong>and</strong> thus to bind the present to the<br />

past; to perfect <strong>and</strong> add to the same, <strong>and</strong> thus to connect the present with the<br />

future; but especially to diffuse through the whole community, <strong>and</strong> to every native<br />

entitled to its laws <strong>and</strong> rights, that quantity <strong>and</strong> quality of knowledge which was<br />

indispensable both for underst<strong>and</strong>ing of those rights, <strong>and</strong> for the performance of<br />

the duties correspondent (34).<br />

Arnold builds on Coleridge’s ideas. Instead of a clerisy, he writes of ‘aliens’ or ‘the<br />

remnant’. But the purpose is essentially the same: the mobilization of culture to police<br />

the unruly forces of mass society. According to Arnold, history shows that societies<br />

have always been destroyed by ‘the moral failure of the unsound majority’ (1954: 640).<br />

Such a reading of history is hardly likely to inspire much confidence in democracy – let<br />

alone in popular culture. Arnold’s vision is based on a curious paradox; the men <strong>and</strong><br />

women of culture know the best that has been thought <strong>and</strong> said, but for whom are they<br />

preserving these treasures when the majority is unsound <strong>and</strong> has always been, <strong>and</strong> always<br />

will be, unsound? The inescapable answer seems to be: for themselves, a self-perpetuating


22<br />

Chapter 2 The ‘culture <strong>and</strong> civilization’ tradition<br />

cultural elite. All that is required from the rest of us is to recognize our cultural difference<br />

<strong>and</strong> acknowledge our cultural deference. Arnold is clear on this point:<br />

The mass of mankind will never have any ardent zeal for seeing things as they are;<br />

very inadequate ideas will always satisfy them. On these inadequate ideas reposes,<br />

<strong>and</strong> must repose, the general practice of the world. That is as much as saying that<br />

whoever sets himself to see things as they are will find himself one of a very small<br />

circle; but it is only by this small circle resolutely doing its own work that adequate<br />

ideas will ever get current at all (364–5).<br />

And again,<br />

The highly instructed few, <strong>and</strong> not the scantily instructed many, will ever be the<br />

organ to the human race of knowledge <strong>and</strong> truth. Knowledge <strong>and</strong> truth in the full<br />

sense of the words, are not attainable by the great mass of the human race at all<br />

(Arnold, 1960–77: 591).<br />

These are very revealing statements. If the mass of humankind is to be always satisfied<br />

with inadequate ideas, never able to attain truth <strong>and</strong> knowledge, for whom are the<br />

small circle working? And what of the adequate ideas they will make current – current<br />

for whom? For other small circles of elites? Arnold’s small circle would appear to be little<br />

more than a self-perpetuating intellectual elite. If they are never to engage in practical<br />

politics, <strong>and</strong> never to have any real influence on the mass of humankind, what is the<br />

purpose of all the gr<strong>and</strong> humanistic claims to be found scattered throughout Arnold’s<br />

work? It would appear that Arnold has been ensnared by his own elitism: <strong>and</strong> the<br />

working class are destined to remain to wallow in ‘their beer, their gin, <strong>and</strong> their fun’<br />

(1954: 591). However, Arnold does not so much reject practical politics, as leave them<br />

in the safe h<strong>and</strong>s of established authority. Therefore, the only politics that are being<br />

rejected are the politics of protest, the politics of opposition. This is a very stale defence<br />

of the dominant order. Despite this, or perhaps because of it, his influence has been<br />

enormous in that the Arnoldian perspective virtually mapped out the way of thinking<br />

about popular culture <strong>and</strong> cultural politics that dominated the field until the late l950s.<br />

Leavisism<br />

For Matthew Arnold it was in some ways less difficult. I am thinking of the so<br />

much more desperate plight of culture today (Leavis, 2009: 12).<br />

The influence of Arnold on F.R. Leavis is there for all to see. Leavis takes Arnold’s cultural<br />

politics <strong>and</strong> applies them to the supposed ‘cultural crisis’ of the 1930s. According<br />

to Leavis <strong>and</strong> the Leavisites, the twentieth century is marked by an increasing cultural


Leavisism 23<br />

decline. What had been identified by Arnold as a feature of the nineteenth century, it<br />

is argued, had continued <strong>and</strong> been compounded in the twentieth: that is, the increasing<br />

spread of a culture of ‘st<strong>and</strong>ardisation <strong>and</strong> levelling down’ (Leavis <strong>and</strong> Thompson,<br />

1977: 3). It is against this process <strong>and</strong> its results that ‘the citizen . . . must be trained to<br />

discriminate <strong>and</strong> to resist’ (5).<br />

The work of Leavisism spans a period of some forty years. However, the Leavisite<br />

attitude to popular culture was formed in the early 1930s with the publication of three<br />

texts: Mass Civilisation <strong>and</strong> Minority <strong>Culture</strong>, by F.R. Leavis, Fiction <strong>and</strong> the Reading Public,<br />

by Q.D. Leavis <strong>and</strong> <strong>Culture</strong> <strong>and</strong> Environment, by F.R. Leavis <strong>and</strong> Denys Thompson.<br />

Together these form the basis of the Leavisite response to popular culture.<br />

Leavisism is based on the assumption that ‘culture has always been in minority<br />

keeping’ (Leavis <strong>and</strong> Thompson, 1977: 3):<br />

Upon the minority depends our power of profiting by the finest human experience<br />

of the past; they keep alive the subtlest <strong>and</strong> most perishable parts of tradition.<br />

Upon them depend the implicit st<strong>and</strong>ards that order the finer living of an age, the<br />

sense that this is worth more than that, this rather than that is the direction in<br />

which to go, that the centre is here rather than there (5).<br />

What has changed is the status of this minority. No longer can it comm<strong>and</strong> cultural<br />

deference, no longer is its cultural authority unchallenged. Q.D. Leavis (1978) refers to<br />

a situation in which ‘the minority, who had hitherto set the st<strong>and</strong>ard of taste without<br />

any serious challenge’ have experienced a ‘collapse of authority’ (185, 187). Just<br />

as Arnold regretted the passing of ‘the strong feudal habits of subordination <strong>and</strong><br />

deference’ (see previous section), Q.D. Leavis is nostalgic for a time when the masses<br />

exhibited an ‘unquestioning assent to authority’ (191). 5 She quotes Edmund Gosse to<br />

confirm the seriousness of the situation:<br />

One danger which I have long foreseen from the spread of the democratic sentiment,<br />

is that of the traditions of literary taste, the canons of literature, being<br />

reversed with success by a popular vote. Up to the present time, in all parts of the<br />

world, the masses of uneducated or semieducated persons, who form the vast<br />

majority of readers, though they cannot <strong>and</strong> do not appreciate the classics of their<br />

race, have been content to acknowledge their traditional supremacy. Of late there<br />

have seemed to me to be certain signs, especially in America, of a revolt of the mob<br />

against our literary masters. . . . If literature is to be judged by a plebiscite <strong>and</strong> if the<br />

plebs recognises its power, it will certainly by degrees cease to support reputations<br />

which give it no pleasure <strong>and</strong> which it cannot comprehend. The revolution against<br />

taste, once begun, will l<strong>and</strong> us in irreparable chaos (190).<br />

According to Leavis <strong>and</strong> Thompson, what Gosse had only feared had now come to pass:<br />

culture has always been in minority keeping. But the minority now is made<br />

conscious, not merely of an uncongenial, but of a hostile environment. . . .


24<br />

Chapter 2 The ‘culture <strong>and</strong> civilization’ tradition<br />

‘Civilisation’ <strong>and</strong> ‘culture’ are coming to be antithetical terms. It is not merely that<br />

the power <strong>and</strong> the sense of authority are now divorced from culture, but that some<br />

of the most disinterested solicitude for civilisation is apt to be, consciously or<br />

unconsciously, inimical to culture (1977: 26).<br />

Mass civilization <strong>and</strong> its mass culture pose a subversive front, threatening ‘to l<strong>and</strong><br />

us in irreparable chaos’. It is against this threat that Leavisism writes its manifestos, <strong>and</strong><br />

proposes ‘to introduce into schools a training in resistance [to mass culture]’ (Leavis,<br />

1933: 188–9); <strong>and</strong> outside schools, to promote a ‘conscious <strong>and</strong> directed effort . . . [to]<br />

take the form of resistance by an armed <strong>and</strong> active minority’ (Q.D. Leavis, 1978: 270).<br />

The threat of democracy in matters both cultural <strong>and</strong> political is a terrifying thought<br />

for Leavisism. Moreover, according to Q.D. Leavis, ‘The people with power no longer<br />

represent intellectual authority <strong>and</strong> culture’ (191). Like Arnold, she sees the collapse of<br />

traditional authority coming at the same time as the rise of mass democracy. Together<br />

they squeeze the cultured minority <strong>and</strong> produce a terrain favourable for ‘anarchy’.<br />

Leavisism isolates certain key aspects of mass culture for special discussion. <strong>Popular</strong><br />

fiction, for example, is condemned for offering addictive forms of ‘compensation’ <strong>and</strong><br />

‘distraction’:<br />

This form of compensation . . . is the very reverse of recreation, in that it tends, not<br />

to strengthen <strong>and</strong> refresh the addict for living, but to increase his unfitness by<br />

habituating him to weak evasions, to the refusal to face reality at all (Leavis <strong>and</strong><br />

Thompson, 1977: 100).<br />

Q.D. Leavis (1978) refers to such reading as ‘a drug addiction to fiction’ (152), <strong>and</strong><br />

for those readers of romantic fiction it can lead to ‘a habit of fantasying [which] will<br />

lead to maladjustment in actual life’ (54). Self-abuse is one thing, but there is worse:<br />

their addiction ‘helps to make a social atmosphere unfavourable to the aspirations<br />

of the minority. They actually get in the way of genuine feeling <strong>and</strong> responsible thinking’<br />

(74). For those not addicted to popular fiction, there is always the danger of<br />

cinema. Its popularity makes it a very dangerous source of pleasure indeed: ‘they<br />

[films] involve surrender, under conditions of hypnotic receptivity, to the cheapest<br />

emotional appeals, appeals the more insidious because they are associated with a<br />

compellingly vivid illusion of actual life’ (Leavis, 2009: 14). For Q.D. Leavis (1978),<br />

Hollywood films are ‘largely masturbatory’ (165). Although the popular press is<br />

described as ‘the most powerful <strong>and</strong> pervasive de-educator of the public mind’ (Leavis<br />

<strong>and</strong> Thompson, 1977: 138), <strong>and</strong> radio is claimed to be putting an end to critical<br />

thought (Leavis, 2009), it is for advertising, with its ‘unremitting, pervasive, masturbatory<br />

manipulations’ (Leavis <strong>and</strong> Thompson, 1977: 139), that Leavisism saves its most<br />

condemnatory tone.<br />

Advertising, <strong>and</strong> how it is consumed, is Leavisism’s main symptom of cultural<br />

decline. To underst<strong>and</strong> why, we must underst<strong>and</strong> Leavisism’s attitude to language. In<br />

<strong>Culture</strong> <strong>and</strong> Environment, Leavis <strong>and</strong> Thompson state: ‘it should be brought home to<br />

learners that this debasement of language is not merely a matter of words; it is a


debasement of emotional life, <strong>and</strong> the quality of living’ (1977: 4). Advertising, therefore,<br />

is not just blamed for debasing the language, but condemned for debasing the<br />

emotional life of the whole language community, reducing ‘the st<strong>and</strong>ard of living’.<br />

They provide examples for analysis (mostly written by F.R. Leavis himself). The questions<br />

they pose are very revealing of Leavisism’s general attitude. Here is a typical example,<br />

an advert for ‘Two Quakers’ tobacco:<br />

THE TOBACCO OF TYPICAL TWIST<br />

‘Yes, it’s the best I’ve ever smoked. But it’s deuced expensive.’ ‘What’s the tuppence<br />

extra? And anyway, you get it back an’ more. Burns clean <strong>and</strong> slow that’s<br />

the typical twist, gives it the odd look. Cute scientific dodge. You see, they experimented.<br />

. . .’ ‘Oh! cut the cackle, <strong>and</strong> give us another fill. You talk like an advertisement.’<br />

Thereafter peace <strong>and</strong> a pipe of Two Quakers.<br />

They then suggest the following questions for school students in the fifth <strong>and</strong> sixth<br />

forms:<br />

1 Describe the type of person represented.<br />

2 How are you expected to feel towards him?<br />

3 What do you think his attitude would be towards us? How would he behave<br />

in situations where mob passions run high? (16–17)<br />

Two things are remarkable about these questions. First of all, the connection that is<br />

made between the advertisement <strong>and</strong> so-called mob passions. This is an unusual question,<br />

even for students of cultural studies. Second, notice the exclusive ‘we’; <strong>and</strong> note<br />

also how the pronoun attempts to construct membership of a small educated elite.<br />

Other questions operate in much the same way. Here are a few examples:<br />

Describe the kind of reader this passage would please, <strong>and</strong> say why it would<br />

please him. What kind of person can you imagine responding to such an appeal<br />

as this last? What acquaintance would you expect them to have of Shakespeare’s<br />

work <strong>and</strong> what capacity for appreciating it? (40).<br />

Pupils can be asked to recall their own observations of the kind of people they<br />

may have seen visiting ‘shrines’ (51).<br />

In the light of the ‘Gresham Law’, what kind of influence do you expect the<br />

cinema to have on general taste <strong>and</strong> mentality? (114).<br />

What kind of st<strong>and</strong>ards are implied here? What would you judge to be the quality<br />

of the ‘literature’ he reads, <strong>and</strong> the reading he devotes to it? (119).<br />

Why do we wince at the mentality that uses this idiom? (121).<br />

[After describing the cinema as ‘cheapening, debasing, distorting’]: Develop the<br />

discussion of the educational value of cinema as suggested here (144).<br />

Leavisism 25


26<br />

Chapter 2 The ‘culture <strong>and</strong> civilization’ tradition<br />

It is difficult to see how such questions, rather than encouraging ‘discrimination<br />

<strong>and</strong> resistance’, would invite anything other than a critically debilitating <strong>and</strong> selfconfirming<br />

snobbery.<br />

In a temporary escape from the ‘irreparable chaos’ of the present, Leavisism looks back<br />

longingly to a cultural golden age, a mythic rural past, when there existed a shared culture<br />

uncorrupted by commercial interests. The Elizabethan period of Shakespeare’s theatre<br />

is often cited as a time of cultural coherence before the cultural disintegration of<br />

the nineteenth <strong>and</strong> twentieth centuries. F.R. Leavis (1933) writes of Shakespeare belonging<br />

‘to a genuinely national culture, to a community in which it was possible for the<br />

theatre to appeal to the cultivated <strong>and</strong> the populace at the same time’ (216). Q.D.<br />

Leavis (1978), in Fiction <strong>and</strong> the Reading Public, has charted this supposed decline. Her<br />

account of the organic relations between populace <strong>and</strong> cultivated are very revealing: ‘the<br />

masses were receiving their amusement from above. . . . They had to take the same amusements<br />

as their betters. . . . Happily, they had no choice’ (85). According to Q.D. Leavis,<br />

the spectator of Elizabethan drama, though he might not be able to follow the<br />

‘thought’ minutely in the great tragedies, was getting his amusement from the<br />

mind <strong>and</strong> sensibility that produced those passages, from an artist <strong>and</strong> not from<br />

one of his own class. There was then no such complete separation as we have . . .<br />

between the life of the cultivated <strong>and</strong> the life of the generality (264).<br />

What is interesting about their account of the past is what it reveals about their ideal<br />

future. The golden age was not just marked by cultural coherence, but happily for the<br />

Leavisites, a cultural coherence based on authoritarian <strong>and</strong> hierarchical principles. It<br />

was a common culture that gave intellectual stimulation at one end, <strong>and</strong> affective pleasure<br />

at the other. This was a mythic world in which everyone knew their place, knew<br />

their station in life. F.R. Leavis (1984) is insistent ‘that there was in the seventeenth<br />

century, a real culture of the people ...a rich traditional culture ...a positive culture<br />

which has disappeared’ (188–9). Most of this culture was, according to Leavisism,<br />

destroyed by the changes brought about by the Industrial Revolution. The last remnants<br />

of the organic community, however, could still be found in rural communities in<br />

nineteenth-century Engl<strong>and</strong>. He cites the works of George Bourne, Change in the Village<br />

<strong>and</strong> The Wheelwright’s Shop, as evidence of this. 6 In the opening pages of <strong>Culture</strong> <strong>and</strong><br />

Environment, F.R. Leavis <strong>and</strong> Thompson (1977) offer a reminder of what had been lost:<br />

What we have lost is the organic community with the living culture it embodied.<br />

Folk songs, folk dances, Cotswold cottages <strong>and</strong> h<strong>and</strong>icraft products are signs <strong>and</strong><br />

expressions of something more: an art of life, a way of living, ordered <strong>and</strong> patterned,<br />

involving social arts, codes of intercourse <strong>and</strong> a responsive adjustment,<br />

growing out of immemorial experience, to the natural environment <strong>and</strong> the<br />

rhythm of the year (1–2).<br />

They also claim that the quality of work has also deteriorated with the loss of the<br />

organic community. The growing importance placed on leisure is seen as a sign of this


Leavisism 27<br />

loss. Whereas in the past a worker lived in his or her work, he or she now works in<br />

order to live outside his or her work. But as a result of industrialization, the experience<br />

of work has deteriorated to such an extent that workers are actually ‘incapacitated by<br />

their work’ (69). Therefore, instead of recreation (re-creating what is lost in work),<br />

leisure provides workers with only ‘decreation’ (a compounding of the loss experienced<br />

through work). Given such a situation, it is little wonder that people turn to mass<br />

culture for compensation <strong>and</strong> passive distraction; the drug habit develops <strong>and</strong> they<br />

become junkies addicted to ‘substitute living’. A world of rural rhythms has been lost<br />

to the monotony <strong>and</strong> mediocrity of ‘suburbanism’ (99). Whereas in the organic community<br />

everyday culture was a constant support to the health of the individual, in mass<br />

civilization one must make a conscious <strong>and</strong> directed effort to avoid the unhealthy<br />

influence of everyday culture. The Leavisites fail to mention, as Williams (1963)<br />

remarks, ‘the penury, the petty tyranny, the disease <strong>and</strong> mortality, the ignorance <strong>and</strong><br />

frustrated intelligence which were also among its ingredients’ (253). What we are presented<br />

with is not a historical account, but a literary myth to draw attention to the<br />

nature of our supposed loss: ‘the memory of the old order must be the chief incitement<br />

towards a new’ (Leavis <strong>and</strong> Thompson, 1977: 97). But, although the organic community<br />

is lost, it is still possible to get access to its values <strong>and</strong> st<strong>and</strong>ards by reading works<br />

of great literature. Literature is a treasury embodying all that is to be valued in human<br />

experience. Unfortunately, literature as the jewel in the crown of culture, has, like<br />

culture, lost its authority. Leavisism, as noted earlier, made plans to remedy this by dispatching<br />

cultural missionaries, a small select b<strong>and</strong> of literary intellectuals, to establish<br />

outposts of culture within universities to maintain the literary/cultural tradition <strong>and</strong><br />

encourage its ‘continuous collaborative renewal’ (Leavis, 1972: 27); <strong>and</strong> into schools<br />

to arm students to wage war against the general barbarism of mass culture <strong>and</strong> mass<br />

civilization. The re-establishment of literature’s authority would not of course herald<br />

the return of the organic community, but it would keep under control the expansion<br />

of the influence of mass culture <strong>and</strong> thus preserve <strong>and</strong> maintain the continuity of<br />

Engl<strong>and</strong>’s cultural tradition. In short, it would help maintain <strong>and</strong> produce an ‘educated<br />

public’, who would continue the Arnoldian project of keeping in circulation ‘the best<br />

that has been thought <strong>and</strong> said’ (now more or less reduced to the reading of works of<br />

great literature).<br />

It is very easy to be critical of the Leavisite approach to popular culture. But, as<br />

Bennett (1982b) points out,<br />

Even as late as the mid fifties . . . ‘Leavisism’ [provided] the only developed intellectual<br />

terrain on which it was possible to engage with the study of popular culture.<br />

Historically, of course, the work produced by the ‘Leavisites’ was of seminal<br />

importance, constituting the first attempt to apply to popular forms techniques of<br />

literary analysis previously reserved for ‘serious’ works. . . . Perhaps more importantly,<br />

the general impact of ‘Leavisism’ at least as scathing in its criticisms of established<br />

‘high’ <strong>and</strong> ‘middle brow’ culture as of popular forms tended to unsettle the<br />

prevailing canons of aesthetic judgement <strong>and</strong> evaluation with, in the long term,<br />

quite radical <strong>and</strong> often unforeseen consequences (5–6).


28<br />

Chapter 2 The ‘culture <strong>and</strong> civilization’ tradition<br />

In Chapter 3 we shall begin to consider some of these radical <strong>and</strong> often unforeseen<br />

consequences as they appear in the work of Richard Hoggart <strong>and</strong> Raymond Williams.<br />

Mass culture in America: the post-war debate<br />

In the first fifteen or so years following the end of the Second World War, American<br />

intellectuals engaged in a debate about so-called mass culture. Andrew Ross (1989)<br />

sees ‘mass’ as ‘one of the key terms that governs the official distinction between<br />

American/UnAmerican’ (42). He argues that, ‘[t]he history behind this official distinction<br />

is in many ways the history of the formation of the modern national culture’<br />

(ibid.). Following the Second World War, America experienced the temporary success<br />

of a cultural <strong>and</strong> political consensus – supposedly based on liberalism, pluralism <strong>and</strong><br />

classlessness. Until its collapse in the agitation for black civil rights, the formation<br />

of the counterculture, the opposition to America’s war in Vietnam, the women’s liberation<br />

movement, <strong>and</strong> the campaign for gay <strong>and</strong> lesbian rights, it was a consensus<br />

dependent to a large extent on the cultural authority of American intellectuals. As Ross<br />

points out: ‘For perhaps the first time in American history, intellectuals, as a social<br />

grouping, had the opportunity to recognize themselves as national agents of cultural,<br />

moral, <strong>and</strong> political leadership’ (43). This newly found significance was in part due to<br />

‘the intense, <strong>and</strong> quite public, debate about “mass culture” that occupied intellectuals<br />

for almost fifteen years, until the late fifties’ (ibid.). Ross spends most of his time relating<br />

the debate to the Cold War ideology of ‘containment’: the need to maintain a<br />

healthy body politic both within (from the dangers of cultural impoverishment) <strong>and</strong><br />

without (from the dangers of Soviet communism). He identifies three positions in the<br />

debate:<br />

1. An aesthetic–liberal position that bemoans the fact that given the choice the<br />

majority of the population choose so-called second- <strong>and</strong> third-rate cultural texts <strong>and</strong><br />

practices in preference to the texts <strong>and</strong> practices of high culture.<br />

2. The corporate–liberal or progressive–evolutionist position that claims that<br />

popular culture serves a benign function of socializing people into the pleasures of<br />

consumption in the new capitalist–consumerist society.<br />

3. The radical or socialist position which views mass culture as a form of, or means to,<br />

social control.<br />

Towards the end of the 1950s, the debate became increasingly dominated by the first<br />

two positions. This reflected in part the growing McCarthyite pressure to renounce anything<br />

resembling a socialist analysis. Given limited space, I will focus only on the<br />

debate about the health of the body politic within. In order to underst<strong>and</strong> the debate<br />

one publication is essential reading – the anthology Mass <strong>Culture</strong>: The <strong>Popular</strong> Arts in<br />

America, published in 1957. Reading the many contributions, one quickly gets a sense


Mass culture in America: the post-war debate 29<br />

of the parameters of the debate – what is at stake in the debate, <strong>and</strong> who are the principal<br />

participants.<br />

Bernard Rosenberg (co-editor with David Manning White) argues that the material<br />

wealth <strong>and</strong> well-being of American society are being undermined by the dehumanizing<br />

effects of mass culture. His greatest anxiety is that, ‘At worst, mass culture threatens<br />

not merely to cretinize our taste, but to brutalize our senses while paving the way to<br />

totalitarianism’ (1957: 9). He claims that mass culture is not American by nature, or<br />

by example, nor is it the inevitable culture of democracy. Mass culture, according to<br />

Rosenberg, is nowhere more widespread than in the Soviet Union. Its author is not<br />

capitalism, but technology. Therefore America cannot be held responsible for its emergence<br />

or for its persistence. White (1957) makes a similar point but for a different purpose.<br />

‘The critics of mass culture’ (13), White observes, ‘take an exceedingly dim view<br />

of contemporary American society’ (14). His defence of American (mass) culture is to<br />

compare it with aspects of the popular culture of the past. He maintains that critics<br />

romanticize the past in order to castigate the present. He condemns those ‘who discuss<br />

American culture as if they were holding a dead vermin in their h<strong>and</strong>s’ (ibid.), <strong>and</strong> yet<br />

forget the sadistic <strong>and</strong> brutal reality of animal baiting that was the everyday culture in<br />

which Shakespeare’s plays first appeared. His point is that every period in history has<br />

produced ‘men who preyed upon the ignorance <strong>and</strong> insecurities of the largest part of<br />

the populace . . . <strong>and</strong> therefore we need not be so shocked that such men exist today’<br />

(ibid.). The second part of his defence consists of cataloguing the extent to which high<br />

culture flourishes in America: for example, Shakespeare on TV, record figures for book<br />

borrowing from libraries, a successful tour by the Sadler’s Wells Ballet, the fact that<br />

more people attend classical music events than attend baseball games, the increasing<br />

number of symphony orchestras.<br />

A key figure in the debate is Dwight Macdonald. In a very influential essay, ‘A theory<br />

of mass culture’, he attacks mass culture on a number of fronts. First of all, mass<br />

culture undermines the vitality of high culture. It is a parasitic culture, feeding on high<br />

culture, while offering nothing in return.<br />

Folk art grew from below. It was a spontaneous, autochthonous expression of the<br />

people, shaped by themselves, pretty much without the benefit of High <strong>Culture</strong>, to<br />

suit their own needs. Mass <strong>Culture</strong> is imposed from above. It is fabricated by technicians<br />

hired by businessmen; its audience are passive consumers, their participation<br />

limited to the choice between buying <strong>and</strong> not buying. The Lords of kitsch, in<br />

short, exploit the cultural needs of the masses in order to make a profit <strong>and</strong>/or to<br />

maintain their class-rule . . . in Communist countries, only the second purpose<br />

obtains. Folk art was the people’s own institution, their private little garden walled<br />

off from the great formal park of their masters’ High <strong>Culture</strong>. But Mass <strong>Culture</strong><br />

breaks down the wall, integrating the masses into a debased form of High <strong>Culture</strong><br />

<strong>and</strong> thus becoming an instrument of political domination (1998: 23).<br />

Like other contributors to the debate, Macdonald is quick to deny the claim that<br />

America is the l<strong>and</strong> of mass culture: ‘the fact is that the U.S.S.R. is even more a l<strong>and</strong>


30<br />

Chapter 2 The ‘culture <strong>and</strong> civilization’ tradition<br />

of Mass <strong>Culture</strong> than is the U.S.A’ (ibid.). This fact, he claims, is often missed by<br />

critics who focus only on the ‘form’ of mass culture in the Soviet Union. But it is mass<br />

culture (not folk culture: the expression of the people; nor high culture: the expression<br />

of the individual artist); <strong>and</strong> it differs from American mass culture in that ‘its quality is<br />

even lower’, <strong>and</strong> in that ‘it exploits rather than satisfies the cultural needs of the masses<br />

. . . for political rather than commercial reasons’ (24). In spite of its superiority to<br />

Soviet mass culture, American mass culture still represents a problem (‘acute in the<br />

United States’): ‘The eruption of the masses onto the political stage [produced] . . .<br />

disastrous cultural results’ (ibid.). This problem has been compounded by the absence<br />

of ‘a clearly defined cultural elite’ (ibid.). If one existed, the masses could have mass<br />

culture <strong>and</strong> the elite could have high culture. However, without a cultural elite,<br />

America is under threat from a Gresham’s Law of culture: the bad will drive out the<br />

good; the result will be not just a homogeneous culture but a ‘homogenized culture . . .<br />

that threatens to engulf everything in its spreading ooze’ (27), dispersing the cream<br />

from the top <strong>and</strong> turning the American people into infantile masses. His conclusions<br />

are pessimistic to say the least: ‘far from Mass <strong>Culture</strong> getting better, we will be lucky if<br />

it doesn’t get worse’ (29).<br />

The analysis changes again as we move from the disillusioned ex-Trotskyism of<br />

Macdonald to the liberalism of Ernest van den Haag (1957), who suggests that mass<br />

culture is the inevitable outcome of mass society <strong>and</strong> mass production:<br />

The mass produced article need not aim low, but it must aim at an average of<br />

tastes. In satisfying all (or at least many) individual tastes in some respects, it violates<br />

each in other respects. For there are so far no average persons having average<br />

tastes. Averages are but statistical composites. A mass produced article, while<br />

reflecting nearly everybody’s taste to some extent, is unlikely to embody anybody’s<br />

taste fully. This is one source of the sense of violation which is rationalized vaguely<br />

in theories about deliberate debasement of taste (512).<br />

He also suggests another reason: the temptations offered by mass culture to high<br />

culture. Two factors must be particularly tempting: (i) the financial rewards of mass<br />

culture, <strong>and</strong> (ii) the potentially enormous audience. He uses Dante as an illustration.<br />

Although Dante may have suffered religious <strong>and</strong> political pressures, he was not<br />

tempted to shape his work to make it appeal to an average of tastes. Had he been<br />

‘tempted to write for Sports Illustrated’ or had he been asked ‘to condense his work for<br />

Reader’s Digest’ or had he been given a contract ‘to adapt it for the movies’, would he<br />

have been able to maintain his aesthetic <strong>and</strong> moral st<strong>and</strong>ards? Dante was fortunate; his<br />

talent was never really tempted to stray from the true path of creativity: ‘there were no<br />

alternatives to being as good a writer as his talent permitted’ (521).<br />

It is not so much that mass taste has deteriorated, van den Haag argues, but that<br />

mass taste has become more important to the cultural producers in Western societies.<br />

Like White, he notes the plurality of cultural texts <strong>and</strong> practices consumed in America.<br />

However, he also notes the way in which high culture <strong>and</strong> folk culture are absorbed<br />

into mass culture, <strong>and</strong> are consequently consumed as mass culture: ‘it is not new nor


disastrous that few people read classics. It is new that so many people misread them’<br />

(528). He cannot help in the end declaring that mass culture is a drug which ‘lessens<br />

people’s capacity to experience life itself’ (529). Mass culture is ultimately a sign of<br />

impoverishment. It marks the de-individualization of life: an endless search after what<br />

Freud calls ‘substitute gratifications’. 7 The trouble with substitute gratifications, according<br />

to the mass culture critique, is that they shut out ‘real gratifications’ (532–5). This<br />

leads van den Haag to suggest that the consumption of mass culture is a form of repression;<br />

the empty texts <strong>and</strong> practices of mass culture are consumed to fill an emptiness<br />

within, which grows ever more empty the more the empty texts <strong>and</strong> practices of mass<br />

culture are consumed. The operation of this cycle of repression makes it increasingly<br />

impossible to experience ‘real gratification’. The result is a nightmare in which the cultural<br />

‘masturbator’ or the ‘addict’ of mass culture is trapped in a cycle of non-fulfilment,<br />

moving aimlessly between boredom <strong>and</strong> distraction:<br />

Though the bored person hungers for things to happen to him, the disheartening<br />

fact is that when they do he empties them of the very meaning he unconsciously<br />

yearns for by using them as distractions. In popular culture even the second coming<br />

would become just another ‘barren’ thrill to be watched on television till<br />

Milton Berle comes on (535).<br />

Van den Haag differs from the ‘cultural nostalgics’, who use romanticized versions<br />

of the past to condemn the present, in his uncertainty about the past. He knows that<br />

‘popular culture impoverishes life without leading to contentment. But whether “the<br />

mass of men” felt better or worse without mass production techniques of which popular<br />

culture is an ineluctable part, we shall never know’ (536). Edward Shils (1978) has<br />

none of van den Haag’s uncertainty. Moreover, he knows that when van den Haag says<br />

that industry has impoverished life he is talking nonsense:<br />

The present pleasures of the working <strong>and</strong> lower middle class are not worthy of profound<br />

aesthetic, moral or intellectual esteem but they are surely not inferior to the<br />

villainous things which gave pleasure to their European ancestors from the Middle<br />

Ages to the nineteenth century (35).<br />

Shils rejects completely<br />

Mass culture in America: the post-war debate 31<br />

the utterly erroneous idea that the twentieth century is a period of severe intellectual<br />

deterioration <strong>and</strong> that this alleged deterioration is a product of a mass culture.<br />

. . . Indeed, it would be far more correct to assert that mass culture is now less damaging<br />

to the lower classes than the dismal <strong>and</strong> harsh existence of earlier centuries<br />

had ever been (36).<br />

As far as Shils can see the problem is not mass culture, but the response of intellectuals<br />

to mass culture. In similar fashion, D.W. Brogan (1978), whilst in agreement<br />

with much of Macdonald’s argument, remains more optimistic. He believes that


32<br />

Chapter 2 The ‘culture <strong>and</strong> civilization’ tradition<br />

Macdonald in being ‘so grimly critical of the present America, is too kind to the past in<br />

America <strong>and</strong> to the past <strong>and</strong> present in Europe’ (191). In this way, Macdonald’s pessimism<br />

about the present is only sustained by his overly optimistic view of the past. In<br />

short, he ‘exaggerates . . . the bad eminence of the United States’ (193).<br />

In ‘The middle against both ends’, Leslie Fiedler (1957), unlike most other contributors<br />

to the debate, claims that mass culture<br />

is a peculiarly American phenomenon. ...I do not mean . . . that it is found only<br />

in the United States, but that wherever it is found, it comes first from us, <strong>and</strong> is still<br />

to be discovered in fully developed form only among us. Our experience along<br />

these lines is, in this sense, a preview for the rest of the world of what must follow<br />

the inevitable dissolution of the older aristocratic cultures (539).<br />

For Fiedler, mass culture is popular culture that ‘refuses to know its place’. As he<br />

explains,<br />

contemporary vulgar culture is brutal <strong>and</strong> disturbing: the quasi spontaneous expression<br />

of the uprooted <strong>and</strong> culturally dispossessed inhabitants of anonymous cities,<br />

contriving mythologies which reduce to manageable form the threat of science, the<br />

horror of unlimited war, the general spread of corruption in a world where the<br />

social bases of old loyalties <strong>and</strong> heroisms have long been destroyed (540).<br />

Fiedler poses the question: What is wrong with American mass culture? He knows that<br />

for some critics, at home <strong>and</strong> abroad, the fact that it is American is enough reason to<br />

condemn it. But, for Fiedler, the inevitability of the American experience makes the<br />

argument meaningless; that is, unless those who support the argument are also against<br />

industrialization, mass education <strong>and</strong> democracy. He sees America ‘in the midst of a<br />

strange two-front class war’. In the centre is ‘the genteel middling mind’, at the top is<br />

‘the ironical-aristocratic sensibility’, <strong>and</strong> at the bottom is ‘the brutal-populist mentality’<br />

(545). The attack on popular culture is a symptom of timidity <strong>and</strong> an expression<br />

of conformity in matters of culture: ‘the fear of the vulgar is the obverse of the fear<br />

of excellence, <strong>and</strong> both are aspects of the fear of difference: symptoms of a drive for<br />

conformity on the level of the timid, sentimental, mindless-bodiless genteel’ (547).<br />

The genteel middling mind wants cultural equality on its own terms. This is not the<br />

Leavisite dem<strong>and</strong> for cultural deference, but an insistence on an end to cultural difference.<br />

Therefore, Fiedler sees American mass culture as hierarchical <strong>and</strong> pluralist, rather<br />

than homogenized <strong>and</strong> levelling. Moreover, he celebrates it as such.<br />

Shils (1978) suggests a similar model – American culture is divided into three<br />

cultural ‘classes’, each embodying different versions of the cultural: ‘“superior” or<br />

“refined” culture’ at the top, ‘“mediocre” culture’ in the middle, <strong>and</strong> ‘“brutal” culture’<br />

at the bottom (206). Mass society has changed the cultural map, reducing the<br />

significance of ‘superior or refined culture’, <strong>and</strong> increasing the importance of both<br />

‘mediocre’ <strong>and</strong> ‘brutal’ (209). However, Shils does not see this as a totally negative<br />

development: ‘It is an indication of a crude aesthetic awakening in classes which


previously accepted what was h<strong>and</strong>ed down to them or who had practically no aesthetic<br />

expression <strong>and</strong> reception’ (ibid.). Like Fiedler, Shils does not shy away from the<br />

claim that America is the home of mass culture. He calls America ‘that most massive of<br />

all mass societies’ (218). But he remains optimistic: ‘As a matter of fact, the vitality, the<br />

individuality, which may rehabilitate our intellectual public will probably be the fruits<br />

of the liberation of powers <strong>and</strong> possibilities inherent in mass societies’ (226). As Ross<br />

(1989) suggests, in Fiedler’s essay, <strong>and</strong> in the work of other writers in the 1950s <strong>and</strong><br />

early 1960s,<br />

the concept of ‘class’ makes a conditional return after its years in the intellectual<br />

wilderness. This time, however, class analysis returns not to draw attention to<br />

conflicts <strong>and</strong> contradictions, as had been the case in the thirties, but rather to serve<br />

a hegemonic moment in which a consensus was being established about the non<br />

antagonistic coexistence of different political conceptions of the world. <strong>Cultural</strong><br />

classes could exist as long as they kept themselves to themselves (58).<br />

<strong>Cultural</strong> choice <strong>and</strong> consumption become both the sign of class belonging <strong>and</strong> the<br />

mark of class difference. However, instead of class antagonism, there is only plurality<br />

of consumer choice within a general consensus of the dangers within <strong>and</strong> the dangers<br />

without. In short, the debate about mass culture had become the terrain on which to<br />

construct the Cold War ideology of containment. After all, as Melvin Tumin (1957)<br />

points out, ‘America <strong>and</strong> Americans have available to them the resources, both of mind<br />

<strong>and</strong> matter, to build <strong>and</strong> support the finest culture the world has ever known’ (550).<br />

The fact that this has not yet occurred does not dismay Tumin; for him it simply<br />

prompts the question: How do we make it happen? For the answer, he looks to<br />

American intellectuals, who ‘never before have . . . been so well placed in situations<br />

where they can function as intellectuals’ (ibid.), <strong>and</strong> through the debate on mass<br />

culture, to take the lead in helping to build the finest popular culture the world has ever<br />

known.<br />

The culture of other people<br />

The culture of other people 33<br />

It is easy to be critical of the ‘culture <strong>and</strong> civilization’ tradition’s approach to popular<br />

culture. Given the recent developments in the field of cultural theory, it is almost<br />

enough to present a narrative of its approach to condemn it to populist disapproval.<br />

However, it must be remembered that from a historical point of view, the tradition’s<br />

work is absolutely foundational to the project of the study of popular culture in British<br />

cultural studies. Furthermore, the impact of the tradition is difficult to overestimate: for<br />

more than a century it was undoubtedly the dominant paradigm in cultural analysis.<br />

Indeed, it could be argued that it still forms a kind of repressed ‘common sense’ in certain<br />

areas of British <strong>and</strong> American academic <strong>and</strong> non-academic life.


34<br />

Chapter 2 The ‘culture <strong>and</strong> civilization’ tradition<br />

Although the ‘culture <strong>and</strong> civilization’ tradition, especially in its Leavisite form, created<br />

an educational space for the study of popular culture, there is also a real sense in<br />

which this approach to popular culture ‘actively impeded its development as an area<br />

of study’ (Bennett, 1982b: 6). The principal problem is its working assumption that<br />

popular culture always represents little more than an example of cultural decline <strong>and</strong><br />

potential political disorder. Given this assumption, theoretical research <strong>and</strong> empirical<br />

investigation continued to confirm what it always expected to find.<br />

It was an assumption of the theory that there was something wrong with popular<br />

culture <strong>and</strong>, of course, once that assumption had been made, all the rest followed:<br />

one found what one was looking for – signs of decay <strong>and</strong> deterioration – precisely<br />

because the theory required that these be found. In short, the only role offered to<br />

the products of popular culture was that of fall guy (ibid.).<br />

As we have noted, popular culture is condemned for many things. However, as<br />

Bennett points out, the ‘culture <strong>and</strong> civilization’ tradition is not noted for its detailed<br />

analyses of the texts <strong>and</strong> practices of popular culture. Instead, it looked down from the<br />

splendid heights of high culture to what it saw as the commercial wastel<strong>and</strong>s of popular<br />

culture, seeking only confirmation of cultural decline, cultural difference, <strong>and</strong> the<br />

need for cultural deference, regulation <strong>and</strong> control. It<br />

was very much a discourse of the ‘cultured’ about the culture of those without ‘culture’.<br />

. . . In short, popular culture was approached from a distance <strong>and</strong> gingerly,<br />

held at arm’s length by outsiders who clearly lacked any sense of fondness for or<br />

participation in the forms they were studying. It was always the culture of ‘other<br />

people’ that was at issue (ibid.).<br />

The anxieties of the ‘culture <strong>and</strong> civilization’ tradition are anxieties about social<br />

<strong>and</strong> cultural extension: how to deal with challenges to cultural <strong>and</strong> social exclusivity.<br />

As the nineteenth century receded, <strong>and</strong> those traditionally outside ‘culture’ <strong>and</strong><br />

‘society’ dem<strong>and</strong>ed inclusion, strategies were adopted to incorporate <strong>and</strong> to exclude.<br />

Acceptance brought into being ‘high society’ <strong>and</strong> ‘high culture’, to be distinguished<br />

from society <strong>and</strong> culture or, better still, mass society <strong>and</strong> mass culture. In short, it is<br />

a tradition that dem<strong>and</strong>ed, <strong>and</strong> expected, two responses from the ‘masses’ (see<br />

Photo 2.1) – cultural <strong>and</strong> social difference <strong>and</strong> cultural <strong>and</strong> social deference. As we<br />

shall see (in Chapters 9 <strong>and</strong> 10), some of the debates around postmodernism may be<br />

in part little more than the latest struggle for inclusion in, <strong>and</strong> exclusion from, <strong>Culture</strong><br />

(with a capital C), which ultimately is less about texts, <strong>and</strong> much more about people<br />

<strong>and</strong> their everyday lived cultures.


Photo 2.1 A day trip to Blackpool in the early 1950s. There are ...no masses;<br />

there are only ways of seeing [other] people as masses (Raymond<br />

Williams, 1963: 289).<br />

Further reading<br />

Further reading 35<br />

Storey, John (ed.), <strong>Cultural</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Popular</strong> <strong>Culture</strong>: A Reader, 4th edition, Harlow:<br />

Pearson Education, 2009. This is the companion volume to this book. It contains<br />

examples of most of the work discussed here. This book <strong>and</strong> the companion Reader<br />

are supported by an interactive website (www.pearsoned.co.uk/storey). The website<br />

has links to other useful sites <strong>and</strong> electronic resources.<br />

Baldick, Chris, The Social Mission of English 1848–1932, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1983.<br />

Contains interesting <strong>and</strong> informed chapters on Arnold <strong>and</strong> Leavisism.<br />

Bilan, R.P., The Literary Criticism of F.R. Leavis, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,<br />

1979. Although mostly on Leavis as a literary critic, it contains some useful material<br />

on his attitude to high <strong>and</strong> popular culture.<br />

Bramson, Leon, The Political Context of Sociology, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University<br />

Press, 1961. Contains an illuminating chapter on the mass culture debate in America.<br />

Gans, Herbert J., <strong>Popular</strong> <strong>Culture</strong> <strong>and</strong> High <strong>Culture</strong>: An Analysis <strong>and</strong> Evaluation of Taste,<br />

New York: Basic Books, 1974. The book is a late contribution to the mass culture<br />

debate in America. It presents a compelling argument in defence of cultural pluralism.


36<br />

Chapter 2 The ‘culture <strong>and</strong> civilization’ tradition<br />

Johnson, Lesley, The <strong>Cultural</strong> Critics, London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1979. Contains<br />

useful chapters on Arnold <strong>and</strong> on F.R. Leavis.<br />

Mulhern, Francis, The Moment of Scrutiny, London: New Left Books, 1979. Perhaps the<br />

classic account of Leavisism.<br />

Ross, Andrew, No Respect: Intellectuals <strong>and</strong> <strong>Popular</strong> <strong>Culture</strong>, London: Routledge, 1989.<br />

An interesting book, with a useful chapter on the mass culture debate in America.<br />

Trilling, Lionel, Matthew Arnold, London: Unwin University Press, 1949. Still the best<br />

introduction to Arnold.<br />

Waites, Bernard, Tony Bennett <strong>and</strong> Graham Martin (eds), <strong>Popular</strong> <strong>Culture</strong>: Past <strong>and</strong><br />

Present, London: Croom Helm, 1982. A collection of essays on different examples<br />

of popular culture. Chapters 1, 4 <strong>and</strong> 6 address popular culture <strong>and</strong> the historical<br />

context that gave rise to the anxieties of the ‘culture <strong>and</strong> civilization’ tradition.<br />

Williams, Raymond, <strong>Culture</strong> <strong>and</strong> Society, Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1963. The seminal<br />

book on the ‘culture <strong>and</strong> civilization’ tradition: includes chapters on Arnold <strong>and</strong><br />

F.R. Leavis.


3 <strong>Cultural</strong>ism<br />

In this chapter I will consider the work produced by Richard Hoggart, Raymond<br />

Williams, E.P. Thompson, <strong>and</strong> Stuart Hall <strong>and</strong> Paddy Whannel in the late 1950s <strong>and</strong><br />

early 1960s. This body of work, despite certain differences between its authors, constitutes<br />

the founding texts of culturalism. As Hall (1978) was later to observe, ‘Within<br />

cultural studies in Britain, “culturalism” has been the most vigorous, indigenous<br />

str<strong>and</strong>’ (19). The chapter will end with a brief discussion of the institutionalization of<br />

culturalism at the Centre for Contemporary <strong>Cultural</strong> Studies.<br />

Both Hoggart <strong>and</strong> Williams develop positions in response to Leavisism. As we noted<br />

in Chapter 2, the Leavisites opened up in Britain an educational space for the study of<br />

popular culture. Hoggart <strong>and</strong> Williams occupy this space in ways that challenge many<br />

of the basic assumptions of Leavisism, whilst also sharing some of these assumptions.<br />

It is this contradictory mixture – looking back to the ‘culture <strong>and</strong> civilization’ tradition,<br />

whilst at the same time moving forward to culturalism <strong>and</strong> the foundations of the<br />

cultural studies approach to popular culture – which has led The Uses of Literacy, <strong>Culture</strong><br />

<strong>and</strong> Society <strong>and</strong> The Long Revolution to be called both texts of the ‘break’ <strong>and</strong> examples<br />

of ‘left-Leavisism’ (Hall, 1996a).<br />

Thompson, on the other h<strong>and</strong>, would describe his work, then <strong>and</strong> always, as<br />

Marxist. The term ‘culturalism’ was coined to describe his work, <strong>and</strong> the work of<br />

Hoggart <strong>and</strong> Williams, by one of the former directors of the Centre for Contemporary<br />

<strong>Cultural</strong> Studies, Richard Johnson (1979). Johnson uses the term to indicate the presence<br />

of a body of theoretical concerns connecting the work of the three theorists. Each,<br />

in his different way, breaks with key aspects of the tradition he inherits. Hoggart <strong>and</strong><br />

Williams break with Leavisism; Thompson breaks with mechanistic <strong>and</strong> economistic<br />

versions of Marxism. What unites them is an approach which insists that by analysing<br />

the culture of a society – the textual forms <strong>and</strong> documented practices of a culture – it<br />

is possible to reconstitute the patterned behaviour <strong>and</strong> constellations of ideas shared<br />

by the men <strong>and</strong> women who produce <strong>and</strong> consume the texts <strong>and</strong> practices of that society.<br />

It is a perspective that stresses ‘human agency’, the active production of culture,<br />

rather than its passive consumption. Although not usually included in accounts of the<br />

formation of culturalism out of left-Leavisism, Hall <strong>and</strong> Whannel’s The <strong>Popular</strong> Arts is<br />

included here because of its classic left-Leavisite focus on popular culture. Taken<br />

together as a body of work, the contributions of Hoggart, Williams, Thompson, <strong>and</strong><br />

Hall <strong>and</strong> Whannel, clearly mark the emergence of what is now known as the cultural


38<br />

Chapter 3 <strong>Cultural</strong>ism<br />

studies approach to popular culture. The institutional home of these developments<br />

was, especially in the 1970s <strong>and</strong> early 1980s, the Centre for Contemporary <strong>Cultural</strong><br />

Studies, at the University of Birmingham (see Green, 1996).<br />

Richard Hoggart: The Uses of Literacy<br />

The Uses of Literacy is divided into two parts: ‘An “older” order’, describing the workingclass<br />

culture of Hoggart’s childhood in the 1930s; <strong>and</strong> ‘Yielding place to new’, describing<br />

a traditional working-class culture under threat from the new forms of mass entertainment<br />

of the 1950s. Dividing the book in this way in itself speaks volumes about<br />

the perspective taken <strong>and</strong> the conclusions expected. On the one h<strong>and</strong>, we have the<br />

traditional ‘lived culture’ of the 1930s. On the other, we have the cultural decline of the<br />

1950s. Hoggart is in fact aware that during the course of writing the book, ‘nostalgia<br />

was colouring the material in advance: I have done what I could to remove its effects’<br />

(1990: 17). He is also aware that the division he makes between the ‘older’ <strong>and</strong> the<br />

‘new’, underplays the amount of continuity between the two. It should also be noted<br />

that his evidence for the ‘older’ depends, not on ‘invoking some rather mistily conceived<br />

pastoral tradition the better to assault the present, [but] to a large extent on<br />

memories of my childhood about twenty years ago’ (23, 24). His evidence for the cultural<br />

decline represented by the popular culture of the 1950s is material gathered as a<br />

university lecturer <strong>and</strong> researcher. In short, the ‘older’ is based on personal experience;<br />

the ‘new’ on academic research. This is a significant <strong>and</strong> informing distinction.<br />

It is also worth noting something about Hoggart’s project that is often misunderstood.<br />

What he attacks is not a ‘moral’ decline in the working class as such, but what<br />

he perceives as a decline in the ‘moral seriousness’ of the culture provided for the working<br />

class. He repeats on a number of occasions his confidence in the working class’s<br />

ability to resist many of the manipulations of mass culture: ‘This is not simply a power<br />

of passive resistance, but something which, though not articulate, is positive. The working<br />

classes have a strong natural ability to survive change by adapting or assimilating<br />

what they want in the new <strong>and</strong> ignoring the rest’ (32). His confidence stems from his<br />

belief that their response to mass culture is always partial: ‘with a large part of themselves<br />

they are just “not there”, are living elsewhere, living intuitively, habitually, verbally,<br />

drawing on myth, aphorism, <strong>and</strong> ritual. This saves them from some of the worst<br />

effects’ (33).<br />

According to Hoggart,<br />

working class people have traditionally, or at least for several generations, regarded<br />

art as escape, as something enjoyed but not assumed to have much connexion with<br />

the matter of daily life. Art is marginal, ‘fun’. . .‘real’ life goes on elsewhere. ...Art<br />

is for you to use (238).


Richard Hoggart: The Uses of Literacy 39<br />

He describes the aesthetic of the working class as an ‘overriding interest in the close<br />

detail’ of the everyday; a profound interest in the already known; a taste for culture that<br />

‘shows’ rather than ‘explores’. The working-class consumer, according to Hoggart’s<br />

account, therefore seeks not ‘an escape from ordinary life’, but its intensification, in the<br />

embodied belief ‘that ordinary life is intrinsically interesting’ (120). The new mass<br />

entertainment of the 1950s is said to undermine this aesthetic:<br />

Most mass entertainments are in the end what D.H. Lawrence described as ‘antilife’.<br />

They are full of a corrupt brightness, of improper appeals <strong>and</strong> moral evasions<br />

. . . they offer nothing which can really grip the brain or heart. They assist a<br />

gradual drying up of the more positive, the fuller, the more cooperative kinds of<br />

enjoyment, in which one gains much by giving much (340).<br />

It is not just that the pleasures of mass entertainment are ‘irresponsible’ <strong>and</strong> ‘vicarious’<br />

(ibid.); they are also destroying the very fabric of an older, healthier, working-class<br />

culture. He is adamant that (in the 1950s)<br />

we are moving towards the creation of a mass culture; that the remnants of what<br />

was at least in parts an urban culture ‘of the people’ are being destroyed; <strong>and</strong> that<br />

the new mass culture is in some important ways less healthy than the often crude<br />

culture it is replacing (24).<br />

He claims that the working-class culture of the 1930s expressed what he calls ‘The rich<br />

full life’, marked by a strong sense of community. This is a culture that is by <strong>and</strong> large<br />

made by the people. Here is a fairly well-known example of what he means – his<br />

description of a typical day at the seaside:<br />

the ‘charas’ go rolling out across the moors for the sea, past the road houses which<br />

turn up their noses at coach parties, to one the driver knows where there is coffee<br />

<strong>and</strong> biscuits or perhaps a full egg <strong>and</strong> bacon breakfast. Then on to a substantial<br />

lunch on arrival, <strong>and</strong> after that a fanning out in groups. But rarely far from one<br />

another, because they know their part of the town <strong>and</strong> their bit of beach, where<br />

they feel at home. . . . They have a nice walk past the shops; perhaps a drink; a sit<br />

in a deck chair eating an ice cream or sucking mint humbugs; a great deal of loud<br />

laughter – at Mrs Johnson insisting on a paddle with her dress tucked in her<br />

bloomers, at Mrs Henderson pretending she has ‘got off’ with the deck chair attendant,<br />

or in the queue at the ladies lavatory. Then there is the buying of presents for<br />

the family, a big meat tea, <strong>and</strong> the journey home with a stop for drinks on the way.<br />

If the men are there, <strong>and</strong> certainly if it is a men’s outing, there will probably be<br />

several stops <strong>and</strong> a crate or two of beer in the back for drinking on the move.<br />

Somewhere in the middle of the moors the men’s parties all tumble out, with<br />

much horseplay <strong>and</strong> noisy jokes about bladder capacity. The driver knows exactly<br />

what is expected of him as he steers his warm, fuggy, <strong>and</strong> singing community back


40<br />

Chapter 3 <strong>Cultural</strong>ism<br />

to the town; for his part he gets a very large tip, collected during the run through<br />

the last few miles of the town streets (147–8).<br />

This is a popular culture that is communal <strong>and</strong> self-made. Hoggart can be criticized for<br />

his romanticism, but we should also recognize here, in the passage’s utopian energy,<br />

an example of Hoggart’s struggle to establish a working distinction to distinguish<br />

between a culture ‘of the people’ <strong>and</strong> a ‘world where things are done for the people’<br />

(151).<br />

The first half of The Uses of Literacy consists mostly of examples of communal <strong>and</strong><br />

self-made entertainment. The analysis is often in considerable advance of Leavisism.<br />

For example, he defends working-class appreciation of popular song against the dismissive<br />

hostility of Cecil Sharp’s (Leavisesque) longing for the ‘purity’ of folk music<br />

(see Storey, 2003) in terms which were soon to become central to the project of cultural<br />

studies. Songs only succeed, he argues, ‘no matter how much Tin Pan Alley plugs<br />

them’ (159), if they can be made to meet the emotional requirements of their popular<br />

audience. As he says of the popular appropriation of ‘After the Ball is Over’, ‘they have<br />

taken it on their own terms, <strong>and</strong> so it is not for them as poor a thing as it might have<br />

been’ (162).<br />

The idea of an audience appropriating for its own purposes – on its own terms – the<br />

commodities offered to it by the culture industries is never fully explored. But the idea<br />

is there in Hoggart; again indicating the underexploited sophistication of parts of The<br />

Uses of Literacy – too often dismissed as a rather unacademic, <strong>and</strong> nostalgic, semiautobiography.<br />

The real weakness of the book is its inability to carry forward the<br />

insights from its treatment of the popular culture of the 1930s into its treatment of the<br />

so-called mass culture of the 1950s. If it had done, it would have, for example, quickly<br />

found totally inadequate the contrasting descriptive titles, ‘The full rich life’ <strong>and</strong><br />

‘Invitations to a c<strong>and</strong>y-floss world’. It is worth noting at this point that it is not necessary<br />

to say that Hoggart’s picture of the 1930s is romanticized in order to prove that his<br />

picture of the 1950s is exaggeratedly pessimistic <strong>and</strong> overdrawn; he does not have to<br />

be proved wrong about the 1930s, as some critics seem to think, in order to be proved<br />

wrong about the 1950s. It is possible that he is right about the 1930s, whilst being<br />

wrong about the 1950s. Like many intellectuals whose origins are working class, he is<br />

perhaps prone to bracket off his own working-class experience against the real <strong>and</strong><br />

imagined condescension of his new middle-class colleagues: ‘I know the contemporary<br />

working class is deplorable, but mine was different.’ Although I would not wish to overstress<br />

this motivation, it does get some support in Williams’s (1957) review of The Uses<br />

of Literacy, when he comments on ‘lucky Hoggart’s’ account of the scholarship boy:<br />

‘which I think’, Williams observes, ‘has been well received by some readers (<strong>and</strong> why<br />

not? it is much what they wanted to hear, <strong>and</strong> now an actual scholarship boy is saying<br />

it)’ (426–7). Again, in a discussion of the ‘strange allies’ dominant groups often attract,<br />

Williams (1965) makes a similar, but more general point:<br />

In our own generation we have a new class of the same kind: the young men <strong>and</strong><br />

women who have benefited by the extension of public education <strong>and</strong> who, in


Richard Hoggart: The Uses of Literacy 41<br />

surprising numbers, identify with the world into which they have been admitted,<br />

<strong>and</strong> spend much of their time, to the applause of their new peers, expounding <strong>and</strong><br />

documenting the hopeless vulgarity of the people they have left: the one thing that<br />

is necessary now, to weaken belief in the practicability of further educational extension<br />

(377–8).<br />

When, in the second part of his study, Hoggart turns to consider ‘some features of<br />

contemporary life’ (169), the self-making aspect of working-class culture is mostly kept<br />

from view. The popular aesthetic, so important for an underst<strong>and</strong>ing of the workingclass<br />

pleasure on show in the 1930s, is now forgotten in the rush to condemn the<br />

popular culture of the 1950s. The success of ‘the radio “soap operas”, with working<br />

class women . . . is due to the consummateness of their attention . . . to their remarkably<br />

sustained presentation of the perfectly ordinary <strong>and</strong> unremarkable’ (181). This is<br />

repeated in newspaper cartoons featuring such figures as ‘the “little man” worrying for<br />

days on end about his daughter’s chances in the school cookery competition ...a daily<br />

exercise in spinning out the unimportant <strong>and</strong> insignificant’ (ibid.). What has happened<br />

to the intrinsic significance of the everyday? Instead of talk of a popular aesthetic, we<br />

are invited on a tour of the manipulative power of the culture industries. The popular<br />

culture of the 1950s, as described by Hoggart, no longer offers the possibility of a full<br />

rich life; everything is now far too thin <strong>and</strong> insipid. The power of ‘commercial culture’<br />

has grown, relentless in its attack on the old (traditional working-class culture) in the<br />

name of the new, the ‘shiny barbarism’ (193) of mass culture. This is a world in which<br />

‘To be “old fashioned” is to be condemned’ (192). It is a condition to which the young<br />

are particularly vulnerable. These ‘barbarians in wonderl<strong>and</strong>’ (193) dem<strong>and</strong> more, <strong>and</strong><br />

are given more, than their parents <strong>and</strong> their gr<strong>and</strong>parents had or expected to have. But<br />

such supposedly mindless hedonism, fed by thin <strong>and</strong> insipid fare, leads only to debilitating<br />

excess.<br />

‘Having a good time’ may be made to seem so important as to override almost all<br />

other claims; yet when it has been allowed to do so, having a good time becomes<br />

largely a matter of routine. The strongest argument against modern mass entertainments<br />

is not that they debase taste – debasement can be alive <strong>and</strong> active – but<br />

that they over excite it, eventually dull it, <strong>and</strong> finally kill it. . . . They kill it at the<br />

nerve, <strong>and</strong> yet so bemuse <strong>and</strong> persuade their audience that the audience is almost<br />

entirely unable to look up <strong>and</strong> say, ‘But in fact this cake is made of sawdust’<br />

(196–7).<br />

Although (in the late 1950s) that stage had not yet been reached, all the signs,<br />

according to Hoggart, indicate that this is the way in which the world is travelling. But<br />

even in this ‘c<strong>and</strong>y-floss world’ (206) there are still signs of resistance. For example,<br />

although mass culture may produce some awful popular songs,<br />

people do not have to sing or listen to these songs, <strong>and</strong> many do not: <strong>and</strong> those<br />

who do, often make the songs better than they really are . . . people often read


42<br />

Chapter 3 <strong>Cultural</strong>ism<br />

them in their own way. So that even there they are less affected than the extent of<br />

their purchases would seem to indicate (231).<br />

Again, this reminds us that Hoggart’s target is (mostly) the producers of the commodities<br />

from which popular culture is made <strong>and</strong> not those who make these commodities<br />

(or not) into popular culture. Although he offers many examples of ‘proof’ of<br />

cultural decline, popular fiction is arguably his key example of deterioration. He compares<br />

a piece of contemporary writing (in fact it is an imitation written by himself) with<br />

an extract from East Lynne <strong>and</strong> an extract from Adam Bede. He concludes that in comparison<br />

the contemporary extract is thin <strong>and</strong> insipid: a ‘trickle of tinned milk <strong>and</strong> water<br />

which staves off the pangs of a positive hunger <strong>and</strong> denies the satisfactions of a solidly<br />

filling meal’ (237). Leaving aside the fact that the contemporary extract is an imitation<br />

(as are all his contemporary examples), Hoggart argues that its inferiority is due to the<br />

fact that it lacks the ‘moral tone’ (236) of the other two extracts. This may be true, but<br />

what is also significant is the way in which the other two extracts are full of ‘moral tone’<br />

in a quite definite sense: they attempt to tell the reader what to think; they are, as he<br />

admits, ‘oratory’ (235). The contemporary extract is similarly thin in a quite definite<br />

sense: it does not tell the reader what to think. Therefore, although there may be various<br />

grounds on which we might wish to rank the three extracts, with Adam Bede at the<br />

top <strong>and</strong> the contemporary extract at the bottom, ‘moral tone’ (meaning fiction should<br />

tell people what to think) seems to lead us nowhere but back to the rather bogus certainties<br />

of Leavisism. Moreover, we can easily reverse the judgement: the contemporary<br />

extract is to be valued for its elliptic <strong>and</strong> interrogative qualities; it invites us to think by<br />

not thinking for us; this is not to be dismissed as an absence of thought (or ‘moral tone’<br />

for that matter), but as an absence full of potential presence, which the reader is invited<br />

to actively produce.<br />

One supposedly striking portent of the journey into the c<strong>and</strong>y-floss world is the<br />

habitual visitor to the new milk bars, ‘the juke box boy’ (247) – his term for the Teddy<br />

boy. Milk bars are themselves symptomatic: they ‘indicate at once, in the nastiness of<br />

their modernistic knick-knacks, their glaring showiness, an aesthetic breakdown so<br />

complete’ (ibid.). Patrons are mostly ‘boys between fifteen <strong>and</strong> twenty, with drape<br />

suits, picture ties, <strong>and</strong> an American slouch’ (248). Their main reason for being there<br />

is to ‘put copper after copper into the mechanical record player’ (ibid.). Records are<br />

played loud: the music ‘is allowed to blare out so that the noise would be sufficient to<br />

fill a good sized ballroom’ (ibid.). Listening to the music, ‘The young men waggle one<br />

shoulder or stare, as desperately as Humphrey Bogart, across the tubular chairs’ (ibid.).<br />

Compared even with the pub around the corner, this is all a peculiarly thin <strong>and</strong><br />

pallid form of dissipation, a sort of spiritual dry-rot amid the odour of boiled milk.<br />

Many of the customers – their clothes, their hair styles, their facial expressions<br />

all indicate – are living to a large extent in a myth world compounded of a few<br />

simple elements which they take to be those of American life (ibid.).<br />

According to Hoggart,


Richard Hoggart: The Uses of Literacy 43<br />

They are a depressing group . . . perhaps most of them are rather less intelligent<br />

than the average [working-class youth], <strong>and</strong> are therefore even more exposed than<br />

others to the debilitating mass trends of the day . . . they have no responsibilities,<br />

<strong>and</strong> little sense of responsibilities, to themselves or to others (248–9).<br />

Although ‘they are not typical’, they are an ominous sign of things to come:<br />

these are the figures some important contemporary forces are tending to create, the<br />

directionless <strong>and</strong> tamed helots of a machine-minding class. . . . The hedonistic but<br />

passive barbarian who rides in a fifty-horse-power bus for threepence, to see a fivemillion-dollar<br />

film for one-<strong>and</strong>-eightpence, is not simply a social oddity; he is a<br />

portent (250).<br />

The juke-box boy symptomatically bears the prediction of a society in which ‘the larger<br />

part of the population is reduced to a condition of obediently receptive passivity, their<br />

eyes glued to television sets, pin ups, <strong>and</strong> cinema screens’ (316).<br />

Hoggart, however, does not totally despair at the march of mass culture. He knows,<br />

for instance, that the working class ‘are not living lives which are imaginatively as poor<br />

as a mere reading of their literature would suggest’ (324). The old communal <strong>and</strong> selfmade<br />

popular culture still remains in working-class ways of speaking, in ‘the Working-<br />

Men’s Clubs, the styles of singing, the brass b<strong>and</strong>s, the older types of magazines, the<br />

close group games like darts <strong>and</strong> dominoes’ (ibid.). Moreover, he trusts their ‘considerable<br />

moral resources’ (325) to allow them, <strong>and</strong> to encourage them, to continue to adapt<br />

for their own purposes the commodities <strong>and</strong> commodified practices of the culture industries.<br />

In short, they ‘are a good deal less affected than they might well be. The question,<br />

of course, is how long this stock of moral capital will last, <strong>and</strong> whether it is being<br />

renewed’ (ibid.). For all his guarded optimism, he warns that it is a ‘form of democratic<br />

self-indulgence to over-stress this resilience’ in the face of the ‘increasingly dangerous<br />

pressures’ (330) of mass culture, with all its undermining of genuine community with<br />

an increasingly ‘hollow . . . invitation to share in a kind of palliness’ (340). His ultimate<br />

fear is that ‘competitive commerce’ (243) may have totalitarian designs:<br />

Inhibited now from ensuring the ‘degradation’ of the masses economically . . .<br />

competitive commerce . . . becomes a new <strong>and</strong> stronger form of subjection; this<br />

subjection promises to be stronger than the old because the chains of cultural subordination<br />

are both easier to wear <strong>and</strong> harder to strike away than those of economic<br />

subordination (243–4).<br />

Hoggart’s approach to popular culture has much in common with the approach of<br />

Leavisism (this is most noticeable in the analysis of popular culture in the second part<br />

of the book); both operate with a notion of cultural decline; both see education in discrimination<br />

as a means to resist the manipulative appeal of mass culture. However,<br />

what makes his approach different from that of Leavisism is his detailed preoccupation<br />

with, <strong>and</strong>, above all, his clear commitment to, working-class culture. His distance from


44<br />

Chapter 3 <strong>Cultural</strong>ism<br />

Leavisism is most evident in the content of his own ‘good past/bad present’ binary<br />

opposition: instead of the organic community of the seventeenth century, his ‘good<br />

past’ is the working-class culture of the 1930s. What Hoggart celebrates from the 1930s,<br />

is, significantly, the very culture that the Leavisites were armed to resist. This alone<br />

makes his approach an implicit critique of, <strong>and</strong> an academic advance on, Leavisism.<br />

But, as Hall (1980b) points out, although Hoggart ‘refused many of [F.R.] Leavis’s<br />

embedded cultural judgements’, he, nevertheless, in his use of Leavisite literary<br />

methodology, ‘continued “a tradition” while seeking, in practice, to transform it’ (18).<br />

Raymond Williams: ‘The analysis of culture’<br />

Raymond Williams’s influence on cultural studies has been enormous. The range of his<br />

work alone is formidable. He has made significant contributions to our underst<strong>and</strong>ing<br />

of cultural theory, cultural history, television, the press, radio <strong>and</strong> advertising. Alan<br />

O’Connor’s (1989) bibliography of Williams’s published work runs to thirty-nine<br />

pages. His contribution is all the more remarkable when one considers his origins in<br />

the Welsh working class (his father was a railway signalman), <strong>and</strong> that as an academic<br />

he was Professor of Drama at Cambridge University. In this section, I will comment<br />

only on his contribution to the founding of culturalism <strong>and</strong> its contribution to the<br />

study of popular culture.<br />

In ‘The analysis of culture’, Williams (2009) outlines the ‘three general categories in<br />

the definition of culture’ (32). First, there is ‘the “ideal”, in which culture is a state or<br />

process of human perfection, in terms of certain absolute or universal values’ (ibid.).<br />

The role of cultural analysis, using this definition, ‘is essentially the discovery <strong>and</strong><br />

description, in lives <strong>and</strong> works, of those values which can be seen to compose a timeless<br />

order, or to have permanent reference to the universal human condition’ (ibid.).<br />

This is the definition inherited from Arnold <strong>and</strong> used by Leavisism: what he calls, in<br />

<strong>Culture</strong> <strong>and</strong> Society, culture as an ultimate ‘court of human appeal, to be set over the<br />

processes of practical social judgement <strong>and</strong> yet to offer itself as a mitigating <strong>and</strong> rallying<br />

alternative’ (Williams, 1963: 17).<br />

Second, there is the ‘documentary’ record: the surviving texts <strong>and</strong> practices of a<br />

culture. In this definition, ‘culture is the body of intellectual <strong>and</strong> imaginative work, in<br />

which, in a detailed way, human thought <strong>and</strong> experience are variously recorded’<br />

(Williams, 2009: ibid.). The purpose of cultural analysis, using this definition, is one of<br />

critical assessment. This can take a form of analysis similar to that adopted with regard<br />

to the ‘ideal’; an act of critical sifting until the discovery of what Arnold calls ‘the best<br />

that has been thought <strong>and</strong> said’ (see Chapter 2). It can also involve a less exalted practice:<br />

the cultural as the critical object of interpretative description <strong>and</strong> evaluation (literary<br />

studies is the obvious example of this practice). Finally, it can also involve a more historical,<br />

less literary evaluative function: an act of critical reading to measure its significance<br />

as a ‘historical document’ (historical studies is the obvious example of this practice).


Raymond Williams: ‘The analysis of culture’ 45<br />

Third, ‘there is the “social” definition of culture, in which culture is a description of a<br />

particular way of life’ (ibid.). The ‘social’ definition of culture is crucial to the founding<br />

of culturalism. This definition introduces three new ways of thinking about culture. First,<br />

the ‘anthropological’ position which sees culture as a description of a particular way of life;<br />

second, the proposition that culture ‘expresses certain meanings <strong>and</strong> values’ (ibid.); third,<br />

the claim that the work of cultural analysis should be the ‘clarification of the meanings<br />

<strong>and</strong> values implicit <strong>and</strong> explicit in a particular way of life, a particular culture’ (ibid.).<br />

Williams is aware that the kind of analysis the ‘social’ definition of culture dem<strong>and</strong>s,<br />

will often ‘involve analysis of elements in the way of life that to followers of the other<br />

definitions are not “culture” at all’ (32). Moreover, whilst such analysis might still operate<br />

modes of evaluation of the ‘ideal’ <strong>and</strong> the ‘documentary’ type, it will also extend<br />

to an emphasis which, from studying particular meanings <strong>and</strong> values, seeks not so<br />

much to compare these, as a way of establishing a scale, but by studying their<br />

modes of change to discover certain general ‘laws’ or ‘trends’, by which social <strong>and</strong><br />

cultural development as a whole can be better understood (32–3).<br />

Taken together, the three points embodied in the ‘social’ definition of culture – culture<br />

as a particular way of life, culture as expression of a particular way of life, <strong>and</strong> cultural<br />

analysis as a method of reconstituting a particular way of life – establish both the general<br />

perspective <strong>and</strong> the basic procedures of culturalism.<br />

Williams, however, is reluctant to remove from analysis any of the three ways of<br />

underst<strong>and</strong>ing culture: ‘there is a significant reference in each . . . <strong>and</strong>, if this is so, it is<br />

the relations between them that should claim our attention’ (33). He describes as<br />

‘inadequate’ <strong>and</strong> ‘unacceptable’ any definition which fails to include the other<br />

definitions: ‘However difficult it may be in practice, we have to try to see the process as<br />

a whole, <strong>and</strong> to relate our particular studies, if not explicitly at least by ultimate reference,<br />

to the actual <strong>and</strong> complex organization’ (34). As he explains,<br />

I would then define the theory of culture as the study of relationships between elements<br />

in a whole way of life. The analysis of culture is the attempt to discover the<br />

nature of the organization which is the complex of these relationships. Analysis of<br />

particular works or institutions is, in this context, analysis of their essential kind of<br />

organization, the relationships which works or institutions embody as parts of the<br />

organization as a whole (35).<br />

In addressing the ‘complex organization’ of culture as a particular way of life, the<br />

purpose of cultural analysis is always to underst<strong>and</strong> what a culture is expressing; ‘the<br />

actual experience through which a culture was lived’; the ‘important common element’;<br />

‘a particular community of experience’ (36). In short, to reconstitute what Williams<br />

calls ‘the structure of feeling’ (ibid.). By structure of feeling, he means the shared values<br />

of a particular group, class or society. The term is used to describe a discursive structure<br />

that is a cross between a collective cultural unconscious <strong>and</strong> an ideology. He uses, for<br />

example, the term to explain the way in which many nineteenth-century novels


46<br />

Chapter 3 <strong>Cultural</strong>ism<br />

employ ‘magic solutions’ to close the gap in that society between ‘the ethic <strong>and</strong> the<br />

experience’. He gives examples of how men <strong>and</strong> women are released from loveless marriages<br />

as a result of the convenient death or the insanity of their partners; legacies turn<br />

up unexpectedly to overcome reverses in fortune; villains are lost in the Empire; poor<br />

men return from the Empire bearing great riches; <strong>and</strong> those whose aspirations could<br />

not be met by prevailing social arrangements are put on a boat to make their dreams<br />

come true elsewhere. All these (<strong>and</strong> more) are presented as examples of a shared structure<br />

of feeling, the unconscious <strong>and</strong> conscious working out in fictional texts of the contradictions<br />

of nineteenth-century society. The purpose of cultural analysis is to read<br />

the structure of feeling through the documentary record, ‘from poems to buildings <strong>and</strong><br />

dress-fashions’ (37). As he makes clear,<br />

What we are looking for, always, is the actual life that the whole organization is<br />

there to express. The significance of documentary culture is that, more clearly than<br />

anything else, it expresses that life to us in direct terms, when the living witnesses<br />

are silent (ibid.).<br />

The situation is complicated by the fact that culture always exists on three levels:<br />

We need to distinguish three levels of culture, even in its most general definition.<br />

There is the lived culture of a particular time <strong>and</strong> place, only fully accessible to<br />

those living in that time <strong>and</strong> place. There is the recorded culture, of every kind,<br />

from art to the most everyday facts: the culture of a period. There is also, as the<br />

factor connecting lived culture <strong>and</strong> period cultures, the culture of the selective<br />

tradition (37).<br />

Lived culture is culture as lived <strong>and</strong> experienced by people in their day-to-day existence<br />

in a particular place <strong>and</strong> at a particular moment in time; <strong>and</strong> the only people who have<br />

full access to this culture are those who actually lived its structure of feeling. Once the<br />

historical moment is gone the structure of feeling begins to fragment. <strong>Cultural</strong> analysis<br />

has access only through the documentary record of the culture. But the documentary<br />

record itself fragments under the processes of ‘the selective tradition’ (ibid.).<br />

Between a lived culture <strong>and</strong> its reconstitution in cultural analysis, clearly, a great deal<br />

of detail is lost. For example, as Williams points out, nobody can claim to have read<br />

all the novels of the nineteenth century. Instead, what we have is the specialist who can<br />

claim perhaps to have read many hundreds; the interested academic who has read<br />

somewhat fewer; the ‘educated reader’ who has read fewer again. This quite clear process<br />

of selectivity does not prevent the three groups of readers from sharing a sense<br />

of the nature of the nineteenth-century novel. Williams is of course aware that no<br />

nineteenth-century reader would in fact have read all the novels of the nineteenth<br />

century. His point, however, is that the nineteenth-century reader ‘had something<br />

which . . . no later individual can wholly recover: that sense of the life within which the<br />

novels were written, <strong>and</strong> which we now approach through our selection’ (38). For<br />

Williams, it is crucial to underst<strong>and</strong> the selectivity of cultural traditions. It always


Raymond Williams: ‘The analysis of culture’ 47<br />

(inevitably) produces a cultural record, a cultural tradition, marked by ‘a rejection of<br />

considerable areas of what was once a living culture’ (38). Furthermore, as he explains<br />

in <strong>Culture</strong> <strong>and</strong> Society, ‘there will always be a tendency for this process of selection to be<br />

related to <strong>and</strong> even governed by the interests of the class that is dominant’ (1963: 313).<br />

Within a given society, selection will be governed by many kinds of special interests,<br />

including class interests. Just as the actual social situation will largely govern<br />

contemporary selection, so the development of the society, the process of historical<br />

change, will largely determine the selective tradition. The traditional culture of<br />

a society will always tend to correspond to its contemporary system of interests <strong>and</strong><br />

values, for it is not an absolute body of work but a continual selection <strong>and</strong> interpretation<br />

(2009: 38–9).<br />

This has quite profound ramifications for the student of popular culture. Given that<br />

selection is invariably made on the basis of ‘contemporary interests’, <strong>and</strong> given the incidence<br />

of many ‘reversals <strong>and</strong> rediscoveries’, it follows that ‘the relevance of past work,<br />

in any future situation, is unforeseeable’ (39). If this is the case, it also follows that<br />

absolute judgements about what is good <strong>and</strong> what is bad, about what is high <strong>and</strong> what<br />

is low, in contemporary culture, should be made with a great deal less certainty, open<br />

as they are to historical realignment in a potential whirlpool of historical contingency.<br />

Williams advocates, as already noted, a form of cultural analysis which is conscious<br />

that ‘the cultural tradition is not only a selection but also an interpretation’ (ibid.).<br />

Although cultural analysis cannot reverse this, it can, by returning a text or practice to<br />

its historical moment, show other ‘historical alternatives’ to contemporary interpretation<br />

<strong>and</strong> ‘the particular contemporary values on which it rests’ (ibid.). In this way, we<br />

are able to make clear distinctions between ‘the whole historical organization within<br />

which it was expressed’ <strong>and</strong> ‘the contemporary organization within which it is used’<br />

(ibid.). By working in this way, ‘real cultural processes will emerge’ (ibid.).<br />

Williams’s analysis breaks with Leavisism in a number of ways. First, there is no<br />

special place for art – it is a human activity alongside other human activities: ‘art is there,<br />

as an activity, with the production, the trading, the politics, the raising of families’ (34).<br />

Williams presses the case for a democratic account of culture: culture as a particular<br />

way of life. In <strong>Culture</strong> <strong>and</strong> Society, he distinguishes between middle-class culture as ‘the<br />

basic individualist idea <strong>and</strong> the institutions, manners, habits of thought, <strong>and</strong> intentions<br />

which proceed from that’ <strong>and</strong> working-class culture as ‘the basic collective idea, <strong>and</strong><br />

the institutions, manners, habits of thought, <strong>and</strong> intentions which proceed from this’<br />

(1963: 313). He then gives this account of the achievements of working-class culture:<br />

The working class, because of its position, has not, since the Industrial Revolution,<br />

produced a culture in the narrower sense. The culture which it has produced, <strong>and</strong><br />

which it is important to recognise, is the collective democratic institution, whether<br />

in the trade unions, the cooperative movement, or a political party. Working-class<br />

culture, in the stage through which it has been passing, is primarily social (in that<br />

it has created institutions) rather than individual (in particular intellectual or


48<br />

Chapter 3 <strong>Cultural</strong>ism<br />

imaginative work). When it is considered in context, it can be seen as a very<br />

remarkable creative achievement (314).<br />

It is when Williams insists on culture as a definition of the ‘lived experience’ of<br />

‘ordinary’ men <strong>and</strong> women, made in their daily interaction with the texts <strong>and</strong> practices<br />

of everyday life, that he finally breaks decisively with Leavisism. Here is the basis for a<br />

democratic definition of culture. He takes seriously Leavis’s call for a common culture.<br />

But the difference between Leavisism <strong>and</strong> Williams on this point is that Williams does<br />

want a common culture, whilst Leavisism wants only a hierarchical culture of difference<br />

<strong>and</strong> deference. Williams’s review of The Uses of Literacy indicates some of the key<br />

differences between his own position <strong>and</strong> the traditions of Leavisism (in which he<br />

partly locates Hoggart):<br />

The analysis of Sunday newspapers <strong>and</strong> crime stories <strong>and</strong> romances is . . . familiar,<br />

but, when you have come yourself from their apparent public, when you recognise<br />

in yourself the ties that still bind, you cannot be satisfied with the older formula:<br />

enlightened minority, degraded mass. You know how bad most ‘popular culture’<br />

is, but you know also that the irruption of the ‘swinish multitude’, which Burke<br />

had prophesied would trample down light <strong>and</strong> learning, is the coming to relative<br />

power <strong>and</strong> relative justice of your own people, whom you could not if you tried<br />

desert (1957: 424–5).<br />

Although he still claims to recognize ‘how bad most “popular culture” is’, this is no<br />

longer a judgement made from within an enchanted circle of certainty, policed by ‘the<br />

older formula: enlightened minority, degraded mass’. Moreover, Williams is insistent<br />

that we distinguish between the commodities made available by the culture industries<br />

<strong>and</strong> what people make of these commodities. He identifies what he calls<br />

the extremely damaging <strong>and</strong> quite untrue identification of ‘popular culture’<br />

(commercial newspapers, magazines, entertainments, etc.) with ‘working-class<br />

culture’. In fact the main source of this ‘popular culture’ lies outside the working<br />

class altogether, for it is instituted, financed <strong>and</strong> operated by the commercial<br />

bourgeoisie, <strong>and</strong> remains typically capitalist in its methods of production <strong>and</strong><br />

distribution. That working-class people form perhaps a majority of the consumers<br />

of this material . . . does not, as a fact, justify this facile identification (425).<br />

In other words, people are not reducible to the commodities they consume. Hoggart’s<br />

problem, according to Williams, is that he ‘has taken over too many of the formulas’,<br />

from ‘Matthew Arnold’ to ‘contemporary conservative ideas of the decay of politics in<br />

the working class’; the result is an argument in need of ‘radical revision’ (ibid.). The<br />

publication of ‘The analysis of culture’, together with the other chapters in The Long<br />

Revolution, has been described by Hall (1980b) as ‘a seminal event in English post-war<br />

intellectual life’ (19), which did much to provide the radical revision necessary to lay<br />

the basis for a non-Leavisite study of popular culture.


E.P. Thompson: The Making of the English Working Class 49<br />

E.P. Thompson: The Making of the English Working<br />

Class<br />

In the Preface to The Making of the English Working Class, E.P. Thompson states:<br />

This book has a clumsy title, but it is one which meets its purpose. Making, because<br />

it is a study in an active process, which owes as much to agency as conditioning.<br />

The working class did not rise like the sun at an appointed time. It was present at<br />

its own making (1980: 8).<br />

The English working class, like any class, is for Thompson ‘a historical phenomenon’;<br />

it is not a ‘structure’ or a ‘category’, but the coming together of ‘a number of disparate<br />

<strong>and</strong> seemingly unconnected events, both in the raw material of experience <strong>and</strong> in<br />

consciousness’; it is ‘something which in fact happens (<strong>and</strong> can be shown to happen)<br />

in human relationships’ (ibid.). Moreover, class is not a ‘thing’, it is always a historical<br />

relationship of unity <strong>and</strong> difference: uniting one class as against another class or<br />

classes. As he explains: ‘class happens when some men, as a result of common experiences<br />

(inherited or shared), feel <strong>and</strong> articulate the identity of their interests as between<br />

themselves, <strong>and</strong> as against other men whose interests are different from (<strong>and</strong> usually<br />

opposed to) theirs’ (8–9). The common experience of class ‘is largely determined by<br />

the productive relations into which men are born – or enter involuntarily’ (9). However,<br />

the consciousness of class, the translation of experience into culture, ‘is defined by<br />

men as they live their own history, <strong>and</strong>, in the end, this is its only definition’ (10). Class<br />

is for Thompson, then, ‘a social <strong>and</strong> cultural formation, arising from processes which<br />

can be studied as they work themselves out over a considerable historical period’ (11).<br />

The Making of the English Working Class details the political <strong>and</strong> cultural formation<br />

of the English working class by approaching its subject from three different but related<br />

perspectives. First, it reconstructs the political <strong>and</strong> cultural traditions of English radicalism<br />

in the late eighteenth century: religious dissent, popular discontent, <strong>and</strong> the<br />

influence of the French Revolution. Second, it focuses on the social <strong>and</strong> cultural experience<br />

of the Industrial Revolution as it was lived by different working groups: weavers,<br />

field labourers, cotton spinners, artisans, etc. Finally, it analyses the growth of workingclass<br />

consciousness evidenced in the corresponding growth in a range of political,<br />

social <strong>and</strong> cultural, ‘strongly based <strong>and</strong> self conscious working-class institutions’<br />

(212–13). As he insists: ‘The working class made itself as much as it was made’ (213).<br />

He draws two conclusions from his research. First, ‘when every caution has been made,<br />

the outst<strong>and</strong>ing fact of the period between 1790 <strong>and</strong> 1830 is the formation of “the<br />

working class”’ (212). Second, he claims that ‘this was, perhaps, the most distinguished<br />

popular culture Engl<strong>and</strong> has known’ (914).<br />

The Making of the English Working Class is the classic example of ‘history from below’.<br />

Thompson’s aim is to place the ‘experience’ of the English working class as central to<br />

any underst<strong>and</strong>ing of the formation of an industrial capitalist society in the decades<br />

leading up to the 1830s. It is a history from below in the double sense suggested by


50<br />

Chapter 3 <strong>Cultural</strong>ism<br />

Gregor McLellan (1982): a history from below in that it seeks to reintroduce workingclass<br />

experience into the historical process; <strong>and</strong> a history from below in that it insists<br />

that the working class were the conscious agents of their own making. 8 Thompson is<br />

working with Marx’s (1977) famous claim about the way in which men <strong>and</strong> women<br />

make history: ‘Men make their own history, but they do not make it just as they please;<br />

they do not make it under circumstances chosen by themselves, but under circumstances<br />

directly encountered, given <strong>and</strong> transmitted from the past’ (10). What<br />

Thompson does is to emphasize the first part of Marx’s claim (human agency) against<br />

what he considers to have been an overemphasis by Marxist historians on the second<br />

part (structural determinants). Paradoxically, or perhaps not so, he has himself been<br />

criticized for overstressing the role of human agency – human experiences, human<br />

values – at the expense of structural factors (see Anderson, 1980).<br />

The Making of the English Working Class is in so many ways a monumental contribution<br />

to social history (in size alone: the Penguin edition runs to over nine hundred pages).<br />

What makes it significant for the student of popular culture is the nature of its historical<br />

account. Thompson’s history is not one of abstract economic <strong>and</strong> political processes;<br />

nor is it an account of the doings of the great <strong>and</strong> the worthy. The book is about ‘ordinary’<br />

men <strong>and</strong> women, their experiences, their values, their ideas, their actions, their<br />

desires: in short, popular culture as a site of resistance to those in whose interests the<br />

Industrial Revolution was made. Hall (1980b) calls it ‘the most seminal work of social<br />

history of the post-war period’, pointing to the way it challenges ‘the narrow, elitist<br />

conception of “culture” enshrined in the Leavisite tradition, as well as the rather evolutionary<br />

approach which sometimes marked Williams’s The Long Revolution’ (19–20).<br />

In an interview a decade or so after the publication of the book, Thompson (1976)<br />

commented on his historical method as follows: ‘If you want a generalization I would<br />

have to say that the historian has got to be listening all the time’ (15). He is by no<br />

means the only historian who listens; the conservative historian G.M. Young also<br />

listens, if in a rather more selective fashion: ‘history is the conversation of people<br />

who counted’ (quoted in McLellan, 1982: 107). What makes Thompson’s listening<br />

radically different is the people to whom he listens. As he explains in a famous passage<br />

from the Preface to The Making of the English Working Class:<br />

I am seeking to rescue the poor stockinger, the Luddite cropper, the ‘obsolete’ h<strong>and</strong><br />

loom weaver, the ‘utopian’ artisan, <strong>and</strong> even the deluded follower of Joanna<br />

Southcott, from the enormous condescension of posterity. Their crafts <strong>and</strong> traditions<br />

may have been dying. Their hostility to the new industrialism may have been<br />

backward looking. Their communitarian ideals may have been fantasies. Their<br />

insurrectionary conspiracies may have been foolhardy. But they lived through<br />

these times of acute social disturbance, <strong>and</strong> we did not. Their aspirations were valid<br />

in terms of their own experience; <strong>and</strong>, if they were casualties of history, they<br />

remain, condemned in their own lives, as casualties (1980: 12).<br />

Before concluding this brief account of Thompson’s contribution to the study of<br />

popular culture, it should be noted that he himself does not accept the term ‘culturalism’


Stuart Hall <strong>and</strong> Paddy Whannel: The <strong>Popular</strong> Arts 51<br />

as a description of his work. This <strong>and</strong> other related points was the subject of a heated<br />

‘History Workshop’ debate between Richard Johnson, Stuart Hall <strong>and</strong> Thompson himself<br />

(see Samuel, 1981). One of the difficulties when reading the contributions to the<br />

debate is the way that culturalism is made to carry two quite different meanings. On<br />

the one h<strong>and</strong>, it is employed as a description of a particular methodology (this is how<br />

I am using it here). On the other, it is used as a term of critique (usually from a more<br />

‘traditional’ Marxist position or from the perspective of Marxist structuralism). This is<br />

a complex issue, but as a coda to this discussion of Hoggart, Williams <strong>and</strong> Thompson,<br />

here is a very simplified clarification: positively, culturalism is a methodology which<br />

stresses culture (human agency, human values, human experience) as being of crucial<br />

importance for a full sociological <strong>and</strong> historical underst<strong>and</strong>ing of a given social formation;<br />

negatively, culturalism is used to suggest the employment of such assumptions<br />

without full recognition <strong>and</strong> acknowledgement that culture is the effect of structures<br />

beyond itself, <strong>and</strong> that these have the effect of ultimately determining, constraining<br />

<strong>and</strong>, finally, producing, culture (human agency, human values <strong>and</strong> human experience).<br />

Thompson disagrees strongly with the second proposition, <strong>and</strong> refutes totally any suggestion<br />

that culturalism, regardless of the definition, can be applied to his own work.<br />

Stuart Hall <strong>and</strong> Paddy Whannel: The <strong>Popular</strong> Arts<br />

The ‘main thesis’ of The <strong>Popular</strong> Arts is that ‘in terms of actual quality . . . the struggle<br />

between what is good <strong>and</strong> worthwhile <strong>and</strong> what is shoddy <strong>and</strong> debased is not a struggle<br />

against the modern forms of communication, but a conflict within these media’ (Hall<br />

<strong>and</strong> Whannel, 1964: 15). Hall <strong>and</strong> Whannel’s concern is with the difficulty of making<br />

these distinctions. They set themselves the task to develop ‘a critical method for<br />

h<strong>and</strong>ling . . . problems of value <strong>and</strong> evaluation’ (ibid.) in the study of popular culture.<br />

In this task they pay specific thanks to the work of Hoggart <strong>and</strong> Williams, <strong>and</strong> passing<br />

thanks to the key figures of Leavisism.<br />

The book was written against a background of concern about the influence of popular<br />

culture in the school classroom. In 1960 the National Union of Teachers (NUT)<br />

Annual Conference passed a resolution that read in part:<br />

Conference believes that a determined effort must be made to counteract the<br />

debasement of st<strong>and</strong>ards which result from the misuse of press, radio, cinema <strong>and</strong><br />

television. . . . It calls especially upon those who use <strong>and</strong> control the media of mass<br />

communication, <strong>and</strong> upon parents, to support the efforts of teachers in an attempt<br />

to prevent the conflict which too often arises between the values inculcated in the<br />

classroom <strong>and</strong> those encountered by young people in the world outside (quoted<br />

in Hall <strong>and</strong> Whannel, 1964: 23).<br />

The resolution led to the NUT Special Conference, ‘<strong>Popular</strong> culture <strong>and</strong> personal<br />

responsibility’. One speaker at the conference, the composer Malcolm Arnold, said:


52<br />

Chapter 3 <strong>Cultural</strong>ism<br />

‘Nobody is in any way a better person morally or in any other way for liking Beethoven<br />

more than Adam Faith. . . . Of course the person who likes both is in a very happy position<br />

since he is able to enjoy much more in his life than a lot of other people’ (ibid.:<br />

27). Although Hall <strong>and</strong> Whannel (1964) recognize ‘the honest intention’ in Arnold’s<br />

remarks, they question what they call ‘the r<strong>and</strong>om use of Adam Faith as an example’<br />

because, as they claim, ‘as a singer of popular songs he is by any serious st<strong>and</strong>ards far<br />

down the list’. Moreover, as they explain, ‘By serious st<strong>and</strong>ards we mean those that<br />

might be legitimately applied to popular music – the st<strong>and</strong>ards set, for example, by<br />

Frank Sinatra or Ray Charles’ (28). What Hall <strong>and</strong> Whannel are doing here is rejecting<br />

the arguments of both Leavisism, <strong>and</strong> the (mostly American) mass culture critique,<br />

which claims that all high culture is good <strong>and</strong> that all popular culture is bad, for an<br />

argument which says, on the one h<strong>and</strong>, that most high culture is good, <strong>and</strong> on the<br />

other, contrary to Leavisism <strong>and</strong> the mass culture critique, that some popular culture is<br />

also good – it is ultimately a question of popular discrimination.<br />

Part of the aim of The <strong>Popular</strong> Arts, then, is to replace the ‘misleading generalizations’<br />

of earlier attacks on popular culture by helping to facilitate popular discrimination<br />

within <strong>and</strong> across the range of popular culture itself. Instead of worrying about the<br />

‘effects’ of popular culture, ‘we should be seeking to train a more dem<strong>and</strong>ing audience’<br />

(35). A more dem<strong>and</strong>ing audience, according to Hall <strong>and</strong> Whannel, is one that prefers<br />

jazz to pop, Miles Davis to Liberace, Frank Sinatra to Adam Faith, Polish films to mainstream<br />

Hollywood, L’Année Dernière à Marienbad to South Pacific; <strong>and</strong> knows intuitively<br />

<strong>and</strong> instinctively that high culture (‘Shakespeare, Dickens <strong>and</strong> Lawrence’) is usually<br />

always best. They take from Clement Greenberg (who took it from Theodor Adorno)<br />

the idea that mass culture is always ‘pre-digested’ (our responses are predetermined<br />

rather than the result of a genuine interaction with the text or practice), <strong>and</strong> use the<br />

idea as a means to discriminate, not just between good <strong>and</strong> bad popular culture, but<br />

to suggest that it can also be applied to examples of high culture: ‘The important point<br />

about such a definition [culture as “pre-digested”] is that it cuts across the commonplace<br />

distinctions. It applies to films but not all, to some TV but not all. It covers segments<br />

of the traditional as well as the popular culture’ (36).<br />

Their approach leads them to reject two common teaching strategies often encountered<br />

when popular culture is introduced into the classroom. First, there is the defensive<br />

strategy that introduces popular culture in order to condemn it as second-rate<br />

culture. Second, the ‘opportunist’ strategy that embraces the popular tastes of students<br />

in the hope of eventually leading them to better things. ‘In neither case’, they contend,<br />

‘is there a genuine response, nor any basis for real judgements’ (37). Neither would<br />

lead to what they insist is necessary: ‘a training in discrimination’ (ibid.). This is not<br />

(to repeat a point made earlier) the classic discrimination of Leavisism, defending the<br />

‘good’ high culture against the encroachments of the ‘bad’ popular culture, but discrimination<br />

within popular culture: the necessity to discriminate within <strong>and</strong> not just<br />

against popular culture; sifting the good popular culture from the bad popular culture.<br />

However, although they do not believe in introducing the texts <strong>and</strong> practices of popular<br />

culture into education ‘as steppingstones in a hierarchy of taste’ leading ultimately<br />

to real culture, 9 they do still insist (as do Hoggart <strong>and</strong> Williams) that there is a


Stuart Hall <strong>and</strong> Paddy Whannel: The <strong>Popular</strong> Arts 53<br />

fundamental categorical difference – a difference of value – between high <strong>and</strong> popular<br />

culture. Nevertheless, the difference is not necessarily a question of superiority/<br />

inferiority; it is more about different kinds of satisfaction: it is not useful to say that<br />

the music of Cole Porter is inferior to that of Beethoven. The music of Porter <strong>and</strong><br />

Beethoven is not of equal value, but Porter was not making an unsuccessful attempt to<br />

create music comparable to Beethoven’s (39).<br />

Not unequal, but of different value, is a very difficult distinction to unload. What it<br />

seems to suggest is that we must judge texts <strong>and</strong> practices on their own terms: ‘recognise<br />

different aims . . . assess varying achievements with defined limits’ (38). Such a<br />

strategy will open up discrimination to a whole range of cultural activity <strong>and</strong> prevent<br />

the defensive ghettoization of high against the rest. Although they acknowledge the<br />

‘immense debt’ they owe to the ‘pioneers’ of Leavisism, <strong>and</strong> accept more or less the<br />

Leavisite view (modified by a reading of William Morris) of the organic culture of<br />

the past, they, nevertheless, in a classic left-Leavisite move, reject the conservatism <strong>and</strong><br />

pessimism of Leavisism, <strong>and</strong> insist, against calls for ‘resistance by an armed <strong>and</strong> conscious<br />

minority’ to the culture of the present (Q.D. Leavis), that ‘if we wish to re-create<br />

a genuine popular culture we must seek out the points of growth within the society<br />

that now exists’ (39). They claim that by adopting ‘a critical <strong>and</strong> evaluative attitude’<br />

(46) <strong>and</strong> an awareness that it is ‘foolish to make large claims for this popular culture’<br />

(40), it is possible ‘to break with the false distinction . . . between the “serious” <strong>and</strong> the<br />

“popular” <strong>and</strong> between “entertainment” <strong>and</strong> “values”’ (47).<br />

This leads Hall <strong>and</strong> Whannel to what we might call the second part of their thesis:<br />

the necessity to recognize within popular culture a distinct category they call ‘popular<br />

art’. <strong>Popular</strong> art is not art that has attempted <strong>and</strong> failed to be ‘real’ art, but art which<br />

operates within the confines of the popular. Using the best of music hall, especially<br />

Marie Lloyd, as an example (but also thinking of the early Charlie Chaplin, The Goon<br />

Show <strong>and</strong> jazz musicians), they offer this definition:<br />

while retaining much in common with folk art, it became an individual art, existing<br />

within a literate commercial culture. Certain ‘folk’ elements were carried<br />

through, even though the artist replaced the anonymous folk artist, <strong>and</strong> the ‘style’<br />

was that of the performer rather than a communal style. The relationships here<br />

are more complex – the art is no longer simply created by the people from below<br />

– yet the interaction, by way of the conventions of presentation <strong>and</strong> feeling, reestablishes<br />

the rapport. Although this art is no longer directly the product of the<br />

‘way of life’ of an ‘organic community’, <strong>and</strong> is not ‘made by the people’, it is still,<br />

in a manner not applicable to the high arts, a popular art, for the people (59).<br />

According to this argument, good popular culture (‘popular art’) is able to re-establish<br />

the relationship (‘rapport’) between performer <strong>and</strong> audience that was lost with the<br />

advent of industrialization <strong>and</strong> urbanization. As they explain:<br />

<strong>Popular</strong> art . . . is essentially a conventional art which re-states, in an intense form,<br />

values <strong>and</strong> attitudes already known; which measures <strong>and</strong> reaffirms, but brings to


54<br />

Chapter 3 <strong>Cultural</strong>ism<br />

this something of the surprise of art as well as the shock of recognition. Such art<br />

has in common with folk art the genuine contact between audience <strong>and</strong> performer:<br />

but it differs from folk art in that it is an individualised art, the art of the known<br />

performer. The audience as community has come to depend on the performer’s<br />

skills, <strong>and</strong> on the force of a personal style, to articulate its common values <strong>and</strong><br />

interpret its experiences (66).<br />

One problem with their distinction between art <strong>and</strong> popular art is that it depends<br />

for its clarity on art as ‘surprise’, but this is art as defined in modernist terms. Before the<br />

modernist revolution in art, everything here claimed for popular art could equally have<br />

been claimed for art in general. They make a further distinction to include ‘mass art’.<br />

There is popular art (good <strong>and</strong> bad), <strong>and</strong> there is art (good <strong>and</strong> not so good), <strong>and</strong> there<br />

is mass art. Mass art is a ‘corrupt’ version of popular art; here they adopt uncritically<br />

the st<strong>and</strong>ard criticisms made of mass culture: it is formulaic, escapist, aesthetically<br />

worthless, emotionally unrewarding. Rather than confront the mass culture critique,<br />

they seek to privilege certain of the texts <strong>and</strong> practices of popular culture <strong>and</strong> thus<br />

remove them from the condemnation of the critics of mass culture. In order to do this<br />

they introduce a new category – the popular arts. <strong>Popular</strong> art is mass culture that has<br />

risen above its origins. Unlike ‘average films or pop music [which] are processed mass<br />

art’, popular art is, for example, the ‘best cinema’, the ‘most advanced jazz’ (78). They<br />

claim that, ‘Once the distinction between popular <strong>and</strong> mass art has been made, we find<br />

we have by-passed the cruder generalizations about “mass culture”, <strong>and</strong> are faced with<br />

the full range of material offered by the media’ (ibid.).<br />

The main focus of The <strong>Popular</strong> Arts is on the textual qualities of popular culture.<br />

However, when Hall <strong>and</strong> Whannel turn to questions of youth culture they find it necessary<br />

to discuss the interaction between text <strong>and</strong> audience. Moreover, they recognize<br />

that to do full justice to the relationship, they have to include other aspects of teenage<br />

life: ‘work, politics, the relation to the family, social <strong>and</strong> moral beliefs <strong>and</strong> so on’ (269).<br />

This of course begs the question why this is not also necessary when other aspects of<br />

popular culture are discussed. Pop music culture – songs, magazines, concerts, festivals,<br />

comics, interviews with pop stars, films, etc. – helps to establish a sense of identity<br />

among youth:<br />

The culture provided by the commercial entertainment market . . . plays a crucial<br />

role. It mirrors attitudes <strong>and</strong> sentiments which are already there, <strong>and</strong> at the same<br />

time provides an expressive field <strong>and</strong> a set of symbols through which these attitudes<br />

can be projected (276).<br />

Moreover, pop songs<br />

reflect adolescent difficulties in dealing with a tangle of emotional <strong>and</strong> sexual<br />

problems. They invoke the need to experience life directly <strong>and</strong> intensely. They


Stuart Hall <strong>and</strong> Paddy Whannel: The <strong>Popular</strong> Arts 55<br />

express the drive for security in an uncertain <strong>and</strong> changeable emotional world. The<br />

fact that they are produced for a commercial market means that the songs <strong>and</strong><br />

settings lack a certain authenticity. Yet they dramatize authentic feelings. They<br />

express vividly the adolescent emotional dilemma (280).<br />

Pop music exhibits ‘emotional realism’; young men <strong>and</strong> women ‘identify with these<br />

collective representations <strong>and</strong> . . . use them as guiding fictions. Such symbolic fictions<br />

are the folklore by means of which the teenager, in part, shapes <strong>and</strong> composes his<br />

mental picture of the world’ (281). Hall <strong>and</strong> Whannel also identify the way in which<br />

teenagers use particular ways of talking, particular places to go, particular ways of dancing,<br />

<strong>and</strong> particular ways of dressing, to establish distance from the world of adults.<br />

They describe dress style, for example, as ‘a minor popular art . . . used to express certain<br />

contemporary attitudes . . . for example, a strong current of social nonconformity<br />

<strong>and</strong> rebelliousness’ (282). This line of investigation would come to full fruition in the<br />

work of the Centre for Contemporary <strong>Cultural</strong> Studies, carried out during the 1970s,<br />

under the directorship of Hall himself. But here Hall <strong>and</strong> Whannel draw back from the<br />

full force of the possibilities opened up by their enquiries; anxious that an ‘anthropological<br />

. . . slack relativism’, with its focus on the functionality of pop music culture,<br />

would prevent them from posing questions of value <strong>and</strong> quality, about likes (‘are those<br />

likes enough?’) <strong>and</strong> needs (‘are the needs healthy ones?’) <strong>and</strong> taste (‘perhaps tastes can<br />

be extended’) (296).<br />

In their discussion of pop music culture, they concede that the claim that ‘the<br />

picture of young people as innocents exploited’ by the pop music industry ‘is oversimplified’<br />

(ibid.). Against this, they argue that there is very often conflict between the<br />

use made of a text, or a commodity that is turned into a text (see discussion of the<br />

difference in Chapter 10) by an audience, <strong>and</strong> the use intended by the producers.<br />

Significantly, they observe, ‘This conflict is particularly marked in the field of teenage<br />

entertainments . . . [although] it is to some extent common to the whole area of mass<br />

entertainment in a commercial setting’ (270). The recognition of the potential conflict<br />

between commodities <strong>and</strong> their use leads Hall <strong>and</strong> Whannel to a formulation that<br />

is remarkably similar to the cultural studies appropriation (led by Hall himself) of<br />

Gramsci’s concept of hegemony (see Chapter 4): ‘Teenage culture is a contradictory<br />

mixture of the authentic <strong>and</strong> manufactured: it is an area of self-expression for the<br />

young <strong>and</strong> a lush grazing pasture for the commercial providers’ (276).<br />

As we noted earlier, Hall <strong>and</strong> Whannel compare pop music unfavourably with<br />

jazz. They claim that jazz is ‘infinitely richer . . . both aesthetically <strong>and</strong> emotionally’<br />

(311). They also claim that the comparison is ‘much more rewarding’ than the more<br />

usual comparison between pop music <strong>and</strong> classical music, as both jazz <strong>and</strong> pop are<br />

popular musics. Now all this may be true, but what is the ultimate purpose of the<br />

comparison? In the case of classical against pop music, it is always to show the<br />

banality of pop music <strong>and</strong> to say something about those who consume it. Is Hall<br />

<strong>and</strong> Whannel’s comparison fundamentally any different? Here is their justification for<br />

the comparison:


56<br />

Chapter 3 <strong>Cultural</strong>ism<br />

The point behind such comparisons ought not to be simply to wean teenagers<br />

away from the juke-box heroes, but to alert them to the severe limitations <strong>and</strong><br />

ephemeral quality of music which is so formula dominated <strong>and</strong> so directly attuned<br />

to the st<strong>and</strong>ards set by the commercial market. It is a genuine widening of sensibility<br />

<strong>and</strong> emotional range which we should be working for – an extension<br />

of tastes which might lead to an extension of pleasure. The worst thing which<br />

we would say of pop music is not that it is vulgar, or morally wicked, but, more<br />

simply, that much of it is not very good (311–12).<br />

Despite the theoretical suggestiveness of much of their analysis (especially their<br />

identification of the contradictions of youth culture), <strong>and</strong> despite their protests to the<br />

contrary, their position on pop music culture is a position still struggling to free itself<br />

from the theoretical constraints of Leavisism: teenagers should be persuaded that their<br />

taste is deplorable <strong>and</strong> that by listening to jazz instead of pop music they might break<br />

out of imposed <strong>and</strong> self-imposed limitations, widen their sensibilities, broaden their<br />

emotional range, <strong>and</strong> perhaps even increase their pleasure. In the end, Hall <strong>and</strong><br />

Whannel’s position seems to drift very close to the teaching strategy they condemn as<br />

‘opportunist’ – in that they seem to suggest that because most school students do not<br />

have access, for a variety of reasons, to the best that has been thought <strong>and</strong> said, they<br />

can instead be given critical access to the best that has been thought <strong>and</strong> said within<br />

the popular arts of the new mass media: jazz <strong>and</strong> good films will make up for the<br />

absence of Beethoven <strong>and</strong> Shakespeare. As they explain,<br />

This process – the practical exclusion of groups <strong>and</strong> classes in society from the<br />

selective tradition of the best that has been <strong>and</strong> is being produced in the culture –<br />

is especially damaging in a democratic society, <strong>and</strong> applies to both the traditional<br />

<strong>and</strong> new forms of high art. However, the very existence of this problem makes it<br />

even more important that some of the media which are capable of communicating<br />

work of a serious <strong>and</strong> significant kind should remain open <strong>and</strong> available, <strong>and</strong> that<br />

the quality of popular work transmitted there should be of the highest order possible,<br />

on its own terms (75).<br />

Where they do break significantly with Leavisism is in that they advocate training<br />

in critical awareness, not as a means of defence against popular culture, but as a means<br />

to discriminate between what is good <strong>and</strong> what is bad within popular culture. It is<br />

a move which was to lead to a decisive break with Leavisism when the ideas of Hall<br />

<strong>and</strong> Whannel, <strong>and</strong> those of Hoggart, Williams <strong>and</strong> Thompson, were brought together<br />

under the banner of culturalism at the Birmingham University Centre for Contemporary<br />

<strong>Cultural</strong> Studies.


The Centre for Contemporary <strong>Cultural</strong> Studies<br />

The Centre for Contemporary <strong>Cultural</strong> Studies 57<br />

In the introduction to The Long Revolution, Williams (1965) regrets the fact that ‘there<br />

is no academic subject within which the questions I am interested in can be followed<br />

through; I hope one day there might be’ (10). Three years after the publication of these<br />

comments, Hoggart established the Centre for Contemporary <strong>Cultural</strong> Studies at the<br />

University of Birmingham. In the inaugural lecture, ‘Schools of English <strong>and</strong> contemporary<br />

society’, establishing the Centre, Hoggart (1970) states: ‘It is hard to listen to a<br />

programme of pop songs . . . without feeling a complex mixture of attraction <strong>and</strong><br />

repulsion’ (258). Once the work of the Centre began its transition, as Michael Green<br />

(1996) describes it, ‘from Hoggart to Gramsci’ (49), especially under the directorship<br />

of Hall, we find emerging a very different attitude towards pop music culture, <strong>and</strong> popular<br />

culture in general. Many of the researchers who followed Hoggart into the Centre<br />

(including myself) did not find listening to pop music in the least repulsive; on the<br />

contrary, we found it profoundly attractive. We focused on a different Hoggart, one<br />

critical of taking what is said at face value, a critic who proposed a procedure that<br />

would eventually resonate through the reading practices of cultural studies:<br />

we have to try <strong>and</strong> see beyond the habits to what the habits st<strong>and</strong> for, to see through<br />

the statements to what the statements really mean (which may be the opposite of<br />

the statements themselves), to detect the differing pressures of emotion behind<br />

idiomatic phrases <strong>and</strong> ritualistic observances. . . . [And to see the way] mass publications<br />

[for example] connect with commonly accepted attitudes, how they are<br />

altering those attitudes, <strong>and</strong> how they are meeting resistance (1990: 17–19).<br />

<strong>Cultural</strong>ists study cultural texts <strong>and</strong> practices in order to reconstitute or reconstruct<br />

the experiences, values, etc. – the ‘structure of feeling’ of particular groups or classes<br />

or whole societies, in order to better underst<strong>and</strong> the lives of those who lived the<br />

culture. In different ways Hoggart’s example, Williams’s social definition of culture,<br />

Thompson’s act of historical rescue, Hall <strong>and</strong> Whannel’s ‘democratic’ extension of<br />

Leavisism – each contribution discussed here argues that popular culture (defined as<br />

the lived culture of ordinary men <strong>and</strong> women) is worth studying. It is on the basis<br />

of these <strong>and</strong> other assumptions of culturalism, channelled through the traditions of<br />

English, sociology <strong>and</strong> history, that British cultural studies began. However, research at<br />

the Centre quickly brought culturalism into complex <strong>and</strong> often contradictory <strong>and</strong><br />

conflictual relations with imports of French structuralism (see Chapter 6), in turn<br />

bringing the two approaches into critical dialogue with developments in ‘western<br />

Marxism’, especially the work of Louis Althusser <strong>and</strong> Antonio Gramsci (see Chapter 4).<br />

It is from this complex <strong>and</strong> critical mixture that the ‘post-disciplinary’ field of British<br />

cultural studies was born.


58<br />

Chapter 3 <strong>Cultural</strong>ism<br />

Further reading<br />

Storey, John (ed.), <strong>Cultural</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Popular</strong> <strong>Culture</strong>: A Reader, 4th edition, Harlow:<br />

Pearson Education, 2009. This is the companion volume to this book. It contains<br />

examples of most of the work discussed here. This book <strong>and</strong> the companion Reader<br />

are supported by an interactive website (www.pearsoned.co.uk/storey). The website<br />

has links to other useful sites <strong>and</strong> electronic resources.<br />

Chambers, Iain, <strong>Popular</strong> <strong>Culture</strong>: The Metropolitan Experience, London: Routledge, 1986.<br />

An interesting <strong>and</strong> informed survey – mostly from the perspective of culturalism –<br />

of the rise of urban popular culture since the 1880s.<br />

Clarke, John, Chas Critcher <strong>and</strong> Richard Johnson (eds), Working Class <strong>Culture</strong>: Studies<br />

in History <strong>and</strong> <strong>Theory</strong>, London: Hutchinson, 1979. Some good essays from a culturalist<br />

perspective. See especially Richard Johnson’s ‘Three problematics: elements of<br />

a theory of working class culture’.<br />

Eagleton, Terry (ed.), Raymond Williams: Critical Perspectives, Cambridge: Polity Press,<br />

1989. Essays in critical appreciation of the work of Raymond Williams.<br />

Hall, Stuart <strong>and</strong> Tony Jefferson (eds), Resistance Through Rituals, London: Hutchinson,<br />

1976. The Centre for Contemporary <strong>Cultural</strong> Studies’ seminal account of youth subcultures.<br />

Chapter 1 provides a classic statement of the CCCS’s version of culturalism.<br />

Hall, Stuart, Dorothy Hobson, Andrew Lowe <strong>and</strong> Paul Willis (eds), <strong>Culture</strong>, Media,<br />

Language, London: Hutchinson, 1980. A selection of essays covering almost the first<br />

ten years of the CCCS’s published work. See especially Chapter 1, Stuart Hall’s<br />

important account of the theoretical development of work at the CCCS: ‘<strong>Cultural</strong><br />

studies <strong>and</strong> the Centre: some problematics <strong>and</strong> problems’.<br />

Jones, Paul, Raymond Williams’s Sociology of <strong>Culture</strong>: A Critical Reconstruction,<br />

Basingstoke: Palgrave, 2004. An interesting account. But its insistence on claiming<br />

Williams for sociology distorts his place in cultural studies.<br />

Kaye, Harvey J. <strong>and</strong> Keith McClell<strong>and</strong> (eds), E.P. Thompson: Critical Perspectives, Oxford:<br />

Polity Press, 1990. A collection of critical essays on different aspects of Thompson’s<br />

contribution to the study of history; some useful references to The Making of the<br />

English Working Class.<br />

O’Connor, Alan (ed.), Raymond Williams: Writing, <strong>Culture</strong>, Politics, Oxford: Basil Blackwell,<br />

1989. Provides a critical survey of Williams’s work. Excellent bibliography.


4 Marxisms<br />

Classical Marxism<br />

Marxism is a difficult <strong>and</strong> contentious body of work. But it is also more than this: it is<br />

a body of revolutionary theory with the purpose of changing the world. As Marx<br />

(1976b) famously said: ‘The philosophers have only interpreted the world, in various<br />

ways; the point is to change it’ (65). This makes Marxist analysis political in a quite<br />

specific way. But this is not to suggest that other methods <strong>and</strong> approaches are apolitical;<br />

on the contrary, Marxism insists that all are ultimately political. As the American<br />

Marxist cultural critic Fredric Jameson (1981) puts it, ‘the political perspective [is] the<br />

absolute horizon of all reading <strong>and</strong> all interpretation’ (17).<br />

The Marxist approach to culture insists that texts <strong>and</strong> practices must be analysed in<br />

relation to their historical conditions of production (<strong>and</strong> in some versions, the changing<br />

conditions of their consumption <strong>and</strong> reception). What makes the Marxist methodology<br />

different from other ‘historical’ approaches to culture is the Marxist conception<br />

of history. The fullest statement of the Marxist approach to history is contained in the<br />

Preface <strong>and</strong> Introduction to A Contribution to a Critique of Political Economy. Here Marx<br />

outlines the now famous ‘base/superstructure’ account of social <strong>and</strong> historical development.<br />

In Chapter 1, I discussed this formulation briefly in relation to different concepts<br />

of ideology. I will now explain the formulation in more detail <strong>and</strong> demonstrate<br />

how it might be used to underst<strong>and</strong> the ‘determinations’ that influence the production<br />

<strong>and</strong> consumption of popular culture.<br />

Marx argues that each significant period in history is constructed around a particular<br />

‘mode of production’: that is, the way in which a society is organized (i.e. slave, feudal,<br />

capitalist) to produce the necessaries of life – food, shelter, etc. In general terms, each<br />

mode of production produces: (i) specific ways of obtaining the necessaries of life; (ii)<br />

specific social relationships between workers <strong>and</strong> those who control the mode of production,<br />

<strong>and</strong> (iii) specific social institutions (including cultural ones). At the heart of<br />

this analysis is the claim that how a society produces its means of existence (its particular<br />

‘mode of production’) ultimately determines the political, social <strong>and</strong> cultural<br />

shape of that society <strong>and</strong> its possible future development. As Marx explains, ‘The mode<br />

of production of material life conditions the social, political <strong>and</strong> intellectual life process


60<br />

Chapter 4 Marxisms<br />

in general’ (1976a: 3). This claim is based on certain assumptions about the relationship<br />

between ‘base’ <strong>and</strong> ‘superstructure’. It is on this relationship – between ‘base’<br />

<strong>and</strong> ‘superstructure’ – that the Marxist account of culture rests.<br />

The ‘base’ consists of a combination of the ‘forces of production’ <strong>and</strong> the ‘relations<br />

of production’. The forces of production refer to the raw materials, the tools, the technology,<br />

the workers <strong>and</strong> their skills, etc. The relations of production refer to the class<br />

relations of those engaged in production. That is, each mode of production, besides<br />

being different, say, in terms of its basis in agrarian or industrial production, is also different<br />

in that it produces particular relations of production: the slave mode produces<br />

master/slave relations; the feudal mode produces lord/peasant relations; the capitalist<br />

mode produces bourgeois/proletariat relations. It is in this sense that one’s class position<br />

is determined by one’s relationship to the mode of production.<br />

The ‘superstructure’ (which develops in conjunction with a specific mode of<br />

production) consists of institutions (political, legal, educational, cultural, etc.), <strong>and</strong><br />

‘definite forms of social consciousness’ (political, religious, ethical, philosophical, aesthetic,<br />

cultural, etc.) generated by these institutions. The relationship between base <strong>and</strong><br />

superstructure is twofold. On the one h<strong>and</strong>, the superstructure both expresses <strong>and</strong> legitimates<br />

the base. On the other, the base is said to ‘condition’ or ‘determine’ the content<br />

<strong>and</strong> form of the superstructure. This relationship can be understood in a range of different<br />

ways. It can be seen as a mechanical relationship (‘economic determinism’) of<br />

cause <strong>and</strong> effect: what happens in the superstructure is a passive reflection of what is<br />

happening in the base. This often results in a vulgar Marxist ‘reflection theory’ of culture,<br />

in which the politics of a text or practice are read off from, or reduced to, the<br />

economic conditions of its production. The relationship can also be seen as the setting<br />

of limits, the providing of a specific framework in which some developments are probable<br />

<strong>and</strong> others unlikely.<br />

After Marx’s death in 1883, Frederick Engels, friend <strong>and</strong> collaborator, found<br />

himself having to explain, through a series of letters, many of the subtleties of Marxism<br />

to younger Marxists who, in their revolutionary enthusiasm, threatened to reduce<br />

it to a form of economic determinism. Here is part of his famous letter to Joseph<br />

Bloch:<br />

According to the materialist conception of history, the ultimately determining element<br />

in history is the production <strong>and</strong> reproduction of real life. Neither Marx nor I<br />

have ever asserted more than this. Therefore if somebody twists this into saying<br />

that the economic factor is the only determining one, he is transforming that<br />

proposition into a meaningless, abstract, absurd phrase. The economic situation is<br />

the basis, but the various components of the superstructure . . . also exercise their<br />

influence upon the course of the historical struggles <strong>and</strong> in many cases determine<br />

their form. . . . We make our own history, but, first of all, under very definite<br />

assumptions <strong>and</strong> conditions. Among these the economic ones are ultimately decisive.<br />

But the political ones, etc., <strong>and</strong> indeed even the traditions which haunt<br />

human minds also play a part, although not the decisive one (2009: 61).


Classical Marxism 61<br />

What Engels claims is that the economic base produces the superstructural terrain<br />

(this terrain <strong>and</strong> not that), but that the form of activity that takes place there is determined<br />

not just by the fact that the terrain was produced <strong>and</strong> is reproduced by the economic<br />

base (although this clearly sets limits <strong>and</strong> influences outcomes), but by the<br />

interaction of the institutions <strong>and</strong> the participants as they occupy the terrain. Therefore,<br />

although texts <strong>and</strong> practices are never the ‘primary force’ in history, they can be active<br />

agents in historical change or the servants of social stability.<br />

Marx <strong>and</strong> Engels (2009) claim that, ‘The ideas of the ruling class are in every epoch<br />

the ruling ideas, i.e. the class which is the ruling material force in society, is at the<br />

same time its ruling intellectual force’ (58). What they mean by this is that the dominant<br />

class, on the basis of its ownership of, <strong>and</strong> control over, the means of material<br />

production, is virtually guaranteed to have control over the means of intellectual production.<br />

However, this does not mean that the ideas of the ruling class are simply<br />

imposed on subordinate classes. A ruling class is ‘compelled . . . to represent its interest<br />

as the common interest of all the members of society . . . to give its ideas the form<br />

of universality, <strong>and</strong> represent them as the only rational, universally valid ones’ (59).<br />

Given the uncertainty of this project, ideological struggle is almost inevitable. During<br />

periods of social transformation it becomes chronic: as Marx (1976a) points out, it is<br />

in the ‘ideological forms’ of the superstructure (which include the texts <strong>and</strong> practices of<br />

popular culture) that men <strong>and</strong> women ‘become conscious of . . . conflict <strong>and</strong> fight it<br />

out’ (4).<br />

A classical Marxist approach to popular culture would above all else insist that to<br />

underst<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> explain a text or practice it must always be situated in its historical<br />

moment of production, analysed in terms of the historical conditions that produced it.<br />

There are dangers here: historical conditions are ultimately economic; therefore cultural<br />

analysis can quickly collapse into economic analysis (the cultural becomes a<br />

passive reflection of the economic). It is crucial, as Engels <strong>and</strong> Marx warn, <strong>and</strong>, as<br />

Thompson demonstrates (see Chapter 3), to keep in play a subtle dialectic between<br />

‘agency’ <strong>and</strong> ‘structure’. For example, a full analysis of nineteenth-century stage melodrama<br />

would have to weave together into focus both the economic changes that produced<br />

its audience <strong>and</strong> the theatrical traditions that produced its form. The same also<br />

holds true for a full analysis of music hall. Although in neither instance should performance<br />

be reduced to changes in the economic structure of society, what would be<br />

insisted on is that a full analysis of stage melodrama or music hall would not be possible<br />

without reference to the changes in theatre attendance brought about by changes<br />

in the economic structure of society. It is these changes, a Marxist analysis would argue,<br />

which ultimately produced the conditions of possibility for the performance of a play<br />

like My Poll <strong>and</strong> My Partner Joe, 10 <strong>and</strong> for the emergence <strong>and</strong> success of a performer like<br />

Marie Lloyd. In this way, then, a Marxist analysis would insist that ultimately, however<br />

indirectly, there is nevertheless a real <strong>and</strong> fundamental relationship between the emergence<br />

of stage melodrama <strong>and</strong> music hall <strong>and</strong> changes that took place in the capitalist<br />

mode of production. I have made a similar argument about the invention of the ‘traditional’<br />

English Christmas in the nineteenth century (Storey, 2009b).


62<br />

Chapter 4 Marxisms<br />

The Frankfurt School<br />

The Frankfurt School is the name given to a group of German intellectuals associated<br />

with the Institute for Social Research at the University of Frankfurt. The Institute was<br />

established in 1923. Following the coming to power of Hitler in 1933, it moved to<br />

New York, attaching itself to the University of Columbia. In 1949 it moved back to<br />

Germany. ‘Critical <strong>Theory</strong>’ is the name given to the Institute’s critical mix of Marxism<br />

<strong>and</strong> psychoanalysis. The Institute’s work on popular culture is mostly associated with<br />

the writings of Theodor Adorno, Walter Benjamin, Max Horkheimer, Leo Lowenthal<br />

<strong>and</strong> Herbert Marcuse.<br />

In 1944 Theodor Adorno <strong>and</strong> Max Horkheimer (1979) coined the term ‘culture<br />

industry’ to designate the products <strong>and</strong> processes of mass culture. The products of the<br />

culture industry, they claim, are marked by two features: homogeneity, ‘film, radio <strong>and</strong><br />

magazines make up a system which is uniform as a whole <strong>and</strong> in every part . . . all mass<br />

culture is identical’ (120–1); <strong>and</strong> predictability:<br />

As soon as the film begins, it is quite clear how it will end, <strong>and</strong> who will be<br />

rewarded, punished, or forgotten. In light music [popular music], once the trained<br />

ear has heard the first notes of the hit song, it can guess what is coming <strong>and</strong> feel<br />

flattered when it does come. . . . The result is a constant reproduction of the same<br />

thing (125, 134).<br />

Whereas Arnold <strong>and</strong> Leavisism had worried that popular culture represented a threat<br />

to cultural <strong>and</strong> social authority, the Frankfurt School argue that it actually produces the<br />

opposite effect; it maintains social authority. Where Arnold <strong>and</strong> Leavis saw ‘anarchy’,<br />

the Frankfurt School see only ‘conformity’: a situation in which ‘the deceived masses’<br />

(133) are caught in a ‘circle of manipulation <strong>and</strong> retroactive need in which the unity<br />

of the system grows ever stronger’ (121). Here is Adorno reading an American situation<br />

comedy about a young schoolteacher who is both underpaid [some things do<br />

not change], <strong>and</strong> continually fined by her school principal. As a result, she is without<br />

money <strong>and</strong> therefore without food. The humour of the storyline consists in her various<br />

attempts to secure a meal at the expense of friends <strong>and</strong> acquaintances. In his reading<br />

of this situation comedy, Adorno is guided by the assumption that whilst it is<br />

always difficult, if not impossible, to establish the unmistakable ‘message’ of a work of<br />

‘authentic’ culture, the ‘hidden message’ of a piece of mass culture is not at all difficult<br />

to discern. According to Adorno (1991a), ‘the script implies’:<br />

If you are humorous, good natured, quick witted, <strong>and</strong> charming as she is, do not<br />

worry about being paid a starvation wage. . . . In other words, the script is a shrewd<br />

method of promoting adjustment to humiliating conditions by presenting them as<br />

objectively comical <strong>and</strong> by giving a picture of a person who experiences even her<br />

own inadequate position as an object of fun apparently free of any resentment<br />

(143–4).


The Frankfurt School 63<br />

This is one way of reading this TV comedy. But it is by no means the only way.<br />

Bertolt Brecht, Benjamin’s close friend (considered to be ‘crude’ by Adorno), might<br />

have offered another way of reading, one that implies a less passive audience. Discussing<br />

his own play, Mother Courage <strong>and</strong> Her Children, Brecht (1978) suggests, ‘Even if<br />

Courage learns nothing else at least the audience can, in my view, learn something by<br />

observing her’ (229). The same point can be made against Adorno with reference to the<br />

schoolteacher’s behaviour.<br />

Leo Lowenthal (1961) contends that the culture industry, by producing a culture<br />

marked by ‘st<strong>and</strong>ardisation, stereotype, conservatism, mendacity, manipulated consumer<br />

goods’ (11), has worked to depoliticize the working class – limiting its horizon<br />

to political <strong>and</strong> economic goals that could be realized within the oppressive <strong>and</strong><br />

exploitative framework of capitalist society. He maintains that, ‘Whenever revolutionary<br />

tendencies show a timid head, they are mitigated <strong>and</strong> cut short by a false<br />

fulfilment of wish-dreams, like wealth, adventure, passionate love, power <strong>and</strong> sensationalism<br />

in general’ (ibid.). In short, the culture industry discourages the ‘masses’<br />

from thinking beyond the confines of the present. As Herbert Marcuse (1968a) claims<br />

in One Dimensional Man:<br />

the irresistible output of the entertainment <strong>and</strong> information industry [the culture<br />

industry] carry with them prescribed attitudes <strong>and</strong> habits, certain intellectual <strong>and</strong><br />

emotional reactions which bind the consumers more or less pleasantly to the producers<br />

<strong>and</strong>, through the latter, to the whole. The products indoctrinate <strong>and</strong> manipulate;<br />

they promote a false consciousness which is immune against its falsehood<br />

. . . it becomes a way of life. It is a good way of life – much better than before – <strong>and</strong><br />

as a good way of life, it militates against qualitative change. Thus emerges a pattern<br />

of one-dimensional thought <strong>and</strong> behaviour in which ideas, aspirations, <strong>and</strong> objectives<br />

that, by their content, transcend the established universe of discourse <strong>and</strong><br />

action are either repelled or reduced to terms of this universe (26–7).<br />

In other words, by supplying the means to the satisfaction of certain needs, capitalism<br />

is able to prevent the formation of more fundamental desires. The culture industry thus<br />

stunts the political imagination.<br />

As with Arnold <strong>and</strong> Leavisism, art or high culture is seen to be working differently.<br />

It embodies ideals denied by capitalism. As such it offers an implicit critique of<br />

capitalist society, an alternative, utopian vision. ‘Authentic’ culture, according to<br />

Horkheimer (1978), has taken over the utopian function of religion: to keep alive the<br />

human desire for a better world beyond the confines of the present; it carries the key<br />

to unlock the prison-house established by the development of mass culture by the<br />

capitalist culture industry (5). But increasingly the processes of the culture industry<br />

threaten the radical potential of ‘authentic’ culture. The culture industry increasingly<br />

flattens out what remains of<br />

the antagonism between culture <strong>and</strong> social reality through the obliteration of the<br />

oppositional, alien, <strong>and</strong> transcendent elements in the higher culture by virtue of which


64<br />

Chapter 4 Marxisms<br />

it constituted another dimension of reality. This liquidation of two-dimensional<br />

culture takes place not through the denial <strong>and</strong> rejection of the ‘cultural values’, but<br />

through their wholesale incorporation into the established order, through their<br />

reproduction <strong>and</strong> display on a massive scale (Marcuse, 1968a: 58).<br />

Therefore, the better future promised by ‘authentic’ culture is no longer in contradiction<br />

with the unhappy present – a spur to make the better future; culture now<br />

confirms that this is the better future – here <strong>and</strong> now – the only better future. It offers<br />

‘fulfilment’ instead of the promotion of ‘desire’. Marcuse holds to the hope that the<br />

‘most advanced images <strong>and</strong> positions’ of ‘authentic’ culture may still resist ‘absorption’<br />

<strong>and</strong> ‘continue to haunt the consciousness with the possibility of their rebirth’ in a<br />

better tomorrow (60). He also hopes that one day those on the margins of society, ‘the<br />

outcasts <strong>and</strong> outsiders’ (61), who are out of reach of the full grasp of the culture industry,<br />

will undo the defeats, fulfil the hopes, <strong>and</strong> make capitalism keep all its promises in<br />

a world beyond capitalism. Or, as Horkheimer (1978) observes,<br />

One day we may learn that in the depths of their hearts, the masses . . . secretly<br />

knew the truth <strong>and</strong> disbelieved the lie, like catatonic patients who make known<br />

only at the end of their trance that nothing had escaped them. Therefore it may not<br />

be entirely senseless to continue speaking a language that is not easily understood<br />

(17).<br />

But, as Adorno (1991b) points out, mass culture is a difficult system to challenge:<br />

Today anyone who is incapable of talking in the prescribed fashion, that is of<br />

effortlessly reproducing the formulas, conventions <strong>and</strong> judgments of mass culture<br />

as if they were his own, is threatened in his very existence, suspected of being an<br />

idiot or an intellectual (79).<br />

The culture industry, in its search for profits <strong>and</strong> cultural homogeneity, deprives<br />

‘authentic’ culture of its critical function, its mode of negation – ‘[its] Great Refusal’<br />

(Marcuse, 1968a: 63). Commodification (sometimes understood by other critics as<br />

‘commercialization’) devalues ‘authentic’ culture, making it too accessible by turning it<br />

into yet another saleable commodity.<br />

The neo-conservative critics of leftist critics of mass culture ridicule the protest<br />

against Bach as background music in the kitchen, against Plato <strong>and</strong> Hegel, Shelley<br />

<strong>and</strong> Baudelaire, Marx <strong>and</strong> Freud in the drugstore. Instead, they insist on recognition<br />

of the fact that the classics have left the mausoleum <strong>and</strong> come to life again,<br />

that people are just so much more educated. True, but coming to life as classics,<br />

they come to life as other than themselves; they are deprived of their antagonistic<br />

force, of the estrangement which was the very dimension of their truth. The intent<br />

<strong>and</strong> function of these works have thus fundamentally changed. If they once stood<br />

in contradiction to the status quo, this contradiction is now flattened out (63–4).


The Frankfurt School 65<br />

It is not difficult to think of examples of this process (whether or not we read them in<br />

quite the same way, leftist or neo-conservative). In the 1960s, a bedsit without a poster<br />

of Che Guevara was hardly furnished at all. Was the poster a sign of a commitment to<br />

revolutionary politics or a commitment to the latest fashion (or was it a complicated<br />

mixture of both)? Bennett (1977) provides a telling example of an advertisement<br />

inserted in The Times in 1974:<br />

an advertisement which consisted of a full page colour reproduction of Matisse’s<br />

Le Pont, below which there appeared the legend: ‘Business is our life, but life isn’t<br />

all business.’ Profoundly contradictory, what was ostensibly opposed to economic<br />

life was made to become a part of it, what was separate became assimilated since<br />

any critical dimension which might have pertained to Matisse’s painting was<br />

eclipsed by its new <strong>and</strong> unsolicited function as an advertisement for the wares of<br />

finance capital (45).<br />

We might also think of the way opera <strong>and</strong> classical music is used to sell anything<br />

from bread to expensive motorcars (for examples see Table 4.1). Is it possible, for<br />

instance, to hear the second movement from Dvoqák’s New World Symphony, without<br />

conjuring up an image of Hovis bread?<br />

It is not that Marcuse or the other members of the Frankfurt School object to the<br />

‘democratization’ of culture, only that they believe that the culture industry’s ‘assimilation<br />

is historically premature; it establishes cultural equality while preserving domination’<br />

(Marcuse, 1968a: 64). In short, the democratization of culture results in the<br />

blocking of the dem<strong>and</strong> for full democracy; it stabilizes the prevailing social order.<br />

According to the Frankfurt School, work <strong>and</strong> leisure under capitalism form a compelling<br />

relationship: the effects of the culture industry are guaranteed by the nature of<br />

work; the work process secures the effects of the culture industry. The function of the<br />

culture industry is therefore, ultimately, to organize leisure time in the same way as<br />

industrialization has organized work time. Work under capitalism stunts the senses;<br />

the culture industry continues the process: ‘The escape from everyday drudgery which<br />

the whole culture industry promises . . . [is a] paradise ...[of] the same old drudgery . . .<br />

escape . . . [is] predesigned to lead back to the starting point. Pleasure promotes the<br />

resignation which it ought to help to forget’ (Adorno <strong>and</strong> Horkheimer, 1979: 142). In<br />

short, work leads to mass culture; mass culture leads back to work. Similarly, art or<br />

‘authentic’ culture circulated by the culture industry operates in the same way. Only<br />

‘authentic’ culture operating outside the confines of the culture industry could ever<br />

hope to break the cycle.<br />

To make more concrete these general points, I will now examine a specific example<br />

of the Frankfurt School’s approach to popular culture – Adorno’s (2009) essay, ‘On<br />

popular music’. In the essay he makes three specific claims about popular music. First,<br />

he claims that it is ‘st<strong>and</strong>ardised’. ‘St<strong>and</strong>ardisation’ as Adorno points out, ‘extends from<br />

the most general features to the most specific ones’ (64). Once a musical <strong>and</strong>/or lyrical<br />

pattern has proved successful it is exploited to commercial exhaustion, culminating<br />

in ‘the crystallisation of st<strong>and</strong>ards’ (ibid.). Moreover, details from one popular song


66<br />

Chapter 4 Marxisms<br />

Table 4.1 Depriving ‘authentic’ culture of its critical function.<br />

The Use of Opera <strong>and</strong> Classical Music in Advertisements<br />

Bach: Suite No. 3 in D – Hamlet Cigars<br />

Bach: Sleepers Awake! – Lloyds Bank<br />

Bach: Harpsichord Concerto in F minor –<br />

NASDAQ<br />

Beethoven: Symphony No. 6 in F – Blueb<strong>and</strong><br />

Margarine<br />

Beethoven: Für Elise – Heinz Spaghetti/Uncle<br />

Ben’s rice<br />

Bellini: Norma – Ford Mondeo<br />

Boccherini: Minuet – Save <strong>and</strong> Prosper<br />

Building Society<br />

Britten: Simple Symphony Opus 4 – Royal Bank<br />

of Scotl<strong>and</strong><br />

Debussy: Suite bergamasque – Boursin Cheese<br />

Delibes: Lakmé – British Airways/Basmati Rice/<br />

Ryvita/IBM Computers/Kleenex tissues<br />

Delibes: Coppelia – Jus-Rol<br />

Dukas: The Sorcerer’s Apprentice – Fiesta<br />

Towels/Sun Liquid/Royal Bank of Scotl<strong>and</strong>/<br />

Philips/DCC<br />

Dvocák: New World Symphony – Hovis Bread<br />

Fauré: Requiem Opus 48 – Lurpak Butter<br />

Gluck: Orfeo ed Euridice – Comfort Fabric<br />

Softener<br />

Grieg: Peer Gynt – Nescafe/AEG/Alton Towers<br />

H<strong>and</strong>el: Serse – Rover<br />

H<strong>and</strong>el: Solomon – Woolworths<br />

Holst: The Planet Suite – Dulux Weathershield<br />

Khachaturian: Spartacus – Nescafe<br />

Mascagni: Cavalleria rusticana – Kleenex<br />

tissues/Stella Artois/Baci Chocolates<br />

Mozart: Piano Concerto No. 21 – Aer Lingus<br />

Mozart: The Marriage of Figaro – Citroën ZX<br />

Mozart: Cosí fan tutte – Mercedes Benz<br />

Mozart: Horn Concerto No. 4 – Vauxhall Carlton<br />

Mussorgsky: Night on a Bare Mountain –<br />

Maxell Tapes<br />

Offenbach: Tales of Hoffmann – Bailey’s Irish<br />

Cream<br />

Offenbach: Orpheus in the Underworld – Bio<br />

Speed Weed<br />

Orff: Carmina Burana – Old Spice/Carling Black<br />

Label/Fiat Marea<br />

Pachelbel: Canon in D – Thresher Wines<br />

Prokofiev: Peter <strong>and</strong> the Wolf – Vauxhall Astra<br />

Prokofiev: Romeo <strong>and</strong> Juliet – Chanel L’Egoiste<br />

Puccini: Madama Butterfly – Twinings tea/<br />

Del Monte orange juice<br />

Puccini: Gianni Schicchi – Phillips DCC<br />

Puccini: La Bohème – Sony Walkman<br />

Puccini: Tosca – FreeServe<br />

Ravel: Boléro – Ryvita<br />

Rimsky-Korsakov: Tsar Saltan – Black <strong>and</strong><br />

Decker<br />

Rossini: The Barber of Seville – Ragu Pasta<br />

Sauce/Fiat Strada/Braun cordless shavers<br />

Saint-Saëns: Carnival of the Animals – Tesco<br />

Satie: Gymnopédie No. 3 – Bourneville<br />

Chocolate/Strepsils lozenges<br />

Schumann: Scenes from Childhood –<br />

Chocolate Break<br />

Smetana: Má Vlast – Peugeot 605<br />

J Strauss: Morning Papers Waltz – TSB<br />

Tchaikovsky: The Nutcracker Suite – Reactolite<br />

sunglasses/Cadbury’s Fruit <strong>and</strong><br />

Nut/Hellmann’s Mayonnaise<br />

Verdi: Aida – Diet Pepsi/Michelob/Egypt<br />

Verdi: Il Trovatore – Ragu Pasta Sauce<br />

Verdi: La Forza del Destino – Stella Artois<br />

Verdi: Nabucco – British Airways<br />

Verdi: Rigoletto – Ragu Pasta Sauce/Little<br />

Caesar’s Pizza<br />

Vivaldi: The Four Seasons – Chanel 19<br />

perfume/Kingsmill Bread/Citroën BX/Braun<br />

can be interchanged with details from another. Unlike the organic structure of ‘serious<br />

music’, where each detail expresses the whole, popular music is mechanical in the<br />

sense that a given detail can be shifted from one song to another without any real effect<br />

on the structure as a whole. In order to conceal st<strong>and</strong>ardization, the music industry


The Frankfurt School 67<br />

engages in what Adorno calls ‘pseudo-individualization’: ‘St<strong>and</strong>ardisation of song hits<br />

keeps the customers in line by doing their listening for them, as it were. Pseudoindividualization,<br />

for its part, keeps them in line by making them forget that what they<br />

listen to is already listened to for them, or “pre-digested”’ (69).<br />

Adorno’s second claim is that popular music promotes passive listening. As already<br />

noted, work under capitalism is dull <strong>and</strong> therefore promotes the search for escape,<br />

but, because it is also dulling, it leaves little energy for real escape – the dem<strong>and</strong>s of<br />

‘authentic’ culture. Instead refuge is sought in forms such as popular music – the consumption<br />

of which is always passive, <strong>and</strong> endlessly repetitive, confirming the world as<br />

it is. Whereas ‘serious’ music (Beethoven, for example) plays to the pleasure of the<br />

imagination, offering an engagement with the world as it could be, popular music is the<br />

‘non-productive correlate’ (70) to life in the office or on the factory floor. The ‘strain<br />

<strong>and</strong> boredom’ of work lead men <strong>and</strong> women to the ‘avoidance of effort’ in their leisure<br />

time (ibid.). Adorno makes it all sound like the hopeless ritual of a heroin addict (as<br />

taken from the detective genre he detested so much). Denied ‘novelty’ in their work<br />

time, <strong>and</strong> too exhausted for it in their leisure time, ‘they crave a stimulant’ – popular<br />

music satisfies the craving.<br />

Its stimulations are met with the inability to vest effort in the ever-identical. This<br />

means boredom again. It is a circle which makes escape impossible. The impossibility<br />

of escape causes the widespread attitude of inattention toward popular<br />

music. The moment of recognition is that of effortless sensation. The sudden attention<br />

attached to this moment burns itself out instanter <strong>and</strong> relegates the listener to<br />

a realm of inattention <strong>and</strong> distraction (71).<br />

<strong>Popular</strong> music operates in a kind of blurred dialectic: to consume it dem<strong>and</strong>s inattention<br />

<strong>and</strong> distraction, whilst its consumption produces in the consumer inattention <strong>and</strong><br />

distraction.<br />

Adorno’s third point is the claim that popular music operates as ‘social cement’ (72).<br />

Its ‘socio-psychological function’ is to achieve in the consumers of popular music ‘psychical<br />

adjustment’ to the needs of the prevailing structure of power (ibid.). This ‘adjustment’<br />

manifests itself in ‘two major socio-psychological types of mass behaviour . . .<br />

the “rhythmically” obedient type <strong>and</strong> the “emotional” type’ (ibid.). The first type dances<br />

in distraction to the rhythm of his or her own exploitation <strong>and</strong> oppression. The second<br />

type wallows in sentimental misery, oblivious to the real conditions of existence.<br />

There are a number of points to be made about Adorno’s analysis. First, we must<br />

acknowledge that he is writing in 1941. <strong>Popular</strong> music has changed a great deal since<br />

then. However, having said that, Adorno never thought to change his analysis following<br />

the changes that occurred in popular music up until his death in 1969. Is<br />

popular music as monolithic as he would have us believe? For example, does pseudoindividualization<br />

really explain the advent of rock’n’roll in 1956, the emergence of the<br />

Beatles in 1962, the music of the counterculture in 1965? Does it explain punk rock<br />

<strong>and</strong> Rock Against Racism in the 1970s, acid house <strong>and</strong> indie pop in the 1980s, rave <strong>and</strong><br />

hip hop in the 1990s? Moreover, is the consumption of popular music as passive as


68<br />

Chapter 4 Marxisms<br />

Adorno claims? Simon Frith (1983) provides sales figures that suggest not: ‘despite the<br />

difficulties of the calculations . . . most business commentators agree that about 10 per<br />

cent of all records released (a little less for singles, a little more for LPs) make money’<br />

(147). In addition to this, only about another 10 per cent cover their costs (ibid.). This<br />

means that about 80 per cent of records actually lose money. Moreover, Paul Hirsch<br />

has calculated that at least 60 per cent of singles released are never played by anyone<br />

(cited in Frith, 1983: 147). This does not suggest the workings of an all-powerful culture<br />

industry, easily able to manipulate its consumers. It sounds more like a culture<br />

industry trying desperately to sell records to a critical <strong>and</strong> discriminating public.<br />

Such figures certainly imply that consumption is rather more active than Adorno’s<br />

argument suggests. Subcultural use of music is clearly at the leading edge of such active<br />

discrimination, but is by no means the only example. Finally, does popular music<br />

really function as social cement? Subcultures or music taste cultures, for instance,<br />

would appear to consume popular music in a way not too dissimilar to Adorno’s ideal<br />

mode for the consumption of ‘serious music’. Richard Dyer (1990) argues that this is<br />

certainly the case with regard to the gay consumption of disco. He detects a certain<br />

romanticism in disco that keeps alive a way of being that is always in conflict with the<br />

mundane <strong>and</strong> the everyday. As he explains, ‘Romanticism asserts that the limits of<br />

work <strong>and</strong> domesticity are not the limits of experience’ (417).<br />

The analysis offered by the majority of the Frankfurt School works with a series<br />

of binary oppositions held in place by the supposed fundamental difference between<br />

culture <strong>and</strong> mass culture (Table 4.2).<br />

Walter Benjamin’s (1973) essay ‘The work of art in the age of mechanical reproduction’<br />

is much more optimistic about the possibility of a revolutionary transformation<br />

of capitalism. He claims that capitalism will ‘ultimately . . . create conditions which<br />

would make it possible to abolish capitalism itself’ (219). Benjamin believes that<br />

changes in the technological reproduction of culture are changing the function of culture<br />

in society: ‘technical reproduction can put the copy of the original into situations<br />

which would be out of reach for the original itself’ (222). Reproduction thus challenges<br />

what Benjamin calls the ‘aura’ of texts <strong>and</strong> practices.<br />

Table 4.2 ‘<strong>Culture</strong>’ <strong>and</strong> ‘mass culture’ according to the Frankfurt School.<br />

<strong>Culture</strong> Mass culture<br />

Real False<br />

European American<br />

Multi-dimensional One-dimensional<br />

Active consumption Passive consumption<br />

Individual creation Mass production<br />

Imagination Distraction<br />

Negation Social cement


The Frankfurt School 69<br />

One might generalise by saying: the technique of reproduction detaches the reproduced<br />

object from the domain of tradition. By making many reproductions it<br />

substitutes a plurality of copies for a unique existence. And in permitting the reproduction<br />

to meet the beholder or listener in his own particular situation, it reactivates<br />

the object reproduced. These two processes lead to a tremendous shattering<br />

of tradition . . . Their most powerful agent is film. Its social significance, particularly<br />

in its most positive form, is inconceivable without its destructive, cathartic aspect,<br />

that is, the liquidation of the traditional value of the cultural heritage (223).<br />

The ‘aura’ of a text or practice is its sense of ‘authenticity’, ‘authority’, ‘autonomy’<br />

<strong>and</strong> ‘distance’. The decay of the aura detaches the text or practice from the authority<br />

<strong>and</strong> rituals of tradition. It opens them to a plurality of reinterpretation, freeing them to<br />

be used in other contexts, for other purposes. No longer embedded in tradition,<br />

significance is now open to dispute; meaning becomes a question of consumption,<br />

an active (political), rather than a passive (for Adorno: psychological) event. Technological<br />

reproduction changes production: ‘To an ever greater degree the work of art<br />

reproduced becomes the work of art designed for reproducibility’ (226). Consumption<br />

is also changed: from its location in religious ritual to its location in the rituals of<br />

aesthetics, consumption is now based on the practice of politics. <strong>Culture</strong> may have<br />

become mass culture, but consumption has not become mass consumption.<br />

Mechanical reproduction of art changes the reaction of the masses toward art. The<br />

reactionary attitude toward a Picasso painting changes into the progressive reaction<br />

toward a Chaplin movie. The progressive reaction is characterised by the direct,<br />

intimate fusion of visual <strong>and</strong> emotional enjoyment with the orientation of the<br />

expert (236).<br />

Questions of meaning <strong>and</strong> consumption shift from passive contemplation to active<br />

political struggle. Benjamin’s celebration of the positive potential of ‘mechanical reproduction’,<br />

his view that it begins the process of a move from an ‘auratic’ culture to a<br />

‘democratic’ culture in which meaning is no longer seen as unique, but open to question,<br />

open to use <strong>and</strong> mobilization, has had a profound (if often unacknowledged)<br />

influence on cultural theory <strong>and</strong> popular culture. Susan Willis (1991) describes<br />

Benjamin’s essay thus: ‘This may well be the single most important essay in the development<br />

of Marxist popular culture criticism’ (10). Whereas Adorno locates meaning in<br />

the mode of production (how a cultural text is produced determines its consumption<br />

<strong>and</strong> significance), Benjamin suggests that meaning is produced at the moment of consumption;<br />

significance is determined by the process of consumption, regardless of the<br />

mode of production. As Frith points out, the ‘debate’ 11 between Adorno <strong>and</strong> Benjamin<br />

– between a socio-psychological account of consumption combined with an insistence<br />

on the determining power of production, against the argument that consumption is<br />

a matter of politics – continues to be argued in contemporary accounts of popular<br />

music: ‘Out of Adorno have come analyses of the economics of entertainment . . . [<strong>and</strong><br />

the] ideological effects of commercial music making. . . . From Benjamin have come


70<br />

Chapter 4 Marxisms<br />

subcultural theories, descriptions of the struggle . . . to make their own meanings in<br />

their acts of consumption’ (57).<br />

Despite its Marxist sophistication <strong>and</strong> admirable political intent, the approach of<br />

the Frankfurt School to popular culture (with the exception of Benjamin) would in<br />

some respects fit easily into the ‘culture <strong>and</strong> civilization’ tradition discussed in Chapter 2.<br />

Like the perspective developed by Arnold, Leavisism <strong>and</strong> some of the American mass<br />

culture theorists, the Frankfurt School perspective on popular culture is essentially a<br />

discourse from above on the culture of other people (a discourse of ‘us’ <strong>and</strong> ‘them’).<br />

It is true that the Frankfurt School are very critical of conservative cultural critics<br />

who bemoaned the passing of, or threat to, a ‘pure’ autonomous culture for its own<br />

sake. Adorno, as J.M. Bernstein (1978) points out, ‘regards the conservative defence<br />

of high culture as reflecting an unreflective hypostatization of culture that protects<br />

the economic status quo’ (15). Nevertheless, it remains the case that there are certain<br />

similarities between the focus of the ‘culture <strong>and</strong> civilization’ tradition <strong>and</strong> that of<br />

the Frankfurt School. They condemn the same things, but for different reasons. The<br />

‘culture <strong>and</strong> civilization’ tradition attack mass culture because it threatens cultural st<strong>and</strong>ards<br />

<strong>and</strong> social authority, the Frankfurt School attack mass culture because it threatens<br />

cultural st<strong>and</strong>ards <strong>and</strong> depoliticizes the working class, <strong>and</strong> thus maintains the iron grip<br />

of social authority: ‘obedience to the rhythm of the iron system . . . the absolute power<br />

of capitalism’ (Adorno <strong>and</strong> Horkheimer, 1979: 120; my italics). It is very difficult to<br />

imagine the possibility of political agency in a situation of absolute power.<br />

Althusserianism<br />

The ideas of Louis Althusser have had an enormous influence on cultural theory <strong>and</strong><br />

popular culture. As Hall (1978) suggests, ‘Althusser’s interventions <strong>and</strong> their consequent<br />

development are enormously formative for the field of cultural studies’ (21).<br />

Althusser’s most significant contribution to the field is his different attempts to theorize<br />

the concept of ideology. I shall therefore restrict discussion to this aspect of his<br />

work.<br />

Althusser begins by rejecting mechanistic interpretation of the base/superstructure<br />

formulation, insisting instead on the concept of the social formation. According to<br />

Althusser (1969), a social formation consists of three practices: the economic, the<br />

political <strong>and</strong> the ideological. The relationship between the base <strong>and</strong> the superstructure<br />

is not one of expression, i.e. the superstructure being an expression or passive reflection<br />

of the base, but rather the superstructure is seen as necessary to the existence of the<br />

base. The model allows for the relative autonomy of the superstructure. Determination<br />

remains, but it is determination in ‘the last instance’. This operates through what he<br />

calls the ‘structure in dominance’; that is, although the economic is always ultimately<br />

‘determinant’, this does not mean that in a particular historical conjuncture it will necessarily<br />

be dominant. Under feudalism, for example, the political was the dominant


Althusserianism 71<br />

level. Nevertheless, the practice that is dominant in a particular social formation will<br />

depend on the specific form of economic production. What he means by this is that<br />

the economic contradictions of capitalism never take a pure form: ‘the lonely hour of<br />

the last instance never comes’ (113). The economic is determinant in the last instance,<br />

not because the other instances are its epiphenomena, but because it determines which<br />

practice is dominant. In volume one of Capital, Marx (1976c) makes a similar point in<br />

response to criticisms suggesting definite limits to the critical reach of Marxist analysis:<br />

[Marxism, so its critics say,] is all very true for our own time, in which material<br />

interests are preponderant, but not for the Middle Ages, dominated by Catholicism,<br />

nor for Athens <strong>and</strong> Rome, dominated by politics. . . . One thing is clear: the<br />

Middle Ages could not live on Catholicism, nor could the ancient world on politics.<br />

On the contrary, it is the manner in which they gained their livelihood which<br />

explains why in one case politics, in the other case Catholicism, played the chief<br />

part. . . . And then there is Don Quixote, who long ago paid the penalty for<br />

wrongly imagining that knight errantry was compatible with all economic forms of<br />

society (176).<br />

Althusser produced three definitions of ideology, two of which have proved particularly<br />

fruitful for the student of popular culture. The first definition, which overlaps in<br />

some ways with the second, is the claim that ideology – ‘a system (with its own logic<br />

<strong>and</strong> rigour) of representations (images, myths, ideas or concepts)’ (1969: 231) – is a<br />

‘practice’ through which men <strong>and</strong> women live their relations to the real conditions of<br />

existence. ‘By practice ...I...mean any process of transformation of a determinate<br />

given raw material into a determinate product, a transformation effected by a determinate<br />

human labour, using determinate means (of “production”)’ (166). Therefore,<br />

as the economic, the historically specific mode of production, transforms certain raw<br />

materials into products by determinate means of production, involving determinate<br />

relations of production, so ideological practice shapes an individual’s lived relations<br />

to the social formation. In this way, ideology dispels contradictions in lived experience.<br />

It accomplishes this by offering false, but seemingly true, resolutions to real problems.<br />

This is not a ‘conscious’ process; ideology ‘is profoundly unconscious’ (233) in its<br />

mode of operation.<br />

In ideology men . . . express, not the relation between them <strong>and</strong> their conditions<br />

of existence, but the way they live the relation between them <strong>and</strong> their conditions<br />

of existence: this presupposes both a real relation <strong>and</strong> an ‘imaginary’, ‘lived’ relation.<br />

Ideology . . . is the expression of the relation between men <strong>and</strong> their ‘world’,<br />

that is, the (overdetermined) unity of the real relation <strong>and</strong> the imaginary relation<br />

between them <strong>and</strong> their real conditions of existence (233–4).<br />

The relationship is both real <strong>and</strong> imaginary in the sense that ideology is the way we<br />

live our relationship to the real conditions of existence at the level of representations<br />

(myths, concepts, ideas, images, discourses): there are real conditions <strong>and</strong> there are the


72<br />

Chapter 4 Marxisms<br />

ways we represent these conditions to ourselves <strong>and</strong> to others. This applies to both<br />

dominant <strong>and</strong> subordinate classes; ideologies do not just convince oppressed groups<br />

that all is well with the world, they also convince ruling groups that exploitation <strong>and</strong><br />

oppression are really something quite different, acts of universal necessity. Only a<br />

‘scientific’ discourse (Althusser’s Marxism) can see through ideology to the real conditions<br />

of existence.<br />

Because ideology is for Althusser a closed system, it can only ever set itself such<br />

problems as it can answer; that is, to remain within its boundaries (a mythic realm<br />

without contradictions), it must stay silent on questions which threaten to take it<br />

beyond these boundaries. This formulation leads Althusser to the concept of the ‘problematic’.<br />

He first uses the concept to explain the ‘epistemological break’, which he<br />

claims occurs in Marx’s work in 1845. Marx’s problematic, ‘the objective internal reference<br />

system . . . the system of questions comm<strong>and</strong>ing the answers given’ (67), determines<br />

not only the questions <strong>and</strong> answers he is able to bring into play, but also the<br />

absence of problems <strong>and</strong> concepts in his work.<br />

According to Althusser a problematic consists of the assumptions, motivations,<br />

underlying ideas, etc., from which a text (say, an advert) is made. In this way, it is<br />

argued, a text is structured as much by what is absent (what is not said) as by what is<br />

present (what is said). Althusser argues that if we are to fully underst<strong>and</strong> the meaning<br />

of a text, we have to be aware of not only what is in a text but also the assumptions<br />

which inform it (<strong>and</strong> which may not appear in the text itself in any straightforward way<br />

but exist only in the text’s problematic). One way in which a text’s problematic is supposedly<br />

revealed is in the way a text may appear to answer questions which it has not<br />

formally posed. Such questions, it is argued, have been posed in the text’s problematic.<br />

The task of an Althusserian critical practice is to deconstruct the text to reveal the problematic.<br />

To do this is to perform what Althusser calls a ‘symptomatic reading’.<br />

In Reading Capital, Althusser characterizes Marx’s method of reading the work of<br />

Adam Smith as ‘symptomatic’ in that<br />

it divulges the undivulged event in the text it reads, <strong>and</strong> in the same movement<br />

relates it to a different text, present as a necessary absence in the first. Like his first<br />

reading, Marx’s second reading presupposes the existence of two texts, <strong>and</strong> the<br />

measurement of the first against the second. But what distinguishes this new reading<br />

from the old is the fact that in the new one the second text is articulated with<br />

the lapses in the first text (Althusser <strong>and</strong> Balibar, 1979: 67).<br />

By a symptomatic reading of Smith, Marx is able to construct for analysis ‘the problematic<br />

initially visible in his writings against the invisible problematic contained in<br />

the paradox of an answer which does not correspond to any question posed’ (28). Marx<br />

(1951) himself says this of Smith, ‘Adam Smith’s contradictions are of significance<br />

because they contain problems which it is true he does not solve, but which he reveals<br />

by contradicting himself’ (146).<br />

To read a text symptomatically, therefore, is to perform a double reading: reading<br />

first the manifest text, <strong>and</strong> then, through the lapses, distortions, silences <strong>and</strong> absences


Althusserianism 73<br />

(the ‘symptoms’ of a problem struggling to be posed) in the manifest text, to produce<br />

<strong>and</strong> read the latent text. For example, a symptomatic reading of the film Taxi Driver<br />

would reveal a problematic in which answers are posed to questions it can hardly<br />

name: ‘How does the Veteran return home to America after the imperial horrors of<br />

Vietnam?’ At the heart of the film’s problematic are questions relating to real historical<br />

problems, albeit deformed <strong>and</strong> transformed into a fantasy quest <strong>and</strong> a bloody resolution.<br />

A symptomatic reading of Taxi Driver, reading the ‘symptoms’ for evidence of an<br />

underlying dis-ease, would construct from the film’s contradictions, its evasions, its<br />

silences, its inexplicable violence, its fairy-tale ending, the central <strong>and</strong> structuring<br />

absence – America’s war in Vietnam.<br />

Another example can be seen in the number of recent car advertisements that<br />

situate vehicles isolated in nature (for example, see Photos 4.1 <strong>and</strong> 4.2). This mode of<br />

advertising, I would argue, is a response to the growing body of negative publicity<br />

which car ownership has attracted (especially in terms of pollution <strong>and</strong> road congestion).<br />

To prevent this publicity having an adverse effect on car sales these criticisms<br />

have to be countered. To confront them in a direct way would always run the risk of<br />

allowing the criticisms to come between the car being advertised <strong>and</strong> any potential<br />

buyer. Therefore, showing cars in both nature (unpolluted) <strong>and</strong> space (uncongested)<br />

confronts the claims without the risk of giving them a dangerous <strong>and</strong> unnecessary<br />

visibility. In this way, the criticisms are answered without the questions themselves<br />

having been formally posed. The emphasis placed on nature <strong>and</strong> space is, therefore, a<br />

response to the twin questions (which remain unasked in the advertisement itself but<br />

exist in the assumptions which organize the advert – in the text’s ‘problematic’): does<br />

Photo 4.1 Advertising as an example of the ‘problematic’.


74<br />

Chapter 4 Marxisms<br />

Photo 4.2 Advertising as an example of the ‘problematic’.<br />

buying a car increase both pollution <strong>and</strong> road congestion? The answer given, without<br />

the question being asked, is that this car, as if by magic, neither pollutes nor contributes<br />

to road congestion.<br />

Pierre Macherey’s (1978) A <strong>Theory</strong> of Literary Production is undoubtedly the most<br />

sustained attempt to apply the technique of the Althusserian symptomatic reading to<br />

cultural texts. Although, as the book’s title implies, Macherey’s main focus is on literary<br />

production, the approach developed in the book is of great interest to the student<br />

of popular culture.<br />

In his elaboration of Althusser’s method of symptomatic reading, he rejects what he<br />

calls ‘the interpretative fallacy’: the view that a text has a single meaning which it is the<br />

task of criticism to uncover. For him the text is not a puzzle that conceals a meaning;<br />

it is a construction with a multiplicity of meanings. To ‘explain’ a text is to recognize<br />

this. To do so it is necessary to break with the idea that a text is a harmonious unity,<br />

spiralling forth from a moment of overwhelming intentionality. Against this, he claims<br />

that the literary text is ‘decentred’; it is incomplete in itself. To say this does not mean<br />

that something needs to be added in order to make it whole. His point is that all literary<br />

texts are ‘decentred’ (not centred on an authorial intention) in the specific sense<br />

that they consist of a confrontation between several discourses: explicit, implicit, present<br />

<strong>and</strong> absent. The task of critical practice is not, therefore, the attempt to measure<br />

<strong>and</strong> evaluate a text’s coherence, its harmonious totality, its aesthetic unity, but instead<br />

to explain the disparities in the text that point to a conflict of meanings.


Althusserianism 75<br />

This conflict is not the sign of an imperfection; it reveals the inscription of an<br />

otherness in the work, through which it maintains a relationship with that which<br />

it is not, that which happens at its margins. To explain the work is to show that,<br />

contrary to appearances, it is not independent, but bears in its material substance<br />

the imprint of a determinate absence which is also the principle of its identity. The<br />

book is furrowed by the allusive presence of those other books against which it is<br />

elaborated; it circles about the absence of that which it cannot say, haunted by the<br />

absence of certain repressed words which make their return. The book is not the<br />

extension of a meaning; it is generated from the incompatibility of several meanings,<br />

the strongest bond by which it is attached to reality, in a tense <strong>and</strong> ever<br />

renewed confrontation (79–80; my italics).<br />

It is this conflict of several meanings that structures a text: it displays this conflict but<br />

cannot speak it – its determinate absence. Traditionally, criticism has seen its role as<br />

making explicit what is implicit in the text, to make audible that which is merely a<br />

whisper (i.e. a single meaning). For Macherey, it is not a question of making what is<br />

there speak with more clarity so as to be finally sure of the text’s meaning. Because a<br />

text’s meanings are ‘both interior <strong>and</strong> absent’ (78), to simply repeat the text’s selfknowledge<br />

is to fail to really explain the text. The task of a fully competent critical practice<br />

is not to make a whisper audible, nor to complete what the text leaves unsaid, but<br />

to produce a new knowledge of the text: one that explains the ideological necessity of<br />

its silences, its absences, its structuring incompleteness – the staging of that which it<br />

cannot speak.<br />

The act of knowing is not like listening to a discourse already constituted, a mere<br />

fiction which we have simply to translate. It is rather the elaboration of a new discourse,<br />

the articulation of a silence. Knowledge is not the discovery or reconstruction<br />

of a latent meaning, forgotten or concealed. It is something newly raised up,<br />

an addition to the reality from which it begins (6).<br />

Borrowing from Freud’s work on dreams (see Chapter 5), Macherey contends that<br />

in order for something to be said, other things must be left unsaid. It is the reason(s)<br />

for these absences, these silences, within a text that must be interrogated. ‘What is<br />

important in the work is what it does not say’ (87). Again, as with Freud, who believed<br />

that the meanings of his patients’ problems were not hidden in their conscious<br />

discourse, but repressed in the turbulent discourse of the unconscious, necessitating a<br />

subtle form of analysis acute to the difference between what is said <strong>and</strong> what is shown,<br />

Macherey’s approach dances between the different nuances of telling <strong>and</strong> showing. This<br />

leads him to the claim that there is a ‘gap’, an ‘internal distanciation’, between what a<br />

text wants to say <strong>and</strong> what a text actually says. To explain a text it is necessary to go<br />

beyond it, to underst<strong>and</strong> what it ‘is compelled to say in order to say what it wants to<br />

say’ (94). It is here that the text’s ‘unconscious’ is constituted (Macherey’s term for the<br />

Althusser’s problematic). And it is in a text’s unconscious that its relationship to the<br />

ideological <strong>and</strong> historical conditions of its existence is revealed. It is in the absent


76<br />

Chapter 4 Marxisms<br />

centre, hollowed out by conflicting discourses, that the text is related to history – to a<br />

particular moment in history <strong>and</strong> to the specific ideological discourses that circulate in<br />

that moment. The text’s unconscious does not reflect historical contradictions; rather,<br />

it evokes, stages <strong>and</strong> displays them, allowing us, not a ‘scientific’ knowledge of ideology,<br />

but an awareness of ‘ideology in contradiction with itself’; breaking down before<br />

questions it cannot answer, failing to do what ideology is supposed to do: ‘ideology<br />

exists precisely in order to efface all trace of contradiction’ (130).<br />

In a formal sense, a text always begins by posing a problem that is to be solved. The<br />

text then exists as a process of unfolding: the narrative movement to the final resolution<br />

of the problem. Macherey contends that between the problem posed <strong>and</strong> the resolution<br />

offered, rather than continuity, there is always a rupture. It is by examining this<br />

rupture that we discover the text’s relationship with ideology <strong>and</strong> history: ‘We always<br />

eventually find, at the edge of the text, the language of ideology, momentarily hidden,<br />

but eloquent by its very absence’ (60).<br />

All narratives contain an ideological project: that is, they promise to tell the ‘truth’<br />

about something. Information is initially withheld on the promise that it will be<br />

revealed. Narrative constitutes a movement towards disclosure. It begins with a truth<br />

promised <strong>and</strong> ends with a truth revealed. To be rather schematic, Macherey divides the<br />

text into three instances: the ideological project (the ‘truth’ promised), the realization<br />

(the ‘truth’ revealed), <strong>and</strong> the unconscious of the text (produced by an act of symptomatic<br />

reading): the return of the repressed historical ‘truth’. ‘Science’, he claims, ‘does<br />

away with ideology, obliterates it; literature challenges ideology by using it. If ideology<br />

is thought of as a non-systematic ensemble of significations, the work proposes<br />

a reading of these significations, by combining them as signs. Criticism teaches us to<br />

read these signs’ (133). In this way, Machereyan critical practice seeks to explain the<br />

way in which, by giving ideology form, the literary text displays ideology in contradiction<br />

with itself.<br />

In a discussion of the work of the French science fiction writer Jules Verne, he<br />

demonstrates how Verne’s work stages the contradictions of late-nineteenth-century<br />

French imperialism. He argues that the ideological project of Verne’s work is the<br />

fantastic staging of the adventures of French imperialism: its colonizing conquest of<br />

the earth. Each adventure concerns the hero’s conquest of Nature (a mysterious isl<strong>and</strong>,<br />

the moon, the bottom of the sea, the centre of the earth). In telling these stories, Verne<br />

is ‘compelled’ to tell another: each voyage of conquest becomes a voyage of rediscovery,<br />

as Verne’s heroes discover that others either have been there before or are there<br />

already. The significance of this, for Macherey, lies in the disparity he perceives between<br />

‘representation’ (what is intended: the subject of the narrative) <strong>and</strong> ‘figuration’ (how<br />

it is realized: its inscription in narrative): Verne ‘represents’ the ideology of French<br />

imperialism, whilst at the same time, through the act of ‘figuration’ (making material<br />

in the form of a fiction), undermines one of its central myths in the continual staging of<br />

the fact that the l<strong>and</strong>s are always already occupied (similarly, the first edition of this<br />

book was written in the middle of a discursive avalanche of media – <strong>and</strong> other – claims<br />

that America was discovered in 1492). ‘In the passage from the level of representation<br />

to that of figuration, ideology undergoes a complete modification . . . perhaps because


Althusserianism 77<br />

no ideology is sufficiently consistent to survive the test of figuration’ (194–5). Thus by<br />

giving fictional form to the ideology of imperialism, Verne’s work – ‘to read it against<br />

the grain of its intended meaning’ (230) – stages the contradictions between the myth<br />

<strong>and</strong> the reality of imperialism. The stories do not provide us with a ‘scientific’ denunciation<br />

(‘a knowledge in the strict sense’) of imperialism, but by an act of symptomatic<br />

reading ‘which dislodges the work internally’, they ‘make us see’, ‘make us perceive’,<br />

‘make us feel’, the terrible contradictions of the ideological discourses from which each<br />

text is constituted: ‘from which it is born, in which it bathes, from which it detaches<br />

itself . . . <strong>and</strong> to which it alludes’ (Althusser, 1971: 222). Verne’s science fiction, then,<br />

can be made to reveal to us – though not in the ways intended – the ideological <strong>and</strong><br />

historical conditions of its emergence.<br />

In the nineteenth century there were a great number of books written to advise<br />

young women on appropriate conduct. Here, for example, is an extract from Thomas<br />

Broadhurst’s Advice to Young Ladies on the Improvement of the Mind <strong>and</strong> Conduct of Life<br />

(1810),<br />

She who is faithfully employed in discharging the various duties of a wife <strong>and</strong><br />

daughter, a mother <strong>and</strong> a friend, is far more usefully occupied than one who, to<br />

the culpable neglect of the most important obligations, is daily absorbed by philosophic<br />

<strong>and</strong> literary speculations, or soaring aloft amidst the enchanted regions of<br />

fiction <strong>and</strong> romance (quoted in Mills, 2004: 80).<br />

Rather than see this as a straightforward sign of women’s oppression, a Machereyan<br />

analysis would interrogate the extent to which this text is also an indication of the failure<br />

of women to occupy positions traditionally dem<strong>and</strong>ed of them. In other words, if<br />

women were not engaging in philosophic <strong>and</strong> literary speculation, there would be no<br />

need to advise them against it. Women actually engaging in literary <strong>and</strong> philosophic<br />

speculation (<strong>and</strong> probably so much more) is, therefore, the determinate absence of the<br />

text. Similarly, Sara Mills (2004) points out how women’s travel writing in the nineteenth<br />

century had to continually address discourse of femininity which suggested that<br />

travel was something beyond a woman’s strength <strong>and</strong> commitment. For example, in<br />

Alex<strong>and</strong>ra David-Neel’s account of her travels in Tibet we read, ‘For nineteen hours we<br />

had been walking. Strangely enough, I did not feel tired’ (quoted in Mills, 2004: 90).<br />

It is the phrase ‘strangely enough’ that points to a determinate absence: a masculine<br />

discourse of disbelief that haunts the unconscious of the text.<br />

Finally, Photo 4.3 shows two figures on an otherwise empty beach; they look cold<br />

<strong>and</strong> uncomfortable. When trying to decide what this photograph signifies, it is very<br />

likely that our interpretation may well be organized <strong>and</strong> shaped by a historically<br />

specific determinate absence: a normative expectation of a beach as a place of holidaymakers,<br />

relaxed <strong>and</strong> enjoying themselves. It is this determinate absence that locates the<br />

‘meaning’ of the photograph in a specific historical moment: before the rise of the<br />

seaside holiday in the 1840s, this normative expectation would have been unavailable<br />

as an interpretative framework. In other words, the meaning we make is both historical<br />

<strong>and</strong> structured by absence.


78<br />

Chapter 4 Marxisms<br />

Photo 4.3 Two figures on a beach.<br />

In Althusser’s second formulation, ideology is still a representation of the imaginary<br />

relationship of individuals to the real conditions of existence, only now ideology is no<br />

longer seen only as a body of ideas, but as a lived, material practice – rituals, customs,<br />

patterns of behaviour, ways of thinking taking practical form – reproduced through<br />

the practices <strong>and</strong> productions of the Ideological State Apparatuses (ISAs): education,<br />

organized religion, the family, organized politics, the media, the culture industries, etc.<br />

According to this second definition, ‘all ideology has the function (which defines it)<br />

of “constructing” concrete individuals as subjects’ (2009: 309). Ideological subjects are<br />

produced by acts of ‘hailing’ or ‘interpellation’. Althusser uses the analogy of a police<br />

officer hailing an individual: ‘Hey, you there!’ When the individual hailed turns in<br />

response, he or she has been interpellated, has become a subject of the police officer’s<br />

discourse. In this way, ideology is a material practice that creates subjects who are in<br />

turn subjected to its specific patterns of thought <strong>and</strong> modes of behaviour.<br />

This definition of ideology has had a significant effect on the field of cultural studies<br />

<strong>and</strong> the study of popular culture. Judith Williamson (1978), for example, deploys<br />

Althusser’s second definition of ideology in her influential study of advertising,<br />

Decoding Advertisements. She argues that advertising is ideological in the sense that it<br />

represents an imaginary relationship to our real conditions of existence. Instead of class<br />

distinctions based on our role in the process of production, advertising continually


suggests that what really matters are distinctions based on the consumption of particular<br />

goods. Thus social identity becomes a question of what we consume rather than<br />

what we produce. Like all ideology, advertising functions by interpellation: it creates<br />

subjects who in turn are subjected to its meanings <strong>and</strong> its patterns of consumption. The<br />

consumer is interpellated to make meaning <strong>and</strong> ultimately to purchase <strong>and</strong> consume<br />

<strong>and</strong> purchase <strong>and</strong> consume again. For example, when I am addressed in terms such as<br />

‘people like you’ are turning this or that product, I am interpellated as one of a group,<br />

but more importantly as an individual ‘you’ of that group. I am addressed as an individual<br />

who can recognize myself in the imaginary space opened up by the pronoun<br />

‘you’. Thus I am invited to become the imaginary ‘you’ spoken to in the advertisement.<br />

But such a process is for Althusser an act of ideological ‘misrecognition’. First, in the<br />

sense that in order for the advert to work it must attract many others who also recognize<br />

themselves in the ‘you’ (each one thinking they are the real ‘you’ of its discourse).<br />

Second, it is misrecognition in another sense: the ‘you’ I recognize in the advert is in<br />

fact a ‘you’ created by the advertisement. As Slavoj yizek (1992) points out, interpellation<br />

works like this: ‘I don’t recognise myself in it because I’m its addressee, I become<br />

its addressee the moment I recognise myself in it’ (12). Advertising, then, according to<br />

this perspective, flatters us into thinking we are the special ‘you’ of its discourse <strong>and</strong> in<br />

so doing we become subjects of <strong>and</strong> subjected to its material practices: acts of consumption.<br />

Advertising is thus ideological both in the way it functions <strong>and</strong> in the effects<br />

it produces.<br />

One of the problems with Althusser’s second model of ideology, <strong>and</strong> its application<br />

in cultural theory, is that it seems to work too well. Men <strong>and</strong> women are always successfully<br />

reproduced with all the necessary ideological habits required by the capitalist<br />

mode of production; there is no sense of failure, let alone any notion of conflict, struggle<br />

or resistance. In terms of popular culture, do advertisements, for example, always<br />

successfully interpellate us as consuming subjects? Moreover, even if interpellation<br />

works, previous interpellations may get in the way (contradict <strong>and</strong> prevent from working)<br />

of current interpellations. Put simply, if I know that racism is wrong, a racist joke<br />

will fail to interpellate me. It was against this background of concerns that many working<br />

within the field of cultural studies turned to the work of the Italian Marxist Antonio<br />

Gramsci.<br />

Hegemony<br />

Hegemony 79<br />

Central to the cultural studies appropriation of Gramsci is the concept of hegemony.<br />

Hegemony is for Gramsci a political concept developed to explain (given the exploitative<br />

<strong>and</strong> oppressive nature of capitalism) the absence of socialist revolutions in the<br />

Western capitalist democracies. The concept of hegemony is used by Gramsci (2009)<br />

to refer to a condition in process in which a dominant class (in alliance with other classes<br />

or class fractions) does not merely rule a society but leads it through the exercise of


80<br />

Chapter 4 Marxisms<br />

‘intellectual <strong>and</strong> moral leadership (75)’. Hegemony involves a specific kind of consensus:<br />

a social group seeks to present its own particular interests as the general interests of the<br />

society as a whole. In this sense, the concept is used to suggest a society in which,<br />

despite oppression <strong>and</strong> exploitation, there is a high degree of consensus, a large<br />

measure of social stability; a society in which subordinate groups <strong>and</strong> classes appear to<br />

actively support <strong>and</strong> subscribe to values, ideals, objectives, cultural <strong>and</strong> political meanings,<br />

which bind them to, <strong>and</strong> ‘incorporate’ them into, the prevailing structures of<br />

power. For example, throughout most of the course of the twentieth century, general<br />

elections in Britain were contested by what are now the two main political parties,<br />

Labour <strong>and</strong> Conservative. On each occasion the contest circled around the question,<br />

who best can administer capitalism (usually referred to by the less politically charged<br />

term ‘the economy’) – less public ownership, more public ownership, less taxation,<br />

more taxation, etc. And on each occasion, the mainstream media concurred. In this<br />

sense, the parameters of the election debate are ultimately dictated by the particular<br />

needs <strong>and</strong> interests of capitalism, presented as the interests <strong>and</strong> needs of society as a<br />

whole. This is clearly an example of a situation in which the interests of one powerful<br />

section of society have been ‘universalized’ as the interests of the society as a whole.<br />

The situation seems perfectly ‘natural’, virtually beyond serious contention. But it was<br />

not always like this. Capitalism’s hegemony is the result of profound political, social,<br />

cultural <strong>and</strong> economic changes that have taken place over a period of at least 300 years.<br />

Until as late as the second part of the nineteenth century, capitalism’s position was still<br />

uncertain. 12 It is only in the twenty-first century that the system seems to have won, or<br />

at least to be winning, especially with the political <strong>and</strong> economic collapse of the Soviet<br />

Union <strong>and</strong> Eastern Europe, <strong>and</strong> the introduction of the ‘Open Door’ policy <strong>and</strong> ‘market<br />

socialism’ in China. Capitalism is now, more or less, internationally hegemonic.<br />

Although hegemony implies a society with a high degree of consensus, it should not<br />

be understood to refer to a society in which all conflict has been removed. What the<br />

concept is meant to suggest is a society in which conflict is contained <strong>and</strong> channelled<br />

into ideologically safe harbours. That is, hegemony is maintained (<strong>and</strong> must be continually<br />

maintained: it is an ongoing process) by dominant groups <strong>and</strong> classes ‘negotiating’<br />

with, <strong>and</strong> making concessions to, subordinate groups <strong>and</strong> classes. For example,<br />

consider the historical case of British hegemony in the Caribbean. One of the ways in<br />

which Britain attempted to secure its control over the indigenous population, <strong>and</strong> the<br />

African men, women <strong>and</strong> children it had transported there as slaves, was by means<br />

of the imposition of a version of British culture (a st<strong>and</strong>ard practice for colonial<br />

regimes everywhere): part of the process was to institute English as the official language.<br />

In linguistic terms, the result was not the imposition of English, but for the<br />

majority of the population, the creation of a new language. The dominant element of<br />

this new language is English, but the language itself is not simply English. What<br />

emerged was a transformed English, with new stresses <strong>and</strong> new rhythms, with some<br />

words dropped <strong>and</strong> new words introduced (from African languages <strong>and</strong> elsewhere).<br />

The new language is the result of a ‘negotiation’ between dominant <strong>and</strong> subordinate<br />

cultures, a language marked by both ‘resistance’ <strong>and</strong> ‘incorporation’: that is, not a language<br />

imposed from above, nor a language which spontaneously had arisen from


Hegemony 81<br />

below, but a language that is the result of a hegemonic struggle between two language<br />

cultures – a dominant language culture <strong>and</strong> subordinate language cultures, involving<br />

both ‘resistance’ <strong>and</strong> ‘incorporation’.<br />

Hegemony is never simply power imposed from above: it is always the result of<br />

‘negotiations’ between dominant <strong>and</strong> subordinate groups, a process marked by both<br />

‘resistance’ <strong>and</strong> ‘incorporation’. There are of course limits to such negotiations <strong>and</strong> concessions.<br />

As Gramsci makes clear, they can never be allowed to challenge the economic<br />

fundamentals of class power. Moreover, in times of crisis, when moral <strong>and</strong> intellectual<br />

leadership is not enough to secure continued authority, the processes of hegemony are<br />

replaced, temporarily, by the coercive power of the ‘repressive state apparatus’: the<br />

army, the police, the prison system, etc.<br />

Hegemony is ‘organized’ by those whom Gramsci designates ‘organic intellectuals’.<br />

According to Gramsci, intellectuals are distinguished by their social function. That is to<br />

say, all men <strong>and</strong> women have the capacity for intellectual endeavour, but only certain<br />

men <strong>and</strong> women have in society the function of intellectuals. Each class, as Gramsci<br />

explains, creates ‘organically’ its own intellectuals:<br />

one or more strata of intellectuals which give it homogeneity <strong>and</strong> an awareness of<br />

its own function not only in the economic sphere but also in the social <strong>and</strong> political<br />

fields. The capitalist entrepreneur [for example] creates alongside himself the<br />

industrial technician, the specialist in political economy, the organisers of a new<br />

culture, of a new legal system, etc. (2009: 77).<br />

Organic intellectuals function as class organizers (in the broadest sense of the term).<br />

It is their task to shape <strong>and</strong> to organize the reform of moral <strong>and</strong> intellectual life. I have<br />

argued elsewhere 13 that Matthew Arnold is best understood as an organic intellectual,<br />

what Gramsci identifies as one of ‘an elite of men of culture, who have the function of<br />

providing leadership of a cultural <strong>and</strong> general ideological nature’ (Storey 1985: 217).<br />

Gramsci tends to speak of organic intellectuals as individuals, but the way the concept<br />

has been mobilized in cultural studies, following Althusser’s barely acknowledged<br />

borrowings from Gramsci, is in terms of collective organic intellectuals – the so-called<br />

‘ideological state apparatuses’ of the family, television, the press, education, organized<br />

religion, the culture industries, etc.<br />

Using hegemony theory, popular culture is what men <strong>and</strong> women make from their<br />

active consumption of the texts <strong>and</strong> practices of the culture industries. Youth subcultures<br />

are perhaps the most spectacular example of this process. Dick Hebdige (1979)<br />

offers a clear <strong>and</strong> convincing explanation of the process (‘bricolage’) by which youth<br />

subcultures appropriate for their own purposes <strong>and</strong> meanings the commodities commercially<br />

provided. Products are combined or transformed in ways not intended by<br />

their producers; commodities are rearticulated to produce ‘oppositional’ meanings.<br />

In this way, <strong>and</strong> through patterns of behaviour, ways of speaking, taste in music, etc.,<br />

youth subcultures engage in symbolic forms of resistance to both dominant <strong>and</strong> parent<br />

cultures. Youth cultures, according to this model, always move from originality<br />

<strong>and</strong> opposition to commercial incorporation <strong>and</strong> ideological diffusion as the culture


82<br />

Chapter 4 Marxisms<br />

industries eventually succeed in marketing subcultural resistance for general consumption<br />

<strong>and</strong> profit. As Hebdige explains: ‘Youth cultural styles may begin by issuing symbolic<br />

challenges, but they must end by establishing new sets of conventions; by<br />

creating new commodities, new industries or rejuvenating old ones’ (96).<br />

The concept of hegemony allows students of popular culture to free themselves from<br />

the disabling analysis of many of the previous approaches to the subject. <strong>Popular</strong> culture<br />

is no longer a history-stopping, imposed culture of political manipulation (the<br />

Frankfurt School); nor is it the sign of social decline <strong>and</strong> decay (the ‘culture <strong>and</strong> civilization’<br />

tradition); nor is it something emerging spontaneously from below (some versions<br />

of culturalism); nor is it a meaning-machine imposing subjectivities on passive<br />

subjects (some versions of structuralism). Instead of these <strong>and</strong> other approaches, hegemony<br />

theory allows us to think of popular culture as a ‘negotiated’ mix of what is made<br />

both from ‘above’ <strong>and</strong> from ‘below’, both ‘commercial’ <strong>and</strong> ‘authentic’; a shifting<br />

balance of forces between resistance <strong>and</strong> incorporation. This can be analysed in many<br />

different configurations: class, gender, generation, ethnicity, ‘race’, region, religion, disability,<br />

sexuality, etc. From this perspective, popular culture is a contradictory mix of<br />

competing interests <strong>and</strong> values: neither middle nor working class, neither racist nor<br />

non-racist, neither sexist nor non-sexist, neither homophobic nor homophilic ...but<br />

always a shifting balance between the two – what Gramsci calls ‘a compromise equilibrium’<br />

(2009: 76). The commercially provided culture of the culture industries is<br />

redefined, reshaped <strong>and</strong> redirected in strategic acts of selective consumption <strong>and</strong> productive<br />

acts of reading <strong>and</strong> articulation, often in ways not intended or even foreseen by<br />

its producers.<br />

Post-Marxism <strong>and</strong> cultural studies<br />

As Angela McRobbie (1992) observes, Marxism is no longer as influential in cultural<br />

studies as it has been in the past:<br />

Marxism, a major point of reference for the whole cultural studies project in the<br />

UK, has been undermined not just from the viewpoint of the postmodern critics<br />

who attack its teleological propositions, its meta-narrative status, its essentialism,<br />

economism, Eurocentrism, <strong>and</strong> its place within the whole Enlightenment project,<br />

but also, of course, as a result of the events in Eastern Europe, with the discrediting<br />

of much of the socialist project (719).<br />

What is certain, as she explains, is that ‘the return to a pre-postmodern Marxism as<br />

marked out by critics like Fredric Jameson (1984) <strong>and</strong> David Harvey (1989) is untenable<br />

because the terms of that return are predicated on prioritizing economic relations<br />

<strong>and</strong> economic determinations over cultural <strong>and</strong> political relations by positioning<br />

these latter in a mechanical <strong>and</strong> reflectionist role’ (ibid.). But more than this, there is a


Post-Marxism <strong>and</strong> cultural studies 83<br />

real sense in which cultural studies was always-already post-Marxist. As Hall (1992)<br />

points out,<br />

There was never a prior moment when cultural studies <strong>and</strong> Marxism represented<br />

a perfect theoretical fit. From the beginning . . . there was always-already the<br />

question of the great inadequacies, theoretically <strong>and</strong> politically, the resounding<br />

silences, the great evasions of Marxism – the things that Marx did not talk about or<br />

seem to underst<strong>and</strong> which were our privileged object of study: culture, ideology,<br />

language, the symbolic. These were always-already, instead, the things which had<br />

imprisoned Marxism as a mode of thought, as an activity of critical practice – its<br />

orthodoxy, its doctrinal character, its determinism, its reductionism, its immutable<br />

law of history, its status as a metanarrative. That is to say, the encounter between<br />

British cultural studies <strong>and</strong> Marxism has first to be understood as the engagement<br />

with a problem – not a theory, not even a problematic (279).<br />

Post-Marxism can mean at least two things. As Ernesto Laclau <strong>and</strong> Chantal Mouffe<br />

(2001) point out in their deeply influential contribution to post-Marxism, Hegemony<br />

<strong>and</strong> Socialist Strategy: Towards a Radical Democratic Politics, ‘if our intellectual project in<br />

this book is post-Marxist, it is evidently also post-Marxist’ (4). To be post-Marxist is to<br />

leave behind Marxism for something better, whereas to be post-Marxist is to seek to<br />

transform Marxism, by adding to it recent theoretical developments from, especially,<br />

feminism, postmodernism, post-structuralism <strong>and</strong> Lacanian psychoanalysis. Laclau<br />

<strong>and</strong> Mouffe are more post-Marxist than they are post-Marxist. They envisage a partnership<br />

between Marxism <strong>and</strong> the ‘new feminism, the protest movements of ethnic,<br />

national <strong>and</strong> sexual minorities, the anti-institutional ecology struggles waged by<br />

marginalized layers of the population, the anti-nuclear movement, the atypical forms<br />

of social struggle in countries on the capitalist periphery’ (1). In my view, cultural studies<br />

is post-Marxist in the positive sense advocated by Laclau <strong>and</strong> Mouffe.<br />

The concept of discourse is central to the development of post-Marxism. As Laclau<br />

(1993) explains, ‘The basic hypothesis of a discursive approach is that the very possibility<br />

of perception, thought <strong>and</strong> action depends on the structuration of a certain<br />

meaningful field which pre-exists any factual immediacy’ (431). To explain what they<br />

mean by discourse Laclau <strong>and</strong> Mouffe (2009) give an example of two people building<br />

a wall. The first person asks the second to pass him/her a brick. On receiving the brick,<br />

the second person adds it to the wall. The totality of this operation consists in a<br />

linguistic moment (the request for a brick) <strong>and</strong> a non-linguistic moment (adding the<br />

brick to the wall). Discourse, according to Laclau <strong>and</strong> Mouffe, consists in the totality<br />

of the linguistic <strong>and</strong> non-linguistic. In other words, they use the term discourse ‘to<br />

emphasize the fact that every social configuration is meaningful. If I kick a spherical<br />

object in the street or if I kick a ball in a football match, the physical fact is the same,<br />

but its meaning is different. The object is a football only to the extent that it establishes<br />

a system of relations with other objects, <strong>and</strong> these relations are not given by the<br />

mere referential materiality of the objects, but are, rather, socially constructed. This systematic<br />

set of relations is what we call discourse’ (159). Moreover,


84<br />

Chapter 4 Marxisms<br />

the discursive character of an object does not, by any means, imply putting its<br />

existence into question. The fact that a football is only a football as long as it is<br />

integrated within a system of socially constructed rules does not mean that it ceases<br />

to be a physical object. . . . For the same reason it is the discourse which constitutes<br />

the subject position of the social agent, <strong>and</strong> not, therefore, the social agent which<br />

is the origin of discourse – the same system of rules that makes that spherical<br />

object into a football, makes me a player (159).<br />

In other words, objects exist independently of their discursive articulation, but it is only<br />

within discourse that they can exist as meaningful objects. For example, earthquakes<br />

exist in the real world, but whether they are<br />

constructed in terms of ‘natural phenomena’ or ‘expressions of the wrath of God’,<br />

depends upon the structuring of a discursive field. What is denied is not that such<br />

objects exist externally to thought, but the rather different assertion that they could<br />

constitute themselves as objects outside any discursive condition of emergence<br />

(Laclau <strong>and</strong> Mouffe, 2001: 108).<br />

The meanings produced in discourse inform <strong>and</strong> organize action. It is only in<br />

discourse, for example, that ‘a relation of subordination’ can become ‘a relation of<br />

oppression’, <strong>and</strong> thereby constitute itself as a site of struggle (153). Someone may be<br />

‘objectively’ oppressed but unless they recognize their subordination as oppression, it<br />

is unlikely that this relation will ever become antagonistic <strong>and</strong> therefore open to the<br />

possibility of change. Hegemony works, as Laclau (1993) explains, by the transformation<br />

of antagonism into simple difference.<br />

A class is hegemonic not so much to the extent that it is able to impose a uniform<br />

conception of the world on the rest of society, but to the extent that it can articulate<br />

different visions of the world in such a way that their potential antagonism is<br />

neutralised. The English bourgeoisie of the 19th century was transformed into a<br />

hegemonic class not through the imposition of a uniform ideology upon other<br />

classes, but to the extent that it succeeded in articulating different ideologies to its<br />

hegemonic project by an elimination of their antagonistic character (161–2).<br />

‘Articulation’ is a key term in post-Marxist cultural studies. ‘The practice of articulation’,<br />

as Laclau <strong>and</strong> Mouffe (2001) explain, ‘consists in the . . . partial fix[ing] of meaning’<br />

(113). Hall (1996b) has developed the concept to explain the ways in which<br />

culture is a terrain of ideological struggle. Like Laclau <strong>and</strong> Mouffe, he argues that texts<br />

<strong>and</strong> practices are not inscribed with meaning; meaning is always the result of an act<br />

of articulation. As he points out, ‘Meaning is a social production, a practice. The world<br />

has to be made to mean’ (2009a: 121). He also draws on the work of the Russian theorist<br />

Valentin Volosinov (1973). Volosinov argues that texts <strong>and</strong> practices are ‘multiaccentual’:<br />

that is, they can be ‘spoken’ with different ‘accents’ by different people


Post-Marxism <strong>and</strong> cultural studies 85<br />

in different discourses <strong>and</strong> different social contexts for different politics. When, for<br />

example, a black performer uses the word ‘nigger’ to attack institutional racism, it is<br />

‘spoken’ with an ‘accent’ very different from the ‘accent’ given the word in, say, the<br />

racist discourse of a neo-Nazi. This is, of course, not simply a question of linguistic<br />

struggle – a conflict over semantics – but a sign of political struggle about who can<br />

claim the power <strong>and</strong> the authority to (partially) fix the meaning of social reality.<br />

An interesting example of the processes of articulation is the reggae music of<br />

Rastafarian culture. Bob Marley, for example, had international success with songs<br />

articulating the values <strong>and</strong> beliefs of Rastafari. This success can be viewed in two ways.<br />

On the one h<strong>and</strong>, it signals the expression of the message of his religious convictions<br />

to an enormous audience worldwide; undoubtedly for many of his audience the music<br />

had the effect of enlightenment, underst<strong>and</strong>ing <strong>and</strong> perhaps even conversion to, <strong>and</strong><br />

bonding for those already convinced of, the principles of the faith. On the other h<strong>and</strong>,<br />

the music has made <strong>and</strong> continues to make enormous profits for the music industry<br />

(promoters, Isl<strong>and</strong> Records, etc.). What we have is a paradox in which the anti-capitalist<br />

politics of Rastafari are being articulated in the economic interests of capitalism: the<br />

music is lubricating the very system it seeks to condemn; that is, the politics of Rastafari<br />

are being expressed in a form which is ultimately of financial benefit to the dominant<br />

culture (i.e. as a commodity which circulates for profit). Nevertheless, the music is an<br />

expression of an oppositional (religious) politics, <strong>and</strong> it may circulate as such, <strong>and</strong> it<br />

may produce certain political <strong>and</strong> cultural effects. Therefore, Rastafarian reggae is a<br />

force for change that paradoxically stabilizes (at least economically) the very forces of<br />

power it seeks to overthrow.<br />

Another example, in some ways more compelling than that of reggae, is the music<br />

of the American counterculture. It inspired people to resist the draft <strong>and</strong> to organize<br />

against Amerika’s war in Vietnam; yet, at the same time, its music made profits (over<br />

which it had no control) that could then be used to support the war effort in Vietnam.<br />

The more Jefferson Airplane sang ‘All your private property/Is target for your enemy/<br />

And your enemy/Is We’, 14 the more money RCA Records made. The proliferation of<br />

Jefferson Airplane’s anti-capitalist politics increased the profits of their capitalist record<br />

company. Again, this is an example of the process of articulation: the way in which<br />

dominant groups in society attempt to ‘negotiate’ oppositional voices on to a terrain<br />

which secures for the dominant groups a continued position of leadership. The music<br />

of the counterculture was not denied expression (<strong>and</strong> there can be little doubt that this<br />

music produced particular cultural <strong>and</strong> political effects), but what is also true is that<br />

this music was articulated in the economic interests of the war-supporting capitalist<br />

music industry. 15 As Keith Richards of The Rolling Stones said,<br />

We found out, <strong>and</strong> it wasn’t for years that we did, that all the bread we made for<br />

Decca was going into making black boxes that go into American Air Force bombers<br />

to bomb fucking North Vietnam. They took the bread we made for them <strong>and</strong> put<br />

it into the radar section of their business. When we found that out, it blew our<br />

minds. That was it. Goddam, you find out you’ve helped kill God knows how<br />

many thous<strong>and</strong>s of people without really knowing it (quoted in Storey 2009: 92).


86<br />

Chapter 4 Marxisms<br />

In Chapter 3 we examined Williams’s (2009) social definition of culture. We discussed<br />

it in terms of how it broadens the definition of culture: instead of culture<br />

being defined as only the ‘elite’ texts <strong>and</strong> practices (ballet, opera, the novel, poetry),<br />

Williams redefined culture to include as culture, for example, pop music, television,<br />

cinema, advertising, going on holiday, etc. However, another aspect of Williams’s<br />

social definition of culture has proved even more important for cultural studies, especially<br />

post-Marxist cultural studies – the connection he makes between meaning <strong>and</strong><br />

culture.<br />

There is the ‘social’ definition of culture, in which culture is a description of a<br />

particular way of life, which expresses certain meanings <strong>and</strong> values not only in art <strong>and</strong><br />

learning but also in institutions <strong>and</strong> ordinary behaviour. The analysis of culture,<br />

from such a definition, is the clarification of the meanings <strong>and</strong> values implicit in a<br />

particular way of life (32; my italics).<br />

The importance of a particular way of life is that it ‘expresses certain meanings <strong>and</strong><br />

values‘. Moreover, cultural analysis from the perspective of this definition of culture ‘is<br />

the clarification of the meanings <strong>and</strong> values implicit in a particular way of life’.<br />

Moreover, culture as a signifying system is not reducible to ‘a particular way of life’;<br />

rather, it is fundamental to the shaping <strong>and</strong> holding together of a particular way of<br />

life. This is not to reduce everything ‘upwards’ to culture as a signifying system, but<br />

it is to insist that culture defined in this way, should be understood ‘as essentially<br />

involved in all forms of social activity’ (Williams, 1981: 13). While there is more to life<br />

than signifying systems, it is nevertheless the case that ‘it would . . . be wrong to suppose<br />

that we can ever usefully discuss a social system without including, as a central<br />

part of its practice, its signifying systems, on which, as a system, it fundamentally<br />

depends’ (207).<br />

Following this definition, <strong>and</strong> the discourse theory of Laclau <strong>and</strong> Mouffe, post-<br />

Marxist cultural studies defines culture as the production, circulation, <strong>and</strong> consumption<br />

of meanings. As Hall (1997b), for example, explains, ‘<strong>Culture</strong> . . . is not so much<br />

a set of things – novels <strong>and</strong> paintings or TV programmes <strong>and</strong> comics – as a process, a<br />

set of practices. Primarily, culture is concerned with the production <strong>and</strong> exchange of<br />

meanings – the giving <strong>and</strong> taking of meaning’ (2). According to this definition, cultures<br />

do not so much consist of, say, books; cultures are the shifting networks of signification<br />

in which, say, books are made to signify as meaningful objects. For example, if I pass a<br />

business card to someone in China, the polite way to do it is with two h<strong>and</strong>s. If I pass<br />

it with one h<strong>and</strong> I may cause offence. This is clearly a matter of culture. However, the<br />

culture is not so much in the gesture as in the meaning of the gesture. In other words,<br />

there is nothing essentially polite about using two h<strong>and</strong>s; using two h<strong>and</strong>s has been<br />

made to signify politeness. Nevertheless, signification has become embodied in a material<br />

practice, which may, in turn, produce material effects (I will say more about this<br />

later). Similarly, as Marx (1976c) observed, ‘one man is king only because other men<br />

st<strong>and</strong> in the relation of subjects to him. They, on the contrary, imagine that they are<br />

subjects because he is king’ (149). This relationship works because they share a culture


Post-Marxism <strong>and</strong> cultural studies 87<br />

in which such relations are meaningful. Outside such a culture this relationship would<br />

be meaningless. Being a king, therefore, is not a gift of nature but something constructed<br />

in culture. It is culture <strong>and</strong> not nature that gives the relation meaning.<br />

To share a culture, therefore, is to interpret the world – make it meaningful <strong>and</strong><br />

experience it as meaningful – in recognizably similar ways. So-called ‘culture shock’<br />

happens when we encounter radically different networks of meaning: when our ‘natural’<br />

or our ‘common sense’ is confronted by someone else’s ‘natural’ or ‘common<br />

sense’. However, cultures are never simply shifting networks of shared meanings.<br />

On the contrary, cultures are always both shared <strong>and</strong> contested networks of meanings:<br />

culture is where we share <strong>and</strong> contest meanings of ourselves, of each other <strong>and</strong> of the<br />

social worlds in which we live.<br />

Post-Marxist cultural studies draws two conclusions from this way of thinking about<br />

culture. First, although the world exists in all its enabling <strong>and</strong> constraining materiality<br />

outside culture, it is only in culture that the world can be made to mean. In other words,<br />

culture constructs the realities it appears only to describe. Second, because different<br />

meanings can be ascribed to the same ‘text’ (anything that can be made to signify),<br />

meaning making (i.e. the making of culture) is always a potential site of struggle<br />

<strong>and</strong>/or negotiation. For example, masculinity has real material conditions of existence,<br />

which we think of as ‘biological’, but there are different ways of representing masculinity<br />

in culture, different ways of ‘being masculine’. Moreover, these different ways<br />

do not all carry the same claims to ‘authenticity’ <strong>and</strong> ‘normality’. Masculinity, therefore,<br />

may depend on biological conditions of existence, but what it means, <strong>and</strong> the<br />

struggle over what it means, always takes place in culture. This is not a question of<br />

semantic difference – a simple question of interpreting the world differently – it is<br />

about relations of culture <strong>and</strong> power; about who can claim the power <strong>and</strong> authority to<br />

define social reality; to make the world (<strong>and</strong> the things in it) mean in particular ways.<br />

<strong>Culture</strong> <strong>and</strong> power is the primary object of study in post-Marxist cultural studies. As<br />

Hall (1997: 4) explains, ‘Meanings [i.e. cultures] . . . regulate <strong>and</strong> organize our conduct<br />

<strong>and</strong> practices – they help to set the rules, norms <strong>and</strong> conventions by which social life<br />

is ordered <strong>and</strong> governed. They are ..., therefore, what those who wish to govern <strong>and</strong><br />

regulate the conduct <strong>and</strong> ideas of others seek to structure <strong>and</strong> shape’. Meanings have a<br />

‘material’ existence, in that they help organize practice; they establish norms of behaviour,<br />

as we recognized in the examples of different masculinities <strong>and</strong> the passing of a<br />

business card in China.<br />

In other words, then, dominant ways of making the world meaningful, produced by<br />

those with the power to make their meanings circulate in the world, can generate the<br />

‘hegemonic truths’, which may come to assume an authority over the ways in which we<br />

see, think, communicate <strong>and</strong> act in the world <strong>and</strong> become the ‘common sense’ which<br />

directs our actions or become that against which our actions are directed. However,<br />

although post-Marxist cultural studies recognizes that the culture industries are a major<br />

site of ideological production, constructing powerful images, descriptions, definitions,<br />

frames of reference for underst<strong>and</strong>ing the world, it rejects the view that ‘the people’<br />

who consume these productions are ‘cultural dupes’, victims of ‘an up-dated form of<br />

the opium of the people’. As Hall (2009b) insists,


88<br />

Chapter 4 Marxisms<br />

That judgment may make us feel right, decent <strong>and</strong> self-satisfied about our denunciations<br />

of the agents of mass manipulation <strong>and</strong> deception – the capitalist cultural<br />

industries: but I don’t know that it is a view which can survive for long as an<br />

adequate account of cultural relationships; <strong>and</strong> even less as a socialist perspective<br />

on the culture <strong>and</strong> nature of the working class. Ultimately, the notion of the people<br />

as a purely passive, outline force is a deeply unsocialist perspective (512).<br />

Post-Marxist cultural studies is informed by the proposition that people make popular<br />

culture from the repertoire of commodities supplied by the culture industries. Making<br />

popular culture (‘production in use’) can be empowering to subordinate <strong>and</strong> resistant<br />

to dominant underst<strong>and</strong>ings of the world. But this is not to say that popular culture is<br />

always empowering <strong>and</strong> resistant. To deny the passivity of consumption is not to deny<br />

that sometimes consumption is passive; to deny that consumers are cultural dupes is<br />

not to deny that the culture industries seek to manipulate. But it is to deny that popular<br />

culture is little more than a degraded l<strong>and</strong>scape of commercial <strong>and</strong> ideological<br />

manipulation, imposed from above in order to make profit <strong>and</strong> secure social control.<br />

Post-Marxist cultural studies insists that to decide these matters requires vigilance <strong>and</strong><br />

attention to the details of the production, distribution <strong>and</strong> consumption of the commodities<br />

from which people may or may not make culture. These are not matters that<br />

can be decided once <strong>and</strong> for all (outside the contingencies of history <strong>and</strong> politics) with<br />

an elitist glance <strong>and</strong> a condescending sneer. Nor can they be read off from the moment<br />

of production (locating meaning, pleasure, ideological effect, the probability of incorporation,<br />

the possibility of resistance, in, variously, the intention, the means of production<br />

or the production itself): these are only aspects of the contexts for ‘production<br />

in use’; <strong>and</strong> it is, ultimately, in ‘production in use’ that questions of meaning, pleasure,<br />

ideological effect, incorporation or resistance, can be (contingently) decided.<br />

Further reading<br />

Storey, John (ed.), <strong>Cultural</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Popular</strong> <strong>Culture</strong>: A Reader, 4th edition, Harlow:<br />

Pearson Education, 2009. This is the companion volume to this book. It contains<br />

examples of most of the work discussed here. This book <strong>and</strong> the companion Reader<br />

are supported by an interactive website (www.pearsoned.co.uk/storey). The website<br />

has links to other useful sites <strong>and</strong> electronic resources.<br />

Barrett, Michele, The Politics of Truth: From Marx to Foucault, Cambridge: Polity Press,<br />

1991. An interesting introduction to ‘post-Marxism’.<br />

Bennett, Tony, Formalism <strong>and</strong> Marxism, London: Methuen, 1979. Contains helpful<br />

chapters on Althusser <strong>and</strong> Macherey.<br />

Bennett, Tony, Colin Mercer <strong>and</strong> Janet Woollacott (eds), <strong>Culture</strong>, Ideology <strong>and</strong> Social<br />

Process, London: Batsford, 1981. Section 4 consists of extracts from Gramsci <strong>and</strong>


Further reading 89<br />

three essays informed by hegemony theory. The book also contains similar sections<br />

on culturalism <strong>and</strong> structuralism.<br />

Hebdige, Dick, Subculture: The Meaning of Style, London: Methuen, 1979. The seminal<br />

account of youth subcultures: an excellent introduction to hegemony theory <strong>and</strong><br />

popular culture.<br />

Laing, Dave, The Marxist <strong>Theory</strong> of Art: An Introductory Survey, Hemel Hempstead:<br />

Harvester Wheatsheaf, 1978. A very readable introduction to Marxist theories of<br />

culture. Contains an interesting section on popular culture.<br />

Marx, Karl <strong>and</strong> Frederick Engels, On Literature <strong>and</strong> Art, St Louis: Telos, 1973. A useful<br />

selection of the writings by Marx <strong>and</strong> Engels on matters cultural.<br />

Nelson, Cary <strong>and</strong> Lawrence Grossberg (eds), Marxism <strong>and</strong> the Interpretation of <strong>Culture</strong>,<br />

London: Macmillan, 1988. An interesting collection of recent essays on Marxism<br />

<strong>and</strong> culture.<br />

Showstack Sassoon, Anne, (ed.), Approaches to Gramsci, London: Writers <strong>and</strong> Readers,<br />

1982. A collection of essays on Gramsci. Contains a useful glossary of key terms.<br />

Sim, Stuart (ed.), Post-Marxism: A Reader, Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 1998.<br />

Interesting collection of essays on the question of post-Marxism.<br />

Simon, Roger, Gramsci’s Political Thought: An Introduction, London: Lawrence & Wishart,<br />

1982. A very readable introduction to Gramsci.<br />

Slater, Phil, Origin <strong>and</strong> Significance of the Frankfurt School: A Marxist Perspective, London:<br />

Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1977. The book provides a critical overview of the work of<br />

the Frankfurt School. Chapter 4, on the culture industry, is of particular interest to<br />

the student of popular culture.


5 Psychoanalysis<br />

In this chapter I will explore psychoanalysis as a method of reading texts <strong>and</strong> practices.<br />

This means that although I will to a certain extent explain how psychoanalysis underst<strong>and</strong>s<br />

human behaviour, this will be done only as it can be extended to cultural analysis<br />

in cultural studies. Therefore, I will be very selective in terms of which aspects of<br />

psychoanalysis I choose for discussion.<br />

Freudian psychoanalysis<br />

Sigmund Freud (1973a) argues that the creation of civilization has resulted in the repression<br />

of basic human instincts. Moreover, ‘each individual who makes a fresh entry<br />

into human society repeats this sacrifice of instinctual satisfaction for the benefit of the<br />

whole community’ (47). The most important instinctual drives are sexual. Civilization<br />

dem<strong>and</strong>s that these are redirected in unconscious processes of sublimation:<br />

that is to say, they are diverted from their sexual aims <strong>and</strong> directed to others that<br />

are socially higher <strong>and</strong> no longer sexual. But this arrangement is unstable; the sexual<br />

are imperfectly tamed, <strong>and</strong>, in the case of every individual who is supposed to<br />

join in the work of civilization, there is a risk that his sexual instincts may refuse<br />

to be put to that use. Society believes that no greater threat to its civilization could<br />

arise than if the sexual instincts were to be liberated <strong>and</strong> returned to their original<br />

aims (47–8). 16<br />

Fundamental to this argument is Freud’s discovery of the unconscious. He first<br />

divides the psyche into two parts, the conscious <strong>and</strong> the unconscious. The conscious is<br />

the part that relates to the external world, while the unconscious is the site of instinctual<br />

drives <strong>and</strong> repressed wishes. He then adds to this binary model the preconscious.<br />

What we cannot remember at any given moment, but know we can recall with some<br />

mental effort, is recovered from the preconscious. What is in the unconscious, as a consequence<br />

of censorship <strong>and</strong> resistance, is only ever expressed in distorted form; we cannot,<br />

as an act of will recall material from the unconscious into the conscious. Freud’s


92<br />

Chapter 5 Psychoanalysis<br />

Figure 5.1 The Freudian psyche.<br />

final model of the psyche introduces three new terms: the ego, the super-ego, <strong>and</strong> the<br />

id (see Figure 5.1). 17<br />

The id is the most primitive part of our being. It is the part of ‘our nature [which] is<br />

impersonal, <strong>and</strong>, so to speak, subject to natural law’ (Freud, 1984: 362); it ‘is the dark,<br />

inaccessible part of our personality ...a chaos, a cauldron full of seething excitations.<br />

. . . It is filled with energy reaching it from the instincts, but it has no organization, produces<br />

no collective will, but only a striving to bring about the satisfaction of the instinctual<br />

needs subject to the observance of the pleasure principle’ (Freud, 1973b: 106).<br />

The ego develops out of the id: ‘the ego cannot exist in the individual from the start;<br />

the ego has to be developed’ (1984: 69). As he further explains, the ego<br />

is that part of the id which has been modified by the direct influence of the external<br />

world. . . . Moreover, the ego seeks to bring the influence of the external world<br />

to bear upon the id <strong>and</strong> its tendencies, <strong>and</strong> endeavours to substitute the reality<br />

principle for the pleasure principle which reigns unrestrictedly in the id. ...The<br />

ego represents what may be called reason <strong>and</strong> common sense, in contrast to the id,<br />

which contains the passions (363–4).<br />

Freud (1973b) compares the relationship between the id <strong>and</strong> the ego as similar to a<br />

person riding a horse: ‘The horse supplies the locomotive energy, while the rider has<br />

the privilege of deciding on the goal <strong>and</strong> of guiding the powerful animal’s movement.<br />

But only too often there arises between the ego <strong>and</strong> the id the not precisely ideal situation<br />

of the rider being obliged to guide the horse along the path by which it itself<br />

wants to go’ (109–10). In fact, the ego struggles to serve three masters, the ‘external<br />

world’, the ‘libido of the id’, <strong>and</strong> the ‘severity of the super-ego’ (1984: 397).<br />

It is with the dissolution of the Oedipus complex (discussed later in this chapter)<br />

that the super-ego emerges. The super-ego begins as the internalization or introjection<br />

of the authority of the child’s parents, especially of the father. This first authority is then<br />

overlaid with other voices of authority, producing what we think of as ‘conscience’.<br />

Although the super-ego is in many ways the voice of culture, it remains in alliance with<br />

the id. Freud explains it thus: ‘Whereas the ego is essentially the representative of the<br />

external world, of reality, the super-ego st<strong>and</strong>s in contrast to it as the representative of


Figure 5.2 Freud’s conflict model of the human psyche.<br />

Freudian psychoanalysis 93<br />

the internal world, of the id’ (366). ‘Thus the super-ego is always close to the id <strong>and</strong><br />

can act as its representative vis-à-vis the ego. It reaches deep down into the id <strong>and</strong> for<br />

that reason is farther from consciousness than the ego is’ (390). Furthermore, ‘Analysis<br />

eventually shows that the super-ego is being influenced by processes that have<br />

remained unknown to the ego’ (392).<br />

There are two particular things to note about Freud’s model of the psyche. First, we<br />

are born with an id, while the ego develops through contact with culture, which in turn<br />

produces the super-ego. In other words, our ‘nature’ is governed (sometimes successfully,<br />

sometimes not) by culture. What is called ‘human nature’ is not something<br />

‘essentially’ natural but the governance of our nature by culture. This means that<br />

human nature is not something innate <strong>and</strong> unchangeable, it is something at least in<br />

part introduced from outside. Moreover, given that culture is always historical <strong>and</strong> variable,<br />

it is itself always open to change. Second, <strong>and</strong> perhaps much more fundamental<br />

to psychoanalysis, the psyche is envisaged as a site of perpetual conflict (see Figure 5.2).<br />

The most fundamental conflict is between the id <strong>and</strong> the ego. The id wants desires<br />

satisfied regardless of the claims of culture, while the ego, sometimes in loose alliance<br />

with the super-ego, is obliged to meet the claims <strong>and</strong> conventions of society. This<br />

conflict is sometimes portrayed as a struggle between the ‘pleasure principle’ <strong>and</strong> the<br />

‘reality principle’. For example, while the id (governed by the pleasure principle) may<br />

dem<strong>and</strong> ‘I want it’ (whatever ‘it’ might be), the ego (governed by the reality principle)<br />

must defer thinking about ‘it’ in order to consider how to get ‘it’.<br />

‘The essence of repression’, according to Freud, ‘lies simply in turning something<br />

away, <strong>and</strong> keeping it at a distance, from the conscious’ (147). In this way, then, we<br />

could say that repression is a special form of amnesia; it removes all the things with<br />

which we cannot or will not deal. But as Freud (1985) makes clear, we may have<br />

repressed these things, but they have not really gone away: ‘Actually, we never give anything<br />

up; we only exchange one thing for another. What appears to be a renunciation<br />

is really the formation of a substitute or surrogate’ (133). These ‘substitutive formations’<br />

make possible the ‘return of the repressed’ (Freud, 1984: 154). Dreams provide<br />

perhaps the most dramatic staging of the return of the repressed. As Freud (1976)<br />

claims, ‘The interpretation of dreams is the royal road to the unconscious’ (769).<br />

The primary function of dreams is to be ‘the guardians of sleep which get rid of disturbances<br />

of sleep’ (Freud, 1973a: 160). Sleep is threatened from three directions:<br />

external stimulus, recent events, <strong>and</strong> ‘repressed instinctual impulses which are on the<br />

watch for an opportunity of finding expression’ (45). Dreams guard sleep by incorporating<br />

potential disturbances into the narrative of the dream. If, for example, a noise<br />

sounds during sleep, a dream will attempt to include the noise in its narrative organization.<br />

Similarly, when a sleeper experiences somatic disturbances (indigestion is the


94<br />

Chapter 5 Psychoanalysis<br />

most obvious example), the dream will attempt to accommodate this in order not to<br />

disturb the dreamer’s sleep. However, outside <strong>and</strong> inside stimulus of this sort is always<br />

transformed. As he explains, ‘Dreams do not simply reproduce the stimulus; they work<br />

it over, they make allusions to it, they include it in some context, they replace it by<br />

something else’ (125). An alarm clock, for example, may appear as the sound of church<br />

bells on a sunny Sunday morning or as the sound of the fire brigade rushing to the<br />

scene of a devastating fire. Therefore, although we can recognize how outside stimulation<br />

may contribute something to a dream, it does not explain why or how this something<br />

is worked over. Similarly, dreams are also informed by recent experiences, ‘the<br />

day’s residues’ (264). These may often determine much of the content of a dream, but,<br />

as Freud insists, this, as with noise <strong>and</strong> somatic disturbances, is merely the material out<br />

of which the dream is formulated <strong>and</strong> is not the same as the unconscious wish. As he<br />

explains, the ‘unconscious impulse is the true creator of the dream; it is what produces<br />

the psychical energy for the dream’s construction’ (1973b: 47).<br />

Dreams, according to Freud, are always a ‘compromise-structure’ (48). That is, a<br />

compromise between wishes emanating from the id <strong>and</strong> censorship enacted by the<br />

ego: ‘If the meaning of our dreams usually remains obscure to us . . . it is because<br />

[they contain] wishes of which we are ashamed; these we must conceal from ourselves,<br />

<strong>and</strong> they have consequently been repressed, pushed into the unconscious. Repressed<br />

wishes of this sort <strong>and</strong> their derivatives are only allowed to come to expression in a very<br />

distorted form’ (1985: 136). Censorship occurs but wishes are expressed; that is, they<br />

are coded in an attempt to elude censorship. According to Freud’s (1976) famous formulation,<br />

‘a dream is a (disguised) fulfilment of a (suppressed or repressed) wish’ (244).<br />

Dreams move between two levels: the latent dream thoughts (unconscious) <strong>and</strong> the<br />

manifest content (what the dreamer remembers dreaming). Dream analysis attempts<br />

to decode the manifest content in order to discover the ‘real meaning’ of the dream. To<br />

do this it has to decipher the different mechanisms that have translated latent dream<br />

thoughts into manifest content. He calls these mechanisms the ‘dream-work’ (2009:<br />

246). The dream-work consists of four processes: condensation, displacement, symbolization,<br />

<strong>and</strong> secondary revision. Each in turn produces ‘the transformation of<br />

thoughts into hallucinatory experience’ (1973a: 250).<br />

The manifest content is always smaller than the latent content. This is the result of<br />

condensation, which can work in three different ways: (i) latent elements are omitted;<br />

(ii) only part of a latent element arrives in the manifest content, <strong>and</strong> (iii) latent elements<br />

which have something in common are condensed into ‘composite structures’<br />

(2009: 247). ‘As a result of condensation, one element in the manifest dream may correspond<br />

to numerous elements in the latent dream-thoughts; but, conversely too, one<br />

element in the dream-thoughts may be represented by several images in [the manifest<br />

content of] the dream’ (1973b: 49). Freud provides the following example:<br />

You will have no difficulty in recalling instances from your own dreams of different<br />

people being condensed into a single one. A compromise figure of this kind<br />

may look like A perhaps, but may be dressed like B, may do something that we<br />

remember C doing, <strong>and</strong> at the same time we may know that he is D (2009: ibid.).


Freudian psychoanalysis 95<br />

Latent elements also appear in the manifest content via a chain of association or allusion<br />

Freud calls displacement. This process works in two ways:<br />

In the first, a latent element is replaced not by a component part of itself but by<br />

something more remote – that is, by an allusion; <strong>and</strong> in the second, the psychical<br />

accent is shifted from an important element on to another which is unimportant,<br />

so that the dream appears differently centred <strong>and</strong> strange (248).<br />

This first aspect of displacement operates along chains of association in which<br />

what is in the manifest content alludes to something in the latent dream thoughts.<br />

If, for example, I know someone who works as a schoolteacher, she may appear in<br />

my dreams as a satchel. In this way, affect (the emotional intensity attached to the<br />

figure) is shifted from its source (she who works in a school), to something associated<br />

with her working in a school. Or if I know someone called Clarke, she may<br />

appear in my dreams as someone working in an office. Again, affect has been moved<br />

along a chain of association from the name of someone I know to an activity associated<br />

with her name. I may have a dream situated in an office, in which I observe<br />

someone working at a desk (it may not even be a woman), but the ‘essence’ of my<br />

dream is a woman I know called Clarke. These examples work metonymically in terms<br />

of similarity based on contraction: a part st<strong>and</strong>ing in for a whole. The second mechanism<br />

of displacement changes the focus of the dream. What appears in the manifest<br />

content is ‘differently centred from the dream-thoughts – its content has different<br />

elements as its central point’ (1976: 414). ‘With the help of displacement the dreamcensorship<br />

creates substitutive structures which . . . are allusions which are not easily<br />

recognizable as such, from which the path back to the genuine thing is not easily<br />

traced, <strong>and</strong> which are connected with the genuine thing by the strangest, most unusual,<br />

external associations’ (1973a: 272). He illustrates this second aspect of displacement<br />

with a joke.<br />

There was a blacksmith in a village, who had committed a capital offence. The<br />

Court decided that the crime must be punished; but as the blacksmith was the only<br />

one in the village <strong>and</strong> was indispensable, <strong>and</strong> as on the other h<strong>and</strong> there were three<br />

tailors living there, one of them was hanged instead (2009: 249).<br />

In this example, the chain of association <strong>and</strong> affect has shifted dramatically. To get<br />

back to the blacksmith from the fate of one of the tailors would require a great deal of<br />

analysis, but the central idea seems to be: ‘Punishment must be exacted even if it does<br />

not fall upon the guilty’ (1984: 386). Moreover, as he explains, ‘No other part of the<br />

dream-work is so much responsible for making the dream strange <strong>and</strong> incomprehensible<br />

to the dreamer. Displacement is the principal means used in the dream-distortion<br />

to which the [latent] dream-thoughts must submit under the influence of the censorship’<br />

(1973b: 50).<br />

The third aspect of the dream-work, operative in the first two, is symbolization,<br />

the ‘translation of dream-thoughts into a primitive mode of expression similar to


96<br />

Chapter 5 Psychoanalysis<br />

picture-writing’ (1973a: 267), in which ‘the latent dream-thoughts . . . are dramatized<br />

<strong>and</strong> illustrated’ (1973b: 47). Symbolization transforms ‘the latent [dream] thoughts<br />

which are expressed in words into sensory images, mostly of a visual sort’ (1973a: 215).<br />

But as Freud makes clear, not everything is transformed in this way: certain elements<br />

exist in other forms. Nevertheless, symbols ‘comprise the essence of the formation of<br />

dreams’ (2009: 249). Furthermore, ‘The very great majority of symbols in dreams’, as<br />

Freud maintains, ‘are sexual symbols’ (1973a: 187). So, for example, male genitals are<br />

represented in dreams by a range of ‘symbolic substitutes’ that are erect such as ‘sticks,<br />

umbrellas, posts, trees’ <strong>and</strong> things that are able to penetrate such as ‘knives, daggers,<br />

spears, sabres . . . rifles, pistols <strong>and</strong> revolvers’ (188). Female genitals are represented<br />

by things that share the ‘characteristic of enclosing a hollow space which can take<br />

something into itself’ such as ‘pits, cavities . . . hollows . . . vessels <strong>and</strong> bottles . . .<br />

receptacles, boxes, trunks, cases, chests, pockets, <strong>and</strong> so on’ (189). These symbolic substitutes<br />

are drawn from an ever-changing repertoire of symbols. He makes this clear<br />

in his discussion of the way in which objects that are able to defy the laws of gravity<br />

are used to represent the male erection. Writing in 1917, he points to the fact that<br />

the Zeppelin airship had recently joined the repertoire of such objects (1976: 188).<br />

Although these symbols are drawn from myths, religion, fairy stories, jokes, <strong>and</strong> everyday<br />

language use, objects are not consciously selected from the repertoire: ‘the knowledge<br />

of symbolism is unconscious to the dreamer . . . it belongs to his mental life’<br />

(1973a: 200). Another example of the play of culture in psychoanalysis is language.<br />

The associations a patient may bring to something will be enabled <strong>and</strong> constrained by<br />

the language(s) he or she may speak. Moreover, the various examples that Freud<br />

(1976) provides of words st<strong>and</strong>ing in for something other than their literal meaning,<br />

is also limited to the language(s) the patient underst<strong>and</strong>s.<br />

Freud is absolutely clear about ‘the impossibility of interpreting a dream unless one<br />

has the dreamer’s associations to it at one’s disposal’ (1973b: 36). Symbols may provide<br />

a preliminary answer to the question ‘What does this dream mean?’ But it is only<br />

a preliminary answer, to be confirmed, or otherwise, by an analysis of other aspects of<br />

the dream-work in conjunction with analysis of the associations brought into play by<br />

the person whose dream is being analysed. As he warns: ‘I should like to utter an<br />

express warning against overestimating the importance of symbols in dream-interpretation,<br />

against restricting the work of translating dreams merely to translating symbols<br />

<strong>and</strong> against ab<strong>and</strong>oning the technique of making use of the dreamer’s associations’<br />

(477). Moreover, symbols ‘frequently have more than one or even several meanings,<br />

<strong>and</strong> . . . the correct interpretation can only be arrived at on each occasion from the context’<br />

(1976: 470). Again, context will be something established by the dreamer.<br />

The dream-work’s final process is secondary revision. This is the narrative placed by<br />

the dreamer on the dream symbolism. It takes two forms. First, it is the verbal account<br />

of the dream: the translation of symbols into language <strong>and</strong> narrative – ‘we fill in gaps<br />

<strong>and</strong> introduce connections, <strong>and</strong> in doing so are often guilty of gross misunderst<strong>and</strong>ings’<br />

(1973b: 50). Second, <strong>and</strong> more importantly, secondary revision is the final policing<br />

<strong>and</strong> channelling strategy of the ego, making meaning <strong>and</strong> coherence in an act of<br />

(unconscious) censorship.


Freudian psychoanalysis 97<br />

After the interpretation of dreams, Freud is perhaps best known for his theory of the<br />

Oedipus complex. Freud develops the complex from Sophocles’ drama Oedipus the<br />

King (c.427 BC). In Sophocles’ play Oedipus kills his father (unaware that he is his<br />

father) <strong>and</strong> marries his mother (unaware that she is his mother). On discovering the<br />

truth, Oedipus blinds himself <strong>and</strong> goes into exile. Freud developed two versions of the<br />

Oedipus complex, one for boys <strong>and</strong> one for girls. At around the age of three to five<br />

years, the mother (or who has the symbolic role of the mother) becomes an object of<br />

the boy’s desire. In the light of this desire, the father (or who has the symbolic role of<br />

the father) is seen as a rival for the mother’s love <strong>and</strong> affection. As a consequence, the<br />

boy wishes for the father’s death. However, the boy fears the father’s power, in particular<br />

his power to castrate. So the boy ab<strong>and</strong>ons his desire for the mother <strong>and</strong> begins to<br />

identify with the father, confident in the knowledge that one day he will have the<br />

father’s power, including a wife (a substitute symbolic mother) of his own.<br />

Freud was unsure how the Oedipus complex worked for girls: ‘It must be admitted<br />

. . . that in general our insight into these developmental processes in girls is unsatisfactory,<br />

incomplete <strong>and</strong> vague’ (1977: 321). 18 As a consequence, he continued to revise<br />

his thinking on this subject. One version begins with the girl desiring the father (or<br />

who has the symbolic role of the father). The mother (or who has the symbolic role<br />

of the mother) is seen as a rival for the father’s love <strong>and</strong> affection. The girl wishes for<br />

the mother’s death. The complex is resolved when the girl identifies with the mother,<br />

recognizing that one day she will be like her. But it is a resentful identification – the<br />

mother lacks power. In another account, he argues that the Oedipus complex ‘seldom<br />

goes beyond the taking her mother’s place <strong>and</strong> the adopting of a feminine attitude<br />

towards her father’ (ibid.). Already aware that she has been castrated, the girl seeks<br />

compensation: ‘She gives up her wish for a penis <strong>and</strong> puts in place of it a wish for<br />

a child: <strong>and</strong> with that purpose in view she takes her father as a love-object’ (340). The<br />

girl’s desire for her father’s child gradually diminishes: ‘One has the impression that<br />

the Oedipus complex is then gradually given up because the wish is never fulfilled’<br />

(321). The paradox being, ‘Whereas in boys the Oedipus complex is destroyed by<br />

the castration complex, in girls it is made possible <strong>and</strong> led up to by the castration complex’<br />

(341). 19<br />

There at least two ways that Freudian psychoanalysis can be used as a method to<br />

analyse texts. The first approach is author-centred, treating the text as the equivalent to<br />

an author’s dream. Freud (1985) identifies what he calls ‘the class of dreams that have<br />

never been dreamt at all – dreams created by imaginative writers <strong>and</strong> ascribed to<br />

invented characters in the course of a story’ (33). The surface of a text (words <strong>and</strong><br />

images, etc.) are regarded as the manifest content, while the latent content is the<br />

author’s hidden desires. Texts are read in this way to discover an author’s fantasies;<br />

these are seen as the real meaning of the text. According to Freud (1973a),<br />

An artist is . . . an introvert, not far removed from neurosis. He is oppressed by<br />

excessively powerful instinctual needs. He desires to win honour, power, wealth,<br />

<strong>and</strong> the love of women; but he lacks the means for achieving these satisfactions.<br />

Consequently, like any other unsatisfied man, he turns away from reality <strong>and</strong>


98<br />

Chapter 5 Psychoanalysis<br />

transfers all his interest, <strong>and</strong> his libido too, to the wishful constructions of his life<br />

of phantasy, whence the path might lead to neurosis (423).<br />

The artist sublimates his or her desire. In so doing, she or he makes his or her<br />

fantasies available to others, thus making ‘it possible for others to share in the enjoyment<br />

of them’ (423–4). He or she ‘makes it possible for other people . . . to derive consolation<br />

<strong>and</strong> pleasure in their unconscious which have become inaccessible to them’<br />

(424). Texts ‘allay ungratified wishes – in the first place in the creative artist himself <strong>and</strong><br />

subsequently in his audience or spectators’ (1986: 53). As he explains: ‘The artist’s first<br />

aim is to set himself free <strong>and</strong>, by communicating his work to other people suffering<br />

from the same arrested desires, he offers them the same liberation’ (53).<br />

The second approach is reader-centred, <strong>and</strong> derives from the secondary aspect of the<br />

author-centred approach. This approach is concerned with how texts allow readers to<br />

symbolically play out desires <strong>and</strong> fantasies in the texts they read. In this way, a text<br />

works like a substitute dream. Freud deploys the idea of ‘fore-pleasure’ to explain the<br />

way in which the pleasures of the text ‘make possible the release of still greater pleasure<br />

arising from deeper psychical sources’ (1985: 141). In other words, fictional texts<br />

stage fantasies that offer the possibility of unconscious pleasure <strong>and</strong> satisfaction. As he<br />

further explains,<br />

In my opinion, all the aesthetic pleasure which a creative writer affords us has the<br />

character of a fore-pleasure . . . our actual enjoyment of an imaginative work proceeds<br />

from a liberation of tensions in our minds . . . enabling us thenceforward to<br />

enjoy our day-dreams without self-reproach or shame (ibid.).<br />

In other words, although we may derive pleasure from the aesthetic qualities of a text,<br />

these are really only the mechanism that allows us access to the more profound pleasures<br />

of unconscious fantasy.<br />

Little Redcape<br />

There was once a sweet little girl who was loved by everyone who so much as<br />

looked at her, <strong>and</strong> most of all her gr<strong>and</strong>mother loved her <strong>and</strong> was forever trying<br />

to think of new presents to give the child. Once she gave her a little red velvet<br />

cape, <strong>and</strong> because it suited her so well <strong>and</strong> she never again wanted to wear anything<br />

else, she was known simply as Little Redcape. One day her mother said to<br />

her: ‘Come, Little Redcape, here’s a piece of cake <strong>and</strong> a bottle of wine; take them<br />

out to your gr<strong>and</strong>mother, she’s sick <strong>and</strong> weak <strong>and</strong> she’ll enjoy them very much.<br />

Set out before it gets hot, <strong>and</strong> when you’re on your way watch your step like a<br />

good girl <strong>and</strong> don’t stray from the path, or you’ll fall <strong>and</strong> break the bottle <strong>and</strong><br />

gr<strong>and</strong>mother will get nothing. And when you go into her room, remember to say<br />

good morning <strong>and</strong> not to stare all round the room first.’<br />

‘Don’t worry, I’ll do everything as I should,’ said Little Redcape to her mother<br />

<strong>and</strong> promised faithfully. Now her gr<strong>and</strong>mother lived out in the forest, half an


Freudian psychoanalysis 99<br />

hour from the village. And as Little Redcape entered the forest the wolf met her.<br />

But Little Redcape didn’t know what a wicked beast he was, <strong>and</strong> wasn’t afraid of<br />

him. ‘Good morning, Little Redcape,’ he said. ‘Thank you, wolf.’ ‘Where are you<br />

going so early, Little Redcape?’ ‘To my gr<strong>and</strong>mother’s.’ ‘What are you carrying<br />

under your apron?’ ‘Cake <strong>and</strong> wine – we were baking yesterday, <strong>and</strong> my gr<strong>and</strong>mother’s<br />

ill <strong>and</strong> weak, so she’s to have something nice to help her get strong<br />

again.’ ‘Little Redcape, where does your gr<strong>and</strong>mother live?’ ‘A good quarter of an<br />

hour’s walk further on in the forest, under the three big oak trees, that’s where her<br />

house is; there are hazel hedges by it, I’m sure you know the place,’ said Little<br />

Redcape. The wolf thought to itself: This delicate young thing, she’ll make a<br />

plump morsel, she’ll taste even better than the old woman. But I must go about<br />

it cunningly <strong>and</strong> I’ll catch them both. So he walked for a while beside Little<br />

Redcape <strong>and</strong> then said: ‘Little Redcape, just look at those lovely flowers growing<br />

all round us, why don’t you look about you? I think you don’t even notice how<br />

sweetly the birds are singing. You’re walking straight ahead as if you were going<br />

to school, <strong>and</strong> yet it’s such fun out here in the wood.<br />

Little Redcape looked up, <strong>and</strong> when she saw the sunbeams dancing to <strong>and</strong> fro<br />

between the trees <strong>and</strong> all the lovely flowers growing everywhere, she thought: If I<br />

take Gr<strong>and</strong>mama a bunch of fresh flowers, that’ll please her too; it’s so early that<br />

I’ll still get there soon enough. And she ran off the path <strong>and</strong> into the forest to look<br />

for flowers. And every time she picked one she seemed to see a prettier one growing<br />

further on, <strong>and</strong> she ran to pick it <strong>and</strong> got deeper <strong>and</strong> deeper into the forest.<br />

But the wolf went straight to her gr<strong>and</strong>mother’s house <strong>and</strong> knocked at the door.<br />

‘Who’s there?’ ‘Little Redcape, bringing you some cake <strong>and</strong> wine; open the door.’<br />

‘Just push down the latch,’ said the gr<strong>and</strong>mother, ‘I’m too weak to get out of bed.’<br />

The wolf pushed down the latch, <strong>and</strong> without a word he went straight to the old<br />

woman’s bed <strong>and</strong> gobbled her up. Then he put on her clothes <strong>and</strong> her nightcap<br />

<strong>and</strong> lay down in her bed <strong>and</strong> closed the curtains.<br />

But Little Redcape had been running about picking flowers, <strong>and</strong> when she had<br />

collected so many that she couldn’t carry any more she remembered her gr<strong>and</strong>mother<br />

<strong>and</strong> set out again towards her house. She was surprised to find the door<br />

open, <strong>and</strong> when she went into the room everything seemed so strange that she<br />

thought: Oh my goodness, how nervous I feel today, <strong>and</strong> yet I always enjoy<br />

visiting Gr<strong>and</strong>mama! She called out: ‘Good morning,’ but got no answer. Then<br />

she went to the bed <strong>and</strong> drew back the curtains – <strong>and</strong> there lay her gr<strong>and</strong>mother<br />

with her bonnet pulled down low over her face <strong>and</strong> looking so peculiar.<br />

‘Why, Gr<strong>and</strong>mama, what big ears you have!’ ‘The better to hear you with,’<br />

‘Why Gr<strong>and</strong>mama, what big eyes you have!’ ‘The better to see you with.’ ‘Why,<br />

Gr<strong>and</strong>mama, what big h<strong>and</strong>s you have!’ ‘The better to grab you with.’ ‘But,<br />

Gr<strong>and</strong>mama, what terrible big jaws you have!’ ‘The better to eat you with.’ And<br />

no sooner had the wolf said that than it made one bound out of the bed <strong>and</strong><br />

gobbled up poor Little Redcape.<br />

Having satisfied its appetite, the wolf lay down on the bed again, went to sleep<br />

<strong>and</strong> began to snore very loudly. The huntsman was just passing the house at that


100<br />

Chapter 5 Psychoanalysis<br />

moment <strong>and</strong> he thought: How the old woman is snoring; let’s see if anything’s<br />

the matter with her. So he came into the room, <strong>and</strong> when he got to the bed he<br />

saw the wolf lying there: ‘So I’ve found you here, you old sinner,’ he said, ‘I’ve<br />

been looking for you for a long time.’ He was just about to take aim with his gun<br />

when it occurred to him that the wolf might have swallowed the old woman <strong>and</strong><br />

she might still be saved – so instead of firing he took a pair of scissors <strong>and</strong> began<br />

to cut open the sleeping wolf’s stomach. When he had made a snip or two, he saw<br />

the bright red of the little girl’s cape, <strong>and</strong> after another few snips she jumped out<br />

<strong>and</strong> cried: ‘Oh, how frightened I was, how dark it was inside the wolf!’ And then<br />

her old gr<strong>and</strong>mother came out too, still alive though she could hardly breathe.<br />

But Little Redcape quickly fetched some big stones, <strong>and</strong> with them they filled the<br />

wolf’s belly, <strong>and</strong> when he woke up he tried to run away; but the stones were so<br />

heavy that he collapsed at once <strong>and</strong> was killed by the fall.<br />

At this all three of them were happy; the huntsman skinned the wolf <strong>and</strong> took<br />

his skin home, the gr<strong>and</strong>mother ate the cake <strong>and</strong> drank the wine that Little<br />

Redcape had brought, <strong>and</strong> they made her feel much better. But Little Redcape said<br />

to herself: As long as I live I’ll never again leave the path <strong>and</strong> run into the forest<br />

by myself, when my mother has said I mustn’t.<br />

The above is a fairy story collected by Jacob <strong>and</strong> Wilhelm Grimm in the early nineteenth<br />

century. A psychoanalytic approach to this story would analyse it as a substitute<br />

dream (looking for the processes of the dream-work) in which the drama of the<br />

Oedipus complex is staged. Little Redcape is the daughter who desires the father<br />

(played in the first instance by the wolf). To remove the mother (condensed into the<br />

composite figure of mother <strong>and</strong> gr<strong>and</strong>mother), Little Redcape directs the wolf to her<br />

gr<strong>and</strong>mother’s house. In a story that is extremely elliptical, it is significant that her<br />

description of where her gr<strong>and</strong>mother lives is the only real moment of detail in the<br />

whole story. Answering the wolf’s question, she says, ‘A good quarter of an hour’s walk<br />

further on in the forest, under the three big oak trees, that’s where her house is; there<br />

are hazel hedges by it, I’m sure you know the place.’ The wolf eats the gr<strong>and</strong>mother (a<br />

displacement for sexual intercourse) <strong>and</strong> then eats Little Redcape. The story ends with<br />

the huntsman (the post-Oedipal father) delivering the (gr<strong>and</strong>)mother <strong>and</strong> daughter to<br />

a post-Oedipal world, in which ‘normal’ family relations have been restored. The wolf<br />

is dead <strong>and</strong> Little Redcape promises never again to ‘leave the path <strong>and</strong> run into the forest<br />

by myself, when mother has said I mustn’t’. The final clause hints at Freud’s point<br />

about a resentful identification. In addition to these examples of condensation <strong>and</strong> displacement,<br />

the story contains many instances of symbolization. Examples include the<br />

flowers, the forest, the path, the red velvet cape, the bottle of wine beneath her apron<br />

(if she leaves the path she may ‘fall <strong>and</strong> break the bottle’) – all of these add a definite<br />

symbolic charge to the narrative.<br />

What Freud said about the interpretation of dreams should be borne in mind when<br />

we consider the activities of readers. As you will recall, he warned about ‘the impossibility<br />

of interpreting a dream unless one has the dreamer’s associations to it at one’s


disposal’ (1973b: 36). This raises some very interesting theoretical issues with regard to<br />

the meaning of texts. It suggests that the meaning of a text is not merely in the text<br />

itself; rather, that we need to know the associations a reader brings to bear upon the<br />

text. In other words, he is clearly pointing to the claim that the reader does not passively<br />

accept the meaning of a text: he or she actively produces its meaning, using the<br />

discourses he or she brings to the encounter with the text. My particular reading of<br />

Little Redcape is only possible because of my knowledge of Freudian discourse.<br />

Without this knowledge, my interpretation would be very different.<br />

Freud’s translation of psychoanalysis to textual analysis begins with a somewhat<br />

crude version of psychobiography <strong>and</strong> ends with a rather sophisticated account of how<br />

meanings are made. However, his suggestions about the real pleasures of reading may<br />

have a certain disabling effect on psychoanalytic criticism. That is, if meaning depends<br />

on the associations a reader brings to a text, what value can there be in psychoanalytic<br />

textual analysis? When a psychoanalytic critic tells us that the text really means X, the<br />

logic of Freudian psychoanalysis is to say that this is only what it means to you.<br />

Lacanian psychoanalysis<br />

Lacanian psychoanalysis 101<br />

Jacques Lacan rereads Freud using the theoretical methodology developed by structuralism.<br />

He seeks to anchor psychoanalysis firmly in culture rather than biology. As<br />

he explains, his aim is to turn ‘the meaning of Freud’s work away from the biological<br />

basis he would have wished for it towards the cultural references with which it is shot<br />

through’ (1989: 116). He takes Freud’s developmental structure <strong>and</strong> rearticulates it<br />

through a critical reading of structuralism to produce a post-structuralist psychoanalysis.<br />

Lacan’s account of the development of the human ‘subject’ has had an enormous<br />

influence on cultural studies, especially the study of film.<br />

According to Lacan, we are born into a condition of ‘lack’, <strong>and</strong> subsequently spend<br />

the rest of our lives trying to overcome this condition. ‘Lack’ is experienced in different<br />

ways <strong>and</strong> as different things, but it is always a non-representable expression of the<br />

fundamental condition of being human. The result is an endless quest in search of<br />

an imagined moment of plenitude. Lacan figures this as a search for what he terms<br />

l’objet petit a (the object small other); that which is desired but forever out of reach;<br />

a lost object, signifying an imaginary moment in time. Unable to ever take hold of this<br />

object, we console ourselves with displacement strategies <strong>and</strong> substitute objects.<br />

Lacan argues that we make a journey through three determining stages of development.<br />

The first is the ‘mirror stage’, the second is the ‘fort-da’ game, <strong>and</strong> the third is the<br />

‘Oedipus complex’. Our lives begin in the realm Lacan calls the Real. Here we simply<br />

are. In the Real we do not know where we end <strong>and</strong> where everything else begins. The<br />

Real is like Nature before symbolization (i.e. before cultural classification). It is both<br />

outside in what we might call ‘objective reality’ <strong>and</strong> inside in what Freud calls our<br />

instinctual drives. The Real is everything before it became mediated by the Symbolic.


102<br />

Chapter 5 Psychoanalysis<br />

The Symbolic cuts up the Real into separate parts. If it were possible to get beyond the<br />

Symbolic, we would see the Real as everything merged into one mass. What we think<br />

of as a natural disaster is an irruption of the Real. However, how we categorize it is<br />

always from within the Symbolic; even when we call it a natural disaster, we have symbolized<br />

the Real. To put it another way, nature as Nature is always an articulation of<br />

culture: the Real exists, but always as a reality constituted (that is, brought into being)<br />

by culture – the Symbolic. As Lacan explains it, ‘the kingdom of culture’ is superimposed<br />

‘on that of nature’ (73): ‘the world of words . . . creates the world of things’ (72).<br />

In the realm of the Real, our union with the mother (or who is playing this symbolic<br />

role) is experienced as perfect <strong>and</strong> complete. We have no sense of a separate selfhood.<br />

Our sense of being a unique individual only begins to emerge in what Lacan (2009)<br />

calls ‘the mirror stage’. As Lacan points out, we are all born prematurely. It takes time<br />

to be able to control <strong>and</strong> coordinate our movements. This has not been fully accomplished<br />

when the infant first sees itself in a mirror (between the ages of 6 <strong>and</strong> 18<br />

months). 20 The infant, ‘still sunk in his motor incapacity <strong>and</strong> nursling dependence’<br />

(256), forms an identification with the image in the mirror. The mirror suggests control<br />

<strong>and</strong> coordination that as yet does not exist. Therefore, when the infant first sees itself<br />

in a mirror, it sees not only an image of its current self but also the promise of a more<br />

complete self; it is in this promise that the ego begins to emerge. According to Lacan,<br />

‘The mirror stage is a drama whose internal thrust is precipitated from insufficiency<br />

to anticipation – <strong>and</strong> which manufactures for the subject, caught up in the lure of<br />

spatial identification, the succession of phantasies that extends from a fragmented<br />

body-image to a form of its totality’ (257). On the basis of this recognition or, more<br />

properly, misrecognition (not the self, but an image of the self), we begin to see<br />

ourselves as separate individuals: that is, as both subject (self that looks) <strong>and</strong> object<br />

(self that is looked at). The ‘mirror phase’ heralds the moment of entry into an order<br />

of subjectivity Lacan calls the Imaginary:<br />

The imaginary for Lacan is precisely this realm of images in which we make<br />

identifications, but in the very act of doing so we are led to misperceive <strong>and</strong> misrecognize<br />

ourselves. As a child grows up, it will continue to make such imaginary<br />

identifications with objects, <strong>and</strong> this is how the ego will be built up. For Lacan, the<br />

ego is just this narcissistic process whereby we bolster up a fictive sense of unitary<br />

selfhood by finding something in the world with which we can identify (Eagleton,<br />

1983: 165).<br />

With each new image we will attempt to return to a time before ‘lack’, to find ourselves<br />

in what is not ourselves; <strong>and</strong> each time we will fail. ‘The subject . . . is the place of lack,<br />

an empty place that various attempts at identification try to fill’ (Laclau, 1993: 436).<br />

In other words, desire is the desire to find that which we lack, our selves whole again,<br />

as we were before we encountered the Imaginary <strong>and</strong> the Symbolic. All our acts of<br />

identification are always acts of misidentification; it is never our selves that we recognize<br />

but only ever another potential image of our selves. ‘[D]esire is a metonymy’<br />

(Lacan, 1989: 193): it allows us to discover another part, but never ever the whole.


Lacanian psychoanalysis 103<br />

The second stage of development is the ‘fort-da’ game, originally named by Freud<br />

after watching his gr<strong>and</strong>son throw a cotton reel away (‘gone’) <strong>and</strong> then pull it back<br />

again by means of an attached thread (‘here’). Freud saw this as the child’s way of coming<br />

to terms with its mother’s absence – the reel symbolically representing the mother,<br />

over which the child is exerting mastery. In other words, the child compensates for his<br />

mother’s disappearance by taking control of the situation: he makes her disappear<br />

(fort) <strong>and</strong> then reappear (da). Lacan rereads this as a representation of the child beginning<br />

to enter the Symbolic, <strong>and</strong>, in particular, its introduction into language: ‘the<br />

moment when desire becomes human is also that in which the child is born into language’<br />

(113). Like the ‘fort-da’ game, language is ‘a presence made of absence’ (71).<br />

Once we enter language, the completeness of the Real is gone forever. Language introduces<br />

an alienating split between being <strong>and</strong> meaning; before language we had only<br />

being (a self-complete nature), after language we are both object <strong>and</strong> subject: this is<br />

made manifest every time I think (subject) about myself (object). In other words, ‘I<br />

identify myself in language, but only by losing myself in it like an object’ (94). I am ‘I’<br />

when I speak to you <strong>and</strong> ‘you’ when you speak to me. As Lacan explains, ‘It is not a<br />

question of knowing whether I speak of myself in a way that conforms to what I am,<br />

but rather of knowing whether I am the same as that of which I speak’ (182). In an<br />

attempt to explain this division, Lacan rewrites Rene Descartes’s (1993) ‘I think therefore<br />

I am’ as ‘I think where I am not, therefore I am where I do not think’ (Lacan, 1989:<br />

183). In this formulation ‘I think’ is the subject of the enunciation (the Imaginary/<br />

Symbolic subject) <strong>and</strong> ‘I am’ is the subject of the enunciated (the Real subject).<br />

Therefore, there is always a gap between the I who speaks <strong>and</strong> the I of whom is<br />

spoken. Entry into the Symbolic results in what Lacan (2001) describes as castration:<br />

the symbolic loss of being that is necessary to enter meaning. In order to engage in<br />

culture we have given up self-identity with our nature. When ‘I’ speak I am always<br />

different from the ‘I’ of whom I speak, always sliding into difference <strong>and</strong> defeat: ‘when<br />

the subject appears somewhere as meaning, he is manifested elsewhere as “fading”,<br />

as disappearance’ (218).<br />

The Symbolic is an intersubjective network of meanings, which exists as a structure<br />

we must enter. As such, it is very similar to the way in which culture is understood in<br />

post-Marxist cultural studies (see Chapter 4). It is, therefore, what we experience as<br />

reality: reality being the symbolic organization of the Real. Once in the Symbolic our<br />

subjectivity is both enabled (we can do things <strong>and</strong> make meaning) <strong>and</strong> constrained<br />

(there are limits to what we can do <strong>and</strong> how we can make meaning). The Symbolic<br />

order confirms who we are. I may think I am this or that, but unless this is confirmed<br />

– unless I <strong>and</strong> others can recognize this in the Symbolic – it will not be really true. The<br />

day before I was awarded my first degree I was no more intelligent than the day after,<br />

but in a symbolic sense I was: I now had a degree! The Symbolic order recognized <strong>and</strong><br />

therefore allowed me <strong>and</strong> others to recognize my new intellectual status.<br />

The third stage of development is the ‘Oedipus complex’: the encounter with sexual<br />

difference. Successful completion of the Oedipus complex enforces our transition from<br />

the Imaginary to the Symbolic. It also compounds our sense of ‘lack’. The impossibility<br />

of fulfilment is now experienced as a movement from signifier to signifier, unable


104<br />

Chapter 5 Psychoanalysis<br />

to fix upon a signified. For Lacan (1989), desire is the hopeless pursuit of the fixed<br />

signified (the ‘other’, the ‘Real’, the moment of plenitude, the mother’s body), always<br />

forever becoming another signifier – the ‘incessant sliding of the signified under the<br />

signifier’ (170). Desire exists in the impossibility of closing the gap between self <strong>and</strong> other<br />

– to make good that which we ‘lack’. We long for a time when we existed in ‘nature’<br />

(inseparable from the mother’s body), where everything was simply itself, before the<br />

mediations of language <strong>and</strong> the Symbolic. As we move forward through the narrative<br />

of our lives, we are driven by a desire to overcome the condition, <strong>and</strong> as we look back,<br />

we continue to ‘believe’ (this is mostly an unconscious process) that the union with the<br />

mother (or the person playing the symbolic role of the mother) was a moment of plenitude<br />

before the fall into ‘lack’. The ‘lesson’ of the ‘Oedipus complex’ is that<br />

[t]he child must now resign itself to the fact that it can never have any direct access<br />

to . . . the prohibited body of the mother. . . . [A]fter the Oedipus crisis, we will<br />

never again be able to attain this precious object, even though we will spend all our<br />

lives hunting for it. We have to make do instead with substitute objects . . . with<br />

which we try vainly to plug the gap at the very centre of our being. We move<br />

among substitutes for substitutes, metaphors for metaphors, never able to recover<br />

the pure (if fictive) self-identity <strong>and</strong> self-completion. ...In Lacanian theory, it is<br />

an original lost object – the mother’s body – which drives forward the narrative of<br />

our lives, impelling us to pursue substitutes for this lost paradise in the endless<br />

metonymic movement of desire (Eagleton, 1983: 167, 168, 185).<br />

The ideology of romantic love – in which ‘love’ is the ultimate solution to all our<br />

problems – could be cited as an example of this endless search. What I mean by this is<br />

the way that romance as a discursive practice (see discussion of Foucault in Chapter 6<br />

<strong>and</strong> post-Marxism in Chapter 4) holds that love makes us whole, it completes our<br />

being. Love in effect promises to return us to the Real: that blissful moment of plenitude,<br />

inseparable from the body of the mother. We can see this played out in the<br />

masculine romance of Paris, Texas. The film can be read as a road movie of the unconscious,<br />

a figuration of Travis Henderson’s impossible struggle to return to the moment<br />

of plenitude. The film stages three attempts at return: first, Travis goes to Mexico in<br />

search of his mother’s origins; then he goes to Paris (Texas) in search of the moment<br />

when he was conceived in his mother’s body; finally, in an act of ‘displacement’, he<br />

returns Hunter to Jane (a son to his mother), in symbolic recognition that his own quest<br />

is doomed to failure.<br />

Cine-psychoanalysis<br />

Laura Mulvey’s (1975) essay ‘Visual pleasure <strong>and</strong> narrative cinema’ is perhaps the classic<br />

statement on popular film from the perspective of feminist psychoanalysis. The


Cine-psychoanalysis 105<br />

essay is concerned with how popular cinema produces <strong>and</strong> reproduces what she<br />

calls the ‘male gaze’. Mulvey describes her approach as ‘political psychoanalysis’.<br />

Psychoanalytic theory is ‘appropriated . . . as a political weapon [to demonstrate] the<br />

way the unconscious of patriarchal society has structured film form’ (6).<br />

The inscription of the image of woman in this system is twofold: (i) she is the object<br />

of male desire, <strong>and</strong> (ii) she is the signifier of the threat of castration. In order to challenge<br />

popular cinema’s ‘manipulation of visual pleasure’, Mulvey calls for what she<br />

describes as the ‘destruction of pleasure as a radical weapon’ (7). She is uncompromising<br />

on this point: ‘It is said that analysing pleasure, or beauty, destroys it. This is<br />

the intention of this article’ (8).<br />

So what are the pleasures that must be destroyed? She identifies two. First, there is<br />

scopophilia, the pleasure of looking. Citing Freud, she suggests that it is always more<br />

than just the pleasure of looking: scopophilia involves ‘taking other people as objects,<br />

subjecting them to a controlling gaze’ (ibid.). The notion of the controlling gaze is crucial<br />

to her argument. But so is sexual objectification: scopophilia is also sexual, ‘using<br />

another person as an object of sexual stimulation through sight’ (10). Although it<br />

clearly presents itself to be seen, Mulvey argues that the conventions of popular cinema<br />

are such as to suggest a ‘hermetically sealed world which unwinds magically, indifferent<br />

to the presence of the audience’ (9). The audience’s ‘voyeuristic fantasy’ is encouraged<br />

by the contrast between the darkness of the cinema <strong>and</strong> the changing patterns of<br />

light on the screen.<br />

<strong>Popular</strong> cinema promotes <strong>and</strong> satisfies a second pleasure: ‘developing scopophilia<br />

in its narcissistic aspect’ (ibid.). Here Mulvey draws on Lacan’s (2009) account of the<br />

‘mirror stage’ (see earlier section) to suggest that there is an analogy to be made<br />

between the constitution of a child’s ego <strong>and</strong> the pleasures of cinematic identification.<br />

Just as a child recognizes <strong>and</strong> misrecognizes itself in the mirror, the spectator recognizes<br />

<strong>and</strong> misrecognizes itself on the screen. She explains it thus:<br />

The mirror phase occurs at a time when the child’s physical ambitions outstrip his<br />

motor capacity, with the result that his recognition of himself is joyous in that<br />

he imagines his mirror image to be more complete, more perfect than he experiences<br />

his own body. Recognition is thus overlaid with misrecognition: the image<br />

recognised is conceived as the reflected body of the self, but its misrecognition as<br />

superior projects this body outside itself as an ideal ego, the alienated subject,<br />

which, re-introjected as an ego ideal, gives rise to the future generation of identification<br />

with others (9–10).<br />

Her argument is that popular cinema produces two contradictory forms of visual<br />

pleasure. The first invites scopophilia; the second promotes narcissism. The contradiction<br />

arises because ‘in film terms, one implies a separation of the erotic identity of the<br />

subject from the object on the screen (active scopophilia), the other dem<strong>and</strong>s identification<br />

of the ego with the object on the screen through the spectator’s fascination<br />

with <strong>and</strong> recognition of his like’ (10). In Freudian terms, the separation is between<br />

‘scopophilic instinct (pleasure in looking at another person as an erotic object)’ <strong>and</strong>


106<br />

Chapter 5 Psychoanalysis<br />

‘ego libido (forming identification processes)’ (17). But in a world structured by<br />

‘sexual imbalance’, the pleasure of the gaze has been separated into two distinct positions:<br />

men look <strong>and</strong> women exhibit ‘to-be-looked-at-ness’ – both playing to, <strong>and</strong> signifying,<br />

male desire (11). Women are therefore crucial to the pleasure of the (male) gaze.<br />

Traditionally, the woman displayed has functioned on two levels: as erotic object<br />

for the characters within the screen story, <strong>and</strong> as erotic object for the spectator<br />

within the auditorium, with a shifting tension between the looks on either side of<br />

the screen (11–12).<br />

She gives the example of the showgirl who can be seen to dance for both looks.<br />

When the heroine removes her clothes, it is for the sexual gaze of both the hero in the<br />

narrative <strong>and</strong> the spectator in the auditorium. It is only when they subsequently make<br />

love that a tension arises between the two looks.<br />

<strong>Popular</strong> cinema is structured around two moments: moments of narrative <strong>and</strong><br />

moments of spectacle. The first is associated with the active male, the second with the<br />

passive female. The male spectator fixes his gaze on the hero (‘the bearer of the look’)<br />

to satisfy ego formation, <strong>and</strong> through the hero to the heroine (‘the erotic look’) to<br />

satisfy libido. The first look recalls the moment of recognition/misrecognition in front<br />

of the mirror. The second look confirms women as sexual objects. The second look is<br />

made more complex by the claim that<br />

[u]ltimately, the meaning of woman is sexual difference. . . . She connotes something<br />

that the look continually circles around but disavows: her lack of a penis,<br />

implying a threat of castration <strong>and</strong> hence unpleasure. . . . Thus the woman as icon,<br />

displayed for the gaze <strong>and</strong> enjoyment of men, the active controllers of the look,<br />

always threatens to evoke the anxiety it originally signified (13).<br />

To salvage pleasure <strong>and</strong> escape an unpleasurable re-enactment of the original castration<br />

complex, the male unconscious can take two routes to safety. The first means of<br />

escape is through detailed investigation of the original moment of trauma, usually<br />

leading to ‘the devaluation, punishment or saving of the guilty object’ (ibid.). She cites<br />

the narratives of film noir as typical of this method of anxiety control. The second<br />

means of escape is through ‘complete disavowal of castration by the substitution of a<br />

fetish object or turning the represented figure itself into a fetish so that it becomes reassuring<br />

rather than dangerous’ (13–14). She gives the example of ‘the cult of the female<br />

star . . . [in which] fetishistic scopophilia builds up the physical beauty of the object,<br />

transforming it into something satisfying in itself’ (14). This often leads to the erotic<br />

look of the spectator no longer being borne by the look of the male protagonist, producing<br />

moments of pure erotic spectacle as the camera holds the female body (often<br />

focusing on particular parts of the body) for the unmediated erotic look of the spectator.<br />

Mulvey concludes her argument by suggesting that the pleasure of popular cinema<br />

must be destroyed in order to liberate women from the exploitation <strong>and</strong> oppression of<br />

being the ‘(passive) raw material for the (active) male gaze’ (17). She proposes what


amounts to a Brechtian revolution in the making of films. 21 To produce a cinema no<br />

longer ‘obsessively subordinated to the neurotic needs of the male ego’ (18), it is necessary<br />

to break with illusionism, making the camera material, <strong>and</strong> producing in the<br />

audience ‘dialectics, passionate detachment’ (ibid.). Moreover, ‘[w]omen, whose image<br />

has continually been stolen <strong>and</strong> used for this end [objects of the male gaze], cannot<br />

view the decline of the traditional film form with anything much more than sentimental<br />

regret’ (ibid.). (For feminist criticisms of Mulvey’s argument, see Chapter 7).<br />

Slavoj 2i4ek <strong>and</strong> Lacanian fantasy<br />

Slavoj biaek <strong>and</strong> Lacanian fantasy 107<br />

Terry Eagleton describes the Slovenian critic Slavoj yizek ‘as the most formidably brilliant<br />

exponent of psychoanalysis, indeed of cultural theory in general, to have emerged<br />

in Europe for some decades (quoted in Myers, 2003: 1). Ian Parker (2004), on the<br />

other h<strong>and</strong>, claims that ‘[t]here is no theoretical system as such in yizek’s work, but it<br />

often seems as if there is one. . . . He does not actually add any specific concepts to<br />

those of other theorists but articulates <strong>and</strong> blends the concepts of others’ (115, 157).<br />

The three main influences on yizek’s work are the philosophy of Georg Wilhelm<br />

Friedrich Hegel, the politics of Marx <strong>and</strong> the psychoanalysis of Lacan. It is, however,<br />

the influence of Lacan that organizes the place of Marx <strong>and</strong> Hegel in his work. Whether<br />

we agree with Eagleton or Parker, what is true is that yizek is an interesting reader of<br />

texts (see, for example, yizek, 1991, 2009). In this short account, I will focus almost<br />

exclusively on his elaboration of the Lacanian notion of fantasy.<br />

Fantasy is not the same as illusion; rather, fantasy organizes how we see <strong>and</strong> underst<strong>and</strong><br />

reality. It works as a frame through which we see <strong>and</strong> make sense of the world.<br />

Our fantasies are what make us unique; they provide us with our point of view; organizing<br />

how we see <strong>and</strong> experience the world around us. When the pop musician Jarvis<br />

Cocker (former lead singer with Pulp) appeared on BBC Radio 4’s long-running programme,<br />

Desert Isl<strong>and</strong> Discs (24 April 2005), he made this comment: ‘It doesn’t really<br />

matter where things happen, it’s kinda what’s going on in your head that makes life<br />

interesting.’ This is an excellent example of the organizing role of fantasy.<br />

yizek (1989) argues that ‘ “Reality” is a fantasy construction which enables us to<br />

mask the Real of our desire’ (45). Freud (1976) gives an account of a man who dreams<br />

that his dead son came to him to complain, ‘Can’t you see that I am burning?’ The<br />

father, Freud argues, is awoken by the overwhelming smell of burning. In other words,<br />

the outside stimulation (burning), which had been incorporated into the dream, had<br />

become too strong to be accommodated by the dream. According to yizek (1989),<br />

The Lacanian reading is directly opposed to this. The subject does not awake himself<br />

when the external irritation becomes too strong; the logic of his awakening is<br />

quite different. First he constructs a dream, a story which enables him to prolong his<br />

sleep, to avoid awakening into reality. But the thing that he encounters in the dream,


108<br />

Chapter 5 Psychoanalysis<br />

the reality of his desire, the Lacanian Real – in our case, the reality of the child’s<br />

reproach to his father, ‘Can’t you see that I am burning?’, implying the father’s fundamental<br />

guilt – is more terrifying than so-called external reality itself, <strong>and</strong> that is<br />

why he awakens: to escape the Real of his desire, which announces itself in the<br />

terrifying dream. He escapes into so-called reality to be able to continue to sleep,<br />

to maintain his blindness, to elude awakening into the real of his desire (45).<br />

It is the father’s guilt about not having done enough to prevent his son’s death that is<br />

the Real that the dream seeks to conceal. In other words, the reality to which he awakes<br />

is less Real than that which he encountered in his dream.<br />

yizek (2009) provides other examples from popular culture of the fantasy construction<br />

of reality. Rather than fulfilling desire, fantasy is the staging of desire. As he explains,<br />

[W]hat the fantasy stages is not a scene in which our desire is fulfilled, fully<br />

satisfied, but on the contrary, a scene that realises, stages, the desire as such. The<br />

fundamental point of psychoanalysis is that desire is not something given in<br />

advance, but something that has to be constructed – <strong>and</strong> it is precisely the role of<br />

fantasy to give the coordinates of the subject’s desire, to specify its object, to locate<br />

the position the subject assumes in it. It is only through fantasy that the subject is<br />

constituted as desiring: through fantasy, we learn how to desire (335).<br />

In this way, then, ‘fantasy space functions as an empty surface, a kind of screen for the<br />

projection of desires’ (336). He gives as an example a short story by Patricia Highsmith,<br />

‘Black House’. In a small American town old men gather in a bar each evening to<br />

remember the past. In different ways their memories always seem to become focused<br />

on an old black house on a hill just outside town. It is in this house that each man can<br />

recall certain adventures, especially sexual, having taken place. There is now, however,<br />

a general agreement amongst the men that it would be dangerous to go back to the<br />

house. A young newcomer to the town informs the men that he is not afraid to visit<br />

the old house. When he does explore the house, he finds only ruin <strong>and</strong> decay.<br />

Returning to the bar, he informs the men that the black house is no different from any<br />

other old, decaying property. The men are outraged by this news. As he leaves, one of<br />

the men attacks him, resulting in the young newcomer’s death. Why were the men so<br />

outraged by the young newcomer’s behaviour? yizek explains it thus:<br />

[T]he ‘black house’ was forbidden to the men because it functioned as an empty<br />

space wherein they could project their nostalgic desires, their distorted memories;<br />

by publicly stating that the ‘black house’ was nothing but an old ruin, the young<br />

intruder reduced their fantasy space to everyday, common reality. He annulled the<br />

difference between reality <strong>and</strong> fantasy space, depriving the men of the place in<br />

which they were able to articulate their desires (337).<br />

Desire is never fulfilled or fully satisfied, it is endlessly reproduced in our fantasies.<br />

‘Anxiety is brought on by the disappearance of desire’ (336). In other words, anxiety is


the result of getting too close to what we desire, thus threatening to eliminate ‘lack’<br />

itself <strong>and</strong> end desire. This is further complicated by the retroactive nature of desire. As<br />

yizek observes, ‘The paradox of desire is that it posits retroactively its own cause, i.e.<br />

the objet a [object small other] is an object that can be perceived only by a gaze “distorted”<br />

by desire, an object that does not exist for an “objective” gaze’ (339). In other<br />

words, what I desire is organized by processes of fantasy which fix on an object <strong>and</strong><br />

generate a desire which appears to have drawn me to the object but which in fact did<br />

not exist until I first fixed upon the object: what appears to be a forward movement is<br />

always retroactive.<br />

Further reading<br />

Further reading 109<br />

Storey, John (ed.), <strong>Cultural</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Popular</strong> <strong>Culture</strong>: A Reader, 4th edition, Harlow:<br />

Pearson Education, 2009. This is the companion volume to this book. It contains<br />

examples of most of the work discussed here. This book <strong>and</strong> the companion Reader<br />

are supported by an interactive website (www.pearsoned.co.uk/storey). The website<br />

has links to other useful sites <strong>and</strong> electronic resources.<br />

Belsey, Catherine, <strong>Culture</strong> <strong>and</strong> the Real, London: Routledge, 2005. A very clear account<br />

of Lacan <strong>and</strong> yizek.<br />

Easthope, Antony, The Unconscious, London: Routledge, 1999. An excellent introduction<br />

to psychoanalysis. Highly recommended.<br />

Evans, Dylan, An Introductory Dictionary of Lacanian Psychoanalysis, London: Routledge,<br />

1996. Indispensable for underst<strong>and</strong>ing Lacan.<br />

Frosh, Stephen, Key Concepts in Psychoanalysis, London: British Library, 2002. An excellent<br />

introduction.<br />

Kay, Sarah, yiZek: A Critical Introduction, Cambridge: Polity Press, 2003. An excellent<br />

introduction. I particularly like the way she acknowledges that sometimes she just<br />

does not underst<strong>and</strong> what yizek is saying.<br />

Laplanche, J. <strong>and</strong> J.-B. Pontalis, The Language of Psychoanalysis, London: Karnac Books,<br />

1988. A brilliant glossary of concepts.<br />

Mitchell, Juliet, Psychoanalysis <strong>and</strong> Feminism, Harmondsworth: Pelican, 1974. A classic<br />

<strong>and</strong> groundbreaking account of how feminism can use psychoanalysis to undermine<br />

patriarchy. As she claims, ‘psychoanalysis is not a recommendation for a patriarchal<br />

society, but an analysis of one.’<br />

Myers, Tony, Slavoj YiZek, London: Routledge, 2003. A very accessible introduction to<br />

yizek’s work.<br />

Parker, Ian, Slavoj YiZek: A Critical Introduction, London: Pluto, 2004. Another very good<br />

account of yizek’s work. The most critical of the recent introduction.<br />

Wright, Elizabeth, Psychoanalytic Criticism, London: Methuen, 1984. A very good introduction<br />

to psychoanalytic criticism.


6 Structuralism <strong>and</strong><br />

post-structuralism<br />

Structuralism, unlike the other approaches discussed here, is, as Terry Eagleton (1983)<br />

points out, ‘quite indifferent to the cultural value of its object: anything from War <strong>and</strong><br />

Peace to The War Cry will do. The method is analytical, not evaluative’ (96). Structuralism<br />

is a way of approaching texts <strong>and</strong> practices that is derived from the theoretical<br />

work of the Swiss linguist Ferdin<strong>and</strong> de Saussure. Its principal exponents are French:<br />

Louis Althusser in Marxist theory, Rol<strong>and</strong> Barthes in literary <strong>and</strong> cultural studies,<br />

Michel Foucault in philosophy <strong>and</strong> history, Jacques Lacan in psychoanalysis, Claude<br />

Lévi-Strauss in anthropology <strong>and</strong> Pierre Macherey in literary theory. Their work is often<br />

very different, <strong>and</strong> at times very difficult. What unites these authors is the influence of<br />

Saussure, <strong>and</strong> the use of a particular vocabulary drawn from his work. It is as well, then,<br />

to start our exploration with a consideration of his work in linguistics. This is best<br />

approached by examining a number of key concepts.<br />

Ferdin<strong>and</strong> de Saussure<br />

Saussure divides language into two component parts. When I write the word ‘dog’ it<br />

produces the inscription ‘dog’, but also the concept or mental image of a dog: a fourlegged<br />

canine creature. He calls the first the ‘signifier’, <strong>and</strong> the second the ‘signified’.<br />

Together (like two sides of a coin or a sheet of paper) they make up the ‘sign’. He then<br />

goes on to argue that the relationship between signifier <strong>and</strong> signified is completely<br />

arbitrary. The word ‘dog’, for example, has no dog-like qualities; there is no reason why<br />

the signifier ‘dog’ should produce the signified ‘dog’: four-legged canine creature (other<br />

languages have different signifiers to produce the same signified). The relationship<br />

between the two is simply the result of convention – of cultural agreement. The<br />

signifier ‘dog’ could just as easily produce the signified ‘cat’: four-legged feline creature.<br />

On the basis of this claim, he suggests that meaning is not the result of an essential correspondence<br />

between signifiers <strong>and</strong> signifieds; it is rather the result of difference <strong>and</strong><br />

relationship. In other words, Saussure’s is a relational theory of language. Meaning is<br />

produced, not through a one-to-one relation to things in the world, but by establishing<br />

difference. For example, ‘mother’ has meaning in relation to ‘father’, ‘daughter’,


112<br />

Chapter 6 Structuralism <strong>and</strong> post-structuralism<br />

‘son’, etc. For example, traffic lights operate within a system of four signs: red = stop,<br />

green = go, amber = prepare for red, amber <strong>and</strong> red = prepare for green. The relationship<br />

between the signifier ‘green’ <strong>and</strong> the signified ‘go’ is arbitrary; there is nothing in<br />

the colour green that naturally attaches it to the verb ‘go’. Traffic lights would work<br />

equally well if red signified ‘go’ <strong>and</strong> green signified ‘stop’. The system works not by<br />

expressing a natural meaning but by marking a difference, a distinction within a system<br />

of difference <strong>and</strong> relationships. To make the point about meaning being relational<br />

rather than substantial, Saussure gives the example of train systems. The 12.11 from<br />

Bochum to Bremen, for instance, runs every day at the same time. To each of these<br />

trains we assign the same identity (‘the 12.11 from Bochum to Bremen’). However, we<br />

know that the locomotive, the carriages, the staff, are unlikely to be the same each day.<br />

The identity of the train is not fixed by its substance, but by its relational distinction<br />

from other trains, running at other times, on other routes. Saussure’s other example is<br />

the game of chess. A knight, for example, could be represented in any way a designer<br />

thought desirable, provided that how it was represented marked it as different from the<br />

other chess pieces.<br />

According to Saussure, meaning is also made in a process of combination <strong>and</strong> selection,<br />

horizontally along the syntagmatic axis, <strong>and</strong> vertically along the paradigmatic<br />

axis. For example, the sentence, ‘Miriam made chicken broth today’, is meaningful<br />

through the accumulation of its different parts: Miriam/made/chicken broth/today.<br />

Its meaning is only complete once the final word is spoken or inscribed. Saussure calls<br />

this process the syntagmatic axis of language. One can add other parts to extend its<br />

meaningfulness: ‘Miriam made chicken broth today while dreaming about her lover.’<br />

Meaning is thus accumulated along the syntagmatic axis of language. This is perfectly<br />

clear when a sentence is interrupted. For example, ‘I was going to say that . . .’; ‘It is<br />

clear to me that Luie should . . .’; ‘You promised to tell me about . . .’.<br />

Substituting certain parts of the sentence for new parts can also change meaning. For<br />

example, I could write, ‘Miriam made salad today while dreaming about her lover’ or<br />

‘Miriam made chicken broth today while dreaming about her new car’. Such substitutions<br />

are said to be operating along the paradigmatic axis of language. Let us consider<br />

a more politically charged example. ‘Terrorists carried out an attack on an army base<br />

today.’ Substitutions from the paradigmatic axis could alter the meaning of this sentence<br />

considerably. If we substitute ‘freedom fighters’ or ‘anti-imperialist volunteers’ for<br />

the word ‘terrorists’ we would have a sentence meaningful in quite a different way. This<br />

would be achieved without any reference to a corresponding reality outside of the<br />

sentence itself. The meaning of the sentence is produced through a process of selection<br />

<strong>and</strong> combination. This is because the relationship between ‘sign’ <strong>and</strong> ‘referent’ (in our<br />

earlier example, real dogs in the real world) is also arbitrary. It follows, therefore, that<br />

the language we speak does not simply reflect the material reality of the world; rather,<br />

by providing us with a conceptual map with which to impose a certain order on what<br />

we see <strong>and</strong> experience, the language we speak plays a significant role in shaping what<br />

constitutes for us the reality of the material world.<br />

Structuralists argue that language organizes <strong>and</strong> constructs our sense of reality – different<br />

languages in effect produce different mappings of the real. When, for example, a


Ferdin<strong>and</strong> de Saussure 113<br />

European gazes at a snowscape, he or she sees snow. An Inuit, with over fifty words to<br />

describe snow, looking at the same snowscape would presumably see so much more.<br />

Therefore an Inuit <strong>and</strong> a European st<strong>and</strong>ing together surveying the snowscape would<br />

in fact be seeing two quite different conceptual scenes. Similarly, Australian Aborigines<br />

have many words to describe the desert. What these examples demonstrate to a structuralist<br />

is that the way we conceptualize the world is ultimately dependent on the<br />

language we speak. And by analogy, it will depend on the culture we inhabit. The<br />

meanings made possible by language are thus the result of the interplay of a network<br />

of relationships between combination <strong>and</strong> selection, similarity <strong>and</strong> difference.<br />

Meaning cannot be accounted for by reference to an extra-linguistic reality. As Saussure<br />

(1974) insists, ‘in language there are only differences without positive terms ...<br />

[L]anguage has neither ideas nor sounds that existed before the linguistic system, but<br />

only conceptual <strong>and</strong> phonic differences that have issued from the system’ (120). We<br />

might want to query this assumption by noting that Inuits name the snowscape differently<br />

because of the material bearing it has on their day-to-day existence. It could also<br />

be objected that substituting ‘terrorists’ for ‘freedom fighters’ produces meanings not<br />

accounted for purely by linguistics (see Chapter 4).<br />

Saussure makes another distinction that has proved essential to the development of<br />

structuralism. This is the division of language into langue <strong>and</strong> parole. Langue refers to<br />

the system of language, the rules <strong>and</strong> conventions that organize it. This is language as<br />

a social institution, <strong>and</strong> as Rol<strong>and</strong> Barthes (1967) points out, ‘it is essentially a collective<br />

contract which one must accept in its entirety if one wishes to communicate’ (14).<br />

Parole refers to the individual utterance, the individual use of language. To clarify this<br />

point, Saussure compares language to the game of chess. Here we can distinguish<br />

between the rules of the game <strong>and</strong> an actual game of chess. Without the body of rules<br />

there could be no actual game, but it is only in an actual game that these rules are made<br />

manifest. Therefore, there is langue <strong>and</strong> parole, structure <strong>and</strong> performance. It is the<br />

homogeneity of the structure that makes the heterogeneity of the performance possible.<br />

Finally, Saussure distinguishes between two theoretical approaches to linguistics.<br />

The diachronic approach which studies the historical development of a given language,<br />

<strong>and</strong> the synchronic approach which studies a given language in one particular moment<br />

in time. He argues that in order to found a science of linguistics it is necessary to adopt<br />

a synchronic approach. Structuralists have, generally speaking, taken the synchronic<br />

approach to the study of texts or practices. They argue that in order to really underst<strong>and</strong><br />

a text or practice it is necessary to focus exclusively on its structural properties. This of<br />

course allows critics hostile to structuralism to criticize it for its ahistorical approach to<br />

culture.<br />

Structuralism takes two basic ideas from Saussure’s work. First, a concern with the<br />

underlying relations of texts <strong>and</strong> practices, the ‘grammar’ that makes meaning possible.<br />

Second, the view that meaning is always the result of the interplay of relationships of<br />

selection <strong>and</strong> combination made possible by the underlying structure. In other words,<br />

texts <strong>and</strong> practices are studied as analogous to language. Imagine, for example, that<br />

aliens from outer space had l<strong>and</strong>ed in Barcelona in May 1999, <strong>and</strong> as an earthly display<br />

of welcome they were invited to attend the Champions League Final between


114<br />

Chapter 6 Structuralism <strong>and</strong> post-structuralism<br />

Manchester United <strong>and</strong> Bayern Munich. What would they witness? Two groups of men<br />

in different coloured costumes, one red, the other in silver <strong>and</strong> maroon, moving at different<br />

speeds, in different directions, across a green surface, marked with white lines.<br />

They would notice that a white spherical projectile appeared to have some influence on<br />

the various patterns of cooperation <strong>and</strong> competition. They would also notice a man<br />

dressed in dark green, with a whistle which he blew to stop <strong>and</strong> start the combinations<br />

of play. They would also note that he appeared to be supported by two other men<br />

also dressed in dark green, one on either side of the main activity, each using a flag to<br />

support the limited authority of the man with the whistle. Finally, they would note the<br />

presence of two men, one at each end of the playing area, st<strong>and</strong>ing in front of partly<br />

netted structures. They would see that periodically these men engaged in acrobatic<br />

routines that involved contact with the white projectile. The visiting aliens could<br />

observe the occasion <strong>and</strong> describe what they saw to each other, but unless someone<br />

explained to them the rules of association football, its structure, the Champions League<br />

Final, in which Manchester United became the first team in history to win the ‘treble’<br />

of Champions League, Premier League <strong>and</strong> FA Cup, would make very little sense to<br />

them at all. It is the underlying rules of cultural texts <strong>and</strong> practices that interest structuralists.<br />

It is structure that makes meaning possible. The task of structuralism, therefore,<br />

is to make explicit the rules <strong>and</strong> conventions (the structure) which govern the<br />

production of meaning (acts of parole).<br />

Claude Lévi-Strauss, Will Wright <strong>and</strong> the American<br />

Western<br />

Claude Lévi-Strauss (1968) uses Saussure to help him discover the ‘unconscious foundations’<br />

(18) of the culture of so-called ‘primitive’ societies. He analyses cooking, manners,<br />

modes of dress, aesthetic activity <strong>and</strong> other forms of cultural <strong>and</strong> social practices<br />

as analogous to systems of language; each in its different way is a mode of communication,<br />

a form of expression. As Terence Hawkes (1977) points out, ‘His quarry, in<br />

short, is the langue of the whole culture; its system <strong>and</strong> its general laws: he stalks it<br />

through the particular varieties of its parole’ (39). In pursuit of his quarry, Lévi-Strauss<br />

investigates a number of ‘systems’. It is, however, his analysis of myth that is of central<br />

interest to the student of popular culture. He claims that beneath the vast heterogeneity<br />

of myths, there can be discovered a homogeneous structure. In short, he argues that<br />

individual myths are examples of parole, articulations of an underlying structure or<br />

langue. By underst<strong>and</strong>ing this structure we should be able to truly underst<strong>and</strong> the<br />

meaning – ‘operational value’ (Lévi-Strauss, 1968: 209) – of particular myths.<br />

Myths, Lévi-Strauss argues, work like language: they comprise individual<br />

‘mythemes’, analogous to individual units of language, ‘morphemes’ <strong>and</strong> ‘phonemes’.<br />

Like morphemes <strong>and</strong> phonemes, mythemes only take on meaning when combined in


Claude Lévi-Strauss, Will Wright <strong>and</strong> the American Western 115<br />

particular patterns. Seen in this way, the anthropologists’ task is to discover the underlying<br />

‘grammar’: the rules <strong>and</strong> regulations that make it possible for myths to be meaningful.<br />

He also observes that myths are structured in terms of ‘binary oppositions’.<br />

Dividing the world into mutually exclusive categories produces meaning: culture/<br />

nature, man/woman, black/white, good/bad, us/them, for example. Drawing on<br />

Saussure, he sees meaning as a result of the interplay between a process of similarity<br />

<strong>and</strong> difference. For example, in order to say what is bad we must have some notion of<br />

what is good. In the same way, what it means to be a man is defined against what it<br />

means to be a woman.<br />

Lévi-Strauss claims that all myths have a similar structure. Moreover, he also claims<br />

– although this is by no means his primary focus – that all myths have a similar sociocultural<br />

function within society. That is, the purpose of myth is to make the world<br />

explicable, to magically resolve its problems <strong>and</strong> contradictions. As he contends,<br />

‘mythical thought always progresses from the awareness of oppositions toward their<br />

resolution. . . . The purpose of myth is to provide a logical model capable of overcoming<br />

a contradiction’ (224, 229). Myths are stories we tell ourselves as a culture in order<br />

to banish contradictions <strong>and</strong> make the world underst<strong>and</strong>able <strong>and</strong> therefore habitable;<br />

they attempt to put us at peace with ourselves <strong>and</strong> our existence.<br />

In Sixguns <strong>and</strong> Society, Will Wright (1975) uses Lévi-Strauss’s structuralist methodology<br />

to analyse the Hollywood Western. He argues that much of the narrative power<br />

of the Western is derived from its structure of binary oppositions. However, Wright differs<br />

from Lévi-Strauss in that his concern ‘is not to reveal a mental structure but to show<br />

how the myths of a society, through their structure, communicate a conceptual order<br />

to the members of that society’ (17). In short, whereas Lévi-Strauss’s primary concern<br />

is the structure of the human mind, Wright’s focus is on the way the Western ‘presents<br />

a symbolically simple but remarkably deep conceptualisation of American social<br />

beliefs’ (23). He contends that the Western has evolved through three stages: ‘classic’<br />

(including a variation he calls ‘vengeance’), ‘transition theme’ <strong>and</strong> ‘professional’.<br />

Despite the genre’s different types, he identifies a basic set of structuring oppositions,<br />

shown in Table 6.1. But, as he insists (taking him beyond Lévi-Strauss), in order to<br />

fully underst<strong>and</strong> the social meaning of a myth, it is necessary to analyse not only its<br />

binary structure but its narrative structure – ‘the progression of events <strong>and</strong> the resolution<br />

of conflicts’ (24). The ‘classic’ Western, according to Wright, is divided into sixteen<br />

narrative ‘functions’ (see Propp, 1968):<br />

Table 6.1 Structuring oppositions in the Western.<br />

Inside society Outside society<br />

Good Bad<br />

Strong Weak<br />

Civilization Wilderness (49)


116<br />

Chapter 6 Structuralism <strong>and</strong> post-structuralism<br />

1. The hero enters a social group.<br />

2. The hero is unknown to the society.<br />

3. The hero is revealed to have an exceptional ability.<br />

4. The society recognizes a difference between themselves <strong>and</strong> the hero; the hero is<br />

given a special status.<br />

5. The society does not completely accept the hero.<br />

6. There is a conflict of interests between the villains <strong>and</strong> the society.<br />

7. The villains are stronger than the society; the society is weak.<br />

8. There is a strong friendship or respect between the hero <strong>and</strong> a villain.<br />

9. The villains threaten the society.<br />

10. The hero avoids involvement in the conflict.<br />

11. The villains endanger a friend of the hero.<br />

12. The hero fights the villains.<br />

13. The hero defeats the villains.<br />

14. The society is safe.<br />

15. The society accepts the hero.<br />

16. The hero loses or gives up his special status (165).<br />

Shane (1953) is perhaps the best example of the classic Western: the story of a<br />

stranger who rides out of the wilderness <strong>and</strong> helps a group of farmers defeat a powerful<br />

rancher, <strong>and</strong> then rides away again, back into the wilderness. In the classic Western<br />

the hero <strong>and</strong> society are (temporarily) aligned in opposition to the villains who remain<br />

outside society. In the ‘transition theme’ Western, which Wright claims provides a<br />

bridge between the classic Western, the form which dominated the 1930s, the 1940s<br />

<strong>and</strong> most of the 1950s, <strong>and</strong> the professional Western, the form which dominated the<br />

1960s <strong>and</strong> 1970s, the binary oppositions are reversed, <strong>and</strong> we see the hero outside<br />

society struggling against a strong, but corrupt <strong>and</strong> corrupting civilization (Table 6.2).<br />

Many of the narrative functions are also inverted. Instead of being outside the society,<br />

the hero begins as a valued member of the society. But the society is revealed to be<br />

the real ‘villain’ in opposition to the hero <strong>and</strong> those outside society <strong>and</strong> civilization. In<br />

his support for, <strong>and</strong> eventual alignment with, those outside society <strong>and</strong> civilization, he<br />

himself crosses from inside to outside <strong>and</strong> from civilization to wilderness. But in the<br />

end the society is too strong for those outside it, who are ultimately powerless against<br />

its force. The best they can do is escape to the wilderness.<br />

Table 6.2 Structuring oppositions in the ‘professional’ Western.<br />

Hero Society<br />

Outside society Inside society<br />

Good Bad<br />

Weak Strong<br />

Wilderness Civilization (48–9)


Claude Lévi-Strauss, Will Wright <strong>and</strong> the American Western 117<br />

Although, according to Wright, the last ‘transition theme’ Western was Johnny Guitar<br />

in 1954, it appears clear, using his own binary oppositions <strong>and</strong> narrative functions,<br />

that Dances with Wolves, made in 1990, is a perfect example of the form. A cavalry<br />

officer, decorated for bravery, rejects the East (‘civilization’) <strong>and</strong> requests a posting to<br />

the West (‘wilderness’) – as the film publicity puts it, ‘in 1864 one man went in search<br />

of the frontier <strong>and</strong> found himself’. He also found society among the Sioux. The film tells<br />

the story of how ‘he is drawn into the loving <strong>and</strong> honourable folds of a Sioux tribe . . .<br />

<strong>and</strong> ultimately, the crucial decision he must make as white settlers continue their violent<br />

<strong>and</strong> ruthless journey into the l<strong>and</strong>s of the Native Americans’ (Guild Home Video,<br />

1991). His decision is to fight on the side of the Sioux against the ‘civilization’ he has<br />

rejected. Finally, considered a traitor by the cavalry, he decides to leave the Sioux, so as<br />

not to give the cavalry an excuse to butcher them. The final scene, however, shows his<br />

departure as, unbeknown to him or the Sioux, the cavalry close in for what is to be<br />

undoubtedly the massacre of the tribe.<br />

If we accept Dances with Wolves as a ‘transition theme’ Western, it raises some interesting<br />

questions about the film as myth. Wright (1975) claims that each type of<br />

Western ‘corresponds’ to a different moment in the recent economic development of<br />

the United States:<br />

the classic Western plot corresponds to the individualistic conception of society<br />

underlying a market economy. . . . [T]he vengeance plot is a variation that begins<br />

to reflect changes in the market economy. . . . [T]he professional plot reveals a new<br />

conception of society corresponding to the values <strong>and</strong> attitudes inherent in a<br />

planned, corporate economy (15).<br />

Each type in turn articulates its own mythic version of how to achieve the American<br />

Dream:<br />

The classical plot shows that the way to achieve such human rewards as friendship,<br />

respect, <strong>and</strong> dignity is to separate yourself from others <strong>and</strong> use your strength as an<br />

autonomous individual to succor them. . . . The vengeance variation . . . weakens<br />

the compatibility of the individual <strong>and</strong> society by showing that the path to respect<br />

<strong>and</strong> love is to separate yourself from others, struggling individually against your<br />

many <strong>and</strong> strong enemies but striving to remember <strong>and</strong> return to the softer values<br />

of marriage <strong>and</strong> humility. The transition theme, anticipating new social values,<br />

argues that love <strong>and</strong> companionship are available at the cost of becoming a social<br />

outcast to the individual who st<strong>and</strong>s firmly <strong>and</strong> righteously against the intolerance<br />

<strong>and</strong> ignorance of society. Finally, the professional plot . . . argues that companionship<br />

<strong>and</strong> respect are to be achieved only by becoming a skilled technician, who<br />

joins an elite group of professionals, accepts any job that is offered, <strong>and</strong> has loyalty<br />

only to the integrity of the team, not to any competing social or community<br />

values (186–7).<br />

Given the critical <strong>and</strong> financial success of Dances with Wolves (winner of seven<br />

Oscars; fifth most successful film in both the UK <strong>and</strong> the USA, grossing £10.9 million


118<br />

Chapter 6 Structuralism <strong>and</strong> post-structuralism<br />

<strong>and</strong> $122.5 million in the first year of release in the UK <strong>and</strong> USA respectively), it may<br />

well (if we accept Wright’s rather reductive correspondence theory) represent a<br />

‘transition theme’ Western that marks the beginning of a reverse transition, back to a<br />

time of less mercenary social <strong>and</strong> community values – back in fact to a time of society<br />

<strong>and</strong> community.<br />

Rol<strong>and</strong> Barthes: Mythologies<br />

Rol<strong>and</strong> Barthes’s early work on popular culture is concerned with the processes of<br />

signification, the mechanisms by which meanings are produced <strong>and</strong> put into circulation.<br />

Mythologies (1973) is a collection of essays on French popular culture. In it he discusses,<br />

among many things, wrestling, soap powders <strong>and</strong> detergents, toys, steak <strong>and</strong><br />

chips, tourism <strong>and</strong> popular attitudes towards science. His guiding principle is always<br />

to interrogate ‘the falsely obvious’ (11), to make explicit what too often remains<br />

implicit in the texts <strong>and</strong> practices of popular culture. His purpose is political; his target<br />

is what he calls the ‘bourgeois norm’ (9). As he states in the ‘Preface’ to the 1957 edition,<br />

‘I resented seeing Nature <strong>and</strong> History confused at every turn, <strong>and</strong> I wanted to track<br />

down, in the decorative display of what-goes-without-saying, the ideological abuse<br />

which, in my view, is hidden there’ (11). Mythologies is the most significant attempt to<br />

bring the methodology of semiology to bear on popular culture. The possibility of<br />

semiology was first posited by Saussure (1974):<br />

Language is a system of signs that express ideas, <strong>and</strong> is therefore comparable to<br />

a system of writing, the alphabet of deaf mutes, symbolic rites, polite formulas,<br />

military signals, etc. ...A science that studies the life of signs within society is<br />

conceivable ...I shall call it semiology (16).<br />

Mythologies concludes with the important theoretical essay, ‘Myth today’. 22 In the essay<br />

Barthes outlines a semiological model for reading popular culture. He takes Saussure’s<br />

schema of signifier/signified = sign <strong>and</strong> adds to it a second level of signification.<br />

As we noted earlier, the signifier ‘dog’ produces the signified ‘dog’: a four-legged<br />

canine creature. Barthes argues that this indicates only primary signification. The sign<br />

‘dog’ produced at the primary level of signification is available to become the signifier<br />

‘dog’ at a second level of signification. This may then produce at the secondary level the<br />

signified ‘dog’: an unpleasant human being. As illustrated in Table 6.3, the sign of primary<br />

signification becomes the signifier in a process of secondary signification. In<br />

Elements of Semiology, Barthes (1967) substitutes the more familiar terms ‘denotation’<br />

(primary signification) <strong>and</strong> ‘connotation’ (secondary signification): ‘the first system<br />

[denotation] becomes the plane of expression or signifier of the second system [connotation].<br />

. . . The signifiers of connotation . . . are made up of signs (signifiers <strong>and</strong><br />

signifieds united) of the denoted system’ (89–91).


Table 6.3 Primary <strong>and</strong> secondary signification.<br />

Primary signification 1. Signifier 2. Signified<br />

Denotation 3. Sign<br />

Secondary signification I. SIGNIFIER II. SIGNIFIED<br />

Connotation III. SIGN<br />

Rol<strong>and</strong> Barthes: Mythologies 119<br />

He claims that it is at the level of secondary signification or connotation that myth<br />

is produced for consumption. By myth he means ideology understood as a body of<br />

ideas <strong>and</strong> practices, which by actively promoting the values <strong>and</strong> interests of dominant<br />

groups in society, defend the prevailing structures of power. To underst<strong>and</strong> this aspect<br />

of his argument, we need to underst<strong>and</strong> the polysemic nature of signs, that is, that they<br />

have the potential to signify multiple meanings. An example might make the point<br />

clearer. I discussed in Chapter 1 how the Conservative Party presented a party political<br />

broadcast that concluded with the word ‘socialism’ being transposed into red prison<br />

bars. This was undoubtedly an attempt to fix the secondary signification or connotations<br />

of the word ‘socialism’ to mean restrictive, imprisoning, against freedom. Barthes<br />

would see this as an example of the fixing of new connotations in the production of<br />

myth – the production of ideology. He argues that all forms of signification can be<br />

shown to operate in this way. His most famous example of the workings of secondary<br />

signification (see Photo 6.1) is taken from the cover of the French magazine Paris Match<br />

(1955). He begins his analysis by establishing that the primary level of signification<br />

consists of a signifier: patches of colour <strong>and</strong> figuration. This produces the signified:<br />

‘a black soldier saluting the French flag’. Together they form the primary sign. The primary<br />

sign then becomes the signifier ‘black soldier saluting the French flag’, producing,<br />

at the level of secondary signification, the signified ‘French imperiality’. Here is his<br />

account of his encounter with the cover of the magazine:<br />

I am at the barber’s, <strong>and</strong> a copy of Paris Match is offered to me. On the cover, a<br />

young Negro in a French uniform is saluting, with his eyes uplifted, probably fixed<br />

on the fold of the tricolour. All this is the meaning of the picture. But, whether<br />

naively or not, I see very well what it signifies to me: that France is a great Empire,<br />

that all her sons, without colour discrimination, faithfully serve under her flag, <strong>and</strong><br />

that there is no better answer to the detractors of an alleged colonialism than the<br />

zeal shown by this Negro in serving his so called oppressors. I am therefore faced<br />

with a greater semiological system: there is a signifier, itself already formed with<br />

a previous system (a black soldier is giving the French salute); there is a signified<br />

(it is a purposeful mixture of Frenchness <strong>and</strong> militariness); finally there is a presence<br />

of the signified through the signifier (2009: 265).<br />

At the first level: black soldier saluting the French flag. At the second level: a positive<br />

image of French imperialism. The cover illustration is therefore seen to represent Paris


120<br />

Chapter 6 Structuralism <strong>and</strong> post-structuralism<br />

Photo 6.1 Black soldier saluting the flag.


Rol<strong>and</strong> Barthes: Mythologies 121<br />

Match’s attempt to produce a positive image of French imperialism. Following the<br />

defeat in Vietnam (1946–54), <strong>and</strong> the then current war in Algeria (1954–62), such an<br />

image would seem to many to be of some political urgency. And as Barthes suggests,<br />

‘myth has ...a double function: it points out <strong>and</strong> it notifies, it makes us underst<strong>and</strong><br />

something <strong>and</strong> it imposes it on us’ (265). What makes this a possibility are the shared<br />

cultural codes on which both Barthes <strong>and</strong> the readership of Paris Match are able to<br />

draw. Connotations are therefore not simply produced by the makers of the image, but<br />

activated from an already existing cultural repertoire. In other words, the image both<br />

draws from the cultural repertoire <strong>and</strong> at the same time adds to it. Moreover, the cultural<br />

repertoire does not form a homogeneous block. Myth is continually confronted<br />

by counter-myth. For example, an image containing references to pop music culture<br />

might be seen by a young audience as an index of freedom <strong>and</strong> heterogeneity, whilst<br />

to an older audience it might signal manipulation <strong>and</strong> homogeneity. Which codes are<br />

mobilized will largely depend on the triple context of the location of the text, the historical<br />

moment <strong>and</strong> the cultural formation of the reader.<br />

In ‘The photographic message’ Barthes (1977a: 26) introduces a number of further<br />

considerations. Context of publication is important, as I have already said. If the photograph<br />

of the black soldier saluting the flag had appeared on the cover of the Socialist<br />

Review, its connotative meaning(s) would have been very different. Readers would have<br />

looked for irony. Rather than being read as a positive image of French imperialism, it<br />

would have been seen as a sign of imperial exploitation <strong>and</strong> manipulation. In addition<br />

to this, a socialist reading the original Paris Match would not have seen the image as a<br />

positive image of French imperialism, but as a desperate attempt to project such an<br />

image given the general historical context of France’s defeat in Vietnam <strong>and</strong> its pending<br />

defeat in Algeria. But despite all this the intention behind the image is clear:<br />

Myth has an imperative, buttonholing character . . . [it arrests] in both the physical<br />

<strong>and</strong> the legal sense of the term: French imperialism condemns the saluting Negro<br />

to be nothing more than an instrumental signifier, the Negro suddenly hails me<br />

in the name of French imperiality; but at the same moment the Negro’s salute<br />

thickens, becomes vitrified, freezes into an eternal reference meant to establish<br />

French imperiality (2009: 265–6). 23<br />

This is not the only way French imperialism might be given positive connotations.<br />

Barthes suggests other mythical signifiers the press might use: ‘I can very well give to<br />

French imperiality many other signifiers beside a Negro’s salute: a French general pins<br />

a decoration on a one-armed Senegalese, a nun h<strong>and</strong>s a cup of tea to a bed ridden Arab,<br />

a white schoolmaster teaches attentive piccaninnies’ (266).<br />

Barthes envisages three possible reading positions from which the image could be<br />

read. The first would simply see the black soldier saluting the flag as an ‘example’ of<br />

French imperiality, a ‘symbol’ for it. This is the position of those who produce such<br />

myths. The second would see the image as an ‘alibi’ for French imperiality. This is the<br />

position of the socialist reader discussed above. The final reading position is that of the<br />

‘myth-consumer’ (268). He or she reads the image not as an example or as a symbol,


122<br />

Chapter 6 Structuralism <strong>and</strong> post-structuralism<br />

nor as an alibi: the black soldier saluting the flag ‘is the very presence of French imperiality’<br />

(267); that is, the black soldier saluting the flag is seen as naturally conjuring up<br />

the concept of French imperiality. There is not anything to discuss: it is obvious that<br />

one implies the presence of the other. The relationship between the black soldier saluting<br />

the flag <strong>and</strong> French imperiality has been ‘naturalized’. As Barthes explains:<br />

what allows the reader to consume myth innocently is that he does not see it as<br />

a semiological system but as an inductive one. Where there is only equivalence,<br />

he sees a kind of causal process: the signifier <strong>and</strong> the signified have, in his eyes, a<br />

natural relationship. This confusion can be expressed otherwise: any semiological<br />

system is a system of values; now the myth-consumer takes the signification for a<br />

system of facts: myth is read as a factual system, whereas it is but a semiological<br />

system (268).<br />

There is of course a fourth reading position, that of Barthes himself – the mythologist.<br />

This reading produces what he calls a ‘structural description’. It is a reading position<br />

that seeks to determine the means of ideological production of the image, its<br />

transformation of history into nature. According to Barthes, ‘Semiology has taught us<br />

that myth has the task of giving an historical intention a natural justification, <strong>and</strong> making<br />

contingency appear eternal. Now this process is exactly that of bourgeois ideology’<br />

(ibid.). His argument is that ‘myth is constituted by the loss of the historical quality of<br />

things: in it, things lose the memory that they once were made’ (ibid.). It is what he<br />

calls ‘depoliticized speech’.<br />

In the case of the soldier Negro . . . what is got rid of is certainly not French imperiality<br />

(on the contrary, since what must be actualised is its presence); it is the<br />

contingent, historical, in one word: fabricated, quality of colonialism. Myth does<br />

not deny things, on the contrary, its function is to talk about them; simply, it purifies<br />

them, it makes them innocent, it gives them a natural <strong>and</strong> eternal justification, it<br />

gives them a clarity which is not that of an explanation but that of a statement of<br />

fact. If I state the fact of French imperiality without explaining it, I am very near<br />

to finding that it is natural <strong>and</strong> goes without saying. . . . In passing from history to<br />

nature, myth acts economically: it abolishes the complexity of human acts ...it<br />

organises a world which is without contradictions because it is without depth, a<br />

world wide open <strong>and</strong> wallowing in the evident, it establishes a blissful clarity:<br />

things appear to mean something by themselves (269). 24<br />

Images rarely appear without the accompaniment of a linguistic text of one kind or<br />

another. A newspaper photograph, for example, will be surrounded by a title, a caption,<br />

a story, <strong>and</strong> the general layout of the page. It will also, as we have already noted,<br />

be situated within the context of a particular newspaper or magazine. The context provided<br />

by the Daily Telegraph (readership <strong>and</strong> reader expectation) is very different from<br />

that provided by the Socialist Worker. The accompanying text controls the production<br />

of connotations in the image.


Rol<strong>and</strong> Barthes: Mythologies 123<br />

Formerly, the image illustrated the text (made it clearer); today, the text loads the<br />

image, burdening it with culture, a moral, an imagination. Formerly, there was<br />

reduction from text to image; today, there is amplification from one to the other.<br />

The connotation is now experienced only as the natural resonance of the fundamental<br />

denotation constituted by the photographic analogy <strong>and</strong> we are thus confronted<br />

with a typical process of naturalisation of the cultural (Barthes, 1977a: 26).<br />

In other words, image does not illustrate text, it is the text which amplifies the connotative<br />

potential of the image. He refers to this process as ‘relay’. The relationship can<br />

of course work in other ways. For example, rather than ‘amplifying a set of connotations<br />

already given in the photograph . . . the text produces (invents) an entirely new<br />

signified which is retroactively projected into the image, so much so as to appear<br />

denoted there’ (27). An example might be a photograph taken in 2007 (see Figure 6.1)<br />

of a rock star looking reflective, <strong>and</strong> originally used to promote a love song: ‘My baby<br />

done me wrong’. In late 2008 the photograph is reused to accompany a newspaper<br />

account of the death by a drug overdose of one of the rock star’s closest friends. The<br />

photograph is recaptioned: ‘Drugs killed my best friend’ (see Figure 6.2). The caption<br />

would feed into the image producing (inventing) connotations of loss, despair, <strong>and</strong> a<br />

certain thoughtfulness about the role of drugs in rock music culture. Barthes refers to<br />

this process as ‘anchorage’. What this example of the different meanings made of the<br />

same photograph of the rock star reveals, as noted earlier, is the polysemic nature of all<br />

signs: that is, their potential for multiple signification. Without the addition of a linguistic<br />

text the meaning of the image is very difficult to pin down. The linguistic message<br />

works in two ways. It helps the reader to identify the denotative meaning of the<br />

image: this is a rock star looking reflective. Second, it limits the potential proliferation<br />

of the connotations of the image: the rock star is reflective because of the drug overdose<br />

by one of his closest friends. Therefore, the rock star is contemplating the role of<br />

drugs in rock music culture. Moreover, it tries to make the reader believe that the connotative<br />

meaning is actually present at the level of denotation.<br />

Figure 6.1 Rock-a-day Johnny ‘My baby done me wrong’ from the album Dogbucket<br />

Days.


124<br />

Chapter 6 Structuralism <strong>and</strong> post-structuralism<br />

Figure 6.2 Rock-a-day Johnny ‘Drugs killed my best friend’.<br />

What makes the move from denotation to connotation possible is the store of social<br />

knowledge (a cultural repertoire) upon which the reader is able to draw when he or she<br />

reads the image. Without access to this shared code (conscious or unconscious) the<br />

operations of connotation would not be possible. And of course such knowledge is<br />

always both historical <strong>and</strong> cultural. That is to say, it might differ from one culture to<br />

another, <strong>and</strong> from one historical moment to another. <strong>Cultural</strong> difference might also<br />

be marked by differences of class, race, gender, generation or sexuality. As Barthes<br />

points out,<br />

reading closely depends on my culture, on my knowledge of the world, <strong>and</strong> it is<br />

probable that a good press photograph (<strong>and</strong> they are all good, being selected)<br />

makes ready play with the supposed knowledge of its readers, those prints being<br />

chosen which comprise the greatest possible quantity of information of this kind<br />

in such a way as to render the reading fully satisfying (29).<br />

Again, as he explains, ‘the variation in readings is not, however, anarchic; it depends<br />

on the different kinds of knowledge – practical, national, cultural, aesthetic – invested<br />

in the image [by the reader]’ (Barthes, 1977b: 46). Here we see once again the analogy<br />

with language. The individual image is an example of parole, <strong>and</strong> the shared code (cultural<br />

repertoire) is an example of langue. The best way to draw together the different<br />

elements of this model of reading is to demonstrate it. In 1991 the Department<br />

of Education <strong>and</strong> Science (DES) produced an advertisement that they placed in the<br />

popular film magazine Empire (see Photo 6.2). The image shows two 14-year-old<br />

schoolgirls: Jackie intends to go to university; Susan intends to leave school at 16.<br />

The poster’s aim is to attract men <strong>and</strong> women to the teaching profession. It operates a<br />

double bluff. That is, we see the two girls, read the caption <strong>and</strong> decide which girl wants<br />

to go to university, which girl wants to leave at 16. The double bluff is that the girl who<br />

wants to leave is the one convention – those without the required cultural competence


Photo 6.2 Advertising for teachers.<br />

Rol<strong>and</strong> Barthes: Mythologies 125<br />

to teach – would consider studious. It is a double bluff because we are not intended to<br />

be taken in by the operation. We can congratulate ourselves on our perspicacity. We,<br />

unlike others, have not been taken in – we have the necessary cultural competence.<br />

Therefore we are excellent teacher material. The advertisement plays with the knowledge<br />

necessary to be a teacher <strong>and</strong> allows us to recognize that knowledge in ourselves:<br />

it provides us with a position from which to say: ‘Yes, I should be a teacher.’


126<br />

Chapter 6 Structuralism <strong>and</strong> post-structuralism<br />

Post-structuralism<br />

Post-structuralists reject the idea of an underlying structure upon which meaning can<br />

rest secure <strong>and</strong> guaranteed. Meaning is always in process. What we call the ‘meaning’<br />

of a text is only ever a momentary stop in a continuing flow of interpretations following<br />

interpretations. Saussure, as we have noted, posited language as consisting of<br />

the relationship between the signifier, signified <strong>and</strong> the sign. The theorists of poststructuralism<br />

suggest that the situation is more complex than this: signifiers do not produce<br />

signifieds, they produce more signifiers. Meaning as a result is a very unstable<br />

thing. In ‘The death of the author’, the now post-structuralist Barthes (1977c) insists<br />

that a text is ‘a multi dimensional space in which a variety of writings, none of them<br />

original, blend <strong>and</strong> clash. The text is a tissue of quotations drawn from the innumerable<br />

centres of culture’ (146). Only a reader can bring a temporary unity to a text.<br />

Unlike the work that can be seen lying in apparent completion on library shelves <strong>and</strong><br />

in bookshops, the text ‘is experienced only in an activity of production’ (157). A text is<br />

a work seen as inseparable from the active process of its many readings.<br />

Jacques Derrida<br />

Post-structuralism is virtually synonymous with the work of Jacques Derrida. The sign,<br />

as we noted already, is for Saussure made meaningful by its location in a system of differences.<br />

Derrida adds to this the notion that meaning is also always deferred, never<br />

fully present, always both absent <strong>and</strong> present (see discussion of defining popular culture<br />

in Chapter 1). Derrida (1973) has invented a new word to describe the divided<br />

nature of the sign: différance, meaning both to defer <strong>and</strong> to differ. Saussure’s model of<br />

difference is spatial, in which meaning is made in the relations between signs that are<br />

locked together in a self-regulating structure. Derrida’s model of différance, however, is<br />

both structural <strong>and</strong> temporal; meaning depends on structural difference but also on<br />

temporal relations of before <strong>and</strong> after. For example, if we track the meaning of a word<br />

through a dictionary we encounter a relentless deferment of meaning. If we look up<br />

the signifier ‘letter’ in the Collins Pocket Dictionary of the English Language, we discover it<br />

has five possible signifieds: a written or printed message, a character of the alphabet,<br />

the strict meaning of an agreement, precisely (as in ‘to the letter’) <strong>and</strong> to write or mark<br />

letters on a sign. If we then look up one of these, the signified ‘[a written or printed]<br />

message’, we find that it too is a signifier producing four more signifieds: a communication<br />

from one person or group to another, an implicit meaning, as in a work of art,<br />

a religious or political belief that someone attempts to communicate to others, <strong>and</strong> to<br />

underst<strong>and</strong> (as in ‘to get the message’). Tracking through the dictionary in this way<br />

confirms a relentless intertextual deferment of meaning, ‘the indefinite referral of


Jacques Derrida 127<br />

signifier to signifier . . . which gives the signified meaning no respite . . . so that it<br />

always signifies again’ (1978a: 25). It is only when located in a discourse <strong>and</strong> read in a<br />

context that there is a temporary halt to the endless play of signifier to signifier. For<br />

example, if we read or hear the words ‘nothing was delivered’, they would mean something<br />

quite different depending on whether they were the opening words of a novel, a<br />

line from a poem, an excuse, a jotting in a shopkeeper’s notebook, a line from a song,<br />

an example from a phrase book, part of a monologue in a play, part of a speech in a<br />

film, an illustration in an explanation of différance. But even context cannot fully control<br />

meaning: the phrase ‘nothing was delivered’ will carry with it the ‘trace’ of meanings<br />

from other contexts. If I know the line is from a song, this will resonate across the<br />

words as I read them in a shopkeeper’s notebook.<br />

For Derrida, the binary opposition, so important to structuralism, is never a simple<br />

structural relation; it is always a relation of power, in which one term is in a position<br />

of dominance with regard to the other. Moreover, the dominance of one over the other<br />

(a matter of, say, priority or privilege) is not something which arises ‘naturally’ out of<br />

the relationship, but something which is produced in the way the relationship is constructed.<br />

Black <strong>and</strong> white, it could be argued, exist in a binary opposition, one always<br />

existing as the absent other when one of the terms is defined. But it is not difficult to<br />

see how in many powerful discourses, white is the positive term, holding priority <strong>and</strong><br />

privilege over black. Even leaving aside racism, there is a long history of black connoting<br />

negatively <strong>and</strong> white connoting positively. The DES advertisement I discussed earlier<br />

contains what Derrida (1978b) would call a ‘violent hierarchy’ (41) in its couplet:<br />

‘good’ girl, who is interested in electromagnetism, genetics <strong>and</strong> Charles Dickens; <strong>and</strong><br />

‘bad’ girl, who prefers music, clothes <strong>and</strong> boys. Derrida (1976) refers to the ‘strange<br />

economy of the supplement’ (154) to point to the unstable interplay between such<br />

binary oppositions. In his analyses of Jean Jacques Rousseau’s ‘confessional’ <strong>and</strong><br />

linguistic writings, Derrida deconstructs the binary opposition between speech <strong>and</strong><br />

writing. Rousseau considers speech as the natural way to express thought; writing, he<br />

regards as a ‘dangerous supplement’. However, when presence is no longer guaranteed<br />

by speech, writing becomes a necessary means to protect presence. But for Rousseau<br />

writing can only be a ‘supplement to speech’: ‘it is not natural. It diverts the immediate<br />

presence of thought. . . . [It is] a sort of artificial <strong>and</strong> artful ruse to make speech present<br />

when it is actually absent. It is a violence done to the natural destiny of the language’<br />

(144). To supplement means both to add <strong>and</strong> to substitute. Writing is therefore both<br />

an addition to speech <strong>and</strong> a substitute for speech. But speech itself is a supplement. It<br />

does not exist outside culture. Speech cannot therefore play Edenic nature to writing’s<br />

fallen culture, both always already belong to ‘the order of the supplement’ (149).<br />

For, as Derrida insists, ‘the indefinite process of supplementarity has always already<br />

infiltrated presence, always already inscribed there the space of repetition <strong>and</strong> the<br />

splitting of the self [from pure self-presence]’ (163). Nature may have preceded culture,<br />

but our sense of nature as pure presence is a product of culture. Writing is not the fall<br />

of language, it is inscribed in its origins. Rousseau, in a sense, already knows this:<br />

according to Derrida, he ‘declares what he wishes to say’, but he also ‘describes that which


128<br />

Chapter 6 Structuralism <strong>and</strong> post-structuralism<br />

he does not wish to say’ (229). It is in the unravelling of this contradiction that the binary<br />

oppositions speech/writing, nature/culture are deconstructed – the privileged term in<br />

the opposition is shown to be dependent on the other for its meaning.<br />

We noted in Chapter 1 how high culture has often depended on popular culture to<br />

give it definitional solidity. Derrida’s critique of Rousseau alerts us to the way in which<br />

one side in such couplets is always privileged over the other; one side always claims a<br />

position of status (of pure presence) over the other. Derrida also demonstrates that<br />

they are not pure opposites – each is motivated by the other, ultimately dependent on<br />

the absent other for its own presence <strong>and</strong> meaning. There is no naturally ‘good’ girl<br />

who stays on at school, which can be opposed to a naturally ‘bad’ girl who wants<br />

to leave at 16. Simply to reverse the binary opposition would be to keep in place the<br />

assumptions already constructed by the opposition. We must do more than ‘simply . . .<br />

neutralise the binary oppositions. . . . One of the two terms controls the other . . .<br />

holds the superior position. To deconstruct the opposition [we must] . . . overthrow<br />

the hierarchy’ (1978b: 41). Instead of accepting the double bluff, a ‘deconstructive’<br />

reading would wish to dismantle the couplet to demonstrate that it can only be held<br />

in place by a certain ‘violence’ – a certain set of dubious assumptions about gender <strong>and</strong><br />

sexuality. A deconstructive reading could also be made of Dances with Wolves: instead<br />

of the film being seen to invert the binary oppositions <strong>and</strong> narrative functions of<br />

Wright’s model, we might perhaps consider the way the film challenges the hierarchy<br />

implicit in the model. As Derrida (1976) points out:<br />

[A deconstructive] reading must always aim at a certain relationship, unperceived<br />

by the writer, between what he comm<strong>and</strong>s <strong>and</strong> what he does not comm<strong>and</strong> of the<br />

patterns of language that he uses. This relationship is ...a signifying structure that<br />

critical [i.e. deconstructive] reading should produce. . . . [That is, a] production<br />

[which] attempts to make the not seen accessible to sight (158, 163).<br />

Discourse <strong>and</strong> power: Michel Foucault<br />

One of the primary concerns of Michel Foucault is the relationship between knowledge<br />

<strong>and</strong> power <strong>and</strong> how this relationship operates within discourses <strong>and</strong> discursive formations.<br />

Foucault’s concept of discourse is similar to Althusser’s idea of the ‘problematic’;<br />

that is, both are organized <strong>and</strong> organizing bodies of knowledge, with rules <strong>and</strong> regulations<br />

which govern particular practices (ways of thinking <strong>and</strong> acting).<br />

Discourses work in three ways: they enable, they constrain, <strong>and</strong> they constitute. As<br />

Foucault (1989) explains, discourses are ‘practices that systematically form the objects<br />

of which they speak’ (49). Language, for example, is a discourse: it enables me to speak,<br />

it constrains what I can say, it constitutes me as a speaking subject (i.e. it situates <strong>and</strong> produces<br />

my subjectivity: I know myself in language; I think in language; I talk to myself<br />

in language). Academic disciplines are also discourses: like languages, they enable,


Table 6.4 Film as an object of study.<br />

Economics = commodity<br />

Literary studies = artistic text similar to literary text<br />

History = historical document<br />

Art history = example of visual culture<br />

<strong>Cultural</strong> studies = example of popular culture<br />

Film studies = textual object of study<br />

Media studies = particular type of media<br />

Discourse <strong>and</strong> power: Michel Foucault 129<br />

constrain, <strong>and</strong> constitute. Table 6.4 outlines the different ways film may be studied.<br />

Each discipline speaks about film in a particular way <strong>and</strong> in so doing it enables <strong>and</strong><br />

constrains what can be said about film. But they do not just speak about film; by constructing<br />

film as a specific object of study, they constitute film as a specific reality (‘the<br />

real meaning of film’). The game of netball is also a discourse: to play netball (regardless<br />

of individual talent), you must be familiar with the rules of the game; these both<br />

enable <strong>and</strong> constrain your performance. But they also constitute you as a netball<br />

player. In other words, you are only a netball player if you play netball. Being a netball<br />

player is not a ‘given’ (i.e. expression of ‘nature’): it is enabled, constrained <strong>and</strong> constituted<br />

in discourse (i.e. a product of ‘culture’). In these ways, discourses produce subject<br />

positions we are invited to occupy (member of a language community; student of<br />

film; netball player). Discourses, therefore, are social practices in which we engage;<br />

they are like social ‘scripts’ we perform (consciously <strong>and</strong> unconsciously). What we<br />

think of as ‘experience’ is always experience in or of a particular discourse. Moreover,<br />

what we think of as our ‘selves’ is the internalization of a multiplicity of discourses.<br />

In other words, all the things we are, are enabled, constrained <strong>and</strong> constituted in<br />

discourses.<br />

Discursive formations consist of the hierarchical criss-crossing of particular discourses.<br />

The different ways to study film discussed earlier produces a discursive formation.<br />

In The History of Sexuality, Foucault (1981) charts the development of the<br />

discursive formation of sexuality. In doing this, he rejects what he calls ‘the repressive<br />

hypothesis’ (10); that is, the idea of sexuality as something ‘essential’ that the<br />

Victorians repressed. Instead he follows a different set of questions:<br />

Why has sexuality been so widely discussed <strong>and</strong> what has been said about it? What<br />

were the effects of power generated by what was said? What are the links between<br />

these discourses, these effects of power, <strong>and</strong> the pleasures that were invested by<br />

them? What knowledge (savoir) was formed as a result of this linkage? (11)<br />

He tracks the discourse of sexuality through a series of discursive domains: medicine,<br />

demography, psychiatry, pedagogy, social work, criminology, governmental. Rather<br />

than silence, he encounters ‘a political, economic <strong>and</strong> technical incitement to talk


130<br />

Chapter 6 Structuralism <strong>and</strong> post-structuralism<br />

about sex’ (22–3). He argues that the different discourses on sexuality are not about sexuality,<br />

they actually constitute the reality of sexuality. In other words, the Victorians<br />

did not repress sexuality, they actually invented it. This is not to say that sexuality did<br />

not exist non-discursively, but to claim that our ‘knowledge’ of sexuality <strong>and</strong> the<br />

‘power–knowledge’ relations of sexuality are discursive.<br />

Discourses produce knowledge <strong>and</strong> knowledge is always a weapon of power: ‘it is in<br />

discourse that power <strong>and</strong> knowledge are joined together’ (Foucault, 2009: 318). The<br />

Victorian invention of sexuality did not just produce knowledge about sexuality, it<br />

sought to produce power over sexuality; this was knowledge that could be deployed to<br />

categorize <strong>and</strong> to organize behaviour; divide it into the ‘normal’ <strong>and</strong> the unacceptable.<br />

In this way, then, ‘power produces knowledge . . . power <strong>and</strong> knowledge directly imply<br />

one another . . . there is no power relation without the correlative constitution of a<br />

field of knowledge, nor any knowledge that does not presuppose <strong>and</strong> constitute at the<br />

same time power relations’ (1979: 27). Power, however, should not be thought of as a<br />

negative force, something which denies, represses, negates; power is productive.<br />

We must cease once <strong>and</strong> for all to describe the effects of power in negative terms:<br />

it ‘excludes’, it ‘represses’, it ‘censors’, it ‘abstracts’, it ‘masks’, it ‘conceals’. In fact,<br />

power produces; it produces reality; it produces domains of objects <strong>and</strong> rituals of<br />

truth (194).<br />

Power produces reality; through discourses it produces the ‘truths’ we live by: ‘Each<br />

society has its own regime of truth, its “general politics” of truth – that is, the types<br />

of discourse it accepts <strong>and</strong> makes function as true’ (Foucault, 2002a: 131). One of his<br />

central aims, therefore, is to discover ‘how men [<strong>and</strong> women] govern (themselves <strong>and</strong><br />

others) by the production of truth (. . . the establishment of domains in which the<br />

practice of true <strong>and</strong> false can be made at once ordered <strong>and</strong> pertinent)’ (2002b: 230).<br />

What Foucault calls ‘regimes of truth’ do not have to be ‘true’; they have only to be<br />

thought of as ‘true’ <strong>and</strong> acting on as if ‘true’. If ideas are believed, they establish <strong>and</strong><br />

legitimate particular regimes of truth. For example, before it was discovered that the<br />

earth is round, thinking the earth was flat was to be in the regime of truth of contemporary<br />

of science <strong>and</strong> theology; saying it was round could get you tortured or killed. In<br />

Chapter 8 we will examine Orientalism as a powerful regime of truth.<br />

Discourse is not just about the imposition of power. As Foucault (2009) points out,<br />

‘Where there is power there is resistance’ (315).<br />

Discourses are not once <strong>and</strong> for all subservient to power or raised up against it, any<br />

more than silences are. We must make allowances for the complex <strong>and</strong> unstable<br />

process whereby discourse can be both an instrument <strong>and</strong> an effect of power, but<br />

also an hindrance, a stumbling block, a point of resistance <strong>and</strong> a starting point<br />

for an opposing strategy. Discourse transmits <strong>and</strong> produces power; it reinforces it,<br />

but also undermines it <strong>and</strong> exposes it, renders it fragile <strong>and</strong> makes it possible to<br />

thwart it (318).


The panoptic machine<br />

The panoptic machine 131<br />

The panopticon is a type of prison building designed by Jeremy Bentham in 1787 (see<br />

Figure 6.3). At the centre of the building is a tower that allows an inspector to observe<br />

all the prisoners in the surrounding cells without the prisoners knowing whether or not<br />

they are in fact being observed. According to Bentham, the panopticon is ‘A new mode<br />

of obtaining power of mind over mind, in a quantity hitherto without example: <strong>and</strong><br />

that, to a degree equally without example’ (Bentham 1995: 31). He also believed that<br />

the panopticon design might also be used in ‘any sort of establishment, in which persons<br />

of any description are to be kept under inspection, [including] poor-houses,<br />

lazarettos, houses of industry, manufactories, hospitals, work-houses, mad-houses,<br />

<strong>and</strong> schools’ (29).<br />

According to Foucault (1979),<br />

the major effect of the Panopticon [is] to induce in the inmate a state of conscious<br />

<strong>and</strong> permanent visibility that assures the automatic functioning of power. . . .<br />

[S]urveillance is permanent in its effects, even if it is discontinuous in its action;<br />

that the perfection of power should tend to render its actual exercise unnecessary.<br />

Figure 6.3 The panoptic machine.


132<br />

Chapter 6 Structuralism <strong>and</strong> post-structuralism<br />

. . . [T]he inmates . . . [are] caught up in a power situation of which they are themselves<br />

the bearers. . . . He who is subjected to a field of visibility, <strong>and</strong> who knows<br />

it, assumes responsibility for the constraints of power; he makes them play spontaneously<br />

upon himself; he inscribes in himself the power relation in which he<br />

simultaneously plays both roles; he becomes the principle of his own subjection<br />

(201, 202–3).<br />

In other words, inmates do not know whether or not they are actually being watched.<br />

Therefore, they learn to behave as if they are always being watched. This is the power<br />

of the panopticon. Panopticism is the extension of this system of surveillance to society<br />

as a whole.<br />

According to Foucault, Bentham’s panopticon is, therefore, profoundly symptomatic<br />

of a historical shift, from the eighteenth century onwards, in methods of<br />

social control. This is a movement from punishment (enforcing norms of behaviour<br />

through spectacular displays of power: public hangings <strong>and</strong> torture, etc.) to discipline<br />

(enforcing norms of behaviour through surveillance); a shift from ‘exceptional discipline<br />

to one of generalised surveillance . . . the formation of what might be called in<br />

general the disciplinary society’ (209). As he explains, the panopticon is ‘a generalizable<br />

model [for] . . . defining power relations in terms of the everyday life. . . . [I]t is a<br />

diagram of a mechanism of power reduced to its ideal form’ (205). The movement<br />

from spectacle to surveillance turns ‘the whole social body into a field of perception’<br />

(214). The intersecting gazes of power criss-cross the social body, drawing more <strong>and</strong><br />

more aspects of human existence into its field of vision. But it is not simply that power<br />

catches us in its gaze, rather power works when we recognize its gaze. As Foucault<br />

makes clear, using a theatre metaphor, ‘We are neither in the amphitheatre, nor on the<br />

stage, but in the panoptic machine, invested by its effects of power, which we bring to<br />

ourselves since we are part of the mechanism’ (217). In this way, then, he argues,<br />

surveillance has become the dominant mode of the operation of power. ‘Panopticism<br />

is a form of power . . . organised around the norm, in terms of what [is] normal or not,<br />

correct or not, in terms of what one must do or not do’ (2002c, 58–9). It is a fundamental<br />

aspect of what he calls ‘normalisation’ (79).<br />

An obvious confirmation of his claim is the widespread use of surveillance technologies<br />

in contemporary society. For example, a survey conducted in 2002 estimated<br />

that there are around 4.2 million CCTV cameras in the United Kingdom; roughly<br />

equivalent to one camera for every fourteen people. 25 This st<strong>and</strong>s in direct relation to<br />

Bentham’s panopticon. But the discipline of surveillance has also had a profound<br />

influence on popular culture. I can think of at least four examples of surveillance<br />

media. Perhaps the most obvious examples are television programmes such as Big<br />

Brother <strong>and</strong> I’m a Celebrity, Get me Out of Here, in which surveillance is a fundamental<br />

aspect of how these programmes work. In many ways Big Brother is panopticon television<br />

in its most visible form. Undoubtedly, part of its appeal is that it appears to enable<br />

us to assume the role of Bentham’s imaginary inspector, as we take pleasure in the<br />

ability to observe without being observed, to be involved without being involved, <strong>and</strong><br />

to judge without being judged. However, in the light of Foucault’s point about the


production of regimes of truth, we should not assume that we are really outside the<br />

reach of the st<strong>and</strong>ards <strong>and</strong> norms that Big Brother promotes <strong>and</strong> legitimates. In other<br />

words, it might be possible to argue that the gaze of Big Brother is reciprocal; it disciplines<br />

us as much as the contestants we watch being disciplined: we are in the cells<br />

<strong>and</strong> not in the inspector’s tower.<br />

The increasing number of celebrity surveillance magazines, such as Reveal, Closer,<br />

Heat <strong>and</strong> New, work in a similar way. Celebrities are monitored <strong>and</strong> scrutinized, especially<br />

in terms of body size <strong>and</strong> sexual <strong>and</strong> social behaviour, for our supposedly anonymous<br />

pleasure <strong>and</strong> entertainment. But again, the norms <strong>and</strong> st<strong>and</strong>ards that are used to<br />

criticize <strong>and</strong> ridicule celebrities are the same norms <strong>and</strong> st<strong>and</strong>ards that can be used to<br />

discipline us. Similarly, in ‘make-over’ <strong>and</strong> ‘talk-show’ surveillance programmes such<br />

as The Jerry Springer Show <strong>and</strong> The Jeremy Kyle Show, <strong>and</strong> What Not To Wear <strong>and</strong> Ten<br />

Years Younger, advice is freely combined with abuse <strong>and</strong> ridicule, as subjects are encouraged,<br />

often aggressively <strong>and</strong> to the smug self-satisfaction of the presenters, to embrace<br />

self-discipline in order to comply with currently accepted st<strong>and</strong>ards of aesthetic <strong>and</strong><br />

behavioural normality. 26 The fact that we are on the other side of the screen does not<br />

mean that we are safe from the dem<strong>and</strong> to conform, or safely outside of the panoptic<br />

machine.<br />

Further reading<br />

Further reading 133<br />

Storey, John (ed.), <strong>Cultural</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Popular</strong> <strong>Culture</strong>: A Reader, 4th edition, Harlow:<br />

Pearson Education, 2009. This is the companion volume to this book. It contains<br />

examples of most of the work discussed here. This book <strong>and</strong> the companion Reader<br />

are supported by an interactive website (www.pearsoned.co.uk/storey). The website<br />

has links to other useful sites <strong>and</strong> electronic resources.<br />

During, Simon, Foucault <strong>and</strong> Literature: Towards a Genealogy of Writing, London:<br />

Routledge, 1992. Although the focus is on literature, this is nevertheless a very<br />

useful introduction to Foucault.<br />

Eagleton, Terry, Literary <strong>Theory</strong>: An Introduction, Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1983.<br />

Contains an excellent chapter on post-structuralism.<br />

Easthope, Antony, British Post-Structuralism, London: Routledge, 1988. An ambitious<br />

attempt to map the field. Useful chapters on film theory, cultural studies, deconstruction<br />

<strong>and</strong> historical studies.<br />

Hawkes, Terence, Structuralism <strong>and</strong> Semiotics, London: Methuen, 1977. A useful introduction<br />

to the subject.<br />

McNay, Lois, Foucault: A Critical Introduction, Cambridge: Polity Press, 1994. An excellent<br />

introduction to Foucault’s work.<br />

Norris, Christopher, Derrida, London: Fontana, 1987. A clear <strong>and</strong> interesting introduction<br />

to Derrida.


134<br />

Chapter 6 Structuralism <strong>and</strong> post-structuralism<br />

Sarup, Madan, An Introductory Guide to Post-Structuralism <strong>and</strong> Postmodernism, 2nd edn,<br />

Harlow: Prentice Hall, 1993. An excellent introduction to post-structuralism.<br />

Sheridan, Alan, Michel Foucault: The Will to Truth, London: Tavistock, 1980. Still the<br />

most readable introduction to Foucault.<br />

Silverman, Kaja, The Subject of Semiotics, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1983. An<br />

interesting <strong>and</strong> accessible account of structuralism, semiotics, psychoanalysis, feminism<br />

<strong>and</strong> post-structuralism. Especially useful on Barthes.<br />

Sturrock, John (ed.), Structuralism <strong>and</strong> Since: From Lévi-Strauss to Derrida, Oxford:<br />

Oxford University Press, 1979. Contains good introductory essays on Lévi-Strauss,<br />

Barthes, Foucault, <strong>and</strong> Derrida.<br />

Twaites, Tony, Lloyd Davis <strong>and</strong> Mules Warwick, Tools for <strong>Cultural</strong> Studies: An<br />

Introduction, Melbourne: Macmillan, 1994. Presents an informed account of the<br />

place of semiotics in the field of cultural studies.<br />

Weedon, Chris, Feminist Practice <strong>and</strong> Poststructuralist <strong>Theory</strong>, Oxford: Basil Blackwell,<br />

1987. An interesting introduction to post-structuralism from a feminist perspective.<br />

Helpful chapter on Foucault.


7 Gender <strong>and</strong><br />

sexuality<br />

Feminisms<br />

‘One of the most striking changes in the humanities in the 1980s has been the rise of<br />

gender as a category of analysis’ (Showalter, 1990: 1). This is the opening sentence in<br />

Elaine Showalter’s introduction to a book on gender <strong>and</strong> literary studies. There can be<br />

no doubt that without the emergence of feminism (the second wave) in the early 1970s<br />

this sentence could not have been written. It is feminism that has placed gender on the<br />

academic agenda. However, the nature of the agenda has provoked a vigorous debate<br />

within feminism itself. So much so that it is really no longer possible, if it ever was, to<br />

talk of feminism as a monolithic body of research, writing <strong>and</strong> activity; one should<br />

really speak of feminisms.<br />

There are at least four different feminisms: radical, Marxist, liberal <strong>and</strong> what Sylvia<br />

Walby (1990) calls dual-systems theory. Each responds to women’s oppression in a<br />

different way, positing different causes <strong>and</strong> different solutions. Radical feminists<br />

argue that women’s oppression is the result of the system of patriarchy, a system of<br />

domination in which men as a group have power over women as a group. In Marxist<br />

feminist analysis the ultimate source of oppression is capitalism. The domination of<br />

women by men is seen as a consequence of capital’s domination over labour. Liberal<br />

feminism differs from both Marxist <strong>and</strong> radical feminisms in that it does not posit<br />

a system – patriarchy or capitalism – determining the oppression of women. Instead,<br />

it tends to see the problem in terms of male prejudice against women, embodied in<br />

law or expressed in the exclusion of women from particular areas of life. Dual-systems<br />

theory represents the coming together of Marxist <strong>and</strong> radical feminist analysis in the<br />

belief that women’s oppression is the result of a complex articulation of both patriarchy<br />

<strong>and</strong> capitalism. There are of course other feminist perspectives. Rosemary Tong<br />

(1992), for example, lists: liberal, Marxist, radical, psychoanalytic, socialist, existentialist<br />

<strong>and</strong> postmodern.<br />

Feminism, like Marxism (discussed in Chapter 4), is always more than a body of<br />

academic texts <strong>and</strong> practices. It is also, <strong>and</strong> perhaps more fundamentally so, a political<br />

movement concerned with women’s oppression <strong>and</strong> the ways <strong>and</strong> means to empower<br />

women – what the African-American critic bell hooks (1989) describes as ‘finding a<br />

voice’.


136<br />

Chapter 7 Gender <strong>and</strong> sexuality<br />

As a metaphor for self-transformation . . . [‘finding a voice’] . . . has been especially<br />

relevant for groups of women who have previously never had a public voice,<br />

women who are speaking <strong>and</strong> writing for the first time, including many women of<br />

color. Feminist focus on finding a voice may sound clichéd at times. . . . However,<br />

for women within oppressed groups . . . coming to voice is an act of resistance.<br />

Speaking becomes both a way to engage in active self-transformation <strong>and</strong> a rite of<br />

passage where one moves from being object to being subject. Only as subjects can<br />

we speak (12).<br />

Feminism, therefore, is not just another method of reading texts. Nevertheless, it has<br />

proved an incredibly productive way of reading. As Showalter explains,<br />

There is an optical illusion which can be seen as either a goblet or two profiles. The<br />

images oscillate in their tension before us, one alternately superseding the other<br />

<strong>and</strong> reducing it to meaningless background. In the purest feminist literary theory<br />

we are similarly presented with a radical alteration of our vision, a dem<strong>and</strong> that we<br />

see meaning in what has previously been empty space. The orthodox plot recedes,<br />

<strong>and</strong> another plot, hitherto submerged in the anonymity of the background, st<strong>and</strong>s<br />

out in bold relief like a thumb print (quoted in Modleski, 1982: 25).<br />

What Showalter claims for feminist literary criticism can equally be claimed for<br />

feminist work on popular culture. <strong>Popular</strong> culture has been the object of a great deal<br />

of feminist analysis. As Michèle Barrett (1982) points out, ‘<strong>Cultural</strong> politics are crucially<br />

important to feminism because they involve struggles over meaning’ (37). Lana<br />

Rakow (2009) makes much the same point, ‘Feminists approaching popular culture<br />

proceed from a variety of theoretical positions that carry with them a deeper social<br />

analysis <strong>and</strong> political agenda’ (195). Moreover, as Rakow observes,<br />

Though contemporary feminists have taken a diversity of approaches to popular<br />

culture, they have shared two major assumptions. The first is that women have a<br />

particular relationship to popular culture that is different from men’s. ...The second<br />

assumption is that underst<strong>and</strong>ing how popular culture functions both for women<br />

<strong>and</strong> for a patriarchal culture is important if women are to gain control over their own<br />

identities <strong>and</strong> change both social mythologies <strong>and</strong> social relations. . . . Feminists<br />

are saying that popular culture plays a role in patriarchal society <strong>and</strong> that theoretical<br />

analysis of this role warrants a major position in ongoing discussions (186).<br />

Women at the cinema<br />

In Chapter 5 we discussed Mulvey’s (1975) extremely influential account of the female<br />

spectator. Mulvey’s analysis is impressive <strong>and</strong> telling throughout, <strong>and</strong> despite the fact


Women at the cinema 137<br />

that it is made in an essay of fewer than thirteen pages, its influence has been enormous.<br />

27 However, having acknowledged the essay’s power <strong>and</strong> influence, it should also<br />

be noted that Mulvey’s ‘solution’ is somewhat less telling than her analysis of the ‘problem’.<br />

As an alternative to popular cinema, she calls for an avant-garde cinema ‘which<br />

is radical in both a political <strong>and</strong> an aesthetic sense <strong>and</strong> challenges the basic assumptions<br />

of the mainstream film’ (7–8). Some feminists, including Lorraine Gamman <strong>and</strong><br />

Margaret Marshment (1988), have begun to doubt the ‘universal validity’ (5) of<br />

Mulvey’s argument, questioning whether ‘the gaze is always male’, or whether it is<br />

‘merely “dominant” ’ (ibid.) among a range of different ways of seeing, including the<br />

female gaze. Moreover, as they insist,<br />

It is not enough to dismiss popular culture as merely serving the complementary<br />

systems of capitalism <strong>and</strong> patriarchy, peddling ‘false consciousness’ to the duped<br />

masses. It can also be seen as a site where meanings are contested <strong>and</strong> where<br />

dominant ideologies can be disturbed (1).<br />

They advocate a cultural politics of intervention: ‘we cannot afford to dismiss the<br />

popular by always positioning ourselves outside it’ (2). It is from popular culture<br />

that most people in our society get their entertainment <strong>and</strong> their information. It is<br />

here that women (<strong>and</strong> men) are offered the culture’s dominant definitions of<br />

themselves. It would therefore seem crucial to explore the possibilities <strong>and</strong> pitfalls<br />

of intervention in popular forms in order to find ways of making feminist meanings<br />

a part of our pleasures (1).<br />

Christine Gledhill (2009) makes a similar point: she advocates a feminist cultural<br />

studies ‘which relates commonly derided popular forms to the condition of their consumption<br />

in the lives of sociohistorical constituted audiences’ (98). ‘In this respect’,<br />

she observes, ‘feminist analysis of the woman’s film <strong>and</strong> soap opera is beginning to<br />

counter more negative cine-psychoanalytic . . . accounts of female spectatorship, suggesting<br />

colonized, alienated or masochistic positions of identification’ (ibid.).<br />

Jackie Stacey’s (1994) Star Gazing: Hollywood <strong>and</strong> Female Spectatorship presents a clear<br />

rejection of the universalism <strong>and</strong> textual determinism of much psychoanalytic work on<br />

female audiences. Her own analysis begins with the audience in the cinema rather than<br />

the audience constructed by the text. Her approach takes her from the traditions of film<br />

studies (as informed by Mulvey’s position) to the theoretical concerns of cultural studies.<br />

Table 7.1 illustrates the differences marking out the two paradigms (24).<br />

Stacey’s study is based on an analysis of responses she received from a group of<br />

white British women, mostly aged over 60, <strong>and</strong> mostly working class, who had been<br />

keen cinema-goers in the 1940s <strong>and</strong> 1950s. On the basis of letters <strong>and</strong> completed questionnaires,<br />

she organized her analysis in terms of three discourses generated by the<br />

responses themselves: escapism, identification <strong>and</strong> consumerism.<br />

Escapism is one of the most frequently cited reasons given by the women for going<br />

to the cinema. Seeking to avoid the pejorative connotations of escapism, Stacey uses


138<br />

Chapter 7 Gender <strong>and</strong> sexuality<br />

Table 7.1 Film as object of study in film studies <strong>and</strong> cultural studies.<br />

Film studies <strong>Cultural</strong> studies<br />

Spectatorship positioning Audience readings<br />

Textual analysis Ethnographic methods<br />

Meaning as production-led Meaning as consumption-led<br />

Passive viewer Active viewer<br />

Unconscious Conscious<br />

Pessimistic Optimistic<br />

Richard Dyer’s (1999) excellent argument for the utopian sensibility of much popular<br />

entertainment, to construct an account of the utopian possibilities of Hollywood<br />

cinema for British women in the 1940s <strong>and</strong> 1950s. Dyer deploys a set of binary<br />

oppositions to reveal the relationship between the social problems experienced by<br />

audiences <strong>and</strong> the textual solutions played out in the texts of popular entertainment<br />

(Table 7.2).<br />

Table 7.2 <strong>Popular</strong> texts <strong>and</strong> utopian solutions.<br />

Social problems Textual solutions<br />

Scarcity Abundance<br />

Exhaustion Energy<br />

Dreariness Intensity<br />

Manipulation Transparency<br />

Fragmentation Community 28<br />

For Dyer, entertainment’s utopian sensibility is a property of the text. Stacey extends<br />

his argument to include the social context in which entertainment is experienced.<br />

The letters <strong>and</strong> completed questionnaires by the women made it clear to her that the<br />

pleasures of cinema expressed by them were always more than the visual <strong>and</strong> aural<br />

pleasures of the cinema text – they included the ritual of attending a screening, the<br />

shared experience <strong>and</strong> imagined community of the audience, the comfort <strong>and</strong> comparative<br />

luxury of the cinema building. It was never a simple matter of enjoying the<br />

glamour of Hollywood. As Stacey (1994) explains,<br />

The physical space of the cinema provided a transitional space between everyday<br />

life outside the cinema <strong>and</strong> the fantasy world of the Hollywood film about to be<br />

shown. Its design <strong>and</strong> decor facilitated the processes of escapism enjoyed by these<br />

female spectators. As such, cinemas were dream palaces not only in so far as they<br />

housed the screening of Hollywood fantasies, but also because of their design <strong>and</strong><br />

decor which provided a feminised <strong>and</strong> glamorised space suitable for the cultural<br />

consumption of Hollywood films (99).


Women at the cinema 139<br />

Escapism is always a historically specific two-way event. Stacey’s women, therefore,<br />

were not only escaping into the luxury of the cinema <strong>and</strong> the glamour of Hollywood<br />

film, they were also escaping from the hardships <strong>and</strong> the restrictions of wartime <strong>and</strong><br />

post-war Britain. It is this mix of Hollywood glamour, the relative luxury of the cinema<br />

interiors, experienced in a context of war <strong>and</strong> its aftermath of shortages <strong>and</strong> sacrifice,<br />

which generates ‘the multi-layered meanings of escapism’ (97).<br />

Identification is Stacey’s second category of analysis. She is aware of how it often<br />

functions in psychoanalytic criticism to point to the way in which film texts are said to<br />

position female spectators in the interests of patriarchy. According to this argument,<br />

identification is the means by which women collude <strong>and</strong> become complicit in their<br />

own oppression. However, by shifting the focus from the female spectator constructed<br />

within the film text to the actual female audience in the cinema, she claims that<br />

identification can be shown often to work quite differently. Her respondents continually<br />

draw attention to the way in which stars can generate fantasies of power, control<br />

<strong>and</strong> self-confidence, fantasies that can inform the activities of everyday life.<br />

Her third category is consumption. Again, she rejects the rather monolithic position<br />

which figures consumption as entangled in a relationship, always successful, of domination,<br />

exploitation <strong>and</strong> control. She insists instead that ‘consumption is a site of<br />

negotiated meanings, of resistance <strong>and</strong> of appropriation as well as of subjection <strong>and</strong><br />

exploitation’ (187). Much work in film studies, she claims, has tended to be productionled,<br />

fixing its critical gaze on ‘the ways in which the film industry produces cinema<br />

spectators as consumers of both the film <strong>and</strong> the [associated] products of other industries’<br />

(188). Such analysis is never able to pose theoretically (let alone discuss in concrete<br />

detail) how audiences actually use <strong>and</strong> make meanings from the commodities<br />

they consume. She argues that the women’s accounts reveal a more contradictory relationship<br />

between audiences <strong>and</strong> what they consume. For example, she highlights the<br />

ways in which ‘American feminine ideals are clearly remembered as transgressing<br />

restrictive British femininity <strong>and</strong> thus employed as strategies of resistance’ (198). Many<br />

of the letters <strong>and</strong> completed questionnaires reveal the extent to which Hollywood<br />

stars represented an alternative femininity, exciting <strong>and</strong> transgressive. In this way,<br />

Hollywood stars, <strong>and</strong> the commodities associated with them, could be used as a means<br />

to negotiate with, <strong>and</strong> to extend the boundaries of, what was perceived as a socially<br />

restrictive British femininity. She is careful not to argue that these women were free to<br />

construct through consumption entirely new feminine identities. Similarly, she does<br />

not deny that such forms of consumption may p<strong>and</strong>er to the patriarchal gaze. The key<br />

to her position is the question of excess. The transformation of self-image brought<br />

about by the consumption of Hollywood stars <strong>and</strong> other associated commodities may<br />

produce identities <strong>and</strong> practices that are in excess of the needs of patriarchal culture.<br />

She contends that,<br />

[p]aradoxically, whilst commodity consumption for female spectators in mid to<br />

late 1950s Britain concerns producing oneself as a desirable object, it also offers an<br />

escape from what is perceived as the drudgery of domesticity <strong>and</strong> motherhood<br />

which increasingly comes to define femininity at this time. Thus, consumption


140<br />

Chapter 7 Gender <strong>and</strong> sexuality<br />

may signify an assertion of self in opposition to the self-sacrifice associated with<br />

marriage <strong>and</strong> motherhood in 1950s Britain (238).<br />

Stacey’s work represents something of a rebuke to the universalistic claims of much<br />

cine-psychoanalysis. By studying the audience, ‘female spectatorship might be seen as<br />

a process of negotiating the dominant meanings of Hollywood cinema, rather than<br />

one of being passively positioned by it’ (12). From this perspective, Hollywood’s patriarchal<br />

power begins to look less monolithic, less seamless, its ideological success never<br />

guaranteed.<br />

Reading romance<br />

In Loving with a Vengeance, Tania Modleski (1982) claims that women writing about<br />

‘feminine narratives’ tend to adopt one of three possible positions: ‘dismissiveness;<br />

hostility – tending unfortunately to be aimed at the consumers of the narratives; or,<br />

most frequently, a flippant kind of mockery’ (14). Against this, she declares: ‘It is time<br />

to begin a feminist reading of women’s reading’ (34). She argues that what she calls<br />

‘mass-produced fantasies for women’ (including the romance novel) ‘speak to very real<br />

problems <strong>and</strong> tensions in women’s lives’ (14). In spite of this, she acknowledges that<br />

the way in which these narratives resolve problems <strong>and</strong> tensions will rarely ‘please<br />

modern feminists: far from it’ (25). However, the reader of fantasies <strong>and</strong> the feminist<br />

reader do have something in common: dissatisfaction with women’s lives. For example,<br />

she claims, referring to Harlequin Romances, ‘What Marx (Marx <strong>and</strong> Engels, 1957) said<br />

of religious suffering is equally true of “romantic suffering”: it is “at the same time an<br />

expression of real suffering <strong>and</strong> a protest against real suffering” ’ (47).<br />

Modleski does not condemn the novels or the women who read them. Rather, she<br />

condemns ‘the conditions which have made them necessary’, concluding that ‘the contradictions<br />

in women’s lives are more responsible for the existence of Harlequins than<br />

Harlequins are for the contradictions’ (57). She drifts towards, then draws back from,<br />

the full force of Marx’s position on religion, which would leave her, despite her protests<br />

to the contrary, having come very close to the mass culture position of popular culture<br />

as opiate. Nevertheless, she notes how ‘students occasionally cut their women’s studies<br />

classes to find out what is going on in their favourite soap opera. When this happens,<br />

it is time for us to stop merely opposing soap operas <strong>and</strong> to start incorporating them,<br />

<strong>and</strong> other mass-produced fantasies, into our study of women’ (113–14).<br />

Rosalind Coward’s (1984) Female Desire is about women’s pleasure in popular culture.<br />

The book explores fashion, romance, pop music, horoscopes, soap operas, food,<br />

cooking, women’s magazines <strong>and</strong> other texts <strong>and</strong> practices which involve women in an<br />

endless cycle of pleasure <strong>and</strong> guilt: ‘guilt – it’s our speciality’ (14 ). Coward does not<br />

approach the material as an ‘outsider ...a stranger to [pleasure <strong>and</strong>] guilt. The pleasures<br />

I describe are often my pleasures. ...I don’t approach these things as a distant


Reading romance 141<br />

critic but as someone examining myself, examining my own life under a microscope’<br />

(ibid.). Her position is in marked contrast to that, say, of the ‘culture <strong>and</strong> civilization’<br />

tradition or the perspective of the Frankfurt School. <strong>Popular</strong> culture is not looked<br />

down on from an Olympian height as the disappointing, but rather predictable, culture<br />

of other people. This is a discourse about ‘our’ culture. Furthermore, she refuses to<br />

see the practices <strong>and</strong> representations of popular culture (the discourse of ‘female<br />

desire’) ‘as the forcible imposition of false <strong>and</strong> limiting stereotypes’ (16).<br />

Instead I explore the desire presumed by these representations, the desire which<br />

touches feminist <strong>and</strong> non-feminist women alike. But nor do I treat female desire<br />

as something unchangeable, arising from the female condition. I see the representations<br />

of female pleasure <strong>and</strong> desire as producing <strong>and</strong> sustaining feminine positions.<br />

These positions are neither distant roles imposed on us from outside which<br />

it would be easy to kick off, nor are they the essential attributes of femininity. Feminine<br />

positions are produced as responses to the pleasures offered to us; our subjectivity<br />

<strong>and</strong> identity are formed in the definitions of desire which encircle us. These<br />

are the experiences which make change such a difficult <strong>and</strong> daunting task, for<br />

female desire is constantly lured by discourses which sustain male privilege (ibid.).<br />

Coward’s interest in romantic fiction is in part inspired by the intriguing fact that<br />

‘over the past decade [the 1970s], the rise of feminism has been paralleled almost<br />

exactly by a mushroom growth in the popularity of romantic fiction’. 29 She believes<br />

two things about romantic novels. First, that ‘they must still satisfy some very definite<br />

needs’; <strong>and</strong> second, that they offer evidence of, <strong>and</strong> contribute to, ‘a very powerful <strong>and</strong><br />

common fantasy’ (190). She claims that the fantasies played out in romantic fiction are<br />

‘pre-adolescent, very nearly pre-conscious’ (191–2). She believes them to be ‘regressive’<br />

in two key respects. On the one h<strong>and</strong>, they adore the power of the male in ways reminiscent<br />

of the very early child–father relationship, whilst on the other, they are regressive<br />

because of the attitude taken to female sexual desire – passive <strong>and</strong> without guilt,<br />

as the responsibility for sexual desire is projected on to the male. In other words, sexual<br />

desire is something men have <strong>and</strong> to which women merely respond. In short,<br />

romantic fiction replays the girl’s experience of the Oedipal drama; only this time without<br />

its conclusion in female powerlessness; this time she does marry the father <strong>and</strong><br />

replace the mother. Therefore there is a trajectory from subordination to a position of<br />

power (in the symbolic position of the mother). But, as Coward points out,<br />

Romantic fiction is surely popular because it . . . restores the childhood world of<br />

sexual relations <strong>and</strong> suppresses criticisms of the inadequacy of men, the suffocation<br />

of the family, or the damage inflicted by patriarchal power. Yet it simultaneously<br />

manages to avoid the guilt <strong>and</strong> fear which might come from that childhood<br />

world. Sexuality is defined firmly as the father’s responsibility, <strong>and</strong> fear of suffocation<br />

is overcome because women achieve a sort of power in romantic fiction.<br />

Romantic fiction promises a secure world, promises that there will be safety with<br />

dependence, that there will be power with subordination (196).


142<br />

Chapter 7 Gender <strong>and</strong> sexuality<br />

Janice Radway (1987) begins her study of romance reading with the observation<br />

that the increased popularity of the genre can be in part explained by the ‘important<br />

changes in book production, distribution, advertising <strong>and</strong> marketing techniques’ (13).<br />

Taking issue with earlier accounts, Radway points out that the increasing success of<br />

romances may have as much to do with the sophisticated selling techniques of publishers,<br />

making romances more visible, more available, as with any simple notion of<br />

women’s increased need for romantic fantasy.<br />

Radway’s study is based on research she carried out in ‘Smithton’, involving a group<br />

of forty-two women romance readers (mostly married with children). The women are<br />

all regular customers at the bookshop where ‘Dorothy Evans’ works. It was in fact Dot’s<br />

reputation that attracted Radway to Smithton. Out of her own enthusiasm for the<br />

genre, Dot publishes a newsletter (‘Dorothy’s diary of romance reading’) in which<br />

romances are graded in terms of their romantic worth. The newsletter, <strong>and</strong> Dot’s general<br />

advice to customers, has in effect created what amounts to a small but significant<br />

symbolic community of romance readers. It is this symbolic community that is the<br />

focus of Radway’s research. Research material was compiled through individual questionnaires,<br />

open-ended group discussions, face-to-face interviews, some informal discussions,<br />

<strong>and</strong> by observing the interactions between Dot <strong>and</strong> her regular customers at<br />

the bookshop. Radway supplemented this by reading the titles brought to her attention<br />

by the Smithton women.<br />

The influence of Dot’s newsletter on the purchasing patterns of readers alerted<br />

Radway to the inadequacy of a methodology that attempts to draw conclusions about<br />

the genre from a sample of current titles. She discovered that in order to underst<strong>and</strong><br />

the cultural significance of romance reading, it is necessary to pay attention to popular<br />

discrimination, to the process of selection <strong>and</strong> rejection which finds some titles satisfying<br />

<strong>and</strong> others not. She also encountered the actual extent of romance reading. The<br />

majority of the women she interviewed read every day, spending eleven to fifteen hours<br />

a week on romance reading. At least a quarter of the women informed her that, unless<br />

prevented by domestic <strong>and</strong> family dem<strong>and</strong>s, they preferred to read a romance from<br />

start to finish in one sitting. Consumption varies from one to fifteen books a week.<br />

Four informants actually claimed to read between fifteen <strong>and</strong> twenty-five romances a<br />

week. 30<br />

According to the Smithton women, the ideal romance is one in which an intelligent<br />

<strong>and</strong> independent woman with a good sense of humour is overwhelmed, after much<br />

suspicion <strong>and</strong> distrust, <strong>and</strong> some cruelty <strong>and</strong> violence, by the love of a man, who in<br />

the course of their relationship is transformed from an emotional pre-literate to<br />

someone who can care for her <strong>and</strong> nurture her in ways that are traditionally expected<br />

only from a woman to a man. As Radway explains: ‘The romantic fantasy is . . . not<br />

a fantasy about discovering a uniquely interesting life partner, but a ritual wish to<br />

be cared for, loved, <strong>and</strong> validated in a particular way’ (83). It is a fantasy about reciprocation;<br />

the wish to believe that men can bestow on women the care <strong>and</strong> attention<br />

women are expected regularly to bestow on men. But the romantic fantasy offers<br />

more than this; it recalls a time when the reader was in fact the recipient of an intense<br />

‘maternal’ care.


Reading romance 143<br />

Drawing on the work of Nancy Chodorow (1978), Radway claims that romantic<br />

fantasy is a form of regression in which the reader is imaginatively <strong>and</strong> emotionally<br />

transported to a time ‘when she was the center of a profoundly nurturant individual’s<br />

attention’ (Radway, 1987: 84). However, unlike regression centred on the father as<br />

suggested by Coward, this is regression focused on the figure of the mother. Romance<br />

reading is therefore a means by which women can vicariously – through the hero–<br />

heroine relationship – experience the emotional succour which they themselves are<br />

expected to provide to others without adequate reciprocation for themselves in their<br />

everyday existence.<br />

She also takes from Chodorow the notion of the female self as a self-in-relation-to<br />

others, <strong>and</strong> the male self as a self autonomous <strong>and</strong> independent. Chodorow argues that<br />

this results from the different relations that girls <strong>and</strong> boys have with their mothers.<br />

Radway sees a correlation between the psychological events described by Chodorow<br />

<strong>and</strong> the narrative pattern of the ideal romance: in the journey from identity in crisis to<br />

identity restored, ‘the heroine successfully establishes by the end of the ideal narrative<br />

. . . the now familiar female self, the self-in-relation’ (139). Radway also takes from<br />

Chodorow the belief that women emerge from the Oedipus complex with a ‘triangular<br />

psychic structure intact’; which means that ‘not only do they need to connect themselves<br />

with a member of the opposite sex, but they also continue to require an intense<br />

emotional bond with someone who is reciprocally nurturant <strong>and</strong> protective in a maternal<br />

way’ (140). In order to experience this regression to maternal emotional fulfilment,<br />

she has three options: lesbianism, a relationship with a man, or to seek fulfilment by<br />

other means. The homophobic nature of our culture limits the first; the nature of masculinity<br />

limits the second; romance reading may be an example of the third. Radway<br />

suggests that<br />

the fantasy that generates the romance originates in the oedipal desire to love <strong>and</strong><br />

be loved by an individual of the opposite sex <strong>and</strong> in the continuing pre-oedipal<br />

wish that is part of a woman’s inner-object configuration, the wish to regain the<br />

love of the mother <strong>and</strong> all that it implies – erotic pleasure, symbiotic completion,<br />

<strong>and</strong> identity confirmation (146).<br />

The resolution to the ideal romance provides perfect triangular satisfaction: ‘fatherly<br />

protection, motherly care, <strong>and</strong> passionate adult love’ (149).<br />

The failed romance is unable to provide these satisfactions because on the one h<strong>and</strong>,<br />

it is too violent, <strong>and</strong> on the other, it concludes sadly, or with an unconvincing happy<br />

ending. This highlights in an unpleasurable way the two structuring anxieties of all<br />

romances. The first is the fear of male violence. In the ideal romance, this is contained<br />

by revealing it to be not the fearful thing it appears to be, either an illusion or benign.<br />

The second anxiety is the ‘fear of an awakened female sexuality <strong>and</strong> its impact on men’<br />

(169). In the failed romance, female sexuality is not confined to a permanent <strong>and</strong><br />

loving relationship; nor is male violence convincingly brought under control. Together<br />

they find form <strong>and</strong> expression in the violent punishment inflicted on women who<br />

are seen as sexually promiscuous. In short, the failed romance is unable to produce a


144<br />

Chapter 7 Gender <strong>and</strong> sexuality<br />

reading experience in which emotional fulfilment is satisfied through the vicarious<br />

sharing of the heroine’s journey from a crisis of identity to an identity restored in the<br />

arms of a nurturing male. Whether a romance is good or bad is ultimately determined<br />

by the kind of relationship the reader can establish with the heroine.<br />

If the events of the heroine’s story provoke too intense feelings such as anger at<br />

men, fear of rape <strong>and</strong> violence, worry about female sexuality, or worry about the<br />

need to live with an unexciting man, that romance will be discarded as a failure or<br />

judged to be very poor. If, on the other h<strong>and</strong>, those events call forth feelings of<br />

excitement, satisfaction, contentment, self-confidence, pride, <strong>and</strong> power, it matters<br />

less what events are used or how they are marshalled. In the end, what counts most<br />

is the reader’s sense that for a short time she has become other <strong>and</strong> been elsewhere.<br />

She must close that book reassured that men <strong>and</strong> marriage really do mean good<br />

things for women. She must also turn back to her daily round of duties, emotionally<br />

reconstituted <strong>and</strong> replenished, feeling confident of her worth <strong>and</strong> convinced<br />

of her ability <strong>and</strong> power to deal with the problems she knows she must confront<br />

(184).<br />

In this way, the Smithton women ‘partially reclaim the patriarchal form of the<br />

romance for their own use’ (ibid.). The principal ‘psychological benefits’ of reading<br />

romance novels derive from ‘the ritualistic repetition of a single, immutable cultural<br />

myth’ (198, 199). The fact that 60 per cent of the Smithton readers find it occasionally<br />

necessary to read the ending first, to ensure that the experience of the novel will not<br />

counteract the satisfactions of the underlying myth, suggests quite strongly that it is the<br />

underlying myth of the nurturing male that is ultimately most important in the<br />

Smithton women’s experience of romance reading.<br />

Following a series of comments from the Smithton women, Radway was forced to<br />

the conclusion that if she really wished to underst<strong>and</strong> their view of romance reading<br />

she must relinquish her preoccupation with the text, <strong>and</strong> consider also the very act of<br />

romance reading itself. In conversations it became clear that when the women used the<br />

term ‘escape’ to describe the pleasures of romance reading, the term was operating in a<br />

double but related sense. As we have seen, it can be used to describe the process of<br />

identification between the reader <strong>and</strong> the heroine/hero relationship. But it became<br />

clear that the term was also used ‘literally to describe the act of denying the present,<br />

which they believe they accomplish each time they begin to read a book <strong>and</strong> are drawn<br />

into its story’ (90). Dot revealed to Radway that men often found the very act of<br />

women reading threatening. It is seen as time reclaimed from the dem<strong>and</strong>s of family<br />

<strong>and</strong> domestic duties. Many of the Smithton women describe romance reading as ‘a special<br />

gift’ they give themselves. To explain this, Radway cites Chodorow’s view of the<br />

patriarchal family as one in which, ‘There is a fundamental asymmetry in daily reproduction<br />

. . . men are socially <strong>and</strong> psychologically reproduced by women, but women<br />

are reproduced (or not) largely by themselves’ (91, 94). Romance reading is therefore<br />

a small but not insignificant contribution to the emotional reproduction of the<br />

Smithton women: ‘a temporary but literal denial of the dem<strong>and</strong>s women recognise as


Reading romance 145<br />

an integral part of their roles as nurturing wives <strong>and</strong> mothers’ (97). And, as Radway<br />

suggests, ‘Although this experience is vicarious, the pleasure it induces is nonetheless<br />

real’ (100).<br />

I think it is logical to conclude that romance reading is valued by the Smithton<br />

women because the experience itself is different from ordinary existence. Not only<br />

is it a relaxing release from the tension produced by daily problems <strong>and</strong> responsibilities,<br />

but it creates a time or a space within which a woman can be entirely on<br />

her own, preoccupied with her personal needs, desires, <strong>and</strong> pleasure. It is also a means<br />

of transportation or escape to the exotic or, again, to that which is different (61).<br />

The conclusion Reading the Romance finally comes to is that it is at present very<br />

difficult to draw absolute conclusions about the cultural significance of romance reading.<br />

To focus on the act of reading or to focus on the narrative fantasy of the texts<br />

produces different, contradictory answers. The first suggests that ‘romance reading is<br />

oppositional because it allows the women to refuse momentarily their self-abnegating<br />

social role’ (210). To focus on the second suggests that ‘the romance’s narrative structure<br />

embodies a simple recapitulation <strong>and</strong> recommendation of patriarchy <strong>and</strong> its<br />

constituent social practices <strong>and</strong> ideologies’ (ibid.). It is this difference, ‘between the<br />

meaning of the act <strong>and</strong> the meaning of the text as read’ (ibid.), that must be brought<br />

into tight focus if we are to underst<strong>and</strong> the full cultural significance of romance reading.<br />

On one thing Radway is clear: women do not read romances out of a sense of contentment<br />

with patriarchy. Romance reading contains an element of utopian protest, a<br />

longing for a better world. But against this, the narrative structure of the romance<br />

appears to suggest that male violence <strong>and</strong> male indifference are really expressions of<br />

love waiting to be decoded by the right woman. This suggests that patriarchy is only a<br />

problem until women learn how to read it properly. It is these complexities <strong>and</strong> contradictions<br />

that Radway refuses to ignore or pretend to resolve. Her only certainty is<br />

that it is too soon to know if romance reading can be cited simply as an ideological<br />

agent of the patriarchal social order.<br />

I feel compelled to point out . . . that neither this study nor any other to date provides<br />

enough evidence to corroborate this argument fully. We simply do not know<br />

what practical effects the repetitive reading of romances has on the way women<br />

behave after they have closed their books <strong>and</strong> returned to their normal, ordinary<br />

round of daily activities (217).<br />

Therefore we must continue to acknowledge the activity of readers – their selections,<br />

purchases, interpretations, appropriations, uses, etc. – as an essential part of the cultural<br />

processes <strong>and</strong> complex practices of making meaning in the lived cultures of everyday<br />

life. By paying attention in this way we increase the possibility of ‘articulating the<br />

differences between the repressive imposition of ideology <strong>and</strong> oppositional practices<br />

that, though limited in their scope <strong>and</strong> effect, at least dispute or contest the control of<br />

ideological forms’ (221–2). The ideological power of romances may be great, but where


146<br />

Chapter 7 Gender <strong>and</strong> sexuality<br />

there is power there is always resistance. The resistance may be confined to selective<br />

acts of consumption – dissatisfactions momentarily satisfied by the articulation of<br />

limited protest <strong>and</strong> utopian longing – but as feminists<br />

[w]e should seek it out not only to underst<strong>and</strong> its origins <strong>and</strong> its utopian longing<br />

but also to learn how best to encourage it <strong>and</strong> bring it to fruition. If we do not, we<br />

have already conceded the fight <strong>and</strong>, in the case of the romance at least, admitted<br />

the impossibility of creating a world where the vicarious pleasure supplied by its<br />

reading would be unnecessary (222).<br />

Charlotte Brunsdon (1991) calls Reading the Romance ‘the most extensive scholarly<br />

investigation of the act of reading’, crediting Radway with having installed in the classroom<br />

‘the figure of the ordinary woman’ (372). In a generally sympathetic review of<br />

the British edition of Reading the Romance, Ien Ang (2009) makes a number of criticisms<br />

of Radway’s approach. She is unhappy with the way in which Radway makes a<br />

clear distinction between feminism <strong>and</strong> romance reading: ‘Radway, the researcher, is a<br />

feminist <strong>and</strong> not a romance fan, the Smithton women, the researched, are romance<br />

readers <strong>and</strong> not feminists’ (584). Ang sees this as producing a feminist politics of ‘them’<br />

<strong>and</strong> ‘us’ in which non-feminist women play the role of an alien ‘them’ to be recruited<br />

to the cause. In her view, feminists should not set themselves up as guardians of the<br />

true path. According to Ang, this is what Radway does in her insistence that ‘ “real”<br />

social change can only be brought about . . . if romance readers would stop reading<br />

romances <strong>and</strong> become feminist activists instead’ (585). As we shall see shortly, in my<br />

discussion of Watching Dallas, Ang does not believe that one (romance reading) excludes<br />

the other (feminism). Radway’s ‘vanguardist . . . feminist politics’ leads only to ‘a form<br />

of political moralism, propelled by a desire to make “them” more like “us” ’. Ang<br />

believes that what is missing from Radway’s analysis is a discussion of pleasure as pleasure.<br />

Pleasure is discussed, but always in terms of its unreality – its vicariousness, its<br />

function as compensation, <strong>and</strong> its falseness. Ang’s complaint is that such an approach<br />

focuses too much on the effects, rather than the mechanisms of pleasure. Ultimately,<br />

for Radway, it always becomes a question of ‘the ideological function of pleasure’.<br />

Against this, Ang argues for seeing pleasure as something which can ‘empower’ women<br />

<strong>and</strong> not as something which always works ‘against their own “real” interests’ (585–6).<br />

Janice Radway (1994) has reviewed this aspect of her work <strong>and</strong> concluded,<br />

Although I tried very hard not to dismiss the activities of the Smithton women <strong>and</strong><br />

made an effort to underst<strong>and</strong> the act of romance reading as a positive response to<br />

the conditions of everyday life, my account unwittingly repeated the sexist assumption<br />

that has warranted a large portion of the commentary on romance. It was still<br />

motivated, that is, by the assumption that someone ought to worry responsibly<br />

about the effect of fantasy on women readers . . . [<strong>and</strong> therefore repeated] the<br />

familiar pattern whereby the commentator distances herself as knowing analyst<br />

from those who, engrossed <strong>and</strong> entranced by fantasy, cannot know. . . . Despite the<br />

fact that I wanted to claim the romance for feminism, this familiar opposition


etween blind fantasy <strong>and</strong> perspicacious knowing continued to operate within<br />

my account. Thus I would now link it [Reading the Romance], along with Tania<br />

Modleski’s Loving with a Vengeance, with the first early efforts to underst<strong>and</strong> the<br />

changing genre, a stage in the debate that was characterised most fundamentally,<br />

I believe, by suspicion about fantasy, daydream, <strong>and</strong> play (19).<br />

She cites with approval Alison Light’s (1984) point that feminist ‘cultural politics must<br />

not become “a book-burning legislature” ’, nor should feminists fall into the traps of<br />

moralism or dictatorship when discussing romances. ‘ “It is conceivable . . . that<br />

Barbara Cartl<strong>and</strong> could turn you into a feminist. Reading is never simply a linear con<br />

job but a . . . process which therefore remains dynamic <strong>and</strong> open to change” ’ (quoted<br />

in Radway, 1994: 220). 31<br />

Watching Dallas<br />

Watching Dallas 147<br />

Ien Ang’s Watching Dallas was originally published in the Netherl<strong>and</strong>s in 1982. The<br />

version under discussion here is the revised edition translated into English in 1985.<br />

The context for Ang’s study is the emergence of the American ‘prime time soap’ Dallas<br />

as an international success (watched in over ninety countries) in the early 1980s. In the<br />

Netherl<strong>and</strong>s, Dallas was regularly watched by 52 per cent of the population. With its<br />

spectacular success, Dallas soon gathered around itself a whole discourse of activity –<br />

from extensive coverage in the popular press to souvenir hats reading ‘I Hate JR’. It also<br />

attracted critics like Jack Lang, the French Minister of <strong>Culture</strong>, who viewed it as the<br />

latest example of ‘American cultural imperialism’ (quoted in Ang, 1985: 2). Whether<br />

cause of pleasure or threat to ‘national identity’, Dallas made an enormous impact<br />

worldwide in the early 1980s. It is in this context that Ang placed the following advertisement<br />

in Viva, a Dutch women’s magazine: ‘I like watching the TV serial Dallas, but<br />

often get odd reactions to it. Would anyone like to write <strong>and</strong> tell me why you like<br />

watching it too, or dislike it? I should like to assimilate these reactions in my university<br />

thesis. Please write to . . .’ (Ang, 1985: 10).<br />

Following the advertisement she received forty-two letters (thirty-nine from women<br />

or girls), from both lovers <strong>and</strong> haters of Dallas. These form the empirical basis of her<br />

study of the pleasure(s) of watching Dallas for its predominantly female audience. She<br />

is not concerned with pleasure understood as the satisfaction of an already pre-existent<br />

need, but ‘the mechanisms by which pleasure is aroused’ (9). Instead of the question<br />

‘What are the effects of pleasure?’ she poses the question ‘What is the mechanism of<br />

pleasure; how is it produced <strong>and</strong> how does it work?’<br />

Ang writes as ‘an intellectual <strong>and</strong> a feminist’, but also as someone who has ‘always<br />

particularly liked watching soap operas like Dallas’ (12). Again, we are a long way from<br />

the view from above which has so often characterized the relations between cultural<br />

theory <strong>and</strong> popular culture.


148<br />

Chapter 7 Gender <strong>and</strong> sexuality<br />

The admission of the reality of this pleasure [my own] . . . formed the starting<br />

point for this study. I wanted in the first place to underst<strong>and</strong> this pleasure, without<br />

having to pass judgment on whether Dallas is good or bad, from a political, social<br />

or aesthetic view. Quite the contrary; in my opinion it is important to emphasise<br />

how difficult it is to make such judgments – <strong>and</strong> hence to try to formulate the<br />

terms for a progressive cultural politics – when pleasure is at stake (ibid.).<br />

For Ang’s letter-writers the pleasures or displeasures of Dallas are inextricably linked<br />

with questions of ‘realism’. The extent to which a letter-writer finds the programme<br />

‘good’ or ‘bad’ is determined by whether they find it ‘realistic’ (good) or ‘unrealistic’<br />

(bad). Critical of both ‘empiricist realism’ (a text is considered realistic to the extent to<br />

which it adequately reflects that which exists outside itself) (34–8) <strong>and</strong> ‘classic realism’<br />

(the claim that realism is an illusion created by the extent to which a text can successfully<br />

conceal its constructedness) (38–41), she contends that Dallas is best understood<br />

as an example of what she calls ‘emotional realism’ (41–7). She connects this to the<br />

way in which Dallas can be read on two levels: the level of denotation <strong>and</strong> the level of<br />

connotation (see Chapter 6). The level of denotation refers to the literal content of the<br />

programme, general storyline, character interactions, etc. The level of connotation(s)<br />

refers to the associations, implications, which resonate from the storyline <strong>and</strong> character<br />

interactions, etc.<br />

It is striking; the same things, people, relations <strong>and</strong> situations which are regarded<br />

at the denotative level as unrealistic, <strong>and</strong> unreal, are at the connotative level apparently<br />

not seen at all as unreal, but in fact as ‘recognisable’. Clearly, in the connotative<br />

reading process the denotative level of the text is put in brackets (42).<br />

Viewing Dallas, like watching any other programme, is a selective process, reading<br />

across the text from denotation to connotation, weaving our sense of self in <strong>and</strong> out of<br />

the narrative. As one letter-writer says: ‘Do you know why I like watching it? I think it’s<br />

because those problems <strong>and</strong> intrigues, the big <strong>and</strong> little pleasures <strong>and</strong> troubles occur<br />

in our own lives too. . . . In real life I know a horror like JR, but he’s just an ordinary<br />

builder’ (43). It is this ability to make our own lives connect with the lives of a family<br />

of Texan millionaires that gives the programme its emotional realism. We may not be<br />

rich, but we may have other fundamental things in common: relationships <strong>and</strong> broken<br />

relationships, happiness <strong>and</strong> sadness, illness <strong>and</strong> health. Those who find it realistic<br />

shift the focus of attention from the particularity of the narrative (‘denotation’) to the<br />

generality of its themes (‘connotation’).<br />

Ang uses the term a ‘tragic structure of feeling’ (46) to describe the way in which<br />

Dallas plays with the emotions in an endless musical chairs of happiness <strong>and</strong> misery.<br />

As one letter-writer told her: ‘Sometimes I really enjoy having a good cry with them.<br />

And why not? In this way my other bottled-up emotions find an outlet’ (49). Viewers<br />

who ‘escape’ in this way are not so much engaging in ‘a denial of reality as playing with<br />

it . . . [in a] game that enables one to place the limits of the fictional <strong>and</strong> the real under


Watching Dallas 149<br />

discussion, to make them fluid. And in that game an imaginary participation in the<br />

fictional world is experienced as pleasurable’ (ibid.).<br />

Whatever else is involved, part of the pleasure of Dallas is quite clearly connected to<br />

the amount of fluidity viewers are able or willing to establish between its fictional<br />

world <strong>and</strong> the world of their day-to-day existence. In order to activate Dallas’s tragic<br />

structure of feeling the viewer must have the necessary cultural capital to occupy a<br />

‘reading formation’ 32 informed by what she calls, following Peter Brooks (1976), the<br />

‘melodramatic imagination’. The melodramatic imagination is the articulation of a way<br />

of seeing that finds in ordinary day-to-day existence, with its pain <strong>and</strong> triumphs, its<br />

victories <strong>and</strong> defeats, a world that is as profoundly meaningful <strong>and</strong> significant as the<br />

world of classical tragedy. In a world cut loose from the certainties of religion, the<br />

melodramatic imagination offers a means of organizing reality into meaningful contrasts<br />

<strong>and</strong> conflicts. As a narrative form committed to melodrama’s emphatic contrasts,<br />

conflicts <strong>and</strong> emotional excess, Dallas is well placed to give sustenance to, <strong>and</strong> make<br />

manifest, the melodramatic imagination. For those who see the world in this way (Ang<br />

claims that it dem<strong>and</strong>s a cultural competence most often shared by women), ‘the pleasure<br />

of Dallas . . . is not a compensation for the presumed drabness of daily life, nor<br />

a flight from it, but a dimension of it’ (Ang, 1985: 83). The melodramatic imagination<br />

activates Dallas’s tragic structure of feeling, which in turn produces the pleasure of<br />

emotional realism. However, because the melodramatic imagination is an effect of a<br />

specific reading formation, it follows that not all viewers of Dallas will activate the text<br />

in this way.<br />

A key concept in Ang’s analysis is what she calls ‘the ideology of mass culture’ (15).<br />

The ideology articulates (in the Gramscian sense discussed in Chapter 4) the view that<br />

popular culture is the product of capitalist commodity production <strong>and</strong> is therefore subject<br />

to the laws of the capitalist market economy; the result of which is the seemingly<br />

endless circulation of degraded commodities, whose only real significance is that they<br />

make a profit for their producers. She quite rightly sees this as a distorted <strong>and</strong> one-sided<br />

version of Marx’s analysis of capitalist commodity production, in that it allows<br />

‘exchange value’ to completely mask ‘use value’ (see Chapter 10). Against this, she<br />

insists, as would Marx, that it is not possible to read off how a product might be consumed<br />

from the means by which it was produced. The ideology of mass culture, like<br />

other ideological discourses, seeks to interpellate individuals into specific subject<br />

positions (see discussion of Althusser in Chapter 4). The letters suggest four positions<br />

from which to consume Dallas: (i) those who hate the programme; (ii) ironical viewers;<br />

(iii) fans, <strong>and</strong> (iv) populists.<br />

Those letter-writers who claim to hate Dallas draw most clearly on the ideology.<br />

They use it in two ways. First, the programme is identified negatively as an example of<br />

mass culture, second, as a means to account for <strong>and</strong> support their dislike of the programme.<br />

As Ang puts it, ‘their reasoning boils down to this: “Dallas is obviously bad<br />

because it’s mass culture, <strong>and</strong> that’s why I dislike it” ’ (95-6). In this way, the ideology<br />

both comforts <strong>and</strong> reassures: ‘it makes a search for more detailed <strong>and</strong> personal explanations<br />

superfluous, because it provides a finished explanatory model that convinces,<br />

sounds logical <strong>and</strong> radiates legitimacy’ (96). This is not to say that it is wrong to


150<br />

Chapter 7 Gender <strong>and</strong> sexuality<br />

dislike Dallas, only that professions of dislike are often made without thinking, in fact<br />

with a confidence born of uncritical thought.<br />

Viewers who occupy the second position demonstrate how it is possible to like<br />

Dallas <strong>and</strong> still subscribe to the ideology of mass culture. The contradiction is resolved<br />

by ‘mockery <strong>and</strong> irony’ (97). Dallas is subjected to an ironizing <strong>and</strong> mocking commentary<br />

in which it ‘is transformed from a seriously intended melodrama to the reverse:<br />

a comedy to be laughed at. Ironizing viewers therefore do not take the text as it presents<br />

itself, but invert its preferred meaning through ironic commentary’ (98). From this<br />

position the pleasure of Dallas derives from the fact that it is bad – pleasure <strong>and</strong> bad<br />

mass culture are reconciled in an instant. As one of the letter-writers puts it: ‘Of course<br />

Dallas is mass culture <strong>and</strong> therefore bad, but precisely because I am so well aware of<br />

that I can really enjoy watching it <strong>and</strong> poke fun at it’ (100). For both the ironizing<br />

viewer <strong>and</strong> the hater of Dallas, the ideology of mass culture operates as a bedrock of<br />

common sense, making judgements obvious <strong>and</strong> self-evident. Although both operate<br />

within the normative st<strong>and</strong>ards of the ideology, the difference between them is marked<br />

by the question of pleasure. On the one h<strong>and</strong>, the ironizers can have pleasure without<br />

guilt, in the sure <strong>and</strong> declared knowledge that they know mass culture is bad. On the<br />

other h<strong>and</strong>, the haters, although secure in the same knowledge, can, nevertheless, suffer<br />

‘a conflict of feelings if, in spite of this, they cannot escape its seduction’ (101).<br />

Thirdly, there are the fans, those who love Dallas. For the viewers who occupy the<br />

previous two positions, to actually like Dallas without resort to irony is to be identified<br />

as someone duped by mass culture. As one letter-writer puts it: ‘The aim is simply to<br />

rake in money, lots of money. And people try to do that by means of all these things –<br />

sex, beautiful people, wealth. And you always have people who fall for it’ (103). The<br />

claim is presented with all the confidence of having the full weight of the ideology’s<br />

discursive support. Ang analyses the different strategies that those who love Dallas must<br />

use to deal consciously <strong>and</strong> unconsciously with such condescension. The first strategy<br />

is to ‘internalize’ the ideology; to acknowledge the ‘dangers’ of Dallas, but to declare<br />

one’s ability to deal with them in order to derive pleasure from the programme. It is a<br />

little like the heroin user in the early 1990s British drugs awareness campaign, who,<br />

against the warnings of impending addiction, declares: ‘I can h<strong>and</strong>le it.’ A second strategy<br />

used by fans is to confront the ideology of mass culture as one letter-writer does:<br />

‘Many people find it worthless or without substance. But I think it does have substance’<br />

(105). But, as Ang points out, the writer remains firmly within the discursive constraints<br />

of the ideology as she attempts to relocate Dallas in a different relationship to<br />

the binary oppositions – with substance/without substance, good/bad. ‘This letterwriter<br />

“negotiates” as it were within the discursive space created by the ideology of<br />

mass culture, she does not situate herself outside it <strong>and</strong> does not speak from an opposing<br />

ideological position’ (106). A third strategy of defence deployed by fans against the<br />

normative st<strong>and</strong>ards of the ideology of mass culture is to use irony. These fans are different<br />

from Ang’s second category of viewer, the ironist, in that the strategy involves the<br />

use of ‘surface irony’ to justify what is in all other respects a form of non-ironic pleasure.<br />

Irony is used to condemn the characters as ‘horrible’ people, whilst at the same<br />

time demonstrating an intimate knowledge of the programme <strong>and</strong> a great involvement


Watching Dallas 151<br />

in its narrative development <strong>and</strong> character interactions. The letter-writer who uses this<br />

strategy is caught between the dismissive power of the ideology <strong>and</strong> the pleasure she<br />

obviously derives from watching Dallas. Her letter seems to suggest that she adheres to<br />

the former when viewing with friends, <strong>and</strong> to the latter when viewing alone (<strong>and</strong> perhaps<br />

secretly when viewing with friends). As Ang explains: ‘irony is here a defence<br />

mechanism with which this letter-writer tries to fulfil the social norms set by the<br />

ideology of mass culture, while secretly she “really” likes Dallas’ (109).<br />

As Ang shows, the fans of Dallas find it necessary to locate their pleasure in relation<br />

to the ideology of mass culture; they ‘internalize’ the ideology; they ‘negotiate’ with the<br />

ideology; they use ‘surface irony’ to defend their pleasure against the withering dismissal<br />

of the ideology. What all these strategies of defence reveal is that ‘there is no<br />

clear-cut ideological alternative which can be employed against the ideology of mass<br />

culture – at least no alternative that offsets the latter in power of conviction <strong>and</strong> coherence’<br />

(109–10). The struggle therefore, as so far described, between those who like<br />

Dallas <strong>and</strong> those who dislike it, is an unequal struggle between those who argue from<br />

within the discursive strength <strong>and</strong> security of the ideology of mass culture, <strong>and</strong> those<br />

who resist from within (for them) its inhospitable confines. ‘In short, these fans do not<br />

seem to be able to take up an effective ideological position – an identity – from which<br />

they can say in a positive way <strong>and</strong> independently of the ideology of mass culture:<br />

“I like Dallas because . . .”.’ (Ibid.).<br />

The final viewing position revealed in the letters, one that might help these fans, is<br />

a position informed by the ideology of populism. At the core of this ideology is the<br />

belief that one person’s taste is of equal value to another person’s taste. As one letterwriter<br />

puts it: ‘I find the people who react oddly rather ludicrous – they can’t do anything<br />

about someone’s taste. And anyway they might find things pleasant that you just<br />

can’t st<strong>and</strong> seeing or listening to’ (113). The ideology of populism insists that as taste<br />

is an autonomous category, continually open to individual inflection, it is absolutely<br />

meaningless to pass aesthetic judgements on other people’s preferences. Given that this<br />

would seem to be an ideal discourse from which to defend one’s pleasure in Dallas,<br />

why do so few of the letter-writers adopt it? Ang’s answer is to point to the ideology’s<br />

extremely limited critical vocabulary. After one has repeated ‘there’s no accounting for<br />

taste’ a few times, the argument begins to appear somewhat bankrupt. Compared to<br />

this, the ideology of mass culture has an extensive <strong>and</strong> elaborate range of arguments<br />

<strong>and</strong> theories. Little wonder, then, that when invited to explain why they like or dislike<br />

Dallas, the letter-writers find it difficult to escape the normative discourse of the ideology<br />

of mass culture.<br />

However, according to Ang, there are ways to escape: it is the very ‘theoretical’ nature<br />

of the discourse which restricts its influence ‘to people’s opinions <strong>and</strong> rational consciousness,<br />

to the discourse people use when talking about culture. These opinions <strong>and</strong><br />

rationalizations need not, however, necessarily prescribe people’s cultural practices’<br />

(115). This would in part explain the contradictions experienced by some letterwriters:<br />

confronted by both ‘the intellectual dominance of the ideology of mass culture<br />

<strong>and</strong> the “spontaneous”, practical attraction of the populist ideology’ (ibid.). The<br />

difficulty with adopting the populist ideology for a radical politics of popular culture


152<br />

Chapter 7 Gender <strong>and</strong> sexuality<br />

is that it has already been appropriated by the culture industries for its own purposes<br />

of profit maximization. However, drawing on the work of Bourdieu, Ang argues that<br />

populism is related to the ‘popular aesthetic’, in which the moral categories of middleclass<br />

taste are replaced by an emphasis on contingency, on pluralism, <strong>and</strong> above all, on<br />

pleasure (see Chapter 10). Pleasure, for Ang, is the key term in a transformed feminist<br />

cultural politics. Feminism must break with ‘the paternalism of the ideology of mass<br />

culture . . . [in which w]omen are . . . seen as the passive victims of the deceptive messages<br />

of soap operas . . . [their] pleasure . . . totally disregarded’ (118–19). Even when<br />

pleasure is considered, it is there only to be condemned as an obstruction to the feminist<br />

goal of women’s liberation. The question Ang poses is: Can pleasure through<br />

identification with the women of ‘women’s weepies’ or the emotionally masochistic<br />

women of soap operas, ‘have a meaning for women which is relatively independent of<br />

their political attitudes’? (133). Her answer is yes: fantasy <strong>and</strong> fiction do not<br />

function in place of, but beside, other dimensions of life (social practice, moral<br />

or political consciousness). It . . . is a source of pleasure because it puts ‘reality’ in<br />

parenthesis, because it constructs imaginary solutions for real contradictions<br />

which in their fictional simplicity <strong>and</strong> their simple fictionality step outside the<br />

tedious complexity of the existing social relations of dominance <strong>and</strong> subordination<br />

(135).<br />

Of course this does not mean that representations of women do not matter. They can<br />

still be condemned for being reactionary in an ongoing cultural politics. But to experience<br />

pleasure from them is a completely different issue: ‘it need not imply that we are<br />

also bound to take up these positions <strong>and</strong> solutions in our relations to our loved ones<br />

<strong>and</strong> friends, our work, our political ideals, <strong>and</strong> so on’ (ibid.).<br />

Fiction <strong>and</strong> fantasy, then, function by making life in the present pleasurable, or<br />

at least livable, but this does not by any means exclude radical political activity<br />

or consciousness. It does not follow that feminists must not persevere in trying<br />

to produce new fantasies <strong>and</strong> fight for a place for them. . . . It does, however,<br />

mean that, where cultural consumption is concerned, no fixed st<strong>and</strong>ard exists for<br />

gauging the ‘progressiveness’ of a fantasy. The personal may be political, but the<br />

personal <strong>and</strong> the political do not always go h<strong>and</strong> in h<strong>and</strong> (135–6).<br />

In an unnecessarily hostile review of Watching Dallas, Dana Polan (1988) accuses<br />

Ang of simplifying questions of pleasure by not bringing into play psychoanalysis. He<br />

also claims that Ang’s attack on the ideology of mass culture simply reverses the valuations<br />

implicit <strong>and</strong> explicit in the high culture / popular culture divide. Instead of the<br />

consumer of high culture imagining ‘high taste as a kind of free expression of a full subjectivity<br />

always in danger of being debased by vulgar habits’, Ang is accused of presenting<br />

‘the fan of mass culture as a free individual in danger of having his/her open<br />

access to immediate pleasure corrupted by artificial <strong>and</strong> snobbish values imposed from<br />

on high’ (198). Polan claims that Ang is attacking ‘an antiquarian <strong>and</strong> anachronistic


approach to mass culture’, <strong>and</strong> that she is out of touch with the new postmodern<br />

sensibility, still clinging instead ‘to mythic notions of culture as tragedy, culture as<br />

meaning’ (202). The idea that the ideology of mass culture is antiquated <strong>and</strong> anachronistic<br />

might be true in the fantasy realms of American academic psychoanalytic cultural<br />

criticism, but it is still very much alive in the conscious/unconscious world of everyday<br />

culture.<br />

Reading women’s magazines<br />

Reading women’s magazines 153<br />

In the Preface to Inside Women’s Magazines, Janice Winship (1987) explains how she<br />

has been doing research on women’s magazines since 1969. She also tells us that it was<br />

also around the same time that she began to regard herself as a feminist. Integrating the<br />

two, she admits, has sometimes proved difficult; often it was hinted that she should<br />

research ‘something more important politically’. But she insists that the two must be<br />

integrated: ‘to simply dismiss women’s magazines was also to dismiss the lives of millions<br />

of women who read <strong>and</strong> enjoyed them each week. More than that, I still enjoyed<br />

them, found them useful <strong>and</strong> escaped with them. And I knew I couldn’t be the only<br />

feminist who was a “closet” reader’ (ibid.). As she continues, this did not mean that she<br />

was not (or is not still) critical of women’s magazines, but what is crucial to a feminist<br />

cultural politics is this dialectic of ‘attraction <strong>and</strong> rejection’ (ibid.).<br />

Many of the guises of femininity in women’s magazines contribute to the secondary<br />

status from which we still desire to free ourselves. At the same time it is the<br />

dress of femininity which is both source of the pleasure of being a woman – <strong>and</strong><br />

not a man – <strong>and</strong> in part the raw material for a feminist vision of the future. . . .<br />

Thus for feminists one important issue women’s magazines can raise is how do we<br />

take over their feminine ground to create new untrammelled images of <strong>and</strong> for<br />

ourselves? (xiii–xiv).<br />

Part of the aim of Inside Women’s Magazines is, ‘then, to explain the appeal of the magazine<br />

formula <strong>and</strong> to critically consider its limitations <strong>and</strong> potential for change’ (8).<br />

Since their inception in the late eighteenth century, women’s magazines have<br />

offered their readers a mixture of advice <strong>and</strong> entertainment. Regardless of politics,<br />

women’s magazines continue to operate as survival manuals, providing their readers<br />

with practical advice on how to survive in a patriarchal culture. This might take the<br />

form of an explicit feminist politics, as in Spare Rib, for example; or stories of women<br />

triumphing over adversity, as, for example, in Woman’s Own. The politics may be different,<br />

but the formula is much the same.<br />

Women’s magazines appeal to their readers by means of a combination of entertainment<br />

<strong>and</strong> useful advice. This appeal, according to Winship, is organized around<br />

a range of ‘fictions’. These can be the visual fictions of advertisements, or items on


154<br />

Chapter 7 Gender <strong>and</strong> sexuality<br />

fashion, cookery or family <strong>and</strong> home. They can also be actual fictions: romantic serials,<br />

five-minute stories, for example. There are also the stories of the famous <strong>and</strong> reports<br />

of events in the lives of ‘ordinary’ women <strong>and</strong> men. Each in its different way attempts<br />

to draw the reader into the world of the magazine, <strong>and</strong> ultimately into a world of consumption.<br />

This often leads to women ‘being caught up in defining their own femininity,<br />

inextricably, through consumption’ (39). But pleasure is not totally dependent on<br />

purchase. She recalls how in the hot July in which she wrote Inside Women’s Magazines,<br />

without any intention of buying the product, she gained enormous visual pleasure<br />

from a magazine advertisement showing a woman diving into an ocean surrealistically<br />

continuous with the tap-end of a bath. As she explains,<br />

We recognise <strong>and</strong> relish the vocabulary of dreams in which ads deal; we become<br />

involved in the fictions they create; but we know full well that those commodities<br />

will not elicit the promised fictions. It doesn’t matter. Without bothering to buy<br />

the product we can vicariously indulge in the good life through the image alone.<br />

This is the compensation for the experience you do not <strong>and</strong> cannot have (56).<br />

Magazine advertisements, like the magazines themselves, therefore provide a terrain on<br />

which to dream. In this way, they generate a desire for fulfilment (through consumption).<br />

Paradoxically, this is deeply pleasurable because it also always acknowledges the<br />

existence of the labours of the everyday.<br />

They would not offer quite the same pleasure, however, if it were not expected of<br />

women that they perform the various labours around fashion <strong>and</strong> beauty, food<br />

<strong>and</strong> furnishing. These visuals acknowledge those labours while simultaneously<br />

enabling the reader to avoid doing them. In everyday life ‘pleasure’ for women can<br />

only be achieved by accomplishing these tasks; here the image offers a temporary<br />

substitute, as well as providing an (allegedly) easy, often enjoyable pathway to<br />

their accomplishment (56–7).<br />

Desire is generated for something more than the everyday, yet it can only be accomplished<br />

by what is for most women an everyday activity – shopping. What is ultimately<br />

being sold in the fictions of women’s magazines, in editorial or advertisements,<br />

fashion <strong>and</strong> home furnishing items, cookery <strong>and</strong> cosmetics, is successful <strong>and</strong> therefore<br />

pleasurable femininity. Follow this practical advice or buy this product <strong>and</strong> be a better<br />

lover, a better mother, a better wife, <strong>and</strong> a better woman. The problem with all this<br />

from a feminist perspective is that it is always constructed around a mythical individual<br />

woman, situated outside the influence of powerful social <strong>and</strong> cultural structures <strong>and</strong><br />

constraints.<br />

The commitment to the ‘individual solution’ is often revealed by the way in which<br />

women’s magazines also seek to construct ‘fictional collectivities’ (67) of women.<br />

This can be seen in the insistent ‘we’ of editorials; but it is also there in the reader/<br />

editor interactions of the letters page. Here we often find women making sense of the<br />

everyday world through a mixture of optimism <strong>and</strong> fatalism. Winship identifies these


Reading women’s magazines 155<br />

tensions as an expression of women being ‘ideologically bound to the personal terrain<br />

<strong>and</strong> in a position of relative powerlessness about public events’ (70). Like the so-called<br />

‘triumph over tragedy’ stories, the readers’ letters <strong>and</strong> editorial responses often reveal<br />

a profound commitment to the ‘individual solution’. Both ‘teach’ the same parable:<br />

individual effort will overcome all odds. The reader is interpellated as admiring subject<br />

(see discussion of Althusser in Chapter 4), her own problems put in context, able to<br />

carry on. Short stories work in much the same way. What also links these different<br />

‘fictions’ is ‘that the human triumphs they detail are emotional <strong>and</strong> not material ones’<br />

(76). In many ways this is essential for the continued existence of the magazines’ imagined<br />

communities; for to move from the emotional to the material is to run the risk of<br />

encountering the divisive presence of, for example, class, sexuality, disability, ethnicity<br />

<strong>and</strong> ‘race’.<br />

Thus the ‘we women’ feeling magazines construct is actually comprised of different<br />

cultural groups; the very notion of ‘we’ <strong>and</strong> ‘our world’, however, constantly undercuts<br />

those divisions to give the semblance of a unity inside magazines. Outside,<br />

when the reader closes her magazine, she is no longer ‘friends’ with Esther Rantzen<br />

<strong>and</strong> her ilk; but while it lasted it has been a pleasant <strong>and</strong> reassuring dream (77).<br />

This is perhaps even more evident on the problem page. Although the problems are<br />

personal, <strong>and</strong> therefore seek personal solutions, Winship argues that ‘unless women<br />

have access to knowledge which explains personal lives in social terms . . . the onus on<br />

“you” to solve “your” problem is likely to be intimidating or . . . only lead to frustrated<br />

“solutions” ’ (80). She gives the example of a letter about a husb<strong>and</strong> (with a sexual<br />

past) who cannot forget or forgive his wife’s sexual past. As Winship points out, a personal<br />

solution to this problem cannot begin to tackle the social <strong>and</strong> cultural heritage<br />

of the sexual double st<strong>and</strong>ard. To pretend otherwise is to mislead.<br />

Agony aunties (<strong>and</strong> magazines) act as ‘friends’ to women – they bring women<br />

together in their pages <strong>and</strong> yet by not providing the knowledge to allow women to<br />

see the history of their common social condition, sadly <strong>and</strong> ironically, they come<br />

between women, expecting, <strong>and</strong> encouraging, them to do alone what they can only<br />

do together (ibid.).<br />

At the centre of Winship’s book are three chapters, which in turn discuss the individual<br />

<strong>and</strong> family values of Woman’s Own, the (hetero)sexual liberation ideology of<br />

Cosmopolitan <strong>and</strong> the feminist politics of Spare Rib. I have space only to make one point<br />

with reference to these chapters. Discussing Spare Rib’s reviews of popular film <strong>and</strong> television,<br />

Winship responds with comments that echo through much recent ‘post-feminist’<br />

analysis (<strong>and</strong> much of the work discussed in this chapter) on popular culture:<br />

These reviews . . . bolster the reviewer’s position <strong>and</strong> raise feminism <strong>and</strong> feminists<br />

to the lofty pedestal of ‘having seen the light’, with the consequent dismissal not<br />

only of a whole range of cultural events but also of many women’s pleasurable <strong>and</strong>


156<br />

Chapter 7 Gender <strong>and</strong> sexuality<br />

interested experiences of them. Whether intentionally or not, feminists are setting<br />

themselves distinctly apart: ‘us’ who know <strong>and</strong> reject most popular cultural forms<br />

(including women’s magazines), ‘them’ who remain in ignorance <strong>and</strong> continue to<br />

buy Woman’s Own or watch Dallas. The irony, however, is that many of ‘us’ feel<br />

like ‘them’: closet readers <strong>and</strong> viewers of this fare (140).<br />

Winship’s comments bring us to the complex question of post-feminism. Does the<br />

term imply that the moment of feminism has been <strong>and</strong> gone; that it is now a movement<br />

of the past? Certainly, there are those who would wish to suggest that this is the<br />

case. According to Winship, ‘if it means anything useful’, the term refers to the way in<br />

which the ‘boundaries between feminists <strong>and</strong> non-feminists have become fuzzy’ (149).<br />

This is to a large extent due to the way in which ‘with the “success” of feminism some<br />

feminist ideas no longer have an oppositional charge but have become part of many<br />

people’s, not just a minority’s, common sense’ (ibid.). Of course this does not mean<br />

that all feminist dem<strong>and</strong>s have been met (far from it), <strong>and</strong> that feminism is now<br />

redundant. On the contrary, ‘it suggests that feminism no longer has a simple coherence<br />

around a set of easily defined principles . . . but instead is a much richer, more<br />

diverse <strong>and</strong> contradictory mix than it ever was in the 1970s’ (ibid.).<br />

In Reading Women’s Magazines, Joke Hermes (1995) begins with an observation on<br />

previous feminist work on women’s magazines: ‘I have always felt strongly that the<br />

feminist struggle in general should be aimed at claiming respect. It is probably for that<br />

reason that I have never felt comfortable with the majority of (feminist) work that has<br />

been done on women’s magazines. Almost all of these studies show concern rather than<br />

respect for those who read women’s magazines’ (1). This kind of approach (what might<br />

be called ‘modernist feminism’), she maintains, generates a form of media criticism in<br />

which the feminist scholar is both ‘prophet <strong>and</strong> exorcist’ (ibid.). As she explains,<br />

‘Feminists using modernity discourse speak on behalf of others who are, implicitly,<br />

thought to be unable to see for themselves how bad such media texts as women’s<br />

magazines are. They need to be enlightened; they need good feminist texts in order to<br />

be saved from their false consciousness <strong>and</strong> to live a life free of false depictions as<br />

mediated by women’s magazines, of where a woman might find happiness’ (ibid.).<br />

Against this way of thinking <strong>and</strong> working, Hermes advocates what she calls ‘a more<br />

postmodern view, in which respect rather than concern – or, for that matter, celebration,<br />

a term often seen as the hallmark of a postmodern perspective – would have a<br />

central place’ (ibid.). She is aware ‘that readers of all kinds (including we critics) enjoy<br />

texts in some contexts that we are critical of in other contexts’ (2). The focus of her<br />

study, therefore, is to ‘underst<strong>and</strong> how women’s magazines are read while accepting<br />

the preferences of [the women she interviewed]’ (ibid.). Working from the perspective<br />

of ‘a postmodern feminist position’, she advocates an ‘appreciation that readers are<br />

producers of meaning rather than the cultural dupes of the media institutions.<br />

Appreciation too of the local <strong>and</strong> specific meanings we give to media texts <strong>and</strong> the different<br />

identities any one person may bring to bear on living our multi-faceted lives<br />

in societies saturated with media images <strong>and</strong> texts of which women’s magazines are<br />

a part’ (ibid.). More specifically, she seeks to situate her work in a middle ground


Reading women’s magazines 157<br />

between a focus on how meanings are made of specific texts (Ang, 1985, Radway,<br />

1987, for example) <strong>and</strong> a focus on the contexts of media consumption (Gray, 1992,<br />

Morley, 1986, for example). In other words, rather than begin with a text <strong>and</strong> show<br />

how people appropriate it <strong>and</strong> make it meaningful, or begin with the contexts of consumption<br />

<strong>and</strong> show how these constrain the ways in which appropriation <strong>and</strong> the<br />

making of meaning can take place, she has ‘tried to reconstruct the diffuse genre or set<br />

of genres that is called women’s magazines <strong>and</strong> [to demonstrate] how they become<br />

meaningful exclusively through the perception of their readers’ (Hermes, 1995: 6). She<br />

calls this approach ‘the theorisation of meaning production in everyday contexts’<br />

(ibid.). In working in this way, she is able to avoid the deployment of textual analysis,<br />

with its implied notion of an identifiably correct meaning, or limited set of meanings,<br />

which a reader may or may not activate. ‘My perspective’, she explains, ‘is that texts<br />

acquire meaning only in the interaction between readers <strong>and</strong> texts <strong>and</strong> that analysis of<br />

the text on its own is never enough to reconstruct these meanings’ (10). To enable this<br />

way of working she introduces the concept of ‘repertoires’. She explains the concept as<br />

follows: ‘Repertoires are the cultural resources that speakers fall back on <strong>and</strong> refer to.<br />

Which repertoires are used depends on the cultural capital of an individual reader’ (8).<br />

Moreover, ‘Texts do not directly have meaning. The various repertoires readers use<br />

make texts meaningful’ (40).<br />

Hermes conducted eighty interviews with both women <strong>and</strong> men. She was initially<br />

disappointed at the fact that her interviewees seemed reluctant to talk about how they<br />

made meanings from the women’s magazines they read; <strong>and</strong> when they did discuss this<br />

issue, they often suggested instead, against the ‘common sense’ of much media <strong>and</strong> cultural<br />

theory, that their encounters with these magazines were hardly meaningful at all.<br />

After the initial disappointment, these discussions gradually prompted Hermes to recognize<br />

what she calls ‘the fallacy of meaningfulness’ (16). What this phrase is intended<br />

to convey is her rejection of a way of working in media <strong>and</strong> cultural analysis that is<br />

premised on the view that the encounter between reader <strong>and</strong> text should always be<br />

understood solely in terms of the production of meaning. This general preoccupation<br />

with meaning, she claims, has resulted from an influential body of work that concentrated<br />

on fans (<strong>and</strong>, I would add, youth subcultures), rather than on the consumption<br />

practices of ordinary people; <strong>and</strong>, moreover, it resulted from a conspicuous failure to<br />

situate consumption in the routines of everyday life. Against the influence of this body<br />

of work, she argues for a critical perspective in which ‘the media text has to be displaced<br />

in favour of readers’ reports of their everyday lives’ (148). As she explains, ‘To underst<strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>and</strong> theorize everyday media use, a more sophisticated view of meaning production<br />

is required than one that does not recognise different levels of psychological<br />

investment or emotional commitment <strong>and</strong> reflection’ (16).<br />

By a detailed <strong>and</strong> critical analysis of recurrent themes <strong>and</strong> repeated issues that arise<br />

in the interview material she collected, Hermes attempts to reconstruct the various<br />

repertoires employed by the interviewees in the consumption of women’s magazines.<br />

She identifies four repertoires: ‘easily put down’, ‘relaxation’, ‘practical knowledge’ <strong>and</strong><br />

‘emotional learning <strong>and</strong> connected knowing’ (31). The first of these repertoires, perhaps<br />

the most straightforward to underst<strong>and</strong>, identifies women’s magazines as a genre


158<br />

Chapter 7 Gender <strong>and</strong> sexuality<br />

that makes limited dem<strong>and</strong>s on its readers. It is a genre that can be easily picked up<br />

<strong>and</strong> easily put down, <strong>and</strong> because of this, it can be easily accommodated into the routines<br />

of everyday life.<br />

The second repertoire, clearly related to the first, <strong>and</strong> perhaps as expected as the first<br />

repertoire, identifies reading women’s magazines as a form of ‘relaxation’. But, as<br />

Hermes points out, relaxation (like ‘escapism’ discussed earlier in this chapter) should<br />

not be understood as an innocent or a self-evident term – it is, as she maintains, ‘ideologically<br />

loaded’ (36). On the one h<strong>and</strong>, the term can be employed simply as a valid<br />

description of a particular activity, <strong>and</strong>, on the other, it can be used as a blocking mechanism<br />

in defence against personal intrusion. Given the low cultural status of women’s<br />

magazines, as Hermes reminds us, using the term ‘relaxation’ as a means to block further<br />

entry into a private realm is perhaps underst<strong>and</strong>able. In other words, I am reading<br />

this magazine to indicate to others that I am currently not available to do other things.<br />

The third repertoire, the repertoire of ‘practical knowledge’, can range from tips on<br />

cooking to film <strong>and</strong> book reviews. But its apparently secure anchorage in practical<br />

application is deceptive. The repertoire of practical knowledge may offer much more<br />

than practical hints on how to become adept at making Indian cuisine or culturally<br />

knowing about which films are worth going to the cinema to see. Readers can use these<br />

practical tips, Hermes claims, to fantasize an ‘ideal self . . . [who] is pragmatic <strong>and</strong><br />

solution-oriented, <strong>and</strong> a person who can take decisions <strong>and</strong> is an emancipated consumer;<br />

but above all she is a person in control’ (39). The final repertoire, the repertoire<br />

of ‘emotional learning <strong>and</strong> connected knowing’, is also about learning, but rather than<br />

being about the collection of practical tips, it is learning through the recognition<br />

of oneself, one’s lifestyle <strong>and</strong> one’s potential problems, in the problems of others as<br />

represented in the pages of magazine stories <strong>and</strong> articles. As one interviewee told<br />

Hermes, she likes to read ‘short pieces about people who have had certain problems .<br />

. . [<strong>and</strong>] how such a problem can be solved’ (41). Or as another interviewee told her,<br />

‘I like to read about how people deal with things’ (42). With specific reference to problem<br />

pages, another interviewee observed, ‘you learn a lot from other people’s problems<br />

. . . <strong>and</strong> the advice they [the magazine] give’ (43). As with the repertoire of practical<br />

knowledge, the repertoire of emotional <strong>and</strong> connected learning may also involve<br />

the production of an ideal self, a self who is prepared for all the potential emotional<br />

dangers <strong>and</strong> human crises that might need to be confronted in the social practices<br />

of everyday life. As Hermes explains, ‘Both the repertoire of practical knowledge <strong>and</strong><br />

the repertoire of connected knowing may help readers to gain (an imaginary <strong>and</strong> temporary)<br />

sense of identity <strong>and</strong> confidence, of being in control or feeling at peace with<br />

life, that lasts while they are reading <strong>and</strong> dissipates quickly [unlike the practical tips]<br />

when the magazine is put down’ (48).<br />

Hermes’s originality is to have broken decisively with an approach to cultural analysis<br />

in which the researcher insists on the necessity to establish first the substantive<br />

meaning of a text or texts <strong>and</strong> then how an audience may or may not read the text to<br />

make this meaning. Against this way of working, as she observes, ‘the repertoires that<br />

readers use give meaning to women’s magazine genres in a way that to a quite remarkable<br />

extent is independent of the women’s magazine text. Readers construct new texts


in the form of fantasies <strong>and</strong> imagined “new” selves. This leads to the conclusion that a<br />

genre study can be based entirely on how women’s magazines are read <strong>and</strong> that it does<br />

not need to address the (narrative) structure or content of the text itself at all’ (146).<br />

Against more celebratory accounts of women <strong>and</strong> consumption, Hermes’s investigation<br />

of the role of repertoires makes her reluctant to see in the practices of women<br />

reading magazines an unproblematical form of empowerment. Instead, she argues, we<br />

should think of the consumption of women’s magazines as providing only temporary<br />

‘moments of empowerment’ (51).<br />

Men’s studies <strong>and</strong> masculinities<br />

Men’s studies <strong>and</strong> masculinities 159<br />

Feminism has brought into being many things, but one that some feminists have<br />

already disowned is men’s studies. Despite Peter Schwenger’s concern that for a man<br />

‘to think about masculinity is to become less masculine oneself. . . . The real man<br />

thinks about practical matters rather than abstract ones <strong>and</strong> certainly does not brood<br />

upon himself or the nature of his sexuality’ (quoted in Showalter, 1990: 7), many men<br />

have thought, spoken <strong>and</strong> written about masculinity. As Antony Easthope 33 (1986)<br />

writes in What a Man’s Gotta Do, ‘It is time to try to speak about masculinity, about<br />

what it is <strong>and</strong> how it works’ (1). Easthope’s focus is on what he calls dominant masculinity<br />

(the myth of heterosexual masculinity as something essential <strong>and</strong> self-evident<br />

which is tough, masterful, self-possessed, knowing, always in control, etc.). He begins<br />

from the proposition that masculinity is a cultural construct; that is, it is not ‘natural’,<br />

‘normal’ or ‘universal’. He argues that dominant masculinity operates as a gender<br />

norm, <strong>and</strong> that it is against this norm that the many other different types of ‘lived masculinities’<br />

(including gay masculinities) are invited to measure themselves. As part of<br />

this argument, he analyses the way dominant masculinity is represented across a range<br />

of popular cultural texts: pop songs, popular fiction, films, television <strong>and</strong> newspapers,<br />

<strong>and</strong> concludes:<br />

Clearly men do not passively live out the masculine myth imposed by the stories<br />

<strong>and</strong> images of the dominant culture. But neither can they live completely outside<br />

the myth, since it pervades the culture. Its coercive power is active everywhere – not<br />

just on screens, hoardings <strong>and</strong> paper, but inside our own heads (167).<br />

From a similar perspective, Sean Nixon’s (1996) examination of ‘new man’ masculinity<br />

explores it as ‘a regime of representation’, focusing on ‘four key sites of cultural<br />

circulation: television advertising, press advertising, menswear shops <strong>and</strong> popular<br />

magazines for men’ (4).<br />

Although it is true that feminists have always encouraged men to examine their masculinity,<br />

many feminists are less than impressed with men’s studies, as Joyce Canaan<br />

<strong>and</strong> Christine Griffin (1990) make clear:


160<br />

Chapter 7 Gender <strong>and</strong> sexuality<br />

While feminist underst<strong>and</strong>ings of patriarchy would undoubtedly be wider if<br />

we had access to men’s underst<strong>and</strong>ings of how they construct <strong>and</strong> transform this<br />

pervasive system of relationships, we nevertheless fear that such research might distort,<br />

belittle, or deny women’s experiences with men <strong>and</strong> masculinity. Feminists<br />

therefore must be even more insistent about conducting research on men <strong>and</strong><br />

masculinity at a time when a growing number of men are beginning to conduct<br />

apparently ‘comparable’ research (207–8).<br />

Queer theory<br />

Queer theory, as Paul Burston <strong>and</strong> Colin Richardson (1995) explain, ‘provides a discipline<br />

for exploring the relationships between lesbians, gay men <strong>and</strong> the culture which<br />

surrounds <strong>and</strong> (for the large part) continues to seek to exclude us’ (1). Moreover, ‘[b]y<br />

shifting the focus away from the question of what it means to be lesbian or gay within<br />

the culture, <strong>and</strong> onto the various performances of heterosexuality created by the<br />

culture, Queer <strong>Theory</strong> seeks to locate Queerness in places that had previously been<br />

thought of as strictly for the straights’ (ibid.). In this way, they contend, ‘Queer <strong>Theory</strong><br />

is no more “about” lesbians <strong>and</strong> gay men than women’s studies is “about” women.<br />

Indeed, part of the project of Queer is to attack . . . the very “naturalness” of gender<br />

<strong>and</strong>, by extension, the fictions supporting compulsory heterosexuality’ (ibid.).<br />

To discuss the supposed naturalness of gender <strong>and</strong> the ideological fictions supporting<br />

compulsory heterosexuality, there is no better place to begin than with one of the<br />

founding texts of queer theory, Judith Butler’s (1999) very influential book Gender<br />

Trouble. Butler begins from Simone de Beauvoir’s (1984) observation that ‘one is not<br />

born a woman, but, rather, becomes one’ (12). De Beauvoir’s distinction establishes an<br />

analytical difference between biological sex (‘nature’) <strong>and</strong> gender (‘culture’), suggesting<br />

that while biological sex is stable, there will always be different <strong>and</strong> competing (historically<br />

<strong>and</strong> socially variable) ‘versions’ of femininity <strong>and</strong> masculinity (see Figure 7.1).<br />

Although de Beauvoir’s argument has the advantage of seeing gender as something<br />

made in culture – ‘the cultural meanings that the sexed body assumes’ (Butler, 1999:<br />

10) – <strong>and</strong> not something fixed by nature, the problem with this model of sex/gender,<br />

according to Butler, is that it works with the assumption that there are only two biological<br />

sexes (‘male’ <strong>and</strong> ‘female’), which are determined by nature, <strong>and</strong> which in turn<br />

Figure 7.1 The binary gender system.


Queer theory 161<br />

generate <strong>and</strong> guarantee the binary gender system. Against this position, she argues that<br />

biology is itself always already culturally gendered as ‘male’ <strong>and</strong> ‘female’, <strong>and</strong>, as such,<br />

already guarantees a particular version of the feminine <strong>and</strong> the masculine. Therefore,<br />

the distinction between sex <strong>and</strong> gender is not a distinction between nature <strong>and</strong> culture:<br />

‘the category of “sex” is itself a gendered category, fully politically invested, naturalized<br />

but not natural’ (143). In other words, there is not a biological ‘truth’ at the heart of<br />

gender; sex <strong>and</strong> gender are both cultural categories.<br />

Furthermore, it is not just that ‘gender is not to culture as sex is to nature; gender is<br />

also the discursive/cultural means by which “sexed nature” or “a natural sex” is produced<br />

<strong>and</strong> established as “prediscursive”, prior to culture, a politically neutral surface<br />

on which culture acts. . . . [In this way,] the internal stability <strong>and</strong> binary frame for sex is<br />

effectively secured . . . by casting the duality of sex in a prediscursive domain’ (11). As<br />

Butler explains, ‘there is no reason to divide up human bodies into male <strong>and</strong> female<br />

sexes except that such a division suits the economic needs of heterosexuality <strong>and</strong> lends<br />

a naturalistic gloss to the institution of heterosexuality’ (143). Therefore, as she contends,<br />

‘one is not born a woman, one becomes one; but further, one is not born female,<br />

one becomes female; but even more radically, one can if one chooses, become neither<br />

female nor male, woman nor man’ (33).<br />

According to Butler’s argument, gender is not the expression of biological sex, it is<br />

performatively constructed in culture. In this way, ‘Gender is the repeated stylization of<br />

the body, a set of repeated acts within a highly rigid regulatory frame that congeal over<br />

time to produce the appearance of substance, of a natural sort of being’ (43–4). In<br />

other words, gender identities consist of the accumulation of what is outside (i.e. in<br />

culture) in the belief that they are an expression of what is inside (i.e. in nature). As a<br />

result ‘ “persons” only become intelligible through becoming gendered in conformity<br />

with recognizable st<strong>and</strong>ards of intelligibility’ (22). 34 Femininity <strong>and</strong> masculinity are<br />

not expressions of ‘nature’, they are ‘cultural performances in which their “naturalness”<br />

[is] constituted through discursively constrained performative acts . . . that create the<br />

effect of the natural, the original, <strong>and</strong> the inevitable’ (xxviii–xxix).<br />

Butler’s theory of performativity is a development of J.L. Austin’s (1962) theory of<br />

performative language. Austin divides language into two types, constative <strong>and</strong> performative.<br />

Constative language is descriptive language. ‘The sky is blue’, is an example of<br />

a constative statement. Performative language, on the other h<strong>and</strong>, does not merely<br />

describe what already exists, it brings something into being. ‘I now pronounce you husb<strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>and</strong> wife’ is an obvious example; it does not describe something, it brings it into<br />

existence; that is, when the words are spoken by an appropriate person, they transform<br />

two single people into a married couple. Butler argues that gender works in much the<br />

same way as performative language. As she explains, ‘there is no identity behind the<br />

expressions of gender; that identity is performatively constituted by the very “expressions”<br />

that are said to be its results’ (Butler, 1999: 33). One of the first performative<br />

speech acts we all encounter is the pronouncement, ‘It’s a girl’ or ‘It’s a boy’. Each pronouncement<br />

comes with rules <strong>and</strong> regulations, which we are expected to follow <strong>and</strong><br />

obey: ‘little boys do this, little girls don’t do that’, etc. Various discourses, including<br />

those from parents, educational institutions, the media, will all combine to ensure our


162<br />

Chapter 7 Gender <strong>and</strong> sexuality<br />

conformity to ‘performativity as cultural ritual, as the reiteration of cultural norms’<br />

(Butler, 2000: 29). In this way, ‘the performance of gender creates the illusion of a prior<br />

substantiality – a core gendered self – <strong>and</strong> construes the effect of the performative ritual<br />

of gender as necessary emanations or causal consequences of that prior substance’ (ibid.).<br />

Butler’s concept of performativity should not be confused with the idea of performance<br />

understood as a form of play-acting, in which a more fundamental identity<br />

remains intact beneath the theatricality of the identity on display. Gender<br />

performativity is not a voluntary practice, it is a continual process of almost disciplinary<br />

reiteration: ‘gender performativity cannot be theorized apart from the forcible<br />

<strong>and</strong> reiterative practice of regulatory sexual regimes . . . <strong>and</strong> in no way presupposes<br />

a choosing subject’ (Butler, 1993: 15). Sarah E. Chinn (1997) provides an excellent<br />

summary of the process:<br />

While we may recognize that gender is coercive, it is familiar; it is ourselves. The<br />

naturalizing effects of gender means that gender feels natural – even the underst<strong>and</strong>ing<br />

that it is performative, that our subjectivities themselves are constructed<br />

through its performance, does not make it feel any the less intrinsic. Our identities<br />

depend upon successful performance of our genders, <strong>and</strong> there is an entire cultural<br />

arsenal of books, films, television, advertisements, parental injunctions <strong>and</strong> peer<br />

surveillance to make sure those performances are (ideally) unconscious <strong>and</strong> successful<br />

(306–7).<br />

Butler (1999) chooses ‘drag’ as a model for explanation not, as some critics seem to<br />

think, because she thinks it is ‘an example of [the] subversion [of gender]’ (xxii), but<br />

because ‘it dramatize[s] the signifying gestures through which gender itself is established’<br />

(xxviii). Drag exposes the assumed <strong>and</strong> apparent unity <strong>and</strong> fictional coherence<br />

of the normative heterosexual performance of gender. As Butler explains, ‘In imitating<br />

gender, drag implicitly reveals the imitative structure of gender itself – as well as its<br />

contingency’ (175). To be in drag is not to copy an original <strong>and</strong> natural gender identity,<br />

it is to ‘imitate the myth of originality itself’ (176). 35 As she explains,<br />

If gender attributes . . . are not expressive but performative, then these attributes<br />

effectively constitute the identity they are said to express or reveal. The distinction<br />

between expression <strong>and</strong> performativeness is crucial. If gender attributes <strong>and</strong> acts,<br />

the various ways in which a body shows or produces its cultural signification, are<br />

performative, then there is no preexisting identity by which an act or attribute<br />

might be measured; there would be no true or false, real or distorted acts of gender,<br />

<strong>and</strong> the postulation of a true gender identity would be revealed as a regulatory<br />

fiction. That gender reality is created through sustained social performances means<br />

that the very notions of an essential sex <strong>and</strong> a true or abiding masculinity or<br />

femininity are also constituted as part of the strategy that conceals gender’s performative<br />

character <strong>and</strong> the performative possibilities for proliferating gender<br />

configurations outside the restricting frames of masculinist domination <strong>and</strong> compulsory<br />

heterosexuality (180). 36


Queer theory 163<br />

Butler (2009) gives the example of Aretha Franklin singing, ‘you make me feel like a<br />

natural woman’: 37<br />

she seems at first to suggest that some natural potential of her biological sex is actualized<br />

by her participation in the cultural position of ‘woman’ as object of heterosexual<br />

recognition. Something in her ‘sex’ is thus expressed by her ‘gender’ which<br />

is then fully known <strong>and</strong> consecrated within the heterosexual scene. There is no<br />

breakage, no discontinuity between ‘sex’ as biological facticity <strong>and</strong> essence, or<br />

between gender <strong>and</strong> sexuality. Although Aretha appears to be all too glad to have<br />

her naturalness confirmed, she also seems fully <strong>and</strong> paradoxically mindful that<br />

that confirmation is never guaranteed, that the effect of naturalness is only<br />

achieved as a consequence of that moment of heterosexual recognition. After all,<br />

Aretha sings, you make me feel like a natural woman, suggesting that this is a kind<br />

of metaphorical substitution, an act of imposture, a kind of sublime <strong>and</strong> momentary<br />

participation in an ontological illusion produced by the mundane operation<br />

of heterosexual drag (2009: 235; italics in original).<br />

If, as Butler (1999) maintains, ‘gender reality is created through sustained social performances’<br />

(180), perhaps one of the principal theatres for its creation is consumption.<br />

Michael Warner (1993) has noted a connection between gay culture <strong>and</strong> particular patterns<br />

of consumption. Such a relationship, he argues, dem<strong>and</strong>s a rethinking of the<br />

political economy of culture (see Chapter 10). As he explains, there is<br />

the close connection between consumer culture <strong>and</strong> the most visible spaces of<br />

gay culture: bars, discos, advertising, fashion, br<strong>and</strong>-name identification, mass<br />

cultural-camp, ‘promiscuity’. Gay culture in this most visible mode is anything<br />

but external to advanced capitalism <strong>and</strong> to precisely those features of advanced<br />

capitalism that many on the left are most eager to disavow. Post-Stonewall urban<br />

gay men reek of the commodity. We give off the smell of capitalism in rut, <strong>and</strong><br />

therefore dem<strong>and</strong> of theory a more dialectical view of capitalism than many<br />

people have imagination for (xxxi).<br />

In a similar way, Corey K. Creekmur <strong>and</strong> Alex<strong>and</strong>er Doty (1995) point out that ‘the<br />

identity that we designate homosexual arose in t<strong>and</strong>em with capitalist consumer culture’<br />

(1). They draw attention to the particular relationship that gays <strong>and</strong> lesbians have often<br />

had with popular culture: ‘an alternative or negotiated, if not fully subversive, reception<br />

of the products <strong>and</strong> messages of popular culture, [wondering] how they might<br />

have access to mainstream culture without denying or losing their oppositional identities,<br />

how they might participate without necessarily assimilating, how they might take<br />

pleasure in, <strong>and</strong> make affirmative meanings out of, experiences <strong>and</strong> artefacts that they<br />

have been told do not offer queer pleasures <strong>and</strong> meanings’ (1–2). In other words, ‘a<br />

central issue is how to be “out in culture”: how to occupy a place in mass culture, yet<br />

maintain a perspective on it that does not accept its homophobic <strong>and</strong> heterocentrist<br />

definitions, images, <strong>and</strong> terms of analysis’ (2).


164<br />

Chapter 7 Gender <strong>and</strong> sexuality<br />

Alex<strong>and</strong>er Doty (1995) argues that ‘queerness as a mass culture reception practice<br />

. . . is shared by all sorts of people in varying degrees of consistency <strong>and</strong> intensity’ (73).<br />

As he explains, queer reading is not confined to gays <strong>and</strong> lesbians, ‘heterosexual,<br />

straight-identifying people can experience queer moments’ (ibid.). The term ‘queer’ is<br />

used by Doty ‘to mark a flexible space for the expression of all aspects of non- (anti-,<br />

contra-) straight cultural production <strong>and</strong> reception. As such, ‘this “queer space” recognizes<br />

the possibility that various <strong>and</strong> fluctuating queer positions might be occupied<br />

whenever anyone produces or responds to culture’ (73; italics in original). The ‘queer<br />

space’ identified by Doty is, as he explains, best thought of as a ‘contrastraight, rather<br />

than strictly antistraight, space’ (83):<br />

Queer positions, queer readings, <strong>and</strong> queer pleasures are part of a reception space<br />

that st<strong>and</strong>s simultaneously beside <strong>and</strong> within that created by heterosexual <strong>and</strong><br />

straight positions. . . . What queer reception often does, however, is st<strong>and</strong> outside<br />

the relatively clear-cut <strong>and</strong> essentializing categories of sexual identity under which<br />

most people function. You might identify yourself as a lesbian or a straight woman<br />

yet queerly experience the gay erotics of male buddy films such as Red River <strong>and</strong><br />

Butch Cassidy <strong>and</strong> the Sundance Kid; or maybe as a gay man your cultlike devotion<br />

to Laverne <strong>and</strong> Shirley, Kate <strong>and</strong> Allie, or The Golden Girls has less to do with straightdefined<br />

cross-gender identification than with articulating the loving relationship<br />

between women. Queer readings aren’t ‘alternative’ readings, wishful or wilful misreadings,<br />

or ‘reading too much into things’ readings. They result from the recognition<br />

<strong>and</strong> articulation of the complex range of queerness that has been in popular<br />

culture texts <strong>and</strong> their audiences all along (83–4).<br />

Further reading<br />

Storey, John (ed.), <strong>Cultural</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Popular</strong> <strong>Culture</strong>: A Reader, 4th edition, Harlow:<br />

Pearson Education, 2009. This is the companion volume to this book. It contains<br />

examples of most of the work discussed here. This book <strong>and</strong> the companion Reader<br />

are supported by an interactive website (www.pearsoned.co.uk/storey). The website<br />

has links to other useful sites <strong>and</strong> electronic resources.<br />

Ang, Ien, Living Room Wars: Rethinking Media Audiences for a Postmodern World, London:<br />

Routledge, 1995. An excellent collection of essays from one of the leading intellectuals<br />

in the field.<br />

Barrett, Michèle, Women’s Oppression Today: Problems in Marxist Feminist Analysis,<br />

London: Verso, 1980. The book is of general interest to the student of popular culture<br />

in its attempt to synthesize Marxist <strong>and</strong> feminist modes of analysis; of particular<br />

interest is Chapter 3, ‘Ideology <strong>and</strong> the cultural production of gender’.<br />

Brunt, Rosalind <strong>and</strong> Caroline Rowan (eds), Feminism, <strong>Culture</strong> <strong>and</strong> Politics, London:<br />

Lawrence & Wishart, 1982. A collection of essays illustrative of feminist modes of


Further reading 165<br />

analysis. See especially: Michèle Barrett, ‘Feminism <strong>and</strong> the definition of cultural<br />

politics’.<br />

Burston, Paul <strong>and</strong> Colin Richardson (eds), A Queer Romance: Lesbians, Gay Men <strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>Popular</strong> <strong>Culture</strong>, London: Routledge, 1995. An interesting collection of essays looking<br />

at popular culture from the perspective(s) of queer theory.<br />

Creekmur, Corey K. <strong>and</strong> Alex<strong>and</strong>er Doty (eds), Out in <strong>Culture</strong>: Gay, Lesbian, <strong>and</strong> Queer<br />

Essays on <strong>Popular</strong> <strong>Culture</strong>, London: Cassell, 1995. An excellent collection of essays<br />

on contemporary popular culture from an antihomophobic <strong>and</strong> antiheterocentrist<br />

perspective.<br />

Easthope, Antony, What a Man’s Gotta Do: The Masculine Myth in <strong>Popular</strong> <strong>Culture</strong>,<br />

London: Paladin, 1986. A useful <strong>and</strong> entertaining account of the ways in which<br />

masculinity is represented in contemporary popular culture.<br />

Franklin, Sarah, Celia Lury <strong>and</strong> Jackie Stacy (eds), Off Centre: Feminism <strong>and</strong> <strong>Cultural</strong><br />

Studies, London: HarperCollins, 1991. An excellent collection of feminist work in<br />

cultural studies.<br />

Geraghty, Christine, Women <strong>and</strong> Soap Opera: A Study of Prime Time Soaps, Cambridge:<br />

Polity Press, 1991. A comprehensive introduction to feminist analysis of soap<br />

operas.<br />

Jeffords, Susan, The Remasculinization of America: Gender <strong>and</strong> the Vietnam War,<br />

Bloomington <strong>and</strong> Indianapolis: Indiana University Press, 1989. The book explores<br />

representations of masculinity across a range of popular texts to argue that following<br />

the crisis of defeat in Vietnam strenuous attempts have been made to remasculinize<br />

American culture.<br />

Macdonald, Myra, Representing Women: Myths of Femininity in <strong>Popular</strong> Media, London:<br />

Edward Arnold, 1995. An excellent introduction to the way women are talked about<br />

<strong>and</strong> constructed visually across a range of popular media.<br />

McRobbie, Angela, Feminism <strong>and</strong> Youth <strong>Culture</strong>, London: Macmillan, 1991. A selection<br />

from the work of one of the leading figures in feminist analysis of popular culture.<br />

Pribram, Deidre E. (ed.), Female Spectators: Looking at Film <strong>and</strong> Television, London:<br />

Verso, 1988. A useful collection of essays looking at different aspects of filmic <strong>and</strong><br />

televisual popular culture.<br />

Thornham, Sue, Passionate Detachments: An Introduction to Feminist Film <strong>Theory</strong>, London:<br />

Edward Arnold, 1997. An excellent introduction to the contribution of feminism to<br />

the study of film.


8 ‘Race’, racism <strong>and</strong><br />

representation<br />

In this chapter I will examine the concept of ‘race’ <strong>and</strong> the historical development of<br />

racism in Engl<strong>and</strong>. I will then explore a particular regime of racial representation,<br />

Edward Said’s analysis of Orientalism. I will use Hollywood’s account of America’s war<br />

in Vietnam, <strong>and</strong> its potential impact on recruitment for the first Gulf War as an example<br />

of Orientalism in popular culture. The chapter will conclude with a brief discussion of<br />

cultural studies <strong>and</strong> anti-racism.<br />

‘Race’ <strong>and</strong> racism<br />

The first thing to insist on in discussions of ‘race’ is that there is just one human race.<br />

Human biology does not divide people into different ‘races’; it is racism (<strong>and</strong> sometimes<br />

its counter arguments) that insists on this division. In other words, ‘race’ is a<br />

cultural <strong>and</strong> historical category, a way of making difference signify between people of a<br />

variety of skin tones. What is important is not difference as such, but how it is made to<br />

signify; how it is made meaningful in terms of a social <strong>and</strong> political hierarchy (see<br />

Chapters 4 <strong>and</strong> 6). This is not to deny that human beings come in different colours <strong>and</strong><br />

with different physical features, but it is to insist that these differences do not issue<br />

meanings; they have to be made to mean. Moreover, there is no reason why skin colour<br />

is more significant than hair colour or the colour of a person’s eyes. In other words,<br />

racism is more about signification than it is about biology. As Paul Gilroy observes,<br />

Accepting that skin ‘colour’, however meaningless we know it to be, has a strictly<br />

limited basis in biology, opens up the possibility of engaging with theories of signification<br />

which can highlight the elasticity <strong>and</strong> the emptiness of ‘racial’ signifiers as<br />

well as the ideological work which has to be done in order to turn them into signifiers<br />

in the first place. This perspective underscores the definition of ‘race’ as an open<br />

political category, for it is struggle that determines which definition of ‘race’ will<br />

prevail <strong>and</strong> the conditions under which they will endure or wither away (2002: 36).<br />

This should not be mistaken for a form of idealism. Difference exists whether it<br />

is made to signify or not. But how it is made to signify is always a result of politics<br />

<strong>and</strong> power, rather than a question of biology. As Gilroy points out, ‘“Race” has to be


168<br />

Chapter 8 ‘Race’, racism <strong>and</strong> representation<br />

socially <strong>and</strong> politically constructed <strong>and</strong> elaborate ideological work is done to secure<br />

<strong>and</strong> maintain the different forms of “racialization” which have characterized capitalist<br />

development. Recognizing this makes it all the more important to compare <strong>and</strong> evaluate<br />

the different historical situations in which “race” has become politically pertinent’<br />

(35). Working from this perspective, analysis of ‘race’ in popular culture would be the<br />

exploration of the different ways in which it has <strong>and</strong> can be made to signify.<br />

As Stuart Hall points out, there are three key moments in the history of ‘race’ <strong>and</strong><br />

racism in the West (Hall 1997c). These occur around slavery <strong>and</strong> the slave trade, colonialism<br />

<strong>and</strong> imperialism, <strong>and</strong> 1950s immigration following decolonization. In the<br />

next section I will focus on how slavery <strong>and</strong> the slave trade produced the first detailed<br />

public discussions around ‘race’ <strong>and</strong> racism. It was in these discussions that the basic<br />

assumptions <strong>and</strong> vocabulary of ‘race’ <strong>and</strong> racism were first formulated. It is important<br />

to underst<strong>and</strong> that ‘race’ <strong>and</strong> racism are not natural or inevitable phenomena; they<br />

have a history <strong>and</strong> are the result of human actions <strong>and</strong> interactions. But often they are<br />

made to appear as inevitable, something grounded in nature rather than what they<br />

really are, products of human culture. Again, as Paul Gilroy observes,<br />

For those timid souls, it would appear that becoming resigned both to the absolute<br />

status of ‘race’ as a concept <strong>and</strong> to the intractability of racism as a permanent<br />

perversion akin to original sin, is easier than the creative labour involved in invisioning<br />

<strong>and</strong> producing a more just world, purged of racial hierarchy . . . Rather<br />

than accepting the power of racism as prior to politics <strong>and</strong> seeing it as an<br />

inescapable natural force that configures human consciousness <strong>and</strong> action in ways<br />

<strong>and</strong> forms that merely political considerations simply can never match, this ongoing<br />

work involves making ‘race’ <strong>and</strong> racism into social <strong>and</strong> political phenomena<br />

again (xx).<br />

According to Gilroy, there needs to be a reduction in ‘the exaggerated dimensions<br />

of racial difference to a liberating ordinary-ness’, adding that ‘“race” is nothing special,<br />

a virtual reality given meaning only by the fact that racism endures’ (xxii). In other<br />

words, without racism there would be little meaning to the concept of ‘race’. It is racism<br />

that keeps the concept alive. What needs to be recognized is ‘the banality of intermixture<br />

<strong>and</strong> the subversive ordinariness of this country’s [the United Kingdom] convivial<br />

cultures in which “race” is stripped of meaning <strong>and</strong> racism just an after-effect of<br />

long gone imperial history’ (xxxviii).<br />

The ideology of racism: its historical emergence<br />

While it is possible to argue that xenophobia, deriving from ignorance <strong>and</strong> fear, has<br />

perhaps existed as long as different ethnic groups have existed, ‘race’ <strong>and</strong> racism have<br />

a very particular history. Racism first develops in Engl<strong>and</strong> as a defence of slavery <strong>and</strong>


The ideology of racism: its historical emergence 169<br />

the slave trade. As Peter Fryer (1984) points out, ‘Once the English slave trade, English<br />

sugar-producing plantation slavery, <strong>and</strong> English manufacturing industry had begun to<br />

operate as a trebly profitable interlocking system, the economic basis had been laid for<br />

all those ancient scraps of myth <strong>and</strong> prejudice to be woven into a more or less coherent<br />

racist ideology: a mythology of race’ (134). In other words, racism first emerges as<br />

a defensive ideology, promulgated in order to defend the economic profits of slavery<br />

<strong>and</strong> the slave trade.<br />

A key figure in the development of the ideology of racism is the planter <strong>and</strong> judge<br />

Edward Long. In his book History of Jamaica (1774) he popularized the idea that black<br />

people are inferior to white people, thus suggesting that slavery <strong>and</strong> the slave trade<br />

were perfectly acceptable institutions. His starting position is the assertion that there is<br />

an absolute racial division between black <strong>and</strong> white people:<br />

I think there are extremely potent reasons for believing, that the White <strong>and</strong> the<br />

Negroe are two distinct species. . . . When we reflect on . . . their dissimilarity to the<br />

rest of mankind, must we not conclude, that they are a different species of the same<br />

genus? . . . Nor do [orang-utans] seem at all inferior in the intellectual faculties to<br />

many of the Negroe race; with some of whom, it is credible that they have the most<br />

intimate connection <strong>and</strong> consanguinity. The amorous intercourse between them<br />

may be frequent . . . <strong>and</strong> it is certain, that both races agree perfectly well in lasciviousness<br />

of disposition (quoted in Fryer 1984, 158–9).<br />

Charles White, writing in 1795 made similar claims, ‘The white European . . . being<br />

most removed from brute creation, may, on that account, be considered as the most<br />

beautiful of the human race. No one will doubt his superiority in intellectual powers;<br />

<strong>and</strong> I believe it will be found that his capacity is naturally superior also to that of every<br />

other man’ (168).<br />

Edward Long’s own racism is clearly underpinned by sexual anxieties. In a pamphlet<br />

published in 1772, in which racism is mixed with his contempt for working-class<br />

women, he claims that<br />

[t]he lower class of women in Engl<strong>and</strong>, are remarkably fond of the blacks, for<br />

reasons too brutal to mention; they would connect themselves with horses <strong>and</strong><br />

asses if the law permitted them. By these ladies they generally have a numerous<br />

brood. Thus, in the course of a few generations more, the English blood will<br />

become so contaminated with this mixture, <strong>and</strong> from the chances, the ups <strong>and</strong><br />

downs of life, this alloy may spread extensively, as even to reach the middle,<br />

<strong>and</strong> then the higher orders of the people, till the whole nation resembles the<br />

Portuguese <strong>and</strong> Moriscos in complexion of skin <strong>and</strong> baseness of mind (157).<br />

Similarly, in Considerations on the Negroe Cause (1772), Samuel Estwick argued that<br />

black people should be prevented from entering the country in order to ‘preserve the<br />

race of Britons from stain <strong>and</strong> contamination’ (156). Philip Thicknesse, writing in<br />

1778, makes similar points:


170<br />

Chapter 8 ‘Race’, racism <strong>and</strong> representation<br />

in the course of a few centuries they will over-run this country with a race of men<br />

of the very worst sort under heaven. . . . London abounds with an incredible number<br />

of these black men . . . <strong>and</strong> [in] every country town, nay in almost every village<br />

are to be seen a little race of mulattoes, mischievous as monkeys <strong>and</strong> infinitely<br />

more dangerous. ...A mixture of negro blood with the natives of this country is<br />

big with great <strong>and</strong> mighty mischief (162).<br />

Linking this concern directly to the abolition of slavery, John Scattergood, writing in<br />

1792, argued that if slavery is allowed to end, ‘the Negroes from all parts of the world<br />

will flock hither, mix with the natives, spoil the breed of our common people, increase<br />

the number of crimes <strong>and</strong> criminals, <strong>and</strong> make Britain the sink of all the earth, for<br />

mongrels, vagrants, <strong>and</strong> vagabonds’ (164).<br />

A letter published in the London Chronicle in 1764, which finds an insidious echo in<br />

contemporary debates on immigration, is concerned that too many black servants are<br />

coming into Britain:<br />

As they fill the places of so many of our own people, we are by this means depriving<br />

so many of them of the means of getting their bread, <strong>and</strong> thereby decreasing<br />

our native population in favour of a race, whose mixture with us is disgraceful, <strong>and</strong><br />

whose use cannot be so various <strong>and</strong> essential as those of white people . . . They<br />

never can be considered as a part of the people, <strong>and</strong> therefore their introduction<br />

into the community can only serve to elbow as many out of it who are genuine<br />

subjects, <strong>and</strong> in every point preferable. . . . It is . . . high time that some remedy be<br />

applied for the cure of so great an evil, which may be done by totally prohibiting<br />

the importation of any more of them (155).<br />

Given that slavery <strong>and</strong> the slave trade were of economic benefit to many people not<br />

directly involved with its practice, the new ideology of racism spread quickly among<br />

those without a direct economic interest in slavery <strong>and</strong> the slave trade. Scottish<br />

philosopher David Hulme, for example, was quite clear about the difference between<br />

whites <strong>and</strong> non-whites. Writing in 1753, he observed,<br />

I am apt to suspect the negroes, <strong>and</strong> in general all the other species of men (for<br />

there are four or five different kinds) to be naturally inferior to the whites. There<br />

never was a civilised nation of any other complexion than white. . . . Such a uniform<br />

<strong>and</strong> constant difference could not happen, in so many countries <strong>and</strong> ages, if<br />

nature had not made an original distinction betwixt these breeds of men. ...In<br />

Jamaica indeed they talk of one negroe 38 as a man of parts <strong>and</strong> learning; but ’tis<br />

likely he is admired for very slender accomplishments, like a parrot, who speaks a<br />

few words plainly (152).<br />

By the nineteenth-century, it was widely taken for granted that the human race was<br />

divided into superior whites <strong>and</strong> inferior others. With such natural gifts, it would seem<br />

only right that white Europeans should establish colonies across the globe. Moreover,


as Fryer points out, ‘racism was not confined to a h<strong>and</strong>ful of cranks. Virtually every scientist<br />

<strong>and</strong> intellectual in nineteenth-century Britain took it for granted that only people<br />

with white skin were capable of thinking <strong>and</strong> governing’ (1984: 169). In fact, it was<br />

probably only after the Second World War that racism finally lost its scientific support.<br />

In the nineteenth-century racism could even make colonial conquest appear as if<br />

directed by God. According to Thomas Carlyle, writing in 1867, ‘The Almighty Maker<br />

appointed him [“the Nigger”] to be a Servant’ (quoted in Fryer, 1984: 172). Sir Harry<br />

Johnston (1899), who had worked as a colonial administrator in South Africa <strong>and</strong><br />

Ug<strong>and</strong>a, claimed that ‘The negro in general is a born slave’, with the natural capacity<br />

to ‘toil hard under the hot sun <strong>and</strong> in unhealthy climates of the torrid zone’ (173).<br />

Even if the hot sun or the unhealthy climate proved too much, the white Europeans<br />

should not overly concern themselves with possibilities of suffering <strong>and</strong> injustice.<br />

Dr Robert Knox, for example, described by Philip Curtin as ‘one of the key figures in<br />

the general Western . . . pseudo-scientific racism’ (1964: 377), was very reassuring on<br />

this point: ‘What signify these dark races to us? . . . [T]he sooner they are put out of the<br />

way the better. . . . Destined by the nature of their race, to run, like all other animals, a<br />

certain limited course of existence, it matters little how their extinction is brought<br />

about’ (quoted in Fryer, 1984: 175).<br />

Knox is certainly extreme in his racism. A less extreme version, justifying imperialism<br />

on grounds of a supposed civilising mission, was expressed by James Hunt.<br />

Founder of the Anthropological Society of London in 1863, Hunt argued that although<br />

‘the Negro is inferior intellectually to the European, [he or she] becomes more humanised<br />

when in his natural subordination to the European than under any other circumstances’<br />

(177). In fact, as he makes clear, ‘the Negro race can only be humanised <strong>and</strong><br />

civilised by Europeans’ (ibid.). Colonial secretary Joseph Chamberlain (1895) offers a<br />

wonderful summary of this argument: ‘I believe that the British race is the greatest of<br />

governing races the world has ever seen. I say this not merely as an empty boast, but as<br />

proved <strong>and</strong> shown by the success which we have had in administering vast dominions<br />

. . . <strong>and</strong> I believe there are no limits accordingly to its future’ (183).<br />

Orientalism<br />

Orientalism 171<br />

Edward Said (1985), in one of the founding texts of post-colonial theory, shows how<br />

a Western discourse on the Orient – ‘Orientalism’ – has constructed a ‘knowledge’ of<br />

the East <strong>and</strong> a body of ‘power–knowledge’ relations articulated in the interests of the<br />

‘power’ of the West. According to Said, ‘The Orient was a European invention’ (1).<br />

‘Orientalism’ is the term he uses to describe the relationship between Europe <strong>and</strong> the<br />

Orient, in particular, the way ‘the Orient has helped to define Europe (or the West) as<br />

its contrasting image, idea, personality, experience’ (1–2). He ‘also tries to show that<br />

European culture gained in strength <strong>and</strong> identity by setting itself off against the Orient<br />

as a sort of surrogate <strong>and</strong> even underground self’ (3).


172<br />

Chapter 8 ‘Race’, racism <strong>and</strong> representation<br />

Orientalism can be discussed <strong>and</strong> analysed as the corporate institution for dealing<br />

with the Orient – dealing with it by making statements about it, authorising views<br />

of it, describing it, by teaching it, settling it, ruling over it: in short, Orientalism as<br />

a Western style for dominating, restructuring, <strong>and</strong> having authority over the Orient<br />

(ibid.).<br />

In other words, Orientalism, a ‘system of ideological fiction’ (321), is a matter of<br />

power. It is one of the mechanisms by which the West maintained its hegemony over<br />

the Orient. This is in part achieved by an insistence on an absolute difference between<br />

the West <strong>and</strong> the Orient, in which ‘the West . . . is rational, developed, humane, superior,<br />

<strong>and</strong> the Orient . . . is aberrant, undeveloped, inferior’ (300).<br />

How does all this, in more general terms, relate to the study of popular culture? It<br />

is not too difficult to see how imperial fictions might be better understood using the<br />

approach developed by Said. There are basically two imperial plot structures. First, stories<br />

that tell of white colonizers succumbing to the primeval power of the jungle <strong>and</strong>,<br />

as the racist myth puts it, ‘going native’. Kurtz of both Heart of Darkness <strong>and</strong> Apocalypse<br />

Now is such a figure. Then there are stories of whites, who because of the supposed<br />

power of their racial heredity impose themselves on the jungle <strong>and</strong> its inhabitants.<br />

‘Tarzan’ (novels, films <strong>and</strong> myth) is the classic representation of this imperial fiction.<br />

From the perspective of Orientalism both narratives tell us a great deal more about the<br />

desires <strong>and</strong> anxieties of the culture of imperialism than they can ever tell us about the<br />

people <strong>and</strong> places of colonial conquest. What the approach does is to shift the focus of<br />

attention away from what <strong>and</strong> where the narratives are about to the ‘function’ that they<br />

may serve to the producers <strong>and</strong> consumers of such fictions. It prevents us from slipping<br />

into a form of naive realism: that is, away from a focus on what the stories tell us about<br />

Africa or the Africans, to what such representations tell us about Europeans <strong>and</strong><br />

Americans. In effect, it shifts our concern from ‘how’ the story is told to ‘why’, <strong>and</strong> from<br />

those whom the story is about to those who tell <strong>and</strong> consume the story.<br />

Hollywood’s Vietnam, the way it tells the story of America’s war in Vietnam, is in<br />

many ways a classic example of a particular form of Orientalism. Rather than the silence<br />

of defeat, there has been a veritable ‘incitement’ to talk about Vietnam. America’s<br />

most unpopular war has become its most popular when measured in discursive <strong>and</strong><br />

commercial terms. Although America no longer has ‘authority over’ Vietnam, it continues<br />

to hold authority over Western accounts of America’s war in Vietnam. Hollywood<br />

as a ‘corporate institution’ deals with Vietnam ‘by making statements about it,<br />

authorising views of it, describing it, by teaching it’. Hollywood has ‘invented’ Vietnam<br />

as a ‘contrasting image’ <strong>and</strong> a ‘surrogate <strong>and</strong> . . . underground self’ of America. In this<br />

way Hollywood – together with other discursive practices, such as songs, novels, TV<br />

serials, etc. – has succeeded in producing a very powerful discourse on Vietnam: telling<br />

America <strong>and</strong> the world that what happened there, happened because Vietnam is like<br />

that. These different discourses are not just about Vietnam; they may increasingly<br />

constitute for many Americans the experience of Vietnam. They may become the war<br />

itself.


Orientalism 173<br />

From the perspective of Orientalism it does not really matter whether Hollywood’s<br />

representations are ‘true’ or ‘false’ (historically accurate or not); what matters is the<br />

‘regime of truth’ (Michel Foucault; discussed in Chapter 6) they put into circulation.<br />

From this perspective, Hollywood’s power is not a negative force, something that<br />

denies, represses, negates. On the contrary, it is productive. Foucault’s general point<br />

about power is also true with regard to Hollywood’s power:<br />

We must cease once <strong>and</strong> for all to describe the effects of power in negative terms:<br />

it ‘excludes’, it ‘represses’, it ‘censors’, it ‘abstracts’, it ‘masks’, it ‘conceals’. In fact,<br />

power produces; it produces reality; it produces domains of objects <strong>and</strong> rituals of<br />

truth (1979: 194).<br />

Moreover, as he also points out, ‘Each society has its own regime of truth, its “general<br />

politics” of truth – that is, the types of discourse it accepts <strong>and</strong> makes function as true’<br />

(2002a: 131). On the basis of this, I want now to briefly describe three narrative<br />

paradigms, models for underst<strong>and</strong>ing, or ‘regimes of truth’, which featured strongly in<br />

Hollywood’s Vietnam in the 1980s. 39<br />

The first narrative paradigm is ‘the war as betrayal’. This is first of all a discourse<br />

about bad leaders. In Uncommon Valor, Missing in Action I, Missing in Action II: The<br />

Beginning, Braddock: Missing in Action III <strong>and</strong> Rambo: First Blood Part II, for example,<br />

politicians are blamed for America’s defeat in Vietnam. When John Rambo (Sylvester<br />

Stallone) is asked to return to Vietnam in search of American soldiers missing in action,<br />

he asks, with great bitterness: ‘Do we get to win this time?’ In other words, will the<br />

politicians let them win? Second, it is a discourse about weak military leadership in the<br />

field. In Platoon <strong>and</strong> Casualties of War, for example, defeat, it is suggested, is the result<br />

of an incompetent military comm<strong>and</strong>. Third, it is also a discourse about civilian<br />

betrayal. Both Cutter’s Way <strong>and</strong> First Blood suggest that the war effort was betrayed back<br />

home in America. Again John Rambo’s comments are symptomatic. When he is told<br />

by Colonel Trautman, ‘It’s over Johnny’, he responds,<br />

Nothing is over. You don’t just turn it off. It wasn’t my war. You asked me, <strong>and</strong> I<br />

did what I had to do to win, but somebody wouldn’t let us win. And I come back<br />

to the world <strong>and</strong> see these maggots protesting at the airport, calling me baby-killer.<br />

Who are they to protest me? I was there, they weren’t!<br />

Interestingly, all the films in this category are structured around loss. In Uncommon<br />

Valor, Missing in Action I, II, <strong>and</strong> III, Rambo: First Blood Part II, <strong>and</strong> POW: The Escape, it<br />

is lost prisoners; in Cutter’s Way, First Blood, <strong>and</strong> Born on the Fourth of July, it is lost<br />

pride; in Platoon <strong>and</strong> Casualties of War it is lost innocence. It seems clear that the different<br />

versions of what is lost are symptomatic of a displacement of a greater loss: the<br />

displacement of that which can barely be named, America’s defeat in Vietnam. The use<br />

of American POWs is undoubtedly the most ideologically charged of these displacement<br />

strategies. It seems to offer the possibility of three powerful political effects. First,


174<br />

Chapter 8 ‘Race’, racism <strong>and</strong> representation<br />

to accept the myth that there are Americans still being held in Vietnam is to begin to<br />

retrospectively justify the original intervention. If the Vietnamese are so barbaric as to<br />

still hold prisoners decades after the conclusion of the conflict, then there is no need<br />

to feel guilty about the war, as they surely deserved the full force of American military<br />

intervention. Second, Susan Jeffords identifies a process she calls the ‘femininization<br />

of loss’ (1989: 145). That is, those blamed for America’s defeat, whether they are<br />

unpatriotic protesters, an uncaring government, a weak <strong>and</strong> incompetent military<br />

comm<strong>and</strong>, or corrupt politicians, are always represented as stereotypically feminine:<br />

‘the stereotyped characteristics associated with the feminine in dominant U.S. culture<br />

– weakness, indecisiveness, dependence, emotion, nonviolence, negotiation, unpredictability,<br />

deception’ (145). Jeffords’ argument is illustrated perfectly in the MIA cycle<br />

of films in which the ‘feminine’ negotiating stance of the politicians is played out<br />

against the ‘masculine’, no-nonsense approach of the returning veterans. The implication<br />

being that ‘masculine’ strength <strong>and</strong> single-mindedness would have won the war,<br />

whilst ‘feminine’ weakness <strong>and</strong> duplicity lost it. Third, perhaps most important of all<br />

is how these films turned what was thought to be lost into something which was only<br />

missing. Defeat is displaced by the ‘victory’ of finding <strong>and</strong> recovering American POWs.<br />

Puzzled by the unexpected success of Uncommon Valor in 1983, the New York Times sent<br />

a journalist to interview the film’s ‘audience’. One moviegoer was quite clear why the<br />

film was such a box-office success: ‘We get to win the Vietnam War’ (quoted in H. Bruce<br />

Franklin 1993: 141).<br />

The second narrative paradigm is ‘the inverted firepower syndrome’. This is a narrative<br />

device in which the United States’ massive techno-military advantage is inverted.<br />

Instead of scenes of the massive destructive power of American military force, we are<br />

shown countless narratives of individual Americans fighting the numberless (<strong>and</strong> often<br />

invisible) forces of the North Vietnamese Army <strong>and</strong>/or the sinister <strong>and</strong> shadowy men<br />

<strong>and</strong> women of the National Liberation Front (‘Viet Cong’). Missing In Action I, II, <strong>and</strong><br />

III, Rambo: First Blood Part II, <strong>and</strong> Platoon, all contain scenes of lone Americans struggling<br />

against overwhelming odds. John Rambo, armed only with a bow <strong>and</strong> arrow, is<br />

perhaps the most notorious example. Platoon, however, takes this narrative strategy on<br />

to another plane altogether. In a key scene, ‘good’ Sergeant Elias is pursued by a countless<br />

number of North Vietnamese soldiers. He is shot continually until he falls to his<br />

knees, spreading his arms out in a Christ-like gesture of agony <strong>and</strong> betrayal. The camera<br />

pans slowly to emphasize the pathos of his death throes. In Britain the film was<br />

promoted with a poster showing Elias in the full pain of his ‘crucifixion’. Above the<br />

image is written the legend: ‘The First Casualty of War is Innocence’. Loss of innocence<br />

is presented as both a realization of the realities of modern warfare <strong>and</strong> as a result of<br />

America playing fair against a brutal <strong>and</strong> ruthless enemy. The ideological implication<br />

is clear: if America lost by playing the good guy, it is ‘obvious’ that it will be necessary<br />

in all future conflicts to play the tough guy in order to win.<br />

The third narrative paradigm is ‘the Americanization of the war’. What I want to<br />

indicate by this term is the way in which the meaning of the Vietnam War has become<br />

in Hollywood’s Vietnam (<strong>and</strong> elsewhere in US cultural production) an absolutely<br />

American phenomenon. This is an example of what we might call ‘imperial narcissism’,


Orientalism 175<br />

in which the United States is centred <strong>and</strong> Vietnam <strong>and</strong> the Vietnamese exist only to<br />

provide a context for an American tragedy, whose ultimate brutality is the loss of<br />

American innocence. And like any good tragedy, it was doomed from the beginning to<br />

follow the dictates of fate. It was something that just happened. Hollywood’s Vietnam<br />

exhibits what Linda Dittmar <strong>and</strong> Gene Michaud call a ‘mystique of unintelligibility’<br />

(1990: 13). Perhaps the most compelling example of the mystique of unintelligibility<br />

is the opening sequence in the American video version of Platoon. It begins with a few<br />

words of endorsement from the then chairman of the Chrysler Corporation. We see<br />

him moving through a clearing in a wood towards a jeep. He stops at the jeep, <strong>and</strong> resting<br />

against it, addresses the camera,<br />

This jeep is a museum piece, a relic of war. Norm<strong>and</strong>y, Anzio, Guadalcanal, Korea,<br />

Vietnam. I hope we will never have to build another jeep for war. This film Platoon<br />

is a memorial not to war but to all the men <strong>and</strong> women who fought in a time <strong>and</strong><br />

in a place nobody really understood, who knew only one thing: they were called <strong>and</strong><br />

they went. It was the same from the first musket fired at Concord to the rice paddies<br />

of the Mekong Delta: they were called <strong>and</strong> they went. That in the truest sense<br />

is the spirit of America. The more we underst<strong>and</strong> it, the more we honor those who<br />

kept it alive [my italics] (quoted in Harry W. Haines 1990: 81).<br />

This is a discourse in which there is nothing to explain but American survival.<br />

Getting ‘Back to the World’ is everything it is about. It is an American tragedy <strong>and</strong><br />

America <strong>and</strong> Americans are its only victims. The myth is expressed with numbing precision<br />

in Chris Taylor’s (Charlie Sheen) narration at the end of Platoon. Taylor looks<br />

back from the deck of a rising helicopter on the dead <strong>and</strong> dying of the battlefield<br />

below. Samuel Barber’s mournful <strong>and</strong> very beautiful Adagio for Strings seems to dictate<br />

the cadence <strong>and</strong> rhythm of his voice as he speaks these words of psycho-babble, about<br />

a war in which more than two million Vietnamese were killed, ‘I think now looking<br />

back, we did not fight the enemy, we fought ourselves. The enemy was in us’. Time<br />

Magazine’s (26 January 1987) review of the film echoes <strong>and</strong> elaborates this theme:<br />

Welcome back to the war that, just 20 years ago, turned America schizophrenic.<br />

Suddenly we were a nation split between left <strong>and</strong> right, black <strong>and</strong> white, hip <strong>and</strong><br />

square, mothers <strong>and</strong> fathers, parents <strong>and</strong> children. For a nation whose war history<br />

had read like a John Wayne war movie – where good guys finished first by being<br />

tough <strong>and</strong> playing fair – the polarisation was soul-souring. Americans were fighting<br />

themselves, <strong>and</strong> both sides lost.<br />

Platoon’s function in this scenario is to heal the schizophrenia of the American body<br />

politic. The film’s rewriting of the war not only excludes the Vietnamese, it also rewrites<br />

the anti-war movement. Pro-war <strong>and</strong> anti-war politics are re-enacted as different positions<br />

in a debate on how best to fight <strong>and</strong> win the war. One group (led by the ‘good’<br />

Sergeant Elias <strong>and</strong> who listens to Jefferson Airplane’s ‘White Rabbit’ <strong>and</strong> smokes marijuana)<br />

wants to fight the war with honour <strong>and</strong> dignity, whilst the other (led by the


176<br />

Chapter 8 ‘Race’, racism <strong>and</strong> representation<br />

‘bad’ Sergeant Barnes <strong>and</strong> who listens to Merle Haggard’s ‘Okie from Muskogee’ <strong>and</strong><br />

drinks beer) wants to fight the war in any way which will win it. We are asked to<br />

believe that this was the essential conflict which tore America apart – the anti-war<br />

movement, dissolved into a conflict on how best to fight <strong>and</strong> win the war. As Michael<br />

Klein contends ‘the war is decontextualized, mystified as a tragic mistake, an existential<br />

adventure, or a rite of passage through which the White American Hero discovers his<br />

identity’ (1990: 10).<br />

Although I have outlined three of the dominant narrative paradigms in Hollywood’s<br />

Vietnam, I do not want to suggest that these were or are unproblematically consumed by<br />

its American audiences (or any other audience). My claim is only that Hollywood produced<br />

a particular regime of truth. But film (like any other cultural text or practice) has<br />

to be made to mean (see Chapter 10). To really discover the extent to which Hollywood’s<br />

Vietnam has made its ‘truth’ tell requires a consideration of consumption. This will<br />

take us beyond a focus on the meaning of a text, to a focus on the meanings that can<br />

be made in the encounter between the discourses of the text <strong>and</strong> the discourses of<br />

the ‘consumer’, as it is never a matter of verifying (with an ‘audience’) the real meaning<br />

of, say, Platoon. The focus on consumption (understood as ‘production in use’) is to<br />

explore the political effectivity (or otherwise) of, say, Platoon. If a cultural text is to<br />

become effective (politically or otherwise) it must be made to connect with people’s<br />

lives – become part of their ‘lived culture’. Formal analysis of Hollywood’s Vietnam may<br />

point to how the industry has articulated the war as an American tragedy of bravery <strong>and</strong><br />

betrayal, but this does not tell us that it has been consumed as a war of bravery <strong>and</strong><br />

betrayal.<br />

In the absence of ethnographic work on the audience for Hollywood’s Vietnam,<br />

I want to point to two pieces of evidence that may provide us with clues to the circulation<br />

<strong>and</strong> effectivity of Hollywood’s articulation of the war. The first consists of<br />

speeches made by President George Bush in the build-up to the first Gulf War, <strong>and</strong><br />

the second are comments made by American Vietnam veterans about Hollywood<br />

<strong>and</strong> other representations of the war. But, to be absolutely clear, these factors, however<br />

compelling they may be in themselves, do not provide conclusive proof that<br />

Hollywood’s account of the war has become hegemonic where it matters – in the lived<br />

practices of everyday life.<br />

In the weeks leading up to the first Gulf War, Newsweek (10 December 1990)<br />

featured a cover showing a photograph of a serious-looking George Bush. Above the<br />

photograph was the banner headline, ‘This will not be another Vietnam’. The headline<br />

was taken from a speech made by Bush in which he said, ‘In our country, I know that<br />

there are fears of another Vietnam. Let me assure you . . . this will not be another<br />

Vietnam’. In another speech, Bush again assured his American audience that, ‘This will<br />

not be another Vietnam’. But this time he explained why: ‘Our troops will have the best<br />

possible support in the entire world. They will not be asked to fight with one h<strong>and</strong> tied<br />

behind their backs’ (quoted in the Daily Telegraph, January 1991).<br />

In these speeches, Bush was seeking to put to rest a spectre that had come to haunt<br />

America’s political <strong>and</strong> military self-image, what former President Richard Nixon had


Orientalism 177<br />

called the ‘Vietnam Syndrome’ (1986). The debate over American foreign policy had,<br />

according to Nixon, been ‘grotesquely distorted’ by reluctance ‘to use power to defend<br />

national interests’ (13). Fear of another Vietnam, had made America ‘ashamed of . . .<br />

[its] power, guilty about being strong’ (19).<br />

In the two Bush speeches from which I have quoted, <strong>and</strong> in many other similar<br />

speeches, Bush was articulating what many powerful American voices throughout the<br />

1980s had sought to make the dominant meaning of the war: ‘the Vietnam War as a<br />

noble cause betrayed – an American tragedy’. For example, in the 1980 presidential campaign<br />

Ronald Reagan declared, in an attempt to put an end to the Vietnam Syndrome,<br />

‘It is time we recognized that ours was, in truth, a noble cause’ (quoted in John Carlos<br />

Rowe <strong>and</strong> Rick Berg, 1991: 10). Moreover, Reagan insisted, ‘Let us tell those who<br />

fought in that war that we will never again ask young men to fight <strong>and</strong> possibly die in<br />

a war our government is afraid to let us win’ (quoted in Stephen Vlastos, 1991: 69). In<br />

1982 (almost a decade after the last US combat troops left Vietnam), the Vietnam<br />

Veterans’ memorial was unveiled in Washington. Reagan observed that Americans were<br />

‘beginning to appreciate that [the Vietnam War] was a just cause’ (quoted in Barbie<br />

Zelizer, 1995: 220). In 1984 (eleven years after the last US combat troops left Vietnam)<br />

the Unknown Vietnam Soldier was buried; at the ceremony President Reagan claimed,<br />

‘An American hero has returned home. . . . He accepted his mission <strong>and</strong> did his duty.<br />

And his honest patriotism overwhelms us’ (quoted in Rowe <strong>and</strong> Berg, 1991: 10). In<br />

1985 (twelve years after the last US combat troops left Vietnam), New York staged<br />

the first of the ‘Welcome Home’ parades for Vietnam veterans. In this powerful mix<br />

of political rhetoric <strong>and</strong> national remembering, there is a clear attempt to put in place<br />

a new ‘consensus’ about the meaning of America’s war in Vietnam. It begins in 1980<br />

in Reagan’s successful presidential campaign <strong>and</strong> ends in 1991 with the triumphalism<br />

of Bush after victory in the first Gulf War. Therefore, when, in the build-up to the<br />

Gulf War, Bush had asked Americans to remember the Vietnam War, the memories<br />

recalled by many Americans may have been of a war they had lived cinematically; a<br />

war of bravery <strong>and</strong> betrayal. Hollywood’s Vietnam had provided the materials to<br />

rehearse, elaborate, interpret <strong>and</strong> retell an increasingly dominant memory of America’s<br />

war in Vietnam.<br />

This was a memory that had little relationship to the ‘facts’ of the war. Put simply,<br />

the United States deployed in Vietnam the most intensive firepower the world had ever<br />

witnessed. Hollywood narratives do not feature the deliberate defoliation of large areas<br />

of Vietnam, the napalm strikes, the search-<strong>and</strong>-destroy missions, the use of Free Fire<br />

Zones, the mass bombing. For example, during the ‘Christmas bombing’ campaign of<br />

1972, the United States ‘dropped more tonnage of bombs on Hanoi <strong>and</strong> Haiphong<br />

than Germany dropped on Great Britain from 1940 to 1945’ (Franklin, 1993: 79). In<br />

total, the United States dropped three times the number of bombs on Vietnam as had<br />

been dropped anywhere during the whole of the Second World War (Pilger, 1990). In<br />

a memor<strong>and</strong>um to President Johnson in 1967, Secretary of Defense Robert McNamara<br />

wrote: ‘[The] picture of the world’s greatest superpower killing or seriously injuring<br />

1,000 noncombatants a week [his estimate of the human cost of the US bombing


178<br />

Chapter 8 ‘Race’, racism <strong>and</strong> representation<br />

campaign], while trying to pound a tiny backward nation into submission on an issue<br />

whose merits are hotly disputed, is not pretty’ (quoted in Martin, 1993: 19–20). This<br />

makes very unconvincing Bush’s claim that the United States fought the war with one<br />

h<strong>and</strong> tied behind its back.<br />

A second example of the consumption of Hollywood’s Vietnam is provided by the<br />

comments of American Vietnam veterans. As Marita Sturken observes, ‘Some Vietnam<br />

veterans say they have forgotten where some of their memories came from – their own<br />

experiences, documentary photographs, or Hollywood movies?’ (1997: 20). For example,<br />

Vietnam veteran William Adams makes this telling point:<br />

When Platoon was first released, a number of people asked me, ‘Was the war really<br />

like that?’ I never found an answer, in part because, no matter how graphic <strong>and</strong><br />

realistic, a movie is after all a movie, <strong>and</strong> war is only like itself. But I also failed to find<br />

an answer because what ‘really’ happened is now so thoroughly mixed up in my<br />

mind with what has been said about what happened that the pure experience is no<br />

longer there. This is odd, even painful, in some ways. But it is also testimony to the<br />

way our memories work. The Vietnam War is no longer a definite event so much<br />

as it is a collective <strong>and</strong> mobile script in which we continue to scrawl, erase, rewrite<br />

our conflicting <strong>and</strong> changing view of ourselves (quoted in Sturken, 1997: 86).<br />

Similarly, academic <strong>and</strong> Vietnam veteran Michael Clark writes of how the ticker-tape<br />

welcome home parade for Vietnam veterans staged in New York in 1985, together with<br />

the media coverage of the parade <strong>and</strong> the Hollywood films which seemed to provide<br />

the context for the parade, had worked together to produce a particular memory of the<br />

war – a memory with potentially deadly effects:<br />

they had constituted our memory of the war all along . . . [They] healed over the<br />

wounds that had refused to close for ten years with a balm of nostalgia, <strong>and</strong> transformed<br />

guilt <strong>and</strong> doubt into duty <strong>and</strong> pride. And with a triumphant flourish [they]<br />

offered us the spectacle of [their] most successful creation, the veterans who will<br />

fight the next war (Clark, 1991: 180).<br />

Moreover, as Clark is at pains to stress, ‘the memory of Vietnam has ceased to be a<br />

point of resistance to imperialist ambitions <strong>and</strong> is now invoked as a vivid warning to<br />

do it right next time’ (206). These concerns were fully justified by Bush’s triumphalism<br />

as the end of the first Gulf War, when he boasted, as if the war had been fought for no<br />

other reason than to overcome a traumatic memory, ‘By God, we’ve kicked the Vietnam<br />

Syndrome once <strong>and</strong> for all’ (quoted in Franklin, 1993: 177). Echoing these comments,<br />

the New York Times (2 December 1993) featured an article with the title, ‘Is the Vietnam<br />

Syndrome Dead? Happily, It’s Buried in the Gulf’. Vietnam, the sign of American loss<br />

<strong>and</strong> division had been buried in the s<strong>and</strong>s of the Persian Gulf. Kicking the Vietnam<br />

Syndrome (with the help of Hollywood’s Vietnam) had supposedly liberated a nation<br />

from old ghosts <strong>and</strong> doubts; had made America once again strong, whole <strong>and</strong> ready for<br />

the next war.


Anti-racism <strong>and</strong> cultural studies<br />

Anti-racism <strong>and</strong> cultural studies 179<br />

As was noted with both feminist <strong>and</strong> Marxist approaches to popular culture, discussions<br />

of ‘race’ <strong>and</strong> representation inevitably, <strong>and</strong> quite rightly, involve an ethical imperative<br />

to condemn the deeply inhuman discourses of racism. With this in mind, I want<br />

to end this section with two quotations, followed by a brief discussion <strong>and</strong> another<br />

quotation. The first quotation is from Stuart Hall <strong>and</strong> the second from Paul Gilroy.<br />

[T]he work that cultural studies has to do is to mobilise everything that it can find<br />

in terms of intellectual resources in order to underst<strong>and</strong> what keeps making the<br />

lives we live, <strong>and</strong> the societies we live in, profoundly <strong>and</strong> deeply antihumane in<br />

their capacity to live with difference. <strong>Cultural</strong> studies’ message is a message for academics<br />

<strong>and</strong> intellectuals but, fortunately, for many other people as well. ...I am<br />

convinced that no intellectual worth his or her salt, <strong>and</strong> no university that wants<br />

to hold up its head in the face of the twenty-first century, can afford to turn dispassionate<br />

eyes away from the problems of race <strong>and</strong> ethnicity that beset our world<br />

(Hall, 1996e: 343).<br />

We need to know what sorts of insight <strong>and</strong> reflection might actually help increasingly<br />

differentiated societies <strong>and</strong> anxious individuals to cope successfully with the<br />

challenges involved in dwelling comfortably in proximity to the unfamiliar without<br />

becoming fearful <strong>and</strong> hostile. We need to consider whether the scale upon<br />

which sameness <strong>and</strong> difference are calculated might be altered productively so that<br />

the strangeness of strangers goes out of focus <strong>and</strong> other dimensions of basic sameness<br />

can be acknowledged <strong>and</strong> made significant. We also need to consider how a<br />

deliberate engagement with the twentieth century’s history of suffering might furnish<br />

resources for the peaceful accommodation of otherness in relation to fundamental<br />

commonality. . . . [That is,] namely that human beings are ordinarily far<br />

more alike than they are unalike, that most of the time we can communicate with<br />

each other, <strong>and</strong> that the recognition of mutual worth, dignity, <strong>and</strong> essential similarity<br />

imposes restrictions on how we can behave if we wish to act justly (Gilroy<br />

2004: 3–4).<br />

The work of cultural studies, like that of all reasonable intellectual traditions, is to<br />

intellectually, <strong>and</strong> by example, help to defeat racism, <strong>and</strong> by so doing, help to bring<br />

into being a world in which the term ‘race’ is little more than a long disused historical<br />

category, signifying in the contemporary nothing more than the human race. However,<br />

as Gilroy observed in 1987, <strong>and</strong>, unfortunately, still the case more than twenty years<br />

later, until that moment arrives,<br />

‘Race’ must be retained as an analytic category not because it corresponds to any<br />

biological or epistemological absolutes, but because it refers investigation to the<br />

power that collective identities acquire by means of their roots in tradition. These


180<br />

Chapter 8 ‘Race’, racism <strong>and</strong> representation<br />

identities, in the forms of white racism <strong>and</strong> black resistance, are the most volatile<br />

political forces in Britain today (2002: 339).<br />

Further reading<br />

Storey, John (ed.), <strong>Cultural</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Popular</strong> <strong>Culture</strong>: A Reader, 4th edition, Harlow:<br />

Pearson Education, 2009. This is the companion volume to this book. It contains<br />

examples of most of the work discussed here. This book <strong>and</strong> the companion Reader<br />

are supported by an interactive website (www.pearsoned.co.uk/storey). The website<br />

has links to other useful sites <strong>and</strong> electronic resources.<br />

Baker, Houston A. Jr, Manthia Diawara <strong>and</strong> Ruth H. Lindeborg (eds), Black British<br />

<strong>Cultural</strong> Studies: A Reader, Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1996. A very interesting<br />

collection of essays.<br />

Dent, Gina (ed.), Black <strong>Popular</strong> <strong>Culture</strong>, Seattle: Bay Press, 1992. A very useful collection<br />

of essays.<br />

Dittmar, Linda <strong>and</strong> Michaud, Gene (eds), From Hanoi To Hollywood: The Vietnam War<br />

in American Film, New Brunswick <strong>and</strong> London: Rutgers University Press, 1990. The<br />

best collection of work on Hollywood’s Vietnam.<br />

Fryer, Peter, Staying Power: The History of Black People in Britain, London: Pluto, 1984.<br />

A brilliant book.<br />

G<strong>and</strong>hi, Leela, Postcolonial <strong>Theory</strong>: A Critical Introduction, Edinburgh: Edinburgh<br />

University Press, 1998. A good introduction to post-colonial theory.<br />

Gilroy, Paul, There Ain’t No Black in the Union Jack, London: Routledge, 1987/2002.<br />

One of the classic cultural studies encounters with ‘race’.<br />

Gilroy, Paul, The Black Atlantic, London: Verso, 1993. A brilliant argument against<br />

‘cultural absolutism’.<br />

Williams, Patrick <strong>and</strong> Laura Chrisman (eds), Colonial Discourse <strong>and</strong> Post-Colonial <strong>Theory</strong>:<br />

A Reader, Harlow: Prentice Hall, 1993. An interesting collection of essays on postcolonial<br />

theory.


9 Postmodernism<br />

The postmodern condition<br />

Postmodernism is a term current inside <strong>and</strong> outside the academic study of popular culture.<br />

It has entered discourses as different as pop music journalism <strong>and</strong> Marxist debates<br />

on the cultural conditions of late or multinational capitalism. As Angela McRobbie<br />

(1994) observes,<br />

Postmodernism has entered into a more diverse number of vocabularies more<br />

quickly than most other intellectual categories. It has spread outwards from the<br />

realms of art history into political theory <strong>and</strong> onto the pages of youth culture<br />

magazines, record sleeves, <strong>and</strong> the fashion pages of Vogue. This seems to me to<br />

indicate something more than the mere vagaries of taste (13).<br />

She also suggests that ‘the recent debates on postmodernism possess both a positive<br />

attraction <strong>and</strong> a usefulness to the analyst of popular culture’ (15). What is certainly the<br />

case is that as a concept postmodernism shows little sign of slowing down its coloniallike<br />

expansion. Here is Dick Hebdige’s (1988) list of the ways in which the term has<br />

been used:<br />

When it becomes possible for people to describe as ‘postmodern’ the decor of a<br />

room, the design of a building, the diegesis of a film, the construction of a record,<br />

or a ‘scratch’ video, a television commercial, or an arts documentary, or the ‘intertextual’<br />

relations between them, the layout of a page in a fashion magazine or critical<br />

journal, an anti-teleological tendency within epistemology, the attack on the<br />

‘metaphysics of presence’, a general attenuation of feeling, the collective chagrin<br />

<strong>and</strong> morbid projections of a post-War generation of baby boomers confronting<br />

disillusioned middle age, the ‘predicament’ of reflexivity, a group of rhetorical<br />

tropes, a proliferation of surfaces, a new phase in commodity fetishism, a fascination<br />

for images, codes <strong>and</strong> styles, a process of cultural, political, or existential fragmentation<br />

<strong>and</strong>/or crisis, the ‘de-centring’ of the subject, an ‘incredulity towards<br />

metanarratives’, the replacement of unitary power axes by a plurality of power/<br />

discourse formations, the ‘implosion of meaning’, the collapse of cultural hierarchies,


182<br />

Chapter 9 Postmodernism<br />

the dread engendered by the threat of nuclear self-destruction, the decline of the<br />

university, the functioning <strong>and</strong> effects of the new miniaturised technologies, broad<br />

societal <strong>and</strong> economic shifts into a ‘media’, ‘consumer’ or ‘multinational’ phase, a<br />

sense (depending on who you read) of ‘placelessness’ or the ab<strong>and</strong>onment of<br />

placelessness (‘critical regionalism’) or (even) a generalised substitution of spatial<br />

for temporal coordinates – when it becomes possible to describe all these things as<br />

‘postmodern’ . . . then it’s clear we are in the presence of a buzzword (2009: 429).<br />

For the purposes of this discussion I will, with the exception of some necessary theoretical<br />

exposition, consider postmodernism only as it relates to the study of popular<br />

culture. To facilitate this I will focus on the development of postmodern theory from<br />

its beginnings in the United States <strong>and</strong> Britain in the late 1950s <strong>and</strong> early 1960s,<br />

through its theorization in the work of Jean-François Lyotard, Jean Baudrillard <strong>and</strong><br />

Fredric Jameson. This will be followed by a discussion of two examples of postmodern<br />

culture: pop music <strong>and</strong> television. The chapter will conclude with a discussion of three<br />

more general aspects of postmodernism: the collapse of absolute st<strong>and</strong>ards of value,<br />

the culture of globalization, <strong>and</strong> convergence culture.<br />

Postmodernism in the 1960s<br />

Although the term ‘postmodern’ had been in cultural circulation since the 1870s (Best<br />

<strong>and</strong> Kellner, 1991), it is only in the late 1950s <strong>and</strong> 1960s that we see the beginnings of<br />

what is now understood as postmodernism. In the work of Susan Sontag (1966) <strong>and</strong><br />

Leslie Fiedler (1971) we encounter the celebration of what Sontag calls a ‘new sensibility’<br />

(1966: 296). It is in part a sensibility in revolt against the canonization of modernism’s<br />

avant-garde revolution; it attacks modernism’s official status, its canonization<br />

in the museum <strong>and</strong> the academy, as the high culture of the modern capitalist world. It<br />

laments the passing of the sc<strong>and</strong>alous <strong>and</strong> bohemian power of modernism, its ability<br />

to shock <strong>and</strong> disgust the middle class. Instead of outraging from the critical margins of<br />

bourgeois society, the work of Pablo Picasso, James Joyce, T.S. Eliot, Virginia Woolf,<br />

Bertolt Brecht, Igor Stravinsky <strong>and</strong> others, had not only lost the ability to shock <strong>and</strong><br />

disturb, but also become central, classical: in a word – canonized. Modernist culture<br />

has become bourgeois culture. Its subversive power has been drained by the academy<br />

<strong>and</strong> the museum. It is now the canon against which an avant-garde must struggle. As<br />

Fredric Jameson (1984) points out,<br />

This is surely one of the most plausible explanations for the emergence of postmodernism<br />

itself, since the younger generation of the 1960s will now confront the<br />

formerly oppositional modern movement as a set of dead classics, which ‘weigh<br />

like a nightmare on the brains of the living’, as Marx [1977] once said in a different<br />

context (56).


Jameson (1988) argues that postmodernism was born out of<br />

Postmodernism in the 1960s 183<br />

the shift from an oppositional to a hegemonic position of the classics of modernism,<br />

the latter’s conquest of the university, the museum, the art gallery network<br />

<strong>and</strong> the foundations, the assimilation . . . of the various high modernisms, into the<br />

‘canon’ <strong>and</strong> the subsequent attenuation of everything in them felt by our gr<strong>and</strong>parents<br />

to be shocking, sc<strong>and</strong>alous, ugly, dissonant, immoral <strong>and</strong> antisocial (299).<br />

For the student of popular culture perhaps the most important consequence of the<br />

new sensibility, with its ab<strong>and</strong>onment of ‘the Matthew Arnold notion of culture,<br />

finding it historically <strong>and</strong> humanly obsolescent’ (Sontag, 1966: 299), is its claim that<br />

‘the distinction between “high” <strong>and</strong> “low” culture seems less <strong>and</strong> less meaningful’ (302).<br />

In this sense, it is a sensibility in revolt against what is seen as the cultural elitism of<br />

modernism. Modernism, in spite of the fact that it often quoted from popular culture,<br />

is marked by a deep suspicion of all things popular. Its entry into the museum <strong>and</strong> the<br />

academy was undoubtedly made easier (regardless of its declared antagonism to ‘bourgeois<br />

philistinism’) by its appeal to, <strong>and</strong> homologous relationship with, the elitism of<br />

class society. The postmodernism of the late 1950s <strong>and</strong> 1960s was therefore in part a<br />

populist attack on the elitism of modernism. It signalled a refusal of what Andreas<br />

Huyssen (1986) calls ‘the great divide . . . [a] discourse which insists on the categorical<br />

distinction between high art <strong>and</strong> mass culture’ (viii). Moreover, according to Huyssen,<br />

‘To a large extent, it is by the distance we have travelled from this “great divide”<br />

between mass culture <strong>and</strong> modernism that we can measure our own cultural postmodernity’<br />

(57).<br />

The American <strong>and</strong> British pop art of the 1950s <strong>and</strong> 1960s presented a clear rejection<br />

of the ‘great divide’. It rejected Arnold’s definition of culture as ‘the best that has been<br />

thought <strong>and</strong> said’ (see Chapter 2), preferring instead Williams’s social definition of<br />

culture as ‘a whole way of life’ (see Chapter 3). British pop art dreamed of America<br />

(seen as the home of popular culture) from the grey deprivation of 1950s Britain. As<br />

Lawrence Alloway, the movement’s first theorist, explains,<br />

The area of contact was mass produced urban culture: movies, advertising, science<br />

fiction, pop music. We felt none of the dislike of commercial culture st<strong>and</strong>ard<br />

among most intellectuals, but accepted it as a fact, discussed it in detail, <strong>and</strong> consumed<br />

it enthusiastically. One result of our discussions was to take Pop culture out<br />

of the realm of ‘escapism’, ‘sheer entertainment’, ‘relaxation’, <strong>and</strong> to treat it with<br />

the seriousness of art (quoted in Frith <strong>and</strong> Horne, 1987: 104).<br />

Andy Warhol was also a key figure in the theorizing of pop art. Like Alloway, he<br />

refuses to take seriously the distinction between commercial <strong>and</strong> non-commercial art.<br />

He sees ‘commercial art as real art <strong>and</strong> real art as commercial art’ (109). He claims that<br />

‘“real” art is defined simply by the taste (<strong>and</strong> wealth) of the ruling class of the period.<br />

This implies not only that commercial art is just as good as “real” art – its value simply<br />

being defined by other social groups, other patterns of expenditure’ (ibid.). We can


184<br />

Chapter 9 Postmodernism<br />

of course object that Warhol’s merging of high <strong>and</strong> popular is a little misleading.<br />

Whatever the source of his ideas <strong>and</strong> his materials, once located in an art gallery the<br />

context locates them as art <strong>and</strong> thus high culture. John Rockwell argues that this was<br />

not the intention or the necessary outcome. Art, he argues, is what you perceive as art:<br />

‘A Brillo box isn’t suddenly art because Warhol puts a stacked bunch of them in a<br />

museum. But by putting them there he encourages you to make your every trip to the<br />

supermarket an artistic adventure, <strong>and</strong> in so doing he has exalted your life. Everybody’s<br />

an artist if they want to be’ (120).<br />

Huyssen (1986) claims that the full impact of the relationship between pop art <strong>and</strong><br />

popular culture can only be fully understood when located within the larger cultural<br />

context of the American counterculture <strong>and</strong> the British underground scene: ‘Pop in the<br />

broadest sense was the context in which a notion of the postmodern first took shape,<br />

<strong>and</strong> from the beginning until today, the most significant trends within postmodernism<br />

have challenged modernism’s relentless hostility to mass culture’ (188). In this way,<br />

then, postmodernism can be said to have been at least partly born out of a generational<br />

refusal of the categorical certainties of high modernism. The insistence on an absolute<br />

distinction between high <strong>and</strong> popular culture came to be regarded as the ‘un-hip’<br />

assumption of an older generation. One sign of this collapse was the merging of pop<br />

art <strong>and</strong> pop music. For example, Peter Blake designed The Beatles’ Sergeant Pepper’s<br />

Lonely Hearts Club B<strong>and</strong> album; Richard Hamilton designed their ‘white album’; Andy<br />

Warhol designed the Rolling Stones’ album Sticky Fingers. Similarly, we could cite the<br />

new seriousness emerging in pop music itself, most evident in the work of performers<br />

such as Bob Dylan <strong>and</strong> The Beatles; there is a new seriousness in their work <strong>and</strong> their<br />

work is taken seriously in a way unknown before in considerations of pop music.<br />

Huyssen also detects a clear relationship between the American postmodernism of<br />

the 1960s <strong>and</strong> certain aspects of an earlier European avant-garde; seeing the American<br />

counterculture – its opposition to the war in Vietnam, its support for black civil rights,<br />

its rejection of the elitism of high modernism, its birthing of the second wave of<br />

feminism, the welcome it gave to the gay liberation movement, its cultural experimentalism,<br />

its alternative theatre, its happenings, its love-ins, its celebration of the everyday,<br />

its psychedelic art, its acid rock, its ‘acid perspectivism’ (Hebdige, 2009) – ‘as the<br />

closing chapter in the tradition of avantgardism’ (Huyssen, 1986: 195).<br />

By the late 1970s the debate about postmodernism crossed the Atlantic. The next<br />

three sections will consider the responses of two French cultural theorists to the debate<br />

on the ‘new sensibility’, before returning to America <strong>and</strong> Fredric Jameson’s account of<br />

postmodernism as the cultural dominant of late capitalism.<br />

Jean-François Lyotard<br />

Jean-François Lyotard’s (1984) principal contribution to the debate on postmodernism<br />

is The Postmodern Condition, published in France in 1979, <strong>and</strong> translated into English


Jean-François Lyotard 185<br />

in 1984. The influence of this book on the debate has been enormous. In many<br />

respects it was this book that introduced the term ‘postmodernism’ into academic<br />

circulation.<br />

For Lyotard the postmodern condition is marked by a crisis in the status of knowledge<br />

in Western societies. This is expressed as an ‘incredulity towards metanarratives’<br />

<strong>and</strong> what he calls ‘the obsolescence of the metanarrative apparatus of legitimation’<br />

(xxiv). What Lyotard is referring to is the supposed contemporary collapse or widespread<br />

rejection of all overarching <strong>and</strong> totalizing frameworks that seek to tell universal<br />

stories (‘metanarratives’): Marxism, liberalism, Christianity, for example. According to<br />

Lyotard, metanarratives operate through inclusion <strong>and</strong> exclusion, as homogenizing<br />

forces, marshalling heterogeneity into ordered realms, silencing <strong>and</strong> excluding other<br />

discourses, other voices in the name of universal principles <strong>and</strong> general goals. Postmodernism<br />

is said to signal the collapse of all metanarratives with their privileged truth<br />

to tell, <strong>and</strong> to witness instead the increasing sound of a plurality of voices from the<br />

margins, with their insistence on difference, on cultural diversity, <strong>and</strong> the claims of<br />

heterogeneity over homogeneity. 40<br />

Lyotard’s particular focus is on the status <strong>and</strong> function of scientific discourse <strong>and</strong><br />

knowledge. Science is important for Lyotard because of the role assigned to it by the<br />

Enlightenment. 41 Its task, through the accumulation of scientific knowledge, is to play<br />

a central role in the gradual emancipation of humankind. In this way, science assumes<br />

the status of a metanarrative, organizing <strong>and</strong> validating other narratives on the royal<br />

road to human liberation. However, Lyotard claims that since the Second World War,<br />

the legitimating force of science’s status as a metanarrative has waned considerably.<br />

It is no longer seen to be slowly making progress on behalf of humankind towards<br />

absolute knowledge <strong>and</strong> absolute freedom. It has lost its way – its ‘goal is no longer<br />

truth, but performativity’ (46). Similarly, higher education is ‘called upon to create<br />

skills, <strong>and</strong> no longer ideals’ (48). Knowledge is no longer seen as an end in itself, but<br />

as a means to an end. Like science, education will be judged by its performativity; <strong>and</strong><br />

as such it will be increasingly shaped by the dem<strong>and</strong>s of power. No longer will it<br />

respond to the question, ‘Is it true?’ It will hear only, ‘What use is it?’ ‘How much is<br />

it worth?’ <strong>and</strong> ‘Is it saleable?’ (51). Postmodern pedagogy would teach how to use<br />

knowledge as a form of cultural <strong>and</strong> economic capital without recourse to concern or<br />

anxiety about whether what is taught is true or false.<br />

Before leaving Lyotard, it is worth noting his own less than favourable response to<br />

the changed status of culture. The popular culture (‘contemporary general culture’) of<br />

the postmodern condition is for Lyotard an ‘anything goes’ culture, a culture of ‘slackening’,<br />

where taste is irrelevant, <strong>and</strong> money the only sign of value (79). The only relief<br />

is Lyotard’s view that postmodernist culture is not the end of the much superior culture<br />

of modernism, but the sign of the advent of a new modernism. Postmodernism is<br />

that which breaks with one modernism to form a new modernism: ‘A work can<br />

become modern only if it is first postmodern. Postmodernism thus understood is not<br />

modernism at its end but in the nascent state, <strong>and</strong> this state is constant’ (ibid.).<br />

Steven Connor (1989) suggests that The Postmodern Condition may be read ‘as a<br />

disguised allegory of the condition of academic knowledge <strong>and</strong> institutions in the


186<br />

Chapter 9 Postmodernism<br />

contemporary world’ (41). Lyotard’s ‘diagnosis of the postmodern condition is, in one<br />

sense, the diagnosis of the final futility of the intellectual’ (ibid.). Lyotard is himself<br />

aware of what he calls the contemporary intellectual’s ‘negative heroism’. Intellectuals<br />

have, he argues, been losing their authority since ‘the violence <strong>and</strong> critique mounted<br />

against the academy during the sixties’ (quoted in Connor, 1989: 41). As Iain<br />

Chambers (1988) observes,<br />

the debate over postmodernism can . . . be read as the symptom of the disruptive<br />

ingression of popular culture, its aesthetics <strong>and</strong> intimate possibilities, into a previously<br />

privileged domain. <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>and</strong> academic discourses are confronted by the<br />

wider, unsystemized, popular networks of cultural production <strong>and</strong> knowledge. The<br />

intellectual’s privilege to explain <strong>and</strong> distribute knowledge is threatened; his<br />

authority, for it is invariably ‘his’, redimensionalized. This in part explains both the<br />

recent defensiveness of the modernist, particularly Marxist, project, <strong>and</strong> the cold<br />

nihilism of certain notorious str<strong>and</strong>s in postmodernism (216).<br />

Angela McRobbie (1994) claims that postmodernism has enfranchised a new body<br />

of intellectuals: ‘the coming into being of those whose voices were historically<br />

drowned out by the (modernist) metanarratives of mastery, which were in turn both<br />

patriarchal <strong>and</strong> imperialist’ (15). Moreover, as Kobena Mercer (1994) points out,<br />

While the loudest voices in the culture announced nothing less than the end of<br />

everything of any value, the emerging voices, practices <strong>and</strong> identities of dispersed<br />

African, Caribbean <strong>and</strong> Asian peoples crept in from the margins of postimperial<br />

Britain to dislocate commonplace certainties <strong>and</strong> consensual ‘truths’ <strong>and</strong> thus<br />

open up new ways of seeing, <strong>and</strong> underst<strong>and</strong>ing, the peculiarities of living in the<br />

twilight of an historic interregnum in which ‘the old is dying <strong>and</strong> the new cannot<br />

be born’ [Gramsci,1971] (Mercer, 1994: 2).<br />

Jean Baudrillard<br />

Jean Baudrillard, according to Best <strong>and</strong> Kellner (1991), ‘has achieved guru status<br />

throughout the English speaking world’ (109). They claim that ‘Baudrillard has<br />

emerged as one of the most high profile postmodern theorists’ (111). His presence has<br />

not been confined to the world of academia; articles <strong>and</strong> interviews have appeared in<br />

many popular magazines.<br />

Baudrillard claims that we have reached a stage in social <strong>and</strong> economic development<br />

in which ‘it is no longer possible to separate the economic or productive realm from<br />

the realms of ideology or culture, since cultural artefacts, images, representations, even<br />

feelings <strong>and</strong> psychic structures have become part of the world of the economic’<br />

(Connor, 1989: 51). This is partly explained, Baudrillard argues, by the fact that there


Jean Baudrillard 187<br />

has been a historical shift in the West, from a society based on the production of things<br />

to one based on the production of information. In For a Critique of the Political Economy<br />

of the Sign, he describes this as ‘the passage from a metallurgic into a semiurgic society’<br />

(1981: 185). However, for Baudrillard, postmodernism is not simply a culture of the<br />

sign: rather it is a culture of the ‘simulacrum’.<br />

A simulacrum is an identical copy without an original. In Chapter 4, we examined<br />

Benjamin’s claim that mechanical reproduction had destroyed the ‘aura’ of the work of<br />

art; Baudrillard argues that the very distinction between original <strong>and</strong> copy has itself<br />

now been destroyed. He calls this process ‘simulation’. This idea can be demonstrated<br />

with reference to CDs <strong>and</strong> films. For example, when someone buys a copy of Steve<br />

Earle’s The Revolution Starts Now, it makes little sense to speak of having purchased the<br />

original. Similarly, it would make no sense for someone having seen The Eternal<br />

Sunshine of the Spotless Mind in Newcastle to be told by someone having seen the film<br />

in Shanghai or Berlin that he had seen the original <strong>and</strong> she had not. Both would have<br />

witnessed an exhibition of a copy without an original. In both cases, film <strong>and</strong> CD, we<br />

see or hear a copy without an original. A film is a construction made from editing<br />

together film footage shot in a different sequence <strong>and</strong> at different times. In the same<br />

way, a music recording is a construction made from editing together sounds recorded<br />

in a different sequence <strong>and</strong> at different times.<br />

Baudrillard (1983) calls simulation ‘the generation by models of a real without<br />

origins or reality: a hyperreal’ (2). Hyperrealism, he claims, is the characteristic mode<br />

of postmodernity. In the realm of the hyperreal, the distinction between simulation<br />

<strong>and</strong> the ‘real’ implodes; the ‘real’ <strong>and</strong> the imaginary continually collapse into each<br />

other. The result is that reality <strong>and</strong> simulation are experienced as without difference –<br />

operating along a roller-coaster continuum. Simulations can often be experienced as<br />

more real than the real itself – ‘even better than the real thing’ (U2). Think of the way<br />

in which Apocalypse Now has become the mark against which to judge the realism of<br />

representations of America’s war in Vietnam. Asking if it has the ‘look’ of Apocalypse<br />

Now is virtually the same as asking if it is realistic.<br />

The evidence for hyperrealism is said to be everywhere. For example, we live in a<br />

society in which people write letters to characters in soap operas, making them offers<br />

of marriage, sympathizing with their current difficulties, offering them new accommodation,<br />

or just writing to ask how they are coping with life. Television villains are<br />

regularly confronted in the street <strong>and</strong> warned about the possible future consequences<br />

of not altering their behaviour. Television doctors, television lawyers <strong>and</strong> television<br />

detectives regularly receive requests for advice <strong>and</strong> help. I saw an American tourist on<br />

television enthusing about the beauty of the British Lake District. Searching for suitable<br />

words of praise, he said, ‘It’s just like Disneyl<strong>and</strong>.’ In the early 1990s the Northumbria<br />

police force introduced ‘cardboard police cars’ in an attempt to keep motorists within<br />

the law. I recently visited an Italian restaurant in Morpeth in which a painting of<br />

Marlon Br<strong>and</strong>o as the ‘Godfather’ is exhibited as a mark of the restaurant’s genuine<br />

Italianicity. Visitors to New York can do tours which bus them around the city, not as<br />

‘itself’ but as it appears in Sex <strong>and</strong> the City. The riots, following the acquittal of the four<br />

Los Angeles police officers captured on video physically assaulting the black motorist


188<br />

Chapter 9 Postmodernism<br />

Rodney King, were headlined in two British newspapers as ‘LA Lawless’, <strong>and</strong> in another<br />

as ‘LA War’ – the story anchored not by a historical reference to similar disturbances in<br />

Watts, Los Angeles in 1965, or to the implications of the words – ‘No justice no peace’<br />

– chanted by demonstrators during the riots; the editors chose instead to locate the<br />

story within the fictional world of the American television series LA Law. Baudrillard<br />

calls this ‘the dissolution of TV into life, the dissolution of life into TV’ (55). Politicians<br />

increasingly play on this, relying on the conviction politics of the ‘photo-opportunity’<br />

<strong>and</strong> the ‘sound-byte’ in an attempt to win the hearts <strong>and</strong> minds of voters.<br />

In New York in the mid-1980s the City Arts Workshop <strong>and</strong> Adopt a Building commissioned<br />

artists to paint murals on a block of ab<strong>and</strong>oned buildings. After consultations<br />

with local residents it was agreed to depict images of what the community lacked:<br />

grocery store, newsst<strong>and</strong>, laundromat <strong>and</strong> record shop (Frith <strong>and</strong> Horne, 1987: 7).<br />

What the story demonstrates is something similar to the Northumbria police story –<br />

the substitution of an image for the real thing: instead of police cars, the illusion of<br />

police cars; instead of enterprise, the illusion of enterprise. Simon Frith <strong>and</strong> Howard<br />

Horne’s (1987) rather patronizing account of working-class youth out on the weekend<br />

illustrates much the same point:<br />

What made it all real for them: the TAN. The tan courtesy of the sun bed. No one<br />

here had been on a winter break (this is the Tebbit generation); they’d bought their<br />

look across the counter of the hairdresser, the beauty parlour <strong>and</strong> the keep fit<br />

centre. And so every weekend they gather in dreary, drizzly York <strong>and</strong> Birmingham<br />

<strong>and</strong> Crewe <strong>and</strong> act not as if they were on holiday but as if they were in an advertisement<br />

for holidays. Shivering. A simulation, but for real (182).<br />

The 1998 case of the imprisonment of Coronation Street character Deirdre Rachid<br />

is perhaps a classic example of hyperrealism (see Figure 9.1). The tabloid press not<br />

only covered the story, it campaigned for her release, in much the same way as if this<br />

was an incident from ‘real life’. The Daily Star launched a campaign to ‘Free the<br />

Weatherfield One’, <strong>and</strong> invited readers to phone or fax them to register their protest.<br />

They also produced a free poster for readers to display in car windows. The Sun asked<br />

readers to sign their petition <strong>and</strong> invited them to buy specially produced campaign Tshirts.<br />

MPs were described as sympathetic to Deirdre’s plight. The Star quoted Labour<br />

MP Fraser Kemp’s intention to speak to Home Secretary Jack Straw: ‘I will tell the Home<br />

Secretary that there has been an appalling miscarriage of justice. The Home Secretary<br />

should intervene to ensure justice is done <strong>and</strong> Deidre is released.’ Questions were asked<br />

in the Houses of Parliament. The broadsheets joined in (in the way they always do) by<br />

commenting on the tabloid commentary.<br />

In spite of all this, I think we can say with some confidence that the overwhelming<br />

majority of people who demonstrated their outrage at Deirdre Rachid’s imprisonment<br />

<strong>and</strong> celebrated her release, did so without believing that she was a real person, who had<br />

been unjustly sent to prison. What she is – <strong>and</strong> what they knew her to be – is a real<br />

character (<strong>and</strong> has been for over twenty-five years) in a real soap opera, watched three<br />

times a week by millions of real viewers. It is this that makes her a significant cultural


Figure 9.1 An example of hyperrealism.<br />

Jean Baudrillard 189<br />

figure (<strong>and</strong> of significant cultural reality). If hyperrealism means anything, it cannot<br />

with any credibility signal a decline in people’s ability to distinguish between fiction<br />

<strong>and</strong> reality. It is not, as some Baudrillardians seem to want to suggest, that people can<br />

no longer tell the difference between fiction <strong>and</strong> reality: it is that in some significant<br />

ways the distinction between the two has become less <strong>and</strong> less important. Why this has<br />

happened is itself an important question. But I do not think that hyperrealism really<br />

supplies us with the answer.<br />

The answer may have something to do with the way in which, as noted by John<br />

Fiske (1994), the ‘postmodern media’ no longer provide ‘secondary representations of<br />

reality; they affect <strong>and</strong> produce the reality that they mediate’ (xv). He is aware that to<br />

make an event a media event is not simply in the gift of the media. For something to<br />

become a media event it must successfully articulate (in the Gramscian sense discussed<br />

in Chapter 4) the concerns of both public <strong>and</strong> media. The relationship between media<br />

<strong>and</strong> public is complex, but what is certain in our ‘postmodern world’ is that all events<br />

that ‘matter’ are media events. He cites the example of the arrest of O.J. Simpson: ‘Local<br />

people watching the chase on TV went to O.J.’s house to be there at the showdown, but<br />

took their portable TVs with them in the knowledge that the live event was not a substitute<br />

for the mediated one but a complement to it. On seeing themselves on their<br />

own TVs, they waved to themselves, for postmodern people have no problem in being<br />

simultaneously <strong>and</strong> indistinguishably livepeople <strong>and</strong> mediapeople’ (xxii). The people<br />

who watched the arrest seemed to know implicitly that the media do not simply report<br />

or circulate the news, they produce it. In order to be part of the news of O.J. Simpson’s<br />

arrest it was not enough to be there, one had to be there on television. This suggests<br />

that there is no longer a clear distinction between a ‘real’ event <strong>and</strong> its media representation.<br />

O.J. Simpson’s trial, for example, cannot be neatly separated into a ‘real’ event<br />

that television then represented as a media event. Anyone who watched the proceedings<br />

unfold on TV knows that the trial was conducted for the television audience as<br />

much as for those present in the court. Without the presence of the cameras this would<br />

have been a very different event indeed.


190<br />

Chapter 9 Postmodernism<br />

Baudrillard’s (1983) own example of hyperrealism is Disneyl<strong>and</strong>: he calls it ‘a<br />

perfect model of all the entangled orders of simulation’ (23). He claims that the success<br />

of Disneyl<strong>and</strong> is not due to its ability to allow Americans a fantasy escape from<br />

reality, but because it allows them an unacknowledged concentrated experience of<br />

‘real’ America.<br />

Disneyl<strong>and</strong> is there to conceal the fact that it is the ‘real’ country, all of ‘real’<br />

America, which is Disneyl<strong>and</strong> (just as prisons are there to conceal the fact that it is<br />

the society in its entirety, in its banal omnipresence, which is carceral). Disneyl<strong>and</strong><br />

is presented as imaginary in order to make us believe that the rest is real, when<br />

in fact all of Los Angeles <strong>and</strong> the America surrounding it are no longer real, but of<br />

the order of the hyperreal <strong>and</strong> of simulation. It is no longer a question of a false<br />

representation of reality (ideology), but of concealing the fact that the real is no<br />

longer real (25).<br />

He explains this in terms of Disneyl<strong>and</strong>’s social ‘function’: ‘It is meant to be an infantile<br />

world, in order to make us believe that the adults are elsewhere, in the “real” world,<br />

<strong>and</strong> to conceal the fact that real childishness is everywhere’ (ibid.). He argues that the<br />

reporting of ‘Watergate’ operated in much the same way. It had to be reported as a<br />

sc<strong>and</strong>al in order to conceal the fact that it was a commonplace of American political<br />

life. This is an example of what he calls ‘a simulation of a sc<strong>and</strong>al to regenerative ends’<br />

(30). It is an attempt ‘to revive a moribund principle by simulated sc<strong>and</strong>al ...a question<br />

of proving the real by the imaginary; proving truth by sc<strong>and</strong>al’ (36). In the same<br />

way, it could be argued that recent revelations about the activities of certain businessmen<br />

operating in the financial markets of London had to be reported as a sc<strong>and</strong>al in<br />

order to conceal what Baudrillard calls capitalism’s ‘instantaneous cruelty; its incomprehensible<br />

ferocity; its fundamental immorality’ (28–9).<br />

Baudrillard’s general analysis supports Lyotard’s central point about postmodernism,<br />

the collapse of certainty, <strong>and</strong> the dissolution of the metanarrative of<br />

‘truth’. God, nature, science, the working class, all have lost their authority as centres<br />

of authenticity <strong>and</strong> truth; they no longer provide the evidence on which to rest one’s<br />

case. The result, he argues, is not a retreat from the ‘real’, but the collapse of the real<br />

into hyperrealism. As he says, ‘When the real is no longer what it used to be, nostalgia<br />

assumes its full meaning. There is a proliferation of myths of origin <strong>and</strong> signs of reality<br />

...a panic stricken production of the real <strong>and</strong> the referential’ (12–13). This is an example<br />

of the second historical shift identified by Baudrillard. Modernity was the era of<br />

what Paul Ricoeur calls the ‘hermeneutics of suspicion’, 42 the search for meaning in the<br />

underlying reality of appearances. Marx <strong>and</strong> Freud are obvious examples of this mode<br />

of thinking (see Chapters 4 <strong>and</strong> 5). Hyperreality thus calls into question the claims of<br />

representation, both political <strong>and</strong> cultural. If there is no real behind the appearance,<br />

no beyond or beneath, what can be called with validity a representation? For example,<br />

given this line of argument, Rambo does not represent a type of American thinking on<br />

Vietnam, it is a type of American thinking on Vietnam; representation does not st<strong>and</strong><br />

at one remove from reality, to conceal or distort, it is reality. The revolution proposed


y Baudrillard’s theory is a revolution against latent meaning (providing as it does, the<br />

necessary precondition for ideological analysis). Certainly this is how the argument is<br />

often presented. But if we think again about his accounts of Disneyl<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> Watergate,<br />

does what he has to say about them amount to very much more than a rather traditional<br />

ideological analysis – the discovery of the ‘truth’ behind the appearance?<br />

Baudrillard is ambivalent about the social <strong>and</strong> cultural changes he discusses. On the<br />

one h<strong>and</strong>, he appears to celebrate them. On the other, he suggests they signal a form<br />

of cultural exhaustion: all that remains is endless cultural repetition. I suppose the<br />

truth of Baudrillard’s position is a kind of resigned celebration. Lawrence Grossberg<br />

(1988) calls it ‘celebration in the face of inevitability, an embracing of nihilism without<br />

empowerment, since there is no real possibility of struggle’ (175). John Docker<br />

(1994) is more critical:<br />

Baudrillard offers a classic modernist narrative, history as a linear, unidirectional<br />

story of decline. But whereas the early twentieth-century high literary modernists could<br />

dream of an avant-garde or cultural elite that might preserve the values of the past in<br />

the hope of a future seeding <strong>and</strong> regrowth, no such hope surfaces in Baudrillard’s<br />

vision of a dying, entropic world. It’s not even possible to write in a rational argumentative<br />

form, for that assumes a remaining community of reason (105).<br />

Fredric Jameson<br />

Fredric Jameson 191<br />

Fredric Jameson is an American Marxist cultural critic who has written a number of very<br />

influential essays on postmodernism. Where Jameson differs from other theorists is in<br />

his insistence that postmodernism can best be theorized from within a Marxist or neo-<br />

Marxist framework.<br />

For Jameson postmodernism is more than just a particular cultural style: it is above<br />

all a ‘periodizing concept’ (1985: 113). Postmodernism is ‘the cultural dominant’ of<br />

late or multinational capitalism. His argument is informed by Ernest M<strong>and</strong>el’s (1978)<br />

characterization of capitalism’s three-stage development: ‘market capitalism’,<br />

‘monopoly capitalism’ <strong>and</strong> ‘late or multinational capitalism’. Capitalism’s third stage<br />

‘constitutes . . . the purest form of capital into hitherto uncommodified areas’<br />

(Jameson, 1984: 78). He overlays M<strong>and</strong>el’s linear model with a tripartite schema of<br />

cultural development: ‘realism’, ‘modernism’ <strong>and</strong> ‘postmodernism’ (ibid.). Jameson’s<br />

argument also borrows from Williams’s (1980) influential claim that a given social<br />

formation will always consist of three cultural moments (‘dominant’, ‘emergent’ <strong>and</strong><br />

‘residual’). Williams’s argument is that the move from one historical period to another<br />

does not usually involve the complete collapse of one cultural mode <strong>and</strong> the installation<br />

of another. Historical change may simply bring about a shift in the relative place<br />

of different cultural modes. In a given social formation, therefore, different cultural<br />

modes will exist but only one will be dominant. It is on the basis of this claim that


192<br />

Chapter 9 Postmodernism<br />

Jameson argues that postmodernism is ‘the cultural dominant’ of late or multinational<br />

capitalism (modernism is the residual; it is unclear what is the emergent).<br />

Having established that postmodernism is the cultural dominant within Western<br />

capitalist societies, the next stage for Jameson is to outline the constitutive features of<br />

postmodernism. First, postmodernism is said to be a culture of pastiche: a culture, that<br />

is, marked by the ‘complacent play of historical allusion’ (Jameson, 1988: 105).<br />

Pastiche is often confused with parody; both involve imitation <strong>and</strong> mimicry. However,<br />

whereas parody has an ‘ulterior motive’, to mock a divergence from convention or a<br />

norm, pastiche is a ‘blank parody’ or ‘empty copy’, which has no sense of the very possibility<br />

of there being a norm or a convention from which to diverge. As he explains,<br />

Pastiche is, like parody, the imitation of a peculiar mask, speech in a dead language:<br />

but it is a neutral practice of such mimicry, without any of parody’s ulterior<br />

motives, amputated of the satiric impulse, devoid of laughter <strong>and</strong> of any conviction<br />

that alongside the abnormal tongue you have momentarily borrowed, some<br />

healthy linguistic normality still exists. Pastiche is thus blank parody (1984: 65).<br />

Rather than a culture of supposed pristine creativity, postmodern culture is a culture<br />

of quotations; that is, cultural production born out of previous cultural production. 43<br />

It is therefore a culture ‘of flatness or depthlessness, a new kind of superficiality in the<br />

most literal sense’ (60). A culture of images <strong>and</strong> surfaces, without ‘latent’ possibilities, it<br />

derives its hermeneutic force from other images, other surfaces, the exhausted interplay<br />

of intertextuality. This is the world of postmodern pastiche, ‘a world in which stylistic<br />

innovation is no longer possible, all that is left is to imitate dead styles, to speak through<br />

the masks <strong>and</strong> with the voices of the styles in the imaginary museum’ (1985: 115).<br />

Jameson’s principal example of postmodern pastiche is what he calls the ‘nostalgia<br />

film’. The category could include a number of films from the 1980s <strong>and</strong> 1990s: Back<br />

to the Future I <strong>and</strong> II, Peggy Sue Got Married, Rumble Fish, Angel Heart, Blue Velvet. He<br />

argues that the nostalgia film sets out to recapture the atmosphere <strong>and</strong> stylistic peculiarities<br />

of America in the 1950s. He claims that ‘for Americans at least, the 1950s<br />

remain the privileged lost object of desire – not merely the stability <strong>and</strong> prosperity of<br />

a pax Americana, but also the first naive innocence of the countercultural impulses of<br />

early rock <strong>and</strong> roll <strong>and</strong> youth gangs’ (1984: 67). He also insists that the nostalgia film<br />

is not just another name for the historical film. This is clearly demonstrated by the fact<br />

that his own list includes Star Wars. Now it might seem strange to suggest that a film<br />

about the future can be nostalgic for the past, but as Jameson (1985) explains, ‘[Star<br />

Wars] is metonymically a . . . nostalgia film . . . it does not reinvent a picture of the past<br />

in its lived totality; rather, by reinventing the feel <strong>and</strong> shape of characteristic art objects<br />

of an older period’ (116).<br />

Films such as Raiders of the Lost Ark, Robin Hood: Prince of Thieves, The Mummy Returns<br />

<strong>and</strong> Lord of the Rings operate in a similar way to evoke metonymically a sense of the<br />

narrative certainties of the past. Therefore, according to Jameson, the nostalgia film<br />

works in one or two ways: it recaptures <strong>and</strong> represents the atmosphere <strong>and</strong> stylistic<br />

features of the past; <strong>and</strong> it recaptures <strong>and</strong> represents certain styles of viewing of the


Fredric Jameson 193<br />

past. What is of absolute significance for Jameson is that such films do not attempt to<br />

recapture or represent the ‘real’ past, but always make do with certain myths <strong>and</strong> stereotypes<br />

about the past. They offer what he calls ‘false realism’, films about other films,<br />

representations of other representations (what Baudrillard calls simulations: see discussion<br />

in the previous section): films ‘in which the history of aesthetic styles displaces<br />

“real” history’ (1984: 67). In this way, history is supposedly effaced by ‘historicism . . .<br />

the r<strong>and</strong>om cannibalisation of all the styles of the past, the play of r<strong>and</strong>om stylistic<br />

allusion’ (65–6). Here we might cite films like True Romance, Pulp Fiction <strong>and</strong> Kill Bill.<br />

The failure to be historical relates to a second stylistic feature identified by Jameson,<br />

cultural ‘schizophrenia’. He uses the term in the sense developed by Lacan (see Chapter<br />

5) to signify a language disorder, a failure of the temporal relationship between<br />

signifiers. The schizophrenic experiences time not as a continuum (past–present–<br />

future), but as a perpetual present that is only occasionally marked by the intrusion of<br />

the past or the possibility of a future. The ‘reward’ for the loss of conventional selfhood<br />

(the sense of self as always located within a temporal continuum) is an intensified<br />

sense of the present. Jameson explains it thus:<br />

Note that as temporal continuities break down, the experience of the present<br />

becomes powerfully, overwhelmingly vivid <strong>and</strong> ‘material’: the world comes before<br />

the schizophrenic with heightened intensity, bearing a mysterious <strong>and</strong> oppressive<br />

charge of affect, glowing with hallucinatory energy. But what might for us seem a<br />

desirable experience – an increase in our perceptions, a libidinal or hallucinogenic<br />

intensification of our normally humdrum <strong>and</strong> familiar surroundings – is here felt<br />

as loss, as ‘unreality’ (1985: 120).<br />

To call postmodern culture schizophrenic is to claim that it has lost its sense of history<br />

(<strong>and</strong> its sense of a future different from the present). It is a culture suffering from ‘historical<br />

amnesia’, locked into the discontinuous flow of perpetual presents. The ‘temporal’<br />

culture of modernism has given way to the ‘spatial’ culture of postmodernism.<br />

Jim Collins (2009) has identified a similar trend in recent cinema, what he calls<br />

an ‘emergent type of genericity’ (470): popular films which ‘quote’ other films, selfconsciously<br />

making reference to <strong>and</strong> borrowing from different genres of film. What<br />

makes Collins’s position more convincing than Jameson’s, is his insistence on ‘agency’:<br />

the claim that such films appeal to (<strong>and</strong> help constitute) an audience of knowing<br />

bricoleurs, who take pleasure from this <strong>and</strong> other forms of bricolage. Moreover, whereas<br />

Jameson argues that such forms of cinema are characterized by a failure to be truly historical,<br />

Peter Brooker <strong>and</strong> Will Brooker (1997a), following Collins, see instead ‘a new<br />

historical sense . . . the shared pleasure of intertextual recognition, the critical effect of<br />

play with narrative conventions, character <strong>and</strong> cultural stereotypes, <strong>and</strong> the power<br />

rather than passivity of nostalgia’ (7). Brooker <strong>and</strong> Brooker argue that Quentin<br />

Tarantino’s films, for example,<br />

can be seen as reactivating jaded conventions <strong>and</strong> audience alike, enabling a more<br />

active nostalgia <strong>and</strong> intertextual exploration than a term such as ‘pastiche’, which


194<br />

Chapter 9 Postmodernism<br />

has nowhere to go but deeper into the recycling factory, implies. Instead of ‘pastiche’,<br />

we might think of ‘rewriting’ or ‘reviewing’ <strong>and</strong>, in terms of the spectator’s<br />

experience, of the ‘reactivation’ <strong>and</strong> ‘reconfiguration’ of a given generational ‘structure<br />

of feeling’ within ‘a more dynamic <strong>and</strong> varied set of histories’ (ibid.).<br />

They point to the ways in which Tarantino’s work presents an ‘aesthetic of recycling . . .<br />

an affirmative “bringing back to life”, a “making new”’ (Brooker <strong>and</strong> Brooker, 1997b: 56).<br />

According to Collins (2009), part of what is postmodern about Western societies is<br />

the fact that the old is not simply replaced by the new, but is recycled for circulation<br />

together with the new. As he explains, ‘The ever-exp<strong>and</strong>ing number of texts <strong>and</strong> technologies<br />

is both a reflection of <strong>and</strong> a significant contribution to the “array” – the perpetual<br />

circulation <strong>and</strong> recirculation of signs that forms the fabric of postmodern<br />

cultural life’ (457). He argues that ‘This foregrounded, hyperconscious intertextuality<br />

reflects changes in terms of audience competence <strong>and</strong> narrative technique, as well as a<br />

fundamental shift in what constitutes both entertainment <strong>and</strong> cultural literacy in [postmodern<br />

culture]’ (460). As a consequence of this, Collins argues, ‘Narrative action now<br />

operates at two levels simultaneously – in reference to character adventure <strong>and</strong> in reference<br />

to a text’s adventures in the array of contemporary cultural production’ (464).<br />

Jameson’s final point, implicit in his claim that postmodernism is the ‘cultural<br />

dominant’ of late or multinational capitalism is the claim that postmodernism is a hopelessly<br />

commercial culture. Unlike modernism, which taunted the commercial culture of<br />

capitalism, postmodernism, rather than resisting, ‘replicates <strong>and</strong> reproduces – reinforces<br />

– the logic of consumer capitalism’ (1985: 125). It forms the principal part of a process<br />

in which ‘aesthetic production . . . has become integrated into commodity production<br />

generally’ (1984: 56). <strong>Culture</strong> is no longer ideological, disguising the economic activities<br />

of capitalist society; it is itself an economic activity, perhaps the most important<br />

economic activity of all. <strong>Culture</strong>’s changed situation can have a significant effect on<br />

cultural politics. No longer is it credible to see culture as ideological representation, an<br />

immaterial reflection of the hard economic reality. Rather, what we now witness is not<br />

just the collapse of the distinction between high <strong>and</strong> popular culture, but the collapse<br />

of the distinction between the realm of culture <strong>and</strong> the realm of economic activity.<br />

According to Jameson, when compared to ‘the Utopian “high seriousness” of the<br />

great modernisms’, postmodern culture is marked by an ‘essential triviality’ (85). More<br />

than this, it is a culture that blocks ‘a socialist transformation of society’ (ibid.). Despite<br />

his rejection of a moral critique as inappropriate (‘a category mistake’), <strong>and</strong> regardless<br />

of his citing of Marx’s insistence on a dialectical approach, which would see postmodern<br />

culture as both a positive <strong>and</strong> a negative development, his argument drifts inexorably<br />

to the st<strong>and</strong>ard Frankfurt School critique of popular culture. The postmodern<br />

collapse of the distinction between high <strong>and</strong> popular has been gained at the cost of<br />

modernism’s ‘critical space’. The destruction of this critical space is not the result of an<br />

extinction of culture. On the contrary, it has been achieved by what he calls<br />

an ‘explosion’: a prodigious expansion of culture throughout the social realm, to<br />

the point at which everything in our social life from economic value <strong>and</strong> state


Fredric Jameson 195<br />

power to practices <strong>and</strong> to the very structure of the psyche itself can be said to have<br />

become ‘cultural’ in some original <strong>and</strong> as yet unauthorised sense (89).<br />

The thorough ‘culturalization’ or ‘aestheticization’ of everyday life is what marks<br />

postmodernism off from previous socio-cultural moments. Postmodernism is a culture,<br />

which offers no position of ‘critical distance’; it is a culture in which claims<br />

of ‘incorporation’ or ‘co-optation’ make no sense, as there is no longer a critical space<br />

from which to be incorporated or co-opted. This is Frankfurt School pessimism at<br />

its most pessimistic (see Chapter 4). Grossberg (1988) sounds the critical note with<br />

economy:<br />

For Jameson . . . we need new ‘maps’ to enable us to underst<strong>and</strong> the organisation<br />

of space in late capitalism. The masses, on the other h<strong>and</strong>, remain mute <strong>and</strong> passive,<br />

cultural dupes who are deceived by the dominant ideologies, <strong>and</strong> who<br />

respond to the leadership of the critic as the only one capable of underst<strong>and</strong>ing<br />

ideology <strong>and</strong> constituting the proper site of resistance. At best, the masses succeed<br />

in representing their inability to respond. But without the critic, they are unable<br />

even to hear their own cries of hopelessness. Hopeless they are <strong>and</strong> shall remain,<br />

presumably until someone else provides them with the necessary maps of intelligibility<br />

<strong>and</strong> critical models of resistance (174).<br />

Although Jameson can be located within the traditions of Frankfurt School pessimism,<br />

there is a sense in which he is not quite as postmodern as one of the School’s<br />

leading figures, Herbert Marcuse. Marcuse’s (1968b) discussion of what he calls<br />

‘affirmative culture’ (the culture or cultural space which emerged with the separation of<br />

‘culture’ <strong>and</strong> ‘civilization’, discussed in Chapter 2) contains little of Jameson’s enthusiasm<br />

for the historical emergence of culture as a separate sphere. As he explains,<br />

By affirmative culture is meant that culture of the bourgeois epoch, which led in<br />

the course of its own development to the segregation from civilisation of the mental<br />

<strong>and</strong> spiritual world as an independent realm of value that is also considered<br />

superior to civilisation. Its decisive characteristic is the assertion of a universally<br />

obligatory, eternally better <strong>and</strong> more valuable world that must be unconditionally<br />

affirmed: a world essentially different from the factual world of the daily struggle<br />

for existence, yet realisable by every individual for himself ‘from within’, without<br />

any transformation of the state of fact (95).<br />

Affirmative culture is a realm we may enter in order to be refreshed <strong>and</strong> renewed in<br />

order to be able to continue with the ordinary affairs of everyday life. ‘Affirmative’ culture<br />

invents a new reality: ‘a realm of apparent unity <strong>and</strong> apparent freedom was constructed<br />

within culture in which the antagonistic relations of existence were supposed<br />

to be stabilised <strong>and</strong> pacified. <strong>Culture</strong> affirms <strong>and</strong> conceals the new conditions of social<br />

life’ (96). The promises made with the emergence of capitalism out of feudalism, of a<br />

society to be based on equality, justice <strong>and</strong> progress, were increasingly relegated from


196<br />

Chapter 9 Postmodernism<br />

the world of the everyday to the realm of ‘affirmative’ culture. Like Marx <strong>and</strong> Engels<br />

(1957) on religion, Marcuse (1968b) argues that culture makes an unbearable condition<br />

bearable by soothing the pain of existence.<br />

One of the decisive social tasks of affirmative culture is based on this contradiction<br />

between the insufferable mutability of a bad existence <strong>and</strong> the need for happiness<br />

in order to make such an existence bearable. Within this existence the resolution<br />

can be only illusory. And the possibility of a solution rests precisely on the character<br />

of artistic beauty as illusion. . . . But this illusion has a real effect, producing<br />

satisfaction . . . [in] the service of the status quo (118–24).<br />

Something that produces satisfaction in the service of the status quo does not sound<br />

like something a Marxist would want to regret coming to an end. Moreover, does its<br />

demise really block, as Jameson claims, the transition to a socialist society? It might in<br />

fact be possible to argue just the opposite case.<br />

Ernesto Laclau <strong>and</strong> Chantal Mouffe (2001) share some of Jameson’s analysis of the<br />

postmodern, but unlike Jameson they recognize the possibility of agency.<br />

Today it is not only as a seller of labour-power that the individual is subordinated<br />

to capital, but also through his or her incorporation into a multitude of other<br />

social relations: culture, free time, illness, education, sex <strong>and</strong> even death. There is<br />

practically no domain of individual or collective life which escapes capitalists relations.<br />

But this ‘consumer’ society has not led to the end of ideology, as Daniel Bell<br />

announced, nor to the creation of a one-demensional man, as Marcuse feared. On<br />

the contrary, numerous new struggles have expressed resistance against the new<br />

forms of subordination, <strong>and</strong> this from within the heart of the new society (161).<br />

Laclau <strong>and</strong> Mouffe also refer to ‘the new cultural forms linked to the expansion of the<br />

means of mass communication. These . . . make possible a new mass culture which . . .<br />

profoundly shake[s] traditional identities. Once again, the effects here are ambiguous,<br />

as along with the undeniable effects of massification <strong>and</strong> uniformization, this mediabased<br />

culture also contains powerful elements for the subversion of inequalities’ (163).<br />

This does not mean that there has necessarily been an increase in ‘material’ equality.<br />

Nevertheless,<br />

the cultural democratization which is the inevitable consequence of the action of<br />

the media permit the questioning of privileges based upon older forms of status.<br />

Interpellated as equals in their capacity as consumers, even more numerous groups<br />

are impelled to reject the real inequalities which continue to exist. This ‘democratic<br />

consumer culture’ has undoubtedly stimulated the emergence of new struggles<br />

which have played an important part in the rejection of old forms of subordination,<br />

as was the case in the United States with the struggle of the black movement<br />

for civil rights. The phenomenon of the young is particularly interesting, <strong>and</strong><br />

it is no cause for wonder they should constitute a new axis for the emergence of


antagonisms. In order to create new necessities, they are increasingly constructed<br />

as a specific category of consumer, which stimulates them to seek a financial autonomy<br />

that society is in no condition to give them (164).<br />

Postmodern pop music<br />

Postmodern pop music 197<br />

A discussion of postmodernism <strong>and</strong> popular culture might highlight any number of<br />

different cultural texts <strong>and</strong> practices: for example, television, music video, advertising,<br />

film, pop music, fashion. I have space here to consider only two examples, television<br />

<strong>and</strong> pop music.<br />

For Jameson (1984) the difference between modernist <strong>and</strong> postmodernist pop<br />

music is quite clear: The Beatles <strong>and</strong> The Rolling Stones represent a modernist moment<br />

against which punk rock (The Clash, for example) <strong>and</strong> new wave (Talking Heads, for<br />

example) can be seen as postmodernist. Andrew Goodwin (1991) has quite correctly<br />

pointed out that Jameson’s compressed time-span solution – pop music culture’s rapid<br />

progression through ‘realism’ (rock’n’roll), ‘modernism’, ‘postmodernism’ – enabling<br />

Jameson to establish a modernist moment against which to mark out a postmodernist<br />

response, is a very difficult argument to sustain. As Goodwin convincingly argues, The<br />

Beatles <strong>and</strong> The Rolling Stones are as different from each other as together they are different<br />

from The Clash <strong>and</strong> Talking Heads. In fact, it would be much easier to make an<br />

argument in which the distinction is made between the ‘artifice’ of The Beatles <strong>and</strong><br />

Talking Heads <strong>and</strong> the ‘authenticity’ of The Rolling Stones <strong>and</strong> The Clash.<br />

Goodwin himself considers a number of ways of seeing pop music <strong>and</strong> pop music<br />

culture as postmodernist. Perhaps its most cited aspect is the technological developments<br />

that have facilitated the emergence of ‘sampling’. He acknowledges that the parallel<br />

with some postmodern theorizing is interesting <strong>and</strong> suggestive, but that is all it is<br />

– interesting <strong>and</strong> suggestive. What is often missed in such claims is the way in which<br />

sampling is used. As he explains, ‘textual incorporation cannot be adequately understood<br />

as “blank parody”. We need categories to add to pastiche, which demonstrate<br />

how contemporary pop opposes, celebrates <strong>and</strong> promotes the texts it steals from’<br />

(173). We also need to be aware of ‘the historicizing function of sampling technologies<br />

in contemporary pop’ (ibid.), the many ways in which sampling is ‘used to<br />

invoke history <strong>and</strong> authenticity’ (175). Moreover, in regard to Jameson’s argument<br />

about nostalgia replacing history, ‘it has often been overlooked that the “quoting” of<br />

sounds <strong>and</strong> styles acts to historicize contemporary culture’ (ibid.). Rap is perhaps the<br />

best example of sampling being used in this way. When asked to name the black means<br />

of cultural expression, the African American cultural theorist Cornel West (2009),<br />

answered, ‘music <strong>and</strong> preaching’. He went on to say,<br />

rap is unique because it combines the black preacher <strong>and</strong> the black music tradition,<br />

replacing the liturgical ecclesiastical setting with the African polyrhythms of


198<br />

Chapter 9 Postmodernism<br />

the street. A tremendous articulateness is syncopated with the African drumbeat,<br />

the African funk, into an American postmodernist product: there is no subject<br />

expressing originary anguish here but a fragmented subject, pulling from past <strong>and</strong><br />

present, innovatively producing a heterogeneous product. The stylistic combination<br />

of the oral, the literate, <strong>and</strong> the musical is exemplary . . . it is part <strong>and</strong> parcel<br />

of the subversive energies of black underclass youth, energies that are forced to take<br />

a cultural mode of articulation because of the political lethargy of American society<br />

(386).<br />

This is a rejection of Jameson’s claim that such work can be dismissed as an example<br />

of postmodern pastiche. The intertextual play of quotations in rap is not the<br />

result of aesthetic exhaustion; these are not the fragments of modernism shored against<br />

aesthetic ruin <strong>and</strong> cultural decline, but fragments combined to make a voice to be<br />

heard loudly within a hostile culture: the twisting of dismissal <strong>and</strong> denial into defiance.<br />

Postmodern television<br />

Television, like pop music, does not have a period of modernism to which it can be<br />

‘post’. But, as Jim Collins (1992) points out, television is often seen as the<br />

‘quintessence’ of postmodern culture. This claim can be made on the basis of a number<br />

of television’s textual <strong>and</strong> contextual features. If we take a negative view of postmodernism,<br />

as the domain of simulations, then television seems an obvious example<br />

of the process – with its supposed reduction of the complexities of the world to an everchanging<br />

flow of depthless <strong>and</strong> banal visual imagery. If, on the other h<strong>and</strong>, we take a<br />

positive view of postmodernism, then the visual <strong>and</strong> verbal practices of television can<br />

be put forward, say, as the knowing play of intertextuality <strong>and</strong> ‘radical eclecticism’<br />

(Charles Jenks in Collins, 1992: 338), encouraging, <strong>and</strong> helping to produce, the<br />

‘sophisticated bricoleur’ (Collins, 1992: 337) of postmodern culture. For example, a<br />

television series like Twin Peaks both helps to constitute an audience as bricoleurs <strong>and</strong><br />

is watched in turn by an audience who celebrate the programme’s bricolage. According<br />

to Collins,<br />

Postmodernist eclecticism might only occasionally be a preconceived design<br />

choice in individual programs, but it is built into the technologies of media sophisticated<br />

societies. Thus television, like the postmodern subject, must be conceived as<br />

a site – an intersection of multiple, conflicting cultural messages. Only by recognising<br />

this interdependency of bricolage <strong>and</strong> eclecticism can we come to appreciate<br />

the profound changes in the relationship of reception <strong>and</strong> production in<br />

postmodern cultures. Not only has reception become another form of meaning<br />

production, but production has increasingly become a form of reception as it<br />

rearticulates antecedent <strong>and</strong> competing forms of representation (338).


Postmodern television 199<br />

Another divide within the approach to television as postmodern is between textual<br />

<strong>and</strong> ‘economic’ analysis. Instead of the semiotic sophistication of its intertextual play<br />

<strong>and</strong> radical eclecticism, television is condemned as hopelessly commercial. Collins<br />

uses Twin Peaks as a means of bringing together the different str<strong>and</strong>s of the relationship<br />

between postmodernism <strong>and</strong> television. Twin Peaks is chosen because it ‘epitomises the<br />

multiple dimensions of televisual postmodernism’ (341). He argues that the postmodernism<br />

of the television series is the result of a number of interrelated factors:<br />

David Lynch’s reputation as a film maker, the stylistic features of the series, <strong>and</strong>, finally,<br />

its commercial intertextuality (the marketing of related products: for example, The<br />

Secret Diary of Laura Palmer).<br />

At the economic level, Twin Peaks marks a new era in network television’s view of<br />

the audience. Instead of seeing the audience as an homogeneous mass, the series was<br />

part of a strategy in which the audience is seen as fragmented, consisting of different<br />

segments – stratified by age, class, gender, sexuality, geography, ethnicity <strong>and</strong> ‘race’ –<br />

each of interest to different advertisers. Mass appeal now involves attempts to intertwine<br />

the different segments to enable them to be sold to different sections of the<br />

advertising market. The significance of Twin Peaks, at least from this perspective, is that<br />

it represents an attempt by American network television to win back affluent sections<br />

of the television audience supposedly lost to cable, cinema <strong>and</strong> video – in short, the<br />

so-called ‘yuppie’ generation. Collins demonstrates this by addressing the way the<br />

series was promoted. First, there was the intellectual appeal – Lynch as auteur, Twin<br />

Peaks as avant-garde television. This was followed by Twin Peaks as soap opera.<br />

Together the two appeals soon coalesced into a postmodern reading formation in<br />

which the series was ‘valorised as would-be cinema <strong>and</strong> would-be soap opera’ (345).<br />

Similar marketing techniques have been used to promote many recent television programmes.<br />

The obvious examples are Desperate Housewives, Sex <strong>and</strong> the City, Six Feet<br />

Under, The Sopranos <strong>and</strong> Lost.<br />

The marketing of Twin Peaks (<strong>and</strong> similar television programmes) is undoubtedly<br />

supported <strong>and</strong> sustained by the polysemic play of Twin Peaks itself. The series is, as<br />

Collins suggests, ‘aggressively eclectic’ (ibid.), not only in its use of conventions from<br />

Gothic horror, police procedural, science fiction <strong>and</strong> soap opera, but also in the different<br />

ways – from straight to parody – these conventions are mobilized in particular<br />

scenes. Collins also notes the play of ‘tonal variations . . . within <strong>and</strong> across scenes’<br />

(ibid.). This has led some critics to dismiss Twin Peaks as ‘mere camp’. But it is never<br />

simply camp – it is never simply anything – continually playing with our expectations,<br />

moving the audience, as it does, from moments of parodic distance to moments of<br />

emphatic intimacy. Although this is a known aspect of Lynch’s filmic technique, more<br />

significantly it is also a characteristic ‘reflective of changes in television entertainment<br />

<strong>and</strong> of viewer involvement in that entertainment’ (347). As Collins explains,<br />

That viewers would take a great deal of pleasure in this oscillation <strong>and</strong> juxtaposition<br />

is symptomatic of the ‘suspended’ nature of viewer involvement in television<br />

that developed well before the arrival of Twin Peaks. The ongoing oscillation in<br />

discursive register <strong>and</strong> generic conventions describes not just Twin Peaks but the


200<br />

Chapter 9 Postmodernism<br />

very act of moving up <strong>and</strong> down the televisual scale of the cable box. While watching<br />

Twin Peaks, viewers may be overtly encouraged to move in <strong>and</strong> out of an ironic<br />

position, but watching other television soap operas (nighttime or daytime)<br />

involves for many viewers a similar process of oscillation in which emotional<br />

involvement alternates with ironic detachment. Viewing perspectives are no longer<br />

mutually exclusive, but set in perpetual alternation (347–8).<br />

Oscillation in discursive register <strong>and</strong> generic conventions is a primary factor in many<br />

recent television programmes. Again, the obvious examples are Desperate Housewives,<br />

Sex <strong>and</strong> the City, Six Feet Under, <strong>and</strong> The Sopranos. The key point to underst<strong>and</strong> with<br />

regard to Twin Peaks <strong>and</strong> postmodernism is that what makes the programme different<br />

from other television programmes is not that it produces shifting viewing positions,<br />

but that it ‘explicitly acknowledges this oscillation <strong>and</strong> the suspended nature of television<br />

viewing. . . . [It] doesn’t just acknowledge the multiple subject positions that<br />

television generates; it recognises that one of the great pleasures of the televisual text is<br />

that very suspension <strong>and</strong> exploits it for its own sake’ (348).<br />

Umberto Eco (1984) has identified a postmodern sensibility exhibited in an awareness<br />

of what he calls the ‘already said’. He gives the example of a lover who cannot tell<br />

his lover ‘I love you madly’, <strong>and</strong> says instead: ‘As Barbara Cartl<strong>and</strong> would put it, I love<br />

you madly’ (39). Given that we now live in an increasingly media-saturated world, the<br />

‘already said’ is, as Collins (1992) observes, ‘still being said’ (348). For example, we can<br />

identify this in the way that television, in a effort to fill the space opened up by the<br />

growth in satellite <strong>and</strong> cable channels, recycles its own accumulated past, <strong>and</strong> that of<br />

cinema, <strong>and</strong> broadcasts these alongside what is new in both media. 44 This does not<br />

mean that we must despair in the face of Jameson’s postmodern ‘structure’; rather we<br />

should think in terms of both ‘agency’ <strong>and</strong> ‘structure’ – which ultimately is always a<br />

question of ‘articulation’ (see Chapter 4). Collins provides this example of different<br />

strategies of articulation:<br />

The Christian Broadcasting Network <strong>and</strong> Nickelodeon both broadcast series from<br />

the late fifties <strong>and</strong> early sixties, but whereas the former presents these series as a<br />

model for family entertainment the way it used to be, the latter offers them as fun<br />

for the contemporary family, ‘camped up’ with parodic voice-overs, supergraphics,<br />

reediting designed to deride their quaint vision of American family life, which we<br />

all know never really existed even ‘back then’ (334).<br />

There can be little doubt that similar things are happening in, for example, music,<br />

cinema, advertising, fashion, <strong>and</strong> in the different lived cultures of everyday life. It is not<br />

a sign that there has been a general collapse of the distinctions people make between,<br />

say, high culture / low culture, past/present, history/nostalgia, fiction/reality; but it is a<br />

sign that such distinctions (first noticed in the 1960s, <strong>and</strong> gradually more so ever since)<br />

are becoming increasingly less important, less obvious, less taken for granted. But this<br />

does not of course mean that such distinctions cannot be, <strong>and</strong> are not being, articulated<br />

<strong>and</strong> mobilized for particular strategies of social distinction. But above all, we


should not take any of these changes at face value; we must always be alert to the what,<br />

why <strong>and</strong> for whom something is being articulated, <strong>and</strong> how it can always be articulated<br />

differently, in other contexts (see Chapter 10).<br />

Postmodernism <strong>and</strong> the pluralism of value<br />

Postmodernism <strong>and</strong> the pluralism of value 201<br />

Postmodernism has disturbed many of the old certainties surrounding questions of<br />

cultural value. In particular, it has problematized the question of why some texts are<br />

canonized, while others disappear without trace: that is, why only certain texts supposedly<br />

‘pass the test of time’. There are a number of ways to answer this question.<br />

First, we can insist that the texts which are valued <strong>and</strong> become part of what Williams<br />

calls the ‘selective tradition’ (see Chapter 3) are those which are sufficiently polysemic<br />

to sustain multiple <strong>and</strong> continuous readings. 45 The problem with this approach is that<br />

it seems to ignore questions of power. It fails to pose the question: ‘Who is doing the<br />

valuing, in what context(s) <strong>and</strong> with what effects of power?’ In short, it is very difficult<br />

to see how a process, in which only certain people have the power <strong>and</strong> cultural authority<br />

to ensure the canonical reproduction of texts <strong>and</strong> practices, can really be described<br />

as simply an effect of a text’s polysemy.<br />

Rather than begin with polysemy, cultural studies would begin with power. Put simply,<br />

a text will survive its moment of production if it is selected to meet the needs <strong>and</strong><br />

desires of people with cultural power. Surviving its moment of production makes<br />

it available to meet the (usually different) desires <strong>and</strong> needs of other generations of<br />

people with cultural power. The selective tradition, as Williams (2009) points out, is<br />

‘governed by many kinds of special interests, including class interests’. Therefore rather<br />

than being a natural repository of what Arnold thought of as ‘the best that has been<br />

thought <strong>and</strong> said’ (see Chapter 2), it ‘will always tend to correspond to its contemporary<br />

system of interests <strong>and</strong> values, for it is not an absolute body of work but a continual<br />

selection <strong>and</strong> interpretation’ (38–9). Particular interests, articulated in specific social<br />

<strong>and</strong> historical contexts, always inform the selective tradition. In this way, what constitutes<br />

the selective tradition is as much about policing knowledge as it is about organizing<br />

terrains of critical inquiry.<br />

It is not difficult to demonstrate how the selective tradition forms <strong>and</strong> re-forms in<br />

response to the social <strong>and</strong> political concerns of those with cultural power. We have<br />

only to think of the impact that, say, feminism, queer theory <strong>and</strong> post-colonial theory<br />

have had on the study of literature – women writers, gay writers, writers from the<br />

so-called colonial periphery have become a part of the institution of literature, not<br />

because their value has suddenly been recognized in some disinterested sweep of the<br />

field: they are there because power encountered resistance. Even when the selected texts<br />

remain the same, how <strong>and</strong> why they are valued certainly changes. So much so that<br />

they are hardly the same texts from one historical moment to the next. 46 As the Four<br />

Tops put it, in a slightly different context: ‘It’s the same old song / But with a different


202<br />

Chapter 9 Postmodernism<br />

meaning since you’ve been gone.’ 47 Or to put it in a less danceable discourse, a text is<br />

never really the issuing source of value, but always the site where the construction of<br />

value – variable values – can take place.<br />

Of course, when we ascribe value to a text or practice, we are not (or rarely ever) saying<br />

this is only of value to me; our evaluation always (or usually always) includes the<br />

notion that the text or practice should also be of value to others. The trouble with some<br />

forms of evaluation is that they insist that their community of others is an ideal community,<br />

with absolute cultural authority over all other valuing communities. It is not<br />

that they insist that all others should consume what they value (it is usually better for<br />

‘value’ if they do not), but they do insist on due deference for their judgements <strong>and</strong><br />

absolute recognition of their cultural authority to judge (see discussion of the ‘culture<br />

<strong>and</strong> civilization’ tradition in Chapter 2). 48<br />

The postmodern return to questions of value has witnessed an increased interest in<br />

the work of Pierre Bourdieu (1984). As I pointed out in Chapter 1, Bourdieu argues<br />

that distinctions of ‘culture’ (whether understood as text, practice or way of living) are<br />

a significant aspect in the struggle between dominant <strong>and</strong> subordinate groups in society.<br />

He shows how arbitrary tastes <strong>and</strong> arbitrary ways of living are continually transmuted<br />

into legitimate taste <strong>and</strong> the only legitimate way of life. The consumption of<br />

culture is thus a means to produce <strong>and</strong> to legitimate social difference, <strong>and</strong> to secure<br />

social deference.<br />

Bourdieu’s project is to (re-)locate ‘value’ in the world of everyday experience, to<br />

suggest that similar things are happening when I ‘value’ a holiday destination or a particular<br />

mode of dress, as are happening when I ‘value’ a poem by T.S. Eliot or a song<br />

by Otis Redding or a photograph by Cindy Sherman or a piece of music by Gavin<br />

Bryars. Such evaluations are never a simple matter of individual taste; cultural value<br />

operates both to identify <strong>and</strong> to maintain social difference <strong>and</strong> sustain social deference.<br />

Distinction is generated by learned patterns of consumption that are internalized as<br />

‘natural’ preferences <strong>and</strong> interpreted <strong>and</strong> mobilized as evidence of ‘natural’ competences,<br />

which are, ultimately, used to justify forms of social domination. The cultural<br />

tastes of dominant groups are given institutional form, <strong>and</strong> then, with deft ideological<br />

sleight of h<strong>and</strong>, their taste for this institutionalized culture (i.e. their own) is held up<br />

as evidence of their cultural, <strong>and</strong>, ultimately, their social, superiority. The effect of such<br />

cultural distinction is to produce <strong>and</strong> reproduce social distinction, social separation<br />

<strong>and</strong> social hierarchy. It becomes a means of establishing differences between dominated<br />

<strong>and</strong> dominant groups in society. The production <strong>and</strong> reproduction of cultural<br />

space thus produces <strong>and</strong> reproduces social space.<br />

Bourdieu’s purpose is not to prove the self-evident, that different classes have different<br />

lifestyles, different tastes in culture, but to identify <strong>and</strong> interrogate the processes<br />

by which the making of cultural distinctions secures <strong>and</strong> legitimates forms of power<br />

<strong>and</strong> control rooted in economic inequalities. He is interested not so much in the actual<br />

differences, but in how these differences are used by dominant groups as a means<br />

of social reproduction. The much heralded collapse of st<strong>and</strong>ards rehearsed (almost<br />

weekly) in the ‘quality’ media, may be nothing more than a perceived sense that the<br />

opportunities to use culture to make <strong>and</strong> mark social distinction are becoming more


<strong>and</strong> more difficult to find, as Pavarotti tops the charts, Gorecki outsells most of the acts<br />

on Top of the Pops, <strong>and</strong> Premier League football is, in many instances, as expensive as,<br />

say, ballet or opera.<br />

Perhaps the most significant thing about postmodernism for the student of popular<br />

culture is the dawning recognition that there is no absolute categorical difference<br />

between high <strong>and</strong> popular culture. This is not to say that one text or practice might not<br />

be ‘better’ (for what / for whom, etc., must always be decided <strong>and</strong> made clear) than<br />

another text or practice. But it is to say that there are no longer any easy reference<br />

points, to which we can refer, <strong>and</strong> which will automatically preselect for us the good<br />

from the bad. Some might regard such a situation (or even the description of such a<br />

situation) with horror – the end of St<strong>and</strong>ards. On the contrary, without easy recourse<br />

to fixed categories of value, it calls for rigorous, if always contingent, st<strong>and</strong>ards, if our<br />

task is to separate the good from the bad, the usable from the obsolete, the progressive<br />

from the reactionary. As John Fekete (1987) points out,<br />

By contrast [to modernism], postmodernism may be at last ready – or may, at least,<br />

represent the transition to a readiness – unneurotically, to get on without the<br />

Good-God-Gold St<strong>and</strong>ards, one <strong>and</strong> all, indeed without any capitalised St<strong>and</strong>ards,<br />

while learning to be enriched by the whole inherited inventory once it is transferred<br />

to the lower case. . . . We need to believe <strong>and</strong> enact the belief that there are<br />

better <strong>and</strong> worse ways to live the pluralism of value. To see all cows as the same<br />

colour would truly amount to being lost in the night. But the prospect of learning<br />

to be at ease with limited warranties, <strong>and</strong> with the responsibility for issuing them,<br />

without the false security of inherited guarantees, is promising for a livelier, more<br />

colourful, more alert, <strong>and</strong>, one hopes, more tolerant culture that draws enjoyment<br />

from the dappled relations between meaning <strong>and</strong> value (17).<br />

Fekete’s point is not significantly different from the argument made by Susan Sontag<br />

(1966) at the birth of the postmodern ‘new sensibility’:<br />

The new sensibility is defiantly pluralistic; it is dedicated both to an excruciating<br />

seriousness <strong>and</strong> to fun <strong>and</strong> wit <strong>and</strong> nostalgia. It is also extremely history-conscious;<br />

<strong>and</strong> the voracity of its enthusiasms (<strong>and</strong> of the supercession of these enthusiasms)<br />

is very high-speed <strong>and</strong> hectic. From the vantage point of this new sensibility, the<br />

beauty of a machine or of the solution to a mathematical problem, of a painting<br />

by Jasper Johns, of a film by Jean-Luc Godard, <strong>and</strong> of the personalities <strong>and</strong> music<br />

of the Beatles is equally accessible (304).<br />

The global postmodern<br />

The global postmodern 203<br />

One way in which the world is said to be becoming postmodern is in its increasing<br />

globalization. Perhaps the dominant view of globalization, especially in discussions of


204<br />

Chapter 9 Postmodernism<br />

Photo 9.1 The Coca-Colonization of China.<br />

globalization <strong>and</strong> culture, is to see it as the reduction of the world to an American<br />

‘global village’: a global village in which everyone speaks English with an American<br />

accent, wears Levi jeans <strong>and</strong> Wrangler shirts, drinks Coca-Cola, eats at McDonald’s,<br />

surfs the net on a computer overflowing with Microsoft software, listens to rock or<br />

country music, watches a mixture of MTV <strong>and</strong> CNN, Hollywood movies <strong>and</strong> reruns<br />

of Dallas, <strong>and</strong> then discusses the prophetically named World Series, while drinking a<br />

bottle of Budweiser <strong>and</strong> smoking a Marlboro cigarette. According to this scenario, globalization<br />

is the supposed successful imposition of American culture around the globe,<br />

in which the economic success of American capitalism is underpinned by the cultural<br />

work that its commodities supposedly do in effectively destroying indigenous cultures<br />

<strong>and</strong> imposing an American way of life on ‘local’ populations. Photo 9.1 presents a very<br />

succinct version of this argument. It is a photograph of a sculpture depicting people<br />

entering a Coca-Cola house as Chinese citizens <strong>and</strong> leaving as little Coca-Cola people.<br />

There are at least three problems with this view of globalization.<br />

The first problem with globalization as cultural Americanization is that it operates<br />

with a very reductive concept of culture: it assumes that ‘economic’ success is the same<br />

as ‘cultural’ imposition. In other words, the recognition of the obvious success of<br />

American companies in placing products in most of the markets of the world is understood<br />

as self-evidently <strong>and</strong> unproblematically ‘cultural’ success. For example, American<br />

sociologist Herbert Schiller (1979) claims that the ability of American companies to<br />

successfully unload commodities around the globe is producing an American global


The global postmodern 205<br />

capitalist culture. The role of media corporations, he claims, is to make programmes<br />

which ‘provide in their imagery <strong>and</strong> messagery, the beliefs <strong>and</strong> perspectives that create<br />

<strong>and</strong> reinforce their audiences’ attachments to the way things are in the system overall’ (30).<br />

There are two overlapping problems with this position. First, it is simply assumed<br />

that commodities are the same as culture: establish the presence of the former <strong>and</strong> you<br />

can predict the details of the latter. But as John Tomlinson (1999) points out, ‘if we<br />

assume that the sheer global presence of these goods is in itself token of a convergence<br />

towards a capitalist monoculture, we are probably utilising a rather impoverished concept<br />

of culture – one that reduces culture to its material goods’ (83). It may be the case<br />

that certain commodities are used, made meaningful <strong>and</strong> valued in ways which promote<br />

American capitalism as a way of life, but this is not something which can be<br />

established by simply assuming that market penetration is the same as cultural or<br />

ideological penetration.<br />

Another problem with this position is that it is an argument that depends on the<br />

claim that commodities have inherent values <strong>and</strong> singular meanings, which can be<br />

imposed on passive consumers. In other words, the argument operates with a very discredited<br />

account of the flow of influence. It simply assumes that the dominant globalizing<br />

culture will be successfully injected into the weaker ‘local’ culture. That is, it is<br />

assumed that people are the passive consumers of the cultural meanings that supposedly<br />

flow directly <strong>and</strong> straightforwardly from the commodities they consume. To<br />

think that economic success is the same as cultural success is to work under the<br />

influence of what I will call ‘mode of production determinism’. That is, the argument<br />

that how something is made determines what it can mean or what it is worth (it is<br />

Hollywood, etc., what do you expect?). Such analysis always seems to want to suggest<br />

that ‘agency’ is always overwhelmed by ‘structure’; that consumption is a mere shadow<br />

of production; that audience negotiations are fictions, merely illusory moves in a game<br />

of economic power. Moreover, ‘mode of production determinism’ is a way of thinking<br />

which seeks to present itself as a form of radical cultural politics. But all too often this<br />

is a politics in which attacks on power are rarely little more than self-serving revelations<br />

about how ‘other people’ are always ‘cultural dupes’ (see Chapters 4 <strong>and</strong> 10).<br />

A second problem with globalization as cultural Americanization is that it operates<br />

with a limited concept of the ‘foreign’. First of all, it works with the assumption that<br />

what is foreign is always a question of national difference. But what is foreign can<br />

equally be a question of class, ethnicity, gender, sexuality, generation, or any other<br />

marker of social difference (see Figure 9.2). Moreover, what is foreign in terms of being<br />

imported from another country may be less foreign than differences already established<br />

by, say, class or generation. Furthermore, the imported foreign may be used<br />

against the prevailing power relations of the ‘local’ (see Photo 9.2 <strong>and</strong> Figure 9.3). This<br />

is probably what is happening with the export of hip hop. What are we to make of the<br />

global success of ‘hip hop’? Are, for example, South African, French, Chinese or British<br />

rappers (<strong>and</strong> fans of hip hop) the victims of American cultural imperialism? Are they<br />

the cultural dupes of a transnational music industry? A more interesting approach<br />

would be to look at how South Africans, French, Chinese or British youth have ‘appropriated’<br />

hip hop; used it to meet their local needs <strong>and</strong> desires. In other words, a more


206<br />

Chapter 9 Postmodernism<br />

Figure 9.2 The ‘foreign’.<br />

Photo 9.2 ‘Imagine there’s no countries’.<br />

interesting approach would be one that looked at what they do with it, rather than only<br />

what it supposedly does to them. American culture is worked on; it is used to make<br />

space within what is perceived as the dominant national culture.<br />

Another problem with this very limited notion of the foreign is that it is always<br />

assumed that the ‘local’ is the same as the national. But within the national, there<br />

may well be many ‘locals’. Moreover, there may be considerable conflict between them,<br />

<strong>and</strong> between them <strong>and</strong> the dominant culture (i.e. ‘the national’). Globalization can


Figure 9.3 ‘Imagine there’s no countries’.<br />

The global postmodern 207<br />

therefore both help confirm <strong>and</strong> help undo local cultures; it can keep one in place <strong>and</strong><br />

it can make one suddenly feel out of place. For example, in 1946, addressing a conference<br />

of Spanish clerics, the Archbishop of Toledo wondered ‘[h]ow to tackle’ what<br />

he called ‘woman’s growing demoralization – caused largely by American customs<br />

introduced by the cinematograph, making the young woman independent, breaking<br />

up the family, disabling <strong>and</strong> discrediting the future consort <strong>and</strong> mother with exotic<br />

practices that make her less womanly <strong>and</strong> destabilize the home’ (quoted in Tomlinson,<br />

1997: 123). Spanish women may have taken a different view.<br />

A third problem with the model of globalization as cultural Americanization is that<br />

it assumes that American culture is monolithic. Even in the more guarded accounts of<br />

globalization it is assumed that we can identify something singular called American<br />

culture. George Ritzer (1999), for example, makes the claim that ‘while we will continue<br />

to see global diversity, many, most, perhaps eventually all of those cultures will<br />

be affected by American exports: America will become virtually everyone’s “second<br />

culture”’ (89).<br />

Globalization as cultural Americanization assumes that cultures can be lined up as<br />

distinct monolithic entities, hermetically sealed from one another until the fatal<br />

moment of the globalizing injection. Against such a view, Jan Nederveen Pieterse<br />

(1995) argues that globalization, as cultural Americanization,<br />

overlooks the countercurrents – the impact non-Western cultures have been making<br />

on the West. It downplays the ambivalence of the globalising momentum <strong>and</strong><br />

ignores the role of local reception of Western culture – for example the indigenization<br />

of Western elements. It fails to see the influence non-Western cultures<br />

have been exercising on one another. It has no room for crossover culture – as in<br />

the development of ‘third cultures’ such as world music. It overrates the homogeneity<br />

of Western culture <strong>and</strong> overlooks the fact that many of the st<strong>and</strong>ards


208<br />

Chapter 9 Postmodernism<br />

exported by the West <strong>and</strong> its cultural industries themselves turn out to be of culturally<br />

mixed character if we examine their cultural lineages (53).<br />

Moreover, the idea of globalization as the imposition of a singular <strong>and</strong> monolithic<br />

American culture (a middle-class culture of whiteness) begins to look very different,<br />

less monolithic, when we consider, for example, the fact that America has the third<br />

largest Hispanic population in the world. In addition, it is estimated that by 2076, the<br />

tricentennial of the American Revolution, people of Native American, African, Asian or<br />

Latin descent, will make up the majority of its population.<br />

Hall (1996b) has written that postmodernism ‘is about how the world dreams itself<br />

to be American’ (132). If this is the case, we may be all dreaming of many different<br />

Americas, depending on which bits of America we choose to consume. For example,<br />

if the material for our dreams is gathered from American popular music, the geography<br />

<strong>and</strong> geometry, the values, images, myths, styles, will be different depending on<br />

whether, for example, it is blues, country, dance, folk, heavy metal, jazz, rap, rock-<br />

’n’roll, sixties rock, or soul. At the very least, each genre of music would produce<br />

different political articulations, in terms of class, gender, race, ethnicity, sexuality,<br />

<strong>and</strong> generation. To recognize this is to recognize that cultures, even powerful cultures<br />

like that of the USA, are never monolithic. As Said (1993) observes, ‘[A]ll cultures are<br />

involved in one another; none is single <strong>and</strong> pure, all are hybrid, heterogeneous,<br />

extraordinarily differentiated, <strong>and</strong> unmonolithic’ (xxix). Moreover,<br />

[n]o one today is purely one thing. Labels like Indian, or woman, or Muslim, or<br />

American are now [no] more than starting points, which if followed into actual<br />

experience for only a moment are quickly left behind. Imperialism consolidated<br />

the mixture of cultures <strong>and</strong> identities on a global scale. But its worst <strong>and</strong> most paradoxical<br />

gift was to allow people to believe that they were only, mainly exclusively,<br />

White, or Black, or Western, or Oriental (407–8).<br />

Globalization is much more complex <strong>and</strong> contradictory than the simple imposition<br />

of, say, American culture. It is certainly true that we can travel around the world while<br />

never being too far from signs of American commodities. What is not true, however,<br />

is that commodities equal culture. Globalization involves the ebb <strong>and</strong> flow of both<br />

homogenizing <strong>and</strong> heterogenizing forces, the meeting <strong>and</strong> the mingling of the ‘local’<br />

<strong>and</strong> the ‘global’. To underst<strong>and</strong> this in a different way: what is exported always finds<br />

itself in the context of what already exists. That is, exports become imports, as they are<br />

incorporated into the indigenous culture. This can in turn impact on the cultural production<br />

of the ‘local’. Ien Ang (1996) gives the example of the Cantonese Kung Fu<br />

movies that revitalized the declining Hong Kong film industry. The films are a mixture<br />

of ‘Western’ narratives <strong>and</strong> Cantonese values. As she explains:<br />

<strong>Cultural</strong>ly speaking, it is hard to distinguish here between the ‘foreign’ <strong>and</strong> the<br />

‘indigenous’, the ‘imperialist’ <strong>and</strong> the ‘authentic’: what has emerged is a highly distinctive<br />

<strong>and</strong> economically viable hybrid cultural form in which the global <strong>and</strong> the


The global postmodern 209<br />

local are inextricably intertwined, in turn leading to the modernized reinvigoration<br />

of a culture that continues to be labelled <strong>and</strong> widely experienced as ‘Cantonese’. In<br />

other words, what counts as ‘local’ <strong>and</strong> therefore ‘authentic’ is not a fixed content,<br />

but subject to change <strong>and</strong> modification as a result of the domestication of<br />

imported cultural goods (154–5).<br />

Globalization may be making the world smaller, generating new forms of cultural<br />

hybridity, but it is also bringing into collision <strong>and</strong> conflict different ways of making the<br />

world mean. While some people may celebrate the opening up of new global ‘routes’,<br />

other people may resist globalization in the name of local ‘roots’. Resistance in the<br />

form of a reassertion of the local against the flow of the global can be seen in the<br />

increase in religious fundamentalism (Christianity, Hinduism, Islam <strong>and</strong> Judaism) <strong>and</strong><br />

the re-emergence of nationalism, most recently in the former Soviet Union <strong>and</strong> the former<br />

Yugoslavia. A more benign example of the insistence on ‘roots’ is the explosive<br />

growth in family history research in Europe <strong>and</strong> America. In all of these examples,<br />

globalization may be driving the search for ‘roots’ in a more secure past in the hope of<br />

stabilizing identities in the present.<br />

Globalization is a complex process, producing contradictory effects, in changing<br />

relations of culture <strong>and</strong> power. One way to underst<strong>and</strong> the processes of globalization<br />

is in terms of Gramsci’s concept of hegemony. From the perspective of the post-Marxist<br />

cultural studies appropriation of hegemony theory, cultures are neither something<br />

‘authentic’ (spontaneously emerging from ‘below’), nor something which is simply<br />

imposed from ‘above’, but a ‘compromise equilibrium’ (Gramsci, 1971: 161) between<br />

the two; a contradictory mix of forces from both ‘below’ <strong>and</strong> ‘above’; both ‘commercial’<br />

<strong>and</strong> ‘authentic’; both ‘local’ <strong>and</strong> ‘global’; marked by both ‘resistance’ <strong>and</strong> ‘incorporation’,<br />

involving both ‘structure’ <strong>and</strong> ‘agency’. Globalization can also be seen in this<br />

way. As Hall (1991) observes:<br />

what we usually call the global, far from being something which, in a systematic<br />

fashion, rolls over everything, creating similarity, in fact works through particularity,<br />

negotiates particular spaces, particular ethnicities, works through mobilizing<br />

particular identities <strong>and</strong> so on. So there is always a dialectic, between the local <strong>and</strong><br />

the global (62).<br />

Hegemony is a complex <strong>and</strong> contradictory process; it is not the same as injecting<br />

people with ‘false consciousness’. It is certainly not explained by the adoption of the<br />

assumption that ‘hegemony is prepackaged in Los Angeles, shipped out to the global<br />

village, <strong>and</strong> unwrapped in innocent minds’ (Liebes <strong>and</strong> Katz, 1993: xi). A better way of<br />

underst<strong>and</strong>ing the processes of globalization is one that takes seriously, not just the<br />

power of global forces, but also those of the local. This is not to deny power but to insist<br />

that a politics in which ‘local’ people are seen as mute <strong>and</strong> passive victims of processes<br />

they can never hope to underst<strong>and</strong>, a politics which denies agency to the vast majority,<br />

or at best only recognizes certain activities as signs of agency, is a politics which can<br />

exist without causing too much trouble to the prevailing structures of global power.


210<br />

Chapter 9 Postmodernism<br />

Convergence culture<br />

Another aspect of the postmodern is convergence culture, ‘where old <strong>and</strong> new media<br />

collide, where grassroots <strong>and</strong> corporate media intersect, where the power of the media<br />

producer <strong>and</strong> the power of the media consumer interact in unpredictable ways’ (Henry<br />

Jenkins, 2006: 2). Convergence involves the flow of media content across a range of<br />

different platforms. This is not simply a matter of new technologies but a process that<br />

requires the active participation of consumers.<br />

Convergence culture, like most popular culture discussed in this book, is a site<br />

of struggle <strong>and</strong> negotiation. It cannot be explained <strong>and</strong> understood as something<br />

imposed from ‘above’ or as something spontaneously emerging from ‘below’, but as a<br />

complex <strong>and</strong> contradictory combination of both forces. As Jenkins observes,<br />

Convergence . . . is both a top–down corporate-driven process <strong>and</strong> a bottom–up<br />

consumer-driven process. Corporate convergence coexists with grassroots convergence.<br />

Media companies are learning how to accelerate the flow of media content<br />

across delivery channels to exp<strong>and</strong> revenue opportunities, broaden markets, <strong>and</strong><br />

reinforce viewer commitments. Consumers are learning how to use these different<br />

media technologies to bring the flow of media more fully under their control <strong>and</strong><br />

to interact with other consumers (18).<br />

Convergence culture is the result of three factors. The first is concentration of media<br />

ownership. Owning a range of different platforms encourages producers to distribute<br />

content across these different platforms. So, for example, a company may publish<br />

the book of the film, together with the game based on both <strong>and</strong> promote these in its<br />

magazines <strong>and</strong> newspapers <strong>and</strong> through its internet sites <strong>and</strong> mobile phone companies.<br />

The second is technological change. This has created a new range of platforms for<br />

media content. For example, we can now do so many more things with our mobile<br />

phones than just make phone calls. We can take, send <strong>and</strong> receive photos <strong>and</strong> videos;<br />

make send <strong>and</strong> receive sound files; send <strong>and</strong> receive text messages; download information<br />

from the internet; receive ‘goal alerts’; play games; use it as a calendar, an alarm<br />

clock <strong>and</strong> a calculator (see Jewitt, 2005).<br />

The third factor involves the consumers of media. I may, for example, choose to<br />

listen to my favourite music on my laptop, my CD or DVD player, my iPod, my car<br />

radio, or on TV or radio. The same music is made available on different platforms, but<br />

I have to actively participate to make the system work. Moreover, I select which platform<br />

best suits my pleasure <strong>and</strong> convenience.<br />

The British science fiction television series Doctor Who, as Neil Perryman (2009)<br />

points out, ‘embraces convergence culture on an unprecedented scale’ (478). The BBC<br />

has made the programme available across a range of different platforms: mobile<br />

phones, podcasts, video blogs, websites, interactive red-button adventures, <strong>and</strong> online<br />

games. In addition, it has launched two complementary series that take characters into<br />

other contexts. As Perryman observes,


Doctor Who is a franchise that has actively embraced both the technical <strong>and</strong> cultural<br />

shifts associated with media convergence since it returned to our television<br />

screens in 2005. Its producers have attempted to provide extra-value content <strong>and</strong><br />

narrative complexity for both a hardcore fanbase <strong>and</strong> a mainstream audience by<br />

deploying a series of evolving <strong>and</strong> changing storytelling strategies across a wide<br />

range of media platforms (488).<br />

Afterword<br />

Postmodernism has changed the theoretical <strong>and</strong> the cultural basis of the study of popular<br />

culture. It raises many questions, not least the role that can be played by the student<br />

of popular culture: that is, what is our relationship to our object of study? With what<br />

authority, <strong>and</strong> for whom, do we speak? As Frith <strong>and</strong> Horne (1987) suggest,<br />

In the end the postmodern debate concerns the source of meaning, not just its relationship<br />

to pleasure (<strong>and</strong>, in turn, to the source of that pleasure) but its relationship<br />

to power <strong>and</strong> authority. Who now determines significance? Who has the right<br />

to interpret? For pessimists <strong>and</strong> rationalists like Jameson the answer is multinational<br />

capital – records, clothes, films, TV shows, etc. – are simply the results of<br />

decisions about markets <strong>and</strong> marketing. For pessimists <strong>and</strong> irrationalists, like<br />

Baudrillard, the answer is nobody at all – the signs that surround us are arbitrary.<br />

For optimists like lain Chambers <strong>and</strong> Larry Grossberg the answer is consumers<br />

themselves, stylists <strong>and</strong> subculturalists, who take the goods on offer <strong>and</strong> make their<br />

own marks with them (169).<br />

The next chapter will consist mostly of an attempt to find answers to some of these<br />

questions.<br />

Further reading<br />

Further reading 211<br />

Storey, John (ed.), <strong>Cultural</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Popular</strong> <strong>Culture</strong>: A Reader, 4th edition, Harlow:<br />

Pearson Education, 2009. This is the companion volume to this book. It contains<br />

examples of most of the work discussed here. This book <strong>and</strong> the companion Reader<br />

are supported by an interactive website (www.pearsoned.co.uk/storey). The website<br />

has links to other useful sites <strong>and</strong> electronic resources.<br />

Appignansesi, Lisa, (ed.), Postmodernism, London: ICA, 1986. A collection of essays –<br />

mostly philosophical – on postmodernism. McRobbie’s contribution, ‘Postmodernism<br />

<strong>and</strong> popular culture’, is essential reading.


212<br />

Chapter 9 Postmodernism<br />

Best, Steven, <strong>and</strong> Douglas Kellner, Postmodern <strong>Theory</strong>: Critical Interrogations, London:<br />

Macmillan, 1991. An excellent introduction to the debate about postmodernism.<br />

Boyne, Roy <strong>and</strong> Ali Rattansi (eds), Postmodernism <strong>and</strong> Society, London: Macmillan,<br />

1990. A useful collection of essays, with a very good introduction to the main issues<br />

in the debate about postmodernism.<br />

Brooker, Peter <strong>and</strong> Will Brooker (eds), Postmodern After-Images: A Reader in Film,<br />

Television <strong>and</strong> Video, London: Edward Arnold, 1997. An excellent collection of<br />

essays, with very good introductory sections.<br />

Campbell, Neil, Jude Davies, <strong>and</strong> George McKay, Issues in Americanization, Edinburgh:<br />

Edinburgh University Press, 2004. A very good collection of essays on a variety of<br />

topics relating to the idea of Americanization. The introduction is excellent.<br />

Collins, Jim, Uncommon <strong>Culture</strong>s: <strong>Popular</strong> <strong>Culture</strong> <strong>and</strong> Postmodernism, London:<br />

Routledge, 1989. A very interesting book, situating popular culture in the debate<br />

about postmodernism.<br />

Connor, Steven, Postmodernist <strong>Culture</strong>: An Introduction to Theories of the Contemporary,<br />

Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1989. A comprehensive introduction to postmodernism:<br />

useful discussion of popular culture.<br />

Docker, John, Postmodernism <strong>and</strong> <strong>Popular</strong> <strong>Culture</strong>: A <strong>Cultural</strong> History, Cambridge:<br />

Cambridge University Press, 1994. The aim of the book is to challenge the way a<br />

century of modernist theory has understood twentieth-century popular culture.<br />

Intelligent, polemical <strong>and</strong> very readable.<br />

Featherstone, Mike, Consumer <strong>Culture</strong> <strong>and</strong> Postmodernism, London: Sage, 1991. An interesting<br />

sociological discussion of consumer culture <strong>and</strong> postmodernism. Essential<br />

reading.<br />

Hebdige, Dick, Hiding in the Light, London: Comedia, 1988. A Collection of essays<br />

mostly related to questions of postmodernism <strong>and</strong> popular culture. Essential reading.<br />

Jenkins, Henry, Convergence <strong>Culture</strong>: Where Old <strong>and</strong> New Media Collide, New York:<br />

New York University Press, 2006. The key book on the emergence of ‘convergence<br />

culture’.<br />

Morris, Meaghan, The Pirate’s Fiancée: Feminism, Reading, Postmodernism, London:<br />

Verso, 1988. A collection of essays concerned with both theory <strong>and</strong> analysis.<br />

Essential reading.<br />

Ross, Andrew (ed.), Universal Ab<strong>and</strong>on: The Politics of Postmodernism, Minneapolis:<br />

University of Minnesota Press, 1988. A useful collection of essays on postmodernism:<br />

some interesting discussion of popular culture.<br />

Woods, Tim, Beginning Postmodernism, Manchester: Manchester University Press, 1999.<br />

Perhaps the best introduction to the debate that is postmodernism.


10 The politics of the<br />

popular<br />

I have tried in this book to outline something of the history of the relationship<br />

between cultural theory <strong>and</strong> popular culture. In the main I have tended to focus on the<br />

theoretical <strong>and</strong> methodological aspects <strong>and</strong> implications of the relationship, as this, in<br />

my opinion, is the best way in which to introduce the subject. However, I am aware that<br />

this has been largely at the expense of, on the one h<strong>and</strong>, the historical conditions<br />

of the production of theory about popular culture, <strong>and</strong> on the other, the political relations<br />

of its production <strong>and</strong> reproduction (these are analytical emphases <strong>and</strong> not separate<br />

<strong>and</strong> distinct ‘moments’).<br />

Something I hope I have demonstrated, however, is the extent to which popular culture<br />

is a concept of ideological contestation <strong>and</strong> variability, to be filled <strong>and</strong> emptied,<br />

articulated <strong>and</strong> disarticulated, in a range of different <strong>and</strong> competing ways. Even my<br />

own truncated <strong>and</strong> selective history of the study of popular culture shows that ‘studying’<br />

popular culture can be a very serious business indeed – a serious political business.<br />

A paradigm crisis in cultural studies?<br />

In <strong>Cultural</strong> Populism, Jim McGuigan (1992) claims that the study of popular culture<br />

within contemporary cultural studies is in the throes of a paradigm crisis. This is<br />

nowhere more clearly signalled than in the current polities of ‘cultural populism’.<br />

McGuigan defines cultural populism as ‘the intellectual assumption, made by some<br />

students of popular culture, that the symbolic experiences <strong>and</strong> practices of ordinary<br />

people are more important analytically <strong>and</strong> politically than <strong>Culture</strong> with a capital C’<br />

(4). On the basis of this definition, I am a cultural populist, <strong>and</strong>, moreover, so is<br />

McGuigan. However, the purpose behind McGuigan’s book is not to challenge cultural<br />

populism as such, but what he calls ‘an uncritical populist drift in the study of popular<br />

culture’ (ibid.), with an increasing fixation on strategies of interpretation at the expense<br />

of an adequate grasp of the historical <strong>and</strong> economic conditions of consumption. He<br />

contends that there has been an uncritical drift away from the ‘once compelling . . .<br />

neo-Gramscian hegemony theory’ (5) 49 towards an uncritical populism. In some ways,<br />

this was inevitable (he claims) given the commitment of cultural studies to a


214<br />

Chapter 10 The politics of the popular<br />

hermeneutic mode at the expense of the perspective of political economy. But what<br />

is worse, he maintains, is that cultural studies has increasingly narrowed its focus to<br />

questions of interpretation without situating such questions within a context of material<br />

relations of power. To reverse this trend, he advocates a dialogue between cultural<br />

studies <strong>and</strong> the political economy of culture. He fears that for cultural studies to remain<br />

separate is for it to remain politically ineffective as a mode of explanation, <strong>and</strong> thus for<br />

it to remain complicit with the prevailing exploitative <strong>and</strong> oppressive structures of<br />

powers.<br />

In my view, the separation of contemporary cultural studies from the political<br />

economy of culture has been one of the most disabling features of the field of<br />

study. The core problematic was virtually premised on a terror of economic reductionism.<br />

In consequence, the economic aspects of media institutions <strong>and</strong> the<br />

broader economic dynamics of consumer culture were rarely investigated, simply<br />

bracketed off, thereby severely undermining the explanatory <strong>and</strong>, in effect, critical<br />

capacities of cultural studies (40–1).<br />

Nicholas Garnham (2009) makes a similar point: ‘the project of cultural studies can<br />

only be successfully pursued if the bridge with political economy is rebuilt’ (619). Work<br />

on consumption in cultural studies has, or so the argument goes, vastly overestimated<br />

the power of consumers, by failing to keep in view the ‘determining’ role production<br />

plays in limiting the possibilities of consumption.<br />

<strong>Cultural</strong> studies is thus accused of failing to situate consumption within the ‘determining’<br />

conditions of production. Although the introduction of neo-Gramscian hegemony<br />

theory into cultural studies had promised to do this, according to McGuigan<br />

(1992), ‘it has never done so adequately due to the original schism with the political<br />

economy of culture’ (76). Can we return to hegemony theory revitalized by political<br />

economy? It seems that the answer is no: hegemony theory inevitably leads to an<br />

uncritical populism, fixated with consumption at the expense of production. Our only<br />

hope is to embrace the political economy of culture perspective.<br />

McGuigan also claims that cultural populism’s exclusive focus on consumption <strong>and</strong><br />

a corresponding uncritical celebration of popular reading practices has produced a ‘crisis<br />

of qualitative judgment’ (79). What he means by this is that there are no longer<br />

absolutist criteria of judgement. What is ‘good’ <strong>and</strong> what is ‘bad’ is now open to dispute.<br />

He blames postmodern uncertainty fostered by cultural populism, claiming that<br />

‘the reinsertion of aesthetic <strong>and</strong> ethical judgment into the debate is a vital rejoinder to<br />

the uncritical drift of cultural populism <strong>and</strong> its failure to dispute laissez-faire conceptions<br />

of consumer sovereignty <strong>and</strong> quality’ (159). Clearly unhappy with the intellectual<br />

uncertainties of postmodernism, he desires a return to the full authority of the<br />

modernist intellectual: always ready to make clear <strong>and</strong> comprehensive that which the<br />

ordinary mind is unable to grasp. He seeks a return to the Arnoldian certainties – culture<br />

is the best that has been thought <strong>and</strong> said (<strong>and</strong> the modernist intellectual will tell<br />

us what this is). He seems to advocate an intellectual discourse in which the university<br />

lecturer is the guardian of the eternal flame of <strong>Culture</strong>, initiating the uninitiated into


A paradigm crisis in cultural studies? 215<br />

the glow of its absolute moral <strong>and</strong> aesthetic value; students assume the role of passive<br />

consumers of an already constituted knowledge – fixed, formulated <strong>and</strong> administered<br />

by the professorial guardians of the flame. The refusal to privilege aesthetic judgement<br />

is not in my opinion a crisis, but a welcome recognition that there are other, sometimes<br />

far more interesting, questions to be asked (see Chapter 9). What is aesthetically ‘good’<br />

<strong>and</strong> what is aesthetically ‘bad’ changes <strong>and</strong> changes again in context after context.<br />

Moreover, what is ‘good’ aesthetically may be ‘bad’ in terms of politics; what is ‘bad’<br />

aesthetically may be ‘good’ politically. Rather than being trapped by a hopeless quest<br />

for abstract certainty, it is much more productive to recognize that it is only in<br />

grounded contexts that these questions can be really answered. But more than this, cultural<br />

studies should be little concerned with making speculative value judgements<br />

about the inherent qualities of commodities <strong>and</strong> focus its time instead on what people<br />

do with them, make from them, etc., in the constraining <strong>and</strong> enabling structures of<br />

everyday life. These are what I mean by more interesting questions. Those who insist<br />

on a return to absolute st<strong>and</strong>ards are saying little more than that it is too confusing<br />

now: I want back my easy <strong>and</strong> unquestioned authority to tell ordinary people what it<br />

is worth <strong>and</strong> how it is done.<br />

That ordinary people use the symbolic resources available to them under present<br />

conditions for meaningful activity is both manifest <strong>and</strong> endlessly elaborated upon<br />

by new revisionism. Thus emancipatory projects to liberate people from their alleged<br />

entrapment, whether they know they are entrapped or not, are called into question<br />

by this fundamental insight. Economic exploitation, racism, gender <strong>and</strong> sexual<br />

oppression, to name but a few, exist, but the exploited, estranged <strong>and</strong> oppressed<br />

cope, <strong>and</strong>, furthermore, if such writers as John Fiske <strong>and</strong> Paul Willis are to be believed,<br />

they cope very well indeed, making valid sense of the world <strong>and</strong> obtaining grateful<br />

pleasure from what they receive. Apparently, there is so much action in the micropolitics<br />

of everyday life that the Utopian promises of a better future, which were<br />

once so enticing for critics of popular culture, have lost all credibility (171).<br />

Most of this is simply untrue. Even Fiske (his prime example) does not celebrate an<br />

achieved utopia, but the active struggle of men <strong>and</strong> women to make sense of <strong>and</strong> make<br />

space in a world structured around exploitation <strong>and</strong> oppression. McGuigan seems to<br />

be saying that pleasure (<strong>and</strong> its identification <strong>and</strong> celebration) is in some fundamental<br />

sense counter-revolutionary. The duty <strong>and</strong> historical destiny of ordinary men <strong>and</strong><br />

women is to suffer <strong>and</strong> be still, until moral leftists reveal what is to be enjoyed on the<br />

glorious morning of the long day after the Revolution. Feminists unwilling to lie back<br />

<strong>and</strong> think about the economic base exposed the rhetorical vacuousness of this kind of<br />

thinking long ago. It simply is not the case that claims that audiences produce meaning<br />

are in some profound sense a denial of the need for political change. We can celebrate<br />

symbolic resistance without ab<strong>and</strong>oning our commitment to radical politics.<br />

This is in effect the core of Ang’s point (see Chapter 7). Presented in this way, political<br />

economy seems to amount to little more than another (sometimes sophisticated) version<br />

of the ‘ideology of mass culture’.


216<br />

Chapter 10 The politics of the popular<br />

Despite my criticisms, I believe McGuigan makes an important argument of some<br />

significance to students of popular culture. As he names John Fiske <strong>and</strong> Paul Willis as<br />

perhaps the most ‘guilty’ of uncritical cultural populists, I shall outline some of the key<br />

features of their recent work to explain what is at issue in what is so far a rather onesided<br />

debate. In order to facilitate this, I will introduce two new concepts that have their<br />

provenance in the work of Pierre Bourdieu, the ‘cultural field’ <strong>and</strong> the ‘economic field’.<br />

The cultural field<br />

John Fiske is generally seen as the epitome of the uncritical drift into cultural populism.<br />

According to McGuigan, ‘Fiske’s position is . . . indicative of the critical decline of<br />

British cultural studies’ (85). Fiske is said to continually sacrifice economic <strong>and</strong> technological<br />

determinations to make space for interpretation – a purely hermeneutic version<br />

of cultural studies. For example, he is accused of reducing the study of television<br />

‘to a kind of subjective idealism’ (72), in which the popular reading is king or queen,<br />

always ‘progressive’ – untroubled by questions of sexism or racism, <strong>and</strong> always<br />

ungrounded in economic <strong>and</strong> political relations. In short, Fiske is accused of an uncritical<br />

<strong>and</strong> unqualified celebration of popular culture; he is the classic example of what<br />

happened to cultural studies following the supposed collapse of hegemony theory <strong>and</strong><br />

the consequent emergence of what McGuigan refers to as the ‘new revisionism’,<br />

the reduction of cultural studies to competing hermeneutic models of consumption.<br />

New revisionism, with its supposed themes of pleasure, empowerment, resistance <strong>and</strong><br />

popular discrimination, is said to represent a moment of ‘retreat from more critical<br />

positions’ (75). In political terms, it is at best an uncritical echo of liberal claims about<br />

the ‘sovereignty of the consumer’, <strong>and</strong> at worse it is uncritically complicit with prevailing<br />

‘free market’ ideology.<br />

Fiske would not accept ‘new revisionism’ as an accurate description of his position<br />

on popular culture. He would also reject absolutely two assumptions implicit in the<br />

attack on his work. First, he would dismiss totally the view that ‘the capitalist culture<br />

industries produce only an apparent variety of products whose variety is finally illusory<br />

for they all promote the same capitalist ideology’ (Fiske, 1987: 309). Second, he is<br />

emphatic in his refusal of any argument which depends for its substance on the claim<br />

‘that “the people” are “cultural dupes”. . . a passive, helpless mass incapable of discrimination<br />

<strong>and</strong> thus at the economic, cultural, <strong>and</strong> political mercy of the barons of the<br />

industry’ (ibid.). Against these assumptions, Fiske argues that the commodities from<br />

which popular culture is made circulate in two simultaneous economies, the financial<br />

<strong>and</strong> the cultural.<br />

The workings of the financial economy cannot account adequately for all cultural<br />

factors, but it still needs to be taken into account in any investigation. ...But the<br />

cultural commodity cannot be adequately described in financial terms only: the


The cultural field 217<br />

circulation that is crucial to its popularity occurs in the parallel economy – the<br />

cultural (311).<br />

Whereas the financial economy is primarily concerned with exchange value, the cultural<br />

is primarily focused on use – ‘meanings, pleasures, <strong>and</strong> social identities’ (ibid.).<br />

There is of course dialogical interaction between these separate, but related, economies.<br />

Fiske gives the example of the American television programme Hill Street Blues. The<br />

programme was made by MTM <strong>and</strong> sold to NBC. NBC then ‘sold’ the potential audience<br />

to Mercedes Benz, the sponsors of the programme. This all takes place in the<br />

financial economy. In the cultural economy, the television series changes from commodity<br />

(to be sold to NBC) to a site for the production of meanings <strong>and</strong> pleasures for<br />

its audience. And in the same way, the audience changes from a potential commodity<br />

(to be sold to Mercedes Benz) to a producer (of meanings <strong>and</strong> pleasures). He argues<br />

that ‘the power of audiences-as-producers in the cultural economy is considerable’<br />

(313). The power of the audience, he contends,<br />

derives from the fact that meanings do not circulate in the cultural economy in the<br />

same way that wealth does in the financial. They are harder to possess (<strong>and</strong> thus to<br />

exclude others from possessing), they are harder to control because the production<br />

of meaning <strong>and</strong> pleasure is not the same as the production of the cultural commodity,<br />

or of other goods, for in the cultural economy the role of consumer does<br />

not exist as the end point of a linear economic transaction. Meanings <strong>and</strong> pleasures<br />

circulate within it without any real distinction between producers <strong>and</strong> consumers<br />

(ibid.).<br />

The power of the consumer derives from the failure of producers to predict what will<br />

sell. ‘Twelve out of thirteen records fail to make a profit, TV series are axed by the<br />

dozen, expensive films sink rapidly into red figures (Raise the Titanic is an ironic example<br />

– it nearly sank the Lew Grade empire)’ (ibid.). In an attempt to compensate for<br />

failures, the culture industries produce ‘repertoires’ of goods in the hope of attracting<br />

an audience; whereas the culture industries seek to incorporate audiences as commodity<br />

consumers, the audience often excorporates the text to its own purposes. Fiske cites<br />

the example of the way Australian Aboriginal viewers appropriated Rambo as a figure<br />

of resistance, relevant to their own political <strong>and</strong> cultural struggles. He also cites the<br />

example of Russian Jews watching Dallas in Israel <strong>and</strong> reading it as ‘capitalism’s selfcriticism’<br />

(320).<br />

Fiske argues that resistance to the power of the powerful by those without power in<br />

Western societies takes two forms, semiotic <strong>and</strong> social. The first is mainly concerned<br />

with meanings, pleasures <strong>and</strong> social identities; the second is dedicated to transformations<br />

of the socio-economic system. He contends that ‘the two are closely related,<br />

although relatively autonomous’ (316). <strong>Popular</strong> culture operates mostly, ‘but not<br />

exclusively’, in the domain of semiotic power. It is involved in ‘the struggle between<br />

homogenisation <strong>and</strong> difference, or between consensus <strong>and</strong> conflict’ (ibid.). In this<br />

sense, popular culture is a semiotic battlefield in which audiences constantly engage in


218<br />

Chapter 10 The politics of the popular<br />

‘semiotic guerrilla warfare’ (316) in a conflict fought out between the forces of incorporation<br />

<strong>and</strong> the forces of resistance: between an imposed set of meanings, pleasures<br />

<strong>and</strong> social identities, <strong>and</strong> the meanings, pleasures <strong>and</strong> social identities produced in acts<br />

of semiotic resistance, where ‘the hegemonic forces of homogeneity are always met by<br />

the resistances of heterogeneity’ (Fiske, 1989a: 8). In Fiske’s semiotic war scenario, the<br />

two economies favour opposing sides of the struggle: the financial economy is more<br />

supportive of the forces of incorporation <strong>and</strong> homogenization; the cultural economy<br />

is more accommodating to the forces of resistance <strong>and</strong> difference. Semiotic resistance,<br />

he argues, has the effect of undermining capitalism’s attempt at ideological homogeneity:<br />

dominant meanings are challenged by subordinate meanings; thus, the dominant<br />

class’s intellectual <strong>and</strong> moral leadership is challenged. Fiske states his position<br />

without apology <strong>and</strong> with absolute clarity:<br />

It . . . sees popular culture as a site of struggle, but, while accepting the power of<br />

the forces of dominance, it focuses rather upon the popular tactics by which these<br />

forces are coped with, are evaded or are resisted. Instead of tracing exclusively the<br />

processes of incorporation, it investigates rather that popular vitality <strong>and</strong> creativity<br />

that makes incorporation such a constant necessity. Instead of concentrating on<br />

the omnipresent, insidious practices of the dominant ideology, it attempts to<br />

underst<strong>and</strong> the everyday resistances <strong>and</strong> evasions that make that ideology work so<br />

hard <strong>and</strong> insistently to maintain itself <strong>and</strong> its values. This approach sees popular<br />

culture as potentially, <strong>and</strong> often actually, progressive (though not radical), <strong>and</strong> it<br />

is essentially optimistic, for it finds in the vigour <strong>and</strong> vitality of the people evidence<br />

both of the possibility of social change <strong>and</strong> of the motivation to drive it (20–1).<br />

Fiske also locates popular culture in what Pierre Bourdieu (1984) calls ‘the cultural<br />

field’ (113–20), in which takes place a cultural struggle between dominant or official<br />

culture <strong>and</strong> popular culture abstracted from economic <strong>and</strong> technological determinations,<br />

but ultimately overdetermined by them. According to Bourdieu, as Nicholas<br />

Garnham <strong>and</strong> Raymond Williams (1980) explain,<br />

all societies are characterised by a struggle between groups <strong>and</strong>/or classes <strong>and</strong> class<br />

fractions to maximise their interests in order to ensure their reproduction. The<br />

social formation is seen as a hierarchically organised series of fields within which<br />

human agents are engaged in specific struggles to maximise their control over the<br />

social resources specific to that field, the intellectual field, the educational field, the<br />

economic field etc. . . . The fields are hierarchically organised in a structure overdetermined<br />

by the field of class struggle over the production <strong>and</strong> distribution of<br />

material resources <strong>and</strong> each subordinate field reproduces within its own structural<br />

logic, the logic of the field of class struggle (215).<br />

The historical creation of a unique space – the cultural field – in which <strong>Culture</strong> with<br />

a capital C could develop above <strong>and</strong> beyond the social has for Bourdieu the purpose,<br />

or at least the consequence, of reinforcing <strong>and</strong> legitimizing class power as cultural <strong>and</strong>


The cultural field 219<br />

aesthetic difference. The class relations of the cultural field are structured around two<br />

divisions: on the one h<strong>and</strong>, between the dominant classes <strong>and</strong> the subordinate classes,<br />

<strong>and</strong> on the other, within the dominant classes between those with high economic capital<br />

as opposed to high cultural capital, <strong>and</strong> those with high cultural capital as opposed<br />

to high economic capital. Those whose power stems primarily from cultural rather<br />

than economic power are engaged in a constant struggle within the cultural field ‘to<br />

raise the social value of the specific competences involved in part by constantly trying<br />

to raise the scarcity of those competences. It is for this reason that . . . they will always<br />

resist as a body moves towards cultural democracy’ (220). 50<br />

As we noted in Chapter 1 (see also Chapter 9), for Bourdieu (1984) the category of<br />

‘taste’ functions as a marker of ‘class’ (using the word in a double sense to mean both<br />

a socio-economic category <strong>and</strong> the suggestion of a particular level of quality). At the<br />

pinnacle of the hierarchy of taste is the ‘pure’ aesthetic gaze – a historical invention –<br />

with its emphasis on form over function. The ‘popular aesthetic’ reverses this emphasis,<br />

subordinating form to function. Accordingly, popular culture is about performance,<br />

high culture is about contemplation; high culture is about representation, popular culture<br />

is about what is represented. As he explains, ‘Intellectuals could be said to believe<br />

in the representation – literature, theatre, painting – more than in the things represented,<br />

whereas the people chiefly expect representations <strong>and</strong> the conventions which<br />

govern them to allow them to believe “naively” in the things represented’ (5).<br />

Aesthetic ‘distance’ is in effect the denial of function: it insists on the ‘how’ <strong>and</strong> not<br />

the ‘what’. It is analogous to the difference between judging a meal good because it was<br />

economically priced <strong>and</strong> filling, <strong>and</strong> judging a meal good on the basis of how it was<br />

served, where it was served. The ‘pure’ aesthetic or cultured gaze emerges with the emergence<br />

of the cultural field, <strong>and</strong> becomes institutionalized in the art museum. Once<br />

inside the museum art loses all prior functions (except that of being art) <strong>and</strong> becomes<br />

pure form: ‘Though originally subordinated to quite different or even incompatible<br />

functions (crucifix <strong>and</strong> fetish, Pieta <strong>and</strong> still life), these juxtaposed works tacitly<br />

dem<strong>and</strong> attention to form rather than function, technique rather than theme’ (30). For<br />

example, an advertisement for soup displayed in an art gallery becomes an example of<br />

the aesthetic, whereas the same advertisement in a magazine is an example of commerce.<br />

The effect of the distinction is to produce ‘a sort of ontological promotion akin<br />

to a transubstantiation’ (6).<br />

As Bourdieu says, ‘it is not easy to describe the “pure” gaze without also describing<br />

the naive gaze which it defines itself against’ (32). The naive gaze is of course the gaze<br />

of the popular aesthetic:<br />

The affirmation of continuity between art <strong>and</strong> life, which implies the subordination<br />

of form to function ...a refusal of the refusal which is the starting point of<br />

the high aesthetic, i.e. the clear cut separation of ordinary dispositions from the<br />

specially aesthetic disposition (ibid.).<br />

The relations between the pure gaze <strong>and</strong> the popular/naive gaze are needless to say<br />

not those of equality, but a relation of dominant <strong>and</strong> dominated. Moreover, Bourdieu


220<br />

Chapter 10 The politics of the popular<br />

argues that the two aesthetics articulate relations of power. Without the required<br />

cultural capital to decipher the ‘code’ of art we are made socially vulnerable to the<br />

condescension of those who have the required cultural capital. What is cultural (i.e.<br />

acquired) is presented as natural (i.e. innate), <strong>and</strong> is, in turn, used to justify what are<br />

social relations. In this way, ‘art <strong>and</strong> cultural consumption are predisposed . . . to fulfil<br />

a social function of legitimating social differences’ (7). Bourdieu calls the operation of<br />

such distinctions the ‘ideology of natural taste’ (68). According to the ideology, only a<br />

supposedly instinctively gifted minority armed against the mediocrity of the masses<br />

can attain genuine ‘appreciation’. Ortega y Gasset makes the point with precision: ‘art<br />

helps the “best” to know <strong>and</strong> recognise one another in the greyness of the multitude<br />

<strong>and</strong> to learn their mission, which is to be few in number <strong>and</strong> to have to fight against<br />

the multitude’ (31). Aesthetic relations both mimic <strong>and</strong> help reproduce social relations<br />

of power. As Bourdieu observes,<br />

Aesthetic intolerance can be terribly violent. . . . The most intolerable thing for<br />

those who regard themselves as the possessors of legitimate culture is the sacrilegious<br />

reuniting of tastes which taste dictates shall be separated. This means that the<br />

games of artists <strong>and</strong> aesthetes <strong>and</strong> their struggles for the monopoly of artistic legitimacy<br />

are less innocent than they seem. At stake in every struggle over art there is<br />

also the imposition of an art of living, that is, the transmutation of an arbitrary way<br />

of living into the legitimate way of life which casts every other way of living into<br />

arbitrariness (57).<br />

Like other ideological strategies, ‘The ideology of natural taste owes its plausibility <strong>and</strong><br />

its efficacy to the fact that . . . it naturalises real differences, converting differences in<br />

the mode of acquisition of culture into differences of nature’ (68).<br />

In an argument that draws heavily on the work of Bourdieu, Paul Willis (1990)<br />

argues that the aesthetic appreciation of ‘art’ has undergone an ‘internal hyperinstitutionalization’<br />

(2) – the dissociation of art from life, a stress on form over function – in<br />

a further attempt to distance itself <strong>and</strong> those who ‘appreciate’ it from the ‘uncultured<br />

mass’. Part of this process is the denial of the necessary relationship between aesthetics<br />

<strong>and</strong> ‘education’ (understood in its broadest sense to include both formal <strong>and</strong><br />

informal): the production <strong>and</strong> reproduction of the necessary ‘knowledge’ on which<br />

aesthetic appreciation is founded. In denial of such a relationship, aesthetic appreciation<br />

is presented as something innate, rather than something learned. Rather than<br />

seeing this as a question of non-access to knowledge – they have not been ‘educated’<br />

in the necessary code to ‘appreciate’ the formal qualities of high culture – the majority<br />

of the population are encouraged to view ‘themselves as ignorant, insensitive <strong>and</strong><br />

without the finer sensibilities of those who really “appreciate”. Absolutely certainly<br />

they’re not the “talented” or “gifted”, the elite minority held to be capable of performing<br />

or creating “art”’ (3). This manufactures a situation in which people who make<br />

culture in their everyday lives see themselves as uncultured. Against the strategies of the<br />

‘internal hyperinstitutionalization’ of culture, Willis argues the case for what he calls<br />

‘grounded aesthetics’: the process through which ordinary people make cultural sense


The cultural field 221<br />

of the world: ‘the ways in which the received natural <strong>and</strong> social world is made human<br />

to them <strong>and</strong> made, to however small a degree (even if finally symbolic), controllable<br />

by them’ (22).<br />

[Grounded aesthetics] is the creative element in a process whereby meanings are<br />

attributed to symbols <strong>and</strong> practices <strong>and</strong> where symbols <strong>and</strong> practices are selected,<br />

reselected, highlighted <strong>and</strong> recomposed to resonate further appropriate <strong>and</strong> particularised<br />

meanings. Such dynamics are emotional as well as cognitive. There are<br />

as many aesthetics as there are grounds for them to operate in. Grounded aesthetics<br />

are the yeast of common culture (21).<br />

Grounded aesthetic value is never intrinsic to a text or practice, a universal quality<br />

of its form; it is always inscribed in the ‘sensuous/emotive/cognitive’ (24) act of consumption<br />

(how a commodity is appropriated, ‘used’ <strong>and</strong> made into culture). This is an<br />

argument against those who locate creativity only in the act of production, consumption<br />

being merely the recognition or misrecognition of the aesthetic intention. Against<br />

such claims, Willis insists that consumption is a symbolic act of creativity. His ‘fundamental<br />

point . . . is that “messages” are not now so much “sent” <strong>and</strong> “received” as made<br />

in reception. . . .“Sent message” communication is being replaced by “made message”<br />

communication’ (135). <strong>Cultural</strong> communication is ceasing to be a process of listening<br />

to the voices of others. Grounded aesthetics is the insistence that commodities are consumed<br />

(<strong>and</strong> made into culture) on the basis of use, rather than in terms of supposed<br />

inherent <strong>and</strong> ahistorical qualities (textual or authorial). In grounded aesthetics, meanings<br />

or pleasures are undecidable in advance of the practices of ‘production in use’. This<br />

of course means that a commodity or a commodified practice which is judged to be<br />

banal <strong>and</strong> uninteresting (on the basis of textual analysis or an analysis of its mode of<br />

production), may be made to bear or to do, in its ‘production in use’, all sorts of interesting<br />

things within the lived conditions of a specific context of consumption. In this<br />

way, Willis’s argument is a rebuke to both textualism, which makes judgements on the<br />

basis of formal qualities, <strong>and</strong> the political economy of culture approach, which makes<br />

judgements on the basis of the relations of production. The ‘symbolic work’ of consumption,<br />

he maintains, is never a simple repetition of the relations of production, nor<br />

is it a direct confirmation of the semiotic certainties of the lecture theatre.<br />

People bring living identities to commerce <strong>and</strong> the consumption of cultural commodities<br />

as well as being formed there. They bring experiences, feelings, social<br />

position <strong>and</strong> social memberships to their encounter with commerce. Hence they<br />

bring a necessary creative symbolic pressure, not only to make sense of cultural<br />

commodities, but partly through them also to make sense of contradiction <strong>and</strong><br />

structure as they experience them in school, college, production, neighbourhood,<br />

<strong>and</strong> as members of certain genders, races, classes <strong>and</strong> ages. The results of this<br />

necessary symbolic work may be quite different from anything initially coded into<br />

cultural commodities (21).


222<br />

Chapter 10 The politics of the popular<br />

The French cultural theorist Michel de Certeau (1984, 2009) also interrogates the<br />

term ‘consumer’, to reveal the activity that lies within the act of consumption or what<br />

he prefers to call ‘secondary production’ (2009: 547). Consumption, as he says, ‘is<br />

devious, it is dispersed, but it insinuates itself everywhere, silently <strong>and</strong> almost invisibly,<br />

because it does not manifest itself through its own products, but rather through<br />

its ways of using the products imposed by a dominant economic order’ (546). For de<br />

Certeau, the cultural field is a site of continual conflict (silent <strong>and</strong> almost invisibly)<br />

between the ‘strategy’ of cultural imposition (production) <strong>and</strong> the ‘tactics’ of cultural<br />

use (consumption or ‘secondary production’). The cultural critic must be alert to<br />

‘the difference or similarity between . . . production . . . <strong>and</strong> . . . secondary production<br />

hidden in the process of . . . utilisation’ (547). 51 He characterizes the active consumption<br />

of texts as ‘poaching’: ‘readers are travellers; they move across l<strong>and</strong>s belonging to<br />

someone else, like nomads poaching their way across the fields they did not write’<br />

(1984: 174).<br />

The idea of reading as poaching is clearly a rejection of any theoretical position that<br />

assumes that the ‘message’ of a text is something which is imposed on a reader. Such<br />

approaches, he argues, are based on a fundamental misunderst<strong>and</strong>ing of the processes<br />

of consumption. It is a ‘misunderst<strong>and</strong>ing [which] assumes that “assimilating” necessarily,<br />

means “becoming similar to” what one absorbs, <strong>and</strong> not “making something<br />

similar” to what one is, making it one’s own, appropriating or reappropriating it’ (166).<br />

Acts of textual poaching are always in potential conflict with the ‘scriptural economy’<br />

(131–76) of textual producers <strong>and</strong> those institutional voices (professional critics,<br />

academics, etc.) who, through an insistence on the authority of authorial <strong>and</strong>/or textual<br />

meaning, work to limit <strong>and</strong> to confine the production <strong>and</strong> circulation of ‘unauthorized’<br />

meanings. In this way, de Certeau’s notion of ‘poaching’ is a challenge to<br />

traditional models of reading, in which the purpose of reading is the passive reception<br />

of authorial <strong>and</strong>/or textual intent: that is, models of reading in which reading is<br />

reduced to a question of being ‘right’ or ‘wrong’. He makes an interesting observation<br />

about how the notion of a text containing a hidden meaning may help sustain certain<br />

relationships of power in matters of pedagogy:<br />

This fiction condemns consumers to subjection because they are always going to<br />

be guilty of infidelity or ignorance when confronted by the mute ‘riches’ of the treasury.<br />

. . . The fiction of the ‘treasury’ hidden in the work, a sort of strong-box full<br />

of meaning, is obviously not based on the productivity of the reader, but on the<br />

social institution that overdetermines his relation with the text. Reading is as it<br />

were overprinted by a relationship of forces (between teachers <strong>and</strong> pupils ...)<br />

whose instrument it becomes (171).<br />

This may in turn produce a teaching practice in which ‘students . . . are scornfully<br />

driven back or cleverly coaxed back to the meaning “accepted” by their teachers’<br />

(172). 52 This is often informed by what we might call ‘textual determinism’: 53 the view<br />

that the value of something is inherent in the thing itself. This position can lead to<br />

a way of working in which certain texts <strong>and</strong> practices are prejudged to be beneath


The cultural field 223<br />

the legitimate concerns of the academic gaze. Against this way of thinking, I would<br />

contend that what really matters is not the object of study, but how the object is<br />

studied.<br />

Many areas of everyday life could be said to illustrate de Certeau’s account of the<br />

practice of consumption but perhaps none more so than the consumption practices of<br />

fan cultures. Together with youth subcultures, fans are perhaps the most visible part of<br />

the audience for popular texts <strong>and</strong> practices. In recent years f<strong>and</strong>om has come increasingly<br />

under the critical gaze of cultural studies. Traditionally, fans have been treated in<br />

one of two ways – ridiculed or pathologized. According to Joli Jenson (1992), ‘The literature<br />

on f<strong>and</strong>om is haunted by images of deviance. The fan is consistently characterised<br />

(referencing the term’s origins) as a potential fanatic. This means that f<strong>and</strong>om<br />

is seen as excessive, bordering on deranged, behaviour’ (9). Jenson suggests two typical<br />

types of fan pathology, ‘the obsessed individual’ (usually male) <strong>and</strong> ‘the hysterical<br />

crowd’ (usually female). She contends that both figures result from a particular reading<br />

<strong>and</strong> ‘unacknowledged critique of modernity’, in which fans are viewed ‘as a psychological<br />

symptom of a presumed social dysfunction’ (ibid.). Fans are presented as<br />

one of the dangerous ‘others’ of modern life. ‘We’ are sane <strong>and</strong> respectable; ‘they’ are<br />

either obsessed or hysterical.<br />

This is yet another discourse on other people. F<strong>and</strong>om is what ‘other people’ do.<br />

This can be seen clearly in the way in which f<strong>and</strong>om is assigned to the cultural activities<br />

of popular audiences, whilst dominant groups are said to have cultural interests,<br />

tastes <strong>and</strong> preferences. Moreover, as Jenson points out, this is a discourse that seeks to<br />

secure <strong>and</strong> police distinctions between class cultures. This is supposedly confirmed by<br />

the object(s) of admiration which mark off the tastes of dominant groups from those<br />

of popular audiences, 54 but it is also supposedly sustained by the methods of appreciation<br />

– popular audiences are said to display their pleasure to emotional excess,<br />

whereas the audience for dominant culture is always able to maintain respectable<br />

aesthetic distance <strong>and</strong> control. 55<br />

Perhaps one of the most interesting accounts of a fan culture from within cultural<br />

studies is Henry Jenkins’s (1992) Textual Poachers. In an ethnographic investigation<br />

of a fan community (mostly, but not exclusively, white middle-class women), he<br />

approaches f<strong>and</strong>om as ‘both . . . an academic (who has access to certain theories of<br />

popular culture, certain bodies of critical <strong>and</strong> ethnographic literature) <strong>and</strong> as a fan<br />

(who has access to the particular knowledge <strong>and</strong> traditions of that community)’ (5).<br />

Fan reading is characterized by an intensity of intellectual <strong>and</strong> emotional involvement.<br />

‘The text is drawn close not so that the fan can be possessed by it but rather so<br />

that the fan may more fully possess it. Only by integrating media content back into<br />

their everyday lives, only by close engagement with its meanings <strong>and</strong> materials, can<br />

fans fully consume the fiction <strong>and</strong> make it an active resource’ (62). Arguing against textual<br />

determinism (the text determines how it will be read <strong>and</strong> in so doing positions the<br />

reader in a particular ideological discourse), he insists that ‘[t]he reader is drawn not<br />

into the preconstituted world of the fiction but rather into a world she has created from<br />

textual materials. Here, the reader’s pre-established values are at least as important as<br />

those preferred by the narrative system’ (63).


224<br />

Chapter 10 The politics of the popular<br />

Fans do not just read texts, they continually reread them. This changes profoundly<br />

the nature of the text–reader relationship. Rereading undermines the operations of<br />

what Barthes (1975) calls the ‘hermeneutic code’ (the way a text poses questions to<br />

generate the desire to keep reading). Rereading in this way thus shifts the reader’s attention<br />

from ‘what will happen’ to ‘how things happen’, to questions of character relations,<br />

narrative themes, the production of social knowledges <strong>and</strong> discourses.<br />

Whereas most reading is a solitary practice, performed in private, fans consume texts<br />

as part of a community. Fan culture is about the public display <strong>and</strong> circulation of<br />

meaning production <strong>and</strong> reading practices. Fans make meanings to communicate with<br />

other fans. The public display <strong>and</strong> circulation of these meanings are crucial to a fan<br />

culture’s reproduction. As Jenkins explains, ‘Organised f<strong>and</strong>om is, perhaps first <strong>and</strong><br />

foremost, an institution of theory <strong>and</strong> criticism, a semistructured space where competing<br />

interpretations <strong>and</strong> evaluations of common texts are proposed, debated, <strong>and</strong><br />

negotiated <strong>and</strong> where readers speculate about the nature of the mass media <strong>and</strong> their<br />

own relationship to it’ (86).<br />

Fan cultures are not just bodies of enthusiastic readers; they are also active cultural<br />

producers. Jenkins notes ten ways in which fans rewrite their favourite television shows<br />

(162–77):<br />

1. Recontextualization – the production of vignettes, short stories <strong>and</strong> novels which<br />

seek to fill in the gaps in broadcast narratives <strong>and</strong> suggest additional explanations<br />

for particular actions.<br />

2. Exp<strong>and</strong>ing the series timeline – the production of vignettes, short stories, novels<br />

which provide background history of characters, etc., not explored in broadcast<br />

narratives or suggestions for future developments beyond the period covered by<br />

the broadcast narrative.<br />

3. Refocalization – this occurs when fan writers move the focus of attention from the<br />

main protagonists to secondary figures. For example, female or black characters<br />

are taken from the margins of a text <strong>and</strong> given centre stage.<br />

4. Moral realignment – a version of refocalization in which the moral order of the<br />

broadcast narrative is inverted (the villains become the good guys). In some versions<br />

the moral order remains the same but the story is now told from the point<br />

of view of the villains.<br />

5. Genre shifting – characters from broadcast science fiction narratives, say, are relocated<br />

in the realms of romance or the Western, for example.<br />

6. Cross-overs – characters from one television programme are introduced into<br />

another. For example, characters from Doctor Who may appear in the same narrative<br />

as characters from Star Wars.<br />

7. Character dislocation – characters are relocated in new narrative situations, with<br />

new names <strong>and</strong> new identities.<br />

8. Personalization – the insertion of the writer into a version of their favourite television<br />

programme. For example, I could write a short story in which I am recruited<br />

by Doctor Who to travel with him in the Tardis on a mission to explore what has<br />

become of Manchester United in the twenty-fourth century. However, as Jenkins


The cultural field 225<br />

points out, many in the fan culture discourage this subgenre of fan writing.<br />

9. Emotional intensification – the production of what are called ‘hurt-comfort’ stories<br />

in which favourite characters, for example, experience emotional crises.<br />

10. Eroticization – stories that explore the erotic side of a character’s life. Perhaps the<br />

best known of this subgenre of fan writing is ‘slash’ fiction, so called because it<br />

depicts same-sex relationships (as in Kirk/Spock, etc.).<br />

In addition to fan fiction, fans make music videos in which images from favourite<br />

programmes are edited into new sequences to a soundtrack provided by a popular<br />

song; they make fan art; they produce fanzines; they engage in ‘filking’ (the writing <strong>and</strong><br />

performing at conferences of songs – filk songs – about programmes, characters or the<br />

fan culture itself); <strong>and</strong> they organize campaigns to encourage television networks to<br />

bring back favourite programmes or to make changes in existing ones. 56 As Jenkins<br />

points out, echoing de Certeau, ‘Fans are poachers who get to keep what they take <strong>and</strong><br />

use their plundered goods as the foundations for the construction of an alternative cultural<br />

community’ (223).<br />

In his discussion of filking, Jenkins draws attention to a common opposition within<br />

filk songs between f<strong>and</strong>om <strong>and</strong> ‘Mundania’ (the world in which non-fans – ‘mundane<br />

readers’ or ‘mundanes’ – live). The difference between the two worlds is not simply one<br />

of intensity of response: ‘Fans are defined in opposition to the values <strong>and</strong> norms of<br />

everyday life, as people who live more richly, feel more intensely, play more freely, <strong>and</strong><br />

think more deeply than “mundanes”’ (268). Moreover, ‘F<strong>and</strong>om constitutes ...a<br />

space . . . defined by its refusal of mundane values <strong>and</strong> practices, its celebration of<br />

deeply held emotions <strong>and</strong> passionately embraced pleasures. F<strong>and</strong>om’s very existence<br />

represents a critique of conventional forms of consumer culture’ (283).<br />

What he finds particularly empowering about fan cultures is their struggle to create<br />

‘a more participatory culture’ from ‘the very forces that transform many Americans into<br />

spectators’ (284). It is not the commodities that are empowering, it is what the fans do<br />

with them that empowers. As Jenkins explains,<br />

I am not claiming that there is anything particularly empowering about the texts<br />

fans embrace. I am, however, claiming that there is something empowering about<br />

what fans do with those texts in the process of assimilating them to the particulars<br />

of their lives. F<strong>and</strong>om celebrates not exceptional texts but rather exceptional readings<br />

(though its interpretive practices make it impossible to maintain a clear or precise<br />

distinction between the two) (ibid.).<br />

In a way reminiscent of the classic cultural studies model of subcultural reading, fan<br />

cultures, according to Jenkins, struggle to resist the dem<strong>and</strong>s of the ordinary <strong>and</strong> the<br />

everyday. Whereas youth subcultures define themselves against parent <strong>and</strong> dominant<br />

cultures, fan cultures define themselves in opposition to the supposed everyday cultural<br />

passivities of ‘Mundania’.<br />

Grossberg (1992) is critical of the ‘subcultural’ model of fan cultures, in which ‘fans<br />

constitute an elite fraction of the larger audience of passive consumers’ (52).


226<br />

Chapter 10 The politics of the popular<br />

Thus, the fan is always in constant conflict, not only with the various structures of<br />

power, but also with the vast audience of media consumers. But such an elitist view<br />

of f<strong>and</strong>om does little to illuminate the complex relations that exist between forms<br />

of popular culture <strong>and</strong> their audiences. While we may all agree that there is a difference<br />

between the fan <strong>and</strong> the consumer, we are unlikely to underst<strong>and</strong> the<br />

difference if we simply celebrate the former category <strong>and</strong> dismiss the latter one<br />

(ibid.).<br />

In a similar way, subcultural analysis has always tended to celebrate the extraordinary<br />

against the ordinary – a binary opposition between resistant ‘style’ <strong>and</strong> conformist<br />

‘fashion’. Subcultures represent youth in resistance, actively refusing to conform to the<br />

passive commercial tastes of the majority of youth. Once resistance has given way to<br />

incorporation, analysis stops, waiting for the next ‘great refusal’. Gary Clarke (1990)<br />

draws attention to the London-centredness of much British subcultural theory, with<br />

its suggestion that the appearance of a given youth subculture in the provinces is a<br />

telling sign of its incorporation. It is not surprising, then, that he also detects a certain<br />

level of cultural elitism structuring much of the classic cultural studies work on youth<br />

subcultures.<br />

I would argue generally that the subcultural literature’s focus on the stylistic<br />

deviance of a few contains (albeit implicitly) a similar treatment of the rest of the<br />

working class as unproblematically incorporated. This is evident, for example, in<br />

the distaste felt for youth deemed as outside subcultural activity – even though most<br />

‘straight’ working-class youths enjoy the same music, styles, <strong>and</strong> activities as the<br />

subcultures – <strong>and</strong> in the disdain for such cults as glam, disco, <strong>and</strong> the Ted revival,<br />

which lack ‘authenticity’. Indeed, there seems to be an underlying contempt for<br />

‘mass culture’ (which stimulates the interest in those who deviate from it) that<br />

stems from the work of the Marxism of the Frankfurt School <strong>and</strong>, within the<br />

English tradition, to the fear of mass culture expressed in The Uses of Literacy (90).<br />

If subcultural consumption is to remain an area of concern in cultural studies,<br />

Clarke suggests that future analysis ‘should take the breakthrough of a style as its starting<br />

point’ (92), rather than seeing this as the defining moment of incorporation. Better<br />

still, cultural studies should focus on ‘the activities of all youths to locate continuities<br />

<strong>and</strong> discontinuities in culture <strong>and</strong> social relations <strong>and</strong> to discover the meaning these<br />

activities have for the youths themselves’ (95).<br />

The economic field<br />

McGuigan (1992) claims, as I observed earlier, that ‘the separation of contemporary<br />

cultural studies from the political economy of culture has been one of the most


The economic field 227<br />

disabling features of the field of study’ (40). So what can political economy offer to<br />

cultural studies? 57 Here is Peter Golding <strong>and</strong> Graham Murdock’s (1991) outline of its<br />

protocols <strong>and</strong> procedures:<br />

What distinguishes the critical political economy perspective . . . is precisely its<br />

focus on the interplay between the symbolic <strong>and</strong> economic dimensions of public<br />

communications [including popular culture]. It sets out to show how different<br />

ways of financing <strong>and</strong> organising cultural production have traceable consequences<br />

for the range of discourses <strong>and</strong> representations in the public domain <strong>and</strong> for audiences’<br />

access to them (15; my italics).<br />

The significant word here is ‘access’ (privileged over ‘use’ <strong>and</strong> ‘meaning’). This reveals<br />

the limitations of the approach: good on the economic dimensions but weak on the<br />

symbolic. Golding <strong>and</strong> Murdock suggest that the work of theorists such as Willis <strong>and</strong><br />

Fiske in its ‘romantic celebration of subversive consumption is clearly at odds with<br />

cultural studies’ long-st<strong>and</strong>ing concern with the way the mass media operate ideologically,<br />

to sustain <strong>and</strong> support prevailing relations of domination’ (17). What is<br />

particularly revealing about this claim is not the critique of Willis <strong>and</strong> Fiske, but the<br />

assumptions about the purposes of cultural studies. They seem to be suggesting that<br />

unless the focus is firmly <strong>and</strong> exclusively on domination <strong>and</strong> manipulation, cultural<br />

studies is failing in its task. There are only two positions: on the one h<strong>and</strong>, romantic<br />

celebration, <strong>and</strong> on the other, the recognition of ideological power – <strong>and</strong> only the second<br />

is a serious scholarly pursuit. Are all attempts to show people resisting ideological<br />

manipulation forms of romantic celebration? Are left pessimism <strong>and</strong> moral leftism the<br />

only guarantees of political <strong>and</strong> scholarly seriousness?<br />

Political economy’s idea of cultural analysis seems to involve little more than<br />

detailing access to, <strong>and</strong> availability of, texts <strong>and</strong> practices. Nowhere do they actually<br />

advocate a consideration of what these texts <strong>and</strong> practices might mean (textually) or be<br />

made to mean in use (consumption). As Golding <strong>and</strong> Murdock point out,<br />

in contrast to recent work on audience activity within cultural studies, which concentrates<br />

on the negotiation of textual interpretations <strong>and</strong> media use in immediate<br />

social settings, critical political economy seeks to relate variations in people’s<br />

responses to their overall location in the economic system (27).<br />

This seems to suggest that the specific materiality of a text is unimportant, <strong>and</strong> that<br />

audience negotiations are mere fictions, illusory moves in a game of economic power.<br />

Whilst it is clearly important to locate the texts <strong>and</strong> practices of popular culture<br />

within the field of their economic conditions of existence, it is clearly insufficient to do<br />

this in the way advocated by political economy <strong>and</strong> to think then that you have also<br />

analysed <strong>and</strong> answered important questions to do with both the specific materiality of<br />

a text, <strong>and</strong> audience appropriation <strong>and</strong> use. It seems to me that post-Marxist hegemony<br />

theory still holds the promise of keeping in active relationship production, text <strong>and</strong><br />

consumption, whereas political economy threatens, in spite of its admirable intentions,<br />

to collapse everything back into the economic.


228<br />

Chapter 10 The politics of the popular<br />

It is Willis’s attitude to the capitalist market that most offends political economy,<br />

especially his claim that the capitalist drive for profit produces the very conditions for<br />

the production of new forms of common culture.<br />

No other agency has recognised this realm [common culture] or supplied it with<br />

usable symbolic materials. And commercial entrepreneurship of the cultural field<br />

has discovered something real. For whatever self-serving reasons it was accomplished,<br />

we believe that this is an historical recognition. It counts <strong>and</strong> is irreversible.<br />

Commercial cultural forms have helped to produce an historical present<br />

from which we cannot now escape <strong>and</strong> in which there are many more materials –<br />

no matter what we think of them – available for necessary symbolic work than ever<br />

there were in the past. Out of these come forms not dreamt of in the commercial<br />

imagination <strong>and</strong> certainly not in the official one – forms which make up common<br />

culture (1990: 19).<br />

Capitalism is not a monolithic system. Like any ‘structure’ it is contradictory in that<br />

it both constrains <strong>and</strong> enables ‘agency’. For example, whilst one capitalist bemoans the<br />

activities of the latest youth subculture, another embraces it with economic enthusiasm,<br />

<strong>and</strong> is prepared to supply it with all the commodities it is able to desire. It is these,<br />

<strong>and</strong> similar, contradictions in the capitalist market system which have produced the<br />

possibility of a common culture.<br />

Commerce <strong>and</strong> consumerism have helped to release a profane explosion of everyday<br />

symbolic life <strong>and</strong> activity. The genie of common culture is out of the bottle –<br />

let out by commercial carelessness. Not stuffing it back in, but seeing what wishes<br />

may be granted, should be the stuff of our imagination (27).<br />

This entails what Willis knows will be anathema for many, not least the advocates of<br />

political economy, the suggestion of ‘the possibility of cultural emancipation working,<br />

at least in part, through ordinary, hitherto uncongenial economic mechanisms’ (131).<br />

Although it may not be entirely clear what is intended by ‘cultural emancipation’,<br />

beyond, that is, the claim that it entails a break with the hegemonic exclusions of<br />

‘official culture’. What is clear, however, <strong>and</strong> remains anathema to political economy,<br />

is that he sees the market, in part, because of its contradictions – ‘supplying materials<br />

for its own critique’ (139) – <strong>and</strong> despite its intentions <strong>and</strong> its distortions, as facilitating<br />

the symbolic creativity of the realm of common culture.<br />

People find on the market incentives <strong>and</strong> possibilities not simply for their own<br />

confinement but also for their own development <strong>and</strong> growth. Though turned<br />

inside out, alienated <strong>and</strong> working through exploitation at every turn, these incentives<br />

<strong>and</strong> possibilities promise more than any visible alternative. . . . Nor will it<br />

suffice any longer in the face of grounded aesthetics to say that modern ‘consumer<br />

identities’ simply repeat ‘inscribed positions’ within market provided texts <strong>and</strong><br />

artefacts. Of course the market does not provide cultural empowerment in


The economic field 229<br />

anything like a full sense. There are choices, but not choices over choices – the<br />

power to set the cultural agenda. Nevertheless the market offers a contradictory<br />

empowerment which has not been offered elsewhere. It may not be the best way<br />

to cultural emancipation for the majority, but it may open up the way to a better way<br />

(160; my italics).<br />

Like capitalism, the culture industries, which supply the commodities from which<br />

people make culture, are themselves not monolithic <strong>and</strong> non-contradictory. From the<br />

very first of the culture industries, nineteenth-century stage melodrama, to perhaps one<br />

of the most powerful in the twentieth century, pop music, cultural commodities have<br />

been ‘articulated’ in ways which ‘may open the way to a better future’. For example,<br />

Figure 10.1 is a poster for a benefit organized at the Queen’s Theatre (a commercial<br />

site established to sell commodified entertainment) in Manchester. The poster shows<br />

how the theatre had given itself over (or had been taken over) for a benefit performance<br />

in support of bookbinders striking in London. 58 Another significant example<br />

is the fact that Nelson M<strong>and</strong>ela’s first major public appearance, following his release in<br />

1990, was to attend a concert to thank a pop music audience (consumers of the commodified<br />

practice that is pop music) because they ‘chose to care’. 59 Both examples challenge<br />

the idea that capitalism <strong>and</strong> the capitalist culture industries are monolithic <strong>and</strong><br />

non-contradictory.<br />

Willis also makes the point that it is crude <strong>and</strong> simplistic to assume that the effects<br />

of consumption must mirror the intentions of production. As Terry Lovell (2009)<br />

points out, drawing on the work of Marx (1976c), the capitalist commodity has a<br />

double existence, as both use value <strong>and</strong> exchange value. Use value refers to ‘the ability<br />

of the commodity to satisfy some human want’ (539). Such wants, says Marx, ‘may<br />

spring from the stomach or from the fancy’ (ibid.). The exchange value of a commodity<br />

is the amount of money realized when the commodity is sold in the market. Crucial<br />

to Willis’s argument is the fact, as pointed out by Lovell, that ‘the use value of a commodity<br />

cannot be known in advance of investigation of actual use of the commodity’<br />

(540). Moreover, as Lovell indicates, the commodities from which popular culture is<br />

made<br />

have different use values for the individuals who use <strong>and</strong> purchase them than they<br />

have for the capitalists who produce <strong>and</strong> sell them, <strong>and</strong> in turn, for capitalism as<br />

a whole. We may assume that people do not purchase these cultural artefacts<br />

in order to expose themselves to bourgeois ideology . . . but to satisfy a variety of<br />

different wants which can only be guessed at in the absence of analysis <strong>and</strong> investigation.<br />

There is no guarantee that the use-value of the cultural object for its purchaser<br />

will even be compatible with its utility to capitalism as bourgeois ideology<br />

(542).<br />

Almost everything we buy helps reproduce the capitalist system economically.<br />

But everything we buy does not necessarily help secure us as ‘subjects’ of capitalist<br />

ideology. If, for example, I go to an anti-capitalist demonstration, my travel, food,


230<br />

Chapter 10 The politics of the popular<br />

Figure 10.1 For the benefit of striking bookbinders.


The economic field 231<br />

accommodation, clothing, etc., all contribute to the reproduction of the system I would<br />

like to overthrow. Therefore, although most of, if not all, my consumption is ‘capitalist’,<br />

this does not prevent me from being anti-capitalist. There is always a potential contradiction<br />

between exchange value <strong>and</strong> use value.<br />

The primary concern of capitalist production is exchange value leading to surplus<br />

value (profit). This does not mean, of course, that capitalism is uninterested in use<br />

value: without use value, commodities would not sell (so every effort is made to stimulate<br />

dem<strong>and</strong>). But it does mean that the individual capitalist’s search for surplus value<br />

can often be at the expense of the general ideological needs of the system as a whole.<br />

Marx was more aware than most of the contradictions in the capitalist system. In a discussion<br />

of the dem<strong>and</strong>s of capitalists that workers should save in order to better endure<br />

the fluctuations of boom <strong>and</strong> slump, he points to the tension that may exist between<br />

‘worker as producer’ <strong>and</strong> ‘worker as consumer’:<br />

each capitalist does dem<strong>and</strong> that his workers should save, but only his own,<br />

because they st<strong>and</strong> towards him as workers; but by no means the remaining world<br />

of workers, for these st<strong>and</strong> towards him as consumers. In spite of all ‘pious’<br />

speeches he therefore searches for means to spur them on to consumption, to give<br />

his wares new charms, to inspire them with new needs by constant chatter, etc.<br />

(Marx, 1973: 287).<br />

The situation is further complicated by tensions between particular capitals <strong>and</strong> capitalism<br />

as a whole. Common class interests – unless specific restraints, censorship, etc.,<br />

are imposed – usually take second place to the interests of particular capitals in search<br />

of surplus value.<br />

If surplus value can be extracted from the production of cultural commodities<br />

which challenge, or even subvert, the dominant ideology, then all other things<br />

being equal it is in the interests of particular capitals to invest in the production of<br />

such commodities. Unless collective class restraints are exercised, the individual<br />

capitalist’s pursuit of surplus value may lead to forms of cultural production which<br />

are against the interests of capitalism as a whole (Lovell, 2009: 542–3).<br />

To explore this possibility would require specific focus on consumption as opposed to<br />

production. This is not to deny the claim of political economy that a full analysis must<br />

take into account technological <strong>and</strong> economic determinations. But it is to insist that if<br />

our focus is consumption, then our focus must be consumption as it is experienced <strong>and</strong><br />

not as it should be experienced given a prior analysis of the relations of production.<br />

Those on the moral <strong>and</strong> pessimistic left who attack the capitalist relations of consumption<br />

miss the point: it is the capitalist relations of production that are oppressive<br />

<strong>and</strong> exploitative <strong>and</strong> not the consumer choice facilitated by the capitalist market. This<br />

also seems to be Willis’s point. Moral leftists <strong>and</strong> left pessimists have allowed themselves<br />

to become trapped in an elitist <strong>and</strong> reactionary argument that claims more<br />

(quantity) always means less (quality).


232<br />

Chapter 10 The politics of the popular<br />

It is important to distinguish between the power of the culture industries <strong>and</strong> the<br />

power of their influence. Too often the two are conflated, but they are not necessarily<br />

the same. The trouble with the political economy approach is that too often it is<br />

assumed that they are the same. Warner Bros is undoubtedly part of a powerful multinational<br />

company, dealing in capitalist commodities. But once this is established, what<br />

next? Does it follow, for example, that all Warner Bros’ products are the bearers of capitalist<br />

ideology? Despite what REM, for example, may say or think to the contrary, are<br />

they really mere purveyors of capitalist ideology? Those who buy their records, pay to<br />

see them live, are they really in effect buying capitalist ideology; being duped by a capitalist<br />

multinational; being reproduced as capitalist subjects, ready to spend more <strong>and</strong><br />

more money <strong>and</strong> consume more <strong>and</strong> more ideology? The problem with this approach<br />

is that it fails to acknowledge fully that capitalism produces commodities on the basis<br />

of their exchange value, whereas people tend to consume the commodities of capitalism<br />

on the basis of their use value. There are two economies running in parallel<br />

courses: the economy of use, <strong>and</strong> the economy of exchange – we do not underst<strong>and</strong><br />

one by interrogating only the other. We cannot underst<strong>and</strong> consumption by collapsing<br />

it into production, nor will we underst<strong>and</strong> production by reading it off consumption.<br />

Of course the difficulty is not in keeping them apart, but in bringing them into a relationship<br />

that can be meaningfully analysed. However, if when studying popular<br />

culture our interest is the repertoire of products available for consumption, then<br />

production is our primary concern, whereas, if we are interested in discovering the particular<br />

pleasures of a specific text or practice, our primary focus should be on consumption.<br />

In both instances, our approach would be determined by the questions we<br />

seek to answer. Although it is certainly true that in an ideal research situation – given<br />

adequate time <strong>and</strong> funding – cultural analysis would remain incomplete until production<br />

<strong>and</strong> consumption had been dialectically linked, in the real world of study this is<br />

not always going to be the case. In the light of this, political economy’s insistence that<br />

it offers the only really valid approach to the study of popular culture is not only<br />

untrue, but, if widely believed, could result in either a reductive distortion, or a complete<br />

stifling, of cultural studies research.<br />

Post-Marxist cultural studies: hegemony revisited<br />

The critique of cultural studies offered by political economy is important not for what<br />

it says but because it draws attention to a question, which, needless to say, it does not<br />

itself answer. The question is how to keep in analytical view the ‘conditions of existence’<br />

of the texts <strong>and</strong> practices of everyday life. The problem with the mode of analysis<br />

advocated by political economy is that it only addresses the beginning of the<br />

process of making culture. What they describe is better understood, to borrow Stuart<br />

Hall’s (1996c) phrase, as ‘determination by the economic in the first instance’ (45).<br />

There are economic conditions, <strong>and</strong> fear of economic reductionism cannot just will


Post-Marxist cultural studies: hegemony revisited 233<br />

them away. However, the point is not simply to detail these conditions, to produce an<br />

underst<strong>and</strong>ing of how these conditions generate a repertoire of commodities; what is<br />

also required is an underst<strong>and</strong>ing of the many ways in which people select, appropriate<br />

<strong>and</strong> use these commodities, <strong>and</strong> make them into culture. In other words, what is<br />

needed is an underst<strong>and</strong>ing of the relationship between ‘structure’ <strong>and</strong> ‘agency’. This<br />

will not be achieved by ab<strong>and</strong>oning one side of the relationship. Hall (1996d) is<br />

undoubtedly right to suggest that a number of people working in cultural studies have<br />

at times turned away from ‘economic’ explanations:<br />

What has resulted from the ab<strong>and</strong>onment of deterministic economism has been,<br />

not alternative ways of thinking questions about the economic relations <strong>and</strong> their<br />

effects, as the ‘conditions of existence’ of other practices . . . but instead a massive,<br />

gigantic, <strong>and</strong> eloquent disavowal. As if, since the economic in the broadest sense,<br />

definitely does not, as it was once supposed to do, ‘determine’ the real movement<br />

of history ‘in the last instance’, it does not exist at all! (258).<br />

Hall describes this as ‘a failure of theorisation so profound, <strong>and</strong> . . . so disabling, that<br />

. . . it has enabled much weaker <strong>and</strong> less conceptually rich paradigms to continue to<br />

flourish <strong>and</strong> dominate the field’ (ibid.). A return there must be to a consideration of<br />

the ‘conditions of existence’, but it cannot be a return to the kind of analysis canvassed<br />

by political economy, in which it is assumed that ‘access’ is the same as appropriation<br />

<strong>and</strong> use, <strong>and</strong> that production tells us all we need to know about textuality <strong>and</strong> consumption.<br />

Nor is it a matter of having to build bridges to political economy; what is<br />

required, as McRobbie <strong>and</strong> others have canvassed, is a return to what has been, since<br />

the 1970s, the most convincing <strong>and</strong> coherent theoretical focus of (British) cultural<br />

studies – hegemony theory.<br />

McRobbie accepts that cultural studies has been radically challenged as debates<br />

about postmodernism <strong>and</strong> postmodernity have replaced the more familiar debates<br />

about ideology <strong>and</strong> hegemony. She argues that it has responded in two ways. On the<br />

one h<strong>and</strong>, there have been those who have advocated a return to the certainties of<br />

Marxism. Whilst on the other, there have been those who have turned to consumption<br />

(understood too exclusively in terms of pleasure <strong>and</strong> meaning-making). In some ways,<br />

as she recognizes, this is almost a rerun of the structuralism/culturalism debate of the<br />

late 1970s <strong>and</strong> early 1980s. It could also be seen as yet another performance of the<br />

playing of one side of Marx’s (1977) dialectic against the other (we are made by history<br />

/ we make history). McRobbie (1994) rejects a return ‘to a crude <strong>and</strong> mechanical<br />

base–superstructure model, <strong>and</strong> also the dangers of pursuing a kind of cultural populism<br />

to a point at which anything which is consumed <strong>and</strong> is popular is also seen as<br />

oppositional’ (39). Instead, she calls for ‘an extension of Gramscian cultural analysis’<br />

(ibid.); <strong>and</strong> for a return to ethnographic cultural analysis which takes as its object of<br />

study ‘the lived experience which breathes life into [the]. . . inanimate objects [the<br />

commodities supplied by the culture industries]’ (27).<br />

Post-Marxist hegemony theory at its best insists that there is always a dialogue<br />

between the processes of production <strong>and</strong> the activities of consumption. The consumer


234<br />

Chapter 10 The politics of the popular<br />

always confronts a text or practice in its material existence as a result of determinate<br />

conditions of production. But in the same way, the text or practice is confronted by a<br />

consumer who in effect produces in use the range of possible meaning(s) – these cannot<br />

just be read off from the materiality of the text or practice, or the means or relations of<br />

its production. 60<br />

The ideology of mass culture<br />

We have to start from here <strong>and</strong> now, <strong>and</strong> acknowledge that we (all of us) live in a world<br />

dominated by multinational capitalism, <strong>and</strong> will do so for the foreseeable future –<br />

‘pessimism of the intelligence, optimism of the will’, as Gramsci said (1971: 175). We<br />

need to see ourselves – all people, not just vanguard intellectuals – as active participants<br />

in culture: selecting, rejecting, making meanings, attributing value, resisting <strong>and</strong>,<br />

yes, being duped <strong>and</strong> manipulated. This does not mean that we forget about ‘the politics<br />

of representation’. What we must do (<strong>and</strong> here I agree with Ang) is see that although<br />

pleasure is political, pleasure <strong>and</strong> politics can often be different. Liking Desperate<br />

Housewives or The Sopranos does not determine my politics, making me more left-wing<br />

or less left-wing. There is pleasure <strong>and</strong> there is politics: we can laugh at the distortions,<br />

the evasions, the disavowals, whilst still promoting a politics that says these are distortions,<br />

evasions, disavowals. We must teach each other to know, to politicize for, to<br />

recognize the difference between different versions of reality, <strong>and</strong> to know that each can<br />

require a different politics. This does not mean the end of a feminist or a socialist cultural<br />

politics, or the end of struggles around the representations of ‘race’, class, gender,<br />

disability or sexuality, but it should mean the final break with the ‘culture <strong>and</strong> civilization’<br />

problematic, with its debilitating insistence that particular patterns of consumption<br />

determine the moral <strong>and</strong> political worth of an individual.<br />

In many ways, this book has been about what Ang calls ‘the ideology of mass culture’.<br />

Against this ideology, I have posed the patterns of pleasure in consumption <strong>and</strong><br />

the consumption of pleasure, aware that I continually run the risk of advocating an<br />

uncritical cultural populism. Ultimately, I have argued that popular culture is what we<br />

make from the commodities <strong>and</strong> commodified practices made available by the culture<br />

industries. To paraphrase what I said in the discussion of post-Marxist cultural studies,<br />

making popular culture (‘production in use’) 61 can be empowering to subordinate <strong>and</strong><br />

resistant to dominant underst<strong>and</strong>ings of the world. But this is not to say that popular<br />

culture is always empowering <strong>and</strong> resistant. To deny the passivity of consumption is<br />

not to deny that sometimes consumption is passive; to deny that the consumers of<br />

popular culture are cultural dupes is not to deny that the culture industries seek to<br />

manipulate. But it is to deny that popular culture is little more than a degraded l<strong>and</strong>scape<br />

of commercial <strong>and</strong> ideological manipulation, imposed from above in order to<br />

make profit <strong>and</strong> secure social control. Post-Marxist cultural studies insists that to decide<br />

these matters requires vigilance <strong>and</strong> attention to the details of production, textuality


<strong>and</strong> consumption. These are not matters that can be decided once <strong>and</strong> for all (outside<br />

the contingencies of history <strong>and</strong> politics) with an elitist glance <strong>and</strong> a condescending<br />

sneer. Nor can they be read off from the moment of production (locating meaning,<br />

pleasure, ideological effect, the probability of incorporation, the possibility of resistance,<br />

in, variously, the intention, the means of production or the production itself):<br />

these are only aspects of the contexts for ‘production in use’; <strong>and</strong> it is, ultimately, in<br />

‘production in use’ that questions of meaning, pleasure, ideological effect, incorporation<br />

or resistance, can be (contingently) decided.<br />

Such an argument will not satisfy those ideologues of mass culture whose voices<br />

seemed to grow suddenly louder, more insistent, during the period of writing the first<br />

edition of this book. I am thinking of the British <strong>and</strong> American media panic about<br />

the threat to high culture’s authority – the debates about dumbing down, ‘political<br />

correctness’ <strong>and</strong> multiculturalism. The canon is wielded like a knife to cut away at<br />

critical thinking. They dismiss with arrogance what most of us call culture. Saying<br />

popular culture (or more usually, mass culture) <strong>and</strong> high culture (or more usually,<br />

just culture) is just another way of saying ‘them’ <strong>and</strong> ‘us’. They speak with the authority<br />

<strong>and</strong> support of a powerful discourse behind them. Those of us who reject this<br />

discourse, recognizing its thinking <strong>and</strong> unthinking elitism, find ourselves often with<br />

only the discursive support of the (often equally disabling) ideology of populism. The<br />

task for new pedagogies of popular culture is to find ways of working which do not<br />

fall victim to the disabling tendencies of, on the one h<strong>and</strong>, a dismissive elitism, <strong>and</strong><br />

on the other, a disarming anti-intellectualism. Although this book has not established<br />

any new ways of working, I hope it has at least mapped the existing approaches in<br />

such a way as to help make future discoveries a real possibility for other students of<br />

popular culture.<br />

Further reading<br />

Further reading 235<br />

Storey, John (ed.), <strong>Cultural</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Popular</strong> <strong>Culture</strong>: A Reader, 4th edition, Harlow:<br />

Pearson Education, 2009. This is the companion volume to this book. It contains<br />

examples of most of the work discussed here. This book <strong>and</strong> the companion Reader<br />

are supported by an interactive website (www.pearsoned.co.uk/storey). The website<br />

has links to other useful sites <strong>and</strong> electronic resources.<br />

Bennett, Tony, <strong>Culture</strong>: A Reformer’s Science, London: Sage, 1998. A collection of essays,<br />

ranging across the recent history <strong>and</strong> practice of cultural studies, by one of the leading<br />

figures in the field.<br />

During, Simon (ed.), The <strong>Cultural</strong> Studies Reader, 2nd edn, London: Routledge, 1999. A<br />

good selection of material from many of the leading figures in the field.<br />

Gilroy, Paul, Grossberg, Lawrence, Hall, Stuart (eds), Without Guarantees: In Honour of<br />

Stuart Hall. An excellent collection of essays engaging with the work of Stuart Hall.


236<br />

Chapter 10 The politics of the popular<br />

Gray, Ann <strong>and</strong> Jim McGuigan (eds), Studying <strong>Culture</strong>: An Introductory Reader, London:<br />

Edward Arnold, 1993. A good selection of material from many of the leading figures<br />

in the field.<br />

Grossberg, Lawrence, Bringing it all Back Home: Essays on <strong>Cultural</strong> Studies, Durham,<br />

North Carolina: Duke University Press, 1997. An excellent collection of theoretical<br />

essays by one of the leading figures in cultural studies.<br />

Grossberg, Lawrence, Dancing in Spite of Myself: Essays on <strong>Popular</strong> <strong>Culture</strong>, Durham,<br />

North Carolina: Duke University Press, 1997. An excellent collection of essays on<br />

popular culture by one of the leading figures in cultural studies.<br />

Grossberg, Lawrence, Cary Nelson <strong>and</strong> Paula Treichler (eds), <strong>Cultural</strong> Studies, London:<br />

Routledge, 1992. The collection consists of forty essays (most followed by discussion).<br />

An excellent introduction to relatively recent debates in cultural studies.<br />

Morley, David <strong>and</strong> Kuan-Hsing Chen (eds), Stuart Hall: Critical Dialogues in <strong>Cultural</strong><br />

Studies, London: Routledge, 1995. This is a brilliant book. It brings together interviews<br />

<strong>and</strong> essays (on <strong>and</strong> by Stuart Hall). Together they weave an image of the past,<br />

present <strong>and</strong> possible future of cultural studies.<br />

Munns, Jessica <strong>and</strong> Gita Rajan, A <strong>Cultural</strong> Studies Reader: History, <strong>Theory</strong>, Practice, New<br />

York: Longman, 1995. Well organized, with a good selection of interesting essays.<br />

Storey, John (ed.), What is <strong>Cultural</strong> Studies? A Reader, London: Edward Arnold, 1996.<br />

An excellent collection of essays that in different ways attempt to answer the question,<br />

‘What is cultural studies?’


Notes<br />

1. For a discussion of Shakespeare as popular culture in nineteenth-century America, see<br />

Lawrence Levine (1988).<br />

2. Slavoj yizek (1991) identifies the retroactive evaluation which fixed film noir’s current status:<br />

‘It started to exist only when it was discovered by French critics in the ’50s (it is no accident<br />

that even in English, the term used to designate this genre is French: film noir). What was, in<br />

America itself, a series of low-budget B-productions of little critical prestige, was miraculously<br />

transformed, through the intervention of the French gaze, into a sublime object of<br />

art, a kind of film pendant to philosophical existentialism. Directors who had in America the<br />

status of skilled craftsmen, at best, became auteurs, each of them staging in his films a unique<br />

tragic vision of the universe’ (112).<br />

3. For a discussion of opera in popular culture, see Storey, 2002a, 2003 <strong>and</strong> 2006.<br />

4. See Storey, 2003 <strong>and</strong> 2005.<br />

5. John Docker (1994) refers to her as ‘an old-style colonialist ethnographer, staring with distaste<br />

at the barbaric ways of strange <strong>and</strong> unknown people’ (25).<br />

6. It is not just that F.R. Leavis offers us an idealized account of the past, which he does; he actually<br />

idealizes Bourne’s own account, failing to mention his criticisms of rural life.<br />

7. It should be noted, contrary to van den Haag, that Freud is referring to all art, <strong>and</strong> not just<br />

popular culture.<br />

8. For another excellent example of ‘history from below’, see Chauncey (1994). As Chauncey<br />

explains, ‘As my focus on street-level policing of gender suggests, another of the underlying<br />

arguments of this book is that histories of homosexuality – <strong>and</strong> sex <strong>and</strong> sexuality more generally<br />

– have suffered from their overreliance on the discourse of the elite. The most powerful<br />

elements of American society devised the official maps of the culture. . . . While this book<br />

pays those maps their due, it is more interested in reconstructing the maps etched in the city<br />

streets by daily habit, the paths that guided men’s practices even if they were never published<br />

or otherwise formalized. . . . This book seeks to analyze . . . the changing representation of<br />

homosexuality in popular culture <strong>and</strong> the street-level social practices <strong>and</strong> dynamics that<br />

shaped the ways homosexually active men were labelled, understood themselves, <strong>and</strong> interacted<br />

with others’ (26–7).<br />

9. I remember at secondary school a teacher who encouraged us to bring to music lessons our<br />

records by The Beatles, Dylan <strong>and</strong> The Stones. The class would always end the same way –<br />

he would try to convince us of the fundamental error of our adolescent musical taste.<br />

10. See Storey (1992).<br />

11. See New Left Review (1977).<br />

12. See Stedman Jones (1998).<br />

13. See Storey (1985).<br />

14. ‘We Can Be Together’, from the album Volunteers (1969).<br />

15. See Storey (2009).


238<br />

Notes<br />

16. The film Human Nature presents a very funny staging of this idea. Freud (1985) uses the<br />

volcanic irruption at Pompeii in AD 55 as a means to explain repression <strong>and</strong> how to undo its<br />

work: ‘There is, in fact, no better analogy for repression, by which something in the mind is<br />

at once made inaccessible <strong>and</strong> preserved, than burial of the sort to which Pompeii fell a<br />

victim <strong>and</strong> from which it could emerge once more through the work of spades’ (65).<br />

17. In the original German, ego, super-ego <strong>and</strong> id are Ich (I), über-Ich (over-I) <strong>and</strong> es (it).<br />

18. The manner in which Freud discusses the girl’s experience of the Oedipus complex, especially<br />

the language he uses, seems to suggest that a real underst<strong>and</strong>ing of the process was not very<br />

important to him.<br />

19. It should also be noted that Freud (1977) believed there were two ways to navigate the<br />

Oedipus complex: ‘positive’, which resulted in heterosexuality, <strong>and</strong> ‘negative’, which produces<br />

homosexuality. A boy may ‘take the place of his mother <strong>and</strong> be loved by his father’ (318).<br />

20. ‘As a witty poet remarks so rightly, the mirror would do well to reflect a little more before<br />

returning our image to us’ (Lacan, 1989: 152).<br />

21. For Brechtian aesthetics, see Brecht (1978).<br />

22. Barthes’s ‘Myth today’ <strong>and</strong> Williams’s ‘The analysis of culture’ are two of the founding texts<br />

of British cultural studies.<br />

23. Barthes’s formulation is remarkably similar to the concept of ‘interpellation’ developed by<br />

Louis Althusser some years later (see discussion in Chapter 4).<br />

24. Myth works in much the same way as Foucault’s concept of power; it is productive (see later<br />

in this chapter).<br />

25. See hyperlink: http://news.bbc.co.uk/1/hi/uk/6108496.stm<br />

26. If you enter Jeremy Kyle in the search engine on YouTube you will find Jon Culshaw’s wonderful<br />

parody. Culshaw quite brilliantly captures the agression, the discourse of social class<br />

<strong>and</strong> the smug self-satisfaction of this type of programme.<br />

27. Mulvey’s essay has been anthologized at least ten times.<br />

28. Based on a diagram in Dyer (1999: 376).<br />

29. Charlotte Lamb, originally in The Guardian, 13 September 1982 (quoted in Coward, 1984: 190).<br />

30. Janice Radway finds this figure implausible.<br />

31. In similar fashion, it may be the case that reading Enid Blyton’s Secret Seven books as a child<br />

– with their imperative of collective action – prepared the ground for my commitment to<br />

socialism as an adult.<br />

32. See Bennett (1983) <strong>and</strong> Storey (1992).<br />

33. Antony died in December 1999. I knew him both as a teacher <strong>and</strong> as a colleague. Although<br />

I often disagreed with him, his influence on my work (<strong>and</strong> on the work of others) has been<br />

considerable.<br />

34. Butler (1999) uses the term ‘heterosexual matrix’ ‘to designate that grid of cultural intelligibility<br />

through which bodies, genders, <strong>and</strong> desires are naturalized. ...[This is] a hegemonic<br />

discursive/epistemic model of gender intelligibility that assumes that for bodies to cohere<br />

<strong>and</strong> make sense there must be a stable sex expressed through a stable gender (masculine<br />

expresses male, feminine expresses female) that is oppositionally <strong>and</strong> hierarchically defined<br />

through the compulsory practice of heterosexuality’ (194).<br />

35. Esther Newton (1999), whose work on drag is used by Butler, makes the point that ‘children<br />

learn sex-role identity before they learn any strictly sexual object choices. In other words,<br />

I think that children learn they are boys or girls before they are made to underst<strong>and</strong> that<br />

boys only love girls <strong>and</strong> vice versa’ (108). Harold Beaver (1999) writes, ‘What is “natural” is<br />

neither heterosexual nor homosexual desire but simply desire. . . . Desire is like the pull of a<br />

gravitational field, the magnet that draws body to body’ (161).


36. As Newton (1972) explains, ‘if sex-role behaviour can be achieved by the “wrong” sex, it<br />

logically follows that it is in reality also achieved, not inherited, by the “right” sex’ (103).<br />

37. ‘(You Make Me Feel Like) A Natural Woman’ was written by Gerry Goffin, Carole King, <strong>and</strong><br />

Jerry Wexler. Carole King’s recording of the song is on her album Tapestry. Aretha Franklin’s<br />

version is on her Greatest Hits album.<br />

38. Hume is referring to Francis Williams, who graduated from Cambridge University with a<br />

degree in mathematics.<br />

39. For a fuller version of this argument, see Storey (2002b).<br />

40. The rise of religious fundamentalism is difficult to locate in Lyotard’s postmodern condition.<br />

41. For a critical introduction to the Enlightenment, see Porter (1990).<br />

42. See Ricoeur (1981).<br />

43. In the eighteenth-century opera, pastiche was a very common practice. See Storey (2006).<br />

44. The expansion of the market in DVD ‘box sets’ has undoubtedly contributed to this development.<br />

45. See Easthope (1991), Connor (1992) <strong>and</strong> the debate on value between Easthope <strong>and</strong><br />

Connor in Textual Practice, 4 (3), 1990 <strong>and</strong> 5 (3), 1991. See also Frow (1995).<br />

46. See Thomkins (1985) <strong>and</strong> Smith (1988).<br />

47. The Four Tops, ‘It’s The Same Old Song’, Four Tops Motown Greatest Hits, Motown Record<br />

Company.<br />

48. See Storey (2003).<br />

49. What McGuigan calls neo-Gramscian I prefer to call post-Marxist.<br />

50. Operating in a slightly different register, but making the same point, two friends at the university<br />

where I work, who, to be fair, have had to endure much mocking with regard to their<br />

long-term devotion to Doctor Who, have recently shown signs of resentment at the apparent new<br />

popularity of the TV series. It would seem that the new democracy of enjoyment threatens<br />

their, admittedly embattled, ‘ownership’ of all things Doctor Who.<br />

51. Here is an example of the ‘tactics’ of secondary production: Although my parents always<br />

voted for the Labour Party, for many years at elections they invariably voted separately. The<br />

reason is that my father always accepted a lift to the polling station in a large grey Bentley<br />

driven by a Conservative member of the local council. My mother, born <strong>and</strong> brought up in<br />

a mining village in the Durham coalfield, who had lived through the bitter aftermath of the<br />

General Strike of 1926, refused to even countenance the prospect of riding in a Tory’s Bentley<br />

– ‘I would not be seen dead in that car.’ My father, who had grown up amidst the general<br />

hardship of life in the part of urban Salford depicted so well in Walter Greenwood’s Love on<br />

the Dole, always responded in the same way: he would insist that there was much humour to<br />

be had from being driven by a Tory to vote Labour.<br />

52. Andy Medhurst (1999) describes this way of teaching, quite accurately I think, as the ‘missionary<br />

imposition’ (98).<br />

53. See Storey (1999a).<br />

54. Jenson (1992: 19–20) argues convincingly that it is possible to be a fan of James Joyce in<br />

much the same way as it is possible to be a fan of Barry Manilow.<br />

55. Audiences for classical music <strong>and</strong> opera had to learn the aesthetic mode of consumption. See<br />

Storey (2006).<br />

56. See Perryman (2009) for a discussion of how Doctor Who fans helped to bring back the programme<br />

to television.<br />

57. For an informed <strong>and</strong> polemical debate between cultural studies <strong>and</strong> the political economy<br />

of culture, see Critical Studies in Mass Communication, 12, 1995. See also ‘Part Seven’ of<br />

<strong>Cultural</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Popular</strong> <strong>Culture</strong>: A Reader, 4th edn, edited by John Storey, Harlow: Pearson<br />

Education, 2009.<br />

Notes 239


240<br />

Notes<br />

58. See Storey (1992).<br />

59. See Storey (1994).<br />

60. The ‘circuit of culture’ model developed by Gay et al. (1997) is undoubtedly a tremendous<br />

contribution to work in post-Marxist cultural studies.<br />

61. Marx (1976a) makes the point that ‘a product only obtains its last finish in consumption.<br />

. . . For example, a dress becomes a real dress only in the act of being worn; a house which<br />

is uninhabited is in fact no real house; in other words, a product, as distinct from a mere<br />

natural object, proves itself as such, becomes a product, only in consumption’ (19). This is<br />

the difference between a book <strong>and</strong> a text; the first is produced by a publisher, the second is<br />

produced by a reader.


Bibliography<br />

Abercrombie, Nicholas, Stephen Hill <strong>and</strong> Bryan S. Turner (1980), The Dominant Ideology Thesis,<br />

London: Allen & Unwin.<br />

Adorno, Theodor (1991a), ‘How to look at television’, in The <strong>Culture</strong> Industry, London:<br />

Routledge.<br />

Adorno, Theodor (1991b), ‘The schema of mass culture’, in The <strong>Culture</strong> Industry, London:<br />

Routledge.<br />

Adorno, Theodor (2009), ‘On popular music’, in <strong>Cultural</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Popular</strong> <strong>Culture</strong>: A Reader,<br />

4th edn, edited by John Storey, Harlow: Pearson Education.<br />

Adorno, Theodor <strong>and</strong> Max Horkheimer (1979), Dialectic of Enlightenment, London: Verso.<br />

Althusser, Louis (1969), For Marx, London: Allen Lane.<br />

Althusser, Louis (1971), Lenin <strong>and</strong> Philosophy, New York: Monthly Review Press.<br />

Althusser, Louis (2009), ‘Ideology <strong>and</strong> ideological state apparatuses’, in <strong>Cultural</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>Popular</strong> <strong>Culture</strong>: A Reader, 4th edn, edited by John Storey, Harlow: Pearson Education.<br />

Althusser, Louis <strong>and</strong> Etienne Balibar (1979), Reading Capital, London: Verso.<br />

Anderson, Perry (1980), Arguments within English Marxism, London: Verso.<br />

Ang, Ien (1985), Watching Dallas: Soap Opera <strong>and</strong> the Melodramatic Imagination, London: Methuen.<br />

Ang, I. (1996) ‘<strong>Culture</strong> <strong>and</strong> communication: towards an ethnographic critique of media consumption<br />

in the transnational media system’, in What is <strong>Cultural</strong> Studies? A Reader, edited by<br />

John Storey. London: Edward Arnold.<br />

Ang, Ien (2009), ‘Feminist desire <strong>and</strong> female pleasure’, in <strong>Cultural</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Popular</strong> <strong>Culture</strong>: A<br />

Reader, 4th edn, edited by John Storey, Harlow: Pearson Education.<br />

Arnold, Matthew (1896), Letters 1848–1888, Volume I, London: Macmillan.<br />

Arnold, Matthew (1954), Poetry <strong>and</strong> Prose, London: Rupert Hart Davis.<br />

Arnold, Matthew (1960), <strong>Culture</strong> <strong>and</strong> Anarchy, London: Cambridge University Press.<br />

Arnold, Matthew (1960–77), Complete Prose Works, Volume III, Ann Arbor: University of<br />

Michigan Press.<br />

Arnold, Matthew (1973), On Education, Harmondsworth: Penguin.<br />

Austin, J.L., (1962), How to Do Things with Words, Oxford: Clarendon Press.<br />

Barrett, Michèle (1982), ‘Feminism <strong>and</strong> the definition of cultural politics’, in Feminism, <strong>Culture</strong><br />

<strong>and</strong> Politics, edited by Rosalind Brunt <strong>and</strong> Caroline Rowan, London: Lawrence & Wishart.<br />

Barthes, Rol<strong>and</strong> (1967), Elements of Semiology, London: Jonathan Cape.<br />

Barthes, Rol<strong>and</strong> (1973), Mythologies, London: Paladin.<br />

Barthes, Rol<strong>and</strong> (1975), S/Z, London: Jonathan Cape.<br />

Barthes, Rol<strong>and</strong> (1977a), ‘The photographic message’, in Image–Music–Text, London: Fontana.<br />

Barthes, Rol<strong>and</strong> (1977b), ‘Rhetoric of the image’, in Image–Music–Text, London: Fontana.<br />

Barthes, Rol<strong>and</strong> (1977c), ‘The death of the author’, in Image–Music–Text, London: Fontana.<br />

Barthes, Rol<strong>and</strong> (2009), ‘Myth today’, in <strong>Cultural</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Popular</strong> <strong>Culture</strong>: A Reader, 4th edn,<br />

edited by John Storey, Harlow: Pearson Education.


242<br />

Bibliography<br />

Baudrillard, Jean (1981), For a Critique of the Political Economy of the Sign, St Louis: Telos Press.<br />

Baudrillard, Jean (1983), Simulations, New York: Semiotext(e).<br />

Baudrillard, Jean (2009), ‘The precession of simulacra’, in <strong>Cultural</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Popular</strong> <strong>Culture</strong>: A<br />

Reader, 4th edn, edited by John Storey, Harlow: Pearson Education.<br />

Beauvoir, Simone de (1984), The Second Sex, New York: Vintage.<br />

Beaver, Harold (1999), ‘Homosexual signs: in memory of Rol<strong>and</strong> Barthes’, in Camp: Queer<br />

Aesthetics <strong>and</strong> the Performing Subject: A Reader, edited by Fabio Cleto, Edinburgh: Edinburgh<br />

University Press.<br />

Benjamin, Walter (1973), ‘The work of art in the age of mechanical reproduction’, in<br />

Illuminations, London: Fontana.<br />

Bennett, Tony (1977), ‘Media theory <strong>and</strong> social theory’, in Mass Communications <strong>and</strong> Society DE<br />

353, Milton Keynes: Open University Press.<br />

Bennett, Tony (1979), Formalism <strong>and</strong> Marxism, London: Methuen.<br />

Bennett, Tony (1980), ‘<strong>Popular</strong> culture: a teaching object’, Screen Education, 34.<br />

Bennett, Tony (1982a), ‘<strong>Popular</strong> culture: defining our terms’, in <strong>Popular</strong> <strong>Culture</strong>: Themes <strong>and</strong> Issues<br />

1, Milton Keynes: Open University Press.<br />

Bennett, Tony (1982b), ‘<strong>Popular</strong> culture: themes <strong>and</strong> issues’, in <strong>Popular</strong> <strong>Culture</strong> U203, Milton<br />

Keynes: Open University Press.<br />

Bennett, Tony (1983), ‘Text, readers, reading formations’, Literature <strong>and</strong> History, 9(2).<br />

Bennett, Tony (1986), ‘The politics of the popular’, in <strong>Popular</strong> <strong>Culture</strong> <strong>and</strong> Social Relations, Milton<br />

Keynes: Open University Press.<br />

Bennett, Tony (2009), ‘<strong>Popular</strong> culture <strong>and</strong> the turn to Gramsci’, in <strong>Cultural</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Popular</strong><br />

<strong>Culture</strong>: A Reader, 4th edn, edited by John Storey, Harlow: Pearson Education.<br />

Bentham, Jeremy (1995), The Panopticon Writings, edited <strong>and</strong> introduced by Miran Bozovic,<br />

London: Verso.<br />

Bernstein, J.M. (1978), ‘Introduction’, in The <strong>Culture</strong> Industry, London: Routledge.<br />

Best, Steven <strong>and</strong> Douglas Kellner (1991), Postmodern <strong>Theory</strong>: Critical Investigations, London:<br />

Macmillan.<br />

Bourdieu, Pierre (1984), Distinction: A Social Critique of the Judgment of Taste, translated by<br />

Richard Nice, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.<br />

Bowie, Malcolm (1991), Lacan, London: Fontana.<br />

Brecht, Bertolt (1978), On Theatre, translated by John Willett, London: Methuen.<br />

Brogan, D.W. (1978), ‘The problem of high <strong>and</strong> mass culture’, in Literary Taste, <strong>Culture</strong>, <strong>and</strong> Mass<br />

Communication, Volume I, edited by Peter Davison, Rolf Meyersohn <strong>and</strong> Edward Shils,<br />

Cambridge: Chadwyck Healey.<br />

Brooker, Peter <strong>and</strong> Will Brooker (1997a), ‘Introduction’, in Postmodern After-Images, edited by<br />

Peter Brooker <strong>and</strong> Will Brooker, London: Edward Arnold.<br />

Brooker, Peter <strong>and</strong> Will Brooker (1997b), ‘Styles of pluralism’, in Postmodern After-Images, edited<br />

by Peter Brooker <strong>and</strong> Will Brooker, London: Edward Arnold.<br />

Brooks, Peter (1976), The Melodramatic Imagination, New Haven: Yale University Press.<br />

Brunsdon, Charlotte (1991), ‘Pedagogies of the feminine: feminist teaching <strong>and</strong> women’s genres’,<br />

Screen, 32 (4).<br />

Burke, Peter (1994), <strong>Popular</strong> <strong>Culture</strong> in Early Modern Europe, Aldershot: Scolar Press.<br />

Burston, Paul <strong>and</strong> Colin Richardson (1995), ‘Introduction’, in A Queer Romance: Lesbians, Gay<br />

Men <strong>and</strong> <strong>Popular</strong> <strong>Culture</strong>, edited by Paul Burston <strong>and</strong> Colin Richardson, London: Routledge.<br />

Butler, Judith (1993), Bodies That Matter: On the Discursive Limits of Sex, New York: Routledge.<br />

Butler, Judith (1999), Gender Trouble: Feminism <strong>and</strong> the Subversion of Identity, 10th anniversary<br />

edn, New York: Routledge.


Bibliography 243<br />

Butler, Judith (2000), ‘Restaging the universal’, in Contingency, Hegemony, Universality:<br />

Contemporary Dialogues on the Left, by Judith Butler, Ernesto Laclau <strong>and</strong> Slavoj yizek, London,<br />

Verso.<br />

Butler, Judith (2009), ‘Imitation <strong>and</strong> gender insubordination’, in <strong>Cultural</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Popular</strong><br />

<strong>Culture</strong>: A Reader, 4th edn, edited by John Storey, Harlow: Pearson Education.<br />

Butler, Judith, Ernesto Laclau <strong>and</strong> Slavoj yizek (2000), Contingency, Hegemony, Universality:<br />

Contemporary Dialogues on the Left, London, Verso.<br />

Canaan, Joyce <strong>and</strong> Christine Griffin (1990), ‘The new men’s studies: part of the problem or part<br />

of the solution’, in Men, Masculinities <strong>and</strong> Social <strong>Theory</strong>, edited by Jeff Hearn <strong>and</strong> David<br />

Morgan, London: Unwin Hyman.<br />

Carey, James W. (1996), ‘Overcoming resistance to cultural studies’, in What Is <strong>Cultural</strong> Studies?<br />

A Reader, edited by John Storey, London: Edward Arnold.<br />

Certeau, Michel de (1984), The Practice of Everyday Life, Berkeley: University of California, 1984.<br />

Certeau, Michel de (2009), ‘The practice of everyday life’, in <strong>Cultural</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Popular</strong> <strong>Culture</strong>:<br />

A Reader, 4th edn, edited by John Storey, Harlow: Pearson Education.<br />

Chambers, Iain (1988), <strong>Popular</strong> <strong>Culture</strong>: The Metropolitan Experience, London: Routledge.<br />

Chauncey, George (1994), Gay New York: Gender, Urban <strong>Culture</strong>, <strong>and</strong> the Making of the Gay Male<br />

World, 1890–1940, New York: Basic Books.<br />

Chinn, Sarah E. (1997), ‘Gender perormativity’, in The Lesbian <strong>and</strong> Gay Studies Reader: A Critical<br />

Introduction, edited by Andy Medhurst <strong>and</strong> Sally R. Munt, London: Cassell.<br />

Chodorow, Nancy (1978), The Reproduction of Mothering: Psychoanalysis <strong>and</strong> the Sociology of<br />

Gender, Berkeley: University of California Press.<br />

Clark, Michael (1991), ‘Remembering Vietnam’, in John Carlos Rowe <strong>and</strong> Rick Berg (eds), The<br />

Vietnam War <strong>and</strong> American <strong>Culture</strong>, New York: Columbia University Press.<br />

Clarke, Gary (1990), ‘Defending ski-jumpers: a critique of theories of youth subcultures’, in On<br />

Record, edited by Simon Frith <strong>and</strong> Andrew Goodwin, New York: Pantheon.<br />

Cleto, Fabio (ed.) (1999), Camp: Queer Aesthetics <strong>and</strong> the Performing Subject, Edinburgh:<br />

Edinburgh University Press.<br />

Coleridge, Samuel Taylor (1972), On the Constitution of the Church <strong>and</strong> State, London: Dent.<br />

Collins, Jim (1992), ‘Postmodernism <strong>and</strong> television’, in Channels of Discourse, Reassembled, edited<br />

by Robert C. Allen, London: Routledge, 1992.<br />

Collins, Jim (2009), ‘Genericity in the nineties’, in <strong>Cultural</strong> theory <strong>and</strong> <strong>Popular</strong> <strong>Culture</strong>: A Reader,<br />

4th edn, edited by John Storey, Harlow: Pearson Education.<br />

Connor, Steven (1989), Postmodernist <strong>Culture</strong>: An Introduction to Theories of the Contemporary,<br />

Oxford: Blackwell.<br />

Connor, Steven (1992), <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Cultural</strong> Value, Oxford: Blackwell.<br />

Coward, Rosalind (1984), Female Desire: Women’s Sexuality Today, London: Paladin.<br />

Creed, Barbara (2009), ‘From here to modernity: feminism <strong>and</strong> postmodernism’, in <strong>Cultural</strong> <strong>Theory</strong><br />

<strong>and</strong> <strong>Popular</strong> <strong>Culture</strong>: A Reader, 4th edn, edited by John Storey, Harlow: Pearson Education.<br />

Creekmur, Corey K. <strong>and</strong> Alex<strong>and</strong>er Doty (1995), ‘Introduction’, in Out in <strong>Culture</strong>: Gay, Lesbian,<br />

<strong>and</strong> Queer Essays on <strong>Popular</strong> <strong>Culture</strong>, edited by Corey K. Creekmur <strong>and</strong> Alex<strong>and</strong>er Doty,<br />

London: Cassell.<br />

Curtin, Philip (1964), Images of Africa, Wisconsin: University of Wisconsin Press.<br />

Derrida, Jacques (1973), Speech <strong>and</strong> Phenomena, Evanston: North Western University Press.<br />

Derrida, Jacques (1976), Of Grammatology, Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.<br />

Derrida, Jacques (1978a), Writing <strong>and</strong> Difference, London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.<br />

Derrida, Jacques (1978b), Positions, London: Athlone Press.<br />

Descartes, Rene (1993), Meditations on First Philosophy, London: Hackett.


244<br />

Bibliography<br />

DiMaggio, Paul (2009), ‘<strong>Cultural</strong> entrepreneurship in nineteenth-century Boston: the creation of<br />

an organizational base for high culture in America’, in <strong>Cultural</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Popular</strong> <strong>Culture</strong>: A<br />

Reader, 4th edn, edited by John Storey, Harlow: Pearson Education.<br />

Disraeli, Benjamin (1980), Sybil, or the Two Nations, Harmondsworth: Penguin.<br />

Dittmar, Linda, <strong>and</strong> Michaud, Gene (1990) (eds), From Hanoi To Hollywood: The Vietnam War in<br />

American Film, New Brunswick <strong>and</strong> London: Rutgers University Press.<br />

Docker, John (1994), Postmodernism <strong>and</strong> <strong>Popular</strong> <strong>Culture</strong>: A <strong>Cultural</strong> History, Cambridge:<br />

Cambridge University Press.<br />

Doty, Alex<strong>and</strong>er (1995), ‘Something queer here’, in Out in <strong>Culture</strong>: Gay, Lesbian <strong>and</strong> Queer Essays<br />

on <strong>Popular</strong> <strong>Culture</strong>, edited by Corey K. Creekmur <strong>and</strong> Alex<strong>and</strong>er Doty, London: Cassell.<br />

Dyer, Richard (1990), ‘In defence of disco’, in On Record: Rock, Pop, <strong>and</strong> the Written Word, edited<br />

by Simon Frith <strong>and</strong> Andrew Goodwin, London: Routledge.<br />

Dyer, Richard (1999), ‘Entertainment <strong>and</strong> utopia’, in The <strong>Cultural</strong> Studies Reader, 2nd edn, edited<br />

by Simon During, London: Routledge.<br />

Eagleton, Terry (1983), Literary <strong>Theory</strong>: An Introduction, Oxford: Blackwell.<br />

Easthope, Antony (1986), What a Man’s Gotta Do: The Masculine Myth in <strong>Popular</strong> <strong>Culture</strong>, London:<br />

Paladin.<br />

Easthope, Antony (1991), Literary into <strong>Cultural</strong> Studies, London: Routledge.<br />

Eco, Umberto (1984), Postscript to The Name of the Rose, New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich.<br />

Engels, Frederick (2009), ‘Letter to Joseph Bloch’, in <strong>Cultural</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Popular</strong> <strong>Culture</strong>: A Reader,<br />

4th edn, edited by John Storey, Harlow: Pearson Education.<br />

Fekete, John (1987), ‘Introductory notes for a postmodern value agenda’, in Life After<br />

Postmodernism, edited by John Fekete, New York: St Martin’s Press.<br />

Fiedler, Leslie (1957), ‘The middle against both ends’, in Mass <strong>Culture</strong>: The <strong>Popular</strong> Arts in America,<br />

edited by Bernard Rosenberg <strong>and</strong> David Manning White, New York: Macmillan.<br />

Fiedler, Leslie (1971), The Collected Essays of Leslie Fiedler, Volume 2, New York: Stein <strong>and</strong> Day.<br />

Fiske, John (1987), Television <strong>Culture</strong>, London: Routledge.<br />

Fiske, John (1989a), Underst<strong>and</strong>ing <strong>Popular</strong> <strong>Culture</strong>, London: Unwin Hyman.<br />

Fiske, John (1989b), Reading the <strong>Popular</strong>, London: Unwin Hyman.<br />

Fiske, John (1994), Media Matters: Everyday <strong>Culture</strong> <strong>and</strong> Media Change, Minnesota: University of<br />

Minnesota Press.<br />

Foucault, Michel (1979), Discipline <strong>and</strong> Punish, Harmondsworth: Penguin.<br />

Foucault, Michel (1981), The History of Sexuality, Harmondsworth: Penguin.<br />

Foucault, Michel (1989), The Archaeology of Knowledge, London: Routledge.<br />

Foucault, Michel (2002a), ‘Truth <strong>and</strong> power’, in James D. Faubion (ed.), Michel Foucault Essential<br />

Works: Power, Harmondsworth: Penguin.<br />

Foucault, Michel (2002b), ‘Question of method’, in James D. Faubion (ed.), Michel Foucault<br />

Essential Works: Power, Harmondsworth: Penguin.<br />

Foucault, Michel (2002c), ‘Truth <strong>and</strong> juridical forms’, in James D. Fabion (ed.), Michel Foucault<br />

Essential Works: Power, Harmondsworth: Penguin.<br />

Foucault, Michel (2009), ‘Method’, in <strong>Cultural</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Popular</strong> <strong>Culture</strong>: A Reader, 4th edn,<br />

edited by John Storey, Harlow: Pearson Education.<br />

Franklin, H. Bruce (1993), M.I.A. or Mythmaking in America, New Brunswick: Rutgers University<br />

Press.<br />

Freud, Sigmund (1973a), Introductory Lectures on Psychoanalysis, Harmondsworth: Pelican.<br />

Freud, Sigmund (1973b), New Introductory Lectures on Psychoanalysis, Harmondsworth: Pelican.<br />

Freud, Sigmund (1976), The Interpretation of Dreams, Harmondsworth: Pelican.<br />

Freud, Sigmund (1977), On Sexuality, Harmondsworth: Pelican.


Bibliography 245<br />

Freud, Sigmund (1984), On Metapsychology: The <strong>Theory</strong> of Psychoanalysis, Harmondsworth: Pelican.<br />

Freud, Sigmund (1985), Art <strong>and</strong> Literature, Harmondsworth: Pelican.<br />

Freud, Sigmund (1986), Historical <strong>and</strong> Expository Works on Psychoanalysis, Harmondsworth: Pelican.<br />

Freud, Sigmund (2009), ‘The Dream-Work’, in <strong>Cultural</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Popular</strong> <strong>Culture</strong>: A Reader, 4th<br />

edn, edited by John Storey, Harlow: Pearson Education.<br />

Frith, Simon (1983), Sound Effects: Youth, Leisure <strong>and</strong> the Politics of Rock, London: Constable.<br />

Frith, Simon (2009), ‘The good, the bad <strong>and</strong> the indifferent: defending popular culture from the<br />

populists’, in <strong>Cultural</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Popular</strong> <strong>Culture</strong>: A Reader, 4th edn, edited by John Storey,<br />

Harlow: Pearson Education.<br />

Frith, Simon <strong>and</strong> Howard Horne (1987), Art into Pop, London: Methuen.<br />

Frow, John (1995), <strong>Cultural</strong> Studies <strong>and</strong> Value, New York: Oxford University Press.<br />

Fryer, Peter (1984), Staying Power, London: Pluto.<br />

Gamman, Lorraine <strong>and</strong> Margaret Marshment (1988), ‘Introduction’, in The Female Gaze, Women<br />

as Viewers of <strong>Popular</strong> <strong>Culture</strong>, edited by Lorraine Gamman <strong>and</strong> Margaret Marshment, London:<br />

The Women’s Press.<br />

Garnham, Nicholas (2009), ‘Political economy <strong>and</strong> cultural studies: reconciliation or divorce’, in<br />

<strong>Cultural</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Popular</strong> <strong>Culture</strong>: A Reader, 4th edn, edited by John Storey, Harlow: Pearson<br />

Education.<br />

Garnham, Nicholas <strong>and</strong> Raymond Williams (1980), ‘Pierre Bourdieu <strong>and</strong> the sociology of culture:<br />

an introduction’, Media, <strong>Culture</strong> <strong>and</strong> Society, 2 (3).<br />

Gay, Paul du, Stuart Hall, Linda Janes, Hugh Mackay <strong>and</strong> Keith Negus (1997), Doing <strong>Cultural</strong><br />

Studies, London: Sage.<br />

Gilroy, Paul (2002), There Ain’t No Black in the Union Jack, London: Routledge Classics.<br />

Gilroy, Paul (2004), After Empire, London: Routledge.<br />

Gilroy, Paul (2009), ‘“Get up, get into it <strong>and</strong> get involved” – soul, civil rights <strong>and</strong> black power’,<br />

in <strong>Cultural</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Popular</strong> <strong>Culture</strong>: A Reader, 4th edn, edited by John Storey, Harlow:<br />

Pearson Education.<br />

Gilroy, Paul, Grossbery, Lawrence, <strong>and</strong> McRobbie, Angela (2000) (eds), Without Guarantees: In<br />

Honour of Stuart Hall, London: Verso.<br />

Gledhill, Christine (2009), ‘Pleasurable negotiations’, in <strong>Cultural</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Popular</strong> <strong>Culture</strong>: A<br />

Reader, 4th edn, edited by John Storey, Harlow: Pearson Education.<br />

Golding, Peter <strong>and</strong> Graham Murdock (1991), ‘<strong>Culture</strong>, communications <strong>and</strong> political economy’,<br />

in Mass Media <strong>and</strong> Society, edited by James Curran <strong>and</strong> Michael Gurevitch, London: Edward<br />

Arnold.<br />

Goodwin, Andrew (1991), ‘<strong>Popular</strong> music <strong>and</strong> postmodern theory’, <strong>Cultural</strong> Studies, 5 (2).<br />

Gramsci, Antonio (1971), Selections from Prison Notebooks, London: Lawrence & Wishart.<br />

Gramsci, Antonio (2009), ‘Hegemony, intellectuals, <strong>and</strong> the state’, in <strong>Cultural</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Popular</strong><br />

<strong>Culture</strong>: A Reader, 4th edn, edited by John Storey, Harlow: Pearson Education.<br />

Gray, Ann (1992), Video Playtime: The Gendering of Leisure Technology, London: Routledge.<br />

Green, Michael (1996), ‘The Centre for Contemporary <strong>Cultural</strong> Studies’, in What is <strong>Cultural</strong><br />

Studies? A Reader, edited by John Storey, London: Edward Arnold.<br />

Grossberg, Lawrence (1988), It’s a Sin: Essays on Postmodernism, Politics <strong>and</strong> <strong>Culture</strong>, Sydney: Power<br />

Publications.<br />

Grossberg, Lawrence (1992), ‘Is there a fan in the house?’, in The Adoring Audience, edited by Lisa<br />

Lewis, London: Routledge.<br />

Grossberg, Lawrence (2009), ‘<strong>Cultural</strong> studies vs. political economy: is anybody else bored with<br />

this debate?’, in <strong>Cultural</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Popular</strong> <strong>Culture</strong>: A Reader, 4th edn, edited by John Storey,<br />

Harlow: Pearson Education.


246<br />

Bibliography<br />

Haag, Ernest van den (1957), ‘Of happiness <strong>and</strong> despair we have no measure’, in Mass <strong>Culture</strong>:<br />

The <strong>Popular</strong> Arts in America, edited by Bernard Rosenberg <strong>and</strong> David Manning White, New<br />

York: Macmillan.<br />

Haines, Harry W. (1990), ‘They were called <strong>and</strong> they went’: the political rehabilitation of the<br />

Vietnam veteran’, in Linda Dittmar <strong>and</strong> Gene Michaud (eds), From Hanoi To Hollywood: The<br />

Vietnam War in American Film, New Brunswick <strong>and</strong> London: Rutgers University Press.<br />

Haines, Harry (1995), ‘Putting Vietnam Behind Us: Hegemony <strong>and</strong> the Gulf War’, in Studies in<br />

Communication, 5.<br />

Hall, Stuart (1978), ‘Some paradigms in cultural studies’, Annali, 3.<br />

Hall, Stuart (1980a), ‘Encoding/decoding’, in <strong>Culture</strong>, Media, Language, edited by Stuart Hall,<br />

Dorothy Hobson, Andrew Lowe <strong>and</strong> Paul Willis, London: Hutchinson.<br />

Hall, Stuart (1980b), ‘<strong>Cultural</strong> studies <strong>and</strong> the Centre; some problematics <strong>and</strong> problems’, in<br />

<strong>Culture</strong>, Media, Language, edited by Stuart Hall, Dorothy Hobson, Andrew Lowe <strong>and</strong> Paul<br />

Willis, London: Hutchinson.<br />

Hall, Stuart (1991), ‘Old <strong>and</strong> new ethnicities’, in <strong>Culture</strong>, Globalization <strong>and</strong> the World-System,<br />

edited by Anthony Smith, London, Macmillam.<br />

Hall, Stuart (1992), ‘<strong>Cultural</strong> studies <strong>and</strong> its theoretical legacies’, in <strong>Cultural</strong> Studies, edited by<br />

Lawrence Grossberg, Cary Nelson <strong>and</strong> Paula Treichler, London: Routledge.<br />

Hall, Stuart (1996a), ‘<strong>Cultural</strong> studies: two paradigms’, in What is <strong>Cultural</strong> Studies? A Reader,<br />

edited by John Storey, London: Edward Arnold.<br />

Hall, Stuart (1996b), ‘On postmodernism <strong>and</strong> articulation: an interview with Stuart Hall’, in<br />

Stuart Hall: <strong>Cultural</strong> Dialogues in <strong>Cultural</strong> Studies, edited by David Morley <strong>and</strong> Kuan-Hsing<br />

Chen, London: Routledge.<br />

Hall, Stuart (1996c), ‘The problem of ideology: Marxism without guarantees’, in Stuart Hall:<br />

<strong>Cultural</strong> Dialogues in <strong>Cultural</strong> Studies, edited by David Morley <strong>and</strong> Kuan-Hsing Chen, London:<br />

Routledge.<br />

Hall, Stuart (1996d), ‘When was the “post-colonial”? Thinking at the limit’, in The Postcolonial<br />

Question, edited by L. Chambers <strong>and</strong> L. Curti, London: Routledge.<br />

Hall, Stuart (1996e) ‘Race, culture, <strong>and</strong> communications: looking backward <strong>and</strong> forward at cultural<br />

studies’, in John Storey (ed.), What is <strong>Cultural</strong> Studies: A Reader, London: Edward Arnold.<br />

Hall, Stuart (1997a), Doing <strong>Cultural</strong> Studies, London: Sage.<br />

Hall, Stuart (1997b), ‘Introduction’, in Representation, edited by Stuart Hall, London: Sage.<br />

Hall, Stuart (1997c), ‘The spectacle of the “other”’, in Representation, edited by Stuart Hall,<br />

London: Sage.<br />

Hall, Stuart (2009a), ‘The rediscovery of ideology: the return of the repressed in media studies’,<br />

in <strong>Cultural</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Popular</strong> <strong>Culture</strong>: A Reader, 4th edn, edited by John Storey, Harlow:<br />

Pearson Education.<br />

Hall, Stuart (2009b), ‘Notes on deconstructing “the popular”’, in <strong>Cultural</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Popular</strong><br />

<strong>Culture</strong>: A Reader, 4th edn, edited by John Storey, Harlow: Pearson Education.<br />

Hall, Stuart (2009c), ‘What is this “black” in black popular culture?’, in <strong>Cultural</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>Popular</strong> <strong>Culture</strong>: A Reader, 4th edn, edited by John Storey, Harlow: Pearson Education.<br />

Hall, Stuart <strong>and</strong> Paddy Whannel (1964), The <strong>Popular</strong> Arts, London: Hutchinson.<br />

Harvey, David (1989), The Condition of Postmodernity, Oxford: Blackwell.<br />

Hawkes, Terence (1977), Structuralism <strong>and</strong> Semiotics, London: Methuen.<br />

Hebdige, Dick (1979), Subculture: The Meaning of Style, London: Methuen.<br />

Hebdige, Dick (1988), ‘Banalarama, or can pop save us all?’ New Statesman & Society, 9 December.<br />

Hebdige, Dick (2009), ‘Postmodernism <strong>and</strong> “the other side”’, in <strong>Cultural</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Popular</strong><br />

<strong>Culture</strong>: A Reader, 4th edn, edited by John Storey, Harlow: Pearson Education.


Bibliography 247<br />

Hermes, Joke (1995), Reading Women’s Magazines, Cambridge: Polity Press, 1995.<br />

Hoggart, Richard (1970), ‘Schools of English <strong>and</strong> contemporary society’, in Speaking to Each<br />

Other, Volume II, edited by Richard Hoggart, London: Chatto <strong>and</strong> Windus.<br />

Hoggart, Richard (1990), The Uses of Literacy, Harmondsworth: Penguin.<br />

hooks, bell (1989), Talking Back: Thinking Feminist, Thinking Black, London: Sheba Feminist<br />

Publishers.<br />

hooks, bell (2009), ‘Postmodern blackness’, in <strong>Cultural</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Popular</strong> <strong>Culture</strong>: A Reader, 4th<br />

edn, edited by John Storey, Harlow: Pearson Education.<br />

Horkheimer, Max (1978), ‘Art <strong>and</strong> mass culture’, in Literary Taste, <strong>Culture</strong> <strong>and</strong> Mass<br />

Communication, Volume XII, edited by Peter Davison, Rolf Meyersohn <strong>and</strong> Edward Shils,<br />

Cambridge: Chadwyck Healey.<br />

Huyssen, Andreas (1986), After the Great Divide: Modernism, Mass <strong>Culture</strong> <strong>and</strong> Postmodernism,<br />

London: Macmillan.<br />

Jameson, Fredric (1981), The Political Unconscious, London: Methuen.<br />

Jameson, Fredric (1984), ‘Postmodernism, or the cultural logic of late capitalism’, New Left<br />

Review, 146.<br />

Jameson, Fredric (1985), ‘Postmodernism <strong>and</strong> consumer society’, in Postmodern <strong>Culture</strong>, edited by<br />

Hal Foster, London: Pluto.<br />

Jameson, Fredric (1988), ‘The politics of theory: ideological positions in the postmodernism<br />

debate’, in The Ideologies of <strong>Theory</strong> Essays, Volume 2, London: Routledge.<br />

Jeffords, Susan (1989), The Remasculinization of America: Gender <strong>and</strong> the Vietnam War,<br />

Bloomington <strong>and</strong> Indianapolis: Indiana University Press.<br />

Jenkins, Henry (1992), Textual Poachers, New York: Routledge.<br />

Jenkins, Henry (2006), Convergence <strong>Culture</strong>: Where Old <strong>and</strong> New Media Collide, New York: New<br />

York University Press.<br />

Jenson, Joli (1992), ‘F<strong>and</strong>om as pathology’, in The Adoring Audience, edited by Lisa Lewis,<br />

London: Routledge.<br />

Jewitt, Robert (2005), ‘Mobile networks: globalisation, networks <strong>and</strong> the mobile phone’, in<br />

<strong>Culture</strong> <strong>and</strong> Power: <strong>Culture</strong> <strong>and</strong> Society in the Age of Globalisation, edited by Chantal Cornut-<br />

Gentille, Zaragoza: Zaragoza University Press.<br />

Johnson, Richard (1979), ‘Three problematics: elements of a theory of working-class culture’, in<br />

Working Class <strong>Culture</strong>: Studies in History <strong>and</strong> <strong>Theory</strong>, edited by John Clarke et al., London:<br />

Hutchinson.<br />

Johnson, Richard (1996), ‘What is cultural studies anyway?’ in What is <strong>Cultural</strong> Studies? A Reader,<br />

edited by John Storey, London: Arnold.<br />

Klein, Michael (1990), Historical memory, film, <strong>and</strong> the Vietnam era, in Linda Dittmar <strong>and</strong> Gene<br />

Michaud (eds), From Hanoi To Hollywood: The Vietnam War in American Film, New Brunswick<br />

<strong>and</strong> London: Rutgers University Press.<br />

Lacan, Jacques (1989), Four Fundamental Concepts in Psychoanalysis, New York: Norton.<br />

Lacan, Jacques (2001), Ecrits, London: Routledge.<br />

Lacan, Jacques (2009), ‘The mirror stage’, in <strong>Cultural</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Popular</strong> <strong>Culture</strong>: A Reader, 4th<br />

edn, edited by John Storey, Harlow: Pearson Education.<br />

Laclau, Ernesto (1979), Politics <strong>and</strong> Ideology in Marxist <strong>Theory</strong>, London: Verso.<br />

Laclau, Ernesto (1993), ‘Discourse’, in A Companion to Contemporary Political Philosophy, edited by<br />

R.E. Goodin <strong>and</strong> P. Pettit, London: Blackwell.<br />

Laclau, Ernesto <strong>and</strong> Chantal Mouffe (2001), Hegemony <strong>and</strong> Socialist Strategy, 2nd edn, London: Verso.<br />

Laclau, Ernesto <strong>and</strong> Chantal Mouffe (2009), ‘Post-Marxism without apologies’, in <strong>Cultural</strong> <strong>Theory</strong><br />

<strong>and</strong> <strong>Popular</strong> <strong>Culture</strong>: A Reader, 4th edn, edited by John Storey, Harlow: Pearson Education.


248<br />

Bibliography<br />

Leavis, F.R. (1933), For Continuity, Cambridge: Minority Press.<br />

Leavis, F.R. (1972), Nor Shall My Sword, London: Chatto <strong>and</strong> Windus.<br />

Leavis, F.R. (1984), The Common Pursuit, London: Hogarth.<br />

Leavis, F.R. (2009), ‘Mass civilisation <strong>and</strong> minority culture’, in <strong>Cultural</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Popular</strong> <strong>Culture</strong>:<br />

A Reader, 4th edn, edited by John Storey, Harlow: Pearson Education.<br />

Leavis, F.R. <strong>and</strong> Denys Thompson (1977), <strong>Culture</strong> <strong>and</strong> Environment, Westport, Connecticut:<br />

Greenwood Press.<br />

Leavis, Q.D. (1978), Fiction <strong>and</strong> the Reading Public, London: Chatto <strong>and</strong> Windus.<br />

Levine, Lawrence (1988), Highbrow/Lowbrow: The Emergence of <strong>Cultural</strong> Hierarchy in America,<br />

Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.<br />

Lévi-Strauss, Claude (1968), Structural Anthropology, London: Allen Lane.<br />

Liebes, T. <strong>and</strong> E. Katz (1993), The Export of Meaning: Cross-cultural Readings of Dallas, 2nd edn.<br />

Cambridge: Polity Press.<br />

Light, Alison (1984), ‘“Returning to M<strong>and</strong>erley”: romance fiction, female sexuality <strong>and</strong> class’,<br />

Feminist Review, 16.<br />

Lovell, Terry (2009), ‘<strong>Cultural</strong> production’, in <strong>Cultural</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Popular</strong> <strong>Culture</strong>: A Reader, 4th<br />

edn, edited by John Storey, Harlow: Pearson Education.<br />

Lowenthal, Leo (1961), Literature, <strong>Popular</strong> <strong>Culture</strong> <strong>and</strong> Society, Palo Alto, California: Pacific Books.<br />

Lyotard, Jean-François (1984), The Postmodern Condition: A Report on Knowledge, Manchester:<br />

Manchester University Press.<br />

Macdonald, Dwight (1998), ‘A theory of mass culture’, in <strong>Cultural</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Popular</strong> <strong>Culture</strong>: A<br />

Reader, 2nd edn, edited by John Storey, Harlow: Prentice Hall.<br />

Macherey, Pierre (1978), A <strong>Theory</strong> of Literary Production, London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.<br />

Maltby, Richard (1989), ‘Introduction’, in Dreams for Sale: <strong>Popular</strong> <strong>Culture</strong> in the 20th Century,<br />

edited by Richard Maltby, London: Harrap.<br />

M<strong>and</strong>el, Ernest (1978), Late Capitalism, London: Verso.<br />

Marcuse, Herbert (1968a), One Dimensional Man, London: Sphere.<br />

Marcuse, Herbert (1968b), Negations, London: Allen Lane.<br />

Martin, Andrew (1993), Receptions of War: Vietnam in American <strong>Culture</strong>, Norman: University of<br />

Oklahoma Press.<br />

Marx, Karl (1951), Theories of Surplus Value, London: Lawrence & Wishart.<br />

Marx, Karl (1973), Grundrisse, Harmondsworth: Penguin.<br />

Marx, Karl (1976a) ‘Preface’ <strong>and</strong> ‘Introduction’, in Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy,<br />

Peking: Foreign Languages Press.<br />

Marx, Karl (1976b), ‘Theses on Feuerbach’, in Ludwig Feuerbach <strong>and</strong> the End of Classical German<br />

Philosophy, by Frederick Engels, Peking: Foreign Languages Press.<br />

Marx, Karl (1976c), Capital, Volume I, Harmondsworth: Penguin.<br />

Marx, Karl (1977), The Eighteenth Brumaire of Louis Bonaparte, Moscow: Progress Publishers.<br />

Marx, Karl <strong>and</strong> Frederick Engels (1957), On Religion, Moscow: Progress Publishers.<br />

Marx, Karl <strong>and</strong> Frederick Engels (1974), The German Ideology (student edition), edited <strong>and</strong> introduced<br />

by C.J. Arthur, London: Lawrence & Wishart.<br />

Marx, Karl <strong>and</strong> Frederick Engels (2009), ‘Ruling class <strong>and</strong> ruling ideas’, in <strong>Cultural</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>Popular</strong> <strong>Culture</strong>: A Reader, 4th edn, edited by John Storey, Harlow: Pearson Education.<br />

McGuigan, Jim (1992), <strong>Cultural</strong> Populism, London: Routledge.<br />

McLellan, Gregor (1982), ‘E.P. Thompson <strong>and</strong> the discipline of historical context’, in Making Histories:<br />

Studies in History Writing <strong>and</strong> Politics, edited by Richard Johnson, London: Hutchinson.<br />

McRobbie, Angela (1992), ‘Post-Marxism <strong>and</strong> cultural studies: a post-script’, in <strong>Cultural</strong> Studies,<br />

edited by Lawrence Grossberg, Cary Nelson <strong>and</strong> Paula Treichler, London: Routledge.


Bibliography 249<br />

McRobbie, Angela (1994), Postmodernism <strong>and</strong> <strong>Popular</strong> <strong>Culture</strong>, London: Routledge.<br />

Medhurst, Andy (1999), ‘Teaching queerly: politics, pedagogy <strong>and</strong> identity in lesbian <strong>and</strong> gay<br />

studies’, in Teaching <strong>Culture</strong>: The Long Revolution in <strong>Cultural</strong> Studies, Leicester: NIACE Press.<br />

Melly, George (1989), Revolt into Style: Pop Arts in the 50s <strong>and</strong> 60s, Oxford: Oxford University<br />

Press.<br />

Mercer, Kobena (1994), Welcome to the Jungle: New Positions in Black <strong>Cultural</strong> Studies, London:<br />

Routledge.<br />

Mills, Sara (2004), Discourse, 2nd edn, London: Routledge.<br />

Modleski, Tania (1982), Loving with a Vengeance: Mass Produced Fantasies for Women, Hamden,<br />

Connecticut: Archon Books.<br />

Morley, David (1980), The Nationwide Audience, London: BFI.<br />

Morley, David (1986), Family Television: <strong>Cultural</strong> Power <strong>and</strong> Domestic Leisure, London: Comedia.<br />

Morris, R.J. (1979), Class <strong>and</strong> Class Consciousness in the Industrial Revolution 1780–1850, London:<br />

Macmillan.<br />

Mouffe, Chantal (1981), ‘Hegemony <strong>and</strong> ideology in Gramsci’, in <strong>Culture</strong>, Ideology <strong>and</strong> Social<br />

Process, edited by Tony Bennett, Colin Mercer <strong>and</strong> Janet Woollacott, Milton Keynes: Open<br />

University Press.<br />

Mulvey, Laura (1975), ‘Visual pleasure <strong>and</strong> narrative cinema’, in Screen, 16: 3.<br />

Myers, Tony (2003), Slavoj YiZek, London: Routledge.<br />

Neale, R.S. (1987), ‘E.P. Thompson: a history of culture <strong>and</strong> culturalist history’, in Creating<br />

<strong>Culture</strong>, edited by Diane J. Austin Broos, London: Allen & Unwin.<br />

Nederveen Pieterse, J. (1995), ‘Globalisation as hybridisation’, in International Sociology, 9:2,<br />

161–84.<br />

New Left Review (eds) (1977), Aesthetics <strong>and</strong> Politics, London: Verso.<br />

Newton, Esther (1972), Mother Camp: Female Impersonators in America, Englewood Cliffs: Prentice<br />

Hall.<br />

Newton, Esther (1999), ‘Role models’, in Camp: Queer Aesthetics <strong>and</strong> the Performing Subject: A<br />

Reader, edited by Fabio Cleto, Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.<br />

Nixon, Richard (1986), No More Vietnams, London: W H Allen.<br />

Nixon, Sean (1996), Hard Looks: Masculinities, Spectatorship <strong>and</strong> Contemporary Consumption,<br />

London: UCL Press.<br />

Nowell-Smith, Geoffrey (1987), ‘<strong>Popular</strong> culture’, New Formations, 2.<br />

O’Connor, Alan (1989) Raymond Williams: Writing, <strong>Culture</strong>, Politics, Oxford: Basil Blackwell.<br />

Parker, Ian (2004), Slavoj YiZek: A Critical Introduction, London: Pluto Press.<br />

Perryman, Neil (2009), ‘Doctor Who <strong>and</strong> the convergence of media’, in <strong>Cultural</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>Popular</strong> <strong>Culture</strong>: A Reader, 4th edn, edited by John Storey, Harlow: Pearson Education.<br />

Pilger, John (1990), Vietnam movies, in Weekend Guardian, 24–5 February.<br />

Polan, Dana (1988), ‘Complexity <strong>and</strong> contradiction in mass culture analysis: on Ien Ang<br />

Watching Dallas’, Camera Obscura, 16.<br />

Porter, Roy (1990), The Enlightenment, Basingstoke: Macmillan.<br />

Propp, Vladimir (1968), The Morphology of the Folktale, Austin: Texas University Press.<br />

Radway, Janice (1987), Reading the Romance: Women, Patriarchy, <strong>and</strong> <strong>Popular</strong> Literature, London: Verso.<br />

Radway, Janice (1994), ‘Romance <strong>and</strong> the work of fantasy: struggles over feminine sexuality <strong>and</strong><br />

subjectivity at the century’s end’, in Viewing, Reading, Listening: Audiences <strong>and</strong> <strong>Cultural</strong><br />

Reception, edited by Jon Cruz <strong>and</strong> Justin Lewis, Boulder: CO Westview Press.<br />

Rakow, Lana F. (2009), ‘Feminist approaches to popular culture: giving patriarchy its due’, in<br />

<strong>Cultural</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Popular</strong> <strong>Culture</strong>: A Reader, 4th edn, edited by John Storey, Harlow: Pearson<br />

Education.


250<br />

Bibliography<br />

Ricoeur, Paul (1981), Hermeneutics <strong>and</strong> the Human Sciences, New York: Cambridge University Press.<br />

Ritzer, G. (1999), The McDonaldization Thesis, London: Sage.<br />

Rosenberg, Bernard (1957), ‘Mass culture in America’, in Mass <strong>Culture</strong>: The <strong>Popular</strong> Arts in America,<br />

edited by Bernard Rosenberg <strong>and</strong> David Manning White, New York: Macmillan.<br />

Ross, Andrew (1989), No Respect: Intellectuals <strong>and</strong> <strong>Popular</strong> <strong>Culture</strong>, London: Routledge.<br />

Rowe, John Carlos <strong>and</strong> Berg, Rick (eds) (1991), The Vietnam War <strong>and</strong> American <strong>Culture</strong>, New York:<br />

Columbia University Press.<br />

Saeed, Amir (2009), ‘Musical jihad’, in <strong>Cultural</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Popular</strong> <strong>Culture</strong>: A Reader, 4th edn,<br />

edited by John Storey, Harlow: Pearson Education.<br />

Said, Edward (1985), Orientalism, Harmondsworth: Penguin.<br />

Said, Edward (1993), <strong>Culture</strong> <strong>and</strong> Imperialism, New York: Vintage Books.<br />

Samuel, Raphael (1981), Peoples’ History <strong>and</strong> Socialist <strong>Theory</strong>, London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.<br />

Saussure, Ferdin<strong>and</strong> de (1974), Course in General Linguistics, London: Fontana.<br />

Schiller, Herbert (1978), ‘Transnational media <strong>and</strong> national development’, in National Sovereignty<br />

<strong>and</strong> International Communication, edited by K. Nordensteng <strong>and</strong> Herbert Schiller, Norwood, NJ:<br />

Ablex.<br />

Schiller, Herbert (1979), ‘Translating media <strong>and</strong> national development’, in National Sovereignty<br />

<strong>and</strong> International Communication, edited by K. Nordenstreng <strong>and</strong> Herbert Schiller.<br />

Schudson, Michael (2009), ‘The new validation of popular culture: sense <strong>and</strong> sentimentality in<br />

academia’, in <strong>Cultural</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Popular</strong> <strong>Culture</strong>: A Reader, 4th edn, edited by John Storey,<br />

Harlow: Pearson Education.<br />

Shils, Edward (1978), ‘Mass society <strong>and</strong> its culture’, in Literary Taste, <strong>Culture</strong>, <strong>and</strong> Mass<br />

Communication, Volume I, edited by Peter Davison, Rolf Meyersohn <strong>and</strong> Edward Shils,<br />

Cambridge: Chadwyck Healey.<br />

Showalter, Elaine (1990), ‘Introduction’, in Speaking of Gender, edited by Elaine Showalter,<br />

London: Routledge.<br />

Smith, Barbara Herrnstein (1988), Contingencies of Value, Cambridge: Harvard University Press.<br />

Sontag, Susan (1966), Against Interpretation, New York: Deli.<br />

Stacey, Jackie (1994), Star Gazing: Hollywood <strong>and</strong> Female Spectatorship, London: Routledge.<br />

Stedman Jones, Gareth (1998), ‘Working-class culture <strong>and</strong> working-class politics in London,<br />

1870–1900: notes on the remaking of a working class’, in <strong>Cultural</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Popular</strong> <strong>Culture</strong>,<br />

2nd edn, edited by John Storey, Harlow: Prentice Hall.<br />

Storey, John (1985), ‘Matthew Arnold: The politics of an organic intellectual’, Literature <strong>and</strong><br />

History, 11 (2).<br />

Storey, John (1992), ‘Texts, readers, reading formations: My Poll <strong>and</strong> My Partner Joe in Manchester<br />

in 1841’, Literature <strong>and</strong> History, 1 (2).<br />

Storey, John (1994), ‘“Side-saddle on the golden calf”: Moments of utopia in American pop<br />

music <strong>and</strong> pop music culture’, in An American Half Century: Postwar <strong>Culture</strong> <strong>and</strong> Politics in the<br />

USA, edited by Michael Klein, London: Pluto Press.<br />

Storey, John (ed.) (1996), What is <strong>Cultural</strong> Studies: A Reader, London: Edward Arnold.<br />

Storey, John (1999a), <strong>Cultural</strong> Consumption <strong>and</strong> Everyday Life, London: Edward Arnold.<br />

Storey, John (1999b), ‘Postmodernism <strong>and</strong> popular culture’, in The Routledge Dictionary of<br />

Postmodernism, edited by Stuart Sim, London: Routledge.<br />

Storey, John (2001a), ‘The sixties in the nineties: Pastiche or hyperconsciousness’, in Tough Guys,<br />

Smooth Operators <strong>and</strong> Foxy Chicks, edited by Anna Gough-Yates <strong>and</strong> Bill Osgerby, London:<br />

Routledge.<br />

Storey, John (2001b), ‘The social life of opera’, in European Journal of <strong>Cultural</strong> Studies, 6:1.


Bibliography 251<br />

Storey, John (2002a), ‘Expecting rain: opera as popular culture’, in High-Pop, edited by Jim<br />

Collins, Oxford: Blackwell.<br />

Storey, John (2002b), ‘The articulation of memory <strong>and</strong> desire: from Vietnam to the war in the<br />

Persian Gulf’, in Film <strong>and</strong> <strong>Popular</strong> Memory, edited by Paul Grainge, Manchester University<br />

Press.<br />

Storey, John (2003), Inventing <strong>Popular</strong> <strong>Culture</strong>: From Folklore to Globalisation, Oxford: Blackwell.<br />

Storey, John (2004), <strong>Cultural</strong> Studies <strong>and</strong> the Study of <strong>Popular</strong> <strong>Culture</strong>, 2nd edn, Edinburgh:<br />

Edinburgh University Press.<br />

Storey, John (2005), ‘<strong>Popular</strong>’, in New Key Words: A Revised Vocabulary of <strong>Culture</strong> <strong>and</strong> Society,<br />

edited by Tony Bennett et al., Oxford: Blackwell.<br />

Storey, John (2006), ‘Inventing opera as art in nineteenth-century Manchester’, in International<br />

Journal of <strong>Cultural</strong> Studies, 9: 4.<br />

Storey, John (2008), ‘The invention of the English Christmas’, in Christmas, Ideology <strong>and</strong> <strong>Popular</strong><br />

<strong>Culture</strong>, edited by Sheila Whiteley, Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.<br />

Storey, John (2009), ‘Rockin’ hegemony: West Coast rock <strong>and</strong> Amerika’s war in Vietnam’, in<br />

<strong>Cultural</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Popular</strong> <strong>Culture</strong>: A Reader, 4th edn, edited by John Storey, Harlow: Pearson<br />

Education.<br />

Storey, John (2009b) <strong>Cultural</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Popular</strong> <strong>Culture</strong>: A Reader, 4th edn, Harlow: Pearson<br />

Education.<br />

Sturken, Marita (1997), Tangled Memories: The Vietnam War, the AIDS Epidemic, <strong>and</strong> the Politics of<br />

Remembering, Berkeley: University of California Press.<br />

Thomkins, Jane (1985), Sensational Designs: The <strong>Cultural</strong> Work of American Fiction, 1790–1860,<br />

New York: Oxford University Press.<br />

Thompson, E.P. (1976), ‘Interview’, Radical History Review, 3.<br />

Thompson, E.P. (1980), The Making of the English Working Class, Harmondsworth: Penguin.<br />

Thompson, E.P. (1995), The Poverty of <strong>Theory</strong>, 2nd edn, London: Merlin Press.<br />

Tomlinson, John (1997), ‘Internationalism, globalization <strong>and</strong> cultural imperialism’, in Media <strong>and</strong><br />

Regulation, edited by Kenneth Thompson, London: Sage.<br />

Tomlinson, John (1999), Globalization <strong>and</strong> <strong>Culture</strong>, Cambridge: Polity Press.<br />

Tong, Rosemary (1992), Feminist Thought: A Comprehensive Introduction, London: Routledge.<br />

Tumin, Melvin (1957), ‘<strong>Popular</strong> culture <strong>and</strong> the open society’, in Mass <strong>Culture</strong>: The <strong>Popular</strong> Arts<br />

in America, edited by Bernard Rosenberg <strong>and</strong> David Manning White, New York: Macmillan.<br />

Turner, Graeme (1996), British <strong>Cultural</strong> Studies: An Introduction, 2nd edn, London: Routledge.<br />

Vlastos, Stephen (1991), ‘America’s “enemy”: the absent presence in revisionist Vietnam War history’,<br />

in John Carlos Rowe <strong>and</strong> Rick Berg (eds), The Vietnam War <strong>and</strong> American <strong>Culture</strong>, New<br />

York: Columbia University Press.<br />

Volosinov, Valentin (1973), Marxism <strong>and</strong> the Philosophy of Language, New York: Seminar Press.<br />

Walby, Sylvia (1990), Theorising Patriarchy, Oxford: Blackwell.<br />

Walton, David (2008), Introducing <strong>Cultural</strong> Studies: Learning through Practice, London: Sage.<br />

Warner, Michael (1993), ‘Introduction’, in Fear of a Queer Planet, edited by Michael Warner,<br />

Minneapolis: Minnesota University Press.<br />

Webster, Duncan (1988), Looka Yonder!, London: Comedia, 1988.<br />

Webster, Duncan (2009), ‘Pessimism, optimism, pleasure: the future of cultural studies’, in<br />

<strong>Cultural</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Popular</strong> <strong>Culture</strong>: A Reader, 4th edn, edited by John Storey, Harlow: Pearson<br />

Education.<br />

West, Cornel (2009), ‘Black postmodernist practices’, in <strong>Cultural</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Popular</strong> <strong>Culture</strong>: A<br />

Reader, 4th edn, edited by John Storey, Harlow: Pearson Education.


252<br />

Bibliography<br />

White, David Manning (1957), ‘Mass culture in America: another point of view’, in Mass <strong>Culture</strong>:<br />

The <strong>Popular</strong> Arts in America, edited by Bernard Rosenberg <strong>and</strong> David Manning White, New<br />

York: Macmillan.<br />

Williams, Raymond (1957), ‘Fiction <strong>and</strong> the writing public’, Essays in Criticism, 7.<br />

Williams, Raymond (1963), <strong>Culture</strong> <strong>and</strong> Society, Harmondsworth: Penguin.<br />

Williams, Raymond (1965), The Long Revolution, Harmondsworth: Penguin.<br />

Williams, Raymond (1980), ‘Base <strong>and</strong> superstructure in Marxist cultural theory’, in Problems in<br />

Materialism <strong>and</strong> <strong>Culture</strong>, London: Verso.<br />

Williams, Raymond (1981), <strong>Culture</strong>, London: Fontana.<br />

Williams, Raymond (1983), Keywords, London: Fontana.<br />

Williams, Raymond (2009), ‘The analysis of culture’, in <strong>Cultural</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Popular</strong> <strong>Culture</strong>: A<br />

Reader, 4th edn, edited by John Storey, Harlow: Pearson Education.<br />

Williamson, Judith (1978), Decoding Advertisements, London: Marion Boyars.<br />

Willis, Paul (1990), Common <strong>Culture</strong>, Buckingham: Open University Press.<br />

Willis, Susan (1991), A Primer for Daily Life, London: Routledge.<br />

Winship, Janice (1987), Inside Women’s Magazines, London: P<strong>and</strong>ora.<br />

Wright, Will (1975), Sixguns <strong>and</strong> Society: A Structural Study of the Western, Berkeley: University of<br />

California Press.<br />

Zelizer, Barbie (1995), ‘Reading the past against the grain: the shape of memory studies’, in<br />

Critical Studies in Mass Communication, June.<br />

yizek, Slavoj (1989), The Sublime Object of Ideology, London: Verso.<br />

yizek, Slavoj (1991), Looking Awry: An Introduction to Jacques Lacan through <strong>Popular</strong> <strong>Culture</strong>,<br />

Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.<br />

yizek, Slavoj (1992), Enjoy Your Symptom: Jacques Lacan in Hollywood <strong>and</strong> Out, London: Routledge.<br />

yizek, Slavoj (2009), ‘From reality to the real’, in <strong>Cultural</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Popular</strong> <strong>Culture</strong>: A Reader,<br />

4th edn, edited by John Storey, Harlow: Pearson Education.


Index<br />

Adams, William, 178<br />

Adorno, Theodor, 62–7, 69–70<br />

advertisements<br />

Althusserianism, 73–4<br />

art, reproduction of, 65<br />

cars, 73–4<br />

consumption, distinctions based on, 79<br />

ideology, 78–9<br />

interpellation, 78–9<br />

language, debasement of, 24–6<br />

Leavisism, 24–6<br />

mob, 25<br />

music, 12, 65, 66<br />

symptomatic advertising, 72–3<br />

women’s magazines, reading, 154<br />

aesthetics, 219–21<br />

agency <strong>and</strong> structure, dialectic between, 61<br />

Alloway, Lawrenjce, 183<br />

Althusser, Louis, 4–5, 57, 70–9, 111, 128<br />

Althusserianism, 70–9, 128<br />

American culture see also American westerns<br />

counterculture, 85–6, 184<br />

countercurrents, 207–8<br />

Dallas (television), watching, 147<br />

definition of popular culture, 8–9<br />

dream to be American, 117, 208<br />

imperialism, 147<br />

mass culture, 28–33, 52<br />

monolithic, assumption that American<br />

culture is, 207–8<br />

postmodernism, 204–8<br />

Vietnam war, representations of, 174–7<br />

American Westerns, 115–18<br />

American Dream, 117<br />

binary oppositions, 115–16<br />

classic, vengeance, transition <strong>and</strong><br />

professional themes, 115–18<br />

myths, 115–16<br />

narrative functions, 115–16<br />

oppositions, structuring, 116<br />

society <strong>and</strong> community, 117–18<br />

‘Analysis of <strong>Culture</strong>’, 44–8, 57<br />

anarchy, popular culture as, 19–22<br />

Ang, Ien, 146–53, 208–9, 215, 234<br />

Apocalypse Now (film), 172, 187<br />

Arnold, Malcolm, 51–2<br />

Arnold, Matthew, 8, 14, 18–23, 27, 44, 48,<br />

62, 63, 70, 81, 183, 201, 214<br />

art<br />

advertisements, 65<br />

mass art, 54<br />

museum art, 219<br />

pop art, 183–4<br />

popular art within popular culture, 53<br />

reproduction, 65<br />

working class, real art <strong>and</strong>, 183–4<br />

articulation, 84–5, 200–1<br />

audience<br />

commodity, as, 217<br />

fan cultures, 223–6<br />

industrialization <strong>and</strong> urbanization, 63–4<br />

performer, relationship with, 53–4<br />

politics of the popular, 217, 223–6<br />

producer of meanings <strong>and</strong> pleasures, as,<br />

217<br />

Austin, JL, 161<br />

authenticity, 8, 12, 62–4, 66–7, 69<br />

authority, collapse of, 23, 26–7<br />

avant-garde, 184<br />

Barbarians, Philistines <strong>and</strong> Populace,<br />

19–20<br />

Barber, Samuel. Adagio for Strings, 175<br />

Barrett, Michèle, 136<br />

Barthes, Rol<strong>and</strong>, 4, 111, 113, 118–25, 126,<br />

224


254<br />

Index<br />

base/superstructure formulation, 59–61,<br />

70–1, 233<br />

Baudrillard, Jean, 182, 186–91<br />

Beatles (group), 184, 197<br />

Beethoven, Ludwig van, 53, 56<br />

Bell, Daniel, 196<br />

Benjamin, Walter, 62–3, 68, 70, 187<br />

Bennett, Tony, 1, 10–11, 13–14, 27, 65<br />

Bentham, Jeremy, 131–2<br />

Bernstein, JM, 70<br />

Best, Steven, 186<br />

Big Brother (TV show), 132–3<br />

binary oppositions, 115–16, 127–8<br />

biological sex <strong>and</strong> gender, 160–3<br />

Blake, Peter, 184<br />

Bloch, Joseph, 60<br />

Bourdieu, Pierre, 6, 152, 202–3, 216, 218–20<br />

Bourne, George, 26<br />

Br<strong>and</strong>o, Marlon, 187<br />

Brecht, Bertolt, 4, 63, 107<br />

bricolage, 198–9<br />

British underground scene, 184<br />

Broadhurst, Thomas, 77<br />

Brogan, DW, 31–2<br />

Brooker, Peter, 193–4<br />

Brooker, Will, 193–4<br />

Brooks, Peter, 149<br />

Brundson, Charlotte, 146<br />

Burston, Paul, 160<br />

Bush, George HW, 176–8<br />

Butler, Judith, 160–3<br />

Canaan, Joyce, 159–60<br />

capitalism<br />

American counter-culture, music of, 85–6<br />

articulation, 85–6<br />

consumption, 228–31<br />

feminisms, 135<br />

Frankfurt School, 65, 68, 70<br />

hegemony, 80<br />

mass culture, ideology of, 234<br />

politics of the popular, 216, 228–32<br />

postmodernism, 191, 194, 195–6, 204–5<br />

work <strong>and</strong> leisure, 65<br />

Carey, James, 2<br />

Caribbean, language <strong>and</strong> British hegemony in<br />

the, 80<br />

Carlyle, Thomas, 13, 171<br />

Cartl<strong>and</strong>, Barbara, 147, 200<br />

Casualties of War (film), 173<br />

CCTV, 132–3<br />

celebrity surveillance magazines, 133<br />

Centre for Contemporary <strong>Cultural</strong> Sides, 57<br />

certainties, 190, 192–3, 214–15<br />

Chamberlain, Joseph, 171<br />

Chambers, Iain, 186<br />

Chartism, 18<br />

Chinn, Sarah E, 162<br />

Chodorow, Nancy, 143–5<br />

Christmas, invention of the traditional, 61<br />

cine-psychoanalysis, 104–7<br />

civilization<br />

culture <strong>and</strong> civilization tradition, 18–35,<br />

37, 70<br />

education, 20<br />

Freudian psychoanalysis, 91<br />

working class culture as anarchy, 20<br />

Clark, Michael, 178<br />

Clarke, Gary, 226<br />

Clash (group), 10, 197<br />

class 19–21 see also working class<br />

common experience of class, 49<br />

definition of popular culture, 6, 13<br />

intellectuals as organizers, 81<br />

mass culture in America, 33<br />

politics of the popular, 218–19, 231<br />

postmodernism, 202–3<br />

residential separation of class, 13<br />

ruling classes, intellectual force of the, 61<br />

segregation, 13, 17<br />

taste, 219<br />

classical music, 55–6, 65, 66<br />

clerisy, notion of the, 21<br />

Coca-Cola, 204<br />

Cocker, Jarvis, 107<br />

Cold War, 33<br />

Coleridge, Samuel Taylor, 21<br />

collective dream world, popular culture as,<br />

9<br />

Collins, Jim, 193–4, 198–200<br />

colonialism <strong>and</strong> imperialism, 76–7, 80–1,<br />

119–22, 168, 170–1<br />

commercial culture, definition of popular<br />

culture as, 6, 8, 9–10<br />

commodities, 64–5, 217, 228–34<br />

communal <strong>and</strong> self-made entertainment, 40


community<br />

American westerns, 117–18<br />

loss of organic communities, 8, 26–7<br />

sense of community, 39–40<br />

women’s magazines, imagined<br />

communities <strong>and</strong>, 155<br />

conduct books, 77<br />

conformity, 62, 64<br />

Connor, Steven, 185–6<br />

connotation <strong>and</strong> denotation, 118–19, 123,<br />

148–9<br />

conscience, 92–3<br />

Conservative Party, 119<br />

consumption<br />

advertisements, 79<br />

capitalism, 228–31<br />

definition of popular culture, 6, 8<br />

economic field, 227<br />

fan cultures, 223<br />

Frankfurt School, 68, 69–70<br />

hegemony, 81–2, 233–4<br />

mass culture, ideology of, 234–5<br />

mythologies, 119<br />

passivity, 88<br />

poaching, 222<br />

politics of the popular, 214–16, 221–3,<br />

227<br />

pop music, 68<br />

production, 232<br />

Queer <strong>Theory</strong>, 163<br />

Vietnam war, representations of, 176,<br />

178<br />

women’s magazines, reading, 154, 157<br />

youth culture, 81–2<br />

convergence culture, 210–11<br />

Coronation Street (television), 188–9<br />

counterculture, 85–6, 184<br />

Coward, Rosalind, 140–1, 143<br />

Creekmur, Corey K, 163<br />

critical theory, 62<br />

culturalism, 37–58<br />

<strong>Culture</strong> <strong>and</strong> Anarchy. Matthew Arnold,<br />

18–20<br />

culture <strong>and</strong> civilization tradition, 18–35, 70<br />

culture, definition of 1–2, 44–5<br />

culture shock, 87<br />

Curtin, Philip, 171<br />

customs <strong>and</strong> rituals, 5<br />

Daily Telegraph, 122<br />

Dallas (television), watching, 147–53, 156,<br />

217<br />

American cultural imperialism, 147<br />

denotation <strong>and</strong> connotation, 148–9<br />

feminism, 147, 152<br />

ideology of mass culture, 149–53<br />

irony, 150–1<br />

melodramatic imagination, 149<br />

pleasure, 147–9, 150–3<br />

populism, ideology of, 151–2<br />

psychoanalysis, 152<br />

realism, 148–9<br />

Dances with Wolves (film), 117–18, 128<br />

Dante Alighieri, 30<br />

David-Neel, Alex<strong>and</strong>ra, 77<br />

de Beauvoir, Simone, 160–1<br />

de Certeau, Michel, 222–4<br />

definition of culture, 44–5<br />

definition of popular culture 1–2, 3–13<br />

democracy, 24, 65<br />

denotation <strong>and</strong> connotation, 118–19, 123,<br />

148–9<br />

Derrida, Jacques, 126–8<br />

Descartes, Rene, 103<br />

Desert Isl<strong>and</strong> Discs, 107<br />

desire, 105, 108–9, 141<br />

Dickens, Charles, 9<br />

différance, 126–7<br />

discipline, social control <strong>and</strong>, 132<br />

discourse <strong>and</strong> power, 128–33<br />

discipline, 132<br />

film as an object of study, 129<br />

hierarchical criss-crossing of discourses,<br />

129<br />

knowledge, 128, 130<br />

language, 128–9<br />

panoptic machine, 131–3<br />

post-Marxism, 83–4<br />

sexuality, 129–30<br />

social practices, 129<br />

surveillance, 131–3<br />

truth, 130<br />

Disneyl<strong>and</strong>, 190–1<br />

Disraeli, Benjamin, 18<br />

Dittmar, Linda, 175<br />

diversity, 185<br />

Docker, John, 191<br />

Index 255


256<br />

Index<br />

Doctor Who (television), 210–11, 224–5<br />

Doty, Alex<strong>and</strong>er, 163–4<br />

drag, 162<br />

dreams<br />

American dream, 117, 208<br />

censorship, 84<br />

collective dream world, popular culture as,<br />

9<br />

dream-distortion, 95–6<br />

Freudian psychoanalysis, 93–100<br />

interpretation, 93–100<br />

manifest <strong>and</strong> latent content, 94–5<br />

sexual symbols, 96<br />

dumbing down, elitism <strong>and</strong>, 234<br />

Dvorak, Antonin, 65<br />

Dyer, Richard, 68, 138<br />

Dylan, Bob, 184<br />

Eagleton, Terry, 107, 111<br />

Earle, Steve, 187<br />

Easthope, Antony, 159<br />

Eco, Umberto, 200<br />

economy<br />

Althusserianism, 70–1<br />

development, 186<br />

economic determinism, 60–1<br />

economic field, 213–15, 226–32<br />

financial economy, 216–18<br />

hegemony, 232–3<br />

ideological practices, 70<br />

Marxism, 60–1<br />

politics of the popular, 213–15,<br />

226–32<br />

social formation, 70<br />

success <strong>and</strong> cultural imposition, 204–5<br />

education, 20, 40–1, 51–3, 220–3<br />

ego, 92–3, 102<br />

elite, 13, 21–2, 183, 234<br />

Empire (magazine), 124<br />

employee <strong>and</strong> employer relationships,<br />

13<br />

Engels, Frederick, 60–1, 196<br />

entertainment, women’s magazines <strong>and</strong>,<br />

153–4<br />

entrepreneurs, 17<br />

escapism, 137–9, 144–5<br />

Estwick, Samuel, 169<br />

European avant-garde, 184<br />

everyday life<br />

construction of, 12<br />

ideology, 4–5<br />

practices of, 4–5<br />

exclusion <strong>and</strong> inclusion, 34<br />

Faith, Adam, 52<br />

family history research, 209<br />

fan cultures, 223–6<br />

fantasy, 107–9, 142–4<br />

Fekete, John, 203<br />

femininity, 154<br />

feminisms, 135–7<br />

capitalism, 135<br />

cine-psychoanalysis, 104–7<br />

Dallas (television), watching, 147, 152<br />

dual-systems theory, 135<br />

film studies, 104–7, 137<br />

gender, 135<br />

hegemony, 11<br />

intervention, politics of, 137<br />

masculinities, 159–60<br />

meaning, 136<br />

patriarchy, 135<br />

pleasure, destruction of, 105, 106–7<br />

post-feminism, 155–6<br />

romantic fiction, reading, 140–7<br />

scopophilia (pleasure of looking), 105–7<br />

sexual objectification, 105–6<br />

them <strong>and</strong> us, politics of, 146<br />

types of feminism, 135<br />

women’s magazines, reading, 153, 155–6<br />

fiction<br />

Leavisism, 24<br />

moral tone, lack of, 42<br />

romantic fiction, reading, 140–7<br />

Fiedler, Leslie, 32–3, 182<br />

film studies, women <strong>and</strong>, 136–40<br />

consumption, 137, 139–40<br />

escapism, 137–9<br />

feminism, 137<br />

Hollywood stars, alternative femininity of,<br />

139–40<br />

identification, 137, 139<br />

imagined community, 138<br />

patriarchy, 139–40<br />

psychoanalysis, 137, 139, 140<br />

utopian sensibilities, 138


films see also American westerns<br />

Cantonese Kung Fu films, 208–9<br />

cine-psychoanalysis, 104–7<br />

false realism, 193<br />

film noir, 6, 10, 106<br />

Frankfurt School, 62<br />

genericity, 193–4<br />

nostalgia, 192–3<br />

object of study, as, 129<br />

postmodernism, 192–4, 208–9<br />

schizophrenia, 193<br />

Vietnam war, representations of, 173–6,<br />

178<br />

women, 136–40<br />

Fiske, John 8, 12, 189, 215–18, 227<br />

folk culture, 8, 30–1, 40, 53<br />

football, 113–14<br />

foreign, concept of the, 205–7<br />

Foucault, Michel, 111, 128–33, 173<br />

Four Tops (group), 201–2<br />

France<br />

imperialism, 76–7, 119–22<br />

mythologies, 118–25<br />

Frankfurt School<br />

authenticity, 62–4, 66, 69<br />

capitalism, 65, 68, 70<br />

commodification, 64–5<br />

conformity, 62, 64<br />

consumption, 68, 69–70<br />

critical theory, 62<br />

culture <strong>and</strong> civilization tradition, 70<br />

democratization of culture, 65<br />

Leavisism, 62, 63, 70<br />

Marxism, 62–70<br />

mass culture, culture industry <strong>and</strong>, 62–5,<br />

68–70<br />

pop music, 65–8<br />

postmodernism, 194–5<br />

production, mode of 68–70<br />

texts <strong>and</strong> practices, culture of, 68–9<br />

work <strong>and</strong> leisure under capitalism, 65<br />

Franklin, Aretha, 163<br />

Freud, Sigmund 75, 91–101, 103, 105–8, 190<br />

Freudian psychoanalysis, 91–101, 103,<br />

105–6<br />

civilization, 91<br />

conflict, 93<br />

conscience, 92–3<br />

displacement, 94–5<br />

dreams, interpretation of, 93–100<br />

ego, super-ego <strong>and</strong> id, 92–3<br />

human nature, 93<br />

language, 96<br />

Oedipus complex, 92–3, 97<br />

pleasure principle <strong>and</strong> reality principle, 93<br />

psyche, model of the, 91–3<br />

repression, 91, 93<br />

sexual drives, 91<br />

symbolization, 95–6<br />

text analysis, 97–101<br />

unconscious, 91–2, 94–5<br />

Frith, Simon, 8, 68, 69, 188, 211<br />

Fryer, Peter, 169<br />

Gamman, Lorraine, 137<br />

Garnham, Nicholas, 214, 218<br />

Gasset, Ortega Y, 220<br />

gender see also feminisms<br />

film studies, women <strong>and</strong>, 136–40<br />

Queer <strong>Theory</strong>, 160–3<br />

Gilroy, Paul, 167–8, 179–80<br />

Gledhill, Christine, 137<br />

global postmodernism, 203–9<br />

golden age, 26<br />

Golding, Peter, 227<br />

Goodwin, Andrew, 197<br />

Gosse, Edmund, 23–4<br />

Gramsci, Antonio, 10, 55, 57, 79–82, 209,<br />

213–14, 233–4<br />

Green, Michael, 57<br />

Greenberg, Clement, 52<br />

Griffin, Christine, 159–60<br />

Grimm, Jacob <strong>and</strong> Wilhelm, 100<br />

Grossberg, Lawrence, 191, 195, 225–6<br />

Guevara, Che, 65<br />

Gulf War 1991, Vietnam <strong>and</strong>, 176–7<br />

Haag, Ernest van den, 30–1<br />

Hall, Stuart, 4, 8, 11, 37, 44, 48, 50–6, 57, 70,<br />

83–4, 86–8, 168, 208–9, 232–3<br />

Hamilton, Richard, 184<br />

Harvey, David, 82<br />

Hawkes, Terence, 114<br />

Heart of Darkness, 172<br />

Hebdige, Dick, 14, 81, 181–2<br />

Hegel, GWH, 107<br />

Index 257


258<br />

Index<br />

hegemony<br />

articulation, 11<br />

base-superstructure model, 233<br />

capitalism, 80<br />

class organizers, intellectuals as, 81<br />

commodities, 233<br />

compromise equilibrium, 10–11<br />

consensus, 80<br />

consumption, 81–2, 233–4<br />

definition of popular culture, 10–12<br />

economic conditions, 232–3<br />

feminisms, 11<br />

ideological state apparatuses, 81<br />

intellectuals, social function of organic, 81<br />

language, 80–1<br />

Marxism, 79–82, 84, 87, 232–4<br />

negotiated mix, popular culture as, 80–1<br />

political economy, 232–3<br />

politics of the popular, 214, 216, 227–9,<br />

232–4<br />

post-Marxist cultural studies, 84, 87,<br />

232–4<br />

postmodernism, 209, 233<br />

production, 233–4<br />

repressive state analysis, 81<br />

semiotic use of concept, 12<br />

subordinate groups <strong>and</strong> classes, concessions<br />

to, 80–1<br />

truth, 87<br />

youth subcultures, 55, 81–2<br />

Hermes, Joke 156–9<br />

heterosexuality, institution of, 161<br />

high culture<br />

definition of popular culture, 6–7, 12<br />

devaluation, 6–7<br />

education, 220<br />

mass culture in America, 30–1<br />

merger with popular culture, 183–4, 194–5,<br />

203<br />

politics of the popular, 220<br />

postmodernism, 12<br />

superiority, 52<br />

what is left over after high culture, pop<br />

culture as, 6<br />

Highsmith, Patricia, 108<br />

Hill Street Blues (television), 217<br />

hip hop, 205–6<br />

history, Marxist conception of, 59–60<br />

Hoggart, Richard, 37, 38–43, 48, 51, 56, 57<br />

homogeneity, 62<br />

hooks, bell, 135–6<br />

Horkheimer, Max, 62, 63–4<br />

Horne, Howard, 188, 211<br />

Hulme, David, 170<br />

Hunt, James, 171<br />

Huyssen, Andreas, 183–4<br />

hyperrealism, 187–91<br />

ideal, 44, 167–8<br />

ideology, 2–5<br />

advertisements, 78–9<br />

Althusserianism, 70–2, 76–9<br />

conflict, 4<br />

definitions, 2–3, 71–2, 78–9<br />

distortions, 3<br />

everyday life, practices of, 4–5<br />

hegemony, 81<br />

ideological forms, 4<br />

Ideological State Apparatuses (ISAs), 78<br />

mass culture, 149–53, 234–5<br />

material practice, ideology as a, 4–5<br />

misrecognition, 79<br />

modification, 76–7<br />

pleasure, 146<br />

politics of the popular, 220<br />

populism, 151–2<br />

practice, as, 71<br />

presentation <strong>and</strong> figuration, 76–7<br />

race <strong>and</strong> racism, 168–71<br />

romantic fiction, reading, 145–6<br />

romantic love, 104<br />

social formation, 71<br />

social order, rituals <strong>and</strong> customs binding<br />

people to, 5<br />

socialism, 4<br />

state apparatuses, 81<br />

structuralism, 9<br />

subordination, 3<br />

taste, 220<br />

truth, 76<br />

unconsciousness of the text, 76<br />

Imaginary, 102, 103–4<br />

imagined communities, women’s magazines<br />

<strong>and</strong>, 155<br />

imperialism, 76–7, 119–22, 168, 170–2<br />

inclusion <strong>and</strong> exclusion, 34


industrialization <strong>and</strong> urbanization, 12–13,<br />

17–18, 21, 26–7, 53–4, 65<br />

intellectuals, 28, 33, 81, 186<br />

irony, 150–1<br />

Jam (group), 10<br />

Jameson, Fredric, 59, 82, 182–3, 191–7, 200<br />

jazz, 55–6<br />

Jeffords, Susan, 174<br />

Jenkins, Henry, 210, 223–5<br />

Jenson, Joli, 223–5<br />

Johnny Guitar (film), 117<br />

Johnson, LB, 177<br />

Johnson, Richard, 37, 51<br />

Johnston, Harry, 171<br />

judgement, absolutist criteria of, 214–15<br />

Kellner, Douglas, 186<br />

Kemp, Fraser, 188<br />

King, Rodney, 187–8<br />

Klein, Michael, 176<br />

knowledge, 18, 22<br />

discourse, 128, 130<br />

Orientalism, 171<br />

power, as, 130<br />

science, 185<br />

sexuality, 130<br />

signification, 124–5<br />

women’s magazines, reading, 158<br />

Knox, Robert, 171<br />

kung fu films, 208–9<br />

LA Law (television), 188<br />

Lacan, Jacques, 101–4, 105, 107–9, 111, 193<br />

Lacanian psychoanalysis, 101–4, 105, 107–9,<br />

111<br />

Lack, Lacanian psychoanalysis <strong>and</strong>, 101–2<br />

Laclau, Ernesto, 83, 86, 196–7<br />

Lang, Jack, 147<br />

language<br />

advertising, 24–6<br />

Caribbean, British hegemony in the, 80<br />

debasement of language, 24–6<br />

diachronic approach to linguistics, 113<br />

differences, marking, 111–12<br />

discourse <strong>and</strong> power, 128–9<br />

Freudian psychoanalysis, 96<br />

hegemony, 80–1<br />

langue <strong>and</strong> parole, 113, 114<br />

Leavisism, 24–6<br />

meaningfulness, 112<br />

Queer <strong>Theory</strong>, 161–2<br />

reality, 112–13<br />

relational theory, 111–12<br />

signifier <strong>and</strong> signified, 111<br />

structuralism, 111–14<br />

substitution, 112<br />

synchronic approach to linguistics, 113<br />

syntagmatic axis of language, 112<br />

Lawrence, DH, 39<br />

Leavisism, 22–8, 32, 40, 43–4, 52–3, 56–7<br />

advertising, 24–6<br />

‘Analysis of <strong>Culture</strong>’, 47–8<br />

authority, collapse of, 23, 26–7<br />

culturalism, 37<br />

democracy, 24<br />

fiction, 24<br />

Frankfurt School, 62, 63, 70<br />

golden age, 26<br />

ideal, 44<br />

industrialization, 26–7<br />

language, 24–5<br />

left-Leavisism, 37<br />

literature, authority of, 27<br />

mass civilization <strong>and</strong> culture, 24, 27<br />

minority, culture in keeping of, 23–4<br />

organic community, loss of, 26–7<br />

suburbanism, 27<br />

working class, 50<br />

Levi jeans, 10<br />

Lévi-Strauss, Claude, 111, 114–18<br />

Light, Alison, 147–8<br />

lived cultures or practices, 2, 46<br />

locals <strong>and</strong> dominant culture, 206–8<br />

Long, Edward, 169<br />

Lovell, Terry, 229<br />

Lowenthal, Leo, 62, 63<br />

Lynch, David, 199<br />

Lyotard, Jean-François, 182, 184–6, 190<br />

MacDonald, Dwight, 29–31<br />

Macherey, Pierre, 74–7, 111<br />

magazines<br />

celebrity surveillance, 133<br />

Frankfurt School, 62<br />

women’s magazines, reading, 153–9<br />

Index 259


260<br />

Index<br />

make-over <strong>and</strong> talk shows, 133<br />

Making of the English Working Class. EP<br />

Thompson, 49–51<br />

Maltby, Richard, 9<br />

M<strong>and</strong>el, Ernest, 191<br />

Marcuse, Herbert, 63, 64, 65, 195<br />

Marley, Bob, 85<br />

Marshment, Margaret, 137<br />

Marx, Karl <strong>and</strong> Marxisms, 3, 50–1, 59–89,<br />

107, 140, 149, 190–7, 229, 232–4<br />

see also post-Marxism <strong>and</strong> cultural studies<br />

masculinities, 87, 141, 143–5, 159–60<br />

mass culture, 21–2<br />

aesthetic-liberal position, 28<br />

America, in, 28–33, 52<br />

art, 54<br />

capitalism, 65, 234<br />

class, 33<br />

commodities, 234<br />

conformity, 62, 64<br />

consumption, 234–5<br />

corporate-liberal position, 28<br />

definition of popular culture, 6, 8–9, 12<br />

dumbing down, elitism <strong>and</strong>, 234<br />

films, radio <strong>and</strong> magazines, 62<br />

folk culture, 30–1<br />

Frankfurt School, 62–5, 68–70<br />

high culture, 30–1<br />

homogeneity, 62<br />

ideology, 149–53, 234–5<br />

impoverishment, 31<br />

intellectuals, 28, 33<br />

Leavisism, 24, 27<br />

pleasure <strong>and</strong> politics, 234<br />

politics of the popular, 234–5<br />

postmodernism, 196–7<br />

production, 6, 8–9, 12, 234–5<br />

radical or socialist position, 28<br />

reproduction, 68–9<br />

romantic fiction, reading, 140<br />

Soviet Union, 29–30<br />

superior or refined culture, mediocre<br />

culture <strong>and</strong> brutal culture, 32–3<br />

work <strong>and</strong> leisure under capitalism, 65<br />

working class, 38–42<br />

Matisse, Henri, 65<br />

McGuigan, Jim, 213–16, 226–7<br />

McLellan, Gregor, 50<br />

McNamara, Robert, 177–8<br />

McRobbie, Angela, 82, 181, 186, 233<br />

meanings, 74, 86–7, 126–7, 136, 217<br />

media ownership, concentration of, 210<br />

Michaud, Gene, 175<br />

milk bars, 42–3<br />

Mills, Sara, 77<br />

mirror stage, psychoanalysis <strong>and</strong>, 101–2,<br />

105–6<br />

modernism, 182–5, 190, 191, 194, 197–8,<br />

203<br />

Modleski, Tania, 140<br />

Morley, David, 11<br />

morphemes, 114–15<br />

Mouffe, Chantal, 11, 83–4, 86, 196–7<br />

Mulvey, Laura, 104–7, 136–7<br />

Murdock, Graham, 227<br />

music see also pop music<br />

advertisements, 65, 66<br />

classical music, 55–6, 65, 66<br />

folk songs, 40<br />

jazz, 55–6<br />

opera <strong>and</strong> classical music, 65, 66<br />

music hall, 53, 61<br />

mythemes, 114–15<br />

Mythologies. Rol<strong>and</strong> Barthes, 118–25<br />

myths, 118–25<br />

American Dream, 117<br />

American westerns, 115–16<br />

binary oppositions, 115–16<br />

grammar, 114–15<br />

narrative structure, 115–16<br />

similarity <strong>and</strong> difference, 115–16<br />

structuralism, 114–16<br />

naïve gaze <strong>and</strong> pure gaze, 219–20<br />

narcissism, 105–6<br />

narrative <strong>and</strong> spectacle, moments of, 106<br />

Nixon, Richard, 176–7<br />

Nixon, Sean, 159<br />

nostalgia, 38, 192–3<br />

Nowell-Smith, Geoffrey, 14<br />

O’Connor, Alan, 44<br />

Oedipus complex, 92–3, 97, 103–4, 141–2,<br />

143<br />

opera, 65, 66<br />

organic communities, loss of, 8, 26–7


Orientalism, 171–8<br />

other/otherness, 1, 13–14, 33–5<br />

ownership of media, concentration of, 210<br />

panoptic machine, 131–3<br />

Paris Match (magazine), 119–22<br />

Paris, Texas (film), 104<br />

Parker, Ian, 107<br />

parody, 192<br />

passive listening, promotion of, 67<br />

pastiche, 192–4, 198<br />

patriarchy, 135, 139–40, 144, 145, 153,<br />

160<br />

Pavarotti, Luciano, 6–7, 203<br />

Perryman, Neil, 210–11<br />

phonemes, 114–15<br />

photographs, text accompanying, 122–3<br />

Pieterse, Jan Nederveen, 207–8<br />

Platoon (film), 173, 174–6, 178<br />

pleasure<br />

audience as producer of pleasures, 217<br />

Dallas (television), watching, 147–9,<br />

150–3<br />

destruction of pleasure, 105, 106–7<br />

feminist psychoanalysis, 105, 106–7<br />

Freudian psychoanalysis, 93<br />

ideological function of pleasure, 146<br />

mass culture, ideology of, 234<br />

politics, 234<br />

romantic fiction, reading, 146<br />

scopophilia (pleasure of looking), 105–7<br />

pluralism of value, 201–3<br />

poaching, 222, 225<br />

Polan, Dana, 152–3<br />

politics see also politics of the popular<br />

Althusserianism, 70<br />

definition of popular culture, 10–11<br />

economy, 213–15, 226–33<br />

hegemony, 232–3<br />

mass culture, ideology of, 234<br />

pleasure, 234<br />

psychoanalysis, 105<br />

politics of the popular, 213–36<br />

aesthetics, 219–21<br />

audience, 217, 223–6<br />

capitalism, 216, 228–32<br />

certainties, 214–15<br />

class, 218–19, 231<br />

commodities, 228–32<br />

consumption, 214–16, 221–3, 228–32<br />

cultural field, 216–26<br />

dominant <strong>and</strong> dominates, 219–20<br />

economic field, 213–15, 226–32<br />

education, 220–3<br />

fan cultures, 223–6<br />

financial economy, 216–18<br />

hegemony, 214, 216, 227–9, 232–4<br />

high culture, education <strong>and</strong>, 220<br />

influence of culture industries, 232<br />

interpretation, 216<br />

judgement, absolutist criteria of, 214–15<br />

mass culture, ideology of, 234–5<br />

museum art, 219<br />

naïve gaze <strong>and</strong> pure gaze, 219–20<br />

new revisionism, 216<br />

paradigm crisis in cultural studies,<br />

213–16<br />

poaching 222, 225<br />

political economy of culture, 213–15,<br />

226–32<br />

post-Marxism cultural studies, 232–4<br />

postmodernism, uncertainties of, 214<br />

power, 220, 232<br />

production, 221–2, 224–5, 231<br />

semiotic <strong>and</strong> social resistance to power,<br />

217–18<br />

taste, 219, 220<br />

texts <strong>and</strong> practices, access to, 227<br />

textual determinism, 222–4<br />

youth subcultures, 225–6<br />

pop art, 183–4<br />

pop music, 54–7<br />

advertisements, 12, 65, 66<br />

American counterculture, 85–6<br />

authenticity, 67<br />

capitalism, 85–6<br />

classical music, 55–6<br />

consumption, 68<br />

Frankfurt School, 65–8<br />

gay consumption of disco, 68<br />

hip hop, 205–6<br />

jazz, 55–6<br />

modernism, 197–8<br />

passive listening, promotion of, 67<br />

pop art, 184<br />

post-Marxist cultural studies, 85–6<br />

Index 261


262<br />

Index<br />

pop music (continued)<br />

postmodernism, 184, 197–8, 205–6<br />

profits, lack of, 68<br />

pseudo-individualization, 67–8<br />

Rastafarian reggae music 85<br />

sampling, 197<br />

social cement, as, 67, 68<br />

st<strong>and</strong>ardisation, 65–8<br />

teenagers, 54–5<br />

value <strong>and</strong> evaluation, problems of 54–6<br />

working class culture, 41–2<br />

<strong>Popular</strong> Arts. Stuart Hall <strong>and</strong> Paddy Whannel,<br />

51–6<br />

popular of popular culture, 6<br />

populism, 151–2<br />

Porter, Cole, 53<br />

post-Marxism <strong>and</strong> cultural studies, 82–8,<br />

232–4<br />

postmodernism, 181–212<br />

1960s, in the, 182–4<br />

affirmative culture, 195–6<br />

American counterculture, 184<br />

Americanisation of culture, 204–8<br />

articulation, 84–5<br />

British underground scene, 184<br />

capitalism, 191, 194, 195–6, 204–5<br />

certainty, collapse of, 190, 192–3, 214<br />

class, 202–3<br />

convergence culture, 210–11<br />

cultural diversity, 185<br />

definition, 12<br />

dominant <strong>and</strong> subordinate groups,<br />

202–3<br />

economic development, 186<br />

economic success <strong>and</strong> cultural imposition,<br />

204–5<br />

elitism, revolt against, 183<br />

European avant-garde, 184<br />

family history research, 209<br />

films, 192–4, 208–9<br />

foreign, concept of the, 205–7<br />

Frankfurt School, 194–5<br />

global postmodernism, 203–9<br />

hegemony, 209, 233<br />

high culture <strong>and</strong> popular culture,<br />

definition of popular culture, 6<br />

merging of, 183–4, 194–5, 203<br />

hip hop, 205–6<br />

historical change, 191–2<br />

hyperrealism, 187–91<br />

inclusion <strong>and</strong> exclusion, 34<br />

intellectuals, 186<br />

knowledge, status of, 185–6<br />

locals <strong>and</strong> dominant culture, 206–8<br />

Marxism or neo-Marxism, 191–7<br />

mass culture, 196–7<br />

media,<br />

consumers, 210<br />

convergence culture, 210–11<br />

ownership, concentration of, 210<br />

public <strong>and</strong>, relationship between, 189<br />

metanarratives, 185, 190<br />

modernism, 182–5, 190, 191, 194, 197–8,<br />

203<br />

monolithic, assumption that American<br />

culture is, 207–8<br />

new modernism, 185<br />

nostalgia, 190, 192, 197<br />

parody, 192<br />

passive consumption, 205<br />

pastiche, as culture of, 192–4, 198<br />

pluralism of value, 201–3<br />

police cars, simulations of, 187–8<br />

politics of the popular, 214<br />

pop art, 183–4<br />

pop music, 184, 197–8, 205–6<br />

power, 201<br />

production, 194, 201, 205<br />

real <strong>and</strong> imaginary, 187–90<br />

real art, working classes <strong>and</strong>, 183–4<br />

realism, 191, 193<br />

repetition, 191<br />

representations, 190–1<br />

reproduction, 187<br />

sampling, 197<br />

schizophrenia, 193<br />

science, knowledge <strong>and</strong>, 185<br />

selective tradition, 201–2<br />

simulacrum, as culture of the, 187<br />

simulation, 187–90<br />

st<strong>and</strong>ards, end of, 203<br />

taste, 202–3<br />

technological change, 210<br />

television, 187–9, 198–201<br />

truth, 191<br />

women’s magazines, reading, 156


post-structuralists, 9, 126–34<br />

binary opposition, 127–8<br />

black <strong>and</strong> white, 127<br />

deconstruction, 128<br />

difference, 126–7<br />

meaning, 126–7<br />

nature <strong>and</strong> culture, 127–8<br />

power, 127<br />

signification, 2, 126–7<br />

supplementarity, 127–8<br />

writing <strong>and</strong> speech, 127–8<br />

power<br />

discourse, 128–33<br />

franchise, 20<br />

industrialization <strong>and</strong> urbanization, 17<br />

knowledge, 130<br />

normalization, 132<br />

Orientalism, 172<br />

panoptic machine, 131–3<br />

people, popular culture as originating from<br />

the, 11<br />

politics of the popular, 217–18, 220, 232<br />

post-Marxist cultural studies, 87<br />

postmodernism, 201<br />

post-structuralists, 127<br />

reality, 130<br />

resistance, 130<br />

semiotic <strong>and</strong> social resistance to power,<br />

217–18<br />

primitive societies, culture of, 114–15<br />

problem pages in women’s magazines, 155<br />

problematics, 72–4, 128<br />

production<br />

consumption, 232<br />

fan cultures, 224–5<br />

Frankfurt School, 68–70<br />

hegemony, 233–4<br />

Marxism, 59–61<br />

mass culture, ideology of, 234–5<br />

modes of production, 59–61, 68–70<br />

politics of the popular, 221–2, 224–5, 231<br />

post-Marxist cultural studies, 88<br />

postmodernism, 194, 201, 205<br />

psyche, model of the, 91–3<br />

psychoanalysis 91–109 see also Freudian<br />

psychoanalysis<br />

cine-psychoanalysis, 104–7, 137, 139, 140<br />

Dallas (television), watching, 152<br />

fantasy, 107<br />

Lacanian psychoanalysis, 101–4, 105,<br />

107–9, 111<br />

women, film studies <strong>and</strong>, 137, 139, 140<br />

Puccini, Giacomo, 6–7<br />

Queer <strong>Theory</strong>, 160–4<br />

biological sex <strong>and</strong> gender, 160–3<br />

consumption, 163<br />

drag, 162<br />

heterosexuality, institution of, 161<br />

queer space, 164<br />

race <strong>and</strong> racism, 167–80<br />

anti-racism <strong>and</strong> cultural studies, 179–80<br />

colonialism <strong>and</strong> imperialism, 168, 170–1<br />

history of race <strong>and</strong> racism in the West,<br />

168–71<br />

idealism, 167–8<br />

ideology of racism, 168–71<br />

Orientalism, 171–8<br />

slavery <strong>and</strong> slave trade, 168–71<br />

radicalism, 13–14, 17–18, 28<br />

radio, 62<br />

Radway, Janice, 142–7<br />

Rakow, Lana, 136<br />

Rambo films, 173, 174, 190, 217<br />

Rastafarian reggae music, 85<br />

reading<br />

advertising, 72–3<br />

Althusserianism, 72–6<br />

decentred, literary texts as, 74–5<br />

definition of popular culture, 9<br />

latent text, 72–3<br />

multiplicity of texts, 74<br />

poaching, as, 222<br />

problematic, 72–4<br />

romantic fiction, reading, 140–7<br />

unconsciousness of text, 75–7<br />

women’s magazines, 153–9<br />

Reagan, Ronald, 177<br />

realism <strong>and</strong> reality<br />

Dallas (television), watching, 148–9<br />

emotional realism, 148–9<br />

films, false realism of, 193<br />

Freudian psychoanalysis, 93<br />

language, 112–13<br />

postmodernism, 187–90, 191, 193<br />

Index 263


264<br />

Index<br />

realism <strong>and</strong> reality (continued)<br />

Real, Lacanian psychoanalysis <strong>and</strong>, 101–4,<br />

107–8<br />

structuralism, 112–13<br />

working class <strong>and</strong> real art, 183–4<br />

repression, 81, 91, 93, 129–30<br />

reproduction, 68–9, 187<br />

Richards, Keith, 85–6<br />

Richardson, Colin, 160<br />

Ricoeur, Paul, 190<br />

rituals <strong>and</strong> customs, 5<br />

Ritzer, George, 207<br />

Rockwell, John, 184<br />

Rolling Stones (group), 197<br />

romantic fiction, reading, 140–7<br />

emotional reproduction, 144–5<br />

escape, 144–5<br />

feminism, 140–7<br />

ideology, 145–6<br />

mass culture, 140<br />

Oedipal drama, 141–2, 143<br />

patriarchy, 144, 145<br />

pleasure, ideological function of, 146<br />

reciprocation fantasies, 142–3<br />

regression, 143<br />

sexual desire as male, 141<br />

sexuality, fear of awakened, 143–4<br />

them <strong>and</strong> us, feminist politics of, 146<br />

utopian protest, as, 145<br />

violence, fear of male, 143–4, 145<br />

romantic love, ideology of, 104<br />

Rosenberg, Bernard, 29<br />

Ross, Andrew, 9, 28, 33<br />

Rousseau, Jean-Jacques, 127–8<br />

Said, Edward, 171–2, 208<br />

sampling in pop music, 197<br />

Saussure, Ferdin<strong>and</strong> de, 111–15, 118, 126<br />

Scattergood, John, 170<br />

Schiller, Herbert, 204–5<br />

schizophrenia, postmodernism <strong>and</strong>, 193<br />

Schwenger, Peter, 159<br />

science, knowledge <strong>and</strong>, 185<br />

scopophilia (pleasure of looking), 105–7<br />

seaside holidays, 10<br />

segregation of classes, 13, 17<br />

self-made entertainment, 40<br />

semiology, 118, 122, 217–18<br />

sexuality<br />

discourse, 129–30<br />

drives, 91<br />

fear of awakened sexuality, 143–4<br />

male, sexual desire as being, 141<br />

objectification, 105–6<br />

romantic fiction, reading, 143–4<br />

Shakespeare, William, 6, 26, 29, 56<br />

Shane (film), 116<br />

Sharp, Cecil, 40<br />

Shils, Edward, 31–3<br />

scholarship pupils, 40–1<br />

Showalter, Elaine, 135–6<br />

signification, 2, 86–7, 111, 118–25<br />

Simpson, OJ, 189<br />

simulacrum, 187<br />

simulation, 187–90<br />

slavery <strong>and</strong> slave trade, 168–71<br />

Smith, Adam, 72<br />

social definition of culture, 46, 57<br />

social order, rituals <strong>and</strong> customs binding<br />

people to, 5<br />

socialism, 4, 28<br />

Socialist Review (magazine), 121<br />

Socialist Worker, 122<br />

Sontag, Susan, 182, 203<br />

Sophocles, 97<br />

Soviet Union, 29–30<br />

Spare Rib (magazine), 153, 154<br />

Stacey, Jackie, 137–40<br />

st<strong>and</strong>ardization, pop music <strong>and</strong>, 65–8<br />

Star Wars (film), 192<br />

structuralism, 111–26 see also poststructuralists,<br />

American Westerns, 115–18<br />

ideology, 9<br />

Lacanian psychoanalysis, 101<br />

language, 111–14<br />

mythemes, morphemes <strong>and</strong> phonemes,<br />

114–15<br />

myths, 114–17<br />

primitive societies, culture of, 114–15<br />

reality, 112–13<br />

signifying practices, culture as, 2<br />

texts <strong>and</strong> practices, underlying relations of<br />

113–14<br />

subordination, 3, 11, 80–1<br />

suburbanism, 27


superior or refined culture, 32–3<br />

surveillance, 131–3<br />

survival manuals, women’s magazines as, 153<br />

symbols, 95–6, 101–4<br />

Talking Heads (group), 197<br />

Tarantino, Quentin, 193–4<br />

Tarzan, 173<br />

taste<br />

class, 219<br />

definition of popular culture, 6<br />

politics of the popular, 219, 220<br />

postmodernism, 202–3<br />

Taxi Driver (film) 73<br />

technological change, 210<br />

television see also Dallas (television), watching<br />

advertising, songs in, 12<br />

articulation, strategies of, 200–1<br />

Big Brother, 132–3<br />

bricolage, 198–9<br />

Coronation Street, 188–9<br />

Doctor Who, 210–11, 224–5<br />

fan cultures, rewriting of shows by, 224–5<br />

Hill Street Blues (television), 217<br />

hyperrealism, 187–9<br />

LA Law (television), 188<br />

make-over <strong>and</strong> talk shows, 133<br />

music, 12<br />

oscillation, 199–200<br />

postmodernism, 198–201<br />

surveillance, 133<br />

textual <strong>and</strong> economic analysis, 199<br />

Twin Peaks, 198–200<br />

telling <strong>and</strong> showing, difference between, 75<br />

texts<br />

access, 227<br />

analysis, 97–101<br />

decentred, literary text as, 74–5<br />

determinism, 222–4<br />

Frankfurt School, 68–9<br />

Freudian psychoanalysis, 97–101<br />

politics of the popular, 222–4, 227<br />

postmodernism, 199<br />

practices,<br />

culture of, 68–9<br />

underlying relations of, 113–14<br />

structuralism, 113–14<br />

unconsciousness of text, 75–7<br />

Thiknesse, Philip, 169–7<br />

Thomson, Denys, 23–6<br />

Thompson, EP, 17, 37, 49–51, 56, 61<br />

Tomlinson, John, 205<br />

Tong, Rosemary, 135<br />

triumphs over tragedies, 155<br />

truth, 76, 87, 130, 176, 191<br />

Tumin, Melvin, 33<br />

Turner, Graeme, 2<br />

Twin Peaks (television), 198–200<br />

‘two nations’, 18<br />

Uncommon Valor (film), 174<br />

unconscious, 91–2, 94–5<br />

underground scene in Britain, 184<br />

urbanization, 12–13, 17–18, 21, 26–7, 53–4,<br />

65<br />

Uses of Literacy. Richard Hoggart, 37, 38–44<br />

value <strong>and</strong> evaluation, 51–6, 201–3<br />

Verne, Jules, 76–7<br />

Vietnam war, representations of, 172–8<br />

Americanization of war, 174–7<br />

anti-war movement, 176<br />

betrayal, war as, 173<br />

consumption, 176, 178<br />

feminization of loss, 174<br />

films, 173–6, 178<br />

Gulf War 1991, 176–7<br />

inverted firepower syndrome, 174<br />

representations, 172–7<br />

truth, 176<br />

violence, fear of male, 143–4, 145<br />

Viva (magazine), 147<br />

Volosinov, Valentin, 84–5<br />

Walby, Sylvia, 135<br />

Warhol, Andy, 183–4<br />

Warner Bros, 232<br />

Warner, Michael, 163<br />

Watergate, 190–1<br />

West, Cornel, 197–8<br />

Whannel, Paddy, 37, 51–6<br />

White, Charles, 169<br />

White, David Manning, 29, 30<br />

Williams, Raymond, 1–2, 5, 11, 12–13, 27,<br />

37, 44–8, 56, 57, 86, 183, 191–2, 201,<br />

218<br />

Index 265


266<br />

Index<br />

Williamson, Judith, 78<br />

Willis, Paul, 215–16, 220–1, 227–9, 231<br />

Willis, Susan, 69<br />

Winship, Janice, 153–6<br />

Woman’s Own (magazine), 153–4, 155–6<br />

women’s magazines, reading, 153–9<br />

advertisements, 154<br />

advice, 153–4<br />

consumption, 154, 157<br />

empowerment, 159<br />

entertainment, 153–4<br />

femininity, 154<br />

feminism, 153, 155–6<br />

fictional collectivities, 154–5<br />

imagined communities, 155<br />

individual solutions, 154–5<br />

patriarchy, 153<br />

post-feminism, 155–6<br />

postmodernism, 156<br />

practical knowledge, repertoire of, 158<br />

problem page, 155<br />

relaxation, 157–8<br />

repertoires, 157–9<br />

survival manuals, 153<br />

triumphs over tragedies, 155<br />

working class, 38–43<br />

‘Analysis of <strong>Culture</strong>’, 47–8<br />

anarchy, 19–22<br />

civilization, 20<br />

common experience of class, 49<br />

communal <strong>and</strong> self-made entertainment,<br />

40<br />

community, sense of, 39–40<br />

education, 20<br />

lived culture, 19–22<br />

formation of working class, 49<br />

historical phenomenon, working class as a,<br />

49<br />

history from below, 49–50<br />

Leavisism, 50<br />

Making of the English Working Class. EP<br />

Thompson, 49–51<br />

mass culture, 38–42<br />

nostalgia, 38<br />

pop songs, 41–2<br />

real art, 183–4<br />

scholarship pupils, 40–1<br />

segregation, 13, 17<br />

Wright, Will 114–18, 128<br />

Young, GM, 50<br />

youth culture<br />

consumption, 81–2<br />

hegemony, 55, 81–2<br />

politics of the popular, 225–6<br />

pop songs, 54–5<br />

yizek, Slavoj, 79, 107–9

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!