28.07.2013 Views

The Cuban missile crisis and intelligence performance

The Cuban missile crisis and intelligence performance

The Cuban missile crisis and intelligence performance

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

This article was downloaded by: [Harvard College]<br />

On: 18 September 2012, At: 08:23<br />

Publisher: Routledge<br />

Informa Ltd Registered in Engl<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> Wales Registered Number:<br />

1072954 Registered office: Mortimer House, 37-41 Mortimer Street,<br />

London W1T 3JH, UK<br />

Intelligence <strong>and</strong> National<br />

Security<br />

Publication details, including instructions for<br />

authors <strong>and</strong> subscription information:<br />

http://www.t<strong>and</strong>fonline.com/loi/fint20<br />

<strong>The</strong> <strong>Cuban</strong> <strong>missile</strong><br />

<strong>crisis</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>intelligence</strong><br />

<strong>performance</strong><br />

James G. Blight a & David A. Welch b<br />

a Professor of International Relations<br />

(Research) at the Thomas J. Watson Jr<br />

Institute for International Studies, Brown<br />

University, USA<br />

b Associate Professor of Political Science,<br />

University of Toronto<br />

Version of record first published: 02 Jan 2008.<br />

To cite this article: James G. Blight & David A. Welch (1998): <strong>The</strong> <strong>Cuban</strong><br />

<strong>missile</strong> <strong>crisis</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>intelligence</strong> <strong>performance</strong>, Intelligence <strong>and</strong> National Security,<br />

13:3, 173-217<br />

To link to this article: http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/02684529808432498<br />

PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE<br />

Full terms <strong>and</strong> conditions of use: http://www.t<strong>and</strong>fonline.com/page/<br />

terms-<strong>and</strong>-conditions<br />

This article may be used for research, teaching, <strong>and</strong> private study<br />

purposes. Any substantial or systematic reproduction, redistribution,


Downloaded by [Harvard College] at 08:23 18 September 2012<br />

reselling, loan, sub-licensing, systematic supply, or distribution in any<br />

form to anyone is expressly forbidden.<br />

<strong>The</strong> publisher does not give any warranty express or implied or make<br />

any representation that the contents will be complete or accurate<br />

or up to date. <strong>The</strong> accuracy of any instructions, formulae, <strong>and</strong> drug<br />

doses should be independently verified with primary sources. <strong>The</strong><br />

publisher shall not be liable for any loss, actions, claims, proceedings,<br />

dem<strong>and</strong>, or costs or damages whatsoever or howsoever caused arising<br />

directly or indirectly in connection with or arising out of the use of this<br />

material.


Downloaded by [Harvard College] at 08:23 18 September 2012<br />

<strong>The</strong> <strong>Cuban</strong> Missile Crisis <strong>and</strong><br />

Intelligence Performance<br />

JAMES G. BLIGHT <strong>and</strong> DAVID A. WELCH<br />

<strong>The</strong> foregoing essays collectively raise important questions, not only about<br />

what happened in the <strong>Cuban</strong> <strong>missile</strong> <strong>crisis</strong> (<strong>and</strong> why), but also about<br />

<strong>intelligence</strong> assessment more broadly. 1 As we stated in our introduction, we<br />

see them as the beginning of a more extended conversation between<br />

scholars, <strong>intelligence</strong> professionals, <strong>and</strong> (we would hope) policy makers,<br />

rather than as the final word on any topic in particular. A proper synthesis<br />

is clearly premature. But given the Sisyphean nature of <strong>missile</strong> <strong>crisis</strong><br />

scholarship, it may be doubted whether the time will ever be ripe for a true<br />

synthesis. Hence in this essay we make so bold as to offer an interpretation<br />

of the collective import of the preceding pages, knowing full well that some<br />

of it must later st<strong>and</strong> to be corrected.<br />

We would like to try to grapple with deep <strong>and</strong> abstract questions having<br />

to do with the evaluation of <strong>intelligence</strong> <strong>performance</strong>, <strong>and</strong> the theory <strong>and</strong><br />

practice of <strong>intelligence</strong> assessment — though we shall evince some<br />

skepticism about the possibility of a 'theory' of <strong>intelligence</strong> assessment per<br />

se. While not everything we will have to say on this score will be entirely<br />

novel, we hope that the perspective in which we will attempt to put it will<br />

be unfamiliar <strong>and</strong> fresh. <strong>The</strong>se are our chief aims. However, we believe it<br />

would be fruitful to ease our way into these topics by first having a closer<br />

look at some of the nuts <strong>and</strong> bolts of <strong>intelligence</strong> assessment in the <strong>missile</strong><br />

<strong>crisis</strong>, both to provide some real-world purchase on more abstract issues,<br />

<strong>and</strong> to flag items that require further exploration. We begin with unresolved<br />

or puzzling empirical questions that arise from the preceding essays -<br />

questions first about what actually happened, <strong>and</strong> then about why certain<br />

things happened <strong>and</strong> others did not - <strong>and</strong> then proceed to examine <strong>and</strong><br />

evaluate certain important perceptions, judgments, <strong>and</strong> inferences. This will<br />

help us frame <strong>and</strong> anchor the more abstract discussion to follow.


Downloaded by [Harvard College] at 08:23 18 September 2012<br />

174 INTELLIGENCE AND THE CUBAN MISSILE CRISIS<br />

'WHAT' QUESTIONS<br />

Owing to the various dimensions of imbalance that we discussed in our<br />

introductory essay, rather more questions about what actually happened in<br />

<strong>intelligence</strong> assessment <strong>and</strong> <strong>intelligence</strong>-policy interactions in the <strong>Cuban</strong><br />

<strong>missile</strong> <strong>crisis</strong> arise with respect to the Soviet Union <strong>and</strong> Cuba than with<br />

respect to the United States. This is not to say that the American <strong>intelligence</strong><br />

story is an open book - far from it - merely that there are relatively few<br />

aspects of the American story that remain utterly mysterious to outsiders.<br />

<strong>The</strong> single most important lacuna, of course, is signals <strong>intelligence</strong> (Sigint),<br />

encompassing communications <strong>intelligence</strong> (Comint) <strong>and</strong> electronic<br />

<strong>intelligence</strong> (Elint). Whether the United States had broken Soviet <strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>Cuban</strong> codes - <strong>and</strong> if so, what of importance, if anything, they learned from<br />

eavesdropping on Soviets <strong>and</strong> <strong>Cuban</strong>s - are some of the important pieces of<br />

information not yet on the public record. Neither do we have details of<br />

Soviet or <strong>Cuban</strong> Sigint, of course - but it is at least ironic that in the Soviet<br />

<strong>and</strong> <strong>Cuban</strong> cases, we have clear testimony to the effect that their capabilities<br />

were limited <strong>and</strong> not very useful. 2 We do not even have a general<br />

characterization of this sort with respect to American Sigint. As Raymond<br />

Garthoff notes, one direct reference to signals <strong>intelligence</strong> in a nowdeclassified<br />

document, coupled with judicious inferences about security<br />

deletions from other declassified documents, permits the surmise that Sigint<br />

was on balance more useful to the United States than was human<br />

<strong>intelligence</strong> (Humint), but less useful than photo<strong>intelligence</strong> (Photint). 3 This<br />

would confirm the sense students of the <strong>missile</strong> <strong>crisis</strong> without security<br />

clearances have had (ourselves included) that the United States probably did<br />

benefit from signals <strong>intelligence</strong>, but that our underst<strong>and</strong>ing of the event<br />

would not change radically if the Sigint story could be told in full. But this,<br />

of course, remains to be seen.<br />

Although Aleks<strong>and</strong>r Fursenko <strong>and</strong> Timothy Naftali have done a<br />

remarkable job of painting what was until very recently an almost entirely<br />

blank canvas, the Soviet <strong>intelligence</strong> picture is less complete. Three<br />

question in particular arise as a result of apparent inconsistencies between<br />

the accounts of Fursenko <strong>and</strong> Naftali on the one h<strong>and</strong>, <strong>and</strong> Domingo<br />

Amuchastegui on the other; a fourth question arises out of inconsistencies<br />

between the documentary <strong>and</strong> testimonial records.<br />

1. Did the KGB consider an American invasion of Cuba imminent between<br />

the Bay of Pigs <strong>and</strong> the <strong>Cuban</strong> <strong>missile</strong> <strong>crisis</strong>, <strong>and</strong> if so, did they report this<br />

to Moscow? Fursenko <strong>and</strong> Naftali maintain that the KGB provided the<br />

Kremlin with raw information that could be construed in two quite different<br />

ways: suggesting both that there was great danger of an American invasion


Downloaded by [Harvard College] at 08:23 18 September 2012<br />

INTELLIGENCE PERFORMANCE 175<br />

of Cuba, <strong>and</strong> that such an invasion was unlikely. <strong>The</strong>y suggest that the KGB<br />

hedged its reports, even at the price of blatant inconsistency, so as to be able<br />

to defend itself in the face of any contingency. 4 Nevertheless, the KGB was<br />

unable to reach a firm determination of American intentions toward Cuba,<br />

<strong>and</strong> never issued a clear warning that an invasion was imminent. <strong>The</strong> best<br />

<strong>and</strong> most insightful <strong>intelligence</strong> suggested that it was not. Aleks<strong>and</strong>r<br />

Feklisov, the KGB rezident in Washington, judged quite perceptively that<br />

Kennedy would have to be provoked into invading Cuba <strong>and</strong> would not<br />

willingly attack otherwise. 5 Fursenko <strong>and</strong> Naftali even imply that in judging<br />

an American attack unlikely, the KGB relied in part upon <strong>Cuban</strong><br />

assessments. 6 Amuchastegui, however, reports that in 1961 Soviet<br />

<strong>intelligence</strong> began furnishing Cuba with 'constant, unambiguous, dire threat<br />

assessments ... for which there was no good-quality evidence'. 7<br />

As Amuchastegui readily acknowledges, the lack of <strong>Cuban</strong> documents<br />

represents a major obstacle for scholars who wish to get to the bottom of<br />

issues such as this. It is entirely possible, however, that Fursenko <strong>and</strong><br />

Naftali on the one h<strong>and</strong>, <strong>and</strong> Amuchastegui on the other, are both correct.<br />

<strong>The</strong> KGB may have deliberately skewed its reports to Cuba for some<br />

ulterior purpose. Indeed, this is what Amuchastegui reports <strong>Cuban</strong><br />

<strong>intelligence</strong> eventually decided. <strong>The</strong> conclusion <strong>Cuban</strong> <strong>intelligence</strong><br />

retrospectively drew from this - that Khrushchev must have conceived the<br />

nuclear deployment in 1961, <strong>and</strong> that he made use of falsified KGB threat<br />

assessments to prime Castro to accept it - is logically consistent with,<br />

though not logically entailed by, such dissimulation. Khrushchev may have<br />

had other goals in mind in pursuit of which it would have been useful to<br />

persuade Castro that the <strong>Cuban</strong> Revolution was in imminent danger from<br />

the United States. He might simply have sought to draw Cuba closer to the<br />

Soviet Union, for instance. 8<br />

2. What did the Soviet <strong>intelligence</strong> community know about the plan to<br />

deploy <strong>missile</strong>s, <strong>and</strong> when did it know it? Fursenko <strong>and</strong> Naftali claim that<br />

Aleks<strong>and</strong>r Alekseev was the only KGB field officer who was briefed on the<br />

<strong>Cuban</strong> initiative. 9 Alekseev was summoned to Moscow in May, appointed<br />

ambassador, informed of the plan, <strong>and</strong> dispatched back to Cuba with a<br />

delegation led by alternate Presidium member Sharaf Rashidov <strong>and</strong> Deputy<br />

Minister of Defense (<strong>and</strong> Comm<strong>and</strong>er-in-Chief of the Strategic Rocket<br />

Forces) Marshal S. S. Biryuzov, whose primary task was to sell the idea to<br />

Castro. 10 By all accounts, however, neither Georgi Bolshakov - the GRU's<br />

man in Washington — nor Aleks<strong>and</strong>r Feklisov knew of the deployment<br />

before President Kennedy announced it to the world on 22 October.<br />

Semichastny claims he found out about the deployment only when the KGB<br />

took custody of nuclear warheads aboard Soviet merchant ships in late


Downloaded by [Harvard College] at 08:23 18 September 2012<br />

176 INTELLIGENCE AND THE CUBAN MISSILE CRISIS<br />

summer." This implies that certain KGB units charged with transport <strong>and</strong><br />

custody of nuclear munitions must also have been aware of the decision at<br />

some point. 12 But without knowing precisely who in the Soviet <strong>intelligence</strong><br />

community knew of the deployment, when they knew it, <strong>and</strong> why they were<br />

(or were not) informed, it is difficult to come to a refined assessment of the<br />

relevance <strong>and</strong> <strong>performance</strong> of Soviet <strong>intelligence</strong> in the episode.<br />

3. Did the KGB orchestrate a campaign to mask the nuclear deployment by<br />

funneling accurate information about it to the CIA through <strong>Cuban</strong> sources?<br />

If the KGB was unaware of the <strong>missile</strong> deployment, then it could not have<br />

attempted to mask it by leaking accurate information about it. Yet Domingo<br />

Amuchastegui claims that this is precisely what the KGB did: 'This<br />

campaign presupposed - quite correctly - that the CIA would discount this<br />

information, because they would not consider the individuals <strong>and</strong> groups<br />

peddling it to be credible." 3 One can only admire the daring <strong>and</strong> the genius<br />

of such a plan. But if Fursenko <strong>and</strong> Naftali are correct that Alekseev was the<br />

only KGB field officer briefed on the deployment, then unless Alekseev<br />

personally directed it - <strong>and</strong> he has never claimed that he did -<br />

Amuchastegui must be mistaken.<br />

Here, again, we must await further documentation for a definitive<br />

resolution. But it is entirely plausible to imagine that the KGB <strong>and</strong> <strong>Cuban</strong><br />

<strong>intelligence</strong> did cooperate on such a campaign.<br />

One possibility is that the KGB in Cuba did, in fact, know about the<br />

nuclear deployment. Indeed, it is difficult to imagine that they did not.<br />

Thous<strong>and</strong>s of Soviet troops in Cuba surely were aware of it; why would the<br />

local KGB be unaware? If they had not been informed in advance, certainly<br />

they would have discovered it in any case (<strong>Cuban</strong> <strong>intelligence</strong> did, after all,<br />

despite not being informed). But it is difficult to imagine why the local KGB<br />

would not have been informed. <strong>The</strong>y would have been the most useful cadre<br />

imaginable for protecting the secrecy of the deployment. It is easy to<br />

imagine that Fursenko <strong>and</strong> Naftali err to imply that only Alekseev knew.<br />

It is equally easy to imagine, however, that Amuchastegui errs in<br />

recalling - or perhaps in assuming - that the KGB could only have<br />

conceived <strong>and</strong> carried out such a plan if they knew that the deployment<br />

actually included strategic nuclear <strong>missile</strong>s. <strong>The</strong> KGB officers involved in<br />

designing the campaign could have believed that the Soviet Union was only<br />

deploying conventional military forces to the isl<strong>and</strong>, <strong>and</strong> yet still would<br />

have appreciated the value of tales about nuclear <strong>missile</strong>s. <strong>The</strong>ir task was to<br />

capitalize on the CIA's low estimate of <strong>Cuban</strong> credibility. Why would they<br />

not make use of stories that they, in their ignorance, believed to be false, <strong>and</strong><br />

as such all the more incredible? 14


Downloaded by [Harvard College] at 08:23 18 September 2012<br />

INTELLIGENCE PERFORMANCE 177<br />

4. What exactly happened between Scali <strong>and</strong> Feklisov? This particular<br />

question is shaping up to become one of the enduring mysteries of the<br />

<strong>Cuban</strong> <strong>missile</strong> <strong>crisis</strong>. Fursenko <strong>and</strong> Naftali do an excellent job of<br />

summarizing what we know, <strong>and</strong> sketch out plausible scenarios. 15 We fully<br />

concur with their judgments, <strong>and</strong> have nothing to add to their discussion.<br />

We would like, however, to highlight their conclusion, which underscores<br />

the truly important point: 'While it is only speculation that the contradiction<br />

between the accounts suggests that Scali <strong>and</strong> Feklisov misunderstood each<br />

other on 26 October, it is certain that the United States <strong>and</strong> the USSR<br />

misunderstood what went on between the two men." 6 Any positive effect<br />

this <strong>intelligence</strong> side-show may have had was entirely fortuitous.<br />

Two additional 'what' questions arise from Domingo Amuchastegui's<br />

essay, one of which has important implications for the accuracy of the<br />

historical record, <strong>and</strong> one of which does not. <strong>The</strong> minor issue is whether<br />

Cuba accepted Soviet offers of <strong>intelligence</strong> assistance, as Fursenko <strong>and</strong><br />

Naftali state, or whether Cuba requested it, as Amuchastegui implies. 17<br />

Nothing of real importance would seem to turn on the answer, though the<br />

divergent representations may be evidence of the turbulent undercurrent of<br />

national pride that undoubtedly complicated the Soviet-<strong>Cuban</strong> <strong>intelligence</strong><br />

relationship, just as it profoundly complicated the Soviet-<strong>Cuban</strong> political<br />

relationship. 18<br />

<strong>The</strong> important question is whether Che Guevara traveled to Moscow in<br />

April 1962. Amuchastegui provides a detailed account of the mission, <strong>and</strong><br />

characterizes it as a crucial turning point in Soviet-<strong>Cuban</strong> relations.<br />

According to Amuchastegui, the purpose of the trip was not only to request<br />

increased levels of military aid, but also military aid of a 'qualitatively<br />

different' character. Amuchastegui claims that Che 'left it up to IChrushchev<br />

himself to make a concrete proposal', <strong>and</strong> that '[a]t no point did Che suggest<br />

a deployment of Soviet nuclear <strong>missile</strong>s, nor did Khrushchev offer them at<br />

that time'. 19 Nevertheless, if Khrushchev understood Che to be probing for<br />

an offer of nuclear assistance, this could certainly help explain why the idea<br />

took root in Khrushchev's own mind almost immediately thereafter. <strong>The</strong><br />

timing would be perfect.<br />

<strong>The</strong> difficulty is that we have been unable to confirm Amuchastegui's<br />

claim that any such trip took place. We cannot locate any reference to such<br />

a mission in any of the published literature, <strong>and</strong> the knowledgeable<br />

<strong>Cuban</strong>ologists whom we have consulted on the matter have no recollection<br />

of it. Neither Alekseev nor Oleg Daroussenkov - Che's special assistant in<br />

1961 <strong>and</strong> 1962, a former staff member <strong>and</strong> interpreter in the Soviet embassy<br />

in Havana, <strong>and</strong> thereafter the leading Cuba specialist at the Central<br />

Committee - can remember such a visit. Nor is there any evidence of it in


Downloaded by [Harvard College] at 08:23 18 September 2012<br />

178 INTELLIGENCE AND THE CUBAN MISSILE CRISIS<br />

the material Aleks<strong>and</strong>r Fursenko viewed in the Russian Presidential <strong>and</strong><br />

Foreign Intelligence Service (SVR) archives during the course of his<br />

collaboration with Timothy Naftali. 20<br />

It is not out of the question that Che undertook such a mission, but it is<br />

highly curious that this particular trip would be shrouded in such secrecy<br />

when other trips to the Soviet Union by high-ranking <strong>Cuban</strong>s dealing with<br />

equally sensitive topics (arguably, more sensitive topics) have been matters<br />

of public record for some time. This would suggest that if Che did travel to<br />

Moscow in April, something far more sensitive than Amuchastegui<br />

suggestions must have transpired - something of the order of an explicit<br />

request for nuclear assistance. By all accounts, however, Castro evinced<br />

surprise when Biryuzov suggested a nuclear deployment during his trip to<br />

Cuba at the end of May.<br />

Might Che have made such a request on his own initiative? Che <strong>and</strong><br />

Castro certainly had their share of disagreements, but they were very close,<br />

<strong>and</strong> it is difficult to imagine that Che would make such a request without at<br />

least vetting it with Fidel. In any case, since the Soviets would not have<br />

known the purpose of Che's visit in advance, there would have been no<br />

reason why Alekseev or Daroussenkov would have been unaware at least of<br />

the fact that Che intended to go to Moscow. Nor would there have been any<br />

reason for the visit to pass entirely without mention in Soviet documents. If<br />

the trip indeed took place, then we must wonder very seriously about the<br />

recollections of former Soviet officials, the accuracy <strong>and</strong> completeness of<br />

the Russian archives that have been opened to scholars, or both.<br />

Is someone simply lying? We find it difficult to imagine what personal,<br />

professional, or national interest would be served by fabricating such a<br />

story. Nothing in it smacks of personal or professional accomplishment, let<br />

alone triumph. <strong>The</strong> story does not tend to cast Cuba, <strong>Cuban</strong> <strong>intelligence</strong>,<br />

Che Guevara, or Khrushchev in either a favorable or an unfavorable light.<br />

It provides no basis for explaining away an embarrassment, or escaping<br />

some blame. It is simply an interesting story with no particular valence.<br />

It is possible that Amuchastegui has some other trip in mind. <strong>The</strong>re are<br />

two possibilities. Che did travel to Moscow in late 1960 for the purpose of<br />

requesting increasing levels of military aid, <strong>and</strong> there are at least some<br />

indications that, while in Moscow, he did float a trial balloon about a Soviet<br />

nuclear deployment in Cuba. 21 However, Amuchastegui distinctly connects<br />

Che's trip <strong>and</strong> the Escalante affair (March 1962), which means that if he<br />

were thinking of Che's 1960 trip, he would have to be confusing two<br />

significant events separated by almost a year <strong>and</strong> a half. Of course,<br />

Amuchastegui's claim that 'Khrushchev did not raise the Escalante affair or<br />

the expulsion of Kudriavtsev during the course of his meetings with Che' 22<br />

would certainly make sense if the trip had taken place in late 1960, rather


Downloaded by [Harvard College] at 08:23 18 September 2012<br />

INTELLIGENCE PERFORMANCE 179<br />

than in April 1962, since the Escalante affair had not yet taken place. 23<br />

A second possibility is that Amuchastegui is thinking instead of the trip<br />

to Moscow by Ramiro Valdes in March 1962. <strong>The</strong> timing is much better; but<br />

on first glance the context would appear to be wrong. Available records<br />

indicate that Valdes dealt primarily with KGB officials in Moscow, <strong>and</strong> that<br />

the chief purpose of his visit was to coordinate strategy for promoting<br />

revolution in Latin America (a task in which he failed utterly, much to his<br />

disgust). 24 However, Valdes was certainly a member of Castro's inner circle,<br />

<strong>and</strong> it is entirely possible that he could have been charged with the task of<br />

requesting increased military assistance. He could easily have approached<br />

Khrushchev secretly on this, <strong>and</strong> it would not be surprising that no mention<br />

of it appears in the available accounts. It may also be significant that when<br />

Rashidov <strong>and</strong> Biryuzov traveled to Cuba in late May to propose a nuclear<br />

deployment, Valdes was one of the five <strong>Cuban</strong> leaders (along with Fidel<br />

Castro, Raul Castro, Che Guevara, <strong>and</strong> Osvaldo Dorticos) who met to<br />

decide whether to accept the demarche. 25 This solution to the puzzle<br />

involves the fewest logical hurdles, the smallest number of facts which must<br />

be adjusted (only two: the date of the trip, <strong>and</strong> the lead member of the <strong>Cuban</strong><br />

delegation), the fewest gaps in the documentary record that must be<br />

accounted for, <strong>and</strong> the smallest number of people whose recollections must<br />

be mistaken. Additionally, of the two facts that must be adjusted, one - the<br />

date of the trip - requires a trivially minor adjustment.<br />

While we must await further evidence from <strong>Cuban</strong> (or Russian) sources<br />

before we can solve this particular mystery, it is worth noting here what may<br />

hang on its outcome: namely, whether Cuba prompted, or Khrushchev<br />

proposed, a nuclear deployment. This is not a question that concerns<br />

<strong>intelligence</strong> specifically, but it is one that certainly bears on the genesis of<br />

the <strong>crisis</strong>. If Amuchastegui's story is correct, Castro may have deliberately<br />

sowed the seed that germinated in Khrushchev's mind.<br />

'WHY' QUESTIONS<br />

It is likely that as the documentary <strong>and</strong> testimonial record grows richer,<br />

many more questions about what actually happened will arise. For now,<br />

though, we wish to put them aside <strong>and</strong> ask why certain things happened, <strong>and</strong><br />

why others did not. All five of the preceding essays do this throughout, of<br />

course, in somewhat different ways, <strong>and</strong> space prohibits a comprehensive<br />

review. Nevertheless, we would like to flag <strong>and</strong> explore some of the more<br />

interesting <strong>and</strong> more important puzzles before we move on to consider<br />

deeper issues, such as what constitutes a 'good answer' to questions of this<br />

kind. For the moment we are still concerned with fairly nitty-gritty matters<br />

of historical detail that emerge from the three empirical essays. Later in the


Downloaded by [Harvard College] at 08:23 18 September 2012<br />

180 INTELLIGENCE AND THE CUBAN MISSILE CRISIS<br />

essay we will tackle the larger, more cosmic questions, such as why the<br />

three countries so badly misunderstood each other - questions which are the<br />

primary focus of the essays by Wirtz <strong>and</strong> Fischer.<br />

US Puzzles<br />

As we explain in our introductory essay, we believe the two most commonly<br />

asked 'why' questions about American <strong>intelligence</strong> in the <strong>Cuban</strong> <strong>missile</strong><br />

<strong>crisis</strong> - (1) Why did DCI McCone, but not his analysts, anticipate a Soviet<br />

deployment?; <strong>and</strong> (2) Why did American <strong>intelligence</strong> discover the <strong>missile</strong>s<br />

only in mid-October? - are both relatively unimportant <strong>and</strong> fairly easy to<br />

answer when understood - as most historians of the <strong>crisis</strong> have understood<br />

them - as questions of historical detail. McCone got lucky (an insight<br />

devoid of practical implications for <strong>intelligence</strong>); the weather in Cuba was<br />

bad (ditto). We do not propose to consider them further here. <strong>The</strong>y do,<br />

however, raise larger 'why' questions which we propose to examine in some<br />

detail later: namely, (1) Why did US <strong>intelligence</strong>, in attempting to estimate<br />

the likelihood of a Soviet nuclear deployment in Cuba, use as the basis of<br />

their judgment one set of assumptions about Soviet behavior rather than<br />

some other available set that might have led to a radically different<br />

estimate?; <strong>and</strong> (2) Why did American <strong>intelligence</strong> employ such an exacting<br />

st<strong>and</strong>ard of proof — direct photographic evidence of nuclear <strong>missile</strong>s —<br />

before being willing to conclude that a deployment of the kind President<br />

Kennedy had specifically warned the Soviet Union against, both publicly<br />

<strong>and</strong> privately, was, in fact, underway?<br />

To help answer these larger 'why' questions, it would be helpful to know<br />

the answers to two related nitty-gritty questions. First, why did US analysts<br />

ignore the estimate of the size of the Soviet force in Cuba provided by the<br />

operational branch of the CIA? Samuel Halpern has testified that Task Force<br />

W concluded in September 1962 that there were 45,000-50,000 Soviet<br />

military personnel in Cuba. <strong>The</strong> official American estimate in early October<br />

was 4,000-4,500 - an order of magnitude lower. 26 As we now know, the<br />

operations people had it just about right. Halpern is certain that CIA<br />

analysts received the Task Force W estimate in September, but does not<br />

know what happened to it. Why did the estimators dismiss it?<br />

<strong>The</strong> only defensible reason would be that they had some contrary<br />

evidence to suggest that the estimate must have been off by about an order<br />

of magnitude. If so, this evidence has never been made public. <strong>The</strong>re are at<br />

least three other possible (non-mutually-exclusive) explanations - one<br />

bureaucratic, one cognitive, <strong>and</strong> one motivated:<br />

• <strong>The</strong> estimators may simply have been defending their turf. Estimates,<br />

after all, were their job.


Downloaded by [Harvard College] at 08:23 18 September 2012<br />

INTELLIGENCE PERFORMANCE 181<br />

• <strong>The</strong> CIA's presumption about the nature of the Soviet mission - to train<br />

<strong>Cuban</strong> troops - may have skewed their estimate. <strong>The</strong> CIA did not<br />

believe at that time that the Soviets intended to deploy to Cuba a<br />

substantial nuclear deterrent <strong>and</strong> a full battle-capable conventional force<br />

to defend the isl<strong>and</strong> from American attack. A training mission would<br />

have required no more than a few thous<strong>and</strong> Soviet troops, but many<br />

times more would be needed to mount a proper deterrent <strong>and</strong> defense. 27<br />

<strong>The</strong>y may simply have seen what they expected to see.<br />

• CIA estimators may not have wanted to believe they were off by an<br />

order of magnitude, because of the painful personal or professsional<br />

repercussions of being wrong.<br />

We cannot say for certain which (if any) of these explains the error, singly<br />

or in combination, although our sense, from discussions with scholars <strong>and</strong><br />

former <strong>intelligence</strong> professionals - as well as from a close reading between<br />

the lines of the available documents — is that the cognitive explanation is<br />

most plausible, the bureaucratic explanation somewhat less no, <strong>and</strong> the<br />

motivational explanation unlikely. 28<br />

<strong>The</strong> second question is related, <strong>and</strong> may be an important part of the<br />

answer to the first: Why did CIA estimators so heavily discount information<br />

from <strong>Cuban</strong> sources? Is Domingo Amuchastegui correct to infer that 'there<br />

was a pervasive <strong>and</strong> unprofessional distrust of <strong>Cuban</strong> sources"? 29 Garthoff<br />

writes:<br />

Most reports were of no value, or perhaps negative value; there were<br />

literally thous<strong>and</strong>s of reports of <strong>missile</strong>s in Cuba in the period before<br />

any <strong>missile</strong>s were actually brought there. Only in late September <strong>and</strong><br />

early October (after the 19 September SNIE) were a few reports from<br />

Opa-Locka received in Washington that, in retrospect, probably were<br />

valid sightings of the medium-range <strong>missile</strong>s — but that could not be<br />

determined at the time. <strong>The</strong> existence of hundreds of other reports that<br />

were found to be not valid, <strong>and</strong> many hundreds of others of<br />

undetermined validity, made it ever more difficult to credit the few<br />

that were later found to be true. 30<br />

It is one thing to question the accuracy <strong>and</strong> usefulness of a report because it<br />

is vague, confused, insufficiently detailed, self-contradictory, or<br />

inconsistent with other reliable information; it is entirely a different thing to<br />

question the accuracy <strong>and</strong> usefulness of a report because one suspects the<br />

motives, competence, or <strong>intelligence</strong> of the class of persons to which the<br />

reporter belongs. <strong>The</strong> poor quality or suspiciousness of one <strong>Cuban</strong> refugee<br />

report provides no valid logical ground for discounting another, high-


Downloaded by [Harvard College] at 08:23 18 September 2012<br />

182 INTELLIGENCE AND THE CUBAN MISSILE CRISIS<br />

quality, <strong>Cuban</strong> refugee report; nor do 50 low-quality or suspicious reports<br />

provide twice the reason for discounting the 51st report as do 25 for<br />

discounting the 26th. Every single report should be assessed on its merits.<br />

We would certainly criticize a doctor who based a diagnosis on the<br />

frequency of diseases in the general population, rather than on the patient's<br />

symptom profile: the fact that a disease is extremely rare does not mean that<br />

any given patient must not have it.<br />

We do know that a few reports from <strong>Cuban</strong> sources were gems - very<br />

precise <strong>and</strong> very detailed descriptions of what, in retrospect, almost<br />

certainly were Soviet MRBMs. 31 We also know that some of these reports<br />

reached Washington well before the photographic discovery of <strong>missile</strong>s on<br />

15 October. We also know that, as a result of numerous false sightings <strong>and</strong><br />

misinterpretations, 'CIA analysts had naturally come to view all such<br />

reports with a high degree of suspicion.' 32 It is easy to imagine that the CIA<br />

was prejudiced against <strong>Cuban</strong> sources; that this prejudice delayed the<br />

Kennedy administration's conclusion that a nuclear deployment was<br />

underway; <strong>and</strong> that it prevented the CIA from appreciating the true size of<br />

the Soviet expeditionary force.<br />

Soviet Puzzles<br />

Many questions arise with respect to Soviet <strong>intelligence</strong>, of which clearly<br />

the most important - stated most generally - surely must be, 'Why was<br />

<strong>intelligence</strong> so marginal to Soviet policy making?' 33 We can ask four more<br />

specific questions in an attempt to probe the possible answers.<br />

1. Why was the KGB not tasked to assess the likely US response to a nuclear<br />

<strong>missile</strong> deployment? Khrushchev had a deep <strong>and</strong> abiding fear of nuclear<br />

war, <strong>and</strong> apparently also genuinely worried that the United States might<br />

crush the delicate flower of socialism in Cuba. It is fair to assume that if<br />

Khrushchev truly believed that the United States, in response to a covert<br />

nuclear deployment, would take measures dramatically increasing the<br />

danger of both outcomes, he would not have undertaken it. He must<br />

therefore have believed that they would not. Khrushchev could not<br />

reasonably consider himself an expert on American politics, or on President<br />

Kennedy; so it would be natural - if he were reasonable - for him to ask<br />

those better qualified than himself to prepare a sober assessment.<br />

Among those better qualified was his personal aide on foreign policy<br />

matters, Oleg Troyanovsky, who, as the son of the first Soviet ambassador<br />

to the United States, had grown up in Washington, attended Swarthmore<br />

College, <strong>and</strong> knew the American political scene extremely well.<br />

Troyanovsky's testimony is worth quoting at some length:


Downloaded by [Harvard College] at 08:23 18 September 2012<br />

INTELLIGENCE PERFORMANCE 183<br />

Even though I was familiar with all the information that IChrushchev<br />

received on foreign policy, I did not immediately find out about his<br />

intention to deploy nuclear <strong>missile</strong>s to Cuba. I recall perfectly well the<br />

day when another adviser ... told me that we were contemplating the<br />

idea of deploying nuclear <strong>missile</strong>s in Cuba if the <strong>Cuban</strong> leadership<br />

agreed. I was definitely taken aback with this information, because<br />

being someone knowledgeable of U.S. affairs, <strong>and</strong> realizing the<br />

importance of such a step, I knew this would entail serious<br />

consequences. I was then faced with the dilemma of discussing this<br />

with Khrushchev or not, although my colleagues in the Secretariat<br />

told me that there was no sense in discussing this because the decision<br />

had been made <strong>and</strong> a change in the decision would be impossible.<br />

However, I was doing this just to calm my own conscience, <strong>and</strong> when<br />

I found the appropriate time I talked to Khrushchev. He said that he<br />

was aware that this was a very serious decision, but why should we<br />

not do what the Americans had been doing all along? Why couldn't<br />

we deploy <strong>missile</strong>s in Cuba when we were surrounded by US military<br />

bases <strong>and</strong> US <strong>missile</strong>s? He even said that the Americans appealed to<br />

the Monroe Doctrine every so often, but that the Monroe Doctrine did<br />

not just call for the non-intervention of European states in U.S. affairs,<br />

but also the non-intervention of the U.S. in European affairs. <strong>The</strong><br />

United States had already discarded this doctrine. 3! Against this logic,<br />

what was I to say, especially since I really did not expect a change in<br />

the decision that had been made? That was the end of our discussion. 36<br />

What is interesting here is Khrushchev's academic, legalistic, <strong>and</strong> deductive<br />

approach to the problem. In effect, Khrushchev thought that if the<br />

Americans were reasonable, they would tolerate the Soviet deployment.<br />

<strong>The</strong> Americans were reasonable; ergo, they would tolerate the deployment.<br />

This was clearly unreasonable. Even if Khrushchev's minor premise were<br />

correct, the major premise evinced an astonishing naivete about American<br />

sensibilities. Troyanovsky, Soviet Ambassador to the United States Anatoly<br />

Dobrynin, Aleks<strong>and</strong>r Feklisov, <strong>and</strong> no doubt other <strong>intelligence</strong> <strong>and</strong> foreign<br />

service officers who devoted their lives to the American political scene,<br />

could have corrected Khrushchev's astounding misapprehension about<br />

American complaisance." But he asked none of them.<br />

Fursenko <strong>and</strong> Naftali explain the failure to task the KGB to estimate the<br />

US response in terms of the organizational culture of <strong>intelligence</strong> in the<br />

Soviet Union:<br />

For Western scholars, it is even more startling that no one in the KGB<br />

was asked for a formal assessment of the likely American reaction to<br />

the placement of <strong>missile</strong>s in Cuba. Since World War II, the US


Downloaded by [Harvard College] at 08:23 18 September 2012<br />

184 INTELLIGENCE AND THE CUBAN MISSILE CRISIS<br />

<strong>intelligence</strong> community had attempted to provide estimates of the<br />

intentions <strong>and</strong> capabilities of important foreign countries. While these<br />

estimates often evinced the flaws of committee-generated reports,<br />

they at least reflected an effort to coordinate <strong>and</strong> make sense of secret<br />

knowledge on a certain policy matter. In some cases, these reports<br />

sought to clarify the murky world of the subjunctive, to illuminate<br />

what might happen. Called '<strong>intelligence</strong> estimates' in the Anglo-<br />

Saxon <strong>intelligence</strong> world, these reports were foreign to Soviet<br />

experience. In Moscow, 'what if questions were reserved for the<br />

consideration of the Presidium alone. 38<br />

This does not strike us as quite right. 'What ifs' are an inherent part of threat<br />

assessment. As Fursenko <strong>and</strong> Naftali themselves note, the KGB was tasked<br />

to provide an assessment of US intentions toward Cuba several times - for<br />

example, immediately after Aleksei Adzhubei's meeting with President<br />

Kennedy in January 1962" - <strong>and</strong> in some of these assessments, the KGB<br />

attempted to identify hypothetical conditions under which the United States<br />

might attack. An especially interesting example of this was a July 1960<br />

estimate that a US invasion of Cuba was unlikely unless the <strong>Cuban</strong>s invaded<br />

the US naval base at Guantanamo Bay or unless the Soviets attempted to<br />

station nuclear <strong>missile</strong>s in Cuba." 0 This estimate - which Fursenko <strong>and</strong><br />

Naftali imply had never formally been withdrawn or revised — was, in our<br />

view, a quality piece of <strong>intelligence</strong> that certainly should have given<br />

Khrushchev pause had he not been so convinced (for whatever reason) that<br />

the deployment would succeed.<br />

While it may well have been unusual for Soviet leaders to pose direct<br />

'what if questions to the KGB, it was not unusual for the KGB to consider<br />

them. But more to the point, the organizational culture of Soviet <strong>intelligence</strong><br />

cannot explain this particular failure well because the real question is not<br />

simply 'why was the KGB not tasked to assess the likely US response to a<br />

nuclear <strong>missile</strong> deployment?', but why was nobody asked? Quite simply,<br />

Khrushchev did not think it necessary. He was the kind of man - headstrong<br />

<strong>and</strong> brimming with self-confidence — who did not feel the need to ask the<br />

experts. 41<br />

2. Did <strong>intelligence</strong> play any role in Khrushchev's judgment that the<br />

deployment would succeed? Troyanovsky's testimony highlights<br />

Khrushchev's deductive approach to forecasting; but there was <strong>intelligence</strong><br />

available that could have buttressed Khrushchev's confidence. A 'highly<br />

regarded source' indicated to Feklisov in March 1962 that Kennedy would<br />

not risk military action against Cuba before the mid-term congressional<br />

elections in November. 42 This report could have encouraged Khrushchev to


Downloaded by [Harvard College] at 08:23 18 September 2012<br />

INTELLIGENCE PERFORMANCE 185<br />

believe that he had an eight-month window of opportunity to act. Of course,<br />

as Fursenko <strong>and</strong> Naftali note, the KGB provided the Kremlin with ample<br />

material that could just as reasonably be construed to indicate American<br />

hostilities were likely at any time. <strong>The</strong>refore, if Khrushchev had been<br />

paying attention to Soviet <strong>intelligence</strong> when attempting to gauge the likely<br />

American response, he was clearly paying attention selectively.<br />

3. Why was the GRU not tasked to assess the prospects for a successful<br />

covert deployment? Quite distinct from the question of whether the United<br />

States would tolerate Soviet nuclear <strong>missile</strong>s in Cuba was the question of<br />

whether the Soviets stood a decent chance of transporting them, building<br />

facilities for them, <strong>and</strong> making them operational before the United States<br />

could discover them. Khrushchev seems to have believed quite strongly that<br />

it was necessary to deploy covertly <strong>and</strong> to confront the United States with a<br />

fait accompli. Despite his academic <strong>and</strong> legalistic turn of mind, he<br />

energetically resisted when, in late September, Che Guevara <strong>and</strong> Emilio<br />

Aragones pleaded with him to go public with the deployment, stressing the<br />

sovereign right of the Soviet Union to supply, <strong>and</strong> of Cuba to accept, any<br />

armaments whatsoever that they deemed necessary for Cuba's defense.<br />

<strong>The</strong>y proposed this so as to deprive the United States of a pretext for<br />

action. 43 Presumably, Khrushchev thought Americans were reasonable with<br />

guns pointed at their heads, but not otherwise.<br />

Soviet military <strong>intelligence</strong> would have been the most competent body<br />

to assess the feasibility of a secret deployment. <strong>The</strong>re is no indication,<br />

however, that the GRU was asked to conduct a study <strong>and</strong> make a report. It<br />

would appear that Khrushchev was satisfied to allow Biryuzov to make that<br />

determination himself while in Cuba in late May <strong>and</strong> early June. Biryuzov<br />

appears to have concluded that MRBMs could easily be hidden in Cuba, in<br />

caves <strong>and</strong> mountains, or disguised as palm trees. 44 It is unclear what, if<br />

anything, Biryuzov thought about the feasibility of hiding the roads,<br />

buildings, <strong>and</strong> launch pads associated with the sites, or of preventing the<br />

United States from noticing the removal of already-deployed weapons from<br />

the Ukraine <strong>and</strong> their shipment 8,000 miles into the United States'<br />

backyard. <strong>The</strong> problem of maskirovka was simply left to the planners of<br />

Operation 'Anadyr' <strong>and</strong> treated as an operational detail. 45<br />

As with the first Soviet puzzle, the best explanation for the failure to task<br />

the GRU with a more intensive study may be Khrushchev's over-confidence<br />

<strong>and</strong> commitment. It would certainly appear that the Soviet leadership did<br />

not appreciate the difficulties of a secret deployment, which may reflect<br />

ignorance of logistical technicalities <strong>and</strong>/or American capabilities. 46 We do<br />

not know whether it would have been unusual for the Kremlin to ask<br />

military <strong>intelligence</strong> to conduct feasibility studies for secret military


Downloaded by [Harvard College] at 08:23 18 September 2012<br />

186 INTELLIGENCE AND THE CUBAN MISSILE CRISIS<br />

deployments, so it is difficult to gauge an organizational-cultural<br />

explanation. It would be interesting to know in any case what the GRU<br />

would have concluded about the prospects for covert deployment if it had<br />

been given the opportunity to study the problem closely.<br />

4. What explains the sloppiness <strong>and</strong> amateurishness of KGB reporting in the<br />

<strong>Cuban</strong> <strong>missile</strong> <strong>crisis</strong>? Fursenko <strong>and</strong> Naftali give an account of Soviet<br />

<strong>intelligence</strong> during the <strong>Cuban</strong> <strong>missile</strong> <strong>crisis</strong> that is astonishing given the<br />

KGB's reputation for competence. Students of <strong>intelligence</strong> will know that<br />

laymen <strong>and</strong> outsiders consistently overrate the capabilities of <strong>intelligence</strong><br />

services; but even when measured against a more realistic st<strong>and</strong>ard, the<br />

KGB appears to have performed extremely poorly in this episode. Fursenko<br />

<strong>and</strong> Naftali describe an organization obsessed with espionage, unable to<br />

integrate secret <strong>and</strong> open sources, either unwilling or unable to synthesize<br />

<strong>and</strong> interpret, ill-informed about Soviet policy, lacking well-placed<br />

informants, reduced to the ignominy of hanging around a parking lot at the<br />

crack of dawn to keep a journalist under observation, <strong>and</strong> - if one of the<br />

more plausible versions of the Scali-Fomin story is correct - undisciplined<br />

to boot.<br />

While we can certainly blame Khrushchev personally for certain<br />

dem<strong>and</strong>-side <strong>intelligence</strong> failures, clearly he cannot be responsible for<br />

supply-side failures. We are inclined to credit Fursenko <strong>and</strong> Naftali's<br />

organizational culture explanation here. 'Professional prudence was the<br />

principal reason for the inadequacy of Soviet <strong>intelligence</strong> analysis', they<br />

write, combined with a 'limiting institutional ethos' emphasizing the<br />

collection of secret information. 47 This goes quite a long way toward<br />

explaining why the KGB fared so poorly. But in addition to this, it is worth<br />

noting that the KGB suffered from technical shortcomings that made its<br />

<strong>performance</strong> seem all the worse. <strong>The</strong> KGB's inability to fathom the mind<br />

of John F. Kennedy did not reflect institutional incapacity per se, since a<br />

different ethos, <strong>and</strong> a different set of procedures, could not have<br />

compensated for a lack of quality sources at or close to the White House.<br />

But unlike the CIA - which was equally unable to fathom the mind of<br />

Nikita Khrushchev, <strong>and</strong> which appears likewise to have had no good<br />

sources close to the Kremlin - the KGB could not fall back on impressive<br />

technical collection of <strong>intelligence</strong> on the adversary's capabilities in order<br />

to contribute to policy making, <strong>and</strong> to appear busy <strong>and</strong> productive to<br />

national leaders.<br />

<strong>Cuban</strong> Puzzles<br />

We have so little information on <strong>Cuban</strong> <strong>intelligence</strong> — there was essentially<br />

none, prior to Domingo Amuchastegui's essay - that it is difficult even to


Downloaded by [Harvard College] at 08:23 18 September 2012<br />

INTELLIGENCE PERFORMANCE 187<br />

speculate about possible explanations for certain obvious questions, let<br />

alone hazard tentative answers. Nevertheless, several are worth flagging.<br />

First, Amuchastegui emphasizes the stark disagreement between Soviet<br />

<strong>intelligence</strong> <strong>and</strong> the Direction General de Inteligencia (DGI) on the<br />

likelihood of an American attack on Cuba. Amuchastegui's discussion of<br />

the various possible explanations for that disagreement is both fascinating<br />

<strong>and</strong> instructive. For the moment, however, it is worth recalling<br />

Amuchastegui's claim that <strong>Cuban</strong> military <strong>intelligence</strong> - the Direction de<br />

Inteligencia Militar (DIM) - consistently echoed the Soviets' dire threat<br />

assessments. 48 What, then, explains the stark disagreement between DIM<br />

<strong>and</strong> DGI?<br />

Both organizations had high-level Soviet advisers, so it seems unlikely<br />

that the difference can be accounted for simply by a closer professional<br />

relationship between Soviet <strong>and</strong> <strong>Cuban</strong> personnel in one case than in the<br />

other. DIM fell under the Ministry of the Revolutionary Armed Forces<br />

(MINFAR) led by Raul Castro, however, <strong>and</strong> it is conceivable that Raul's<br />

pro-Soviet sympathies may have had some influence on DIM's willingness<br />

to accept Soviet assessments. Another possibility is that DIM's professional<br />

focus on military threat assessment led it to rely heavily on American<br />

military capabilities as an indicator of political intent. DGI appears to have<br />

based its assessment on a broader analysis of political context, <strong>and</strong> on its<br />

reading of the goals of Operation 'Mongoose' (certainly a more defensible<br />

basis, since military capabilities are not reliable indicators of political<br />

intent).<br />

A second puzzle is Fidel Castro's failure to inform his own <strong>intelligence</strong><br />

services of the true nature of the Soviet deployment. It is not clear why<br />

Castro would wish to keep his own <strong>intelligence</strong> service in the dark, although<br />

one obvious possibility is that he wished to limit dissemination of this<br />

information to reduce the danger of leakage. Given the state of unrest in<br />

Cuba <strong>and</strong> the intense activity of counterrevolutionary groups, it would have<br />

been reasonable for Castro to fear that the CIA had informants within his<br />

<strong>intelligence</strong> services. Yet <strong>Cuban</strong> <strong>intelligence</strong> could not properly fulfill its<br />

primary m<strong>and</strong>ate - warning of an American attack - without knowing what<br />

the Soviets in Cuba were up to that might provoke one.<br />

This leads directly to a third puzzle: namely, if <strong>Cuban</strong> <strong>intelligence</strong> did,<br />

in fact, catch on to the nuclear deployment, <strong>and</strong> did attempt to warn the<br />

<strong>Cuban</strong> leadership of the danger that this might provoke the United States,<br />

why did Pineiro refuse to pass that threat assessment on to Castro?<br />

Amuchastegui explains this in terms of Pineiro's 'reluctance to submit to the<br />

<strong>Cuban</strong> leadership assessments that would challenge or even contradict Fidel<br />

Castro's own thinking'. 49 It is certainly possible that Pineiro worried Castro<br />

might shoot the messenger. Yet if this is the case, why did Castro send Che


Downloaded by [Harvard College] at 08:23 18 September 2012<br />

188 INTELLIGENCE AND THE CUBAN MISSILE CRISIS<br />

<strong>and</strong> Aragones to Moscow in late August to plead for public disclosure?<br />

Surely Castro himself must have been concerned that the Soviet deployment<br />

could precipitate an American attack. It is far from clear that on this score<br />

the judgment of <strong>Cuban</strong> <strong>intelligence</strong> would challenge or contradict Castro's<br />

thinking. Pineiro may have known that, of course, in which case he would<br />

have been wise not to pass on a report containing nothing Castro did not<br />

already know or believe. This would only irritate Castro, <strong>and</strong> in <strong>Cuban</strong><br />

politics, that would be a mistake.<br />

Fourth - <strong>and</strong>, for moment, finally - what was the basis of Castro's<br />

confidence on 26 October that an American attack was imminent?<br />

Amuchastegui insists DGI did not provide Castro with any information to<br />

that effect. Certainly it is unusual for political leaders to warn <strong>intelligence</strong><br />

analysts of an impending assault. 50 Amuchastegui is probably correct to<br />

infer that the information did not come from Soviet <strong>intelligence</strong>, since<br />

Castro issued precisely the same warning to Khrushchev. It is possible, as<br />

Amuchastegui speculates, that Castro drew this conclusion from his own<br />

reading of open sources, or, as Fursenko <strong>and</strong> Naftali suggest, from Brazilian<br />

President Joao Goulart, whose explicit warning of an imminent attack<br />

coincided with, <strong>and</strong> reinforced, an otherwise inconclusive report from<br />

<strong>Cuban</strong> <strong>intelligence</strong> in New York. 51 As far as we know, Castro himself has<br />

never identified a particular source for his judgment. 52 It thus remains a<br />

mystery.<br />

EVALUATING INTELLIGENCE PERFORMANCE<br />

<strong>The</strong> authors of our three empirical essays all make judgments about the<br />

<strong>performance</strong> of the respective <strong>intelligence</strong> bodies they examine (<strong>and</strong>, in at<br />

least one case, of the adversary's <strong>intelligence</strong> service as well). Were they to<br />

assign grades, we suspect that Garthoff would give the American<br />

<strong>intelligence</strong> community an A-; Fursenko <strong>and</strong> Naftali would give the Soviet<br />

<strong>intelligence</strong> community at best a C- (if not an 'Absent'); <strong>and</strong> Amuchastegui<br />

would give the <strong>Cuban</strong> <strong>intelligence</strong> community a solid B+ (<strong>and</strong> the CIA a D).<br />

<strong>The</strong> Stennis Committee <strong>and</strong> the President's Foreign Intelligence Advisory<br />

Board (PFLAB) both probably would have given the CIA a grade of B-; 53<br />

DCI McCone, in his response to the PFIAB report, a B+. 54 We know of no<br />

official Soviet <strong>intelligence</strong> post mortems, so we cannot determine how the<br />

Soviets assessed their own <strong>intelligence</strong> <strong>performance</strong>. Amuchastegui notes<br />

that there were major changes to <strong>Cuban</strong> <strong>intelligence</strong> after the <strong>crisis</strong>,<br />

indicating some dissatisfaction, but that many of these changes simply<br />

sought to reduce Cuba's reliance on Soviet <strong>and</strong> East European <strong>intelligence</strong>.<br />

It is natural to try to judge the <strong>performance</strong> of <strong>intelligence</strong> communities,<br />

yet it is very difficult to know what st<strong>and</strong>ards or benchmarks to employ. It


Downloaded by [Harvard College] at 08:23 18 September 2012<br />

INTELLIGENCE PERFORMANCE 189<br />

is unrealistic to expect <strong>intelligence</strong> to know everything, <strong>and</strong> to know it right<br />

away. Omniscience, omnipotence, <strong>and</strong> ubiquity are out of the question.<br />

Even an <strong>intelligence</strong> service operating at peak efficiency <strong>and</strong> unhampered<br />

by resource constraints will make mistakes <strong>and</strong> fail to anticipate important<br />

events every once in a while. In her essay, Beth Fischer argues that perfectly<br />

normal human psychology imposes a '<strong>performance</strong> limit' on <strong>intelligence</strong>.<br />

Two decades ago Richard Betts eloquently <strong>and</strong> perceptively identified a<br />

number of other insurmountable obstacles to perfection, psychological <strong>and</strong><br />

otherwise. 55<br />

How, then, do we know how well an <strong>intelligence</strong> community is<br />

performing? We cannot design meaningful tests of real-world <strong>performance</strong>,<br />

as we can (say) for student drivers. <strong>The</strong>re are two reasons for this. First, we<br />

cannot manipulate the international environment. Certainly it would have<br />

been an intriguing idea for American officials to ask Nikita Khrushchev to<br />

deploy nuclear <strong>missile</strong>s in Cuba, so that they could test the CIA's<br />

forecasting skills; but there would have been no way to secure Khrushchev's<br />

compliance, <strong>and</strong> in any case, this would have been perverse. Second, since<br />

we cannot predict the future, we cannot know the 'right answers' before we<br />

administer a test. If we could, we would not need <strong>intelligence</strong> services.<br />

Occasionally it is possible to know in real time when an <strong>intelligence</strong><br />

service misses something. From time to time crucial information of the kind<br />

it is the <strong>intelligence</strong> community's job to acquire reaches national leaders<br />

through entirely different channels. This does not, however, provide a basis<br />

for determining whether <strong>intelligence</strong> communities are performing well or<br />

poorly in general. An <strong>intelligence</strong> community that is performing extremely<br />

well in general will, unavoidably, miss certain things. This is logically<br />

implied by the notion of a <strong>performance</strong> limit.<br />

Retrospective Evaluation: Three Temptations<br />

Most judgments about the <strong>performance</strong> of <strong>intelligence</strong> arise from<br />

retrospective evaluations, such as official post mortems <strong>and</strong> academic<br />

studies. Retrospective evaluation has the crucial advantage of a fixed<br />

historical record against which to assess analysts' perceptions, beliefs, <strong>and</strong><br />

inferences. <strong>The</strong>re is always some irreducible element of uncertainty about<br />

what actually happened, of course, but this degree of uncertainty cannot<br />

compare with our uncertainty about what is happening now <strong>and</strong> what will<br />

happen in the future. Retrospection is the best we have.<br />

How accurately can we gauge <strong>intelligence</strong> <strong>performance</strong> in retrospect?<br />

We submit that the answer is 'not very', largely for straightforward<br />

epistemological reasons. However, we would like to suggest that<br />

retrospective evaluation - though imperfect - can be useful if we have a<br />

particular underst<strong>and</strong>ing in mind of how we can benefit from it. We suspect,


Downloaded by [Harvard College] at 08:23 18 September 2012<br />

190 INTELLIGENCE AND THE CUBAN MISSILE CRISIS<br />

however, that unrealistic expectations about <strong>intelligence</strong> <strong>performance</strong>,<br />

coupled with underst<strong>and</strong>able but misguided views about what retrospective<br />

evaluation is for, typically frustrate the enterprise.<br />

Three common temptations represent obstacles to fruitful retrospective<br />

evaluation: the temptation to focus on the specific <strong>and</strong> the spectacular (a<br />

form of selection bias); the temptation to privilege hindsight; <strong>and</strong> the<br />

temptation to try to evaluate <strong>performance</strong> in terms of a 'rate of success.'<br />

1. Selection bias. It is almost irresistible to focus on particular dramatic<br />

failures when assessing <strong>intelligence</strong> <strong>performance</strong> retrospectively. <strong>The</strong><br />

enormous literature on surprise attacks provides a useful example.<br />

Admittedly, these are engrossing events. It may be doubted whether studies<br />

of <strong>intelligence</strong> successes could compete for our attention, because one of the<br />

chief things that makes a failure spectacular is that it has a dramatic<br />

consequence. A properly-exploited <strong>intelligence</strong> success may lead to the<br />

prevention of something spectacular. Moreover, a success does not provide<br />

the occasion for public angst about <strong>intelligence</strong> capabilities, <strong>and</strong> would not<br />

normally spawn public review or discussion. Our fascination with failures<br />

is entirely underst<strong>and</strong>able. However, it is clear that by focusing our attention<br />

on failures, we may overestimate the weaknesses of an <strong>intelligence</strong><br />

community - much as aviation disasters incline people to exaggerate the<br />

dangers of flying (uneventful flights do not make headlines).<br />

In principle, we could avoid this temptation by making an effort to study<br />

a representative sample of <strong>intelligence</strong> episodes - selecting not on the<br />

outcome, but r<strong>and</strong>omly, or by period of time. But this is easier said than<br />

done. Successes leave less of a documentary trail than failures, <strong>and</strong><br />

mundane episodes attract less attention than dramatic ones. <strong>The</strong>re may<br />

simply not be enough information available to conduct a truly balanced<br />

study. <strong>The</strong> combination of inherent allure <strong>and</strong> available information means<br />

that spectacular <strong>intelligence</strong> failures have an almost irresistible gravitational<br />

pull.<br />

2. Privileging hindsight. Hindsight tends to color our judgments of how<br />

<strong>intelligence</strong> analysts should have interpreted information. This leads to<br />

unrealistic expectations about <strong>performance</strong>.<br />

Once we know what has happened, we can easily distinguish between<br />

meaningful <strong>and</strong> meaningless indicators: the signals st<strong>and</strong> out starkly from<br />

the noise. But to <strong>intelligence</strong> analysts attempting to anticipate events, those<br />

same signals may be barely perceptible, <strong>and</strong> quite underst<strong>and</strong>ably so. 56 After<br />

the Japanese attacked Pearl Harbor, it was easy to see that there was plenty<br />

of information available on the basis of which US <strong>intelligence</strong> might have<br />

anticipated the attack. It is tempting to take the further step <strong>and</strong> fault US


Downloaded by [Harvard College] at 08:23 18 September 2012<br />

INTELLIGENCE PERFORMANCE 191<br />

<strong>intelligence</strong> for not anticipating it. Hindsight provides such a powerful<br />

prism that the intellectually frail often cannot resist the conclusion that US<br />

<strong>intelligence</strong> must have known about Pearl Harbor in advance. Thus are<br />

conspiracy theories born. 57<br />

It is in the nature of Monday-morning quarterbacking to argue that if<br />

<strong>intelligence</strong> had done X rather than Y, they would have plucked the signals<br />

from the noise <strong>and</strong> correctly anticipated events. And it may well be true that<br />

if US <strong>intelligence</strong> had concentrated on certain targets rather than others,<br />

relied more heavily on certain methods of collection than others, h<strong>and</strong>led<br />

information differently, made use of different working assumptions, etc.,<br />

etc., they would have reached the conclusion that the Japanese were about<br />

to attack Pearl Harbor in time to do something about it. <strong>The</strong> problem is that<br />

we cannot know this, even with the benefit of hindsight. All choices have<br />

trade-offs <strong>and</strong> opportunity costs that are difficult to estimate. Choosing X<br />

might have induced other (possibly cascading) errors.<br />

Moreover, to go the extra step to conclude that <strong>intelligence</strong> should have<br />

done X rather than Y begs additional questions. Was X technically possible?<br />

Would <strong>intelligence</strong> have had good reasons for doing X at the time? Would<br />

those reasons have been better than the reasons they already had for doing<br />

Y? How do we know what reasons are good, what reasons are bad, <strong>and</strong>, of<br />

two good reasons, which is the better? 58<br />

3. <strong>The</strong> temptation to determine a 'rate of success'. In an enlightening <strong>and</strong><br />

deservedly well-regarded essay written shortly after the <strong>Cuban</strong> <strong>missile</strong><br />

<strong>crisis</strong>, Klaus Knorr attempted to underst<strong>and</strong> why American <strong>intelligence</strong><br />

failed to anticipate the Soviet deployment, <strong>and</strong> to put that failure in a context<br />

that would permit a meaningful evaluation of <strong>intelligence</strong> <strong>performance</strong>.<br />

Knorr quite properly acknowledged the inevitability of surprise. In a nowfamous<br />

passage, however, he stated that 'the practical problem is to improve<br />

the "batting average" - say, from .275 to .301 - rather than to do away<br />

altogether with surprise'. 59 We believe this to be misguided.<br />

It is a natural temptation to think of 'good' <strong>intelligence</strong> <strong>performance</strong> in<br />

terms of a high rate of success, <strong>and</strong> 'poor' <strong>intelligence</strong> <strong>performance</strong> in terms<br />

of a low one. Just as we can be confident that a baseball player batting .350<br />

must be doing things right <strong>and</strong> a player batting .125 needs serious work, an<br />

<strong>intelligence</strong> agency that fails rarely must be doing well, <strong>and</strong> one that fails<br />

often must be doing badly. It is also natural to think that retrospective<br />

evaluation, despite its various pitfalls <strong>and</strong> difficulties, at the very least<br />

permits us to gauge the relative frequency of correct <strong>and</strong> incorrect<br />

judgments. On first glance, this seems straightforward. When an<br />

<strong>intelligence</strong> community correctly anticipates the enemy's move, we score a<br />

hit; when it does not - as the CIA did not, in failing to foresee the Soviet


Downloaded by [Harvard College] at 08:23 18 September 2012<br />

192 INTELLIGENCE AND THE CUBAN MISSILE CRISIS<br />

nuclear deployment to Cuba - we score an out.<br />

<strong>The</strong> moment we begin to think about operationalizing these assessments,<br />

however, we quickly discover that the metaphor is both meaningless <strong>and</strong><br />

unworkable. Consider SNIE 85-3-62:<br />

<strong>The</strong> USSR could derive considerable military advantage from the<br />

establishment of Soviet medium <strong>and</strong> intermediate range ballistic<br />

<strong>missile</strong>s in Cuba, or from the establishment of a Soviet submarine<br />

base there. As between these two, the establishment of a submarine<br />

base would be more likely. Either development, however, would be<br />

incompatible with Soviet practice to date <strong>and</strong> with Soviet policy as we<br />

presently estimate it. It would indicate a far greater willingness to<br />

increase the level of risk in US-Soviet relations than the USSR has<br />

displayed thus far, <strong>and</strong> consequently would have important policy<br />

implications with respect to other areas <strong>and</strong> other problems. 60<br />

<strong>The</strong> estimate equivocated. In effect, it said that a nuclear deployment was<br />

unlikely, but not impossible. It did not assign probabilities, but, for the sake<br />

of argument, we can imagine that SNIE 85-3-62 meant to communicate that<br />

there was a 0.2 probability that the USSR would deploy MRBMs to Cuba,<br />

<strong>and</strong> a 0.8 probability that it would not. When calculating the CIA's batting<br />

average, should we count this as one-fifth of a hit, <strong>and</strong> four-fifths of an out?<br />

DCI McCone estimated the reverse. Was he at bat, too, or only the authors<br />

of the SNIE?<br />

Suppose that Khrushchev had consulted with his American specialists<br />

earlier in the game, got cold feet, <strong>and</strong> decided to subtract the nuclear<br />

component from the Soviet deployment. In that case, SNIE 85-3-62 would<br />

have been right on the money, <strong>and</strong> we would have to score it a hit (or, at<br />

least, 80 per cent of a hit). And yet, in this scenario, there is nothing<br />

whatsoever that the CIA would have done differently. Do we want our<br />

evaluations of the <strong>performance</strong> of an <strong>intelligence</strong> community to turn on<br />

extraneous stochastic contingencies? Put another way: why should we not<br />

blame Khrushchev, rather than the Office of National Estimates, for the<br />

mistaken SNIE? 61<br />

Consider now <strong>Cuban</strong> <strong>intelligence</strong>. <strong>The</strong> DGI predicted that the United<br />

States would not tolerate the presence of Soviet nuclear <strong>missile</strong>s in Cuba.<br />

By 'not tolerate', they had in mind a military response. Now, the DGI was<br />

correct to predict that the United States would not tolerate the <strong>missile</strong>s, but<br />

it did not anticipate the blockade. How do we score this? Do we count it as<br />

two at-bats - one hit <strong>and</strong> one out for a batting average of .500? Or was the<br />

second estimate simply part of the first - a swing-<strong>and</strong>-a-miss during the one<br />

at-bat of consequence, so to speak - for an average of 1.000? 62<br />

Consider also that from April 1961 to September 1962, DGI estimated


Downloaded by [Harvard College] at 08:23 18 September 2012<br />

INTELLIGENCE PERFORMANCE 193<br />

that an American attack was not imminent. 63 During that period, no such<br />

attack took place. How do we score this? Do we count one successful at-bat<br />

for every day that the United States did not invade? Every week? Every<br />

month? Every three months? Our decision will certainly have dramatic<br />

implications for DGI's batting average. 64<br />

It is clear that there is no non-arbitrary, rigorous way to gauge the<br />

relative frequency of successful <strong>and</strong> unsuccessful judgments, even in<br />

retrospect. Even if there were, we could not be certain that this would be a<br />

valid indicator of the competence of an <strong>intelligence</strong> community. Sloppy<br />

estimates are sometimes right, <strong>and</strong> careful estimates sometimes wrong, for<br />

reasons over which the estimators have no control. <strong>The</strong> batting average<br />

metaphor is therefore misplaced.<br />

Indeed, it is possible to argue that a batting average is an imperfect<br />

indicator of skill even in baseball. Batters who play more games on artificial<br />

turf, against weaker pitchers, <strong>and</strong> against weaker defensive teams will have<br />

higher batting averages than better batters who play on grass against<br />

stronger pitchers <strong>and</strong> better defensive teams. Over a long season, a batting<br />

average can be a fairly reliable indicator of skill for players who play in a<br />

league with a balanced schedule, because these circumstances approximate<br />

the ceteris paribus condition. But even then a batting average is only a<br />

relative measure of skill, <strong>and</strong> the valid comparison group is limited to other<br />

players in the league. Intelligence analysis takes place under comparatively<br />

few parametric constraints. Analysts may be called upon to predict<br />

anything, anywhere, by anyone. Different <strong>intelligence</strong> communities may<br />

face radically different challenges - as James Wirtz discusses in his essay -<br />

<strong>and</strong> one <strong>intelligence</strong> community may face consistently more difficult tasks<br />

than another. Finally, in <strong>intelligence</strong> assessment there is no 'st<strong>and</strong>ard<br />

equipment', <strong>and</strong> corked bats, far from being forbidden, are actively<br />

encouraged. Intelligence 'batting averages', therefore, would be<br />

meaningless measures of relative <strong>performance</strong> even if it were possible to<br />

calculate them in a rigorous, non-arbitrary way.<br />

Knorr might reply that he did not intend for us to take him so literally.<br />

Perhaps he simply meant his metaphor to imply that the practical problem<br />

is to minimize the number of errors. Some might be tempted to say that this<br />

goes without saying. We are not so sure. It may not be the number of errors<br />

that best measures <strong>intelligence</strong> <strong>performance</strong>, but the kind of errors.<br />

Perils Illustrated: the US 'Failure' to Predict the Soviet Deployment<br />

It might be helpful at this point to examine an important judgment that has<br />

attracted special attention in the preceding essays (<strong>and</strong> elsewhere), to see<br />

some of these temptations at work, to illustrate the difficulties of avoiding<br />

them, <strong>and</strong> to highlight the difficulties of making rigorous evaluations. This


Downloaded by [Harvard College] at 08:23 18 September 2012<br />

194 INTELLIGENCE AND THE CUBAN MISSILE CRISIS<br />

will help prepare the ground for our discussion of how retrospective<br />

evaluation can be used constructively. Because of the richness of the<br />

available record, the US 'failure' to predict the Soviet deployment will<br />

serve well.<br />

<strong>The</strong> Stennis Report concluded that the 'predisposition of the [US]<br />

<strong>intelligence</strong> community to the philosophical conviction that it would be<br />

incompatible with Soviet policy to introduce strategic <strong>missile</strong>s into Cuba'<br />

was the primary cause of its failure to predict the deployment. 65 This<br />

preconception, according to the report, prevented the <strong>intelligence</strong><br />

community from giving 'proper weight' to 'indications to the contrary'. 66<br />

<strong>The</strong> implication is that US <strong>intelligence</strong> should not have been so firmly<br />

wedded to its preconceptions, <strong>and</strong> if it had not been, it might not have made<br />

this important error.<br />

<strong>The</strong> Stennis Report's conclusions provide an interesting example of<br />

Monday-morning quarterbacking. Did the US <strong>intelligence</strong> community have<br />

'good reasons' for relying less heavily upon the preconception that such a<br />

deployment would be incompatible with Soviet strategic policy? Garthoff<br />

writes: 'In the absence of clear evidence of deployment, the estimate [i.e.,<br />

SNIE 85-3-62] had to rest on an assessment of Soviet intentions, <strong>and</strong> the<br />

past record tended to support the conclusion that the Soviet leaders would<br />

not deploy strategic nuclear <strong>missile</strong>s in Cuba.' 67 Our sense is that most<br />

professional <strong>intelligence</strong> analysts, <strong>and</strong> most scholars of the <strong>Cuban</strong> <strong>missile</strong><br />

<strong>crisis</strong>, would concur with this judgment.<br />

Garthoff's statement has several interesting features. <strong>The</strong> first is the<br />

phrase, 'In the absence of clear evidence of deployment'. What, exactly, is<br />

'clear evidence of deployment'? 'Only direct evidence, such as aerial<br />

photographs, could be convincing', Garthoff writes. 68 As a psychological<br />

matter, this was undoubtedly true in 1962. Neither President Kennedy, nor<br />

senior members of the <strong>intelligence</strong> community - DCI McCone included, we<br />

suspect, since he was so concerned about stepping up photographic<br />

coverage of the isl<strong>and</strong> - would have been willing to conclude that the<br />

Soviets were deploying <strong>missile</strong>s to Cuba without photographs of Soviet<br />

<strong>missile</strong>s in Cuba. But ought American officials to have had such a<br />

dem<strong>and</strong>ing st<strong>and</strong>ard of proof? <strong>The</strong> Stennis Report did not state, but seemed<br />

to imply, that the answer was no, concluding that a contributing cause of the<br />

failure was the CIA's tendency 'to discredit <strong>and</strong> downgrade the reports of<br />

<strong>Cuban</strong> refugees <strong>and</strong> exiles'. 69 As we have already suggested, if the CIA<br />

discounted reports simply on the ground that they came from <strong>Cuban</strong><br />

sources, this would at least have been a logical error, <strong>and</strong> might also have<br />

been a pathological prejudice. 70 But would it have been an avoidable one? It<br />

is easy to say in retrospect that the CIA should not have been so hard on<br />

<strong>Cuban</strong> refugee reports, but it is difficult to imagine how CIA analysts


Downloaded by [Harvard College] at 08:23 18 September 2012<br />

INTELLIGENCE PERFORMANCE 195<br />

working without the benefit of hindsight could have 'corrected' for a<br />

prejudice of which they were not conscious, <strong>and</strong> which, though illogical, is<br />

perfectly normal psychologically. 71<br />

<strong>The</strong> second interesting feature of Garthoff's rejoinder is the phrase, 'the<br />

estimate had to rest on an assessment of Soviet intentions'. If the CIA could<br />

not see that a deployment was underway, it would have to try to read Soviet<br />

minds. <strong>The</strong> CIA had no sources in the Kremlin, <strong>and</strong> hence no good<br />

information on whether Khrushchev <strong>and</strong> his colleagues were contemplating<br />

a nuclear deployment. How, then, were they to know what Khrushchev was<br />

thinking?<br />

Enter the third interesting feature of Garthoff's statement: 'the past<br />

record tended to support the conclusion that the Soviet leaders would not<br />

deploy strategic nuclear <strong>missile</strong>s in Cuba'. Garthoff here invokes the<br />

principle of induction: namely, that the future will resemble the past.<br />

Several logical difficulties arise here. First, the CIA was attempting to<br />

ascertain the likelihood of something that had never happened before, <strong>and</strong><br />

to do so relied upon a principle whose strict application will always result<br />

in failure to anticipate the unprecedented. Second, the CIA made the logical<br />

mistake of inferring intentions from behavior. It is fallacious to infer present<br />

intentions from present behavior, let alone to infer present intentions from<br />

past behavior. An act, a practice, or a policy may be consistent with a variety<br />

of incompatible purposes (the deployment itself was logically consistent<br />

with both offensive <strong>and</strong> defensive motives, for example). 72 Third, even if<br />

past behavior could predict present intentions <strong>and</strong> future behavior, the<br />

inference would be arbitrary unless we could determine which of several<br />

possible ways of setting up the induction applied in a given case. It is<br />

certainly correct, as the CIA noted <strong>and</strong> emphasized, that the Soviet Union<br />

had never before deployed nuclear <strong>missile</strong>s beyond its borders. But neither<br />

had the Soviet Union ever failed to extend its nuclear umbrella over a<br />

friendly Marxist-Leninist state. Nor had the USSR ever passed up an<br />

opportunity to deploy l<strong>and</strong>-based nuclear <strong>missile</strong>s in the Western<br />

Hemisphere (Cuba was, after all, the first opportunity to arise). Finally, 'past<br />

Soviet behavior' was a composite of the behavior of several Soviet leaders,<br />

only one of whom was Khrushchev, <strong>and</strong> he had not yet had much of an<br />

opportunity to leave his imprint. As Beth Fischer notes, the CIA might have<br />

attempted to base the estimate specifically on an assessment of<br />

Khrushchev's intentions <strong>and</strong> Khrushchev's risk-taking propensities, instead<br />

of on some generic 'Soviet' characterization. 73 <strong>The</strong>re was no guarantee that<br />

Khrushchev would do what Lenin or Stalin would have done had they been<br />

in his shoes instead.<br />

Most US officials were shocked by the discovery of the deployment<br />

because it seemed to them to be so out of character. Nevertheless, it was


Downloaded by [Harvard College] at 08:23 18 September 2012<br />

196 INTELLIGENCE AND THE CUBAN MISSILE CRISIS<br />

trivially easy for analysts working with the benefit of hindsight to construct<br />

explanations of Khrushchev's behavior that conformed with their<br />

preconceptions. Some of these retrospective assessments cut the Gordian<br />

knot simply by assigning blame to Khrushchev for failing to appreciate the<br />

nature <strong>and</strong> intensity of American concerns about Soviet forces in Cuba, or<br />

for overestimating the likelihood that a covert deployment might succeed.<br />

<strong>The</strong> current record shows that Khrushchev erred, but it is interesting to note<br />

that these retrospective assessments - while in this respect quite accurate -<br />

themselves made various indefensible logical leaps. Knorr, for example,<br />

making use of a constructive distinction between technical <strong>and</strong> behavioral<br />

surprise (that is, surprise that results because someone succeeds in fooling<br />

us, <strong>and</strong> surprise that succeeds because it is, or seems to be, inconsistent with<br />

our set of expectations), 74 concludes that there was nothing wrong with the<br />

set of expectations about Soviet behavior prevalent in the US <strong>intelligence</strong><br />

community in 1962, <strong>and</strong> that the Stennis Report erred in finding fault with<br />

it. Instead, Knorr considers the failure to anticipate the deployment a case<br />

of 'apparent behavioral surprise', where the USSR seemed to have adopted<br />

a course of behavior that was inconsistent with US expectations, but, in fact,<br />

was not. In support of this conclusion, Knorr reasons that the lengthy period<br />

of planning <strong>and</strong> preparation that must have been involved in the deployment<br />

was 'not conducive to a strong component of emotional or irrational<br />

decision-making', <strong>and</strong> that Moscow's underestimation of the risk of the<br />

deployment can most probably be attributed to Soviet <strong>intelligence</strong> failure. 75<br />

Knorr is undoubtedly correct to suppose that there were Soviet <strong>intelligence</strong><br />

failures; but we now know that the Soviet mistake was over-determined,<br />

<strong>and</strong> that emotional or 'irrational' factors most certainly played a role.<br />

Other retrospective assessments downplayed Soviet errors <strong>and</strong> quite<br />

creatively constructed a set of beliefs on the basis of which Khrushchev<br />

'must' have been operating that would have made the covert deployment<br />

appear to be a rational gamble. <strong>The</strong>se are interesting because they managed<br />

to preserve three key assumptions: (1) that Khrushchev was aware of the<br />

nature <strong>and</strong> intensity of the American interest in Cuba; (2) that Khrushchev<br />

would not behave fundamentally differently from his predecessors; <strong>and</strong> (3)<br />

that Khrushchev would not accept a poor gamble. <strong>The</strong>se explanations<br />

typically relied heavily (for example) on the claim that Khrushchev had a<br />

low estimate of Kennedy's resolve - because of his youth, his 'liberalism',<br />

his failure to follow up the Bay of Pigs disaster with full-scale American<br />

intervention, his overly-intellectual <strong>performance</strong> at the 1961 Vienna<br />

summit, <strong>and</strong> so on - <strong>and</strong>/or the claim that Khrushchev thought that his<br />

stranglehold on Berlin gave him the leverage he needed to force Kennedy<br />

to accept a nuclear <strong>missile</strong> deployment in Cuba. <strong>The</strong>se assessments also<br />

make enormous logical leaps, egregiously demonstrating the fallacy of


Downloaded by [Harvard College] at 08:23 18 September 2012<br />

INTELLIGENCE PERFORMANCE 197<br />

inferring motives <strong>and</strong> calculations from behavior. 76 Even nuanced<br />

retrospective analyses that made some allowance for Soviet miscalculations<br />

tended to make indefensible assumptions <strong>and</strong> inferences that we now know,<br />

on the basis of a much richer record, to have been in error. Most strikingly,<br />

as Garthoff discusses at length, US post mortems consistently neglected or<br />

downplayed the extent to which Khrushchev's behavior was consistent with<br />

defensive or deterrent purposes. 77 It is interesting to note that every time US<br />

analysts raised the possibility - in real time or in retrospect - that<br />

Khrushchev might be operating on the basis of defensive motivations, they<br />

let this possible explanation wither on the vine.<br />

<strong>The</strong> conclusion we must draw, then, is that there was no logically valid<br />

way for the CIA to infer Khrushchev's intentions from the information<br />

available. 78 <strong>The</strong> information was consistent with any number of possible<br />

explanations <strong>and</strong> predictions. <strong>The</strong> best the CIA could do, as a matter of<br />

logic, was to say that Khrushchev might deploy nuclear <strong>missile</strong>s to Cuba,<br />

but that he might not. <strong>The</strong>y could also say, in effect, 'If we were in<br />

Khrushchev's position, knowing what we know, we would not attempt to<br />

deploy nuclear <strong>missile</strong>s to Cuba.' We think this is not a bad way of<br />

interpreting SNIE 85-3-62. <strong>The</strong> difficulty is that it tells us a great deal about<br />

the CIA, but very little about Khrushchev.<br />

And yet it is difficult to specify exactly what the CIA should have done<br />

differently, given existing constraints on information. When the President of<br />

the United States asked whether the Soviet Union was likely to station<br />

nuclear <strong>missile</strong>s in Cuba, the CIA had a duty to try to answer. To predict the<br />

deployment correctly, the CIA would have had to assume a number of<br />

cockamamie things - for example, that Khrushchev would not ask any of<br />

his experts about how the United States would react to a nuclear deployment<br />

in Cuba, <strong>and</strong> that Khrushchev could believe that the Soviet military could<br />

send 45,000 men <strong>and</strong> dozens of ballistic <strong>missile</strong>s 8,000 miles into the<br />

Caribbean without the United States catching on. It is easy to imagine how<br />

the President of the United States would have reacted to an estimate that<br />

stated these two assumptions explicitly.<br />

Even if the CIA had fully factored Khrushchev's risk-acceptance <strong>and</strong> his<br />

defensive or deterrent motivations into its estimates, it is not at all clear that<br />

the CIA would have concluded that such a deployment was, on balance,<br />

probable. It was a breathtaking gamble. We are inclined to agree with<br />

Garthoff that, even taking into account what was not then known, the<br />

estimate might have concluded that Soviet leaders probably would not place<br />

nuclear <strong>missile</strong>s in Cuba, even while giving 'more weight <strong>and</strong> attention to<br />

the possibility that they would do so'. 79 But it is unlikely that this would<br />

have made any practical difference to a President already keenly intent on<br />

monitoring the Soviet buildup in Cuba. 80


Downloaded by [Harvard College] at 08:23 18 September 2012<br />

198 INTELLIGENCE AND THE CUBAN MISSILE CRISIS<br />

Failures Consequential <strong>and</strong> Otherwise: How Should we Evaluate<br />

Intelligence Performance?<br />

It is ironic that the US <strong>intelligence</strong> community made such an intense effort<br />

to look for something that they did not expect to see. And while it is possible<br />

that the United States might have discovered the Soviet nuclear deployment,<br />

<strong>and</strong> detected the true size <strong>and</strong> nature of the Soviet conventional deployment,<br />

somewhat earlier than it did, had it relaxed its expectations, its st<strong>and</strong>ards of<br />

proof, or both, it is worth recalling - as Garthoff puts it - that '<strong>intelligence</strong><br />

did identify the <strong>missile</strong>s in sufficient time to allow successful American<br />

initiative <strong>and</strong> action to compel their withdrawal'. 81 'Discovery a week or<br />

two earlier in October,' Garthoff writes, '... would not have changed the<br />

situation faced by the President <strong>and</strong> his advisers'. 82<br />

In what sense, then, did the CIA 'fail'? It certainly failed to make a clear<br />

prediction that the Soviet Union would attempt to deploy nuclear <strong>missile</strong>s<br />

to Cuba. But it did not fail American policy makers who deeply dreaded the<br />

prospect. <strong>The</strong> CIA was vigilant, <strong>and</strong> told the President all that he really<br />

needed to know. Certain things the CIA did not know, <strong>and</strong> could not tell the<br />

President, even though he would have preferred knowing them: for<br />

example, exactly when the Soviet MRBMs in Cuba would become<br />

operational; whether or not nuclear warheads had yet arrived in Cuba, <strong>and</strong><br />

if so, where they were stored, <strong>and</strong> whether they had been issued to <strong>missile</strong><br />

units; <strong>and</strong> exactly how many Soviet troops were on the ground. We can call<br />

these failures if we like; but we are not certain that we see the point of doing<br />

so. Only the last was something the CIA could have been, able to divine<br />

given its existing capabilities, <strong>and</strong> given the information at its disposal. <strong>The</strong><br />

others are very difficult tasks, <strong>and</strong> the CIA could only have known these had<br />

it been lucky in data collection. 83 But in any case, none had a negative policy<br />

consequence. As Garthoff notes, the White House, the Pentagon, <strong>and</strong> the<br />

CIA all assumed in prudence that the Soviet <strong>missile</strong>s were operational <strong>and</strong><br />

that warheads were present, <strong>and</strong> given the nature of US contingency plans<br />

for military operations against Cuba, it is unlikely that the underestimate of<br />

the number of Soviet soldiers there would have materially affected the<br />

outcome of an invasion. 84<br />

<strong>The</strong> only significant lacuna that we can identify concerns the presence<br />

of tactical nuclear weapons. American officials did not presume that Soviet<br />

forces in Cuba would be equipped with tactical nuclear weapons, <strong>and</strong> had<br />

Kennedy sent American forces into Cuba, they would not have been<br />

equipped with similar weapons themselves. But while this was certainly a<br />

lacuna, it is unclear that the CIA should have been expected to discover that<br />

the Soviet Union had equipped its forces with tactical nuclear weapons, <strong>and</strong><br />

it is possible to argue that the CIA had furnished Kennedy with ample


Downloaded by [Harvard College] at 08:23 18 September 2012<br />

INTELLIGENCE PERFORMANCE 199<br />

information on the basis of which to conclude that an invasion carried with<br />

it unacceptable risks in any case. Since he did not choose to invade Cuba,<br />

the CIA's failure to establish the presence of tactical nuclear weapons did<br />

not have negative consequences. In fact, as Garthoff argues (correctly, in<br />

our view), the CIA's failure to establish the full size <strong>and</strong> character of the<br />

Soviet deployment had a distinctly positive policy consequence: it<br />

facilitated the resolution of the <strong>crisis</strong>. It may be an unusual circumstance<br />

when <strong>intelligence</strong> serves policy better by knowing less rather than more; but<br />

this is a useful reminder nonetheless that the task of <strong>intelligence</strong> is not to<br />

know everything, but to serve policy, <strong>and</strong> that <strong>intelligence</strong> can serve policy<br />

well even when it does not know everything, <strong>and</strong> sometimes even when it<br />

makes mistakes.<br />

What we see on the American side of the <strong>Cuban</strong> <strong>missile</strong> <strong>crisis</strong>, at least,<br />

is a constructive <strong>intelligence</strong>-policy dynamic. Communications between the<br />

White House <strong>and</strong> the CIA were far from perfect, <strong>and</strong> there was a great deal<br />

of uncertainty in the air. But while the CIA did not predict a Soviet nuclear<br />

deployment, <strong>and</strong> did not fully appreciate the size, purpose, <strong>and</strong> battlefield<br />

capability of the Soviet expeditionary force even after identifying MRBMs<br />

in Cuba, it managed to avoid communicating any overconfidence in what it<br />

did know (or believe) that would have either encouraged recklessness, or<br />

undercut the President's respect for, <strong>and</strong> appreciation of, the <strong>intelligence</strong><br />

process. Taking in the broad sweep of the CIA's assessments before, during,<br />

<strong>and</strong> after the acute phase of the <strong>crisis</strong>, we believe that it did quite an<br />

impressive job of serving US policy, in the light of its technical capabilities<br />

<strong>and</strong> the inherent limits of <strong>intelligence</strong> assessment. We can try to learn from<br />

its failure to predict the Soviet nuclear deployment, but it should not bear<br />

more than marginally on our evaluation of its <strong>performance</strong> over the course<br />

of the <strong>crisis</strong> as a whole.<br />

What of Soviet <strong>and</strong> <strong>Cuban</strong> <strong>intelligence</strong>? <strong>The</strong>re is a sense in which Soviet<br />

<strong>intelligence</strong> was never really given a chance to fail, at least prior to the acute<br />

phase. Intelligence cannot serve policy when policy makers do not take it<br />

into their confidence <strong>and</strong> ask it policy-relevant questions. Once the <strong>crisis</strong><br />

broke, it would appear that Soviet <strong>intelligence</strong> strove to give the Kremlin<br />

information useful for managing the <strong>crisis</strong>, but came up with very little.<br />

Certainly the KGB <strong>and</strong> GRU cannot be faulted for not having technical<br />

capabilities to rival CIA's or NSA's. But given the Soviet investment in<br />

Humint, one might have expected a better <strong>performance</strong> than Fursenko <strong>and</strong><br />

Naftali describe. We will never know, of course, what contribution to policy<br />

Soviet <strong>intelligence</strong> might have made had it better integrated <strong>and</strong> synthesized<br />

sources, <strong>and</strong> had it not engaged in self-censorship. But we do know that<br />

these shortcomings deprived it of any real possibility. Our expectations of<br />

the <strong>performance</strong> of Soviet <strong>intelligence</strong> must be somewhat lower than for


Downloaded by [Harvard College] at 08:23 18 September 2012<br />

200 INTELLIGENCE AND THE CUBAN MISSILE CRISIS<br />

American <strong>intelligence</strong> to begin with, in view of its technical inferiority <strong>and</strong><br />

the acute challenges it faced by virtue of the structural <strong>and</strong> domestic<br />

political circumstances under which it operated (as Wirtz discusses at<br />

length). Nevertheless, even when measured against a lower st<strong>and</strong>ard of<br />

reasonable expectations, Soviet <strong>intelligence</strong> hardly acquitted itself well. We<br />

may say in its defense, however, that while it had great difficulty being<br />

relevant, at least it cannot be held responsible for disastrous policy.<br />

We cannot hold <strong>Cuban</strong> <strong>intelligence</strong> up to a st<strong>and</strong>ard of <strong>performance</strong><br />

appropriate either to American or Soviet <strong>intelligence</strong>. It was a nascent<br />

community operating under severe technical <strong>and</strong> resource constraints.<br />

Moreover, the <strong>Cuban</strong> leadership was clearly selective in what questions it<br />

asked its <strong>intelligence</strong> community, how it listened, <strong>and</strong> how it used<br />

<strong>intelligence</strong>. Amuchastegui's account suggests that most of the pathologies<br />

evident in the <strong>Cuban</strong> <strong>intelligence</strong>-policy relationship lay on the policy side.<br />

Nevertheless, as Amuchastegui makes clear, <strong>Cuban</strong> <strong>intelligence</strong> did make<br />

mistakes. <strong>The</strong>y were not, however, mistakes of the kind that would<br />

encourage faulty policy, <strong>and</strong> Amuchastegui's tale indicates to us that <strong>Cuban</strong><br />

<strong>intelligence</strong> had a remarkably mature demeanor throughout the episode in<br />

question. It was circumspect, relatively open-minded, <strong>and</strong> acutely aware of<br />

the structural <strong>and</strong> domestic political challenges it faced. In professionalism,<br />

it certainly compared favorably with the KGB.<br />

Evaluating the <strong>performance</strong> of an <strong>intelligence</strong> community in this way -<br />

rather than focusing intently on specific spectacular judgments (usually<br />

misjudgments), second-guessing analysts with the benefit of hindsight, or<br />

attempting to gauge a rate of success - has, we believe, at least four merits.<br />

First, it forces us to factor into our evaluations some baseline expectation of<br />

<strong>performance</strong>. Clearly <strong>intelligence</strong> communities differ from each other in<br />

raw capability <strong>and</strong> the challenges they face. Simply counting successes <strong>and</strong><br />

failures - even if we could do it meaningfully - could tell us nothing about<br />

how well they are doing relative to each other. But at least we can determine<br />

roughly how well an <strong>intelligence</strong> community is doing relative to its own<br />

<strong>performance</strong> in the past when we begin by trying to establish a reasonable<br />

expectation. Second, while judgments of this kind can never be scientific,<br />

<strong>and</strong> while judgments of what is a 'reasonable' expectation are bound to be<br />

somewhat impressionistic, this style of evaluation has the virtue of<br />

highlighting the notion of a <strong>performance</strong> limit. All <strong>intelligence</strong> communities<br />

are going to make mistakes. Third, by forcing us to think about <strong>performance</strong><br />

over an extended period of time, rather than with respect to a specific<br />

judgment, it makes it easier to bear in mind that at the end of the day the<br />

crucial judgment we wish to make is how well <strong>intelligence</strong> serves policy,<br />

not how well <strong>intelligence</strong> performs in purely intellectual exercises such as<br />

forecasting. Fourth, by evaluating <strong>performance</strong> over an extended period of


Downloaded by [Harvard College] at 08:23 18 September 2012<br />

INTELLIGENCE PERFORMANCE 201<br />

time, it is possible to discern habits <strong>and</strong> tendencies to cultivate or to try to<br />

eliminate, strengths to exploit in the future, <strong>and</strong> weaknesses to try to shore<br />

up. 85 No clear practical implication follows from the conclusion that the<br />

CIA failed to predict the Soviet nuclear deployment. Clear practical<br />

implications follow from the conclusion that <strong>Cuban</strong> <strong>intelligence</strong> depended<br />

too heavily on Soviet <strong>and</strong> East European technical services, that the KGB<br />

relied too heavily on espionage, <strong>and</strong> that the CIA was excellent at technical<br />

monitoring but weaker at political analysis. We learn these things only by<br />

taking in the broad view.<br />

Monday-morning quarterbacking <strong>and</strong> attempting to improve the batting<br />

average, then, are misguided approaches to evaluating <strong>intelligence</strong><br />

<strong>performance</strong>. We offer instead a third sporting metaphor drawn from the<br />

only game harder than life itself- golf. As a metaphor, it has a few obvious<br />

weaknesses, but we believe that it also has much to commend it. So as not<br />

to try the non-sporting reader's patience unduly, we will simply highlight a<br />

few relevant points about the game of golf, leaving readers to tease out for<br />

themselves the isomorphisms:<br />

• <strong>The</strong> best golfers <strong>and</strong> the worst golfers all play the same courses. <strong>The</strong>re<br />

is a sense, then, in which their scores are directly comparable to one<br />

another. Moreover, built into the very nature of golf is a <strong>performance</strong><br />

limit. Excellent golfers will consistently beat par, but no golfer can even<br />

in principle score lower than 18 in one round of golf, <strong>and</strong> certainly no<br />

golfer playing a st<strong>and</strong>ard par-72 course with regulation equipment could<br />

ever hope to score (say) 36. Indeed, scores in the low 60s are rare.<br />

• While all golfers' scores are directly comparable to one another, the<br />

overwhelming majority of golfers compete not against others, but<br />

against themselves. A 'good' round of golf is one in which one scores<br />

lower than usual; a 'poor' round is one in which one scores higher than<br />

usual. (Amateur golfers who do compete against each other sometimes<br />

factor in their h<strong>and</strong>icaps - constrained averages of their previous scores<br />

- so that, no matter what the skill differential may be, they can make a<br />

game of it. Notice that even in this case, they are playing against<br />

themselves at the same time as they play against their opponents,<br />

because the player who scores best relative to his or her own average<br />

round wins.)<br />

• A golfer can make what for him or her would be an excellent score<br />

despite making some number of poor shots. Indeed, a round without a<br />

single poor shot is almost unheard of, even for professionals. <strong>The</strong> best<br />

golfers are those who make relatively few poor shots, <strong>and</strong> recover from<br />

them well.


Downloaded by [Harvard College] at 08:23 18 September 2012<br />

202 INTELLIGENCE AND THE CUBAN MISSILE CRISIS<br />

• <strong>The</strong> game has an important strategic element in addition to its simple<br />

mechanics. Players with beautiful swings who consistently choose the<br />

wrong clubs or make poor decisions about where to aim - players, for<br />

example, who refuse to acknowledge the existence of tall trees <strong>and</strong> water<br />

hazards - may score worse than players whose swings are technically<br />

inferior, but who play a smarter game.<br />

• Golfers have different styles, <strong>and</strong> different strengths <strong>and</strong> weaknesses.<br />

Some are risk-averse, <strong>and</strong> some are risk-acceptant. Some are better off<br />

the tee; others are better around the green; still others are better on the<br />

green. Some have no difficulty with s<strong>and</strong> traps <strong>and</strong> do not take pains to<br />

avoid them; others have great difficulty <strong>and</strong> try to avoid them at all costs.<br />

• Golfers rarely play only one course, though typically they become quite<br />

familiar with some number of courses. <strong>The</strong>y enjoy the challenge of<br />

playing new courses, though they underst<strong>and</strong> that, given two courses of<br />

approximately equal difficulty, they cannot expect to score as well on the<br />

course that they have never played before.<br />

• Golfers are strong believers in post mortems. When they score well, they<br />

like to try to identify <strong>and</strong> explain particularly good shots (often these are<br />

recovery shots). When they score poorly, they reflect solemnly upon<br />

their poor shots - though they may not choose to do so publicly. Golfers<br />

try to cultivate practices that work well, <strong>and</strong> to eliminate bad habits.<br />

• All golfers profoundly appreciate the role of luck.<br />

CONCLUSION: THE 'THEORY' AND PRACTICE OF INTELLIGENCE<br />

ASSESSMENT<br />

MENO: How will you look for it, Socrates, when you do not know at<br />

all what it is? How will you aim to search for something you do not<br />

know at all? If you should meet with it, how will you know that this is<br />

the thing that you did not know?" 6<br />

In 1978, Richard Betts lamented the lack of a 'theory' of <strong>intelligence</strong>. Betts<br />

suggested that '[njegative or descriptive theory - the empirical<br />

underst<strong>and</strong>ing of how <strong>intelligence</strong> systems make mistakes - is well<br />

developed,' but that positive theory <strong>and</strong> normative theory were not. '<strong>The</strong><br />

distinction is significant', Betts wrote, 'because there is little evidence that<br />

either scholars or practitioners have succeeded in translating such<br />

knowledge into reforms that measurably reduce failure. Development of a<br />

normative theory of <strong>intelligence</strong> has been inhibited because the lessons of<br />

hindsight do not guarantee improvement in foresight, <strong>and</strong> hypothetical


Downloaded by [Harvard College] at 08:23 18 September 2012<br />

INTELLIGENCE PERFORMANCE 203<br />

solutions to failure only occasionally produce improvement in practice.' 87<br />

We might quibble with the notion that failure can be reduced<br />

'measurably', but otherwise Betts's point is well-taken, <strong>and</strong> we see no<br />

evidence that scholars have managed to redress the lack of theory that he<br />

lamented. Certainly if by 'positive theory' we mean a robust <strong>and</strong> heuristic<br />

set of propositions relating causes <strong>and</strong> effects - e.g., condition x predicts y<br />

with probability p - it is impossible to identify anything in the open<br />

literature that would count as a 'theory' of <strong>intelligence</strong> assessment. And we<br />

may justly wonder whether any such thing is possible in principle. <strong>The</strong> very<br />

difficulty of operationalizing the notion of 'success' <strong>and</strong> 'failure' would<br />

seem an insurmountable obstacle. But this is the least of it. Intelligence<br />

assessment is not, strictly speaking, a science. It is an art. Intelligence<br />

analysts are not in the business of drawing logically-necessary conclusions<br />

about behavior on the basis of evidence generally knowable to be sufficient<br />

for that task. 88 Leaders of states do not make decisions under constraints<br />

sufficiently numerous <strong>and</strong> sufficiently knowable to make talk of the<br />

'probabilities' of their choosing alternative courses of action objectively<br />

meaningful. 89 Such language conveys information not about the target, but<br />

about the analyst. 90 When McCone <strong>and</strong> his subordinates at the Office of<br />

National Estimates debated whether Khrushchev was 'likely' or 'unlikely'<br />

to deploy MRBMs to Cuba, they articulated differences in their own fears<br />

<strong>and</strong> beliefs, <strong>and</strong> their own judgments of the implications of what American<br />

<strong>intelligence</strong> saw on the high seas <strong>and</strong> in Cuba. Khrushchev, however, was<br />

not literally rolling dice. <strong>The</strong>re was no objectively knowable 'likelihood'<br />

that he would do anything in particular. McCone was right for bad reasons,<br />

<strong>and</strong> his analysts were wrong for less-bad reasons, but Khrushchev was<br />

Khrushchev - a complicated man with a mind of his own, not some<br />

automaton preprogrammed according to a 'Soviet' behavioral algorithm.<br />

Betts is clearly correct that '[n]egative or descriptive theory - the<br />

empirical underst<strong>and</strong>ing of how <strong>intelligence</strong> systems make mistakes - is<br />

well developed', if by this he means that there are many different bodies of<br />

theory upon which to draw in order to try to explain errors. Fischer's essay<br />

provides a good example. <strong>The</strong> style of argument whereby one assesses the<br />

'goodness of fit' of a body of propositions well-established in one domain<br />

with the empirical details of a particular case in another does not, however,<br />

lead to the kind of cumulation or generalization to which positive science<br />

aspires. Nor does the application of any one body of theory to a series of<br />

cases of <strong>intelligence</strong> failures tend to satisfy (e.g.) a Lakatosian criterion of<br />

theoretical 'progress'." It is often possible to say that a body of theory can<br />

help us make sense of an otherwise puzzling event, because it supplies us<br />

with concepts <strong>and</strong> cause-effect propositions in terms of which to underst<strong>and</strong><br />

it. But the difficulty is that there may be many different bodies of theory that


Downloaded by [Harvard College] at 08:23 18 September 2012<br />

204 INTELLIGENCE AND THE CUBAN MISSILE CRISIS<br />

can do this, or that the body of theory that does the best job of helping us<br />

make sense of one puzzle may do a poor job, vis-a-vis some other body of<br />

theory, with respect to another.<br />

Without a positive theory of <strong>intelligence</strong> assessment, it is difficult to<br />

know how to go about constructing normative theory. Put another way, there<br />

can be no engineering without natural science. This is why it may be<br />

unfortunate that 'official post mortems of <strong>intelligence</strong> blunders inevitably<br />

produce recommendations for reorganization <strong>and</strong> changes in operating<br />

norms'. 92 Not only can we not be certain that we would have avoided one<br />

mistake had the organization <strong>and</strong> process of <strong>intelligence</strong> been different in<br />

the particular case at h<strong>and</strong>, but our tinkering may well induce other, possibly<br />

more serious mistakes in the future.<br />

What then, can we know in general about <strong>intelligence</strong> assessment, <strong>and</strong><br />

how can this knowledge help improve the <strong>performance</strong> of <strong>intelligence</strong>?<br />

Recognizing that there is a <strong>performance</strong> limit to <strong>intelligence</strong>, <strong>and</strong> that<br />

<strong>intelligence</strong> assessment is an art rather than a science, should certainly<br />

induce caution against lofty expectations. But there is one general<br />

phenomenon characteristic of human judgment <strong>and</strong> perception the greater<br />

appreciation of which can cultivate a useful circumspection in <strong>intelligence</strong><br />

assessment. Before closing, we will touch upon it <strong>and</strong> reflect upon how it<br />

might bear on practice.<br />

When Meno asked Socrates, 'How will you look for it ... when you do<br />

not know at all what it is?', he did not make the mere 'debater's argument'<br />

for which Socrates chided him. 93 Meno asked a profound question: how can<br />

we have knowledge of something without some prior familiarity with it?<br />

Once we allow some prior familiarity, we court infinite regress <strong>and</strong> the<br />

disturbing conclusion that knowledge is not possible at all. Socrates's<br />

solution — that all learning is mere recollection, for the immortal soul knows<br />

everything 94 - would seem on the face of it to substitute one paradox (the<br />

paradox of time) for another (the paradox of knowledge). In any case, the<br />

metaphysical presuppositions of Socrates's answer seem in no less want of<br />

justification than the answer itself.<br />

<strong>The</strong> paradox remains unresolved, though its contours <strong>and</strong> implications<br />

are now clearer, thanks to the efforts .of Gadamer, Quine, Chomsky, <strong>and</strong><br />

others. 95 For purposes of underst<strong>and</strong>ing <strong>intelligence</strong> assessment, the paradox<br />

is most enlightening when we throw it into reverse: we do hold certain<br />

beliefs (sometimes we like to call this 'knowledge'), <strong>and</strong> they do influence<br />

how we underst<strong>and</strong> new things. <strong>The</strong>re are many vocabularies to use when<br />

describing <strong>and</strong> exploring the phenomenon <strong>and</strong> many angles from which to<br />

look at it. Fischer describes it in the language of cognitive psychology, but<br />

we could just as well do so in the language of structural sociology,<br />

semiotics, cultural anthropology, or hermeneutics. 96


Downloaded by [Harvard College] at 08:23 18 September 2012<br />

INTELLIGENCE PERFORMANCE 205<br />

<strong>The</strong> insight that our own concepts <strong>and</strong> beliefs affect our interpretation of<br />

the behavior of others can incline <strong>intelligence</strong> analysts to reflect on the<br />

perspective they bring to bear on an <strong>intelligence</strong> problem, <strong>and</strong> the<br />

possibility that, in the absence of very good quality evidence about others'<br />

deliberations <strong>and</strong> motives, their judgments may say more about themselves<br />

than about their targets. This does not necessarily mean that analysts will<br />

have an easy time trying to achieve some 'perspective on perspective',<br />

however. Garthoff writes:<br />

Today, I believe it is clear that there was a failure of estimative<br />

empathy, of viewing the situation as the Soviet leaders did as they<br />

made their decision to place <strong>missile</strong>s in Cuba. In particular, even if<br />

Soviet considerations of redressing the unfavorable strategic global<br />

balance for defensive <strong>and</strong> offensive purposes was paramount, as I<br />

continue to believe it was, it is now evident that deterrence of a US<br />

attack on Cuba was also a consideration of major if not equal<br />

importance. Yet the failure to see the situation through Soviet (to say<br />

nothing of <strong>Cuban</strong>) eyes blinded the US <strong>intelligence</strong> community as a<br />

whole to that significant factor. American <strong>intelligence</strong> estimators<br />

should have recognized a Soviet incentive to defend Cuba against a<br />

plausible American threat well before the Soviet decision to deploy<br />

<strong>missile</strong>s was made. 97<br />

Certainly if American decision-makers had appreciated that Khrushchev felt<br />

boxed in, they might have considered an attempt to deploy nuclear <strong>missile</strong>s to<br />

Cuba rather more likely. As Garthoff supposes, this might have given the<br />

President additional reasons to try to forestall it by means of earlier <strong>and</strong><br />

stronger warnings. 98 But how should we interpret Garthoff's claim that the<br />

CIA 'should have recognized a Soviet incentive to defend Cuba against a<br />

plausible American threat well before the Soviet decision to deploy <strong>missile</strong>s<br />

was made'? As a retrospective lament, we endorse it completely. If Garthoff<br />

means to suggest that this was an avoidable mistake, however, we are not so<br />

sure. <strong>The</strong>re were many reasons why US <strong>intelligence</strong> did not <strong>and</strong> could not<br />

easily empathize with Khrushchev. It took the shock of the <strong>Cuban</strong> <strong>missile</strong><br />

<strong>crisis</strong> to demonstrate to American officials that they badly misunderstood<br />

him, <strong>and</strong> even then they did not appreciate exactly how they had<br />

misunderstood him. 99 It is difficult enough to empathize with an adversary in<br />

retrospect; it is asking a great deal of analysts to empathize in prospect. 100<br />

<strong>The</strong> paradox of knowledge must incline us to disagree with Fischer that<br />

there is a useful distinction to make between theory-driven <strong>and</strong> data-driven<br />

thinking. <strong>The</strong>re is no such thing as data-driven thinking. Facts never speak<br />

for themselves. We can only make sense of the world on the basis of some<br />

prior underst<strong>and</strong>ing. <strong>The</strong>re is a distinction to make, however, between


Downloaded by [Harvard College] at 08:23 18 September 2012<br />

206 INTELLIGENCE AND THE CUBAN MISSILE CRISIS<br />

people who are tightly wedded to their beliefs, <strong>and</strong> people who are<br />

relatively more open to the possibility that their beliefs <strong>and</strong> assumptions<br />

may be wrong, or who appreciate the potential explanatory power of two or<br />

more different sets of beliefs <strong>and</strong> assumptions. 101<br />

Intelligence analysis can never transcend its dependence upon prior<br />

assumptions <strong>and</strong> beliefs. Underst<strong>and</strong>ing presupposes them. Yet at the same<br />

time, underst<strong>and</strong>ing must always, to some extent, be frustrated by them. All<br />

<strong>intelligence</strong> communities would like to minimize the frustration, <strong>and</strong> to tip<br />

the balance between knowledge of self <strong>and</strong> knowledge of other in the<br />

direction of the latter. As a practical matter, though, how do <strong>intelligence</strong><br />

analysts avoid tripping over their prior assumptions <strong>and</strong> beliefs without<br />

being paralyzed by ambiguity <strong>and</strong> indecision? How do they steer between<br />

the Scylla of overcommitment, <strong>and</strong> the Charybdis of uncertainty ('an open<br />

mind is an empty mind')? 102 Scholars <strong>and</strong> practitioners have been very<br />

creative in proposing solutions, but, as Berts effectively demonstrates, the<br />

most prominent ones — assuming the worst, multiple advocacy,<br />

consolidation, Devil's advocacy (e.g., 'Team B' exercises), sanctions <strong>and</strong><br />

incentives, <strong>and</strong> 'cognitive rehabilitation <strong>and</strong> methodological consciousness'<br />

- all face important obstacles or have serious defects. 103 Betts is certainly<br />

correct that <strong>intelligence</strong> failures are inevitable, <strong>and</strong> he rather pessimistically<br />

concludes that the inherent limits of <strong>intelligence</strong> assessment suggest that we<br />

are unlikely to realize more than marginal benefits from procedural<br />

innovation.<br />

Fatalism may be entirely appropriate - if we insist upon thinking of<br />

'better' <strong>intelligence</strong> as an improvement in some rate of success, or as a<br />

purely intellectual measure of the accuracy of an <strong>intelligence</strong> community's<br />

judgments of an adversary. But we may be able to improve the effectiveness<br />

of <strong>intelligence</strong> quite dramatically simply by keying on possible sources of<br />

intellectual error. If <strong>intelligence</strong> failures are inevitable, why not exploit that<br />

fact when attempting to serve policy?<br />

Because <strong>intelligence</strong> assessment is so heavily dependent upon<br />

assumptions <strong>and</strong> specific modes of inference, it st<strong>and</strong>s to reason that if<br />

policy makers were more fully aware of them, they would be better able to<br />

read, underst<strong>and</strong>, <strong>and</strong> make use of <strong>intelligence</strong>. National leaders are often<br />

sophisticated analysts in their own right, who operate on the basis of certain<br />

assumptions about the world, <strong>and</strong> who draw their own conclusions on the<br />

basis of their own beliefs. <strong>The</strong>re is ample evidence of this on all sides in the<br />

<strong>Cuban</strong> <strong>missile</strong> <strong>crisis</strong>, certainly, although of the three leaders Khrushchev<br />

appears to have relied upon his own analysis most heavily, <strong>and</strong> Kennedy<br />

least. But all leaders are, to some extent, their own analysts, <strong>and</strong> are<br />

therefore confronted with the task of having to make sense of <strong>intelligence</strong><br />

assessments which may or may not reinforce their own expectations. Some


Downloaded by [Harvard College] at 08:23 18 September 2012<br />

INTELLIGENCE PERFORMANCE 207<br />

political leaders - Castro, for example - have a fascination for <strong>intelligence</strong>,<br />

<strong>and</strong> like to wade into the assessment process, voraciously seeking details on<br />

the source <strong>and</strong> content of the information their <strong>intelligence</strong> services acquire.<br />

Most, perhaps, are too busy to do this even should they wish to do so, <strong>and</strong><br />

must be content to receive the <strong>intelligence</strong> community's distilled wisdom.<br />

But relatively few, we suspect, think hard about their own assumptions,<br />

beliefs, <strong>and</strong> modes of inference, let alone those of their <strong>intelligence</strong> analysts,<br />

<strong>and</strong> accordingly most have but a dim appreciation of the underlying points<br />

of, <strong>and</strong> reasons for, similarity or disagreement.<br />

A political leader with strong beliefs <strong>and</strong> a high degree of selfconfidence<br />

may simply dismiss as flawed an <strong>intelligence</strong> report dissonant<br />

with his or her own judgments. Over time, given enough points of<br />

disagreement, this would quite naturally lead to an <strong>intelligence</strong>-policy rift.<br />

If <strong>intelligence</strong> analysts took pains, however, to flag the assumptions <strong>and</strong><br />

inference patterns undergirding their estimates, this would not only tend to<br />

improve the rigor <strong>and</strong> consistency of estimates, but it would enable policy<br />

makers to see more easily why they agreed or disagreed. In some cases this<br />

might even lead to a productive dialogue between policy makers <strong>and</strong><br />

analysts on crucial assumptions. This was precisely the rationale for an<br />

intriguing innovation instituted by the former Chairman of the National<br />

Intelligence Council, Joseph S. Nye Jr, who required <strong>intelligence</strong> estimates<br />

to identify <strong>and</strong> flag the crucial assumptions upon which they were based.<br />

<strong>The</strong> <strong>intelligence</strong> community initially resisted the requirement, but came to<br />

regard it as salutary for helping structure <strong>and</strong> clarify their own<br />

assessments. 104 For policy makers, it provided several points at which to<br />

engage an otherwise terse <strong>and</strong> remote summary document.<br />

As policy makers bear the ultimate burden of responsibility, anything<br />

that helps them to better underst<strong>and</strong> both <strong>intelligence</strong> <strong>and</strong> the<br />

presuppositions of policy represents a potentially important contribution.<br />

We can imagine taking Nye's innovation two steps further: (1) offering<br />

incoming national leaders briefings on the nature <strong>and</strong> limits of <strong>intelligence</strong><br />

early in their tenure; <strong>and</strong> (2) wherever possible appending to <strong>intelligence</strong><br />

estimates analyses of how crucial judgments in it would change if certain<br />

key assumptions were modified or relaxed. 105 <strong>The</strong>se practices would help<br />

prime policy makers to appreciate the <strong>performance</strong> limits of <strong>intelligence</strong>,<br />

<strong>and</strong> to integrate estimates more fully <strong>and</strong> more easily with their own<br />

judgments. At the same time, they would preserve <strong>intelligence</strong> estimates<br />

intact for those policy makers who are only interested in the distilled<br />

wisdom of the <strong>intelligence</strong> community <strong>and</strong> who have neither the time nor<br />

the inclination to peruse appendices.<br />

<strong>The</strong> main attractiveness of the practice lies in its potential for engaging<br />

decision makers in the <strong>intelligence</strong>-policy process. From a practical point of


Downloaded by [Harvard College] at 08:23 18 September 2012<br />

208 INTELLIGENCE AND THE CUBAN MISSILE CRISIS<br />

view, it makes little sense to conclude, as did Dean Rusk, McGeorge Bundy,<br />

<strong>and</strong> John McCone, that US <strong>intelligence</strong> estimates 'took too little account of<br />

the possibility of a dangerous new departure in Soviet policy'. 106 What does<br />

it mean to 'take more account of a possibility'? Would this have materially<br />

affected President Kennedy's use of CIA estimates? We think not. However,<br />

even if the CIA had not changed its estimates, it might have been useful to<br />

try to make more explicit the assumptions on the basis of which they drew<br />

the conclusion that Khrushchev most likely would not deploy nuclear<br />

weapons to Cuba, <strong>and</strong> it might have been helpful to try to identify the<br />

conditions under which Khrushchev might attempt to do so (e.g., if he failed<br />

to underst<strong>and</strong> that a US president would face enormous domestic <strong>and</strong><br />

international pressure not to tolerate such a deployment; if he<br />

underestimated US <strong>intelligence</strong> capabilities; <strong>and</strong> if he were motivated by<br />

fear <strong>and</strong> insecurity, rather than by opportunity). At a minimum this would<br />

have given Kennedy <strong>and</strong> the ExComm a head start on trying to fathom<br />

Khrushchev's mistake after 15 October. 107<br />

But no adjustment to the presentation <strong>and</strong> content of estimates st<strong>and</strong>s<br />

even a remote chance of improving <strong>intelligence</strong> <strong>performance</strong> when political<br />

leaders ignore, manipulate, lead, or censor their <strong>intelligence</strong> services. Both<br />

Amuchastegui <strong>and</strong> Fursenko <strong>and</strong> Naftali provide ample evidence of<br />

pathological <strong>intelligence</strong>-policy relationships caused by meddling or<br />

overconfident leaders. 108 This serves to underscore the importance of<br />

recalling that effective policy requires a certain disposition on the part of<br />

political leaders, as well as a certain competence on the part of professional<br />

<strong>intelligence</strong> analysts. <strong>The</strong> wide variation evident in the three <strong>intelligence</strong>policy<br />

relationships examined in this volume strikes us as utterly typical of<br />

<strong>intelligence</strong>-policy relationships in general. If so, this may be the only sense<br />

in which the <strong>Cuban</strong> <strong>missile</strong> <strong>crisis</strong> was run-of-the-mill.<br />

Certain events may reflect the significant dimensions of all your life,<br />

mirroring your entire history in a passing moment. Have you ever had<br />

an experience like that? Have you been caught by an event that<br />

suddenly pulled the curtains back?<br />

- Michael Murphy, Golf in the Kingdom


Downloaded by [Harvard College] at 08:23 18 September 2012<br />

INTELLIGENCE PERFORMANCE 209<br />

NOTES<br />

1. Throughout we will cite the essays in this volume by author, without title.<br />

2. Fursenko <strong>and</strong> Naftali, p.79; <strong>and</strong> Amuchastegui, p.89.<br />

3. Garthoff, p.45, citing U.S. Department of State, Foreign Relations of the United States,<br />

1961-1963, Vol. XI, <strong>Cuban</strong> Missile Crisis <strong>and</strong> Aftermath (Washington DC: GPO 1997)<br />

p.625 (hereafter cited as FRUS, 1961-63).<br />

4. Fursenko <strong>and</strong> Naftali, p.66.<br />

5. 'Before being sent out to the US to run the KGB's principal station there, Feklisov had<br />

overseen the <strong>intelligence</strong> assessment in 1960 that Eisenhower was unlikely to invade<br />

without a <strong>Cuban</strong> assault on Guantánamo Bay or the creation of a <strong>missile</strong> base on the isl<strong>and</strong>.<br />

Two years later, he still believed this, despite the change in administration <strong>and</strong> the<br />

experience of the Bay of Pigs. In the middle of March 1962, Feklisov reported that<br />

Kennedy was unlikely to approve an invasion because a military intervention would<br />

undermine the Alliance For Progress.' Fursenko <strong>and</strong> Naftali, pp.73-4. Surviving senior<br />

members of the Kennedy administration overwhelmingly concur that Kennedy would not<br />

have authorized an invasion of Cuba without some serious provocation, such as a<br />

deployment of Soviet nuclear <strong>missile</strong>s to Cuba James G. Blight <strong>and</strong> David A. Welch, On<br />

the Brink: Americans <strong>and</strong> Soviets Reexamine the <strong>Cuban</strong> Missile Crisis, 2nd ed. (NY:<br />

Noonday 1990); James G. Blight, Bruce J. Allyn, <strong>and</strong> David A. Welch, Cuba on the Brink:<br />

Castro, <strong>The</strong> Missile Crisis, <strong>and</strong> the Soviet Collapse (NY: Pantheon 1993) passim.<br />

6. Fursenko <strong>and</strong> Naftali, p.73.<br />

7. Amuchastegui, pp.99-100.<br />

8. <strong>The</strong> weight of evidence <strong>and</strong> testimony available today would strongly suggest that<br />

Khrushchev did not seriously begin to consider a nuclear deployment to Cuba until April<br />

or May 1962, <strong>and</strong> that planning for the operation did not begin until shortly thereafter. See,<br />

e.g., Gen. Anatoli I. Gribkov <strong>and</strong> William Y. Smith, Operation Anadyr: U.S. <strong>and</strong> Soviet<br />

Generals Recount the <strong>Cuban</strong> Missile Crisis (Chicago: Edition Q 1994); Richard Ned<br />

Lebow <strong>and</strong> Janice Gross Stein, We All Lost the Cold War (Princeton UP 1994); Raymond<br />

L. Garthoff, Reflections on the <strong>Cuban</strong> Missile Crisis, rev. ed. (Washington DC: Brookings<br />

1989); Blight <strong>and</strong> Welch, On the Brink (note 5); Blight, Allyn, <strong>and</strong> Welch, Cuba on the<br />

Brink (note 5). <strong>The</strong> second reason which apparently led <strong>Cuban</strong> <strong>intelligence</strong> to conclude that<br />

Khrushchev must have conceived the deployment much earlier was the judgment that the<br />

Soviet Union - a notoriously sluggish <strong>and</strong> bureaucratic state - could not have planned <strong>and</strong><br />

carried out such an ambitious redeployment in a mere 90 days. It is important to note,<br />

however, that <strong>Cuban</strong> <strong>intelligence</strong> apparently believed that the deployment was substantially<br />

complete by mid-September, <strong>and</strong> did not appreciate that the first Soviet MRBMs in Cuba<br />

only became operational in late October - four <strong>and</strong> a half months after planning could have<br />

begun in earnest following a late-May decision to proceed - <strong>and</strong> that the IRBMs never<br />

arrived. While this would still be a significant accomplishment for a notoriously sluggish<br />

<strong>and</strong> bureaucratic state, it could not be considered downright unbelievably rapid.<br />

9. Fursenko <strong>and</strong> Naftali, p.84.<br />

10. Blight, Allyn, <strong>and</strong> Welch, Cuba on the Brink (note 5), pp.77-80. <strong>The</strong> second task of the<br />

delegation was to assess the prospect that strategic nuclear <strong>missile</strong>s could be deployed in<br />

Cuba without the United States discovering them. See p. 185, below.<br />

Fursenko <strong>and</strong> Naftali are correct to state that Alekseev 'was [not]consulted on the<br />

project' (p.75) if by this they mean that he was not brought in on the deliberations before<br />

Khrushchev had made up his mind to propose the deployment to Castro. However, as<br />

Alekseev recounts the tale, once Khrushchev had decided to make the offer, he did ask<br />

Alekseev how he thought Castro would react. Alekseev predicted incorrectly that Castro<br />

would not agree. Blight, Allyn, <strong>and</strong> Welch, Cuba on the Brink (note 5) pp.77-8.<br />

11. Timothy Naftali, personal communication.<br />

12. See, e.g., Graham T. Allison, Essence of Decision: Explaining the <strong>Cuban</strong> Missile Crisis<br />

(Boston: Little, Brown 1971) p. 110.<br />

13. Amuchastegui, p. 101.<br />

14. Since <strong>Cuban</strong> <strong>intelligence</strong> apparently discovered the true nature of the deployment in due


Downloaded by [Harvard College] at 08:23 18 September 2012<br />

210 INTELLIGENCE AND THE CUBAN MISSILE CRISIS<br />

course, it is conceivable that they simply inferred that Soviet <strong>intelligence</strong> in Cuba must<br />

have been aware of it as well. This might have been an accurate judgment. But even if it<br />

were incorrect, it would be natural, because the <strong>Cuban</strong>s - like the Americans - understood<br />

the Soviet Union as a coherent rational actor. See our discussion in note 96, below.<br />

15. Fursenko <strong>and</strong> Naftali, pp.80-82.<br />

16. Ibid. p.82.<br />

17. Fursenko <strong>and</strong> Naftali, p.70; Amuchastegui, pp.91-2.<br />

18. Nicola Miller, Soviet Relations with Latin America 1959-1987 (Cambridge UP 1989);<br />

Jorge I. Dominguez, To Make a World Safe for Revolution: Cuba's Foreign Policy<br />

(Cambridge, MA: Harvard UP 1989).<br />

19. Amuchastegui, p.99.<br />

20. Personal communications. Naftali adds in another personal communication: 'It seems odd<br />

that Alekseev would have been recalled [to Moscow] in the manner he was if Che was on<br />

his way to Cuba. [Also,] I have a clear recollection of the letters prepared by the Presidium<br />

for Castro in the first week of May, <strong>and</strong> not one refers to a fraternal visit by El Che.'<br />

21. Aleks<strong>and</strong>r Fursenko <strong>and</strong> Timothy Naftali, 'One Hell of a Gamble': Khrushchev, Castro <strong>and</strong><br />

Kennedy, 1958-1964 (NY: Norton 1997) p.70. Amuchastegui finds it difficult to imagine<br />

that Che would have made such a probe at that time, <strong>and</strong> recalls that the chief purpose of<br />

Che's visit was to discuss economic cooperation (personal communication).<br />

22. Amuchastegui, p.99.<br />

23. Che's next documented voyage to the Soviet Union took place in late August 1962. <strong>The</strong><br />

chief purpose of that trip was to propose making the deployment public. It seems unlikely<br />

that Amuchastegui is thinking of this particular trip, as increasing levels of military aid<br />

were not on the agenda. Blight <strong>and</strong> Welch, On the Brink (note 5) pp.333-4.<br />

24. Fursenko <strong>and</strong> Naftali, 'One Hell of a Gamble' (note 21) p.168.<br />

25. Ibid. p. 187.<br />

26. Garthoff, pp.28-9, 58, note 28.<br />

27. See ibid. p.28.<br />

28. Beth Fischer gives good reasons for preferring a cognitive to a motivational explanation in<br />

her essay [pp. 28-9].<br />

29. Amuchastegui, pp.115-16, note 38.<br />

30. Garthoff, pp.22-3.<br />

31. See, e.g., the reports of 27 Sept. <strong>and</strong> 1 Oct., reprinted in Mary S. McAuliffe (ed.) CIA<br />

Documents on the <strong>Cuban</strong> Missile Crisis (Washington DC: CIA History Staff 1992)<br />

pp. 107-9 (hereafter CIA Documents).<br />

32. [Richard Lehman], Excerpt from Memo for Director of Central Intelligence, 'CIA<br />

H<strong>and</strong>ling of the Soviet Buildup in Cuba', 14 Nov. 1962 [Excerpt], Top Secret, declassified;<br />

in CIA Documents (note 31) p.99.<br />

33. Certainly there is ample evidence that the KGB played at best a minor role throughout. It<br />

would appear from the somewhat thinner testimonial <strong>and</strong> documentary record on Soviet<br />

military <strong>intelligence</strong> that the GRU was marginalized as well. See generally Fursenko <strong>and</strong><br />

Naftali, 'One Hell of a Gamble' (note 21) passim.<br />

34. Fursenko <strong>and</strong> Naftali, p.75.<br />

35. In his annual message to Congress on 2 Dec. 1823, President James Monroe warned<br />

European states against any future attempts to colonize the Americas, declared that the<br />

United States would consider any attempt by the nations of Europe to extend their system<br />

into the hemisphere 'dangerous to our peace <strong>and</strong> safety', <strong>and</strong> disavowed American<br />

participation in European wars. See Ernest R. May, <strong>The</strong> Making of the Monroe Doctrine<br />

(Cambridg, MA: Belknap 1975). While Khrushchev may have believed that American<br />

participation in World Wars I <strong>and</strong> II represented a renunciation of the Monroe Doctrine,<br />

Troyanovsky would have known that no one in the United States so considered it.<br />

36. Blight, Allyn, <strong>and</strong> Welch, Cuba on the Brink (note 5) p.72.<br />

37. <strong>The</strong> KGB, despite a lack of highly-placed sources, seems to have had a fairly good<br />

underst<strong>and</strong>ing of President Kennedy, his attitude toward Cuba, <strong>and</strong> the constraints under<br />

which he operated domestically. Fursenko <strong>and</strong> Naftali, pp.68-9.<br />

<strong>The</strong> KGB's reading of the Bay of Pigs - that JFK had been pushed by the CIA <strong>and</strong> by


Downloaded by [Harvard College] at 08:23 18 September 2012<br />

INTELLIGENCE PERFORMANCE 211<br />

the hawks in his administration, <strong>and</strong> would, if left to his own devices, act less aggressively<br />

toward Castro (ibid, p.69) - is extremely interesting, <strong>and</strong> it would be useful to know exactly<br />

why the KGB drew this particular conclusion. Cf. James G. Blight <strong>and</strong> Peter Kornbluh<br />

(eds) Politics of Illusion: <strong>The</strong> Bay of Pigs Invasion Reexamined (Boulder, CO: Lynne<br />

Rienner 1997).<br />

38. Fursenko <strong>and</strong> Naftali, p.75.<br />

39. Ibid., p.72.<br />

40. Ibid.<br />

41. It is conceivable that Khrushchev chose not to task the KGB with such an assessment in<br />

part because he feared it would compromise the secret, as Beth Fischer surmises (p. 165).<br />

<strong>The</strong>re is no direct evidence to this effect, however.<br />

42. Fursenko <strong>and</strong> Naftali, p.74.<br />

43. Blight <strong>and</strong> Welch, On the Brink (note 5) pp.333^4. It is interesting to note that senior<br />

members of the Kennedy administration unanimously agree that had Khrushchev<br />

attempted to deploy the <strong>missile</strong>s openly, the United States would have been in a much more<br />

difficult position. <strong>The</strong> secrecy <strong>and</strong> deception surrounding the deployment enabled the<br />

United States to characterize it as sinister <strong>and</strong> aggressive, <strong>and</strong> to deflect attention from the<br />

undeniable fact that what the Soviet Union <strong>and</strong> Cuba were doing was entirely legal.<br />

44. Ibid. p.239; Sergei Khrushchev, personal communication.<br />

45. Graham Allison has suggested that organizational routines may explain the failure of the<br />

Soviet military to camouflage the <strong>missile</strong> sites effectively; Essence of Decision, (note 12),<br />

p.111. An explanation more consistent with the available evidence is incompetence. See<br />

David A. Welch, '<strong>The</strong> Organizational Process <strong>and</strong> Bureaucratic Politics Paradigms:<br />

Retrospect <strong>and</strong> Prospect', International Security Mil (Fall 1992) pp.112-46.<br />

46. 'Sharaf Rashidov had reported to the Defense Council that Cuba's forests would provide<br />

just the needed cover for our <strong>missile</strong>s. Only someone with absolutely no competence in<br />

such technical matters could have reached such a conclusion.' Gribkov <strong>and</strong> Smith,<br />

Operation Anadyr (note 8), p.40.<br />

47. Fursenko <strong>and</strong> Naftali, p.66.<br />

48. Amuchastegui, p.91.<br />

49. Ibid. p.102.<br />

50. Ibid. pp.104-5.<br />

51. Fursenko <strong>and</strong> Naftali, 'One Hell of a Gamble' (note 21) pp.268, 272.<br />

52. Castro has spoken in general terms about his conviction that the United States, once ready,<br />

would pounce, <strong>and</strong> would seek to do so without warning. Evidently he was determined not<br />

to make the mistake Stalin had made in 1941 of failing to prepare to meet an assault that<br />

could be launched at any time. See Blight, Allyn <strong>and</strong> Welch, Cuba on the Brink (note 5)<br />

pp.109-10.<br />

53. US Senate, Committee on Armed Services, Investigation of the Preparedness Program,<br />

Interim Report on the <strong>Cuban</strong> Military Buildup by the Preparedness Investigating<br />

Subcommittee (Washington DC: GPO 1963) (hereafter Stennis Report); President's<br />

Foreign Intelligence Advisory Board, James R. Killian Jr, Chairman, Memo for the<br />

President <strong>and</strong> Report, 4 Feb. 1963, Top Secret, 10 pp.; reprinted in CIA Documents (note<br />

31) pp.361-71.<br />

54. McCone, Memo for the President, 28 Feb. 1963, <strong>and</strong> 'Conclusions', in ibid, pp.373-6.<br />

55. Richard K. Berts, 'Analysis, War, <strong>and</strong> Decision: Why Intelligence Failures are Inevitable',<br />

World Politics 31/1 (Oct. 1978) pp.61-89. Many of the constraints on <strong>intelligence</strong><br />

assessment that Berts identifies may be understood in terms of the psychological dynamics<br />

. Fischer discusses in her essay, although his study predates much of the research upon<br />

which Fischer draws. Betts concludes that '[<strong>intelligence</strong> failure is political <strong>and</strong><br />

psychological more often than organizational'. Ibid. p.61.<br />

Betts also draws our attention to the fact that <strong>intelligence</strong> communities are often engaged<br />

in a zero-sum strategic interaction, whereby success for one logically implies failure for the<br />

other. <strong>The</strong> fact that even in the most celebrated cases surprise is never truly absolute further<br />

underscores the sense in which 'the best possible' <strong>performance</strong> is always something less<br />

than 'perfect <strong>performance</strong>'. Richard K. Betts, 'Surprise Despite Warning: Why Sudden


Downloaded by [Harvard College] at 08:23 18 September 2012<br />

212 INTELLIGENCE AND THE CUBAN MISSILE CRISIS<br />

Attacks Succeed', Political Science Quarterly 95/4 (Winter 1980-81) pp.551-72. See also<br />

Michael H<strong>and</strong>el, 'Intelligence <strong>and</strong> the Problem of Strategic Surprise', Journal of Strategic<br />

Studies 7/3 (Sept. 1984) p.230.<br />

56. See, e.g., Garthoff, p.23: 'Some ambiguous or equivocal <strong>intelligence</strong> indications in<br />

September-October were noted but did not comm<strong>and</strong> as much attention as, in hindsight,<br />

they should have. In particular, it was observed that several Soviet merchant ships with<br />

large hatches en route to Cuba were riding high in the water, indicating bulky but relatively<br />

light cargo, such as <strong>missile</strong>s. Some of these ships were seen unloading normal cargoes, but<br />

others were reported to be unloaded at night, again a possible indicator of a cargo of special<br />

sensitivity. After the <strong>missile</strong>s were discovered, in retrospect it was recognized that these<br />

particular ships had undoubtedly brought in the <strong>missile</strong>s in early to mid-September.' US<br />

<strong>intelligence</strong> did notice all of this at the time, but it may be doubted whether the CIA had<br />

compelling reasons in 1962 to regard it all as more significant than they did.<br />

57. <strong>The</strong> classic study is Roberta Wohlstetter, Pearl Harbor: Warning <strong>and</strong> Decision (Stanford<br />

UP 1962). For an early yet insightful comparison of the <strong>Cuban</strong> <strong>and</strong> Pearl Harbor cases, see<br />

idem, 'Cuba <strong>and</strong> Pearl Harbor: Hindsight <strong>and</strong> Foresight', Foreign Affairs 43/4 (July 1965)<br />

pp.691-707.<br />

58. Monday-morning quarterbacking is much easier for football fans than for critics of<br />

<strong>intelligence</strong>, because in football it is possible to play the percentages. We can justifiably<br />

criticize a coach for calling a long pass on third-<strong>and</strong>-inches, because a running play would<br />

have a much better chance of success (<strong>and</strong> a much lower chance of resulting in a turnover).<br />

Critics of <strong>intelligence</strong> do not ordinarily have good-quality base rate information with which<br />

to second-guess <strong>intelligence</strong> professionals.<br />

59. Klaus Knorr, 'Failures in National Intelligence Estimates: <strong>The</strong> Case of the <strong>Cuban</strong> Missiles',<br />

World Politics 16/3 (April 1964) pp.455-67, 460.<br />

60. Special National Intelligence Estimate (SNIE) 85-3-62, <strong>The</strong> Military Buildup in Cuba, 19<br />

Sept. 1962, Secret; in CIA Documents (note 31), p. 93; also reprinted FRUS. 1961-1963<br />

(note 3), Vol.X, Cuba, Jan.l961-Sept. 1962, pp.1070-80.<br />

61. Garthoff notes that some of the authors of the September SNIE subsequently argued that<br />

the estimate had been correct <strong>and</strong> that Khrushchev had been mistaken (p.21). <strong>The</strong>re is a<br />

sense in which this is undoubtedly true. One possible rebuttal is that the CIA should have<br />

known that Khrushchev would not consult his American specialists, <strong>and</strong> that they should<br />

have factored this into their estimate. This reply, however, begs all of the difficult questions<br />

to which we allude under the previous head.<br />

62. Echoing the point of the previous paragraph, it is worth noting that had President Kennedy<br />

not chosen to deliberate for a week before choosing his response to the Soviet deployment,<br />

he might very well have done as <strong>Cuban</strong> <strong>intelligence</strong> anticipated. On 16 Oct., the mood in<br />

the White House cabinet room was decidedly belligerent. <strong>The</strong> delay was crucial for<br />

permitting tempers to cool. See generally James G. Blight, <strong>The</strong> Shattered Crystal Ball:<br />

Fear <strong>and</strong> Learning in the <strong>Cuban</strong> Missile Crisis (Savage, MD:Rowman & Littlefield 1990).<br />

Although the timing of the American response was not something <strong>Cuban</strong> <strong>intelligence</strong><br />

controlled, it might well have had a significant effect on our retrospective assessment of<br />

their <strong>performance</strong>.<br />

63. Amuchastegui, p.114, note 26.<br />

64. According to Amuchastegui, DGI also considered an American attack inevitable (ibid.).<br />

Since this was an open-ended prediction, we are technically still not in a position to<br />

determine whether that estimate was correct.<br />

65. Stennis Report (note 53), p.2.<br />

66. Ibid. p. 11.<br />

67. Garthoff, p.21. Note that Garthoff does not make this statement specifically in reply to the<br />

Stennis Report.<br />

68. Ibid., p.23.<br />

69. Stennis Report (note 53), p.5. Cf. Amuchastegui's claim that '[n]othing [<strong>Cuban</strong> sources]<br />

said would be credited unless they showed up in Miami with a Soviet <strong>missile</strong>' (p.103).<br />

70. See pp.181-2 above.<br />

71. Fischer's essay extensively documents the propensity to evaluate information in the light


Downloaded by [Harvard College] at 08:23 18 September 2012<br />

INTELLIGENCE PERFORMANCE 213<br />

of pre-existing beliefs. Clearly the large number of false reports of <strong>missile</strong> sightings by<br />

<strong>Cuban</strong> agents <strong>and</strong> refugees had led CIA analysts to believe that <strong>Cuban</strong> sources were<br />

unreliable, <strong>and</strong> that their reports had ulterior purposes.<br />

72. It might be replied here that certain kinds of behavior unambiguously telegraph intentions.<br />

For example, we can infer reliably that a leader who masses troops on the border in a full<br />

battle-ready posture intends to attack. This behavior, however, is fully consistent with other<br />

intentions: e.g., to provoke an attack, to intimidate, to signal acute concern, <strong>and</strong> so forth.<br />

See Michael H<strong>and</strong>el, Perception, Deception <strong>and</strong> Surprise: <strong>The</strong> Case of the Yom Kippur War<br />

(Jerusalem: Leonard Davis Institute 1976); <strong>and</strong> Janice Gross Stein, 'Calculation,<br />

Miscalculation, <strong>and</strong> Conventional Deterrence II: <strong>The</strong> View from Jerusalem', in Robert<br />

Jervis, Richard Ned Lebow <strong>and</strong> Janice Gross Stein (eds) Psychology & Deterrence<br />

(Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins UP 1985) pp.60-88.<br />

73. Fischer, p. 159.<br />

74. 'Failures in National Intelligence Estimates' (note 59), p.462,<br />

75. Ibid. pp.463, 465.<br />

76. <strong>The</strong> best example is Arnold L. Horelick, '<strong>The</strong> <strong>Cuban</strong> Missile Crisis: An Analysis of Soviet<br />

Calculations <strong>and</strong> Behavior', World Politics 16/3 (April 1964) pp.363-89. Cf. also Arnold<br />

Horelick <strong>and</strong> Myron Rush, Strategic Power <strong>and</strong> Soviet Foreign Policy (U. of Chicago Press<br />

1966) p.141: 'Soviet calculations throughout the <strong>Cuban</strong> <strong>missile</strong> <strong>crisis</strong> can be reconstructed<br />

with some degree of confidence, because the confrontation with the United States was so<br />

open'.<br />

77. Garthoff, pp.24-6, 36, 46-7.<br />

78. Similarly, US analysts <strong>and</strong> policy makers had insufficient evidence on the basis of which<br />

to draw reliable conclusions about what Soviet leaders might be willing to consider by way<br />

of retaliation for American military action against Cuba. Garthoff writes: 'In response to<br />

either an air strike or an invasion, the <strong>intelligence</strong> estimators concluded that because the<br />

Soviet leaders "would almost certainly not resort to general war <strong>and</strong> could not hope to<br />

prevail locally, we believe that the Soviets would consider retaliatory actions outside<br />

Cuba", <strong>and</strong> the most likely place would be Berlin - but "major harassments", not a military<br />

move on West Berlin. As for a countering strike against some US base around the world<br />

(such as the <strong>missile</strong>s in Turkey, although not specified), a Soviet retaliatory move of this<br />

kind was considered "possible but in our view unlikely". Again, this judgment was never<br />

tested, but although the estimated Soviet response (to "consider" retaliation by a noncombat<br />

harassing action) was much more mild than many (including Secretary McNamara<br />

<strong>and</strong> some other members of the ExComm) believed likely, <strong>and</strong> was certainly a prudent<br />

caution, it appears from all we now know to have been the most the Soviet leaders would<br />

have done, if that.' Ibid. pp.30-1.<br />

79. Ibid. p.21. N.B. that Garthoff argues, on the basis of present knowledge, that this is what<br />

the estimate should have concluded,<br />

80. Klaus Knorr therefore seems to us to be splitting hairs unduly finely when he states, '<strong>The</strong><br />

question is: why did the <strong>intelligence</strong> community fail to warn the government earlier that<br />

such a Soviet move was distinctly possible, if not probable, instead of estimating that it was<br />

improbable, though not impossible?' 'Failures in National Intelligence Estimates' (note<br />

59), p.456.<br />

81. Garthoff, p.18. We would choose some word other than 'compel', in view of the fact that<br />

the United States agreed secretly to withdraw its Jupiter <strong>missile</strong>s from Turkey as a quid pro<br />

quo.<br />

82. Ibid. p.24.<br />

83. See, e.g., Mark Kramer, '<strong>The</strong> <strong>Cuban</strong> Missile Crisis <strong>and</strong> Nuclear Proliferation', Security<br />

Studies 5/1 (Autumn 1995) pp.171-9 ; <strong>and</strong> James G. Blight <strong>and</strong> David A. Welch, 'On<br />

Historical Judgment <strong>and</strong> Inference: A Reply to Mark Kramer', ibid. 5/4 (Summer 1996)<br />

pp.172-82. We should qualify this last statement by noting that we do not know whether<br />

US signals <strong>intelligence</strong> had collected anything that would have clarified any of these<br />

matters.<br />

84. Garthoff, pp.27-9.<br />

85. We appreciate that how one bounds the relevant period may be a choice of some


Downloaded by [Harvard College] at 08:23 18 September 2012<br />

214 INTELLIGENCE AND THE CUBAN MISSILE CRISIS<br />

consequence. Defining 'an event' spatio-temporally is, to some extent, arbitrary, <strong>and</strong> is<br />

perhaps usefully understood as a function of socio-cultural propensities. We have remarked<br />

before upon the different underst<strong>and</strong>ings of the <strong>crisis</strong> in the United States, the Soviet Union<br />

(now Russia), <strong>and</strong> Cuba, <strong>and</strong> the significance of the different names by which it is known<br />

in each country. We have also argued that culturally-rooted differences in problemrepresentation<br />

help account for its genesis <strong>and</strong> greatly complicated its resolution. See<br />

Blight, Allyn, <strong>and</strong> Welch, Cuba on the Brink (note 5) pp.318-72. We do not believe that<br />

this represents a serious obstacle for the present point, however: as long as it is possible to<br />

conceptualize an <strong>intelligence</strong> encounter as having taken place over some period of time,<br />

<strong>and</strong> as consisting of some number of discrete phases or episodes, it should be possible —<br />

within limits - to arrive at some evaluation of <strong>performance</strong>, even if those<br />

conceptualizations are arbitrary, <strong>and</strong> the episodes in fact linked. Thus by contrasting US<br />

<strong>intelligence</strong> <strong>performance</strong> with respect to Cuba over the period 1958-61 <strong>and</strong> 1961-62 —<br />

with the Bay of Pigs <strong>and</strong> the <strong>Cuban</strong> <strong>missile</strong> <strong>crisis</strong> as foci - we can meaningfully conclude<br />

that the CIA performed poorly in one period <strong>and</strong> well in another, <strong>and</strong> we can learn<br />

something of practical consequence from the contrast.<br />

86. Plato, Meno, 80d; in Five Dialogues, trans. G.M.A. Grube (Indianapolis: Hackett 1981) p.<br />

69.<br />

87. Berts, 'Analysis, War, <strong>and</strong> Decision' (note 55), p.61.<br />

88. Consider, for example, the following: 'Castro in March had moved to purge key old<br />

Moscow-line communist leaders from his regime, <strong>and</strong> some in the US <strong>intelligence</strong><br />

community saw this as causing a significant rift in <strong>Cuban</strong>-Soviet relations. Military<br />

shipments from the USSR, after a buildup in 1961, were lower in the first half of 1962. <strong>The</strong><br />

evidence before July 1962 thus tended to support an estimate that a major Soviet military<br />

buildup in Cuba was not likely.' Garthoff, p.22. US <strong>intelligence</strong> apparently inferred from<br />

the Escalante affair that Soviet-<strong>Cuban</strong> relations would deteriorate; yet, as Amuchastegui<br />

explains, the purpose of Castro's purge was precisely the reverse: to prepare the ground for<br />

a closer security relationship (Amuchastegui, p.92). <strong>The</strong> purge itself was consistent with<br />

diametrically opposite motivations, <strong>and</strong> US <strong>intelligence</strong> simply leapt to the conclusion that<br />

it implied one in particular. Garthoff considers the US judgment 'intuitive', but this, of<br />

course, is merely another way of saying that it was more consistent with suppressed<br />

assumptions.<br />

89. This is a complicated claim whose full exegesis would take us very far afield. <strong>The</strong> gist,<br />

however, is that leaders of states make decisions on the basis of idiosyncratic beliefs <strong>and</strong><br />

judgments about the lessons of history <strong>and</strong> how the world works, <strong>and</strong> do so consciously in<br />

reaction to the historical record, often precisely so as to surprise. Important choices are<br />

often unprecedented, or have important unique features, such that the historical record<br />

provides no basis for estimating a probability distribution. Among the important works that<br />

touch various aspects of this issue are Robert Jervis, '<strong>The</strong> Future of World Politics: Will it<br />

Resemble the Past?' International Security 16/3 (Winter 1991/92) pp.39-73; Yuen Foong<br />

Khong, Analogies at War: Korea, Munich, Dien Bien Phu, <strong>and</strong> the Vietnam Decisions of<br />

1965 (Princeton UP 1992); <strong>and</strong> Richard E. Neustadt <strong>and</strong> Ernest R. May, Thinking in Time:<br />

<strong>The</strong> Uses of History for Decision-Makers (NY: Free Press 1986). See also Masato Kimura<br />

<strong>and</strong> David A. Welch, 'Specifying "Interests": Japan's Claim to the Northern Territories <strong>and</strong><br />

Its Implications for International Relations <strong>The</strong>ory', International Studies Quarterly 42/2<br />

(June 1998) pp.213-44.<br />

90. Among political scientists there is a widespread impression that 'expected utility theory'<br />

can serve as the basis for <strong>intelligence</strong> assessment. Bruce Bueno de Mesquita claims a<br />

successful point-prediction rate of over 90 per cent across a variety of political decisionmaking<br />

domains for a particular expected-utility model based upon Black's median voter<br />

theorem. Bruce Bueno de Mesquita, David Newman <strong>and</strong> Alvin Rabushka, Forecasting<br />

Political Events: <strong>The</strong> Future of Hong Kong (New Haven, CT: Yale UP 1985); Duncan<br />

Black, Voting in Committees <strong>and</strong> Elections (Cambridge UP 1958). Bueno de Mesquita's<br />

model is not, however, an 'expected utility' theory at all, merely a computational device for<br />

aggregating subjective judgments of actors' weighted preferences on a given issue. Its<br />

predictive power - whatever that may be (many of the details are classified) - depends


Downloaded by [Harvard College] at 08:23 18 September 2012<br />

INTELLIGENCE PERFORMANCE 215<br />

essentially upon the quality of the inputs, which are themselves generated by area<br />

specialists in a non-scientific way. For further discussion, see Janice Gross Stein <strong>and</strong> David<br />

A. Welch, 'Rational <strong>and</strong> Psychological Approaches to the Study of International Conflict:<br />

Comparative Strengths <strong>and</strong> Weaknesses', in Alex Mintz <strong>and</strong> Nehemia Geva (eds)<br />

Decision-Making on War <strong>and</strong> Peace: <strong>The</strong> Cognitive-Rational Debate (Boulder, CO: Lynne<br />

Rienner 1997) pp.51-77.<br />

91. Imre Lakatos, 'Falsification <strong>and</strong> the Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes', in<br />

idem <strong>and</strong> Alan Musgrave (eds) Criticism <strong>and</strong> the Growth of Knowledge (Cambridge UP<br />

1970) pp.91-196; idem <strong>The</strong> Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes, Vol.1 (ibid.<br />

1978). To simplify a bit, Lakatos argued that we should prefer theory x to theory y when x<br />

explains everything y explains, plus additional facts.<br />

92. Betts, 'Analysis, War, <strong>and</strong> Decision' (note 55), p.63.<br />

93. 'I know what you want to say, Meno. Do you realize what a debater's argument you are<br />

bringing up, that a man cannot search either for what he knows or for what he does not<br />

know? He cannot search for what he knows - since he knows it, there is no need to search<br />

- nor for what he does know, for he does not know what to look for.' Meno, 80e, p.69.<br />

94. Ibid. 81b-d, pp.6-70.<br />

95. Hans-Georg Gadamer, Truth <strong>and</strong> Method, trans. Garrett Barden <strong>and</strong> John Cumming<br />

(London: Sheed & Ward 1975); Willard Van Orman Quine, Word <strong>and</strong> Object (Cambridge,<br />

MA: MIT Press 1964); Noam Chomsky, Syntactic Structures (<strong>The</strong> Hague: Mouton 1965).<br />

See also Graeme Nicholson, Seeing <strong>and</strong> Reading (London: Macmillan 1984).<br />

96. For applications of a competing perspective (which the author calls 'critical<br />

constructivism') on the phenomenon as it bears on problem-representation in the <strong>Cuban</strong><br />

<strong>missile</strong> <strong>crisis</strong>, see Jutta Weldes, Constructing National Interests: <strong>The</strong> U.S. <strong>and</strong> the <strong>Cuban</strong><br />

Missile Crisis (U. of Minnesota Press forthcoming 1998). For a critical cultural perspective<br />

as it bears on <strong>intelligence</strong> assessment, see Robert B. Bathurst, Intelligence <strong>and</strong> the Mirror:<br />

On Creating an Enemy (Oslo: PRIO 1993).<br />

It would certainly appear that what might be thought of as 'intellectual culture' has a<br />

profound effect on political judgments of all kinds, including <strong>intelligence</strong> assessments. In<br />

the Western world, at least five stock assumptions about how international politics works,<br />

<strong>and</strong> about how leaders make decisions — roughly congruent with the 'Realist'<br />

underst<strong>and</strong>ing of international politics - tend to dominate. Among the most important of<br />

these assumptions are (1) that all states always seek 'power'; (2) that leaders are 'rational';<br />

(3) that all leaders underst<strong>and</strong>, <strong>and</strong> respond to, threats <strong>and</strong> incentives; (4) that the<br />

adversary's behavior is always intentional; <strong>and</strong> (5) that the adversary's actions are always<br />

coordinated <strong>and</strong> meaningful. Typically, when leaders <strong>and</strong> analysts attempt to make sense of<br />

an adversary's behavior, they infer evil intent from actions they dislike, <strong>and</strong> dismiss as<br />

disingenuous <strong>and</strong> instrumental arguments adversaries make that appeal to notions such as<br />

justice or fairness. Often these are important mistakes. <strong>The</strong>se assumptions exert a powerful<br />

spin on ambiguous data, <strong>and</strong> can lead to tragic misjudgments. For extensive discussion, see<br />

David A. Welch, Justice <strong>and</strong> the Genesis of War, Cambridge Studies in International<br />

Relations 29 (Cambridge UP 1993); <strong>and</strong> idem, 'Remember the Falkl<strong>and</strong>s? Missed Lessons<br />

of a Misunderstood War', InternationalJournal 52/3 (Summer 1997) pp.483-507.<br />

97. Garthoff, p.46.<br />

98. As we suggest in our introductory essay, these may not have been effective in the absence<br />

of credible offers to alleviate Khrushchev's anxieties, <strong>and</strong> it is difficult to imagine what<br />

those offers might have been, given the political realities of the day. Moreover, this is not<br />

an <strong>intelligence</strong> failure: Kennedy did not need the impetus of an <strong>intelligence</strong> assessment to<br />

communicate more clearly with Khrushchev. Yet, conceivably, had the CIA raised the<br />

alarm earlier, it might have been able to serve policy even better than it did.<br />

99. <strong>The</strong>re were glimmers of underst<strong>and</strong>ing: 'In seeking to underst<strong>and</strong> why Khrushchev <strong>and</strong> the<br />

other Soviet leaders believed they could succeed', Garthoff writes, 'the ORR study<br />

concluded (in my view correctly) that Khrushchev, "having lived restively under the<br />

shadow of U.S. strategic bases for more than a decade", <strong>and</strong> now having his first<br />

opportunity to do likewise, "may have felt confident that the U.S. would underst<strong>and</strong> the<br />

rules as he did - that military bases on the opponent's periphery are facts of great power


Downloaded by [Harvard College] at 08:23 18 September 2012<br />

216 INTELLIGENCE AND THE CUBAN MISSILE CRISIS<br />

life which fall far short of a provocation to war".' Ibid.,p.39. But as Garthoff also notes<br />

extensively, even after the shock of the <strong>missile</strong> <strong>crisis</strong>, retrospective evaluations consistently<br />

underestimated Khrushchev's deterrent <strong>and</strong> defensive motivations.<br />

100. It seems to us undeniable that the self-awareness of the US government - perhaps of the<br />

entire country - was so deficient, <strong>and</strong> so discrepant with <strong>Cuban</strong> perceptions of the United<br />

States, as to be laughable were not the stakes too high for laughter. In all the posturing, no<br />

one seems to have asked two questions: (1) Are our actions scaring the <strong>Cuban</strong>s as well as<br />

deterring the Soviets? (2) If so, might Cuba's sense of insecurity drive the Soviets to<br />

undertake desperate measures on its behalf? From the American perspective, Cuba was<br />

simply absent from the <strong>Cuban</strong> <strong>missile</strong> <strong>crisis</strong>.<br />

While it is possible to imagine that some American official or commentator might have<br />

posed these questions <strong>and</strong> answered them affirmatively in 1962, it is difficult to imagine<br />

this having had much effect on America's Cuba policy, given the grip that the rational<br />

deterrence/Cold War perspective had on the American imagination at the time.<br />

101. See, e.g., Janice Gross Stein, 'Political Learning by Doing: Gorbachev as Uncommitted<br />

Thinker <strong>and</strong> Motivated Learner', International Organization 48/2 (Spring 1994)<br />

pp. 155-83. Notwithst<strong>and</strong>ing their judgment that the United States would eventually try to<br />

destroy the <strong>Cuban</strong> Revolution, <strong>Cuban</strong> <strong>intelligence</strong> concluded that an American attack was<br />

not imminent after the Bay of Pigs because (a) the pattern of activity conducted under the<br />

rubric of Operation 'Mongoose' seemed ill-designed to prepare the ground for an<br />

American invasion; <strong>and</strong> (b) <strong>Cuban</strong> <strong>intelligence</strong> believed that the United States would not<br />

invade Cuba without adequate diplomatic 'cover' <strong>and</strong> the sanction of other Latin American<br />

states. Amuchastegui, pp.96-7. Clearly DGI drew heavily upon assumptions about<br />

American behavior when attempting to predict American behavior. We disagree with<br />

Fischer that '[d]ata-driven thinking could have led [Khrushchev] to the (correct)<br />

conclusion that the Kennedy administration was not planning an attack in 1962.' Fischer,<br />

p.156. Since American behavior was consistent with different interpretations, data-driven<br />

thinking, even if it were possible, would have led to no particular conclusion at all. Instead,<br />

we would suggest that Khrushchev would have reached the same conclusion as <strong>Cuban</strong><br />

<strong>intelligence</strong> if he had relied upon a different set of assumptions with which to interpret<br />

ambiguous American behavior.<br />

Fischer also writes: 'It is also interesting to note that while <strong>Cuban</strong> <strong>and</strong> American<br />

<strong>intelligence</strong> reached the same (inaccurate) conclusion about Soviet motives, they appear to<br />

have done so via different methods of information processing. American analysis appears<br />

to have been heavily theory driven. Beginning with the assumption that the Soviet Union<br />

was a cautious, opportunistic aggressor unlikely to risk a nuclear deployment to Cuba,<br />

American analysts concluded that the purpose of the deployment was to give the Soviets a<br />

strategic advantage over the United States once the deployment became evident. <strong>Cuban</strong><br />

<strong>intelligence</strong>, on the other h<strong>and</strong>, inferred Soviet motives from the available data —<br />

specifically, the discrepancy between the dire Soviet assessments of the American threat<br />

<strong>and</strong> <strong>Cuban</strong> assessments that such a threat was receding. This finding suggests that there is<br />

no necessary relationship between one method of information processing <strong>and</strong> the accuracy<br />

of inferences. Data-driven <strong>and</strong> theory-driven information processing can both lead to<br />

inaccurate assessments.' Ibid. pp.163-4. We underst<strong>and</strong> <strong>Cuban</strong> judgments here as no less<br />

theory-driven than American judgments.<br />

According to Amuchastegui's account, <strong>Cuban</strong>s had been somewhat suspicious of Soviet<br />

intentions all along, <strong>and</strong> therefore, among the available set of working assumptions about<br />

Soviet behavior, was the hypothesis that Soviet policy with respect to Cuba was driven by<br />

narrow self-interest rather than altruism. <strong>Cuban</strong> <strong>intelligence</strong> was never wedded to the<br />

altruism assumption <strong>and</strong> had no difficulty assimilating the available evidence to an<br />

alternative assumption. Note also that Soviet dissimulation did not logically imply that the<br />

Soviet motive in deploying nuclear <strong>missile</strong>s to Cuba was to gain a strategic advantage over<br />

the United States. Many possible purposes could be served thereby, as Americans<br />

recognized — including the defense of Cuba (Khrushchev may simply have believed that the<br />

<strong>Cuban</strong>s would never take what was necessary for their defense unless he exaggerated the<br />

American threat). See., e.g, Allison, Essence of Decision (note 12) pp.43-56.


Downloaded by [Harvard College] at 08:23 18 September 2012<br />

INTELLIGENCE PERFORMANCE 217<br />

102. Betts, 'Analysis, War, <strong>and</strong> Decision' (note 55) p.84.<br />

103. Ibid. pp.73-84.<br />

104. We are not clear on the chief reason for the resistance, though it is possible to imagine that<br />

estimators feared it would be onerous, distracting, or superfluous.<br />

105. One of the striking features both of US <strong>intelligence</strong> assessment <strong>and</strong> White House<br />

decisionmaking during the <strong>Cuban</strong> <strong>missile</strong> <strong>crisis</strong> was the partial success achieved in relaxing<br />

certain common assumptions <strong>and</strong> articulating the implications - specifically, the<br />

assumptions that the adversary is a 'unitary' <strong>and</strong> 'rational' actor. Garthoff writes that 'Two<br />

special national <strong>intelligence</strong> estimates issued on 19 October (SNIE 11-18-62) <strong>and</strong> 20<br />

October (SNIE-11-19-62) ... [recognized] "the possibility that the Soviets, under pressure<br />

to respond, would again miscalculate <strong>and</strong> respond in a way which, through a series of<br />

actions <strong>and</strong> reactions, could escalate into general war",' <strong>and</strong> that 'in any use of military<br />

force by the United States, the Soviet leaders would be "alarmed <strong>and</strong> agitated" (SNIE 11-<br />

18-62) or at least "surprised <strong>and</strong> probably alarmed" (SNIE-11-19-62).' Garthoff, p.30. US<br />

policy makers, similarly, 'prudently allowed for the possibility that even if Moscow<br />

instructions prohibited initiative of Soviet forces in Cuba to fire the nuclear <strong>missile</strong>s there,<br />

in case of an American air strike or invasion any surviving Soviet <strong>missile</strong>s might be fired<br />

either with or without authorization from Moscow. Both the general assumption of tight<br />

Moscow control, <strong>and</strong> the recognition that it nonetheless might fail, were properly taken into<br />

account.' Ibid. p.54. In our view, US policy makers were encouraged to relax these<br />

assumptions about Soviet behavior in part because of their own experience during the <strong>crisis</strong><br />

- <strong>and</strong> particularly at its climax - of American comm<strong>and</strong>-<strong>and</strong>-control problems. See<br />

generally Blight <strong>and</strong> Welch, On the Brink (note 5), passim. Contrast Argentine leaders'<br />

rigid (<strong>and</strong> illogical) ascriptions of unity <strong>and</strong> rationality to British actions prior to <strong>and</strong> during<br />

the Falkl<strong>and</strong>s/Malvinas war of 1982 (Welch, 'Remember the Falkl<strong>and</strong>s?' note 96); Alberto<br />

A. De Vita, Malvinas 82: Como y Por Que (Buenos Aires: Institute de Publicaciones<br />

Navales 1994).<br />

106. McCone meeting with Kennedy, 5 Jan. 1963, in FRUS, 196-1963, Vol.XI, pp.702-4; cited<br />

by Garthoff, p.46.<br />

107. Note also that it would have helped minimize the dangers of post-hoc rationalization<br />

characteristic of several prominent retrospective studies that attempted to make sense of<br />

Khrushchev's calculations. See the discussion on pp.196-7, above.<br />

108. Amuchastegui, for example, writes: 'Not only did <strong>Cuban</strong> leaders privilege Soviet over<br />

<strong>Cuban</strong> assessments, but <strong>Cuban</strong> <strong>intelligence</strong> was instructed to treat the inevitable<br />

confrontation with the United States as its guiding strategic assumption shaping every<br />

aspect of data collection <strong>and</strong> interpretation' (p.98), <strong>and</strong> that 'in June 1962, Piñeiro had<br />

given strict instructions not to reflect upon the topic of Soviet forces <strong>and</strong> <strong>missile</strong>s in Cuba<br />

in any <strong>Cuban</strong> assessments' (p.100).<br />

109. Michael Murphy, Golf in the Kingdom (NY: Arkana 1972) p.127.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!