19.07.2013 Views

Earliness Principle - Lear

Earliness Principle - Lear

Earliness Principle - Lear

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

-6-<br />

2.1 Argument #1 for the Innertness of do: __ Conditional Inversion (C-Inv)<br />

English, like a number of Germanic and Romance languages, shows a type of<br />

subject-verb inversion in conditionals. The complementary distribution of Conditional Inversion<br />

(C-Inv) and lexical if, _ seen in (15), suggests, as noted by den Besten (1983) and Holmberg (1986),<br />

that the Conditional Inversion crucially involves COMP. Let us therefore assume, with these<br />

authors, that C-Inv is a rule that moves the contents of INFL to C.<br />

(15) a. If John had read the book, he would have known the answer.<br />

b. Had John read the book, he would have known the answer.<br />

c. *If had John read the book, he would have known the answer.<br />

d. *Had if John read the book, he would have known the answer.<br />

W ewill show that do __does<br />

not undergo this rule, and use this fact to argue for<br />

LP-structure. T o accord any significance to this fact, however, it is first necessary to look at what<br />

elements of the verbal and auxiliary systems may ____ undergo this rule. 6<br />

In English, C-Inv applies only to counterfactuals. ____________ Thus, whenever C-Inv is found, the<br />

protasis is always presupposed to be false (or unlikely). I will use the ability to take an apodasis<br />

with the modal would _____ as a sign that a conditional is counterfactual, which seems correct.<br />

2.1.1 Non-inverted ________________________<br />

Counterfactuals<br />

Before asking what elements can occur in counterfactuals with ____________ inversion, we must ask<br />

what elements can occur in the INFL of the protasis of counterfactuals without ______ inversion. A<br />

complete listing can be found in (16), where (16a-g) contain auxiliaries and modals that do occur in<br />

non-inverted counterfactuals, and (16h-o) contains those modals that do not occur in<br />

counterfactuals.<br />

(16) a. If John had solved the problem, he would have shown up.<br />

b. If Mary should meet him, she would certainly come and<br />

tell us. [“non-obligational ______ should”]<br />

c. If John were to solve the problem, we would be happy.<br />

d. If Mary were dying, she would look worse.<br />

e. If Mary could speak French, she would have shown up.<br />

f. ?If we were to take out the garbage every day, they would<br />

have left us a note.<br />

(on the reading “if we were to” ≈“If we were expected to”)<br />

g. If John would drive a little faster, he would get there a<br />

little sooner. [“agentive _____ would”]<br />

h. *If Mary can speak French, she would have translated for us.<br />

i. *If Bill may leave, we would have been told.<br />

j. *If Bill might leave, Sue would have informed us.<br />

k. *If Sue must take out the garbage each morning, she would have<br />

asked for higher wages. [cf. (93f)]<br />

l. *If Bill ought to take out the garbage each morning, Sue would<br />

have informed us.<br />

m. *If Mary shall speak French, she would have started already.<br />

n. *If Bill should take out the garbage, we would have known about it.<br />

[“obligational ______ should”]<br />

o. *If Sue will speak French, she would have told us.<br />

(17) shows that paraphrases of many of the bad modals in (16) are acceptable. We<br />

therefore can’t look to their meaning for a simple answer:

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!