03.07.2013 Views

insanity.pdf

insanity.pdf

insanity.pdf

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

8 INSANITY AND DIMINISHED CAPACITY<br />

BEFORE THE COURT<br />

Adelene Africa<br />

After reading this chapter you should be able to<br />

∗ Distinguish between ‘<strong>insanity</strong>’ and ‘mental disorder’<br />

∗ Understand the legal test for criminal responsibility<br />

∗ Distinguish between pathological and non-pathological criminal incapacity<br />

* Understand the role which psychological knowledge plays in determining mental state<br />

* Be familiar with the controversies surrounding expert psychological testimony in cases of<br />

criminal responsibility<br />

Importance of this chapter<br />

Mental illness is one of several factors recognised by South African law as<br />

negating criminal responsibility. Statutory provision in the form of the<br />

<strong>insanity</strong> defence has been made for people who suffer from mental illness, and<br />

they cannot be held responsible for their actions. Consequently, the law<br />

acknowledges that mentally ill offenders cannot be sanctioned in the same<br />

way as sane offenders (Snyman, 2002). Thus, where mental illness and<br />

criminal responsibility are concerned, the law is clear as to the legal test which<br />

has to be applied, the nature of expert testimony which has to be adduced, and<br />

the disposition of such offenders. Psychologists (and psychiatrists) 1 play an<br />

important role in assisting the court with expert testimony regarding the<br />

mental state of the offender. In some instances, this role may be problematic<br />

because the nature of psychological evidence adduced in cases concerned with<br />

questions of ‘sanity’ can be contentious.<br />

Developments in the last twenty years have resulted in judicial recognition<br />

of the role of psychological factors, other than mental illness, in the negation<br />

of criminal responsibility. This recognition is typically expressed in the<br />

defence of non-pathological criminal incapacity and encompasses the idea that<br />

transient mental states are grounds for exculpation. The acceptance of this<br />

defence into South African law widened the scope of expert psychological and<br />

psychiatric testimony to include psychological evidence.<br />

Lawyers and mental health professionals often cross swords in cases where<br />

a defence of non-pathological criminal incapacity is mounted., The differences<br />

in interpretation and application have sparked controversy both within and<br />

between these professions. For example, mental health professionals differ in<br />

the way that they construe the defence, resulting in a myriad of diagnostic<br />

categories which are ostensibly ‘temporary mental conditions’ (Gillmer,<br />

1996). The defence has received much attention from legal commentators,<br />

1 A Psychologist has a Masters degree in Psychology . For the purposes of this chapter,<br />

the term will refer to those practitioners who have postgraduate training in Clinical<br />

Psychology. A Psychiatrist is a medical doctor who has specialised in Psychiatry.


Insanity and diminished capacity 2<br />

who have focussed largely on its form and content, as well as the factors<br />

which the courts have taken into account in passing judgement. These<br />

discussions have also focussed on the content of expert psychological<br />

testimony in cases where it has been adduced, specifically in relation to<br />

reasons why courts have either accepted or rejected such testimony (Snyman,<br />

1989; 1991; 1995; Rumpff, 1990; Burchell, 1995; Boister, 1996).<br />

This chapter explores the role which psychological knowledge plays in<br />

assisting the court in determining criminal responsibility where the accused’s<br />

mental state is in question. In order to achieve this aim, the chapter provides<br />

an overview of the statutory provisions for defences which negate criminal<br />

responsibility. These include the <strong>insanity</strong> defence, the defence of diminished<br />

responsibility, and the defence of non-pathological incapacity. This provides a<br />

platform to explore some of the difficulties which arise when psychological<br />

conceptions of mental illness (or disorder) intersect with legal notions of<br />

<strong>insanity</strong>. Figure 8.1 provides a flowchart summary that the reader may wish to<br />

refer to during the course of the chapter.<br />

Yes<br />

Was X able to act in accordance with an<br />

appreciation of wrongfulness?<br />

Yes<br />

Trial proceeds<br />

Verdict: Guilty<br />

or not guilty<br />

Disposition:<br />

Imprisonment<br />

X is charged with an offence<br />

Did X appreciate the wrongfulness of the act?<br />

No<br />

What was X’s mental state at the time of the<br />

offence?<br />

Pathological condition? Non-pathological condition?<br />

Mental<br />

disorder<br />

Mental defect Temporary<br />

emotional<br />

states<br />

Verdict: Not<br />

guilty by<br />

reason of<br />

mental illness<br />

Disposition:<br />

Indefinite<br />

hospitalisation<br />

Verdict: Not<br />

guilty<br />

Figure 8.1 Flowchart of the possible routes through the criminal justice<br />

system when criminal responsibility is at stake<br />

Free


Africa 3<br />

Insanity is a<br />

legally defined<br />

state of mind and<br />

does not refer to<br />

a mental<br />

disorder<br />

Mental illness<br />

refers to a<br />

behavioural or<br />

psychological<br />

pattern which<br />

causes personal<br />

distress and<br />

impairment<br />

The Insanity Defence (Pathological Criminal Incapacity)<br />

The term ‘<strong>insanity</strong>’ refers to a legally defined state of mind and does not<br />

refer to a particular psychological disorder or state. In fact, as will be shown,<br />

legal conceptions of <strong>insanity</strong> may be far removed from psychiatric or<br />

psychological conceptions of mental illness.<br />

Fitness to stand trial<br />

In terms of criminal procedure, every person is presumed to be sane until<br />

the contrary is proven. However in the case of mental illness or defect, when<br />

an accused’s capacity to follow court proceedings is compromised, he or she<br />

cannot be tried in a court of law. Section 77 of the Criminal Procedure Act 51<br />

of 1977 (CPA) therefore makes provision for an inquiry and report on the<br />

accused’s fitness to stand trial. Further statutory provision is made for expert<br />

testimony to establish the presence of mental illness or defect and the extent to<br />

which it impacts on the accused’s ability to follow proceedings. Where the<br />

offence has been violent, as in the case of murder, rape or culpable homicide,<br />

Section 79 of the CPA provides for the inquiry to be conducted by a panel of<br />

psychiatrists at a psychiatric hospital. Psychiatric evidence regarding the<br />

presence of mental illness and its impact on the capacity of the accused to<br />

understand proceedings is contained within the report presented to the court.<br />

However, the court may also require psychological evidence - for example,<br />

evidence pertaining to the accused person’s level of intellectual functioning.<br />

This inquiry is conducted and reported on by a psychologist 2 . If the findings of<br />

the psychiatrists and psychologist conclude that the accused is not fit to stand<br />

trial, he or she will be admitted to a state psychiatric hospital for an indefinite<br />

period of time.<br />

Where fitness to stand trial is concerned, the<br />

psychologist may play a role at the court’s request.<br />

Psychological knowledge regarding factors such as<br />

intellectual functioning, personality functioning and<br />

emotional functioning may therefore be admitted as<br />

testimony so that the court is put in a position to make a<br />

finding regarding the accused person’s capacity to<br />

follow proceedings.<br />

The impact which the accused person’s mental state has on his or her<br />

functioning is relevant to both the capacity to understand and to follow court<br />

proceedings, as well as his or her criminal responsibility. However, as will see,<br />

an inquiry into an accused’s fitness to stand trial has no bearing on the inquiry<br />

into his or her responsibility.<br />

The Legal Test for Insanity in South Africa<br />

When the <strong>insanity</strong> defence is raised, the court is concerned as to whether<br />

the accused can be held criminally responsible in light of the purported mental<br />

2 In terms of Section 6 of the Criminal Matters Amendment Act 68 of 1998 (which amends Section 79<br />

(1) of Act 51 of 1977), clinical psychologists are also empowered to conduct and report on forensic<br />

assessments concerning pathological mental states. Prior to this, only psychiatrists were legally<br />

allowed to perform this duty.<br />

Activity 8.1.<br />

X is accused of murdering his neighbour.<br />

In court he babbles incoherently and laughs<br />

inappropriately when the judge addresses<br />

him. Is he fit to stand trial? Explain your<br />

answer.


Affective<br />

functioning<br />

refers to<br />

emotional<br />

functioning.<br />

Conative<br />

functioning<br />

refers to<br />

volitional<br />

functioning<br />

Insanity and diminished capacity 4<br />

illness or defect (Reed and Seago, 1999). There are various legal tests which<br />

must be applied when this defence is raised, and while there are differences in<br />

various jurisdictions, these tests, and the defence in general, have their roots in<br />

English law.<br />

The legal test for <strong>insanity</strong> in South Africa is rooted in the McNaughton<br />

Rules of 1843 which stemmed from a murder trial where the accused was<br />

found ‘not guilty on the ground of <strong>insanity</strong>’. This right-from-wrong test is<br />

concerned with the accused’s legal responsibility at the time of the alleged<br />

offence and Card (1992, p.127) summarises it as follows:<br />

(a) Everyone is presumed sane until the contrary is proved.<br />

(b) It is a defence to a criminal prosecution for the accused to show<br />

that he was labouring under such a defect of reason, due to disease<br />

of the mind, as either not to know the nature and quality of his act<br />

or, if he did know this, not to know that he was<br />

doing wrong.<br />

Activity 8.3<br />

Discuss the difference between affective,<br />

conative and cognitive functioning.<br />

The McNaughton test relies heavily on the accused’s<br />

cognitive capacity (intellectual capacity) which may<br />

have compromised his or her insight and judgment. ‘Defect of reason due to<br />

disease of mind’ is central to the defence and does not consider other aspects<br />

Affective<br />

functioning<br />

refers to<br />

Activity 8.2<br />

emotional What is the legal test for <strong>insanity</strong> in South<br />

functioning. Africa?<br />

Conative<br />

functioning<br />

refers to<br />

volitional<br />

functioning<br />

of psychological functioning namely,<br />

affective (emotional) and conative (volitional)<br />

functioning, which are integral to human<br />

nature.. As a result, in English law, the<br />

defence cannot be raised if the offence was committed because of emotional<br />

upheaval caused by emotions such as rage, jealousy or stress. Equally, it is not<br />

possible to raise the defence of <strong>insanity</strong> where the accused has committed an<br />

alleged offence because of poor self-control as would be in the case of an<br />

‘irresistible impulse’. Card (1992) criticises the McNaughton Rules as being<br />

too restrictive because they do not allow for a defence of ‘irresistible impulse’.<br />

He says that the narrow focus on impaired cognitive capacities ignores the<br />

reality that mental illness can impair conative functioning.<br />

English law therefore explicitly requires biological evidence of mental<br />

illness and its concomitant effects, with the result that psychiatrists generally<br />

serve as expert witnesses in cases where ‘sanity’ is contested. This may<br />

explain why affective and volitional factors are not recognised in this defence,<br />

as they can be better understood within a psychological framework as opposed<br />

to a strictly medical or biological model.<br />

Box 8.1 Who was Daniel McNaughton?<br />

Mental defect<br />

refers to<br />

significantly<br />

below average<br />

intellectual<br />

functioning<br />

The McNaughton Rules of 1843 have their roots in the trial of Daniel McNaughton who was accused<br />

of murdering Edward Drummond. McNaughton, a wood-turner from Glasgow was in his early thirties<br />

and suffered from persistent delusions of persecution by the Tories. He was plagued by these delusions<br />

for several years prior to the murder and he tried to evade the ‘spies who were following him by going to<br />

England and to France. He claimed that they continued to follow him and that he was compelled to kill<br />

the British Prime Minister, Sir Robert Peel but mistakenly shot Edward Drummond who was Prime<br />

Minister’s Private Secretary. At his trial eight medical witnesses testified that his psychosis resulted in an<br />

inability to distinguish right from wrong. Today McNaughton’s symptoms would probably qualify for a<br />

diagnosis of schizophrenia, however as the diagnosis has not been developed at that time, records show<br />

that he was diagnosed with ‘chronic mania and dementia’.


Africa 5<br />

The jury found McNaughton ‘not guilty by reason of <strong>insanity</strong>’and he was remanded to a psychiatric<br />

institution for the rest of his life. (Rollin,1977).<br />

In the late nineteenth century, the scope of the McNaughton Rules was<br />

broadened in South Africa [CT3]so as to include the ‘irresistible impulse’ rule.<br />

The courts acknowledged that mental illness or defect could impair conative<br />

functioning and therefore negate responsibility (Kruger, 1980). In R v Koortz<br />

1953 (1) SA 371 (A), the re-formulated McNaughton Rules were accepted by<br />

the court:<br />

A person is not punishable for conduct which would in ordinary<br />

circumstances have been criminal if, at the time, through disease of mind<br />

or mental defect -<br />

(a) he was prevented from knowing the nature and quality of the<br />

conduct, or that it was wrong; or<br />

(b) he was the subject of an irresistible impulse which prevented him<br />

from controlling such conduct<br />

(Gardiner and Lansdown, cited in Kruger, 1980, p.156).<br />

Where the <strong>insanity</strong> defence was raised, most cases were decided under the<br />

‘irresistible impulse’ rule but several difficulties arose in its application. These<br />

centred around establishing whether in fact the impulse derived from mental<br />

illness and not from emotional factors such as jealousy, greed or revenge. In<br />

addition, it was difficult to establish whether the impulse was indeed<br />

irresistible and whether the accused genuinely had no control over it. These<br />

problems and perceived loopholes within the law were addressed by the<br />

Rumpff Commission of Inquiry into the Responsibility of Mentally Deranged<br />

Persons and Related Matters (RP 69/1967), which was established following<br />

the assassination of the South African Prime Minister, Hendrik Verwoerd, by<br />

a mentally ill offender. The Rumpff Commission concluded that a person’s<br />

responsibility for his or her actions is based on the ability to exercise free<br />

choice and the ability to distinguish between right and wrong (Kruger, 1980).<br />

The recommendations of the Commission subsequently gave rise to the<br />

provisions in Section 78(1) of the CPA which states that:<br />

A person who commits an act which constitutes an offence and who at<br />

the time of such commission suffers from a mental illness or mental<br />

defect which makes him incapable<br />

(a) of appreciating the wrongfulness of his act; or<br />

(b) of acting in accordance with an appreciation of the wrongfulness of<br />

his act,<br />

shall not be criminally responsible for such act.3<br />

3 This section of the Act has subsequently been amended as follows:<br />

A person who commits an act or makes an omission which constitutes an offence and<br />

who at the time of such commission suffers from a mental illness or mental defect<br />

which makes him or her incapable<br />

(a) of appreciating the wrongfulness of his or her act or omission; or<br />

(b) of acting in accordance with an appreciation of the wrongfulness of his or her act<br />

or omission.shall not be criminally responsible for such act or omission<br />

Section 5 of the Criminal Matters Amendment Act 68 of 1998<br />

The clinical<br />

assessment<br />

process includes<br />

the clinical<br />

interview,<br />

psychological<br />

testing and<br />

collateral<br />

information


Insanity and diminished capacity 6<br />

Diagnosing Mental Illness<br />

The criteria which courts apply with respect to responsibility embody a<br />

right-from-wrong-test, which assesses the capacity to act according to the<br />

appropriate insight. The test has biological (i.e. presence<br />

of mental illness) and psychological components (i.e.<br />

impairment of cognitive and/or conative functions) and<br />

a successful defence requires the presence of both.<br />

Case example 8.1 : Depression, murder and criminal responsiblity<br />

Activity 8.5<br />

Discuss the difference between mental<br />

illness and mental defect.<br />

In S v Kavin 1978 (2) SA 731 (W), the accused was charged with murdering his wife, daughter and son. He was<br />

also charged with the attempted murder of another daughter. His defence was that he was suffering from a mental<br />

illness which rendered him non-responsible. He was examined by three psychiatrists who concurred with a<br />

diagnosis of ‘severe reactive depression superimposed on a type of personality disorder displaying immature and<br />

unreflective behaviour’ (p. 734). Two psychiatrists opined that he was able to appreciate the wrongfulness of his<br />

act while a third was uncertain. However, all three concurred that his depressive state rendered him incapable of<br />

acting in accordance with an appreciation of wrongfulness. In this case the accused’s conative functioning was<br />

impaired by a depressive disorder.<br />

Case Exercise<br />

Read the case, along with S v Mahlinza 1967 1 SA 408 (A) (both can be accessed in the collections of law reports<br />

held by most academic libraries). Compare the arguments regarding what constitutes mental illness by focussing<br />

on the expert evidence which was led.<br />

The DSM-IV TR<br />

is a taxonomy of<br />

mental disorders<br />

The law does not provide a definition of mental illness or mental defect<br />

and therefore makes provision for expert testimony to establish this (Van<br />

Oosten, 1990). In order to make a diagnosis of mental illness, the psychologist<br />

uses a variety of tools as part of the clinical assessment process. The clinical<br />

interview provides the psychologist with the opportunity to gather salient<br />

aspects of the accused’s psychosocial history. This history-taking includes<br />

information such as the nature of the symptoms, the level of distress which is<br />

experienced, family history and occupational functioning. In addition the<br />

clinician (psychologist) may make use of measures such as psychological tests<br />

which provide objective information about the accused’s functioning. For<br />

example, personality tests will yield information regarding personality style<br />

and functioning while intelligence tests assess cognitive<br />

functioning. Collateral information (third party<br />

information) may be gathered from significant others so<br />

as to provide additional insight into the accused’s<br />

functioning in various spheres. This information may<br />

be provided by family members, work colleagues or other professionals (such<br />

as general practitioners, psychiatrists and psychologists) whom the accused<br />

has consulted.<br />

An important diagnostic tool which psychologists in South Africa use to<br />

make diagnoses, is the Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders<br />

(DSM-IV TR) 8(APA, 2000). This system classifies mental disorders in terms<br />

of their diagnostic criteria (symptoms) and provides clinicians with the<br />

information necessary to make diagnoses. For example, to make a diagnosis of<br />

Schizophrenia 4 , the clinician has to establish the presence of psychotic<br />

symptoms, the duration of these symptoms and the degree to which the<br />

4 Schizophrenia is a psychotic disorder characterised by delusions, hallucinations, disorganised speech<br />

and disorganised or catatonic behaviour. (DSM-IV-TR, APA, 2000).<br />

Activity 8.4<br />

What are the various tools which the<br />

psychologist may use to make a diagnosis?<br />

Psychologists<br />

diagnose mental<br />

illness and do<br />

not determine<br />

criminal<br />

responsibility


Africa 7<br />

person’s functioning has been impaired. The DSM-IV TR (APA, 2000)<br />

provides guidelines which assist the clinician in this process. The evidence<br />

which the psychologist presents in court will therefore allude to the presence<br />

of mental illness (for example, Schizophrenia) and how this impacts on the<br />

accused’s functioning.<br />

It is important to note that the psychologist, in providing a diagnosis, is not<br />

required or able to offer an opinion on the accused’s criminal responsibility.<br />

This is a matter to be decided by the courts. As Ogilivie Thompson J A in R v<br />

Harris 1965 (2) SA 340 (A) at 365 B-C states,<br />

... it must be borne in mind that...in the ultimate analysis, the crucial<br />

issue of the appellant’s criminal responsibility for his actions at the<br />

relevant time is a matter to be determined not by psychiatrists but by the<br />

Court itself. In determining that issue - initially the trial Court and on<br />

appeal this Court - must of necessity have regard not only to expert<br />

medical evidence but also to all the other facts of the case, including the<br />

reliability of the appellant as a witness and the nature of his proved<br />

actions throughout the relevant period’. This dictum highlights that the<br />

issue of determining criminal responsibility is a legal question while the<br />

diagnosis of mental illness is a psychological question.<br />

A diagnosis of mental illness does not automatically imply that an accused<br />

is non-responsible. Snyman (2002) says that the fact that a person has been<br />

declared mentally ill in terms of the Mental Health Act 18 of 1973, does not<br />

imply that he or she is also mentally ill in terms of s78(1) of the CPA. This is<br />

because the latter is chiefly concerned with how mental illness negates<br />

responsibility, and not with the nature of mental illness itself. For example, if a Mentally ill<br />

person is diagnosed with Schizophrenia and certified in terms of the Mental offenders are<br />

Health Act 18 of 1973, this does not automatically negate responsibility. In hospitalised for<br />

order for a successful defence to be raised, it has to be<br />

indefinite<br />

Activity 8.6 periods of time<br />

proven that the symptoms of Schizophrenia impaired What kind of psychological knowledge can<br />

the person’s cognitive and/or conative functioning. assist the court in making findings<br />

regarding mental state?<br />

Disposition of Mentally Ill Offenders<br />

Where the court accepts the defence of <strong>insanity</strong>, the accused is found not<br />

guilty and will be remanded into the care of a state psychiatric hospital for an<br />

indefinite period of time (Kruger 1999). For example, in S v Kavin 1978 (2)<br />

SA 731 (W), the court accepted the evidence that the accused’s depression<br />

impaired his conative functioning and therefore he was found not guilty of<br />

murder and attempted murder. He was remanded into the care of a state<br />

psychiatric hospital for an indefinite period, and was declared unfit to possess<br />

a firearm. In cases such as this, provision is made for the review of the<br />

patient’s progress and the hospital may recommend a discharge based on the<br />

prognosis of the illness and the danger which the patient poses to him or<br />

herself and society. This process has to be ratified by the courts, particularly<br />

where the offence has been violent (Kruger, 1980).<br />

The Insanity Defence – Controversies and Challenges<br />

The <strong>insanity</strong> defence in South Africa has not evoked the same kind of<br />

controversy as in the case of American jurisdictions. For this reason it is useful<br />

to explore some of the debates which have plagued legal and psychological


Insanity and diminished capacity 8<br />

The legal test for<br />

pathological<br />

incapacity is<br />

identical to that<br />

for nonpathological<br />

incapacity<br />

practitioners in the U.S. American conceptions of <strong>insanity</strong> are much broader<br />

than those found in South African law. Consequently, a wide range of<br />

psychological states, which do not necessarily have a biological basis, are<br />

considered to be instances of <strong>insanity</strong> (Slovenko, 1995). The inclusion of an<br />

array of diagnoses as grounds for exculpation has been viewed as problematic<br />

by various legal commentators. Dershowitz (1994), for example, is sceptical<br />

of the mitigating function of syndrome evidence involving allegations of<br />

abuse. He views such evidence as an ‘abuse excuse’ which purely functions as<br />

a means of evading responsibility. He comments on psychiatry and<br />

psychology’s complicity in helping offenders to evade appropriate punishment<br />

by providing them with ‘cop-outs’ and ‘sob stories’ couched in psychological<br />

jargon. He feels that this kind of evidence threatens the foundations of the<br />

American legal system as it expands the parameters of excusable behaviour.<br />

This kind of thinking, along with the public outcry subsequent to the acquittal<br />

of John Hinckley 5 , has resulted in the re-evaluation of the <strong>insanity</strong> defence at<br />

both state and federal levels in the US. Consequently, some American<br />

jurisdictions have abolished the defence while in others the McNaughton rules<br />

have been modified (Steadman, McGreevy, Morrissey, Callahan, Robbins and<br />

Cirincione, 1993).<br />

Slovenko (1995) argues that it is difficult to establish the current status of<br />

the <strong>insanity</strong> defence in America, given the many changes which it has<br />

undergone in various states. Current debate has centred on whether or not the<br />

defence should be abolished completely, particularly because it is seen as a<br />

loophole for those who should be subject to the full force of the law. Some<br />

proponents of abolition argue that criminal responsibility is a matter of law<br />

and should be left to juries for deliberation and not to the assessment of<br />

psychiatric experts. Slovenko says that these critics argue that ‘psychiatry is<br />

corrupting the criminal justice system by expanding the concept of mental<br />

illness, always at the expense of the concept of responsibility’ (1995, p.34).<br />

While South African law has not been plagued with the same conundrums,<br />

there is some controversy regarding the legal test which is applied. The debate<br />

centres on the fact that the tests for pathological and non-pathological<br />

incapacity are identical. The defence of non-pathological incapacity<br />

acknowledges that psychological states such as anger, fear, shock and<br />

emotional stress may render a person non-responsible for his or her actions.<br />

Consequently, the circumstances within which an accused may be exculpated<br />

are substantially broadened. Unlike a successful <strong>insanity</strong> plea, a verdict of not<br />

guilty does not imply indefinite hospitalisation. Instead the accused is free to<br />

resume his or her life.<br />

Petty (1998) argues that the application of the provisions within s78 (1) of<br />

the CPA to what are in fact two distinct mental states, is problematic. The<br />

dilemma which this poses is exacerbated by the fact that because the law<br />

construes mental illness in terms of the degree of criminal responsibility, no<br />

diagnostic parameters have been set. From a psychological perspective, there<br />

is a clear distinction between distress and impairment caused by pathology and<br />

that which is caused by a temporary emotional state. However, these kinds of<br />

5 Public outcry followed the 1982 <strong>insanity</strong> acquittal of John Hinckley following the<br />

assassination attempt on President Reagan (Steadman, McGreevy, Morrissey,<br />

Callahan, Robbins and Cirincione, 1993).


Africa 9<br />

distinctions are not central to legal deliberations because the court is<br />

concerned with whether the accused met the criteria for the legal test and not<br />

with the nature of the mental state. Petty (1998) feels that the lack of<br />

conceptual clarity and the fact that the defences can be raised in the<br />

alternative, present challenges for the psychologist. Consequently, the<br />

boundaries between the defences are blurred, resulting in ‘an anomalous,<br />

circuitous process whereby the court applies the test for criminal capacity...’<br />

(Petty, 1998, p. 4).<br />

Diminished Responsibility<br />

South African law, in line with Anglo-American jurisdictions,<br />

acknowledges that there are varying degrees of criminal responsibility. As a<br />

result, Section 78(7) of the Criminal Procedure Act (51 of 1977) states that:<br />

If the court finds that the accused at the time of the commission of the<br />

act in question was criminally responsible for the act but that his<br />

capacity to appreciate the wrongfulness of the act or to act in accordance<br />

with an appreciation of wrongfulness of the act was diminished by<br />

reason of mental illness or mental defect, the court may take the fact of<br />

such diminished responsibility into account when sentencing the<br />

accused.<br />

In terms of this provision, the accused may be suffering from some form of<br />

mental illness but the level of impairment experienced does not fulfil the<br />

requirements for the legal test of <strong>insanity</strong>. The pathology is then considered to<br />

be a mitigating factor in the degree of responsibility. A defence of diminished<br />

responsibility does not afford the accused complete exculpation, but may<br />

result in a reduced sentence instead of indefinite confinement to a state<br />

psychiatric hospital (Snyman, 2002).<br />

Controversy<br />

It stands to reason that expert testimony is required to establish that an<br />

abnormality of the mind existed at the time of the offence. However some<br />

English legal commentators have questioned the role which psychiatrists and<br />

psychologists play in assessing diminished responsibility. In a report by the<br />

Butler Committee on Mentally Abnormal Offenders (cited in Clarkson and<br />

Keating, 1990), the proficiency of such experts in<br />

assessing degrees of mental responsibility was<br />

questioned, since this is a concept of law and morality<br />

and not of psychiatry or psychology. The Committee<br />

questioned whether the accused’s ability to conform to<br />

the law could be measured clinically given that the law requires a substantial<br />

impairment of mental responsibility. Allen argues that ‘ the question of<br />

substantial impairment is inappropriate for medical witnesses as it is one of<br />

degree and whether it exists depends not only on the medical evidence but on<br />

all the evidence of the case relating to the facts and circumstances of the<br />

killing’ (1995, p. 128). He argues that the courts have allowed expert opinion<br />

in these matters so as to produce a greater range of exemptions from murder.<br />

Activity 8.78.<br />

Discuss the elements of the defence of<br />

diminished responsibility


Insanity and diminished capacity 10<br />

The defence of<br />

automatism<br />

questions the<br />

voluntariness of<br />

the act<br />

Sane automatism<br />

is caused by a<br />

psychological<br />

blow resulting in<br />

an altered state<br />

of consciousness<br />

Dissociative<br />

amnesia is<br />

characterised by<br />

gaps in memory<br />

caused by<br />

traumatic events<br />

Other Defences Related to Capacity/voluntariness of the act – Sane and<br />

Insane Automatism<br />

The provisions within s78 (1) of the CPA are chiefly concerned with the<br />

extent to which mental illness affects criminal capacity. Thus while the court<br />

acknowledges that an offence has been committed, its chief concern is whether<br />

the accused can be held criminally responsible. However, there are instances<br />

where the court questions whether the act itself was voluntary, and in these<br />

cases the defence of automatism is raised. In this defence, an altered state of<br />

consciousness is presumed to result in a person committing an offence in an<br />

automaton state. When the voluntariness of the act is in question, it does not<br />

constitute an act in law and therefore the accused cannot be held criminally<br />

responsible (Kruger, 1999).<br />

South African courts, in line with Anglo-American<br />

jurisdictions, distinguish between sane and insane<br />

automatism. While the voluntariness of the act is central<br />

to both of these defences, a successful outcome has<br />

Activity 8.89.<br />

Explain how the defence of diminished<br />

responsibility differs from the <strong>insanity</strong><br />

defence<br />

differing implications for the accused. In cases of sane automatism, an<br />

acquittal means that the accused is free, while in instances of insane<br />

automatism, the accused is remanded to a psychiatric hospital for an indefinite<br />

period of time.<br />

Sane Automatism<br />

Sane automatism occurs when a person involuntarily performs an action<br />

while experiencing a change in his or her state of consciousness. This altered<br />

state does not have a pathological basis which can be linked to some inherent<br />

biological cause. Instead, the automatism is presumed to arise from severe<br />

psychological stress caused by life events, and results in ‘dissociation’. This<br />

complete splitting between mental and physical activity renders the person<br />

incapable of controlling his or her actions and consequently the act which is<br />

performed cannot be recognised as an act in law (Schopp, 1995).<br />

Dissociation is a psychological state which involves ‘a disruption in the<br />

usually integrated functions of consciousness, memory, identity or perception<br />

of the environment’ (Barnard, 1998, p. 28). The impairment in the integration<br />

of functions is caused by a ‘psychological blow’ which causes the person to<br />

dissociate. In the same way that a physical blow to the head can result in an<br />

altered state of consciousness, so too can traumatic experiences impair<br />

functioning. For example, if a person experiences a horrific attack, he or she<br />

may dissociate from that experience and experience amnesia for the event.<br />

Consequently, the person will be unable to recall details of the event while not<br />

experiencing any other difficulties in memory. This dissociation and the<br />

resultant amnesia occur, ostensibly because the psychological effects of the<br />

event are too traumatic for the conscious mind to deal with.<br />

Dissociative amnesia is an example of a dissociative disorder which has<br />

been forwarded as a diagnosis in the defence of sane automatism. The<br />

diagnostic features (symptoms) which are reported relate to gaps in memory,<br />

and these in turn are linked to traumatic or stressful events. In essence, a<br />

person suffering from dissociative amnesia will not suffer any other memory<br />

impairment and the amnesia is limited to the traumatic experience itself<br />

(DSM-IV TR, APA, 2000). For example, a person may report amnesia for<br />

Dissociation is a<br />

complete<br />

splitting between<br />

mental and<br />

physical activity


Africa 11<br />

episodes of sexual abuse at the hands of another. The physical and<br />

psychological trauma which characterises sexual abuse triggers the<br />

dissociative episode resulting in an altered state of consciousness. He or she<br />

‘blocks out’ the painful episodes and experiences<br />

amnesia for these events. Consequently the person is<br />

unable to relate any of these experiences as they are<br />

inaccessible to conscious memory. Mounting a defence<br />

of sane automatism<br />

In order to mount a defence of sane automatism it must be proven that the<br />

there has been an antecedent build-up such as a period of conflict or dispute<br />

which the person has experienced. The dissociative episode which the person<br />

undergoes must have been caused by some external trigger mechanism For<br />

example, a person a who has been experiencing marital difficulties may be so<br />

overwhelmed by the news that his or her is spouse is filing for divorce that he<br />

or she reacts violently and murders the spouse. Consequently, he or she may<br />

have no conscious memory of this action because of the extreme nature of the<br />

emotional reaction (in this example, rage), which completely overwhelms the<br />

conscious mind and renders him or her incapable of goal-directed action.<br />

Where such a claim is made, the psychologist has to assess whether the<br />

accused experienced a discrete dissociative episode at the time of the murder.<br />

An integral part of this diagnosis is whether the person has amnesia for the<br />

event. This diagnosis is15 difficult to make in that the psychologist relies on<br />

the accused’s version of events, which may not always be reliable. The<br />

assessment as to whether the person has a true absence of memory for that<br />

discrete period is also problematic, given that the clinician again relies on the<br />

accused’s account. On one hand, it may be more plausible that a person<br />

‘blocks out’ memories of situations in which they have<br />

been victimised, while on the other, it is more difficult<br />

to accept such claims made by a person who is the<br />

victimiser. While the question of the veracity of such<br />

claims falls within the ambit of the court, the<br />

psychologist is to a certain extent placed in the position of assessing the<br />

accused’s truthfulness. In essence one has to ask whether it is plausible that<br />

someone who commits a crime triggered by an external stressor is so<br />

overwhelmed by emotion, that he or she has no memory of it.<br />

For example, in S v Pederson [1998] 3 All SA 321, the appellant appealed<br />

against his conviction for the murder of his estranged wife. The appellant<br />

claimed that he had not acted consciously and voluntarily in killing his wife<br />

and that even if the act was voluntary, he had no intention of murdering her.<br />

He claimed that he was under the influence of alcohol and had been angry and<br />

aggressive because his wife was leaving him. There was a history of domestic<br />

violence which culminated in the stabbing of the wife. The appellant claimed<br />

to have no recollection of the incident as he had experienced an acute<br />

catathymic crisis at the time of the murder. The psychological evidence<br />

defined this crisis as a ‘mental storm’ which overwhelmed his mental capacity<br />

such that he was unable to exert control over actions. The Court questioned<br />

whether the Appellant had experienced a true absence of memory for the<br />

incident or whether the amnesia served the purpose of repressing the trauma<br />

caused by the incident. The Court held that for the defence of sane automatism<br />

to succeed, the Appellant had to prove that he had experienced true amnesia<br />

Activity 8.910.<br />

Explain what is meant by the voluntariness<br />

of an act.<br />

Activity 8.1011<br />

Give three examples of psychological<br />

blows which may result in sane automatism


Insanity and diminished capacity 12<br />

for the event and that there was an absence of control by the mind over his<br />

actions. The Court upheld the conviction the basis of the evidence that the<br />

accused had not acted in an automaton state and that his actions were<br />

sufficiently goal-directed.<br />

Case example 8.2 : How do we assess the truthfulness of an accused claiming sane automatism?<br />

In S v Potgieter 1994 (1) SACR 61 (A) the appellant appealed against the conviction and sentence which was<br />

imposed for the murder of her partner. At the trial, the defence argued that the appellant acted in a state of sane<br />

automatism and therefore was not criminally liable. The evidence which was led, indicated that she has been in a<br />

abusive relationship with her partner for six years. She had endured physical, verbal, emotional and financial<br />

abuse and also witnessed the maltreatment of her children from a previous marriage. The appellant testified that<br />

on the day in question, the deceased had once again assaulted her and ordered her to leave the house with her<br />

children. He left the house and she called a locksmith to open the safe so that she could retrieve the pistol which<br />

was kept there. She inserted a magazine and left the holstered pistol on the vanity slab in the bathroom. She<br />

testified that that night, she had woken up when she heard the baby crying. She found the deceased sitting in the<br />

lounge and asked him to turn down the volume on the television. She gave the baby his bottle and when she<br />

returned to her room, the deceased stood in the doorway, grabbed her and threw her against the wall. Her last<br />

memory was of him shouting at her and she saw his blurred image moving away from her. She then heard a loud<br />

bang after which she realised that she had a pistol in her hand and that he must have shot the deceased who was<br />

lying on the bed. Based on her account of events, the defence argued that the appellant had acted in an automaton<br />

state. The psychological evidence to support this highlighted her emotional reaction subsequent to the shooting as<br />

well as the fact that she did not have a history of violence. The state however questioned her account and her<br />

truthfulness as a witness. There were several inconsistencies in her testimony which did not accord with the facts<br />

of the case. Consequently, the state argued that her actions were not consistent with automatism as she had<br />

performed several goal-directed actions which resulted in the death of her partner. The court accepted the state’s<br />

evidence and found that the accused’s version of the events did not accord with the factual evidence. On appeal,<br />

the court upheld the conviction and supported the findings of the trial court. However in considering the sentence<br />

imposed, the court found that the trial court had erred in imposing a sentence of imprisonment. The court held that<br />

the abusive conditions which the appellant had endured, had resulted adversely affected her and that murder was<br />

committed when she was emotionally distraught and unable to exercise the requisite self-control. Consequently,<br />

the sentence was set aside and the matter was remitted to the trial court for consideration of a sentence of<br />

correctional supervision.<br />

Case Exercise<br />

Read the full case (in the law reports). Consider the argument advanced by the defence counsel. Construct your<br />

own argument in support of the defence’s contention that the trial judge had misdirected himself in finding that the<br />

appellant had acted in a goal-directed manner.<br />

Insane Automatism<br />

While sane automatism is brought about by external factors, insane<br />

automatism arises from a change in consciousness which is caused by mental<br />

illness (Reed and Seago, 1999). In this sense it can be seen as a variant of the<br />

<strong>insanity</strong> 16 defence in that it also requires the ‘disease of mind’ criterion. For<br />

example, the psychotic symptoms associated with schizophrenia can impair<br />

cognitive and volitional functioning to such an extent that the person is unable<br />

to act in a goal-directed manner. Consquently, the law acknowledges that an<br />

accused who suffers from a biological condition which may induce an<br />

automaton state, cannot be held criminally responsible as the act occurred<br />

outside of conscious awareness. A successful defence of insane automatism<br />

results in a verdict of ‘not guilty by reason of <strong>insanity</strong>’ which requires<br />

mandatory commitment to a psychiatric hospital for an indefinite period of<br />

time. The conditions governing commitment are therefore the same as for


Africa 13<br />

those who have been found not guilty under the <strong>insanity</strong> plea (Reed and<br />

Seago, 1999).<br />

Automatism : controversies and challenges<br />

While English courts have clear-cut guidelines as to the interpretation of<br />

sane automatism, American courts have failed to develop any clarity as to<br />

their interpretations. Schopp (1995), in reflecting on the stance in American<br />

jurisdictions, says that some courts have viewed automatism as a variation of<br />

the <strong>insanity</strong> plea while others have expressly rejected this notion and<br />

considered it a separate defence. Finkel (1988) refers to the sane automatism<br />

defence as an ‘atypical’ <strong>insanity</strong> defence because the jury rules on whether<br />

there was an act and does not concern itself with the existence of disease of<br />

mind or the issue of intent. Thus the mental state of the accused is not central<br />

to ascertaining responsibility. Finkel (1988) argues that psychiatric testimony<br />

provides ‘the room, shadings, and interpretative leeway’ (p. 291) which<br />

enables lawyers to employ the defence if other avenues have failed.<br />

The legal debates as to the interpretation of the defence are paralleled by<br />

psychological debates regarding the clinical veracity of acute periods of<br />

dissociative amnesia. Schopp (1999) argues that the incidence of the complete<br />

splitting between mental and physical activity is a clinical rarity. In fact, the<br />

DSM-IV TR (APA, 2000) states that an acute form of dissociative amnesia<br />

which is characterised by a sudden onset is less common than dissociation<br />

arising from protracted periods of trauma.<br />

As in Anglo-American jurisdictions, claims of sane automatism are viewed<br />

with caution by South African courts because a diagnosis of dissociation relies<br />

heavily on the accused’s account of the event. There are no objective<br />

psychological measures for assessing whether he or she experienced a discrete<br />

dissociative episode or the concomitant amnesia. While the factual evidence is<br />

central to the court’s deliberations, the psychologist’s diagnosis hinges on the<br />

accused’s account. The difficulty which arises is that expert psychological<br />

evidence is based on a claim of a discrete period of dissociation which<br />

occurred some time before the assessment. Kruger (1999) says that the<br />

reliability and truthfulness of the accused are crucial factors in laying a factual<br />

basis for the defence. This raises the question as to whether the expert is<br />

placed in the position of assessing the reliability of the accused or whether<br />

such claims are accepted on the face of what the accused has said. It is<br />

therefore an ethical and professional dilemma - does the expert have to assume<br />

the role of moral judge when asked to adduce evidence of such a nature? In<br />

addition, if the accused’s truthfulness is questioned by the court, how is the<br />

expert’s testimony viewed, based as it is on the accused’s account?<br />

Non-pathological Criminal Incapacity<br />

In the last twenty years South African courts have come to recognise the<br />

importance of psychological factors in the assessment of criminal<br />

responsibility. The provisions within s78(1) of the CPA have been interpreted<br />

in such a way that factors other than mental illness have been considered in the<br />

issue of non-responsibility (Strauss, 1995). Thus the biological component<br />

(i.e. mental illness) of this test is not the sole negating factor, and emotional<br />

factors have been held to affect criminal capacity.


Insanity and diminished capacity 14<br />

Non-pathological states refer to a wide range of temporary emotional<br />

reactions17 which may affect the accused’s ability to distinguish between right<br />

and wrong or the ability to act in accordance with an appreciation of<br />

wrongfulness (Snyman, 1989). As with the concept of <strong>insanity</strong>, nonpathological<br />

incapacity is not a psychological construct and merely refers to<br />

non-responsibility which does not arise from mental illness. Several landmark<br />

cases (such as S v Arnold 1985 (3) SA 256 (C) and S v Campher 1987 (1) SA<br />

940 (A) introduced the notion of non-pathological states<br />

such as emotional stress, personality disintegration,<br />

shock or anger, which can impair cognitive and/or<br />

conative functioning. In S v Laubscher 1988 (1) SA 163<br />

(A) for example, the accused appealed against his<br />

Activity 8.1112.<br />

Identify the elements of the defence of<br />

provocation<br />

conviction for the murder of his father-in-law. The shooting occurred as result<br />

of a confrontation with his parents-in-law regarding their efforts to dissolve<br />

his marriage and to deny him access to his son. The accused confronted his<br />

father-in-law, whereupon he fired twenty-one rounds into various rooms, some<br />

of which hit and killed the deceased. The defence led psychological and<br />

psychiatric evidence at the trial and the accused was said to have suffered<br />

from a ‘total personality disintegration’ which resulted in an impairment of<br />

functioning. However, both the trial and appeal court held that the expert<br />

testimony did not accord with the facts of the case. These facts showed that<br />

the accused demonstrated insight into what he was doing and that his actions<br />

were goal-directed and voluntary. The Laubscher judgement also commented<br />

that expert testimony is not indispensable in this defence and that the court is<br />

in a position to make a decision based on the facts of the case.<br />

Given that commonly accepted textbook diagnoses for temporary<br />

impairment do not exist, the defence has been interpreted by experts in various<br />

ways. Consequently, various psychological terms have been bandied about in<br />

an attempt to explain phenomena which do not fall within the parameters of<br />

psychopathology. Gillmer (1996) describes the defence as a ‘many-headed<br />

creature’ which can embody anything from a ‘total psychological<br />

disintegration’ to a ‘narrowing of consciousness’, ‘a separation of intellect and<br />

emotion’, ‘annihilator rage’, ‘dissociation’ or ‘good old-fashioned<br />

automatism’ (p. 20). It would seem as if psychology has attempted to provide<br />

the language and understanding to describe those non-pathological states<br />

which do not fit into the law’s conception of human nature. However, Gillmer<br />

(1996) questions whether psychology has not been complicit in assisting the<br />

law with diagnoses to support claims of temporary impairment, in order that<br />

courts view these as more credible and therefore acceptable as grounds for<br />

non-responsibility.<br />

Provocation<br />

The defence of provocation also falls within the ambit of non-pathological<br />

incapacity because it focuses on words or behaviour or a combination of the<br />

two which incite a person to react violently (Snyman, 2002). The emotional<br />

state induced by the provocation is temporary but may be so intense that the<br />

person’s cognitive and or conative functioning is impaired. The law is<br />

concerned with the effect of provocation on the accused, taking into account<br />

personal characteristics such as temperament which may explain the violent<br />

behaviour (Theron du Toit, 1993).


Africa 15<br />

An example of the way in which expert testimony has been adduced in this<br />

defence, is that of spousal homicide. Theron du Toit draws on the work of<br />

Hoffman and Zeffert (1988) by saying that ‘[t]he opinion of expert witnesses<br />

is admissible whenever, by reason of their special knowledge or skill, they are<br />

better qualified to draw inferences than the court. The admissibility of the<br />

evidence of expert witnesses is furthermore governed by the relevance of that<br />

evidence’ (1993, p. 247). She says that developments within case law<br />

regarding spousal homicide have pointed to the need for psychiatric or<br />

psychological evidence in ascertaining criminal responsibility. In the case of S<br />

v Campher 1987 (1) SA 940 (A), the court acknowledged this need and<br />

consequently expert testimony regarding battered woman syndrome was<br />

considered to be relevant and admissible. However, as cases such as S v Wiid<br />

1990 (1) SACR 561 (A) have shown, expert testimony is not indispensable,<br />

particularly when a factual foundation for non-responsibility has been laid in<br />

evidence. The result is that the onus is on the State to prove that the accused<br />

was criminally responsible. When a factual foundation has been laid, expert<br />

testimony may serve the purpose of facilitating this process but in the final<br />

analysis, it may well be superfluous (Theron du Toit, 1993). This antithetical<br />

situation highlights the difficulties which arise in defences which fall within<br />

the ambit of non-pathological incapacity. On one hand, expert testimony<br />

serves the purpose of outlining the psychological factors which lead to nonresponsibility.<br />

On the other, expert testimony is not required by law because<br />

the court may be in a position to make a finding based solely on the factual<br />

evidence (Van Oosten, 1993).<br />

Case example 8.3: Can rage impair conative functioning?<br />

In S v Moses 1996 (1) SACR 701 (C), the accused was charged with the murder of his lover. On the day<br />

in question, the accused and the deceased had unprotected intercourse after which the deceased declared<br />

that he had AIDS. The accused testified that he became enraged at hearing this and went to find an<br />

ornament with which he struck the deceased twice on his head. He then went to the kitchen to get a<br />

small knife and stabbed the deceased in the side. He returned to the kitchen to find a big knife with which<br />

he slit the deceased’s throat and wrists. The accused testified that he was overwhelmed with hatred for<br />

the deceased and he felt that his trust had been abused. It also reminded him of the sexual abuse which he<br />

had suffered at the hands of his father. His mind was flooded with thoughts as to how he would break the<br />

news of being HIV positive to his family and he also feared dying a horrible death. He testified that he<br />

was aware of what he was doing but was unable to control his actions because he was so enraged. In<br />

support of the defence of non-pathological incapacity resulting from extreme provocation, the defence<br />

led psychiatric and psychological evidence. This evidence focused on the accused’s psychosocial history<br />

which included sexual abuse, domestic violence and depression. He was diagnosed with borderline<br />

personality disorder and it was argued that he had manifested various neurotic behaviours such as head<br />

banging, bedwetting and fear of the dark, in childhood. This psychiatric ‘picture’ of the accused was<br />

coupled with a psychological ‘picture’ which traced a pattern of poor impulse control. It was argued that<br />

he was prone to anger and outbursts of violence and that he had exhibited rage reactions whenever he<br />

was provoked. The defence argued that given the accused’s personality structure and poor impulse<br />

control, his conative ability was impaired. He was therefore unable to control himself even though he<br />

was cognitively aware of his actions. In contrast, the state led rebuttal evidence in which the psychiatrist<br />

argued that a person’s conative functioning can only be impaired in sane automatism or other<br />

pathological states. It was argued that the accused did not act in an involuntary or automatic manner and<br />

that his actions were goal-directed and guided by conscious thought. He therefore had the cognitive<br />

capacity to distinguish right from wrong. The accused did not exhibit any signs of dissociative amnesia


Insanity and diminished capacity 16<br />

and therefore did not fulfil the criteria for sane automatism. The court found that the state’s evidence was<br />

problematic as it focussed on the accused’s cognitive capacity – which was never in dispute. The defence<br />

had argued that the accused had the cognitive capacity to appreciate wrongfulness but was unable to<br />

control his actions because of extreme provocation. In weighing up the evidence, the court found the<br />

accused’s ability to control his actions was significantly impaired and he was therefore acquitted.<br />

Case Exercise<br />

Read the case in the law reports. Provide a coherent argument as to why the accused should not have<br />

been acquitted.<br />

Non-pathological incapacity : controversies and challenges<br />

There are several problematic issues regarding the defence of nonpathological<br />

incapacity which are highlighted by legal commentators.<br />

The first issue relates to the onus of proof. Unlike the <strong>insanity</strong> defence, the<br />

accused does not bear the onus of proof, instead the State is required to prove<br />

beyond reasonable doubt that that s/he had criminal capacity at the time of the<br />

offence. However, the accused has to lay a foundation in evidence which the<br />

State then has to rebut (Boister, 1997). Burchell (1995) argues that there is an<br />

‘inherent injustice’ in placing the burden of proof on the accused claiming<br />

<strong>insanity</strong> while a plea of non-pathological incapacity places the onus of proof<br />

on the state. This ‘injustice’ is extended to the successful outcomes of these<br />

defences - in the former, it means confinement to a psychiatric hospital while<br />

the latter provides for complete acquittal. Burchell (1995) feels that a complete<br />

revision of legislation and burden of proof standards may address these<br />

problems but he is not optimistic about this occurring. It would seem that the<br />

courts are intent on applying the subjective test of criminal capacity<br />

particularly in the case of non-pathological incapacity.<br />

Following on from this, Burchell (1997) questions<br />

whether South African law is correct in applying a 19<br />

subjective test of criminal capacity and argues that it<br />

may be more useful to have some kind of objective test<br />

by which to measure the accused’s behaviour. He<br />

Activity 8.1213<br />

Identify three non-pathological states<br />

which may be used as grounds for<br />

exculpation.<br />

views the normative yardstick used in Anglo-American jurisdictions as being<br />

more useful and argues that a partial excuse as opposed to complete<br />

exculpation is more appropriate. .<br />

A third issue centres around a concern that the defence may be abused by<br />

those who have exhausted all other avenues in attempt to escape punishment.<br />

Snyman (1991) says that the courts have therefore treated such defences with<br />

great caution because they can be easily raised. In the same way that courts are<br />

circumspect with regards to the defence of sane automatism, so too do they<br />

view the defence of non-pathological incapacity. Snyman (2002) says that in<br />

those cases in which the defence has been considered seriously, the accused<br />

had shown a cumulative build-up of stress and/or provocation which then<br />

resulted in a temporary impairment of cognitive and/or conative functioning.<br />

Fourthly, while the notion of temporary emotional reactions suggests an<br />

interplay of psychological phenomena, there is no statutory requirement for<br />

expert evidence in such cases. It would appear that while a significant number<br />

of reported cases have relied on expert testimony, it is unclear whether the<br />

courts consider this evidence as indispensable for the defence to succeed.<br />

Kruger (1999) argues that psychiatric and psychological evidence do not play


Africa 17<br />

an indispensable role because the court itself is in a good position to make a<br />

decision based on the facts of the case. Burchell (1995) views the indecision<br />

regarding the importance of this testimony as problematic. There are instances<br />

when courts do not receive a balanced view of the accused’s actions because<br />

the state has not adduced psychiatric or psychological evidence. He suggests<br />

that judges should require the state to lead such evidence so as to mitigate<br />

against a one-sided view of the accused’s actions.<br />

The ambivalent attitude which courts have towards expert testimony is further<br />

fuelled by the courts’ concern as to the accused’s reliability and truthfulness<br />

since this defence hinges on the accused’s account of events. Burchell (1995)<br />

says that this defence by its very nature, is viewed with caution and if the<br />

accused’s reliability and truthfulness are questionable then the expert<br />

testimony will also be viewed in the same light (see, for example, S v<br />

Potgieter 1994 (1) SACR 61 (A). Burchell (1995) argues that one of the<br />

problems which arises in the forensic assessment of an accused, is that it<br />

occurs before the evidence has been heard in court. Therefore in pursuit of the<br />

truth, it would be advisable to allow the expert to re-evaluate his/her opinion<br />

after the factual evidence has been led. In this way greater weight may be<br />

given to such evidence after it has been established that the accused has<br />

provided the court with a convincing account of events.<br />

Finally, while the defence has been the focus of legal debate, it has also<br />

received some attention from mental health professionals, albeit to a lesser<br />

extent. The focus of discussion in these circles has been on the nature of<br />

expert evidence which is adduced (Van Rensburg & Verschoor, 1989; Strauss,<br />

1995; Van der Merwe, 1997). However the role of expert testimony in these<br />

cases has raised particular challenges for experts, and Zabow (1990) says that<br />

they ‘have been less than successful in attempting to adapt theory, diagnosis<br />

and clinical method to the framework of existing legal standards’ (p.5). In<br />

addition, in these cases experts do not have recourse to textbook diagnoses<br />

which can describe temporary cognitive or conative impairment (Strauss,<br />

1995).<br />

The discussion has shown that South African courts have been more accepting<br />

of the role of psychological factors in negating criminal responsibility but it<br />

would seem that a rather ambivalent attitude towards expert testimony<br />

prevails. As Boister concludes ‘[t]his indicates clearly that the crucial aspect<br />

of the defence of non-pathological criminal incapacity is not its psychological<br />

validity but its legal validity’ (1996, p. 373).<br />

Summary<br />

1. The legal test for <strong>insanity</strong> in South Africa has a biological component<br />

(ie the presence of mental illness) and a psychological component (the<br />

impairment of cognitive and/or conative functioning).<br />

2. The diagnosis of mental illness falls within the domain of psychiatrists<br />

and psychologists while the assessment of criminal responsibility falls<br />

within the domain of the court.<br />

3. In the defence of automatism the voluntariness of the act is in question.<br />

The person cannot be held criminally liable because the act is


Insanity and diminished capacity 18<br />

committed while he or she is an altered state of consciousness and is<br />

unable to perform goal-directed actions.<br />

4. The defence of non-pathological incapacity allows for temporary<br />

emotional states to be used as grounds for exculpation.<br />

Recommended reading<br />

Boland, F (1999). Anglo-American <strong>insanity</strong> defence reform: The war between<br />

law and medicine. Aldershot: Ashgate/Dartmouth.<br />

Burchell, J. M. (1997). South African Criminal Law and Procedure vol 1:<br />

General principles of Criminal Law. (Third edition) Cape Town: Juta.<br />

Reznek, L. (1997). Evil or ill? Justifying the <strong>insanity</strong> defence. London:<br />

Routledge.<br />

Snyman, C. R. ( 2002). Criminal Law. (Fourth edition). Durban: Butterworths.<br />

Slovenko, R. (1995) Psychiatry and criminal culpability. New York: John<br />

Wiley and Sons.<br />

Exercises<br />

1. How does the assessment of fitness to stand trial differ from an assessment<br />

of criminal responsibility. Use two examples to illustrate your answer.<br />

2. The defence of non-pathological incapacity provides a loophole in the law<br />

for those accused who want to evade criminal responsibility. Discuss this<br />

statement .<br />

3. Psychological evidence is superfluous in assisting the court in determining<br />

criminal responsibility. Argue in favour or against this statement by<br />

drawing on case law to support your argument.<br />

4. John is charged with the murder of his mother and his attorney raises<br />

queries regarding his mental state at the time of the offence. Collateral<br />

information from his sister indicates that John had been ‘acting strangely’<br />

for a few weeks prior to the offence. She reports that he was agitated,<br />

unable to sleep at night and would pace around restlessly. He also had an<br />

insatiable appetite which was quite out of character. On the day of the<br />

murder, John’s mother told him to do some gardening. He seemed very<br />

upset and agitated and was mumbling incoherently. He became enraged<br />

and bludgeoned his mother with a spade. Using a diagram, illustrate the<br />

process which should be followed to ascertain whether John can be held<br />

criminally responsible.<br />

5. Emma is charged with the murder of her lover but claims to have no<br />

memory of the incident when questioned by the police. She recalls that<br />

they had an argument about her partner’s infidelity and that she had been<br />

very upset by this. She has no memory of shooting her partner and says<br />

that it feels as if she ‘blacked out’ for a while. Her first memory<br />

subsequent to the shooting is of seeing her partner lying on the floor with<br />

the gun next to her. When Emma was questioned by the police, she<br />

appeared confused, disoriented and tearful. As her attorney, you will be


Africa 19<br />

arguing that Emma cannot be held criminally responsible on nonpathological<br />

grounds. Construct an argument to support your claim that<br />

she was unable to exercise volitional control because she was<br />

overwhelmed by rage. Draw on case law to support your argument and<br />

suggest how psychological evidence may assist your case.<br />

References<br />

Allen, M. J. (1995). Textbook on Criminal Law. London : Blackstone Press Limited.<br />

American Psychiatric Association (2000). Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental<br />

Disorders-TR (Fourth edition Revised).<br />

Barnard, P. G. (1998). Diminished capacity and automatism as a defence. American<br />

Journal of Forensic Psychology, 16(2), 27- 62.<br />

Boister, N. (1996). Recent cases : general principles of liability. South African Journal of<br />

Criminal Justice, 9(3), 371-374.<br />

Burchell, J. (1995). Non-pathological incapacity: evaluation of psychiatric testimony. South<br />

African Journal of Criminal Justice, 8(1), 37-42.<br />

Burchell, J. M. (1997). South African Criminal Law and Procedure Vol 1: General Principles<br />

of Criminal Law. (Third edition) Cape Town: Juta.<br />

Card, R. (1992). Criminal Law. London : Butterworths.<br />

Clarkson, C. M.. V. and Keating, H. M. (1990). Criminal Law : Texts and materials. London<br />

: Sweet and Maxwell.<br />

Criminal Procedure Act, 51 of 1977.<br />

Criminal Matters Amendment Act 68 of 1998.<br />

Dershowitz, A (1994). The Abuse Excuse and other cop–outs, sob-stories and evasions of<br />

responsibility. New York : Free Press.<br />

Finkel, N. J. (1988). Insanity on trial. New York: Plenum Press.<br />

Gillmer, B. (1996). Psycho-legal incoherence. Paper presented to the National Congress of the<br />

South African Psychological Society. Johannesburg, September 1996.<br />

Kruger, A. (1980). Mental health law in South Africa. Durban: Butterworths.<br />

Kruger, A. (1999). Accused: Capacity to understand proceedings: Mental illness and criminal<br />

responsibility. In E. Du Toit, F. De Jager, A. Paizes, A. Skeen& S. van der Merwe(eds.).<br />

Commentary on the Criminal Procedure Act (Service 22). Cape Town: Juta.<br />

Rollin, H (1977). ‘McNaughton’s madness’. In D. West and A.Walk (eds). Daniel<br />

McNaughton: His trial and the aftermath. Kent: Gaskell Books.<br />

Petty, C. (1998). The psychopathology of self-control. Unpublished MA thesis, University of<br />

Stellenbosch.<br />

Reed, A. and Seago, P. (1999). Criminal Law. London: Sweet and Maxwell.<br />

Rumpff, (1990). Feite of woorde. Consultus, 3 (1), 19-22.<br />

R v Harris 1965 (2) SA 340 (A)<br />

S v Arnold 1985 (3) SA 256 (C)<br />

S v Campher 1987 (1) SA 940 (A)<br />

S v Kavin 1978 (2) SA 731 (W)<br />

S v Laubscher 1988 (1) S A 163 (A)<br />

S v Mahlinza 1967 (1) SA 408 (A)<br />

S v Moses 1996 (1) SACR 701 (C)<br />

S v Pederson 1998 3 All SA 321<br />

S v Potgieter 1994 (1) SACR 61 (A)<br />

S v Wiid 1990 (1) SACR 561 (A)<br />

Schopp, R. F. (1991). Automatism, <strong>insanity</strong> and the psychology of criminal responsibility: A<br />

philosophical enquiry. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.<br />

Slovenko, R. (1995) Psychiatry and criminal culpability. New York: John Wiley and Sons.<br />

Snyman, C. R. (1989). Die verweer van nie-patologiese ontoerekeningsvatbaarheid in<br />

die strafreg. Tydskrif vir Regswetenskap, 14(1), 1-15.<br />

Snyman, C. R. (1991). Provokasie as volkome verweer in die Strafreg. Consultus, 4(1),35-38.<br />

Snyman, C. R. ( 2002). Criminal Law. (Fourth edition). Durban: Butterworths.<br />

Steadman H., McGreevy, M., Callahan, L., Robbins, P. and Cirincone, C. (1993). Before and<br />

after Hinckley: evaluating <strong>insanity</strong> defence reform. New York: Guilford Press.


Insanity and diminished capacity 20<br />

Strauss, S. A. (1995). Nie-patologiese ontoerekeningsvatbaarheid as verweer in die<br />

strafreg. South African Practice Management, 16(4), 14-34.<br />

Theron Du Toit, R. (1993). Provocation to killing in domestic relationships. Responsa<br />

Meridiana, 6, (3), 230-252.<br />

Van der Merwe, R. (1997). Sielkundige perspektiewe op tydelike nie-patologiese<br />

ontoerekeningsvatbaarheid. Obiter, 18(1), 138-144.<br />

Van Oosten, F. F.W. (1990). The <strong>insanity</strong> defence : its place and role in criminal law. South<br />

African Journal of Criminal Justice, 3(1), 1-9.<br />

Van Oosten, F. F.W. (1993). Non-pathological criminal incapacity versus pathological<br />

criminal incapacity. South African Journal of Criminal Justice, 6(2), 127-147.<br />

Van Rensburg, P. and Verschoor, T. (1989) Medies-geregtelike aspekte van amnesie.<br />

Tydskrif vir Regswetenskap,14(2), 40-54.<br />

Zabow, T. (1990). Conditions other than mental illness or mental disorder in ‘criminal’ and<br />

‘diminished responsibility’ (the meaning of psychiatric disorder in criminal responsibility).<br />

Psychiatric Insight, 7 (1), 4-5.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!