08.08.2013 Views

Agreement in Modern Greek Coordinate Noun Phrases

Agreement in Modern Greek Coordinate Noun Phrases

Agreement in Modern Greek Coordinate Noun Phrases

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

<strong>Agreement</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>Modern</strong> <strong>Greek</strong> Coord<strong>in</strong>ate<br />

<strong>Noun</strong> <strong>Phrases</strong><br />

Desp<strong>in</strong>a Kazana<br />

A thesis submitted for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy<br />

Department of Language and L<strong>in</strong>guistics<br />

University of Essex<br />

June, 2011


Abstract<br />

A central issue posited by those who have studied agreement with coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns is<br />

that the <strong>in</strong>dividual conjuncts have different agreement features from the coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase<br />

(Dalrymple and Kaplan, 2000). This thesis explores agreement <strong>in</strong> MG coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns<br />

with<strong>in</strong> the constra<strong>in</strong>t-based framework of Lexical-Functional Grammar. It <strong>in</strong>vestigates<br />

predicate-argument and head-modifier agreement with coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns and agreement<br />

with disjunctively conjo<strong>in</strong>ed nouns.<br />

In predicate-argument agreement, the syntactic and semantic (Corbett, 1991; Wechsler,<br />

2009; Sadler, 2006) agreement pr<strong>in</strong>ciples occur crossl<strong>in</strong>guistically. I argue that a referential<br />

pr<strong>in</strong>ciple also exists, motivated by a Contextually Introduced Referent implied <strong>in</strong> the<br />

sentence. CIR is the superord<strong>in</strong>ate term of the coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns and the predicative adjective/participle<br />

copies its agreement features. Thus, I propose an LFG syntactic account for<br />

referential agreement. In head-modifier agreement, MG modifiers behave different from the<br />

def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er. I argue that a shared modifier shows concord agreement, it scopes<br />

over coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns and occurs with the jo<strong>in</strong>t and split <strong>in</strong>terpretations. A shared determ<strong>in</strong>er<br />

shows <strong>in</strong>dex/concord agreement, it scopes over coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns and occurs only<br />

with the jo<strong>in</strong>t <strong>in</strong>terpretation. The def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er allows some exceptional patterns <strong>in</strong><br />

plural and occurs with a split read<strong>in</strong>g when nouns are a natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation. I capture natural<br />

coord<strong>in</strong>ation patterns follow<strong>in</strong>g the standard analysis on coord<strong>in</strong>ation. In agreement<br />

with disjunctive coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns, I argue that native speakers choose an agree<strong>in</strong>g verb<br />

based on the <strong>in</strong>terpretation of disjunction as ‘and-coord<strong>in</strong>ate’ and as ‘exclusive-or’. I capture<br />

this follow<strong>in</strong>g Eggert’s analysis which treats or as a subset function, us<strong>in</strong>g lamda-DRT,<br />

and I <strong>in</strong>troduce a special lexical entry for or which can be <strong>in</strong>terpreted either way. However,<br />

I show that verb agreement is also determ<strong>in</strong>ed by other factors, such as the features of<br />

<strong>in</strong>dividual conjuncts, the type of sentence and the subject position <strong>in</strong> the sentence.


Acknowledgements<br />

This thesis would never have been completed without the help and support of a number of<br />

people. The first person I am deeply grateful to is my supervisor Professor Louisa Sadler.<br />

Her encouragement and support was really valuable to me and kept me go<strong>in</strong>g through the<br />

hard times all these years. Louisa has been an endless source of <strong>in</strong>spiration from many<br />

different aspects. Her deep knowledge <strong>in</strong> l<strong>in</strong>guistics and her ability to come across her<br />

ideas is unique. She taught me so many th<strong>in</strong>gs and answered countless questions through<br />

the time we worked together and she was always there to listen and advise me when I<br />

encountered difficulties. She supported me <strong>in</strong> evey way she could, not only on l<strong>in</strong>guistic<br />

issues but also on personal issues. Even towards the end when th<strong>in</strong>gs became really hard,<br />

she believed <strong>in</strong> me and motivated me to stick to my goal and not give up.<br />

I would also like to thank Doug Arnold, who was there to help me any time of the<br />

day, especially with my LaTex problems. Also, many thanks go to Andrew Spencer, Bob<br />

Borsley, who advised me and guided me <strong>in</strong> the supervisory board meet<strong>in</strong>gs, and Mary<br />

Dalrymple and Ash Asudeh who provided me with some <strong>in</strong>sightful comments <strong>in</strong> LFG09.<br />

My special thanks go to Maria Flouraki for be<strong>in</strong>g a good friend, for shar<strong>in</strong>g with me her<br />

passion <strong>in</strong> l<strong>in</strong>guistics, for her encouragement and for the great collaboration we had, which<br />

I hope will cont<strong>in</strong>ue.<br />

Many thanks go to a number of people <strong>in</strong> the department of Language and L<strong>in</strong>guistics<br />

at Essex University. In particular, I thank the staff and the members of the Constra<strong>in</strong>tbased<br />

L<strong>in</strong>guistics Discussion Group: Ryo Otoguro, Takafumi Maekawa, Antonis Polentas,<br />

Miriam Urgelles and Kakia Chatsiou. Also, my deep appreciation goes to Wyn Johnson<br />

for giv<strong>in</strong>g me the opportunity to work as a Graduate Teach<strong>in</strong>g Assistant and improve my<br />

teach<strong>in</strong>g skills <strong>in</strong> the field of l<strong>in</strong>guistics.<br />

My PhD research has been supported f<strong>in</strong>ancially from the Economic & Social Research<br />

Council, British Government. I am grateful to them s<strong>in</strong>ce they funded my work all these<br />

years and they also gave me the opportunity to participate <strong>in</strong> a number of conferences<br />

abroad.<br />

Last but not least, I would like to thank my family. Many thanks go to my parents<br />

and my sister for their support especially towards the end. My deepest thanks go to my<br />

partner and husband Apostolos P<strong>in</strong>akidis who believed <strong>in</strong> me from the very beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g,<br />

urged me to start this difficult ‘journey’ and supported me <strong>in</strong> every aspect from the start.<br />

His motivat<strong>in</strong>g words and strong encouragement brought me back when I felt lost and gave<br />

me the courage to f<strong>in</strong>ish what I started. Though, I am mostly grateful to him for be<strong>in</strong>g a<br />

‘mother’ apart from a father to our baby son. I also need to thank him for his technical<br />

support and feedback and for patiently answer<strong>in</strong>g data questions, even though he found it<br />

tir<strong>in</strong>g at times. ..<br />

F<strong>in</strong>ally, I would like to say my deepest thanks to my baby son Manthos who ‘occasionally’<br />

showed some patience when see<strong>in</strong>g me work<strong>in</strong>g long hours <strong>in</strong> front of the computer.<br />

I would like to say a big sorry to him for not be<strong>in</strong>g there most of the time to look after<br />

him as I should. His smile and his hugs were the most important reason to f<strong>in</strong>ish what I<br />

started and look forward to what is com<strong>in</strong>g up next...


To my partner and son,<br />

Apostolos and Manthos P<strong>in</strong>akidis<br />

iii


List of Abbreviations<br />

MG = <strong>Modern</strong> <strong>Greek</strong><br />

pers = person<br />

gend = gender<br />

semgend = semantic gender<br />

num = number<br />

1 = first person<br />

2 = second person<br />

3 = third person<br />

masc = mascul<strong>in</strong>e<br />

fem = fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e<br />

neut = neuter<br />

sg = s<strong>in</strong>gular<br />

pl = plural<br />

nom = nom<strong>in</strong>ative<br />

gen = genitive<br />

acc = accusative<br />

anim = animate<br />

CCA = Closest Conjunct <strong>Agreement</strong><br />

CIR = Contextually Introduced Referent


Contents<br />

1 Introduction 1<br />

1.1 Overview of the thesis . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 3<br />

2 LFG: An overview 5<br />

2.1 Constituent-structure . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 6<br />

2.2 Functional-Structure . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 8<br />

2.2.1 C-structure and f-structure correspondence . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 10<br />

2.3 Semantic-Structure . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 14<br />

2.4 <strong>Agreement</strong> <strong>in</strong> LFG . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 17<br />

2.4.1 Coord<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>in</strong> LFG . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 19<br />

2.4.1.1 Distributive vs Nondistributive Features . . . . . . . . . . . 20<br />

2.4.1.2 Predicate Coord<strong>in</strong>ation . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 21<br />

2.4.1.3 <strong>Noun</strong> Phrase Coord<strong>in</strong>ation . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 23<br />

2.4.2 The Semantics of Coord<strong>in</strong>ation . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 25<br />

2.5 Summary . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 28<br />

3 Theories of <strong>Agreement</strong> 29<br />

3.1 Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 29<br />

3.2 Theoretical Approaches to Predicate-Argument <strong>Agreement</strong> . . . . . . . . . 29<br />

3.2.1 Corbett’s Descriptive Approach . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 29<br />

3.2.2 Dalrymple and Kaplan’s Set-Based Theory . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 32<br />

3.2.3 Wechsler’s Theory of Gender Resolution . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 36<br />

3.2.4 Sadler’s Theory of Resolution <strong>in</strong> Rumanian . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 41<br />

3.2.5 Badecker’s Optimality Theory . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 45<br />

3.3 Theoretical Approaches to Head-Modifier <strong>Agreement</strong> . . . . . . . . . . . . . 51<br />

3.3.1 <strong>Agreement</strong> <strong>in</strong> HPSG . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 52<br />

3.3.2 K<strong>in</strong>g and Dalrymple’s Theory . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 54<br />

3.3.3 Dalrymple and Nikolaeva’s theory of natural and accidental coord<strong>in</strong>ation<br />

. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 61<br />

3.4 Discuss<strong>in</strong>g the theoretical approaches to agreement . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 66<br />

4 Predicate Argument <strong>Agreement</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>Modern</strong> <strong>Greek</strong> 70<br />

4.1 Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 70<br />

4.2 The <strong>Modern</strong> <strong>Greek</strong> Data . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 70<br />

4.2.1 Resolution <strong>in</strong> MG Animate <strong>Noun</strong>s . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 72<br />

4.2.2 Resolution <strong>in</strong> MG Inanimate <strong>Noun</strong>s . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 79<br />

4.2.3 Mix<strong>in</strong>g Animate and Inanimate <strong>Noun</strong>s <strong>in</strong> Coord<strong>in</strong>ate Constructions 87<br />

4.3 Resolution Pr<strong>in</strong>ciples <strong>in</strong> MG . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 88<br />

4.3.1 Semantic Resolution <strong>in</strong> Animate <strong>Noun</strong>s . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 88<br />

4.3.2 Syntactic Resolution <strong>in</strong> Inanimate <strong>Noun</strong>s . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 94<br />

4.4 Reference Transfer <strong>in</strong> Noncoord<strong>in</strong>ate Constructions . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 97


CONTENTS vi<br />

4.4.1 Reference Transfer <strong>in</strong> <strong>Modern</strong> <strong>Greek</strong> . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 100<br />

4.5 An Approach to Gender <strong>Agreement</strong> <strong>in</strong> MG . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 102<br />

4.5.1 Problems of the Current Theories for the MG data . . . . . . . . . . 102<br />

4.5.2 An Analysis of the MG Expected Patterns . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 106<br />

4.5.3 An Approach to the MG Referential <strong>Agreement</strong> Patterns . . . . . . 109<br />

4.6 Conclusion . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 115<br />

5 Head Modifier <strong>Agreement</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>Modern</strong> <strong>Greek</strong> 117<br />

5.1 Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 117<br />

5.2 NP Internal <strong>Agreement</strong> and Interpretation of the Coord<strong>in</strong>ate <strong>Noun</strong>s . . . . 118<br />

5.3 NP Internal <strong>Agreement</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>Modern</strong> <strong>Greek</strong> . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 121<br />

5.4 The <strong>Modern</strong> <strong>Greek</strong> Modifiers . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 121<br />

5.4.1 concord agreement with the MG Modifiers . . . . . . . . . . . . . 127<br />

5.5 The <strong>Modern</strong> <strong>Greek</strong> Def<strong>in</strong>ite Determ<strong>in</strong>er . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 135<br />

5.5.1 Uniform Number and Gender <strong>in</strong> Coord<strong>in</strong>ate <strong>Noun</strong>s . . . . . . . . . . 135<br />

5.5.2 Uniform Number and Different Gender <strong>in</strong> Coord<strong>in</strong>ate <strong>Noun</strong>s . . . . 140<br />

5.5.2.1 Motivation for the Exceptional Coord<strong>in</strong>ate Constructions . 142<br />

5.5.3 <strong>in</strong>dex/concord agreement with the MG Def<strong>in</strong>ite Determ<strong>in</strong>er . . . 145<br />

5.5.4 Natural Coord<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>in</strong> <strong>Modern</strong> <strong>Greek</strong> . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 148<br />

5.6 Conclusion . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 153<br />

6 Disjunctively Conjo<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>Noun</strong> <strong>Phrases</strong> 155<br />

6.1 Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 155<br />

6.2 Inclusive vs Exclusive or . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 156<br />

6.2.1 Natural Language or . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 161<br />

6.3 Approaches to Disjunctive Coord<strong>in</strong>ated NPs . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 162<br />

6.3.1 Morgan’s Analysis of Disjunctive NPs . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 162<br />

6.3.2 Peterson’s Analysis of Disjunctive NPs . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 164<br />

6.3.3 An Intermodular Theory of Disjunction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 168<br />

6.3.4 Discuss<strong>in</strong>g the three approaches . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 175<br />

6.4 Verb <strong>Agreement</strong> <strong>in</strong> MG Disjunctive Coord<strong>in</strong>ate <strong>Noun</strong>s . . . . . . . . . . . . 176<br />

6.4.1 Interpretation and Verb <strong>Agreement</strong> <strong>in</strong> Disjunctive Coord<strong>in</strong>ate <strong>Noun</strong>s 177<br />

6.4.2 Syntax and Verb <strong>Agreement</strong> <strong>in</strong> Disjunctive Coord<strong>in</strong>ate <strong>Noun</strong>s . . . . 181<br />

6.4.3 Speakers’ Strategies and Verb <strong>Agreement</strong> <strong>in</strong> MG Disjunctive <strong>Noun</strong>s 186<br />

6.5 Issues on the MG positive & negative predisjunction-disjunction . . . . . . 191<br />

6.6 Analys<strong>in</strong>g Verb <strong>Agreement</strong> <strong>in</strong> Disjunctive Coord<strong>in</strong>ate <strong>Noun</strong>s . . . . . . . . . 196<br />

6.7 Conclusion . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 202<br />

7 Conclud<strong>in</strong>g Remarks 204<br />

A Questionnaires on Predicate Argument <strong>Agreement</strong> 207<br />

A.1 Discussion of questionnnaires . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 207<br />

A.2 Predicate Argument <strong>Agreement</strong> sets of examples . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 208<br />

A.3 Tables . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 209<br />

B Questionnaires on agreement with Disjunctively Conjo<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>Noun</strong>s 213<br />

B.1 Discussion of questionnnaires . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 213<br />

B.2 Disjunctive Coord<strong>in</strong>ate <strong>Noun</strong>s sets of examples . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 214<br />

B.3 Tables . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 215<br />

C Orig<strong>in</strong>al Questionnaires <strong>in</strong> <strong>Greek</strong> 220


Chapter 1<br />

Introduction<br />

The objective of this thesis is to provide an analysis of agreement phenomena <strong>in</strong> <strong>Modern</strong><br />

<strong>Greek</strong> 1 coord<strong>in</strong>ate noun phrases jo<strong>in</strong>ed by the conjunction ke ‘and’ and the disjunction i ‘or’.<br />

We will focus on predicate-argument agreement, which is agreement of the coord<strong>in</strong>ate noun<br />

phrase with the predicate of the sentence (i.e. verb or predicative adjective/participle), and<br />

head-modifier agreement, which is agreement of modifiers (i.e. determ<strong>in</strong>ers, attributive<br />

adjectives) with the coord<strong>in</strong>ate noun phrase. Also, we will discuss verb agreement with<br />

disjunctively conjo<strong>in</strong>ed nouns.<br />

A number of features are <strong>in</strong>volved <strong>in</strong> agreement, which vary from language to language.<br />

MG predicate-argument agreement <strong>in</strong>volves the features gender, number and person. A<br />

s<strong>in</strong>gle or a coord<strong>in</strong>ate noun phrase shows agreement with the verb <strong>in</strong> number and person<br />

while it shows agreement with the predicative adjective/participle <strong>in</strong> gender and number.<br />

The follow<strong>in</strong>g example illustrates the different types of agreement with a noncoord<strong>in</strong>ate<br />

noun:<br />

(1) O<br />

Kostas<br />

the.masc.sg.3 Kostas.masc.sg.3<br />

‘Kostas is very active’<br />

<strong>in</strong>e<br />

is.sg.3<br />

poli<br />

very<br />

drastirios<br />

active.masc.sg<br />

In most languages, agreement with coord<strong>in</strong>ate noun phrases is <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g s<strong>in</strong>ce the<br />

coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns usually have different agreement features from the features of the agree<strong>in</strong>g<br />

verb or predicative adjective/participle. For example, <strong>in</strong> MG coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrases conjuncts<br />

with a masc and a fem gender show masc agreement, conjuncts with a 1st and a 2nd<br />

person show 1st person agreement, while two s<strong>in</strong>g conjuncts show pl agreement. Consider<br />

the follow<strong>in</strong>g examples:<br />

(2) O antras ke<br />

the.masc.sg<br />

xarumeni<br />

happy.masc.pl<br />

man.masc.sg and<br />

‘The man and woman are happy’<br />

(3) Ego ke esi tha<br />

I.1.sg and you.2.sg will<br />

‘Me and you will meet at the house’<br />

i<br />

the.fem.sg<br />

vrethume<br />

meet.2.pl<br />

j<strong>in</strong>eka<br />

woman.fem.sg<br />

sto spiti<br />

at-the house<br />

<strong>in</strong>e<br />

are.pl<br />

In MG predicate-argument agreement with coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns, we focus on the gender<br />

feature. Most l<strong>in</strong>guists acknowledge the existence of two different pr<strong>in</strong>ciples <strong>in</strong> gender<br />

agreement with coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns, the syntactic and the semantic (Corbett, 1991; Wechsler<br />

and Zlatić, 2003; Dalrymple and Kaplan, 2000; Sadler, 2006). We will argue that MG<br />

1 We will refer to <strong>Modern</strong> <strong>Greek</strong> with the <strong>in</strong>itials MG from now on.


gender agreement with coord<strong>in</strong>ate noun phrases shows great variation due to an extra<br />

type of pr<strong>in</strong>ciple. MG admits syntactic agreement, semantic agreement, and a third type,<br />

which we will call referential agreement. Therefore, we will attempt to propose a syntacticsemantic<br />

analysis for the first two types of agreement and a syntactic analysis for referential<br />

agreement, although it is contextually determ<strong>in</strong>ed.<br />

MG head-modifier agreement <strong>in</strong>volves the features number, gender and case. A<br />

determ<strong>in</strong>er or attributive adjective agrees with a s<strong>in</strong>gle noun <strong>in</strong> all three features:<br />

(4) O<br />

Janis<br />

the.masc.sg.nom<br />

antras<br />

man.masc.sg.nom<br />

John.masc.sg.nom<br />

‘John is an active man’<br />

<strong>in</strong>e<br />

is<br />

drastirios<br />

active.masc.sg.nom<br />

In coord<strong>in</strong>ate noun phrases similar requirements hold. A shared attributive adjective<br />

always agrees with the closest conjunct <strong>in</strong> gender, irrespective of the fact that the two<br />

nouns may have the same or different gender features, and with both conjuncts <strong>in</strong> case and<br />

number. A shared determ<strong>in</strong>er agrees with both conjuncts <strong>in</strong> gender, case and number.<br />

These possibilities are shown below:<br />

(5) Oreo<br />

nice.neut.sg.nom<br />

‘Nice house and car’<br />

spiti<br />

house.neut.sg.nom<br />

(6) I<br />

fili<br />

the.masc.pl.nom<br />

mu<br />

my<br />

friends.masc.pl.nom<br />

‘My friends and colleagues’<br />

ke<br />

and<br />

ke<br />

and<br />

aftok<strong>in</strong>ito<br />

car.neut.sg.nom<br />

s<strong>in</strong>adelfi<br />

colleagues.masc.pl.nom<br />

In MG head-modifier agreement with coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns, we discuss the number feature<br />

and the gender feature. K<strong>in</strong>g and Dalrymple (2004) proposed three different agreement<br />

systems (<strong>in</strong> concord, <strong>in</strong>dex and concord/<strong>in</strong>dex) that determ<strong>in</strong>e the number feature<br />

<strong>in</strong> head-modifier agreement <strong>in</strong> a number of languages. In MG, we will argue that the<br />

def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er is captured by the concord/<strong>in</strong>dex system and it also occurs with a<br />

restricted set of structures that have the characteristics of natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation (Dalrymple<br />

and Nikolaeva, 2006). The rest of the modifiers are captured by the concord system. We<br />

will assume different analyses for the determ<strong>in</strong>er and the rest of the modifiers, while we will<br />

assume the standard analysis of accidental coord<strong>in</strong>ation for the restricted set of structures<br />

of natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation admitted by the determ<strong>in</strong>er.<br />

MG disjunctive coord<strong>in</strong>ate noun phrases will also be discussed <strong>in</strong> the current thesis.<br />

The ma<strong>in</strong> issues posited by those who have studied disjunctive coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns (Morgan,<br />

1972, 1984, 1985; Peterson, 1986; Jenn<strong>in</strong>gs, 1994; Eggert, 2002; Alonso-Ovalle, 2006) are<br />

the semantics of disjunction as a truth-functional <strong>in</strong>clusive or and a truth-functional exclusive<br />

or, number verb agreement, which is either sg or pl, and the factors that determ<strong>in</strong>e<br />

it. Our focus is on number verb agreement. In most languages <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g MG, number<br />

predicate agreement with disjunctive conjo<strong>in</strong>ed nouns varies greatly. Follow<strong>in</strong>g Morgan<br />

(1985), we will argue that <strong>in</strong> MG the most crucial factor that determ<strong>in</strong>es verb agreement is<br />

the <strong>in</strong>terpretation of the disjunctive coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase either as an ‘and-coord<strong>in</strong>ate’ result<strong>in</strong>g<br />

<strong>in</strong> plural verb agreement, or as an ‘exclusive-or’ result<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> s<strong>in</strong>gular verb agreement.<br />

Native speakers assign either the one or the other <strong>in</strong>terpretation to the coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase<br />

and this <strong>in</strong>terpretation plays a crucial role <strong>in</strong> the choice of the agree<strong>in</strong>g verb. In the follow<strong>in</strong>g<br />

example, speakers choose either a sg verb or a pl verb. The first form is seen as a<br />

result of hav<strong>in</strong>g to choose only one of the two dr<strong>in</strong>ks that are available and therefore the<br />

2


1.1 Overview of the thesis 3<br />

emphasis is given on the choice of one of the two dr<strong>in</strong>ks. The second form is the result of<br />

the fact that two different dr<strong>in</strong>ks are available after the meal and therefore the emphasis<br />

is on the availability of two different dr<strong>in</strong>ks:<br />

(7) Kafes i tsai servir-ete/-onte<br />

coffee or tea is.sg/are.pl-served<br />

‘Coffee or tea is/are served after the d<strong>in</strong>ner’<br />

meta<br />

after<br />

to<br />

the<br />

gevma<br />

d<strong>in</strong>ner<br />

We will argue, however, that agreement ‘by read<strong>in</strong>g’ is one strategy alongside a number<br />

of others <strong>in</strong> MG disjunctive coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrases. Verb agreement is alternatively determ<strong>in</strong>ed<br />

by syntactic factors, such as the presence or absence of a predicative adjective/participle <strong>in</strong><br />

the coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase, the type of sentence (i.e declarative, <strong>in</strong>terrogative), or the speaker’s<br />

strategies, such as pl w<strong>in</strong>s, prox and fc w<strong>in</strong>s (Peterson, 1986). Our proposal adopts<br />

the λ-DRT framework and captures successfully the two different <strong>in</strong>terpretations assigned<br />

to disjunctive coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns. However, it captures only phenomena of <strong>in</strong>terpretation<br />

whereas a complete account should extend to all the aforementioned factors <strong>in</strong> order to<br />

cover the wide range of data.<br />

F<strong>in</strong>ally, it is <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g to note that agreement <strong>in</strong> noun phrase coord<strong>in</strong>ate structures <strong>in</strong><br />

MG has not been discussed <strong>in</strong> traditional handbooks and descriptive grammars. Most handbooks<br />

and grammars (Clairis et al. (2004), Holton et al. (1997), Triantaphyllidis (1994),<br />

Triantaphyllidis (2005), Joseph and Philippaki-Warburton (1987) and Mackridge (1985))<br />

present basic issues of the conjunction ke ‘and’ and the disjunction i such as the type of<br />

phrases they coord<strong>in</strong>ate (Mackridge (1985), Joseph and Philippaki-Warburton (1987)) or<br />

the fact that agreement is necessarilly plural <strong>in</strong> coord<strong>in</strong>ate structures (Holton et al. (1997),<br />

Triantaphyllidis (1994), Triantaphyllidis (2005)). The central phenomena of referential<br />

agreement, natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation and <strong>in</strong>terpretation <strong>in</strong> disjunctive coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns <strong>in</strong> MG<br />

are not found <strong>in</strong> any of the traditional grammars so our research aims to shed some light<br />

<strong>in</strong>to new l<strong>in</strong>guistic areas <strong>in</strong> MG.<br />

1.1 Overview of the thesis<br />

The organisation of the thesis is as follows. The first chapter (i.e. Chapter 2) presents<br />

an overview of Lexical Functional Grammar summaris<strong>in</strong>g the basic ideas on constituentstructure,<br />

functional-structure, the correspondence between the two, and semantic-structure.<br />

We will particularly focus on how agreement and coord<strong>in</strong>ation phenomena are treated<br />

with<strong>in</strong> LFG. We present the syntactic and the semantic treatment of sentential coord<strong>in</strong>ation,<br />

predicate coord<strong>in</strong>ation and noun phrase coord<strong>in</strong>ation.<br />

Chapter 3 presents an overview of the most central theories of agreement. We will review<br />

theoretical approaches to predicate-argument agreement that discuss the gender feature<br />

<strong>in</strong> coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns. These are Corbett (1983b, 1991), a descriptive approach to gender<br />

resolution, and Dalrymple and Kaplan (2000), a syntactic approach to gender resolution.<br />

Wechsler and Zlatić (2000) and Sadler (2006), who propose a syntactic-semantic analysis<br />

for gender resolution with<strong>in</strong> LFG, and Badecker (2008) a theory of gender agreement <strong>in</strong><br />

Optimality Theory. Next, we revisit the theories <strong>in</strong> head-modifier agreement that discuss<br />

the number feature <strong>in</strong> coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns. These <strong>in</strong>clude Kathol (1999) and Wechsler and<br />

Zlatić (2000) with<strong>in</strong> HPSG; K<strong>in</strong>g and Dalrymple (2004), which presents three different<br />

agreement systems <strong>in</strong> NP <strong>in</strong>ternal agreement, and Dalrymple and Nikolaeva (2006), which<br />

deals with natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation phenomena <strong>in</strong> a number of languages with<strong>in</strong> LFG.<br />

Chapter 4 describes gender resolution <strong>in</strong> MG coord<strong>in</strong>ate noun phrases. We will discuss<br />

animate and <strong>in</strong>animate nouns and we will show that three ma<strong>in</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>ciples control<br />

gender agreement <strong>in</strong> MG animate and <strong>in</strong>animate nouns, the syntactic pr<strong>in</strong>ciple <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>animate<br />

nouns, the semantic pr<strong>in</strong>ciple <strong>in</strong> animate nouns and the referential pr<strong>in</strong>ciple <strong>in</strong> both


1.1 Overview of the thesis 4<br />

groups of nouns. For the syntactic and semantic resolution pr<strong>in</strong>ciples, we will propose an<br />

analysis that will comb<strong>in</strong>e both syntax and semantics <strong>in</strong> the resolution process. For the<br />

referential agreement pr<strong>in</strong>ciple, we propose a prelim<strong>in</strong>ary analysis with<strong>in</strong> the framework of<br />

LFG by assum<strong>in</strong>g an extra level of representation, the Contextual level C, mapped to the<br />

syntactic level through the <strong>in</strong>verse mapp<strong>in</strong>g function d −1 , and we <strong>in</strong>troduce the Contextually<br />

Introduced Referent that accounts effectively for the unexpected gender agreement<br />

form found <strong>in</strong> certa<strong>in</strong> noun phrase coord<strong>in</strong>ations.<br />

Chapter 5 discusses ma<strong>in</strong>ly number agreement and gender agreement <strong>in</strong> head-modifier<br />

coord<strong>in</strong>ate noun phrases. A shared MG def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er allows only a jo<strong>in</strong>t (i.e. when<br />

the coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns refer to the same <strong>in</strong>dividual/entity) <strong>in</strong>terpretation and it is accounted<br />

for by the <strong>in</strong>dex/concord system. A shared MG modifier allows a jo<strong>in</strong>t and a split (i.e.<br />

when the coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns refer to different <strong>in</strong>dividuals/entities) <strong>in</strong>terpretation and it is<br />

accounted for by the concord system. A number of data, however, show an unexpected<br />

behaviour, such as the case where a split <strong>in</strong>terpretation is admitted when a shared MG<br />

plural def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er modifies two plural conjuncts. We will argue that these patterns<br />

must be treated as special cases of natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation but we will analyse them assum<strong>in</strong>g<br />

the f-structure of ord<strong>in</strong>ary coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns s<strong>in</strong>ce MG behaves different and the f-structure<br />

of natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation (Dalrymple and Nikolaeva, 2006) cannot capture the MG patterns.<br />

Chapter 6 presents disjunctive coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns <strong>in</strong> MG. Verb agreement varies greatly<br />

<strong>in</strong> these constructions s<strong>in</strong>ce it can be either sg or pl. Our data will show that different<br />

factors determ<strong>in</strong>e verb agreement, such as syntactic, semantic, pragmatic (i.e. contextual<br />

<strong>in</strong>terpretation of the phrase) or speakers’ <strong>in</strong>dividual strategies. Our analysis, however,<br />

focuses on the <strong>in</strong>terpretation issue of the disjunctive coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase and it is formalised<br />

with<strong>in</strong> the framework of λ-DRT, which is context dependent. Thus, we provide an account<br />

tak<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>to consideration that the disjunctively conjo<strong>in</strong>ed noun phrase can be <strong>in</strong>terpreted<br />

either with an ‘exclusive’ sense, where a s<strong>in</strong>gular verb form is preferred, or with an ‘andcoord<strong>in</strong>ate’<br />

sense, where a plural verb form is preferred.<br />

The last chapter summarises the whole thesis and discusses some rema<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g issues for<br />

future research.


Chapter 2<br />

LFG: An overview<br />

This chapter is an overview of the formalism of Lexical Functional Grammar (LFG) as<br />

presented <strong>in</strong> Nordl<strong>in</strong>ger and Bresnan (To appear), Dalrymple (2001), Falk (2001), Bresnan<br />

(2001) and Aust<strong>in</strong> (2001). LFG was orig<strong>in</strong>ally developed <strong>in</strong> the 1970s by Joan Bresnan and<br />

Ronald Kaplan. The actual name of the theory reveals its <strong>in</strong>ternal structure. It is a lexical<br />

theory, s<strong>in</strong>ce the lexicon plays a major role and most of the work is done with<strong>in</strong> the lexicon.<br />

The lexicon captures the syntactic or semantic <strong>in</strong>formation of the different word classes,<br />

<strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g any exceptional <strong>in</strong>formation. LFG’s syntactic structures are built of words and<br />

the lexicon is the place where words are created. As a lexicalist theory, LFG respects the<br />

Lexical Integrity Pr<strong>in</strong>ciple. It is also “nonderivational” or “nontransformational” s<strong>in</strong>ce verbal<br />

diatheses relations are stated <strong>in</strong> the lexicon and not through transformations as <strong>in</strong> other<br />

theories. F<strong>in</strong>ally, syntactic structures are built monotonically, mean<strong>in</strong>g that <strong>in</strong>formation<br />

can be added but no deletion or change of <strong>in</strong>formation is allowed.<br />

The theory is also functional and not configurational. This means that grammatical<br />

functions, like subject or object, are central <strong>in</strong> the theory and they are used to represent<br />

the syntactic structures of the various languages. This type of syntactic <strong>in</strong>formation is represented<br />

not <strong>in</strong> terms of a phrase structure tree but <strong>in</strong> terms of feature-structures. The<br />

basic idea is that grammatical functions appear as features and other elements that have<br />

a specific function appear as the values to those features. F-structures exist <strong>in</strong> parallel to<br />

c-structures.<br />

As opposed to generative grammar, the theory is also constra<strong>in</strong>t-based. The architecture<br />

of LFG uses parallel structures <strong>in</strong> order to represent the different aspects of l<strong>in</strong>guistic<br />

<strong>in</strong>formation. These structures or levels have their own architecture, vocabulary and obey a<br />

series of constra<strong>in</strong>ts <strong>in</strong> order to function properly. The central levels of representation are<br />

the c(onstituent)-structure, the f(unctional)-structure, the a(rgument)-structure, the semantic<br />

(σ)- structure, the i(nformation)-structure, the m(orphological) and p(honological)structures.<br />

These parallel levels are l<strong>in</strong>ked to each other via correspondence pr<strong>in</strong>ciples,<br />

us<strong>in</strong>g correspondence functions or “projection” functions. C-structure, f-structure and astructure<br />

focus on the syntactic aspects of a language, s-structure deals with semantics,<br />

i-structure explores discourse functions and m-structure and p-structure focus on the morphological<br />

and phonological properties of a language. The different levels of representation<br />

and their <strong>in</strong>dependent constra<strong>in</strong>ts make the theory both universal and applicable to a<br />

number of variable languages. In the current thesis, we focus on the syntactic levels (the<br />

c-structure and f-structure) and the semantic level (the s-structure) and we will describe<br />

how LFG accounts for agreement, focus<strong>in</strong>g on agreement <strong>in</strong> coord<strong>in</strong>ate noun phrases.


2.1 Constituent-structure 6<br />

2.1 Constituent-structure<br />

C-structure encodes the surface phrasal syntactic organisation of a language, such as l<strong>in</strong>ear<br />

order, hierarchical group<strong>in</strong>gs and syntactic categories of constituents, while it <strong>in</strong>terfaces<br />

with the phonological component of the grammar. Constituency <strong>in</strong>formation is expressed<br />

through phrase structure trees which depend on phrase structure rules. LFG c-structures<br />

adopt the X-bar model, which accounts effectively for the crossl<strong>in</strong>guistic variation traced<br />

<strong>in</strong> phrase structures.<br />

LFG’s c-structure level assumes two types of categories, lexical and functional categories.<br />

The lexical categories are N(oun), P(reposition), V(erb), A(djective) and A(dverb),<br />

which function as heads of phrases of the correspond<strong>in</strong>g phrasal categories NP, PP, VP,<br />

AdjP and AdvP. The functional categories are I, C 1 . The category I (orig<strong>in</strong>ally for INFL)<br />

(Falk, 1984) is the head of IP, it functions as the head of a f<strong>in</strong>ite clause and can be filled by<br />

tensed auxiliary verbs or other f<strong>in</strong>ite verbs. The category C (Fassi-Fehri, 1981) is the head<br />

of CP and it can be filled by a verbal element or other elements. In English, for example,<br />

the C position can be filled by a complementiser like that.<br />

S<strong>in</strong>ce the organisation of LFG c-structure is based on X-bar theory, it follows the basic<br />

pr<strong>in</strong>ciples of the latter. In X-bar theory any functional or lexical category X is related to<br />

its correspond<strong>in</strong>g projections, the nonmaximal projection X ′ (with “one bar level”) and<br />

the maximal projection X ′′ (with “two bar levels”).<br />

The organisation of <strong>in</strong>formation <strong>in</strong> the phrase structure tree assumes that a lexical<br />

item X is the head of a phrasal item X ′ and it is also the sister to a number of complement<br />

and adjunct phrases (YP...). In turn, X ′ is the head of the phrasal constituent XP and<br />

it is also the sister to a number of specifier phrases (ZP...), all of which form the phrasal<br />

constituent XP (Dalrymple, 2001, 57). In figure (2.1), the whole sentence corresponds to<br />

the IP category. The head of IP is the phrasal item I ′ which also has as its head the lexical<br />

item I. The tensed auxiliary verb fills <strong>in</strong> the I position and the ma<strong>in</strong> verb appears with<strong>in</strong><br />

the VP. The specifier of IP is the NP ‘David’ and the complement of V ′ is the NP beans:<br />

NP<br />

N<br />

David<br />

IP<br />

I<br />

is<br />

I ′<br />

V<br />

eat<strong>in</strong>g<br />

VP<br />

V ′<br />

NP<br />

N<br />

beans<br />

Figure 2.1: A simple phrase structure tree<br />

A central pr<strong>in</strong>ciple <strong>in</strong> LFG’s c-structure is the Pr<strong>in</strong>ciple of Endocentricity and the categories<br />

<strong>in</strong>volved are called endocentric categories (Bloomfield, 1962). This means that the<br />

phrase structure rules of a language are organised as hierarchical, c-structure configurations<br />

follow<strong>in</strong>g X ′ Theory. Thus, the maximal projection XP and the nonmaximal projection X ′<br />

are headed categories whose head is X.<br />

1 Two more functional categories are D and K but they will not be discussed here. For details see Bresnan<br />

(1997, 2001c), Sadler (1997) and Dalrymple (2001).


2.1 Constituent-structure 7<br />

A second pr<strong>in</strong>ciple that governs LFG’s c-structure is the Pr<strong>in</strong>ciple of Exocentricity<br />

(Nordl<strong>in</strong>ger and Bresnan, To appear; Bresnan, 2001; Dalrymple, 2001). Although English<br />

and a number of other languages are endocentric, there is also evidence that languages<br />

can make use of exocentric categories. Such languages allow for flatter structures where<br />

the subject and all of the arguments are sisters to the head and syntactic functions are<br />

morphologically determ<strong>in</strong>ed. For these languages, LFG <strong>in</strong>troduces the exocentric and nonprojective<br />

category S, which is not headed by a lexical head of the same category as itself<br />

and dom<strong>in</strong>ates any number of lexical or phrasal heads. S is a category that conta<strong>in</strong>s a<br />

predicate and any number of arguments, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g the subject of the phrase. The example<br />

below is from Falk (2001):<br />

(1) aanaye kut.t.i kan.t.u<br />

elephant.acc child.nom saw<br />

‘The child saw the elephant’<br />

S<br />

NP<br />

aanaye<br />

NP<br />

kut.t.i<br />

V<br />

kan. t.u<br />

S<strong>in</strong>ce LFG uses both pr<strong>in</strong>ciples, it can accommodate data of both types of languages more<br />

effectively and it is a universally applicable theory.<br />

LFG c-structures are subject to the Lexical Integrity Pr<strong>in</strong>ciple, which enforces a dist<strong>in</strong>ction<br />

between the morphological and the syntactic components. The <strong>in</strong>ternal structure<br />

of words is part of the lexicon and the structure of phrases or sentences is part of syntax.<br />

Morphology determ<strong>in</strong>es the <strong>in</strong>ternal word formation and syntax deals with phrasal or sentential<br />

composition. Thus, the formation of the <strong>in</strong>ternal structure of words is <strong>in</strong>visible to<br />

syntax. The pr<strong>in</strong>ciple is stated as follows:<br />

Lexical Integrity Pr<strong>in</strong>ciple<br />

Morphologically complete words are leaves of the c-structure tree and each leaf<br />

corresponds to one and only one c-structure node.<br />

(Bresnan, 2001, 92)<br />

Follow<strong>in</strong>g the above, LFG allows only fully <strong>in</strong>flected words to occupy the position of cstructure<br />

term<strong>in</strong>al nodes, and not parts of words or empty categories. Despite the dist<strong>in</strong>ction<br />

of morphology and syntax, it is possible for both components to contribute the same<br />

k<strong>in</strong>d of <strong>in</strong>formation, be<strong>in</strong>g functionally equivalent (Nordl<strong>in</strong>ger and Bresnan, To appear;<br />

Bresnan, 2001).<br />

For a theory that represents <strong>in</strong>formation <strong>in</strong> the form of phrase structure trees, phrase<br />

structure rules are also required to admit or describe the correspond<strong>in</strong>g phrase structure<br />

trees. Thus, PS rules function as conditions that will license the different nodes <strong>in</strong> a tree.<br />

The follow<strong>in</strong>g example illustrates a simple phrase structure rule:<br />

(2) S −→ NP VP<br />

The categories on the right of the arrow are the c-structure daughters of the categories<br />

on the left.<br />

LFG’s phrase structure rules are more expressive than the phrase structure rules of<br />

other theories s<strong>in</strong>ce they consist of a regular expression (Kaplan and Bresnan, 1982) <strong>in</strong><br />

the right-hand side. Thus, optionality, recursion and disjunction are some of the processes<br />

that are represented <strong>in</strong> the PS rules admitted by LFG. For example, the rule <strong>in</strong> (3) states<br />

that either an NP or a PP can appear as the specifier of IP. The disjunction of two


2.2 Functional-Structure 8<br />

different phrase structure categories is represented by the curly brackets and the different<br />

possibilities are stated with a vertical bar |:<br />

(3) IP −→ {NP|PP} I ′<br />

(Dalrymple, 2001, 93)<br />

Similarly, <strong>in</strong> (4) the parentheses around the NP denotes optionality and the Kleene star<br />

annotation on the PP <strong>in</strong>dicates that any number of PPs can appear after the optional NP:<br />

(4) VP −→ V (NP) PP*<br />

(Dalrymple, 2001, 94)<br />

PS rules allow two types of relations, dom<strong>in</strong>ance relations and precedence relations.<br />

Dom<strong>in</strong>ance relations are expressed through Immediate Dom<strong>in</strong>ance statements, stated with<br />

a comma between the daughter nodes. The rule below states that the VP dom<strong>in</strong>ates a V<br />

and an NP node:<br />

(5) VP −→ V, NP<br />

(Dalrymple, 2001, 96)<br />

Precedence relations maybe expressed through L<strong>in</strong>ear Precedence statements. This is<br />

stated by the <strong>in</strong>troduction of a separate constra<strong>in</strong>t with the symbol


2.2 Functional-Structure 9<br />

(8)<br />

⎡<br />

⎤<br />

pred ‘cry〈subj〉’<br />

⎢<br />

⎢tense<br />

past<br />

⎥<br />

⎢ ⎡ ⎤⎥<br />

g: ⎢ pred ‘mary’ ⎥<br />

⎢ ⎢ ⎥<br />

⎣subj<br />

f: ⎣num<br />

sg<br />

⎥<br />

⎦<br />

pers 3<br />

The label g corresponds to the f-structure of the whole sentence. The three attributes are:<br />

pred, tense and subj. The value of the pred attribute is the semantic form ‘cry〈subj〉’,<br />

which subcategorises for another grammatical function, a subj, and has a unique <strong>in</strong>stantiation,<br />

<strong>in</strong>dicated by s<strong>in</strong>gle quotes. The attribute tense has the atomic value past, whereas<br />

the attribute subj has a whole f-structure as its value, which is the f-structure f and it<br />

is the subject of the sentence. In turn, the subj f-structure with label f conta<strong>in</strong>s the basic<br />

syntactic <strong>in</strong>formation that mary contributes. The value of the pred attribute is also<br />

the semantic form ‘mary’, which gives rise to a uniquely <strong>in</strong>stantiated occurrence. The<br />

attribute num has a sg value and the attribute pers has a 3 value (Dalrymple, 2001, 31).<br />

In the same way that c-structures are descibed by a set of phrase structure rules,<br />

f-structures are described by a set of equations known as a “functional description” (Dalrymple,<br />

2001, 101). Thus, the equation <strong>in</strong> example (9) is satisfied by the f-structure <strong>in</strong><br />

example (10) s<strong>in</strong>ce it conta<strong>in</strong>s the attribute num with the value sg:<br />

(9) (f num)= sg<br />

(10) f [num sg]<br />

The relation between an f-structure and the correspond<strong>in</strong>g equation is formally presented<br />

as follows:<br />

(f α)= υ holds if and only if 〈α, υ〉 ∈ f, where f is an f-structure, α is a symbol,<br />

υ is a value<br />

(Dalrymple, 2001, 101)<br />

LFG requires that an f-structure must be the m<strong>in</strong>imal solution that satisfies all the<br />

constra<strong>in</strong>ts that the words and phrases of an utterance <strong>in</strong>troduce (Dalrymple, 2001, 101).<br />

In the case of the constra<strong>in</strong>t (9), the f-structure <strong>in</strong> (10) is the m<strong>in</strong>imal solution as required.<br />

The organisation of an f-structure is restricted by the well-formedness conditions of<br />

completeness, coherence and uniqueness. Completeness ensures that all of the arguments<br />

that a predicate subcategorises for are present <strong>in</strong> the f-structure. This is formally<br />

stated as follows:<br />

Completeness:<br />

An f-structure is locally complete if and only if it conta<strong>in</strong>s all the governable<br />

grammatical functions that its predicate governs. An f-structure is complete if<br />

and only if it and all its subsidiary f-structures are locally complete. (Dalrymple,<br />

2001, 37)<br />

The sentence below is <strong>in</strong>complete because there is an argument miss<strong>in</strong>g:<br />

(11) *David saw<br />

The f-structure <strong>in</strong> (12) of the pred ‘see’ requires the grammatical functions subj and<br />

obj. Example (11) conta<strong>in</strong>s only a subj and not an obj which makes it <strong>in</strong>complete and<br />

therefore unacceptable:<br />

(12) <br />

<br />

pred ‘see〈subj,obj〉’


2.2 Functional-Structure 10<br />

The pr<strong>in</strong>ciple of coherence can be seen as the opposite of completeness. It ensures that<br />

only the arguments subcategorised by the predicate are present <strong>in</strong> the f-structure and not<br />

any extra ones. The formal def<strong>in</strong>ition is below:<br />

Coherence<br />

An f-structure is locally coherent if and only if all the governable grammatical<br />

functions that it conta<strong>in</strong>s are governed by a local predicate. An f-structure is<br />

coherent if and only if it and all its subsidiary f-structures are locally coherent.<br />

(Dalrymple, 2001, 39)<br />

Sentence (13) is ungrammatical s<strong>in</strong>ce there is an extra grammatical function, the obj noun<br />

phrase the boy, not subcategorised by the predicate:<br />

(13) *Mary cried the boy<br />

Thus, the f-structure is <strong>in</strong>coherent s<strong>in</strong>ce the sentence conta<strong>in</strong>s the extra grammatical function<br />

obj, which the predicate cry does not require:<br />

(14) ⎡<br />

⎤<br />

pred ‘cry〈subj〉’<br />

⎢ ⎥<br />

⎢<br />

⎢subj<br />

pred ‘mary’ ⎥<br />

⎣ ⎦<br />

obj pred ‘boy’<br />

F<strong>in</strong>ally, f-structure postulates the uniqueness or consistency condition which ensures<br />

that an attribute must have only one value and not more than one:<br />

uniqueness or consistency<br />

In a given f-structure a particular attribute may have at most one value<br />

(Dalrymple, 2001, p.39)<br />

The sentence below is ungrammatical s<strong>in</strong>ce the subj noun phrase the girl is s<strong>in</strong>gular but<br />

the verb cry requires its subject to be plural.<br />

(15) *The girl cry<br />

The f-structure is ill-formed because the attribute num has two different values at the<br />

same time. To be well-formed, it needs to have either a sg or pl value and not both<br />

simultaneously:<br />

(16) ⎡<br />

⎤<br />

pred ‘cry〈subj〉’<br />

⎢ ⎥<br />

⎢<br />

⎣ pred ‘girl’ ⎥<br />

subj ⎦<br />

num sg/pl<br />

The most important aspect about LFG’s f-structure is that it follows the pr<strong>in</strong>ciple of<br />

universality which states “that <strong>in</strong>ternal structures are largerly <strong>in</strong>variant across languages”<br />

(Bresnan, 2001, 45). Thus, sentences <strong>in</strong> different languages, which are translational equivalents,<br />

will have the same f-structures despite possible differences <strong>in</strong> their c-structures.<br />

2.2.1 C-structure and f-structure correspondence<br />

This section provides a short description of the correspondence between the two levels<br />

of representation: c-structure and f-structure. LFG uses a formal way to represent the<br />

relation between the two structures, a function 5 φ (phi). This is stated as follows:<br />

5 A function is “a special type of relation which assigns a unique value to its argument” (Dalrymple,<br />

2001, 30).


2.2 Functional-Structure 11<br />

(17) φ: N → F<br />

(Kaplan, 1995)<br />

The correspondence between the c-structure nodes and the f-structure is many-to-one and<br />

each c-structure node is related to a specific and only one f-structure through the φ function.<br />

The examples below display simple diagrams. In example (18), a s<strong>in</strong>gle node corresponds<br />

to an f-structure, whereas <strong>in</strong> example (19) more than one node corresponds to the same<br />

f-structure. The correspondence from the c-structure to the f-structure is represented by<br />

an arrow:<br />

(18) V<br />

cried<br />

(19) NP<br />

N ′<br />

N<br />

Mary<br />

<br />

pred ‘cry〈subj〉’<br />

tense past<br />

⎡ ⎤<br />

pred ‘mary’<br />

⎢ ⎥<br />

⎣num<br />

sg ⎦<br />

pers 3<br />

<br />

The mapp<strong>in</strong>g function from c-structure to f-structure is not arbitrary but it obeys certa<strong>in</strong><br />

pr<strong>in</strong>ciples that are <strong>in</strong> accordance with the c-structural and f-structural configurations.<br />

In general, a c-structure head and its phrasal projections correspond to the same f-structure,<br />

as <strong>in</strong> example (19) 6 . Specifiers of the functional categories IP or CP are mapped either<br />

to the grammatical function subj or to the discourse functions topic or focus. Thus, <strong>in</strong><br />

English and many other languages the specifier position of IP can be filled by the subj<br />

function or by the topic/focus functions, whereas the specifier position of CP corresponds<br />

to the focus function.<br />

Complements of functional categories are f-structure co-heads and will be mapped to<br />

the same f-structure as their heads, and complements of lexical categories are mapped to<br />

any of the grammatical functions, exclud<strong>in</strong>g the subj and the discourse functions. These<br />

notions are shown below:<br />

(20) Mary is call<strong>in</strong>g Chris<br />

NP<br />

N<br />

Mary<br />

IP<br />

I<br />

is<br />

I ′<br />

V<br />

call<strong>in</strong>g<br />

VP<br />

NP<br />

N<br />

Chris<br />

⎡<br />

⎤<br />

pred ‘call〈subj,obj〉’<br />

⎢ ⎥<br />

⎢<br />

⎢subj<br />

pred ‘mary’ ⎥<br />

⎣ ⎦<br />

obj pred ‘chris’<br />

The specifier NP Mary is mapped to the subj function. The complement of the lexical<br />

category V, which is the NP Chris, is mapped to the obj function. The auxiliary and the<br />

ma<strong>in</strong> verb are co-heads and they correspond to the same f-structure whose pred value is<br />

the verb call. When more than one complement appears usually the first one is mapped<br />

to the obj and the second to the objθ, as <strong>in</strong> the English example <strong>in</strong> (21):<br />

6 An exception is Japanese which is a “pro-drop” language with no verbal agreement morphology and<br />

the s<strong>in</strong>gle word kowareta ‘broke’ appears without an overt subject noun phrase. Thus, the subj f-structure<br />

does not corrrespond to any node <strong>in</strong> the c-structure (Kameyama (1985) cited <strong>in</strong> Dalrymple (2001)). For a<br />

schematic representation see Dalrymple (2001, 71).


2.2 Functional-Structure 12<br />

(21) Mary gave Chris the keys<br />

NP<br />

N<br />

Mary<br />

V<br />

gave<br />

IP<br />

NP<br />

N<br />

I ′<br />

VP<br />

V ′<br />

Chris<br />

Det<br />

the<br />

NP<br />

N ′<br />

N<br />

keys<br />

⎡<br />

⎤<br />

pred ‘give〈subj,obj,objθ〉’<br />

⎢ ⎥<br />

⎢<br />

⎢subj<br />

g: pred ‘mary’<br />

⎥<br />

⎢<br />

⎥<br />

f: ⎢obj<br />

h: pred ‘chris ⎥<br />

⎢ <br />

⎥<br />

⎢<br />

⎣ pred ‘keys’ ⎥<br />

objθ i:<br />

⎦<br />

def +<br />

In such a mathematical framework, it is possible to express the <strong>in</strong>verse f-structure to cstructure<br />

mapp<strong>in</strong>g through the use of the <strong>in</strong>verse mapp<strong>in</strong>g function φ −1 . The mapp<strong>in</strong>g<br />

function from c-structure to f-structure and from f-structure to c-structure is possible s<strong>in</strong>ce<br />

the various levels of representation exist simultaneously <strong>in</strong> different dimensions and no<br />

derivational process is carried out.<br />

LFG postulates a formal and powerful way of express<strong>in</strong>g the above schematic correspondence<br />

between a c-structure and an f-structure by apply<strong>in</strong>g a series of functionaldescriptions<br />

or equations to the correspond<strong>in</strong>g phrase structure rules. At the core of these<br />

functional equations are two symbols: ∗, ˆ∗, together with the c-structure to f-structure<br />

function φ. The symbol ∗ denotes the f-structure of the current c-structure node on which<br />

the constra<strong>in</strong>t is placed and the symbol ˆ∗ denotes the f-structure corrrespond<strong>in</strong>g to the<br />

mother node. A more simplified way to state these notations is the use of arrows, the<br />

up-arrow (↑) and the down-arrow (↓). Based on Dalrymple (2001), these are restated as<br />

follows:<br />

(22) ˆ∗ mother’s f-structure = ↑<br />

∗ self’s f-structure = ↓<br />

The use of such notation relates to the way trees are represented. The upward arrow ↑<br />

denotes the mother node, while the downward ↓ denotes the current node itself, and the<br />

need to show any relevant <strong>in</strong>formation is locally passed up the tree from the daughter to<br />

the mother nodes.<br />

Consider the simple example, Mary saw Tom. To show the process clearly, we assign a<br />

variable to each node and relative f-structure, such as fip, fnp, fi ′ etc, and we assume the<br />

follow<strong>in</strong>g c-structure tree correspond<strong>in</strong>g to the f-structure below:<br />

(23) IPfip<br />

NPfnp I ′ fi ′<br />

⎡<br />

⎤<br />

pred ‘see〈subj,obj〉’<br />

⎢<br />

⎥<br />

⎢<br />

tense past ⎥<br />

⎢<br />

⎥<br />

Nfn<br />

Mary<br />

Vfv<br />

saw<br />

VPfvp<br />

V ′ fv ′<br />

NPfnp<br />

Nfn<br />

Tom<br />

fip,fi ′,fvp,fv ′,fv<br />

The f-descriptions for the above f-structure are as follows:<br />

⎢ pred ‘mary’ ⎥<br />

⎢subj<br />

fnp,fn<br />

⎥<br />

⎢<br />

num sg ⎥<br />

⎢ ⎥<br />

⎢<br />

⎣<br />

pred ‘tom’ ⎥<br />

obj fnp,fn<br />

⎦<br />

num sg


2.2 Functional-Structure 13<br />

(24) (fipsubj) = fnp<br />

fnp = fn<br />

(fnpred) = ‘mary’<br />

fip = fi ′<br />

fi ′ = fvp<br />

fvp = fv ′<br />

fv ′ = fv<br />

(fvpred) = ‘see’<br />

(fvtense) = past<br />

(fv ′obj) = fnp<br />

fnp = fn<br />

(fnpred) = ‘tom’<br />

The phrase structure rules with the relevant annotations for example (23) are the follow<strong>in</strong>g:<br />

(25) IP → NP I ′<br />

(fipsubj)= fnp<br />

NP → N<br />

fnp = fn<br />

fip = fi ′<br />

I ′ → ( I ) VP<br />

VP → V ′<br />

fvp = fv ′<br />

fi ′ = fvp<br />

V ′ → V NP<br />

fv ′ = fv (fv ′obj) = fnp<br />

The f-descriptions that correspond to a particular c-structure tree can be replaced with<br />

the ↑ and ↓ arrows, as follows:<br />

(26) IP → NP I ′<br />

NP → N<br />

(↑subj)= ↓ ↑ = ↓<br />

↑ = ↓<br />

I ′ → ( I ) VP<br />

VP → V ′<br />

↑ = ↓<br />

↑ = ↓<br />

V ′ → V NP<br />

↑ = ↓ (↑obj) = ↓<br />

Generally, <strong>in</strong> any annotated phrase structure rule, any daughter node, which appears<br />

on the right hand side of a rule, can be annotated with constra<strong>in</strong>ts that capture the relation<br />

between its f-structure and the f-structure of the mother node. If the daughter node is the<br />

head, they map to the same f-structure; if the daughter node is a nonhead, the daughter’s<br />

f-structure will have some relation (say, the obj relation) to the mother’s f-structure. The<br />

two arrows used <strong>in</strong> the rules assign a stronger locality, s<strong>in</strong>ce only the functional relation


2.3 Semantic-Structure 14<br />

between a daughter and its mother can be stated. Relations among the f-structures of<br />

a daughter node of an annotated rule with its grandmother node are not allowed to be<br />

expressed (Dalrymple, 2001, 117-120).<br />

The same metavariables are used <strong>in</strong> lexical entries. Information that relates to each<br />

lexical item will be captured under each lexical entry and that <strong>in</strong>formation corresponds to<br />

the relevant f-structure. The lexical entries for example (23) are illustrated below:<br />

(27) saw V (↑ pred) = ‘see〈subj,obj〉’<br />

(↑ tense) = past<br />

Mary N (↑ pred) = ‘mary’<br />

(↑ pers) = 3<br />

(↑ num) = sg<br />

Tom N (↑ pred) = ‘tom’<br />

(↑ pers) = 3<br />

(↑ num) = sg<br />

The ↑ and ↓ arrows have exactly the same use <strong>in</strong> a lexical entry as the one <strong>in</strong> the rules s<strong>in</strong>ce<br />

↑ arrow refers to the node that dom<strong>in</strong>ates the lexical item, and ↓ refers to the f-structure<br />

that corresponds to the word itself (Dalrymple, 2001, 120). The same equations can be<br />

annotated to c-structure nodes with which they are associated to make the connection<br />

clearer.<br />

The correspondence between the c-structure to f-structure is most effectively captured<br />

with<strong>in</strong> the pr<strong>in</strong>ciple of Economy of Expression which is stated as follows:<br />

economy of expression<br />

All syntactic phrase structure nodes are optional and are not used unless required<br />

by <strong>in</strong>dependent pr<strong>in</strong>ciples (completeness, coherence, semantic expressivity).<br />

(Bresnan, 2001, 91)<br />

This pr<strong>in</strong>ciple ensures that only the syntactic phrase structure nodes that contribute to<br />

important <strong>in</strong>formation at the f-structure level are licensed <strong>in</strong> the phrase structure tree while<br />

it disallows any empty c-structure category, which dom<strong>in</strong>ates a non term<strong>in</strong>al element, to<br />

be expressed <strong>in</strong> the c-structure tree. Thus, it is immediately related to the f-structure pr<strong>in</strong>ciples<br />

of completeness, coherence and semantic expressivity and admits only the necessary<br />

and m<strong>in</strong>imal <strong>in</strong>formation <strong>in</strong>to the c-structure, which will map to the relevant f-structure.<br />

2.3 Semantic-Structure<br />

LFG is a theoretical framework that does not follow the rule-to-rule hypothesis of the<br />

Pr<strong>in</strong>ciple of Compositionality, which states that the rules of syntax are closely related to<br />

the rules of semantics (Bach, 1989), while it does not assume that the rules that comb<strong>in</strong>e<br />

the mean<strong>in</strong>g of a sentence should depend on phrasal dom<strong>in</strong>ance or l<strong>in</strong>ear order<strong>in</strong>g relations<br />

(Dalrymple, 2001, 218). In LFG, semantic composition is associated to the f-structure and<br />

not to the c-structure level. An important advantage of encod<strong>in</strong>g semantic composition<br />

based on the f-structures is that certa<strong>in</strong> crossl<strong>in</strong>guistic facts are expressed <strong>in</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>ciples<br />

of semantic composition that would otherwise rema<strong>in</strong> obscure if we assumed an analysis<br />

follow<strong>in</strong>g c-structure. Thus, semantic composition relies on the <strong>in</strong>formation encoded at the<br />

f-structure level to derive the <strong>in</strong>formation at the separate level of semantic-structure.<br />

In LFG, each lexical entry contributes a mean<strong>in</strong>g constructor also known as a premise to<br />

a logical deduction. A mean<strong>in</strong>g constructor is a set of logical <strong>in</strong>structions applied to obta<strong>in</strong>


2.3 Semantic-Structure 15<br />

the mean<strong>in</strong>g of the f-structure headed by the lexical entry, by comb<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g the mean<strong>in</strong>gs of the<br />

lexical entry and its syntactic arguments. Then, it uses logical ‘glue’ for mean<strong>in</strong>g assembly<br />

(Dalrymple et al., 2002; Dalrymple, 2001). Therefore, once all the required constra<strong>in</strong>ts<br />

are gathered, deduction <strong>in</strong> the logic is used to obta<strong>in</strong> a mean<strong>in</strong>g for the entire structure.<br />

Mean<strong>in</strong>g constructors consist of a left-hand side known as the mean<strong>in</strong>g side and the righthand<br />

side, which is the glue side, hav<strong>in</strong>g the form P : L where a mean<strong>in</strong>g P is paired with<br />

a l<strong>in</strong>ear logic formula L.<br />

The left-hand side or the mean<strong>in</strong>g side is often represented as a λ-expression 7 which<br />

is a convenient formalism to represent the mean<strong>in</strong>gs of sentences. The lambda operator λ<br />

constructs a function by abstract<strong>in</strong>g on a variable conta<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong> a proposition. The function<br />

is applied to its argument as follows:<br />

(28) Function application: [λX.P](a)<br />

The function λX.P is applied to the argument a.<br />

(Dalrymple, 2001, 225)<br />

The expression above states that the lambda operator b<strong>in</strong>ds the variable X, which occurs<br />

at least once <strong>in</strong> the proposition P. Thus, <strong>in</strong> the example Mary cried represented as<br />

[λX.cry(X)]Mary us<strong>in</strong>g the λ-calculus, if we replace all occurrences of X <strong>in</strong> P with Mary,<br />

we can derive the expression cry(Mary), which is the semantic equivalent. Although the λcalculus<br />

is a useful formalism for assembl<strong>in</strong>g the semantics of a sentence provided by surface<br />

constituent structure trees, it is not an effective tool to comb<strong>in</strong>e mean<strong>in</strong>gs of f-structure<br />

constituents. This is due to the fact that f-structures are unordered and λ-calculus follows<br />

a fixed order of comb<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g a functor with its arguments (Dalrymple et al., 2002).<br />

To avoid the problems posed by the λ-calculus, LFG uses the glue approach a formula<br />

<strong>in</strong> l<strong>in</strong>ear logic <strong>in</strong> the right-hand side. This is a deductive approach to mean<strong>in</strong>g assembly<br />

which comb<strong>in</strong>es the mean<strong>in</strong>gs associated with attribute-value structures, through a series<br />

of constra<strong>in</strong>ts, so as to deduce the mean<strong>in</strong>g of the whole structure. Thus, once the mean<strong>in</strong>g<br />

constructor or premise of each f-structure has been derived then we use the glue approach<br />

to comb<strong>in</strong>e the mean<strong>in</strong>g constructor of the lexical entry with its syntactic arguments <strong>in</strong><br />

order to form the mean<strong>in</strong>g of the whole utterance.<br />

LFG also postulates a semantic-structure, which is a separate level of l<strong>in</strong>guistic representation.<br />

The f-structure is associated with the semantic-structure by the correspondence<br />

function σ8 , represented by an arrow from the f-structure to the s-structure. The semantic<br />

projection of an f-structure represents its mean<strong>in</strong>g and it is denoted with the subscript<br />

σ. Thus, the notation fσ is the semantic projection of the f f-structure. An example with<br />

a one-place predicate, such as Mary cried, <strong>in</strong>troduces the follow<strong>in</strong>g f-structure and the<br />

correspond<strong>in</strong>g s-structure:<br />

⎡<br />

⎤ <br />

(29) pred ‘cry〈subj〉’ fσ : (f subj)σ :<br />

⎢ ⎡ ⎤⎥<br />

⎢<br />

f: ⎢<br />

pred ‘mary’ ⎥<br />

⎢ ⎢ ⎥<br />

⎥<br />

⎣subj<br />

g: ⎣pers<br />

3 ⎦<br />

⎥<br />

⎦<br />

num sg<br />

For the simple sentence Mary cried, the follow<strong>in</strong>g augmented lexical entries are <strong>in</strong>troduced:<br />

7 Other formalisms are DRT and Predicate Calculus. For a def<strong>in</strong>ition and details on the lambda calculus<br />

see Partee et al. (1993).<br />

8 The <strong>in</strong>verse correpondence function σ −1 also holds of an s-structure to an f-structure.


2.3 Semantic-Structure 16<br />

(30) Mary N (g pred) = ‘mary’<br />

Mary : gσ<br />

cry V (f pred)= ‘cry’<br />

λX.cry(X) : (f subj)σ ⊸ fσ<br />

In the first lexical entry, the expression Mary : gσ is the mean<strong>in</strong>g constructor. It does<br />

not really construct any mean<strong>in</strong>g here s<strong>in</strong>ce it is an <strong>in</strong>dividual-denot<strong>in</strong>g expression. Mary<br />

is the mean<strong>in</strong>g and it is associated with the s-structure gσ which is the semantic projection<br />

of the f-structure g. The second lexical entry with the expression λX.cry(X) : (f subj)σ<br />

⊸ f σ shows how we construct mean<strong>in</strong>gs. The left part λX.cry(X) displays a one-place<br />

predicate us<strong>in</strong>g the λ-calculus. The right part is a formula which conta<strong>in</strong>s the connective ⊸<br />

known as the l<strong>in</strong>ear implication symbol <strong>in</strong> l<strong>in</strong>ear logic. This symbol expresses a mean<strong>in</strong>g<br />

like if...then...: and it carries a requirement of production and consumption. Thus, the<br />

formula <strong>in</strong> the second l<strong>in</strong>e of the lexical entry of the verb cry, (f subj)σ ⊸ fσ, <strong>in</strong>dicates<br />

that if a semantic resource (f subj)σ is found, it is consumed and the semantic resource<br />

fσ is produced, which is the semantics of the whole structure. Thus, the mean<strong>in</strong>g for the<br />

whole structure is produced once the mean<strong>in</strong>g of the arguments of the verb are obta<strong>in</strong>ed.<br />

The mean<strong>in</strong>g constructors for the argument Mary and the predicate cry are as follows:<br />

(31) [Mary] Mary : gσ<br />

[cry] λX.cry(X) : (f subj)σ ⊸ fσ<br />

If we <strong>in</strong>stantiate the f-structure for Mary with label g and the f-structure for cry with label<br />

f, we can derive the follow<strong>in</strong>g:<br />

(32) [Mary] Mary : gσ<br />

[cry] λX.cry(X) : gσ ⊸ fσ<br />

Discharg<strong>in</strong>g the antecedent of an implication on the right hand side of the formula<br />

labeled [cry] means apply<strong>in</strong>g a function to its argument on the left-hand side. The formula<br />

[Mary-cry] is def<strong>in</strong>ed as follows:<br />

(33) [Mary-cry] : cry(Mary) : fσ<br />

If we comb<strong>in</strong>e the premises [Mary] and [cry], we derive the follow<strong>in</strong>g 9 :<br />

(34) [Mary], [cry]<br />

⊢ [Mary-cry]<br />

⊢ cry(Mary) : fσ<br />

Glue semantics postulates specific rules which associate the mean<strong>in</strong>g side (on the left)<br />

with the glue side (on the right side), shown below:<br />

(35) X : gσ<br />

P : gσ ⊸ fσ<br />

P(X) : fσ<br />

(Dalrymple, 2001, 235)<br />

The rule states that the glue side requires as its argument a semantic structure gσ and the<br />

mean<strong>in</strong>g side also requires an argument for the one-place predicate. Once this argument is<br />

9 The symbol ⊢ stands for the l<strong>in</strong>ear logic entailment relation.


2.4 <strong>Agreement</strong> <strong>in</strong> LFG 17<br />

available <strong>in</strong> both cases then it is possible to derive the complete semantic resource <strong>in</strong> both<br />

the mean<strong>in</strong>g side and the glue sides.<br />

To summarise, l<strong>in</strong>ear logic allows the various mean<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>in</strong> a sentence to be expressed<br />

as premises <strong>in</strong> a logical deduction and derives the mean<strong>in</strong>g of the sentence by comb<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g<br />

these mean<strong>in</strong>gs. Thus, through logical deduction mean<strong>in</strong>g contributions are perceived<br />

as resources that are produced and consumed while no semantic composition is assumed,<br />

follow<strong>in</strong>g the rules of phrasal composition. Accord<strong>in</strong>g to Dalrymple et al. (2002), this entails<br />

a resource-sensitivity of l<strong>in</strong>ear logic that disallows any arbitrary duplication, deletion or<br />

addition of formulas. Therefore, each word or phrase makes a unique contribution, which<br />

is shown <strong>in</strong> the f<strong>in</strong>al mean<strong>in</strong>g of the sentence.<br />

2.4 <strong>Agreement</strong> <strong>in</strong> LFG<br />

This section provides an <strong>in</strong>troduction to the basic notions of agreement and coord<strong>in</strong>ation<br />

with<strong>in</strong> the architecture of Lexical Functional Grammar. Most constra<strong>in</strong>t-based theories,<br />

which analyse agreement, assert that predicates, such as verbs, place constra<strong>in</strong>ts on the<br />

features of their arguments and more precisely on the central grammatical features person,<br />

number, gender and case.<br />

In LFG, agreement between a f<strong>in</strong>ite verb and its subject is stated through a series<br />

of equations <strong>in</strong> the lexical entries of the agree<strong>in</strong>g elements and it is represented at the fstructure<br />

level. For example, the verb below is morphologically marked to <strong>in</strong>dicate that its<br />

subject must be third person s<strong>in</strong>gular while the subject must carry the same feature-values<br />

to agree with the verb:<br />

(36) Mary arrives<br />

In the example above, the verb arrives agrees with the subject Mary. The f-structure<br />

<strong>in</strong>cludes the attributes person and number, and <strong>in</strong>stantiates the values for these attributes<br />

<strong>in</strong> the follow<strong>in</strong>g way:<br />

⎡<br />

⎤<br />

(37) pred ‘arrive〈subj〉’<br />

⎢ ⎡ ⎤⎥<br />

⎢<br />

f: ⎢<br />

pred ‘Mary’ ⎥<br />

⎢ ⎢ ⎥<br />

⎥<br />

⎣subj<br />

g: ⎣person<br />

3 ⎦<br />

⎥<br />

⎦<br />

num sg<br />

The agreement of the two elements is successfully captured by the equations contributed<br />

by the lexical entries for Mary and arrives, <strong>in</strong>stantiated as follows:<br />

(38) arrives: (f subj person) = 3<br />

(f subj num) = sg<br />

Mary: (g person) = 3<br />

(g num) = sg<br />

The annotations on the English phrase structure rules require that the subject of the verb<br />

be the f-structure g follow<strong>in</strong>g the equation (f subj) = g:<br />

(39) IP → NP VP<br />

(↑subj)=↓ ↑=↓<br />

S<strong>in</strong>ce the agreement features specified by the noun phrase match the agreement features<br />

required by the verb, we can conclude that the agreement features of the whole phrase are<br />

consistent and the sentence is well-formed.


2.4 <strong>Agreement</strong> <strong>in</strong> LFG 18<br />

In NP <strong>in</strong>ternal agreement, LFG assumes the dist<strong>in</strong>ction between concord and <strong>in</strong>dex<br />

agreement features associated with the nouns and posited at the level of functional<br />

structure, follow<strong>in</strong>g work <strong>in</strong> HPSG (Pollard and Sag, 1994; Kathol, 1999; Wechsler and<br />

Zlatić, 2000, 2003). concord features are associated to the declension class of a noun and<br />

control agreement between a noun and its determ<strong>in</strong>er or adjective, and <strong>in</strong>dex features are<br />

associated to the semantics of the noun and control agreement between a noun phrase and<br />

a bound pronoun or a verb (K<strong>in</strong>g and Dalrymple, 2004). The follow<strong>in</strong>g simplified phrase<br />

structure rule is <strong>in</strong>troduced:<br />

(40) NP → Det N<br />

↑=↓ ↑=↓<br />

(K<strong>in</strong>g and Dalrymple, 2004, 71)<br />

The annotation ↑=↓ <strong>in</strong> the phrase structure rule for both the det and the np requires<br />

that they are co-heads and therefore they share the same f-structure. K<strong>in</strong>g and Dalrymple<br />

(2004) propose the follow<strong>in</strong>g phrase structure tree and f-structure for the simple noun<br />

phrase ‘this boy’:<br />

(41) This boy<br />

DET<br />

this<br />

NP<br />

N<br />

boy<br />

⎡<br />

⎤<br />

spec ‘this’<br />

⎢<br />

⎥<br />

⎢<br />

pred ‘boy’ ⎥<br />

⎢<br />

⎥<br />

⎢concord<br />

num sg ⎥<br />

⎢<br />

⎣ <br />

⎥<br />

⎦<br />

<strong>in</strong>dex num sg<br />

(K<strong>in</strong>g and Dalrymple, 2004, 72)<br />

The lexical entries for the determ<strong>in</strong>er this and the noun boy are illustrated below:<br />

(42) this (↑spec) = ‘this’<br />

(↑concord num)= sg<br />

boy (↑pred) = ‘boy’<br />

(↑concord num)= sg<br />

(↑<strong>in</strong>dex num)= sg<br />

(K<strong>in</strong>g and Dalrymple, 2004, 72)<br />

The lexical entry of the determ<strong>in</strong>er this requires <strong>in</strong> its f-structure a noun with sg value<br />

for its concord num feature specification. This is imposed by the equation (↑concord<br />

num)=sg. The lexical entry of the noun boy contributes two types of agreement <strong>in</strong>formation,<br />

concord and <strong>in</strong>dex. In both specifications, it has sg value for the num feature.<br />

The former is related to the agreement of the noun with its determ<strong>in</strong>er and the latter is<br />

related to the agreement of the noun with the verb. The noun’s agreement <strong>in</strong>formation<br />

satisfies the requirements of the determ<strong>in</strong>er s<strong>in</strong>ce the noun contributes the same concord<br />

feature value as the one required by the determ<strong>in</strong>er, and they form a grammatical phrase.<br />

Therefore, noun phrase <strong>in</strong>ternal agreement depends on the concord feature only (Wechsler<br />

and Zlatić, 2000). If the determ<strong>in</strong>er specifies <strong>in</strong>formation that conflicts with that of<br />

the noun, such as <strong>in</strong> the phrase *this boys, the f-structure is unacceptable s<strong>in</strong>ce the value<br />

of the num feature is required to be simultaneously sg by the determ<strong>in</strong>er and pl by the<br />

noun, and therefore it does not obey the uniqueness condition.<br />

Thus, agreement <strong>in</strong> all languages <strong>in</strong>volves the <strong>in</strong>teraction of multiple elements and LFG<br />

has the mechanism to encode effectively this <strong>in</strong>teraction, us<strong>in</strong>g constra<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g equations <strong>in</strong>


2.4 <strong>Agreement</strong> <strong>in</strong> LFG 19<br />

the lexical entries of the agree<strong>in</strong>g elements and represent<strong>in</strong>g these equations <strong>in</strong> well-formed<br />

f-structures.<br />

2.4.1 Coord<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>in</strong> LFG<br />

LFG architecture has the mechanism to capture the phenomenon of coord<strong>in</strong>ation, which<br />

will concern us <strong>in</strong> the rest of the thesis. We will briefly discuss all types of coord<strong>in</strong>ation<br />

but the ma<strong>in</strong> focus will be on noun phrase coord<strong>in</strong>ation.<br />

Coord<strong>in</strong>ation was orig<strong>in</strong>ally discussed with<strong>in</strong> the framework of LFG by Bresnan et al.<br />

(1985b) and was more formally explored by Kaplan and Maxwell (1988) and Dalrymple<br />

et al. (1995). Coord<strong>in</strong>ation phenomena are usually divided <strong>in</strong>to two different types, constituent<br />

coord<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>in</strong> which the coord<strong>in</strong>ated elements are phrasal or lexical constituents,<br />

and nonconstituent coord<strong>in</strong>ation where the coord<strong>in</strong>ated elements are fragments of phrasal<br />

constituents (Dalrymple et al., 1995). The follow<strong>in</strong>g sentences represent examples of constituent<br />

and nonconstituent coord<strong>in</strong>ation:<br />

(43) a. Constituent Coord<strong>in</strong>ation<br />

Bill cried and Mary laughed<br />

Mary cooked and ate the cake<br />

b. Nonconstituent Coord<strong>in</strong>ation<br />

Mary flew to Dallas on Wednesday and New York on Friday<br />

David <strong>in</strong>troduced Chris to Tracy and Mary to Tom<br />

Although constituent coord<strong>in</strong>ation seems more straightforward than nonconstituent<br />

coord<strong>in</strong>ation, it still raises important issues for the more traditional approaches, such as<br />

Conjunction Reduction (CR), proposed by Chomsky (1957) and ref<strong>in</strong>ed by Dougherty<br />

(1970, 1971). A ma<strong>in</strong> problem for those approaches was that it is not always possible to<br />

derive coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrases from full sentences. For example, the two sentences below cannot<br />

be conjo<strong>in</strong>ed and form the coord<strong>in</strong>ate structure <strong>in</strong> (44c):<br />

(44) a. The girl promised John to go<br />

b. The girl persuaded John to go<br />

c. *The girl promised and persuaded John to go<br />

(Kaplan and Maxwell, 1988, 303)<br />

A second problem relates to semantics and that it is possible to have a different semantic<br />

<strong>in</strong>terpretation <strong>in</strong> a coord<strong>in</strong>ate construction, which derives from two separate propositions.<br />

Thus, <strong>in</strong> example (45a), the noun man may refer to two different persons, whereas <strong>in</strong><br />

example (45b), man refers to a s<strong>in</strong>gle person:<br />

(45) a. A man saw Tom and a man greeted Tom<br />

b. A man saw and greeted Tom.<br />

In LFG, coord<strong>in</strong>ate structures, either constituent or nonconsituent, are treated as a<br />

set conta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g the f-structures that correspond to the two coord<strong>in</strong>ated elements (Bresnan<br />

et al., 1985b; Kaplan and Maxwell, 1988). In other words, each conjunct has its own fstructure<br />

which is part of a set. The major advantage of a set representation is that it has<br />

the ability to hold an unbounded number of elements <strong>in</strong> a s<strong>in</strong>gle construction and none of<br />

these elements dom<strong>in</strong>ates or scopes over the others. The follow<strong>in</strong>g rule from Dalrymple<br />

(2001, 362) captures coord<strong>in</strong>ate structures 10 :<br />

10 The Kleene plus operator ( + ) allows any number of IPs to appear with<strong>in</strong> the phrase.


2.4 <strong>Agreement</strong> <strong>in</strong> LFG 20<br />

(46) IP −→ IP + Conj IP<br />

↓∈↑ ↑=↓ ↓∈↑<br />

This phrase structure rule states that the coord<strong>in</strong>ate sentence consists of a sentence (or more<br />

than one), which is the first conjunct, a conjunction and another sentence follow<strong>in</strong>g the<br />

latter. The functional annotations <strong>in</strong> the phrase structure rule specify that the f-structure<br />

of each conjunct is an element of the f-structure that corresponds to the whole coord<strong>in</strong>ate<br />

phrase. A characteristic example of sentential coord<strong>in</strong>ation is the sentence Tom cried and<br />

Mary laughed where the two sentences Tom cried and Mary laughed are conjo<strong>in</strong>ed by the<br />

conjunction and. The correspondence of the c-structure to the relevant f-structure is seen<br />

below:<br />

(47) Tom cried and Mary laughed<br />

NP<br />

N<br />

Tom<br />

IP<br />

I ′<br />

VP<br />

V<br />

cried<br />

IP<br />

Conj<br />

and<br />

NP<br />

N<br />

Mary<br />

IP<br />

I ′<br />

VP<br />

V<br />

laughed<br />

⎧ ⎡<br />

⎤ ⎫<br />

pred ‘cry〈subj〉’<br />

⎣ ⎦<br />

⎪⎨ subj pred ‘tom’ ⎪⎬<br />

⎡<br />

⎤<br />

pred ‘laugh’<br />

⎣ ⎦<br />

⎪⎩ subj pred ‘mary’ ⎪⎭<br />

The whole structure appears as a set which conta<strong>in</strong>s the f-structures that correspond to<br />

the conjunct sentences. Sentential coord<strong>in</strong>ation is rather straightforward. Cases of nonsentential<br />

coord<strong>in</strong>ation are more complicated and LFG has the mechanism to capture them.<br />

Before turn<strong>in</strong>g to these, we <strong>in</strong>troduce the important dist<strong>in</strong>ction between distributive and<br />

nonditributive features.<br />

2.4.1.1 Distributive vs Nondistributive Features<br />

Coord<strong>in</strong>ate structures are special s<strong>in</strong>ce they have features that are different from the features<br />

of their elements, motivat<strong>in</strong>g a dist<strong>in</strong>ction between distributive and nondistributive<br />

features.<br />

A distributive feature is a feature which is associated with each member of the set and<br />

not with the set as a whole. For example, <strong>in</strong> a coord<strong>in</strong>ate noun phrase with nom<strong>in</strong>ative case<br />

case is a distributive feature s<strong>in</strong>ce each conjunct noun needs to specify <strong>in</strong> its f-structure<br />

the attribute case with nom value. Thus, each member of the set needs to have the pair<br />

case nom. An example from <strong>Greek</strong> illustrates the above:<br />

(48) To<br />

the<br />

agori<br />

boy.nom.sg.3<br />

ke<br />

and<br />

‘The boy and the girl are happy’<br />

to<br />

the<br />

koritsi<br />

girl.nom.sg.3<br />

<strong>in</strong>e<br />

are.pl<br />

xarumena<br />

happy


2.4 <strong>Agreement</strong> <strong>in</strong> LFG 21<br />

NP<br />

to-agori<br />

NP<br />

Conj<br />

ke<br />

NP<br />

to-koritsi<br />

⎡<br />

⎤<br />

num pl<br />

⎢⎧<br />

⎡ ⎤ ⎫⎥<br />

⎢ pred ‘agori’<br />

⎥<br />

⎢ ⎢ ⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢ ⎢case<br />

nom ⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢ ⎢ ⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢ d: ⎢<br />

⎢num<br />

sg ⎥ ⎥<br />

⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢ ⎢<br />

⎢ ⎣pers<br />

3<br />

⎥ ⎥<br />

⎦ ⎥<br />

⎢<br />

f: ⎢<br />

⎪⎨<br />

⎪⎬<br />

⎥<br />

def + ⎥<br />

⎢ ⎡<br />

⎤ ⎥<br />

⎢<br />

pred ‘koritsi’ ⎥<br />

⎢ ⎢<br />

⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢ ⎢case<br />

nom ⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢ ⎢<br />

⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢ b: ⎢<br />

⎢ ⎢num<br />

sg ⎥ ⎥<br />

⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢ ⎢<br />

⎣ ⎣pers<br />

3<br />

⎥ ⎥<br />

⎦ ⎥<br />

⎪⎩<br />

⎪⎭<br />

⎦<br />

def +<br />

Bresnan et al. (1985b) and Dalrymple and Kaplan (2000) formally state the above by<br />

extend<strong>in</strong>g the def<strong>in</strong>ition of function-application (f α) = υ to apply to sets as well. This is<br />

shown below:<br />

If α is a distributive feature and s is a set of f-structures, then (s α)= υ holds<br />

iff (f α) = υ for all f-structures f that are members of the set s.<br />

(Dalrymple, 2001, 365)<br />

A nondistributive feature, on the other hand, is one which appears as a property of the<br />

coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase as a whole. In example (48) above, the num feature with value pl holds<br />

of the whole coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase and not of the <strong>in</strong>dividual conjuncts and it is nondistributive.<br />

Dalrymple and Kaplan (2000, 72) propose the follow<strong>in</strong>g formal def<strong>in</strong>ition for nondistributive<br />

features:<br />

If α is a nondistributive feature, then (f α) = υ holds iff the pair 〈α,υ〉 ∈ f.<br />

(Dalrymple, 2001, 158)<br />

Apart from num and pers <strong>in</strong> the above example, preconjunctions, such as both and<br />

either, and conjunctions such as and and or are classified as nondistributive features s<strong>in</strong>ce<br />

they are attributes of the coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase as a whole. Thus, the lexical entry for and or<br />

or is represented as follows:<br />

(49) and conj (↑conj) = and (Dalrymple, 2001, 267)<br />

The dist<strong>in</strong>ction of distributive and nondistributive features is central <strong>in</strong> the sections<br />

that follow.<br />

2.4.1.2 Predicate Coord<strong>in</strong>ation<br />

LFG also captures non-sentential coord<strong>in</strong>ation. Predicate coord<strong>in</strong>ation and more specifically<br />

verb coord<strong>in</strong>ation is a type of non-sentential coord<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>in</strong> which some parts of the<br />

sentence (i.e. subj and/or obj) are shared by the coord<strong>in</strong>ated constituents. The phrase<br />

structure rule for coord<strong>in</strong>ate predicates uses the same functional annotations as the ones<br />

proposed for sentential coord<strong>in</strong>ation but different categories are used s<strong>in</strong>ce predicates are<br />

the coord<strong>in</strong>ate elements. Thus, it is rewritten as follows:<br />

(50) V −→ V + Cnj V<br />

↓ ∈ ↑ ↓ ∈ ↑<br />

(Dalrymple, 2001, 364)


2.4 <strong>Agreement</strong> <strong>in</strong> LFG 22<br />

Based on the rule above, the c-structure and f-structure of the coord<strong>in</strong>ated predicates saw<br />

and bought are shown below:<br />

(51) saw and bought<br />

V<br />

saw<br />

V<br />

Cnj<br />

and<br />

V<br />

bought<br />

⎧<br />

⎫<br />

⎪⎨ pred ‘see〈subj,obj〉’<br />

⎪⎬<br />

f: <br />

<br />

⎪⎩ pred ‘buy〈subj,obj〉’ ⎪⎭<br />

When verbs are coord<strong>in</strong>ated they need to comply with the restrictions imposed by the<br />

Coherence and Completeness conditions for the sentence to be grammatically acceptable.<br />

For example, the two predicates <strong>in</strong> (51) are transitive and each of them needs to have<br />

a subj and an obj for the phrase to be grammatical. This restriction is satisfied if both<br />

predicates share the same subj and obj, or alternatively if the two features distribute to the<br />

<strong>in</strong>dividual conjuncts. In the f-structure and c-structure <strong>in</strong> (52) distributivity requirements<br />

are satisfied. The NP Tom functions as the subject of the f-structure set through the equation<br />

(↑subj)=↓ and the NP oranges functions as the object of the f-structure set through<br />

the equation (↑obj)=↓. Hence both subj and obj features distribute to the <strong>in</strong>dividual<br />

conjuncts and therefore the Coherence and Completeness conditions are satisfied:<br />

(52) Tom saw and bought oranges<br />

NP<br />

N<br />

Tom<br />

V<br />

saw<br />

IP<br />

V ′<br />

V<br />

Conj<br />

and<br />

I ′<br />

VP<br />

V<br />

bought<br />

NP<br />

N<br />

oranges<br />

⎧⎡<br />

⎤⎫<br />

pred ‘see〈subj,obj〉’<br />

⎢ ⎥<br />

⎢<br />

⎢subj<br />

pred ‘〈tom〉’ ⎥<br />

⎪⎨<br />

⎣ <br />

⎦⎪⎬<br />

obj pred ‘〈oranges〉’<br />

⎡<br />

⎤<br />

pred ‘buy’<br />

⎢<br />

⎥<br />

⎣subj<br />

⎦<br />

⎪⎩<br />

⎪⎭<br />

obj<br />

The major advantage of the notion of distributivity is that it accounts for both grammatical<br />

and ungrammatical cases. In the case above, the subj and obj are distributed<br />

to each member of the set and this is why the two verbs share the same values for the<br />

subj and obj attributes and the sentence is grammatical. The second advantage is that<br />

distributivity accounts for ungrammatical cases as the ones below:<br />

(53) *Mary promised and persuaded John to go<br />

V<br />

NP<br />

N<br />

Mary<br />

promised<br />

V ′<br />

V<br />

Conj<br />

and<br />

IP<br />

V<br />

I ′<br />

VP<br />

persuaded<br />

NP<br />

N<br />

John<br />

Part<br />

to<br />

VP<br />

The f-structure of the above sentence is shown below:<br />

V ′<br />

V<br />

go


2.4 <strong>Agreement</strong> <strong>in</strong> LFG 23<br />

(54)<br />

⎧⎡<br />

⎤ ⎫<br />

pred ‘promise〈subj,xcomp〉’<br />

⎢ <br />

⎥<br />

⎢<br />

⎢subj<br />

pred ‘〈Mary〉’<br />

⎥<br />

⎢<br />

⎥<br />

⎢obj<br />

pred ‘〈John〉’ ⎥<br />

⎢ <br />

<br />

⎥<br />

⎢<br />

⎪⎨ ⎣ pred ‘go〈Mary〉’ ⎥<br />

xcomp<br />

⎦ ⎪⎬<br />

f:<br />

subj<br />

⎡<br />

⎤<br />

pred ‘persuade〈subj,obj,xcomp〉’<br />

⎢<br />

⎢subj<br />

⎥<br />

⎢<br />

⎥<br />

⎢obj<br />

⎥<br />

⎢ <br />

⎥<br />

⎢<br />

⎣ pred ‘go〈John〉’<br />

⎥<br />

⎦<br />

⎪⎩<br />

xcomp<br />

⎪⎭<br />

subj<br />

The two xcomps are required to be token identical but they are not s<strong>in</strong>ce they do not<br />

share the same subject. Thus, the phrase is ungrammatical.<br />

2.4.1.3 <strong>Noun</strong> Phrase Coord<strong>in</strong>ation<br />

<strong>Noun</strong> phrase coord<strong>in</strong>ation is the last type of constituent coord<strong>in</strong>ation we will present and<br />

which will concern us <strong>in</strong> the rest of the thesis. The central agreement features <strong>in</strong> NP<br />

coord<strong>in</strong>ation are number, person, gender, case and <strong>in</strong> some languages noun class 11 .<br />

As <strong>in</strong> the other types of coord<strong>in</strong>ation, noun phrase coord<strong>in</strong>ation uses the standard LFG<br />

rule:<br />

(55) NP −→ NP + Cnj NP<br />

↓ ∈ ↑ ↑=↓ ↓ ∈ ↑<br />

(Dalrymple, 2001, 381)<br />

<strong>Noun</strong> phrase coord<strong>in</strong>ation also assumes the dist<strong>in</strong>ction between concord and <strong>in</strong>dex 12<br />

agreement features, as non-coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns. <strong>in</strong>dex agreement is formally stated by K<strong>in</strong>g<br />

and Dalrymple (2004) as follows:<br />

<strong>in</strong>dex agreement with a coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase depends on the <strong>in</strong>dex features of<br />

the coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase as a whole. (K<strong>in</strong>g and Dalrymple, 2004, 74)<br />

In predicate-argument agreement, the <strong>in</strong>dex features are number, person, gender<br />

and optionally case 13 . A very simple example of a coord<strong>in</strong>ate noun phrase is given below<br />

from Dalrymple and Kaplan (2000, 778):<br />

(56) Jose y yo hablamos/*habláis/*hablan<br />

Jose and I speak.1.pl/*speak.2.pl/*speak.3.pl<br />

‘Jose and I speak’<br />

11 The most characteristic languages with noun class are Bantu languages.<br />

12 Dalrymple and Kaplan (2000) and Dalrymple (2001) when discuss<strong>in</strong>g agreement <strong>in</strong> coord<strong>in</strong>ate noun<br />

phrases do not assume the dist<strong>in</strong>ction of the <strong>in</strong>dex and concord features with<strong>in</strong> the f-structure. This<br />

dist<strong>in</strong>ction was later <strong>in</strong>troduced by K<strong>in</strong>g and Dalrymple (2004).<br />

13 case is considered to be either distributive or non-distributive, which means that it is one of the <strong>in</strong>dex<br />

or concord features, depend<strong>in</strong>g on the language <strong>in</strong>volved. Dalrymple and Kaplan (2000) seem to suggest<br />

that case and noun class are distributive but Sadler (2003) and McCloskey (1986) argue this is too strong<br />

a position when consider<strong>in</strong>g case mismatches <strong>in</strong> coord<strong>in</strong>ate structures <strong>in</strong> a number of languages <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g<br />

English such as the example She and him/he will drive to the movies (Sadler, 2003, 74).


2.4 <strong>Agreement</strong> <strong>in</strong> LFG 24<br />

The coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase conta<strong>in</strong>s a first person s<strong>in</strong>gular conjunct and a third person s<strong>in</strong>gular<br />

conjunct. However, verb agreement is as for a first person plural phrase. Thus, the <strong>in</strong>dex<br />

person and <strong>in</strong>dex number agreement features of the coord<strong>in</strong>ate structure differ from the<br />

features of <strong>in</strong>dividual conjuncts. A simple functional structure which shows clearly the<br />

representation of the <strong>in</strong>dex features and the features of the conjuncts for the coord<strong>in</strong>ate<br />

phrase <strong>in</strong> (56) is shown below from Dalrymple and Kaplan (2000):<br />

⎡⎧<br />

⎡ ⎤⎫⎤<br />

(57)<br />

⎢<br />

pred ‘Jose’<br />

⎢ ⎢ ⎥<br />

⎥<br />

⎢ f: ⎣person<br />

3 ⎦<br />

⎥<br />

⎢⎪⎨<br />

⎪⎬ ⎥<br />

⎢ num sg ⎥<br />

⎢ ⎡ ⎤ ⎥<br />

⎢ pred ‘pro’ ⎥<br />

⎢<br />

fi: ⎢ ⎢ ⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢<br />

i: ⎣person<br />

1 ⎦ ⎥<br />

⎢⎪⎩<br />

⎪⎭<br />

⎥<br />

⎢ num sg<br />

⎥<br />

⎢<br />

⎥<br />

⎢ person 1 ⎥<br />

⎢<strong>in</strong>dex<br />

⎥<br />

⎢<br />

⎣<br />

num pl ⎥<br />

⎦<br />

pred conj<br />

K<strong>in</strong>g and Dalrymple (2004) propose that <strong>in</strong>dex features are nondistributive features.<br />

Thus, the set represent<strong>in</strong>g a coord<strong>in</strong>ate structure is allowed to have features that represent<br />

the agreement features for the coord<strong>in</strong>ate set. These are the <strong>in</strong>dex features.<br />

concord agreement is also def<strong>in</strong>ed by K<strong>in</strong>g and Dalrymple (2004) as follows:<br />

concord agreement with a coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase depends on the concord features<br />

of each conjunct. (K<strong>in</strong>g and Dalrymple, 2004, 77)<br />

In head-modifier agreement, the concord features are usually number, gender and<br />

optionally case. In the example below from MG, the adjective needs to agree with each<br />

conjunct <strong>in</strong> case and num, otherwise the phrase is ungrammatical:<br />

(58) Eksipno<br />

clever.sg.nom<br />

‘Clever boy and girl’<br />

agori<br />

boy.sg.nom<br />

ke<br />

and<br />

koritsi<br />

girl.sg.nom<br />

The adjective is nom<strong>in</strong>ative s<strong>in</strong>gular and specifies <strong>in</strong> its lexical entry the feature values<br />

concord num sg and concord case nom. Therefore, each conjunct also needs to be<br />

nom<strong>in</strong>ative s<strong>in</strong>gular. The f-structure of the coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase eksipno agori ke koritsi ‘clever<br />

boy and girl’ below shows the basic concepts of the concord feature and the features of<br />

the conjuncts:<br />

(59) eksipno agori ke koritsi<br />

eksipno: (↑concord num) = sg<br />

(↑concord case) = nom


2.4 <strong>Agreement</strong> <strong>in</strong> LFG 25<br />

⎡ <br />

<br />

⎤<br />

adj [pred ‘clever’]<br />

⎢<br />

⎥<br />

⎢<br />

⎥<br />

⎢<strong>in</strong>dex<br />

[num pl](nondistrib. feat. of c) ⎥<br />

⎢⎧<br />

⎢ ⎡<br />

⎤⎫<br />

⎥<br />

⎢ pred ‘boy’<br />

⎥<br />

⎢ ⎢ ⎥<br />

⎥<br />

⎢ ⎢<br />

⎢ b: ⎢<br />

num sg ⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢ ⎢concord<br />

⎥ ⎥<br />

c: ⎢ ⎣ case nom ⎥ ⎥<br />

⎦ ⎥<br />

⎢⎪⎨<br />

⎪⎬ ⎥<br />

⎢ <strong>in</strong>dex [num sg]<br />

⎥<br />

⎢ ⎡<br />

⎤ ⎥<br />

⎢ pred ‘girl’<br />

⎥<br />

⎢ ⎢ ⎥<br />

⎥<br />

⎢ ⎢<br />

⎢ g: ⎢<br />

num sg ⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢ ⎢concord<br />

⎥ ⎥<br />

⎣ ⎣ case nom ⎥ ⎥<br />

⎦ ⎥<br />

⎦<br />

⎪⎩ <strong>in</strong>dex [num sg]<br />

⎪⎭<br />

Thus, the agreement features of the adjective distribute to each conjunct and require<br />

feature match<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> order for the phrase to be grammatical. K<strong>in</strong>g and Dalrymple (2004)<br />

propose that concord features are distributive features and they are associated only with<br />

the <strong>in</strong>dividual members of the set represent<strong>in</strong>g the coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase and not the set as a<br />

whole. These features appear as features of the <strong>in</strong>dividual conjuncts only.<br />

To summarise, <strong>in</strong> noun phrase coord<strong>in</strong>ation LFG assumes the dist<strong>in</strong>ction between two<br />

central features <strong>in</strong>dex and concord. concord features are distributive and are associated<br />

only with the <strong>in</strong>dividual conjuncts of a set of a coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase. These are usually<br />

number, gender and case. <strong>in</strong>dex features are nondistributive mean<strong>in</strong>g that the set as<br />

a whole represent<strong>in</strong>g the coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase, can have <strong>in</strong>dex features. These are usually<br />

person, number, gender and case (depend<strong>in</strong>g on the language) as well as any type<br />

of conjunction (Dalrymple and Kaplan, 2000). Thus, a coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase as a whole is a<br />

hybrid object that apart from the elements it conta<strong>in</strong>s, it also has its own attributes and<br />

values.<br />

2.4.2 The Semantics of Coord<strong>in</strong>ation<br />

In this section, we will summarise semantics <strong>in</strong> coord<strong>in</strong>ate structures. Both sentential<br />

and subsentential coord<strong>in</strong>ate structures derive their mean<strong>in</strong>gs from the mean<strong>in</strong>gs of their<br />

conjuncts. A simple coord<strong>in</strong>ate structure and the mean<strong>in</strong>g representation is shown below:<br />

(60) Tom cried and Mary laughed<br />

cry(Tom) ∧ laugh(Mary)<br />

For the whole sentence to be true, it must be the case that both conjuncts are true. The<br />

follow<strong>in</strong>g mean<strong>in</strong>g constructor and f-structure are assumed for the above sentence, follow<strong>in</strong>g<br />

Dalrymple (2001):<br />

(61) cry(Tom) ∧ laugh(Mary): fσ<br />

⎧ ⎡<br />

⎤⎫<br />

pred ‘cry〈subj〉’<br />

⎪⎨<br />

p: ⎣ ⎦<br />

subj pred ‘tom’ ⎪⎬<br />

f: ⎡<br />

⎤<br />

pred ‘laugh〈subj〉’<br />

q: ⎣ ⎦<br />

⎪⎩ subj pred ‘mary’ ⎪⎭<br />

The conjunction ∧ above imposes the restriction that both propositions must be true for<br />

the whole proposition to be true. The mean<strong>in</strong>g constructor is as follows:


2.4 <strong>Agreement</strong> <strong>in</strong> LFG 26<br />

(62) [and] λX.λY.X∧Y: (↑ ∈)σ ⊸ [(↑ ∈)σ ⊸ ↑σ]<br />

(Dalrymple, 2001, 374)<br />

The glue side states that two semantic resources are required of type t represented by the<br />

(↑ ∈)σ symbol, which corresponds to each proposition. These semantic resources are<br />

elements of the set which is stated by the ∈ symbol. Once these resources are found and<br />

consumed only then we are able to create a semantic resource for the whole set, represented<br />

as ↑σ.<br />

The detailed mean<strong>in</strong>g constructors for the separate conjuncts and for the conjunction<br />

and are shown below as <strong>in</strong> Dalrymple (2001):<br />

(63) [cry] λX.cry(X) : hσ ⊸ pσ<br />

[Tom] Tom : hσ<br />

[laugh] λX.laugh(X) : iσ ⊸ qσ<br />

[Mary] Mary : iσ<br />

[and] λX.λY.X∧Y: pσ ⊸ [qσ ⊸ fσ]<br />

Thus, we first comb<strong>in</strong>e the mean<strong>in</strong>g constructors of the first conjunct [cry] and [Tom]<br />

then of the second conjunct [laugh] and [Mary] and f<strong>in</strong>ally the result of the two will<br />

be comb<strong>in</strong>ed with the conjunction [and] <strong>in</strong> order to give the whole coord<strong>in</strong>ate structure.<br />

Follow<strong>in</strong>g Dalrymple (2001), this is shown below:<br />

(64) [cry], [Tom] ⊢ cry(Tom) : pσ<br />

[laugh], [Mary] ⊢ laugh(Mary) : qσ<br />

[and], [Tom-cry], [Mary-laugh] ⊢ cry(Tom) ∧ laugh(Mary): fσ<br />

<strong>Noun</strong> phrase coord<strong>in</strong>ate structures follow a similar process with the ma<strong>in</strong> difference that<br />

the conjunction and is a group-form<strong>in</strong>g ‘and’. This type of and requires arguments of type<br />

e, which is the type used for <strong>in</strong>dividuals. The mean<strong>in</strong>g constructor of the group-form<strong>in</strong>g<br />

‘and’ is illustrated below:<br />

(65) [and] λX.λY.X,Y: (↑ ∈)σ ⊸ [(↑ ∈)σ ⊸ ↑σ]<br />

(Dalrymple, 2001, 384)<br />

The glue side states that two semantic resources are required of type e, which are<br />

members of the set and they are represented as (↑ ∈)σ which corresponds to each<br />

conjunct. Once these are found, they are consumed and therefore we can deduce the<br />

semantic resource of the whole coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase, represented as ↑σ.<br />

A simple coord<strong>in</strong>ate noun phrase, such as Tom and Mary met, has the correspond<strong>in</strong>g<br />

mean<strong>in</strong>g constructor and f-structure:<br />

(66) meet({Tom,Mary}) : fσ<br />

⎡<br />

⎤<br />

pred ‘meet〈subj〉’<br />

⎢ ⎡<br />

⎤⎥<br />

⎢<br />

num pl ⎥<br />

⎢ ⎢<br />

⎥<br />

⎥<br />

⎢ ⎢conj<br />

and ⎥<br />

⎥<br />

f: ⎢ ⎢⎧<br />

⎢subj<br />

g: ⎢<br />

⎫⎥<br />

⎥<br />

⎢ ⎢⎪⎨<br />

h: pred ‘tom’<br />

⎪⎬<br />

⎥<br />

⎥<br />

⎥<br />

⎥<br />

⎢ ⎢<br />

⎣ ⎣ <br />

⎥<br />

⎥<br />

⎪⎩ i: pred ‘mary’ ⎪⎭<br />

⎦<br />

⎥<br />

⎦<br />

(Dalrymple, 2001, 384)<br />

The mean<strong>in</strong>g deduction for the above coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase is as follows:


2.4 <strong>Agreement</strong> <strong>in</strong> LFG 27<br />

(67) [meet] λX.meet(X) : gσ ⊸ fσ<br />

[Tom] Tom : hσ<br />

[Mary] Mary : iσ<br />

[g-and] λX.λY.X,Y: hσ ⊸ [iσ ⊸ gσ]<br />

Once we comb<strong>in</strong>e the two nouns [Tom], [Mary], and the [g-and], we derive the premise<br />

[Tom-and-Mary] as follows:<br />

(68) [Tom-and-Mary] {Tom,Mary} : gσ<br />

The semantic resource gσ is required by the mean<strong>in</strong>g constructor of the verb [meet].<br />

Once the latter is comb<strong>in</strong>ed with the coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase [Tom-and-Mary], we can derive<br />

the mean<strong>in</strong>g constructor for the whole sentence:<br />

(69) [Tom-and-Mary], [meet] ⊢ meet({Tom, Mary}) : fσ<br />

A similar process holds if one of the conjuncts is a quantifier. The mean<strong>in</strong>g for the<br />

simple sentence Tom and a student met is the follow<strong>in</strong>g accord<strong>in</strong>g to Dalrymple (2001):<br />

(70) Tom and a student met<br />

a(Y, student(Y), meet({Tom, Y}))<br />

The relevant mean<strong>in</strong>g constructor and f-structure for the sentence is shown below, based<br />

on Dalrymple (2001):<br />

(71) a(Y, student(Y), meet({Tom, Y})) : fσ<br />

⎡<br />

pred ‘meet〈subj〉’<br />

⎢ ⎡<br />

⎢<br />

num pl<br />

⎢ ⎢<br />

⎢ ⎢conj<br />

and<br />

⎢ ⎢⎧<br />

f: ⎢ ⎢<br />

<br />

⎢ ⎢<br />

⎢subj<br />

g: ⎢⎪⎨<br />

h: pred ‘tom’<br />

⎢ ⎢ ⎡<br />

⎢ ⎢<br />

⎢ ⎢<br />

⎣ ⎣ i: ⎣<br />

⎪⎩<br />

spec<br />

⎤<br />

⎤ ⎥<br />

⎥<br />

⎥<br />

⎥<br />

⎥<br />

⎫⎥<br />

⎥<br />

⎥<br />

⎥<br />

⎥<br />

⎥<br />

⎤<br />

⎪⎬ ⎥<br />

⎥<br />

⎥<br />

⎥<br />

pred ‘a’<br />

⎥<br />

⎥<br />

⎦<br />

⎥<br />

⎥<br />

⎪⎭<br />

⎦<br />

⎥<br />

⎦<br />

pred ‘student’<br />

(Dalrymple, 2001, 384)<br />

The mean<strong>in</strong>g deduction for the above coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase is as follows 14 :<br />

(72) [meet] λX.meet(X) : gσ ⊸ fσ<br />

[Tom] Tom : hσ<br />

[a-student] λS.a(Y, student(Y),S(Y)) : ∀H.[iσ ⊸ H] ⊸ H<br />

[g-and] λX.λY.X,Y: hσ ⊸ [iσ ⊸ gσ]<br />

First, we comb<strong>in</strong>e the mean<strong>in</strong>g [Tom] and [g-and] <strong>in</strong> order to produce the mean<strong>in</strong>g constructor<br />

[Tom-and]:<br />

(73) [Tom-and] λY.{Tom, Y} : iσ ⊸ gσ<br />

14 The universal quantifier ∀ means all or every. It b<strong>in</strong>ds the variable H and ranges over semantic structures<br />

which correspond to different scopes of the quantifier. Also, the expression [iσ ⊸ H] ⊸ H asserts that if a<br />

resource of any H is found that satisfies [iσ ⊸ H] then H can be obta<strong>in</strong>ed (Partee et al., 1993, Chapter 7).


2.5 Summary 28<br />

Next, the follow<strong>in</strong>g abstraction rule is used which allows us to <strong>in</strong>troduce and then discharge<br />

a hypothetical premise <strong>in</strong> the deduction:<br />

(74) X : [iσ]<br />

.<br />

P(X) : fσ<br />

λX.P(X) : iσ ⊸ fσ<br />

(Dalrymple, 2001, 236)<br />

The hypothetical premise X : [iσ ] is <strong>in</strong>troduced which can be comb<strong>in</strong>ed with the premises<br />

[Tom-and] and [meet] <strong>in</strong> order to give the mean<strong>in</strong>g constructor [Tom-and-X-meet].<br />

This is shown below:<br />

(75) X : [iσ ] [Tom-and]<br />

{Tom, X} : gσ<br />

[meet]<br />

meet({Tom, X}) : fσ<br />

[Tom-and-X-meet] λX.meet({Tom, X}) : iσ ⊸ fσ<br />

(Dalrymple, 2001, 386)<br />

F<strong>in</strong>ally, if we comb<strong>in</strong>e the premise [Tom-and-X-meet] with the premise [a-student] we<br />

derive the whole phrase:<br />

(76) [Tom-and-X-meet], [a-student] ⊢ a(Y, student(Y), meet({Tom,Y})): fσ<br />

(Dalrymple, 2001, 386)<br />

The above section presented a brief summary of how semantic composition works <strong>in</strong><br />

coord<strong>in</strong>ate structures us<strong>in</strong>g l<strong>in</strong>ear logic and <strong>in</strong> particular ‘glue’ semantics. The basic idea<br />

is to derive the mean<strong>in</strong>g of a sentence by comb<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g the mean<strong>in</strong>gs of its parts, which are<br />

represented as premises. Hence, through a series of logical deductions we can derive the<br />

mean<strong>in</strong>g of the sentence.<br />

2.5 Summary<br />

This chapter briefly presented the central concepts <strong>in</strong> the formalism of Lexical-Functional<br />

Grammar. We focused on the syntactic and semantic levels of representation, analys<strong>in</strong>g<br />

agreement <strong>in</strong> coord<strong>in</strong>ate constructions. We tried to describe the central notions of sentential<br />

and non-sentential coord<strong>in</strong>ation, which generally follow the same mechanism. The rest of<br />

the thesis deals with non-sentential noun phrase coord<strong>in</strong>ation. The next chapter focuses on<br />

a review of the most important theoretical approaches to predicate-argument agreement<br />

and head-modifier agreement that capture various phenomena <strong>in</strong> noun phrase coord<strong>in</strong>ation.


Chapter 3<br />

Theories of <strong>Agreement</strong><br />

3.1 Introduction<br />

Several theories have been developed concern<strong>in</strong>g the phenomenon of agreement <strong>in</strong> noun<br />

phrase coord<strong>in</strong>ate constructions. Most theories focus on the gender, number and person<br />

features. The current section presents an overview of the theories that analyse the gender<br />

and number agreement features <strong>in</strong> coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns. Predicate-argument agreement and<br />

head-modifier agreement will be presented with reference to the features of gender and<br />

number, respectively.<br />

In predicate-argument agreement, gender ‘resolution’ (Givon, 1970) will be discussed<br />

s<strong>in</strong>ce it presents crossl<strong>in</strong>guistic and language-specific variation. The central notion concern<strong>in</strong>g<br />

gender agreement resolution, as proposed by a number of l<strong>in</strong>guists (Corbett, 1991;<br />

Wechsler and Zlatić, 2003; K<strong>in</strong>g and Dalrymple, 2004), is whether the resolved form is<br />

based on a syntactic pr<strong>in</strong>ciple, a semantic pr<strong>in</strong>ciple or both pr<strong>in</strong>ciples.<br />

In head-modifier agreement, the number feature will be the ma<strong>in</strong> focus. number<br />

agreement of determ<strong>in</strong>ers with coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns shows unexpected variation s<strong>in</strong>ce there are<br />

languages, such as English, where number agreement is determ<strong>in</strong>ed syntactically and other<br />

languages, such as Russian, where syntax or semantics determ<strong>in</strong>e number agreement. The<br />

person feature does not display any special characteristics at least with<strong>in</strong> the languages<br />

presented here and it will not be discussed <strong>in</strong> any detail.<br />

3.2 Theoretical Approaches to Predicate-Argument <strong>Agreement</strong><br />

gender resolution has been mostly discussed <strong>in</strong> theoretical approaches to predicate-argument<br />

agreement. The term ‘resolution’ (Givon, 1970) refers to any rule that specifies the form<br />

of an agree<strong>in</strong>g element, known as the target, when the controller, the element which determ<strong>in</strong>es<br />

the agreement, consists of conjo<strong>in</strong>ed nouns. A characteristic approach to gender<br />

resolution is that of Corbett (1991) which uses a list of statements <strong>in</strong> the form of sets of resolution<br />

rules for the agreement patterns of different languages. Other approaches <strong>in</strong>clude<br />

those of Dalrymple and Kaplan (2000), Wechsler and Zlatić (2003, Chap. 8) and Sadler<br />

(2006), which use the set-based approach, but they differ significantly <strong>in</strong> the operation they<br />

use s<strong>in</strong>ce they resort either to union or to <strong>in</strong>tersection. F<strong>in</strong>ally, a fairly recent proposal<br />

on predicate-argument agreement <strong>in</strong> coord<strong>in</strong>ate constructions is that of Badecker (2007,<br />

2008), based on the <strong>in</strong>teract<strong>in</strong>g effects of ranked constra<strong>in</strong>ts with<strong>in</strong> Optimality Theoretic<br />

Syntax. Each of these theories will be presented and discussed <strong>in</strong> this chapter.<br />

3.2.1 Corbett’s Descriptive Approach<br />

Corbett (1983b, 1991) <strong>in</strong>troduces a set of resolution rules for the features person, number<br />

and gender. Concern<strong>in</strong>g the person and number features, Corbett (1983b) argues that


3.2 Theoretical Approaches to Predicate-Argument <strong>Agreement</strong> 30<br />

resolution is straightforward s<strong>in</strong>ce these features show little variation crossl<strong>in</strong>guistically<br />

<strong>in</strong> their resolved forms. person resolution, for example, follows the precedence hierarchy<br />

where “the first person takes precedence over the second, and the second over the<br />

third”(Corbett, 1991, 262), (Siewierska, 2004). person resolution rules are universal s<strong>in</strong>ce<br />

they occur frequently across languages and they also match the hierarchy of reference,<br />

which is able to constra<strong>in</strong> the pronom<strong>in</strong>al system, as proposed by Zwicky (1977, 718, 725).<br />

The person resolution rules occur <strong>in</strong> a specific order and apply <strong>in</strong> that same order:<br />

Person Resolution Rules<br />

1. If the conjuncts <strong>in</strong>clude a first person, first person agreement forms will be<br />

used;<br />

2. If the conjuncts <strong>in</strong>clude a second person, second person agreement forms will<br />

be used;<br />

(The default condition is that third person agreement forms are used.)<br />

(Corbett, 1991, 262)<br />

Also, accord<strong>in</strong>g to Corbett (1983b, 1991, 2000), <strong>in</strong> number resolution conjo<strong>in</strong>ed s<strong>in</strong>gular<br />

elements need plural number. His number resolution rules cover languages with and<br />

without a dual number:<br />

Number Resolution Rules<br />

1. If there are two conjuncts only, both of which are <strong>in</strong> the s<strong>in</strong>gular, then dual<br />

agreement form will be used;<br />

2. In all other cases, provid<strong>in</strong>g there is at least one non-plural conjunct or three<br />

conjuncts, plural agreement forms will be used;<br />

(Corbett, 1991, 263)<br />

Languages without a dual number must follow only the second resolution rule but<br />

languages with a dual number need to follow the first one too. Thus, for a language like<br />

Slovene, a South Slavonic language with s<strong>in</strong>gular, dual and plural number <strong>in</strong> its system,<br />

if two s<strong>in</strong>gulars are conjo<strong>in</strong>ed, the verb appears <strong>in</strong> the dual. If there are more than two<br />

nouns or if one of them is dual or plural, then the predicate is plural.<br />

Gender, on the other hand, is a much more complex feature s<strong>in</strong>ce it shows great variation<br />

across languages and poses problems of whether its resolved form is semantically<br />

or syntactically driven. The central notion of Corbett’s theory related to gender is the<br />

existence of three different strategies <strong>in</strong> gender resolution, a syntactic, a semantic and a<br />

mixed strategy, comb<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g the two former.<br />

Syntactic resolution means “the gender of the conjo<strong>in</strong>ed nouns <strong>in</strong>volved is what counts,<br />

rather than their mean<strong>in</strong>g” (Corbett, 1991, p.279). Corbett (1991) claims that French,<br />

Spanish, Latvian, H<strong>in</strong>di, Panjabi and <strong>Modern</strong> Hebrew display syntactic gender resolution.<br />

French, for example, is a language with two genders, mascul<strong>in</strong>e and fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e. If a noun<br />

phrase consists of a mascul<strong>in</strong>e noun, the mascul<strong>in</strong>e form is used, otherwise the fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e is<br />

used. The fact that resolution rules are the same <strong>in</strong> animate and <strong>in</strong>animate nouns leads<br />

Corbett (1991) to the conclusion that French 1 follows the syntactic pr<strong>in</strong>ciple of resolution.<br />

The follow<strong>in</strong>g examples display the above:<br />

(1) le<br />

a<br />

livre et le cahier<br />

sont neufs<br />

book.masc and an excercise-book.masc are new.masc.pl<br />

‘the book and excercise book are new’<br />

1 We shall see that this conclusion is disputed by Wechsler and Zlatić (2003) and Wechsler (2009), who<br />

present a set-based semantic theory of agreement and assert that French shows mixed gender resolution<br />

accord<strong>in</strong>g to which animate nouns follow the semantic pr<strong>in</strong>ciple and <strong>in</strong>animate nouns follow the syntactic<br />

pr<strong>in</strong>ciple.


3.2 Theoretical Approaches to Predicate-Argument <strong>Agreement</strong> 31<br />

(2) le<br />

a<br />

père et la mère sont excellents<br />

father.masc and a mother.fem are excellent.masc<br />

‘the father and mother are excellent’<br />

(Corbett, 1991, p.279)<br />

The resolution rules <strong>in</strong> French are stated as follows:<br />

Gender Resolution Rules for French<br />

1. If at least one conjunct is mascul<strong>in</strong>e, the mascul<strong>in</strong>e form is used;<br />

2. Otherwise the fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e is used;<br />

(Corbett, 1991, 279)<br />

Semantic gender resolution “<strong>in</strong>volves reference to the mean<strong>in</strong>g of the conjo<strong>in</strong>ed elements<br />

even if this implies disregard for their syntactic gender”(Corbett, 1991, p.269). In other<br />

words the <strong>in</strong>herent mean<strong>in</strong>g of the conjuncts determ<strong>in</strong>es the resolution form to be used and<br />

not their grammatical gender. Corbett (1991) claims that this type is found <strong>in</strong> Dravidian<br />

and Bantu languages. Tamil, for <strong>in</strong>stance, is a language with three genders, mascul<strong>in</strong>e<br />

(for nouns denot<strong>in</strong>g male rationals), fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e (for female rationals) and neuter (for nonrationals)<br />

<strong>in</strong> the s<strong>in</strong>gular and two agreement forms <strong>in</strong> the plural, the rational (for mascul<strong>in</strong>es<br />

and fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>es) and the neuter. When all conjuncts denote rationals (whether of the same<br />

or mixed gender) the rational form is used, otherwise if the conjuncts are neuter, the neuter<br />

agreement is used. Thus, Corbett (1991) characterises this type of resolution as semantic<br />

<strong>in</strong> nature and presents the follow<strong>in</strong>g examples:<br />

(3) raaman-um murukan-um va-nt-aaÒka<br />

Raman-and Murugan-and come-past-3rd.pl.rational<br />

‘Raman and Murugan came’<br />

(4) naay-um<br />

dog-and<br />

puune-yum<br />

cat-and<br />

‘The dog and the cat came’<br />

(Corbett, 1991, 269)<br />

va-nt-atuÒka<br />

come-past-3rd.pl.neut<br />

The resolution rules are presented as follows:<br />

Gender Resolution Rules for Tamil<br />

1. If all conjuncts denote rationals, the rational form is used;<br />

2. If all conjuncts denote non-rationals, the neuter form is used;<br />

3. Otherwise the rational plural may be used<br />

(Corbett, 1991, 285)<br />

The third type, accord<strong>in</strong>g to Corbett (1991), comb<strong>in</strong>es both the syntactic and semantic<br />

resolution pr<strong>in</strong>ciples. He claims that <strong>in</strong> languages like Polish, Lat<strong>in</strong> and Rumanian these<br />

two strategies coexist. He argues that persons display semantic resolution and the rest of<br />

the nouns show syntactic resolution. In Lat<strong>in</strong>, for <strong>in</strong>stance, when the coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns<br />

have a different gender feature then resolution is determ<strong>in</strong>ed based on whether the nouns<br />

are animate or not. If they are animate the mascul<strong>in</strong>e form is used, otherwise neuter is the<br />

resolved gender. These are shown below:<br />

(5) quam pridem pater mihi<br />

how long-ago father.masc me.dat<br />

mortu-i essent<br />

dead-masc.pl were<br />

‘How long ago my father and mother had died’<br />

et<br />

and<br />

mater<br />

mother.fem


3.2 Theoretical Approaches to Predicate-Argument <strong>Agreement</strong> 32<br />

(6) murus<br />

wall.masc<br />

et<br />

and<br />

porta<br />

gate.fem<br />

de<br />

from<br />

caelo<br />

sky<br />

‘The wall and the gate had been struck by lightn<strong>in</strong>g’<br />

(Corbett, 1991, 287)<br />

The resolution rules are presented as below:<br />

tact-a<br />

struck-neut.pl<br />

Gender Resolution Rules for Lat<strong>in</strong><br />

1. If all conjuncts are mascul<strong>in</strong>e, the mascul<strong>in</strong>e is used;<br />

2. If all conjuncts are fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e, the fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e is used;<br />

3. If all conjuncts denote humans, then the mascul<strong>in</strong>e is used;<br />

4. Otherwise the neuter is used<br />

(Corbett, 1991, 285)<br />

erant<br />

were<br />

The first two rules display feature-match<strong>in</strong>g or syntactic resolution, the fourth rule is a<br />

case of syntactic resolution, whereas the third rule follows the semantic pr<strong>in</strong>ciple s<strong>in</strong>ce the<br />

resolved form is determ<strong>in</strong>ed by the human/non-human dist<strong>in</strong>ction. Other languages such<br />

as Polish and Rumanian that fall with<strong>in</strong> the same category are analysed <strong>in</strong> more detail <strong>in</strong><br />

Corbett (1983b, 1991).<br />

A more formal analysis of the above descriptive approach is found <strong>in</strong> Corbett and<br />

Fraser (1993). Corbett and Fraser (1993) propose a prelim<strong>in</strong>ary formal analysis with<strong>in</strong><br />

Network Morphology where they present a DATR account of Russian nom<strong>in</strong>al <strong>in</strong>flections.<br />

To account for animacy <strong>in</strong> Russian nom<strong>in</strong>al morphology, Corbett and Fraser (1993) express<br />

the ‘prediction rules’ as ‘feature change rules’(130). The latter change the value of certa<strong>in</strong><br />

feature comb<strong>in</strong>ations and are extremely powerful. Corbett and Fraser (1993) reta<strong>in</strong> the idea<br />

of the copy<strong>in</strong>g rule <strong>in</strong> its most general form while the ma<strong>in</strong> work done by the feature-change<br />

rules is given to default statements under nom<strong>in</strong>al. Some of the defaults are overridden<br />

<strong>in</strong> particular parts of <strong>in</strong>dividual declension classes 2 .<br />

To summarise, Corbett (1991) provides a series of descriptive rules for all features<br />

person, number and gender and captures a range of languages. However, he does not<br />

attempt a formal approach to these descriptive rules until later <strong>in</strong> Corbett and Fraser<br />

(1993) where he <strong>in</strong>troduces a prelim<strong>in</strong>ary analysis.<br />

3.2.2 Dalrymple and Kaplan’s Set-Based Theory<br />

Dalrymple and Kaplan (2000) attempt a formal account of feature resolution. They propose<br />

a set-based theory of person and gender resolution <strong>in</strong> coord<strong>in</strong>ate constructions with<strong>in</strong><br />

the constra<strong>in</strong>t-based LFG framework. The central problem beh<strong>in</strong>d resolution is that a<br />

coord<strong>in</strong>ate noun phrase has its own feature-values for person, number and gender, as<br />

any other noun or pronoun, dist<strong>in</strong>ct from the conjuncts’ feature-values. In the follow<strong>in</strong>g<br />

example, the first conjunct is third(3) person s<strong>in</strong>gular(sg) and the second conjunct is<br />

first(1) person s<strong>in</strong>gular(sg). The predicate resolves to features not found <strong>in</strong> any of the two<br />

conjuncts, the first person plural(1.pl):<br />

(7) Jose y yo hablamos/*habláis/*hablan<br />

Jose and I speak-1pl/*speak-2pl/*speak-3pl<br />

(Dalrymple and Kaplan, 2000, 778)<br />

In the f-structure below, the first conjunct has different feature-values from the second<br />

conjunct while the whole coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase has its own feature-values which are different<br />

from the two conjuncts:<br />

2 Details of the defaults are shown <strong>in</strong> Corbett and Fraser (1993, 131).


3.2 Theoretical Approaches to Predicate-Argument <strong>Agreement</strong> 33<br />

⎡⎧<br />

⎡ ⎤⎫⎤<br />

(8)<br />

⎢<br />

pred ‘Jose’<br />

⎢ ⎢ ⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢ f: ⎣person<br />

3 ⎦ ⎥<br />

⎢⎪⎨<br />

⎪⎬ ⎥<br />

⎢ num sg ⎥<br />

⎢ ⎡ ⎤ ⎥<br />

⎢ pred ‘pro’ ⎥<br />

⎢<br />

fi⎢<br />

⎢ ⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢<br />

i: ⎣person<br />

1 ⎦ ⎥<br />

⎢⎪⎩<br />

⎪⎭<br />

⎥<br />

⎢ num sg ⎥<br />

⎢<br />

⎥<br />

⎢<br />

⎢person<br />

1 ⎥<br />

⎢<br />

⎥<br />

⎣num<br />

pl ⎦<br />

conj and<br />

(Dalrymple and Kaplan, 2000, 785)<br />

To account for resolution phenomena <strong>in</strong> coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns and the dist<strong>in</strong>ct feature-values<br />

of the conjuncts from the coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase as a whole, Dalrymple and Kaplan (2000) use<br />

set-valued features, assert<strong>in</strong>g that “sets encode complex values” (p.780). They assign set<br />

values to the agreement attributes person and gender of the <strong>in</strong>dividual conjuncts. The<br />

first, second and third persons are represented with any of the follow<strong>in</strong>g marker sets, such<br />

as the empty set {}, the s<strong>in</strong>gleton sets {s} (for speakers), {h} (for hearer) 3 or the two<br />

member set {s,h}. Similarly, the mascul<strong>in</strong>e, fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e and neuter genders are represented<br />

with any of the marker sets, such as the empty set {}, the s<strong>in</strong>gleton sets {m}, {f} or<br />

{n} and the two member sets {m,f}, {f,n} or {m,n}. We need to note that the use and<br />

variation of the set designators depends on the language itself and whether it <strong>in</strong>cludes all<br />

the person and gender values mentioned above.<br />

Once the sets are assigned to the features of <strong>in</strong>dividual conjuncts, the resolved feature<br />

value of the coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase is the set of the union of the values of the conjunct daughters.<br />

The union operator constructs the smallest set and ensures that all the members of the<br />

<strong>in</strong>put sets are <strong>in</strong>cluded with<strong>in</strong> that. Dalrymple and Kaplan (2000) propose a def<strong>in</strong>ition of<br />

set union:<br />

(9) x ∪ y is the smallest set z such that x ⊆ z and y ⊆ z<br />

(Dalrymple and Kaplan, 2000, 785)<br />

This proposition states that “the union will result if we take the smallest set that satisfies<br />

a collection of separately stated mother-daughter subset assertions” (Dalrymple and<br />

Kaplan, 2000, p.785). Dalrymple and Kaplan (2000) argue that LFG can accommodate<br />

both the condition of the smallest set, us<strong>in</strong>g the m<strong>in</strong>imal f-structures for the functional<br />

description of an utterance, and the mother-daughter subset relation, us<strong>in</strong>g the ↑ and<br />

↓ metavariables. Thus, they <strong>in</strong>troduce the follow<strong>in</strong>g PS rule with the relevant annotations:<br />

(10) NP → NP CONJ NP<br />

↓∈↑ ↓∈↑<br />

(↓person) ⊆ (↑person) (↓person) ⊆ (↑person)<br />

(↓gender) ⊆ (↑gender) (↓gender) ⊆ (↑gender)<br />

(Dalrymple and Kaplan, 2000, 788)<br />

The first l<strong>in</strong>e, already known from coord<strong>in</strong>ation of categories, states that each NP<br />

conjunct daughter needs to be a member of the conjunct set of the mother node. The<br />

second l<strong>in</strong>e states that the person value of the coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase will form the smallest<br />

set conta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g the values of the <strong>in</strong>dividual conjuncts, and the same statement is applied to<br />

gender.<br />

3 For languages with more person features, such as the <strong>in</strong>clusive or exclusive, more marker sets are<br />

required. For details see Dalrymple and Kaplan (2000, 780-83).


3.2 Theoretical Approaches to Predicate-Argument <strong>Agreement</strong> 34<br />

Dalrymple and Kaplan (2000) apply their theory to different languages by present<strong>in</strong>g<br />

person resolution <strong>in</strong> Fula, English, Spanish and Slovak, and gender resolution <strong>in</strong> H<strong>in</strong>di.<br />

In person resolution, they focus on the syntactic dist<strong>in</strong>ctions <strong>in</strong> pronouns and not on the<br />

referential ones. For languages like English, they assume that the person feature has sets<br />

whose elements are drawn from the markers s and h. Thus, 1st person is represented as<br />

the set {s,h}, 2nd person as the set {h} and 3rd person as the empty set {}:<br />

(11) English, Spanish and Slovak<br />

{s,h}: first person<br />

{h}: second person<br />

{}: third person<br />

(Dalrymple and Kaplan, 2000, 784)<br />

The agreement patterns for the above languages are shown below:<br />

(12) English, Spanish and Slovak<br />

1 & 2 = 1<br />

1 & 3 = 1<br />

2 & 3 = 2<br />

3 & 3 = 3<br />

(Dalrymple and Kaplan, 2000, 784)<br />

These agreement patterns state that when a 1st person is coord<strong>in</strong>ated with either a<br />

second person or a third person resolution is 1st person, when a 2nd person is coord<strong>in</strong>ated<br />

with a 3rd person pronoun resolution is 2nd person, and when both conjuncts are 3rd<br />

person resolution is 3rd person.<br />

The table below displays how the union of the conjunct sets produces the set of the<br />

coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase:<br />

(13) {s,h}(1) ∪ {h}(2) = {s,h}(1)<br />

{s,h}(1) ∪ {}(3) = {s,h}(1)<br />

{h}(2) ∪ {}(3) = {h}(2)<br />

{}(3) ∪ {}(3) = {}(3)<br />

(Dalrymple and Kaplan, 2000, 784)<br />

In example (14) from Spanish, the third person s<strong>in</strong>gular noun comb<strong>in</strong>es with the second<br />

person s<strong>in</strong>gular pronoun. As predicted by the union of the two conjuncts, the resolution<br />

must be second person plural.<br />

(14) Jose y tu hablais<br />

Jose-3.sg and you-2.sg speak-2.pl<br />

The relevant f-structure is presented below:<br />

(15) Jose y tu hablais


3.2 Theoretical Approaches to Predicate-Argument <strong>Agreement</strong> 35<br />

⎡<br />

⎤<br />

pred ‘speak’<br />

⎢ ⎡<br />

⎢<br />

⎧ ⎡ ⎤⎫⎤<br />

⎥<br />

⎢ ⎢<br />

pred ‘Jose’<br />

⎢ ⎢ ⎢ ⎥ ⎥<br />

⎥<br />

⎢ ⎢ j: ⎣person<br />

{} ⎦<br />

⎥<br />

⎥<br />

⎥<br />

⎥<br />

⎢ ⎢<br />

⎢ ⎢⎪⎨<br />

num sg ⎪⎬<br />

⎥<br />

⎥<br />

⎥<br />

⎥<br />

⎢ ⎢<br />

⎢ ⎢ ⎡ ⎤ ⎥<br />

⎥<br />

⎥<br />

⎥<br />

f ⎢ ⎢ pred ‘pro’ ⎥<br />

⎥<br />

⎢ ⎢<br />

⎢subj<br />

c: ⎢ ⎢ ⎥<br />

⎥<br />

⎥<br />

⎢ ⎢ i: ⎢<br />

⎢ ⎢ ⎣person<br />

h ⎥ ⎥<br />

⎥<br />

⎦ ⎥<br />

⎥<br />

⎢ ⎢⎪⎩<br />

⎪⎭<br />

⎥<br />

⎥<br />

⎢ ⎢ num sg<br />

⎥<br />

⎥<br />

⎥<br />

⎥<br />

⎢ ⎢<br />

⎢ ⎢ ⎥<br />

⎥<br />

⎥<br />

⎥<br />

⎢ ⎢<br />

⎣ ⎣<br />

person h ⎥<br />

⎥<br />

⎦<br />

⎥<br />

⎦<br />

num pl<br />

(Dalrymple and Kaplan, 2000, 785)<br />

Thus, the person feature of the above coord<strong>in</strong>ate noun phrase is the union of the person<br />

features of the conjuncts. The relevant marker sets appear <strong>in</strong> the two conjuncts. Those<br />

sets are subsets of the smallest set that appears <strong>in</strong> the coord<strong>in</strong>ate NP.<br />

In gender resolution, Dalrymple and Kaplan (2000) acknowledge the existence of both<br />

a syntactic and a semantic resolved gender form, although they focus only on syntactic<br />

gender resolution. A case of semantic resolution where the two conjuncts are fem but the<br />

resolved form is masc, is shown below:<br />

(16) [La personne avec la barbe]<br />

[the person with the beard].fem<br />

idiots/?*idiotes<br />

idiots.masc/?*fem<br />

‘The person with the beard and Marie are idiots’<br />

(Wechsler, 2009)<br />

et<br />

and<br />

Marie<br />

Marie.fem<br />

sont<br />

are<br />

For syntactic gender resolution, they present H<strong>in</strong>di as an example, which is a two gender<br />

system, consist<strong>in</strong>g of mascul<strong>in</strong>e and fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e nouns. In H<strong>in</strong>di, when a mascul<strong>in</strong>e and a<br />

fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e noun are coord<strong>in</strong>ated, the coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase has a mascul<strong>in</strong>e gender, as <strong>in</strong> (17).<br />

When the two nouns are fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e the coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase is fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e, as <strong>in</strong> (18):<br />

(17) H<strong>in</strong>di<br />

meraa<br />

my<br />

m˜e<br />

loc<br />

kuttaa aur merii<br />

dog.masc and my<br />

rahte<br />

hãĩ<br />

live.subj gend=masc.pl<br />

billii<br />

cat.fem<br />

‘My dog and my cat live with me <strong>in</strong> the house’<br />

(18) yah larki aur uski mãã<br />

this girl.fem and her mother.fem<br />

rahtii<br />

hãĩ<br />

live.subj gend=fem<br />

‘This girl and her mother live <strong>in</strong> Delhi’<br />

(Dalrymple and Kaplan, 2000, 788-9)<br />

mere<br />

with<br />

dilli<br />

Delhi<br />

saath<br />

me<br />

m˜e<br />

loc<br />

g h ar<br />

house<br />

The above observation is <strong>in</strong>formally presented as a set of rules for gender resolution<br />

below:<br />

(19) H<strong>in</strong>di<br />

· If the conjuncts <strong>in</strong>clude at least one mascul<strong>in</strong>e noun phrase, the mascul<strong>in</strong>e form


3.2 Theoretical Approaches to Predicate-Argument <strong>Agreement</strong> 36<br />

is used.<br />

· Otherwise the fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e form is used.<br />

(Dalrymple and Kaplan, 2000, 789)<br />

The agreement patterns are shown below:<br />

(20) H<strong>in</strong>di<br />

masc & masc= masc<br />

masc & fem= masc<br />

fem & fem= fem<br />

(Dalrymple and Kaplan, 2000, 789)<br />

Due to the two-way gender system, the marker sets are only two, us<strong>in</strong>g a s<strong>in</strong>gle primitive<br />

marker {m}:<br />

(21) H<strong>in</strong>di<br />

masc{m}<br />

fem{}<br />

(Dalrymple and Kaplan, 2000, 789)<br />

Apply<strong>in</strong>g the union operation, they draw the appropriate resolution results for H<strong>in</strong>di:<br />

(22) H<strong>in</strong>di<br />

{m}(masc) ∪ {m}(masc) = {m}(masc)<br />

{m}(masc) ∪ {}(fem) = {m}(masc)<br />

{}(fem) ∪ {}(fem) = {}(fem)<br />

(Dalrymple and Kaplan, 2000, 789)<br />

Dalrymple and Kaplan (2000), us<strong>in</strong>g the feature set representation account for agreement<br />

phenomena <strong>in</strong> a number of other languages, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g Icelandic a language with a<br />

three gender system. In the last section, we will discuss some disadvantages of their theory,<br />

such as that feature assignment is not cross-l<strong>in</strong>guistic but different languages assume<br />

different set-valued features (V<strong>in</strong>cent and Börjars, 2000) and that Slovene and MG, which<br />

have more complicated gender systems, cannot be captured properly by the current theory<br />

without avoid<strong>in</strong>g the addition of further constra<strong>in</strong>ts.<br />

3.2.3 Wechsler’s Theory of Gender Resolution<br />

Wechsler and Zlatić (2000) and Wechsler and Zlatić (2003, Chap. 8) present an account for<br />

gender resolution which <strong>in</strong>cludes both the semantic and syntactic pr<strong>in</strong>ciples. They <strong>in</strong>vestigate<br />

three languages French, Serbian/Croatian and Icelandic and conclude that <strong>in</strong>animate<br />

coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns are subject to syntactic resolution and animate coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns are<br />

subject to semantic resolution. They observe that semantic resolution <strong>in</strong> animate coord<strong>in</strong>ate<br />

NPs is a crossl<strong>in</strong>guistic phenomenon, even though non-coord<strong>in</strong>ate animate/<strong>in</strong>animate<br />

nouns follow grammatical gender.<br />

Evidence for the existence of a semantic resolution pr<strong>in</strong>ciple <strong>in</strong> animate coord<strong>in</strong>ate<br />

nouns is derived from all three languages. French, for <strong>in</strong>stance, shows fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e resolution<br />

when the conjuncts are fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e, and mascul<strong>in</strong>e is the default gender <strong>in</strong> all other cases, <strong>in</strong><br />

both animate and <strong>in</strong>animate coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns:<br />

(23) French rule (M, F):<br />

F.PL: F + F<br />

M.PL: elsewhere<br />

(Wechsler and Zlatić, 2003, 173)


3.2 Theoretical Approaches to Predicate-Argument <strong>Agreement</strong> 37<br />

Accord<strong>in</strong>g to Wechsler and Zlatić (2003), the follow<strong>in</strong>g examples are a clear evidence<br />

that resolution <strong>in</strong> animate nouns obeys the semantic pr<strong>in</strong>ciple. In example (24), the noun<br />

la sent<strong>in</strong>elle ‘sentry’ is grammatically fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e and it can refer to both males and females.<br />

When that noun is coord<strong>in</strong>ated with the grammatically fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e noun la femme ‘woman’,<br />

the result is nonetheless mascul<strong>in</strong>e resolution:<br />

(24) La sent<strong>in</strong>elle et sa femme<br />

the.fem.sg sentry and his wife.fem.sg<br />

pris/*prises en otage<br />

taken.masc/*fem.pl as hostage<br />

‘The sentry and his wife were taken hostage’<br />

(Wechsler and Zlatić, 2003, 177)<br />

ont été<br />

were<br />

Similarly, <strong>in</strong> example (25), the noun mannequ<strong>in</strong> ‘fashion model’ is grammatically mascul<strong>in</strong>e<br />

but it also refers to a female. When its referent is fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e and it is conjo<strong>in</strong>ed with the<br />

grammatically fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e noun maquilleuse ‘make-up artist’, the result triggers fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e<br />

plural agreement:<br />

(25) Le mannequ<strong>in</strong> et sa maquilleuse<br />

the.masc fashion-model and her make-up-artist.fem.sg<br />

assises dans le co<strong>in</strong><br />

seated.fem.pl <strong>in</strong> the corner<br />

‘The fashion model and her make-up artist are seated <strong>in</strong> the corner’<br />

(Wechsler and Zlatić, 2003, 178)<br />

sont<br />

are<br />

The above patterns show that French animate coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns show semantic resolution.<br />

Inanimate nouns follow the syntactic pr<strong>in</strong>ciple of resolution with the patterns shown <strong>in</strong><br />

(23).<br />

Serbian/Croatian has similar resolution rules to French but it is a three gender system,<br />

<strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g a neuter gender. Animate and <strong>in</strong>animate nouns follow the resolution rules below:<br />

(26) Serbian/Croatian rule (M, F, NT):<br />

F.PL: F + F<br />

M.PL: elsewhere<br />

(Wechsler and Zlatić, 2003, 174)<br />

Evidence that resolution is sex based and not grammatically based <strong>in</strong> animate nouns<br />

is drawn from examples where the grammatically neuter noun devojče ‘little girl’ is coord<strong>in</strong>ated<br />

with the grammatically fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e noun devojka ‘girl’ and they resolve to fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e<br />

and not to mascul<strong>in</strong>e:<br />

(27) Ova velika devojka i moje malo<br />

this.fem.sg big girl and my little<br />

se lepo igrale/?igrali<br />

aux.pl refl well played.fem.pl/?masc.pl<br />

‘This big girl and my little girl played well’<br />

(Wechsler and Zlatić, 2003, 179)<br />

devojče su<br />

girl.neut.sg<br />

Inanimate nouns <strong>in</strong> Serbian/Croatian are syntactically resolved as <strong>in</strong> (26).<br />

F<strong>in</strong>ally, Icelandic, which displays the follow<strong>in</strong>g resolution patterns, shows semantic<br />

resolution <strong>in</strong> animate nouns and syntactic resolution <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>animate nouns:<br />

(28) Icelandic rule (M, F, NT):<br />

F.PL: F + F


3.2 Theoretical Approaches to Predicate-Argument <strong>Agreement</strong> 38<br />

M.PL: M + M<br />

NT.PL: elsewhere (<strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g NT and all mixtures)<br />

(Wechsler and Zlatić, 2003, 174)<br />

In the example below, the noun skáld ‘poet’ is grammatically neuter, <strong>in</strong>dependent of<br />

the sex of the poet. When it is coord<strong>in</strong>ated with another male denot<strong>in</strong>g noun and it refers<br />

to a male poet then resolution is mascul<strong>in</strong>e:<br />

(29) Skaldiþ<br />

the-poet.neut<br />

og<br />

and<br />

Jón<br />

Jon<br />

‘The poet and Jon are famous’<br />

(Wechsler and Zlatić, 2003, 179)<br />

eru<br />

are<br />

frægir/*fræg<br />

famous.masc/*neut.pl<br />

Inanimate nouns <strong>in</strong> Icelandic are syntactically resolved as <strong>in</strong> (28).<br />

Thus, the above patterns support Wechsler and Zlatić’ s claim that animate coord<strong>in</strong>ate<br />

NPs are subject to semantic resolution while <strong>in</strong> coord<strong>in</strong>ate constructions when grammatical<br />

and natural gender diverge, resolution follows the natural and not the grammatical<br />

gender as opposed to noncoord<strong>in</strong>ate structures, which always follow grammatical gender.<br />

Inanimate coord<strong>in</strong>ate NPs are subject to syntactic resolution.<br />

In animate nouns, Wechsler and Zlatić (2003, Chapt.8) associate grammatical genders<br />

with semantic correlates: mascul<strong>in</strong>e gender correlates with male sex, and fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e gender<br />

with female sex. An NP is assigned either an <strong>in</strong>herent grammatical gender or a semantic<br />

gender. Grammatical gender is assigned to a non-coord<strong>in</strong>ate NP, which <strong>in</strong>herits the head<br />

features accord<strong>in</strong>g to a feature-shar<strong>in</strong>g mechanism between the head noun and the phrase<br />

it heads. Otherwise, semantic gender is assigned to the NP. Semantic feature assignment<br />

occurs <strong>in</strong> two cases; first, when the head noun is lexically genderless, as <strong>in</strong> non-coord<strong>in</strong>ated<br />

proper nouns (Dupont) or <strong>in</strong> sex-neutral nouns (journaliste). Second, when the phrase lacks<br />

a head noun, as <strong>in</strong> coord<strong>in</strong>ate NPs, which lack a head noun and therefore a grammatical<br />

gender feature. Thus, non-coord<strong>in</strong>ated NPs are assigned grammatical gender unless they<br />

are lexically genderless, <strong>in</strong> which case they acquire their gender feature based on semantic<br />

<strong>in</strong>terpretations. Coord<strong>in</strong>ated NPs are assigned semantic gender, s<strong>in</strong>ce they are perceived<br />

as headless constructions. Wechsler and Zlatić (2003) state the above succ<strong>in</strong>ctly with the<br />

follow<strong>in</strong>g pr<strong>in</strong>ciple:<br />

Gender agreement with an animate NP that lacks <strong>in</strong>herent gender is always<br />

<strong>in</strong>terpreted semantically.<br />

(Wechsler and Zlatić, 2003, p.181)<br />

In French and Serbian/Croatian, which have similar resolution patterns, they propose<br />

two types of genders to derive the resolution facts. The s(emantic)-genders are those with<br />

semantic correlates, such as mascul<strong>in</strong>e and fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e; those without a semantic correlate,<br />

such as neuter are referred to as e(mpty/expletive)-genders. For the s-genders they <strong>in</strong>troduce<br />

the follow<strong>in</strong>g semantic <strong>in</strong>terpretations:<br />

(30) Semantic <strong>in</strong>terpretations of French or Serbian/Croatian s-genders (for NPs without<br />

<strong>in</strong>herent gender)<br />

a. fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e: ‘female’<br />

b. mascul<strong>in</strong>e: ‘non-female’<br />

(Wechsler and Zlatić, 2003, 182)<br />

The semantic <strong>in</strong>terpretations for s-genders follow the crossl<strong>in</strong>guistic generalisation accord<strong>in</strong>g<br />

to which the gender used for mixed-sex groups <strong>in</strong> most languages is also the gender


3.2 Theoretical Approaches to Predicate-Argument <strong>Agreement</strong> 39<br />

used for coord<strong>in</strong>ate structures. In French, this gender is mascul<strong>in</strong>e, found <strong>in</strong> plural pronouns<br />

(ils), non-sex-differentiated plural proper nouns (les Dupont), non-sex-differentiated<br />

plural common nouns (les America<strong>in</strong>s) and <strong>in</strong> coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns (Corbett (1991); Farkas<br />

and Zec (1995) all cited <strong>in</strong> Wechsler and Zlatić (2003, Chap.8, 181)). In Serbian/Croatian<br />

mascul<strong>in</strong>e is the gender used for mixed-sex groups, also found <strong>in</strong> plural pronouns (oni) and<br />

<strong>in</strong> coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns. In Icelandic, neuter is the gender used for mixed-sex groups, and it<br />

is found <strong>in</strong> coord<strong>in</strong>ate constructions too. Thus, <strong>in</strong> Icelandic Wechsler and Zlatić (2003)<br />

propose different semantic representations to derive the desired results, such as mascul<strong>in</strong>e:<br />

‘male’ and fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e: ‘female’.<br />

In French and Serbian/Croatian animate nouns, Wechsler and Zlatić (2003) assume<br />

that the positively def<strong>in</strong>ed semantic feature ‘female’ is a distributive property “where for<br />

any distributive property P and set s, P(s) iff ∀ f ∈ s.P(f)” (Dalrymple and Kaplan, 2000,<br />

769). Thus, a group of animate entities is a female group if and only if all of its members<br />

are female. On the other hand, the negatively def<strong>in</strong>ed semantic feature ‘non-female’ is not<br />

distributive s<strong>in</strong>ce a ‘non-female’ group is any group that refers either to a mixed group<br />

where at least one member is male and the rest are females, or to a group where all of the<br />

members are males. Thus, <strong>in</strong> (30) ‘female’ is distributive s<strong>in</strong>ce it refers to female members<br />

only, whereas ‘non-female’ is not distributive (i.e. ¬‘female’ is true of at least one member<br />

of the group) s<strong>in</strong>ce it may refer to a mixed group where at least one member is male or<br />

to a male group where all of the members are male. In the two languages, the semantic<br />

<strong>in</strong>terpretations assigned to the correspond<strong>in</strong>g grammatical genders entail that mascul<strong>in</strong>e is<br />

the resolved gender for plural animates.<br />

In <strong>in</strong>animate nouns agreement is grammatical. Wechsler and Zlatić (2003) assume the<br />

<strong>in</strong>tersection operation based on the notion of distributivity, mean<strong>in</strong>g that the set represent<strong>in</strong>g<br />

a property of a group is the <strong>in</strong>tersection of the sets represent<strong>in</strong>g the properties of<br />

the members of the group. They represent fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e and mascul<strong>in</strong>e genders as positively<br />

or negatively specified features to produce the required results. For example, <strong>in</strong> French<br />

a mascul<strong>in</strong>e and a fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e noun resolve <strong>in</strong>to mascul<strong>in</strong>e. Thus, each positively specified<br />

grammatical gender, such as fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e, is represented as the s<strong>in</strong>gleton set {f}, and each<br />

negatively specified gender, such as non-fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e (i.e. mascul<strong>in</strong>e), is the empty set {}.<br />

The feature assignment is shown below:<br />

(31) a. fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e = {f}<br />

b. non-fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e (mascul<strong>in</strong>e) = {}<br />

(Wechsler and Zlatić, 2003, 184)<br />

The <strong>in</strong>tersection of two members if one is {f} and the other {} results <strong>in</strong> a mascul<strong>in</strong>e<br />

grammatical gender as required {f} ∩ {} = {}. Otherwise the <strong>in</strong>tersection of two members<br />

which are both fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e results <strong>in</strong> fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e {f} ∩ {f} = {f}.<br />

E-gender features, like neuter, which lack any semantic correlates and do not follow<br />

distributivity, are accounted for by remov<strong>in</strong>g them from the computation of gender features<br />

for NPs denot<strong>in</strong>g groups. They achieve that by <strong>in</strong>tersect<strong>in</strong>g the calculated set with the<br />

set Gs, which represents the s-genders <strong>in</strong> a language. The follow<strong>in</strong>g universal constra<strong>in</strong>t is<br />

<strong>in</strong>troduced:<br />

Constra<strong>in</strong>t on <strong>in</strong>animate aggregate discourse referents<br />

Let γ1...γn be null or unary sets, represent<strong>in</strong>g the respective genders of the<br />

<strong>in</strong>animate discourse referents κ1...κn; let γx be a null or unary set represent<strong>in</strong>g<br />

the gender of the aggregate (group-denot<strong>in</strong>g) discourse referent X, where the<br />

members of X are κ1...κn; and let Gs be the set of s-gender features <strong>in</strong> the<br />

grammar. Then γx= γ1 ∩...∩ γn ∩ Gs.<br />

(Wechsler and Zlatić, 2003, 184)


3.2 Theoretical Approaches to Predicate-Argument <strong>Agreement</strong> 40<br />

This constra<strong>in</strong>t states that the gender value for an aggregate discourse referent is the<br />

<strong>in</strong>tersection of the gender values of the discourse referent’s elements (conjuncts), m<strong>in</strong>us<br />

any features that are not s-gender features (Wechsler and Zlatić, 2003, 184). E-genders<br />

can be represented as either unary {n} or null {} sets.<br />

For example <strong>in</strong> French, the representation of genders is {f} for fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e, with a semantic<br />

correlate ‘female’ and {} for mascul<strong>in</strong>e with a semantic correlate ‘non-female’. The set of<br />

s-genders will be the unary set {f} only and this will be <strong>in</strong>tersected with the <strong>in</strong>animate<br />

discourse referents:<br />

(32) French<br />

a. Set of s-genders: Gs = {f}<br />

b. Set representations of the genders:<br />

fem: {f} (< ‘female’)<br />

masc: {} (< ‘non-female’)<br />

c. Calculat<strong>in</strong>g gender for plural referents<br />

masc & masc = masc {} ∩ {} ∩ Gs = {}<br />

fem & fem = fem {f} ∩ {f} ∩ Gs = {f}<br />

masc & fem = masc {} ∩ {f} ∩ Gs = {}<br />

(Wechsler and Zlatić, 2003, 185)<br />

The above rule and derivation of resolution applies not only to coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrases but<br />

generally to aggregate discourse referents.<br />

To account for semantic or grammatical gender assignment, they use the LFG formalism,<br />

<strong>in</strong> which the features of a grammatical object can be specified by two dist<strong>in</strong>ct<br />

elements appear<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> the f-structure. They use def<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g equations for the semantic gender<br />

and constra<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g equations for the grammatical gender. The semantic values are ‘female’<br />

and ‘non-female’ and they refer to any <strong>in</strong>dividual that is either female or non-female, respectively.<br />

The grammatical values are {f} and {} for the fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e or mascul<strong>in</strong>e genders,<br />

respectively.<br />

Their proposal works as follows. The adjective below specifies disjunctively two different<br />

values for the feature gend. The ‘female’ value is the semantic value whereas the {f} value<br />

is semantically vacuous and therefore it is the grammatical gender value:<br />

(33) a. competente, A<br />

(↑pred) = ‘competent〈(↑subj)〉’<br />

(↑subj gend) =c{f} ∨ (↑subj gend) = ‘female’<br />

(↑subj num) = sg<br />

(Wechsler and Zlatić, 2003, 191)<br />

In example (34), the noun sent<strong>in</strong>elle specifies [gend {f}], <strong>in</strong>herited by the NP [La sent<strong>in</strong>elle<br />

á la barbe]. The semantic form of the predicative adjective [gend ‘female’] would conflict<br />

with the grammatical form specified by the noun and therefore the disjunct [gend {f}] is<br />

selected for the subject. Thus, <strong>in</strong> this case agreement is syntactic:<br />

(34) [La sent<strong>in</strong>elle à la barbe] est compétente<br />

(↑gend)= {f} (↑subj gend)=c{f}<br />

The bearded sentry is competent<br />

(Wechsler and Zlatić, 2003, 192)<br />

Next, we show how their theory accounts for animate coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns. In the lexical<br />

entry below, the French predicative adjective competents specifies disjunctively a grammatical<br />

gender [gend {}] and a semantic gender [gend ‘non-female’]:


3.2 Theoretical Approaches to Predicate-Argument <strong>Agreement</strong> 41<br />

(35) a. competents, A<br />

(↑pred) = ‘compétent〈(↑subj)〉’<br />

(↑subj gend) =c{} ∨ (↑subj gend) = ‘non-female’<br />

(↑subj num) = pl<br />

In example (36), the coord<strong>in</strong>ate construction is headless and therefore it lacks a grammatical<br />

gender. The grammatical gender of the adjective [gend {}] cannot f<strong>in</strong>d the same<br />

feature <strong>in</strong> the coord<strong>in</strong>ate noun phrase s<strong>in</strong>ce the latter lacks a grammatical gender. The semantic<br />

gender value is the only available choice for the noun phrase. Thus, the coord<strong>in</strong>ate<br />

noun phrase is <strong>in</strong>terpreted semantically:<br />

(36) Jean<br />

Jean.masc.sg<br />

et<br />

and<br />

‘Jean and Marie are competent’<br />

Marie<br />

Marie.fem.sg<br />

sont<br />

sont<br />

competents<br />

competent.masc.pl<br />

To summarise, Wechsler and Zlatic’s (2003) theory assumes that non-coord<strong>in</strong>ate NPs<br />

(animate/<strong>in</strong>animate) will be assigned grammatical agreement unless they lack an <strong>in</strong>herent(grammatical)<br />

gender <strong>in</strong> which case they should be <strong>in</strong>terpreted semantically. Coord<strong>in</strong>ate<br />

animate nouns will be assigned semantic agreement, s<strong>in</strong>ce they lack an <strong>in</strong>herent grammatical<br />

gender, while coord<strong>in</strong>ate <strong>in</strong>animate nouns will be assigned grammatical agreement if<br />

they are mascul<strong>in</strong>e or fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e; otherwise, agreement is derived by the constra<strong>in</strong>t on <strong>in</strong>animate<br />

aggregate discourse referents if they are neuter. Thus, Wechsler and Zlatić (2003) use<br />

both semantic and grammatical (syntactic) resolution, where the features are represented<br />

semantically and grammatically, respectively. Some unfortunate aspects of this approach<br />

are that it does not consider languages with different resolution patterns <strong>in</strong> animate and<br />

<strong>in</strong>animate nouns or the problem of undergeneration of some agreement patterns. These<br />

issues will be analysed <strong>in</strong> the last section.<br />

3.2.4 Sadler’s Theory of Resolution <strong>in</strong> Rumanian<br />

Sadler (2006) also proposes an analysis of gender resolution <strong>in</strong> Rumanian and she captures<br />

the dist<strong>in</strong>ction between the syntactic and semantic resolution <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>animate and animate<br />

nouns, respectively.<br />

Accord<strong>in</strong>g to Farkas (1990), Farkas and Zec (1995), Lumsden (1992) and Wechsler and<br />

Zlatić (2003), Rumanian is a language with three genders: mascul<strong>in</strong>e, fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e and neuter.<br />

Generally, animate nouns are masc when they refer to males, and fem when they refer<br />

to females. In coord<strong>in</strong>ate constructions, animate nouns follow the semantic pr<strong>in</strong>ciple of<br />

resolution. Thus, if any of the conjuncts are male-denot<strong>in</strong>g then resolution is mascul<strong>in</strong>e,<br />

otherwise resolution is fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e. The follow<strong>in</strong>g examples, which show the above general<br />

resolution rules, are from Farkas and Zec (1995) and Moosally (1998), respectively:<br />

(37) Maria<br />

Maria.fem.sg<br />

¸si<br />

and<br />

‘Maria and mother were seen’<br />

(Farkas and Zec, 1995, 94)<br />

(38) Maria<br />

Maria.fem.sg<br />

¸si<br />

and<br />

‘Maria and father were seen’<br />

(Moosally, 1998, 112)<br />

mama<br />

mother.fem.sg<br />

tata<br />

father.masc.sg<br />

au fost vǎzute<br />

were seen.fem.pl<br />

au fost vǎzuti<br />

were seen.masc.sg<br />

The relevant table for the above patterns is from Sadler (2006, 306):


3.2 Theoretical Approaches to Predicate-Argument <strong>Agreement</strong> 42<br />

Table 3.1: <strong>Agreement</strong> of Rumanian Animate Coord<strong>in</strong>ate <strong>Noun</strong>s<br />

NP1 NP2 Target<br />

female male male.pl<br />

female female female.pl<br />

male male male.pl<br />

Inanimate nouns may belong to any of the three genders: mascul<strong>in</strong>e, fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e and<br />

neuter. However, an <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g pattern emerges accord<strong>in</strong>g to Corbett (1991), noncoord<strong>in</strong>ate<br />

<strong>in</strong>animates dist<strong>in</strong>guish three agreement classes but they have only two target genders:<br />

mascul<strong>in</strong>e and fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e. Thus, a mascul<strong>in</strong>e noun admits mascul<strong>in</strong>e agreement <strong>in</strong> its dependents,<br />

a fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e noun admits fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e agreement but a neuter noun admits mascul<strong>in</strong>e<br />

agreement <strong>in</strong> the s<strong>in</strong>gular and fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e agreement <strong>in</strong> the plural, as seen below:<br />

(39) un<br />

a.masc<br />

‘a beautiful chair’<br />

(40) douǎ<br />

two.fem<br />

scaun<br />

chair.neut.sg<br />

scaune<br />

chairs.neut.pl<br />

‘two beautiful chairs’<br />

(Sadler, 2006, 303)<br />

frumos<br />

beautiful.masc.sg<br />

frumoase<br />

beautiful.fem.pl<br />

Corbett (1991), despite oppos<strong>in</strong>g views (Wechsler and Zlatić, 2003; Bateman and Pol<strong>in</strong>sky,<br />

2005), claims that the three-gender agreement dist<strong>in</strong>ction suppports the existence of<br />

three genders especially when one considers <strong>in</strong>animate coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns, which follow syntactic<br />

resolution. In the latter, if all conjuncts are mascul<strong>in</strong>e, resolution is mascul<strong>in</strong>e,<br />

otherwise resolution is fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e even if the conjuncts are neuter. The follow<strong>in</strong>g table is<br />

from Sadler (2006, 304):<br />

Table 3.2: <strong>Agreement</strong> of Rumanian Inanimate Coord<strong>in</strong>ate <strong>Noun</strong>s<br />

NP1 NP2 AP NP1 NP2 AP<br />

nsg nsg fpl fsg msg fpl<br />

fsg fsg fpl fsg nsg fpl<br />

msg msg mpl msg nsg fpl<br />

Sadler’s (2006) proposal treats targets of agreement as underspecify<strong>in</strong>g “the agreement<br />

features of their controllers” <strong>in</strong>stead of treat<strong>in</strong>g “neuter nouns as lexically underspecified<br />

for gender” (Sadler, 2006, 310). In other words, targets are not assigned a specific value<br />

based on their controllers but they place their own constra<strong>in</strong>ts. <strong>Noun</strong>s are specified as<br />

belong<strong>in</strong>g to one of the three gender classes, mascul<strong>in</strong>e, fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e or neuter. The lexical<br />

entries of nouns normally appear as follows:<br />

(41) copac (↑ pred)=‘tree’ rochie (↑ pred)=‘dress’<br />

(↑ gend)=masc (↑ gend)=fem<br />

(↑ num)=sg (↑ num)=sg<br />

scaun (↑ pred)=‘chair’<br />

(↑ gend)=neut<br />

(↑ num)=sg<br />

(Sadler, 2006, 310)


3.2 Theoretical Approaches to Predicate-Argument <strong>Agreement</strong> 43<br />

Adjectives and determ<strong>in</strong>ers are represented as follows:<br />

(42) frumoasă frumos › i<br />

((adj∈↑)gend)=fem ((adj∈↑)gend)=masc<br />

((adj∈↑)num)= sg ((adj∈↑)num)= pl<br />

(↑pred)=‘beautiful’ (↑pred)=‘beautiful’<br />

frumos frumoase<br />

((adj∈↑)gend)¬=fem ((adj∈↑)gend)¬=masc<br />

((adj∈↑)num)= sg ((adj∈↑)num)= pl<br />

(↑pred)=‘beautiful’ (↑pred)=‘beautiful’<br />

(Sadler, 2006, 311)<br />

The lexical entries of the first two adjectives can comb<strong>in</strong>e with fsg and mpl nouns<br />

respectively, s<strong>in</strong>ce the adjectives share the gender value of their head. The next two lexical<br />

entries, for msg and fpl forms of nom<strong>in</strong>al modifiers, are underspecified, mean<strong>in</strong>g that the<br />

mascul<strong>in</strong>e s<strong>in</strong>gular form cannot comb<strong>in</strong>e with a fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e noun but it will comb<strong>in</strong>e freely<br />

with a mascul<strong>in</strong>e or neuter s<strong>in</strong>gular, and similarly the fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e plural will comb<strong>in</strong>e with the<br />

fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e or neuter plural. Participles and predicative adjectives are specified <strong>in</strong> a similar<br />

way (Sadler, 2006, 311).<br />

Sadler (2006, 312) adopts the follow<strong>in</strong>g marker sets to represent the values of the three<br />

genders <strong>in</strong> Rumanian:<br />

(43) Marker Sets for Rumanian <strong>Noun</strong>s<br />

masc{m}<br />

fem{m,n}<br />

neut{n}<br />

In the example below, the fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e noun requires a fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e predicative adjective:<br />

(44) O<br />

a.fem.sg<br />

garoafǎ<br />

carnation.fem.sg<br />

‘A white carnation is expensive’<br />

(Farkas, 1990, 539)<br />

alba<br />

white.fem.sg<br />

e<br />

is<br />

scumpǎ<br />

expensive.fem.sg<br />

The lexical entry of the adjective must allow a fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e {m,n} value for the gender of its<br />

subject s<strong>in</strong>ce the noun is fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e. A constra<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g equation must be used to constra<strong>in</strong> the<br />

gender value. This is represented as follows:<br />

(45) scumpǎ (subj gend must be fem)<br />

(↑subj gend)=c{m n}<br />

(↑subj num)= sg<br />

(↑pred)=‘expensive’<br />

(Sadler, 2006, 313)<br />

In the follow<strong>in</strong>g example, the noun sc › aune ‘chair’ is lexically specified (↑ gend)={n}.<br />

The agreement features of the predicative adjective need to be underspecified s<strong>in</strong>ce the<br />

noun itself is neuter(plural) but the agree<strong>in</strong>g elements are fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e(plural):


3.2 Theoretical Approaches to Predicate-Argument <strong>Agreement</strong> 44<br />

(46) Nis › te<br />

some.fem.pl<br />

sc › aune<br />

chair.neut.pl<br />

‘Some comfortable chairs are useful’<br />

(Farkas, 1990, 540)<br />

confortabile<br />

comfortable.fem.pl<br />

e<br />

are<br />

folositoare<br />

useful.fem.pl<br />

The lexical entry of the adjective cannot be the closed set conta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g the s<strong>in</strong>gle element {m}<br />

(mean<strong>in</strong>g that it has to be either neuter {n} or fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e {m,n}). The negative constra<strong>in</strong>t<br />

is used to exclude the possibility of a mascul<strong>in</strong>e value <strong>in</strong> the gender feature:<br />

(47) folositoare (subj gend can’t be masc)<br />

(↑subj gend)¬={m} (f.pl)<br />

(↑subj num)= pl<br />

(↑pred)=‘useful’<br />

(Sadler, 2006, 313)<br />

After plac<strong>in</strong>g the above constra<strong>in</strong>ts, Sadler (2006) turns to coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns, and follow<strong>in</strong>g<br />

Dalrymple and Kaplan (2000), uses set union to derive resolution. The standard<br />

PS rule of coord<strong>in</strong>ation, add<strong>in</strong>g the extra feature anim with values + or −, specify<strong>in</strong>g that<br />

nouns are animate or <strong>in</strong>animate, accounts for <strong>in</strong>animate coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns:<br />

(48) NP → NP CONJ NP<br />

↓∈↑ ↓∈↑<br />

(↓gend) ⊆ (↑gend) (↓gend) ⊆ (↑gend)<br />

(↓anim)= − (↓anim)= −<br />

(Sadler, 2006, 315)<br />

The above rule accounts for all the coord<strong>in</strong>ation cases of <strong>in</strong>animate nouns, as shown below:<br />

Table 3.3: Coord<strong>in</strong>ation with set values <strong>in</strong> Inanimate Rumanian <strong>Noun</strong>s<br />

NP1 NP2 NPcoord Target Morph<br />

{m}(masc) {m}(masc) {m}(masc) mpl<br />

{m,n}(fem) {m,n}(fem) {m,n}(fem) fpl<br />

{n}(neut) {n}(neut) {n}(neut) fpl<br />

{m,n}(fem) {n}(neut) {m,n}(fem) fpl<br />

{m}(masc) {n}(neut) {m,n}(fem) fpl<br />

{m,n}(fem) {m}(masc) {m,n}(fem) fpl<br />

(Sadler, 2006, 314)<br />

The pattern where two neuter s<strong>in</strong>gular nouns resolve to fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e plural is also accounted<br />

s<strong>in</strong>ce the lexical entry of the predicative adjective <strong>in</strong>cludes the constra<strong>in</strong>t (↑subj gend)¬={m},<br />

which disallows {m} as a gend value but allows either the {n} or the {m,n} sets. This is<br />

shown below:<br />

(49) Scaunul ¸si dulapul<br />

chair.def.nsg and cupboard.def.nsg<br />

‘The chair and the cupboard are white’<br />

(50) albe (subj gend can’t be masc)<br />

(↑subj gend)¬= {m} (f.pl)<br />

(↑subj num)= pl<br />

sînt<br />

are<br />

albe<br />

white.fpl


3.2 Theoretical Approaches to Predicate-Argument <strong>Agreement</strong> 45<br />

(↑pred)=‘white’<br />

(Sadler, 2006, 4)<br />

Corbett (1991) argues that animate nouns <strong>in</strong> Rumanian follow semantic resolution. He<br />

<strong>in</strong>troduces the follow<strong>in</strong>g generalisation:<br />

Gender Resolution Rules for Rumanian<br />

1. If one conjunct denotes a male animate then resolution is masc;<br />

2. If all conjuncts are masc, then masc is used;<br />

3. otherwise fem is used<br />

(Corbett, 1991, 289)<br />

To capture the notion of a male referent, Sadler (2006) uses an extra f-structure feature<br />

semgend with values male and female. Thus, lexical entries of nouns which denote<br />

male <strong>in</strong>dividuals (<strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g nouns that are syntactically fem) have the (↑semgend)= male<br />

feature-value and nouns that denote female <strong>in</strong>dividuals are specified as (↑semgend)= female.<br />

She <strong>in</strong>troduces the follow<strong>in</strong>g rule so as to derive resolution <strong>in</strong> animate nouns:<br />

(51) NP → NP CONJ NP<br />

↓∈↑ ↓∈↑<br />

(↓anim)= + (↓anim)= +<br />

(Sadler, 2006, 317)<br />

[(↑∈ semgend)¬= male<br />

(↑ gend)={m,n}<br />

| (↑ gend)={m}]<br />

The first two l<strong>in</strong>es above are the standard rule of coord<strong>in</strong>ation. The second l<strong>in</strong>e states that<br />

both conjuncts need to be animate s<strong>in</strong>ce this rule is animate specific. In the next equation,<br />

Sadler (2006) uses negation, which has a universal <strong>in</strong>terpretation, so as to state that none<br />

of the members of the set should specify a feature-value male <strong>in</strong> which case the coord<strong>in</strong>ate<br />

phrase should resolve <strong>in</strong>to fem ((↑ gend={m,n})), otherwise the gender of the coord<strong>in</strong>ate<br />

phrase should be masc (| (↑ gend={m}) 4 .<br />

The present proposal is rather powerful s<strong>in</strong>ce it accounts for both the semantic and<br />

syntactic resolution cases found <strong>in</strong> animate and <strong>in</strong>animate nouns <strong>in</strong> Rumanian, accord<strong>in</strong>gly.<br />

It also takes <strong>in</strong>to account the central dist<strong>in</strong>ction that animate nouns resolve accord<strong>in</strong>g to<br />

the semantic pr<strong>in</strong>ciple and that <strong>in</strong>animate nouns resolve accord<strong>in</strong>g to the syntactic one. A<br />

problematic aspect is the addition of the extra feature semgend that will be discussed <strong>in</strong><br />

the last section.<br />

3.2.5 Badecker’s Optimality Theory<br />

Badecker (2008) proposes a theory of agreement with<strong>in</strong> the framework of Optimality Theory,<br />

which is based on the <strong>in</strong>teraction of a series of ranked constra<strong>in</strong>ts. His focuses on the<br />

gender feature for languages that preserve gender dist<strong>in</strong>ctions across the s<strong>in</strong>gular-plural<br />

divide. In particular, he argues that gender resolution patterns arise from the <strong>in</strong>teraction of<br />

a series of universal but violable markedness and faithfulness constra<strong>in</strong>ts, conceived with<strong>in</strong><br />

4 This is also compatible with (↑∈ semgend)¬=male s<strong>in</strong>ce it needs to make the two pairs of the dis-<br />

junction mutually exclusive.


3.2 Theoretical Approaches to Predicate-Argument <strong>Agreement</strong> 46<br />

OT (Pr<strong>in</strong>ce and Smolensky, 2002). He assumes the dist<strong>in</strong>ction <strong>in</strong> noun phrase agreement<br />

between concord and <strong>in</strong>dex features (Kathol, 1999; Sadler, 1999; Wechsler and Zlatić,<br />

2000, 2003). He analyzes languages that reta<strong>in</strong> the same gender dist<strong>in</strong>ction with both s<strong>in</strong>gular<br />

and plural nouns, such as <strong>Modern</strong> <strong>Greek</strong>, Icelandic, Serbian/Croatian, Slovene and<br />

Lat<strong>in</strong>, which are three-gender systems, and the two gender systems, Italian and French.<br />

The central concept of his theory is based on six markedness and faithfulness constra<strong>in</strong>ts<br />

for gender resolution, whose rank<strong>in</strong>g and importance vary across the languages he discusses.<br />

The first three are markedness constra<strong>in</strong>ts and govern the expression of the three genders<br />

(fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e, mascul<strong>in</strong>e and neuter), presented below:<br />

Constra<strong>in</strong>t 1, 2, 3<br />

*F, *M, *N: Do not express gender feature f (for each of Fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e, Mascul<strong>in</strong>e<br />

and Neuter). (Badecker, 2008, 9)<br />

The ma<strong>in</strong> function of the above constra<strong>in</strong>ts is to disallow the occurrence of a particular<br />

gender feature <strong>in</strong> the output and impose economy of structure. Their order varies depend<strong>in</strong>g<br />

on the language. These markedness constra<strong>in</strong>ts are dom<strong>in</strong>ated by a number of other<br />

highly ranked faithfulness constra<strong>in</strong>ts, which require “an identity relation between the <strong>in</strong>dex<br />

features of conjo<strong>in</strong>ed NPs and those of their constituent conjuncts” (Badecker, 2008,<br />

9). The first faithfulness constra<strong>in</strong>t requires the same <strong>in</strong>dex between the coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase<br />

and at least one of the conjuncts for the number and gender features, and tries to capture<br />

the effect of conjunct number on gender resolution with mixed gender value conjuncts.<br />

Thus, conjo<strong>in</strong>ed mascul<strong>in</strong>e and fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e s<strong>in</strong>gular number nouns can resolve to neuter, and<br />

conjo<strong>in</strong>ed mascul<strong>in</strong>e and fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e plural number nouns can resolve to mascul<strong>in</strong>e:<br />

Constra<strong>in</strong>t 4<br />

There is a conjunct phrase whose number and gender feature values are identical<br />

to the resolution values for the conjo<strong>in</strong>ed phrase as a whole (∃c[identN ,G(c,ph 5 )]);<br />

violated if the <strong>in</strong>dex number and/or gender of a conjo<strong>in</strong>ed phrase differs from<br />

that of all its conjuncts. (Badecker, 2008, 10)<br />

The above constra<strong>in</strong>t is violated when the number resolved value is plural and the<br />

conjucts are s<strong>in</strong>gular and when the gender resolved value is different from the gender value<br />

of the <strong>in</strong>dividual conjuncts. A relevant example is the <strong>Modern</strong> <strong>Greek</strong> coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase<br />

below, from Badecker (2008, 3):<br />

(52) Laspomena itan o<br />

diadromos<br />

muddy.neut.pl was the.masc.sg corridor.masc.sg<br />

i skala<br />

the.fem.sg flight-of-stairs.fem.sg<br />

‘The corridor and the flight of stairs were muddy’<br />

The next faithfulness constra<strong>in</strong>t imposes the requirement that the gender feature value<br />

of a coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase is identical to the gender feature value of each conjunct. It does not<br />

place any restrictions on the number value. Badecker (2008) states this as follows:<br />

ke<br />

and<br />

(53) Constra<strong>in</strong>t 5<br />

Every phrasal conjunct is identical <strong>in</strong> its gender feature values to the resolution<br />

values for the conjo<strong>in</strong>ed phrase as a whole (∀c[identG(c,ph)]); violated if the<br />

gender of a conjo<strong>in</strong>ed phrase differs from that of any of its conjuncts.<br />

(Badecker, 2008, 10)<br />

5 The symbol c stands for conjunct and the symbol ph stands for the coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase.


3.2 Theoretical Approaches to Predicate-Argument <strong>Agreement</strong> 47<br />

The present constra<strong>in</strong>t is satisfied when the resolved gender value is the same as the<br />

gender value of the conjuncts, and it is violated if at least one of the gender values of the<br />

conjuncts differ from the gender value of the coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase. The current constra<strong>in</strong>t is<br />

satisfied <strong>in</strong> example (54), but it is violated <strong>in</strong> (55):<br />

(54) La donna e la<br />

the.fem.sg woman and the.fem.sg<br />

preoccupate/*preoccupati<br />

worried.fem.pl/*masc.pl<br />

‘The woman and the girl are very worried’<br />

(55) L’ uomo e la<br />

the.masc.sg man and the.fem.sg<br />

preoccupati/*preoccupate<br />

worried.masc.pl/*fem.pl<br />

‘The man and the woman are very worried’<br />

(Badecker, 2008, 6)<br />

ragazza<br />

girl<br />

donna<br />

woman<br />

sono<br />

are.3.pl<br />

sono<br />

are.3.pl<br />

molto<br />

very<br />

molto<br />

very<br />

The last constra<strong>in</strong>t, which relates to the number feature, is known as SemNr and<br />

requires the resolved number value of a conjo<strong>in</strong>ed phrase to be plural (or dual). This<br />

constra<strong>in</strong>t ensures that the morpho-syntactic representation of number (s<strong>in</strong>gular, dual,<br />

plural) obeys the semantic number. Accord<strong>in</strong>g to Badecker (2008), this constra<strong>in</strong>t is highly<br />

ranked compared to the others <strong>in</strong> most languages analysed:<br />

(56) Constra<strong>in</strong>t 6<br />

SemNr: the <strong>in</strong>dex number of a conjo<strong>in</strong>ed NP (if it has one) cannot differ from the<br />

phrase’s semantic number.<br />

(Badecker, 2008, 10)<br />

In his analysis of <strong>Modern</strong> <strong>Greek</strong> <strong>in</strong>animate nouns 6 , he claims that conjo<strong>in</strong>ed mixed<br />

gender nouns with mascul<strong>in</strong>e and fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e conjuncts resolve to neut when conjuncts are<br />

both s<strong>in</strong>gular and to masc when they are both plural. The resolution patterns are as<br />

follows:<br />

Table 3.4: <strong>Agreement</strong> of Inanimate Coord<strong>in</strong>ate <strong>Noun</strong>s<br />

UNIFORM GENDER MIXED GENDER<br />

NP1 & NP2 AP NP1 & NP2 AP<br />

m & m mpl msg & fsg npl<br />

mpl & fpl mpl<br />

f & f fpl m & n npl<br />

n & n npl f & n npl<br />

(Badecker, 2008, 9)<br />

Accord<strong>in</strong>g to the above table, he <strong>in</strong>troduces the follow<strong>in</strong>g rank<strong>in</strong>g for <strong>Modern</strong> <strong>Greek</strong>:<br />

(57) <strong>Modern</strong> <strong>Greek</strong><br />

SemNr ≫ ∃c[identN ,G(c,ph)] ≫ ∀c[identG(c,ph)] ≫ *F ≫ *M ≫ *N<br />

(Badecker, 2008, 10)<br />

The rank<strong>in</strong>g above treats neut as the default gender and fem as the least preferred one.<br />

S<strong>in</strong>ce the faithfulness constra<strong>in</strong>ts ident are placed higher <strong>in</strong> the rank<strong>in</strong>g, the markedness<br />

6 Full discussion of what patterns are actually found <strong>in</strong> MG will follow <strong>in</strong> the next chapters.


3.2 Theoretical Approaches to Predicate-Argument <strong>Agreement</strong> 48<br />

constra<strong>in</strong>ts alone do not determ<strong>in</strong>e the resolution value but rather the ident constra<strong>in</strong>ts<br />

will play a determ<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g factor.<br />

In coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrases with identical gender conjuncts as <strong>in</strong> fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e s<strong>in</strong>gular nouns, the<br />

resolution value is fem plural, which violates the ident constra<strong>in</strong>t ∃c[identN ,G(c,ph)].<br />

However, the fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e plural value is the optimal one s<strong>in</strong>ce it does not violate the SemNr,<br />

which is placed higher <strong>in</strong> the rank<strong>in</strong>g, and the ∀c[identG(c,ph)], which outranks the<br />

markedness constra<strong>in</strong>ts.<br />

(58) I kuz<strong>in</strong>a ke i<br />

the.fem.sg<br />

kathares<br />

clean.fem.pl<br />

kitchen.fem.sg and the.fem.sg<br />

‘The kitchen and the bathroom are both clean’<br />

(Badecker, 2008, 11)<br />

The table below shows the optimal form of the relevant example:<br />

tualeta<br />

bathroom.fem.sg<br />

Table 3.5: MG Coord<strong>in</strong>ate <strong>Noun</strong>s<br />

Identical Gender Conjuncts<br />

[f.sg & f.sg]<strong>in</strong>dex a SemNr ∃c[identN ,G(c,ph)] ∀c[identG(c,ph)] *F *M *N<br />

α= n.sg *! * * *<br />

α= m.sg *! * * *<br />

α= f.sg *! *<br />

α= n.pl * *! *<br />

α= m.pl * *! *<br />

Zα= f.pl * *<br />

(Badecker, 2008, 12)<br />

In mixed gender cases, he argues that <strong>in</strong> mascul<strong>in</strong>e and fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e s<strong>in</strong>gular conjuncts,<br />

resolution is neut plural, as <strong>in</strong> example (59). In mascul<strong>in</strong>e and fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e plural conjuncts,<br />

resolution is masc plural, as <strong>in</strong> example (60):<br />

(59) O dromos ke i<br />

the.masc.sg road.masc.sg and the.fem.sg<br />

jemata kosmo<br />

full.neut.pl of-people<br />

‘The road and the square were full of people.’<br />

platia<br />

square.fem.sg<br />

(60) I<br />

dromi ke i<br />

the.masc/fem.pl roads.masc.pl and the.masc/fem.pl<br />

platies itan jemati kosmo<br />

squares.fem.pl were full.mpl of-people<br />

‘The roads and the squares were full of people’<br />

(Badecker, 2008, 14)<br />

itan<br />

were<br />

Accord<strong>in</strong>g to the rank<strong>in</strong>g of the constra<strong>in</strong>ts proposed by Badecker (2008), the above<br />

resolution forms depend mostly on the gender markedness constra<strong>in</strong>ts and on the identity<br />

constra<strong>in</strong>t ∃c[identN ,G(c,ph)], which determ<strong>in</strong>es number and gender simultaneously and<br />

is ranked above the markedness constra<strong>in</strong>ts for the three genders. In table (3.6), which<br />

corresponds to example (59), we see that conjo<strong>in</strong>ed s<strong>in</strong>gular nouns violate both identity<br />

constra<strong>in</strong>ts, thus markedness constra<strong>in</strong>ts will determ<strong>in</strong>e the gender option. S<strong>in</strong>ce neuter is<br />

the least marked gender, the resolved form is neut plural (Badecker, 2008, 14):<br />

<strong>in</strong>e<br />

are


3.2 Theoretical Approaches to Predicate-Argument <strong>Agreement</strong> 49<br />

Table 3.6: MG Coord<strong>in</strong>ate <strong>Noun</strong>s<br />

Conjo<strong>in</strong>ed Mascul<strong>in</strong>e and Fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e s<strong>in</strong>gular conjuncts<br />

[m.sg & f.sg]<strong>in</strong>dex a SemNr ∃c[identN ,G(c,ph)] ∀c[identG(c,ph)] *F *M *N<br />

α= n.sg *! * * *<br />

α= m.sg *! * *<br />

α= f.sg *! * *<br />

Zα= n.pl * * *<br />

α= m.pl * * *!<br />

α= f.pl * * *!<br />

(Badecker, 2008, 14)<br />

In table (3.7), which refers to example (60), neuter plural resolution violates the identity<br />

constra<strong>in</strong>t for gender and number (∃c[identN ,G(c,ph)]), whereas neither mascul<strong>in</strong>e plural<br />

nor fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e plural violate the same constra<strong>in</strong>t. Therefore, there are only two possible<br />

resolved forms between mascul<strong>in</strong>e and fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e, which makes masc plural the resolution<br />

value:<br />

Table 3.7: MG Coord<strong>in</strong>ate <strong>Noun</strong>s<br />

Conjo<strong>in</strong>ed Mascul<strong>in</strong>e and Fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e plural conjuncts<br />

[m.pl & f.pl]<strong>in</strong>dex a SemNr ∃c[identN ,G(c,ph)] ∀c[identG(c,ph)] *F *M *N<br />

α= n.sg *! * * *<br />

α= m.sg *! * * *<br />

α= f.sg *! * * *<br />

α= n.pl *! * *<br />

Zα= m.pl * *<br />

α= f.pl * *!<br />

(Badecker, 2008, 14)<br />

The same constra<strong>in</strong>ts hold for a number of other attested resolution patterns concern<strong>in</strong>g<br />

languages such as French and Italian, Icelandic, Serbian and Croatian, but the rank<strong>in</strong>g is<br />

different conform<strong>in</strong>g to the resolution patterns of each language. Badecker (2008) presents<br />

the resolution patterns of Italian and French <strong>in</strong> a tabular form as follows:<br />

Table 3.8: Syntactic resolution patterns for Italian and French<br />

UNIFORM GENDER MIXED GENDER<br />

Italian, French: m & m = m m & f = m<br />

f & f = f<br />

(Badecker, 2008, 9)<br />

Accord<strong>in</strong>g to Badecker (2008) the follow<strong>in</strong>g constra<strong>in</strong>t rank<strong>in</strong>g works for languages such<br />

as Italian and French:<br />

(61) Italian, French etc.<br />

*N ≫ ... ≫ SemNr ≫ ∀c[identG(c,ph)] ≫ *F ≫ *M ≫∃c[identN ,G(c,ph)]<br />

(Badecker, 2008, 10)<br />

To account for mixed gender conjuncts the identity constra<strong>in</strong>t ∀c[identG(c,ph)] is placed<br />

higher than the two gender markedness constra<strong>in</strong>ts *F and *M while *F is also placed higher<br />

than *M. For cases of identical gender conjuncts, Badecker (2008) places the markedness<br />

constra<strong>in</strong>ts below the ident constra<strong>in</strong>t while number is accounted aga<strong>in</strong> by the high position<br />

of the SemNr constra<strong>in</strong>t. The table below shows the optimal form of a mixed gender<br />

comb<strong>in</strong>ation:


3.2 Theoretical Approaches to Predicate-Argument <strong>Agreement</strong> 50<br />

Table 3.9: Italian/French Coord<strong>in</strong>ate <strong>Noun</strong>s<br />

Mixed gender comb<strong>in</strong>ations<br />

[m.pl & f.pl]<strong>in</strong>dex a *N SemNr ∀c[identG(c,ph)] *F *M ∃c[identN ,G(c,ph)]<br />

α= n.sg *! * * *<br />

α= m.sg *! * * *<br />

α= f.sg *! * * *<br />

α= n.pl *! * *<br />

Zα= m.pl * *<br />

α= f.pl * *!<br />

(Badecker, 2008, 14)<br />

Other laguages, such as Serbian/Croatian, Slovene and Icelandic 7 are analysed but we<br />

will not discuss the analysis here due to space limitations.<br />

Accord<strong>in</strong>g to Badecker (2008), the above gender resolution patterns obey the syntactic<br />

resolution pr<strong>in</strong>ciple (Corbett, 1991; Wechsler and Zlatić, 2003) s<strong>in</strong>ce they are determ<strong>in</strong>ed by<br />

morphological properties like gender and number, which are syntactic features. He proposes<br />

a similar analysis for languages whose resolved gender is controlled by semantic factors,<br />

such as the animacy (or human/non-human) of the conjuncts. In Lat<strong>in</strong>, for example, he<br />

accounts for semantic resolution by assum<strong>in</strong>g that the semantic dist<strong>in</strong>ctions correspond<br />

to morpho-syntactic features like [± Animate] (or [±Human]). The resolution patterns <strong>in</strong><br />

Lat<strong>in</strong> for identical or mixed gender conjuncts are presented below:<br />

Table 3.10: Semantically motivated resolution for Lat<strong>in</strong><br />

MIXED GENDER<br />

uniform gender uniformly [+human] uniformly [-human]<br />

m & m = m m & f = m m & f = n<br />

f & f = f m & n = m m & n = n<br />

n & n = n f & n = m f & n = n<br />

(Badecker, 2008, 9)<br />

In example (62), the coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase consists of a mascul<strong>in</strong>e and a fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e [-human]<br />

conjunct which resolve to neuter plural. In example (63), the conjuncts are mascul<strong>in</strong>e and<br />

fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e but s<strong>in</strong>ce they are [+human], they resolve to mascul<strong>in</strong>e:<br />

(62) Murus et porta de caelo<br />

wall.masc.sg<br />

errant<br />

were<br />

and gate.fem.sg from sky<br />

‘The wall and gate have been struck by lighten<strong>in</strong>g’<br />

(63) Quam pridem pater mehi<br />

how long-ago father.masc.sg me.dat<br />

mortu-i essen<br />

dead.masc.pl were<br />

‘How long ago my father and mother had died’<br />

(Corbett, 1991; Badecker, 2008)<br />

et<br />

and<br />

tact-a<br />

struck.neut.pl<br />

mater<br />

mother.fem.sg<br />

Badecker (2008) <strong>in</strong>troduces an extra constra<strong>in</strong>t to account for the [±Human] dist<strong>in</strong>ction,<br />

which is a comb<strong>in</strong>ation of the markedness constra<strong>in</strong>t *N with the *[+Human] feature. Its<br />

function is to exclude neuter as a resolution value for conjo<strong>in</strong>ed [+Human] NPs. The<br />

7 For a complete discussion on the rank<strong>in</strong>g of constra<strong>in</strong>ts and relevant examples <strong>in</strong> Serbian/Croatian,<br />

Slovene and Icelandic see Badecker (2008, 20-26).


3.3 Theoretical Approaches to Head-Modifier <strong>Agreement</strong> 51<br />

problem with this constra<strong>in</strong>t is that it also disallows neuter as the resolved gender for<br />

conjo<strong>in</strong>ed nouns that are both neuter. To avoid that, Badecker (2008) places this constra<strong>in</strong>t<br />

lower <strong>in</strong> the rank<strong>in</strong>g, below the ident constra<strong>in</strong>t for gender, but above the markedness<br />

constra<strong>in</strong>ts. F<strong>in</strong>ally, the feature [Human] is assigned to the conjo<strong>in</strong>ed phrase, when the<br />

conjuncts are either [+Human] or [-Human], and this will only affect gender resolution<br />

<strong>in</strong> mixed gender phrases because the ident constra<strong>in</strong>t ∀c[identG(c,ph)] is placed higher<br />

than the rest of the constra<strong>in</strong>ts which relate to gender.<br />

(64) Lat<strong>in</strong><br />

SemNr ≫ ∀c[identG(c,ph)] ≫ *N&*[+Human] ≫ *F ≫ *M ≫ *N<br />

(Badecker, 2008, 25)<br />

The tables below display how rank<strong>in</strong>g works. For mixed gender cases every resolution<br />

value will necessarily violate the constra<strong>in</strong>t ∀c[identG(c,ph)] and therefore the markedness<br />

constra<strong>in</strong>ts will determ<strong>in</strong>e the gender value from the least marked to the most marked <strong>in</strong><br />

[+H] nouns. In table (3.11), gender resolution for [-H] will be determ<strong>in</strong>ed by the rank<strong>in</strong>g<br />

of the simple markedness constra<strong>in</strong>ts (*F > *M > *N) s<strong>in</strong>ce *N&[+H] is not violated by<br />

any resolution options and the resolved gender is always neut:<br />

Table 3.11: Lat<strong>in</strong> Coord<strong>in</strong>ate <strong>Noun</strong>s<br />

Gender resolution as modulated by [-Human]<br />

[m.sg,[-h] & f.sg,[-h]]<strong>in</strong>dex a ∀c[identG(c,ph)] *N&*[+Human] *F *M *N ∃c[identN ,G(c,ph)]<br />

Zα= n.pl,[-h] * * *<br />

α= m.pl,[-h] * *!<br />

α= f.pl,[-h] * *!<br />

(Badecker, 2008, 22)<br />

In table (3.12), gender resolution for [+H] will exclude neuter as the resolved gender due<br />

to the locally conjo<strong>in</strong>ed markedness constra<strong>in</strong>t *N&[+H] while the rema<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g options are<br />

controlled by the rest of the constra<strong>in</strong>ts and the result<strong>in</strong>g value is masc for any comb<strong>in</strong>ation<br />

of conjunct genders which are [+Human]:<br />

Table 3.12: Lat<strong>in</strong> Coord<strong>in</strong>ate <strong>Noun</strong>s<br />

Gender resolution as modulated by [+Human]<br />

[m.sg,[+h] & f.sg,[+h]]<strong>in</strong>dex a ∀c[identG(c,ph)] *N&*[+Human] *F *M *N ∃c[identN ,G(c,ph)]<br />

α= n.pl,[+h] * *! * *<br />

Zα= m.pl,[+h] * *<br />

α= f.pl,[+h] * *!<br />

(Badecker, 2008, 22)<br />

To conclude, the above constra<strong>in</strong>t-based approach which depends on the rank<strong>in</strong>g of<br />

those constra<strong>in</strong>ts captures the multiple patterns and it is rather flexible s<strong>in</strong>ce each language,<br />

depend<strong>in</strong>g on the data requirements, adopts a different rank<strong>in</strong>g of the constra<strong>in</strong>ts and<br />

allows the admission of new constra<strong>in</strong>ts. Two problems are that it becomes non-economical<br />

through the addition of different constra<strong>in</strong>ts for different languages, and the rank<strong>in</strong>g of the<br />

various forms lead<strong>in</strong>g to an optimal form is not favoured <strong>in</strong> agreement cases where more<br />

than one agreement form is considered grammatically correct, such as the ones we will<br />

discuss <strong>in</strong> MG. These issues are discussed <strong>in</strong> the last section.<br />

3.3 Theoretical Approaches to Head-Modifier <strong>Agreement</strong><br />

The theoretical approaches to head-modifier agreement <strong>in</strong> coord<strong>in</strong>ate structures analyse<br />

NP-<strong>in</strong>ternal coord<strong>in</strong>ation follow<strong>in</strong>g the two-fold nature of agreement features <strong>in</strong>dex and


3.3 Theoretical Approaches to Head-Modifier <strong>Agreement</strong> 52<br />

concord with<strong>in</strong> the noun phrase and the dist<strong>in</strong>ction between distributive and nondistributive<br />

features. The theories that will be presented here are those proposed by Kathol (1999)<br />

and Wechsler and Zlatić (2003) <strong>in</strong> HPSG, K<strong>in</strong>g and Dalrymple (2004) and Dalrymple and<br />

Nikolaeva (2006) <strong>in</strong> LFG, focus<strong>in</strong>g on number.<br />

3.3.1 <strong>Agreement</strong> <strong>in</strong> HPSG<br />

A number of recent proposals <strong>in</strong> NP agreement <strong>in</strong> HPSG have postulated the existence of<br />

a head feature agr (Kathol, 1999) or concord (Wechsler and Zlatić, 2000) responsible<br />

for morphosyntactic agreement, together with the <strong>in</strong>dex feature responsible for semantic<br />

agreement.<br />

Kathol (1999) extends the treatment of agreement <strong>in</strong>troduced by Pollard and Sag (1994)<br />

and treats agreement as a phenomenon which “<strong>in</strong>volves merg<strong>in</strong>g of <strong>in</strong>formation contributed<br />

by various resources <strong>in</strong> the sentence” (Kathol, 1999, 234). He proposes that selector categories,<br />

such as verbs, record their own morphosyntactic agreement features and also select<br />

the agreement features of their argument. This results <strong>in</strong> structure shar<strong>in</strong>g with<strong>in</strong> the<br />

selector category. For example, <strong>in</strong> English the verb walks has the follow<strong>in</strong>g lexical entry:<br />

(65) ⎡<br />

⎡ ⎤⎤<br />

f<strong>in</strong>ite<br />

⎢<br />

⎢ ⎥⎥<br />

⎢cat|hd|morsyn|<br />

agr ⎣pers<br />

1 3rd⎦<br />

⎥<br />

⎢<br />

num 2 sg<br />

⎥<br />

⎢ ⎡<br />

⎤ ⎥<br />

⎢ walk<strong>in</strong>g<br />

⎥<br />

⎢ ⎢ ⎡ ⎤⎥<br />

⎥<br />

⎢ ⎢ <strong>in</strong>dex ⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢ ⎢<br />

⎢cont⎢<br />

⎢<br />

⎢ ⎢ ⎢pers<br />

⎥<br />

⎥ ⎥<br />

1⎥<br />

⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢ ⎢walker<br />

3 ⎢ ⎥<br />

⎥ ⎥<br />

⎣ ⎣ ⎣num<br />

2 ⎦<br />

⎥ ⎥<br />

⎦ ⎥<br />

⎦<br />

gend<br />

(Kathol, 1999, 236)<br />

The above entry shows that only pers and num are <strong>in</strong>volved <strong>in</strong> subject-verb agreement<br />

s<strong>in</strong>ce these two features are appropriate for the subsort f<strong>in</strong>ite of agr. Also, the value of<br />

these features is structure-shared with the value of the same features found on the <strong>in</strong>dex of<br />

subject of the verb. F<strong>in</strong>ally, agr, which is the value of morsyn, is part of a larger group<br />

of l<strong>in</strong>guistic <strong>in</strong>formation 8 .<br />

Kathol (1999) posits two types of agreement, morphosyntactic and semantic as follows:<br />

(66) morphosyntactic agr(selector) ≈ 9 agr(arg)<br />

semantic agr(selector) ≈ <strong>in</strong>dex(arg)<br />

For <strong>in</strong>stance, the follow<strong>in</strong>g example <strong>in</strong> French is a hybrid case of agreement, comb<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g<br />

subject-verb morphosyntactic num agreement, subject-verb semantic pers agreement, and<br />

semantic gend and num agreement between the predicative adjective and the noun:<br />

(67) Vous êtes belle<br />

you.2.pl are.pl beautiful.sg.fem<br />

‘You are beautiful’ (Kathol, 1999, 239)<br />

Morphosyntactic num agreement between the subject and the verb is given by the agr<br />

feature. Semantic pers agreement between the verb and the subject and gend and num<br />

agreement between the predicative adjective and the noun are given by the <strong>in</strong>dex feature.<br />

8 For a more elaborate f-structure and detailed explanations of it see Kathol (1999, 236-9).<br />

9 The symbol “≈” means “is structured-shared <strong>in</strong> its relevant parts with” (Kathol, 1999, 241).


3.3 Theoretical Approaches to Head-Modifier <strong>Agreement</strong> 53<br />

In French, <strong>in</strong>dex also reflects the anchor<strong>in</strong>g conditions, mean<strong>in</strong>g that if a phrase refers to a<br />

female <strong>in</strong>dividual the <strong>in</strong>dex <strong>in</strong> its gend feature will have the value fem. However, the analysis<br />

proposed for French does not hold for all languages but it varies s<strong>in</strong>ce morphosyntactic<br />

and semantic agreement differs from language to language 10 . Kathol’s proposal, who posits<br />

a dist<strong>in</strong>ction between morphosyntactic and semantic agreement, captures a wide range of<br />

data that cannot be accounted for by the analysis proposed by Pollard and Sag (1994).<br />

Pollard and Sag (1994, 61) assume a dist<strong>in</strong>ction between <strong>in</strong>dex agreement, which arises<br />

when <strong>in</strong>dices are required to be token identical, concord or syntactic agreement, which<br />

<strong>in</strong>volves structure-shar<strong>in</strong>g between features (referr<strong>in</strong>g ma<strong>in</strong>ly to the features of case and<br />

declension class <strong>in</strong> German) on “selector” and selected category, and pragmatic agreement,<br />

which arises when contextual background assumptions need to be consistent.<br />

Wechsler and Zlatić (2000) also treat agreement as hybrid or mixed and present a theory<br />

of agreement <strong>in</strong> Serbo-Croatian. They view agreement <strong>in</strong> terms of “two elements specify<strong>in</strong>g<br />

partial <strong>in</strong>formation about a s<strong>in</strong>gle l<strong>in</strong>guistic object” (Wechsler and Zlatić, 2003, 7) and this<br />

<strong>in</strong>formation com<strong>in</strong>g from the two elements must be compatible to result <strong>in</strong> agreement. They<br />

assume that any “<strong>in</strong>flected noun has two different feature sets that determ<strong>in</strong>e the agreement<br />

values it triggers” (Wechsler and Zlatić, 2000, 7pp). These are concord, which <strong>in</strong>volves<br />

the features case, num and gender, and <strong>in</strong>dex which <strong>in</strong>volves the features person, num<br />

and gender.<br />

The concord features of a noun are related to the noun’s <strong>in</strong>flected form. Thus,<br />

concord|gender is related to the declension class of a noun and concord|case and<br />

concord|number determ<strong>in</strong>e its <strong>in</strong>flected form. The relation between morphology and<br />

concord is shown as follows:<br />

(68) morphology ⇐⇒ concord<br />

(Wechsler and Zlatić, 2000, 800)<br />

On the other hand, <strong>in</strong>dex|gender and <strong>in</strong>dex|number are associated to the noun’s<br />

semantics, i.e. whether the noun denotes a male or female or an aggregate or non-aggregate<br />

entity. This is shown as follows:<br />

(69) <strong>in</strong>dex ⇐⇒ semantics<br />

(Wechsler and Zlatić, 2000, 800)<br />

The concord and <strong>in</strong>dex features are related to each other as follows:<br />

(70) concord ⇐⇒ <strong>in</strong>dex<br />

(Wechsler and Zlatić, 2000, 800)<br />

Wechsler and Zlatić (2000) summarise <strong>in</strong> a schema the four types of <strong>in</strong>formation concern<strong>in</strong>g<br />

a noun as follows:<br />

(71) morphology ⇐⇒ concord ⇐⇒ <strong>in</strong>dex ⇐⇒ semantics<br />

(Wechsler and Zlatić, 2000, 800)<br />

The ma<strong>in</strong> focus of their work is cases of mismatch agreement and they predict three<br />

types of mismatches <strong>in</strong> languages such as Serbo-Croatian. The first mismatch occurs between<br />

declension and concord. For example, some nouns have mascul<strong>in</strong>e grammatical properties<br />

and they refer to males but they decl<strong>in</strong>e follow<strong>in</strong>g the declension used for fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e<br />

nouns such as Serbian/Croatian. A second mismatch is between <strong>in</strong>dex and the semantics<br />

of a noun. For example, a noun may refer to a female but governs mascul<strong>in</strong>e agreement.<br />

10 For the discussion of languages such as Spanish, German and English see Kathol (1999, 234-250).


3.3 Theoretical Approaches to Head-Modifier <strong>Agreement</strong> 54<br />

F<strong>in</strong>ally, the mismatch we are <strong>in</strong>terested <strong>in</strong> is that between concord and <strong>in</strong>dex. They give as<br />

a characteristic example the Serbo-Croatian noun deca ‘children’. This noun triggers fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e<br />

s<strong>in</strong>gular agreement on attributive modifiers and non-f<strong>in</strong>ite predicate phrases, which<br />

is syntactic agreement, but it triggers neuter plural agreement on coreferential pronouns,<br />

which is semantic agreement. This is illustrated below:<br />

(72) Posmatrali smo ovu dobru decu.<br />

watched.1pl aux this.f.sg good.f.sg children.acc.<br />

su se lepo igrala<br />

aux.3pl refl nicely played.nt.pl<br />

‘We watched these good childreni. Theyi played well.’<br />

(Wechsler and Zlatić, 2000, 51)<br />

Ona<br />

they.nt.pl<br />

Wechsler and Zlatić (2000) <strong>in</strong>troduce the follow<strong>in</strong>g lexical <strong>in</strong>formation for the noun<br />

deca:<br />

(73) ⎡ ⎤<br />

num s<strong>in</strong>g<br />

⎢<br />

concord ⎥<br />

⎢ gend fem ⎥<br />

⎢ <br />

⎥<br />

⎢<br />

⎣ num plur ⎥<br />

<strong>in</strong>dex<br />

⎦<br />

gend neut<br />

(Wechsler and Zlatić, 2003, 51)<br />

The noun specifies two different features concord and <strong>in</strong>dex. concord refers to the<br />

morphosyntactic agreement and <strong>in</strong>dex to the semantic agreement. For Serbo-Croatian, determ<strong>in</strong>ers,<br />

attributive adjectives and secondary predicates show concord agreement whereas<br />

verbs, primary predicates and bound anaphors show <strong>in</strong>dex agreement.<br />

Both approaches proposed by Kathol (1999) and Wechsler and Zlatić (2000) are consistent<br />

with Corbett’s dist<strong>in</strong>ction between “agreement ad formam” (syntactic agreement)<br />

and “agreement ad sensum” (semantic agreement) and his “agreement hierarchy” (Corbett,<br />

1979, 1983a, 1991), presented below:<br />

(74) The <strong>Agreement</strong> Hierarchy<br />

attributive < predicate < relative pronoun < personal pronoun<br />

Corbett (1979) also suggests that the follow<strong>in</strong>g constra<strong>in</strong>t on agreement systems hold:<br />

(75) As we move rightwards along the hierarchy, the likelihood of semantic agreement<br />

will <strong>in</strong>crease monotonically (Corbett, 1979, 210)<br />

Both approaches capture agreement mismatches and also form the basis for the <strong>in</strong>troduction<br />

of the same features with a similar function <strong>in</strong> Lexical Functional Grammar.<br />

3.3.2 K<strong>in</strong>g and Dalrymple’s Theory<br />

Determ<strong>in</strong>er-noun agreement is straightforward with noncoord<strong>in</strong>ate constructions but more<br />

complicated with coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns. In general, <strong>in</strong> noncoord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns, a s<strong>in</strong>gular determ<strong>in</strong>er<br />

goes with a s<strong>in</strong>gular noun and a plural determ<strong>in</strong>er goes with a plural noun (K<strong>in</strong>g<br />

and Dalrymple, 2004). In coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrases, however, agreement is not always straightforward.<br />

In English, for <strong>in</strong>stance, <strong>in</strong> example (76) the s<strong>in</strong>gular determ<strong>in</strong>er will modify two<br />

s<strong>in</strong>gular conjuncts. The phrase as a whole, however, behaves as a plural phrase and forces<br />

plural agreement to the predicate, as <strong>in</strong> example (77):<br />

(76) This boy and girl/ a boy and girl


3.3 Theoretical Approaches to Head-Modifier <strong>Agreement</strong> 55<br />

(77) This boy and girl are happy<br />

(K<strong>in</strong>g and Dalrymple, 2004, 69)<br />

In plural number, the plural determ<strong>in</strong>er will modify two plural conjuncts:<br />

(78) These boys and girls (K<strong>in</strong>g and Dalrymple, 2004, 69)<br />

Mixed coord<strong>in</strong>ations where one conjunct is s<strong>in</strong>gular and the other is plural require<br />

separate determ<strong>in</strong>ers:<br />

(79) These boys and girl*/These boys and this girl<br />

(K<strong>in</strong>g and Dalrymple, 2004, 69)<br />

K<strong>in</strong>g and Dalrymple (2004) adopt the concord and <strong>in</strong>dex feature dist<strong>in</strong>ction with<strong>in</strong><br />

the noun phrase (Chapter 2, section 2.4.1.3). They show that a phrase such as this boy and<br />

girl has a s<strong>in</strong>gular concord value and a plural <strong>in</strong>dex value, account<strong>in</strong>g for the s<strong>in</strong>gular<br />

number <strong>in</strong> the determ<strong>in</strong>er and the two conjuncts, and the plural number <strong>in</strong> the verb,<br />

respectively. The concord and <strong>in</strong>dex dist<strong>in</strong>ction is straightforwardly related to the LFG<br />

dist<strong>in</strong>ction between distributive and nondistributive features.<br />

Unlike concord, <strong>in</strong>dex is a non-distributive feature. The follow<strong>in</strong>g def<strong>in</strong>ition for<br />

<strong>in</strong>dex agreement is repeated from above:<br />

(80) <strong>in</strong>dex agreement with a coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase depends on the <strong>in</strong>dex features of the<br />

coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase as a whole. (K<strong>in</strong>g and Dalrymple, 2004, 74)<br />

In particular, a coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase is treated as plural due to the presence of a pl value<br />

<strong>in</strong> its <strong>in</strong>dex feature regardless of whether its conjuncts are s<strong>in</strong>gular or plural. Even a<br />

phrase with s<strong>in</strong>gular nouns behaves as a plural phrase:<br />

(81) Joe and Fred are happy<br />

K<strong>in</strong>g and Dalrymple (2004, 74) propose a dist<strong>in</strong>ction between semantic number and<br />

syntactic (<strong>in</strong>dex) number. They argue that semantically the number feature of a phrase<br />

represents the number of <strong>in</strong>dividuals it refers to. When one referent is denoted the num<br />

has a s<strong>in</strong>gular value but when more than one referent is denoted the value is plural. As<br />

mentioned above, coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrases usually refer to more than one <strong>in</strong>dividual; thus, the<br />

phrase this boy and girl behaves as a plural phrase and has a plural value <strong>in</strong> its num<br />

feature, as shown <strong>in</strong> S-V agreement:<br />

(82) This boy and girl are happy<br />

There are cases, however, when a coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase refers to a s<strong>in</strong>gle <strong>in</strong>dividual, as <strong>in</strong><br />

my friend and colleague. In this case, the phrase behaves like a s<strong>in</strong>gular phrase and the<br />

value of the num feature is s<strong>in</strong>gular:<br />

(83) My friend and colleague is eat<strong>in</strong>g a pizza<br />

K<strong>in</strong>g and Dalrymple (2004) associate this semantic dist<strong>in</strong>ction with a syntactic dist<strong>in</strong>ction<br />

<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>dex num requirements. They suggest that a phrase like this boy and girl <strong>in</strong>volves<br />

a group-form<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>terpretation of the conjunction and, requir<strong>in</strong>g a pl value for the <strong>in</strong>dex<br />

num of the noun phrase s<strong>in</strong>ce the group is composed of ‘a boy and a girl’. They propose<br />

the follow<strong>in</strong>g LFG annotation:<br />

(84) Group-form<strong>in</strong>g and<br />

(↑<strong>in</strong>dex num) = pl<br />

(K<strong>in</strong>g and Dalrymple, 2004, 76)


3.3 Theoretical Approaches to Head-Modifier <strong>Agreement</strong> 56<br />

Heycock and Zamparelli (2000, 2005) use the term split <strong>in</strong>terpretation/read<strong>in</strong>g to refer to<br />

the group-form<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>terpretation of the conjunction and.<br />

On the other hand, a coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase like my friend and colleague denotes a Boolean<br />

<strong>in</strong>terpretation of and, mean<strong>in</strong>g that the <strong>in</strong>dividual or <strong>in</strong>dividuals referred to have both<br />

properties simultaneously. Thus, <strong>in</strong> example (83) each <strong>in</strong>dividual must be a friend and a<br />

colleague at the same time. In this case, syntactically the <strong>in</strong>dex num of the coord<strong>in</strong>ate<br />

phrase must be the same as the <strong>in</strong>dex num of one of the conjuncts, annotated as follows:<br />

(85) Boolean and<br />

(↑<strong>in</strong>dex num) = (↑∈ <strong>in</strong>dex num)<br />

(K<strong>in</strong>g and Dalrymple, 2004, 76)<br />

The notation (↑∈<strong>in</strong>dex num) refers to a member of the conjunct set where the set<br />

membership symbol is an attribute. At the same time, they assume that semantically<br />

all of the conjuncts have the same number. <strong>Phrases</strong> like my friend and colleaques have<br />

no boolean <strong>in</strong>terpretation s<strong>in</strong>ce the s<strong>in</strong>gular noun friend and the plural noun colleaques<br />

cannot corefer to the same entity. Heycock and Zamparelli (2000, 2005) use the term jo<strong>in</strong>t<br />

<strong>in</strong>terpretation/read<strong>in</strong>g for the Boolean and.<br />

The concord feature is a distributive feature, associated only with the <strong>in</strong>dividual<br />

members of the set represent<strong>in</strong>g the coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase and not the set as a whole. The<br />

follow<strong>in</strong>g def<strong>in</strong>ition for concord agreement is repeated from above:<br />

(86) concord agreement with a coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase depends on the concord features<br />

of each conjunct. (K<strong>in</strong>g and Dalrymple, 2004, 77)<br />

A s<strong>in</strong>gular determ<strong>in</strong>er will require s<strong>in</strong>gular conjuncts and a plural determ<strong>in</strong>er plural conjuncts<br />

s<strong>in</strong>ce the concord features of the conjuncts must match the concord features of<br />

the determ<strong>in</strong>er <strong>in</strong> order to be licenced.<br />

The f-structure of the coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase this boy and girl illustrates the above:<br />

⎡<br />

⎤<br />

(87) spec ‘this’(nondistrib. feat. of c)<br />

⎢<br />

⎥<br />

⎢<strong>in</strong>dex<br />

[num pl](nondistrib. feat. of c) ⎥<br />

⎢<br />

⎢⎧<br />

⎡<br />

⎤⎫<br />

⎥<br />

⎢ pred ‘boy’<br />

⎥<br />

⎢ ⎢<br />

⎥<br />

⎥<br />

⎢ b: ⎣concord<br />

[num sg] ⎦<br />

⎥<br />

c: ⎢⎪⎨<br />

⎪⎬<br />

⎢ <strong>in</strong>dex [num sg]<br />

⎥<br />

⎢<br />

⎡<br />

⎤<br />

⎥<br />

⎢ pred ‘girl’<br />

⎥<br />

⎢<br />

⎢<br />

⎥<br />

⎥<br />

g:<br />

⎣<br />

⎣concord<br />

[num sg] ⎦<br />

⎥<br />

⎪⎩<br />

⎪⎭<br />

⎦<br />

<strong>in</strong>dex [num sg]<br />

(K<strong>in</strong>g and Dalrymple, 2004, 77)<br />

In the f-structure above, the set c has both nondistributive and distributive features. The<br />

spec feature with its value ‘this’ and the <strong>in</strong>dex feature with its value [num pl] are the<br />

nondistributive features. These are associated with the whole set c while the <strong>in</strong>dex pl<br />

feature-value means that the verb is required to show plural agreement. The coord<strong>in</strong>ate<br />

structure also has features which are associated with each of the members b and g of the set<br />

c. These are concord with value [num sg] and <strong>in</strong>dex with value [num sg]. The concord<br />

feature is a distributive feature and it can never be associated with the coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase<br />

as a whole.<br />

The complete representation of the s<strong>in</strong>gular coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase this boy and girl, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g<br />

the lexical entry of the determ<strong>in</strong>er, is presented below:


3.3 Theoretical Approaches to Head-Modifier <strong>Agreement</strong> 57<br />

(88) This boy and girl<br />

this: (↑concord num) = sg<br />

DET<br />

this<br />

NP<br />

N<br />

boy<br />

N<br />

Conj<br />

and<br />

N<br />

girl<br />

(K<strong>in</strong>g and Dalrymple, 2004, 78)<br />

⎡<br />

⎤<br />

spec ‘this’(nondis. feat. )<br />

⎢<br />

⎥<br />

⎢<strong>in</strong>dex<br />

[num pl](nondis. feat.) ⎥<br />

⎢<br />

⎢⎧<br />

⎡<br />

⎤⎫<br />

⎥<br />

⎢ pred ‘boy’<br />

⎥<br />

⎢ ⎢<br />

⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢ b: ⎣concord<br />

[num sg] ⎦ ⎥<br />

c: ⎢⎪⎨<br />

⎪⎬<br />

⎢ <strong>in</strong>dex [num sg]<br />

⎥<br />

⎢<br />

⎡<br />

⎤ ⎥<br />

⎢ pred ‘girl’<br />

⎥<br />

⎢<br />

⎢<br />

⎥ ⎥<br />

g:<br />

⎣<br />

⎣concord<br />

[num sg] ⎦ ⎥<br />

⎪⎩<br />

⎪⎭<br />

⎦<br />

<strong>in</strong>dex [num sg]<br />

The follow<strong>in</strong>g example shows the correspond<strong>in</strong>g plural coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase these boys<br />

and girls, <strong>in</strong> which the demonstrative determ<strong>in</strong>er specifies <strong>in</strong> its lexical entry a concord<br />

feature with a [num pl] value and would require conjuncts with the same value:<br />

(89) These boys and girls<br />

these: (↑concord num) = pl<br />

DET<br />

these<br />

NP<br />

N<br />

boys<br />

N<br />

Conj<br />

and<br />

N<br />

girls<br />

(K<strong>in</strong>g and Dalrymple, 2004, 80)<br />

⎡<br />

⎤<br />

spec ‘these’<br />

⎢<br />

⎥<br />

⎢<strong>in</strong>dex<br />

[num pl] ⎥<br />

⎢<br />

⎢⎧<br />

⎡<br />

⎤⎫<br />

⎥<br />

⎢ pred ‘boys’ ⎥<br />

⎢ ⎢<br />

⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢ b: ⎣concord<br />

[num pl] ⎦ ⎥<br />

c: ⎢⎪⎨<br />

⎪⎬<br />

⎢ <strong>in</strong>dex [num pl]<br />

⎥<br />

⎢<br />

⎡<br />

⎤ ⎥<br />

⎢ pred ‘girls’<br />

⎥<br />

⎢<br />

⎢<br />

⎥ ⎥<br />

g:<br />

⎣<br />

⎣concord<br />

[num pl] ⎦ ⎥<br />

⎪⎩<br />

⎪⎭<br />

⎦<br />

<strong>in</strong>dex [num pl]<br />

Coord<strong>in</strong>ations modified by either a s<strong>in</strong>gular or a plural determ<strong>in</strong>er <strong>in</strong> which one noun is<br />

s<strong>in</strong>gular and the other is plural are disallowed. The reason is that the two nouns will have<br />

f-structures with concord and <strong>in</strong>dex [num sg] feature-values and concord and <strong>in</strong>dex<br />

[num pl] feature-values, respectively. When these coord<strong>in</strong>ated nouns are modified by a<br />

determ<strong>in</strong>er that requires concord [num sg], the sg value is <strong>in</strong>compatible with the value<br />

of the pl conjunct and when they are modified by a determ<strong>in</strong>er that requires concord<br />

[num pl], the pl value is <strong>in</strong>compatible with the value of the sg conjunct, result<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong><br />

ungrammaticallity:<br />

(90) *This boy and girls<br />

DET<br />

this<br />

NP<br />

N<br />

boy<br />

N<br />

Conj<br />

and<br />

N<br />

girls<br />

⎡<br />

⎤<br />

spec ‘this’<br />

⎢<br />

⎥<br />

⎢<strong>in</strong>dex<br />

[num sg]<br />

⎥<br />

⎢<br />

⎢⎧<br />

⎡<br />

⎤ ⎫ ⎥<br />

⎢ pred ‘boy’ ⎥<br />

⎢ ⎢<br />

⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢ b: ⎣concord<br />

[num sg] ⎦ ⎥<br />

c: ⎢⎪⎨<br />

⎪⎬ ⎥<br />

⎢ <strong>in</strong>dex [num sg] ⎥<br />

⎢<br />

⎡<br />

⎤ ⎥<br />

⎢ pred ‘girls’<br />

⎥<br />

⎢<br />

⎢<br />

⎥ ⎥<br />

g:<br />

⎣<br />

⎣concord<br />

[num pl/sg] ⎦ ⎥<br />

⎪⎩<br />

⎪⎭<br />

⎦<br />

<strong>in</strong>dex [num pl]


3.3 Theoretical Approaches to Head-Modifier <strong>Agreement</strong> 58<br />

(K<strong>in</strong>g and Dalrymple, 2004, 81)<br />

K<strong>in</strong>g and Dalrymple (2004) consider both the concord and <strong>in</strong>dex features as central<br />

to NP-<strong>in</strong>ternal agreement. Some languages may require both features or just one of the<br />

two features to participate <strong>in</strong> agreement. Based on this assumption, they propose four<br />

possible agreement patterns <strong>in</strong> NP-<strong>in</strong>ternal agreement <strong>in</strong> terms of the number feature: an<br />

unrestricted one, the concord/<strong>in</strong>dex one, the concord one and the <strong>in</strong>dex one.<br />

The first one is the least restricted accord<strong>in</strong>g to which the determ<strong>in</strong>er places no constra<strong>in</strong>ts<br />

on the number of the nouns it comb<strong>in</strong>es with. A characteristic example <strong>in</strong> English<br />

is the def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er the, which can comb<strong>in</strong>e with coord<strong>in</strong>ated s<strong>in</strong>gular nouns, plural<br />

nouns and even mixed number plural and s<strong>in</strong>gular nouns. The lexical entry of the<br />

determ<strong>in</strong>er is as follows:<br />

(91) the: (↑spec) = ‘the’<br />

All the examples below are well formed:<br />

(92) a. the dog and cat<br />

b. the dogs and cats<br />

c. the dogs and cat<br />

The second system is the most restrictive and <strong>in</strong>volves both <strong>in</strong>dex agreement and redundantly<br />

concord agreement <strong>in</strong> the s<strong>in</strong>gular, and concord agreement and redundantly<br />

<strong>in</strong>dex agreement <strong>in</strong> the plural. The s<strong>in</strong>gular determ<strong>in</strong>er can modify s<strong>in</strong>gular nouns or s<strong>in</strong>gular<br />

coord<strong>in</strong>ated nouns, which refer to the same <strong>in</strong>dividual, as <strong>in</strong> my friend and colleague.<br />

Determ<strong>in</strong>er shar<strong>in</strong>g is not allowed with conjo<strong>in</strong>ed s<strong>in</strong>gular nouns referr<strong>in</strong>g to more than<br />

one <strong>in</strong>dividual or with coord<strong>in</strong>ated structures consist<strong>in</strong>g of mixed number conjuncts. The<br />

plural determ<strong>in</strong>er can modify plural nouns and coord<strong>in</strong>ated plural nouns, but it cannot<br />

modify coord<strong>in</strong>ations where one of the conjuncts is s<strong>in</strong>gular (K<strong>in</strong>g and Dalrymple, 2004,<br />

85). For this system, the follow<strong>in</strong>g annotations are proposed:<br />

(93) concord and <strong>in</strong>dex systems:<br />

a. S<strong>in</strong>gular determ<strong>in</strong>er<br />

(↑concord num) = sg<br />

(↑<strong>in</strong>dex num) = sg<br />

b. Plural determ<strong>in</strong>er<br />

(↑concord num) = pl<br />

(↑<strong>in</strong>dex num) = pl<br />

(K<strong>in</strong>g and Dalrymple, 2004, 85)<br />

Accord<strong>in</strong>g to K<strong>in</strong>g and Dalrymple (2004), languages fall<strong>in</strong>g with<strong>in</strong> such a system are<br />

Brazilian Portuguese and German. In Brazilian Portuguese, the s<strong>in</strong>gular determ<strong>in</strong>er o ‘the’<br />

can modify a s<strong>in</strong>gular noun, as <strong>in</strong> (94), and coord<strong>in</strong>ated s<strong>in</strong>gular nouns referr<strong>in</strong>g to the<br />

same <strong>in</strong>dividual (jo<strong>in</strong>t read<strong>in</strong>g), as <strong>in</strong> (95), but not nouns with different referents, as <strong>in</strong><br />

(96):<br />

(94) o<br />

the.m.sg<br />

‘The dog’<br />

cachorro<br />

dog.m.sg


3.3 Theoretical Approaches to Head-Modifier <strong>Agreement</strong> 59<br />

(95) o<br />

the.m.sg<br />

presidente<br />

president.m.sg<br />

e<br />

and<br />

‘The president and director of Air France’<br />

(96) *o<br />

the.m.sg<br />

cachorro<br />

dog.m.sg<br />

e<br />

and<br />

‘The dog and cat’<br />

(K<strong>in</strong>g and Dalrymple, 2004, 91)<br />

gato<br />

cat.m.sg<br />

The lexical entry of the determ<strong>in</strong>er o is as follows:<br />

(97) o: (↑spec) = ‘the’<br />

(↑concord num) = sg<br />

(↑<strong>in</strong>dex num) = sg<br />

(K<strong>in</strong>g and Dalrymple, 2004, 92)<br />

diretor<br />

director.m.sg<br />

da<br />

of<br />

Air France<br />

Air France<br />

S<strong>in</strong>ce the def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er specifies a sg value for the <strong>in</strong>dex num feature, a coord<strong>in</strong>ate<br />

phrase with pl value <strong>in</strong> its <strong>in</strong>dex num feature, as the one <strong>in</strong> (96), would conflict the<br />

requirement of the determ<strong>in</strong>er and would result <strong>in</strong> an ungrammatical phrase.<br />

The third system <strong>in</strong>volves concord features only. A s<strong>in</strong>gular determ<strong>in</strong>er can modify<br />

s<strong>in</strong>gular nouns and coord<strong>in</strong>ated structures with s<strong>in</strong>gular conjuncts. A plural determ<strong>in</strong>er<br />

can modify a plural noun and coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrases with plural nouns. Determ<strong>in</strong>er shar<strong>in</strong>g<br />

is disallowed with mixed number coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns (K<strong>in</strong>g and Dalrymple, 2004, 86). The<br />

annotations for this system are as follows:<br />

(98) concord systems:<br />

a. S<strong>in</strong>gular determ<strong>in</strong>er<br />

(↑concord num) = sg<br />

b. Plural determ<strong>in</strong>er<br />

(↑concord num) = pl<br />

(K<strong>in</strong>g and Dalrymple, 2004, 86)<br />

Apart form the English demonstrative determ<strong>in</strong>er this/these and that/ those, a language<br />

with such a system is F<strong>in</strong>nish and H<strong>in</strong>di/Urdu. The follow<strong>in</strong>g examples, are from<br />

F<strong>in</strong>nish (K<strong>in</strong>g and Dalrymple, 2004, 89). In (99), the determ<strong>in</strong>er tämä ‘this’ can modify a<br />

s<strong>in</strong>gular noun. In (100), it modifies two s<strong>in</strong>gular conjuncts but not a s<strong>in</strong>gular and a plural<br />

conjunct, as <strong>in</strong> (101):<br />

(99) tämä<br />

this.sg<br />

‘this cat’<br />

(100) tämä<br />

this.sg<br />

(101) *tämä<br />

this.sg<br />

kissa<br />

cat.sg<br />

kissa<br />

cat.sg<br />

‘this cat and dog’<br />

kissa<br />

cat.sg<br />

‘this cat and dog’<br />

ja<br />

and<br />

ja<br />

and<br />

koira<br />

dog.sg<br />

koirat<br />

dog.pl<br />

The lexical entry of the determ<strong>in</strong>er tämä ‘this’ is as follows:


3.3 Theoretical Approaches to Head-Modifier <strong>Agreement</strong> 60<br />

(102) tämä: (↑spec) = ‘tämä’<br />

(↑concord num) = sg<br />

(K<strong>in</strong>g and Dalrymple, 2004, 89)<br />

The sg value <strong>in</strong> the concord num feature distributes to each conjunct and requires the<br />

same sg value <strong>in</strong> the concord num feature of the <strong>in</strong>dividual conjuncts; otherwise the<br />

result is ungrammatical.<br />

The last system they propose is the <strong>in</strong>dex only which is not very common crossl<strong>in</strong>guistically<br />

and places constra<strong>in</strong>ts on the <strong>in</strong>dex feature only. This system allows a plural<br />

determ<strong>in</strong>er to modify either a plural noun or coord<strong>in</strong>ated s<strong>in</strong>gular nouns referr<strong>in</strong>g to different<br />

<strong>in</strong>dividuals, while a s<strong>in</strong>gular determ<strong>in</strong>er can modify a s<strong>in</strong>gular noun or s<strong>in</strong>gular<br />

coord<strong>in</strong>ated nouns only if they refer to the same <strong>in</strong>dividual (K<strong>in</strong>g and Dalrymple, 2004,<br />

86). Such a language is Russian. The annotations for the <strong>in</strong>dex system are as follows:<br />

(103) <strong>in</strong>dex system<br />

a. S<strong>in</strong>gular determ<strong>in</strong>er<br />

(↑<strong>in</strong>dex num) = sg<br />

b. Plural determ<strong>in</strong>er<br />

(↑<strong>in</strong>dex num) = pl<br />

(K<strong>in</strong>g and Dalrymple, 2004, 86)<br />

In example (104), the s<strong>in</strong>gular determ<strong>in</strong>er étot/éta/éto ‘this’ modifies a nonconjo<strong>in</strong>ed<br />

s<strong>in</strong>gular noun, while <strong>in</strong> (105) it modifies a coord<strong>in</strong>ate noun phrase with s<strong>in</strong>gular conjuncts,<br />

referr<strong>in</strong>g to the same <strong>in</strong>dividual:<br />

(104) éta<br />

this.f.sg<br />

‘this woman’<br />

(105) étot<br />

this.m.sg<br />

ˇzenˇsč<strong>in</strong>a<br />

woman.f.sg<br />

drug<br />

friend.m.sg<br />

i<br />

and<br />

‘this friend and colleague’<br />

(K<strong>in</strong>g and Dalrymple, 2004, 95)<br />

kollega<br />

colleague.m.sg<br />

The plural determ<strong>in</strong>er éti modifies a plural noun, as <strong>in</strong> (106), coord<strong>in</strong>ated plural nouns,<br />

as <strong>in</strong> (107), and s<strong>in</strong>gular coord<strong>in</strong>ated nouns, which refer to more than one <strong>in</strong>dividual, as <strong>in</strong><br />

(108):<br />

(106) éti<br />

these.pl<br />

‘these men’<br />

(107) éti<br />

these.pl<br />

muˇzčny<br />

man.m.pl<br />

muˇzč<strong>in</strong>y<br />

man.m.pl<br />

‘these men and women’<br />

(108) éti<br />

these.pl<br />

muˇzc<strong>in</strong>a<br />

man.m.sg<br />

i<br />

and<br />

i<br />

and<br />

‘this man and woman’<br />

(K<strong>in</strong>g and Dalrymple, 2004, 95)<br />

ˇzenˇsč<strong>in</strong>y<br />

woman.f.pl<br />

ˇzenˇsč<strong>in</strong>a<br />

woman.f.sg<br />

The lexical entry for this type of determ<strong>in</strong>ers is presented below:


3.3 Theoretical Approaches to Head-Modifier <strong>Agreement</strong> 61<br />

(109) éti: (↑spec) = ‘éti’<br />

(↑<strong>in</strong>dex num) = pl<br />

(K<strong>in</strong>g and Dalrymple, 2004, 96)<br />

Such a determ<strong>in</strong>er constra<strong>in</strong>s the <strong>in</strong>dex value of the coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase as a whole and<br />

therefore it can be used even with s<strong>in</strong>gular nouns.<br />

To conclude, K<strong>in</strong>g and Dalrymple (2004) <strong>in</strong>troduce three different agreement systems<br />

based on the dist<strong>in</strong>ction between <strong>in</strong>dex and concord agreement features and capture a<br />

wide range of data concern<strong>in</strong>g number NP-<strong>in</strong>ternal agreement <strong>in</strong> coord<strong>in</strong>ated constructions.<br />

3.3.3 Dalrymple and Nikolaeva’s theory of natural and accidental coord<strong>in</strong>ation<br />

Another theory concern<strong>in</strong>g NP-<strong>in</strong>ternal agreement is that proposed by Dalrymple and<br />

Nikolaeva (2006). They exam<strong>in</strong>e agreement phenomena <strong>in</strong> adjectives modify<strong>in</strong>g coord<strong>in</strong>ated<br />

nouns <strong>in</strong> F<strong>in</strong>nish and propose a special f-structure for coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns that are<br />

cases of “natural” coord<strong>in</strong>ation, which is different from the f-structure of nouns <strong>in</strong> “accidental”<br />

coord<strong>in</strong>ation. The dist<strong>in</strong>ction between “natural” and “accidental” noun phrase<br />

coord<strong>in</strong>ation turns out to be an important factor <strong>in</strong> expla<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g some agreement patterns<br />

<strong>in</strong> MG.<br />

Adjectives <strong>in</strong> F<strong>in</strong>nish agree with the nouns they modify <strong>in</strong> number. S<strong>in</strong>gular nouns are<br />

modified by s<strong>in</strong>gular adjectives and plural nouns by plural adjectives, as <strong>in</strong> the follow<strong>in</strong>g<br />

examples:<br />

(110) ilo<strong>in</strong>en<br />

happy.sg<br />

poika<br />

boy.sg<br />

‘the/a happy boy’<br />

(111) iloiset<br />

happy.pl<br />

pojat<br />

boy.pl<br />

‘the happy boys’<br />

(Dalrymple and Nikolaeva, 2006, 824)<br />

In coord<strong>in</strong>ated constructions, plural nouns are modified by a plural adjective, which<br />

scopes over both conjuncts, as seen <strong>in</strong> example (112). There are cases, however, when<br />

s<strong>in</strong>gular nouns are modified by a plural adjective, as <strong>in</strong> (113):<br />

(112) nuoria<br />

young.part.pl<br />

‘young [girls and boys]’<br />

(113) Iloiset<br />

happy.pl<br />

kädessä<br />

hand.<strong>in</strong>es<br />

mies<br />

man.sg<br />

tyttöjä<br />

girls.part.pl<br />

ja<br />

and<br />

ja<br />

and<br />

poika<br />

boy.sg<br />

poikia<br />

boys.part.pl<br />

lähtivät<br />

left.3.pl<br />

‘The happy [man and boy] left together hand <strong>in</strong> hand’<br />

(Dalrymple and Nikolaeva, 2006, 825)<br />

yhdessä<br />

together<br />

käsi<br />

hand<br />

In other cases, a plural adjective with s<strong>in</strong>gular nouns is considered ungrammatical, as<br />

<strong>in</strong> (114):<br />

(114) *Han<br />

he<br />

osti<br />

bought.3.sg<br />

uudet<br />

new.acc.pl<br />

‘He bought a new [house and car]’<br />

(Dalrymple and Nikolaeva, 2006, 829)<br />

talon<br />

house.acc<br />

ja<br />

and<br />

auton<br />

car.acc


3.3 Theoretical Approaches to Head-Modifier <strong>Agreement</strong> 62<br />

Dalrymple and Nikolaeva (2006) show that the acceptance of a plural adjective <strong>in</strong><br />

s<strong>in</strong>gular coord<strong>in</strong>ated nouns is attributed to a semantic dist<strong>in</strong>ction between “natural” and<br />

“accidental” coord<strong>in</strong>ation (Haspelmath, 2004a; Wälchli, 2005). Thus, plural adjectives<br />

with s<strong>in</strong>gular conjuncts are allowed only with naturally coord<strong>in</strong>ated nouns while accidental<br />

coord<strong>in</strong>ation disallows them.<br />

In general, accidental coord<strong>in</strong>ation refers to “coord<strong>in</strong>ation of items that are not expected<br />

to co-occur and which do not have a close semantic relation”(Wälchli, 2005, 5), and natural<br />

coord<strong>in</strong>ation refers to “a semantic relation <strong>in</strong> which two entities are closely related <strong>in</strong><br />

mean<strong>in</strong>g and form a conceptual unit” (Haspelmath, 2004a; Wälchli, 2005). There are<br />

cases, however, when natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation is marked syntactically.<br />

Dalrymple and Nikolaeva (2006) show that, apart from the semantic relation between<br />

the two conjuncts <strong>in</strong> a natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation construction, there are various syntactic characteristics<br />

that are found <strong>in</strong> these structures. Natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation constructions often<br />

<strong>in</strong>clude special coord<strong>in</strong>ation markers. For example, Ud<strong>in</strong>e, which is a ‘with’ language<br />

(Stassen, 2000) 11 , uses the postposition zuÒe ‘with’ <strong>in</strong> accidental coord<strong>in</strong>ation but the<br />

postposition mule ‘with’ to denote natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation. This is illustrated below:<br />

(115) Natural Coord<strong>in</strong>ation<br />

bi<br />

I<br />

mamasa<br />

wife<br />

‘I and my wife’<br />

mule/*zuÒe<br />

with/with<br />

(116) Accidental Coord<strong>in</strong>ation<br />

bi<br />

I<br />

Sergej<br />

Sergej<br />

zuÒe/*mule<br />

with/with<br />

‘I and Sergej’<br />

(Stassen (2000), cited <strong>in</strong> Dalrymple and Nikolaeva (2006, 831))<br />

Also, natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation often <strong>in</strong>volves what Dalrymple and Nikolaeva (2006) refer<br />

to as phonological reduction of the coord<strong>in</strong>ation markers. They present an example from<br />

the Oceanic languages claim<strong>in</strong>g that <strong>in</strong> Lenakel the conjunction m is often found <strong>in</strong> natural<br />

coord<strong>in</strong>ation, which is a phonologically reduced form of m@ne found <strong>in</strong> accidental<br />

coord<strong>in</strong>ation (Moyse-Faurie and Lynch, 2004).<br />

Another characteristic of natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation is “tight coord<strong>in</strong>ation” (Dalrymple and<br />

Nikolaeva, 2006, 831). This means that features such as def<strong>in</strong>iteness, case, possession,<br />

number are marked only once or not at all <strong>in</strong> the coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase. Thus, <strong>in</strong> German<br />

some cases of natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation lack determ<strong>in</strong>ers completely, a pattern which is generally<br />

disallowed under accidental coord<strong>in</strong>ation. This is presented below:<br />

(117) Natural Coord<strong>in</strong>ation<br />

Sonne<br />

sun<br />

und<br />

and<br />

Mond<br />

moon<br />

‘the sun and the moon’<br />

(118) Accidental Coord<strong>in</strong>ation<br />

der<br />

the<br />

Mond<br />

moon<br />

und<br />

and<br />

e<strong>in</strong><br />

a<br />

Sechser<br />

sixpence<br />

11 Accord<strong>in</strong>g to Stassen (2000), a ‘with’ language is one <strong>in</strong> which nom<strong>in</strong>al coord<strong>in</strong>ation is expressed by an<br />

adpositional phrase with the postposition ‘with’ so that the conjuncts have a different syntactic status.


3.3 Theoretical Approaches to Head-Modifier <strong>Agreement</strong> 63<br />

‘the moon and sixpence’<br />

(Lambrecht (1984), cited <strong>in</strong> Dalrymple and Nikolaeva (2006, 831))<br />

F<strong>in</strong>ally, <strong>in</strong> Eastern Armenian natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>in</strong>volves a s<strong>in</strong>gle <strong>in</strong>flectional mark<strong>in</strong>g,<br />

seen below:<br />

(119) Natural Coord<strong>in</strong>ation<br />

ał<br />

salt<br />

u<br />

and<br />

hac’-d<br />

bread.2sg<br />

‘your salt and bread’<br />

(120) Accidental Coord<strong>in</strong>ation<br />

dproc’-i-s<br />

school.dat.1sg<br />

ev<br />

and<br />

usuc’ič’-ner-i-s<br />

teacherpl.dat.1sg<br />

‘for my school and my teacher’<br />

(M<strong>in</strong>assian (1980), cited <strong>in</strong> Dalrymple and Nikolaeva (2006, 831))<br />

Although the above characteristics are associated with cases of natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>in</strong><br />

the above languages, they can occasionally occur <strong>in</strong> cases of accidental coord<strong>in</strong>ation too 12 .<br />

Dalrymple and Nikolaeva (2006) po<strong>in</strong>t out that not all languages use the above syntactic<br />

characteristics <strong>in</strong> natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation. There are languages that may not use any of these<br />

forms but still display cases of natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation, rely<strong>in</strong>g only on the relation between<br />

the nouns. Dalrymple and Nikolaeva (2006) assume the existence of two types of relations<br />

between the conjuncts with<strong>in</strong> a natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation construction. The first is an <strong>in</strong>tr<strong>in</strong>sic<br />

relation, such as that of ‘father and mother’ or ‘cup and saucer’ and may <strong>in</strong>volve cases of<br />

reduced syntax, or frozen word order (Benor and Levy, 2006). The second type of relation<br />

is “contextually specified” and depends on <strong>in</strong>formation derived from previous discourse or<br />

general world knowledge (Lambrecht, 1984; Heycock and Zamparelli, 2003; Dalrymple and<br />

Nikolaeva, 2006). For example, Wälchli (2005) presents the two nouns Igor-t Natashǎt<br />

‘Igor and Natasha’. He argues that these nouns are not <strong>in</strong>tr<strong>in</strong>sically but contextually<br />

related s<strong>in</strong>ce they are perceived as partners and they are coord<strong>in</strong>ated without the need for<br />

the conjunction di ‘and’, which is found <strong>in</strong> accidental coord<strong>in</strong>ation 13 . This second type is<br />

also found <strong>in</strong> natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation structures of the F<strong>in</strong>nish language.<br />

Dalrymple and Nikolaeva (2006) argue that <strong>in</strong> F<strong>in</strong>nish the semantic dist<strong>in</strong>ction beween<br />

natural and accidental coord<strong>in</strong>ation is expressed by different syntactic constructions without<br />

the need “for different coord<strong>in</strong>ation strategies or different morphosyntactic mark<strong>in</strong>gs<br />

on conjuncts”(825) <strong>in</strong> these constructions. In fact, F<strong>in</strong>nish natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation structures<br />

resemble those of accidental coord<strong>in</strong>ation but their difference lies <strong>in</strong> the syntactic features<br />

that are associated with each structure. The features of natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation have similarities<br />

with the features of plural nouns. Natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation admits a plural adjective and<br />

two s<strong>in</strong>gular nouns while the nouns are usually contextually related.<br />

In F<strong>in</strong>nish, two specific structures admit a plural adjective with s<strong>in</strong>gular nouns and<br />

exhibit natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation. The first one is when a plural “symmetric” adjective, such<br />

as similar, match<strong>in</strong>g or compatible modifies two s<strong>in</strong>gular coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns. The follow<strong>in</strong>g<br />

example is acceptable accord<strong>in</strong>g to the speakers:<br />

12 Some exceptions are discussed <strong>in</strong> Dalrymple and Nikolaeva (2006).<br />

13 More arguments to support the same view are presented <strong>in</strong> Dalrymple and Nikolaeva (2006, 832),<br />

Lambrecht (1984, 794) and Heycock and Zamparelli (2003, 445).


3.3 Theoretical Approaches to Head-Modifier <strong>Agreement</strong> 64<br />

(121) On<br />

is<br />

ja<br />

and<br />

vaikeaa<br />

difficult<br />

teatteri<br />

theatre<br />

suunnitella<br />

design<br />

yhteensopivat/*yhteensopiva<br />

compatible.pl/*compatible.sg<br />

‘It is difficult to design a compatible [university and theatre]’<br />

(Dalrymple and Nikolaeva, 2006, 826)<br />

yliopisto<br />

university<br />

The second structure is when the nouns have any of the semantic features of def<strong>in</strong>iteness,<br />

animacy and humaness and are <strong>in</strong> subject position. In the follow<strong>in</strong>g example, repeated from<br />

above, the conjuncts are both considered as def<strong>in</strong>ite, human and occur <strong>in</strong> subject position:<br />

(122) Iloiset<br />

happy.pl<br />

mies<br />

man.sg<br />

ja<br />

and<br />

poika<br />

boy.sg<br />

lähtivät<br />

left.3.pl<br />

‘The happy [man and boy] left together hand <strong>in</strong> hand’<br />

(Dalrymple and Nikolaeva, 2006, 825)<br />

yhdessä<br />

together<br />

käsikädessä<br />

hand-hand.<strong>in</strong>es<br />

Also, <strong>in</strong> the example below, although the two nouns are def<strong>in</strong>ite <strong>in</strong>animate nouns, a<br />

plural adjective is still allowed accord<strong>in</strong>g to Dalrymple and Nikolaeva (2006), s<strong>in</strong>ce the two<br />

conjuncts refer to unique entities, they are subjects, and resemble somehow proper names:<br />

(123) ...wieniläiset<br />

...Viennese.pl<br />

kuoro<br />

choir<br />

ja<br />

and<br />

orkesteri<br />

orchestra<br />

hyökyvät<br />

surge.3.pl<br />

‘...Viennese choir and orchestra surge as they should’<br />

(Dalrymple and Nikolaeva, 2006, 828)<br />

ku<strong>in</strong><br />

as<br />

pitää<br />

needed<br />

F<strong>in</strong>ally, Dalrymple and Nikolaeva (2006) argue that when conjuncts are <strong>in</strong>def<strong>in</strong>ite then<br />

plural modification is less frequent and most of the times totally ungrammatical. Thus,<br />

the follow<strong>in</strong>g example cannot be accepted by native speakers of F<strong>in</strong>nish:<br />

(124) *Tässä<br />

this.<strong>in</strong>es<br />

kaupungissa<br />

city.<strong>in</strong>es<br />

on<br />

is<br />

hyvät<br />

good.pl<br />

yliopisto<br />

university<br />

‘There is a good university and theatre <strong>in</strong> this city’<br />

(Dalrymple and Nikolaeva, 2006, 829)<br />

ja<br />

and<br />

teatteri<br />

theatre<br />

To summarise the f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>gs of Dalrymple and Nikolaeva (2006), all speakers accept a<br />

plural adjective with two s<strong>in</strong>gular conjuncts when the modifier is symmetric and when the<br />

conjuncts are either def<strong>in</strong>ite, animate, or human and <strong>in</strong> subject position. Speakers reject<br />

<strong>in</strong> general <strong>in</strong>def<strong>in</strong>ites and non-subject def<strong>in</strong>ites with plural adjectives 14 . The acceptance<br />

of a plural adjective with two s<strong>in</strong>gular nouns is attributed to the phenomenon of natural<br />

coord<strong>in</strong>ation. Thus, F<strong>in</strong>nish is one of those languages that allows both natural and accidental<br />

coord<strong>in</strong>ation. Accidental coord<strong>in</strong>ation is found with any k<strong>in</strong>d of nouns without<br />

any restrictions either syntactic or semantic <strong>in</strong> the coord<strong>in</strong>ate structure but modification of<br />

s<strong>in</strong>gular conjuncts by a plural adjective is disallowed. Natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation, on the other<br />

hand, <strong>in</strong>volves contextually related nouns which occur <strong>in</strong> s<strong>in</strong>gular number and are modified<br />

by a plural adjective, without us<strong>in</strong>g any specific syntactic constructions, such as tight<br />

coord<strong>in</strong>ation or <strong>in</strong>flectional mark<strong>in</strong>g.<br />

Dalrymple and Nikolaeva (2006) capture natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation phenomena with<strong>in</strong> LFG<br />

and assume the concord and <strong>in</strong>dex feature dist<strong>in</strong>ction. Accidentally coord<strong>in</strong>ated s<strong>in</strong>gular<br />

nouns talo ja auto ‘house and car’ have plural <strong>in</strong>dex s<strong>in</strong>ce the coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase is plural as<br />

a whole, and s<strong>in</strong>gular concord because each conjunct is s<strong>in</strong>gular. The example is shown<br />

below:<br />

14 A detailed analysis and presentation of the F<strong>in</strong>nish data and some exceptions are found <strong>in</strong> Dalrymple<br />

and Nikolaeva (2006, 825-30).


3.3 Theoretical Approaches to Head-Modifier <strong>Agreement</strong> 65<br />

(125) Accidental coord<strong>in</strong>ation<br />

*vanhat/*vanha<br />

old.pl/old.sg<br />

‘old [house and car]’<br />

AdjP<br />

Adj<br />

*vanhat/*vanha<br />

NP<br />

N’<br />

talo<br />

house<br />

N<br />

talo<br />

N’<br />

N<br />

Conj<br />

ja<br />

ja<br />

and<br />

N<br />

auto<br />

(Dalrymple and Nikolaeva, 2006, 840)<br />

auto<br />

car<br />

⎡<br />

⎤<br />

adj [pred ‘old’]<br />

⎢<br />

⎥<br />

⎢<strong>in</strong>dex<br />

[num pl] ⎥<br />

⎢<br />

⎢⎧<br />

⎡<br />

⎤⎫<br />

⎥<br />

⎢ pred ‘house’ ⎥<br />

⎢ ⎢<br />

⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢ ⎣concord<br />

[num sg] ⎦ ⎥<br />

⎢⎪⎨<br />

⎪⎬ ⎥<br />

⎢ <strong>in</strong>dex [num sg] ⎥<br />

⎢<br />

⎡<br />

⎤ ⎥<br />

⎢ pred ‘car’<br />

⎥<br />

⎢<br />

⎢<br />

⎥ ⎥<br />

⎣<br />

⎣concord<br />

[num sg] ⎦ ⎥<br />

⎪⎩<br />

⎪⎭<br />

⎦<br />

<strong>in</strong>dex [num sg]<br />

F<strong>in</strong>nish adjectives constra<strong>in</strong> both the concord and <strong>in</strong>dex values of the conjuncts,<br />

mean<strong>in</strong>g that a s<strong>in</strong>gular adjective requires s<strong>in</strong>gular concord and <strong>in</strong>dex and a plural<br />

adjective requires plural concord and <strong>in</strong>dex. The example above cannot be modified<br />

by either a s<strong>in</strong>gular or a plural adjective. A s<strong>in</strong>gular adjective is disallowed with s<strong>in</strong>gular<br />

conjuncts s<strong>in</strong>ce the phrase ‘house and car’ has plural <strong>in</strong>dex, contradict<strong>in</strong>g the s<strong>in</strong>gular<br />

<strong>in</strong>dex required by the adjective, lead<strong>in</strong>g to agreement feature mismatch. Similarly, a<br />

plural adjective is also disallowed s<strong>in</strong>ce ‘house and car’ has s<strong>in</strong>gular concord but the<br />

adjective requires plural concord and aga<strong>in</strong> the agreement features do not match.<br />

In F<strong>in</strong>nish plural adjectives are allowed with s<strong>in</strong>gular conjuncts <strong>in</strong> natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation.<br />

In order to capture this structure, Dalrymple and Nikolaeva (2006) assume that F<strong>in</strong>nish<br />

specifies a different functional structure, which resembles somehow that of a simple plural<br />

noun. This structure is illustrated below:<br />

(126) Natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation<br />

uskolliset<br />

faithful.pl<br />

aviomies<br />

husband<br />

‘faithful [husband and wife]’<br />

AdjP<br />

Adj<br />

uskolliset<br />

NP<br />

N’<br />

N<br />

aviomies<br />

N’<br />

N<br />

Conj<br />

ja<br />

ja<br />

and<br />

N<br />

vaimo<br />

vaimo<br />

wife<br />

(Dalrymple and Nikolaeva, 2006, 842)<br />

⎡<br />

⎤<br />

pred ‘conj’<br />

⎢<br />

⎥<br />

⎢concord<br />

[num pl] ⎥<br />

⎢<br />

⎥<br />

⎢<br />

⎢<strong>in</strong>dex<br />

[num pl] ⎥<br />

⎢ ⎡<br />

⎤ ⎥<br />

⎢ pred ‘husband’ ⎥<br />

⎢ ⎢<br />

⎥⎥<br />

⎢conj1<br />

⎣concord<br />

[num sg] ⎦ ⎥<br />

⎢ <strong>in</strong>dex [num sg]<br />

⎥<br />

⎢<br />

⎡<br />

⎤⎥<br />

⎢ pred ‘wife’<br />

⎥<br />

⎢<br />

⎢<br />

⎥<br />

conj2<br />

⎢<br />

⎣concord<br />

[num sg] ⎦ ⎥<br />

⎢<br />

⎣ <strong>in</strong>dex [num sg] ⎥<br />

⎦<br />

adj [pred ‘faithful’]<br />

The plural adjective is allowed <strong>in</strong> natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation s<strong>in</strong>ce both concord and <strong>in</strong>dex<br />

have plural values which match the agreement requirements of a plural adjective.


3.4 Discuss<strong>in</strong>g the theoretical approaches to agreement 66<br />

The two characteristics concern<strong>in</strong>g the f-structure of natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation are that these<br />

structures have a specific number of conjuncts, usually no more than two whereas accidental<br />

coord<strong>in</strong>ation can hold more than two conjuncts. Secondly, natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation f-structure<br />

has plural concord and plural <strong>in</strong>dex which makes it similar to the f-structure of a simple<br />

plural noun (Dalrymple and Nikolaeva, 2006).<br />

On the whole, the above analysis captures natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>in</strong> F<strong>in</strong>nish. Dalrymple<br />

and Nikolaeva (2006) claim that the architecture of LFG itself is important s<strong>in</strong>ce it allows<br />

the separation of c-structure and f-structure, facilitat<strong>in</strong>g the analysis of F<strong>in</strong>nish by us<strong>in</strong>g<br />

the same c-structure <strong>in</strong> both natural and accidental coord<strong>in</strong>ation but a different f-structure.<br />

Thus, morphology and phrase structure is identical <strong>in</strong> both types of coord<strong>in</strong>ation while the<br />

only dist<strong>in</strong>ction is made at the f-structure level. Dalrymple and Nikolaeva (2006, 843-<br />

47) present data from other languages, such as Tundra Nenets, Russian and Bahd<strong>in</strong>ani<br />

Kurdish, which are captured by the same approach.<br />

An important aspect of the current theory is that it deals with cases of natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation<br />

and not only with accidental coord<strong>in</strong>ation as most theories do. Also, it proposes<br />

a different f-structure for natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation patterns that captures a great number of<br />

data <strong>in</strong> various languages. The ma<strong>in</strong> drawback is that there are languages like MG whose<br />

natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation patterns cannot be captured by the same f-structure. We will discuss<br />

this issue, however, <strong>in</strong> more detail <strong>in</strong> the next section.<br />

3.4 Discuss<strong>in</strong>g the theoretical approaches to agreement<br />

The above section presented a summary of the theoretical approaches to predicate-argument<br />

and head-modifier agreement, which discuss the gender and number features <strong>in</strong> noun<br />

phrase coord<strong>in</strong>ate structures. In this last section, we will discuss and compare the aforementioned<br />

theories.<br />

In theoretical approaches to predicate-argument agreement, it is generally acknowledged<br />

that gender resolution should comb<strong>in</strong>e syntactic and semantic pr<strong>in</strong>ciples. Most of the<br />

analyses <strong>in</strong>corporate <strong>in</strong>to their account a proposal along these l<strong>in</strong>es apart from Dalrymple<br />

and Kaplan (2000). The latter present a syntactically motivated gender agreement theory<br />

but they admit that there are patterns <strong>in</strong> a number of languages that should be exam<strong>in</strong>ed<br />

from a semantic perspective s<strong>in</strong>ce they show semantic resolution. The follow<strong>in</strong>g example<br />

<strong>in</strong> French is repeated from above:<br />

(127) La personnne avec la barbe<br />

[The person with the beard].fem<br />

idiots/?*idiotes<br />

idiots.masc/?*fem<br />

‘The person with the beard and Marie are idiots’<br />

(Wechsler, 2009)<br />

et<br />

and<br />

Marie<br />

Marie.fem<br />

sont<br />

are<br />

Secondly, all of the theories capture the specific patterns they present <strong>in</strong> the languages<br />

they discuss, even though their actual analysis differs significantly. Dalrymple and Kaplan<br />

(2000) use set-union and Wechsler and Zlatić (2003) use set-<strong>in</strong>tersection. Badecker (2008)<br />

captures gender agreement <strong>in</strong> a large group of languages, rang<strong>in</strong>g from Romance, Slavic,<br />

Icelandic to MG, adopt<strong>in</strong>g a limited number of OT constra<strong>in</strong>ts whose rank<strong>in</strong>g depends<br />

on the language analysed. F<strong>in</strong>ally, Sadler (2006), who also uses set-union, accommodates<br />

mixed gender agreement <strong>in</strong> Rumanian assum<strong>in</strong>g two different PS rules for <strong>in</strong>animate and<br />

animate nouns.<br />

In all these theories, however, there are some important issues that should be discussed.<br />

Corbett (1991) uses a descriptive approach which <strong>in</strong>cludes a series of rules at a theoretical<br />

level. His approach is purely descriptive and does not assume a specific theoretical


3.4 Discuss<strong>in</strong>g the theoretical approaches to agreement 67<br />

framework while he does not attempt to expla<strong>in</strong> the l<strong>in</strong>guistic motivation for some agreement<br />

patterns and not for others; <strong>in</strong>stead he merely records them. Also, the rules that he<br />

proposes for the gender feature are language specific and not crossl<strong>in</strong>guistic as would be<br />

desirable. The ma<strong>in</strong> advantage, though, is that he emphasises the dist<strong>in</strong>ction between two<br />

separate pr<strong>in</strong>ciples <strong>in</strong> gender resolution, the semantic and the syntactic, and this idea was<br />

widely adopted by his followers. Only later on <strong>in</strong> Corbett and Fraser (1993), he proposes<br />

an analysis for animacy <strong>in</strong> Russian nom<strong>in</strong>al <strong>in</strong>flections with<strong>in</strong> Network Morphology.<br />

Dalrymple and Kaplan (2000) present a rather powerful theory comb<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g set-valued<br />

features by set-union. The first problem occurs <strong>in</strong> Slovene where they need to impose an<br />

additional constra<strong>in</strong>t <strong>in</strong> the conjunction conj, an equation f ∈(↑gender), s<strong>in</strong>ce the sets<br />

used for the three genders and their union cannot capture the pattern where two neuter<br />

nouns resolve to mascul<strong>in</strong>e. Thus, the {f} set needs to participate also <strong>in</strong> the union process.<br />

Therefore, their approach cannot cover all cases of coord<strong>in</strong>ation but needs additional<br />

constra<strong>in</strong>ts for any extra or unexpected syntactic pattern that occurs <strong>in</strong> a language. Two<br />

other problems discussed by Wechsler and Zlatić (2003) are those of “undergeneration”<br />

and “overgeneration”. The former possibly refers to those cases of semantic resolution<br />

that Dalrymple and Kaplan (2000) do not capture at all, while the latter refers to some<br />

patterns that are unattested and are still generated by a set-based approach with the union<br />

operation. Wechsler and Zlatić (2003) claim that the follow<strong>in</strong>g unattested pattern can be<br />

generated by the current proposal:<br />

(128) *Unattested (m, f, nt)<br />

a. FEM & FEM = FEM<br />

b. Elsewhere NEUT (NEUT & NEUT; MASC & MASC; and mixes)<br />

(Wechsler and Zlatić, 2003, p.186)<br />

Their presupposition, however, is not expla<strong>in</strong>ed any further <strong>in</strong> terms of the marker sets that<br />

should be assigned to the different genders and s<strong>in</strong>ce there are not any such known gender<br />

systems so far, we cannot consider their argument valid. F<strong>in</strong>ally, V<strong>in</strong>cent and Börjars<br />

(2000) discuss a few more problems concern<strong>in</strong>g the analysis proposed by Dalrymple and<br />

Kaplan (2000), which are worth mentioned here. Regard<strong>in</strong>g first person, they argue that<br />

the different use of features across languages implies that personal identity is conceived<br />

differently while the primitives s and h do not ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong> their semantic content, mean<strong>in</strong>g<br />

that h cannot mean hearer if it appears <strong>in</strong> the set of the pronoun I. Also, V<strong>in</strong>cent and<br />

Börjars (2000) argue that English requires two types of first person based on semantic<br />

and pragmatic evidence. In a control context, you and I differs from John and I <strong>in</strong> the<br />

value of pro 15 . Regard<strong>in</strong>g gender, they argue that feature assignment <strong>in</strong> each language<br />

is determ<strong>in</strong>ed by the union operation, which is compatible with LFG’s characteristic of<br />

construct<strong>in</strong>g the smallest f-structure. An alternative operation could be set <strong>in</strong>tersection,<br />

which constructs the largest set. However, Mary Dalrymple po<strong>in</strong>ts out that <strong>in</strong>tersection is<br />

at odds with the basic architecture of LFG and the fact that the smallest set is consistent<br />

with a given f-description. This means that the <strong>in</strong>tersection of identical gender conjuncts,<br />

such as {m} and {m}, would result <strong>in</strong> {} s<strong>in</strong>ce the empty set is the smallest set which is<br />

15 V<strong>in</strong>cent and Börjars (2000, 7) argue that this is obvious <strong>in</strong> anaphoric control where split antecedence<br />

is allowed and the vale of PRO can refer to two dist<strong>in</strong>ct locations <strong>in</strong> the clause’s f-structure. Consider the<br />

follow<strong>in</strong>g examples:<br />

(1) a. Do you remember that I discussed with you offer<strong>in</strong>g ourselves as candidates for the election?<br />

b. Do you remember that I discussed with John offer<strong>in</strong>g ourselves as candidates for the election?<br />

In (1a), the subject of offer<strong>in</strong>g and antecedent of ourselves is the comb<strong>in</strong>ation of you and I, which is first<br />

person <strong>in</strong>clusive. In (1b), the subject of offer<strong>in</strong>g and antecedent of ourselves is either you and I, John and<br />

I or John, you and I.


3.4 Discuss<strong>in</strong>g the theoretical approaches to agreement 68<br />

a subset of both {m} and {m} (V<strong>in</strong>cent and Börjars, 2000, 16). This is an undesirable<br />

result. F<strong>in</strong>ally, V<strong>in</strong>cent and Börjars (2000) argue that the different set valued features<br />

adopted <strong>in</strong> each language are aga<strong>in</strong>st a crossl<strong>in</strong>guistic analysis. Although we agree with<br />

V<strong>in</strong>cent and Borjars’ arguments concern<strong>in</strong>g person, we strongly disagree with their claims<br />

on gender. The theories showed that gender varies greatly and even <strong>in</strong> a s<strong>in</strong>gle language<br />

different resolution results are drawn depend<strong>in</strong>g on the type of the conjuncts (i.e. animate<br />

or <strong>in</strong>animate). Thus, a crossl<strong>in</strong>gustic theory would be difficult to assume s<strong>in</strong>ce there will<br />

still be languages that would not be accounted for.<br />

The theory developed by Wechsler and Zlatić (2003) has a major advantage. It acknowledges<br />

the dist<strong>in</strong>ction of different resolution rules <strong>in</strong> animate and <strong>in</strong>animate nouns<br />

and provides an account based on that. However, the ma<strong>in</strong> problem is that they do not<br />

analyse languages where the resolution patterns are not common <strong>in</strong> animate and <strong>in</strong>animate<br />

nouns. They make a brief reference to Rumanian as one of those languages, claim<strong>in</strong>g that<br />

“the resolution mechanism for <strong>in</strong>animates is <strong>in</strong>dependent of the determ<strong>in</strong>ants of animate<br />

gender agreement”(Wechsler and Zlatić, 2003, 189) but they do not proceed to any analysis<br />

with<strong>in</strong> the context of their own theory. Moreover, their theory seems to be problematic<br />

for the Slovene extra pattern. The requirement for a masc resolved gender cannot be generated<br />

from the <strong>in</strong>tersection of two neuter conjuncts s<strong>in</strong>ce the <strong>in</strong>tersection of two neuter<br />

nouns will result <strong>in</strong> neuter and not mascul<strong>in</strong>e. Thus, we argue that the problem of undergeneration<br />

is also detected <strong>in</strong> this theory. F<strong>in</strong>ally, as Badecker (2008) claims, Wechsler<br />

and Zlatić (2003) do not provide any account for cases where number <strong>in</strong>teracts with gender<br />

<strong>in</strong> order to provide the required gender agreement form, which is a major drawback<br />

for languages like MG and Serbian/Croatian. This is <strong>in</strong>deed true and the same criticism<br />

could apply to Dalrymple and Kaplan’s (2000) approach, who do not take <strong>in</strong>to account the<br />

<strong>in</strong>teraction of other <strong>in</strong>dex features apart from the gender when they provide an account<br />

for the latter.<br />

Sadler (2006) proposes an account for languages with different resolution patterns <strong>in</strong><br />

animate and <strong>in</strong>animate nouns. The previous theories have addressed the issue but they<br />

have not proposed any concrete analysis, leav<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> the marg<strong>in</strong> a number of languages<br />

with this characteristic, such as Lat<strong>in</strong>, Polish, MG and many others. Also, Sadler (2006)<br />

developes a concise proposal s<strong>in</strong>ce <strong>in</strong> a simple rule us<strong>in</strong>g disjunction she captures both<br />

semantic and syntactic resolution found <strong>in</strong> animate and <strong>in</strong>animate Rumanian nouns, accord<strong>in</strong>gly.<br />

A second advantage is that she comb<strong>in</strong>es a crossl<strong>in</strong>guistic analysis, the set-union<br />

rule, which accounts for the expected patterns of resolution <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>animate nouns found <strong>in</strong><br />

most languages, with a language specific one, the semantic rule of resolution proposed for<br />

Rumanian animate nouns. In fact, this approach could capture resolution <strong>in</strong> coord<strong>in</strong>ate<br />

nouns <strong>in</strong> a number of languages s<strong>in</strong>ce the only modifications required would be to adapt<br />

the equations <strong>in</strong> the semantic rule of resolution for the animate nouns, accord<strong>in</strong>g to the<br />

language analysed, and reta<strong>in</strong> the standard rule of coord<strong>in</strong>ation for the <strong>in</strong>animate nouns.<br />

Her attempt carries the same <strong>in</strong>tuitions as that of Wechsler and Zlatić (2003). The only<br />

disadvantage is that she assumes an extra f-structure feature, semgend, to account for<br />

the semantic patterns <strong>in</strong> Rumanian. It might be desirable to replace this feature by a<br />

constra<strong>in</strong>t which refers to the semantic structure on <strong>in</strong>terpretation. We will show, though,<br />

that this extra feature is required <strong>in</strong> the analysis of the MG animate nouns and possibly<br />

<strong>in</strong> other similar languages, mean<strong>in</strong>g that it is not really a redundant feature.<br />

Badecker (2008) proposes an analysis of gender resolution with<strong>in</strong> the Optimality Theory.<br />

He assumes a number of similar constra<strong>in</strong>ts which differ across languages only <strong>in</strong><br />

their rank<strong>in</strong>g and captures a great range of gender agreement patterns mak<strong>in</strong>g the proposal<br />

economic and crossl<strong>in</strong>guistic. He also takes <strong>in</strong>to consideration the different gender<br />

resolution patterns of animate and <strong>in</strong>animate nouns for some languages and other factors,<br />

such as the number factor <strong>in</strong> the conjuncts, which determ<strong>in</strong>e gender resolution <strong>in</strong> some


3.4 Discuss<strong>in</strong>g the theoretical approaches to agreement 69<br />

cases. A problem is that for any language with different features such as Tamil with the<br />

rational/non-rational dist<strong>in</strong>ction, new constra<strong>in</strong>ts need to be assumed which may result<br />

<strong>in</strong> a different group of constra<strong>in</strong>ts depend<strong>in</strong>g on the language. This would underm<strong>in</strong>e the<br />

economy and conciseness of the exist<strong>in</strong>g theory. Also, agreement is modelled by competition<br />

imply<strong>in</strong>g that many different forms may be possible but only one is the optimal. In<br />

some languages, however, like MG we will see that there are other possible agreement patterns<br />

and therefore agreement is not the result of only one correct form. This fact makes<br />

the theory rather undesirable.<br />

The head-modifier theories focus on number NP <strong>in</strong>ternal agreement. Kathol (1999) was<br />

the first to postulate a dist<strong>in</strong>ction between the two features and these were later adopted<br />

<strong>in</strong> LFG. Also, Wechsler and Zlatić (2000) <strong>in</strong>troduce two additional types of <strong>in</strong>formation<br />

declension and semantics, and capture further agreement mismatches, apart from those<br />

found between concord and <strong>in</strong>dex.<br />

The proposal developed by K<strong>in</strong>g and Dalrymple (2004) is powerful s<strong>in</strong>ce it extends<br />

to determ<strong>in</strong>ers and adjectives as modifiers and it is crossl<strong>in</strong>guistic, account<strong>in</strong>g for various<br />

phenomena <strong>in</strong> NP-<strong>in</strong>ternal agreement <strong>in</strong> a wide range of languages. MG, however,<br />

presents some restrictions that extend beyond the area of syntax. In particular, the <strong>in</strong>dex/concord<br />

system <strong>in</strong> the s<strong>in</strong>gular accounts for noun phrases such as my friend and<br />

colleague is where <strong>in</strong>dex has a sg value and the coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase is semantically <strong>in</strong>terpreted<br />

as referr<strong>in</strong>g to one and the same person only (jo<strong>in</strong>t read<strong>in</strong>g). In the plural, the<br />

same system accounts for noun phrases such as my friends and colleagues are where <strong>in</strong>dex<br />

has a pl value and the coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase is semantically <strong>in</strong>terpreted as denot<strong>in</strong>g the<br />

same referents (jo<strong>in</strong>t) or different referents (split) s<strong>in</strong>ce the resolved number is plural due<br />

to the plural number <strong>in</strong> both conjuncts. Although the <strong>in</strong>dex/concord system captures<br />

syntactically the MG data, the semantic dist<strong>in</strong>ction <strong>in</strong> plural number is problematic s<strong>in</strong>ce<br />

MG occurs only with the jo<strong>in</strong>t read<strong>in</strong>g when a shared determ<strong>in</strong>er scopes over coord<strong>in</strong>ate<br />

nouns either <strong>in</strong> the s<strong>in</strong>gular or <strong>in</strong> the plural number. The split read<strong>in</strong>g is allowed only <strong>in</strong><br />

specific constructions, as we shall see. Thus, MG plural coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns behave different<br />

when compared to the languages discussed by K<strong>in</strong>g and Dalrymple (2004).<br />

F<strong>in</strong>ally, the theory proposed by Dalrymple and Nikolaeva (2006) is important s<strong>in</strong>ce it is<br />

the only one that discusses the impact of “natural” and “accidental” noun phrase coord<strong>in</strong>ation<br />

<strong>in</strong> agreement <strong>in</strong> constra<strong>in</strong>t-based frameworks, such as LFG and HPSG. The difference<br />

between the two types of coord<strong>in</strong>ation and the agreement requirements are captured by<br />

two different f-structures. The natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation f-structure does not represent its conjuncts<br />

us<strong>in</strong>g a set and it postulates plural concord and plural <strong>in</strong>dex requirements. The<br />

ma<strong>in</strong> drawback, however, is whether the f-structure proposed is found crossl<strong>in</strong>guistically.<br />

We will show that at least <strong>in</strong> MG the exact same f-structure <strong>in</strong>troduced by Dalrymple and<br />

Nikolaeva (2006) cannot capture the MG cases of natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation and the agreement<br />

requirements. Languages with similar behaviour may exist and the present f-structure<br />

would require modifications depend<strong>in</strong>g on the characteristics of each language.<br />

Despite the problems discussed <strong>in</strong> the various approaches, each of these theories contributes<br />

greatly and sheds light on the agreement patterns detected <strong>in</strong> the various languages.<br />

The follow<strong>in</strong>g chapters will focus on the analysis of the MG data and we will show that the<br />

ma<strong>in</strong> concepts of some of these theories are crucial for the explanation of some agreement<br />

patterns <strong>in</strong> MG.


Chapter 4<br />

Predicate Argument <strong>Agreement</strong> <strong>in</strong><br />

<strong>Modern</strong> <strong>Greek</strong><br />

4.1 Introduction<br />

<strong>Modern</strong> <strong>Greek</strong> predicate-argument agreement <strong>in</strong> coord<strong>in</strong>ate noun phrases <strong>in</strong>volves the features<br />

gender, number and person. In <strong>Modern</strong> <strong>Greek</strong>, number and person resolution is<br />

straightforward and resembles the patterns found <strong>in</strong> other languages. person resolution,<br />

follows the precedence hierarchy (see Corbett (1991); Siewierska (2004)) where the first<br />

person takes precedence over the second, and the second takes precedence over the third.<br />

In number resolution, coord<strong>in</strong>ation of s<strong>in</strong>gular elements requires plural number (outside<br />

of the jo<strong>in</strong>t read<strong>in</strong>g) <strong>in</strong> the outcome. gender resolution, however, is much more complex<br />

due to the variation it shows and the difficulty for the current theories <strong>in</strong> account<strong>in</strong>g for it.<br />

In this chapter, we will exam<strong>in</strong>e gender agreement <strong>in</strong> predicate argument relations<br />

<strong>in</strong> <strong>Modern</strong> <strong>Greek</strong>. The first section presents the MG data. The next section shows that<br />

MG coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns follow different resolution pr<strong>in</strong>ciples; animate nouns follow semantic<br />

resolution and <strong>in</strong>animate nouns follow syntactic resolution. Our analysis will attempt<br />

to capture both. However, a number of unexpected resolution patterns occur which are<br />

evidence for a third resolution pr<strong>in</strong>ciple. This is referentially derived and depends on<br />

the assumption of a Contextually Introduced element <strong>in</strong> the discourse. The phenomenon<br />

of referential agreement has not been discussed so far <strong>in</strong> the present literature, such as<br />

descriptive grammars or traditional handbooks (Clairis et al. (2004), Holton et al. (1997),<br />

Triantaphyllidis (1994), Triantaphyllidis (2005), Joseph and Philippaki-Warburton (1987)<br />

and Mackridge (1985)). The ma<strong>in</strong> characteristics of referential agreement and an analysis<br />

of the data are presented <strong>in</strong> the last two sections.<br />

4.2 The <strong>Modern</strong> <strong>Greek</strong> Data<br />

MG animate and <strong>in</strong>animate nouns belong to one of the three gender classes: mascul<strong>in</strong>e,<br />

fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e and neuter. In animate nouns, mascul<strong>in</strong>e refers to males whereas fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e refers<br />

to females. Some exceptions <strong>in</strong> MG are nouns whose grammatical gender contradicts<br />

the natural/semantic one, such as agori ‘boy’ and koritsi ‘girl’, which are grammatically<br />

neuter but have a mascul<strong>in</strong>e and a fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e natural/semantic gender, respectively, the<br />

noun anthropos ‘human be<strong>in</strong>g/person’, which is grammatically mascul<strong>in</strong>e but refers to both<br />

males and females, and nouns, which are grammatically neuter but lack a natural/semantic<br />

gender, such as pedi ‘child’, moro ‘baby’ and atomo ‘person’ (see Holton et al. (1997) and<br />

Mackridge (1985)). Inanimate nouns belong to any of the three gender classes, assigned<br />

on formal grounds depend<strong>in</strong>g on the declension class of the noun.<br />

Non-coord<strong>in</strong>ate noun phrases control their agreement “target” (Corbett, 1991), forc<strong>in</strong>g


4.2 The <strong>Modern</strong> <strong>Greek</strong> Data 71<br />

the latter to show grammatical agreement with the former. Thus, the predicative adjective<br />

or participle will agree <strong>in</strong> gender and number 1 with the noun it is predicated of 2 :<br />

(1) O Kostas<br />

the.masc.sg Kostas.masc.sg<br />

‘Kostas is handsome’<br />

(constructed)<br />

(2) I j<strong>in</strong>ekes<br />

the.fem.pl women.fem.pl<br />

‘The women are happy’<br />

(constructed)<br />

<strong>in</strong>e<br />

is.sg<br />

<strong>in</strong>e<br />

are.pl<br />

omorf-os<br />

handsome.masc.sg<br />

xarumen-es<br />

happy.fem.pl<br />

Even nouns whose grammatical gender contradicts their natural control predicative<br />

adjectives and force them to show grammatical gender agreement. For example, the noun<br />

to koritsi ‘the girl’ allows only a neuter predicative adjective despite the fact that it has a<br />

female referent:<br />

(3) To koritsi<br />

the.neut.sg girl.neut.sg<br />

‘The girl is beautiful’<br />

(constructed)<br />

<strong>in</strong>e<br />

is.sg<br />

omorf-o<br />

beautiful.neut.sg<br />

Semantic agreement is also possible once a pronoun occurs subsequently <strong>in</strong> the sentence<br />

and refers back to the “controller” (Corbett, 1991) noun, follow<strong>in</strong>g Corbett’s <strong>Agreement</strong><br />

Hierarchy 3 .<br />

MG <strong>in</strong>animate concrete and abstract nouns 4 also show grammatical agreement. Thus,<br />

the predicative adjective or participle shows agreement with the noun it is predicated of:<br />

(4) O kipos<br />

the.masc.sg garden.masc.sg<br />

‘The garden is big’<br />

(constructed)<br />

(5) I dimokratia<br />

the.fem.sg democracy.fem.sg<br />

‘Democracy is necessary’<br />

(constructed)<br />

<strong>in</strong>e<br />

is.sg<br />

<strong>in</strong>e<br />

is.sg<br />

megal-os<br />

big.masc.sg<br />

aparetit-i<br />

necessary.fem.sg<br />

Gender resolution <strong>in</strong> MG coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns is <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g due to the existence of different<br />

resolution patterns. We impose a dist<strong>in</strong>ction of two major group patterns, the expected<br />

and unexpected ones.<br />

1 As previously mentioned, number is not important for the time be<strong>in</strong>g and therefore we will not discuss<br />

it further.<br />

2 The follow<strong>in</strong>g examples were collected from <strong>Greek</strong> newspapers and various books. I will use the abbre-<br />

viation G.N. to stand for <strong>Greek</strong> Newspaper and G.M. to stand for <strong>Greek</strong> Magaz<strong>in</strong>e followed by the specific<br />

newspaper or magaz<strong>in</strong>e from which I have collected each example. The examples that were constructed are<br />

<strong>in</strong>dicated with the word ‘constructed’.<br />

3 The agreement hierarchy is repeated below:<br />

(1) <strong>Agreement</strong> Hierarchy<br />

attributive < predicate < relative pronoun < personal pronoun<br />

Corbett (1979) argues that “as we move rightwards along the hierarchy, the likelihood of semantic agree-<br />

ment will <strong>in</strong>crease monotonically”(210).<br />

4 We subdivide <strong>in</strong>animate nouns <strong>in</strong>to concrete and abstract s<strong>in</strong>ce this turns out to be relevant <strong>in</strong> the<br />

sections that follow.


4.2 The <strong>Modern</strong> <strong>Greek</strong> Data 72<br />

The expected patterns refer to cases of either grammatical (syntactic) or semantic resolution.<br />

We assume that syntactic resolution occurs <strong>in</strong> MG <strong>in</strong>animate nouns and semantic<br />

resolution occurs <strong>in</strong> MG animate nouns, follow<strong>in</strong>g Corbett (1991) and Wechsler and Zlatić<br />

(2003). Thus, the expected cases of MG are those that show either syntactic or semantic<br />

gender resolution, accord<strong>in</strong>g to animacy dist<strong>in</strong>ctions.<br />

Alongside the expected gender patterns observed, an analysis of data collection by<br />

questionnaire showed the existence of a number of unexpected agreement patterns <strong>in</strong> both<br />

groups of nouns. We will argue that these unexpected patterns fall with<strong>in</strong> a third pr<strong>in</strong>ciple,<br />

which is motivated by “reference transfer” (Nunberg, 1977, 1995, 2005; Pollard and Sag,<br />

1994). Therefore, we postulate three pr<strong>in</strong>ciples of resolution <strong>in</strong> MG, the syntactic, the<br />

semantic and the referential one. As already mentioned above, this last pr<strong>in</strong>ciple has not<br />

been discussed anywhere <strong>in</strong> the literature on MG.<br />

Another unusual aspect of coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns <strong>in</strong> MG is that <strong>in</strong> some cases only the number<br />

of the conjuncts, whether s<strong>in</strong>gular or plural, plays a role <strong>in</strong> determ<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g the preference<br />

for a resolution pattern. Thus, <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>animate nouns a specific resolved gender occurs with<br />

higher frequency <strong>in</strong> s<strong>in</strong>gular conjuncts than <strong>in</strong> plural conjuncts or <strong>in</strong> plural conjuncts than<br />

<strong>in</strong> s<strong>in</strong>gular conjuncts.<br />

The current discussion will start with the presentation of the patterns found <strong>in</strong> animate<br />

coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns and will proceed to <strong>in</strong>animate coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns while we will analyse coord<strong>in</strong>ate<br />

phrases with s<strong>in</strong>gular conjuncts separately from plural conjuncts. The method<br />

used to draw the results of the gender values <strong>in</strong> both groups of nouns is based on the responses<br />

of 26 <strong>Greek</strong> native speakers who answered certa<strong>in</strong> questionnaires. The participants<br />

are all university graduates from North and South Greece. The questionnaires appeared<br />

<strong>in</strong> two different forms, <strong>in</strong> the form of ‘multiple choice’ and <strong>in</strong> the form of ‘fill <strong>in</strong> the gaps’.<br />

The answers of the consultants were based on acceptability judgements and, even though<br />

the number of participants is relatively small, their answers are <strong>in</strong> accordance to my own<br />

orig<strong>in</strong>al <strong>in</strong>tuition about the various gender resolution patterns. F<strong>in</strong>ally, we need to note<br />

that the examples that will follow are all part of the questionnaires that were issued to the<br />

consultants 5 .<br />

4.2.1 Resolution <strong>in</strong> MG Animate <strong>Noun</strong>s<br />

In animate coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns, the ma<strong>in</strong> f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>gs showed that coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrases with s<strong>in</strong>gular<br />

and plural conjuncts display the same expected patterns. Additional unexpected<br />

patterns are found <strong>in</strong> the case of plural conjuncts.<br />

The expected resolved patterns of animate s<strong>in</strong>gular coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns are discussed first.<br />

The responses of the 26 consultants are presented <strong>in</strong> the follow<strong>in</strong>g table 6 :<br />

Table 4.1: Animate S<strong>in</strong>gular Coord<strong>in</strong>ate <strong>Noun</strong>s<br />

Consultant Number: 26<br />

NP1 NP2 Resolution NP1 NP2 Resolution<br />

Mpl Fpl Npl Mpl Fpl Npl<br />

Msg Msg 26 - - Msg Fsg 26 - -<br />

Fsg Fsg - 26 - Msg Nm/f /0sg 26 - -<br />

Nsg Nsg - - 26 Fsg Nm/0sg 26 - -<br />

- - Fsg Nf sg 5 21 -<br />

5 For more details on the methodology and rationale on construct<strong>in</strong>g the questionnaires and on the<br />

responses of the consultants see Appendix A.<br />

6 The order of the conjuncts <strong>in</strong> the table does not correspond to the order of the conjuncts <strong>in</strong> the sentences<br />

that appear <strong>in</strong> the questionnaires. The questionnaires <strong>in</strong>cluded sentences with conjuncts <strong>in</strong> the reverse order<br />

too. We simply present the comb<strong>in</strong>ation of conjuncts <strong>in</strong> the table and show the responses.


4.2 The <strong>Modern</strong> <strong>Greek</strong> Data 73<br />

When a mascul<strong>in</strong>e animate noun is coord<strong>in</strong>ated with either a mascul<strong>in</strong>e, a fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e<br />

or a neuter 7 the resolution form is always mascul<strong>in</strong>e, as <strong>in</strong> examples (6), (7) and (8),<br />

respectively:<br />

(6) O Petros ke o<br />

Janis<br />

the.masc.sg Peter.masc.sg and the.masc.sg John.masc.sg<br />

<strong>in</strong>e kurasmen-i. I dulia tus exi eksantlisi.<br />

are.pl tired.masc.pl. The job them.masc.pl has exhausted<br />

‘Peter and John are tired. The work has exhausted them’<br />

(constructed)<br />

(7) O pateras ke i mitera<br />

the.masc.sg father.masc.sg and the.fem.sg mother.fem.sg<br />

<strong>in</strong>e kurasmen-i. I zoi tus <strong>in</strong>e diskoli<br />

are.pl tired.masc.pl. The life their.masc.pl is difficult<br />

ke apetitiki<br />

and demand<strong>in</strong>g<br />

‘The father and mother are tired. Their life is difficult and demand<strong>in</strong>g’<br />

(constructed)<br />

(8) O Kostas ke<br />

the.masc.sg Kostas.masc.sg and<br />

<strong>in</strong>e poli exipn-i<br />

are.pl very clever.masc.pl<br />

‘Kostas and his child are very clever’<br />

(constructed)<br />

to<br />

the.neut.sg<br />

pedi<br />

child.neut.sg<br />

The responses of the consultants showed that a mascul<strong>in</strong>e gender is chosen by all (26 out<br />

of 26) consultants when a mascul<strong>in</strong>e noun cooccurs with another mascul<strong>in</strong>e conjunct, a<br />

fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e conjunct or a neuter conjunct.<br />

Otherwise, resolution is fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e if two fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e nouns are coord<strong>in</strong>ated, as <strong>in</strong> (9), and<br />

neuter if the coord<strong>in</strong>ated nouns are neuter, as <strong>in</strong> (10):<br />

(9) I Maria<br />

the.fem.sg Maria.fem.sg<br />

<strong>in</strong>e xarumen-es<br />

are.pl happy.fem.pl<br />

‘Mary and Kathr<strong>in</strong>e are happy’<br />

(constructed)<br />

ke<br />

and<br />

i<br />

the.fem.sg<br />

(10) To agori ke to<br />

the.neut.sg boy.neut.sg and the.neut.sg<br />

vriskontan kathismen-a piso<br />

were.pl seated.neut.pl back<br />

‘The boy and the girl were seated at the back’<br />

(constructed)<br />

Kater<strong>in</strong>a<br />

Kater<strong>in</strong>a.fem.sg<br />

koritsi<br />

girl.neut.sg<br />

As shown <strong>in</strong> table (4.1), all consultants (26 of 26) chose a fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e gender <strong>in</strong> example (9),<br />

and a neuter gender <strong>in</strong> example (10).<br />

7 As presented <strong>in</strong> section 1.2, the two grammatically neuter nouns agori ‘boy’ and and koritsi ‘girl’ refer<br />

to a male and a female,respectively, while the pedi ‘child’, moro ‘baby’ and atomo ‘person’ refer to either.<br />

For these nouns, we also <strong>in</strong>troduce the notation Nm/f /0. Thus, if a grammatically neuter noun refers to a<br />

male, it will be described as Nm, if it refers to a female, it will be described as Nf and if it refers to a noun<br />

without a natural/semantic gender, it will be described as N0.<br />

tu<br />

his


4.2 The <strong>Modern</strong> <strong>Greek</strong> Data 74<br />

When a grammatically mascul<strong>in</strong>e noun is coord<strong>in</strong>ated with a grammatically neuter<br />

noun, which is either a semantic neuter noun or a semantically-vacuous neuter noun 8 ,<br />

gender resolution is also mascul<strong>in</strong>e. In the follow<strong>in</strong>g examples, all consultants (26 out of<br />

26) chose a mascul<strong>in</strong>e gender irrespective of the gender denotation of the second conjunct:<br />

(11) O Kostas ke to<br />

the.masc.sg Kostas.masc.sg and the.neut.sg<br />

<strong>in</strong>e etimi ja anaxorisi<br />

are.pl ready.masc.pl to depart<br />

‘Kostas and the boy are ready to depart’<br />

(constructed)<br />

(12) O Kostas ke to<br />

the.masc.sg Kostas.masc.sg and the.neut.sg<br />

<strong>in</strong>e etimi ja anaxorisi<br />

are.pl ready.masc.pl to depart<br />

‘Kostas and the girl are ready to depart’<br />

(constructed)<br />

(13) O Kostas ke to<br />

the.masc.sg Kostas.masc.sg and the.neut.sg<br />

<strong>in</strong>e etimi ja anaxorisi<br />

are.pl ready.masc.pl to depart<br />

‘Kostas and the baby are ready to depart’<br />

(constructed)<br />

agori<br />

boy.neut.sg<br />

koritsi<br />

girl.neut.sg<br />

moro<br />

baby.neut.sg<br />

Also, when two nouns denote females then resolution is fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e; for example, when<br />

the grammatically neuter noun to koritsi ‘the girl’, which refers to a female, is coord<strong>in</strong>ated<br />

with a grammatically fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e noun 21 (out of 26) consultants chose the fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e gender.<br />

However, the questionnaires showed that 5 (out of 26) consultants chose mascul<strong>in</strong>e resolution.<br />

This is due to the fact that mascul<strong>in</strong>e is the default semantic gender <strong>in</strong> MG. Thus,<br />

when referents denote females, resolution is fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e and mascul<strong>in</strong>e occurs less often as a<br />

default gender form. The example that was given to the consultants is shown below:<br />

(14) I Maria ke to koritsi<br />

the.fem.sg Maria.fem.sg and the.neut.sg girl.neut.sg<br />

<strong>in</strong>e enthusiasmen-es/-i ja t<strong>in</strong> kenurja<br />

are.pl enthusiastic.fem.pl/masc.pl for the new<br />

tus<br />

zoi<br />

their.fem/masc.pl life.<br />

‘Mary and her girl are enthusiastic about their new life’<br />

(constructed)<br />

Any other case of coord<strong>in</strong>ation of a grammatically fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e noun with a grammatically<br />

neuter noun that refers to a male or with a semantically-vacuous neuter noun yields<br />

mascul<strong>in</strong>e resolution. An example is shown below:<br />

(15) I Maria<br />

the.fem.sg<br />

agori/moro<br />

Maria.fem.sg<br />

boy.neut.sg/baby.neut.sg<br />

ke<br />

and<br />

<strong>in</strong>e<br />

are.pl<br />

to<br />

the.neut.sg<br />

xarumen-i<br />

happy.masc.pl<br />

8 We will <strong>in</strong>troduce the term semantic neuter noun to refer to the two grammatically neuter nouns that<br />

have a semantic gender, to agori ‘the boy’ and to koritsi ‘the girl’, and semantically-vacuous neuter noun<br />

to refer to the neuter nouns that do not have a semantic gender, such as to pedi ‘the child’, to moro ‘the<br />

baby’ and to atomo ‘the person’.<br />

tis<br />

her


4.2 The <strong>Modern</strong> <strong>Greek</strong> Data 75<br />

‘Mary and the boy/baby are happy’<br />

(constructed)<br />

Semantically-vacuous neuter nouns, such as to pedi ‘the child’ and to moro ‘the baby’,<br />

always display syntactic agreement <strong>in</strong> noncoord<strong>in</strong>ated constructions. In coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrases,<br />

these nouns can be referentially specified, referr<strong>in</strong>g to a specific person whose gender is<br />

known, or unspecified, denot<strong>in</strong>g a person whose gender is unknown. When these nouns are<br />

unspecified for a referent, the resolution is mascul<strong>in</strong>e whether they are coord<strong>in</strong>ated with a<br />

grammatically mascul<strong>in</strong>e or a grammatically fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e noun. When they are referentially<br />

specified, however, the resolved gender depends on whether they cooccur with a male or<br />

female denot<strong>in</strong>g noun. For <strong>in</strong>stance, <strong>in</strong> example (16) when the neuter noun pedi ‘child’ has<br />

a male or a female referrent <strong>in</strong> the questionnaire all consultants (26 out of 26) choose a<br />

mascul<strong>in</strong>e gender. Thus, the grammatically mascul<strong>in</strong>e noun pateras ‘father’ is coord<strong>in</strong>ated<br />

with the grammatically neuter noun pedi ‘child’ and whether or not pedi ‘child’ has a male<br />

or female denotation the resolved gender is always mascul<strong>in</strong>e. In example (17), when the<br />

grammatically neuter noun to moro ‘baby’, which is coord<strong>in</strong>ated with a fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e noun,<br />

refers to a male or an unspecified referent, all consultants chose a mascul<strong>in</strong>e gender (26 out<br />

of 26). Therefore, resolution is mascul<strong>in</strong>e. However, when the neuter noun to moro ‘baby’<br />

has a female referent, 21 (out of 26) consultants chose a fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e gender, and therefore<br />

resolution is fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e. In this last case, mascul<strong>in</strong>e also occurs as a resolved gender but only<br />

5 (out of 26) consultants chose the mascul<strong>in</strong>e form:<br />

(16) O pateras ke to<br />

the.masc.sg father.masc.sg and the.neut.sg<br />

vrethikan dolofonimen-i<br />

were-found.pl murdered.masc.pl<br />

‘The father and child were found murdered’<br />

(G.N.: To Vima)<br />

pedi<br />

child.neut.sg<br />

(17) I Maria ke to moro tis <strong>in</strong>e<br />

the Mary.fem.sg and the baby.neut.sg her are.pl<br />

kukl-i/-es.<br />

Tus/tis<br />

vlepis ke<br />

beautiful.masc/fem.pl. Them.masc/fem.pl you-see and<br />

tus/tis<br />

thavmazeis<br />

them.masc/fem.pl you-admire<br />

‘Mary and her baby are beautiful. You see them and you admire them’<br />

(constructed)<br />

The gender resolution patterns of MG animate s<strong>in</strong>gular coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns are summarised<br />

<strong>in</strong> table (4.2) 9 :<br />

9 The presentation of the two conjuncts <strong>in</strong> the structure does not reflect the order of the conjuncts.<br />

The same conjuncts were tested <strong>in</strong> the reverse order and the results were the same. However, we do not<br />

<strong>in</strong>clude the reverse order to avoid repetition. Also, <strong>in</strong> order to show clearly the preferred resolved gender,<br />

as was chosen by the consultants, we have used the ‘greater than’(>) symbol while the pattern <strong>in</strong>side the<br />

parenthesis is a second pattern chosen by the participants and not an unexpected one.


4.2 The <strong>Modern</strong> <strong>Greek</strong> Data 76<br />

Table 4.2: <strong>Agreement</strong> with SG Animate Coord<strong>in</strong>ate <strong>Noun</strong>s<br />

S<strong>in</strong>gular Conjuncts<br />

NP NP AP NP NP AP<br />

msg msg mpl msg fsg mpl<br />

fsg fsg fpl msg nm/f /0sg mpl<br />

nsg nsg npl fsg nm/0sg mpl<br />

fsg nf sg fpl(>mpl)<br />

Animate plural coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns have the same expected resolution patterns as animate<br />

s<strong>in</strong>gular nouns. The table below presents the responses of the 26 consultants:<br />

Table 4.3: Animate Plural Coord<strong>in</strong>ate <strong>Noun</strong>s<br />

Consultant Number: 26<br />

NP1 NP2 Resolution NP1 NP2 Resolution<br />

Mpl Fpl Npl Mpl Fpl Npl<br />

Mpl Mpl 26 - - Mpl Fpl 26 - -<br />

Fpl Fpl - 26 - Mpl Nm/f /0pl 26 - -<br />

Npl Npl - - 26 Fpl Nm/0pl 19 - 12<br />

Nm/0pl Fpl 19 7<br />

Fpl Nf pl 5 18 5<br />

Nf pl Fpl 5 18 5<br />

When conjuncts have the same gender then that gender is used <strong>in</strong> resolution such as <strong>in</strong><br />

examples (18), (19) and (20), when conjuncts have different gender then mascul<strong>in</strong>e is the<br />

expected default gender, such as <strong>in</strong> examples (21) and (22). If all conjuncts denote females<br />

then fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e is the resolved gender, such as <strong>in</strong> example (23). In the examples below, all<br />

consultants (26 out of 26) chose as the resolved gender the same gender as the one found<br />

<strong>in</strong> the two conjuncts.<br />

(18) I papudes<br />

ke<br />

the.fem.pl grandfathers.fem.pl and<br />

<strong>in</strong>e agapimen-i<br />

are.pl love-each-other.fem.pl<br />

‘The grandfathers and fathers love each other’<br />

(constructed)<br />

i<br />

the.fem.pl<br />

(19) I jajades<br />

ke i<br />

the.fem.pl grandmothers.fem.pl and the.fem.pl<br />

engones<br />

<strong>in</strong>e agapimen-es<br />

grandaughters.fem.pl are.pl love-each-other.fem.pl<br />

‘The grandmothers and grandaughters love each other’<br />

(constructed)<br />

(20) Ta agoria<br />

the.neut.pl<br />

xarumen-a<br />

happy.neut.pl<br />

boys.neut.pl<br />

‘The boys and girls are happy’<br />

(constructed)<br />

ke<br />

and<br />

ta<br />

the.neut.pl<br />

paterades<br />

fathers.fem.pl<br />

koritsia<br />

girls.neut.pl<br />

<strong>in</strong>e<br />

are.pl<br />

In the follow<strong>in</strong>g examples, all consultants (26 out of 26) chose a mascul<strong>in</strong>e gender when<br />

a mascul<strong>in</strong>e noun cooccurs with a fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e or a neuter noun:


4.2 The <strong>Modern</strong> <strong>Greek</strong> Data 77<br />

(21) I<br />

antres ke<br />

the.masc.pl men.masc.pl and<br />

itan etim-i<br />

were.pl ready.masc.pl<br />

‘The men and women were ready’<br />

(constructed)<br />

(22) I<br />

babades ke<br />

the.masc.pl fathers.masc.pl and<br />

<strong>in</strong>e poli demen-i<br />

are.pl very close.masc.pl<br />

‘The fathers and boys are very close’<br />

(constructed)<br />

i<br />

the.fem.pl<br />

ta<br />

the.neut.pl<br />

j<strong>in</strong>ekes<br />

women.fem.pl<br />

agoria<br />

boys.neut.pl<br />

In the follow<strong>in</strong>g example, the majority of the consultants (18 out of 26) chose a fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e<br />

gender as the resolved value and only 5 (out of 26) consultants chose the mascul<strong>in</strong>e gender:<br />

(23) I mamades ke<br />

the.fem.pl mothers.fem.pl and<br />

<strong>in</strong>e agapimen-es/-i<br />

are.pl love-each-other.fem/masc.pl<br />

‘The mothers and girls love each other’<br />

(constructed)<br />

ta<br />

the.neut.pl<br />

koritsia<br />

girls.neut.pl<br />

As opposed to animate s<strong>in</strong>gular coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns, which do not present any unexpected<br />

patterns, animate plural coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns yield two unexpected cases. The first one is when<br />

the coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase consists of a fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e plural and a neuter plural noun, which denotes<br />

a mascul<strong>in</strong>e referent or an unspecified referent, as shown below:<br />

(24) I jajades<br />

ke ta<br />

the.fem.pl grandmothers.fem.pl and the.neut.pl<br />

engonia<br />

<strong>in</strong>e xarumen-i/-a<br />

grandchldren.neut.pl are.pl happy.masc/neut.pl<br />

‘The grandmothers and grandchildren are happy’<br />

(constructed)<br />

The expected resolved gender is mascul<strong>in</strong>e plural but a high number of consultants<br />

(12 out of 26) chose only the neuter gender or the neuter gender alongside the mascul<strong>in</strong>e<br />

one, as the value of the predicative adjective. It could be claimed that neuter gender is a<br />

case of closest conjunct agreement s<strong>in</strong>ce the predicative adjective seems to agree with<br />

the conjunct closest to it (see Corbett (1991), Sadler (1999), Moosally (1999), Sadler<br />

(2003), Villavicencio et al. (2005) for more details). In order to test the possibility of<br />

whether the gender chosen is a case of CCA, we <strong>in</strong>cluded <strong>in</strong> the questionnaires the same<br />

patterns <strong>in</strong> reverse order, as shown <strong>in</strong> example (25). When the conjuncts are reversed as<br />

<strong>in</strong> [nm/0pl & fpl], the results showed that overall 19 (out of 26) consultants chose the<br />

mascul<strong>in</strong>e gender and 7 (out of the 26) participants chose the neuter gender. These 7 (out<br />

of 26) consultants were the same people who chose neuter resolution when the conjucts<br />

displayed the order [fpl & nm/0pl]. Therefore, when the conjuncts have the order [fpl &<br />

nm/0pl] 5 consultants (out of 26) choose the neuter gender as a result of closest conjunct<br />

agreement s<strong>in</strong>ce they chose only mascul<strong>in</strong>e when the conjucts displayed the order [nm/0pl<br />

& fpl] whereas 7 participants chose consistently the neuter gender as a result of resolution<br />

irrespective of the order of the conjuncts. This additional pattern is not a case of CCA<br />

but it is an extra agreement gender value.


4.2 The <strong>Modern</strong> <strong>Greek</strong> Data 78<br />

(25) Ta pedia<br />

ke<br />

the.neut.pl children.neut.pl and<br />

<strong>in</strong>e xarumen-i/-a<br />

are.pl happy.masc/neut.pl<br />

‘The children and mothers are happy’<br />

(constructed)<br />

i<br />

the.fem.pl<br />

mamades<br />

mothers.fem.pl<br />

Neuter gender resolution also occurs when a grammatically fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e plural noun is coord<strong>in</strong>ated<br />

with a grammatically neuter plural noun that denotes a female. The consultants<br />

were more <strong>in</strong>cl<strong>in</strong>ed to choose the fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e gender (18 out of 26) as the ma<strong>in</strong> resolved gender<br />

while neuter occured less often (5 out of 26) with the same frequency as the mascul<strong>in</strong>e<br />

(5 out of 26). In example (26), the grammatically fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e noun comb<strong>in</strong>es with a grammatically<br />

neuter noun koritsia ‘girls’, which denotes a group of females, yield<strong>in</strong>g ma<strong>in</strong>ly<br />

fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e resolution (18 out of 26 consultants). Neuter resolution occurs less often (5 out<br />

of 26) or as a second choice <strong>in</strong> these structures and it is chosen by consultants who chose<br />

neuter <strong>in</strong> all similar cases (5 out of 26). Also, some (5 out of 26) consultants chose the<br />

mascul<strong>in</strong>e gender:<br />

(26) I jajades<br />

the.fem.pl grandmothers.fem.pl<br />

<strong>in</strong>e xarumen-es/-a/-i<br />

are.pl happy.fem/neut/masc.pl<br />

‘The grandmothers and girls are happy’<br />

(constructed)<br />

ke<br />

and<br />

ta<br />

the.neut.pl<br />

koritsia<br />

girls.neut.pl<br />

The same consultants who chose neuter when the conjuncts had the word order [fpl &<br />

npl] also chose neuter as an alternative resolved gender when the conjuncts appeared <strong>in</strong><br />

the reverse order. This shows that CCA does not determ<strong>in</strong>e the gender agreement of the<br />

predicative participle. In the follow<strong>in</strong>g example, conjuncts appear <strong>in</strong> the reverse order [npl<br />

& fpl] and the agree<strong>in</strong>g gender is either fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e (18 out of 26 consultants) or neuter plural<br />

(5 out of 26 consultants) which cooccurs with mascul<strong>in</strong>e plural (5 out of 26 consultants),<br />

favour<strong>in</strong>g the fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e gender:<br />

(27) Ta koritsia ke i<br />

the.neut.pl girls.neut.pl and the.fem.pl<br />

<strong>in</strong>e poli demen-es/-a/-i<br />

are.pl very close.fem/neut/masc.pl<br />

‘The girls and mothers are very close’<br />

(constructed)<br />

mamades<br />

mothers.fem.pl<br />

The observed gender resolution patterns of plural animate coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns are presented<br />

<strong>in</strong> table (4.4) 10 below:<br />

Table 4.4: <strong>Agreement</strong> with PL Animate Coord<strong>in</strong>ate <strong>Noun</strong>s<br />

Plural Conjuncts<br />

NP1 NP2 AP NP1 NP2 AP<br />

mpl mpl mpl mpl fpl mpl<br />

fpl fpl fpl mpl nm/f /0pl mpl<br />

npl npl npl fpl nm/0pl mpl>npl<br />

fpl nf pl fpl>npl/(>mpl)<br />

10 The expected patterns are shown <strong>in</strong> normal fonts. Any unexpected patterns are presented <strong>in</strong> small bold<br />

italics <strong>in</strong> the tables that follow.


4.2 The <strong>Modern</strong> <strong>Greek</strong> Data 79<br />

To summarise, the expected patterns of animate nouns are as follows: animate s<strong>in</strong>gular<br />

and plural nouns with the same gender resolve to the gender of the conjuncts and<br />

animate mixed gender conjuncts resolve to mascul<strong>in</strong>e or else to fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e if nouns denote<br />

females. Animate s<strong>in</strong>gular nouns do not show any unexpected patterns but animate plural<br />

nouns show two unexpected patterns. When the conjucts display the comb<strong>in</strong>ations [fpl &<br />

nm/0pl] and [fpl & nf pl], the unexpected gender value <strong>in</strong> both comb<strong>in</strong>ations is neuter<br />

plural. A summary of the expected and unexpected patterns of animate s<strong>in</strong>gular and plural<br />

nouns <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g the percentage of the responses of the consultants is presented <strong>in</strong> a s<strong>in</strong>gle<br />

table below:<br />

Table 4.5: <strong>Agreement</strong> with SG/PL Animate Coord<strong>in</strong>ate <strong>Noun</strong>s<br />

S<strong>in</strong>gular Conjuncts<br />

NP1 NP2 AP percentage NP1 NP2 AP percentage<br />

msg msg mpl 100% msg fsg mpl 100%<br />

fsg fsg fpl 100% msg nm/f /0sg mpl 100%<br />

nsg nsg npl 100% fsg nm/0sg mpl 100%<br />

fsg nf sg fpl>mpl 80%>20%<br />

Plural Conjuncts<br />

NP1 NP2 AP percentage NP1 NP2 AP percentage<br />

mpl mpl mpl 100% mpl fpl mpl 100%<br />

fpl fpl fpl 100% mpl nm/f /0pl mpl 100%<br />

npl npl npl 100% fpl nm/0pl mpl>npl 73% > 27%<br />

fpl nf pl fpl>npl>mpl 69% >19%> 19%<br />

4.2.2 Resolution <strong>in</strong> MG Inanimate <strong>Noun</strong>s<br />

Inanimate s<strong>in</strong>gular and plural coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns, apart from the expected patterns, admit<br />

a number of unexpected cases too. The expected patterns of s<strong>in</strong>gular and plural <strong>in</strong>animate<br />

nouns are as follows: nouns with shared gender resolve to that shared gender whereas nouns<br />

with mixed gender resolve to neuter. Both concrete and abstract <strong>in</strong>animate coord<strong>in</strong>ate<br />

nouns show the same expected patterns. Differences, however, arise only <strong>in</strong> the unexpected<br />

patterns of the two groups of nouns. Our discussion <strong>in</strong>cludes examples with both concrete<br />

and abstract nouns, which were all <strong>in</strong>cluded <strong>in</strong> the questionnaire.<br />

The discussion beg<strong>in</strong>s with <strong>in</strong>animate s<strong>in</strong>gular nouns. The table below presents the<br />

responses of the 26 consultants:<br />

Table 4.6: Inanimate S<strong>in</strong>gular Coord<strong>in</strong>ate <strong>Noun</strong>s<br />

Consultant Number: 26<br />

NP1 NP2 Resolution NP1 NP2 Resolution<br />

Mpl Fpl Npl Mpl Fpl Npl<br />

Msg Msg 25 - 10 Msg Fsg(Concrete) 12 - 14<br />

Fsg Fsg - 24 11 Msg Fsg(Abstract) 6 6 16<br />

Nsg Nsg - - 26 Msg Nsg - - 26<br />

Fsg Nsg - - 26


4.2 The <strong>Modern</strong> <strong>Greek</strong> Data 80<br />

With <strong>in</strong>animate s<strong>in</strong>gular coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns, if both nouns are mascul<strong>in</strong>e then mascul<strong>in</strong>e<br />

is the resolved gender, as <strong>in</strong> (28), if both nouns are fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e then resolution is fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e, as<br />

<strong>in</strong> (29), and if both nouns are neuter then resolution is neuter, as <strong>in</strong> (30). In particular, 25<br />

(out of the 26) consultants chose the mascul<strong>in</strong>e gender when both connjuncts are mascul<strong>in</strong>e,<br />

24 (out of 26) consultants chose the fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e gender when both conjuncts are fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e and<br />

26 (out of 26) consultants chose the neuter when both conjuncts are neuter. Some of the<br />

examples that were given to the consultants are shown below:<br />

(28) O iroismos ke o<br />

the.masc.sg heroism.masc.sg and the.masc.sg<br />

itan kiriarx-i kata to 1821<br />

were.pl prevalent.masc.pl dur<strong>in</strong>g the 1821<br />

‘Heroism and fight<strong>in</strong>g were prevalent dur<strong>in</strong>g 1821’<br />

(G.N.:To Vima)<br />

(29) I vivliothiki ke i<br />

the.fem.sg bookcase.fem.sg and the.fem.sg<br />

<strong>in</strong>e diaforetik-es<br />

are.pl different.fem.pl<br />

‘The bookcase and d<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g table are different’<br />

(constructed)<br />

(30) To aftok<strong>in</strong>ito ke<br />

the.neut.sg<br />

akriva<br />

car.neut.sg and<br />

expensive.neut.pl<br />

‘The car and house are expensive’<br />

(constructed)<br />

to<br />

the.neut.sg<br />

agonas<br />

fight.masc.sg<br />

trapezaria<br />

d<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g-table.fem.sg<br />

spiti<br />

house.neut.sg<br />

<strong>in</strong>e<br />

are.pl<br />

In conjuncts with mixed gender values, the expected resolution gender is neuter. In<br />

example (31), 16 (out of 26) consultants chose the neuter gender. In example (32), (14 out<br />

of 26) chose the neuter, and <strong>in</strong> examples (33) and (34) all consultants (26 out of 26) chose<br />

the neuter gender:<br />

(31) O agonas ke i<br />

the.masc.sg fight.masc.sg and the.fem.sg<br />

itan kiriarx-a to 1821<br />

were prevalent.neut.pl <strong>in</strong> 1821<br />

‘The fight and self-sacrifice were prevalent <strong>in</strong> 1821’<br />

(G.N.:To Vima)<br />

(32) O kanapes<br />

the.masc.sg<br />

aspr-a<br />

white.neut.pl<br />

sofa.masc.sg<br />

‘The sofa and chair are white’<br />

(constructed)<br />

ke<br />

and<br />

i<br />

the.fem.sg<br />

(33) O erotas ke to<br />

the.masc.sg love.masc.sg and the.neut.sg<br />

<strong>in</strong>e aparetit-a sti zoi mas<br />

are.pl necessary.neut.pl <strong>in</strong>-the life our<br />

‘Love and passion are necessary <strong>in</strong> our life’<br />

(G.M.:VIMAgaz<strong>in</strong>o)<br />

aftothisia<br />

self-sacrifice.fem.sg<br />

karekla<br />

chair.fem.sg<br />

pathos<br />

passion.neut.sg<br />

<strong>in</strong>e<br />

are.pl


4.2 The <strong>Modern</strong> <strong>Greek</strong> Data 81<br />

(34) I prospathia ke to<br />

the.fem.sg effort.fem.sg and the.neut.sg<br />

<strong>in</strong>e apotelesmatik-a<br />

are.pl effective.neut.pl<br />

‘Effort and obst<strong>in</strong>acy have good results’<br />

(constructed)<br />

pisma<br />

obst<strong>in</strong>acy.neut.sg<br />

Three unexpected patterns arise <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>animate s<strong>in</strong>gular coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns. The first two<br />

concern coord<strong>in</strong>ate constructions whose conjuncts have the same gender, either mascul<strong>in</strong>e<br />

or fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e. In these cases, a significant number of consultants were <strong>in</strong>cl<strong>in</strong>ed to choose<br />

the unexpected neuter resolution <strong>in</strong> addition to the expected patterns. In particular, 10<br />

(out of 26) consultants chose the neuter as an alternative form when conjuncts were both<br />

mascul<strong>in</strong>e and 11 (out of the 26) consultants chose the neuter when conjuncts were both<br />

fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e. It is <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g that almost the same consultants chose the neuter gender <strong>in</strong> cases<br />

where both nouns have the same gender. Only one consultant chose neuter as a second<br />

choice when both conjuncts were fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e and not when both conjuncts were mascul<strong>in</strong>e.<br />

Thus, <strong>in</strong>animate s<strong>in</strong>gular mascul<strong>in</strong>e nouns can resolve to mascul<strong>in</strong>e or neuter plural, and<br />

<strong>in</strong>animate s<strong>in</strong>gular fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e nouns can resolve to fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e or neuter plural. Some examples<br />

are shown below:<br />

(35) O p<strong>in</strong>akas ke o<br />

kanapes<br />

the.masc.sg picture.masc.sg and the.masc.sg sofa.masc.sg<br />

<strong>in</strong>e megal-i/-a<br />

ja afto to domatio ke tha<br />

are.pl big.masc.pl/neut.pl for this the room and will<br />

tus/ta<br />

valo sto alo<br />

them.masc.pl/neut.pl I-put <strong>in</strong>-the other<br />

‘The picture and the sofa are big for this room and I will put them <strong>in</strong> the other<br />

one’<br />

(constructed)<br />

(36) I kuz<strong>in</strong>a<br />

the.fem.sg<br />

kathar-es/-a<br />

kitchen.fem.sg<br />

clean.fem/neut.pl<br />

‘The kitchen and toilet are clean’<br />

(constructed)<br />

(37) I eleftheria<br />

the.fem.sg<br />

taftosim-es/-a<br />

freedom.fem.sg<br />

equal.fem/neut.pl<br />

‘Freedom and faith are equal’<br />

(G.N.:To Vima)<br />

ke<br />

and<br />

ke<br />

and<br />

i<br />

the.fem.sg<br />

i<br />

the.fem.sg<br />

tualeta<br />

toilet.fem.sg<br />

pisti<br />

faith.fem.sg<br />

<strong>in</strong>e<br />

are.sg<br />

<strong>in</strong>e<br />

are.pl<br />

The next unexpected pattern occurs <strong>in</strong> s<strong>in</strong>gular mixed gender concrete conjuncts comb<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g<br />

a mascul<strong>in</strong>e and a fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e noun. The gender output <strong>in</strong> these constructions was<br />

not only neuter but also mascul<strong>in</strong>e. In fact, 14 (out of 26) consultants chose neuter as an<br />

agree<strong>in</strong>g gender whereas 12 (out of 26) consultants chose mascul<strong>in</strong>e as an agree<strong>in</strong>g gender <strong>in</strong><br />

<strong>in</strong>animate s<strong>in</strong>gular coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns. The follow<strong>in</strong>g examples illustrate two characteristic<br />

cases:<br />

(38) O kanapes ke<br />

the.masc.sg sofa.masc.sg and<br />

<strong>in</strong>e anet-a/-i<br />

are.pl comfortable.neut/masc.pl<br />

i<br />

the.fem.sg<br />

polithrona<br />

armchair.fem.sg


4.2 The <strong>Modern</strong> <strong>Greek</strong> Data 82<br />

‘The sofa and the armchair are comfortable’<br />

(constructed)<br />

(39) O dromos ke<br />

the.masc.sg street.masc.sg and<br />

<strong>in</strong>e kathar-a/-i<br />

are.pl clean.neut/masc.pl<br />

‘The street and the square are clean’<br />

(constructed)<br />

i<br />

the.fem.sg<br />

platia<br />

square.fem.sg<br />

Badecker (2008), who carried out research on MG <strong>in</strong>animate coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns, argues<br />

that the number of conjuncts is a determ<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g factor <strong>in</strong> the resolution result of <strong>in</strong>animate<br />

coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrases with a mascul<strong>in</strong>e and a fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e noun. He argues that coord<strong>in</strong>ate<br />

<strong>in</strong>animate s<strong>in</strong>gular nouns with a mascul<strong>in</strong>e and a fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e conjunct resolve to neuter but<br />

similar constructions with plural conjuncts resolve to mascul<strong>in</strong>e. Our field work certa<strong>in</strong>ly<br />

contradicts Badecker’s (2008) claim that s<strong>in</strong>gular conjuncts display only neuter resolution.<br />

The fact that almost the same number of consultants chose the mascul<strong>in</strong>e gender (12 of<br />

26) and the neuter (14 of 26) as the resolved forms is a result that cannot be ignored.<br />

An additional unexpected pattern occurs only <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>animate s<strong>in</strong>gular abstract nouns<br />

when the coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase <strong>in</strong>cludes a mascul<strong>in</strong>e and a fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e noun. These coord<strong>in</strong>ate<br />

phrases also resolve to fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e plural, apart from the neuter and mascul<strong>in</strong>e gender. In<br />

particular, 6 (out of 26) consultants chose the fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e, 16 (out of 26) chose the neuter and<br />

6 (out of 26) chose the mascul<strong>in</strong>e. Therefore, although neuter is the expected resolution<br />

gender, a number of consultants realised fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e and mascul<strong>in</strong>e on the agree<strong>in</strong>g adjective.<br />

The first th<strong>in</strong>g we need to check is whether the fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e gender is a case of CCA. The<br />

results show that the same consultants (6 out of 26) who chose fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e as the resolved<br />

gender <strong>in</strong> [msg & fsg] constructions, also chose fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e when conjuncts have the reverse<br />

order [fsg & msg]. Thus, abstract s<strong>in</strong>gular mascul<strong>in</strong>e and fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns show<br />

greater variation with regard to the agree<strong>in</strong>g gender. The examples that were used <strong>in</strong> the<br />

questionnaire are shown below:<br />

(40) O thanatos ke i<br />

the.masc.sg death.masc.sg and the.fem.sg<br />

<strong>in</strong>e simantik-a/-i/-es<br />

to 1821<br />

are.pl important.neut/masc/fem.pl <strong>in</strong> 1821<br />

‘Death and freedom are important <strong>in</strong> 1821’<br />

(G.N.:O Ependitis)<br />

(41) I eleftheria ke o<br />

the.fem.sg freedom.fem.sg and the.masc.sg<br />

itan simantik-a/-i/-es<br />

to 1821<br />

were.pl important.neut/masc/fem.pl <strong>in</strong> 1821<br />

‘Freedom and death were important <strong>in</strong> 1821’<br />

(constructed)<br />

eleftheria<br />

freedom.fem.sg<br />

thanatos<br />

death.masc.sg<br />

The gender resolution patterns of s<strong>in</strong>gular <strong>in</strong>animate nouns are presented <strong>in</strong> the follow<strong>in</strong>g<br />

table 11 :<br />

11 Table (4.7) presents <strong>in</strong> a s<strong>in</strong>gle column the concrete and abstract nouns with the same gender s<strong>in</strong>ce the<br />

results are the same <strong>in</strong> both groups of nouns. It presents separately the concrete and abstract nouns with<br />

mixed gender s<strong>in</strong>ce the results show a difference <strong>in</strong> the two groups of nouns when conjuncts are mixed <strong>in</strong><br />

gender.


4.2 The <strong>Modern</strong> <strong>Greek</strong> Data 83<br />

Table 4.7: <strong>Agreement</strong> with Inanimate SG Coord<strong>in</strong>ate <strong>Noun</strong>s<br />

S<strong>in</strong>gular Conjuncts<br />

Concrete or Abstract <strong>Noun</strong>s Concrete <strong>Noun</strong>s Abstract <strong>Noun</strong>s<br />

NP1 NP2 AP NP1 NP2 AP NP1 NP2 AP<br />

msg msg mpl>npl msg fsg npl>mpl msg fsg npl>mpl/fpl<br />

fsg fsg fpl>npl msg nsg npl msg nsg npl<br />

nsg nsg npl fsg nsg npl fsg nsg npl<br />

The expected patterns <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>animate plural coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns are the same as <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>animate<br />

s<strong>in</strong>gular coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns. The follow<strong>in</strong>g table shows the noun comb<strong>in</strong>ations and the<br />

responses of the consultants:<br />

Table 4.8: Inanimate Plural Coord<strong>in</strong>ate <strong>Noun</strong>s<br />

Consultant Number: 26<br />

NP1 NP2 Resolution NP1 NP2 Resolution<br />

Mpl Fpl Npl Mpl Fpl Npl<br />

Mpl Mpl 26 - - Mpl Fpl(Concrete) 15 - 13<br />

Fpl Fpl - 26 - Fpl Mpl(Concrete) 17 11<br />

Npl Npl - - 26 Mpl Fpl(Abstract) 15 6 13<br />

Fpl Mpl(Abstract) 16 4 11<br />

Mpl Npl - - 26<br />

Fpl Npl - - 26<br />

Coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns with the same gender resolve to that same gender, and coord<strong>in</strong>ate<br />

nouns with mixed gender resolve to neuter. In the follow<strong>in</strong>g examples, concrete and abstract<br />

nouns with the same gender are shown where all consultants (26 out of 26) chose the same<br />

gender as the gender found <strong>in</strong> the two conjuncts:<br />

(42) I<br />

p<strong>in</strong>akes ke<br />

the.masc.pl pictures.masc.pl and<br />

<strong>in</strong>e ateriast-i<br />

are.pl unsuitable.masc.pl<br />

‘The pictures and the sofas are unsuitable’<br />

(constructed)<br />

i<br />

the.masc.pl<br />

kanapedes<br />

sofas.masc.pl<br />

(43) I<br />

kavgathes ke i<br />

the.masc.pl arguments.masc.pl and the.masc.pl<br />

xorismi<br />

<strong>in</strong>e simantiki ja t<strong>in</strong> psixologia<br />

break-ups.masc.pl are.pl important.masc.pl for the psychology<br />

ton pedion<br />

of-the children<br />

‘The arguments and break-ups are important for children’s psychology’<br />

(G.M.:To Pedi)<br />

(44) I filosofies<br />

ke i thriskies<br />

the.fem.pl philosophies.fem.pl and the.fem.pl religions.fem.pl<br />

itan kathoristikes ja tus laus<br />

were.pl determ<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g.fem.pl for the people<br />

‘The philosophies and religions were determ<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g for the people’<br />

(www.<strong>in</strong>.gr)<br />

(45) Ta<br />

the.neut.pl<br />

spitia<br />

houses.neut.pl<br />

ke<br />

and<br />

ta<br />

the.neut.pl<br />

aftok<strong>in</strong>ita<br />

cars.neut.pl


4.2 The <strong>Modern</strong> <strong>Greek</strong> Data 84<br />

<strong>in</strong>e<br />

are.pl<br />

pio<br />

more<br />

akriva<br />

expensive.neut.pl<br />

apo<br />

from<br />

edo<br />

now<br />

‘The houses and cars are more expensive from now on’<br />

(constructed)<br />

ke<br />

and<br />

pera<br />

on<br />

The follow<strong>in</strong>g examples illustrate <strong>in</strong>animate plural coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns with different gender<br />

comb<strong>in</strong>ations that resolve to neuter. In the first example, which comb<strong>in</strong>es a mascul<strong>in</strong>e<br />

and a fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e noun, 13 (out of 26) consultants choose the neuter gender (15 out of 26<br />

choose the unexpected mascul<strong>in</strong>e gender). In the next example, which comb<strong>in</strong>es a mascul<strong>in</strong>e<br />

and a neuter noun, all consultants (26 out of 26) choose the neuter gender and <strong>in</strong><br />

the last two examples, which comb<strong>in</strong>e a fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e and a neuter, all consultants (26 out<br />

of 26) choose the neuter gender. The expected resolved gender is the neuter plural and<br />

consultants choose that gender <strong>in</strong> all cases:<br />

(46) I<br />

dromi ke i<br />

the.masc.pl roads.masc.pl and the.fem.pl<br />

<strong>in</strong>e jemat-a kosmo<br />

are.pl full-of.neut.pl people<br />

‘The roads and the squares are full of people’<br />

(Holton et al., 1997)<br />

(47) I<br />

dromi ke ta<br />

the.masc.pl roads.masc.pl and the.neut.pl<br />

<strong>in</strong>e jemat-a kosmo<br />

are.pl full-of.neut.pl people<br />

‘The roads and the alleys are full of people’<br />

(constructed)<br />

(48) Ta estiatoria ke i<br />

the.neut.pl restaurants.neut.pl and the.fem.pl<br />

itan jemat-a kosmo<br />

were.pl full-of.neut.pl people<br />

‘The restaurants and squares were full of people’<br />

(constructed)<br />

(49) I diamartiries ke ta<br />

the.fem.pl protests.fem.pl and the.neut.pl<br />

<strong>in</strong>e axrist-a s’afti t<strong>in</strong> periptosi<br />

are.pl useless.neut.pl <strong>in</strong> this case<br />

‘The protests and compla<strong>in</strong>ts are useless <strong>in</strong> this case’<br />

(G.M.:To Vima)<br />

platies<br />

squares.fem.pl<br />

sokakia<br />

alleys.neut.pl<br />

platies<br />

squares.fem.pl<br />

parapona<br />

compla<strong>in</strong>ts.neut.pl<br />

In <strong>in</strong>animate plural nouns, only two unexpected genders are confirmed by the questionnaires.<br />

These occur with mixed gender coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrases with a mascul<strong>in</strong>e and a fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e<br />

plural noun, which resolve to the unexpected mascul<strong>in</strong>e or fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e (less often) and not<br />

only to the expected neuter. The consultants chose both gender values, but the mascul<strong>in</strong>e<br />

gender seemed to occur more often than the neuter. In fact, <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>animate concrete plural<br />

nouns, 15 (out of 26) consultants chose the unexpected mascul<strong>in</strong>e gender and 13 (out of<br />

26) consultants chose the expected neuter gender. Also, the same comb<strong>in</strong>ation of conjuncts<br />

but with abstract nouns resulted <strong>in</strong> the additional unexpected fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e gender (6 out of 26<br />

consultants), alongside the unexpected mascul<strong>in</strong>e (15 out of 26 consultants) and expected<br />

neuter (13 out of 26 consultants) genders.


4.2 The <strong>Modern</strong> <strong>Greek</strong> Data 85<br />

(50) I<br />

dromi ke i<br />

the.masc.pl roads.masc.pl and the.fem.pl<br />

<strong>in</strong>e jemat-i/-a<br />

kosmo<br />

are.pl full-of.masc/neut.pl people<br />

‘The roads and the squares are full of people’<br />

(Holton et al., 1997)<br />

platies<br />

squares.fem.pl<br />

(51) I<br />

tifones<br />

ke i plimires<br />

the.masc.pl hurricanes.masc.pl and the.fem.pl floods.fem.pl<br />

itan katastrofik-i/-a/-es<br />

ja t<strong>in</strong> Tailandi<br />

were destructive.masc/neut/fem.pl for the Thailand<br />

‘The hurricanes and floods were destructive for Thailand’<br />

(www.<strong>in</strong>.gr)<br />

In order to test whether these genders are the outcome of resolution, we gave the<br />

same comb<strong>in</strong>ation of nouns with the reverse order [fem & masc] to the consultants. The<br />

examples that were given to the consultants are shown below:<br />

(52) I platies ke i<br />

the.fem.pl squares.fem.pl and the.masc.pl<br />

<strong>in</strong>e jemat-i/-a<br />

kosmo<br />

are.pl full-of.masc/neut.pl people<br />

‘The squares and roads are full of people’<br />

(Holton et al., 1997)<br />

dromi<br />

roads.masc.pl<br />

(53) I plimires ke i<br />

tifones<br />

the.fem.pl floods.fem.pl and the.masc.pl hurricanes.masc.pl<br />

itan katastrofik-i/-a/-es<br />

ja t<strong>in</strong> Tailandi<br />

were destructive.masc/neut/fem.pl for the Thailand<br />

‘The floods and hurricanes were destructive for Thailand’<br />

(www.<strong>in</strong>.gr)<br />

In the first example where conjuncts are concrete, 17 (out of 26) consultants chose<br />

the mascul<strong>in</strong>e gender and 11 (out of 26) consultants chose the neuter gender whereas<br />

when conjuncts are abstract 16 (out of 26) consultants chose the mascul<strong>in</strong>e gender, 11<br />

(out of 26) consultants chose the neuter gender and 4 (out of the 26) consultants showed<br />

preference to the fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e gender. Therefore, <strong>in</strong> [fem & masc] constructions the mascul<strong>in</strong>e<br />

gender appears with higher frequency due to closest conjunct agreement. Thus, <strong>in</strong> [fem<br />

& masc] constructions the occurrence of the mascul<strong>in</strong>e gender with such high frequency<br />

is attributed both to resolution and to CCA and the occurence of the fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e gender is<br />

attributed to resolution. Also, when abstract conjuncts appear with the order [masc &<br />

fem] the occurence of the fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e gender <strong>in</strong> higher numbers is due to closest conjunct<br />

agreement s<strong>in</strong>ce fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e was chosen by fewer consultants (4 out of 26) when conjuncts<br />

appear with the reverse order [fem & masc]. The table below shows both the expected<br />

and unexpected resolved genders <strong>in</strong> this group of nouns:


4.2 The <strong>Modern</strong> <strong>Greek</strong> Data 86<br />

Table 4.9: <strong>Agreement</strong> with Inanimate PL Coord<strong>in</strong>ate <strong>Noun</strong>s<br />

Plural Conjuncts<br />

Concrete or Abstract <strong>Noun</strong>s Concrete <strong>Noun</strong>s Abstract <strong>Noun</strong>s<br />

NP1 NP2 AP NP1 NP2 AP NP1 NP2 AP<br />

mpl mpl mpl mpl fpl npl>mpl mpl fpl npl>mpl/fpl<br />

fpl fpl fpl mpl npl npl mpl npl npl<br />

npl npl npl fpl npl npl fpl npl npl<br />

The data showed that plural coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrases with a mascul<strong>in</strong>e and a fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e noun<br />

resolve to the expected neuter but more often to the unexpected mascul<strong>in</strong>e and less often<br />

to the unexpected fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e. Thus, neuter and mascul<strong>in</strong>e resolution coexist <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>animate<br />

plural nouns with a mascul<strong>in</strong>e and a fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e gender. This contradicts Badecker (2008),<br />

who argues that a mascul<strong>in</strong>e and a fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e plural noun resolve only to mascul<strong>in</strong>e.<br />

To summarise, <strong>in</strong>animate coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns with s<strong>in</strong>gular or plural conjuncts show the<br />

same expected patterns. Inanimate coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns with the same gender resolve to<br />

the gender of the conjuncts and <strong>in</strong>animate nouns with mixed gender resolve to neuter.<br />

With regard to the unexpected cases, <strong>in</strong>animate concrete coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns differ from<br />

<strong>in</strong>animate abstract nouns s<strong>in</strong>ce abstract coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns with a mascul<strong>in</strong>e and a fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e<br />

noun resolve not only to the expected neuter but also to the unexpected mascul<strong>in</strong>e and<br />

fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e genders. Concrete coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns with the same comb<strong>in</strong>ation of nouns resolve<br />

to the expected neuter and to the unexpected mascul<strong>in</strong>e. Also, differences are found <strong>in</strong> the<br />

unexpected patterns which are related to the number of the conjuncts. Inanimate s<strong>in</strong>gular<br />

nouns yield unexpected neuter resolution when the coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns are the same <strong>in</strong> gender,<br />

either mascul<strong>in</strong>e or fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e. Inanimate plural nouns do not allow that. F<strong>in</strong>ally, a difference<br />

is found <strong>in</strong> the frequency of an agree<strong>in</strong>g gender. Inanimate s<strong>in</strong>gular coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns with a<br />

mascul<strong>in</strong>e and a fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e noun yield expected neuter resolution and unexpected mascul<strong>in</strong>e<br />

resolution (and if the conjuncts are abstract unexpected fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e resolution), where neuter<br />

occurs with higher frequency. Inanimate plural nouns yield expected neuter resolution and<br />

unexpected mascull<strong>in</strong>e resolution (and if the conjuncts are abstract unexpected fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e<br />

resolution) where mascul<strong>in</strong>e occurs with higher frequency than neuter. A summary of the<br />

s<strong>in</strong>gular and plural <strong>in</strong>animate nouns, their resolution values and the percentage of responses<br />

are presented below:<br />

Table 4.10: <strong>Agreement</strong> with Inanimate Coord<strong>in</strong>ate <strong>Noun</strong>s<br />

S<strong>in</strong>gular Conjuncts<br />

Concrete/Abstract <strong>Noun</strong>s Concrete <strong>Noun</strong>s Abstract <strong>Noun</strong>s<br />

NP1 NP2 AP percent NP1 NP2 AP percent NP1 NP2 AP percent<br />

msg msg mpl>npl 96%>38% msg fsg npl>mpl 53%>46% msg fsg npl>mpl/fpl 61%>23%/23%<br />

fsg fsg fpl>npl 92%>42% msg nsg npl 100% msg nsg npl 100%<br />

nsg nsg npl 100% fsg nsg npl 100% fsg nsg npl 100%<br />

Plural Conjuncts<br />

Concrete/Abstract <strong>Noun</strong>s Concrete <strong>Noun</strong>s Abstract <strong>Noun</strong>s<br />

NP1 NP2 AP percent NP1 NP2 AP percent NP1 NP2 AP percent<br />

mpl mpl mpl 100% mpl fpl mpl>npl 63%>42% mpl fpl mpl>npl>fpl 61%>42%>15%<br />

fpl fpl fpl 100% mpl npl npl 100% mpl npl npl 100%<br />

npl npl npl 100% fpl npl npl 100% fpl npl npl 100%<br />

Thus, we argue that the number of the conjuncts determ<strong>in</strong>es the resolution pattern,<br />

which agrees with Badecker (2008), but our data show that conjunct number only determ<strong>in</strong>es<br />

the preference towards a gender form over the other and does not necessarily<br />

impose neuter resolution <strong>in</strong> s<strong>in</strong>gular conjucts and mascul<strong>in</strong>e resolution <strong>in</strong> plural conjuncts.


4.2 The <strong>Modern</strong> <strong>Greek</strong> Data 87<br />

Badecker’s analysis, however, is based on a simplification which associates the number of<br />

the conjuncts with an exclusive resolved gender value.<br />

4.2.3 Mix<strong>in</strong>g Animate and Inanimate <strong>Noun</strong>s <strong>in</strong> Coord<strong>in</strong>ate Constructions<br />

In this section, we discuss the possibility of comb<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g animate and <strong>in</strong>animate nouns <strong>in</strong><br />

coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrases <strong>in</strong> MG. We argue that MG allows this possibility if the nouns occur <strong>in</strong><br />

a comitative structure.<br />

Corbett and Mtenje (1987) and Corbett (1991) discussed the possibility of mix<strong>in</strong>g<br />

animate with <strong>in</strong>animate nouns and rational with nonrational nouns <strong>in</strong> subject position 12 <strong>in</strong><br />

a number of languages and argue that some languages allow animate-<strong>in</strong>animate or rationalnonrational<br />

coord<strong>in</strong>ation. English, for example, allows the coord<strong>in</strong>ation of an animate with<br />

an <strong>in</strong>animate noun and the coord<strong>in</strong>ation is acceptable both syntactically and semantically:<br />

(54) The child and his bike are stand<strong>in</strong>g there. Can you see them? (constructed)<br />

Other languages, like Chichewa, disallow the comb<strong>in</strong>ation of animate and <strong>in</strong>animate<br />

nouns. However, if this comb<strong>in</strong>ation is forced then agreement is usually with the <strong>in</strong>animate<br />

noun. This is shown <strong>in</strong> the example below by the agreement marker a or less often zi, used<br />

for non-humans:<br />

(55) Ana ndi malalanje<br />

children.1.pl and oranges.3.pl<br />

‘Children and oranges are miss<strong>in</strong>g’<br />

(Corbett and Mtenje, 1987, 33)<br />

a-ku-sowa<br />

ag-pres-miss<strong>in</strong>g<br />

Also, <strong>in</strong> languages like the Dravidian ones, <strong>in</strong> which conjuncts denote rationals and<br />

nonrationals, Corbett (1991) argues that speakers do not accept a comb<strong>in</strong>ation of a rational<br />

with a nonrational noun. Consider the follow<strong>in</strong>g example <strong>in</strong> Tamil:<br />

(56) *raaman-um naay-um<br />

Raman-and dog-and<br />

‘Raman and the dog came’<br />

(Corbett, 1991, 270)<br />

va-nt-aaÒka<br />

come.past-3rd.pl.rational<br />

When rationals and non-rationals are comb<strong>in</strong>ed an alternative form must be used which<br />

is the comitative structure (Corbett, 1991).<br />

MG resembles languages like Chichewa when it comes to the comb<strong>in</strong>ation of animate<br />

and <strong>in</strong>animate nouns s<strong>in</strong>ce it disfavours the coord<strong>in</strong>ation of animate and <strong>in</strong>animate nouns<br />

as shown below:<br />

(57) ??O kleftis ke to diamanti<br />

the thief.masc.sg and the diamond.neut.sg<br />

afant-i???/afant-os??/afant-a?<br />

disappeared.masc.pl/masc.sg/neut.pl<br />

‘The thief and the diamond are gone’<br />

(constructed)<br />

(58) ??O kleftis ke ta kosmimata<br />

the thief.masc.sg and the jewellery.neut.pl<br />

afant-i???/afant-os??/afant-a?<br />

disappeared.masc.pl/masc.sg/neut.pl<br />

12 Both Corbett and Mtenje (1987) and Corbett (1991) discuss examples <strong>in</strong> subject position. S<strong>in</strong>ce we are<br />

<strong>in</strong>terested <strong>in</strong> the gender feature agreement and this is shown when the coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase occurs <strong>in</strong> subject<br />

position, we also focus on similar examples <strong>in</strong> MG.<br />

<strong>in</strong>e<br />

are<br />

<strong>in</strong>e<br />

are


4.3 Resolution Pr<strong>in</strong>ciples <strong>in</strong> MG 88<br />

‘The thief and the jewellery are gone’<br />

(constructed)<br />

The sentences above are strongly disprefered s<strong>in</strong>ce they comb<strong>in</strong>e an animate and an<br />

<strong>in</strong>animate noun. That structure is rarely found (<strong>in</strong> spoken language only) and if it is<br />

admitted, the least marked forms would be the verb to be <strong>in</strong> plural number and the<br />

predicative adjective/participle to show neuter plural agreement, irrespective of the number<br />

or the gender of the two nouns.<br />

Instead, when MG comb<strong>in</strong>es an animate and an <strong>in</strong>animate noun, it shows strong preference<br />

to the comitative structure where the predicative adjective/participle shows agreement<br />

with the head noun and not with the second noun phrase. This is illustrated below:<br />

(59) O kleftis me ta<br />

the thief.masc.sg with the<br />

afantos<br />

disappeared.masc.sg<br />

‘The thief with the jewellery is gone’<br />

(constructed)<br />

kosmimata<br />

jewellery.neut.pl<br />

The participle afantos ‘disappeared’ shows agreement with the head noun phrase, the<br />

animate noun kleftis ‘thief’ and not with the <strong>in</strong>animate noun kosmimata ‘jewellery’. Thus,<br />

coord<strong>in</strong>ations of animate and <strong>in</strong>animate nouns are strongly dispreferred unless they occur<br />

under the comitative structure.<br />

4.3 Resolution Pr<strong>in</strong>ciples <strong>in</strong> MG<br />

The presentation of the <strong>Modern</strong> <strong>Greek</strong> data <strong>in</strong>troduces a dist<strong>in</strong>ction between (morpho)syntactic<br />

and semantic resolution. In this section, we will argue that MG animate coord<strong>in</strong>ate<br />

nouns follow the semantic resolution pr<strong>in</strong>ciple, and MG <strong>in</strong>animate nouns follow the<br />

syntactic resolution pr<strong>in</strong>ciple. Also, we will argue that the unexpected patterns that are<br />

recorded <strong>in</strong> both groups of coord<strong>in</strong>ate constructions belong to a different pr<strong>in</strong>ciple, the<br />

referential one.<br />

4.3.1 Semantic Resolution <strong>in</strong> Animate <strong>Noun</strong>s<br />

MG animate coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns are complicated <strong>in</strong> terms of the resolution strategies they<br />

employ. We argue that the ma<strong>in</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>ciple <strong>in</strong> the expected patterns of MG animate coord<strong>in</strong>ate<br />

nouns is the semantic pr<strong>in</strong>ciple of resolution, which is the characteristic pr<strong>in</strong>ciple<br />

found <strong>in</strong> most languages. However, there is also evidence that nouns with shared gender<br />

follow feature match<strong>in</strong>g or syntactic agreement irrespective of the referents of the nouns.<br />

F<strong>in</strong>ally, we will show that the unexpected patterns are the result of a third pr<strong>in</strong>ciple, the<br />

referential. The table below is repeated from above for reasons of clarity:<br />

<strong>in</strong>e<br />

is


4.3 Resolution Pr<strong>in</strong>ciples <strong>in</strong> MG 89<br />

Table 4.11: <strong>Agreement</strong> of SG/PL Animate Coord<strong>in</strong>ate <strong>Noun</strong>s<br />

S<strong>in</strong>gular Conjuncts<br />

NP1 NP2 AP NP1 NP2 AP<br />

msg msg mpl msg fsg mpl<br />

fsg fsg fpl msg nm/f /0sg mpl<br />

nsg nsg npl fsg nm/0sg mpl<br />

fsg nf sg fpl(>mpl)<br />

Plural Conjuncts<br />

NP1 NP2 AP NP1 NP2 AP<br />

mpl mpl mpl mpl fpl mpl<br />

fpl fpl fpl mpl nm/f /0pl mpl<br />

npl npl npl fpl nm/0pl mpl>npl<br />

fpl nf pl fpl>npl/(>mpl)<br />

Corbett (1991) (follow<strong>in</strong>g Greenberg (1966) and Schane (1970)), expla<strong>in</strong>s the semantic motivation<br />

beh<strong>in</strong>d resolution <strong>in</strong> animate coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns by associat<strong>in</strong>g the resolved gender<br />

of a coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase with the gender of larger groups of both sexes. Corbett (1991)(cit<strong>in</strong>g<br />

Schane (1970)), claims that French sex-differentiated plural common nouns, such as<br />

les America<strong>in</strong>s(masc.pl), denote a group of male or mixed sex Americans whereas the<br />

correspond<strong>in</strong>g fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e one, les America<strong>in</strong>es(fem.pl), denotes only females. This type of<br />

agreement dist<strong>in</strong>ction is also found <strong>in</strong> French coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrases, which resolve to mascul<strong>in</strong>e<br />

whenever the coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase consists of mixed gender conjuncts, and to fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e if<br />

all conjuncts are female.<br />

Sex-differentiated plural common nouns <strong>in</strong> MG show the same k<strong>in</strong>d of dist<strong>in</strong>ction.<br />

When we refer to a group of males or a group of mixed sex, the mascul<strong>in</strong>e gender is used<br />

but when we refer to a group of females, the fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e gender is used. For example, the<br />

noun xen-i/-es.masc/fem.pl ‘foreigners’ has a mascul<strong>in</strong>e and a fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e gender. If we<br />

want to refer to a group of <strong>in</strong>dividuals that consists of both males and females or only<br />

males the mascul<strong>in</strong>e gender xeni.masc.pl must be used. When the same noun is used <strong>in</strong><br />

its fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e form as <strong>in</strong> xenes.fem.pl ‘foreigners’, it denotes only a group of females 13 . This<br />

is illustrated below:<br />

(60) I Kriti exi polus ksenus<br />

the Crete has many foreigners.masc.pl<br />

‘Crete has many foreigners’ (male/mixed group of <strong>in</strong>dividuals)<br />

(constructed)<br />

(61) I Kriti exi poles ksenes<br />

the Crete has many foreigners.fem.pl<br />

‘Crete has many foreigners’ (female group of <strong>in</strong>dividuals)<br />

(constructed)<br />

Therefore, <strong>in</strong> all mixed gender comb<strong>in</strong>ations of MG animate coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns the<br />

mascul<strong>in</strong>e agreement form is used. Thus, MG animate coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns resolve follow<strong>in</strong>g<br />

sex-differentiated plural common nouns which is the first evidence that resolution follows<br />

the semantic pr<strong>in</strong>ciple.<br />

Wechsler and Zlatić (2003) present futher evidence that supports the existence of semantic<br />

agreement <strong>in</strong> animate coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns of most languages. The follow<strong>in</strong>g pr<strong>in</strong>ciple,<br />

repeated from above, identifies cases where semantic agreement occurs <strong>in</strong> a language:<br />

13 Converted nouns like xen-i/-es.masc/fem.pl ‘foreigners’ <strong>in</strong>flect for gender on the basis of semantics.<br />

Once the sex of their referents can be identified the noun is assigned a gender which acts as the sole controller<br />

of any agreement type (Spencer, 2002, 297).


4.3 Resolution Pr<strong>in</strong>ciples <strong>in</strong> MG 90<br />

(62) “Gender agreement with an animate NP that lacks an <strong>in</strong>herent gender is always<br />

<strong>in</strong>terpreted semantically.”<br />

(Wechsler and Zlatić, 2003, p.181)<br />

Wechsler and Zlatić (2003) argue that this pr<strong>in</strong>ciple is triggered <strong>in</strong> two cases: when the<br />

head noun is lexically genderless or when the phrase lacks a head noun. Cases that lack an<br />

<strong>in</strong>herent grammatical gender are proper nouns, such as the French proper noun Dupont,<br />

and sex-neutral nouns, such as the French journaliste. These two groups of nouns may<br />

trigger male or female agreement depend<strong>in</strong>g on their denotation:<br />

(63) Les Dupont sont beaux/belles<br />

the Duponts are good-look<strong>in</strong>g.masc.pl/good-look<strong>in</strong>g.fem.pl<br />

‘The Duponts(male or mixed/female group) are good-look<strong>in</strong>g’<br />

(64) Les journalistes sont compétents/compétentes<br />

the journalists are competent.masc.pl/competent.fem.pl<br />

‘The journalists (male or mixed/female group) are competent’<br />

(Wechsler and Zlatić, 2003, p.181)<br />

Also, Wechsler and Zlatić (2003) claim that the same agreement forms are found <strong>in</strong><br />

French pronouns, which are mascul<strong>in</strong>e when referr<strong>in</strong>g to a male or mixed group of <strong>in</strong>dividuals<br />

or fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e when they refer to a female group:<br />

(65) Ils/elles<br />

parlent<br />

they.masc.pl/fem.pl talk<br />

‘They are talk<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> the kitchen’<br />

dans<br />

<strong>in</strong><br />

la<br />

the<br />

cuis<strong>in</strong>e<br />

kitchen<br />

The same characteristics are also found <strong>in</strong> MG. Noncoord<strong>in</strong>ate proper names, such as<br />

Filipu or Emanuil, which are lexically genderless nouns, lack a grammatical gender and<br />

they are always <strong>in</strong>terpreted semantically. Thus, <strong>in</strong> the examples below the proper noun<br />

Filipu is <strong>in</strong>terpreted as a male or female due to the respective mascul<strong>in</strong>e/fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e end<strong>in</strong>g<br />

<strong>in</strong> the predicative adjective and determ<strong>in</strong>er, which shows semantic agreement with the<br />

controller noun:<br />

(66) O Filipu<br />

the.masc.sg Filipu<br />

‘Filipu is good-look<strong>in</strong>g’<br />

(constructed)<br />

(67) I Filipu<br />

the.fem.sg Fillipu<br />

‘Filipu is beautiful’<br />

(constructed)<br />

<strong>in</strong>e<br />

is<br />

<strong>in</strong>e<br />

is<br />

omorfos<br />

good-look<strong>in</strong>g.masc.sg<br />

omorfi<br />

beautiful.fem.sg<br />

Also, MG pronouns display the same pattern. The pronoun afti.masc.pl ‘they’ is used<br />

to refer to a group of male or mixed-sex <strong>in</strong>dividuals whereas the pronoun aftes.fem.pl<br />

‘they’ is used to refer only to a group of female <strong>in</strong>dividuals:<br />

(68) Afti/Aftes<br />

kathonte st<strong>in</strong> kuz<strong>in</strong>a<br />

they.masc.pl/they.fem.pl are-sitt<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>-the kitchen<br />

‘They (male or mixed-sex group)/(female group) are-sitt<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> the kitchen’<br />

(constructed)


4.3 Resolution Pr<strong>in</strong>ciples <strong>in</strong> MG 91<br />

Sex-neutral nouns such as those illustrated <strong>in</strong> example (64) are not found <strong>in</strong> the <strong>Greek</strong><br />

language 14 . MG coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns resolve accord<strong>in</strong>g to MG pronouns and lexically genderless<br />

nouns which is a second piece of evidence that they resolve semantically.<br />

The resolution patterns <strong>in</strong> mixed gender coord<strong>in</strong>ate noun phrases are themselves further<br />

evidence that animate nouns follow semantic resolution. The first case concerns the<br />

coord<strong>in</strong>ation of a fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e noun with the neuter noun to agori ‘the boy’, which denotes a<br />

male referent. The gender resolution is mascul<strong>in</strong>e plural s<strong>in</strong>ce the second conjunct denotes<br />

a male and therefore the denotation of the conjuncts determ<strong>in</strong>es the resolved gender form:<br />

(69) I Maria<br />

the.fem.sg<br />

xarumeni<br />

Maria.fem.sg<br />

happy.masc.pl<br />

‘Mary and the boy are happy’<br />

(constructed)<br />

ke<br />

and<br />

to<br />

the.neut.sg<br />

agori<br />

boy.neut.sg<br />

<strong>in</strong>e<br />

are.pl<br />

In similar coord<strong>in</strong>ate constructions where a fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e noun is coord<strong>in</strong>ated with the<br />

neuter noun to koritsi ‘the girl’, which denotes a female, gender resolution is fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e.<br />

This result is motivated by the fact that the two nouns denote females and therefore the<br />

denotation of the conjuncts yields this result:<br />

(70) I Maria ke to koritsi tis<br />

the.fem.sg Maria.fem.sg and the.neut.sg girl.neut.sg her<br />

<strong>in</strong>e enthusiasmen-es ja t<strong>in</strong> kenurja tus<br />

zoi<br />

are.pl enthusiastic.fem.pl for the new their.fem/masc.pl life.<br />

‘Mary and her girl are enthusiastic about their new life’<br />

(constructed)<br />

Similarly, the grammatically fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e proper noun Maria when it is coord<strong>in</strong>ated with<br />

the grammatically neuter noun to atomo me ti fusta ‘the person with the skirt’ yields<br />

fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e resolution s<strong>in</strong>ce, as expected, the second conjunct refers to a female. Thus, both<br />

nouns denote female referents and the result is fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e agreement:<br />

(71) I Maria ke to<br />

the.fem.sg Maria.fem.sg and the.neut.sg<br />

ti fusta <strong>in</strong>e paraksen-es<br />

the skirt are.pl weird.fem.pl<br />

‘Mary and the person with the skirt are weird’<br />

(constructed)<br />

atomo<br />

person.neut.sg<br />

me<br />

with<br />

Also, the coord<strong>in</strong>ation of a fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e noun with the semantically-vacuous neuter noun<br />

to moro ‘the baby’ will result <strong>in</strong> different gender feature values, depend<strong>in</strong>g on the denotation<br />

of the second conjunct. Thus, if the noun to moro ‘the baby’ denotes a male or<br />

it is referentially unspecified then resolution is mascul<strong>in</strong>e, but if it denotes a female then<br />

resolution is fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e. Both options are illustrated below:<br />

(72) I Maria ke<br />

the.fem.sg Mary.fem.sg and<br />

<strong>in</strong>e kukl-i/-es.<br />

are.pl beautiful.masc/fem.pl.<br />

tus/-is<br />

thavmazeis<br />

them.masc/fem.pl you-admire<br />

to moro<br />

the.neut.sg baby.neut.sg<br />

Tus/-is<br />

vlepis<br />

Them.masc/fem.pl you-see<br />

tis<br />

her<br />

ke<br />

and<br />

14 One exception is the noun star ‘star’ borrowed from English. The determ<strong>in</strong>er that precedes this noun<br />

will determ<strong>in</strong>e whether it refers to male or a female. In coord<strong>in</strong>ate structures, it behaves as the semantically-<br />

vacuous neuter nouns, which we discussed above. For more details see Holton et al. (1997).


4.3 Resolution Pr<strong>in</strong>ciples <strong>in</strong> MG 92<br />

‘Mary and her baby are beautiful. You see them and you admire them’<br />

(constructed)<br />

In all cases presented above, if the order of the conjuncts is reversed the resolved<br />

agreement form rema<strong>in</strong>s the same. We randomly take example (72) and we reverse the<br />

order <strong>in</strong> the coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns accord<strong>in</strong>g to which the neuter noun occurs first and the<br />

fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e noun occurs second:<br />

(73) To moro tis ke i Maria<br />

the.neut.sg baby.neut.sg her and the.fem.sg Mary.fem.sg<br />

<strong>in</strong>e kukl-i/-es.<br />

Tus/-is<br />

vlepis ke<br />

are.pl beautiful.masc/fem.pl. Them.masc/fem.pl you-see and<br />

tus/-is<br />

thavmazeis<br />

them.masc/fem.pl you-admire<br />

‘The baby and Mary are beautiful. You see them and you admire them’<br />

(constructed)<br />

Thus, the above patterns are clear cases of resolution accord<strong>in</strong>g to the semantic pr<strong>in</strong>ciple<br />

s<strong>in</strong>ce what matters <strong>in</strong> the resolution outcome is the referent of the two conjuncts and not<br />

their syntactic gender.<br />

Apart from the semantic cases above, there seems to be evidence for a preference to<br />

feature match<strong>in</strong>g or syntactic agreement <strong>in</strong> MG animate coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns. This becomes<br />

more obvious <strong>in</strong> animate grammatically neuter conjuncts that resolve to neuter irrespective<br />

of be<strong>in</strong>g semantic or semantically-vacuous 15 neuter nouns. Semantic neuter nouns, such<br />

as to agori ‘the boy’ and to koritsi ‘the girl’, have a male and a female semantic gender,<br />

respectively. The semantic pr<strong>in</strong>ciple of resolution would consult the natural gender of the<br />

conjuncts and s<strong>in</strong>ce they have a male and a female referent, we would expect mascul<strong>in</strong>e<br />

resolution. However, none of the consultants chose the mascul<strong>in</strong>e gender but selected<br />

the neuter <strong>in</strong>stead. In fact, the mascul<strong>in</strong>e gender appears to be highly marked if not<br />

ungrammatical. The relevant example is illustrated below:<br />

(74) To agori ke to<br />

the.neut boy.neut and the.neut<br />

etima/etimi? na figun<br />

ready.neut/masc? to go<br />

‘The boy and the girl are ready to go’<br />

(constructed)<br />

koritsi<br />

girl.neut<br />

Thus, resolution here depends strictly on feature match<strong>in</strong>g s<strong>in</strong>ce it ignores the mean<strong>in</strong>g<br />

of the conjo<strong>in</strong>ed elements and depends on their grammatical gender.<br />

Similarly, when two referentially unspecified neuter nouns, such as to pedi ‘the child’<br />

and to moro ‘the baby’, are coord<strong>in</strong>ated, they resolve to neuter, irrespective of a male or<br />

female referent, of two male referents or two female referents. This is illustrated <strong>in</strong> the<br />

example below:<br />

(75) To pedi ke<br />

the.neut.sg child.neut.sg and<br />

itan klidomena sto<br />

were.pl locked.neut.pl <strong>in</strong>-the<br />

to<br />

the.neut.sg<br />

domatio<br />

room<br />

<strong>in</strong>e<br />

are<br />

moro<br />

baby.neut.sg<br />

15 The term semantic neuter noun refers to the two grammatically neuter nouns that have a semantic<br />

gender, to agori ‘the boy’ and to koritsi ‘the girl’, and the term semantically-vacuous neuter noun refers to<br />

neuter nouns that do not have a semantic gender, such as to pedi ‘the child’, to moro ‘the baby’ and to<br />

atomo ‘the person’.


4.3 Resolution Pr<strong>in</strong>ciples <strong>in</strong> MG 93<br />

‘The child and the baby were locked <strong>in</strong> the room’<br />

(constructed)<br />

Thus, this is one more piece of evidence that <strong>in</strong> uniform gender nouns the grammatical<br />

gender determ<strong>in</strong>es resolution and not the natural one, lead<strong>in</strong>g to the conclusion that<br />

resolution <strong>in</strong> these patterns is motivated by the grammatical features of the coord<strong>in</strong>ated<br />

nouns.<br />

When the semantic neuter nouns to agori ‘the boy’ and to koritsi ‘the girl’ are coord<strong>in</strong>ated<br />

with one of the semantically-empty neuter nouns to pedi ‘the child’ and to moro<br />

‘the baby’, the resolved gender is still neuter plural, as illustrated below:<br />

(76) To agori<br />

the.neut.sg<br />

lipimena<br />

sad.neut.pl<br />

boy.neut.sg<br />

‘The boy and the baby are sad’<br />

(constructed)<br />

(77) To koritsi<br />

the.neut.sg<br />

lipimena<br />

sad.neut.pl<br />

girl.neut.sg<br />

‘The girl and the baby are sad’<br />

(constructed)<br />

ke<br />

and<br />

ke<br />

and<br />

to<br />

the.neut.sg<br />

to<br />

the.neut.sg<br />

moro<br />

baby.neut.sg<br />

moro<br />

baby.neut.sg<br />

<strong>in</strong>e<br />

are.pl<br />

<strong>in</strong>e<br />

are.pl<br />

In example (76), resolution would be semantic if the semantic neuter noun to agori ‘the<br />

boy’, which refers to a male, and the semantically-vacuous neuter noun to moro ‘the baby’<br />

resolved to mascul<strong>in</strong>e. Similarly, <strong>in</strong> (77), resolution would also follow the semantic pr<strong>in</strong>ciple<br />

if the semantic neuter noun to koritsi ‘the girl’, which denotes a female referent, and the<br />

semantically-vacuous neuter noun to moro ‘the baby’ resolved to mascul<strong>in</strong>e or fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e.<br />

None of these cases, though, resolve accord<strong>in</strong>g to the semantic pr<strong>in</strong>ciple s<strong>in</strong>ce the coord<strong>in</strong>ate<br />

phrase copies the syntactic gender of the conjuncts. Thus, we can conclude that if animate<br />

neuter nouns or generally uniform gender nouns cooccur <strong>in</strong> a coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase, they<br />

strictly follow feature match<strong>in</strong>g agreement and not semantic agreement, despite hav<strong>in</strong>g or<br />

not a natural gender.<br />

The analysis of the data shows that MG animate coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns follow the semantic<br />

pr<strong>in</strong>ciple of resolution, which occurs <strong>in</strong> mixed gender comb<strong>in</strong>ations, and also feature<br />

match<strong>in</strong>g agreement, which occurs when the conjuncts share the same gender irrespective<br />

of their referent. A third pr<strong>in</strong>ciple is also present which will be discussed below.<br />

The follow<strong>in</strong>g table summarises the unexpected resolution patterns <strong>in</strong> animate coord<strong>in</strong>ate<br />

nouns which occur only <strong>in</strong> plural nouns (and not <strong>in</strong> s<strong>in</strong>gulars):<br />

Table 4.12: Animate PL <strong>Noun</strong>s: Unexpected patterns<br />

Plural Conj<br />

NP1 NP2 AP<br />

fpl nm/0pl npl<br />

fpl nf pl npl<br />

The first issue is whether these patterns are <strong>in</strong>stances of semantic resolution. We argued<br />

above that the semantic genders for the MG animate nouns are the mascul<strong>in</strong>e gender,<br />

which refers to males, and the fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e gender, which refers to females. Thus, if resolution<br />

was accord<strong>in</strong>g to the semantic pr<strong>in</strong>ciple, we would expect mascul<strong>in</strong>e resolution <strong>in</strong> the<br />

pattern [fpl & nm/0pl] s<strong>in</strong>ce one of the conjuncts denotes a male referent, and fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e


4.3 Resolution Pr<strong>in</strong>ciples <strong>in</strong> MG 94<br />

resolution <strong>in</strong> the pattern [fpl & nf pl] s<strong>in</strong>ce both conjuncts denote female referents. However,<br />

the resolved gender is neuter and therefore we argue that the above patterns cannot<br />

be considered cases of semantic resolution.<br />

Second, the issue is whether the above patterns follow the feature match<strong>in</strong>g or syntactic<br />

pr<strong>in</strong>ciple of agreement. Grammatical or feature match<strong>in</strong>g agreement occurs only when the<br />

conjuncts share the same gender. In the above comb<strong>in</strong>ations none of the conjuncts have<br />

the same gender and therefore neuter agreement is not a case of syntactic or a feature<br />

match<strong>in</strong>g pr<strong>in</strong>ciple. F<strong>in</strong>ally, <strong>in</strong> an <strong>in</strong>formal discussion with native speakers, they argued<br />

that the choice of the neuter gender was driven by the fact that both nouns could be<br />

referred to by the noun atoma ‘persons’, which is neuter <strong>in</strong> gender; although it does not<br />

occur <strong>in</strong> the sentence, it is implied. Thus, we assume that a different pr<strong>in</strong>ciple is present<br />

<strong>in</strong> these patterns.<br />

4.3.2 Syntactic Resolution <strong>in</strong> Inanimate <strong>Noun</strong>s<br />

Syntactic resolution means that it is the grammatical gender of the nouns that matters<br />

and not their semantic or natural gender. We will argue that the expected patterns of MG<br />

<strong>in</strong>animate nouns admit the syntactic resolution pr<strong>in</strong>ciple. Below we repeat the table of<br />

<strong>in</strong>animate nouns:<br />

Table 4.13: <strong>Agreement</strong> with Inanimate Coord<strong>in</strong>ate <strong>Noun</strong>s<br />

S<strong>in</strong>gular Conjuncts<br />

Concrete/Abstract <strong>Noun</strong>s Concrete <strong>Noun</strong>s Abstract <strong>Noun</strong>s<br />

NP1 NP2 AP NP1 NP2 AP NP1 NP2 AP<br />

msg msg mpl>npl msg fsg npl>mpl msg fsg npl>mpl>fpl<br />

fsg fsg fpl>npl msg nsg npl msg nsg npl<br />

nsg nsg npl fsg nsg npl fsg nsg npl<br />

Plural Conjuncts<br />

Concrete/Abstract <strong>Noun</strong>s Concrete <strong>Noun</strong>s Abstract <strong>Noun</strong>s<br />

NP1 NP2 AP NP1 NP2 AP NP1 NP2 AP<br />

mpl mpl mpl mpl fpl mpl>npl mpl fpl mpl>npl>fpl<br />

fpl fpl fpl mpl npl npl mpl npl npl<br />

npl npl npl fpl npl npl fpl npl npl<br />

Dalrymple and Kaplan (2000) claim that there are three recurr<strong>in</strong>g characteristics <strong>in</strong><br />

syntactic gender resolution. First, a coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase behaves as if it has the same gender<br />

as some noncoord<strong>in</strong>ate element <strong>in</strong> the language and there are no special agreeement markers<br />

that would appear only with coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrases. Secondly, a coord<strong>in</strong>ate structure with<br />

conjuncts that share the same gender behaves as if it has the same gender found <strong>in</strong> the<br />

conjuncts, and thirdly, mixed gender conjuncts usually resolve to a gender feature value<br />

found <strong>in</strong>dependently <strong>in</strong> a language, which may or may not be the same as the gender value<br />

of the conjuncts (788).<br />

These characteristics occur <strong>in</strong> MG <strong>in</strong>animate nouns. Coord<strong>in</strong>ate structures with the<br />

same gender conjuncts result <strong>in</strong> that same gender, which is a case of feature match<strong>in</strong>g of<br />

the grammatical gender value of the <strong>in</strong>dividual conjuncts with the gender feature value of<br />

the whole coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase:<br />

(78) O iroismos ke<br />

the.masc.sg heroism.masc.sg and<br />

itan kiriarx-i kata<br />

were.pl prevalent.masc.pl dur<strong>in</strong>g<br />

o<br />

the.masc.sg<br />

to 1821<br />

the 1821<br />

agonas<br />

fight<strong>in</strong>g.masc.sg


4.3 Resolution Pr<strong>in</strong>ciples <strong>in</strong> MG 95<br />

‘Heroism and fight<strong>in</strong>g were prevalent dur<strong>in</strong>g 1821’<br />

(G.N.: To Vima)<br />

Coord<strong>in</strong>ate structures with mixed gender conjucts also show that syntactic resolution<br />

is the ma<strong>in</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>ciple <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>animate nouns s<strong>in</strong>ce mixed gender conjuncts resolve to neuter.<br />

This is a gender feature value that occurs <strong>in</strong>dependently <strong>in</strong> the language and which is not<br />

necessarily found <strong>in</strong> the <strong>in</strong>dividual conjuncts. For <strong>in</strong>stance, <strong>in</strong> example (79) the coord<strong>in</strong>ate<br />

phrase consists of a mascul<strong>in</strong>e and a fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e noun. The predicative adjective resolves<br />

to neuter which is a different gender value that is not found <strong>in</strong> any of the two conjuncts.<br />

The same gender value occurs <strong>in</strong> example (80) where the coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase consists of a<br />

fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e and a neuter noun. In this case, neuter appears as the gender value only <strong>in</strong> one<br />

of the two conjuncts:<br />

(79) O kanapes ke<br />

the.masc.sg<br />

aspr-a<br />

white.neut.pl<br />

sofa.masc.sg and<br />

‘The sofa and the chair are white’<br />

(constructed)<br />

(80) I karekla ke<br />

the.fem.sg<br />

anet-a<br />

chair.fem.sg and<br />

comfortable.neut.pl<br />

‘The chair and table are comfortable’<br />

(constructed)<br />

i<br />

the.fem.sg<br />

to<br />

the.neut.sg<br />

polithrona<br />

chair.fem.sg<br />

trapezi<br />

table.neut.sg<br />

<strong>in</strong>e<br />

are.pl<br />

<strong>in</strong>e<br />

are.pl<br />

Also, the most important reason that MG <strong>in</strong>animate nouns use the syntactic pr<strong>in</strong>ciple<br />

of resolution is that <strong>in</strong>animate nouns lack a natural gender and therefore semantics<br />

cannot be consulted <strong>in</strong> order to derive resolution. Hence, the only pr<strong>in</strong>ciple they could<br />

obey is the syntactic one. For example, the MG coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase below consists of two<br />

fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns. The nouns that have a fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e grammatical gender do not<br />

have any semantic gender to affect the resolution process and fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e agreement is chosen<br />

syntactically:<br />

(81) I vivliothiki ke<br />

the.fem.sg bookcase.fem.sg and<br />

<strong>in</strong>e skur-es<br />

are.pl dark.fem.pl<br />

‘The bookcase and d<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g-table are dark’<br />

i<br />

the.fem.sg<br />

trapezaria<br />

d<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g-table.fem.sg<br />

Similarly, mixed gender coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns without a natural gender admit neuter agreement<br />

s<strong>in</strong>ce the <strong>in</strong>dividual conjuncts do not have a semantic gender:<br />

(82) O thanatos ke<br />

the.masc.sg death.masc.sg and<br />

<strong>in</strong>e simantik-a<br />

are.pl important.neut.pl<br />

‘Death and freedom are important’<br />

i<br />

the.fem.sg<br />

eleftheria<br />

freedom.fem.sg<br />

Hence, the above examples make it obvious that <strong>in</strong>animate nouns do not allow cases of<br />

semantic resolution <strong>in</strong> any type of gender comb<strong>in</strong>ation.<br />

Let us consider next whether the exceptional patterns follow the syntactic resolution<br />

pr<strong>in</strong>ciple. The table below presents only the unexpected cases found <strong>in</strong> this group of nouns:


4.3 Resolution Pr<strong>in</strong>ciples <strong>in</strong> MG 96<br />

Table 4.14: Inanimate SG/PL <strong>Noun</strong>s: Unexpected patterns<br />

S<strong>in</strong>gular <strong>Noun</strong>s<br />

Concrete/Abstract <strong>Noun</strong>s Concrete <strong>Noun</strong>s Abstract <strong>Noun</strong>s<br />

NP1 NP2 AP NP1 NP2 AP NP1 NP2 AP<br />

msg msg npl msg fsg mpl msg fsg fpl/mpl<br />

fsg fsg npl<br />

Plural <strong>Noun</strong>s<br />

Concrete <strong>Noun</strong>s Abstract <strong>Noun</strong>s<br />

NP1 NP2 AP NP1 NP2 AP<br />

mpl fpl mpl mpl fpl mpl/fpl<br />

Accord<strong>in</strong>g to table (4.14), the coord<strong>in</strong>ate structures which consist of conjuncts with the<br />

same gender, either mascul<strong>in</strong>e or fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e, resolve to the same gender of the conjuncts and<br />

to the neuter gender as well. This is shown <strong>in</strong> the examples below<br />

(83) O iroismos ke o<br />

agonas<br />

the.masc.sg heroism.masc.sg and the.masc.sg fight<strong>in</strong>g.masc.sg<br />

itan kiriarx-i/-a<br />

kata to 1821<br />

were.pl prevalent.masc/neut.pl dur<strong>in</strong>g the 1821<br />

‘Heroism and fight<strong>in</strong>g were prevalent dur<strong>in</strong>g 1821’<br />

(G.N.: To Vima)<br />

(84) I vivliothiki ke<br />

the.fem.sg bookcase.fem.sg and<br />

<strong>in</strong>e skur-es/-a<br />

are.pl dark.fem/neut.pl<br />

‘The bookcase and d<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g-table are dark’<br />

(constructed)<br />

i<br />

the.fem.sg<br />

trapezaria<br />

d<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g-table.fem.sg<br />

Although neuter is the syntactic gender, these cases are not syntactic s<strong>in</strong>ce we would expect<br />

<strong>in</strong> identical gender conjuncts grammatical agreement to result <strong>in</strong> the same gender found <strong>in</strong><br />

the conjuncts and not <strong>in</strong> a different gender. Thus, the unexpected neuter gender resolution<br />

<strong>in</strong> shared gender coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns does not follow the syntactic pr<strong>in</strong>ciple.<br />

Also, mixed gender coord<strong>in</strong>ations with a mascul<strong>in</strong>e and a fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e noun resolve to the<br />

expected neuter gender and to the unexpected mascul<strong>in</strong>e gender. The same comb<strong>in</strong>ation<br />

of nouns also resolves to the unexpected fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e gender only if the conjuncts are abstract.<br />

These examples are shown below:<br />

(85) O kanapes ke<br />

the.masc.sg<br />

aspr-a/-i<br />

sofa.masc.sg and<br />

white.neut/masc.pl<br />

‘The sofa and the chair are white’<br />

(constructed)<br />

i<br />

the.fem.sg<br />

(86) O thanatos ke i<br />

the.masc.sg death.masc.sg and the.fem.sg<br />

<strong>in</strong>e simantik-a/-i/-es<br />

are.pl important.neut.pl/masc.pl/fem.pl<br />

‘Death and freedom are important’<br />

polithrona<br />

chair.fem.sg<br />

eleftheria<br />

freedom.fem.sg<br />

<strong>in</strong>e<br />

are.pl<br />

These gender feature values are rather unusual <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>animate conjuncts s<strong>in</strong>ce the expected<br />

gender <strong>in</strong> mixed gender <strong>in</strong>animate nouns is the neuter gender, which is a syntactic


4.4 Reference Transfer <strong>in</strong> Noncoord<strong>in</strong>ate Constructions 97<br />

gender and not any of the semantic genders, such as the mascul<strong>in</strong>e and fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e genders.<br />

The fact that the above cases resolve to a gender which is not syntactic shows that these<br />

resolution patterns do not follow the syntactic pr<strong>in</strong>ciple. In addition, s<strong>in</strong>ce <strong>in</strong>animate nouns<br />

do not resort to semantic resolution anyway, the above patterns must be evidence of the<br />

existence of a third pr<strong>in</strong>ciple. F<strong>in</strong>ally, an <strong>in</strong>formal discussion with the native speakers revealed<br />

that the choice of the unexpected genders was driven by the fact that both nouns<br />

could be referred to by an implied noun, which has agreement features similar to those<br />

of the unexpected form and it does not occur <strong>in</strong> the sentence. Thus, we assume the unexpected<br />

patterns do not belong to the syntactic or semantic pr<strong>in</strong>ciples of resolution but<br />

they are evidence of a third resolution pr<strong>in</strong>ciple which we will refer to as the referential<br />

pr<strong>in</strong>ciple. Before we analyse referential agreement <strong>in</strong> MG coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns, we need to<br />

expla<strong>in</strong> what referential agreement is and whether English or other languages show cases<br />

of referential agreement.<br />

4.4 Reference Transfer <strong>in</strong> Noncoord<strong>in</strong>ate Constructions<br />

The aim of this section is to present the phenomenon of referential agreement or “reference<br />

transfer”(Pollard and Sag, 1994) and show how the mismatch gender agreement patterns<br />

<strong>in</strong> MG can be expla<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong> terms of this phenomenon.<br />

Mismatch agreement has been studied by a number of l<strong>in</strong>guists and a number of agreement<br />

phenomena have been noticed to be problematic for the conventional purely syntactic<br />

or semantic views. The most characteristic phenomenon of mismatch agreement, relevant<br />

to the MG data, is that of “mean<strong>in</strong>g transfer” or “reference transfer” 16 .<br />

“Mean<strong>in</strong>g transfer”, accord<strong>in</strong>g to Nunberg (1977), refers to the “productive l<strong>in</strong>guistic<br />

processes that enable us to use the same expression to refer to what are <strong>in</strong>tuitively dist<strong>in</strong>ct<br />

sorts of categories of th<strong>in</strong>gs” (Nunberg, 1995, 109). These transfers might <strong>in</strong>volve the<br />

figures that traditional rhetoric describes such as metaphors, synesthesias, metonymies<br />

and synecdotes. Nevertheless, the ma<strong>in</strong> characteristic of reference transfer is that it is a<br />

l<strong>in</strong>guistic process with specific l<strong>in</strong>guistic mechanisms. “Reference transfer” can apply to<br />

predicates of any k<strong>in</strong>d, lexical or phrasal and also to common nouns. Two characterictic<br />

examples of “transfer” are presented below:<br />

(87) a. I am parked out back<br />

b. The ham sandwich is at table 7<br />

(Nunberg, 1995, 110,115)<br />

Nunberg (1995) gives a brief analysis of how “transfer” works <strong>in</strong> the above examples.<br />

In both examples, there is a correspondence between the th<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>in</strong> one doma<strong>in</strong> and the<br />

th<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>in</strong> another doma<strong>in</strong>. Thus, <strong>in</strong> example (87a) I refers to the car parked <strong>in</strong> a specific<br />

location by referr<strong>in</strong>g to the driver of the car and not to the car itself. Similarly, <strong>in</strong> example<br />

(87b) the phrase is uttered by a restaurant waiter, who considers that customers acquire<br />

their dist<strong>in</strong>ctive properties with regard to the dishes they order. Thus, the noun phrase<br />

‘ham sandwich’ refers to the person who has ordered a ham sandwich.<br />

Nunberg (1995) attempts to expla<strong>in</strong> the l<strong>in</strong>guistic mechanisms of “transfer” <strong>in</strong> general.<br />

He dist<strong>in</strong>guishes two types of “transfer”. The first one <strong>in</strong>volves demonstratives or <strong>in</strong>dexicals<br />

and it is mentioned as “deferred ostension” or “deferred <strong>in</strong>dexical reference” (Nunberg,<br />

1995, 111). Accord<strong>in</strong>g to Nunberg (1995), this type of transfer “allows a demonstrative or<br />

<strong>in</strong>dexical to refer to an object that corresponds <strong>in</strong> a certa<strong>in</strong> way to the contextual element<br />

picked out by a demonstration or by the semantic character of the expression” (Nunberg,<br />

1995, 111). Consider the follow<strong>in</strong>g example:<br />

16 Nunberg (1977, 1995, 2005) uses the term “mean<strong>in</strong>g tranfer”. Pollard and Sag (1994) use the term<br />

“reference transfer”. Both of them refer to the same phenomenon.


4.4 Reference Transfer <strong>in</strong> Noncoord<strong>in</strong>ate Constructions 98<br />

(88) This is parked out back (hold<strong>in</strong>g up a key)<br />

(Nunberg, 1995, 110)<br />

Nunberg (1995) argues that it is more likely that the subject refers not to the key that<br />

the speaker is hold<strong>in</strong>g but to the car that the key goes with. The evidence to support<br />

this view is that the number of the demonstrative is determ<strong>in</strong>ed by the <strong>in</strong>tended referent<br />

and not the demonstratum. So even if the customer is hold<strong>in</strong>g up several keys that fit a<br />

s<strong>in</strong>gle car, he would say This is parked out back, whereas if he is hold<strong>in</strong>g up only one key<br />

that fits several cars he would say These are parked out back. Further evidence that the<br />

demonstrative refers to the car is drawn by conjo<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g another predicate that describes the<br />

car, but not a predicate that describes the key:<br />

(89) a. This is parked out back and may not start<br />

b.?? This fits only the left front door and is parked out back<br />

(Nunberg, 1995, 110)<br />

Accord<strong>in</strong>g to Nunberg (1995), the demonstratives and adjectives of other languages<br />

display similar agreement patterns. Italian, for <strong>in</strong>stance, uses the fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e noun for the<br />

word ‘key’, la chiave, and the mascul<strong>in</strong>e noun for the word ‘truck’, il camion. Thus, if a<br />

customer gives an attendant the key to a truck, the referent and not the demonstratum will<br />

determ<strong>in</strong>e the gender of the demonstrative and the adjective for ‘parked’, as seen below:<br />

(90) Hold<strong>in</strong>g up a key(la chiave,fem.sg) to refer to a truck(il camion,masc.sg)<br />

Questo.masc.sg<br />

This.masc<br />

é<br />

is<br />

‘This is parked <strong>in</strong> back’<br />

(Nunberg, 1995, 110)<br />

parcheggiato.masc.sg<br />

parked.masc<br />

<strong>in</strong><br />

<strong>in</strong><br />

dietro<br />

back<br />

A different mechanism of transfer is what is known as “predicate transfer”. In this type<br />

of transfer “the name of a property that applies to someth<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> one doma<strong>in</strong> can sometimes<br />

be used as the name of a property that applies to th<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>in</strong> another doma<strong>in</strong>, provided that<br />

the two properties correspond <strong>in</strong> a certa<strong>in</strong> way”(Nunberg, 1995, 111). This type of transfer<br />

is <strong>in</strong>troduced by the example presented below:<br />

(91) I am parked out back<br />

(Nunberg, 1995, 110)<br />

As Nunberg (1995) claims, most people would say that the transfer <strong>in</strong>volves the subject<br />

of the sentence I. A number of tests, however, <strong>in</strong>dicate that the above example <strong>in</strong>volves a<br />

transfer of the conventional mean<strong>in</strong>g of the predicate parked out back. For <strong>in</strong>stance, if the<br />

speaker had two cars he wouldn’t say:<br />

(92) a. We are parked out back<br />

(Nunberg, 1995, 111)<br />

Secondly, it is possible to conjo<strong>in</strong> any other predicate that describes the speaker, and<br />

not a predicate that describes the car:<br />

(93) a. I am parked out back and have been wait<strong>in</strong>g for 15 m<strong>in</strong>utes<br />

b. *I am parked out back and may not start<br />

(Nunberg, 1995, 111)


4.4 Reference Transfer <strong>in</strong> Noncoord<strong>in</strong>ate Constructions 99<br />

Another piece of evidence is that the verb <strong>in</strong> the sentence is am first-person s<strong>in</strong>gular<br />

and not is third-person s<strong>in</strong>gular as we would expect if the subject referred to a car. Thus,<br />

the subject of I refers to the speaker, and the transfer <strong>in</strong>volves the predicate parked out<br />

back which contributes a property of persons whose cars are parked out back (Nunberg,<br />

2005).<br />

F<strong>in</strong>ally, Nunberg (1995, 2005) claims that mean<strong>in</strong>g transfer operates on the mean<strong>in</strong>gs<br />

of common nouns as well as <strong>in</strong>dexicals, whether they are <strong>in</strong> predicate position or referr<strong>in</strong>g<br />

position. The follow<strong>in</strong>g example is similar to example (87b):<br />

(94) Who is the ham sandwich?<br />

The process of transfer <strong>in</strong> this example is that customers acquire their properties based<br />

on their relation to the dishes they order. The common noun ‘ham sandwich’ has a transferred<br />

mean<strong>in</strong>g and it contributes a property of people who have ordered ham sandwiches.<br />

Pollard and Sag (1994) also discuss the phenomenon of “reference transfer” as part<br />

of agreement mismatches, claim<strong>in</strong>g that agreement is often guided by reference transfer,<br />

rather than the grammatical (<strong>in</strong>herent) agreement properties of the phrase itself. This<br />

notion is illustrated <strong>in</strong> the two classic examples below which show how the agreement<br />

result is affected by this phenomenon:<br />

(95) a. The ham sandwich is at table 7<br />

b. The hash browns at table n<strong>in</strong>e is gett<strong>in</strong>g angry<br />

(Pollard and Sag, 1994, 85)<br />

The first example, repeated from above, displays s<strong>in</strong>gular subject-verb agreement. Even<br />

though, it seems that the verb agrees with the grammatically s<strong>in</strong>gular noun ham sandwich,<br />

this is not the case. As mentioned above, the waiter uses the specific noun to refer to a<br />

person who has ordered a ham sandwich. The person is a nonaggregate entity and the<br />

verb shows agreement with the referred implied noun. The same notion is illustrated more<br />

clearly <strong>in</strong> example (95b). The noun phrase hash browns is grammatically (<strong>in</strong>herently)<br />

plural and therefore we would expect plural verb agreement. Instead, the verb shows<br />

s<strong>in</strong>gular agreement s<strong>in</strong>ce the referent is transferred to the person who has placed the order<br />

and which is a nonaggregate entity.<br />

Pollard and Sag (1994) also <strong>in</strong>troduce another type of reference transfer which occurs<br />

<strong>in</strong> “s<strong>in</strong>gular plurals”. In this group of nouns, there is a conflict between the agreement<br />

features of the subject NP and those that the s<strong>in</strong>gular verb requires from its subject. The<br />

follow<strong>in</strong>g examples illustrate this k<strong>in</strong>d of agreement mismatch:<br />

(96) a. Eggs is my favourite breakfast<br />

b. Eggs bothers me more than okra<br />

(Pollard and Sag, 1994, 70)<br />

In both examples, even though the NP appears <strong>in</strong> plural number, the verb shows<br />

s<strong>in</strong>gular agreement. The noun eggs is referred to by a nonagreggate entity, such as ‘menu<br />

type’ <strong>in</strong> example (96a) or ‘food’ <strong>in</strong> example (96b). Accord<strong>in</strong>g to Pollard and Sag (1994),<br />

<strong>in</strong> both cases the referent of the phrase is <strong>in</strong> some contextual relation to an object usually<br />

picked out by nonmetaphorical utterances of that phrase, allow<strong>in</strong>g s<strong>in</strong>gular agreement.<br />

Similar examples are the ones below, which illustrate the same k<strong>in</strong>d of contextual<br />

relation between the NP and the referred noun:<br />

(97) a. Do<strong>in</strong>g phonology problems and dr<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g vodka makes me sick<br />

b. Unleashed dogs on city sidewalks threatens the health and welfare of law-abid<strong>in</strong>g<br />

citizens<br />

(Pollard and Sag, 1994, 86)


4.4 Reference Transfer <strong>in</strong> Noncoord<strong>in</strong>ate Constructions 100<br />

In both cases, the two NPs refer to different nouns, such as an activity or a social<br />

problem, respectively. S<strong>in</strong>ce the referred noun is perceived as a nonagreggate entity then<br />

it yields s<strong>in</strong>gular agreement to the verb.<br />

The phenomenon of “reference transfer” described above, which affects the agreement<br />

result, seems to be closely related to the type of mismatch gender agreement found <strong>in</strong> the<br />

MG unexpected patterns described <strong>in</strong> the previous section. In the next section, we will<br />

argue that “reference transfer” is found <strong>in</strong> MG data and that it affects the gender and not<br />

the number feature.<br />

4.4.1 Reference Transfer <strong>in</strong> <strong>Modern</strong> <strong>Greek</strong><br />

In this section, we will show that all the unexpected patterns <strong>in</strong> MG are cases of agreement<br />

that fall with<strong>in</strong> the phenomenon of “reference transfer” and we adopt the term referential<br />

agreement or referential pr<strong>in</strong>ciple of resolution to refer to this type of resolution.<br />

As already mentioned above, “reference transfer” seems to affect the agreement result<br />

<strong>in</strong> noncoord<strong>in</strong>ate constructions. In the same way, resolved agreement <strong>in</strong> coord<strong>in</strong>ate<br />

constructions is not an exception and can be determ<strong>in</strong>ed by “reference transfer”. In the<br />

agreement cases discussed by Nunberg (1977, 1995) and Pollard and Sag (1994), the agreement<br />

feature that is affected by “reference transfer” is number, as <strong>in</strong> the case of “s<strong>in</strong>gular<br />

plurals”, repeated from above:<br />

(98) Eggs is my favourite breakfast<br />

(Pollard and Sag, 1994, 70)<br />

The noun eggs, which is the subject <strong>in</strong> the phrase and it is grammatically plural,<br />

is somehow referentially associated with a noun that is implied <strong>in</strong> the phrase and it is<br />

a nonagreggate entity. The fact that the implied noun is s<strong>in</strong>gular leads to a s<strong>in</strong>gular<br />

agreement <strong>in</strong> the verb.<br />

A similar k<strong>in</strong>d of mechanism is <strong>in</strong> operation <strong>in</strong> MG coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns which result <strong>in</strong><br />

unexpected gender resolution 17 . The follow<strong>in</strong>g example discusses how “reference transfer”<br />

works <strong>in</strong> MG:<br />

(99) I<br />

dromi ke i<br />

the.masc.pl roads.masc.pl and the.fem.pl<br />

<strong>in</strong>e jemat-i/-a<br />

kosmo<br />

are.pl full-of.masc/neut.pl people<br />

‘The roads and the alleys are full of people’<br />

platies<br />

squares.fem.pl<br />

The <strong>in</strong>animate coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase with a mascul<strong>in</strong>e plural and a fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e plural noun<br />

yields two types of agreement, the expected neuter gender, and the unexpected mascul<strong>in</strong>e<br />

gender. The former occurs <strong>in</strong> all cases of mixed gender coord<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>animate nouns<br />

and it is the result of syntactic resolution, but the latter is unusual for the simple reason<br />

that neuter is the default gender <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>animate nouns and not mascul<strong>in</strong>e. What allows<br />

the appearance of the mascul<strong>in</strong>e gender <strong>in</strong> mixed gender cases of <strong>in</strong>animate nouns is the<br />

phenomenon of “reference transfer”.<br />

We argue that what happens <strong>in</strong> MG is that the presence of the mascul<strong>in</strong>e gender as the<br />

agreement form <strong>in</strong> the predicative adjective is due to an implied miss<strong>in</strong>g noun, which is<br />

mascul<strong>in</strong>e <strong>in</strong> gender; it does not occur <strong>in</strong> the phrase but it is brought <strong>in</strong>to the context and<br />

denotes the coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns. A number of consultants who chose the mascul<strong>in</strong>e gender as<br />

17 We have not come across relevant literature on reference transfer <strong>in</strong> MG non-coord<strong>in</strong>ate and coord<strong>in</strong>ate<br />

constructions. However, we assume that reference transfer <strong>in</strong> gender occurs only <strong>in</strong> coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns <strong>in</strong> the<br />

patterns discussed here and not <strong>in</strong> non-coord<strong>in</strong>ates.


4.4 Reference Transfer <strong>in</strong> Noncoord<strong>in</strong>ate Constructions 101<br />

the agreement feature value were asked what motivated this choice for this specific gender<br />

and they confirmed that they assumed both coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns were denoted by the common<br />

noun xori ‘spaces’, which is mascul<strong>in</strong>e <strong>in</strong> gender. The above sentence <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g the implied<br />

noun can be rewritten as follows:<br />

(100) I<br />

dromi ke i platies<br />

the.masc.pl roads.masc.pl and the.fem.pl squares.fem.pl<br />

<strong>in</strong>e jemat-i xori<br />

me kosmo<br />

are.pl full.masc.pl places.masc.pl with people<br />

‘The roads and the alleys are places full of people’<br />

As <strong>in</strong> the examples presented by Nunberg (1995) and Pollard and Sag (1994), the<br />

implied miss<strong>in</strong>g noun seems to have a semantic relation to the two nouns that are present<br />

<strong>in</strong> the coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase. In the case of MG, the relation must be one of hyponymy. The<br />

implied miss<strong>in</strong>g noun functions as the superord<strong>in</strong>ate or cover term of the two nouns that<br />

are present <strong>in</strong> the coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase and morphosyntactically determ<strong>in</strong>es the agreement<br />

result s<strong>in</strong>ce the predicative adjective is forced to show morphosyntactic agreement with the<br />

implied noun. Therefore, <strong>in</strong> example (100), the noun xori ‘spaces’ is the superord<strong>in</strong>ate or<br />

cover term of the two nouns dromi ‘roads’ and platies ‘squares’ and, although it is omitted,<br />

it determ<strong>in</strong>es the gender feature of the adjective. We need to note that the noun xori<br />

‘spaces’ is not the only possible superord<strong>in</strong>ate term. In fact, a number of consultants chose<br />

the noun perioxes’ ‘areas’ as the hypernymic term which is fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e <strong>in</strong> gender and it can<br />

also function as a cover term for both nouns. These consultants were fewer (4 out of 26)<br />

when compared to the 15 (out of 26) consultants who chose mascul<strong>in</strong>e and the 13 (out of<br />

26) who chose neuter.<br />

The same process takes place <strong>in</strong> animate coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns. In example (101), the<br />

two conjuncts resolve to the expected semantic gender fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e plural and the unexpected<br />

neuter plural. The latter occurs due to the phenomenon of referential agreement. Thus, an<br />

implied miss<strong>in</strong>g noun is brought <strong>in</strong>to the context, such as atoma ‘persons’, which is neut <strong>in</strong><br />

gender and which determ<strong>in</strong>es morphosyntactically the agreement gender of the predicative<br />

adjective and functions as the superord<strong>in</strong>ate or cover term for the two conjuncts jajades<br />

‘grandmothers’ and koritsia ‘girls’:<br />

(101) I jajades<br />

ke<br />

the.fem.pl grandmothers.fem.pl and<br />

<strong>in</strong>e xarumen-es/-a<br />

are happy.fem/neut.pl<br />

‘The grandmothers and the girls are happy’<br />

ta<br />

the.neut.pl<br />

koritsia<br />

girls.neut.pl<br />

The first issue that needs to be discussed with regard to the phenomenon of referential<br />

agreement <strong>in</strong> MG is that <strong>in</strong> the specific coord<strong>in</strong>ate structures gender is the ma<strong>in</strong> feature<br />

that is affected (also found <strong>in</strong> Italian), and not number, as <strong>in</strong> the case of English. Our data<br />

showed that the number feature does not show any unexpected behaviour (i.e. s<strong>in</strong>gular<br />

agreement) s<strong>in</strong>ce number agreement is always plural with coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns irrespective of<br />

the number of the conjuncts. In fact, s<strong>in</strong>gular verb agreement is ungrammatical when the<br />

conjuncts refer to different entities. On the other hand, the adjective has an unexpected<br />

gender form. This gender form is the same as the gender form of the implied noun that is<br />

referred to by the consultants but never occurs <strong>in</strong> the phrase. Therefore, <strong>in</strong> MG referential<br />

agreement <strong>in</strong>volves the gender feature and not the number feature, as <strong>in</strong> other languages.<br />

The second issue is that referential agreement <strong>in</strong> the MG patterns differs when compared<br />

to the correspond<strong>in</strong>g English ones with regard to the relation of the nouns that are<br />

present <strong>in</strong> the phrase and the referred implied noun. In English, it seems that the relation<br />

is one of metonymy, where the name of one entity is used to refer to another entity, as <strong>in</strong>


4.5 An Approach to Gender <strong>Agreement</strong> <strong>in</strong> MG 102<br />

example (87b), or one of hyponymy, where the implied noun functions as the superord<strong>in</strong>ate<br />

term of the two conjuncts, which are part of the coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase, as <strong>in</strong> examples (96)<br />

and (97). This cover term, which is <strong>in</strong>directly implied, determ<strong>in</strong>es the gender value <strong>in</strong> the<br />

predicative adjective. In MG, it seems to be strictly a hyponymic relation where the two<br />

conjuncts are hyponyms of the superord<strong>in</strong>ate implied noun, at least <strong>in</strong> the cases we have<br />

presented so far.<br />

Also, <strong>in</strong> some cases the consultants do not br<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>to the discourse the same implied<br />

noun but a different one. For <strong>in</strong>stance, as already mentioned <strong>in</strong> example (100) most of the<br />

speakers brought <strong>in</strong>to the context the noun xori ‘spaces’ but some of them brought <strong>in</strong>to the<br />

context the noun perioxes’ ‘areas’. In both cases, the two nouns are considered hypernyms<br />

of the two conjuncts dromi ‘roads’ and platies ‘squares’. Thus, we argue that the consultants<br />

br<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>to the discourse SOME implied noun that it is necessarily the hypernym of<br />

the two coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns. This noun has specific agreement features which determ<strong>in</strong>e the<br />

agreement features of the predicative adjective. The implied noun may differ from speaker<br />

to speaker depend<strong>in</strong>g on the hierarchical group<strong>in</strong>g of the lexical items <strong>in</strong> each speaker’s<br />

m<strong>in</strong>d. In most cases, however, speakers tend to br<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>to the context the same implied<br />

noun.<br />

F<strong>in</strong>ally, the data we have collected and presented to the consultants yield the unexpected<br />

patterns discussed so far. The nature of the phenomenon, which is context dependent,<br />

may allow the possibility of additional unexpected gender values result<strong>in</strong>g from other<br />

coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns. This would require more research and a broader collection of data with<br />

a larger number of consultants to detect a comprehensive list of all the possible unexpected<br />

patterns.<br />

Thus, we have argued that the unexpected gender patterns <strong>in</strong> MG display the phenomenon<br />

of referential agreement. Referential agreement refers to the mismatch gender<br />

agreement between two coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns and the predicative adjective/participle of the<br />

sentence. Accord<strong>in</strong>g to referential agreement, an implied noun is brought <strong>in</strong>to the context,<br />

it functions as the superord<strong>in</strong>ate term of the coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns and its agreement features<br />

are copied by the predicative adjective/participle. Referential agreement <strong>in</strong> MG affects only<br />

the gender feature. In other languages, such as English or Italian, it affects the number<br />

feature or both the number and gender features, respectively.<br />

4.5 An Approach to Gender <strong>Agreement</strong> <strong>in</strong> MG<br />

This section presents an analysis of the expected agreement patterns <strong>in</strong> MG coord<strong>in</strong>ate<br />

nouns us<strong>in</strong>g the set-based theory. Follow<strong>in</strong>g Sadler (2006), we will assume the standard rule<br />

of gender resolution for the syntactic patterns of <strong>in</strong>animate nouns and we will <strong>in</strong>troduce<br />

a specification <strong>in</strong> the phrase structure rule for the semantic patterns of animate nouns.<br />

F<strong>in</strong>ally, we will also propose an analysis of the referential agreement patterns based on<br />

LFG.<br />

4.5.1 Problems of the Current Theories for the MG data<br />

Before we present our analysis, we will discuss the various problems of the different theorerical<br />

approaches for the MG data.<br />

Dalrymple and Kaplan’s set-based approach for gender resolution <strong>in</strong> coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrases<br />

accounts for syntactic cases of gender resolution and not for semantic cases of gender<br />

resolution found <strong>in</strong> animate coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns <strong>in</strong> most languages. MG animate coord<strong>in</strong>ate<br />

phrases show semantic agreement, and therefore their theory of syntactic resolution cannot<br />

capture all the agreement patterns <strong>in</strong> MG.<br />

If both animate and <strong>in</strong>animate nouns are seen as com<strong>in</strong>g under the purview of the<br />

marker set approach <strong>in</strong> order to derive resolution apply<strong>in</strong>g the union operation, it is nec-


4.5 An Approach to Gender <strong>Agreement</strong> <strong>in</strong> MG 103<br />

essary to employ two different groups of marker sets for the animate and <strong>in</strong>animate nouns.<br />

In MG <strong>in</strong>animate nouns, we need to generate the resolution patterns <strong>in</strong> table (4.15) 18 :<br />

Table 4.15: <strong>Agreement</strong> of Inanimate SG/PL Coord<strong>in</strong>ate <strong>Noun</strong>s<br />

S<strong>in</strong>gular Conjuncts<br />

NP1 NP2 AP NP1 NP2 AP<br />

msg msg mpl>npl msg fsg npl>mpl/fpl<br />

fsg fsg fpl>npl msg nsg npl<br />

nsg nsg npl fsg nsg npl<br />

Plural Conjuncts<br />

NP1 NP2 AP NP1 NP2 AP<br />

mpl mpl mpl mpl fpl mpl>npl>fpl<br />

fpl fpl fpl mpl npl npl<br />

npl npl npl fpl npl npl<br />

The follow<strong>in</strong>g marker sets for masc, fem and neut <strong>in</strong>animate nouns are assigned:<br />

(102) Inanimate <strong>Noun</strong>s<br />

masc{m}<br />

fem{f}<br />

neut{m,f}<br />

Once the union operation is applied, the assignments above predict the expected resolution<br />

facts <strong>in</strong> table (4.15), but not the unexpected ones:<br />

(103) Union Operation <strong>in</strong> Inanimate <strong>Noun</strong>s<br />

{m}(MASC) ∪ {m}(MASC) = {m}(MASC)<br />

{f}(FEM) ∪ {f}(FEM) = {f}(FEM)<br />

{m,f}(NEUT) ∪ {m,f}(NEUT) = {m,f}(NEUT)<br />

{m}(MASC) ∪ {f}(FEM) = {m,f}(NEUT)<br />

{m}(MASC) ∪ {m,f}(NEUT) = {m,f}(NEUT)<br />

{f}(FEM) ∪ {m,f}(NEUT) = {m,f}(NEUT)<br />

The resolution patterns of animate nouns are different from those of <strong>in</strong>animate nouns<br />

and we need to assume different marker sets accord<strong>in</strong>g to the patterns <strong>in</strong> table (4.16),<br />

repeated from above:<br />

18 As already discussed above, the unexpected fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e plural agreement occurs <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>animate abstract<br />

s<strong>in</strong>gular and plural nouns only.


4.5 An Approach to Gender <strong>Agreement</strong> <strong>in</strong> MG 104<br />

Table 4.16: <strong>Agreement</strong> of Animate SG/PL Coord<strong>in</strong>ate <strong>Noun</strong>s<br />

S<strong>in</strong>gular Conjuncts<br />

NP1 NP2 AP NP1 NP2 AP<br />

msg msg mpl msg fsg mpl<br />

fsg fsg fpl msg nm/f /0sg mpl<br />

nsg nsg npl fsg nm/0sg mpl<br />

fsg nf sg fpl/(mpl)<br />

Plural Conjuncts<br />

NP1 NP2 AP NP1 NP2 AP<br />

mpl mpl mpl mpl fpl mpl<br />

fpl fpl fpl mpl nm/f /0pl mpl<br />

npl npl npl fpl nm/0pl mpl/npl<br />

fpl nf pl fpl/(mpl)/npl<br />

The marker sets below can produce the desired results for the animate nouns:<br />

(104) Animate <strong>Noun</strong>s<br />

masc{f,n}<br />

fem{f}<br />

neut{n}<br />

The <strong>in</strong>put is aga<strong>in</strong> the successful production of the expected resolution patterns but it<br />

is impossible to account for the semantic pattern [fpl & nf pl=fpl] and the unexpected<br />

patterns:<br />

(105) Union Operation <strong>in</strong> Animate <strong>Noun</strong>s<br />

{f,n} (MASC) ∪ {f,n}(MASC)= {f,n}(MASC)<br />

{f} (FEM) ∪ {f} (FEM) = {f} (FEM)<br />

{n} (NEUT) ∪ {n}(NEUT) = {n}(NEUT)<br />

{f,n} (MASC) ∪ {f}(FEM) = {f,n}(MASC)<br />

{f,n} (MASC) ∪ {n}(NEUT) = {f,n}(MASC)<br />

{f} (FEM) ∪ {n}(NEUT) = {f,n}(MASC)<br />

Several drawbacks result from the use of different marker sets. Firstly, the separate<br />

marker sets are not economical, as would be desirable. Also, the marker sets assumed for<br />

animate nouns cannot capture all the semantic patterns. The noun comb<strong>in</strong>ations [fsg &<br />

nf sg] and [fpl & nf pl] are not captured and therefore additional constra<strong>in</strong>ts are required<br />

to the exist<strong>in</strong>g PS rule, as <strong>in</strong> Slovene. In addition, <strong>in</strong> both animate and <strong>in</strong>animate nouns<br />

none of the unexpected patterns are accounted for by the marker sets assumed and therefore<br />

further constra<strong>in</strong>ts must be imposed so as to capture the unexpected patterns successfully.<br />

Therefore, such an approach is undesirable.<br />

Wechsler and Zlatic’s (2003) proposal also seems problematic for the gender agreement<br />

patterns found <strong>in</strong> MG. Although it accounts for resolution <strong>in</strong> animate nouns accord<strong>in</strong>g<br />

to the semantic pr<strong>in</strong>ciple and resolution <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>animate nouns accord<strong>in</strong>g to the syntactic<br />

pr<strong>in</strong>ciple, their analysis seems to work only for languages with common resolution patterns<br />

<strong>in</strong> animate and <strong>in</strong>animate nouns and not for languages with different resolution patterns<br />

<strong>in</strong> the two groups of nouns like MG. Follow<strong>in</strong>g Wechsler and Zlatić (2003), we assume the<br />

logic of distributivity <strong>in</strong> MG animate nouns and we assign the semantic values ‘female’ for<br />

a female group where all members are female and ‘non-female’ for a male group or a mixed<br />

gender group. E-gender nouns, like neuter, do not have any semantic correlates and are


4.5 An Approach to Gender <strong>Agreement</strong> <strong>in</strong> MG 105<br />

exempt from the logic of distributivity. This assignment would give the desired results <strong>in</strong><br />

animate nouns.<br />

Let us turn to MG <strong>in</strong>animate nouns which resolve to neuter gender <strong>in</strong> mixed gender<br />

conjuncts. If we assign the grammatical gender values of <strong>in</strong>animates based on the correspond<strong>in</strong>g<br />

semantic values of animates, then each positively specified grammatical gender<br />

such as fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e is represented as {f} and each negatively specified gender such as nonfem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e<br />

(i.e. mascul<strong>in</strong>e) is represented as a null set {} and neuter nouns are represented<br />

as the s<strong>in</strong>gleton set {n}. To calculate the gender of <strong>in</strong>animate nouns we need to remove the<br />

e-gender nouns by <strong>in</strong>tersect<strong>in</strong>g the calculated set with the semantic genders (s-genders).<br />

This would result <strong>in</strong> the desired patterns <strong>in</strong> coord<strong>in</strong>ate structures with conjuncts which are<br />

either both mascul<strong>in</strong>e or fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e, such as <strong>in</strong> {f}∩{f} and {}∩{}. However, <strong>in</strong> coord<strong>in</strong>ate<br />

structures with neuter conjuncts or mixed gender conjuncts as <strong>in</strong> {}∩{f} or {}∩{n} the<br />

result is mascul<strong>in</strong>e and not neuter as required. This is illustrated as follows:<br />

(106) MG<br />

a. Set of s-genders<br />

Gs ={f}<br />

b. Set representations of the s-genders<br />

fem:{f} (


4.5 An Approach to Gender <strong>Agreement</strong> <strong>in</strong> MG 106<br />

The above rank<strong>in</strong>g would account for the different gender patterns found <strong>in</strong> animate and<br />

<strong>in</strong>animate nouns because the feature [Human] determ<strong>in</strong>es resolution only <strong>in</strong> mixed gender<br />

conjuncts and also the ident constra<strong>in</strong>t ∀c[identG(c,ph)], which accounts for identical<br />

gender conjuncts, is placed higher than the rest of the constra<strong>in</strong>ts which refer to gender.<br />

In mixed gender cases, the ident constra<strong>in</strong>t ∀c[identG(c,ph)] will be violated and then<br />

the gender choice will be determ<strong>in</strong>ed by shift<strong>in</strong>g from the least marked gender (neuter) to<br />

the next least marked (mascul<strong>in</strong>e) when the conjo<strong>in</strong>ed phrase is [+Human]. However, the<br />

above rank<strong>in</strong>g is unable to capture the pattern [fsg & nf sg=fpl] or [fpl & nf pl=fpl] <strong>in</strong><br />

animate nouns s<strong>in</strong>ce the optimal form would necessarily be mpl and not fpl because the<br />

constra<strong>in</strong>t *F is placed higher <strong>in</strong> the rank<strong>in</strong>g and not lower. In addition, Badecker (2008)<br />

argues that <strong>in</strong>animate s<strong>in</strong>gular coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns with a mascul<strong>in</strong>e and a fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e conjunct<br />

resolve to neuter and the correspond<strong>in</strong>g plural ones resolve to mascul<strong>in</strong>e. Our data showed<br />

that such a difference does not necessarily occur s<strong>in</strong>ce the consultants <strong>in</strong> coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrases<br />

of both numbers pick up the same resolution genders (i.e. neuter and mascul<strong>in</strong>e) but with<br />

greater preference to one or to the other possibly related to the number of conjuncts. Such<br />

a preference cannot be stated <strong>in</strong> terms of the OT ranked constra<strong>in</strong>st s<strong>in</strong>ce OT assumes<br />

only one optimal form. With regard to the unexpected patterns, Badecker’s OT analysis<br />

cannot capture these patterns too. Many different constra<strong>in</strong>ts need to be imposed and for<br />

a theory like OT, which admits only the optimal form, the several agreement choices of the<br />

exceptional referential patterns are difficult to account for.<br />

F<strong>in</strong>ally, the major drawback of Sadler’s (2006) analysis is that it cannot accommodate<br />

the MG data due to the wide range of unexpected resolution patterns which are not either<br />

syntactically or semantically motivated but referentially determ<strong>in</strong>ed. Also, it might be seen<br />

as a disadvantage the use of the additional feature semgend with values male and female<br />

s<strong>in</strong>ce it may not be required by languages that do not impose the dist<strong>in</strong>ction male/female<br />

but other dist<strong>in</strong>ctions, such as non-/rational, as <strong>in</strong> Dravidian languages. In the last case,<br />

we should postulate a different feature with different values too which might result to<br />

redundancies <strong>in</strong> the grammar. Even though her analysis could be seen as language specific,<br />

it can be easily assumed for other languages s<strong>in</strong>ce the standard PS rule is ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong><br />

<strong>in</strong>animate nouns, which follow syntactic resolution, and we can <strong>in</strong>troduce any changes <strong>in</strong><br />

the semantic rule of animate nouns, which may differ across languages. We will attempt a<br />

similar type of analysis for the expected cases of MG.<br />

To conclude, we presented certa<strong>in</strong> problems of the theories on gender resolution with<br />

regard to the MG data, and we argue that none of them fully captures the range of<br />

resolution results that are found <strong>in</strong> MG and especially those resolution patterns that are<br />

derived referentially. Next we turn to our analysis.<br />

4.5.2 An Analysis of the MG Expected Patterns<br />

The data analysis showed that the expected patterns of MG animate and <strong>in</strong>animate coord<strong>in</strong>ates<br />

differ <strong>in</strong> the resolved gender value and the gender resolution pr<strong>in</strong>ciple. Animate<br />

coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns with mixed gender conjuncts resolve to mascul<strong>in</strong>e unless all conjuncts<br />

denote females <strong>in</strong> which case resolution is fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e. If conjuncts have the same gender they<br />

resolve to that shared gender, irrespective of the referents of the nouns. Thus, animate<br />

coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns show semantic resolution. Inanimate coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrases with mixed gender<br />

conjuncts resolve to neuter. If the conjuncts share the same gender then they resolve<br />

to that shared gender. Thus, <strong>in</strong>animate coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns follow the syntactic pr<strong>in</strong>ciple of<br />

resolution.<br />

Accord<strong>in</strong>g to Kazana (2007), the first task is to propose a unified solution for both<br />

groups of nouns <strong>in</strong> order to avoid problems of redundancy. To achieve that we need to<br />

employ the same marker sets for both animate and <strong>in</strong>animate nouns and use the set-union<br />

operation to derive the required resolution results. Assum<strong>in</strong>g the marker set decomposition,


4.5 An Approach to Gender <strong>Agreement</strong> <strong>in</strong> MG 107<br />

we represent the genders for animate and <strong>in</strong>animate nouns with the same group of sets.<br />

The sets assumed for both groups of nouns are those of the <strong>in</strong>animate nouns s<strong>in</strong>ce neuter is<br />

the resolved gender for the <strong>in</strong>animate nouns and also neuter occurs as the resolved gender<br />

<strong>in</strong> animate neuter nouns irrespective of the referents. Therefore, the marker sets used to<br />

derive the syntactic gender <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>animate nouns can equally be adopted for the derivation of<br />

both the semantic patterns and the patterns that show feature match<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> animate nouns.<br />

The marker sets are the follow<strong>in</strong>g:<br />

(108) Marker Sets for Animate & Inanimate <strong>Noun</strong>s<br />

masc{m}<br />

fem {f}<br />

neut {m,f}<br />

(Kazana, 2007)<br />

Inanimate coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns are straightforwardly derived by the above assumption<br />

account<strong>in</strong>g for all the expected non-exceptional cases. The <strong>in</strong>animate expected agreement<br />

patterns are repeated below:<br />

Table 4.17: <strong>Agreement</strong> of Inanimate Coord<strong>in</strong>ate <strong>Noun</strong>s<br />

S<strong>in</strong>gular or Plural Conjuncts<br />

NP1 NP2 AP NP1 NP2 AP<br />

msg/pl msg/pl mpl msg/pl fsg/pl npl<br />

fsg/pl fsg/pl fpl msg/pl nsg/pl npl<br />

nsg/pl nsg/pl npl fsg/pl nsg/pl npl<br />

When the specific marker sets are comb<strong>in</strong>ed through set-union the result is the neuter<br />

gender <strong>in</strong> all mixed gender coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns and the gender of the conjuncts <strong>in</strong> all uniform<br />

gender coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns:<br />

(109) Union Operation <strong>in</strong> Inanimate <strong>Noun</strong>s<br />

{m}(MASC) ∪ {m}(MASC) = {m}(MASC)<br />

{f}(FEM) ∪ {f}(FEM) = {f}(FEM)<br />

{m,f}(NEUT) ∪ {m,f}(NEUT) = {m,f}(NEUT)<br />

{m}(MASC) ∪ {f}(FEM) = {m,f}(NEUT)<br />

{m}(MASC) ∪ {m,f}(NEUT) = {m,f}(NEUT)<br />

{f}(FEM) ∪ {m,f}(NEUT) = {m,f}(NEUT)<br />

(Kazana, 2007)<br />

The LFG phrase structure rule that captures the necessary subset relations is the standard<br />

syntactic rule of coord<strong>in</strong>ation proposed by Dalrymple and Kaplan (2000). However,<br />

follow<strong>in</strong>g Sadler (2006, 14) we also assume that nouns have the lexical specification anim<br />

+/−. Thus, the standard syntactic rule of coord<strong>in</strong>ation is assumed:<br />

(110) Syntactic Rule - Inanimate <strong>Noun</strong>s<br />

NP → NP CONJ NP<br />

↓∈↑ ↓∈↑<br />

(↓anim)= − (↓anim)= −<br />

(↓ gend) ⊆ (↑gend) (↓gend) ⊆ (↑gend)<br />

(Kazana, 2007)<br />

This rule states that <strong>in</strong> a coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase each NP conjunct daughter needs to be a<br />

member of the conjunct set of the mother node. In the second l<strong>in</strong>e, it is specified that each


4.5 An Approach to Gender <strong>Agreement</strong> <strong>in</strong> MG 108<br />

conjunct daughter must be <strong>in</strong>animate while the last l<strong>in</strong>e states that the set value of each<br />

conjunct daughter needs to be a subset of the set value of the mother node, def<strong>in</strong>ed as the<br />

smallest set. Thus, the expected resolution patterns <strong>in</strong> MG <strong>in</strong>animate nouns are captured<br />

us<strong>in</strong>g closed sets for the gender features and they undergo resolution us<strong>in</strong>g set union.<br />

The same marker sets are also assumed to account for the resolution patterns <strong>in</strong> MG<br />

animate nouns. The expected agreement patterns are repeated below:<br />

Table 4.18: <strong>Agreement</strong> of Animate Coord<strong>in</strong>ate <strong>Noun</strong>s<br />

S<strong>in</strong>gular or Plural Conjuncts<br />

NP1 NP2 AP NP1 NP2 AP<br />

msg/pl msg/pl mpl msg/pl fsg/pl mpl<br />

fsg/pl fsg/pl fpl msg/pl nm/f /0sg/pl mpl<br />

nsg/pl nsg/pl npl fsg/pl nm/0sg/pl mpl<br />

fsg/pl nf sg/pl fpl/(>mpl)<br />

Any attempt to apply these marker sets to capture the expected cases results partly <strong>in</strong><br />

the wrong gender feature value s<strong>in</strong>ce the desired gender feature for the mixed gender cases<br />

is the mascul<strong>in</strong>e and not the neuter one, which is generated, as shown below:<br />

(111) Union Operation <strong>in</strong> Animate <strong>Noun</strong>s<br />

{m}(MASC) ∪ {m}(MASC) = {m}(MASC)<br />

{f}(FEM) ∪ {f}(FEM) = {f}(FEM)<br />

{m,f}(NEUT) ∪ {m,f}(NEUT) = {m,f}(NEUT)<br />

{m}(MASC) ∪ {f}(FEM) = {m,f}(NEUT)*<br />

{m}(MASC) ∪ {m,f}(NEUT) = {m,f}(NEUT)*<br />

{f}(FEM) ∪ {m,f}(NEUT) = {m,f}(NEUT)*<br />

Thus, set union cannot be used for the resolution patterns of animate nouns.<br />

In order to overcome this problem, we need to employ two additional phrase structure<br />

rules for the patterns of animate nouns without us<strong>in</strong>g set union for these cases. The first<br />

rule should <strong>in</strong>corporate the necessary specifications to capture coord<strong>in</strong>ations with nouns<br />

that share the same marker sets. This rule should postulate the requirement that if all<br />

daughters share the same marker set, then use that marker set. This is formalised as<br />

follows:<br />

(112) Same Gender Rule - Animate <strong>Noun</strong>s<br />

NP → NP CONJ NP<br />

↓∈↑ ↓∈↑<br />

(↓anim)=+ (↓anim)=+<br />

(↑gend)= (↓gend) (↑gend)=(↓gend)<br />

(Kazana, 2007)<br />

In the above rule, apart from the set membership requirement, two additional specifications<br />

are <strong>in</strong>troduced. The first one requires the conjuncts to be lexically specified as<br />

anim +, and the second requires the conjunct daughters to share the same gender with<br />

the mother node.<br />

The second rule is more complicated s<strong>in</strong>ce it should capture coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrases with<br />

nouns that have different marker sets. In particular, we observed that if the genders of<br />

the conjuncts are different, then we need to use mascul<strong>in</strong>e ({m}) or optionally if conjuncts<br />

denote female <strong>in</strong>dividuals then we need to use fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e ({f}). To achieve that we need<br />

to employ the extra feature semgend with values male and female, proposed by Sadler


4.5 An Approach to Gender <strong>Agreement</strong> <strong>in</strong> MG 109<br />

(2006). Thus, the lexical entries that refer to male <strong>in</strong>dividuals are lexically specified as<br />

(↑semgend)=male and those that refer to female <strong>in</strong>dividuals are lexically specified as<br />

(↑semgend)= female. The rule is formalised as follows:<br />

(113) Mixed Gender Rule - Animate <strong>Noun</strong>s<br />

NP → NP CONJ NP<br />

↓∈↑ ↓∈↑<br />

(↓anim)=+ (↓anim)=+<br />

((↑∈)gend)=(↓gend)<br />

{(↑gend)= {m}<br />

∨<br />

[(↑gend)= {f}<br />

¬(↑∈semgend)= female]}<br />

The first two parts of the above rule impose the set membership requirement and<br />

the specification that the nouns should be lexically specified as anim +. The third l<strong>in</strong>e<br />

postulates the restriction that the daughters have dist<strong>in</strong>ct marker sets, referr<strong>in</strong>g to mixed<br />

gender coord<strong>in</strong>ations. Then, two possibilites arise, either resolution is mascul<strong>in</strong>e ({m}),<br />

or resolution is fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e ({f}) <strong>in</strong> which case all of the conjunct daughters should denote<br />

a female <strong>in</strong>dividual. In the last l<strong>in</strong>e, negation is expressed universally given a wide scope<br />

<strong>in</strong>terpretation:<br />

(114) ¬(↑∈semgend)= female<br />

This means that there is no member of the set whose value is non-female or else for all<br />

daughters the value is constra<strong>in</strong>ed to be female.<br />

To summarise, <strong>in</strong> this section we presented one PS rule that accounts for the expected<br />

resolution patterns <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>animate nouns, us<strong>in</strong>g the crossl<strong>in</strong>guistic set-union approach, and<br />

two separate PS rules that account for the expected resolution patterns <strong>in</strong> animate nouns,<br />

<strong>in</strong>troduc<strong>in</strong>g specifications for semantic resolution.<br />

Our approach, which resembles that of Sadler (2006), has a number of advantages and<br />

disadvantages. The ma<strong>in</strong> advantage is that it captures all the expected patterns <strong>in</strong> animate<br />

and <strong>in</strong>animate nouns us<strong>in</strong>g the same marker sets for both groups of nouns. Also, it uses<br />

the standard PS rule of coord<strong>in</strong>ate structures regard<strong>in</strong>g the gender feature alongside the<br />

widely adopted set-union operation <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>animate nouns. It postulates separate PS rules<br />

only for animate nouns whose resolution patterns are language specific.<br />

A problematic aspect is that we also employ the extra feature semgend <strong>in</strong> the fstructure.<br />

Although this is not advantageous for LFG as it is an extra feature, it turns<br />

out to be useful s<strong>in</strong>ce it is a placeholder for a semantic treatment of the present resolution<br />

rules s<strong>in</strong>ce it captures the dist<strong>in</strong>ction between male and female denotations of nouns.<br />

The most important problem, however, is that it does not capture the exceptional patterns<br />

<strong>in</strong> both groups of nouns. A different approach needs to be assumed for these unexpected<br />

patterns and this is where we will turn to next.<br />

4.5.3 An Approach to the MG Referential <strong>Agreement</strong> Patterns<br />

So far we presented an analysis of the expected patterns of gender resolution <strong>in</strong> coord<strong>in</strong>ate<br />

phrases. The unexpected patterns cannot be captured by the above proposal s<strong>in</strong>ce they are<br />

referentially motivated based on discourse conditions. Thus, we will propose an analysis<br />

tak<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>to account the discourse conditions imposed by the native speakers.<br />

The central idea beh<strong>in</strong>d the phenomenon of referential agreement <strong>in</strong> MG <strong>in</strong>volves SOME


4.5 An Approach to Gender <strong>Agreement</strong> <strong>in</strong> MG 110<br />

implied noun 19 brought <strong>in</strong>to the discourse by native speakers. The speakers when utter<strong>in</strong>g<br />

a coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase modified by a predicative adjective/participle do not necessarily<br />

obey the syntactic or semantic expected patterns of resolution, but they follow referential<br />

agreement by implicitly <strong>in</strong>troduc<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>to the context a specific noun with its own morphosyntactic<br />

features. Such a noun will be referred to as the Contextually Introduced<br />

Referent 20 . The agreement target (i.e. the predicative adjective or participle) is forced<br />

to agree with the morphosyntactic features (i.e. gender and number) of the Contextually<br />

Introduced Referent, which is implicitly present <strong>in</strong> the sentence and which also functions as<br />

the superord<strong>in</strong>ate/hypernymic term of the coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns. In MG, predicative adjectives<br />

agree grammatically with the subject of the sentence and occur <strong>in</strong> copular constructions.<br />

For the analysis of the MG copular constructions, we will follow the open function xcomp<br />

analysis 21 proposed by Dalrymple (2001) and Dalrymple et al. (2004a). This analysis assumes<br />

that the copular verb <strong>in</strong>e ‘be’ subcategorises for an xcomp only, whereas the subj<br />

occurs outside the angled brackets <strong>in</strong> the semantic form and it is not a semantic argument<br />

of the verb. This type of analysis is preferred for languages <strong>in</strong> which the postcopular complement<br />

shows agreement with the subject of the copula, as <strong>in</strong> MG.<br />

Let us first consider an expected case of gender agreement. The follow<strong>in</strong>g example<br />

consists of two s<strong>in</strong>gular mascul<strong>in</strong>e nouns that syntactically resolve to mascul<strong>in</strong>e:<br />

(115) O p<strong>in</strong>akas<br />

the.masc.sg picture.masc.sg<br />

<strong>in</strong>e megali<br />

are.pl big.masc.pl<br />

‘The picture and the sofa are big’<br />

ke<br />

and<br />

The f-structure of the sentence is presented below:<br />

o<br />

the.masc.sg<br />

kanapes<br />

sofa.masc.sg<br />

19 We use capital letters s<strong>in</strong>ce the implied noun assumed by native speakers may vary from speaker to<br />

speaker but the agreement features of different nouns may co<strong>in</strong>cide.<br />

20 We will briefly refer to the Contextually Introduced Referent by the acronym CIR.<br />

21 Dalrymple et al. (2004a) also propose the closed complement predl<strong>in</strong>k analysis which is required<br />

when the postcopular element already has a subject. Accord<strong>in</strong>g to Dalrymple et al. (2004a, 193) such<br />

constructions are that-clauses, certa<strong>in</strong> gerunds and modal uses of the copula with null pronom<strong>in</strong>al subjects.


4.5 An Approach to Gender <strong>Agreement</strong> <strong>in</strong> MG 111<br />

(116) ⎡<br />

⎤<br />

pred ‘be subj’<br />

⎢ ⎡⎧⎡<br />

⎤⎫⎤⎥<br />

⎢ ⎢<br />

pred ‘picture’<br />

⎥<br />

⎢ ⎢ ⎢<br />

⎥ ⎥⎥<br />

⎢ ⎢ ⎢def<br />

+ ⎥ ⎥⎥<br />

⎢ ⎢ ⎢<br />

⎥ ⎥⎥<br />

⎢ ⎢ ⎢<br />

⎢ ⎢ ⎢person<br />

3 ⎥ ⎥⎥<br />

⎥ ⎥⎥<br />

⎢ ⎢ ⎢<br />

⎢ ⎢ ⎣num<br />

sg<br />

⎥ ⎥⎥<br />

⎦ ⎥⎥<br />

⎢ ⎢⎪⎨<br />

⎪⎬<br />

⎥⎥<br />

⎢ ⎢ gend masc<br />

⎥⎥<br />

⎥⎥<br />

⎢ ⎢ ⎡ ⎤ ⎥⎥<br />

⎢ ⎢<br />

⎢ ⎢ pred ‘sofa’<br />

⎥⎥<br />

⎥⎥<br />

⎢ ⎢ ⎢ ⎥ ⎥⎥<br />

⎢ ⎢ ⎢def<br />

+ ⎥ ⎥⎥<br />

⎢subj<br />

⎢ ⎢ ⎥ ⎥⎥<br />

⎢ ⎢ ⎢<br />

⎢ ⎢ ⎢person<br />

3 ⎥ ⎥⎥<br />

⎥ ⎥⎥<br />

⎢ ⎢ ⎢<br />

⎢ ⎢ ⎣num<br />

sg<br />

⎥ ⎥⎥<br />

⎦ ⎥⎥<br />

⎢ ⎢<br />

⎢ ⎢<br />

⎪⎩<br />

⎪⎭<br />

⎥⎥<br />

gend masc ⎥⎥<br />

⎢ ⎢<br />

⎥⎥<br />

⎢ ⎢<br />

⎥⎥<br />

⎢ ⎢person<br />

3 ⎥⎥<br />

⎢ ⎢<br />

⎥⎥<br />

⎢ ⎢<br />

⎢ ⎢num<br />

pl ⎥⎥<br />

⎥⎥<br />

⎢ ⎢<br />

⎢ ⎣gend<br />

masc<br />

⎥⎥<br />

⎦ ⎥<br />

⎢ conj and<br />

⎥<br />

⎢ ⎡<br />

⎤⎥<br />

⎢ pred ‘big ’ ⎥<br />

⎣xcomp<br />

⎣ <br />

⎥<br />

⎦<br />

subj<br />

In the f-structure, the copular verb <strong>in</strong>e ‘be’ subcategorises for an open complement<br />

xcomp, which is the adjective megali ‘big’. S<strong>in</strong>ce the latter is predicative, it should behave<br />

as verbs do. Thus, it requires a subj, which is the same as the subj of the verb <strong>in</strong>e<br />

‘be’. This subj is the coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase and it has a plural number and a masc gender,<br />

which is the resolved gender of the two conjuncts. The above syntactic <strong>in</strong>formation can be<br />

captured <strong>in</strong> the lexical entry of the verb <strong>in</strong>e ‘be’, illustrated below:<br />

(117) <strong>in</strong>e v (↑pred) = ‘be〈xcomp〉subj’<br />

(↑subj) = (↑xcomp subj)<br />

S<strong>in</strong>ce the subject of the verb ‘be’ is structure shared with the subject of the predicative<br />

adjective, the lexical entry of the latter should also specify the follow<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>formation:<br />

(118) megali (↑pred) = ‘big〈subj〉’<br />

(↑subj num)= pl<br />

(↑subj gend)= masc<br />

Thus, <strong>in</strong> the expected pattern of gender resolution the adjective megali ‘big’ agrees with<br />

the syntactic controller which is the subj coord<strong>in</strong>ate noun phrase. The above analysis<br />

works effectively for the expected patterns <strong>in</strong> MG.<br />

The same predicative adjective, however, also presents an alternative unexpected case<br />

of gender agreement, which has the same agreement features with those of SOME implied<br />

noun that occurs <strong>in</strong> the context. For example, <strong>in</strong> (119) the adjective shows unexpected<br />

neuter agreement, which might be the gender of the contextually implied noun pragmata<br />

‘th<strong>in</strong>gs’:<br />

(119) O p<strong>in</strong>akas<br />

the.masc.sg picture.masc.sg<br />

<strong>in</strong>e megala<br />

are.pl big.neut.pl<br />

‘The picture and the sofa are big’<br />

ke<br />

and<br />

o<br />

the.masc.sg<br />

kanapes<br />

sofa.masc.sg


4.5 An Approach to Gender <strong>Agreement</strong> <strong>in</strong> MG 112<br />

Therefore, the unexpected patterns require the predicative adjective, which is the agreement<br />

target, to display agreement features that do not agree with the syntactic controller,<br />

which is the resolved gender of the coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase that the adjective is a predicate of,<br />

but with a contextual controller, the Contextually Introduced Referent.<br />

In order to capture the above phenomenon, we will assume that there is an extra level<br />

of representation, the Contextual level. At the Contextual level, the CIR <strong>in</strong>troduces a<br />

r(eferential)-structure with agreement feature-values that the predicative adjective shows<br />

agreement. The correspondence functions assumed with<strong>in</strong> LFG can be used to relate the<br />

Contextual level and the syntactic level as follows:<br />

Let P be the Contextually Introduced Referent and r be the f-structure of<br />

P <strong>in</strong>troduced at the Contextual level of representation C. The syntactic fstructure<br />

level of representation is mapped to the contextual level of representation<br />

through the mapp<strong>in</strong>g function d. The <strong>in</strong>verse mapp<strong>in</strong>g function d −1<br />

also holds.<br />

Thus, any f-structure f of coord<strong>in</strong>ated NPs at the syntactic level can be associated to<br />

an r-structure r <strong>in</strong>troduced at the contextual level impos<strong>in</strong>g the follow<strong>in</strong>g correspondence<br />

relation: d(f)= r. The <strong>in</strong>verse correpondence relation d −1 (r)= f will also hold denot<strong>in</strong>g<br />

the f-structure from the contextual level to the syntactic level of representation. This is<br />

schematically represented as follows:<br />

f<br />

d<br />

−→ r r<br />

d −1<br />

−−→ f<br />

Figure 4.1: Mapp<strong>in</strong>g correspondence<br />

Based on example (119), the r-structure of the Contextually Introduced Referent <strong>in</strong>troduced<br />

at the contextual level C has the follow<strong>in</strong>g agreement features:<br />

⎡ ⎤<br />

(120) pred ‘th<strong>in</strong>g’<br />

⎢ ⎥<br />

r: ⎣num<br />

pl ⎦<br />

gend neut<br />

The follow<strong>in</strong>g lexical entry will hold for the CIR:<br />

(121) pragmata (r pred) = ‘th<strong>in</strong>g’<br />

(r num)= pl<br />

(r gend)= neut<br />

In the unexpected pattern, the agreement target (i.e. predicative adjective) will agree<br />

with the contextual controller, the CIR, whose agreement features are specified <strong>in</strong> the rstructure<br />

and which occurs only at the contextual level C. In example (119), the CIR is the<br />

noun pragmata ‘th<strong>in</strong>gs’ with the r-structure <strong>in</strong> (120) and with the lexical entry <strong>in</strong> (121).<br />

Thus, the adjective megala, apart from the syntactic agreement, which results from the<br />

syntactic controller (i.e. the subject noun phrase), needs to agree with the morphosyntactic<br />

features of the CIR, which is the contextual controller and has the agreement features<br />

num=pl and gend=neut, shown <strong>in</strong> the r-structure. The lexical entry of the predicative<br />

adjective that shows referential agreement is stated as follows:<br />

(122) megala (↑pred) = ‘big’<br />

(↑d num)= pl<br />

(↑d gend)= neut


4.5 An Approach to Gender <strong>Agreement</strong> <strong>in</strong> MG 113<br />

So the general idea is that the predicative adjective will either agree with a syntactic<br />

controller or with a contextual controller. The syntactic controller is the subject noun<br />

phrase which is a coord<strong>in</strong>ate structure and it triggers agreement as a result of resolution;<br />

the contextual controller is the Contextually Introduced Referent which is some implied<br />

noun that is brought <strong>in</strong>to the discourse by the speakers and it occurs at the contextual<br />

level of representation.<br />

As proposed above, there is a mapp<strong>in</strong>g function d <strong>in</strong> the f-to-r direction and an <strong>in</strong>verse<br />

mapp<strong>in</strong>g function d −1 <strong>in</strong> the r-to-f direction. Then a relationship must hold between f,<br />

which is the f-structure of (↑subj), and r, the r-structure of CIR. This is stated as follows:<br />

(123) d (↑subj) = r<br />

Consider<strong>in</strong>g the equation <strong>in</strong> (123), we propose the follow<strong>in</strong>g lexical entry for the expected<br />

and the unexpected patterns of the predicative adjective/participle:<br />

(124) megala (↑pred) = ‘big〈subj〉’<br />

{(↑subj num)= pl<br />

(↑subj gend)= neut|<br />

((↑subj)d num)= pl<br />

((↑subj)d gend)= neut}<br />

In (124), the predicative adjective <strong>in</strong>troduces a disjunctive lexical entry. The first part<br />

specifies the expected agreement features as a result of syntactic resolution, and the second<br />

part <strong>in</strong>troduces the unexpected agreement features as a result of referential agreement<br />

with the agreement features of the CIR, which is the hypernym of the two conjuncts.<br />

The disjunctive lexical entry of the predicative adjective captures the ma<strong>in</strong> idea of the<br />

phenomenon of referential agreement <strong>in</strong> MG coord<strong>in</strong>ate noun phrases.<br />

There are some challenges that need to be discussed. The first issue concerns the status<br />

of the r-structure which occurs at the contextual level but it is represented as a syntactic<br />

structure. The r-structure, which is a contextual level structure, must be represented as an<br />

f-structure s<strong>in</strong>ce it holds all the syntactic features of the implied noun. However, it has to<br />

occur only at the contextual level and not at the syntactic level s<strong>in</strong>ce it is not syntactically<br />

present <strong>in</strong> the phrase but it is only implied by the native speakers. In addition, the pred<br />

value <strong>in</strong> the r-structure is the semantic form of some noun brought <strong>in</strong>to the context by the<br />

native speakers with a unique <strong>in</strong>stantiation. This pred value needs to be present s<strong>in</strong>ce it is<br />

a specific noun each time which functions as the superord<strong>in</strong>ate term of the two coord<strong>in</strong>ate<br />

nouns of the sentence, although it differs from speaker to speaker depend<strong>in</strong>g on speakers’<br />

perception.<br />

The second issue relates to the requirement of captur<strong>in</strong>g the semantic relation of the<br />

subj noun phrase, which occurs at the syntactic level and functions as the hyponym,<br />

with the CIR, which occurs at the contextual level and functions as the hypernym of the<br />

coord<strong>in</strong>ate subj noun phrase. This semantic relation between the Contextually Introduced<br />

Referent and the coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns is a hypernymic-hyponymic one and could be expressed<br />

with<strong>in</strong> the lexicon <strong>in</strong> the form of a hierarchy.<br />

Constra<strong>in</strong>t-based theories like LFG and HPSG assume the template hierarchy and the<br />

type hierarchy, respectively. In LFG, the template hierarchy encodes lexical generalisations<br />

<strong>in</strong> terms of relations between descriptions of structures and not <strong>in</strong> terms of any<br />

formal <strong>in</strong>heritance relations between types. These templates are f-structure descriptions<br />

with a name which can be used <strong>in</strong> other equations to state more complicated descriptions<br />

(Dalrymple et al., 2004b, 201). In LFG, these hierarchies seem to be abbreviatory. On<br />

the other hand, HPSG builds l<strong>in</strong>guistic generalisations also us<strong>in</strong>g a type hierarchy where<br />

more specific types <strong>in</strong>herit their <strong>in</strong>formation from less specific but related types. In HPSG,


4.5 An Approach to Gender <strong>Agreement</strong> <strong>in</strong> MG 114<br />

lexical generalizations are statable as relations between elements <strong>in</strong> the type lattice, where<br />

different subtypes function as alternatives and a specific type may belong to many supertypes<br />

(Malouf, 1998; Pollard and Sag, 1994). Thus, <strong>in</strong> HPSG these hierarchies relate<br />

ontological objects of the theory and do not simply state abbreviations.<br />

In order to capture the semantic relation of the lexical items, we could assume an<br />

ontological hierarchy resembl<strong>in</strong>g those of LFG or HPSG, which will show how the various<br />

lexical items are related to each other where the more general term <strong>in</strong>cludes with<strong>in</strong> it the<br />

more specific ones. This hierarchy could be represented as follows for the relevant example<br />

<strong>in</strong> (119):<br />

THINGS<br />

DECORATION FURNITURE<br />

PAINTINGS LIGHTS TABLES<br />

Figure 4.2: A simple hierarchy represent<strong>in</strong>g ontological relations<br />

In the hierarchy above, the superord<strong>in</strong>ate term is the noun ‘th<strong>in</strong>gs’ which <strong>in</strong>cludes as<br />

hyponyms the noun ‘decoration’ and the noun ‘furniture’. With<strong>in</strong> the noun ‘furniture’,<br />

which also functions as a general term, other hyponyms are <strong>in</strong>cluded like the nouns ‘lights’<br />

and ‘tables’. Also, the noun ‘lights’ is the hyponym of the general term ‘decorations’ s<strong>in</strong>ce<br />

‘lights’ could be a piece of furniture or a piece of decoration.<br />

A second issue that arises is that the representation of this hierarchy may differ from<br />

speaker to speaker depend<strong>in</strong>g on the world knowledge and perception and on the way the<br />

various lexical items are organised <strong>in</strong> each speaker’s m<strong>in</strong>d. Thus, a person may assume<br />

a specific hierarchy with a specific superord<strong>in</strong>ate term but a different person may assume<br />

a different hierarchy and therefore a different superord<strong>in</strong>ate term for the same coord<strong>in</strong>ate<br />

nouns. As seen above, most speakers chose the noun xori ‘spaces’ as the superord<strong>in</strong>ate<br />

term for the two nouns dromi ‘streets’ and squares ‘platies’ but some speakers chose the<br />

noun perioxes ‘areas’. This clearly shows that native speakers assume a different ontological<br />

representation for the same group of nouns depend<strong>in</strong>g on their world knowledge and<br />

perception.<br />

The second issue is related to the field of ontology and could be expla<strong>in</strong>ed further from<br />

that perspective. Ontology traditionally deals with questions concern<strong>in</strong>g what entities exist<br />

or can be said to exist, and how such entities can be grouped, related with<strong>in</strong> a hierarchy,<br />

and subdivided accord<strong>in</strong>g to similarities and differences (Genesereth and Nilson, 1987).<br />

Thus, ontology focuses on the relations of different concepts with<strong>in</strong> a system. One aspect<br />

of ontological relations is also that of subord<strong>in</strong>ation and superord<strong>in</strong>ation. In Schalley and<br />

Zaefferer (2007, 4), these two relations are def<strong>in</strong>ed as “weak order<strong>in</strong>gs” as follows:<br />

Conceptual subord<strong>in</strong>ation: Concept A 22 is c-subord<strong>in</strong>ated to concept B iff every<br />

<strong>in</strong>stance of A is also an <strong>in</strong>stance of B, and<br />

Conceptual superord<strong>in</strong>ation, its converse.<br />

(Schalley and Zaefferer, 2007, 4)<br />

Accord<strong>in</strong>g to the above def<strong>in</strong>ition, <strong>in</strong> example (119) and similar ones, the native speakers<br />

carry extra-l<strong>in</strong>guistic <strong>in</strong>formation which affects the current l<strong>in</strong>guistic knowledge. This<br />

<strong>in</strong>formation refers to the CIR, which is brought forward <strong>in</strong>to the specific discourse conditions,<br />

and it is usually a superord<strong>in</strong>ate concept which <strong>in</strong>cludes with<strong>in</strong> it <strong>in</strong>stances of the two<br />

coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns. This extral<strong>in</strong>guistic concept, the CIR, has grammatical features that determ<strong>in</strong>e<br />

the gender (and subsequently number) of the predicative adjective. In most cases,<br />

22 A, B and C stand for the related concepts.


4.6 Conclusion 115<br />

native speakers br<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>to the context the same extral<strong>in</strong>guistic concept and therefore the<br />

predicative adjective shows agreement with the features of that specific concept. There are<br />

cases, however, that native speakers br<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>to the discourse different concepts and therefore<br />

there is a divergence <strong>in</strong>to the agreement features of the predicative adjective. This is<br />

more common <strong>in</strong> abstract coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns. In the follow<strong>in</strong>g example, the native speakers<br />

chose different gender features <strong>in</strong> the predicative adjective, mascul<strong>in</strong>e and fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e:<br />

(125) O kopos ke i prospathia<br />

the.masc.sg effort.masc.sg and the.fem.sg trial.fem.sg<br />

aparetit-i/-es ja na proodefsei kanis<br />

necessary.masc/fem.pl for to progress someone<br />

‘The effort and trial are necessary for someone to progress’<br />

The predicative adjective shows mascul<strong>in</strong>e plural agreement s<strong>in</strong>ce native speakers may<br />

br<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>to the discourse the noun tropi.masc.pl ‘ways’ as the superord<strong>in</strong>ate term, which<br />

is mascul<strong>in</strong>e <strong>in</strong> gender. The fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e gender is also <strong>in</strong>herited from the predicative adjective<br />

because the superord<strong>in</strong>ate term assumed by some native speakers is enies.fem.pl<br />

‘mean<strong>in</strong>gs’, which is fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e gender.<br />

Thus, we have proposed a syntactic analysis of referential agreement and we have<br />

provided an ontological hierarchy that could be used to represent the lexical relations<br />

between the two nouns that appear <strong>in</strong> the coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase and the CIR that is implied<br />

by native speakers and appears at the contextual level of representation. The fact that the<br />

CIR may differ from speaker to speaker due to the different way that the various native<br />

speakers perceive the world is viewed from an ontological explanation s<strong>in</strong>ce the ontological<br />

organisation of lexical items is attributed to extral<strong>in</strong>guistic conditions.<br />

4.6 Conclusion<br />

In this chapter, we presented predicate-argument agreement <strong>in</strong> MG coord<strong>in</strong>ate noun phrases,<br />

focus<strong>in</strong>g on the gender feature. The data showed that gender resolution <strong>in</strong> MG does not<br />

follow a straightforward dist<strong>in</strong>ction between syntactic resolution <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>animate nouns and<br />

semantic resolution <strong>in</strong> animate ones. Instead, MG coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns show a comb<strong>in</strong>ation of<br />

expected and unexpected resolution patterns. The expected patterns refer to cases of resolution<br />

that follow either the semantic or the syntactic pr<strong>in</strong>ciples. The unexpected patterns<br />

refer to an additional type of agreement the referential agreement which is determ<strong>in</strong>ed<br />

by contextual factors. This type of agreement depends on the assumption of a Contextually<br />

Introduced Referent on behalf of the consultants, which triggers morphosyntactic<br />

agreement <strong>in</strong> the sentential predicate.<br />

The expected patterns of <strong>in</strong>animate coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns follow the syntactic pr<strong>in</strong>ciple of<br />

resolution and the unexpected patterns follow the referential agreement pr<strong>in</strong>ciple. Similarly,<br />

the expected patterns of animate coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns follow the semantic pr<strong>in</strong>ciple<br />

(same gender nouns show feature match<strong>in</strong>g agreement) and the unexpected patterns follow<br />

referential agreement.<br />

To account for the variation <strong>in</strong> the expected patterns, we assumed the marker-set<br />

decomposition (Dalrymple and Kaplan, 2000) with common marker sets for both groups of<br />

nouns. In <strong>in</strong>animate nouns, syntactic resolution is derived by the standard syntactic rule<br />

for gender resolution which follows the set-union operation. In animate nouns, additional<br />

specifications are <strong>in</strong>troduced <strong>in</strong> the PS rule which capture both the grammatical and the<br />

semantic patterns. Thus, union operation is not applied.<br />

For the unexpected cases, native speakers br<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>to the discourse an extral<strong>in</strong>guistic<br />

concept the Contextually Introduced Referent. In LFG, we <strong>in</strong>troduce an extra level of<br />

<strong>in</strong>e<br />

are


4.6 Conclusion 116<br />

representation, the contextual one, where r-structure is the structure of the referred element.<br />

The agreement features of the referred element <strong>in</strong> r-structure are <strong>in</strong>troduced to the<br />

f-structure of the predicative adjective through the d mapp<strong>in</strong>g function. This prelim<strong>in</strong>ary<br />

analysis captures the basic idea of the referential agreement pr<strong>in</strong>ciple. However, we showed<br />

that the CIR, which functions as the superord<strong>in</strong>ate term of the coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns it refers<br />

to, is extral<strong>in</strong>guistic <strong>in</strong> nature and may differ from speaker to speaker. To expla<strong>in</strong> this<br />

extral<strong>in</strong>guistic phenomenon we have proposed an ontological hierarchy similar to the template<br />

hierarchy assumed by LFG and the type hierarchy assumed by HPSG, which shows<br />

how native speakers represent the various lexical items, and we have argued that the use<br />

of a different CIR across speakers largerly depends on ontology and different perception of<br />

the world.


Chapter 5<br />

Head Modifier <strong>Agreement</strong> <strong>in</strong><br />

<strong>Modern</strong> <strong>Greek</strong><br />

5.1 Introduction<br />

In MG, head-modifier agreement requires the modifier to agree with the noun it modifies<br />

<strong>in</strong> number, gender and case. The situation is more complicated with coord<strong>in</strong>ate noun<br />

phrases. In the present chapter, we will focus on the number and gender features. In<br />

exam<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g a range of modified coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns <strong>in</strong> MG, we found that the MG def<strong>in</strong>ite<br />

determ<strong>in</strong>er differs from the rest of the modifiers. A s<strong>in</strong>gle modifier with wide scope can<br />

modify two coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns and it agrees <strong>in</strong> number with both conjuncts but it agrees<br />

<strong>in</strong> gender with the closest conjunct (CCA), irrespective of the gender of the two nouns.<br />

The shared modifier allows the generation of jo<strong>in</strong>t and split read<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>in</strong> both s<strong>in</strong>gular and<br />

plural nouns. The def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er, however, does not show the same behaviour s<strong>in</strong>ce<br />

each conjunct needs a separate determ<strong>in</strong>er. A shared def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er with wide scope<br />

can modify two coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns and it agrees <strong>in</strong> number with both nouns but it only<br />

occurs with the jo<strong>in</strong>t read<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> both s<strong>in</strong>gular and plural nouns. In terms of gender, a<br />

shared def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er requires uniform gender conjuncts, whereas it is allowed with<br />

mixed gender conjuncts only when the two nouns are mascul<strong>in</strong>e and fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e <strong>in</strong> gender.<br />

Some exceptional data are found when a shared determ<strong>in</strong>er with wide scope modifies two<br />

coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns and occurs with the split read<strong>in</strong>g. We will suggest that these patterns<br />

are cases of natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation (Dalrymple and Nikolaeva, 2006).<br />

The proposal developed by K<strong>in</strong>g and Dalrymple (2004) on determ<strong>in</strong>er agreement and<br />

noun coord<strong>in</strong>ation lays out a putative crossl<strong>in</strong>guistic typology based on three different<br />

agreement systems, concord, <strong>in</strong>dex and concord/<strong>in</strong>dex that relate to the number<br />

feature. We will argue that the MG modifiers are nicely accounted for by the concord<br />

system s<strong>in</strong>ce they comply with the restrictions of that system. The MG determ<strong>in</strong>er, on the<br />

other hand, is best expla<strong>in</strong>ed by the most restrictive system, the concord/<strong>in</strong>dex. The<br />

exceptional data, which allow a shared def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er to modify coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns<br />

and occurs with the split read<strong>in</strong>g, could be analysed accord<strong>in</strong>g to the proposal on natural<br />

coord<strong>in</strong>ation by Dalrymple and Nikolaeva (2006). However, the syntactic structure of MG<br />

natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation patterns differs from the syntactic structure of natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation<br />

proposed by Dalrymple and Nikolaeva (2006). Thus, we follow the standard analysis of<br />

accidental coord<strong>in</strong>ation for the MG natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation cases. It is worth not<strong>in</strong>g that <strong>Modern</strong><br />

<strong>Greek</strong> grammars and traditional textbooks (Clairis et al. (2004), Holton et al. (1997),<br />

Triantaphyllidis (1994), Triantaphyllidis (2005), Joseph and Philippaki-Warburton (1987),<br />

Mackridge (1985) and Holton et al. (1997)) do not present any discussion of modifiers or<br />

the def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er with coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns or the phenomenon of natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation<br />

<strong>in</strong> MG.


5.2 NP Internal <strong>Agreement</strong> and Interpretation of the Coord<strong>in</strong>ate <strong>Noun</strong>s 118<br />

The first section revisits the three different agreement systems proposed by K<strong>in</strong>g and<br />

Dalrymple (2004), and discusses how the <strong>in</strong>dex num feature is associated to a semantic<br />

dist<strong>in</strong>ction between the jo<strong>in</strong>t and split read<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns modified by a shared<br />

determ<strong>in</strong>er. Next, we present MG modifiers with coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns and we argue that they<br />

follow the concord agreement system. Then, we present the MG def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er<br />

with coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns and we argue that it follows the <strong>in</strong>dex/concord system. The<br />

exceptional patterns are captured assum<strong>in</strong>g the standard analysis of accidental coord<strong>in</strong>ation<br />

and not that of natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation.<br />

5.2 NP Internal <strong>Agreement</strong> and Interpretation of the Coord<strong>in</strong>ate <strong>Noun</strong>s<br />

Modification <strong>in</strong> NP coord<strong>in</strong>ate structures is rather complicated s<strong>in</strong>ce a common determ<strong>in</strong>er<br />

cannot always modify two coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns, and if it does, it yields specific <strong>in</strong>terpretations.<br />

As discussed <strong>in</strong> Section 3.3.2, K<strong>in</strong>g and Dalrymple (2004) predict three different agreement<br />

systems based on the <strong>in</strong>dex and concord agreement features when a shared determ<strong>in</strong>er<br />

modifies coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns <strong>in</strong> NP <strong>in</strong>ternal agreement. The concord system requires<br />

determ<strong>in</strong>ers to show agreement only with the concord features of each conjunct. This<br />

system allows a s<strong>in</strong>gular determ<strong>in</strong>er to modify coord<strong>in</strong>ated s<strong>in</strong>gular nouns and a plural<br />

determ<strong>in</strong>er to modify coord<strong>in</strong>ated plural nouns. In both cases, the conjuncts may refer to<br />

the same or different <strong>in</strong>dividuals s<strong>in</strong>ce there is no <strong>in</strong>dex feature restriction.<br />

(1) concord systems:<br />

a. S<strong>in</strong>gular determ<strong>in</strong>er<br />

(↑concord num) = sg<br />

b. Plural determ<strong>in</strong>er<br />

(↑concord num) = pl<br />

(K<strong>in</strong>g and Dalrymple, 2004, 86)<br />

The concord/<strong>in</strong>dex system is the most restrictive system and requires the determ<strong>in</strong>er<br />

to show agreement with the concord features of each conjunct and the <strong>in</strong>dex feature of<br />

the coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase as a whole. This system imposes restrictions on both the concord<br />

and <strong>in</strong>dex agreement features and allows a s<strong>in</strong>gular determ<strong>in</strong>er to modify coord<strong>in</strong>ated<br />

s<strong>in</strong>gular nouns. A consequence of this system is that a s<strong>in</strong>gular determ<strong>in</strong>er can scope over<br />

conjuncts only when they get a jo<strong>in</strong>t or boolean read<strong>in</strong>g. The same system <strong>in</strong> plural allows<br />

a plural determ<strong>in</strong>er to modify plural coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns, which can get either a jo<strong>in</strong>t or a<br />

split read<strong>in</strong>g.<br />

(2) concord and <strong>in</strong>dex systems:<br />

a. S<strong>in</strong>gular determ<strong>in</strong>er<br />

(↑concord num) = sg<br />

(↑<strong>in</strong>dex num) = sg<br />

b. Plural determ<strong>in</strong>er<br />

(↑concord num) = pl<br />

(↑<strong>in</strong>dex num) = pl<br />

(K<strong>in</strong>g and Dalrymple, 2004, 85)


5.2 NP Internal <strong>Agreement</strong> and Interpretation of the Coord<strong>in</strong>ate <strong>Noun</strong>s 119<br />

The <strong>in</strong>dex system requires determ<strong>in</strong>ers to show agreement only with the <strong>in</strong>dex features<br />

of the coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase as a whole (and not with the concord features of the dist<strong>in</strong>ct<br />

conjuncts). This system allows a s<strong>in</strong>gular determ<strong>in</strong>er to modify s<strong>in</strong>gular nouns that refer<br />

to the same <strong>in</strong>dividual and a plural determ<strong>in</strong>er to modify conjo<strong>in</strong>ed s<strong>in</strong>gular nouns.<br />

(3) <strong>in</strong>dex systems:<br />

a. S<strong>in</strong>gular determ<strong>in</strong>er<br />

(↑<strong>in</strong>dex num) = sg<br />

b. Plural determ<strong>in</strong>er<br />

(↑<strong>in</strong>dex num) = pl<br />

(K<strong>in</strong>g and Dalrymple, 2004, 86)<br />

Heycock and Zamparelli (2000, 2005), whose work is discussed <strong>in</strong> K<strong>in</strong>g and Dalrymple<br />

(2004), also exam<strong>in</strong>e modification <strong>in</strong> coord<strong>in</strong>ate noun phrases and discuss the existence of<br />

two possible <strong>in</strong>terpretations when coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns are modified by a shared determ<strong>in</strong>er.<br />

They refer to these <strong>in</strong>terpretations as the “jo<strong>in</strong>t” read<strong>in</strong>g and the “split” read<strong>in</strong>g. The jo<strong>in</strong>t<br />

read<strong>in</strong>g occurs when both nouns denote the same <strong>in</strong>dividual, and the split read<strong>in</strong>g occurs<br />

when the two nouns refer to different <strong>in</strong>dividuals. Both K<strong>in</strong>g and Dalrymple (2004) and<br />

Heycock and Zamparelli (2005) observe that there is a difference concern<strong>in</strong>g the read<strong>in</strong>gs<br />

that are generated between s<strong>in</strong>gular and plural coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns modified by a shared<br />

def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er <strong>in</strong> languages like Italian, Spanish, German, French and Brazilian Portuguese.<br />

In Brazilian Portuguese, for example, <strong>in</strong> s<strong>in</strong>gular conjuncts, a shared determ<strong>in</strong>er can<br />

modify two coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns and the coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase is <strong>in</strong>terpreted with the “jo<strong>in</strong>t”<br />

(Heycock and Zamparelli, 1999, 2000) read<strong>in</strong>g, as illustrated below:<br />

(4) O presidente e diretor da Air<br />

the.sg.masc<br />

France<br />

France<br />

president.sg.masc and director.sg.masc of Air<br />

‘The president and director of Air France’<br />

((Heycock and Zamparelli, 2000, 7) cited <strong>in</strong> (K<strong>in</strong>g and Dalrymple, 2004, 92))<br />

If a s<strong>in</strong>gle determ<strong>in</strong>er modifies coord<strong>in</strong>ate s<strong>in</strong>gular nouns and the coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase is<br />

<strong>in</strong>terpreted with the “split” (Heycock and Zamparelli, 1999, 2000) read<strong>in</strong>g, the phrase is<br />

ungrammatical. This is shown below:<br />

(5) *A mesa e escrivan<strong>in</strong>ha estão arrumadas<br />

‘The table and the small desk are <strong>in</strong> order’<br />

(Heycock and Zamparelli, 2000, 7)<br />

The split read<strong>in</strong>g can only be admitted if a separate determ<strong>in</strong>er appears before each<br />

conjunct, as seen below:<br />

(6) A mesae a escrivan<strong>in</strong>ha estão arrumadas<br />

‘The table and the small desk are <strong>in</strong> order’<br />

(Heycock and Zamparelli, 2000, 7)<br />

The same generalisations do not hold when the conjuncts are plural. All languages<br />

discussed <strong>in</strong> Heycock and Zamparelli (2000, 2005) and K<strong>in</strong>g and Dalrymple (2004) allow<br />

both the “split” and the “jo<strong>in</strong>t” <strong>in</strong>terpretation <strong>in</strong> coord<strong>in</strong>ate plural nouns that are modified


5.2 NP Internal <strong>Agreement</strong> and Interpretation of the Coord<strong>in</strong>ate <strong>Noun</strong>s 120<br />

by a s<strong>in</strong>gle plural determ<strong>in</strong>er. The follow<strong>in</strong>g example is from Italian and it is grammatical<br />

even though a s<strong>in</strong>gle determ<strong>in</strong>er modifies both nouns and it occurs with the split read<strong>in</strong>g:<br />

(7) Gli amici e nemici di Gianni si trovano<br />

the.pl friends.pl and enemies.pl of Gianni were found<br />

d’ accordo su un solo punto<br />

<strong>in</strong> agreement on a s<strong>in</strong>gle po<strong>in</strong>t<br />

‘The friends and enemies of Gianni were <strong>in</strong>-agreement on a s<strong>in</strong>gle po<strong>in</strong>t’<br />

(Heycock and Zamparelli, 2000, 10)<br />

An important aspect of K<strong>in</strong>g and Dalrymple’s proposal, which is related to the dist<strong>in</strong>ction<br />

proposed by Heycock and Zamparelli (2000) between the jo<strong>in</strong>t and split read<strong>in</strong>g, is<br />

that the value of the <strong>in</strong>dex num feature of the coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase represents the number of<br />

<strong>in</strong>dividuals it refers to. Thus, syntactic <strong>in</strong>dex num is associated to the semantic number<br />

of the referents <strong>in</strong> a phrase.<br />

Therefore, we can argue that as well as a syntactic agreement pattern we might f<strong>in</strong>d<br />

some additional semantic aspects. Accord<strong>in</strong>g to K<strong>in</strong>g and Dalrymple (2004, 75), <strong>in</strong> a coord<strong>in</strong>ate<br />

phrase with s<strong>in</strong>gular conjuncts, when the def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er has a sg value <strong>in</strong><br />

the <strong>in</strong>dex num feature the coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase necessarily refers to only one <strong>in</strong>dividual. In<br />

this case, the <strong>in</strong>terpretation of the phrase is the jo<strong>in</strong>t read<strong>in</strong>g and the def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er<br />

imposes the syntactic feature-value requirement <strong>in</strong>dex num=sg. The most characteristic<br />

case is the English example the friend and colleague where the syntactic structure for the<br />

coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase has the annotation <strong>in</strong>dex num=sg and the <strong>in</strong>terpretation is the jo<strong>in</strong>t<br />

read<strong>in</strong>g.<br />

On the other hand, <strong>in</strong> a coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase with plural conjuncts, when the def<strong>in</strong>ite<br />

determ<strong>in</strong>er has a pl value <strong>in</strong> the <strong>in</strong>dex num feature, the coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase can be <strong>in</strong>terpreted<br />

with the jo<strong>in</strong>t or the split read<strong>in</strong>g. The jo<strong>in</strong>t read<strong>in</strong>g derives from the fact that<br />

the two coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns are both plural and they may refer to the same <strong>in</strong>dividuals. A<br />

characteristic case is the English example the friends and colleagues. In this case, the two<br />

nouns refer to the same people and the phrase occurs with the jo<strong>in</strong>t read<strong>in</strong>g, while the<br />

def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er imposes the syntactic requirement <strong>in</strong>dex num=pl. The split read<strong>in</strong>g<br />

is also possible s<strong>in</strong>ce the two coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns are plural and they may also refer to different<br />

<strong>in</strong>dividuals. Thus, the same example can have a split <strong>in</strong>terpretation s<strong>in</strong>ce the two<br />

nouns can refer to different groups of <strong>in</strong>dividuals and the def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er imposes the<br />

syntactic requirement <strong>in</strong>dex num=pl. We observe that the annotation <strong>in</strong> the syntactic<br />

structure is the same irrespective of the <strong>in</strong>terpretation of the coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase as <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>dex<br />

num=pl. Thus, we conclude that <strong>in</strong> coord<strong>in</strong>ated plural nouns the syntactic structure for<br />

the coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase has the annotation <strong>in</strong>dex num=pl and this annotation corresponds<br />

to the jo<strong>in</strong>t or the split <strong>in</strong>terpretation.<br />

The above dist<strong>in</strong>ction between split and jo<strong>in</strong>t read<strong>in</strong>gs and their association to the syntactic<br />

<strong>in</strong>dex num feature with sg or pl values are crucial for the MG data, which present<br />

a slightly different behaviour from the languages discussed by Heycock and Zamparelli<br />

(2000) and K<strong>in</strong>g and Dalrymple (2004). We will show that <strong>in</strong> MG coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrases, a<br />

shared modifier follows the concord system and <strong>in</strong>troduces the semantic requirements of<br />

that system, admit<strong>in</strong>g both jo<strong>in</strong>t and split <strong>in</strong>terpretations. The shared def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er<br />

follows the <strong>in</strong>dex/concord system but it appears to <strong>in</strong>troduce some additional semantic<br />

specifications over and above those generated by the most restrictive syntactic agreement<br />

system of K<strong>in</strong>g and Dalrymple (2004). The def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er allows only the jo<strong>in</strong>t read<strong>in</strong>g<br />

with both s<strong>in</strong>gular and plural conjuncts; the split <strong>in</strong>terpretation under a shared determ<strong>in</strong>er<br />

is allowed <strong>in</strong> plural number only <strong>in</strong> a specific group of data which fall with<strong>in</strong> the case of<br />

natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation (Dalrymple and Nikolaeva, 2006).<br />

The method used for the collection of data was based on a wide Internet search, on


5.3 NP Internal <strong>Agreement</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>Modern</strong> <strong>Greek</strong> 121<br />

newspaper articles and on personal discussions with about fifteen native speakers who<br />

confirmed the acceptability and unacceptability of the collected sentences. Consultants<br />

accepted or rejected a phrase based on whether they would use it <strong>in</strong> everyday language or<br />

they found it unaccaptable and rejected it. Next, we will discuss NP <strong>in</strong>ternal agreement<br />

<strong>in</strong> coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns <strong>in</strong> MG.<br />

5.3 NP Internal <strong>Agreement</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>Modern</strong> <strong>Greek</strong><br />

The MG determ<strong>in</strong>ers and modifiers generally encode a three-way gender 1 dist<strong>in</strong>ction between<br />

mascul<strong>in</strong>e, fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e and neuter <strong>in</strong> both s<strong>in</strong>gular and plural number 2 and agree with<br />

the nouns they modify. In example (8), the def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er o modifies the noun andras<br />

and shows s<strong>in</strong>gular, mascul<strong>in</strong>e, nom<strong>in</strong>ative agreement with the latter. In example (9), the<br />

<strong>in</strong>def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er merika modifies the noun pedia and shows plural, neuter, nom<strong>in</strong>ative<br />

agreement with the latter:<br />

(8) o<br />

the.sg.masc.nom<br />

‘the man’<br />

(constructed)<br />

(9) merika<br />

some.pl.neut.nom<br />

‘some children’<br />

(constructed)<br />

antras<br />

man.sg.masc.nom<br />

pedia<br />

children.pl.neut.nom<br />

Similarly, the adjectival modifier megali ‘big’ shows plural, mascul<strong>in</strong>e, nom<strong>in</strong>ative agreement<br />

with the noun andres ‘men’:<br />

(10) megali<br />

big.pl.masc.nom<br />

‘big men’<br />

(constructed)<br />

antres<br />

men.pl.masc.nom<br />

In the next section, we will discuss first shared MG modifiers with coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns<br />

and then the def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er o-i-to.sg.masc/fem/neut ‘the’ with coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns.<br />

We present data with identical gender conjuncts and mixed gender conjuncts modified by<br />

a shared modifier and by a shared def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er.<br />

5.4 The <strong>Modern</strong> <strong>Greek</strong> Modifiers<br />

Generally, <strong>in</strong> MG modifiers with coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns, a shared modifier scopes over coord<strong>in</strong>ate<br />

nouns and it agrees <strong>in</strong> num with both nouns while it occurs either with the jo<strong>in</strong>t or the<br />

split <strong>in</strong>terpretation <strong>in</strong> both s<strong>in</strong>gular and plural conjuncts. The modifier always agrees <strong>in</strong><br />

gender with the closest conjunct. A separate modifier can also appear before each noun<br />

and agrees with the latter <strong>in</strong> both num and gender. In this case, it occurs only with<br />

a split <strong>in</strong>terpretation. We will discuss examples with various shared modifiers, such as<br />

adjectives, quantifiers and determ<strong>in</strong>ers.<br />

In coord<strong>in</strong>ated s<strong>in</strong>gular nouns with the same gender, a s<strong>in</strong>gular attributive adjective<br />

scopes over two conjuncts and requires s<strong>in</strong>gular num agreement with both nouns and<br />

gender agreement with the closest noun 3 . It can convey either a jo<strong>in</strong>t or a split read<strong>in</strong>g,<br />

1 There are a few exceptions, such as some numerals, the distributive determ<strong>in</strong>er kathe etc that do not<br />

encode this dist<strong>in</strong>ction. For more details see Mackridge (1985) and Holton et al. (1997).<br />

2 The MG determ<strong>in</strong>ers and modifiers dist<strong>in</strong>guish four cases, nom<strong>in</strong>ative, genitive, accusative and dative<br />

apart from the gender and number dist<strong>in</strong>ctions. Case is not central and we will not discuss it further.<br />

3 In uniform gender nouns, the adjective also agrees <strong>in</strong> gender with the second conjunct.


5.4 The <strong>Modern</strong> <strong>Greek</strong> Modifiers 122<br />

depend<strong>in</strong>g on whether the two nouns refer to the same or different <strong>in</strong>dividuals or entities.<br />

In example (11), the shared adjective scopes over both conjuncts and the only possible<br />

<strong>in</strong>terpretation is the jo<strong>in</strong>t one s<strong>in</strong>ce the nouns refer to a s<strong>in</strong>gle <strong>in</strong>dividual and the verb<br />

shows s<strong>in</strong>gular agreement. In example (12), a shared adjective scopes over both nouns but<br />

it conveys a split <strong>in</strong>terpretation s<strong>in</strong>ce the two conjuncts denote different <strong>in</strong>dividuals and<br />

the verb shows plural agreement 4 :<br />

(11) O Gorjias itan megalos<br />

the<br />

ritoras<br />

Gorgias was.sg great.sg.masc<br />

orator.sg.masc<br />

‘Gorgias was a great philosopher and orator’<br />

(History Book, High School 3rd year)<br />

filosofos<br />

philosopher.sg.masc<br />

ke<br />

and<br />

(12) Drastirios pateras ke ijos theorunte<br />

active.sg.masc father.sg.masc and son.sg.masc are-considered.pl<br />

o Onasis ke o Aleksantros<br />

the Onasis and the Alexander<br />

‘Active father and son are considered to be Onassis and Alexander’<br />

(Onasis, 1997)<br />

Also, a s<strong>in</strong>gular adjective cannot modify a s<strong>in</strong>gular and a plural noun simultaneously,<br />

but it only scopes the closest conjunct, which must be s<strong>in</strong>gular, and not the second conjunct:<br />

(13) Drastirios pateras ke iji<br />

theorunte<br />

active.sg.masc father.sg.masc and sons.pl.masc are-considered.pl<br />

o Latsis ke ta pedia tou<br />

the Latsis and the children his<br />

‘Active father and sons are considered Latsis and his children’<br />

In MG, a plural adjective cannot modify s<strong>in</strong>gular conjuncts, as seen is example (14):<br />

(14) *Drastirii pateras ke ijos theorunte<br />

active.pl.masc father.sg.masc and son.sg.masc are-considered.pl<br />

o Onasis ke o Aleksantros<br />

the Onasis and the Alexander<br />

‘Active father and son are considered to be Onassis and Alexander’<br />

(constructed)<br />

In coord<strong>in</strong>ated plural phrases, MG modifiers behave <strong>in</strong> a similar way. The plural<br />

modifier scopes over two conjuncts and specifies plural num agreement with both nouns<br />

and gender agreement with the closest noun. The jo<strong>in</strong>t and the split <strong>in</strong>terpretations<br />

are allowed when a shared adjective scopes over coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns. In example (15), the<br />

conjuncts are modified by the same adjective and they refer to the same concept s<strong>in</strong>ce the<br />

conjuncts are considered synonyms. In example (16), the adjective scopes over both nouns<br />

but the <strong>in</strong>dividuals denote different groups of people and therefore the split read<strong>in</strong>g is the<br />

most plausible <strong>in</strong>terpretation:<br />

4 The follow<strong>in</strong>g examples were collected from <strong>Greek</strong> newspapers and various books. I will use the abbre-<br />

viation G.N. to stand for <strong>Greek</strong> Newspaper and G.M. to stand for <strong>Greek</strong> Magaz<strong>in</strong>e followed by the specific<br />

newspaper or magaz<strong>in</strong>e from which I have collected each example. The examples that were constructed are<br />

<strong>in</strong>dicated with the word ‘constructed’.


5.4 The <strong>Modern</strong> <strong>Greek</strong> Modifiers 123<br />

(15) Isxires antiparathesis ke antiparavoles<br />

strong.pl.fem juxtapositions.pl.fem and contrasts.pl.fem<br />

ekdilothikan st<strong>in</strong> kentriki s<strong>in</strong>edriasi tis Vulis<br />

were-expressed.pl <strong>in</strong>-the central meet<strong>in</strong>g of-the Parliament<br />

‘Strong juxtapositions and contrasts were-expressed <strong>in</strong>-the central meet<strong>in</strong>g of the<br />

Parliament’<br />

(G.N.:To Vima)<br />

(16) Megali angioplastes ke zografi<br />

great.pl.masc<br />

eona...<br />

century...<br />

sculptors.pl.masc and pa<strong>in</strong>ters.pl.masc<br />

‘Great sculptors and pa<strong>in</strong>ters of the 5th century...’<br />

(www.<strong>in</strong>.gr)<br />

tu<br />

of-the<br />

Also, a plural adjective cannot modify a plural and a s<strong>in</strong>gular noun at the same time.<br />

The plural adjective scopes over the closest conjunct, which is also plural, and not the<br />

second conjunct:<br />

(17) Megali angioplastes ke zografos<br />

great.pl.masc<br />

eona...<br />

century...<br />

sculptors.pl.masc and pa<strong>in</strong>ter.sg.masc<br />

‘Great sculptors and a pa<strong>in</strong>ter of the 5th century...’<br />

(constructed)<br />

tu<br />

of-the<br />

Apart from adjectives, the data showed that shared quantifiers and determ<strong>in</strong>ers specify<br />

the same num agreement with both nouns and gender agreement with the closet conjunct,<br />

and allow both a jo<strong>in</strong>t and a split <strong>in</strong>terpretation when they scope over coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns. For<br />

example, the quantifier arket-os/-i/-o.sg.masc/fem/neut ‘quite a lot’ and the correlative<br />

determ<strong>in</strong>er opi-os/-a/-o.sg.masc/fem/neut ‘whoever’ have a mascul<strong>in</strong>e, a fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e and<br />

a neuter form <strong>in</strong> both s<strong>in</strong>gular and plural numbers and can scope over coord<strong>in</strong>ated s<strong>in</strong>gular<br />

or plural nouns that admit both jo<strong>in</strong>t and split read<strong>in</strong>gs, denot<strong>in</strong>g the same or different<br />

entities, respectively. The examples below illustrate the s<strong>in</strong>gular quantifier arket-os/-i/o.sg.masc/fem/neut<br />

‘quite a lot’, which specifies s<strong>in</strong>gular agreement with both nouns<br />

and closest conjunct gender agreement:<br />

(18) Arketi<br />

anastatosi ke anisixia<br />

quite-a-lot-of.sg.fem agitation.sg.fem and worry.sg.fem<br />

proklithike eksetias tis ikonomikis krisis<br />

was-caused.sg because-of the f<strong>in</strong>ancial crisis<br />

‘Quite a lot of agitation and worry was caused because of the f<strong>in</strong>ancial crisis’<br />

(G.N.:Ethnos)<br />

(19) Arketi<br />

dulia ke organosi<br />

quite-a-lot-of.sg.fem work.sg.fem and organisation.sg.fem<br />

xriastikan sto s<strong>in</strong>gekrimeno grafio<br />

were-needed.pl <strong>in</strong>-the specific office<br />

‘Quite-a-lot of work and organisation were needed <strong>in</strong> the specific office’<br />

(G.N.:Kathimer<strong>in</strong>i)<br />

The first case denotes reference to the same entity s<strong>in</strong>ce number verb agreement is s<strong>in</strong>gular.<br />

The second case denotes two different entities and the verb shows plural number<br />

5u<br />

5th<br />

5u<br />

5th


5.4 The <strong>Modern</strong> <strong>Greek</strong> Modifiers 124<br />

agreement 5 .<br />

The plural quantifier arket-i/-es/-a.pl.masc/fem/neut ‘quite a lot’ scopes over coord<strong>in</strong>ated<br />

plural nouns, which refer either to the same or different <strong>in</strong>dividuals, and agrees <strong>in</strong><br />

gender with the closest conjunct. In example (20), the two nouns admit the jo<strong>in</strong>t read<strong>in</strong>g<br />

denot<strong>in</strong>g the same group of <strong>in</strong>dividuals, which has both properties, whereas <strong>in</strong> example<br />

(21), the nouns admit the split read<strong>in</strong>g denot<strong>in</strong>g different <strong>in</strong>dividuals:<br />

(20) Arketi<br />

ftoxi ke anergi<br />

quite-a-lot.pl.masc poor.pl.masc and unemployed.pl.masc<br />

idopiithikan prosfata apo t<strong>in</strong> eforia<br />

were-warned.pl recently from the tax-office<br />

‘Quite-a-lot of poor and unemployed were notified recently from the tax office’<br />

(G.N.:Ependitis)<br />

(21) Arketi<br />

ipurgi<br />

ke ifipurgi<br />

quite-a-lot.pl.masc m<strong>in</strong>isters.pl.masc and deputy-m<strong>in</strong>isters.pl.masc<br />

psifisan to nomosxedio<br />

voted-for.pl the bill<br />

‘Quite a lot of m<strong>in</strong>isters and deputy-m<strong>in</strong>isters voted for the bill’<br />

(G.N.:To Vima)<br />

The s<strong>in</strong>gular or plural correlative determ<strong>in</strong>er opi-os/-a/-o.sg.masc/fem/neut ‘whoever’<br />

modifies coord<strong>in</strong>ated s<strong>in</strong>gular or plural nouns, respectively, and admits both read<strong>in</strong>gs,<br />

denot<strong>in</strong>g the same or different entities. It specifies the same num agreement with both<br />

conjuncts and it always agrees <strong>in</strong> gender with the closest conjunct. Consider the follow<strong>in</strong>g<br />

examples:<br />

(22) Opios<br />

filos ke s<strong>in</strong>adelfos<br />

whoever.sg.masc friend.sg.masc and colleague.sg.masc<br />

kurasmenos dikeute adia<br />

tired is-entitled day-off<br />

‘Any tired friend and colleague is entitled a day off’<br />

(constructed)<br />

(23) Opio<br />

agori ke<br />

whoever.sg.neut boy.sg.neut and<br />

mporun na kanun etisi<br />

can to make application<br />

‘Any <strong>in</strong>terested boy and girl can apply’<br />

(constructed)<br />

koritsi<br />

girl.sg.neut<br />

<strong>in</strong>e<br />

is.sg<br />

endiaferonte<br />

are-<strong>in</strong>terested.pl<br />

The first case denotes reference to only one and the same <strong>in</strong>dividual s<strong>in</strong>ce the verb shows<br />

s<strong>in</strong>gular number agreement. The second case denotes two different <strong>in</strong>dividuals agori ke<br />

koritsi ‘boy and a girl’ and the verb shows plural number agreement.<br />

The plural correlative determ<strong>in</strong>er with coord<strong>in</strong>ated plural nouns also shows the same<br />

syntactic characteristics, while it allows reference to the same or different entities. This is<br />

illustrated <strong>in</strong> the follow<strong>in</strong>g examples:<br />

(24) Opii<br />

ftoxi<br />

whoever.pl.masc poor.pl.masc<br />

voithia dikeunte amesa<br />

help are-entitled immediately<br />

ke apori<br />

and destitutes.pl.masc<br />

epidoma anerjias<br />

jobseeker’s allowance<br />

xriazonte<br />

need.pl<br />

5 We should note that a second possibility might be available <strong>in</strong> the above examples. In particular,<br />

example (18) can also have plural verb agreement with a split <strong>in</strong>terpretation, and example (19) can also<br />

have s<strong>in</strong>gular verb agreement with a jo<strong>in</strong>t <strong>in</strong>terpretation. These were found less often.


5.4 The <strong>Modern</strong> <strong>Greek</strong> Modifiers 125<br />

‘Any poor and destitutes <strong>in</strong> need of help are immediately entitled to jobseeker’s<br />

allowance’<br />

(G.N.:Ependitis)<br />

(25) Opii<br />

ipurgi<br />

ke ifipurgi<br />

whoever.pl.masc m<strong>in</strong>isters.pl.masc and deputy-m<strong>in</strong>isters.pl.masc<br />

psifisan to nomosxedio tha m<strong>in</strong>un sti Vuli<br />

voted-for.pl the bill will stay <strong>in</strong>-the Parliament<br />

‘Any m<strong>in</strong>isters and deputy-m<strong>in</strong>isters that voted for the bill will stay <strong>in</strong> the Parliament’<br />

(G.N.:To Vima)<br />

In example (24), the two nouns refer to the same group of people, but <strong>in</strong> example (25)<br />

two separate groups are denoted.<br />

In coord<strong>in</strong>ate constructions with conjuncts of different gender the above observations<br />

also hold. A shared modifier scopes over coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns and agrees <strong>in</strong> number with both<br />

conjuncts and <strong>in</strong> gender with the closest conjunct, while it allows both a jo<strong>in</strong>t and a split<br />

<strong>in</strong>terpretation.<br />

In example (26), the s<strong>in</strong>gular attributive adjective kalos ‘good’ agrees <strong>in</strong> number with<br />

both conjuncts but <strong>in</strong> gender with the first conjunct, the noun s<strong>in</strong>adelfo ‘colleague’. The<br />

adjective still scopes over both nouns and the two conjuncts denote different referents s<strong>in</strong>ce<br />

they <strong>in</strong>flect for a plural verb agreement:<br />

(26) Eftixos, exo kalo s<strong>in</strong>adelfo ke<br />

luckily, I-have good.sg.masc colleague.sg.masc and<br />

s<strong>in</strong>adelfisa pu <strong>in</strong>e eksipiretiki<br />

colleague.sg.fem who are.pl helpful.pl<br />

‘Luckily, I have a good man-colleague and woman-colleague who are helpful’<br />

(constructed)<br />

In example (27), the s<strong>in</strong>gular attributive adjective agrees <strong>in</strong> number with both conjuncts<br />

but <strong>in</strong> gender with the first conjunct only. Semantically, however, the adjective ipervoliki<br />

‘excessive’ scopes over both nouns and the two nouns denote the same referent s<strong>in</strong>ce they<br />

convey similar mean<strong>in</strong>gs:<br />

(27) I narkisistes xaraktirizonte apo ipervoliki<br />

the narcissists are-characterised by excessive.sg.fem<br />

aftareskia<br />

ke aftothavmasmo<br />

self-complacency.sg.fem and self-admiration sg.masc<br />

‘The narcissists are characterised by excessive self-complacency and self-admiration’<br />

(G.M.:VIMAgaz<strong>in</strong>o)<br />

Similarly, coord<strong>in</strong>ated plural nouns of the same number but different gender are modified<br />

by an adjective, which agrees <strong>in</strong> number with both nouns and <strong>in</strong> gender with the noun<br />

closest to it. Semantically, the adjective scopes over both nouns and the two conjuncts<br />

may refer to different or to identical entities, as <strong>in</strong> examples (28) and (29), respectively:<br />

(28) Katastrofiki sismi<br />

ke plimires<br />

destructive.pl.masc earthquakes.pl.masc and floods.pl.fem<br />

t<strong>in</strong> poli apo to 1965<br />

the town s<strong>in</strong>ce the 1965<br />

‘Destructive earthquakes and floods hit the town s<strong>in</strong>ce 1965’<br />

www.geocities.com/dsvolou14/ergasies/volos/volos.htm<br />

plitun<br />

hit.pl


5.4 The <strong>Modern</strong> <strong>Greek</strong> Modifiers 126<br />

(29) Kathimer<strong>in</strong>es agonies ke agxi<br />

tu<br />

daily.pl.fem agonies.pl.fem and anguishes.pl.neut of-the<br />

mesu el<strong>in</strong>a <strong>in</strong>e i dulia, i akrivia, ke ta<br />

middle<br />

dania<br />

mortgages<br />

<strong>Greek</strong> are.pl the job, the high-prices and the<br />

‘Daily agonies and anguishes of the middle class greek are jobs, high prices and<br />

mortgages’<br />

(G.M.:VIMAgaz<strong>in</strong>o)<br />

In example (28), the two nouns cannot denote the same entity s<strong>in</strong>ce they refer to<br />

different natural phenomena. In example (29), the two nouns agonies ke agxi are closely<br />

related concepts and denote the same entity.<br />

In the same way, the quantifier meriki ‘some’ modifies two plural conjuncts with mixed<br />

gender. It agrees <strong>in</strong> number with both nouns but <strong>in</strong> gender with the noun closest to it. The<br />

quantifier scopes over both nouns and allows a jo<strong>in</strong>t and a split <strong>in</strong>terpretation, respectively:<br />

(30) An ke antimetopise merikus ekfovismus<br />

even though he-faced some.pl.masc <strong>in</strong>timidations.pl.masc<br />

ke apiles s<strong>in</strong>exise to ergo tu<br />

and threats.pl.fem, he-cont<strong>in</strong>ued the work his<br />

‘Even though he faced some <strong>in</strong>timidations and threats, he cont<strong>in</strong>ued his work’<br />

(G.N.:Eleftherotipia)<br />

(31) Ja merikus daskalus<br />

ke<br />

for some.pl.masc men-teachers.pl.masc and<br />

daskales<br />

ta imerologia itan apajorevmena<br />

women-teachers.pl.fem the diaries were not-allowed<br />

‘For some men-teachers and women-teachers diaries were not allowed’<br />

(G.M.:VIMAgaz<strong>in</strong>o)<br />

In example (30), the two nouns denote the same entity, but <strong>in</strong> example (31), daskalus<br />

ke daskales ‘men-teachers and women-teachers’ denote different groups of people.<br />

The f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>in</strong> MG are summarised as follows:<br />

• A s<strong>in</strong>gular modifier modifies s<strong>in</strong>gular coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns and occurs with the jo<strong>in</strong>t and<br />

the split read<strong>in</strong>g<br />

• A plural modifier modifies plural coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns and occurs with the jo<strong>in</strong>t and the<br />

split read<strong>in</strong>g<br />

• In both cases, the shared modifier agrees <strong>in</strong> gender with the closest conjunct<br />

• A plural modifier cannot modify s<strong>in</strong>gular coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns and occur either with the<br />

jo<strong>in</strong>t or with the split read<strong>in</strong>g<br />

Thus, we can conclude that <strong>in</strong> MG coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns with a shared modifier, the number<br />

feature distributes to both conjuncts s<strong>in</strong>ce both nouns need to specify the same number<br />

feature as their modifier, but the gender feature always shows closest conjunct agreement<br />

(CCA). The shared modifier scopes over coord<strong>in</strong>ate s<strong>in</strong>gular or plural nouns and occurs<br />

with the jo<strong>in</strong>t or split <strong>in</strong>terpretation. In the next section, we will present the analysis of<br />

MG shared modifiers with coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns.


5.4 The <strong>Modern</strong> <strong>Greek</strong> Modifiers 127<br />

5.4.1 concord agreement with the MG Modifiers<br />

Next, we turn to the analysis of the MG modifiers and whether any of the agreement<br />

systems outl<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong> K<strong>in</strong>g and Dalrymple (2004), concord, concord/<strong>in</strong>dex and <strong>in</strong>dex,<br />

account for the MG modifiers.<br />

The presentation of coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrases <strong>in</strong> MG modified by a shared modifier, such as an<br />

adjective or a quantifier, showed that a shared modifier agrees <strong>in</strong> number with both nouns<br />

but <strong>in</strong> gender with the closest conjunct. The modifier scopes over coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns and<br />

occurs with the jo<strong>in</strong>t and split read<strong>in</strong>gs, while the conjuncts refer to the same or different<br />

<strong>in</strong>dividuals, respectively. Therefore, we argue that MG modifiers follow the concord<br />

system. This system would predict the follow<strong>in</strong>g patterns <strong>in</strong> MG:<br />

Table 5.1: CONCORD SYSTEM<br />

ANIMATE INANIMATE<br />

JOINT READ <br />

MODsg<br />

Nsg & Nsg SPLIT READ <br />

MODpl<br />

JOINT READ <br />

Npl & Npl SPLIT READ <br />

MODpl<br />

JOINT READ * *<br />

Nsg & Nsg SPLIT READ * *<br />

The follow<strong>in</strong>g examples will show whether the predictions of the concord system<br />

are borne out <strong>in</strong> MG. First, we will present coord<strong>in</strong>ated s<strong>in</strong>gular nouns with the same<br />

and mixed gender, and then coord<strong>in</strong>ated plural nouns with the same and mixed gender.<br />

Accord<strong>in</strong>g to the MG data, a shared s<strong>in</strong>gular modifier modifies coord<strong>in</strong>ated s<strong>in</strong>gular nouns<br />

and agrees <strong>in</strong> gender with the closest conjunct. The shared modifier may occur with the<br />

jo<strong>in</strong>t read<strong>in</strong>g. Consider the follow<strong>in</strong>g example:<br />

(32) O Kostas <strong>in</strong>e kalos<br />

the Kostas is good.sg.masc<br />

s<strong>in</strong>adelfos<br />

colleague.sg.masc<br />

‘Kostas is a good friend and colleague’<br />

filos<br />

friend.sg.masc<br />

A s<strong>in</strong>gular attributive adjective scopes over the coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns which denote the<br />

same <strong>in</strong>dividual. The adjective kalos ‘good’ requires a sg value for the concord num<br />

feature. The concord num features of the two nouns are also sg and match the featurevalue<br />

of the adjective. The concord gend feature of the adjective agrees with the closest<br />

conjunct, which is the noun filos ‘friend’, although <strong>in</strong> this case the second conjunct shares<br />

the same gender. The adjective does not impose any restrictions on the <strong>in</strong>dex feature and<br />

<strong>in</strong>dex agreement is not constra<strong>in</strong>ed. Therefore, it shows concord agreement only and it<br />

can occur with the jo<strong>in</strong>t <strong>in</strong>terpretation. The lexical entry and f-structure without gender<br />

agreement are as follows:<br />

(33) ‘kalos filos ke s<strong>in</strong>adelfos’<br />

kalos: (↑pred) = ‘good’<br />

((adj ∈↑) concord num) = sg<br />

ke<br />

and


5.4 The <strong>Modern</strong> <strong>Greek</strong> Modifiers 128<br />

ADJ<br />

kalos<br />

NP<br />

N<br />

filos<br />

N<br />

Conj<br />

ke<br />

N<br />

s<strong>in</strong>adelfos<br />

⎡ <br />

⎢ adj pred ‘good’<br />

⎢<br />

c: ⎢<br />

⎣<br />

⎤<br />

⎥<br />

<strong>in</strong>dex [num sg] ⎥<br />

⎧ ⎡<br />

⎤⎫<br />

⎥<br />

pred ‘friend’ ⎥<br />

⎢<br />

⎥ ⎥<br />

b: ⎣concord<br />

[num sg] ⎦ ⎥<br />

⎪⎨<br />

⎪⎬ ⎥<br />

<strong>in</strong>dex [num sg] ⎥<br />

⎡<br />

⎤ ⎥<br />

pred ‘colleague’ ⎥<br />

⎢<br />

⎥ ⎥<br />

g: ⎣concord<br />

[num sg] ⎦ ⎥<br />

⎪⎩<br />

⎪⎭<br />

⎦<br />

<strong>in</strong>dex [num sg]<br />

To account for the phenomenon of closest conjunct agreement <strong>in</strong> the gender feature,<br />

we will assume the analysis proposed by Dalrymple and Hristov (2010), which follows the<br />

basic notions of Kuhn and Sadler (2007). For these cases where the gender of the modifier<br />

is the same as the gender of one of the conjuncts only, LFG <strong>in</strong>troduces the strategy of<br />

Closest Conjunct <strong>Agreement</strong> that captures patterns where the conjuncts <strong>in</strong> a coord<strong>in</strong>ate<br />

structure differ <strong>in</strong> a feature value and the modifier agrees only with one of them usually<br />

the closest one, but scopes over both. Considerable work on CCA has been done <strong>in</strong> a<br />

number of languages by Johannessen (1996), Sadler (1999), Sadler (2003), Yatabe (2004),<br />

Villavicencio et al. (2005), Kuhn and Sadler (2007).<br />

Based on Kuhn and Sadler (2007), Dalrymple and Hristov (2010) handle the various<br />

agreement patterns by def<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g metavariables <strong>in</strong> order to allow reference to peripheral<br />

conjuncts <strong>in</strong> a coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase. They adopt the notation of Kuhn and Sadler (2007), fL<br />

and fL, where f is replaced by any expression that refers to an f-structure and they propose<br />

that these def<strong>in</strong>itions refer to the lefmost and rightmost conjunct <strong>in</strong> a coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase,<br />

while it can also refer to a non-coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase. They also reta<strong>in</strong> the assumption that<br />

<strong>in</strong>dex is a nondistributive feature and concord is a distributive feature, and they state<br />

specific agreement requirements based on the two features, while f represents an arbitrary<br />

f-structure. We will not cite the options for the <strong>in</strong>dex feature but only for the concord<br />

feature s<strong>in</strong>ce we are only <strong>in</strong>terested <strong>in</strong> the concord feature agreement 6 . These are:<br />

(34) • (f concord): the concord features of a noncoord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase or each conjunct<br />

of a coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase (the standard <strong>in</strong>terpretation of this coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase)<br />

• (fL concord): the concord features of a noncoord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase or the leftmost<br />

conjunct of a coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase<br />

• (fR concord): the concord features of a noncoord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase or the rightmost<br />

conjunct of a coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase<br />

In concord, Dalrymple and Hristov (2010) do not dist<strong>in</strong>guish between ‘optional’ closest<br />

conjunct agreement and exclusive closest conjunct agreement as <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>dex, s<strong>in</strong>ce <strong>in</strong> cases<br />

when all conjuncts have the same concord value it is impossible to dist<strong>in</strong>guish between<br />

concord agreement with the closest conjunct and concord agreement with all conjuncts.<br />

Instead, they dist<strong>in</strong>guish only between the strongest requirement of distributive concord<br />

agreement and the weaker requirement of agreement with the closest conjunct.<br />

The expressions (f <strong>in</strong>dex) and (f concord) have their standard LFG mean<strong>in</strong>g where<br />

<strong>in</strong>dex is a nondistributive (resolv<strong>in</strong>g) feature and concord is a distributive feature. The<br />

expression f (L) has the follow<strong>in</strong>g def<strong>in</strong>ition 7 :<br />

6 The <strong>in</strong>dex feature allows for more options with regard to the concord feature s<strong>in</strong>ce it allows for<br />

optional or obligatory agreement with the closest conjunct (Dalrymple and Hristov, 2010, 197).<br />

7 ∈* picks out an arbitrarily deeply embedded member to account for nested coord<strong>in</strong>ation. Any con-<br />

stra<strong>in</strong>ts under attributes <strong>in</strong> a functional uncerta<strong>in</strong>ty path are off-path constra<strong>in</strong>ts, regulat<strong>in</strong>g the f-structures


5.4 The <strong>Modern</strong> <strong>Greek</strong> Modifiers 129<br />

(35) f (L) ≡ f ∈*<br />

¬[(←∈) f→]<br />

These def<strong>in</strong>itions refer to any leftmost or rightmost conjunct, and with embedded coord<strong>in</strong>ations<br />

they may refer to a coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase, which is leftmost or rightmost <strong>in</strong> relation<br />

to the other conjuncts, but which conta<strong>in</strong>s conjuncts itself. Dalrymple and Hristov (2010)<br />

also add the requirement that the f-structure that is the controller of agreement must not<br />

itself be a coord<strong>in</strong>ate structure:<br />

(38) fL ≡ f ∈* : ¬(fL ∈)<br />

¬[(←∈)


5.4 The <strong>Modern</strong> <strong>Greek</strong> Modifiers 130<br />

ADJ<br />

kalos<br />

NP<br />

N<br />

filos<br />

N<br />

Conj<br />

ke<br />

N<br />

s<strong>in</strong>adelfos<br />

⎡ <br />

⎢ adj pred ‘good’<br />

⎢<br />

c: ⎢<br />

⎣<br />

⎤<br />

⎥<br />

<strong>in</strong>dex [num sg]<br />

⎥<br />

⎧ ⎡<br />

⎤⎫<br />

⎥<br />

pred ‘friend’ ⎥<br />

⎢ ⎥<br />

⎥<br />

⎢<br />

num sg ⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢concord<br />

⎥ ⎥<br />

b: ⎢ gend masc ⎥ ⎥<br />

⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢ ⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢<br />

⎣ num sg<br />

⎥ ⎥<br />

⎪⎨<br />

<strong>in</strong>dex<br />

⎦ ⎥<br />

gend masc ⎪⎬ ⎥<br />

⎡<br />

⎤ ⎥<br />

pred ‘colleague’ ⎥<br />

⎢ ⎥<br />

⎥<br />

⎢<br />

num sg ⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢concord<br />

⎥ ⎥<br />

g: ⎢ gend masc ⎥ ⎥<br />

⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢ ⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢<br />

⎣ num sg<br />

⎥ ⎥<br />

⎪⎩<br />

<strong>in</strong>dex<br />

⎦ ⎥<br />

⎦<br />

gend masc ⎪⎭<br />

Thus, the modifiers show distributed concord num agreement and closest conjunct<br />

(i.e. leftmost) agreement <strong>in</strong> gender.<br />

Coord<strong>in</strong>ated s<strong>in</strong>gular nouns are also modified by a shared modifier, which agrees <strong>in</strong><br />

number with both nouns and <strong>in</strong> gender with the closest conjunct (i.e. leftmost), while the<br />

modifier occurs with the split read<strong>in</strong>g too. Consider two s<strong>in</strong>gular concrete nouns:<br />

(40) O<br />

the<br />

Kostas<br />

Kostas<br />

exi<br />

has<br />

oreo<br />

nice.sg.neut<br />

‘Kostas has a nice car and house’<br />

aftok<strong>in</strong>ito<br />

car.sg.neut<br />

ke<br />

and<br />

spiti<br />

house.sg.neut<br />

The adjective oreo ‘nice’ scopes over coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns that refer to different entities<br />

and specifies a sg value for the concord num feature. The nouns have a sg value <strong>in</strong> their<br />

concord num feature as specified by the adjective. Also, the adjective does not specify<br />

any restrictions on the <strong>in</strong>dex feature and therefore it shows only concord agreement.<br />

The adjective agrees <strong>in</strong> gender with the closest conjunct, which is the noun aftok<strong>in</strong>ito ‘car’,<br />

although it shows agreement with the second conjunct too due to the uniform gender of<br />

the conjuncts. The split read<strong>in</strong>g is allowed s<strong>in</strong>ce <strong>in</strong>dex agreement is not constra<strong>in</strong>ed. The<br />

relevant lexical entry and f-structure are illustrated below:<br />

(41) ‘oreo aftok<strong>in</strong>ito ke spiti’<br />

oreo: (↑pred) = ‘nice’<br />

((adj ∈↑) concord num) = sg<br />

((adj ∈↑)L concord gend) = neut


5.4 The <strong>Modern</strong> <strong>Greek</strong> Modifiers 131<br />

NP<br />

ADJ<br />

oreo N<br />

aftok<strong>in</strong>ito<br />

N<br />

Conj<br />

ke<br />

N<br />

spiti<br />

⎡ <br />

⎢adj<br />

pred ‘nice’<br />

⎢<br />

c: ⎢<br />

⎣<br />

⎤<br />

⎥<br />

<strong>in</strong>dex [num pl]<br />

⎥<br />

⎧ ⎡<br />

⎤⎫<br />

⎥<br />

pred ‘car<br />

⎥<br />

⎢ ⎥<br />

⎥<br />

⎢<br />

num sg ⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢concord<br />

⎥ ⎥<br />

b: ⎢ gend neut ⎥ ⎥<br />

⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢ ⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢<br />

⎣ num sg<br />

⎥ ⎥<br />

⎪⎨<br />

<strong>in</strong>dex<br />

⎦ ⎥<br />

gend neut ⎪⎬ ⎥<br />

⎡<br />

⎤ ⎥<br />

pred ‘house’ ⎥<br />

⎢ ⎥<br />

⎥<br />

⎢<br />

num sg ⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢concord<br />

⎥ ⎥<br />

g: ⎢ gend neut ⎥ ⎥<br />

⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢ ⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢<br />

⎣ num sg<br />

⎥ ⎥<br />

⎪⎩<br />

<strong>in</strong>dex<br />

⎦ ⎥<br />

⎦<br />

gend neut ⎪⎭<br />

Coord<strong>in</strong>ate s<strong>in</strong>gular nouns with different gender are also modified by the same modifier.<br />

The modifier shows distributive concord num agreement and occurs with a jo<strong>in</strong>t and a<br />

split read<strong>in</strong>g while it shows closest conjunct agreement <strong>in</strong> gender. In example (42), the<br />

s<strong>in</strong>gular adjective megalos agrees with both conjuncts <strong>in</strong> number and with the first conjunct<br />

only <strong>in</strong> gender. It specifies a sg value <strong>in</strong> the concord num feature and the two nouns<br />

have the same feature value. <strong>in</strong>dex agreement is not constra<strong>in</strong>ed by the adjective and<br />

the jo<strong>in</strong>t read<strong>in</strong>g is allowed. The adjective also specifies masc value <strong>in</strong> the concord<br />

gend feature agree<strong>in</strong>g only with the closest conjunct (i.e. leftmost). Thus, the adjective<br />

shows distributive concord agreement <strong>in</strong> number and closest conjunct agreement (CCA)<br />

<strong>in</strong> gender:<br />

(42) Megalos kopos ke prospathia xriazete<br />

Great.sg.masc labour.sg.masc and effort.sg.fem is-needed.sg<br />

ja na s<strong>in</strong>gedrosi to fotografiko iliko...<br />

for to gather the photographic material...<br />

‘Great labour and effort are needed to gather the photographic material...’<br />

The lexical entry and f-structure are illustrated below:<br />

(43) ‘megalos kopos ke prospathia’<br />

megalos: (↑pred) = ‘great’<br />

((adj ∈↑) concord num) = sg<br />

((adj ∈↑)L concord gend) = masc<br />

ADJ<br />

megalos<br />

NP<br />

N<br />

kopos<br />

N<br />

Conj<br />

ke<br />

N<br />

prospathia


5.4 The <strong>Modern</strong> <strong>Greek</strong> Modifiers 132<br />

⎡ <br />

⎢ adj pred ‘great’<br />

⎢<br />

c: ⎢<br />

⎣<br />

⎤<br />

⎥<br />

<strong>in</strong>dex [num sg]<br />

⎥<br />

⎧ ⎡<br />

⎤⎫<br />

⎥<br />

pred ‘labour’ ⎥<br />

⎢ ⎥<br />

⎥<br />

⎢<br />

num sg ⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢concord<br />

⎥ ⎥<br />

b: ⎢ gend masc ⎥ ⎥<br />

⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢ ⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢<br />

⎣ num sg<br />

⎥ ⎥<br />

⎪⎨<br />

<strong>in</strong>dex<br />

⎦ ⎥<br />

gend masc ⎪⎬ ⎥<br />

⎡<br />

⎤ ⎥<br />

pred ‘effort’ ⎥<br />

⎢ ⎥<br />

⎥<br />

⎢<br />

num sg ⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢concord<br />

⎥ ⎥<br />

g: ⎢ gend fem ⎥ ⎥<br />

⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢ ⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢<br />

⎣ num sg<br />

⎥ ⎥<br />

⎪⎩<br />

<strong>in</strong>dex<br />

⎦ ⎥<br />

⎦<br />

gend fem ⎪⎭<br />

Let us turn to coord<strong>in</strong>ated plural nouns with a shared modifier. Coord<strong>in</strong>ated plural<br />

nouns are modified by a plural adjective which agrees <strong>in</strong> number with both nouns and <strong>in</strong><br />

gender with the closest conjunct and occurs with the jo<strong>in</strong>t read<strong>in</strong>g. In example (44), the<br />

adjective specifies a pl value <strong>in</strong> the concord num feature. The two nouns also specify a pl<br />

value <strong>in</strong> their concord num feature. The adjective does not impose any <strong>in</strong>dex agreement<br />

requirements and the two nouns refer to the same entity, which is allowed by the concord<br />

system. Also, the adjective specifies fem value <strong>in</strong> the concord gend feature agree<strong>in</strong>g<br />

only with the closest conjunct (i.e. leftmost). The lexical entry and f-structure are shown<br />

<strong>in</strong> (45):<br />

(44) Isxires antiparathesis ke antiparavoles<br />

strong.pl.fem juxtapositions.pl.fem and contrasts.pl.fem<br />

ekdilothikan st<strong>in</strong> kentriki s<strong>in</strong>edriasi tis Vulis<br />

were-expressed.pl <strong>in</strong>-the central meet<strong>in</strong>g of-the Parliament<br />

‘Strong juxtapositions and contrasts were expressed <strong>in</strong> the central meet<strong>in</strong>g of the<br />

Parliament’<br />

(45) ‘isxires antiparathesis ke antiparavoles’<br />

isxures: (↑pred) = ‘strong’<br />

((adj ∈↑) concord num) = pl<br />

((adj ∈↑)L concord gend) = fem


5.4 The <strong>Modern</strong> <strong>Greek</strong> Modifiers 133<br />

NP<br />

ADJ<br />

isxures N<br />

antiparathesis<br />

N<br />

Conj<br />

ke<br />

N<br />

antiparavoles<br />

⎡ <br />

⎢adj<br />

pred ‘strong’<br />

⎢<br />

c: ⎢<br />

⎣<br />

⎤<br />

⎥<br />

<strong>in</strong>dex [num pl]<br />

⎥<br />

⎧ ⎡<br />

⎤⎫<br />

⎥<br />

pred ‘juxtapositions’ ⎥<br />

⎢ ⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢<br />

num pl ⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢concord<br />

⎥ ⎥<br />

b: ⎢ gend fem ⎥ ⎥<br />

⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢ ⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢<br />

⎣ num pl<br />

⎥ ⎥<br />

⎪⎨<br />

<strong>in</strong>dex<br />

⎦ ⎥<br />

gend fem ⎪⎬ ⎥<br />

⎡<br />

⎤ ⎥<br />

pred ‘contrasts’ ⎥<br />

⎢ ⎥<br />

⎥<br />

⎢<br />

num pl ⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢concord<br />

⎥ ⎥<br />

g: ⎢ gend fem ⎥ ⎥<br />

⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢ ⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢<br />

⎣ num pl<br />

⎥ ⎥<br />

⎪⎩<br />

<strong>in</strong>dex<br />

⎦ ⎥<br />

⎦<br />

gend fem ⎪⎭<br />

Coord<strong>in</strong>ated plural nouns are also modified by a plural adjective which agrees <strong>in</strong> number<br />

with both nouns and <strong>in</strong> gender with the closest one and occurs with the split read<strong>in</strong>g too.<br />

In example (46), the adjective specifies a pl value <strong>in</strong> the concord num feature. The two<br />

nouns also have a pl value <strong>in</strong> their concord num feature. The split <strong>in</strong>terpretation is<br />

generated s<strong>in</strong>ce the <strong>in</strong>dex feature is not constra<strong>in</strong>ed by the adjective. Thus, the adjective<br />

shows only concord agreement. Also, the adjective specifies neut value <strong>in</strong> the concord<br />

gend feature agree<strong>in</strong>g only with the closest conjunct (i.e. leftmost), although the second<br />

conjunct shares the same gender. The lexical entry and f-structure are shown <strong>in</strong> (47):<br />

(46) Pola mikra agoria<br />

many<br />

voithia<br />

help<br />

small.pl.neut boys.pl.neut<br />

‘Many small boys and girls need help’<br />

(47) ‘mikra agoria ke koritsia’<br />

mikra: (↑pred) = ‘young’<br />

((adj ∈↑) concord num) = pl<br />

((adj ∈↑)L concord gend) = neut<br />

ke<br />

and<br />

koritsia<br />

girls.pl.neut<br />

xriazonte<br />

need.pl


5.4 The <strong>Modern</strong> <strong>Greek</strong> Modifiers 134<br />

NP<br />

ADJ<br />

mikra N<br />

agoria<br />

N<br />

Conj<br />

ke<br />

N<br />

koritsia<br />

⎡ <br />

⎢adj<br />

pred ‘young’<br />

⎢<br />

c: ⎢<br />

⎣<br />

⎤<br />

⎥<br />

<strong>in</strong>dex [num pl]<br />

⎥<br />

⎧ ⎡<br />

⎤⎫<br />

⎥<br />

pred ‘boys ⎥<br />

⎢ ⎥<br />

⎥<br />

⎢<br />

num pl ⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢concord<br />

⎥ ⎥<br />

b: ⎢ gend neut ⎥ ⎥<br />

⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢ ⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢<br />

⎣ num pl<br />

⎥ ⎥<br />

⎪⎨<br />

<strong>in</strong>dex<br />

⎦ ⎥<br />

gend neut ⎪⎬ ⎥<br />

⎡<br />

⎤ ⎥<br />

pred ‘girls’ ⎥<br />

⎢ ⎥<br />

⎥<br />

⎢<br />

num pl ⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢concord<br />

⎥ ⎥<br />

g: ⎢ gend neut ⎥ ⎥<br />

⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢ ⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢<br />

⎣ num pl<br />

⎥ ⎥<br />

⎪⎩<br />

<strong>in</strong>dex<br />

⎦ ⎥<br />

⎦<br />

gend neut ⎪⎭<br />

Plural conjuncts with different gender are also modified by the same adjective. The<br />

adjective agrees <strong>in</strong> number with both nouns and occurs with a jo<strong>in</strong>t and a split read<strong>in</strong>g,<br />

while it agrees <strong>in</strong> gender with the closest conjunct. Below we illustrate an example with a<br />

split read<strong>in</strong>g. In example (48), the plural adjective katastrofiki specifies a plural value <strong>in</strong><br />

its concord num feature; the two coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns have a pl value <strong>in</strong> their concord<br />

num feature, while <strong>in</strong>dex agreement is not constra<strong>in</strong>ed. The adjective also specifies a<br />

masc value <strong>in</strong> the concord gend feature, which agrees only with the first conjunct (i.e.<br />

leftmost). The modifier occurs with the split read<strong>in</strong>g s<strong>in</strong>ce the two conjuncts refer to<br />

different natural phenomena:<br />

(48) Katastrofiki sismi<br />

ke plimires<br />

destructive.pl.masc earthquakes.pl.masc and floods.pl.fem<br />

t<strong>in</strong> poli apo to 1965<br />

the town s<strong>in</strong>ce the 1965<br />

‘Destructive earthquakes and floods hit the town s<strong>in</strong>ce 1965’<br />

The lexical entry and f-structure of the coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase are shown below:<br />

(49) ‘katastrofiki sismi ke plimires’<br />

katastrofiki: (↑pred) = ‘destructive’<br />

((adj ∈↑) concord num) = pl<br />

((adj ∈↑)L concord gend) = masc<br />

ADJ<br />

katastrofiki<br />

NP<br />

N<br />

sismi<br />

N<br />

Conj<br />

ke<br />

N<br />

plimires<br />

plitun<br />

hit.pl


5.5 The <strong>Modern</strong> <strong>Greek</strong> Def<strong>in</strong>ite Determ<strong>in</strong>er 135<br />

⎡ <br />

⎢ adj pred ‘destructive’<br />

⎢<br />

c: ⎢<br />

⎣<br />

⎤<br />

⎥<br />

<strong>in</strong>dex [num pl]<br />

⎥<br />

⎧ ⎡<br />

⎤⎫<br />

⎥<br />

pred ‘earthquakes’ ⎥<br />

⎢ ⎥<br />

⎥<br />

⎢<br />

num pl ⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢concord<br />

⎥ ⎥<br />

b: ⎢ gend masc ⎥ ⎥<br />

⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢ ⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢<br />

⎣ num pl<br />

⎥ ⎥<br />

⎪⎨<br />

<strong>in</strong>dex<br />

⎦ ⎥<br />

gend masc ⎪⎬ ⎥<br />

⎡<br />

⎤ ⎥<br />

pred ‘floods’ ⎥<br />

⎢ ⎥<br />

⎥<br />

⎢<br />

num pl ⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢concord<br />

⎥ ⎥<br />

g: ⎢ gend fem ⎥ ⎥<br />

⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢ ⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢<br />

⎣ num pl<br />

⎥ ⎥<br />

⎪⎩<br />

<strong>in</strong>dex<br />

⎦ ⎥<br />

⎦<br />

gend fem ⎪⎭<br />

To summarise, MG shared s<strong>in</strong>gular and plural modifiers show distributive concord<br />

num agreement and closest conjunct (CCA) gend agreement. The modifier agrees <strong>in</strong><br />

number with both nouns and <strong>in</strong> gender with the closest conjunct. The <strong>in</strong>terpretation of<br />

both the jo<strong>in</strong>t and split read<strong>in</strong>g is equally possible when a shared modifier scopes over<br />

coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns s<strong>in</strong>ce the modifier does not specify any restrictions on the <strong>in</strong>dex feature<br />

of the coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase.<br />

5.5 The <strong>Modern</strong> <strong>Greek</strong> Def<strong>in</strong>ite Determ<strong>in</strong>er<br />

5.5.1 Uniform Number and Gender <strong>in</strong> Coord<strong>in</strong>ate <strong>Noun</strong>s<br />

As opposed to MG modifiers, MG determ<strong>in</strong>ers do not have the same behaviour when they<br />

modify coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns. In both coord<strong>in</strong>ate s<strong>in</strong>gular and plural structures, a separate<br />

determ<strong>in</strong>er needs to appear before each conjunct to allow a split read<strong>in</strong>g and each determ<strong>in</strong>er<br />

agrees with the noun it modifies <strong>in</strong> gender, number and case 8 . A shared determ<strong>in</strong>er,<br />

unlike a shared modifier, needs to agree <strong>in</strong> number and gender with both conjuncts and<br />

admits only a jo<strong>in</strong>t read<strong>in</strong>g.<br />

In coord<strong>in</strong>ate s<strong>in</strong>gular nouns, <strong>in</strong> example (50), the mascul<strong>in</strong>e def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er o<br />

appears before each noun and modifies it. Similarly, <strong>in</strong> example (51), the fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e def<strong>in</strong>ite<br />

determ<strong>in</strong>er i is placed before each noun and modifies it. In both cases, the determ<strong>in</strong>er agrees<br />

<strong>in</strong> number and gender with the noun it modifies. Both examples have a split <strong>in</strong>terpretation<br />

s<strong>in</strong>ce there is a separate determ<strong>in</strong>er before each conjunct and the two conjuncts refer to<br />

different <strong>in</strong>dividuals, while the verb and predicative adjective show plural agreement:<br />

(50) O sizigos<br />

the.sg.masc husband.sg.masc<br />

tis <strong>in</strong>e nei<br />

her are.pl young.pl<br />

‘Her husband and father are young’<br />

(constructed)<br />

ke<br />

and<br />

o<br />

the.sg.masc<br />

pateras<br />

father.sg.masc<br />

8 It might be thought that the occurrence of the def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er before each conjunct is attributed<br />

to the fact that it has an affixal status. The MG def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er, however, does not behave as an affix<br />

and therefore we cannot assume such an analysis.


5.5 The <strong>Modern</strong> <strong>Greek</strong> Def<strong>in</strong>ite Determ<strong>in</strong>er 136<br />

(51) I sizigos ke<br />

the.sg.fem wife.sg.fem and<br />

<strong>in</strong>e nees<br />

are.pl young.pl<br />

‘His wife and daughter are young’<br />

(constructed)<br />

i<br />

the.sg.fem<br />

kori<br />

daughter.sg.fem<br />

A s<strong>in</strong>gle def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er scopes over coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns without the requirement for<br />

a second determ<strong>in</strong>er <strong>in</strong> the second conjunct, only when the coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase has a jo<strong>in</strong>t<br />

<strong>in</strong>terpretation and the two nouns denote the same referent. The def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er agrees<br />

<strong>in</strong> number and gender with both nouns, as shown below:<br />

(52) O filos ke s<strong>in</strong>adelfos<br />

the.sg.masc friend.sg.masc and colleague.sg.masc<br />

gnorizo xronia<br />

I-know for-years<br />

‘The friend and colleague who I know for years’<br />

(constructed)<br />

pu<br />

who<br />

tu<br />

his<br />

ton<br />

him<br />

In sentence (52), the <strong>in</strong>dividual denoted is filos ‘friend’ and s<strong>in</strong>adelfos ‘colleague’ at the<br />

same time. In MG, this pattern is rather common not only <strong>in</strong> animate nouns but also <strong>in</strong><br />

<strong>in</strong>animate nouns too 9 . For example, <strong>in</strong> (53) the s<strong>in</strong>gular def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er nouns agrees<br />

<strong>in</strong> number and gender with both conjuncts and admits the jo<strong>in</strong>t <strong>in</strong>terpretation s<strong>in</strong>ce the<br />

two conjuncts fovos ‘fear’ and tromos ‘terror’ are two closely related notions and they refer<br />

to the same concept:<br />

(53) O fovos ke tromos emfanistike<br />

the.sg.masc fear.sg.masc and terror.sg.masc appeared.sg<br />

st<strong>in</strong> perioxi<br />

<strong>in</strong>-the area<br />

‘The fear and terror appeared aga<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong> the area’<br />

http://www.hri.org/E/1996/96-10-18.dir/keimena/greece/greece2.htm<br />

ksana<br />

aga<strong>in</strong><br />

Similarly, <strong>in</strong> example (54), the s<strong>in</strong>gular def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er agrees <strong>in</strong> number and gender<br />

with the nouns grafio ‘office’ and iatrio ‘surgery’ and the determ<strong>in</strong>er admits the jo<strong>in</strong>t<br />

<strong>in</strong>terpretation s<strong>in</strong>ce the conjuncts denote the same place:<br />

(54) To grafio ke iatrio<br />

the.sg.neut office.sg.neut and surgery.sg.neut<br />

j<strong>in</strong>ekologu vriskete sto kentro<br />

gynaecologist is.sg <strong>in</strong>-the centre<br />

‘The office and surgery of the gynaecologist is <strong>in</strong> the centre’<br />

(constructed)<br />

tu<br />

of-the<br />

To summarise, when a common determ<strong>in</strong>er with wide scope modifies coord<strong>in</strong>ate s<strong>in</strong>gular<br />

nouns, it agrees with both conjuncts <strong>in</strong> number and gender and it occurs only with a jo<strong>in</strong>t<br />

<strong>in</strong>terpretation. To generate a split <strong>in</strong>terpretation, the determ<strong>in</strong>er needs to be repeated<br />

before each conjunct.<br />

In plural number, the MG def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er behaves different from the def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>ers<br />

of languages such as Italian, German, Dutch, F<strong>in</strong>nish and Brazilian Portuguese,<br />

which fully allow a split <strong>in</strong>terpretation <strong>in</strong> addition to the jo<strong>in</strong>t one, when a shared plural<br />

9 We have exam<strong>in</strong>ed concrete and abstract nouns separately to check whether there are any differences<br />

between the two but no differences were found.


5.5 The <strong>Modern</strong> <strong>Greek</strong> Def<strong>in</strong>ite Determ<strong>in</strong>er 137<br />

determ<strong>in</strong>er modifies coord<strong>in</strong>ate plural nouns (Heycock and Zamparelli, 1999, 2000; K<strong>in</strong>g<br />

and Dalrymple, 2004). In MG, the plural determ<strong>in</strong>er imposes the same restrictions as the<br />

s<strong>in</strong>gular determ<strong>in</strong>er when it modifies coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns. Thus, a separate plural determ<strong>in</strong>er<br />

needs to modify each conjunct to generate a split <strong>in</strong>terpretation and each determ<strong>in</strong>er agrees<br />

<strong>in</strong> number and gender with the noun it modifies, as shown below:<br />

(55) I<br />

paterades ke i<br />

the.pl.masc fathers.pl.masc and the.pl.masc<br />

papudes<br />

<strong>in</strong>e poli demeni<br />

grandfathers.pl.masc are.pl very close<br />

‘The fathers and grandfathers are very close’<br />

(constructed)<br />

A shared def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er scopes over coord<strong>in</strong>ate plural nouns, agrees <strong>in</strong> number and<br />

gender with both nouns but it occurs only with the jo<strong>in</strong>t <strong>in</strong>terpretation, denot<strong>in</strong>g the same<br />

group of <strong>in</strong>dividuals. This is shown below:<br />

(56) I<br />

paterades ke<br />

the.pl.masc<br />

ikojenias<br />

family<br />

fathers.pl.masc and<br />

‘The fathers and protectors of the family’<br />

(constructed)<br />

prostates<br />

protectors.pl.masc<br />

tis<br />

of-the<br />

This exact same pattern occurs <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>animate nouns too. In the follow<strong>in</strong>g examples, the<br />

two conjuncts are modified by a s<strong>in</strong>gle plural def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er, which agrees with the<br />

conjuncts <strong>in</strong> number and gender, while the jo<strong>in</strong>t read<strong>in</strong>g is the only possible <strong>in</strong>terpretation:<br />

(57) Ta somata ke kalorifer thelun<br />

the.pl.neut radiators.pl.neut and heaters.pl.neut need.pl<br />

alagma me to aerio<br />

to-be-changed with the gas<br />

‘The radiators and heaters need to be changed because of the gas’<br />

(constructed)<br />

(58) I antiparathesis ke antiparavoles tis<br />

the.pl.fem contrasts.pl.fem and juxtapositions.pl.fem of<br />

DAKE itan nootropies tu parelthontos<br />

DAKE were.pl mentalities of-the past<br />

‘The contrasts and juxtapositions of DAKE were mentalities of the past’<br />

(G.N.:Eleftherotipia)<br />

In example (57), the two concrete nouns denote the same items and therefore the<br />

jo<strong>in</strong>t <strong>in</strong>terpretation is generated. In example (58), the two abstract nouns also refer to<br />

the same notion and therefore the jo<strong>in</strong>t <strong>in</strong>terpretation is only possible. Thus, a shared<br />

plural determ<strong>in</strong>er, which scopes over coord<strong>in</strong>ate plural nouns, occurs only with the jo<strong>in</strong>t<br />

<strong>in</strong>terpretation.<br />

F<strong>in</strong>ally, we need to note that a plural def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er cannot modify coord<strong>in</strong>ate<br />

s<strong>in</strong>gular nouns. The follow<strong>in</strong>g examples are ungrammatical:<br />

(59) *I ipurgos ke ifipurgos<br />

the.pl.masc<br />

kivernisis<br />

government<br />

m<strong>in</strong>ister.sg.masc and deputy-m<strong>in</strong>ister.sg.masc<br />

‘The m<strong>in</strong>ister and deputy-m<strong>in</strong>ister of the government’<br />

(constructed)<br />

tis<br />

of-the


5.5 The <strong>Modern</strong> <strong>Greek</strong> Def<strong>in</strong>ite Determ<strong>in</strong>er 138<br />

The f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>in</strong> MG are summarised as follows:<br />

• A s<strong>in</strong>gular def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er modifies s<strong>in</strong>gular coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns and occurs with<br />

the jo<strong>in</strong>t read<strong>in</strong>g only<br />

• A plural def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er modifies plural coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns and occurs with the<br />

jo<strong>in</strong>t read<strong>in</strong>g only<br />

• In both cases, the def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er agrees <strong>in</strong> number and gender with both nouns<br />

• A plural def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er cannot modify s<strong>in</strong>gular coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns and occur either<br />

with the jo<strong>in</strong>t or the split read<strong>in</strong>g<br />

In the plural, there are some very limited exceptions to the generalisation stated above<br />

- namely a few cases <strong>in</strong> which a shared plural def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er scopes over coord<strong>in</strong>ate<br />

nouns and occurs with a split <strong>in</strong>terpretation. The first exceptional pattern occurs <strong>in</strong> a<br />

specific group of animate coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns where the two conjuncts denote closely related<br />

concepts. In the follow<strong>in</strong>g examples, the shared plural mascul<strong>in</strong>e determ<strong>in</strong>er i scopes over<br />

plural animate nouns and occurs with a split <strong>in</strong>terpretation. The def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er agrees<br />

<strong>in</strong> number and gender with the two conjuncts:<br />

(60) I<br />

ipurgi<br />

ke ifipurgi<br />

the.pl.masc m<strong>in</strong>isters.pl.masc and deputy-m<strong>in</strong>isters.pl.masc<br />

kivernisis tis ND<br />

government of ND<br />

‘The m<strong>in</strong>isters and deputy-m<strong>in</strong>isters of the government of ND’<br />

(G.N.:Kathimer<strong>in</strong>i)<br />

(61) I<br />

ergazomeni ke<br />

the.pl.masc<br />

anaferun<br />

mention<br />

employed.pl.masc and<br />

‘The employed and unemployed mention it’<br />

(G.N.:Eleftherotipia)<br />

anerji<br />

unemployed.pl.masc<br />

(62) I<br />

iatri<br />

ke odontiatri<br />

the.pl.masc doctors.pl.masc and dentists.pl.masc<br />

simvasis me to strato<br />

contracts with the army<br />

‘The doctors and dentisists avoid any contracts with the army<br />

http://www.omhroi.gr/article2194.htm<br />

to<br />

it<br />

apofevgun<br />

avoid<br />

tis<br />

of-the<br />

In example (60), the two nouns share a s<strong>in</strong>gle def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er but the two conjuncts<br />

refer to different groups of <strong>in</strong>dividuals, allow<strong>in</strong>g only the split <strong>in</strong>terpretation. Semantically,<br />

it is highly unlikely for the same person to be ipurgos ‘m<strong>in</strong>ister’ and ifipurgos ‘deputym<strong>in</strong>ister’<br />

at the same time, while the two nouns are closely related <strong>in</strong> mean<strong>in</strong>g s<strong>in</strong>ce one<br />

is a ‘m<strong>in</strong>ister’ and the other is a ‘deputy-m<strong>in</strong>ister’. Follow<strong>in</strong>g the same reason<strong>in</strong>g, the two<br />

conjuncts <strong>in</strong> example (61), although they are modified by a shared def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er,<br />

they can only convey the split <strong>in</strong>terpretation s<strong>in</strong>ce the <strong>in</strong>terpretation of the sentence does<br />

not allow the people who are ergazomeni ‘employed’ to be anerji ‘unemployed’ at the same<br />

time. Also, the two nouns are semantically related s<strong>in</strong>ce they denote opposite concepts<br />

related to work. F<strong>in</strong>ally, <strong>in</strong> example (62) the two nouns share a s<strong>in</strong>gle def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er<br />

but the split <strong>in</strong>terpretation is generated s<strong>in</strong>ce the two nouns denote two semantically related<br />

concepts iatri ‘doctors’ and odontiatri ‘dentists’.<br />

tis<br />

the


5.5 The <strong>Modern</strong> <strong>Greek</strong> Def<strong>in</strong>ite Determ<strong>in</strong>er 139<br />

The same restricted pattern also occurs <strong>in</strong> plural abstract and concrete 10 nouns which<br />

are semantically related. Thus, a s<strong>in</strong>gle def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er scopes over coord<strong>in</strong>ated plural<br />

nouns and occurs with a split <strong>in</strong>terpretation. The def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er agrees <strong>in</strong> gender and<br />

number with both conjuncts. Consider the follow<strong>in</strong>g examples:<br />

(63) Ta thetika ke<br />

the.pl.neut positives.pl.neut and<br />

ipothesis <strong>in</strong>e pola<br />

case are.pl many<br />

‘The pros and cons of the case are many’<br />

(G.N.:Ependitis)<br />

arnitika<br />

negatives.pl.neut<br />

(64) Ta ithi<br />

ke ethima<br />

the.pl.neut<br />

diamorfothikan<br />

were-formed.pl<br />

morals.pl.neut and customs.pl.neut<br />

‘The morals and customs as they were formed’<br />

(G.M.:VIMAgaz<strong>in</strong>o)<br />

(65) Ta maxeria ke<br />

the.pl.neut knives.pl.neut and<br />

sto trapezi<br />

the table<br />

‘The knives and forks are on the table’<br />

(G.M.:1000+1 Gefsis)<br />

pirunia<br />

forks.pl.neut<br />

opos<br />

as<br />

<strong>in</strong>e<br />

are.pl<br />

tis<br />

of-the<br />

pano<br />

on<br />

In example (63), the two <strong>in</strong>animate abstract nouns refer to different items while the<br />

def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er used for the first conjunct thetika ‘positive’ scopes over the second<br />

conjunct too, the noun arnitika ‘negative’. The only read<strong>in</strong>g available <strong>in</strong> this case is the<br />

split one. Similarly, <strong>in</strong> examples (64) and (65), the coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns ithi ke ethima ‘morals<br />

and customs’ and maxeria ke pirounia ‘knives and forks’ refer to different notions/entities.<br />

In both cases, a shared def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er scopes over the two conjuncts and the phrases<br />

are acceptable. Thus, <strong>in</strong> all examples the two nouns refer to different entities 11 .<br />

To summarise, syntactically a shared def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er agrees <strong>in</strong> number and gender<br />

with both conjuncts. Semantically, the shared def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er modifies coord<strong>in</strong>ate<br />

nouns and occurs with the jo<strong>in</strong>t read<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> both s<strong>in</strong>gular and plural number. The split<br />

read<strong>in</strong>g is generated only when each conjunct is modified by a separate determ<strong>in</strong>er. There<br />

are some exceptional cases when a shared def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er modifies coord<strong>in</strong>ated plural<br />

nouns. The shared def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er agrees <strong>in</strong> gender and number with both nouns,<br />

while it scopes over both coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns and allows a split read<strong>in</strong>g. We will show that<br />

these cases occur under specific conditions. Thus, MG differs from the other languages<br />

discussed by Heycock and Zamparelli (1999, 2000) and K<strong>in</strong>g and Dalrymple (2004) s<strong>in</strong>ce <strong>in</strong><br />

MG a shared def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er, when modify<strong>in</strong>g coord<strong>in</strong>ated s<strong>in</strong>gular and plural nouns,<br />

generates the jo<strong>in</strong>t read<strong>in</strong>g only. In other languages (i.e. Brazilian Portuguese, French,<br />

Italian or German), however, a shared def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er scopes over coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns<br />

and occurs with the jo<strong>in</strong>t <strong>in</strong>terpretation <strong>in</strong> s<strong>in</strong>gular conjuncts only, but a jo<strong>in</strong>t and a split<br />

<strong>in</strong>terpretation <strong>in</strong> plural conjuncts.<br />

10 In concrete coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns, the split read<strong>in</strong>g under a shared determ<strong>in</strong>er was found less often but it<br />

was accepted by more than half of the native speakers. S<strong>in</strong>ce the data is based on acceptability judgements,<br />

we will assume that these patterns are possible but occur rarely.<br />

11 As we will show <strong>in</strong> the 5.5.2.1, all these patterns are cases of natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation.


5.5 The <strong>Modern</strong> <strong>Greek</strong> Def<strong>in</strong>ite Determ<strong>in</strong>er 140<br />

5.5.2 Uniform Number and Different Gender <strong>in</strong> Coord<strong>in</strong>ate <strong>Noun</strong>s<br />

Next, we turn to coord<strong>in</strong>ate structures with uniform number and mixed gender nouns<br />

modified by a shared def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er. Conjo<strong>in</strong>ed nouns of uniform number and different<br />

gender, either <strong>in</strong> s<strong>in</strong>gular or <strong>in</strong> plural, are modified by a separate determ<strong>in</strong>er each.<br />

In example (66), the s<strong>in</strong>gular animate nouns require a separate determ<strong>in</strong>er s<strong>in</strong>ce the<br />

nouns have different gender and two different <strong>in</strong>dividuals are denoted, the mascul<strong>in</strong>e noun<br />

antras ‘man’ and the neuter noun pedi ‘child’. Therefore, the sentence with a shared<br />

determ<strong>in</strong>er is ungrammatical:<br />

(66) *O antras<br />

the.sg.masc man.sg.masc<br />

‘The man and child’<br />

(constructed)<br />

ke<br />

and<br />

pedi<br />

child.sg.neut<br />

S<strong>in</strong>gular <strong>in</strong>animate conjuncts show the same behaviour. When the coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns<br />

have a s<strong>in</strong>gular number and different gender, even if they refer to the same entity, they<br />

require a separate determ<strong>in</strong>er each, otherwise the result is ungrammatical. In example<br />

(67), each conjunct requires a separate determ<strong>in</strong>er, even though the two nouns denote the<br />

same concept. Thus, the coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase with a shared determ<strong>in</strong>er is ungrammatical:<br />

(67) *To pisma ke isxirognomos<strong>in</strong>i<br />

the.sg.neut spite.sg.neut and stubbornness.sg.fem<br />

‘The spite and stubbornness’<br />

(constructed)<br />

In coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrases with plural conjuncts, the same restrictions hold. Animate nouns<br />

of plural number and different gender cannot occur under the same determ<strong>in</strong>er. Each<br />

conjunct requires a separate def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er, otherwise the sentence is ungrammatical:<br />

(68) *I antres<br />

the.pl.masc men.pl.masc<br />

‘The men and children’<br />

(constructed)<br />

ke<br />

and<br />

pedia<br />

children.pl.neut<br />

Also, plural <strong>in</strong>animate nouns of uniform number and different gender cannot be modified<br />

by a shared def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er. The follow<strong>in</strong>g example is ungrammatical:<br />

(69) *I epeni ke engomia<br />

the.pl.masc praises.pl.masc and commendations.pl.neut<br />

s<strong>in</strong>thetun to sk<strong>in</strong>iko st<strong>in</strong> metaolimpiaki Ath<strong>in</strong>a<br />

comprise.pl the scenery of-the postolympic Athens<br />

‘Praises and commendations comprise the scenery of the postolympic Athens’<br />

(constructed)<br />

Thus, coord<strong>in</strong>ations of nouns where the two conjuncts have a uniform number and<br />

different gender cannot be modified by the same def<strong>in</strong>ite article s<strong>in</strong>ce the number feature<br />

of the article will match those of both nouns but the gender feature of the article will not<br />

match the agreement features of both conjuncts. Instead, they are modified by a separate<br />

determ<strong>in</strong>er and occur with the split read<strong>in</strong>g only. The f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>in</strong> MG are summarised as<br />

follows:<br />

• A s<strong>in</strong>gular def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er cannot modify s<strong>in</strong>gular coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns with different<br />

gender features


5.5 The <strong>Modern</strong> <strong>Greek</strong> Def<strong>in</strong>ite Determ<strong>in</strong>er 141<br />

• A plural def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er cannot modify plural coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns with different<br />

gender features<br />

There is aga<strong>in</strong> a strik<strong>in</strong>g pattern of exceptions to the above which allows a shared<br />

def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er to scope over coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns with uniform number and different<br />

gender and occurs with the split read<strong>in</strong>g. These nouns are usually plural and animate,<br />

with a mascul<strong>in</strong>e and a fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e conjunct. These cases occur due to the <strong>in</strong>determ<strong>in</strong>ate<br />

form (identical morphological and phonological form) of the def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er <strong>in</strong> plural<br />

number. The def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er has the same form i ‘the’.pl.masc/fem <strong>in</strong> mascul<strong>in</strong>e and<br />

fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e plural, which satisfies both the mascul<strong>in</strong>e plural and fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e plural syntactic<br />

requirements 12 . Consider the follow<strong>in</strong>g:<br />

(70) I<br />

mathites<br />

ke<br />

the.pl.masc/fem boy-students.pl.masc and<br />

ton sxolion...<br />

of-the schools...<br />

‘The boy-students and girl-students of the schools...’<br />

(www.<strong>in</strong>.gr)<br />

mathitries<br />

girl-students.pl.fem<br />

(71) I<br />

athlites<br />

ke athlitries<br />

the.pl.masc/fem men-athletes.pl.masc and women-athletes.pl.fem<br />

katatasonte stis teseris katigories<br />

are-classified <strong>in</strong>to-the four categories<br />

‘The men-athletes and women-athletes are classified <strong>in</strong>to four categories’<br />

(www.<strong>in</strong>.gr)<br />

In both examples, the two nouns have different gender but plural number. The first conjunct<br />

is mascul<strong>in</strong>e and the second conjunct is fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e while the def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er has<br />

wide scope over both nouns without posit<strong>in</strong>g any issues of ungrammaticality.<br />

The same phenomenon occurs when the conjuncts appear <strong>in</strong> the reverse order. A shared<br />

plural def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er scopes over coord<strong>in</strong>ated plural nouns and occurs with the split<br />

read<strong>in</strong>g when the first conjunct is fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e and the second conjunct is mascul<strong>in</strong>e, as follows:<br />

(72) I<br />

mathitries ke<br />

the.pl.masc/fem girl-students.pl.fem and<br />

ton sxolion...<br />

of-the schools...<br />

‘The girl-students and boy-students of the schools...’<br />

(constructed)<br />

mathites<br />

boy-students.pl.masc<br />

(73) I<br />

athlitries<br />

ke athlites<br />

the.pl.masc/fem women-athletes.pl.fem and men-athletes.pl.masc<br />

katatasonte stis teseris katigories<br />

are-classified <strong>in</strong>to-the four categories<br />

‘The women-athletes and men-athletes are classified <strong>in</strong>to four categories’<br />

(constructed)<br />

The same pattern is not allowed <strong>in</strong> s<strong>in</strong>gular number when mixed gender (i.e. mascul<strong>in</strong>e<br />

and fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e) s<strong>in</strong>gular nouns are modified by a shared s<strong>in</strong>gular def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er.<br />

12 The MG plural def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er is spelled and pronounced the same <strong>in</strong> the mascul<strong>in</strong>e and femi-<br />

n<strong>in</strong>e genders <strong>in</strong> plural number. The plural neuter def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er has a different form which is ta<br />

‘the’.pl.neut.


5.5 The <strong>Modern</strong> <strong>Greek</strong> Def<strong>in</strong>ite Determ<strong>in</strong>er 142<br />

(74) *O mathitis<br />

ke mathitria<br />

the.sg.masc<br />

sxolion...<br />

schools<br />

boy-student.sg.masc and girl-student.sg.fem<br />

‘The boy-student and girl-student of the schools...’<br />

(constructed)<br />

ton<br />

of-the<br />

Thus, mixed gender but uniform number conjuncts cannot be modified by a shared<br />

def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er and generate a split read<strong>in</strong>g. A few exceptional patterns are found <strong>in</strong><br />

plural when a shared def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er scopes over a coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase with a mascul<strong>in</strong>e<br />

and a fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e plural noun and occurs with the split read<strong>in</strong>g. In the next section, we will<br />

show that the motivation for the occurrence of the exceptional patterns <strong>in</strong> the syntactically<br />

restricted NP structure <strong>in</strong> MG is that the coord<strong>in</strong>ated nouns are cases of natural<br />

coord<strong>in</strong>ation.<br />

5.5.2.1 Motivation for the Exceptional Coord<strong>in</strong>ate Constructions<br />

In this section, we will argue that the exceptional patterns, which allow a shared def<strong>in</strong>ite<br />

determ<strong>in</strong>er to scope over coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns and occurs with a split <strong>in</strong>terpretation, are cases<br />

of natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation (Wälchli, 2005; Haspelmath, 2007; Dalrymple and Nikolaeva, 2006).<br />

We will also consider whether these patterns present any of the syntactic or semantic<br />

characteristics of natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation as proposed by Dalrymple and Nikolaeva (2006).<br />

The exceptional patterns that are cases of natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation refer to examples (60)-(65)<br />

discussed <strong>in</strong> section 5.5.1, and examples (70) and (71) discussed <strong>in</strong> section 5.5.2.<br />

Accord<strong>in</strong>g to Haspelmath (2007), natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation is a special semantic relation<br />

<strong>in</strong> which nouns form a conceptual unit and are related <strong>in</strong> mean<strong>in</strong>g. Also, Wälchli (2005)<br />

argues that natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>in</strong>volves nouns that are expected to cooccur while the<br />

parts (i.e. the conjuncts) express semantically closely related concepts, which are on the<br />

same hierarchical level and the mean<strong>in</strong>g of the whole is more general than the mean<strong>in</strong>g<br />

of the parts, such as brother-sister/‘sibl<strong>in</strong>gs’, hands-feet/‘limbs’ etc. Dalrymple and Nikolaeva<br />

(2006, 12) follow the same assumptions but add that natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation relation is<br />

also contextually specified, depend<strong>in</strong>g on <strong>in</strong>formation drawn from the specific discourse<br />

conditions, general world knowledge or utterance situation.<br />

Dalrymple and Nikolaeva (2006) propose that <strong>in</strong> addition to the above semantic characteristics,<br />

natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation is also expressed syntactically <strong>in</strong> some languages. Some<br />

languages may have different coord<strong>in</strong>ation markers <strong>in</strong> natural and accidental coord<strong>in</strong>ation<br />

(e.g. Ud<strong>in</strong>e), <strong>in</strong> other languages natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>in</strong>volves phonological reduction of<br />

the coord<strong>in</strong>ation markers (e.g. Oceanic languages). Also, it may <strong>in</strong>volve lack of determ<strong>in</strong>ers<br />

and the use of a s<strong>in</strong>gle <strong>in</strong>flectional mark<strong>in</strong>g, such as <strong>in</strong> Eastern Armenian. Another<br />

characteristic is that natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation usually allows only two conjuncts and no more<br />

than two. F<strong>in</strong>ally, accord<strong>in</strong>g to Dalrymple and Nikolaeva (2006) a natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation<br />

f-structure requires that <strong>in</strong>dex and concord feature values must be the same, while the<br />

conjuncts need to be either both s<strong>in</strong>gular or both plural. In any case, the coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase<br />

has an f-structure that resembles the f-structure of a plural noun, as opposed to accidental<br />

coord<strong>in</strong>ation where concord is different from <strong>in</strong>dex 13 .<br />

In MG, the first exceptional structure, which concerns examples (75), (76) and (77)<br />

repeated from above, allows a shared plural def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er to scope over coord<strong>in</strong>ate<br />

plural nouns of the same gender and occurs with a split read<strong>in</strong>g. The nouns coord<strong>in</strong>ated<br />

are not arbitrarily comb<strong>in</strong>ed conjuncts but denote entities that are characterised by, what<br />

we will call, semantic relatedness. The term semantic relatedness will be used to state that<br />

13 See section 3.3.3 for a brief summary of the characteristics of natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation and Dalrymple and<br />

Nikolaeva (2006) for a detailed analysis.


5.5 The <strong>Modern</strong> <strong>Greek</strong> Def<strong>in</strong>ite Determ<strong>in</strong>er 143<br />

the two conjuncts are <strong>in</strong> a special semantic relation with each other by be<strong>in</strong>g members<br />

of the same semantic group of nouns, such as hyponyms of the same superord<strong>in</strong>ate term.<br />

This follows from the def<strong>in</strong>ition of natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation, as proposed by Wälchli (2005),<br />

Haspelmath (2007) and Dalrymple and Nikolaeva (2006). Thus, the first semantic characteristic<br />

<strong>in</strong> MG natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation is that the nouns must be semantically related <strong>in</strong><br />

order to allow a shared def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er to scope over coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns and occur with<br />

a split read<strong>in</strong>g.<br />

(75) I<br />

ipurgi<br />

ke ifipurgi<br />

the.pl.masc m<strong>in</strong>isters.pl.masc and deputy-m<strong>in</strong>isters.pl.masc<br />

kivernisis tis ND<br />

government of ND<br />

‘The m<strong>in</strong>isters and deputy-m<strong>in</strong>isters of the government of ND’<br />

(G.N.:Ependitis)<br />

(76) Ta maxeria ke<br />

the.pl.neut<br />

trapezi<br />

table<br />

knives.pl.neut and<br />

‘The knives and forks are on the table’<br />

(G.M.:1000+1 Gefsis)<br />

pirunia<br />

forks.pl.neut<br />

(77) Ta ithi<br />

ke ethima<br />

the.pl.neut<br />

diamorfothikan<br />

morals.pl.neut and customs.pl.neut<br />

they-were-formed<br />

‘The morals and customs as they were formed’<br />

(G.M.:VIMAgaz<strong>in</strong>o)<br />

<strong>in</strong>e<br />

are.pl<br />

opos<br />

as<br />

sto<br />

on-the<br />

tis<br />

of-the<br />

The nouns <strong>in</strong> example (75), ipurgi ke ifipurgi ‘m<strong>in</strong>isters and deputy-m<strong>in</strong>isters’ are semantically<br />

related and they both denote entities that function as hyponyms of the same<br />

superord<strong>in</strong>ate term. The superord<strong>in</strong>ate term could be the noun ‘government’. Similarly,<br />

the nouns <strong>in</strong> examples (76), maxeria ke pirunia ‘knives and forks’ and (77), ithi ke ethima<br />

‘morals and customs’ are also semantically related and could be perceived as members of<br />

the superord<strong>in</strong>ate terms ‘cutlery’ and ‘traditions of a culture’, respectively. Thus, <strong>in</strong> all<br />

cases the two conjuncts function as hyponyms of a semantically more general term.<br />

In the follow<strong>in</strong>g example the conjuncts cannot be coord<strong>in</strong>ated under a shared def<strong>in</strong>ite<br />

determ<strong>in</strong>er with a split read<strong>in</strong>g:<br />

(78) *I jatri<br />

the.pl.masc doctors.pl.masc<br />

‘The doctors and lawyers’<br />

ke<br />

and<br />

dikigori<br />

lawyers.pl.masc<br />

The two nouns denote two professions and they could be hyponyms of the hypernymic<br />

term ‘professionals’. However, they do not express semantically closely related concepts<br />

or natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation s<strong>in</strong>ce the profession jatros ‘doctor’ does not have any common<br />

characteristics with the profession dikigoros ‘lawyer’. Therefore, the determ<strong>in</strong>er needs to<br />

be overtly specified for each conjunct <strong>in</strong> order for the phrase to be grammatical. Instead, the<br />

profession jatros ‘doctor’ is semantically related to the profession odontiatros ‘dentist’ and<br />

the profession dikigoros ‘lawyer’ is semantically related to the profession dikastis ‘judge’.<br />

Therefore, if we replace the second conjunct with a noun such as odontiatri ‘dentists’, the<br />

coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase is acceptable even with a shared def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er and it allows a split<br />

read<strong>in</strong>g:


5.5 The <strong>Modern</strong> <strong>Greek</strong> Def<strong>in</strong>ite Determ<strong>in</strong>er 144<br />

(79) I<br />

jatri<br />

ke odontiatri<br />

the.pl.masc doctors.pl.masc and dentists.pl.masc<br />

silogu Thesalonikis<br />

association of-Thessaloniki<br />

‘The doctors and dentists of Thessaloniki’s association’<br />

(G.N.:Eleftherotipia)<br />

tu<br />

of-the<br />

A syntactic characteristic <strong>in</strong> natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation constructions, which is also found <strong>in</strong><br />

other languages like German, is that a shared def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er modifies two coord<strong>in</strong>ate<br />

nouns, and the nouns refer to different <strong>in</strong>dividuals (i.e. split <strong>in</strong>terpretation). In MG, this<br />

syntactic structure is admitted <strong>in</strong> accidentally coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns and only if the nouns<br />

denote the same <strong>in</strong>dividual (i.e. jo<strong>in</strong>t <strong>in</strong>terpretation). The same structure is also admitted<br />

<strong>in</strong> the exceptional patterns discussed <strong>in</strong> which the nouns are not accidentally coord<strong>in</strong>ated<br />

but naturally coord<strong>in</strong>ated. Therefore, we could hypothesize that the presence of a s<strong>in</strong>gle<br />

def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er scop<strong>in</strong>g over coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns and generat<strong>in</strong>g the split read<strong>in</strong>g is one<br />

of the syntactic characteristics of natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>in</strong> MG. In other languages, natural<br />

coord<strong>in</strong>ation is expressed by the absence of a determ<strong>in</strong>er or by the use of coord<strong>in</strong>ation<br />

or phonological markers. Also, another syntactic characteristic of natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation is<br />

that the number of conjuncts allowed <strong>in</strong> these constructions is usually two (less often three<br />

conjuncts) at least <strong>in</strong> the languages discussed by Dalrymple and Nikolaeva (2006). In MG,<br />

we usually f<strong>in</strong>d two conjuncts; coord<strong>in</strong>ations of three conjuncts under a shared determ<strong>in</strong>er<br />

are not strictly ungrammatical but they are used less often and only if the nouns are<br />

semantically related:<br />

(80) ?I jatri,<br />

odontiatri ke<br />

the.pl.masc doctors.pl.masc, dentists.pl.masc and<br />

mikroviologi<br />

tu silogu Thesalonikis<br />

microbiologists.pl.masc of-the association of-Thesaloniki<br />

‘The doctors, dentists and microbiologists of Thesaloniki association’<br />

(constructed)<br />

Therefore, the presence of usually two conjuncts <strong>in</strong> the above structures <strong>in</strong> MG should<br />

be considered as one more characteristic of natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation.<br />

F<strong>in</strong>ally, a natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation f-structure requires that <strong>in</strong>dex and concord features<br />

should match and that the coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase has an f-structure that resembles the fstructure<br />

of a plural noun. Also, the conjuncts need to be either both s<strong>in</strong>gular or both<br />

plural. In MG natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation cases, this syntactic representation does not occur. In<br />

MG, <strong>in</strong>dex and concord features are plural due to the requirement for plural conjuncts<br />

by the plural def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er, s<strong>in</strong>ce the exceptional natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation patterns are<br />

only found <strong>in</strong> the plural. The conjuncts can never be s<strong>in</strong>gular while the determ<strong>in</strong>er specifies<br />

for a plural <strong>in</strong>dex and concord feature-value, such as <strong>in</strong> the case of F<strong>in</strong>nish. Therefore,<br />

<strong>in</strong> MG the f-structure of natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation does not resemble the f-structure of a plural<br />

noun but it appears to be the same as the f-structure of accidental coord<strong>in</strong>ation. Thus,<br />

we argue that syntactically the f-structure of MG natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation patterns seems to<br />

resemble the f-structure of accidental coord<strong>in</strong>ation.<br />

The next exceptional structure is when a plural def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er modifies two plural<br />

conjuncts with a mascul<strong>in</strong>e and a fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e gender. First of all, this structure is admitted<br />

due to the fact that the def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er o, i, to ‘the’.sg.masc/fem/neut <strong>in</strong> the plural<br />

number is <strong>in</strong>determ<strong>in</strong>ate and it can show agreement with both a mascul<strong>in</strong>e and a fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e<br />

plural noun. It has a separate form only <strong>in</strong> the neuter gender, which is ta ‘the’.pl.neut.<br />

The <strong>in</strong>determ<strong>in</strong>ate form of the determ<strong>in</strong>er allows the coord<strong>in</strong>ation of a mascul<strong>in</strong>e and a<br />

fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e plural noun under the same plural def<strong>in</strong>ite article s<strong>in</strong>ce the latter can satisfy the<br />

syntactic requirements of both nouns. The follow<strong>in</strong>g example is repeated from above:


5.5 The <strong>Modern</strong> <strong>Greek</strong> Def<strong>in</strong>ite Determ<strong>in</strong>er 145<br />

(81) I<br />

papudes<br />

ke<br />

the.pl.masc/fem grandfathers.pl.masc and<br />

<strong>in</strong>e xarumeni<br />

are.pl happy<br />

‘The grandfathers and grandmothers are happy’<br />

(constructed)<br />

jajades<br />

grandmothers.pl.fem<br />

These patterns are considered cases of natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation s<strong>in</strong>ce a shared determ<strong>in</strong>er<br />

scopes over the two nouns and allows a split read<strong>in</strong>g. Also, these cases only occur with<br />

conjuncts that are necessarily mascul<strong>in</strong>e and fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e, semantically related and the number<br />

of conjuncts is usually two. Any coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase with conjuncts that are mascul<strong>in</strong>e and<br />

fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e but not semantically related or with conjuncts that are mascul<strong>in</strong>e and neuter and<br />

semantically related are strictly ungrammatical. In these patterns, the split read<strong>in</strong>g is the<br />

only possibility. The follow<strong>in</strong>g examples are considered ungrammatical:<br />

(82) *I<br />

daskali ke mathitries<br />

the.pl.masc/fem teachers.pl.masc and girl-students.pl.fem<br />

defteras dimotiku<br />

second-year <strong>in</strong>-primary-school<br />

‘The teachers and girl-students of the second year <strong>in</strong> primary school’<br />

(constructed)<br />

(83) *I<br />

papudes<br />

ke<br />

the.pl.masc/fem grandfathers.pl.masc and<br />

to anaferun<br />

it mention.pl<br />

‘The grandfathers and grandchildren mention it’<br />

(constructed)<br />

tis<br />

of-the<br />

engonia<br />

grandchildren.pl.neut<br />

In example (82), the two conjuncts are not semantically related and therefore they<br />

cannot be coord<strong>in</strong>ated under the same determ<strong>in</strong>er. In example (83), the conjuncts are<br />

semantically related but the phrase is ungrammantical s<strong>in</strong>ce the two nouns are mascul<strong>in</strong>e<br />

and neuter <strong>in</strong> gender and they cannot occur under a shared determ<strong>in</strong>er.<br />

To summarise, the MG def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er presents a number of exceptional patterns<br />

that occur under specific conditions. The first is when a MG shared plural def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er<br />

modifies coord<strong>in</strong>ated plural conjuncts that are semantically related and occurs with<br />

a split <strong>in</strong>terpretation. The second exceptional pattern is when a plural def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er<br />

modifies coord<strong>in</strong>ated plural nouns with a mascul<strong>in</strong>e and a fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e gender that are semantically<br />

related, and also occurs with a split <strong>in</strong>terpretation. This pattern is motivated by<br />

the <strong>in</strong>determ<strong>in</strong>ate form of the def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er <strong>in</strong> plural number, which agrees both with<br />

a mascul<strong>in</strong>e and a fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e plural noun. These patterns should be seen under the realm<br />

of natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation s<strong>in</strong>ce they present some special characteristics - namely a common<br />

determ<strong>in</strong>er for both conjuncts and a split read<strong>in</strong>g, the presence of usually two conjuncts<br />

and semantically related conjuncts. We argued, though, that syntactically these patterns<br />

have an f-structure that seems to resemble the f-structure of accidental coord<strong>in</strong>ation and<br />

not that of natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation. In the next section, we will present the analysis of the<br />

shared def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er with coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns.<br />

5.5.3 <strong>in</strong>dex/concord agreement with the MG Def<strong>in</strong>ite Determ<strong>in</strong>er<br />

We now turn to the analysis of the MG def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er with coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns and<br />

whether any of the three systems, concord, <strong>in</strong>dex/concord and <strong>in</strong>dex, account for it.<br />

We will argue that the MG def<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er follows concord/<strong>in</strong>dex agreement. This


5.5 The <strong>Modern</strong> <strong>Greek</strong> Def<strong>in</strong>ite Determ<strong>in</strong>er 146<br />

system syntactically accounts for the MG def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er but further semantic factors<br />

are <strong>in</strong>volved when it comes to the MG data.<br />

The MG def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er presents specific restrictions with regards to the <strong>in</strong>dex and<br />

concord features. The only system that is restrictive is the <strong>in</strong>dex/concord, and therefore<br />

we will argue that the MG def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er follows <strong>in</strong>dex/concord agreement.<br />

This system would predict the follow<strong>in</strong>g patterns <strong>in</strong> MG:<br />

Table 5.2: INDEX/CONCORD SYSTEM<br />

ANIMATE INANIMATE<br />

JOINT READ <br />

DETsg<br />

Nsg & Nsg SPLIT READ * *<br />

DETpl<br />

JOINT READ <br />

Npl & Npl SPLIT READ <br />

DETpl<br />

JOINT READ * *<br />

Nsg & Nsg SPLIT READ * *<br />

Next, we will exam<strong>in</strong>e whether these predications are borne out <strong>in</strong> MG. In the s<strong>in</strong>gular<br />

number, a shared MG def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er agrees <strong>in</strong> number and gender with both nouns<br />

and scopes over coord<strong>in</strong>ated s<strong>in</strong>gular nouns that refer to a s<strong>in</strong>gle <strong>in</strong>dividual or entity.<br />

Hence, the MG def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er requires a sg value for the <strong>in</strong>dex num feature and,<br />

redundantly, a sg value for the concord num feature. The two s<strong>in</strong>gular conjuncts also<br />

need to have a sg value <strong>in</strong> their concord num feature. F<strong>in</strong>ally, the def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er<br />

specifies that both conjuncts have the same gender value <strong>in</strong> their concord gend feature<br />

as the determ<strong>in</strong>er. Consider the follow<strong>in</strong>g example:<br />

(84) O filos ke s<strong>in</strong>adelfos<br />

the.sg.masc friend.sg.masc and colleague.sg.masc<br />

ton gnorizo xronia<br />

him.sg.masc I-know for-years<br />

‘The friend and colleague whom I know for years’<br />

pu<br />

who<br />

S<strong>in</strong>ce the <strong>in</strong>dex feature is responsible for determ<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g the distribution of the determ<strong>in</strong>er<br />

o ‘the’, the lexical entry of the determ<strong>in</strong>er specifies both <strong>in</strong>dex and concord features.<br />

Also, it specifies concord gend agreement requirements:<br />

(85) o: (↑spec) = ‘the’<br />

(↑concord num) = sg<br />

(↑concord gend) = masc<br />

(↑<strong>in</strong>dex num) = sg<br />

The f-structure would be as follows:


5.5 The <strong>Modern</strong> <strong>Greek</strong> Def<strong>in</strong>ite Determ<strong>in</strong>er 147<br />

(86)<br />

⎡<br />

⎤<br />

spec ‘the’<br />

⎢<br />

⎥<br />

⎢<strong>in</strong>dex<br />

[num sg]<br />

⎥<br />

⎢⎧<br />

⎢ ⎡<br />

⎤⎫<br />

⎥<br />

⎢ pred ‘friend ⎥<br />

⎢ ⎢ ⎥<br />

⎥<br />

⎢ ⎢<br />

⎢ ⎢<br />

num sg ⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢ ⎢concord<br />

⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢ b: ⎢ gend masc ⎥ ⎥<br />

⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢ ⎢ ⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢ ⎢<br />

⎢ ⎣ num sg<br />

⎥ ⎥<br />

c: ⎢⎪⎨<br />

<strong>in</strong>dex<br />

⎦ ⎥<br />

⎢ gend masc ⎪⎬ ⎥<br />

⎢ ⎡<br />

⎤ ⎥<br />

⎢ pred ‘colleague’<br />

⎥<br />

⎢<br />

⎢ ⎥<br />

⎥<br />

⎢<br />

⎢<br />

⎢<br />

⎢<br />

num sg ⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢<br />

⎢concord<br />

⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢<br />

g: ⎢ gend masc ⎥ ⎥<br />

⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢<br />

⎢ ⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢<br />

⎢<br />

⎣<br />

⎣ num sg<br />

⎥ ⎥<br />

⎪⎩<br />

<strong>in</strong>dex<br />

⎦ ⎥<br />

gend masc ⎪⎭<br />

⎦<br />

Thus, the MG s<strong>in</strong>gular def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er that scopes over coord<strong>in</strong>ate s<strong>in</strong>gular nouns<br />

shows <strong>in</strong>dex/concord agreement and generates only the jo<strong>in</strong>t read<strong>in</strong>g and not the split<br />

read<strong>in</strong>g.<br />

In plural number, a shared MG def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er agrees <strong>in</strong> number and gender with<br />

both nouns and scopes over coord<strong>in</strong>ated plural nouns, which must necessarily refer to the<br />

same <strong>in</strong>dividuals or entities. Hence, <strong>in</strong> plural number the MG def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er requires<br />

a pl value for the <strong>in</strong>dex num feature and a pl value for the concord num feature while<br />

the two conjuncts also need to have a pl value <strong>in</strong> their concord num feature. The def<strong>in</strong>ite<br />

determ<strong>in</strong>er also requires that both conjuncts have the same gender value <strong>in</strong> their concord<br />

gend feature as the determ<strong>in</strong>er itself. Consider the follow<strong>in</strong>g example with animate nouns:<br />

(87) I<br />

fili<br />

ke<br />

the.pl.masc<br />

voithia<br />

help<br />

friends.pl.masc and<br />

‘The friends and colleagues need help’<br />

s<strong>in</strong>adelfi<br />

colleagues.pl.masc<br />

xriazonte<br />

need.pl<br />

The lexical entry of the plural def<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er specifies both the <strong>in</strong>dex and concord<br />

features s<strong>in</strong>ce the concord and redudantly the <strong>in</strong>dex feature determ<strong>in</strong>e the distribution<br />

of the determ<strong>in</strong>er:<br />

(88) i: (↑spec) = ‘the’<br />

(↑concord num) = pl<br />

(↑concord gend) = masc<br />

(↑<strong>in</strong>dex num) = pl<br />

The f-structure is as follows:


5.5 The <strong>Modern</strong> <strong>Greek</strong> Def<strong>in</strong>ite Determ<strong>in</strong>er 148<br />

(89)<br />

⎡<br />

⎤<br />

spec ‘the’<br />

⎢<br />

⎥<br />

⎢<strong>in</strong>dex<br />

[num pl]<br />

⎥<br />

⎢⎧<br />

⎢ ⎡<br />

⎤⎫<br />

⎥<br />

⎢ pred ‘friends’ ⎥<br />

⎢ ⎢ ⎥<br />

⎥<br />

⎢ ⎢<br />

⎢ ⎢<br />

num pl ⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢ ⎢concord<br />

⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢ b: ⎢ gend masc ⎥ ⎥<br />

⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢ ⎢ ⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢ ⎢<br />

⎢ ⎣ num pl<br />

⎥ ⎥<br />

c: ⎢⎪⎨<br />

<strong>in</strong>dex<br />

⎦ ⎥<br />

⎢ gend masc ⎪⎬ ⎥<br />

⎢ ⎡<br />

⎤ ⎥<br />

⎢ pred ‘colleagues’<br />

⎥<br />

⎢<br />

⎢ ⎥<br />

⎥<br />

⎢<br />

⎢<br />

⎢<br />

⎢<br />

num pl ⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢<br />

⎢concord<br />

⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢<br />

g: ⎢ gend masc ⎥ ⎥<br />

⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢<br />

⎢ ⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢<br />

⎢<br />

⎣<br />

⎣ num pl<br />

⎥ ⎥<br />

⎪⎩<br />

<strong>in</strong>dex<br />

⎦ ⎥<br />

gend masc ⎪⎭<br />

⎦<br />

Thus, the MG plural def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er that scopes over coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns shows <strong>in</strong>dex/concord<br />

agreement while it generates the jo<strong>in</strong>t read<strong>in</strong>g only.<br />

The analysis above showed that MG s<strong>in</strong>gular def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er modifies coord<strong>in</strong>ate<br />

s<strong>in</strong>gular nouns and occurs only with the jo<strong>in</strong>t read<strong>in</strong>g. Also, the MG plural def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er<br />

modifies coord<strong>in</strong>ate plural nouns and occurs only with the jo<strong>in</strong>t read<strong>in</strong>g when the<br />

coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns represent an accidental coord<strong>in</strong>ation but it occurs with the split read<strong>in</strong>g<br />

when the coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns are cases of natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation. Thus, we state the follow<strong>in</strong>g<br />

generalisation:<br />

Jo<strong>in</strong>t read<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> Plural Coord<strong>in</strong>ate <strong>Noun</strong>s<br />

For languages like MG, a plural def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er imposes <strong>in</strong>dex/concord<br />

agreement and a boolean/jo<strong>in</strong>t <strong>in</strong>terpretation with an accidental coord<strong>in</strong>ation<br />

of plural nouns unless the nouns can be construed as a natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation.<br />

Therefore, we can conclude that syntactically the MG def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er is effectivelly<br />

captured by the <strong>in</strong>dex/concord agreement system, but semantically the MG plural determ<strong>in</strong>er<br />

<strong>in</strong>troduces further semantic factors that are beyond those generated by the <strong>in</strong>dex/concord<br />

system.<br />

To summarise, the MG s<strong>in</strong>gular def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er follows the <strong>in</strong>dex/concord system,<br />

which allows only the jo<strong>in</strong>t read<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> s<strong>in</strong>gular number. The MG plural def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er<br />

is also syntactically captured by the <strong>in</strong>dex/concord agreement system. Semantically,<br />

the present system allows both the jo<strong>in</strong>t and split <strong>in</strong>terpretation <strong>in</strong> plural number.<br />

The MG plural def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er, however, allows the jo<strong>in</strong>t <strong>in</strong>terpretation <strong>in</strong> accidentally<br />

coord<strong>in</strong>ated nouns and the split <strong>in</strong>terpretation <strong>in</strong> natural coord<strong>in</strong>ations. This semantic<br />

restriction is only found <strong>in</strong> MG as opposed to languages such as Brazilian Portuguese, Italian,<br />

French and German, which allow a plural def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er with coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns<br />

to occur with a jo<strong>in</strong>t and a split <strong>in</strong>terpretation (K<strong>in</strong>g and Dalrymple, 2004, 91). In the<br />

next section, we will discuss the patterns of natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>in</strong> MG and whether the<br />

syntactic representation of the <strong>in</strong>dex/concord system accounts for the MG data or a<br />

different syntactic structure is required.<br />

5.5.4 Natural Coord<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>in</strong> <strong>Modern</strong> <strong>Greek</strong><br />

In MG plural nouns, the split read<strong>in</strong>g emerges only when the conjuncts are candidates for<br />

natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation. Dalrymple and Nikolaeva (2006) <strong>in</strong>troduce a special f-structure <strong>in</strong>


5.5 The <strong>Modern</strong> <strong>Greek</strong> Def<strong>in</strong>ite Determ<strong>in</strong>er 149<br />

naturally coord<strong>in</strong>ated nouns, which is different from the f-structure of accidentally coord<strong>in</strong>ated<br />

nouns. As already mentioned, the natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation patterns <strong>in</strong> MG do not have<br />

the same syntactic structure as the syntactic structure of natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation proposed<br />

by Dalrymple and Nikolaeva (2006). Therefore, we will show that MG natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation<br />

cases are not captured by the f-structure proposed by Dalrymple and Nikolaeva<br />

(2006) but they are accounted for by the <strong>in</strong>dex/concord system without any additional<br />

requirements.<br />

The f-structure of natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation requires at most two conjuncts. The coord<strong>in</strong>ate<br />

nouns do not appear as members of the set, as <strong>in</strong> accidental coord<strong>in</strong>ation, but they are<br />

two <strong>in</strong>dependent conjuncts each contribut<strong>in</strong>g its own f-structure with<strong>in</strong> the f-structure of<br />

the phrase as a whole. Also, concord num and <strong>in</strong>dex num features need to have a pl<br />

value, resembl<strong>in</strong>g the f-structure for compound or plural nouns, whereas conjuncts can be<br />

s<strong>in</strong>gular or plural. F<strong>in</strong>ally, the modifier does not impose any requirements on the concord<br />

and <strong>in</strong>dex features as <strong>in</strong> accidental coord<strong>in</strong>ation.<br />

The f-structure below <strong>in</strong> F<strong>in</strong>nish, repeated from Chapter 2, admits a coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase<br />

with a plural modifier and s<strong>in</strong>gular nouns:<br />

(90) Natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation<br />

uskolliset<br />

faithful.pl<br />

aviomies<br />

husband<br />

‘faithful [husband and wife]’<br />

AdjP<br />

Adj<br />

uskolliset<br />

NP<br />

N’<br />

N<br />

aviomies<br />

N’<br />

N<br />

Conj<br />

ja<br />

ja<br />

and<br />

N<br />

vaimo<br />

vaimo<br />

wife<br />

(Dalrymple and Nikolaeva, 2006, 842)<br />

⎡<br />

⎤<br />

pred ‘conj’<br />

⎢<br />

⎥<br />

⎢concord<br />

[num pl] ⎥<br />

⎢<br />

⎥<br />

⎢<br />

⎢<strong>in</strong>dex<br />

[num pl] ⎥<br />

⎢ ⎡<br />

⎤ ⎥<br />

⎢ pred ‘husband’ ⎥<br />

⎢ ⎢<br />

⎥⎥<br />

⎢conj1<br />

⎣concord<br />

[num sg] ⎦ ⎥<br />

⎢ <strong>in</strong>dex [num sg]<br />

⎥<br />

⎢<br />

⎡<br />

⎤⎥<br />

⎢ pred ‘wife’<br />

⎥<br />

⎢<br />

⎢<br />

⎥<br />

conj2<br />

⎢<br />

⎣concord<br />

[num sg] ⎦ ⎥<br />

⎢<br />

⎣ <strong>in</strong>dex [num sg] ⎥<br />

⎦<br />

adj [pred ‘faithful’]<br />

The same f-structure representation 14 cannot account for the MG data. First, MG does<br />

not allow patterns where a plural modifier or determ<strong>in</strong>er scopes over s<strong>in</strong>gular conjuncts.<br />

The follow<strong>in</strong>g examples, repeated from above, are ungrammatical:<br />

(91) *Drastirii pateras ke ijos theorunte<br />

active.pl.masc father.sg.masc and son.sg.masc are-considered.pl<br />

o Onasis ke o Aleksantros<br />

the Onasis and the Alexander<br />

‘Active father and son are considered to be Onassis and Alexander’<br />

(constructed)<br />

(92) *I<br />

the.pl.masc<br />

kivernisis<br />

government<br />

ipurgos<br />

m<strong>in</strong>ister.sg.masc<br />

ke<br />

and<br />

ifipurgos<br />

deputy-m<strong>in</strong>ister.sg.masc<br />

tis<br />

of-the<br />

14 Natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>in</strong> other languages like Tundra Nenets, Russian and Bahd<strong>in</strong>ani Kurdish are cap-<br />

tured by the same f-structure. See Dalrymple and Nikolaeva (2006, 843-847) for a detailed analysis.


5.5 The <strong>Modern</strong> <strong>Greek</strong> Def<strong>in</strong>ite Determ<strong>in</strong>er 150<br />

‘The m<strong>in</strong>ister and deputy-m<strong>in</strong>ister of the government’<br />

(constructed)<br />

Natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>in</strong> MG occurs only with conjuncts that are both plural and whose<br />

modifier/determ<strong>in</strong>er agrees <strong>in</strong> number 15 with the conjucts. The modifier/determ<strong>in</strong>er specifies<br />

a pl value <strong>in</strong> the concord num feature and the conjuncts need to have the same<br />

value <strong>in</strong> their concord num feature. Also, natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation patterns <strong>in</strong> MG allow a<br />

shared determ<strong>in</strong>er to scope over the two conjuncts and it usually occurs with the split <strong>in</strong>terpretation.<br />

Thus, <strong>in</strong>dex num needs to be pl s<strong>in</strong>ce the conjuncts are also plural. F<strong>in</strong>ally,<br />

an important requirement is that the coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns must necessarily be semantically<br />

related. The follow<strong>in</strong>g examples are repeated from above:<br />

(93) I<br />

ipurgi<br />

ke ifipurgi<br />

the.pl.masc<br />

kivernisis<br />

government<br />

m<strong>in</strong>isters.pl.masc and deputy-m<strong>in</strong>isters.pl.masc<br />

‘The m<strong>in</strong>isters and deputy-m<strong>in</strong>isters of the government’<br />

(G.N.:Ependitis)<br />

(94) Ta ithi<br />

ke ethima<br />

the.pl.neut morals.pl.neut and customs.pl.neut<br />

diamorfothikan...<br />

they-were-formed<br />

‘The morals and customs as they were formed’<br />

(G.M.:VIMAgaz<strong>in</strong>o)<br />

opos<br />

as<br />

tis<br />

of-the<br />

Thus, we argue that the f-structure representation proposed by Dalrymple and Nikolaeva<br />

(2006) cannot capture the MG data s<strong>in</strong>ce it would generate patterns that are considered<br />

ungrammatical <strong>in</strong> MG, while natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation patterns <strong>in</strong> MG show different<br />

characteristics from those of the languages discussed <strong>in</strong> Dalrymple and Nikolaeva (2006,<br />

843-847).<br />

To account for the MG patterns, we will assume the standard f-structure of accidental<br />

coord<strong>in</strong>ation. We will represent the conjuncts as set elements follow<strong>in</strong>g the f-structure of<br />

accidentally coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns <strong>in</strong> order to allow the additional number of conjuncts, which<br />

occasionally occurs <strong>in</strong> natural coord<strong>in</strong>ate structures <strong>in</strong> MG. Also, the def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er<br />

will specify <strong>in</strong>dex and concord agreement requirements.<br />

For <strong>in</strong>stance, <strong>in</strong> example (94) the def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er requires a pl value <strong>in</strong> the concord<br />

num feature and the nouns need to have the same feature-value concord num=pl <strong>in</strong> their<br />

f-structure. The <strong>in</strong>dex num feature must have a pl value s<strong>in</strong>ce the two nouns are plural<br />

and refer to different groups of entities. Also, the conjuncts need to be semantically related.<br />

F<strong>in</strong>ally, both conjuncts need to agree <strong>in</strong> gender with the def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er. The lexical<br />

entry and f-structure of example (94) are as follows:<br />

(95) Natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>in</strong> MG with a def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er<br />

(95) ta: (↑spec) = ‘the’<br />

(↑concord num) = pl<br />

(↑concord gend) = neut<br />

(↑<strong>in</strong>dex num) = pl<br />

15 Shared modifiers agree <strong>in</strong> gender with the closest conjunct but the shared def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er agrees <strong>in</strong><br />

gender with both conjuncts.


5.5 The <strong>Modern</strong> <strong>Greek</strong> Def<strong>in</strong>ite Determ<strong>in</strong>er 151<br />

DET<br />

ta<br />

NP<br />

+ N<br />

ithi<br />

N<br />

Conj<br />

ke<br />

N<br />

ethima<br />

⎡<br />

⎤<br />

pred ‘conj’<br />

⎢<br />

⎢spec<br />

‘the’<br />

⎥<br />

⎢<br />

⎥<br />

⎢<strong>in</strong>dex<br />

[num pl]<br />

⎥<br />

⎢⎧<br />

⎢ ⎡<br />

⎤⎫<br />

⎥<br />

⎢ pred ‘morals’ ⎥<br />

⎢ ⎢ ⎥<br />

⎥<br />

⎢ ⎢<br />

⎢ ⎢<br />

num pl ⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢ ⎢concord<br />

⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢ b: ⎢ gend neut ⎥ ⎥<br />

⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢ ⎢ ⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢ ⎢<br />

⎢ ⎣ num pl<br />

⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢⎪⎨<br />

<strong>in</strong>dex<br />

⎦<br />

⎥<br />

⎢ gend neut ⎪⎬ ⎥<br />

⎢ ⎡<br />

⎤ ⎥<br />

⎢ pred ‘customs’ ⎥<br />

⎢ ⎢ ⎥<br />

⎥<br />

⎢ ⎢<br />

⎢ ⎢<br />

num pl ⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢ ⎢concord<br />

⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢ g: ⎢ gend neut ⎥ ⎥<br />

⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢ ⎢ ⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢ ⎢<br />

⎣ ⎣ num pl<br />

⎥ ⎥<br />

⎪⎩<br />

<strong>in</strong>dex<br />

⎦ ⎥<br />

⎦<br />

gend neut ⎪⎭<br />

In example (96) a shared plural def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er scopes over a mascul<strong>in</strong>e and a<br />

fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e animate noun and occurs with a split read<strong>in</strong>g. The determ<strong>in</strong>er requires a pl value<br />

<strong>in</strong> the concord num feature and the nouns need to have the same value <strong>in</strong> their concord<br />

num feature. <strong>in</strong>dex num should also be plural s<strong>in</strong>ce the two nouns are plural. The<br />

conjuncts need to be semantically related. Also, the def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er is <strong>in</strong>determ<strong>in</strong>ate<br />

<strong>in</strong> gender and it agrees with both conjuncts. The follow<strong>in</strong>g example is repeated from above:<br />

(96) I<br />

mathites<br />

ke<br />

the.pl.masc/fem boy-students.pl.masc and<br />

tou sxoliu...<br />

of-the school...<br />

‘The boy-students and girl-students of the school... ’<br />

mathitries<br />

girl-students.pl.fem<br />

Follow<strong>in</strong>g Dalrymple and Kaplan (2000), we capture the fact that the def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er<br />

is <strong>in</strong>determ<strong>in</strong>ate <strong>in</strong> gender <strong>in</strong> the plural number, by assign<strong>in</strong>g two values to the<br />

determ<strong>in</strong>er. This will allow the determ<strong>in</strong>er to agree both with a mascul<strong>in</strong>e and a fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e<br />

conjunct 16 . The lexical entry and f-structure are presented below:<br />

(97) i: (↑spec) = ‘the’<br />

(↑concord num) = pl<br />

(↑concord gend) = {masc,fem}<br />

16 In LFG, Dalrymple and Kaplan (2000) use the set-based approach for cases of shar<strong>in</strong>g of token identical<br />

forms such as the relatives <strong>in</strong> German. For example, the relative pronoun was ‘what’ must be accusative<br />

and nom<strong>in</strong>ative <strong>in</strong> case <strong>in</strong> order to satisfy the verbs gegessen ‘eat’ and übrig ‘left’, respectively:<br />

(1) Ich habe gegessen was übrig war<br />

I have eaten what left was<br />

‘I ate what was left’ (Dalrymple and Kaplan, 2000, 759)<br />

This is captured as follows:<br />

(2) was: (↑case)= {nom,acc}<br />

gegessen: acc ∈ (↑ obj case)<br />

übrig: nom ∈ (↑ subj case) (Dalrymple and Kaplan, 2000, 766)


5.5 The <strong>Modern</strong> <strong>Greek</strong> Def<strong>in</strong>ite Determ<strong>in</strong>er 152<br />

DET<br />

i<br />

(↑<strong>in</strong>dex num) = pl<br />

N<br />

NP<br />

mathites<br />

N<br />

Conj<br />

ke<br />

N<br />

mathitries<br />

⎡<br />

⎤<br />

spec ‘the’<br />

⎢<br />

⎥<br />

⎢<strong>in</strong>dex<br />

[num pl]<br />

⎥<br />

⎢⎧<br />

⎢ ⎡<br />

⎤⎫<br />

⎥<br />

⎢ pred ‘boy-students’ ⎥<br />

⎢ ⎢ ⎥<br />

⎥<br />

⎢ ⎢<br />

⎢ ⎢<br />

num pl ⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢ ⎢concord<br />

⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢ b: ⎢ gend masc ⎥ ⎥<br />

⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢ ⎢ ⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢ ⎢<br />

⎢ ⎣ num pl<br />

⎥ ⎥<br />

c: ⎢⎪⎨<br />

<strong>in</strong>dex<br />

⎦ ⎥<br />

⎢ gend masc ⎪⎬ ⎥<br />

⎢ ⎡<br />

⎤ ⎥<br />

⎢ pred ‘girl-students’<br />

⎥<br />

⎢<br />

⎢ ⎥<br />

⎥<br />

⎢<br />

⎢<br />

⎢<br />

⎢<br />

num pl ⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢<br />

⎢concord<br />

⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢<br />

g: ⎢ gend fem ⎥ ⎥<br />

⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢<br />

⎢ ⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢<br />

⎢<br />

⎣<br />

⎣ num pl<br />

⎥ ⎥<br />

⎪⎩<br />

<strong>in</strong>dex<br />

⎦ ⎥<br />

gend fem ⎪⎭<br />

⎦<br />

Therefore, MG natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation cases with a shared def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er follow the<br />

<strong>in</strong>dex/concord system just like MG accidental coord<strong>in</strong>ation cases.<br />

MG modifiers impose similar requirements <strong>in</strong> natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation structures with those<br />

proposed for accidental coord<strong>in</strong>ation. The follow<strong>in</strong>g example is a case of natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation<br />

with a modifier:<br />

(98) Gnosti ipurgi<br />

ke ifipurgi<br />

famous.pl.masc m<strong>in</strong>isters.pl.masc and deputy-m<strong>in</strong>isters.pl.masc<br />

parevrethikan sta engenia<br />

attended.pl the open<strong>in</strong>g<br />

‘Famous m<strong>in</strong>isters and deputy-m<strong>in</strong>isters attended the open<strong>in</strong>g’<br />

In example (98), the two nouns are coord<strong>in</strong>ated under a shared modifier and the split<br />

read<strong>in</strong>g is generated. As <strong>in</strong> accidental coord<strong>in</strong>ate structures with a modifier, the modifier<br />

requires a pl value <strong>in</strong> the concord num feature and the two conjuncts need to have the<br />

same value <strong>in</strong> their concord num feature. This is satisfied by both conjuncts s<strong>in</strong>ce both<br />

members of the set have a pl value <strong>in</strong> their concord num feature. In modifiers, the<br />

<strong>in</strong>dex num feature is not constra<strong>in</strong>ed and therefore it may denote different referents. The<br />

modifier agrees <strong>in</strong> gender with the closest conjunct (i.e. leftmost). The two nouns are also<br />

semantically related. Thus, the standard f-structure for coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns is also assumed<br />

<strong>in</strong> natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation cases with modifiers. The f-structure of example (98) is illustrated<br />

below:<br />

(99) Natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>in</strong> MG with a modifier<br />

gnosti: (↑pred) = ‘famous’<br />

((adj∈↑) concord num) = pl<br />

((adj ∈↑)L concord gend) = masc


5.6 Conclusion 153<br />

⎡<br />

NP<br />

ADJP<br />

gnosti N<br />

ipurgi<br />

N<br />

Conj<br />

ke<br />

N<br />

ifipurgi<br />

pred ‘conj’<br />

⎢ <br />

⎢ <br />

<br />

⎢<br />

adj pred ‘famous’<br />

⎢<br />

⎣<br />

<br />

⎤<br />

⎥<br />

<strong>in</strong>dex [num pl]<br />

⎥<br />

⎧ ⎡<br />

⎤ ⎫ ⎥<br />

pred ‘m<strong>in</strong>isters’<br />

⎥<br />

⎢ <br />

⎥<br />

⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢<br />

num pl ⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢concord<br />

⎥ ⎥<br />

b: ⎢ gend masc ⎥ ⎥<br />

⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢ ⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢<br />

⎣ num pl<br />

⎥ ⎥<br />

⎪⎨<br />

<strong>in</strong>dex<br />

⎦ ⎥<br />

gend masc ⎪⎬<br />

⎥<br />

⎡<br />

⎤ ⎥<br />

pred ‘deputy-m<strong>in</strong>isters’ ⎥<br />

⎢ ⎥<br />

⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢<br />

num pl ⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢concord<br />

⎥ ⎥<br />

g: ⎢ gend masc ⎥ ⎥<br />

⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢ ⎥ ⎥<br />

⎢<br />

⎣ num pl<br />

⎥ ⎥<br />

⎪⎩<br />

<strong>in</strong>dex<br />

⎦ ⎥<br />

gend masc ⎪⎭<br />

⎦<br />

Thus, the MG natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation cases with a shared modifier follow the concord<br />

system.<br />

To summarise, the standard f-structure of accidental coord<strong>in</strong>ation is assumed for natural<br />

coord<strong>in</strong>ation patterns <strong>in</strong> MG modifiers and the MG def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er. The plural<br />

def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er shows <strong>in</strong>dex/concord agreement <strong>in</strong> accidental and <strong>in</strong> natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation<br />

structures, allow<strong>in</strong>g jo<strong>in</strong>t and split read<strong>in</strong>gs as this system predicts. The modifiers<br />

show concord agreement <strong>in</strong> natural and <strong>in</strong> accidental coord<strong>in</strong>ation structures. The use of<br />

the set representation allows the addition of two or more conjuncts, which is a possibility<br />

<strong>in</strong> MG. Thus, the difference between natural and accidental coord<strong>in</strong>ation is not a difference<br />

<strong>in</strong> syntactic representation for MG as <strong>in</strong> other languages. The f-structure of natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation<br />

<strong>in</strong> MG is the same as the f-structure of accidental coord<strong>in</strong>ation. A problem that<br />

still rema<strong>in</strong>s is that we do not impose any additional restrictions concern<strong>in</strong>g the relation<br />

between the two conjuncts, which must be semantically related <strong>in</strong> natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation<br />

structures. This is someth<strong>in</strong>g that must be expressed at the semantic level but it needs<br />

further <strong>in</strong>vestigation s<strong>in</strong>ce it might relate to a different level of representation with<strong>in</strong> the<br />

framework of LFG and will be left for future research.<br />

5.6 Conclusion<br />

In this chapter, we exam<strong>in</strong>ed NP <strong>in</strong>ternal agreement <strong>in</strong> MG coord<strong>in</strong>ate noun phrases,<br />

focus<strong>in</strong>g on MG modifiers and the MG def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er. The data showed that MG<br />

modifiers behave differently from the MG def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er. A shared MG modifier<br />

agrees <strong>in</strong> number with both conjuncts and <strong>in</strong> gender with the closest conjunct. Also, it<br />

scopes over coord<strong>in</strong>ate s<strong>in</strong>gular or plural nouns and allows two types of read<strong>in</strong>g, the jo<strong>in</strong>t<br />

and the split read<strong>in</strong>g. On the other hand, a shared MG def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er agrees <strong>in</strong><br />

number and gender with both conjuncts and it scopes over coord<strong>in</strong>ate s<strong>in</strong>gular or plural<br />

nouns, generat<strong>in</strong>g only the jo<strong>in</strong>t read<strong>in</strong>g. A number of exceptional patterns occur when<br />

a shared MG plural determ<strong>in</strong>er scopes over coord<strong>in</strong>ate plural nouns and generates a split<br />

<strong>in</strong>terpretation. These patterns are considered cases of natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation.<br />

We showed that MG modifiers show distributive concord agreement <strong>in</strong> number and<br />

closest conjunct agreement <strong>in</strong> gender only and the best system that captures them is the<br />

concord agreement system. Also, the MG def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er shows <strong>in</strong>dex and concord<br />

agreement <strong>in</strong> number and distributive concord agreement <strong>in</strong> gender, while it is captured


5.6 Conclusion 154<br />

by the concord/<strong>in</strong>dex agreement system. Syntactically, the MG def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er is<br />

accounted for by the concord/<strong>in</strong>dex system but <strong>in</strong> plural number the MG determ<strong>in</strong>er<br />

<strong>in</strong>troduces further specifications that are directly related to semantics.<br />

F<strong>in</strong>ally, to account for natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation patterns we argued that we cannot follow<br />

the proposal of Dalrymple and Nikolaeva (2006). Natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation patterns <strong>in</strong> MG<br />

differ from natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation patterns <strong>in</strong> other languages and the f-structure on natural<br />

coord<strong>in</strong>ation proposed by Dalrymple and Nikolaeva (2006) cannot capture MG. Thus, we<br />

argued that the standard f-structure for accidental coord<strong>in</strong>ation is able to account for the<br />

MG data <strong>in</strong> which conjuncts are represented as members of a set, the determ<strong>in</strong>er specifies<br />

both concord and <strong>in</strong>dex agreement requirements and the modifiers specify concord<br />

agreement requirements, while the two conjuncts must be semantically related. Further<br />

work is required to exam<strong>in</strong>e whether and how it is possible to express the semantic relation<br />

between the conjuncts <strong>in</strong> natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation constructions.


Chapter 6<br />

Disjunctively Conjo<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>Noun</strong><br />

<strong>Phrases</strong><br />

6.1 Introduction<br />

Although disjunction was discussed by a number of scholars, it has not been studied as<br />

extensively as conjunction. More recently, there has been some <strong>in</strong>terest by a number of<br />

l<strong>in</strong>guists, such as Morgan (1972, 1984, 1985), Peterson (1986), Jenn<strong>in</strong>gs (1994), Eggert<br />

(2002) and Alonso-Ovalle (2006). The central issues discussed are the existence or not of a<br />

second logical operator the exclusive or, the relation of the logical operators to the natural<br />

language or and verb agreement with a disjunctive coord<strong>in</strong>ate noun phrase.<br />

In truth-conditional semantics, logicians agree on the existence of the primary logical<br />

connective or represented as ∨ and known as the <strong>in</strong>clusive or. A number of l<strong>in</strong>guists,<br />

philosophers and logicians discuss the issue of whether to add to propositional logic a<br />

second logical connective represented as and known as the exclusive or.<br />

Concern<strong>in</strong>g the relation of the logical operators ∨ (and for those who support its<br />

existence) with natural language or, the two former are b<strong>in</strong>ary operators restricted to<br />

propositional logic but the latter is not b<strong>in</strong>ary and seems to coord<strong>in</strong>ate anyth<strong>in</strong>g from<br />

sentences to bare noun phrases. Therefore, natural language or is more flexible than the<br />

two logical connectives which connect only whole sentences. F<strong>in</strong>ally, the last issue is verb<br />

agreement with a coord<strong>in</strong>ate noun phrase that consists of two disjuncts, either s<strong>in</strong>gular<br />

or mixed <strong>in</strong> number 1 . S<strong>in</strong>gular number disjuncts allow either a s<strong>in</strong>gular or a plural verb.<br />

Mixed number disjuncts follow the same pattern. All the above issues show that disjunction<br />

is a complicated but rather <strong>in</strong>trigu<strong>in</strong>g phenomenon.<br />

In this chapter, we will focus on agreement with disjunctively conjo<strong>in</strong>ed nouns. In the<br />

first section, we will discuss the dist<strong>in</strong>ction between the <strong>in</strong>clusive and exclusive or <strong>in</strong> truthconditional<br />

semantics and whether a similar dist<strong>in</strong>ction holds <strong>in</strong> natural language. Next,<br />

we will present an overview of the theories <strong>in</strong> disjunctive coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns. F<strong>in</strong>ally, we will<br />

present disjunction phenomena <strong>in</strong> MG coord<strong>in</strong>ate noun phrases, try<strong>in</strong>g to shed some light<br />

on the factors that play a crucial role <strong>in</strong> determ<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g verbal agreement with MG disjunctive<br />

nouns s<strong>in</strong>ce disjunctive coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns and especially the issue of verb agreement and<br />

<strong>in</strong>terpretation <strong>in</strong> MG has not been discussed <strong>in</strong> any of the MG grammar books (Clairis<br />

et al. (2004), Holton et al. (1997), Triantaphyllidis (1994), Triantaphyllidis (2005), Joseph<br />

and Philippaki-Warburton (1987), Mackridge (1985) and Holton et al. (1997)).<br />

1 Uniformly plural disjuncts will not be exam<strong>in</strong>ed s<strong>in</strong>ce the resolved number is always plural and they<br />

do not present any special <strong>in</strong>terest like uniformly s<strong>in</strong>gular disjuncts or mixed number disjuncts.


6.2 Inclusive vs Exclusive or 156<br />

6.2 Inclusive vs Exclusive or<br />

The semantics of disjunction or has attracted much <strong>in</strong>terest among semanticians, logicians,<br />

philosophers and l<strong>in</strong>guists. A primary concern is whether, apart from the truth-functional<br />

<strong>in</strong>clusive or 2 , there is a purely truth-functional exclusive or as well. The second issue is<br />

if natural language adopts a similar k<strong>in</strong>d of dist<strong>in</strong>ction between an ‘<strong>in</strong>clusive-and’ and an<br />

‘exclusive-or’ <strong>in</strong>terpretation. In the current section, we present some background <strong>in</strong>formation<br />

on the logic of disjunction.<br />

In its very basic semantic <strong>in</strong>terpretation, disjunction is a logical connective which is<br />

truth-functional; the value for a complex proposition formed with a truth-functional connective<br />

is derived by the truth values of two propositions, without mak<strong>in</strong>g any reference<br />

to the content of the propositions while the best way to represent the truth-function of a<br />

complex proposition is a truth table that tabulates the graph of how disjunction works.<br />

The majority of logicians and l<strong>in</strong>guists (see Tarski (1941); Ambrose and Lazerowitz<br />

(1962); Qu<strong>in</strong>e (1972); Brody (1973); Hurford (1974); Manicas (1976); Georgakakos (1979);<br />

Barker (1985)) perceive a two way dist<strong>in</strong>ction of disjunction which is reflected <strong>in</strong> the use<br />

of natural language or. The first one is what is referred to as “<strong>in</strong>clusive disjunction” and<br />

it is commonly glossed as ‘and/or’ (Kearns, 2000) <strong>in</strong> natural language.<br />

In the follow<strong>in</strong>g table from Kearns (2000), assum<strong>in</strong>g that p and q are the two propositions,<br />

<strong>in</strong>clusive or disjunction is represented with the truth-functions below:<br />

Table 6.1: Truth Table of Inclusive or<br />

p q p∨q<br />

T T T<br />

T F T<br />

F T T<br />

F F F<br />

Inclusive or results <strong>in</strong> a truth value whenever one or more of its operands are true and results<br />

<strong>in</strong> a false value if and only if both of its operands are false. So crucially a proposition p∨q<br />

is T(rue) even if both p and q are true. The follow<strong>in</strong>g example shows how the logical<br />

disjunction corresponds to ‘<strong>in</strong>clusive disjunction’ (‘and/or’) <strong>in</strong> natural language:<br />

(1) You can get there by tra<strong>in</strong> or bus<br />

(‘You can get there by tra<strong>in</strong> or you can get there by bus’)<br />

(Kearns, 2000)<br />

In this case, the sentence is true if one of the disjuncts is true and even if both disjuncts<br />

are true.<br />

The second logical operator is what they call “exclusive disjunction” which is commonly<br />

glossed as ‘either/or’ <strong>in</strong> natural language. Exclusive or disjunction would have a different<br />

truth table, which differs from the <strong>in</strong>clusive or only when the disjuncts are both T(rue).<br />

This is illustrated below from Kearns (2000):<br />

2 We will use s<strong>in</strong>gle quotes to refer to the two <strong>in</strong>terpretations of or <strong>in</strong> natural language and italics to refer<br />

to the truh-functional or.


6.2 Inclusive vs Exclusive or 157<br />

Table 6.2: Truth Table of Exclusive or<br />

p q pq<br />

T T F<br />

T F T<br />

F T T<br />

F F F<br />

Hence, exclusive or disjunction results <strong>in</strong> a truth value if and only if exactly one of its<br />

operands is true. In other words, pq is F(alse) if both p and q have either a truth value<br />

or alternatively a false value, whereas it is true if at least or at most one of the propositions<br />

is T(rue). The sentence <strong>in</strong> example (1) illustrates how the logical exclusive or operator<br />

corresponds to natural language. The sentence conveys an exclusive <strong>in</strong>terpretation if it is<br />

paraphrased as ‘You can get there either by tra<strong>in</strong> or by bus, (but not both)’. Thus, the<br />

exclusive use of disjunction or <strong>in</strong> natural language requires the <strong>in</strong>terpretation of sentence<br />

<strong>in</strong> such a way as to allow the addition of the phrase qualification ‘but not both’ at the end<br />

of the comb<strong>in</strong>ed proposition.<br />

An oppos<strong>in</strong>g view to the general claim above is that there is only one truth-functional<br />

or and that the exclusive sense of or is not a purely truth-functional operator but it is<br />

occasionally understood by the hearer or arises <strong>in</strong> discourse conditions. Among others (see<br />

Tapscott (1976); Rub<strong>in</strong> and Young (1989) all cited <strong>in</strong> Jenn<strong>in</strong>gs (1994)), the most <strong>in</strong>fluential<br />

proponents of that view were Barret and Stanner (1971), Pelletier (1978) and more recently<br />

Jenn<strong>in</strong>gs (1994).<br />

Barret and Stanner (1971) deny completely the existence of “a purely truth-functional<br />

use of an exclusive or <strong>in</strong> English”(116), although they accept the existence of both an<br />

‘<strong>in</strong>clusive’ and an ‘exclusive’ sense of or <strong>in</strong> English. They support that the English examples<br />

found <strong>in</strong> logic textbooks that could be used to expla<strong>in</strong> a truth-functional exclusive or fail for<br />

two reasons. First, “the alternants of the alternation <strong>in</strong> question are logically <strong>in</strong>compatible<br />

and the problem of the jo<strong>in</strong>t truth cannot even arise” and second, what seems to be a<br />

truth-functional or is simply an ellipsis for a more complex expression which is not purely<br />

truth-functional (Barret and Stanner, 1971, 117) 3 . The most characteristic examples which<br />

fail for the first reason are the ones <strong>in</strong> (2), which are taken to display the exclusive or <strong>in</strong><br />

logic:<br />

(2) a. it is ra<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g or it is not ra<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g<br />

b. x is equal to two or x is equal to three<br />

(Barret and Stanner, 1971, 117)<br />

Barret and Stanner (1971) <strong>in</strong> order to show that the above examples are not cases of<br />

an exclusive or, they rely on the first row of the truth tables of <strong>in</strong>clusive and exclusive<br />

disjunction. As presented above, exclusive disjunction is dist<strong>in</strong>guished from <strong>in</strong>clusive only<br />

from the first row of the truth tables s<strong>in</strong>ce the former requires an F value while the latter<br />

requires a T value as the result of coord<strong>in</strong>at<strong>in</strong>g two propositions that are both T. Thus,<br />

any example that exemplifies the exclusive or needs both of its components to be T(rue)<br />

but the result to be F(alse). Both examples <strong>in</strong> (2) cannot be expla<strong>in</strong>ed by the first row of<br />

the exclusive or truth table s<strong>in</strong>ce the two alternants are <strong>in</strong>compatible and they cannot be<br />

simultaneously T(rue).<br />

An example which fails for the second reason is shown <strong>in</strong> (3). Firstly, this example<br />

cannot be a case of a truth-functional or s<strong>in</strong>ce it is not a statement and only statements<br />

are truth-functional. Barret and Stanner (1971) assume that example (4) “unpacks” the<br />

3 For more details on how they account for the nonexistence of a truth-functional or see Barret and<br />

Stanner (1971, 116).


6.2 Inclusive vs Exclusive or 158<br />

non-statement <strong>in</strong> (3). In this example, the two alternants are not <strong>in</strong>compatible and or<br />

could be seen as a case of a truth-functional exclusive or while they assume that example<br />

(5) is a paraphrase of example (4):<br />

(3) Tea or milk<br />

(4) You are permitted to have tea or milk<br />

(5) You are permitted to have tea or you are permitted to have milk<br />

(Barret and Stanner, 1971, 118)<br />

However, they show that (5) is not really a rephrasal of (4). They argue that if example<br />

(5) is comb<strong>in</strong>ed with the statement ‘you are not permitted to have tea’, it is considered<br />

a consistent statement of the form ‘p∨q: -p’, allow<strong>in</strong>g an <strong>in</strong>clusive or, or even ‘pq: -<br />

p’, allow<strong>in</strong>g an exclusive or. In this case, or is purely truth-functional and it does not<br />

represent a contradiction. For example, a waiter says ‘You are permitted to have tea or<br />

you are permitted to have milk, I’ve forgotten which’ and sometime later when he returns<br />

to the table he says ‘You are not permitted to have tea so I brought milk’ (Barret and<br />

Stanner, 1971, 119). But if example (4) is comb<strong>in</strong>ed with the same statement, the result<br />

is a self-contradictory statement and or is not purely truth-functional. For example, the<br />

waiter says ‘You are permitted to have tea or milk’ and when he returns to the table he<br />

says ‘You are not permitted to have tea unless you pay extra’ (Barret and Stanner, 1971,<br />

119). For the above reasons or <strong>in</strong> (4) cannot be a truth functional exclusive or 4 whereas<br />

or <strong>in</strong> (5) could be a truth-functional exclusive or. Thus, (5) is not a rephrasal of example<br />

(4) while the phrase tea or milk is simply an ellipsis of the phrase <strong>in</strong> (4).<br />

Similarly, Pelletier (1978) argues that the only or <strong>in</strong> English is the <strong>in</strong>clusive and that<br />

the exclusive or is derived by ellipsis or deletion. His first argument comes from examples<br />

like (6). He supports the claim that the statement is false if taxpayers file for both a s<strong>in</strong>gle<br />

and a jo<strong>in</strong>t return but this <strong>in</strong>terpretation is not due to the disjunction or but rather due<br />

to the restriction imposed by the first conjunct which states that only one return should<br />

be filed:<br />

(6) Taxpayers must file exactly one return, but it may be a s<strong>in</strong>gle or a jo<strong>in</strong>t return<br />

(Pelletier, 1978, 65)<br />

He draws further arguments from sentences which seem to convey an exclusive or as <strong>in</strong><br />

(7). First, he assumes that such a sentence is true if and only if its negation is false. A<br />

sentence with either...or negates with neither...nor <strong>in</strong> order to be false:<br />

(7) Arlene wants a marguerita or a grasshopper<br />

(8) Arlene wants neither a marguerita nor a grasshopper<br />

(Pelletier, 1978, 67)<br />

Also, sentence (8) is true <strong>in</strong> the same circumstances as the follow<strong>in</strong>g is true:<br />

(9) Arlene doesn’t want a marguerita and Arlene doesn’t want a grasshopper<br />

(Pelletier, 1978, 67)<br />

Thus, s<strong>in</strong>ce sentence (9) is <strong>in</strong>terpreted us<strong>in</strong>g the conjunction and <strong>in</strong> order to convey<br />

the equivalent mean<strong>in</strong>g of sentence (8) and <strong>in</strong> order to be the correspond<strong>in</strong>g false one of<br />

the true sentence (7), Pelletier (1978) concludes that sentence (7) is true only when both<br />

disjuncts are true and that their negative forms are false also when both disjuncts are false.<br />

4 Barret and Stanner (1971, 118-20) present more arguments aga<strong>in</strong>st the existence of truth-functional<br />

exclusive or.


6.2 Inclusive vs Exclusive or 159<br />

This shows that sentences with the disjunction or are basically <strong>in</strong>clusive and that exclusive<br />

or is drawn through the process of deletion.<br />

Jenn<strong>in</strong>gs (1994), also, extensively discusses the issues concern<strong>in</strong>g the existence of an<br />

<strong>in</strong>clusive and an exclusive or disjunction argu<strong>in</strong>g towards the view that or, like but not dual<br />

to and, does not function as a b<strong>in</strong>ary logical connective but as a k<strong>in</strong>d of a “list punctuat<strong>in</strong>g<br />

device”(293). For example, both sentences You may have tea, or cofee, or milk or You may<br />

have tea, or you may have cofee, or you may have milk <strong>in</strong>volve lists. The first <strong>in</strong>volves<br />

lists of nouns and the second lists of sentential clauses. None of these two, however, are<br />

disjunctive <strong>in</strong> an <strong>in</strong>clusive or an exlusive sense.<br />

The above argument follows from his view that the same dist<strong>in</strong>ction between an <strong>in</strong>clusive<br />

and an exclusive or disjunction cannot hold <strong>in</strong> Lat<strong>in</strong> either. This means that the lexical<br />

dist<strong>in</strong>ction <strong>in</strong> Lat<strong>in</strong> of the two words vel and aut is not one of <strong>in</strong>clusive and exclusive or.<br />

In Lat<strong>in</strong>, the orig<strong>in</strong>al view was that “the word vel expresses weak or <strong>in</strong>clusive disjunction,<br />

and the word aut corresponds to the word or <strong>in</strong> its strong or exclusive sense” (Copi, 1971,<br />

241). The follow<strong>in</strong>g example could be seen as a clear case of an exclusive or where aut<br />

is used <strong>in</strong> the formation of lists of disjo<strong>in</strong>t or contrasted or opposed items, categories or<br />

classes or states:<br />

(10) Omne enuntiatum aut verum aut falsum est<br />

Every statement is either true or false<br />

(Jenn<strong>in</strong>gs, 1994, 242)<br />

Once Jenn<strong>in</strong>gs (1994) considers a different example the behaviour of disjunction has similar<br />

problems as those <strong>in</strong> English. If the example <strong>in</strong> (11) is negated as <strong>in</strong> (12), the result<strong>in</strong>g<br />

sentence will expect a read<strong>in</strong>g along the l<strong>in</strong>es of <strong>in</strong>clusive disjunction.<br />

(11) Timebat tribunos aut plebes<br />

One feared the magistrates or the mob<br />

(12) Nemo timebat tribunos aut plebes<br />

No one feared the magistrates or the mob<br />

(Jenn<strong>in</strong>gs, 1994, 243)<br />

The example <strong>in</strong> (12) means ‘no one feared either’ and ‘not everyone either feared neither<br />

or feared both’. Thus, it is <strong>in</strong>terpreted as an <strong>in</strong>clusive disjunction and not as an exclusive<br />

disjunction. Therefore, Jenn<strong>in</strong>gs (1994) claims that Lat<strong>in</strong> does not really have two words<br />

for or but that Lat<strong>in</strong> had many words that are translated <strong>in</strong>to English as or.<br />

In search of a solution, Jenn<strong>in</strong>gs (1994) discusses nondisjunctive uses of or found <strong>in</strong> four<br />

different environments. When or occurs <strong>in</strong> the complement of a comparative adjective, as<br />

<strong>in</strong> example (13), when it occurs <strong>in</strong> expressions of preference, as <strong>in</strong> (14), when it occurs with<br />

sentences that express modality, as <strong>in</strong> (15), and when or is immediately subord<strong>in</strong>ated to<br />

if, as <strong>in</strong> (16):<br />

(13) Mary is heavier than Jack or Bob<br />

(14) I prefer shiitakes or truffles to morels or oysters<br />

(15) Jane likes Sally or Peter<br />

(16) If you drop it or if you throw it, it will break<br />

(Jenn<strong>in</strong>gs, 1994, 85-9)<br />

He actually adopts a more speech-act oriented approach plac<strong>in</strong>g or with<strong>in</strong> the realm of<br />

pragmatics and refers to the co-ord<strong>in</strong>ator or as a discourse-adverbial one. Such uses are<br />

when or is used to mark a list of alternatives, as seen below repeated from above:


6.2 Inclusive vs Exclusive or 160<br />

(17) You may have tea or coffee<br />

(Jenn<strong>in</strong>gs, 1994, 289)<br />

Associated with this use is when or is used to correct by weaken<strong>in</strong>g, seen below:<br />

(18) My brother, or my half-brother, arrived yesterday<br />

(Jenn<strong>in</strong>gs, 1994, 290)<br />

A further use is one <strong>in</strong> which possibilities are mooted. This means that or <strong>in</strong> this case<br />

goes unnoticed s<strong>in</strong>ce it <strong>in</strong>itiates whole paragraphs and therefore escapes the notice of our<br />

ma<strong>in</strong>ly sentential focus. F<strong>in</strong>ally, a last use is the exegetical one mostly found with glosses,<br />

as seen below:<br />

(19) This is a theorem schema, or meta-theorem<br />

(Jenn<strong>in</strong>gs, 1994, 290)<br />

The expression theorem schema is glossed by the expression meta-theorem. Thus,<br />

Jenn<strong>in</strong>gs (1994) argues that or is neither truth-functionally <strong>in</strong>clusive or exclusive but it is<br />

seen as discourse-adverbial.<br />

On the opposite side stand a number of scholars who support the claim that the exclusive<br />

or is the prevalent disjunction and that the <strong>in</strong>clusive or occurs less often and sometimes<br />

not at all. Lakoff (1971) claims that or is truth-functionally exclusive. One characteristic<br />

example is illustrated below:<br />

(20) Either John eats meat or Harry eats fish<br />

(Lakoff, 1971, 142)<br />

In the above example, there is only one conjunct that is true and therefore the other one<br />

is not. The <strong>in</strong>terpretation assigned to the above example is below and, as it is seen, there<br />

is only one choice:<br />

(21) a. If John doesn’t eat meat, Harry eats fish<br />

b. If John eats meat, Harry doesn’t eat fish<br />

(Lakoff, 1971, 142)<br />

Lakoff (1971) is led to assert that there is an element like choose that underlies the structure<br />

of or. She does not present any conv<strong>in</strong>c<strong>in</strong>g evidence but her argument is based on the fact<br />

that sentences conta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g or are usually ambiguous <strong>in</strong> that the choice is either assumed<br />

to be that of the speaker or that of the hearer, or that of the participant <strong>in</strong> the action<br />

or that of any other unspecified person 5 . Thus, this k<strong>in</strong>d of analysis, which assumes the<br />

existence of the verb choose <strong>in</strong> the underly<strong>in</strong>g structure of disjunction, shows that Lakoff<br />

(1971) accepts only the exclusive or and not the <strong>in</strong>clusive.<br />

The literature overview showed the different views of scholars regard<strong>in</strong>g the existence<br />

of both a truth-functional <strong>in</strong>clusive and a truth-functional exclusive or. The most common<br />

belief is that an <strong>in</strong>clusive or does exist and truth-conditional semantics accounts for that<br />

based on propositional logic. The existence of a purely truth-functional exclusive or is<br />

rather doubtful s<strong>in</strong>ce <strong>in</strong> many cases natural language expressions that could be seen as<br />

cases of a truth-functional exclusive or are <strong>in</strong>adequate to provide an explanation for its<br />

existence (Barret and Stanner, 1971; Pelletier, 1978; Jenn<strong>in</strong>gs, 1994). Next, we will discuss<br />

some issues related to the natural language or.<br />

5 For more details see Lakoff (1971).


6.2 Inclusive vs Exclusive or 161<br />

6.2.1 Natural Language or<br />

Despite the disagreement concer<strong>in</strong>g or truth-conditional semantics, none of the above scholars<br />

denies the existence of an ‘<strong>in</strong>clusive’(‘and-coord<strong>in</strong>ate’) and an ‘exclusive’(‘or’) sense of<br />

or <strong>in</strong> natural languages. A rather common l<strong>in</strong>e taken by most is that we should be careful<br />

when relat<strong>in</strong>g the truth-conditional <strong>in</strong>clusive or (∨) with or <strong>in</strong> natural languages s<strong>in</strong>ce the<br />

former connects merely propositions while the latter connects not only sentences but any<br />

grammatical type. This means that the natural language or is much more flexible than the<br />

truth-conditional <strong>in</strong>clusive or (∨).<br />

The follow<strong>in</strong>g sentence can be paraphrased accord<strong>in</strong>g to propositional logic and <strong>in</strong> this<br />

case the disjunction of the two NPs corresponds to the disjunction of two propositions. In<br />

this case or is a clear-cut case of the truth-conditional <strong>in</strong>clusive or:<br />

(22) Tom or Mary will visit me tonight<br />

(23) Tom will visit me tonight or Mary will visit me tonight<br />

(de Swart, 1998, 58)<br />

Many examples, however, do not follow that pattern, such as the follow<strong>in</strong>g taken from<br />

de Swart (1998):<br />

(24) A doctor or a dentist can write prescriptions<br />

(p ∧ q) where<br />

p = a doctor can write prescriptions<br />

q = a dentist can write prescriptions<br />

(de Swart, 1998, 58)<br />

Accord<strong>in</strong>g to de Swart (1998), the <strong>in</strong>terpretation of the above example is that both<br />

doctors and dentists can write prescriptions, mean<strong>in</strong>g that the correct translation for the<br />

above phrase is a conjunctive statement and not a truth-conditional disjunctive one. Thus,<br />

the phrase above can be paraphrased with and <strong>in</strong>stead of or.<br />

Also, Jenn<strong>in</strong>gs (1994) showed that natural language or has a wide number of uses that<br />

it can jo<strong>in</strong> almost anyth<strong>in</strong>g especially when tak<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>to consideration discourse conditions.<br />

Thus, the natural language or is much more flexible than the logical connective ∨ and, as<br />

most scholars claim, we should be careful when associat<strong>in</strong>g the logical connective with the<br />

‘<strong>in</strong>clusive-and’(conjunctive) sense of natural language or.<br />

Similarly, although most scholars try to reject the existence of an exclusive or <strong>in</strong> truthconditional<br />

semantics, there is an implicit belief that the purely disjunctive or ‘exclusive’<br />

sense of natural language or occurs across languages, especially if one considers sentences<br />

based on real world knowledge as the ones below:<br />

(25) Mary is (either) at home or at college right now<br />

In the above sentence, Mary has to be only at one place and not at two places simultaneously.<br />

Thus, the phrase conveys an ‘exclusive’ sense <strong>in</strong> natural language and it does<br />

not really need to be expla<strong>in</strong>ed based on the reason<strong>in</strong>g of truth-conditional semantics <strong>in</strong><br />

order to prove the truth of its exclusivity. Thus, we believe that an ‘exclusive’ sense of<br />

natural language or also should be seen separately from the truth-conditions approach and<br />

should be perceived <strong>in</strong> association to the discourse facts, which is what some l<strong>in</strong>guists have<br />

done. The fact that discourse conditions frequently determ<strong>in</strong>e speaker’s perception and<br />

<strong>in</strong>terpretation of various utterances shows that we cannot always rely on syntax and logic<br />

to account for the various grammatical phenomena.<br />

To conclude, we briefly presented evidence show<strong>in</strong>g that the basic controversy among<br />

l<strong>in</strong>guists, logicians and philosophers concerns whether there is an exclusive or <strong>in</strong> truthconditional<br />

semantics, based on propositional logic us<strong>in</strong>g natural language data. What is


6.3 Approaches to Disjunctive Coord<strong>in</strong>ated NPs 162<br />

commonly agreed, though, is that there is an ‘<strong>in</strong>clusive’(‘and-coord<strong>in</strong>ate) and an ‘exclusive’<br />

sense of or <strong>in</strong> natural language, proved by a number of examples that cannot be expla<strong>in</strong>ed<br />

rely<strong>in</strong>g on propositional logic but are based on discourse facts. Thus, speakers have the<br />

ability to perceive and <strong>in</strong>terpret sentences differently and this is why both <strong>in</strong>terpretations<br />

of or seem to occur freely <strong>in</strong> natural languages. This conclusion is crucial for the next<br />

sections s<strong>in</strong>ce it is a view followed by l<strong>in</strong>guists <strong>in</strong> cases where syntax seems <strong>in</strong>adequate to<br />

expla<strong>in</strong> some agreement phenomena.<br />

6.3 Approaches to Disjunctive Coord<strong>in</strong>ated NPs<br />

The present section is an overview of the different approaches that were developed regard<strong>in</strong>g<br />

verb agreement with disjunctive coord<strong>in</strong>ate NPs. The problem of verb agreement with<br />

disjunctive NPs has been approached from different views, the syntactic, semantic and<br />

pragmatic. In this section, we will present an overview of these different approaches and<br />

we will see how each of these expla<strong>in</strong>s number verb agreement <strong>in</strong> disjunctive coord<strong>in</strong>ate<br />

NPs.<br />

6.3.1 Morgan’s Analysis of Disjunctive NPs<br />

Morgan (1972) discussed the issue of number agreement <strong>in</strong> conjo<strong>in</strong>ed and disjo<strong>in</strong>ed noun<br />

phrases, focus<strong>in</strong>g on whether the variation <strong>in</strong> number verb agreement is related to mean<strong>in</strong>g<br />

or to syntactic form.<br />

Morgan (1972) argues that, although verb agreement is a syntactic phenomenon, syntax<br />

is not enough to account for the variation <strong>in</strong> verb agreement s<strong>in</strong>ce it is also determ<strong>in</strong>ed by<br />

semantic/pragmatic pr<strong>in</strong>ciples. He identifies two central problems that occur <strong>in</strong> coord<strong>in</strong>ate<br />

noun phrases, the “determ<strong>in</strong>ation” problem and the “selection” problem. We will present<br />

the “determ<strong>in</strong>ation” problem s<strong>in</strong>ce this is relevant to the current discussion. The determ<strong>in</strong>ation<br />

problem refers to the decision as to “what properties of the selected NP determ<strong>in</strong>e<br />

the appropriate form of agreement <strong>in</strong> the verb”(278).<br />

Two structures that focus on the “determ<strong>in</strong>ation” problem and show how verb agreement<br />

is affected are conjo<strong>in</strong>ed subjects and There-<strong>in</strong>sertion, and or-conjo<strong>in</strong>ed subjects 6 .<br />

In conjo<strong>in</strong>ed subjects, speakers prefer plural verb agreement. There are cases, though,<br />

where the <strong>in</strong>terpretation of the NP determ<strong>in</strong>es verb agreement. In example (26a), the<br />

coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns are perceived as separate entities and the verb is plural, whereas <strong>in</strong><br />

example (26b) they are perceived as one entity and the verb is s<strong>in</strong>gular:<br />

(26) a. Pickles and strawberries taste good<br />

b. Pickles and strawberries tastes good<br />

(Morgan, 1972, 280)<br />

In cases of “there-<strong>in</strong>sertion”, the verb usually agrees with the noun closest to it, display<strong>in</strong>g<br />

closest conjunct agreement (i.e. leftmost). This is illustrated below:<br />

(27) There was a man and a woman <strong>in</strong> the room<br />

(28) There were two women and a man <strong>in</strong> the room<br />

(Morgan, 1972, 280-1)<br />

Thus, Morgan (1972) shows that both syntax and semantics determ<strong>in</strong>e verb agreement<br />

<strong>in</strong> coord<strong>in</strong>ate NPs.<br />

6 These are part of a group of nouns that he calls Complex NPs. Other structures that are part of<br />

Complex NPs are what he refers to as the “highest quantifiers”, “disembodied heads”, “measure phrases”.<br />

We only focus on the two structures mentioned above, which are of <strong>in</strong>terest to us.


6.3 Approaches to Disjunctive Coord<strong>in</strong>ated NPs 163<br />

In or-conjo<strong>in</strong>ed subjects, verb agreement patterns are more complicated s<strong>in</strong>ce cases of<br />

closest conjunct agreement alternate with resolved agreement, but other factors also seem<br />

to play a role <strong>in</strong> verb agreement, i.e. the presence of the preconjunction either:<br />

(29) (Either) Harry or his parents *is/are com<strong>in</strong>g<br />

(30) (Either) Harry’s parents or his wife ?is/*are com<strong>in</strong>g<br />

(31) There was (either) a bee or two flies <strong>in</strong> the room<br />

(32) There were either two flies or a bee <strong>in</strong> the room<br />

(Morgan, 1972, 281)<br />

Accord<strong>in</strong>g to Morgan (1972), <strong>in</strong> the above examples the majority of speakers choose<br />

closest conjunct agreement when either is present whereas more speakers choose resolved<br />

agreement when either is not present. Also, a number of speakers f<strong>in</strong>d both closest conjunct<br />

agreement and resolution with or without the preconjunction either ungrammatical 7 . Thus,<br />

they reject both examples below:<br />

(33) *Are/*is (either) John or his parents here?<br />

(34) *Are/*is (either) John’s parents or his wife here?<br />

(Morgan, 1972, 281)<br />

From the above data, Morgan (1972) concludes that <strong>in</strong> coord<strong>in</strong>ate noun phrases any<br />

speaker acquires a specific verb agreement pr<strong>in</strong>ciple, and if this fails then s/he uses additional<br />

ones end<strong>in</strong>g up with a set of pr<strong>in</strong>ciples. These pr<strong>in</strong>ciples may range from syntactic to<br />

semantic/pragmatic, mean<strong>in</strong>g that both syntax and semantics are <strong>in</strong>volved <strong>in</strong> verb agreement.<br />

Morgan (1985) returns to the “determ<strong>in</strong>ation problem”. His central question is whether<br />

number agreement is syntactically or semantically motivated. If it is syntactic, number<br />

agreement should be associated with the purely formal property of the NPs. If it is semantic,<br />

the question is whether it should be associated with the actual mean<strong>in</strong>g of the NP or<br />

the speaker’s beliefs concern<strong>in</strong>g the properties of the <strong>in</strong>tended referent. In fact, he draws<br />

a dist<strong>in</strong>ction between purely syntactic agreement, semantic/pragmatic agreement and a<br />

complex mixture of syntactic and semantic/pragmatic agreement. In syntactic agreement,<br />

the number properties of an NP depend on its syntactic form. In semantic agreement,<br />

number refers to the properties of expressions that are not related to particular occasions<br />

of use but rather depend on the sense or <strong>in</strong>tended referent of the NP. In the complex type<br />

of agreement, sometimes the syntactic agreement will play an active role and other times<br />

the semantic/pragmatic, while it is also possible that syntactic and semantic/pragmatic<br />

agreement may conflict (Morgan, 1985, 70-1).<br />

In or coord<strong>in</strong>ated NPs, Morgan (1985) argues that verb form is determ<strong>in</strong>ed by semantic/pragmatic<br />

agreement. He argues that two dist<strong>in</strong>ct <strong>in</strong>terpretations seem to determ<strong>in</strong>e<br />

number verb agreement; when the sentence conveys an ‘<strong>in</strong>clusive’(‘and’) sense of or, the NP<br />

forces plural verb agreement. When the sentence conveys an ‘exclusive’(‘or’) sense, the verb<br />

shows s<strong>in</strong>gular agreement. The follow<strong>in</strong>g examples display cases of an ‘<strong>in</strong>clusive’(‘and’) and<br />

an ‘exclusive’(‘or’) read<strong>in</strong>g of or:<br />

(35) John or Bill is/??are go<strong>in</strong>g to w<strong>in</strong> the race<br />

(36) I don’t th<strong>in</strong>k John or Bill are/*is go<strong>in</strong>g to w<strong>in</strong> the race<br />

(Morgan, 1985, 72)<br />

7 Morgan (1972) does not provide any details concern<strong>in</strong>g the number of participants and their responses.


6.3 Approaches to Disjunctive Coord<strong>in</strong>ated NPs 164<br />

Accord<strong>in</strong>g to Morgan (1985), <strong>in</strong> example (35) verb agreement is s<strong>in</strong>gular s<strong>in</strong>ce there<br />

must be only one w<strong>in</strong>ner <strong>in</strong> any world where it is true. He also argues that the same<br />

example can have plural verb agreement such as <strong>in</strong> (36) s<strong>in</strong>ce it may convey the mean<strong>in</strong>g<br />

that out of a group of two <strong>in</strong>dividuals, no one of them is go<strong>in</strong>g to w<strong>in</strong> the race. Thus,<br />

<strong>in</strong> both cases the <strong>in</strong>terpretation of the utterance determ<strong>in</strong>es verb agreement. Therefore,<br />

Morgan shows that <strong>in</strong> disjunctive NPs the different <strong>in</strong>terpretations of the speakers will<br />

determ<strong>in</strong>e verb agreement.<br />

To sum up, Morgan (1972, 1985) concludes that there are crucial syntactic and semantic/pragmatic<br />

pr<strong>in</strong>ciples that determ<strong>in</strong>e number verb agreement <strong>in</strong> coord<strong>in</strong>ate NPs. In<br />

conjo<strong>in</strong>ed nouns, this becomes apparent <strong>in</strong> examples where the referent is <strong>in</strong>terpreted as a<br />

s<strong>in</strong>gle entity and s<strong>in</strong>gular verb agreement is required or as two separate entities and plural<br />

verb agreement is required. In disjunctive coord<strong>in</strong>ate NPs, number verb agreement is even<br />

more undeterm<strong>in</strong>ed s<strong>in</strong>ce the choice of the agree<strong>in</strong>g verb is affected by whether disjunction<br />

conveys an ‘<strong>in</strong>clusive’(‘and’) sense or an ‘exclusive’(‘or’) sense and this <strong>in</strong>terpretation varies<br />

across speakers.<br />

Morgan’s analysis <strong>in</strong>corporates basic notions that constitute the beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g for research<strong>in</strong>g<br />

verb agreement with conjunctive and disjunctive NPs from new perspectives. As it turns<br />

out, syntax is not the only factor responsible for the agreement features of the verb but a<br />

comb<strong>in</strong>ation of different pr<strong>in</strong>ciples drive verb agreement, which range from syntactic to semantic/pragmatic<br />

and relate to speaker perception and variation. One problem, however,<br />

is that, even though he discusses the existence of a pragmatic pr<strong>in</strong>ciple provid<strong>in</strong>g valid<br />

data for his claim, he avoids treat<strong>in</strong>g it as a separate pr<strong>in</strong>ciple, but <strong>in</strong>stead he assumes it is<br />

an <strong>in</strong>tegral part of semantics, <strong>in</strong>corporat<strong>in</strong>g the former with<strong>in</strong> the field of the latter. This<br />

notion ends up be<strong>in</strong>g problematic for examples where verb agreement is dependent only<br />

on contextual <strong>in</strong>terpretation. If we consider the example ‘Do you th<strong>in</strong>k John or Bill is/are<br />

happy?’, both verbs could be equally acceptable depend<strong>in</strong>g on the context and speaker<br />

<strong>in</strong>terpretation, which will largerly determ<strong>in</strong>e the choice of the verb. Thus, his analysis is<br />

very <strong>in</strong>fluential but still ignores the purely pragmatic factors that seem to play a role <strong>in</strong><br />

disjunctive coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns.<br />

6.3.2 Peterson’s Analysis of Disjunctive NPs<br />

Peterson (1986) has more to say about number agreement with disjunctively conjo<strong>in</strong>ed<br />

nouns. He presents some <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g data from English and concludes that syntax itself is<br />

not enough to account for disjunctive conjo<strong>in</strong>ed NPs, but rather speakers resort to what he<br />

calls “patch -up rules” of various types. These “patch-up rules” take the form of generalised<br />

pr<strong>in</strong>ciples. Thus, he goes further than Morgan (1972) by establish<strong>in</strong>g the specific pr<strong>in</strong>ciples<br />

that speakers resort to when they decide on number verb agreement <strong>in</strong> or conjo<strong>in</strong>ed nouns.<br />

The discussion is couched <strong>in</strong> LFG.<br />

Peterson (1986) starts his analysis from the two ma<strong>in</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>ciples that have been acknowledged<br />

by a number of l<strong>in</strong>guists, who have worked on disjunctive conjo<strong>in</strong>ed nouns,<br />

“proximity” and “plural w<strong>in</strong>s”. Proximity is mentioned <strong>in</strong> Morgan (1972) as the “closest<br />

conjunct pr<strong>in</strong>ciple” 8 . Similarly, “plural w<strong>in</strong>s” is described <strong>in</strong> Partridge (1956, 221) as<br />

follows: “if either of the two subjects jo<strong>in</strong>ed by or... is plural, the ensu<strong>in</strong>g verb must be<br />

plural”.<br />

Peterson (1986) carried out a survey to confirm the existence of the two pr<strong>in</strong>ciples<br />

and check whether any extra pr<strong>in</strong>ciples are also <strong>in</strong>volved <strong>in</strong> number verb agreement with<br />

disjunctive NPs. He presented a set of data to 42 undergraduate students at the University<br />

of Newcastle (NSW), who were given a set of sentences and were asked to select one of<br />

8 A number of other l<strong>in</strong>guists discuss “proximity”, such as Langendoen (1970, 25), Quirk and Greenbaum<br />

(1973) and Fowler (1926) without giv<strong>in</strong>g it a formal name.


6.3 Approaches to Disjunctive Coord<strong>in</strong>ated NPs 165<br />

the two given verb forms that they considered to be acceptable. They could also accept<br />

or reject both forms. The questionnaires <strong>in</strong>cluded two types of sentences with or without<br />

either. Declarative sentences, with the verb follow<strong>in</strong>g the subject, such as examples (37)<br />

and (38), and <strong>in</strong>terrogative sentences, with the verb preced<strong>in</strong>g the subject, such as examples<br />

(39) and (40):<br />

(37) A rabbit or a goat has/have eaten all my lettuces<br />

(38) Either John or Bill is/are responsible for the mess<br />

(39) Is/are either Fred or Bob responsible for this mess?<br />

(40) Is/are David or Mark com<strong>in</strong>g with me?<br />

(Peterson, 1986, 234-5)<br />

Interrogative sentences without either are considered two way ambiguous. For example,<br />

(40) has two read<strong>in</strong>gs, the “alternative” and the “yes/no” read<strong>in</strong>g, paraphrased below,<br />

respectively:<br />

(41) a. Which of the two boys is com<strong>in</strong>g with me? (only 1 of the two must be chosen)<br />

b. Is either of the two boys com<strong>in</strong>g with me? (the answer is yes or no)<br />

(Peterson, 1986, 235)<br />

Read<strong>in</strong>g (41a) forces the choice of only one boy to go with the speaker; read<strong>in</strong>g (41b)<br />

requires a ‘yes’ or ‘no’ answer mean<strong>in</strong>g that either both boys or none of them will go with<br />

the speaker.<br />

The responses that were given by the consultants fell <strong>in</strong>to various patterns <strong>in</strong> terms<br />

of number verb agreement. In declarative sentences <strong>in</strong> which conjuncts have the same<br />

number, Peterson (1986) f<strong>in</strong>ds that the consultants choose the plural number whenever the<br />

two disjuncts are plural but there is greater variation <strong>in</strong> verb agreement when disjuncts<br />

are s<strong>in</strong>gular s<strong>in</strong>ce there are people who accept both a plural and a s<strong>in</strong>gular verb. Also, the<br />

presence or absence of either makes no difference to the answers of the participants. His<br />

f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>gs, therefore, contradict Morgan’s (1972) claim that the presence of either disallows<br />

an <strong>in</strong>clusive(‘and-coord<strong>in</strong>ate’) read<strong>in</strong>g of or. Also, Peterson (1986) argues quite strongly<br />

that the <strong>in</strong>clusive(‘and’) versus exclusive(‘or’) or dist<strong>in</strong>ction plays no crucial role <strong>in</strong> the<br />

choice of number verb agreement <strong>in</strong> this group of sentences. If <strong>in</strong>terpretation played a<br />

role, he would expect a higher plural response <strong>in</strong> (42) than <strong>in</strong> (43) s<strong>in</strong>ce the first conveys<br />

more easily the <strong>in</strong>clusive(‘and-coord<strong>in</strong>ate’) read<strong>in</strong>g than the second. However, this was<br />

not confirmed, conclud<strong>in</strong>g that the <strong>in</strong>clusive/exclusive dist<strong>in</strong>ction is not obvious <strong>in</strong> positive<br />

declaratives.<br />

(42) A rabbit or a goat has/have eaten all my lettuces<br />

(43) Either John or Bill is/are responsible for this mess.<br />

(Peterson, 1986, 237)<br />

The responses of the students of the above two sentences are shown below:<br />

SENTENCE SG PL BOTH N/A<br />

(42) 36 2 4 -<br />

(43) 36 6 - -<br />

The same conclusion is drawn with regard to the <strong>in</strong>clusive/exclusive dist<strong>in</strong>ction <strong>in</strong><br />

<strong>in</strong>terrogative sentences. The two way ambiguity <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>terrogatives is mapped to the <strong>in</strong>clusive/exclusive<br />

ambiguity of or. Thus, the “alternative” read<strong>in</strong>g corresponds <strong>in</strong> a way to


6.3 Approaches to Disjunctive Coord<strong>in</strong>ated NPs 166<br />

the “exclusive” read<strong>in</strong>g, and the “yes/no” one corresponds to the “<strong>in</strong>clusive”. In the follow<strong>in</strong>g<br />

sentences, the higher number of plural <strong>in</strong> example (44) than <strong>in</strong> example (45) could<br />

be expla<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong> terms of the <strong>in</strong>clusive <strong>in</strong>terpretation of the former. However, the same<br />

explanation is not applicable <strong>in</strong> example (46), which although it <strong>in</strong>cludes either and would<br />

prevent an <strong>in</strong>clusive read<strong>in</strong>g, there were participants who favoured the plu w<strong>in</strong>s strategy.<br />

(44) Is/are David or Mark com<strong>in</strong>g with me?<br />

(45) Are/Is John or Bill go<strong>in</strong>g to w<strong>in</strong> the next race?<br />

(46) Is/Are either John or Bill responsible for this mess?<br />

(Peterson, 1986, 234-5)<br />

The numbers of the responses are summarised <strong>in</strong> the follow<strong>in</strong>g table:<br />

SENTENCE SG PL BOTH N/A<br />

(44) 30 10 2 -<br />

(45) 40 1 1 -<br />

(46) 28 12 2 -<br />

Thus, Peterson (1986) argues that the <strong>in</strong>clusive/exlusive or dist<strong>in</strong>ction is not <strong>in</strong> operation<br />

even <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>terrogatives. Peterson (1986) concludes that the generalisation <strong>in</strong> these<br />

three types of sentences is that “yes/no” <strong>in</strong>terrogatives favour plural and “alternative”<br />

<strong>in</strong>terrogatives favour s<strong>in</strong>gular verb agreement. So it is the contrast between “yes/no” and<br />

“alternative” <strong>in</strong>terpretation and not the contrast between an “<strong>in</strong>clusive” and “exclusive”<br />

read<strong>in</strong>g of or that is reflected <strong>in</strong> number verb agreement.<br />

Next, he discusses declarative sentences with disjunctive coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns <strong>in</strong> which<br />

the conjuncts differ <strong>in</strong> number. The degree of uncerta<strong>in</strong>ty on the part of the consultants<br />

is much greater for these sentences. He also identifies cases where the consultants gave<br />

different answers when they were asked for a second op<strong>in</strong>ion on the same sentence. In<br />

declarative sentences, when disjuncts occur <strong>in</strong> the follow<strong>in</strong>g order [NP.sg or NP.pl] and<br />

[NP.pl or NP.sg], Peterson (1986) identifies two strategies used by the participants, plu<br />

w<strong>in</strong>s and prox. plu w<strong>in</strong>s is stronger than prox s<strong>in</strong>ce plural is a rather popular choice.<br />

In the follow<strong>in</strong>g examples, the participants would choose a plural verb more often than a<br />

s<strong>in</strong>gular:<br />

(47) a. Either this tree or those shrubs has/have to be cut down<br />

b. Either your cats or my dog has/have eaten all the daisies<br />

(Peterson, 1986, 238)<br />

The table below shows the responses of the participants:<br />

SENTENCE SG PL BOTH N/A<br />

(47a) 6 30 3 3<br />

(47b) 15 25 - 2<br />

A small number of participants used a s<strong>in</strong>gular verb form <strong>in</strong> example (47a). This choice<br />

contradicts both the plu w<strong>in</strong>s and the prox strategy. Peterson (1986) presented two<br />

possible explanations: either the consultants consistently use s<strong>in</strong>gular where at least one<br />

conjunct is s<strong>in</strong>gular (s<strong>in</strong>g w<strong>in</strong>s strategy), or they choose a verb form which agrees with<br />

the first conjunct (fc w<strong>in</strong>s strategy).<br />

S<strong>in</strong>ce there is no conv<strong>in</strong>c<strong>in</strong>g evidence for the s<strong>in</strong>g w<strong>in</strong>s strategy, Peterson (1986) assumes<br />

that the existence of an fc w<strong>in</strong>s strategy is more likely. The high choice for a<br />

s<strong>in</strong>gular verb form <strong>in</strong> example (47a) is seen as evidence that fc w<strong>in</strong>s strategy is more


6.3 Approaches to Disjunctive Coord<strong>in</strong>ated NPs 167<br />

likely to exist than the sg w<strong>in</strong>s strategy. Also, sg w<strong>in</strong>s is rejected because s<strong>in</strong>gular occurs<br />

<strong>in</strong> high numbers <strong>in</strong> (47b) as a result of the prox strategy s<strong>in</strong>ce the second conjunct is s<strong>in</strong>gular<br />

and therefore the prox strategy takes effect. Thus, Peterson (1986, 234) concludes<br />

that a third possible strategy is the one <strong>in</strong> which the verb agrees <strong>in</strong> number with the first<br />

conjunct, known as the fc w<strong>in</strong>s one. Apart from example (47a) <strong>in</strong> which s<strong>in</strong>gular was<br />

chosen by a significant number of consultants, a s<strong>in</strong>gular verb form occurs <strong>in</strong> high numbers<br />

<strong>in</strong> the <strong>in</strong>terrogative sentences below:<br />

(48) a. Have/Has the president or the senators read the documents yet?<br />

b. Was/Were the cake or the scones made by Mary?<br />

(Peterson, 1986, 240)<br />

The responses are summarised below:<br />

SENTENCE SG PL BOTH N/A<br />

(48a) 33 3 4 2<br />

(48b) 27 9 4 2<br />

Accord<strong>in</strong>g to Peterson (1986) <strong>in</strong> the above structures, which <strong>in</strong>volve subject-auxiliary<br />

<strong>in</strong>version, fc w<strong>in</strong>s and prox are equivalent strategies. But even though prox could cause<br />

the occurrence of s<strong>in</strong>gular, it cannot cause the occurrence of s<strong>in</strong>gular <strong>in</strong> example (47a).<br />

Thus, <strong>in</strong> either-or declaratives three strategies are adopted by the speakers, plu w<strong>in</strong>s,<br />

prox and fc w<strong>in</strong>s. The strongest is plu w<strong>in</strong>s, followed by the prox, while fc w<strong>in</strong>s is<br />

the weakest of the three.<br />

F<strong>in</strong>ally, <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>terrogative sentences with mixed number conjuncts, the results are rather<br />

different. In <strong>in</strong>terrogatives without either and a noun order [NP.pl or NP.sg], all three<br />

strategies, plu w<strong>in</strong>s, prox and fc w<strong>in</strong>s, favour a plural verb. In <strong>in</strong>terrogatives with a<br />

noun order [NP.sg or NP.pl], prox and fc w<strong>in</strong>s are <strong>in</strong> conflict with plu w<strong>in</strong>s s<strong>in</strong>ce the<br />

first two would produce s<strong>in</strong>gular responses and plu w<strong>in</strong>s would produce plural responses.<br />

Participants, however, prefered a s<strong>in</strong>gular verb compared to the equivalent declaratives,<br />

which shows a preference for the prox strategy. In <strong>in</strong>terrogatives which conta<strong>in</strong> either,<br />

participants prefer the plu w<strong>in</strong>s strategy more than any other. Thus, for <strong>in</strong>terrogatives<br />

with either the consultants prefer the plu w<strong>in</strong>s than the prox strategy, but for <strong>in</strong>terrogatives<br />

without either the prox strategy w<strong>in</strong>s over the rest.<br />

To sum up, Peterson’s analysis showed that <strong>in</strong> sentences with subject-auxiliary <strong>in</strong>version<br />

prox strategy is stronger but <strong>in</strong> declaratives plu w<strong>in</strong>s is used more often. Thus, prox is<br />

stronger when the verb precedes the subject, and plu w<strong>in</strong>s is stronger for declarative and<br />

<strong>in</strong>terrogative phrases with either. This implies that there is a strong relation of the strength<br />

of each strategy with the type of sentence construction and these should be exam<strong>in</strong>ed<br />

together when attempt<strong>in</strong>g to analyse disjunctive coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns 9 .<br />

Through the above analysis, Peterson (1986) concludes that syntactic rules do not<br />

function as pr<strong>in</strong>ciples for verb agreement with disjunctive conjo<strong>in</strong>ed subjects but <strong>in</strong>stead<br />

native speakers need to use a number of strategies, known as “patch-up rules”. These<br />

“patch-up rules” are not ad hoc but they can be perceived as generalised pr<strong>in</strong>ciples. These<br />

pr<strong>in</strong>ciples may have a syntactic or semantic character and they differ <strong>in</strong> strength from<br />

speaker to speaker and also across constructions.<br />

It is clear that Peterson (1986) draws similar conclusions to Morgan (1972, 1985). His<br />

analysis is <strong>in</strong>sightful s<strong>in</strong>ce it manages to shed some light <strong>in</strong>to the ma<strong>in</strong> strategies employed <strong>in</strong><br />

English, concern<strong>in</strong>g number verb agreement with disjunctive coord<strong>in</strong>ate NPs. In addition,<br />

9 Peterson (1986) also extends his <strong>in</strong>vestigation by look<strong>in</strong>g at neither-nor conjo<strong>in</strong>ed subject NPs. As he<br />

concludes, the results are rather unclear and this is why we will not present any details of his <strong>in</strong>vestigation<br />

here.


6.3 Approaches to Disjunctive Coord<strong>in</strong>ated NPs 168<br />

he identifies formally three different pr<strong>in</strong>ciples used by native speakers, prox, plu w<strong>in</strong>s<br />

and fc w<strong>in</strong>s, reject<strong>in</strong>g sg w<strong>in</strong>s as a fourth strategy with<strong>in</strong> the limitations of the English<br />

language. Another advantage of his analysis is that he stresses the importance of word<br />

order <strong>in</strong> determ<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g verb agreement with disjunctive NPs, draw<strong>in</strong>g concrete conclusions<br />

from the data. F<strong>in</strong>ally, he asserts that number verb agreement with disjunctive coord<strong>in</strong>ate<br />

nouns depends on syntactic and semantic or perceptual pr<strong>in</strong>ciples.<br />

An important drawback of his analysis, however, is that he considers the patch-up<br />

rules as generalised pr<strong>in</strong>ciples and he completely ignores the purely pragmatic or discourse<br />

factors that may determ<strong>in</strong>e verb agreement. Based on his data, he argues that the type of<br />

sentence determ<strong>in</strong>es verb agreement and not the <strong>in</strong>clusive/exclusive or <strong>in</strong>terpretation. In<br />

declaratives, the <strong>in</strong>clusive/exclusive dist<strong>in</strong>ction is not salient whereas <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>terrogatives the<br />

contrast between “yes/no” and “alternatives” drives verb agreement. Morgan (1972, 1985),<br />

on the other hand, appears to accept those two <strong>in</strong>terpretations cross-sententially and this<br />

is why he <strong>in</strong>corporates a semantic/pragmatic pr<strong>in</strong>ciple that determ<strong>in</strong>es verb agreement.<br />

One last th<strong>in</strong>g to note is whether these speaker strategies are crossl<strong>in</strong>guistic and how<br />

many of those are grammaticalised or not <strong>in</strong> the various languages. Concern<strong>in</strong>g the first<br />

po<strong>in</strong>t, we argue that <strong>in</strong> MG these strategies are not all activated. In fact, the flexibility<br />

of the language itself will determ<strong>in</strong>e whether it is possible for all strategies to be used or<br />

not and not all languages display the same k<strong>in</strong>d of flexibility. Secondly, as Peterson (1986)<br />

mentions, <strong>in</strong> some languages some of the strategies are grammaticalised such as the CCA<br />

strategy <strong>in</strong> Albanian 10 . This depends on the <strong>in</strong>ternal structure of the language. In MG,<br />

these strategies are not grammaticalised but they seem to be part of the speakers’ strategic<br />

choices.<br />

6.3.3 An Intermodular Theory of Disjunction<br />

Eggert (2002) exam<strong>in</strong>es disjunctive coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns and discusses all aspects that seem to<br />

be <strong>in</strong>volved <strong>in</strong> determ<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g verb agreement, such as syntax, semantics and pragmatics. He<br />

focuses on an analysis of English verb agreement with disjunctive nouns with<strong>in</strong> the framework<br />

of Autolexical Grammar (Sadock, 1991). The advantage of the specific framework is<br />

that it consists of several <strong>in</strong>dependent modules each with its own set of rules which share<br />

the same lexicon 11 . Also, the current framework is rather useful <strong>in</strong> analys<strong>in</strong>g agreement<br />

s<strong>in</strong>ce it keeps separate each aspect <strong>in</strong> agreement, e.g. syntax or semantics, allow<strong>in</strong>g an<br />

adequate representation of agreement mismatches.<br />

Autolexical Grammar <strong>in</strong>cludes five modules: L<strong>in</strong>earity, Syntax, Argument/Predicate,<br />

Logical-Scope and Morpho-syntax. In his thesis, Eggert (2002) focuses only on the first<br />

three modules, even though he asserts that the other two are still relevant for the phenomenon<br />

of coord<strong>in</strong>ation. L<strong>in</strong>earity encodes “the l<strong>in</strong>ear order of words <strong>in</strong> a sentence”;<br />

“syntax encodes the dom<strong>in</strong>ance and command relations between syntactic phrases <strong>in</strong> a<br />

10 Accord<strong>in</strong>g to Peterson (1986), <strong>in</strong> Albanian the adjectival participle must agree with the closest conjunct,<br />

which is the f<strong>in</strong>al one.<br />

11 The ma<strong>in</strong> difference between LFG and Autolexical Grammar is that LFG dist<strong>in</strong>guishes two syntactic<br />

levels: c-structure (constituent-structure) and f-structure (functional structure) but it has no syntactic<br />

level of LF and no d-structure (Horrocks, 1987); Autolexical Grammar has only one level of syntax, which<br />

corresponds to c-structure <strong>in</strong> LFG. In theoretical discussions of mismatch phenomena this difference becomes<br />

more obvious. For example, <strong>in</strong> LFG the argument-structure properties of the verb seem (as <strong>in</strong> He seems<br />

to like it) are represented <strong>in</strong> terms of f-structure relations, which are <strong>in</strong>dependent of phrase structure<br />

(reference)(Horrocks, 1987). In this case, no movement is <strong>in</strong>volved and the two levels of syntax are more<br />

<strong>in</strong>dependent of each other. In Autolexical Grammar, the <strong>in</strong>formation concern<strong>in</strong>g the argument-structure of<br />

rais<strong>in</strong>g verbs is captured <strong>in</strong> semantics. Accord<strong>in</strong>g to Sadock (1991), verbs like seem justify the dist<strong>in</strong>ction<br />

between phrase structure and semantic structure and say noth<strong>in</strong>g about additional levels of syntax (Francis<br />

and Michaelis, 2000).


6.3 Approaches to Disjunctive Coord<strong>in</strong>ated NPs 169<br />

sentence”, and Argument/Predicate “represents the dom<strong>in</strong>ance and command relations<br />

but between the semantic phrases <strong>in</strong> a sentence” (Sadock, 1991, 7). His central addition<br />

is to supplement the current framework with an extra level, the discourse, that is mapped<br />

off of semantic structure, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g also a set of weighted agreement constra<strong>in</strong>ts.<br />

Eggert (2002) first presents the grammatical structure of coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrases focus<strong>in</strong>g<br />

on agreement phenomena. He argues that agreement is an <strong>in</strong>termodular phenomenon separated<br />

<strong>in</strong>to syntactic agreement, accounted for by the L<strong>in</strong>earity and Syntax modules 12 , and<br />

semantic agreement, accounted for by the Argument/Predicate module 13 with<strong>in</strong> Autolexical<br />

Grammar. A clear case of syntactic agreement concern<strong>in</strong>g number is that of closest<br />

conjunct where the verb agrees <strong>in</strong> number with the noun closest to it, shown below:<br />

(49) a. Either John or his parents were/*was here<br />

b. Either John’s parents or his brother ?was/??were here<br />

(Eggert, 2002, 17)<br />

Semantic agreement is always agreement with the entire noun phrase and depends<br />

on the mean<strong>in</strong>g of the NP. In the examples below, when the two NPs refer to different<br />

<strong>in</strong>dividuals as <strong>in</strong> (50a) (i.e. split read<strong>in</strong>g) the verb shows plural number agreement, whereas<br />

when the NPs refer to the same <strong>in</strong>dividual (i.e. jo<strong>in</strong>t read<strong>in</strong>g) the verb shows s<strong>in</strong>gular<br />

number agreement:<br />

(50) a. Her husband and her lover say that they can’t live without her<br />

b. Her longtime companion and the future editor of her papers was happy to give<br />

his approval to her request (Eggert, 2002, 16)<br />

Eggert (2002) captures the syntactic aspects of agreement <strong>in</strong> coord<strong>in</strong>ate NPs based on<br />

the L<strong>in</strong>earity and Syntax modules. He po<strong>in</strong>ts out that any difference <strong>in</strong> the hierarchical<br />

structure <strong>in</strong> l<strong>in</strong>earity will necessarily result <strong>in</strong> a difference <strong>in</strong> the l<strong>in</strong>ear order. L<strong>in</strong>earity<br />

contributes greatly s<strong>in</strong>ce it accounts for ‘closeness’ factors <strong>in</strong> agreement. The agreement<br />

constra<strong>in</strong>ts that require agreement with a particular conjunct are based on the l<strong>in</strong>ear position<br />

of the noun, which must be closest to the verb. The phrase structure rules that<br />

the L<strong>in</strong>earity module enforces are rather simple, produc<strong>in</strong>g b<strong>in</strong>ary branch<strong>in</strong>g trees (Eggert,<br />

2002, 36-7). Like the Syntax module, the structure of L<strong>in</strong>earity conforms to specific<br />

command relations. The most characteristic relation is for any two constituents α and<br />

β, α precedes β iff α c-commands β. On the other hand, the Syntax module focuses on<br />

constituent structure and command relations. After exam<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g a number of syntactic theories<br />

concern<strong>in</strong>g coord<strong>in</strong>ation, such as Chomsky’s (1957) “Conjunction Reduction”(CR),<br />

Goodall’s (1987) “Three dimensional phrase structure” and Johannessen’s (1996) “Coord<strong>in</strong>ate<br />

Alpha”, he concludes that an adapted version of GPSG is more effective simply<br />

because it does not <strong>in</strong>volve transformations and coord<strong>in</strong>ate structures are base-generated.<br />

GPSG relies on two ma<strong>in</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>ciples, the Head Feature Convention and the Foot Feature<br />

Pr<strong>in</strong>ciple.<br />

The semantic aspects of agreement <strong>in</strong> coord<strong>in</strong>ate NPs are captured by the Argument/Predicate<br />

module. Eggert (2002) argues for a unified analysis for each of the two<br />

connectors and and or that will allow them to operate over conjunct sets of any type and<br />

not simply be<strong>in</strong>g propositional connectors, as has been done <strong>in</strong> the past. He favours a<br />

quantificational account of and and or based on the observation that both operators are<br />

12 Issues <strong>in</strong> morphosyntax are captured with<strong>in</strong> the syntax module. However, he does not discuss further<br />

any issues <strong>in</strong> morphology s<strong>in</strong>ce it is beyond the scope of his thesis.<br />

13 His semantic aspect relates only to the Argument/Predicate module and not the Logical-Scope one.<br />

Although, he notes that a complete analysis of coord<strong>in</strong>ation requires the Logical-Scope module too, he does<br />

not consider it relevant to agreement and he chooses not to discuss it further.


6.3 Approaches to Disjunctive Coord<strong>in</strong>ated NPs 170<br />

<strong>in</strong>volved <strong>in</strong> the same types of scopal ambiguities as quantified NPs; also, <strong>in</strong> this way he can<br />

expla<strong>in</strong> patterns of non-distributive conjunction, which pose problems for other approaches<br />

(i.e. CR approach (Chomsky, 1957) and those by Gazdar (1980) and Montague (1973)).<br />

Eggert (2002) argues that conjunction and and disjunction or semantically resemble<br />

quantifiers. He proves this by treat<strong>in</strong>g and and or as analogous to all and the existentials,<br />

respectively. As is well known, all and a <strong>in</strong>teract <strong>in</strong> sentences and produce scope<br />

ambiguities, such as the ones below:<br />

(51) a. All of his friends belong to a band<br />

b. ‘all of his friends are band members’<br />

c. ‘there is a band that all of his friends belong to’<br />

(Eggert, 2002, 78)<br />

The position of the two quantifiers determ<strong>in</strong>es the difference <strong>in</strong> the two read<strong>in</strong>gs and<br />

which elements have scope over which.<br />

Similar, ambiguities arise <strong>in</strong> example (52a) with and and a, be<strong>in</strong>g ambiguous between<br />

(52b) and (52c), and <strong>in</strong> example (53a) with all and or, be<strong>in</strong>g ambiguous between (53b) and<br />

(53c):<br />

(52) a. Grant and Jacob are members of a band<br />

b. ‘Grant and Jacob are band members’<br />

c. ‘there is a band that Grant and Jacob are members of’<br />

(Eggert, 2002, 79)<br />

(53) a. All of his friends are members of Sunset Valley or Sketchy Afterdeal<br />

b. ‘All of his friends belong to one of the two bands: Sunset Valley or Sketchy<br />

Afterdeal’<br />

c. ‘All of his friends belong to Sunset Valley, or all of his friends belong to Sketchy<br />

Afterdeal’<br />

(Eggert, 2002, 79)<br />

Moreover, and and or <strong>in</strong>teract <strong>in</strong> this k<strong>in</strong>d of ambiguity:<br />

(54) a. Grant and Carm<strong>in</strong>e like Gertrude or Carmelia<br />

b. ‘Grant and Carm<strong>in</strong>e are such that they like Gertrude or Carmelia’<br />

c. ‘Gertrude or Carmelia is such that Grant and Carm<strong>in</strong>e like her’<br />

(Eggert, 2002, 79)<br />

Turn<strong>in</strong>g to a and all, it is impossible for a syntactically lower all to take scope over<br />

a syntactically higher a. For example, most people have trouble gett<strong>in</strong>g read<strong>in</strong>g (55c) for<br />

(55a):<br />

(55) a. A girl likes all the boys<br />

b. ‘A girl is such that she likes all the boys’<br />

c. ‘Every boy is such that a girl likes him’<br />

(Eggert, 2002, 80)<br />

Thus, there is a similarity between and and or and all and a.<br />

Also, and and all show similar behaviour with regard to distributivity s<strong>in</strong>ce they can<br />

be either distributive or non-distributive. In the follow<strong>in</strong>g examples, neither and nor all<br />

can be distributive:<br />

(56) a. Grant and Gertrude met <strong>in</strong> the park


6.3 Approaches to Disjunctive Coord<strong>in</strong>ated NPs 171<br />

b. *‘Grant met <strong>in</strong> the park and Gertrude met <strong>in</strong> the park’<br />

c. All the sheriffs met <strong>in</strong> the park<br />

d. *‘Sheriff1 met <strong>in</strong> the park, Sheriff2 met <strong>in</strong> the park...’<br />

(Eggert, 2002, 81)<br />

In addition, the cases where conjunction is ambiguous between a distributive and a<br />

non-distributive read<strong>in</strong>g are the same ones where sustitut<strong>in</strong>g the phrase all of the Ns is<br />

ambiguous. This is illustrated below:<br />

(57) a. Grant and Gertrude carried the box<br />

b. ‘Grant and Gertrude carried the box severally’<br />

c. ‘Grant and Gertrude carried the box together’<br />

d. All the sheriffs carried the box<br />

e. ‘All the sheriffs carried the box severally’<br />

f. ‘All the sheriffs carried the box together’<br />

(Eggert, 2002, 81)<br />

Thus, Eggert (2002) shows that and and or produce similar scopal ambiguities to<br />

quantifiers and and and all behave similarly with regard to distributivity 14 . The Argument/Predicate<br />

module, which posits a number of rules, can capture a unified treatment of<br />

both operators. The A/P rules, which correspond to arguments and predicates, state how<br />

these comb<strong>in</strong>e to form propositions, and treat conjunctions as operators that are allowed<br />

to comb<strong>in</strong>e with two or more conjuncts of any category but the conjuncts need to be of the<br />

same category. F<strong>in</strong>ally, an A/P coord<strong>in</strong>ation rule is <strong>in</strong>troduced, which treats conjunctions<br />

as n-ary and not b<strong>in</strong>ary 15 .<br />

Eggert (2002) shows that apart from the strict semantic factors, there are also discourse<br />

factors <strong>in</strong>volved when determ<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g the ‘semantic number’ of an argument <strong>in</strong> coord<strong>in</strong>ate<br />

phrases. Thus, he claims that “‘semantic agreement’ should be analysed as a discourse<br />

phenomenon, which is <strong>in</strong>formed by the semantics” (Eggert, 2002, 97). Characteristic cases<br />

of discourse factors mediat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> coord<strong>in</strong>ate NPs and determ<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g verb agreement are<br />

cases of “appositive conjunction”(Hoeksema, 1988, 36) (or otherwise mentioned as jo<strong>in</strong>t<br />

<strong>in</strong>terpretation) and “deferred reference” (Nunberg, 1995, 115).<br />

A case of appositive conjunction or jo<strong>in</strong>t read<strong>in</strong>g is illustrated <strong>in</strong> example (58). The<br />

conjuncts denote the same referent and they trigger s<strong>in</strong>gular agreement. A semantic theory<br />

could capture that. However, appositive conjunction or jo<strong>in</strong>t read<strong>in</strong>g is only allowed with<br />

descriptions as <strong>in</strong> example (58) and not with proper nouns (Hoeksema, 1988, 36), as <strong>in</strong><br />

(59):<br />

(58) Grant’s former wife and his mother’s present girlfriend was on the Jerry Spr<strong>in</strong>ger<br />

show<br />

(59) ??Cassius Clay and Muhammed Ali has/have always been my father’s favorite boxer<br />

(Eggert, 2002, 93)<br />

There are also cases where coreferential proper nouns can be conjo<strong>in</strong>ed but the verb<br />

admits plural verb agreement, as below:<br />

(60) Cassius Clay and Muhammed Ali are the same person<br />

(Eggert, 2002, 93)<br />

14 For more details on how the two coord<strong>in</strong>ation markers resemble quantifiers see Eggert (2002, 78-83).<br />

15 A complete list of the rules is <strong>in</strong> Eggert (2002, 84).


6.3 Approaches to Disjunctive Coord<strong>in</strong>ated NPs 172<br />

Hoeksema (1988, 30-31) argues that these phrases <strong>in</strong>troduce two dist<strong>in</strong>ct <strong>in</strong>tensional<br />

<strong>in</strong>dividuals, which correspond to one real-world entity. In these cases, <strong>in</strong>tensionality rather<br />

than extensionality determ<strong>in</strong>e verb agreement.<br />

Also, <strong>in</strong> cases of “deferred reference” agreement is only with the <strong>in</strong>tended referent.<br />

Thus, demonstratives are s<strong>in</strong>gular or plural depend<strong>in</strong>g on the <strong>in</strong>tended referent, not the<br />

demonstratum:<br />

(61) That/*those french fries is/*are gett<strong>in</strong>g impatient<br />

(Eggert, 2002, 96)<br />

Therefore, Eggert (2002) argues that such cases cannot be handled by purely semantic<br />

theories and therefore a discourse based account should be considered.<br />

To capture the discourse and semantic factors <strong>in</strong> agreement, Eggert (2002) proposes<br />

an analysis of coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrases based on Discourse Representation Theory (Kamp and<br />

Reyle, 1993). DRT uses a discourse structure that is mapped off of grammatical structure.<br />

Such a discourse structure allows the effective <strong>in</strong>corporation of any discourse-pragmatic<br />

features <strong>in</strong>to the mean<strong>in</strong>g of sentences when the latter are uttered <strong>in</strong> a particular discourse<br />

context. DRT has the advantage of account<strong>in</strong>g for complicated phenomena, such as<br />

anaphora, negation and scope. ‘Semantic number’ is also complicated and a DRT analysis<br />

is advantageous s<strong>in</strong>ce it takes both discourse and semantic factors <strong>in</strong>to consideration when<br />

determ<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g the semantic number of an argument. Thus, consider<strong>in</strong>g a given argument,<br />

its semantic number is determ<strong>in</strong>ed by whatever discourse conditions apply to the discourse<br />

referent that corresponds to the argument.<br />

Eggert (2002) develops a uniform theory for and and or <strong>in</strong> order to capture the wide<br />

range of data and also <strong>in</strong>troduce a straightforward def<strong>in</strong>ition for plurality. He achieves that<br />

by comb<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g DRT with Schwarzschild’s cover theory (Schwarzschild, 1996). He treats<br />

and as a type-specific operator mean<strong>in</strong>g that it is a generic operator that is identified with<br />

“whatever operator is def<strong>in</strong>ed for the doma<strong>in</strong> of the conjo<strong>in</strong>ed terms”(Eggert, 2002, 92) and<br />

not with meet per se, as <strong>in</strong> the Boolean approach proposed by Keenan and Faltz (1985).<br />

Thus, and does not map directly <strong>in</strong>to the DRS as set-union but as a generic operator,<br />

mean<strong>in</strong>g that it operates either as set-union or as set-<strong>in</strong>tersection. He achieves that by<br />

assum<strong>in</strong>g that the doma<strong>in</strong>s of the conjo<strong>in</strong>able types are semi-lattices and not Boolean<br />

algebras. Thus, and is assigned to whichever operator is def<strong>in</strong>ed for that doma<strong>in</strong>.<br />

Next, he argues that or is not and’s dual. If they were truly duals, or should denote set<br />

<strong>in</strong>tersection just like and denotes set union. However, this is not the case s<strong>in</strong>ce the simple<br />

phrase Grant or Abigail cannot denote the <strong>in</strong>tersection of {grant} and {abigail}, which<br />

would be the empty set. Also, if and and or were duals, it would be expected to behave<br />

similarly with regard to scope. However, or resembles <strong>in</strong>def<strong>in</strong>ites s<strong>in</strong>ce it can scope above<br />

a structurally higher and, while and cannot scope above a structurally higher or. This is<br />

shown below:<br />

(62) a. Grant and Jakob danced with Rebecca or Sukie<br />

b. Grant or Jakob danced with Rebecca and Sukie<br />

(Eggert, 2002, 103)<br />

F<strong>in</strong>ally, one more argument that and and or are not duals is that there are cases they can<br />

have identical mean<strong>in</strong>gs. For example, (63) paraphrases as (64) and also as (65) accord<strong>in</strong>g<br />

to Jenn<strong>in</strong>gs (1994):<br />

(63) Grant is taller than Gertrude or Abigail<br />

(64) Grant is taller than Gertrude or Grant is taller than Abigail<br />

(65) Grant is taller than Gertrude, and Grant is taller than Abigail<br />

(Jenn<strong>in</strong>gs, 1994)


6.3 Approaches to Disjunctive Coord<strong>in</strong>ated NPs 173<br />

Initially, he adopts the DRT analysis of existentials for disjunction. Existentials trigger<br />

the <strong>in</strong>troduction of a discourse referent that is a member of its restrict<strong>in</strong>g predicate. Disjunction<br />

may also be taken to <strong>in</strong>troduce a discourse referent which is a member of the set<br />

of its disjuncts 16 . For example, we could assign the follow<strong>in</strong>g DRS for the phrase Gertrude<br />

or Abigail:<br />

(66)<br />

x,y,z<br />

gertrude(x)<br />

abigail(y)<br />

z∈{x,y}<br />

(Eggert, 2002, 106)<br />

However, Simons (1998) argues that disjunction does not <strong>in</strong>troduce any discourse referents.<br />

Consider the discouse <strong>in</strong> the example below:<br />

(67) a. Gertrude or Abigail is s<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>g tonight<br />

b. #She might dance, too<br />

The <strong>in</strong>tended read<strong>in</strong>g for (67a) is ‘whoever is s<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>g tonight (i.e. Gertrude or Abigail)<br />

might dance too’; however, this read<strong>in</strong>g does not become available.<br />

S<strong>in</strong>ce disjunction does not seem to <strong>in</strong>troduce a discourse referent (Simons, 1998), Eggert<br />

(2002) argues that disjunction must be treated as a comb<strong>in</strong>ation of the default operator,<br />

which means whatever operator is def<strong>in</strong>ed for the doma<strong>in</strong>, and a subset function, which<br />

means a function that moves from sets to subsets. By treat<strong>in</strong>g disjunction as a subset<br />

function, he avoids <strong>in</strong>troduc<strong>in</strong>g a discourse referent for disjunction. Also, he borrows from<br />

Schwarzschild (1996) the partition theory of plurals and applies that to disjunction. More<br />

precisely, Schwarzschild (1996) argues that accord<strong>in</strong>g to the partition theory of plurals<br />

the collective and distributive semantic difference <strong>in</strong> sentences comes from a contextually<br />

determ<strong>in</strong>ed variable, a partition on the universe of discourse. Schwarzschild (1996) suggests<br />

that the semantics is the same for both read<strong>in</strong>gs and <strong>in</strong>troduces a semantic theory<br />

that treats sentences as vague and not as ambiguous, which should allow for a variety of<br />

<strong>in</strong>terpretations. Therefore, all cases of semantic ambiguity are vague and are expla<strong>in</strong>ed by<br />

a variety of <strong>in</strong>terpretations. Thus, he captures problematic data and gets the distributive<br />

and collective read<strong>in</strong>gs correctly. Consider the follow<strong>in</strong>g sentence:<br />

(68) Three students carried the piano<br />

(Schwarzschild (1996) cited <strong>in</strong> Eggert (2002, 127))<br />

In some contexts, the variable partitions ‘three students’ <strong>in</strong>to three cells, one for each<br />

student, which is the distributive read<strong>in</strong>g, but <strong>in</strong> other contexts, there is only one cell<br />

<strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g all three students, which is the collective read<strong>in</strong>g. This theory also favours the<br />

use of distributive operators and not type-rais<strong>in</strong>g ones. Thus, pragmatics will contribute<br />

<strong>in</strong>to limit<strong>in</strong>g the number of <strong>in</strong>terpretations of a sentence or even disambiguate it.<br />

Eggert (2002) after propos<strong>in</strong>g a theory of semantic number that posits a discourse level,<br />

<strong>in</strong> addition to the modular structures, he also <strong>in</strong>troduces a set of agreement constra<strong>in</strong>ts.<br />

Speakers use these constra<strong>in</strong>ts <strong>in</strong> their attempt to determ<strong>in</strong>e if a disjunctively conjo<strong>in</strong>ed<br />

noun phrase requires s<strong>in</strong>gular or plural verb agreement. He argues that agreement facts<br />

are best analysed with weighted constra<strong>in</strong>ts and not with rules or rank<strong>in</strong>g constra<strong>in</strong>ts,<br />

due to the nature of agreement data. In particular, native speakers have weak <strong>in</strong>tuitions<br />

with regard to agreement phenomena. He claims that there are cases where they are<br />

16 In DRT, disjunction is taken to <strong>in</strong>troduce a discourse referent that is a member of a set of its disjuncts<br />

(z∈{x,y}) (Kamp and Reyle, 1993)


6.3 Approaches to Disjunctive Coord<strong>in</strong>ated NPs 174<br />

<strong>in</strong>decisive as to the correct agreement choice with<strong>in</strong> a pattern. Other times they are able<br />

to state whether one pattern is preferable to another, even though they disagree about<br />

which pattern is preferable. Moreover, sometimes the role of hierarchies is crucial <strong>in</strong> order<br />

to determ<strong>in</strong>e agreement, with animacy hierarchy be<strong>in</strong>g the most important.<br />

Eggert (2002) considers that weighted constra<strong>in</strong>ts are the most effective method to<br />

account for <strong>in</strong>termediate judgements, speaker variation and the role of hierarchies <strong>in</strong> agreement<br />

facts s<strong>in</strong>ce they may <strong>in</strong>teract <strong>in</strong> different ways with different speakers and the preference<br />

of the <strong>in</strong>dividual speaker depends on the relative weights of <strong>in</strong>dividual constra<strong>in</strong>ts.<br />

Such constra<strong>in</strong>ts also <strong>in</strong>teract better with the animacy hierarchy. Rules, on the other hand,<br />

are not able to account for such variation s<strong>in</strong>ce they are restrictive <strong>in</strong> allow<strong>in</strong>g either a grammatical<br />

or ungrammatical structure. Similar problems occur with ranked constra<strong>in</strong>ts s<strong>in</strong>ce<br />

there are only three possible relations that a constra<strong>in</strong>t C1 may have with a constra<strong>in</strong>t C2<br />

when rank<strong>in</strong>g is <strong>in</strong>volved; either C1 out-ranks C2, C1 may be out-ranked by C2 or C1 may<br />

have the same rank as C2.<br />

Eggert (2002) <strong>in</strong>troduces two types of constra<strong>in</strong>ts, syntactic and semantic. The syntactic<br />

constra<strong>in</strong>ts are formnum, highnum, nearnum (Peterson’s prox) and firstnum<br />

(Peterson’s fc w<strong>in</strong>s). These are stated as follows:<br />

(69) formnum: A verb should agree <strong>in</strong> grammatical number with its syntactic subject<br />

highnum: A verb should be plural if one of the NP heads of its syntactic subject<br />

is plural<br />

nearnum: A verb should agree <strong>in</strong> grammatical number with the nearest NP head<br />

of its syntactic subject<br />

firstnum: A verb should agree <strong>in</strong> grammatical number with the first NP head of<br />

its syntactic subject<br />

(Eggert, 2002, 197)<br />

The semantic constra<strong>in</strong>ts are drnum, modelnum, disnum and multijunct while the<br />

def<strong>in</strong>ition of semnum is divided <strong>in</strong>to two parts. These are def<strong>in</strong>ed below 17 :<br />

(70) semnum1: A pred1 should be marked for semantic number<br />

semnum2: If the semantic number of a pred1 is marked it should have the same<br />

number as its semantic subject<br />

drnum: The sum of any two discourse referents should be a plural discourse referent<br />

modelnum: Where x is a discourse referent and [x] is the assignment of x <strong>in</strong> model<br />

m,|x| should be equal to |[x]|<br />

disnum: If a pred1 has a disjunctive arg for subject, it should be unspecified for<br />

number<br />

multijunct: A verb should be marked plural if its syntactic subject consists of<br />

more than two np heads<br />

(Eggert, 2002, 243)<br />

F<strong>in</strong>ally, he <strong>in</strong>troduces a constra<strong>in</strong>t which is a semantic-syntactic one:<br />

(71) semnum=formnum: If a verb is marked for number <strong>in</strong> Syntax, the correspond<strong>in</strong>g<br />

pred1 should be marked for the same number <strong>in</strong> A/P<br />

(Eggert, 2002, 243)<br />

These constra<strong>in</strong>ts capture complicated data, such as disjunctive conjo<strong>in</strong>ed nouns, which<br />

are difficult to analyse due to great variation of speakers’ judgements and <strong>in</strong>tuitions. Eggert<br />

17 In the A/P module, A/P structures show how one forms arguments and predicates and comb<strong>in</strong>es them<br />

to form propositions. Pred1 is def<strong>in</strong>ed as follows: A/P1 PRED1 → β β ∈ {run’, girl’, pretty’,...}.<br />

Therefore, PRED1 refers to any s<strong>in</strong>gle argument predicate.


6.3 Approaches to Disjunctive Coord<strong>in</strong>ated NPs 175<br />

(2002) notes that many factors determ<strong>in</strong>e the speaker’s choice from syntactic, semantic to<br />

discourse or pragmatic while most of the speakers assign weight to the constra<strong>in</strong>ts and<br />

these weights may differ considerably from speaker to speaker. Thus, some speakers use<br />

more semantically based strategies while others may use more syntactically based ones.<br />

There are also those who are between the two.<br />

On the whole, Eggert (2002) proposes an <strong>in</strong>termodular theory of disjunction that analyses<br />

disjunction from the perspective of syntax, semantics and discourse. First, he discusses<br />

the grammatical structure of disjunction <strong>in</strong> the A/P theory, the Syntax and the L<strong>in</strong>earity<br />

modules. Next, he presents a theory of semantic number, which also posits a discourse<br />

level with<strong>in</strong> DRT. F<strong>in</strong>ally, he <strong>in</strong>troduces a set of agreement constra<strong>in</strong>ts which account for<br />

the fact that speakers use these constra<strong>in</strong>ts to determ<strong>in</strong>e whether a sentence should have<br />

s<strong>in</strong>gular or plural verb agreement. Thus, his model views disjunction as a complicated<br />

phenomenon that requires the active participation of different modules <strong>in</strong> order to provide<br />

a complete account for disjunction.<br />

6.3.4 Discuss<strong>in</strong>g the three approaches<br />

In the previous sections, we decribed the three approaches to disjunction developed by<br />

Morgan (1972, 1985), Peterson (1986) and Eggert (2002) and briefly presented the ma<strong>in</strong><br />

advantages and disadvantages of these approaches. From the three approaches to disjunctive<br />

conjo<strong>in</strong>ed nouns, we believe that Eggert’s analysis is more advantageous than the other<br />

two for the simple reason that he acknowledges that discourse conditions play a crucial role<br />

<strong>in</strong> disjunction and he proposes an analysis on discourse.<br />

First of all, although Morgan (1972, 1985) discussed agreement phenomena determ<strong>in</strong>ed<br />

by discourse conditions, such as “deferred referrence”, he did not deal extensively with<br />

those but he chooses to <strong>in</strong>corporate the discourse phenomena to semantics. Therefore,<br />

cases where the <strong>in</strong>terpretation of a sentence and the choice of the verb form depend on<br />

discourse factors are attributed to semantics (and/or pragmatics) accord<strong>in</strong>g to Morgan<br />

(1972, 1985). Some of the cases that can have either s<strong>in</strong>gular or plural verb agreement<br />

depend<strong>in</strong>g on the <strong>in</strong>terpretation are the follow<strong>in</strong>g:<br />

(72) John or Bill is/are??? go<strong>in</strong>g to w<strong>in</strong> the race<br />

(73) Do you th<strong>in</strong>k John or Bill is/are go<strong>in</strong>g to come?<br />

(74) I don’t th<strong>in</strong>k John or Bill are/*is go<strong>in</strong>g to w<strong>in</strong> the race<br />

(75) Either John or Bill is/*are go<strong>in</strong>g to w<strong>in</strong> the race<br />

(Morgan, 1985, 72)<br />

Thus, purely pragmatic factors are ignored <strong>in</strong> this analysis.<br />

Similarly, Peterson (1986) avoided discuss<strong>in</strong>g cases where discourse conditions are the<br />

ma<strong>in</strong> motivation for number verb agreement. In fact, his ma<strong>in</strong> argument is that the type<br />

of sentence determ<strong>in</strong>es the choice of the verb form and not the <strong>in</strong>clusive/exclusive <strong>in</strong>terpretation<br />

of the sentence. Also, he argues that speaker strategies play a crucial role <strong>in</strong> verb<br />

agreement and he identifies three ma<strong>in</strong> strategies <strong>in</strong> English, prox, plu w<strong>in</strong>s and fc w<strong>in</strong>s.<br />

Although speaker strategies do seem to play an important role <strong>in</strong> verb agreement, there are<br />

cases that speakers are <strong>in</strong>decisive concern<strong>in</strong>g the choice of the verb form which implies that<br />

more than one strategy can be possible or even none of the strategies can clearly determ<strong>in</strong>e<br />

the agreement form. In these cases, speakers seem to consult the context and the discourse<br />

conditions, which are able to determ<strong>in</strong>e the choice of the verb form. Unfortunately, this<br />

factor is ignored by Peterson (1986). Also, the strategies <strong>in</strong>troduced by Peterson (1986)<br />

are not crossl<strong>in</strong>guistic. In fact, we will show that <strong>in</strong> MG only two strategies are activated<br />

the prox and plu w<strong>in</strong>s. Thus, the flexibility of the language itself will determ<strong>in</strong>e the<br />

strategies that will be used.


6.4 Verb <strong>Agreement</strong> <strong>in</strong> MG Disjunctive Coord<strong>in</strong>ate <strong>Noun</strong>s 176<br />

Eggert (2002), on the other hand, like Jenn<strong>in</strong>gs (1994), proposes a complete account<br />

based on a discourse based framework DRT. Eggert (2002) draws a dist<strong>in</strong>ction between<br />

purely syntactic strategies, purely semantic and a comb<strong>in</strong>ation of the two. He also takes<br />

<strong>in</strong>to consideration discourse factors that are <strong>in</strong>volved <strong>in</strong> verb agreement with disjo<strong>in</strong>t nouns,<br />

someth<strong>in</strong>g that Morgan (1972, 1985) and Peterson (1986) do not manage.<br />

Another characteristic of Eggert’s analysis is that or corresponds to a subset function,<br />

which picks up either one (i.e. result<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> sg agreement) or both (i.e. result<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> pl<br />

agreement) members of the set, be<strong>in</strong>g polysemous between two mean<strong>in</strong>gs. In fact, he<br />

does not analyse or as be<strong>in</strong>g and’s dual while he argues that there are sentences with<br />

disjunction or that do not translate as propositional disjunction, but rather as propositional<br />

conjunction. In particular, he refers to examples that have been discussed by Jenn<strong>in</strong>gs<br />

(1994), as the one below:<br />

(76) Grant is taller than Gertrude or Abigail (Eggert, 2002, 104)<br />

He claims that Boolean and clausal theories of and and or would predict only the read<strong>in</strong>g<br />

<strong>in</strong> (77) as be<strong>in</strong>g the only available one:<br />

(77) Grant is taller than Gertrude or Grant is taller than Abigail<br />

But (77) also paraphrases as <strong>in</strong> (78):<br />

(78) Grant is taller than Gertrude and Grant is taller than Abigail<br />

Thus, Eggert (2002) discussed the long stand<strong>in</strong>g issues of the different functions of or<br />

as <strong>in</strong>clusive (∨) and exclusive (∧) and also of the different <strong>in</strong>terpretations of disjunction<br />

or as ‘and-coord<strong>in</strong>ate’ and as ‘exclusive’. In fact, he places emphasis and argues <strong>in</strong> favour<br />

of the different <strong>in</strong>terpretations of or <strong>in</strong> discourse. This is taken <strong>in</strong>to consideration when<br />

posit<strong>in</strong>g the syntactic and semantic constra<strong>in</strong>ts for the account of disjunctive coord<strong>in</strong>ated<br />

nouns. Next, we turn to verb agreement <strong>in</strong> MG disjunctively conjo<strong>in</strong>ed nouns.<br />

6.4 Verb <strong>Agreement</strong> <strong>in</strong> MG Disjunctive Coord<strong>in</strong>ate <strong>Noun</strong>s<br />

In this section, we exam<strong>in</strong>e number verb agreement <strong>in</strong> disjunctive coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns <strong>in</strong> MG<br />

and we will show that a number of factors determ<strong>in</strong>e the number of the verb. An important<br />

factor that determ<strong>in</strong>es number verb agreement is the <strong>in</strong>terpretation of disjunction. MG<br />

native speakers assign two different <strong>in</strong>terpretations to natural language disjunction or, as<br />

an ‘and-coord<strong>in</strong>ate’ so that the predicate holds of both disjuncts (this is usually the same as<br />

the <strong>in</strong>clusive <strong>in</strong>terpretation of logical disjunction ∨), and as a true ‘exclusive’ disjunction,<br />

<strong>in</strong> which the predicate is true of either one or the other of the disjuncts. Accord<strong>in</strong>g to the<br />

<strong>in</strong>terpretation, native speakers show a preference to a specific verb form, such as plural <strong>in</strong><br />

the first case and s<strong>in</strong>gular <strong>in</strong> the second.<br />

Second, verb agreement is also determ<strong>in</strong>ed by a number of syntactic factors; for example,<br />

different gender and person features found <strong>in</strong> each disjunct, the type of sentence,<br />

which may be either declarative or <strong>in</strong>terrogative, and the presence of a predicative adjective/participle,<br />

which determ<strong>in</strong>e the choice of a specific verb agreement form. Third, a<br />

number of different strategies adopted by MG native speakers are also associated to verb<br />

agreement. These strategies differ from other languages and have different weight <strong>in</strong> each<br />

language. As we will show, MG adopts two basic strategies as opposed to other languages<br />

whose native speakers use more than two.<br />

F<strong>in</strong>ally, we will briefly refer to coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns jo<strong>in</strong>ed by the positive predisjunction<br />

and disjunction i...i/ite...ite ‘either...or’ and the negative predisjunction and disjunction<br />

oute...oute ‘neither...nor’. The positive predisjunction and disjunction i...i ‘either...or’ behaves<br />

almost the same as bare disjunction i ‘or’. However, the negative predisjunction and


6.4 Verb <strong>Agreement</strong> <strong>in</strong> MG Disjunctive Coord<strong>in</strong>ate <strong>Noun</strong>s 177<br />

disjunction oute...oute ‘neither...nor’ shows great preference to the plural verb agreement<br />

form.<br />

The data analysis was based on two questionnaires that were developed <strong>in</strong> order to<br />

test the prevalent verb agreement form <strong>in</strong> disjunctive structures. The aim was to explore<br />

the different <strong>in</strong>terpretations assigned to the coord<strong>in</strong>ate structures and the syntactic factors<br />

that determ<strong>in</strong>e verb agreement. The first questionnaire focuses on the <strong>in</strong>terpretation of the<br />

disjunctive coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns. The second questionnaire focuses on the syntactic factors and<br />

it consists of both declarative and <strong>in</strong>terrogative sentences. The questionnaire was issued to<br />

20 native speakers who are all university graduates from different areas <strong>in</strong> Greece. Their<br />

choice depends on whether they found the phrase acceptable and they would use it <strong>in</strong><br />

everyday language or not 18 .<br />

6.4.1 Interpretation and Verb <strong>Agreement</strong> <strong>in</strong> Disjunctive Coord<strong>in</strong>ate <strong>Noun</strong>s<br />

In this section, we explore the different <strong>in</strong>terpretations assigned to disjunctive coord<strong>in</strong>ate<br />

nouns. The first group of data <strong>in</strong>volves MG disjunctive phrases with s<strong>in</strong>gular disjuncts. In<br />

MG, number verb agreement with a disjunctive phrase largerly depends on the <strong>in</strong>terpretation<br />

of disjunction as an ‘and-coord<strong>in</strong>ate’ or and as an ‘exclusive’ or. Our aim is to show<br />

that MG native speakers allow s<strong>in</strong>g verb agreement when they assign to the disjunctive<br />

phrase an ‘exclusive’ sense, and a pl verb agreement, when they assign to the phrase an<br />

‘and-coord<strong>in</strong>ate’ sense.<br />

In the follow<strong>in</strong>g example, the coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase consists of two s<strong>in</strong>gular disjuncts, the<br />

proper noun Kostas and the proper noun Maria. The majority of the participants used a<br />

s<strong>in</strong>gular verb agreement (14/20), only 4 participants used a pl verb form while 2 participants<br />

selected both a s<strong>in</strong>gular and a plural form:<br />

(79) O Kostas i i Maria<br />

the.sg Kostas.sg or the.sg Maria.sg<br />

me to aftok<strong>in</strong>ito.<br />

with the car<br />

‘Kostas or Maria will pick me up with the car’<br />

(constructed)<br />

tha<br />

will<br />

me<br />

me<br />

pari<br />

pick-up.sg<br />

The most plausible <strong>in</strong>terpretation for the largest number of native speakers is an ‘exclusive’<br />

one. In example (79), the ‘exclusive’ <strong>in</strong>terpretation is confirmed by the fact that the<br />

sentence can accept the additional phrase as one of them is work<strong>in</strong>g tonight and it can<br />

only be <strong>in</strong>terpreted with an ‘exclusive’ sense:<br />

(80) O Kostas i i Maria tha me pari<br />

the.sg Kostas.sg or the.sg Maria.sg will me pick-up.sg<br />

me to aftok<strong>in</strong>ito, jati enas apo tus dio dulevei<br />

with<br />

apopse.<br />

tonight<br />

the car, as one of the both is-work<strong>in</strong>g<br />

‘Kostas or Maria will pick me up with the car, s<strong>in</strong>ce one of them is work<strong>in</strong>g tonight’<br />

(constructed)<br />

Therefore, example (79) is <strong>in</strong>terpreted by the majority of consultants as an action carried<br />

out by one of the two <strong>in</strong>dividuals and this is why they prefer a s<strong>in</strong>gular verb. Only 4 (out of<br />

20) consultants <strong>in</strong>terpret example (79) as if both of them ‘will pick up the speaker’, which<br />

is why we get a smaller number of consultants that prefer the plural verb.<br />

18 For more details on the methodology and rationale on construct<strong>in</strong>g the questionnaires on disjunctively<br />

conjo<strong>in</strong>ed nouns see Appendix B.


6.4 Verb <strong>Agreement</strong> <strong>in</strong> MG Disjunctive Coord<strong>in</strong>ate <strong>Noun</strong>s 178<br />

Similarly, <strong>in</strong> the follow<strong>in</strong>g example 15 (out of 20) consultants chose a s<strong>in</strong>gular verb.<br />

Therefore, the example is likely to be <strong>in</strong>terpreted with an ‘exclusively’ sense:<br />

(81) To agori i to koritsi prospathi<br />

the.sg boy.sg or the.sg girl.sg tries.sg<br />

s<strong>in</strong>estimata<br />

feel<strong>in</strong>gs<br />

‘The boy or the girl tries to suppress the feel<strong>in</strong>gs’<br />

(constructed)<br />

na<br />

to<br />

katastili<br />

suppress<br />

The exclusive <strong>in</strong>terpretation is confirmed by the presence of modifiers, such as separately,<br />

<strong>in</strong>dividually, only, that assign an ‘exclusive’ sense <strong>in</strong> the sentence. Thus, example<br />

(81) is rewritten as follows:<br />

(82) To agori i to koritsi prospathi<br />

the.sg boy.sg or the.sg girl.sg tries.sg<br />

na katastili ta s<strong>in</strong>estimata<br />

to suppress the feel<strong>in</strong>gs<br />

‘The boy or the girl alone tries to suppress the feel<strong>in</strong>gs’<br />

(constructed)<br />

mono<br />

alone/only<br />

Only 3 (out of 20) consultants chose a plural verb agreement <strong>in</strong> example (81), which<br />

is the result of an ‘and-coord<strong>in</strong>ate’ <strong>in</strong>terpretation of or. The same example with a plural<br />

verb agreement is shown below:<br />

(83) To agori i to koritsi prospathun<br />

the.sg boy.sg or the.sg girl.sg try.pl<br />

ta s<strong>in</strong>estimata<br />

the feel<strong>in</strong>gs<br />

‘The boy or the girl try to suppress the feel<strong>in</strong>gs’<br />

(constructed)<br />

na<br />

to<br />

tu<br />

its<br />

katastilun<br />

suppress<br />

Thus, the ‘and-coord<strong>in</strong>ate’ <strong>in</strong>terpretation is also acceptable and it is a natural choice<br />

for a few (3/20) native speakers but to a smaller degree. F<strong>in</strong>ally, we need to note that only<br />

2 consultants chose both the plural and the s<strong>in</strong>gular verb forms which shows that for these<br />

consultants both <strong>in</strong>terpretations are acceptable.<br />

Alternatively, <strong>in</strong> the follow<strong>in</strong>g example where the coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase also consists of<br />

two s<strong>in</strong>gular disjuncts, the largest number of participants were <strong>in</strong>cl<strong>in</strong>ed to use the plural<br />

verb agreement form (13/20) while the s<strong>in</strong>gular verb form was chosen by fewer (7/20)<br />

consultants:<br />

(84) I j<strong>in</strong>eka i to pedi exun protereotita<br />

the woman.sg or the child.sg have.pl priority<br />

to emvolio kata tis gripis<br />

the vacc<strong>in</strong>e aga<strong>in</strong>st the flu<br />

‘The woman or child have priority for the vacc<strong>in</strong>e aga<strong>in</strong>st the flu’<br />

(G.N.: To Vima)<br />

The above example is most likely assigned an ‘and-coord<strong>in</strong>ate’ <strong>in</strong>terpretation consider<strong>in</strong>g<br />

that both groups are high-risk groups and require the vacc<strong>in</strong>e. This is confirmed by the<br />

fact that modifiers, which assign distributivity, are not used by native speakers <strong>in</strong> these<br />

cases and the sentence is paraphrased with the conjunction and, as seen below:<br />

ja<br />

for<br />

ta<br />

the


6.4 Verb <strong>Agreement</strong> <strong>in</strong> MG Disjunctive Coord<strong>in</strong>ate <strong>Noun</strong>s 179<br />

(85) I j<strong>in</strong>eka ke to pedi exun protereotita<br />

the woman.sg and the child.sg have.pl priority<br />

to emvolio kata tis gripis<br />

the vacc<strong>in</strong>e aga<strong>in</strong>st the flu<br />

‘The woman and child have priority for the vacc<strong>in</strong>e aga<strong>in</strong>st the flu’<br />

(G.N.: O Ependitis)<br />

Similarly, the example (86) is more likely <strong>in</strong>terpreted as an ‘and-coord<strong>in</strong>ate’ phrase. In<br />

particular, 15 (out of 20) consultants chose a plural verb agreement and only 5 (out of 20)<br />

consultants chose a s<strong>in</strong>gular verb agreement. However, none of the consultants chose both<br />

verb agreement forms:<br />

(86) To agori i to koritsi<br />

the.sg<br />

diavasma<br />

study<strong>in</strong>g<br />

boy.sg or the.sg girl.sg<br />

‘The boy or the girl are tired from study<strong>in</strong>g’<br />

(www.<strong>in</strong>.gr)<br />

The above example could be paraphrased as follows:<br />

(87) To agori ke to koritsi<br />

the.sg boy.sg and the.sg girl.sg<br />

to diavasma<br />

the study<strong>in</strong>g<br />

‘The boy and the girl are tired from study<strong>in</strong>g’<br />

(constructed)<br />

exun<br />

have.pl<br />

exun<br />

have.pl<br />

kurasti<br />

tired.pl<br />

kurasti<br />

tired.pl<br />

apo<br />

from<br />

ja<br />

for<br />

apo<br />

from<br />

In fact, example (86) is seen by most consultants as if the event has an effect on both<br />

‘the boy and the girl’ s<strong>in</strong>ce both are perceived to be study<strong>in</strong>g despite the fact that they<br />

may have not participated together <strong>in</strong> the same event. However, we need to note that<br />

only example (87), which can be a paraphrase of example (86), would accept modifiers<br />

which assign collectivity, such as both of them, whereas example (86) does not accept such<br />

modifiers. In fact, <strong>in</strong> example (88), if we add a modifier with a collective mean<strong>in</strong>g, the<br />

sentence is marked if not completely ungrammatical, but not <strong>in</strong> example (89):<br />

(88) ??To agori i to koritsi exun ke<br />

the.sg boy.sg or the.sg girl.sg have.pl and<br />

kurasti apo to diavasma<br />

tired.pl from the study<strong>in</strong>g<br />

‘The boy or the girl are both of them tired from study<strong>in</strong>g’<br />

(constructed)<br />

(89) To agori ke to koritsi exun ke<br />

the.sg boy.sg and the.sg girl.sg have.pl and<br />

kurasti apo to diavasma<br />

tired.pl from the study<strong>in</strong>g<br />

‘The boy and the girl are both of them tired from study<strong>in</strong>g’<br />

(constructed)<br />

ta<br />

the<br />

ta<br />

the<br />

dio<br />

both<br />

dio<br />

both<br />

The fact that some consultants chose the s<strong>in</strong>gular verb form, even though they were<br />

fewer (5/20), shows that an ‘and-coord<strong>in</strong>ate’ <strong>in</strong>terpretation is not the only possibility for<br />

the sentence. Therefore, example (86) was perceived with an ‘exclusive’ sense by a few<br />

to<br />

the


6.4 Verb <strong>Agreement</strong> <strong>in</strong> MG Disjunctive Coord<strong>in</strong>ate <strong>Noun</strong>s 180<br />

speakers. Thus, <strong>in</strong> the two examples above native speakers assigned ma<strong>in</strong>ly an ‘andcoord<strong>in</strong>ate’<br />

<strong>in</strong>terpretation followed by a plural verb with very few cases of an ‘exclusive’<br />

<strong>in</strong>terpretation followed by a s<strong>in</strong>gular verb. The responses of the consultants of the ma<strong>in</strong><br />

examples discussed are shown <strong>in</strong> the follow<strong>in</strong>g table:<br />

Table 6.3: S<strong>in</strong>gular <strong>Noun</strong>s<br />

Consultant Number: 20<br />

Examples Verb <strong>Agreement</strong> Form/Interpretation of or<br />

s<strong>in</strong>gular/‘exclusive’ plural/‘<strong>in</strong>clusive’ s<strong>in</strong>g-pl/both<br />

(79) 14 4 2<br />

(81) 15 3 2<br />

(84) 7 13 -<br />

(86) 5 15 -<br />

The table above shows that participants have a preference to a specific verb form usually<br />

related to the <strong>in</strong>terpretation they assign to the correspond<strong>in</strong>g phrase. However, this is not<br />

the only possibility but <strong>in</strong> all examples a second <strong>in</strong>terpretation is possible, which proves<br />

that the ‘exclusive/and-coord<strong>in</strong>ate’ dist<strong>in</strong>ction is not clear-cut but depends on the speaker’s<br />

perception of the specific phrase <strong>in</strong> the specific discourse conditions.<br />

There are some examples where the ‘exclusive’ and ‘and-coord<strong>in</strong>ate’ <strong>in</strong>terpretations<br />

of or do not overlap but <strong>in</strong>stead there is only one sense assigned to the phrase which is<br />

consistent across native speakers. Jenn<strong>in</strong>gs (1966) holds that a truth-functional exclusive<br />

example <strong>in</strong> English is Mary is related to either Jack or Bob (181). In the correspond<strong>in</strong>g<br />

<strong>Greek</strong> example translated from English, 20 (out of 20) consultants chose the s<strong>in</strong>gular verb<br />

agreement form, based on an ‘exclusive’ only <strong>in</strong>terpretation:<br />

(90) O Kostas i o<br />

the.sg Kostas.sg or the.sg<br />

tis Marias<br />

of-the Maria<br />

‘Kostas or Giorgos is Maria’s relative’<br />

(translation from Jenn<strong>in</strong>gs (1994))<br />

Jorgos<br />

Giorgos.sg<br />

<strong>in</strong>e<br />

is.sg<br />

s<strong>in</strong>genis<br />

relative.sg<br />

The most plausible mean<strong>in</strong>g assigned to the above sentence is, what Jenn<strong>in</strong>gs (1966) also<br />

presents for the correspond<strong>in</strong>g English example, that only one of the two must be Maria’s<br />

relative, otherwise if the sentence is <strong>in</strong>terpreted conjunctively, Maria will be related to<br />

both ‘Kostas’ and ‘Jorgos’ 19 . Logicians who support an exclusive or would claim that the<br />

possibility here is that either the first or the second disjunct is true but def<strong>in</strong>itely not both<br />

for the disjunction to be true. If both disjuncts are true then the whole disjunction is false.<br />

The same phrase, however, can be <strong>in</strong>terpreted purely pragmatically s<strong>in</strong>ce this is what one<br />

would say if they wanted to specify that one of the two people is Maria’s cous<strong>in</strong>. Thus, <strong>in</strong><br />

MG it conveys an ‘exclusive-or’ sense.<br />

Alternatively, there are examples where the ‘and-coord<strong>in</strong>ate’ <strong>in</strong>terpretation is only assigned<br />

by MG native speakers. In the correspond<strong>in</strong>g example <strong>in</strong> MG translated from<br />

English, all native speakers (20/20) used a plural verb agreement as a result of an ‘andcoord<strong>in</strong>ate’<br />

<strong>in</strong>terpretation of or assigned to the phrase:<br />

(91) O jatros<br />

the.sg<br />

farmaka.<br />

doctor.sg<br />

prescriptions<br />

i<br />

or<br />

o<br />

the.sg<br />

odontiatros<br />

dentist.sg<br />

mporun<br />

can.pl<br />

na<br />

to<br />

grapsun<br />

write<br />

19 Of course the read<strong>in</strong>g where ‘Maria’ is related to both is possible but <strong>in</strong> this case the conjunction and<br />

would be used to coord<strong>in</strong>ate the two nouns and not the disjunction or.


6.4 Verb <strong>Agreement</strong> <strong>in</strong> MG Disjunctive Coord<strong>in</strong>ate <strong>Noun</strong>s 181<br />

‘The doctor or dentist can write prescriptions’<br />

(translation from de Swart (1998))<br />

Thus, the ‘and-coord<strong>in</strong>ate’ <strong>in</strong>terpretation is the only possibility here. de Swart (1998,<br />

57) argues that <strong>in</strong> English the disjunctive coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase above does not correspond<br />

to a disjunction of propositions <strong>in</strong> truth-conditional semantics and we should be careful<br />

when we relate the logical connective to natural language or. Even if this is the case, we<br />

cannot deny the fact that native speakers use a plural verb agreement s<strong>in</strong>ce they <strong>in</strong>terpret<br />

the sentence as ‘and-coord<strong>in</strong>ate’ consider<strong>in</strong>g the fact that both a doctor and a dentist can<br />

write prescriptions 20 .<br />

The above data suggest that there are two <strong>in</strong>terpretations for natural language or <strong>in</strong><br />

MG, the ‘and-coord<strong>in</strong>ate’ and the ‘exclusive’ one. In the majority of examples, there is<br />

not a sharp dist<strong>in</strong>ction between the two but the context and the specific conditions seem<br />

to determ<strong>in</strong>e the k<strong>in</strong>d of mean<strong>in</strong>g that will be assigned to the disjunctive phrase by the<br />

speakers. There are cases, however, that either an ‘and-coord<strong>in</strong>ate’ or an ‘exclusive’ <strong>in</strong>terpretation<br />

occurs exclusively. Some of these cases can be expla<strong>in</strong>ed us<strong>in</strong>g truth-conditional<br />

semantics s<strong>in</strong>ce the logical operators ∨ and the <strong>in</strong>terpretation for natural language or may<br />

co<strong>in</strong>cide. However, we cannot always rely on truth-conditional semantic s<strong>in</strong>ce the context<br />

is an important factor to disambiguate the mean<strong>in</strong>g of a phrase.<br />

6.4.2 Syntax and Verb <strong>Agreement</strong> <strong>in</strong> Disjunctive Coord<strong>in</strong>ate <strong>Noun</strong>s<br />

Next, it is <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g to exam<strong>in</strong>e whether any syntactic factors determ<strong>in</strong>e verb agreement<br />

<strong>in</strong> disjunctive coord<strong>in</strong>ate noun phrases. Parker (1983), who studies syntactic number <strong>in</strong><br />

English positive disjunctive coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns with ‘either-or’ and negative disjunctive coord<strong>in</strong>ate<br />

nouns with ‘neither-nor’ 21 , argues that there are relevant variables that determ<strong>in</strong>e<br />

whether verb agreement is s<strong>in</strong>gular or plural. In the case of disjunctive s<strong>in</strong>gular coord<strong>in</strong>ate<br />

nouns, the variables are the gender and the person of the disjuncts. Thus, <strong>in</strong> English<br />

<strong>in</strong> mixed gender or mixed person disjuncts participants favour a syntactically plural verb<br />

form. He argues that this preference to a verb form is attributed to knowledge of the<br />

language itself and not only to knowledge of the world on the part of the speakers. This<br />

means that for Parker (1983) pure syntax also determ<strong>in</strong>es verb agreement as opposed to<br />

other l<strong>in</strong>guists who also focus on speakers’s strategies or semantic factors (Morgan (1972,<br />

1985); Peterson (1986)). Therefore, mixed gender or mixed person disjuncts should be<br />

treated as syntactically plural. Our goal is to <strong>in</strong>vestigate these claims for MG s<strong>in</strong>ce there<br />

is no similar work <strong>in</strong> other languages other than English. We will show that MG coord<strong>in</strong>ate<br />

phrases with s<strong>in</strong>gular number but mixed gender or mixed person nouns show similar<br />

variation to English and favour plural verb agreement <strong>in</strong> declarative sentences and CCA<br />

<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>terrogative sentences.<br />

We will discuss first declarative sentences with mixed gender s<strong>in</strong>gular disjuncts. In<br />

Chapter 4, we saw that the expected resolved gender for mixed gender animate conjuncts<br />

is masc and for mixed gender <strong>in</strong>animate conjuncts is neut, while only adjectives and participles<br />

(not verbs) show gender agreement. In disjunctive coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrases with mixed<br />

gender disjuncts, the same requirements hold but there is a specific restriction concern<strong>in</strong>g<br />

the number feature of the verb. There are two options available <strong>in</strong> declarative sentences<br />

with s<strong>in</strong>gular mixed gender disjuncts and they relate to the presence or absence of a pred-<br />

20 Among others, Jenn<strong>in</strong>gs (1994) and de Swart (1998) argue that modality favours the <strong>in</strong>terpretation of or<br />

as and. Also, accord<strong>in</strong>g to Jenn<strong>in</strong>gs (1994) or behaves like and when or occurs <strong>in</strong> expressions of preference,<br />

when it appears <strong>in</strong> the complement of a comparative adjective and when it is immediately subord<strong>in</strong>ated to<br />

if. 21He refers to disjunctive coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns with ‘either-or’ as “correlative constructions” and negative<br />

disjunctive coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns with ‘neither-nor’ as “negative correlative constructions”.


6.4 Verb <strong>Agreement</strong> <strong>in</strong> MG Disjunctive Coord<strong>in</strong>ate <strong>Noun</strong>s 182<br />

icative adjective/participle, which <strong>in</strong>flects for gender. If a predicative adjective/participle is<br />

not present, s<strong>in</strong>gular and plural verb agreement varies depend<strong>in</strong>g on the <strong>in</strong>terpretation. If<br />

a predicative adjective/participle is present <strong>in</strong> the verb phrase, the number of the agree<strong>in</strong>g<br />

predicate and predicative adjective/participle is preferably the plural and therefore resolution<br />

is obeyed for both the number and gender features. The follow<strong>in</strong>g examples illustrate<br />

these patterns:<br />

(92) O fititis<br />

i i fititria<br />

the male-univ-student.masc.sg or the female-univ-student.fem.sg<br />

pu <strong>in</strong>e siguri ja kathe epilogi tha<br />

that<br />

petixun<br />

are certa<strong>in</strong>.masc.pl about every choice will<br />

succeed.masc.pl<br />

‘The male-student or female-student that is certa<strong>in</strong> about every choice will succeed’<br />

(constructed)<br />

(93) O pateras i i mitera<br />

the father.masc.sg or the mother.fem.sg<br />

enimeri ja t<strong>in</strong> katastasi<br />

<strong>in</strong>formed.masc.pl about the situation<br />

‘The father or mother are <strong>in</strong>formed about the situation’<br />

(constructed)<br />

In examples (92) and (93), both coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrases consist of two disjuncts, a mascul<strong>in</strong>e<br />

s<strong>in</strong>gular and a fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e s<strong>in</strong>gular. In both cases, most (12/20) consultants chose plural <strong>in</strong> the<br />

agree<strong>in</strong>g verb and predicative adjective <strong>in</strong> all 4 sentences that appeared <strong>in</strong> the questionnaire.<br />

A small number of participants (4/20) opted for the s<strong>in</strong>gular. The consultants who chose<br />

a s<strong>in</strong>gular verb chose the gender of the closest conjunct. Thus, they selected the fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e<br />

gender for the predicative adjective/participle follow<strong>in</strong>g closest conjunct agreement, as <strong>in</strong><br />

(94). When conjuncts appeared <strong>in</strong> the reverse order, the consultants who chose s<strong>in</strong>gular<br />

verb agreement opted for the mascul<strong>in</strong>e gender due to CCA, as <strong>in</strong> (95). F<strong>in</strong>ally, there<br />

were 2 (out of 20) consultants who chose the plural <strong>in</strong> 3 of the 4 questions and 2 (out of<br />

20) consultants who chose the plural <strong>in</strong> 2 of the 4 questions. The two examples discussed<br />

appear below:<br />

(94) O fititis<br />

i i fititria<br />

the male-univ-student.masc.sg or the female-univ-student.fem.sg<br />

pu <strong>in</strong>e siguri ja kathe epilogi tha petuxi<br />

who is certa<strong>in</strong>.fem.sg about every choice will succeed.sg<br />

‘The male-student or female-student who is certa<strong>in</strong> about every choice will succeed’<br />

(constructed)<br />

(95) I fititria<br />

i o fititis<br />

the female-univ-student.fem.sg or the male-univ-student.masc.sg<br />

pu <strong>in</strong>e siguros ja t<strong>in</strong> kariera tu tha<br />

that<br />

petixi<br />

is certa<strong>in</strong>.masc.sg about the career his.masc.sg will<br />

succeed.sg<br />

‘The female-student or male-student who is certa<strong>in</strong> about their career will succeed’<br />

(constructed)<br />

On the other hand, <strong>in</strong> mixed gender nouns if a predicative adjective or participle is<br />

not present, then the number of the predicate can be either s<strong>in</strong>gular or plural depend<strong>in</strong>g<br />

on the <strong>in</strong>terpretation of the phrase. For <strong>in</strong>stance, the questionnaire <strong>in</strong>cluded the follow<strong>in</strong>g<br />

<strong>in</strong>e<br />

are


6.4 Verb <strong>Agreement</strong> <strong>in</strong> MG Disjunctive Coord<strong>in</strong>ate <strong>Noun</strong>s 183<br />

two examples with mixed gender nouns and without a predicative adjective/participle, (96)<br />

and (97). In both cases, 7 (out of 20) consultants chose s<strong>in</strong>gular verb agreement, 2 (out of<br />

20) consultants chose plural verb agreement and 11 (out of 20) chose both a s<strong>in</strong>gular and<br />

a plural verb agreement. The result is still natural with either forms s<strong>in</strong>ce verbs show only<br />

number and not gender agreement <strong>in</strong> MG.<br />

(96) O mathitis<br />

i i mathitria<br />

the male-student.masc.sg or the female-student.fem.sg<br />

mpor-i/-un na enimeroth-i/-un apo tus gonis<br />

can.sg/pl to be-<strong>in</strong>formed.sg/pl by the parents<br />

‘The male-student or female-student can be <strong>in</strong>formed by the parents’<br />

(constructed)<br />

(97) O ijios i i kori<br />

the<br />

viothia<br />

help<br />

son.masc.sg or the daughter.fem.sg<br />

‘The son or the daughter need help’<br />

(constructed)<br />

xriaz-ete/-onte<br />

need.sg/pl<br />

Thus, the presence of a predicative adjective/participle, which forces agreement with the<br />

coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase, is crucial for the verb form <strong>in</strong> MG. The table below is a summary of<br />

the above data:<br />

Table 6.4: Disjunction i<br />

S<strong>in</strong>gular Mixed Gender <strong>Noun</strong>s<br />

Consultant Number: 20<br />

Declaratives Verb <strong>Agreement</strong> Form<br />

np.sg or np.sg + verb s<strong>in</strong>gular plural s<strong>in</strong>g-pl/both<br />

(96) 7 2 11<br />

(97) 7 2 11<br />

np.sg or np.sg + verb + pred.adj/part s<strong>in</strong>gular plural s<strong>in</strong>g-pl/both<br />

(92) 4 12 4<br />

(93) 4 12 4<br />

Interrogative sentences without a predicative adjective/participle with s<strong>in</strong>gular mixed<br />

gender coord<strong>in</strong>ate NPs, occurr<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> either preverbal or <strong>in</strong> postverbal position favour s<strong>in</strong>gular<br />

verb agreement (CCA). In example (98), where the <strong>in</strong>terrogative sentence has the<br />

same word order as the declarative and the <strong>in</strong>tonation determ<strong>in</strong>es the type of the sentence,<br />

9 (out of 20) consultants chose s<strong>in</strong>gular verb agreement and only 4 (out of 20) consultants<br />

chose the plural. However, 7 (out of 20) consultants chose both a s<strong>in</strong>gular and a plural<br />

verb. In example (99), the sentence is also <strong>in</strong>terrogative but the coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase occurs<br />

postverbally. In this case, 11 (out of 20) consultants chose a s<strong>in</strong>gular verb, 4 (out of 20)<br />

consultants chose a plural verb, and 5 (out of 20) consultants chose both a s<strong>in</strong>gular and<br />

a plural. In both sentences, the s<strong>in</strong>gular verb is preferred, with higher frequency <strong>in</strong> the<br />

second sentence.<br />

(98) I mitera i to<br />

the.sg.fem mother.sg.fem or the.sg.neut<br />

etimazet-e/-onte ja eksodo;<br />

is-gett<strong>in</strong>g-ready.sg/pl to go-out?<br />

‘Is the mother or the boy gett<strong>in</strong>g ready to go out?’<br />

(constructed)<br />

agori<br />

boy.sg.neut


6.4 Verb <strong>Agreement</strong> <strong>in</strong> MG Disjunctive Coord<strong>in</strong>ate <strong>Noun</strong>s 184<br />

(99) Etimaz-ete/-onte i mitera<br />

is-gett<strong>in</strong>g-ready.sg/pl the.sg.fem mother.sg.fem<br />

agori ja eksodo;<br />

boy.sg.neut to go-out?<br />

‘Is the mother or the boy gett<strong>in</strong>g ready to go out?’<br />

(constructed)<br />

i<br />

or<br />

to<br />

the.sg.neut<br />

In <strong>in</strong>terrogative sentences with a predicative adjective/participle, the plural verb form<br />

is favoured when the disjunctive phrase occurs preverbally, but the s<strong>in</strong>gular verb form<br />

occurs more often when the disjunctive phrase occurs postverbally. In example (100), 13<br />

(out of the 20) consultants chose the plural, 3 (out of the 20) consultants chose the s<strong>in</strong>gular<br />

and 4 (out of the 20) consultants chose both the s<strong>in</strong>gular and the plural form. From the<br />

consultants who chose both a s<strong>in</strong>gular and a plural verb form, 2 of the 4 consultants chose<br />

the plural <strong>in</strong> 2 of the 3 sentences and 2 of the 4 consultants chose the s<strong>in</strong>gular <strong>in</strong> 2 of the<br />

3 sentences. In (101), 9 (out of the 20) consultants chose the s<strong>in</strong>gular, 6 (out of the 20)<br />

consultants chose the plural and 5 (out of the 20) consultants chose both the s<strong>in</strong>gular and<br />

the plural form. From the consultants who chose both a s<strong>in</strong>gular and a plural verb form,<br />

3 of the 5 consultants chose the s<strong>in</strong>gular <strong>in</strong> 2 of the 3 sentences and 2 of the 5 consultants<br />

chose the plural <strong>in</strong> 2 of the 3 sentences.<br />

(100) I mitera i to<br />

the.sg.fem mother.sg.fem or the.sg.neut<br />

etim-i/-o<br />

ja eksodo;<br />

ready.pl.masc/sg.neut to go-out?<br />

‘Is the mother or the boy ready to go out?’<br />

(constructed)<br />

(101) Ine etimi i mitera<br />

is ready.sg.fem the.sg mother.sg.fem<br />

agori ja eksodo;<br />

boy.sg.neut to go-out?<br />

‘Is the mother or the boy ready to go out?’<br />

(constructed)<br />

In the follow<strong>in</strong>g table, we summarise the f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>gs:<br />

i<br />

or<br />

agori<br />

boy.sg.neut<br />

to<br />

the.sg.neut<br />

<strong>in</strong>e<br />

are.pl<br />

Table 6.5: Disjunction i<br />

S<strong>in</strong>gular Mixed Gender <strong>Noun</strong>s<br />

Consultant Number: 20<br />

Interrogatives Verb <strong>Agreement</strong> Form<br />

np.sg or np.sg + verb ? s<strong>in</strong>gular plural s<strong>in</strong>g-pl/both<br />

(98) 9 4 7<br />

verb + np.sg or np.sg? s<strong>in</strong>gular plural s<strong>in</strong>g-pl/both<br />

(99) 11 4 5<br />

np.sg or np.sg + verb + pred.adj/part? s<strong>in</strong>gular plural s<strong>in</strong>g-pl/both<br />

(100) 3 13 4<br />

verb + np.sg or np.sg + pred.adj/part? s<strong>in</strong>gular plural s<strong>in</strong>g-pl/both<br />

(101) 9 6 5<br />

In the first group of <strong>in</strong>terrogative sentences, the number of native speakers who chose<br />

a s<strong>in</strong>gular verb was higher <strong>in</strong> verb-subject constructions than <strong>in</strong> subject-verb constructions.<br />

In the second group of sentences, the native speakers who chose a s<strong>in</strong>gular verb


6.4 Verb <strong>Agreement</strong> <strong>in</strong> MG Disjunctive Coord<strong>in</strong>ate <strong>Noun</strong>s 185<br />

were very few <strong>in</strong> subject-verb constructions whereas <strong>in</strong> verb-subject constructions,<br />

although the s<strong>in</strong>gular verb form was high, the plural verb form was not as low as <strong>in</strong> the<br />

correspond<strong>in</strong>g verb-subject constructions without the predicative adjective/participle.<br />

To summarise, <strong>in</strong> subject-verb <strong>in</strong>terrogatives and <strong>in</strong> verb-subject <strong>in</strong>terrogatives<br />

without a predicative adjective/participle, s<strong>in</strong>gular verb agreement occurs more frequently<br />

than plural. In <strong>in</strong>terrogative sentences with a predicative adjective/participle, the plural<br />

verb form is still preferable <strong>in</strong> subject-verb constructions but the s<strong>in</strong>gular takes over <strong>in</strong><br />

verb-subject constructions.<br />

The next group of coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns that we will analyse is s<strong>in</strong>gular number but different<br />

person disjuncts. The person feature also determ<strong>in</strong>es the choice of verb agreement. In<br />

declarative sentences, participants show preference to a plural resolved verb form. In<br />

examples (102) and (103), 17 (out of 20) consultants opted for a plural verb and a resolved<br />

person follow<strong>in</strong>g the person hierarchy (Corbett, 1991), and 3 (out of 20) consultants chose<br />

the s<strong>in</strong>gular verb form (CCA):<br />

(102) Ego<br />

I.1.sg<br />

(103) Ego<br />

I.1.sg<br />

i<br />

or<br />

esi<br />

you.2.sg<br />

‘Me or you will need help’<br />

(constructed)<br />

i<br />

or<br />

o<br />

the<br />

tha<br />

will<br />

Kostas<br />

Kostas.3.sg<br />

‘Me or Kostas will take over the job’<br />

(constructed)<br />

xriastume<br />

need.1.pl<br />

tha<br />

will<br />

voithia<br />

help<br />

analavume<br />

take-over.1.pl<br />

t<strong>in</strong><br />

the<br />

dulia<br />

job<br />

When the sentence is <strong>in</strong>terrogative but reta<strong>in</strong>s the subject-verb order, the consultants<br />

show preference to a s<strong>in</strong>gular verb form and less often to a plural verb form. In particular,<br />

<strong>in</strong> example (104), 11 (out of 20) consultants chose a s<strong>in</strong>gular verb agreement form and 9<br />

(out of 20) consultants chose a plural verb agreement form. An example is presented below:<br />

(104) Esi<br />

you.2.sg<br />

i<br />

or<br />

i<br />

the<br />

Maria<br />

Maria.3.sg<br />

‘Will you or Maria go to the doctor?’<br />

(constructed)<br />

tha<br />

will<br />

pai<br />

go.3.sg<br />

sto<br />

to-the<br />

jatro;<br />

doctor?<br />

When the <strong>in</strong>terrogative sentence has a verb-subject order then native speakers also<br />

prefer s<strong>in</strong>gular verb agreement (and CCA for person). For <strong>in</strong>stance, <strong>in</strong> example (105), 13<br />

(out of 20) consultants chose a s<strong>in</strong>gular verb agreement form and 7 (out of 20) consultants<br />

chose a plural verb agreement form. Therefore, the s<strong>in</strong>gular verb form (and CCA for person)<br />

occurs with higher frequency <strong>in</strong> verb-subject <strong>in</strong>terrogatives than <strong>in</strong> subject-verb ones.<br />

An example is shown below:<br />

(105) Tha<br />

will<br />

pas<br />

go.2.sg<br />

esi<br />

you.2.sg<br />

i<br />

or<br />

‘Will you or Maria go to the doctor?’<br />

(constructed)<br />

i<br />

the<br />

Maria<br />

Maria.3.sg<br />

sto<br />

to-the<br />

jatro;<br />

doctor?<br />

Thus, <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>terrogative sentences with s<strong>in</strong>gular and mixed person disjuncts, s<strong>in</strong>gular verb<br />

agreement is preferred when the sentence has a subject-verb order or a verb-subject<br />

order. To summarise, <strong>in</strong> declarative sentences with mixed person disjuncts speakers prefer<br />

the plural verb form than the s<strong>in</strong>gular (CCA). In <strong>in</strong>terrogative subject-verb or verbsubject<br />

sentences, the s<strong>in</strong>gular verb form occurs more often than the plural verb form<br />

with higher frequency <strong>in</strong> verb-subject sentences. The responses of the relevant examples<br />

are summarised briefly on the table below:


6.4 Verb <strong>Agreement</strong> <strong>in</strong> MG Disjunctive Coord<strong>in</strong>ate <strong>Noun</strong>s 186<br />

Table 6.6: Disjunction i<br />

S<strong>in</strong>gular Mixed Person <strong>Noun</strong>s<br />

Consultant Number: 20<br />

Affirmative Sentence Verb <strong>Agreement</strong> Form<br />

np.sg or np.sg + verb s<strong>in</strong>gular plural s<strong>in</strong>g-pl/both<br />

(102) 3 17 -<br />

(103) 3 17 -<br />

Interrogative Sentences Verb <strong>Agreement</strong> Form<br />

np.sg or np.sg + verb? s<strong>in</strong>gular plural s<strong>in</strong>g-pl/both<br />

(104) 11 9 -<br />

verb + np.sg or np.sg?<br />

(105) 13 7 -<br />

The current section presents the most important data of disjunctively conjo<strong>in</strong>ed phrases<br />

when disjuncts have a s<strong>in</strong>gular number but different gender and person features. The first<br />

observation is that a different gender and person <strong>in</strong> the disjuncts determ<strong>in</strong>es the choice of<br />

the verb form. Second, the construction itself <strong>in</strong> which the different disjuncts appear plays<br />

a critical role <strong>in</strong> verb agreement. In constructions where a predicative adjective/participle<br />

is present plural is favoured whereas when an adjective/participle is absent the choice of<br />

verb agreement is based on the <strong>in</strong>terpretation of the phrase and verb agreement can be<br />

either s<strong>in</strong>gular or plural. Also, the difference <strong>in</strong> the type of sentence seems to determ<strong>in</strong>e<br />

strongly whether the verb is plural or s<strong>in</strong>gular. Declarative sentences admit both a s<strong>in</strong>gular<br />

and a plural verb agreement whereas <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>terrogative sentences the position of the subject<br />

affects number verb agreement s<strong>in</strong>ce <strong>in</strong> postverbal subjects s<strong>in</strong>gular verb agreement (CCA)<br />

<strong>in</strong>creases greatly as opposed to preverbal subjects. Thus, we can argue that verb agreement<br />

with disjunctive coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns is also partly syntactically determ<strong>in</strong>ed and not only<br />

discourse-based 22 .<br />

6.4.3 Speakers’ Strategies and Verb <strong>Agreement</strong> <strong>in</strong> MG Disjunctive <strong>Noun</strong>s<br />

In the current part, we will focus on the agreement strategies used by MG native speakers.<br />

In uniform number disjuncts, native speakers choose either a s<strong>in</strong>gular or a plural verb,<br />

mean<strong>in</strong>g that the two possible strategies are prox and pl w<strong>in</strong>s 23 . Therefore, we will<br />

focus on coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrases consist<strong>in</strong>g of mixed number disjuncts to check whether any<br />

additional strategies occur and which strategies are stronger when compared to the rest.<br />

The data shows considerable variation with regard to the speakers’ answers. However, as <strong>in</strong><br />

other languages, there are some recurr<strong>in</strong>g stategies followed by MG native speakers when<br />

choos<strong>in</strong>g verb agreement.<br />

We will focus on subject-verb coord<strong>in</strong>ate constructions with a s<strong>in</strong>gular and a plural<br />

disjunct. Three sample sentences are shown below, one declarative and two <strong>in</strong>terrogatives:<br />

(106) To aftok<strong>in</strong>ito i ta mixanakia<br />

the.sg<br />

s<strong>in</strong>toma<br />

soon<br />

car.sg or the.pl mopeds.pl<br />

‘The car or the mopeds will be-sold soon’<br />

(constructed)<br />

tha<br />

will<br />

pulithun<br />

be-sold.pl<br />

22 We need to note that the above are only speculative remarks which need further <strong>in</strong>vestigation with<br />

corpus work and speakers’ personal op<strong>in</strong>ions (though this is more difficult when <strong>in</strong>terpretation is at issue).<br />

23 We will adopt the same terms used <strong>in</strong> Peterson (1986) for reasons of clarity.


6.4 Verb <strong>Agreement</strong> <strong>in</strong> MG Disjunctive Coord<strong>in</strong>ate <strong>Noun</strong>s 187<br />

(107) To moro i ta pedia xriazonte<br />

the.sg<br />

prosoxi;<br />

attention?<br />

baby.sg or the.pl children.pl need.pl<br />

‘Does the baby or the children need more attention?’<br />

(constructed)<br />

(108) O proedros i i ipurgi tha<br />

the.sg president.sg or the.pl m<strong>in</strong>isters.pl will.pl<br />

sto s<strong>in</strong>edrio<br />

<strong>in</strong>-the conference?<br />

‘Will the president or the m<strong>in</strong>isters talk <strong>in</strong> the conference’<br />

(constructed)<br />

perisoteri<br />

more<br />

milisun<br />

talk<br />

The data showed that all 20 (out of 20) consultants choose a plural verb irrespective<br />

of the type of the sentence 24 . The two possible strategies are pl w<strong>in</strong>s and prox but the<br />

plural verb does not show which strategy is employed by the native speakers. pl w<strong>in</strong>s is<br />

favoured for two reasons: the existence of two nouns <strong>in</strong> the noun phrase and the presence<br />

of a lexically plural disjunct. The prox strategy arises because the plural disjunct occurs<br />

close to the verb and therefore the features of that noun are selected to agree with the<br />

verb. The responses of the participants are summarised <strong>in</strong> the table below:<br />

Table 6.7: Disjunction i<br />

Mixed Number <strong>Noun</strong>s<br />

Consultant Number: 20<br />

Conjunct Order Verb <strong>Agreement</strong> Form<br />

np.sg or np.pl s<strong>in</strong>gular plural s<strong>in</strong>g-pl/both<br />

(106) - 20 -<br />

(107) - 20 -<br />

(108) - 20 -<br />

Next, <strong>in</strong> order to check which of the two strategies determ<strong>in</strong>es the choice of the consultants,<br />

we carried out two different tests. In the first test, we gave 4 different sentences<br />

with the reverse order <strong>in</strong> the disjuncts, plac<strong>in</strong>g the plural disjunct first and the s<strong>in</strong>gular<br />

disjunct second. The sample sentences, which are either declarative or <strong>in</strong>terrogative, are<br />

presented below:<br />

(109) I gates i o skilos<br />

the.pl cats.pl or the.sg dog.sg<br />

luludia mu;<br />

flowers my?<br />

‘Did your cats or your dog eat my flowers?’<br />

(constructed)<br />

(110) Ta koritsia i o ijos<br />

the.pl<br />

spiti<br />

house<br />

girls.pl or the.sg son.sg<br />

‘The girls or the son will <strong>in</strong>herit the house’<br />

(constructed)<br />

su<br />

your<br />

tha<br />

will<br />

efag-e/-an<br />

ate.sg/pl<br />

klironomis-i/-un<br />

<strong>in</strong>herit.sg/pl<br />

24 One participant chose s<strong>in</strong>gular <strong>in</strong> 1 sentence out of the 3 <strong>in</strong> the questionnaire and it is probably<br />

attributed to an <strong>in</strong>correct choice.<br />

ta<br />

the<br />

to<br />

the


6.4 Verb <strong>Agreement</strong> <strong>in</strong> MG Disjunctive Coord<strong>in</strong>ate <strong>Noun</strong>s 188<br />

(111) I<br />

the.pl<br />

karekles<br />

chairs.pl<br />

i<br />

or<br />

to<br />

the.sg<br />

trapezi<br />

table.sg<br />

‘Do the chairs or the table need to be pa<strong>in</strong>ted?’<br />

(constructed)<br />

(112) I podosferistes i o dietitis<br />

the.pl<br />

xrimata<br />

money<br />

footballers.pl or the.sg coach.sg<br />

‘The footballers or the coach earn much money’<br />

(constructed)<br />

thel-i/-un<br />

need.sg/pl<br />

kerdiz-i/-un<br />

earn.sg/pl<br />

vapsimo;<br />

pa<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g?<br />

polla<br />

much<br />

For the participants who choose a plural verb <strong>in</strong> the four examples above pl w<strong>in</strong>s<br />

strategy is stronger than the prox. The same can be claimed for examples (106), (107)<br />

and (108) where the plural verb form is ma<strong>in</strong>ly due to the pl w<strong>in</strong>s strategy and less to the<br />

prox one. In particular, the greatest majority of consultants chose plural verb agreement<br />

<strong>in</strong> all 4 sentences whereas the s<strong>in</strong>gular occurs less often, followed by a few consultants<br />

who chose both forms <strong>in</strong> some sentences. More precisely, <strong>in</strong> sentence (109), 15 (out of 20)<br />

consultants chose a plural verb and 4 (out of 20) consultants chose a s<strong>in</strong>gular verb. Only 1<br />

(out of 20) consultant chose both a s<strong>in</strong>gular and a plural verb. In sentence (110), 13 (out<br />

of 20) consultants chose a plural verb, 5 (out of 20) consultants chose a s<strong>in</strong>gular verb and<br />

2 (out of 20) consultants chose both forms. In sentence (111), 16 (out of 20) consultants<br />

chose a plural verb, 4 (out of 20) consultants chose a s<strong>in</strong>gular verb and no consultant chose<br />

both forms. F<strong>in</strong>ally, <strong>in</strong> sentence (112), 15 (out of 20) consultants chose a plural verb, 3<br />

(out of 20) consultants chose a s<strong>in</strong>gular verb and 2 (out of 20) consultants chose both<br />

forms. Thus, <strong>in</strong> the above examples for those who chose only plural, the pl w<strong>in</strong>s strategy<br />

is stronger than the prox one. For those who chose a s<strong>in</strong>gular verb, the prox strategy is<br />

prefered, whereas for those who opted for both a s<strong>in</strong>gular and a plural verb form, both pl<br />

w<strong>in</strong>s and prox are <strong>in</strong> operation. Almost <strong>in</strong> all cases the consultants were consistent <strong>in</strong><br />

their responses choos<strong>in</strong>g the same form with a few exceptions. However, s<strong>in</strong>ce the majority<br />

chose a plural verb form pl w<strong>in</strong>s is the mostly preferred strategy even <strong>in</strong> nouns with the<br />

order [pl + sg]. The table below summarises the responses of the consultants:<br />

Table 6.8: Disjunction i<br />

Mixed Number <strong>Noun</strong>s<br />

Consultant Number: 20<br />

Conjunct Order Verb <strong>Agreement</strong> Form<br />

np.pl or np.sg s<strong>in</strong>gular plural s<strong>in</strong>g-pl/both<br />

(109) 4 15 1<br />

(110) 5 13 2<br />

(111) 4 16 -<br />

(112) 3 15 2<br />

The second test we carried out was to <strong>in</strong>clude a predicative adjective/participle that<br />

follows the coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase. As MG encodes gender agreement <strong>in</strong> the predicative adjective<br />

and not <strong>in</strong> the predicate itself, these examples would help us test whether the plural <strong>in</strong><br />

the verb is based on the pl w<strong>in</strong>s strategy or the prox one. The follow<strong>in</strong>g example consists<br />

of a s<strong>in</strong>gular mascul<strong>in</strong>e and a plural fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e disjunct:<br />

(113) O adelfos<br />

the.masc.sg brother.masc.sg<br />

<strong>in</strong>e taktopiimen-i/-es;<br />

are.pl settled.masc/fem.pl?<br />

i<br />

or<br />

i<br />

the.fem.pl<br />

adelfes<br />

sisters.fem.pl<br />

su<br />

your


6.4 Verb <strong>Agreement</strong> <strong>in</strong> MG Disjunctive Coord<strong>in</strong>ate <strong>Noun</strong>s 189<br />

‘Is/are your brother or your sisters settled?’<br />

(constructed)<br />

The results showed that more than half (13/20) of the native speakers chose the mascul<strong>in</strong>e<br />

plural form <strong>in</strong> the predicative adjective, which clearly <strong>in</strong>dicates that pl w<strong>in</strong>s is the ma<strong>in</strong><br />

strategy, whereas less than half (7/20) chose the fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e plural, which shows that prox<br />

is also chosen. In fact, the results were not much different than those of the first test.<br />

Also, when revers<strong>in</strong>g the order of the conjuncts, as <strong>in</strong> (114), 16 (out of 20) consultants still<br />

choose mascul<strong>in</strong>e plural <strong>in</strong> most cases apart from 4 (out of 20) consultants who chose the<br />

s<strong>in</strong>gular verb form as a result of closest conjunct agreement.<br />

(114) I adelfes<br />

the.fem.pl sisters.fem.pl<br />

<strong>in</strong>e taktopiimeni;<br />

are.pl settled.masc.pl?<br />

i<br />

or<br />

‘Is/are your brother or your sisters settled?’<br />

(constructed)<br />

o<br />

the.masc.sg<br />

adelfos<br />

brother.masc.sg<br />

su<br />

your<br />

The above tests show that <strong>in</strong> MG coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrases with a s<strong>in</strong>gular and a plural<br />

disjunct, two strategies are <strong>in</strong> operation pl w<strong>in</strong>s and prox. The plural verb form occurs<br />

consistently <strong>in</strong> [sg + pl] constructions but with lower frequency <strong>in</strong> [pl + sg] constructions<br />

where prox seems to take over partly. Therefore, the strategies that seem to be <strong>in</strong> operation<br />

<strong>in</strong> MG preverbal coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrases are pl w<strong>in</strong>s, followed by the prox one.<br />

Next, we need to check whether “first conjunct agreement” (fc w<strong>in</strong>s) (Peterson, 1986,<br />

239) or “distant conjunct agreement” (Corbett, 2001; Sadler, 2003) are used <strong>in</strong> MG disjunctive<br />

coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns. As seen above, coord<strong>in</strong>ate noun phrases with a noun order [sg<br />

+ pl] would never yield s<strong>in</strong>gular verb agreement. Therefore, a sentence like the one below<br />

is ungrammatical:<br />

(115) *O<br />

the.masc.sg<br />

exi dulia;<br />

has.sg job?<br />

adelfos<br />

brother.masc.sg<br />

i<br />

or<br />

i<br />

the.fem.pl<br />

‘Has/have your brother or your sisters got a job?’<br />

(constructed)<br />

adelfes<br />

sisters.fem.pl<br />

su<br />

your<br />

Further evidence that fc w<strong>in</strong>s is not a strategy adopted by MG native speakers <strong>in</strong> disjunctive<br />

conjo<strong>in</strong>ed nouns was drawn from sentences with a predicative adjective/participle<br />

where gender agreement is shown. The follow<strong>in</strong>g example <strong>in</strong>cludes a s<strong>in</strong>gular mascul<strong>in</strong>e<br />

and a plural fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e noun:<br />

(116) O pateras i i kores<br />

the.masc.sg father.masc.sg or the.fem.pl daughters.fem.pl<br />

<strong>in</strong>e ipefth<strong>in</strong>-i/-es<br />

ja t<strong>in</strong> eteria<br />

are.pl responsible.masc/fem.pl for the company<br />

‘The father or the daughters are responsible for the company’<br />

(constructed)<br />

As a result of fc w<strong>in</strong>s, we would expect a mascul<strong>in</strong>e s<strong>in</strong>gular agreement form <strong>in</strong> the<br />

adjective above. However, <strong>in</strong> example (116), 13 (out of 20) consultants resort to a plural<br />

verb form with a mascul<strong>in</strong>e plural predicative adjective, as a result of pl w<strong>in</strong>s and gender<br />

resolution, whereas 7 (out of 20) consultants choose fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e plural as a result of CCA.<br />

When revers<strong>in</strong>g the order of the disjuncts, an fc w<strong>in</strong>s strategy would admit a fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e<br />

plural adjective, but <strong>in</strong>stead the plural verb form and the mascul<strong>in</strong>e plural predicative


6.4 Verb <strong>Agreement</strong> <strong>in</strong> MG Disjunctive Coord<strong>in</strong>ate <strong>Noun</strong>s 190<br />

adjective occurs ma<strong>in</strong>ly <strong>in</strong> 16 (out of 20) consultants whereas a mascul<strong>in</strong>e s<strong>in</strong>gular adjective<br />

is chosen by 4 (out of 20) consultants as a second choice due to CCA:<br />

(117) I kores<br />

i o<br />

pateras<br />

the.fem.pl daughters.fem.pl or the.masc.sg father.masc.sg<br />

<strong>in</strong>e ipefth<strong>in</strong>-i/-os<br />

ja t<strong>in</strong> eteria<br />

are.pl responsible.masc.pl/masc.sg for the company<br />

‘The daughters or the father are responsible for the company’<br />

(constructed)<br />

Thus, it appears that there is not evidence to support the existence of an fc w<strong>in</strong>s or<br />

“distant conjunct agreement” strategy <strong>in</strong> MG. Also, the above analysis has not presented<br />

any evidence for the existence of a sg w<strong>in</strong>s (Peterson, 1986, 239) strategy, which seems to<br />

be nonexistent <strong>in</strong> MG coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns.<br />

Let us consider next disjunctive phrases with mixed number disjuncts <strong>in</strong> postverbal<br />

position. The data shows that <strong>in</strong> MG the different sentence structure does not give different<br />

results, still favour<strong>in</strong>g the pl w<strong>in</strong>s strategy more than the prox one. A relevant example<br />

is shown below:<br />

(118) Etimaz-onte ta agoria i to<br />

gett<strong>in</strong>g-prepared.pl the.pl boys.pl or the.sg<br />

ja tis eksetasis;<br />

for the exams?<br />

‘Are the boys or the girl gett<strong>in</strong>g prepared for the exams?’<br />

(constructed)<br />

koritsi<br />

girl.sg<br />

su<br />

your<br />

The results of the questionnaire showed that 20 (out of 20) consultants choose a plural<br />

verb. The plural choice is firstly motivated by the pl w<strong>in</strong>s strategy which seems to<br />

determ<strong>in</strong>e agreement patterns more widely when compared to the prox strategy. The<br />

second possibility is that the plural verb form is due to the existence of a plural disjunct<br />

close to the verb, referr<strong>in</strong>g to the prox strategy.<br />

In order to test aga<strong>in</strong> which strategies are <strong>in</strong>volved <strong>in</strong> postverbal coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns, we<br />

carried out similar tests as above. The reverse order of the conjuncts, as <strong>in</strong> example (119),<br />

will result <strong>in</strong> the choice of a plural verb <strong>in</strong> 11 (out of the 20) consultants <strong>in</strong> the sentences<br />

<strong>in</strong>cluded <strong>in</strong> the questionnaire, show<strong>in</strong>g that pl w<strong>in</strong>s is <strong>in</strong>deed a prevalent strategy. The<br />

prox strategy also ga<strong>in</strong>s some ground <strong>in</strong> verb-subject construction as is expected. In<br />

fact, a s<strong>in</strong>gular verb was chosen <strong>in</strong> all sentences by only one consultant, which is due to<br />

the prox strategy. 8 out of the 20 consultants chose a s<strong>in</strong>gular verb <strong>in</strong> 1 of the 2 sentences<br />

and a plural verb <strong>in</strong> the other sentence. The choice of either a s<strong>in</strong>gular or a plural verb is<br />

attributed to the prox or pl w<strong>in</strong>s strategies, respectively.<br />

(119) Etimaz-ete/-onte<br />

gett<strong>in</strong>g-prepared.sg/pl<br />

ja tis eksetasis;<br />

for the exams?<br />

to<br />

the.sg<br />

koritsi<br />

girl.sg<br />

i<br />

or<br />

ta<br />

the.pl<br />

‘Are/is the girl or the boys gett<strong>in</strong>g prepared for the exams?’<br />

(constructed)<br />

agoria<br />

boys.pl<br />

su<br />

your<br />

In conclusion, <strong>in</strong> postverbal coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrases with a [pl or sg] noun order the prevalent<br />

strategy is pl w<strong>in</strong>s s<strong>in</strong>ce the data analysis showed that most native speakers chose<br />

a plural verb. The prox strategy also seems to affect the result s<strong>in</strong>ce the plural noun is<br />

closest to the plural verb, lead<strong>in</strong>g to a 100% selection of the plural verb. In coord<strong>in</strong>ate<br />

phrases with a [sg or pl] disjunct order, consultants will select either a plural only verb


6.5 Issues on the MG positive & negative predisjunction-disjunction 191<br />

form exclusively, follow<strong>in</strong>g the pl w<strong>in</strong>s strategy, a plural or a s<strong>in</strong>gular verb, balanc<strong>in</strong>g<br />

the pl w<strong>in</strong>s with the prox one, and <strong>in</strong> other cases a s<strong>in</strong>gular verb, follow<strong>in</strong>g the prox<br />

strategy.<br />

The last th<strong>in</strong>g to note is that <strong>in</strong> postverbal coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrases with a plural and a<br />

s<strong>in</strong>gular disjunct the verb cannot be s<strong>in</strong>gular, as below:<br />

(120) *Etimaz-ete ta koritsia i to<br />

gett<strong>in</strong>g-prepared.sg the.pl girl.pl or the.sg<br />

ja tis eksetasis;<br />

for the exams?<br />

‘Are the girls or the boy gett<strong>in</strong>g prepared for the exams?’<br />

(constructed)<br />

agori<br />

boy.sg<br />

su<br />

your<br />

Thus, the possibility of “distant agreement” is not part of the MG agreement system.<br />

On the whole, the above analysis showed that <strong>in</strong> both preverbal and postverbal mixed<br />

number disjunctively coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns, MG native speakers consistently use two ma<strong>in</strong><br />

agreement strategies, pl w<strong>in</strong>s and prox. No evidence exists <strong>in</strong> MG for an fc w<strong>in</strong>s or a<br />

sg w<strong>in</strong>s strategy. In preverbal coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns, the prevalent strategy is pl w<strong>in</strong>s and<br />

this is followed by the prox one. In postverbal coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns, the pl w<strong>in</strong>s is still a<br />

strong strategy but prox seems to play a more active role.<br />

6.5 Issues on the MG positive & negative predisjunction-disjunction<br />

An important part of the literature <strong>in</strong> English concern<strong>in</strong>g disjunction has dealt with the<br />

claim that predisjunction and disjunction either...or behaves different from disjunction or<br />

(see Larson (1985); Morgan (1985); Peterson (1986)). This difference is reflected <strong>in</strong> verb<br />

agreement, which yields different agreement forms when the predisjunction-disjunction<br />

cooccur as opposed to bare disjunction. This section will focus on the presentation of MG<br />

data with the positive and negative predisjunction and disjunction ite...ite ‘either...or’ and<br />

oute...oute ‘neither...nor’, look<strong>in</strong>g at verb agreement.<br />

First, we will present the positive predisjunction and disjunction ite...ite. The results of<br />

the questionnaire, which <strong>in</strong>cluded sentences with the positive predisjunction and disjunction<br />

with disjuncts of the same or mixed number, gender and person, showed a few differences<br />

from the data which did not <strong>in</strong>clude the predisjunction. When the coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase<br />

consists of two s<strong>in</strong>gular disjuncts with the same gender and person, most consultants chose<br />

a s<strong>in</strong>gular verb and fewer consultants chose a plural verb. For <strong>in</strong>stance, <strong>in</strong> example (121),<br />

14 (out of 20) consultants used a s<strong>in</strong>gular verb and 6 (out of 20) used a plural verb, and<br />

<strong>in</strong> example (122), 16 (out of 20) consultants chose a s<strong>in</strong>gular verb and only 4 consultants<br />

chose a plural verb. F<strong>in</strong>ally, <strong>in</strong> example (123), 14 (out of 20) used a s<strong>in</strong>gular verb and 6<br />

(out of 20) used a plural verb. This choice also depends on the <strong>in</strong>terpretation of the phrase,<br />

which is likely to be <strong>in</strong>terpreted as an ‘exclusive’(‘or’) or. Both verb forms are illustrated<br />

<strong>in</strong> the follow<strong>in</strong>g example:<br />

(121) I o ijos i i pateras<br />

either the.sg son.sg or the.sg father.sg<br />

par-i/-un meros sto diagonismo<br />

take.sg/pl part <strong>in</strong>-the contest<br />

‘Either my son or my father will take part <strong>in</strong> the contest’<br />

(constructed)<br />

(122) I i<br />

either the.sg<br />

analav-i/-un<br />

take-over.sg/pl<br />

mitera i<br />

mother.sg or<br />

t<strong>in</strong> epimelia<br />

the custody<br />

i<br />

the.sg<br />

thia<br />

aunt.sg<br />

mu<br />

m<strong>in</strong>e<br />

tha<br />

will<br />

tha<br />

will


6.5 Issues on the MG positive & negative predisjunction-disjunction 192<br />

‘Either the mother or the aunt will take over the custody’<br />

(constructed)<br />

(123) I to agori i to koritsi<br />

either the.sg boy.sg or the.sg girl.sg<br />

ta simer<strong>in</strong>a provlimata<br />

the today problems<br />

‘Either the boy or the girl will face today’s problems’<br />

(constructed)<br />

tha<br />

will<br />

antimetopis-i/-un<br />

face.sg/pl<br />

The number of consultants who chose consistently s<strong>in</strong>gular verb agreement <strong>in</strong> data<br />

with the predisjunction and disjunction was more or less the same as <strong>in</strong> cases without the<br />

predisjunction. The table is shown below:<br />

Table 6.9: S<strong>in</strong>gular <strong>Noun</strong>s with Identical Gender & Number<br />

Consultant Number: 20<br />

Examples Verb <strong>Agreement</strong> Form/Interpretation of or<br />

s<strong>in</strong>gular/‘exclusive’ plural/‘<strong>in</strong>clusive’ s<strong>in</strong>g-pl/both<br />

(121) 14 6 -<br />

(122) 16 4 -<br />

(123) 14 6 -<br />

Cases of mixed gender and mixed person s<strong>in</strong>gular disjuncts with the predisjunction and<br />

disjunction display also similar results as coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrases without the predisjunction.<br />

In mixed gender disjuncts, with a mascul<strong>in</strong>e and a fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e noun, plural verb agreement is<br />

preferred if there is a predicative adjective/participle, whereas the s<strong>in</strong>gular and less often<br />

the plural agreement occur without a predicative adjective/participle. In examples (124)<br />

and (125), which have a predicative adjective, 14 (out of 20) consultants chose a plural verb,<br />

3 (out of 20) consultants chose a s<strong>in</strong>gular verb and 3 (out of 20) consultants chose both a<br />

s<strong>in</strong>gular and a plural verb. In examples (126) and (127), 9 (out of 20) consultants chose a<br />

s<strong>in</strong>gular verb, 3 (out of 20) consultants chose a plural verb and 8 (out of 20) consultants<br />

chose both a s<strong>in</strong>gular and a plural verb. The relevant examples are shown below:<br />

(124) I o<br />

pateras i i mitera<br />

either the.masc.sg father.masc.sg or the.fem.sg mother.fem.sg<br />

<strong>in</strong>e ipefth<strong>in</strong>-i/-i<br />

ja t<strong>in</strong> epimelia tu<br />

are.sg<br />

pediu<br />

child<br />

responsible.masc.pl/fem.sg for the custody of-the<br />

‘Either the father or the mother are responsible for the child’s custody’<br />

(constructed)<br />

(125) I o<br />

ijos i i<br />

either the.masc.sg son.masc.sg or the.fem.sg<br />

<strong>in</strong>e ikan-i/-i<br />

na dosun simvules<br />

are.sg able.masc.pl/fem.sg to give advise<br />

‘Either the son or the daughter are able to give any advise’<br />

(constructed)<br />

(126) I o adelfos i<br />

either the.sg brother.sg or<br />

peras-i/-un sto panepistimio<br />

enter.sg/pl the university<br />

i<br />

the.sg<br />

adelfi<br />

sister.sg<br />

kori<br />

daughter.fem.sg<br />

mu<br />

m<strong>in</strong>e<br />

tha<br />

will


6.5 Issues on the MG positive & negative predisjunction-disjunction 193<br />

‘Either my brother or my sister will enter the university’<br />

(constructed)<br />

(127) I o thios i i thia<br />

either the.sg uncle.sg or the.sg aunt.sg<br />

analav-i/-un to magazi<br />

take-over.sg/pl the shop<br />

‘Either my uncle or my aunt will take over the shop’<br />

(constructed)<br />

The table below summarises the patterns presented:<br />

mu<br />

m<strong>in</strong>e<br />

tha<br />

will<br />

Table 6.10: Predisjunction-Disjunction i...i<br />

S<strong>in</strong>gular Mixed Gender <strong>Noun</strong>s<br />

Consultant Number: 20<br />

Sentence Type Verb <strong>Agreement</strong> Form<br />

either np.sg or np.sg + verb s<strong>in</strong>gular plural s<strong>in</strong>g-pl/both<br />

(124) 3 14 3<br />

(125) 3 14 3<br />

either np.sg or np.sg + verb + pred.adj/part s<strong>in</strong>gular plural s<strong>in</strong>g-pl/both<br />

(126) 9 3 8<br />

(127) 9 3 8<br />

In mixed person disjunctive coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns with the predisjunction and disjunction,<br />

we also f<strong>in</strong>d similar patterns to the cases without the predisjunction. Thus, the plural verb<br />

agreement is favoured <strong>in</strong> declarative sentences, follow<strong>in</strong>g person hierarchy (Corbett, 1991).<br />

In all relevant examples, 16 (out of 20) consultants chose a plural verb form and 4 (out of<br />

20) consultants chose a s<strong>in</strong>gular verb. Some examples are shown below:<br />

(128) I<br />

either<br />

ego<br />

me.1.sg<br />

i<br />

or<br />

esi<br />

you.2.sg<br />

tha<br />

will<br />

‘Either me or you will take over the bus<strong>in</strong>ess’<br />

(constructed)<br />

(129) I esi i o pateras<br />

either<br />

xartia<br />

papers<br />

you.2.sg or the father.3.sg<br />

‘Either you or the father will sign the papers’<br />

(constructed)<br />

analavume<br />

take-over.1.pl<br />

tha<br />

will<br />

t<strong>in</strong><br />

the<br />

ipograpsete<br />

sign.2.pl<br />

epixirisi<br />

bus<strong>in</strong>ess<br />

Interrogative sentences with i...i disjunctively conjo<strong>in</strong>ed nouns <strong>in</strong> preverbal or <strong>in</strong> postverbal<br />

position show s<strong>in</strong>gular and less often plural verb agreement. In particular, <strong>in</strong> example<br />

(130), 11 (out of 20) consultants chose a s<strong>in</strong>gular verb form and 9 (out of 20) consultants<br />

chose a plural verb form. In example (131), 13 (out of 20) consultants chose a s<strong>in</strong>gular<br />

verb form and 7 (out of 20) consultants chose a plural verb form. The relevant examples<br />

are shown below:<br />

(130) I esi i i Maria ex-i/-ete<br />

either you.2.sg or the Maria.3.sg has.3.sg/-ve.3.pl<br />

efth<strong>in</strong>i ja t<strong>in</strong> dulia;<br />

responsibility for the job?<br />

‘Do either you or Maria have the responsibility for the job?’<br />

(constructed)<br />

ta<br />

the<br />

t<strong>in</strong><br />

the


6.5 Issues on the MG positive & negative predisjunction-disjunction 194<br />

(131) Exis i esi i i Maria<br />

have.2.sg either you.2.sg or the Maria.3.sg<br />

efth<strong>in</strong>i ja t<strong>in</strong> dulia;<br />

responsibility for the job?<br />

‘Do either you or Maria have the responsibility for the job?’<br />

(constructed)<br />

The results of mixed person s<strong>in</strong>gular disjuncts are illustrated below:<br />

t<strong>in</strong><br />

the<br />

Table 6.11: Predisjunction-Disjunction i...i<br />

S<strong>in</strong>gular Mixed Person <strong>Noun</strong>s<br />

Consultant Number: 20<br />

Affirmative Verb <strong>Agreement</strong> Form<br />

either np.sg or np.sg + verb. s<strong>in</strong>gular plural s<strong>in</strong>g-pl/both<br />

(128) 4 16 -<br />

(129) 4 16 -<br />

Interrogatives Verb <strong>Agreement</strong> Form<br />

either np.sg or np.sg verb? s<strong>in</strong>gular plural s<strong>in</strong>g-pl/both<br />

(130) 11 9 -<br />

verb either np.sg or np.sg?<br />

(131) 13 7 -<br />

On the whole, the positive predisjunction and disjunction yields almost similar results<br />

to bare disjunction i. A s<strong>in</strong>gular verb is preferable <strong>in</strong> s<strong>in</strong>gular disjuncts and a plural verb<br />

form comes as a second option, related to the <strong>in</strong>terpretation of the phrase. In mixed<br />

gender disjuncts, s<strong>in</strong>gular verb agreement is prefered over plural when no predicative adjective/participle<br />

is present otherwise a plural verb and a resolved gender occurs more often<br />

when a predicative adjective/participle is present. F<strong>in</strong>ally, mixed person disjuncts follow<br />

ma<strong>in</strong>ly resolution <strong>in</strong> declarative sentences and s<strong>in</strong>gular or CCA <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>terrogative sentences 25 .<br />

Disjunctively conjo<strong>in</strong>ed nouns with the negative disjunction oute...oute display a general<br />

preference towards a plural verb form and less often to a s<strong>in</strong>gular verb form irrespective of<br />

the sentence structure <strong>in</strong> which they occur. Parker (1983), who also discusses coord<strong>in</strong>ate<br />

nouns jo<strong>in</strong>ed with neither...nor, f<strong>in</strong>ds similar results <strong>in</strong> English and argues that there are<br />

pragmatic reasons towards this plural choice. He perceives positive or negative disjunctively<br />

conjo<strong>in</strong>ed nouns as def<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g a two-member set, which is divided differently <strong>in</strong> positive and<br />

negative disjunctions. In positive disjunctive phrases, positive disjunction divides the set<br />

<strong>in</strong>to two subsets, with a s<strong>in</strong>gle member each. In negative disjunctive phrases, negative<br />

disjunction divides the two-member set <strong>in</strong>to two subsets but one of the subsets conta<strong>in</strong>s<br />

two members and the other conta<strong>in</strong>s no members at all. This dist<strong>in</strong>ction expla<strong>in</strong>s the<br />

higher percentage of plural number <strong>in</strong> negative disjunction. This is illustrated as follows:<br />

(132) either X or Y = {X} - {Y}<br />

neither X nor Y = {XY} - {∅}<br />

(Parker, 1983, 15)<br />

The <strong>Greek</strong> consultants were given sentences with the negative predisjunction and disjunction<br />

conta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g s<strong>in</strong>gular disjuncts and mixed number disjuncts either of the same or<br />

mixed gender and person. When the disjuncts are both s<strong>in</strong>gular number with the same<br />

gender, 17 (out of 20) consultants chose a plural verb whereas only 3 (out of 20) consultants<br />

chose a s<strong>in</strong>gular form <strong>in</strong> both examples. Two characteristic examples are shown below:<br />

25 More elaborate research with a wider range of data and speakers’ judgements is required to draw more<br />

concrete conclusions.


6.5 Issues on the MG positive & negative predisjunction-disjunction 195<br />

(133) Ute to agori ute to<br />

neither the.neut.sg boy.neut.sg nor the<br />

<strong>in</strong>e etim-a/-o ja afti t<strong>in</strong><br />

are/is.pl/sg ready.neut.pl/sg for this the<br />

‘Neither the boy nor the girl are ready for this change’<br />

(constructed)<br />

koritsi<br />

girl.neut.sg<br />

metavoli<br />

change<br />

(134) Ute o pateras ute o ijos<br />

neither the.neut.sg father.neut.sg nor the son.neut.sg<br />

enekr<strong>in</strong>-e/-an t<strong>in</strong> agora tis eterias<br />

approved.pl/sg the.neut.sg purchase of-the company<br />

‘Neither the father nor the son approved the company purchase’<br />

(constructed)<br />

When the disjuncts are s<strong>in</strong>gular with mixed gender and there is no predicative adjective/participle<br />

then also most (17/20) participants chose a plural verb and only 3 (out of<br />

20) chose a s<strong>in</strong>gular verb <strong>in</strong> all examples. However, when there is a predicative adjective/participle<br />

then a plural verb is used exclusively (20/20) even by those who opted for<br />

a s<strong>in</strong>gular verb agreement when the predicative adjective/participle was not present. The<br />

follow<strong>in</strong>g examples <strong>in</strong>clude sentences with and without a predicative adjective/participle,<br />

respectively:<br />

(135) Ute o<br />

antras ute i<br />

neither the.masc.sg man.masc.sg nor the.fem.sg<br />

j<strong>in</strong>eka simvivaz-onte/-ete t<strong>in</strong> simer<strong>in</strong>i epoxi<br />

woman.fem.sg compromise.pl/sg <strong>in</strong> these days<br />

‘Neither the man nor the woman compromise nowadays’<br />

(constructed)<br />

(136) Ute o<br />

ijos ute i<br />

neither the.masc.sg son.masc.sg nor the.fem.sg<br />

kori<br />

apodex-onte/-ete to diazigio<br />

daughter.fem.sg accept.pl/sg the divorce<br />

‘Neither the son nor the daughter accept the divorce’<br />

(constructed)<br />

(137) Ute o<br />

pateras ute i<br />

neither the.masc.sg father.masc.sg nor the.fem.sg<br />

mitera <strong>in</strong>e xarumen-i me afti t<strong>in</strong><br />

mother.fem.sg are.pl happy.masc.pl with this the<br />

‘Neither the father nor the mother are happy with this situation’<br />

(constructed)<br />

katastasi<br />

situation<br />

(138) Ute o<br />

pelatis<br />

ute i<br />

neither the.masc.sg male-customer.masc.sg nor the.fem.sg<br />

pelatisa<br />

<strong>in</strong>e ikanopiimen-i me t<strong>in</strong> anodo<br />

female-customer.fem.sg are.pl satisfied.masc.pl with the rise<br />

stis times<br />

<strong>in</strong> prices<br />

‘Neither the male nor the female customer are satisfied with the rise <strong>in</strong> prices’<br />

(constructed)<br />

The table below summarises the patterns presented:


6.6 Analys<strong>in</strong>g Verb <strong>Agreement</strong> <strong>in</strong> Disjunctive Coord<strong>in</strong>ate <strong>Noun</strong>s 196<br />

Table 6.12: Negative Predisjunction-Disjunction ute...ute<br />

S<strong>in</strong>gular Uniform Gender <strong>Noun</strong>s<br />

Consultant Number: 20<br />

Sentence Type Verb <strong>Agreement</strong> Form<br />

neither np.sg nor np.sg + verb s<strong>in</strong>gular plural s<strong>in</strong>g-pl/both<br />

(133) 3 17 -<br />

(134) 3 17 -<br />

neither np.sg nornp.sg + verb s<strong>in</strong>gular plural s<strong>in</strong>g-pl/both<br />

(135) 3 17 -<br />

(136) 3 17 -<br />

neither np.sg nor np.sg + verb + pred.adj/part s<strong>in</strong>gular plural s<strong>in</strong>g-pl/both<br />

(137) - 20 -<br />

(138) - 20 -<br />

Disjuncts with the same number and different person yield similar results where the majority<br />

of consultants (17 out of 20) choose a plural verb and fewer consultants (3 out of<br />

20 consultants) choose a s<strong>in</strong>gular. Therefore, the plural verb form is used more often than<br />

the s<strong>in</strong>gular and the person hierarchy is strictly obeyed <strong>in</strong> the former case. Consider the<br />

follow<strong>in</strong>g example:<br />

(139) Ute<br />

neither<br />

esi<br />

you.2.sg<br />

ute<br />

nor<br />

aftos<br />

he.3.sg<br />

‘Neither you nor he will accept the offer’<br />

(constructed)<br />

(140) Ute<br />

neither<br />

esi<br />

you.2.sg<br />

ute<br />

nor<br />

‘Neither you nor I need help’<br />

(constructed)<br />

ego<br />

I.1.sg<br />

tha<br />

will<br />

xriazomaste<br />

need<br />

dextite<br />

accept.3.pl<br />

voithia<br />

help.2.pl<br />

t<strong>in</strong><br />

the<br />

prosfora<br />

offer<br />

From the above data, we conclude that <strong>in</strong> MG the negative predisjunction and disjunction<br />

generates ma<strong>in</strong>ly plural verb agreement. These results seem to be <strong>in</strong> accordance with<br />

Parker’s view that negative disjunction applies to both members of the coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase<br />

simultaneously and not selectively only to one of the disjuncts. This is <strong>in</strong>deed the case s<strong>in</strong>ce<br />

when attempt<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>in</strong>terpret the above examples <strong>in</strong> MG, the predisjunction will negate<br />

the first conjunct and the disjunction will simultaneously negate the second conjunct too<br />

and both conjuncts are perceived as members of the same set 26 .<br />

6.6 Analys<strong>in</strong>g Verb <strong>Agreement</strong> <strong>in</strong> Disjunctive Coord<strong>in</strong>ate <strong>Noun</strong>s<br />

We saw that there are different factors that determ<strong>in</strong>e verb agreement <strong>in</strong> disjunctive coord<strong>in</strong>ate<br />

nouns <strong>in</strong> MG, such as the <strong>in</strong>terpretation of the phrase, syntactic factors (i.e type of<br />

sentence, conjunct’s features, word order) and speaker’s specific strategies. In this section,<br />

we will propose an analysis of verb agreement with disjunctive nouns focus<strong>in</strong>g on the <strong>in</strong>terpretation<br />

of disjunction or as ‘and-coord<strong>in</strong>ate’ or as ‘exclusive-or’ (Flouraki and Kazana,<br />

2009) follow<strong>in</strong>g Eggert (2002).<br />

Eggert (2002) presents a proposal of verb agreement <strong>in</strong> disjunctive coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns,<br />

formulated with<strong>in</strong> DRT, assum<strong>in</strong>g a similar analysis to the DRT analysis of existentials.<br />

Follow<strong>in</strong>g W<strong>in</strong>ter (1997), who uses choice function to analyse existentials <strong>in</strong> model theoretic<br />

26 The above cases also require more elaborate research with a wider range of data and speakers’ personal<br />

op<strong>in</strong>ion <strong>in</strong> order to draw more concrete conclusions.


6.6 Analys<strong>in</strong>g Verb <strong>Agreement</strong> <strong>in</strong> Disjunctive Coord<strong>in</strong>ate <strong>Noun</strong>s 197<br />

semantics, Eggert (2002) treats disjunction not as <strong>in</strong>troduc<strong>in</strong>g a discourse referent but as<br />

a choice function where “the predicate comb<strong>in</strong>es directly with the function on the set that<br />

consists of discourse referents”(107) stand<strong>in</strong>g for the two nouns. A choice function is “a<br />

function f such that for any set A=∅, f(A)∈A” (107). Thus, “a choice function is a function<br />

from a set to a member of that set”(107). This means that if disjuncts are represented as<br />

a set then or as a choice function selects one of the two disjuncts. This is presented as<br />

follows:<br />

(141) CH = {f: for all A =∅, f(A)∈A}<br />

(Eggert, 2002, 110)<br />

Consider the follow<strong>in</strong>g example which is generally problematic for most analyses of or:<br />

(142) Grant is taller than Abigail or Gertrude<br />

(Eggert, 2002, 110)<br />

If one of the disjuncts is selected, mean<strong>in</strong>g that “for some choice function f Grant is taller<br />

than f{Gertrude, Abigail}”(Eggert, 2002, 112), the DRS is as <strong>in</strong> (143):<br />

(143)<br />

x,y,z,f<br />

grant(x)<br />

abigail(y)<br />

gertrude(z)<br />

Ch(f)<br />

taller(x, f{y,z})<br />

(Eggert, 2002, 111)<br />

This represents the potential read<strong>in</strong>g e.g. ‘Grant is taller than Abigail or Gertrude-I forget<br />

which’ which is also predicted by other analyses while the choice function is existentially<br />

closed.<br />

Also, as Jenn<strong>in</strong>gs (1994) suggests or acts <strong>in</strong> the same way as the free choice any <strong>in</strong> such<br />

examples. If all/any disjuncts are selected, which is a second possible read<strong>in</strong>g, mean<strong>in</strong>g<br />

that for “all choice functions f Grant is taller than f{Gertrude, Abigail}” (Eggert, 2002,<br />

112), the DRS is as <strong>in</strong> (144):<br />

(144)<br />

x,y,z<br />

grant(x)<br />

abigail(y)<br />

gertrude(z)<br />

f<br />

Ch(f)<br />

(Eggert, 2002, 111)<br />

→ taller(x, f{y,z})<br />

This represents the read<strong>in</strong>g e.g. ‘Grant is taller than Abigail or/and Gertrude’ while choice<br />

function is universally closed.<br />

Eggert (2002) argues that the ma<strong>in</strong> disadvantage of the above analysis is that or has<br />

an amount of polysemy 27 . Thus, he proposes a modification of the analysis of or as a<br />

choice function. To account for both distributive and collective read<strong>in</strong>gs and the various<br />

<strong>in</strong>terpretations of or <strong>in</strong> a wide range of data, Eggert (2002) assumes that or is a different<br />

type of function, a subset function. First, he assumes that the universe of discourse U<br />

27 A detailed presentation of the problems of the present analysis are <strong>in</strong> Eggert (2002, 113-126).


6.6 Analys<strong>in</strong>g Verb <strong>Agreement</strong> <strong>in</strong> Disjunctive Coord<strong>in</strong>ate <strong>Noun</strong>s 198<br />

does not conta<strong>in</strong> entities, but <strong>in</strong>dividuals, which he takes to be sets of entities E. If E is<br />

a set of entities, then U is generated by E and it is the powerset of E m<strong>in</strong>us the empty<br />

set (U=P(E)-∅). He takes U to be a primitive <strong>in</strong> the model, mean<strong>in</strong>g that most one-place<br />

predicates will be functions from members of U to truth 28 . Thus, the set of one place<br />

predicates P is the doma<strong>in</strong> for terms of type 〈e,t〉 s<strong>in</strong>ce U is the doma<strong>in</strong> for terms of type<br />

〈e〉 (Eggert, 2002, 115).<br />

Follow<strong>in</strong>g Schwarzschild (1996), Eggert (2002) assumes that <strong>in</strong>dividuals (not entities)<br />

are assigned a contextually determ<strong>in</strong>ed partition on the universe of discourse <strong>in</strong> which case<br />

the relationship between arguments and predicates is not set-membership but a subset one<br />

(118). Schwarzschild (1996) suggests that the different read<strong>in</strong>gs found <strong>in</strong> a sentence (i.e.<br />

collective and distributive read<strong>in</strong>gs) are not necessarily associated to different semantic<br />

forms. Instead, he suggests that the semantics is the same for both read<strong>in</strong>gs, but the<br />

perceived difference <strong>in</strong> mean<strong>in</strong>gs comes from a contextually determ<strong>in</strong>ed variable, a partition<br />

on the universe of discourse. Follow<strong>in</strong>g Schwarzschild (1996), Eggert (2002) <strong>in</strong>troduces the<br />

follow<strong>in</strong>g relation <strong>in</strong> the DRS “for any relation r and any x,y∈U, then r(x,y) means that<br />

for some conc (i.e. union or comb<strong>in</strong>ation) of x with y,conc(x,y)⊆r” (Eggert, 2002, 132).<br />

To achieve the above assumptions, he argues that or is a subset function, mean<strong>in</strong>g that for<br />

any “non-empty set A, f(A) is a non-empty subset of A” (Eggert, 2002, 132), stated below:<br />

(145) SUB = {f: (∀ X: X = ∅) (f(X) ⊆ X ∧ f(X)= ∅)}<br />

(Eggert, 2002, 133)<br />

Eggert (2002) presents example (146), which is <strong>in</strong>terpreted <strong>in</strong> two different ways i)<br />

either Abigail notified all four, or Grant did; ii) Abigail notifie some of the four and Grant<br />

notified the rest. S<strong>in</strong>ce notify is taken to be a relation, Eggert (2002) <strong>in</strong>troduces a condition<br />

<strong>in</strong> the DRS which says ‘notify(x,y)’. Then, there must be a concatenation conc whereby<br />

conc(〚x 〛,〚y 〛)⊆〚notify〛. The possible concatenations are limited by the partitions on x<br />

and y. Tak<strong>in</strong>g y to denote the set {gertrude,jakob,beatrice,sukie}, there are three possible<br />

denotations <strong>in</strong> the present example.<br />

(146) Abigail or Grant notified Gertrude, Jacob, Beatrice, and Sukie<br />

(Eggert, 2002, 132)<br />

The DRS for the above example is the follow<strong>in</strong>g based on the present analysis:<br />

(147)<br />

t,u,v,w,x,y,f<br />

abigail(t)<br />

grant(u)<br />

gertrude(v)<br />

beatrice(w)<br />

jakob(x)<br />

sukie(y)<br />

SUB(f)<br />

notify(∪f{t,u},∪{v,w,x,y})<br />

(Eggert, 2002, 133)<br />

The possible denotations are the follow<strong>in</strong>g:<br />

(148) ∪f{t,u}: {{abigail}}, {{grant}} or {{abigail,grant}}<br />

(Eggert, 2002, 133)<br />

There are three possible denotations for example (146). If the denotation is {abigail} then<br />

the f<strong>in</strong>al condition states that for some concatenation conc:<br />

28 See Eggert (2002, 115-116, 141-147) for the two DRSs and for more details of the model he assumes.


6.6 Analys<strong>in</strong>g Verb <strong>Agreement</strong> <strong>in</strong> Disjunctive Coord<strong>in</strong>ate <strong>Noun</strong>s 199<br />

(149) conc({{abigail}},{{gertrude},{jakob},{beatrice},{sukie}}) ⊆ 〚notify〛<br />

(Eggert, 2002, 133)<br />

In fact, there is only one possible concatenation: {,,<br />

,}. For the case where the denotation is {grant},<br />

we substitute ‘abigail’ for ‘grant’ <strong>in</strong> the above formula. F<strong>in</strong>ally, if the denotation is<br />

{abigail,grant}, there are possible concatenation such as {,<br />

,,}. Accord<strong>in</strong>g to Eggert (2002),<br />

we cannot get concatenations <strong>in</strong> which {abigail,grant} is a member of an ordered pair.<br />

Also, a second example is the one <strong>in</strong> (150) repeated below, which is a problematic case<br />

for most analyses.<br />

(150) Grant is taller than Abigail or Gertrude<br />

(Eggert, 2002, 110)<br />

A s<strong>in</strong>gle DRS is proposed as <strong>in</strong> (151), which corresponds to two possible denotations.<br />

(151)<br />

x,y,z,f<br />

grant(x)<br />

abigail(y)<br />

gertrude(z)<br />

SUB(f)<br />

taller(x,∪f{y,z})<br />

(Eggert, 2002, 135)<br />

Each <strong>in</strong>terpretation depends on the assignment of f{y,z} which is as follows:<br />

(152) ∪f{y,z}: {{abigail}}, {{gertrude}} or {{abigail}, {gertrude}}<br />

(Eggert, 2002, 135)<br />

One possible <strong>in</strong>terpretation is ‘Grant is taller than Abigail or Grant is taller than Gertrude’.<br />

This read<strong>in</strong>g follows if we assume 〚f{y,z}〛={{abigail}}, which is possible s<strong>in</strong>ce {{abigail}}⊆<br />

{{abigail}, {gertrude}} or 〚f{y,z}〛={{gertrude}}, which is also possible s<strong>in</strong>ce {{gertrude}}⊆<br />

{{abigail}, {gertrude}} then two possibilities alternate:<br />

(153) conc({{grant}},{{abigail}})⊆ 〚taller〛or<br />

conc({{grant}},{{gertrude}})⊆ 〚taller〛<br />

(Eggert, 2002, 136)<br />

A second possible <strong>in</strong>terpretation, which is the preferred one <strong>in</strong> this type of example,<br />

is ‘Grant is taller than Abigail, and Grant is taller than Gertrude’ which follows<br />

if we assume 〚f({y,z})〛={{abigail},{gertrude}}. This is a possibility s<strong>in</strong>ce {{abigail},<br />

{gertrude}}⊆{{abigail},{gertrude}}. In this case the concatenation is as follows:<br />

(154) conc {, }⊆〚taller〛<br />

(Eggert, 2002, 136)<br />

The above analysis poses a s<strong>in</strong>gle DRS and determ<strong>in</strong>es semantically the different <strong>in</strong>terpretations<br />

found <strong>in</strong> disjunctively coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns, assum<strong>in</strong>g that disjunction is a subset<br />

function of disjuncts.<br />

Our aim is to formalise the above concept <strong>in</strong> λ-DRT and Glue Semantics follow<strong>in</strong>g<br />

Dalrymple (2001) and Kokkonidis (2005)(Flouraki and Kazana, 2009). Let us consider the<br />

follow<strong>in</strong>g simple example <strong>in</strong> English which shows either s<strong>in</strong>gular or plural verb agreement<br />

depend<strong>in</strong>g on the <strong>in</strong>terpretation. The sentence is <strong>in</strong>terpreted as only one of the two is<br />

w<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g the race (‘exclusive’ <strong>in</strong>terpretation) or out of a group of two <strong>in</strong>dividuals one of<br />

them is w<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g (‘and-coord<strong>in</strong>ate’ <strong>in</strong>terpretation):


6.6 Analys<strong>in</strong>g Verb <strong>Agreement</strong> <strong>in</strong> Disjunctive Coord<strong>in</strong>ate <strong>Noun</strong>s 200<br />

(155) Jane or Mary is/are w<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g.<br />

First, we will <strong>in</strong>troduce the lexical entries of the sentence above. Follow<strong>in</strong>g Kokkonidis<br />

(2005), we propose that each word conta<strong>in</strong>s <strong>in</strong>formation concern<strong>in</strong>g its syntactic specification,<br />

its compositional specification and its semantic specification. The first l<strong>in</strong>e of a lexical<br />

entry will give the syntactic category of the word and the f-structure constra<strong>in</strong>ts it comes<br />

with. The second l<strong>in</strong>e will conta<strong>in</strong> a mean<strong>in</strong>g placeholder (which is the word itself) and its<br />

compostional (Glue) type. This functions as the <strong>in</strong>terface between syntax and semantics<br />

with respect to semantic composition s<strong>in</strong>ce words have a semantic content. The third l<strong>in</strong>e<br />

of each of the lexical entries <strong>in</strong>troduces the mean<strong>in</strong>g of the word expressed <strong>in</strong> λ-DRT.<br />

Let us start with the word or. We will assume the standard mean<strong>in</strong>g constructor for or<br />

as proposed for [g-and] <strong>in</strong> Dalrymple (2001). Thus, we assume that the arguments of [or]<br />

are of type e, the type of <strong>in</strong>dividuals, and or is represented with the complex type e → (e<br />

→ e) s<strong>in</strong>ce it jo<strong>in</strong>s <strong>in</strong>dividuals. We also use the notation (↑∈)subj (Kokkonidis, 2005) for the<br />

two disjuncts s<strong>in</strong>ce both are syntactically subjects and members of the whole coord<strong>in</strong>ate<br />

phrase, which is the subject of the predicate. The lexical entry for disjunction or is the<br />

follow<strong>in</strong>g:<br />

(156) (↑conj)= ‘or’<br />

or: e (↑∈)subj ⊸ [e (↑∈)subj ⊸ e↑subj]<br />

Follow<strong>in</strong>g Eggert (2002), we treat or as a subset function, which ranges over a set of<br />

disjuncts, and the set of disjuncts is the concatenation of the members of the set while we<br />

assume that or does not <strong>in</strong>troduce a discourse referent. Thus, the mean<strong>in</strong>g assignment for<br />

or will be captured <strong>in</strong> λ-DRT as follows:<br />

(157)<br />

λx.λy<br />

f<br />

SUB(f)<br />

∪f{x,y}<br />

⊔ y ⊔ x<br />

The complete lexical entry with the syntactic representation and mean<strong>in</strong>g assignment<br />

is as follows:<br />

(158) or Conj (↑conj)= ‘or’<br />

or: e (↑∈)subj ⊸ [e (↑∈)subj ⊸ e↑subj]<br />

λx.λy<br />

f<br />

SUB(f)<br />

∪f{x,y}<br />

⊔ y ⊔ x<br />

The lexical entries for the nouns are also of type e and their lexical entries with the<br />

syntactic representation, mean<strong>in</strong>g constructors and mean<strong>in</strong>g assignment are as follows:<br />

(159) Jane PN (↑pred)= ‘Jane’<br />

Jane: e (↑∈)subj<br />

(160) Mary PN (↑pred)= ‘Mary’<br />

Mary: e (↑∈)subj<br />

λx. Jane(x)<br />

λy. Mary(y)


6.6 Analys<strong>in</strong>g Verb <strong>Agreement</strong> <strong>in</strong> Disjunctive Coord<strong>in</strong>ate <strong>Noun</strong>s 201<br />

The verbal one-place predicate is of type e → t, represented as follows:<br />

(161) w<strong>in</strong> V (↑pred)= ‘w<strong>in</strong>’<br />

w<strong>in</strong>: e (↑SUBJ) ⊸ t↑<br />

λx ′ . w<strong>in</strong>(x ′ )<br />

To derive the DRS for the whole sentence, we need to do the union of the <strong>in</strong>dividual<br />

DRSs. The process that follows shows how the DRSs are united to derive the coord<strong>in</strong>ate<br />

phrase first and then the whole sentence.<br />

First, we start with the coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase. If we do the union of or with Jane, we get<br />

the result shown below:<br />

(162)<br />

λy.<br />

f<br />

SUB(f)<br />

∪f{x,y}<br />

⊔ y ⊔<br />

x<br />

Jane(x)<br />

The above DRS corresponds to the compositional glue type e (↑∈)subj ⊸ e↑subj s<strong>in</strong>ce only<br />

one of the two semantic resources was found and it was consumed.<br />

If we do the union of or Jane with Mary we get the follow<strong>in</strong>g result:<br />

(163)<br />

f<br />

SUB(f)<br />

∪f{x,y}<br />

⊔<br />

y<br />

Mary(y) ⊔<br />

x<br />

Jane(x)<br />

In the glue part, the second semantic resource was found and it was also consumed. Thus,<br />

the DRS above corresponds to the compositional glue type e↑subj.<br />

If we do the DRS unions, we get the follow<strong>in</strong>g DRS for the disjunctive coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase<br />

which is of type e↑subj → t:<br />

(164)<br />

x,y,f<br />

Jane(x)<br />

Mary(y)<br />

SUB(f)<br />

∪f{x,y}<br />

Next we need to apply the verb w<strong>in</strong> to the disjunctive coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase to get the desired<br />

result for the whole sentence:<br />

(165)<br />

x,y,f<br />

Jane(x)<br />

Mary(y)<br />

SUB(f)<br />

w<strong>in</strong>(∪f{x,y})<br />

The above DRS represents the whole coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase which is of type t.<br />

The current approach uses λ-DRT <strong>in</strong> comb<strong>in</strong>ation with glue semantics and accounts<br />

for a simple disjunctive phrase which results <strong>in</strong> s<strong>in</strong>gular or plural verb agreement based<br />

on whether one or both disjuncts are selected. It exclusively focuses on verb agreement


6.7 Conclusion 202<br />

motivated by the <strong>in</strong>terpretation of disjunctively conjo<strong>in</strong>ed nouns. It is a rather simple<br />

analysis based on the central notions proposed by Eggert (2002), such as the assumption<br />

that arguments are treated as <strong>in</strong>dividuals assigned a contextually determ<strong>in</strong>ed partition<br />

and that or is a subset function, while it is able to account contextually for both the<br />

distributive and collective read<strong>in</strong>g of a disjunctive coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase. Also, it borrows<br />

from Kokkonidis (2005), who comb<strong>in</strong>es λ-DRT with glue semantics, lead<strong>in</strong>g to a simple<br />

modular design without chang<strong>in</strong>g the basic concepts <strong>in</strong> the glue part and allow<strong>in</strong>g the<br />

syntactic <strong>in</strong>formation to be imported <strong>in</strong>to the mean<strong>in</strong>g representation language. Further<br />

work is required to account for disjunctive phrases with more than two disjuncts while<br />

more research is needed to <strong>in</strong>clude more complicated types than s<strong>in</strong>gle <strong>in</strong>dividuals and tie<br />

it up with syntax <strong>in</strong> due course (i.e. <strong>in</strong>dex agreement etc.).<br />

6.7 Conclusion<br />

The above prelim<strong>in</strong>ary proposal captures effectively verb agreement variation which depends<br />

on <strong>in</strong>terpretational factors. However, the data showed that verb agreement with<br />

MG disjunctive conjo<strong>in</strong>ed nouns is rather complicated simply because there are many factors<br />

<strong>in</strong>volved when speakers choose the agree<strong>in</strong>g number of the verb.<br />

Apart from the <strong>in</strong>terpretational factor, verb agreement with MG disjunctive conjo<strong>in</strong>ed<br />

nouns is determ<strong>in</strong>ed by syntactic factors and speaker’s <strong>in</strong>dividual strategies. Thus, these<br />

factors should be considered <strong>in</strong> the analysis of verb agreement with disjunctive nouns.<br />

So far even the most <strong>in</strong>termodular and flexible theoretical framework would encounter<br />

difficulties <strong>in</strong> try<strong>in</strong>g to capture the MG data. Eggert’s analysis can cover issues of syntax,<br />

semantics and pragmatics. Despite its flexibility, though, it would still face problems<br />

<strong>in</strong> account<strong>in</strong>g for number verb agreement <strong>in</strong> MG. First, it cannot predict patterns when<br />

disjuncts have different agreement features or when the structure of the sentence is different<br />

(i.e. presence or absence of a predicative adjective/participle). Also, it cannot expla<strong>in</strong><br />

when verb agreement variation depends on the type of the sentence (i.e. declarative or<br />

<strong>in</strong>terrogative) or on the subject position (i.e. preverbal or postverbal subjects).<br />

Similarly, Morgan’s analysis acknowledges that syntax, semantics and pragmatics are<br />

<strong>in</strong>volved <strong>in</strong> verb agreement with disjunctively conjo<strong>in</strong>ed nouns. Still, though, his analysis<br />

cannot expla<strong>in</strong> any of the agreement patterns <strong>in</strong> MG where verb agreement is related to<br />

differences <strong>in</strong> the agreement features of the two conjuncts, <strong>in</strong> the structure of the sentences<br />

such as the presence or absence of a predicative adjective, <strong>in</strong> the type of sentence, (i.e.<br />

declarative or <strong>in</strong>terrogative) and <strong>in</strong> the subject position. Also, Peterson’s “patch-up rules”<br />

cover a wide range of data <strong>in</strong> English and account for various patterns <strong>in</strong> MG such as CCA<br />

and when verb agreement partly depends on the type of the sentences (i.e. declarative or<br />

<strong>in</strong>terrogative). They still encounter problems, though, with cases <strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>g the <strong>in</strong>ternal<br />

structure of the sentence or cases related to the <strong>in</strong>terpretation. Hence, verb agreement<br />

with disjunctive conjo<strong>in</strong>ed nouns is complicated and it may <strong>in</strong>volve various factors rang<strong>in</strong>g<br />

from syntactic to semantic and pragmatic.<br />

Our proposal, on the other hand, does not consider any other factors apart from the<br />

pragmatic one and would face difficulties when verb agreement is determ<strong>in</strong>ed by purely<br />

syntactic factors or the different <strong>in</strong>dividual strategies chosen by native speakers. However,<br />

we believe that <strong>in</strong> MG the <strong>in</strong>terpretation of the disjunctive noun phrase is significant <strong>in</strong> determ<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g<br />

verb agreement and our analysis captures effectively the variation <strong>in</strong> the agree<strong>in</strong>g<br />

verb which arises <strong>in</strong> a wide range of data. We acknowledge, though, that a more complete<br />

analysis is requred for the complicated phenomenon of verb agreement <strong>in</strong> disjunctive coord<strong>in</strong>ate<br />

nouns. In particular, we showed that number verb agreement with MG disjunctive<br />

conjo<strong>in</strong>ed nouns is determ<strong>in</strong>ed by multiple different factors. Firstly, the preference of the<br />

MG native speakers towards a resolved verb form <strong>in</strong> mixed gender conjuncts of declarative


6.7 Conclusion 203<br />

sentences and the choice of the closest conjunct agreement form <strong>in</strong> mixed gender conjuncts<br />

of preverbal or postverbal subject <strong>in</strong>terrogative sentences is certanly directly related to notions<br />

of l<strong>in</strong>earity <strong>in</strong> word order and prosodic factors. Also, the different strategies adopted<br />

by native speakers <strong>in</strong> verb agreement determ<strong>in</strong>ed by the <strong>in</strong>ternal agreement features of<br />

the conjuncts and their position <strong>in</strong> the coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrase are also cases that should be<br />

syntactically treated. F<strong>in</strong>ally, the specific type of each sentence which appears with or<br />

without a predicative adjective/participle is directly related to syntactic issues s<strong>in</strong>ce it is<br />

the presence or absence of the target that becomes apparent to the native speakers and<br />

leads to the choice of either a s<strong>in</strong>gular or a plural verb agreement form. Therefore, these<br />

issues should be seriously considered when attempt<strong>in</strong>g to analyse disjunctively conjo<strong>in</strong>ed<br />

noun phrases <strong>in</strong> MG and <strong>in</strong> other languages.<br />

To conclude, MG verb agreement <strong>in</strong> disjunctive coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns turns out to be even<br />

more complicated than verb agreement <strong>in</strong> conjunctive coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns. The factors that<br />

seem to lead to a specific verb agreement form are related to syntax, semantics, pragmatics<br />

or discourse factors and even prosodic factors <strong>in</strong> some cases. Our analysis focuses only on<br />

the discourse conditions, even though it would be favourable to seek a theory that would<br />

<strong>in</strong>volve all these issues. A lot of work needs to be done towards that direction <strong>in</strong> order to<br />

provide an account consider<strong>in</strong>g all the factors that are <strong>in</strong>volved <strong>in</strong> verb agreement.


Chapter 7<br />

Conclud<strong>in</strong>g Remarks<br />

The aim of the thesis was to make a contribution to the l<strong>in</strong>guistic area of agreement <strong>in</strong> noun<br />

phrase coord<strong>in</strong>ate constructions <strong>in</strong> MG. The discussion was couched with<strong>in</strong> the framework<br />

of Lexical-Functional Grammar.<br />

In agreement <strong>in</strong> MG predicate-argument relations, our ma<strong>in</strong> focus was the gender<br />

feature. We argued that gender resolution <strong>in</strong> MG is not only determ<strong>in</strong>ed by syntactic<br />

and semantic resolution but also by a third pr<strong>in</strong>ciple, which we refered to as the referential<br />

pr<strong>in</strong>ciple. MG <strong>in</strong>animate nouns follow syntactic resolution also found <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>animates<br />

of other languages. MG animate nouns follow the semantic resolution pr<strong>in</strong>ciple. A number<br />

of exceptional patterns are also found <strong>in</strong> both animate and <strong>in</strong>animate nouns which<br />

follow the referential pr<strong>in</strong>ciple. This pr<strong>in</strong>ciple is determ<strong>in</strong>ed by a Contextually Introduced<br />

Referent (CIR), which functions as a superord<strong>in</strong>ate term of the two conjuncts and whose<br />

agreement features are <strong>in</strong>herited by the predicative adjective/participle. Thus, the gender<br />

(and number) of the predicative adjective/participle is derived contextually. To account<br />

for the syntactic and semantic patterns, we proposed an analysis us<strong>in</strong>g the set-based approach,<br />

which comb<strong>in</strong>es the syntactic and semantic resolution. Concern<strong>in</strong>g the referential<br />

agreement, we proposed an analysis based on the formalism of LFG. Also, we proposed an<br />

ontological hierarchy which captures the semantic relation of the coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns with<br />

the hypernymic term. This seems to expla<strong>in</strong> the different gender of the predicative adjective/participle<br />

from the <strong>in</strong>dividual conjuncts <strong>in</strong> referential agreement.<br />

In agreement <strong>in</strong> MG head-modifier relations, we focused on the number and gender<br />

features. We exam<strong>in</strong>ed MG modifiers and the MG def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er and we showed<br />

that they behave different. Follow<strong>in</strong>g the three agreement systems proposed by K<strong>in</strong>g and<br />

Dalrymple (2004), we argued that MG modifiers agree <strong>in</strong> number with both nouns and<br />

<strong>in</strong> gender with the closest conjunct. Thus, modifiers follow the concord system which<br />

allows a shared modifier to scope over coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns and occurs with a jo<strong>in</strong>t and a<br />

split <strong>in</strong>terpretation. On the other hand, the MG def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er agrees <strong>in</strong> number<br />

and gender with both conjuncts. The MG shared determ<strong>in</strong>er follows the <strong>in</strong>dex/concord<br />

system and occurs with the jo<strong>in</strong>t read<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> both s<strong>in</strong>gular and plural number when it scopes<br />

over coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns. A second important f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g is that there are some exceptional<br />

patterns when a shared def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er scopes over coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns and admits a split<br />

<strong>in</strong>terpretation. These patterns occur only when the conjuncts are a natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation.<br />

For the MG natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation patterns, the special f-structure for naturally coord<strong>in</strong>ate<br />

nouns proposed <strong>in</strong> Dalrymple and Nikolaeva (2006) cannot provide an adequate account<br />

so we assumed the standard f-structure of accidentally coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns where conjuncts<br />

are members of a set and the concord and <strong>in</strong>dex features do not match. Thus, the<br />

concord/<strong>in</strong>dex system effectively accounts for these patterns too.<br />

F<strong>in</strong>ally, <strong>in</strong> verb agreement with disjunctive coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns our ma<strong>in</strong> focus was number.<br />

We argued that number verb agreement variation <strong>in</strong> MG depends on the <strong>in</strong>terpre-


205<br />

tation of disjunction as an ‘and-coord<strong>in</strong>ate’ or as an ‘exclusive’ or. Hence, we proposed an<br />

analysis of verb agreement <strong>in</strong> λ-DRT, a discourse model comb<strong>in</strong>ed with λ-calculus, follow<strong>in</strong>g<br />

Eggert (2002) who treats or as a subset function. This analysis captures the patterns<br />

<strong>in</strong> question but it needs further improvements to extend to more complicated disjunctive<br />

coord<strong>in</strong>ate phrases. However, we argued that verb agreement <strong>in</strong> MG disjunctive coord<strong>in</strong>ate<br />

nouns is the result of the effect of other factors too, such as the <strong>in</strong>ternal structure of<br />

a sentence or the type of sentence, the different features of the conjuncts and f<strong>in</strong>ally the<br />

subject position. Thus, more research is required to provide a solution that will <strong>in</strong>volve all<br />

these factors.<br />

There are, however, some rema<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g issues for further research that we need to outl<strong>in</strong>e.<br />

First, it is the status of the r-structure <strong>in</strong> referential agreement <strong>in</strong> predicate-argument<br />

relations. We showed that LFG accounts for these patterns by <strong>in</strong>troduc<strong>in</strong>g a specific lexical<br />

entry where the predicative adjective agrees syntactically with the noun that is present <strong>in</strong><br />

the phrase or referentially with the Contextually Introduced Referent, which occurs only at<br />

the contextual level and not at the syntactic level. The r-structure of the CIR, which occurs<br />

at the contextual level, has a syntactic representation s<strong>in</strong>ce the syntactic features of the<br />

CIR are required to be copied by the predicative adjective/participle and this might be a<br />

shortcom<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> our analysis. Thus, further work needs to be done towards the structure of<br />

this extra level that relates to context. A second important issue is the ontological relation<br />

between the CIR and the two coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns. The CIR is the superord<strong>in</strong>ate term and<br />

the coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns are the hyponyms. In order to capture this relation, we used an<br />

ontological hierarchy, based on an ontological approach. An important question is whether<br />

the <strong>in</strong>formation of the CIR and its relation to the conjuncts can be captured at a different<br />

level with<strong>in</strong> LFG, which is a more abstract level. It could be possible, however, that LFG<br />

does not have the adequate mechanisms to provide such k<strong>in</strong>d of abstract <strong>in</strong>formation like<br />

other theoretical frameworks. These issues need more work and are directly related to the<br />

<strong>in</strong>ternal structure of the framework of LFG.<br />

Second, <strong>in</strong> head-modifier agreement <strong>in</strong> MG coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns, we showed that the MG<br />

def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er is syntactically captured by the <strong>in</strong>dex/concord system. The MG<br />

def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er imposes a further semantic restriction concern<strong>in</strong>g the <strong>in</strong>terpretation<br />

of a shared def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er when it scopes over coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns. In particular, we<br />

showed that the jo<strong>in</strong>t <strong>in</strong>terpretation occurs <strong>in</strong> s<strong>in</strong>gular and plural accidentally coord<strong>in</strong>ate<br />

nouns but the split <strong>in</strong>terpretation occurs only <strong>in</strong> plural naturally coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns. Thus,<br />

despite the fact that the <strong>in</strong>dex/concord system accounts for the MG def<strong>in</strong>ite determ<strong>in</strong>er,<br />

the latter imposes further specifications that are related to the field of semantics. S<strong>in</strong>ce<br />

semantics is not the area of exam<strong>in</strong>ations these may be <strong>in</strong>vestigated <strong>in</strong> the future. A<br />

second important issue is that <strong>in</strong> MG natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation cases the two nouns cooccur<br />

under specific semantic conditions s<strong>in</strong>ce they need to be semantically related. In LFG, this<br />

type of relation is not expressed <strong>in</strong> the analysis of natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation, but s<strong>in</strong>ce it plays a<br />

significant role <strong>in</strong> natural coord<strong>in</strong>ation patterns of some languages it should be given some<br />

attention. Nevertheless, it requires further work s<strong>in</strong>ce it <strong>in</strong>volves the <strong>in</strong>ternal structure of<br />

the framework itself.<br />

F<strong>in</strong>ally, the proposal <strong>in</strong> verb agreement with disjunctive coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns captures the<br />

<strong>in</strong>terpretation of or as ‘and-coord<strong>in</strong>ate’ and as ‘exclusive-or’ and allows both a s<strong>in</strong>gular or<br />

a plural verb agreement form. However, it is a prelim<strong>in</strong>ary analysis focus<strong>in</strong>g on <strong>in</strong>dividuals<br />

of type e only and we need to work further on its modification so as to extend to other<br />

types of disjunctive phrases, such as quantified coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns or verb phrases. Also, we<br />

saw that other factors are <strong>in</strong>volved <strong>in</strong> disjunctive coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns which probably need<br />

to be <strong>in</strong>corporated <strong>in</strong>to the analysis of disjunctively coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns. Hence, the analysis<br />

provided so far needs to be extended <strong>in</strong> order to overcome the above problems and to cover<br />

a wider range of data <strong>in</strong> other languages which may have similar behaviour. These issues


will be left for future research.<br />

206


Appendix A<br />

Questionnaires on Predicate<br />

Argument <strong>Agreement</strong><br />

A.1 Discussion of questionnnaires<br />

The data analysis was based on four different questionnaires that were developed <strong>in</strong> order<br />

to test the gender resolution <strong>in</strong> the same gender or mixed gender animate and <strong>in</strong>animate<br />

coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns. The method used to draw the results of the gender values <strong>in</strong> both<br />

groups of nouns is based on the responses of 26 <strong>Greek</strong> native speakers who answered the<br />

four different questionnaires. The participants are all university graduates from North and<br />

South Greece. The different geographical orig<strong>in</strong>s of the participants did not play any active<br />

role. The questionnaires appeared <strong>in</strong> different forms such as ‘multiple choice’ and ‘fill <strong>in</strong><br />

the gap’. The consultants filled <strong>in</strong> the questionnaires based on the choice of the form they<br />

found most appropriate. They were also asked to choose a second possibility if they found<br />

it acceptable.<br />

Some issues need to be discussed regard<strong>in</strong>g questions that were raised about the questionnaires<br />

and how we approached these. The first issue is the type of the questionnaire<br />

that would be given to the participants. We decided to issue four different questionnaires;<br />

the first three appeared <strong>in</strong> the form of a ‘multiple choice’ where each sentence conta<strong>in</strong>ed<br />

three different choices with regard to the gender feature. The participants were asked to<br />

give one or two possible answers whenever they found it appropriate. The fourth questionnaire<br />

appeared <strong>in</strong> the form of ‘fill <strong>in</strong> the gaps’. In this questionnaire the participants were<br />

asked to respond choos<strong>in</strong>g the best possible answer. Most participants were will<strong>in</strong>g to give<br />

more than one answer. The reason the fourth questionnaire was different was to confirm<br />

some of the responses of the consultants.<br />

The second issue concerned the fact that we needed to check the resolution genders<br />

<strong>in</strong> both animate and <strong>in</strong>animate nouns and <strong>in</strong> s<strong>in</strong>gular and plural conjuncts. We decided<br />

to <strong>in</strong>clude only sentences with s<strong>in</strong>gular animate and <strong>in</strong>animate coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns <strong>in</strong> the<br />

first questionnaire and sentences with plural animate and <strong>in</strong>animate coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns <strong>in</strong><br />

the second questionnaire. The other two questionnaires <strong>in</strong>cluded mixed sentences either<br />

with s<strong>in</strong>gular animate or <strong>in</strong>animate coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns or with plural animate or <strong>in</strong>animate<br />

coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns.<br />

Another issue concerned the time that the questionnaires should be given to the consultants<br />

s<strong>in</strong>ce we wanted to leave a short period of time <strong>in</strong> between the first two questionnaires<br />

and the next two questionnaires. Our aim was to test the consistency of the responses of<br />

the participants. Thus, we issued only the first two questionnaires to the consultants and<br />

then we issued the other two questionnaires after some time to the same consultants <strong>in</strong><br />

order to check whether their responses were consistent. Also, some of the sentences were<br />

repeated <strong>in</strong> the last two questionnaires <strong>in</strong> order to see whether the same form had been


A.2 Predicate Argument <strong>Agreement</strong> sets of examples 208<br />

chosen by the consultants previously. F<strong>in</strong>ally, the ma<strong>in</strong> issue was to avoid controll<strong>in</strong>g the<br />

responses of the participants. The best way to adm<strong>in</strong>ister that was to provide the consultants<br />

with different types of questionnaires and without necessarily provid<strong>in</strong>g a choice of<br />

forms. Therefore, the first three questionnaires <strong>in</strong>cluded sentences where the consultants<br />

had to choose one or two possible forms out of the three forms provided, and <strong>in</strong> the fourth<br />

questionnaire the consultants had to th<strong>in</strong>k and decide themselves the form they would<br />

choose to fill <strong>in</strong> the gap.<br />

The problems that could be found <strong>in</strong> the above questionnaires are summarized as follows.<br />

Some of the examples were repeated especially <strong>in</strong> the third and fourth questionnaire.<br />

Possibly a wider range of examples should be <strong>in</strong>cluded to avoid the problem of repetition.<br />

Second, we presented sentences with animate coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns separately from sentences<br />

with <strong>in</strong>animate coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns <strong>in</strong> the first two questionnaires and this separation may<br />

have the effect of controll<strong>in</strong>g the responses of the consultants to some extent. In order<br />

to m<strong>in</strong>imise the effect of controll<strong>in</strong>g their responses, we issued the last two questionnaires<br />

where we presented a mix of sentences with animate and <strong>in</strong>animate coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns.<br />

F<strong>in</strong>ally, the sentences did not appear <strong>in</strong> a specific context and the responses of the<br />

participants were based only on the sentence they were presented with. However, <strong>in</strong> the<br />

sentences where we exam<strong>in</strong>ed the phenomenon of gender resolution this is not an important<br />

problem s<strong>in</strong>ce we do not focus on the <strong>in</strong>terpretation of the phrase but rather on the resolved<br />

gender form which is derived based on the gender of the two coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns that are<br />

present <strong>in</strong> the phrase.<br />

A.2 Predicate Argument <strong>Agreement</strong> sets of examples<br />

1. Father.m and mother.f are tired. Their life is difficult and demand<strong>in</strong>g<br />

2. Kostas.m and the baby.n are ready to depart<br />

3. Kostas.m and the girl.n are ready to depart<br />

4. Mary.f and her girl.n are enthusiastic about their new life<br />

5. Mary.f and the boy/baby.n are happy<br />

6. Mary.f and her baby.nf are beautiful. You see them and you admire them<br />

7. Mary.f and the person.n with the skirt are weird<br />

8. The child.n and the baby.n were locked <strong>in</strong> the room<br />

9. The boy.n and the girl.n were seated at the back<br />

10. The men.m and the women.f are ready<br />

11. The boys.n and girls.n are happy<br />

12. The fathers.f and boys.n are very close<br />

13. The grandmothers.f and grandchildren.n are happy<br />

14. The children.n and mothers.f are happy<br />

15. The grandmothers.f and girls.n are happy<br />

16. The girls.n and the mothers.f are very close<br />

17. Heroism.m and fight<strong>in</strong>g.m were prevalent dur<strong>in</strong>g 1821<br />

28. The picture.m and the sofa.m are big for this room and I will put them <strong>in</strong> the other<br />

19. The fight.m and self-sacrifice.f were prevalent <strong>in</strong> 1821<br />

20. Death.m and freedom.f are important<br />

21. Freedom.f and death.m were important <strong>in</strong> 1821<br />

22. The sofa.m and the table.n are white<br />

23. The bookcase.f and d<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g-table.f are different<br />

24. Freedom.f and faith.f are equal<br />

25. Effort.f and obst<strong>in</strong>ancy.n have good results<br />

26. Love.f and passion.n are necessary <strong>in</strong> our life<br />

27. The sofa.m and the armchair.f are comfortable


A.3 Tables 209<br />

28. The street.m and the square.f are clean<br />

29. The pictures.m and sofas.m are unsuitable<br />

30. The philosophies.f and religions.f were determ<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g for the people<br />

31. The houses.n and cars.n are more expensive from now on<br />

32. The roads.m and the squares.f are full of people<br />

33. The squares.f and roads.m are full of people<br />

34. The roads.m and the alleys.n are full of people<br />

35. The hurricanes.m and floods.f were destructive for Tailand<br />

36. The protests.f and compla<strong>in</strong>ts.n are useless <strong>in</strong> this case<br />

A.3 Tables<br />

Table A.1: List of consultants of questionnaires 1,2,3,4<br />

Consultant Number: 26<br />

Consultant Number age gender education orig<strong>in</strong><br />

c1 37 F BA,MA,PhD Athens<br />

c2 35 F BA Thessaloniki<br />

c3 34 F BA,MA,PhD Crete<br />

c4 35 M BA,MA,PhD Volos<br />

c5 31 F BA Thessaloniki<br />

c6 33 F BA Thessaloniki<br />

c7 25 F BA Thessaloniki<br />

c8 32 F BA,MA,PhD Athens<br />

c9 31 M BA,MA Thessaloniki<br />

c10 55 F BA Thessaloniki<br />

c11 60 M BA Thessaloniki<br />

c12 24 F BA Thessaloniki<br />

c13 36 M BA,MA Thessaloniki<br />

c14 30 M BA,MA Thessaloniki<br />

c15 32 M BA,MA Thessaloniki<br />

c16 36 F BA,MA Orestiada<br />

c17 30 F BA,MA,PhD Orestiada<br />

c18 31 M BA Thessaloniki<br />

c19 27 M BA,MA Thessaloniki<br />

c20 62 F BA Thessaloniki<br />

c21 36 F BA,MA Thessaloniki<br />

c22 32 F BA,MA,PhD Crete<br />

c23 31 M BA,MA Peloponese<br />

c24 24 F BA Thessaloniki<br />

c25 24 F BA Thessaloniki<br />

c26 24 F BA Thessaloniki


A.3 Tables 210<br />

Table A.2: Results of crucial sets of examples<br />

Consultant Number: 26<br />

examples expected unexpected<br />

No. m f n m f n<br />

1 26 - - - - -<br />

c1-c26<br />

2 26 - - - - -<br />

c1-c26 - - - - -<br />

3 26 - - - - -<br />

c1-c26 - - - - -<br />

4 5 21 - - - -<br />

c4,c14,c18 c1,c2,c3,c5,c6,c7,<br />

c20,c24 c8,c9,c10,c11,c12<br />

c13,c15,c16,c17,c19<br />

c21,c22,c23,c25,c26<br />

5 26 - - - - -<br />

c1-c26 - - - - -<br />

6 5 21 - - - -<br />

c4,c15,c18 c1,c2,c3,c5,c6,c7,<br />

c20,c26 c8,c9,c10,c11,c12<br />

c13,c14,c16,c17,c19<br />

c21,c22,c23,c24,c25<br />

7 - 26 - - - -<br />

c1-c26 - - - -<br />

8 - - 26 - - -<br />

c1-c26<br />

9 - - 26 - - -<br />

c1-c26<br />

10 26 - - - - -<br />

c1-c26 - - - - -<br />

11 - - 26 - - -<br />

- - c1-c26 -<br />

12 26 - - - - -<br />

c1-c26 - - -<br />

13 19 - - - - 12<br />

c2,c4,c5,c6,c7, c1,c3,c6<br />

c9,c11,c12,c13, c8,c9,c10<br />

c14,c16,c18,c19 c15,c16,<br />

c20,c21,c22,c23, c17,c20<br />

c25,c26 c24,c26<br />

14 19 - - - - 7<br />

c2,c4,c5,c6,c7, c1,c3,c8,<br />

c9,c11,c12,c13, c10,c15,<br />

c14,c16,c18,c19 c17,c24<br />

c20,c21,c22,c23,<br />

c25,c26<br />

15 5 18 - - - 5<br />

c4,c14,c18 c2,c5,c6,c7 c1,c3,c8<br />

c20,c24 c8,c9,c10 c17,c24<br />

c11,c12,c13<br />

c15,c16,c17<br />

c19,c21,c22<br />

c23,c25,c26<br />

16 5 18 - - - 5<br />

c4,c15,c18 c2,c5,c6,c7, c1,c3,c8<br />

Cont<strong>in</strong>ued on next page


A.3 Tables 211<br />

Table A.2: Results of crucial sets of examples<br />

Consultant Number: 26<br />

examples expected unexpected<br />

No. m f n m f n<br />

c20,c26 c8,c9,c10, c10,c24<br />

c11,c12,c13,<br />

c14,c16,c17,<br />

c19,c21,c22,<br />

c23,c24,c25<br />

17 25 - - - - 10<br />

c1,c2,c3,c6 c3,c4,c5<br />

c7,c8,c9 c7,c8,c9<br />

,c10,c11,c12 c10,c11,<br />

c13,c14,<br />

c15,c16,c17, c12,c13<br />

c18,c19,c20,<br />

c21,c22,c23,<br />

c24,c25,c26<br />

18 25 - - - - 10<br />

c1,c3,c4 c2,c4,c5,<br />

c6,c7,c8 c7,c8,c9<br />

c9,c10,c11<br />

c12,c13,c14 c10,c11<br />

c15,c16,c17 c20,c24<br />

c18,c19,c20<br />

,c21,c22,c23<br />

c24,c25,c26<br />

19 - - 16 6 6 -<br />

c2,c3,c5,c6 c7,c8 c1,c4,<br />

c7,c8,c9,c11 c12,c14 c10,c16<br />

c13,c17,c19 c15,c18 c21,c24<br />

c20,c22,c23<br />

c25,c26<br />

20 - - 16 6 6 -<br />

c2,c3,c5,c6 c7,c8 c1,c4<br />

c7,c8,c9,c12 c11,c14, c10,c19<br />

c13,c16,c17 c15,c18 c21,c24<br />

c20,c22,c23<br />

c25,c26<br />

21 - - 18 5 5 -<br />

c2,c3,c5,c6,c7 c7,c8 c1,c4<br />

c8,c9,c11,c13 c12,c14 c10,<br />

c15,c16,c17, c18 c21<br />

c19,c20,c22, c24<br />

c23,c25,c26<br />

22 - - 26 - - -<br />

- - c1-c26 -<br />

23 - 24 - - - 11<br />

c1,c2,c3,c5,c6,c7 c3,c4,c7<br />

c8,c9,c10,c11,c13 c8,c9<br />

c14,c15,c16,c17 c10,c11<br />

c18,c19,c20,c21 c12,c13<br />

c22,c23,c24,c25 c20,c24<br />

c26<br />

24 - 24 - - - 11<br />

c1,c2,c3,c5,c6,c7 c3,c4,c5<br />

Cont<strong>in</strong>ued on next page


A.3 Tables 212<br />

Table A.2: Results of crucial sets of examples<br />

Consultant Number: 26<br />

examples expected unexpected<br />

No. m f n m f n<br />

c8,c9,c10,c11,c12 c8,c9<br />

c14,c15,c16,c17 c10,c11<br />

c18,c19,c20,c21 c12,c13<br />

c22,c23,c24,c25 c20,c24<br />

c26<br />

25 - - 26 - - -<br />

- - c1-c26 -<br />

26 - - 26 - - -<br />

- - c1-c26 -<br />

27 - - 14 12 - -<br />

c1,c2,c6, c3,c4,c5<br />

c7,c12,c14, c8,c9,c10,<br />

c15,c16,c17, c11,c13,c21<br />

c18,c19,c22 c20,c24,c26<br />

c23,c25<br />

28 - - 14 12 -<br />

c1,c2,c6,c7 c3,c4,c5<br />

c12,c14, c8,c9,c10,<br />

c15,c16,c17, c11,c13,c21,<br />

c18,c19,c22, c20,c24,c26<br />

c23,c25<br />

29 26 - - - - -<br />

c1-c26 - - -<br />

30 - 26 - - - -<br />

c1-c26 - -<br />

31 - - 26 - - -<br />

- - c1-c26 -<br />

32 - - 13 15 6 -<br />

c1,c2,c6,c7, c3,c4,c5,c8, c1,c2<br />

c14,c15,c16 c9,c10,c11, c7,c18,<br />

c17,c18,c19, c12,c13,c14, c19,c22<br />

c22,c23,c25 c17,c20,c21,<br />

c24,c26<br />

33 - - 11 17 4 -<br />

c1,c2,c6, c3,c4,c5,c7,c8 c1,c2,<br />

c14,c15,c16 c9,c10,c11,c12 c18,c19,<br />

c17,c18,c19, c13,c14,c17<br />

c22,c23 c20,c21,c22,<br />

c24,c25,c26<br />

34 - - 26 - - -<br />

- - c1-c26 -<br />

35 - - 13 15 6 -<br />

c1,c2,c6,c7, c3,c4,c5,c8, c1,c2,<br />

c14,c15,c16 c9,c10,c11 c7,c18<br />

c17,c18,c19, c12,c13,c14, c19,c22<br />

c22,c23,c25 c17,c20,c21<br />

c24,c26<br />

36 - - 26 - - -<br />

- - c1-c26 -


Appendix B<br />

Questionnaires on agreement with<br />

Disjunctively Conjo<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>Noun</strong>s<br />

B.1 Discussion of questionnnaires<br />

The data analysis is based on questionnaires that were developed <strong>in</strong> order to test the<br />

prevalent verb agreement form <strong>in</strong> disjunctively coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns. The aim is to explore<br />

the different <strong>in</strong>terpretations assigned to the coord<strong>in</strong>ate structures and the syntactic factors<br />

that determ<strong>in</strong>e verb agreement. Two different questionnaires were produced for that. The<br />

first questionnaire focused on the choice of verb agreement related to the <strong>in</strong>terpretation of<br />

the disjunctively conjo<strong>in</strong>ed nouns and on the choice of verb agreement related to syntactic<br />

factors, it consists of both declarative and <strong>in</strong>terrogative sentences and it <strong>in</strong>cludes sentences<br />

with s<strong>in</strong>gular disjuncts of the same or different gender and of the same or different person<br />

while the second part consists of mixed number, gender and person disjuncts. The<br />

second questionnaire <strong>in</strong>cludes sentences with the positive predisjunction and disjunction<br />

i...i/ite...ite ‘either...or’ and the negative predisjunction and disjunction oute...oute ‘neither...nor’<br />

with s<strong>in</strong>gular disjuncts of the same or different gender and person and mixed<br />

number disjuncts also of the same or different gender and person. The questionnaires were<br />

issued to 20 <strong>Greek</strong> native speakers who are all university graduates from different areas <strong>in</strong><br />

Greece. The participants were asked to make a choice from three possible verb forms and<br />

were asked to consider two verb forms whenever they found it appropriate.<br />

Some issues need to be discussed regard<strong>in</strong>g questions that were raised about the questionnaires<br />

on disjunctively conjo<strong>in</strong>ed nouns. The first issue concerns the type of the questionnaire<br />

that would be given to the participants. We decided to issue two different questionnaires<br />

which appeared <strong>in</strong> the form of a ‘multiple choice’. Consultants were given three<br />

different choices and were asked to choose one or two possible answers. The second issue<br />

concerns how we would <strong>in</strong>vestigate any different semantic or syntactic phenomena. The<br />

first questionnaire <strong>in</strong>cludes sentences which were related to the <strong>in</strong>terpretation of the disjunctively<br />

conjo<strong>in</strong>ed phrase; these sentences consisted of s<strong>in</strong>gular disjuncts of the same or<br />

different gender and of the same or different person. Also, it <strong>in</strong>cludes sentences with a<br />

s<strong>in</strong>gular and a plural disjunct that <strong>in</strong>vestigates the speakers strategies, and sentences with<br />

s<strong>in</strong>gular disjuncts but with different person and different gender that <strong>in</strong>vestigates other syntactic<br />

factors (i.e. mixed person or gender and verb agreement). The second questionnaire<br />

<strong>in</strong>cludes sentences with the positive predisjunction and disjunction i...i/ite...ite ‘either...or’<br />

and the negative predisjunction and disjunction oute...oute ‘neither...nor’ with s<strong>in</strong>gular disjuncts<br />

of the same or different gender and person, and mixed number disjuncts also of the<br />

same or different gender and person. The aim was to test any difference between the bare<br />

disjunction and the predisjunction and disjunction, and the negative predisjunction and<br />

disjunction <strong>in</strong> relation to verb agreement. A third issue was raised <strong>in</strong> the first questionnaire


B.2 Disjunctive Coord<strong>in</strong>ate <strong>Noun</strong>s sets of examples 214<br />

which focused on the <strong>in</strong>terpretation of the disjunctively conjo<strong>in</strong>ed nouns. In order to make<br />

sure how the consultants <strong>in</strong>terpreted the disjunctively conjo<strong>in</strong>ed nouns they were asked to<br />

give further <strong>in</strong>formation on how they would <strong>in</strong>terpret the particular disjunctive coord<strong>in</strong>ate<br />

phrase.<br />

Some problems arise <strong>in</strong> these questionnaires. Sentences did not appear with<strong>in</strong> a specific<br />

context as would be desirable and the responses of the participants were based only on the<br />

sentence they were presented with. However, s<strong>in</strong>ce the issue of <strong>in</strong>terpretation is crucial<br />

we asked the consultants to give their reason for the choice of the specific verb form by<br />

provid<strong>in</strong>g their personal <strong>in</strong>terpretation of the sentence, such as whether it <strong>in</strong>volves both<br />

coord<strong>in</strong>ate nouns or a s<strong>in</strong>gle noun. A second problem is that <strong>in</strong> disjunctively conjo<strong>in</strong>ed<br />

nouns we discussed both <strong>in</strong>terpretational factors and syntactic factors and therefore a<br />

wider range of examples should be <strong>in</strong>cluded to have more accurate results. We need to<br />

note, though, that this was only a prelim<strong>in</strong>ary research which can be expanded further<br />

<strong>in</strong> the future <strong>in</strong> order to test accurately both the pragmatic factors and the syntactic<br />

factors. Also, some of the data were repeated <strong>in</strong> both questionnaires. Probably a wider<br />

range of sentences would give more precise and exact results concern<strong>in</strong>g the outcome of the<br />

research. F<strong>in</strong>ally, a major disadvantage is the fact that the participants who responded to<br />

the follow<strong>in</strong>g questionnaires were around 20, although the questionnaires were orig<strong>in</strong>ally<br />

sent to around 30 people. This was a serious problem s<strong>in</strong>ce a larger number of participants<br />

would help us make out possible differences on the way the language is used and draw more<br />

concrete conclusions concern<strong>in</strong>g our results.<br />

B.2 Disjunctive Coord<strong>in</strong>ate <strong>Noun</strong>s sets of examples<br />

1. Kostas or Maria will pick me up with the car<br />

2. The boy or the girl tries to suppress the feel<strong>in</strong>gs<br />

3. The woman or child have priority for the vacc<strong>in</strong>e aga<strong>in</strong>st flu<br />

4. The boy or the girl are tired from study<strong>in</strong>g<br />

5. Kostas or Giorgos is Maria’s relative<br />

6. The doctor or dentist can write prescriptions<br />

7. The male-student or female-student that is certa<strong>in</strong> about every choice will succeed<br />

8. The male-student or female-student can be <strong>in</strong>formed by the parents<br />

9. The son or the daughter need help<br />

10. Is the mother or the boy gett<strong>in</strong>g ready to go out<br />

11. The mother or the boy ready to go out<br />

12. Me or you will need help<br />

13. Me or Kostas will over the job<br />

14. Will you or Maria go to the doctor?<br />

15. The car or the mopeds will be-sold soon<br />

16. Your cats or your dog ate my owers<br />

17. The footballers or the coach earn much money<br />

18. Are your brother or your sisters settled?<br />

19. Is/are your sisters or your brother settled?<br />

20. The father or the daughters are responsible for the company<br />

21. The daughters or the father are responsible for the company?<br />

22. Are the boys or the girl gett<strong>in</strong>g prepared for the exams<br />

23. Are the girl or the boys gett<strong>in</strong>g prepared for the exams<br />

24. Either my son or my father will take part <strong>in</strong> the contest<br />

25. Either the mother or the aunt will take over the custody<br />

26. Either the father or the mother are responsible for the child’s custody<br />

27. Either my brother or my sister will enter the university


B.3 Tables 215<br />

28. Either me or you will take over the bus<strong>in</strong>ess<br />

29. Either you or the father will sign the papers<br />

30. Do either you or Maria have the responsibility for the job<br />

31. Neither the boy nor the girl are ready for this change<br />

32. Neither the father nor the mother are happy with this situation<br />

33. Neither the man nor the woman compromise nowadays<br />

34. Neither you nor he will accept the offer<br />

B.3 Tables<br />

Table B.1: List of consultants for questionnaires 1,2<br />

Consultant Number: 20<br />

Consultant Number age gender education orig<strong>in</strong><br />

c1 60 F - Thessaloniki<br />

c2 32 M BA,MA Thessaloniki<br />

c3 54 F - Thessaloniki<br />

c4 32 F BA Thessaloniki<br />

c5 33 F BA,MA,PhD Crete<br />

c6 32 F BA Thessaloniki<br />

c7 31 M BA,MA Patras<br />

c8 60 M BA Thessaloniki<br />

c9 35 F BA,MA Thessaloniki<br />

c10 35 F - Thessaloniki<br />

c11 40 M BA,MA Thessaloniki<br />

c12 32 F BA,MA Messolongi<br />

c13 26 F BA,MA Thessaloniki<br />

c14 36 F BA,MA,PhD Athens<br />

c15 30 F BA,MA,PhD Orestiada<br />

c16 35 M BA,MA,PhD Volos<br />

c17 27 M BA,MA Thessaloniki<br />

c18 32 F BA Athens<br />

c19 32 F BA,MA Thessaloniki<br />

c20 32 F BA,MA Thessaloniki<br />

Table B.2: Results of crucial sets of examples<br />

Consultant Number: 20<br />

examples sg pl both<br />

1 14 4 2<br />

c1,c2,c3,c4 c8,c11, c17,c19<br />

c5,c6,c7,c9 c16,c20<br />

c10,c12,c13<br />

c14,c15,c18<br />

Cont<strong>in</strong>ued on next page


B.3 Tables 216<br />

Table B.2: Results of crucial sets of examples<br />

Consultant Number: 20<br />

examples sg pl both<br />

2 15 3 2<br />

c1,c2,c3,c5 c8,c11,c16 c4,c12<br />

c6,c7,c9,c10<br />

c13,c14,c15,c17<br />

c18,c19,c20<br />

3 7 13 -<br />

c5,c6,c11,c12 c1,c2,c3,c4<br />

c13,c14,c15 c7,c8,c9,c10<br />

c16,c17,c18<br />

c19,c20<br />

4 5 15 -<br />

c5,c6,c11 c1,c2,c3,c4<br />

c12,c13 c7,c8,c9,c10<br />

c14,c15,c16,<br />

c17,c18,c19,c20<br />

5 20 - -<br />

c1-c20<br />

6 - 20 -<br />

c1-c20<br />

7 4 12 4<br />

c6,c7, c1,c2,c3,c4 c17,c18<br />

c14,c15 c5,c8,c9,c10 c19,c20<br />

c11,c12,c13,<br />

c16<br />

8 7 2 11<br />

c9,c12,c13,c14 c3,c6 c1,c2,c4,c5<br />

c15,c18,c20 c7,c8,c9,c10<br />

c11,c16,c17,c19<br />

9 7 2 11<br />

c9,c12,c13,c14 c3,c6 c1,c2,c4,c5<br />

c15,c18,c20 c7,c8,c9,c10<br />

c11,c16,c17,c19<br />

10 9 4 7<br />

c2,c4,c5,c6 c1,c3,c8,c10 c11,c12,c13,c17<br />

c7,c9,c14,c15 c18,c19,c20<br />

c16<br />

11 3 13 4<br />

c9,c10,c14 c1,c2,c3,c4 c11,c12,c13,c17<br />

c5,c6,c7,c8<br />

c15,c16,c18<br />

c19,c20<br />

12 3 17 -<br />

c6,c7,c9 c1,c2,c3,c4<br />

c5,c8,c10,c11<br />

c12,c13,c14,c15<br />

c16,c17,c18,c19<br />

Cont<strong>in</strong>ued on next page


B.3 Tables 217<br />

Table B.2: Results of crucial sets of examples<br />

Consultant Number: 20<br />

examples sg pl both<br />

c20<br />

13 3 17 -<br />

c6,c7,c9 c1,c2,c3,c4<br />

c5,c8,c10,c11<br />

c12,c13,c14,c15<br />

c16,c17,c18,c19<br />

c20<br />

14 11 9 -<br />

c2,c3,c4,c5 c1,c8,c10,c11<br />

c6,c7,c9,c13 c12,c17,c18,c19<br />

c14,c15,c16 c20<br />

15 - 20 -<br />

c1-c20<br />

16 4 15 1<br />

c6,c8,c12,c17 c1,c2,c3,c4 c19<br />

c5,c7,c9,c10<br />

c11,c13,c14,c15<br />

c16,c18,c20<br />

17 3 15 2<br />

c2,c4,c6 c1,c3,c5,c7 c17,c19<br />

c8,c9,c10,c11<br />

c12,c13,c14,c15<br />

c16,c18,c20<br />

18 7 13 -<br />

c12,c13,c14 c1,c2,c3,c4<br />

c16,c17,c18,c19 c5,c6,c7,c8<br />

c9,c10,c11<br />

c15,c20<br />

19 4 16 -<br />

c6,c9,c10,c11 c1,c2,c3,c4<br />

c5,c7,c8,c12<br />

c13,c14,c15,c16<br />

c17,c18,c19,c20<br />

20 7 13 -<br />

c8,c9,c10,c11 c1,c2,c3,c4<br />

c14,c16,c17 c5,c6,c7,c12<br />

c13,c15,c18<br />

c19,c20<br />

21 4 16 -<br />

c9,c10,c11,c16 c1,c2,c3,c4<br />

c5,c6,c7,c8<br />

c12,c13,c14<br />

c15,c17,c18<br />

c19,c20<br />

22 - 20 -<br />

c1-c20<br />

Cont<strong>in</strong>ued on next page


B.3 Tables 218<br />

Table B.2: Results of crucial sets of examples<br />

Consultant Number: 20<br />

examples sg pl both<br />

23 1 11 8<br />

c1 c2,c3,c7,c12 c4,c5,c6,c8<br />

c13,c14,c16 c9,10,c11,c15<br />

c17,c18,c19,c20<br />

24 14 6 -<br />

c1,c2,c3,c4 c6,c7,c8,c12<br />

c5,c9,c10,c11 c13,c14<br />

c15,c16,c17,c18<br />

c19,c20<br />

25 16 4 -<br />

c1,c2,c3,c4 c6,c7,c8,c12<br />

c5,c9,c10,c11<br />

c13,c14,c15,c16<br />

c17,c18,c19,c20<br />

26 5 12 3<br />

c2,c3,c5,c9 c1,c4,c11,c12 c6,c7,c8<br />

c10 c13,c14,c15,c16<br />

c17,c18,c19,c20<br />

27 9 3 8<br />

c1,c3,c4,c9 c2,c12,c13 c5,c6,c7,c8<br />

c10,c14,c15 c11,c17,c19,c20<br />

c16,c18<br />

28 4 16 -<br />

c6,c7,c9,c10 c1,c2,c3,c4<br />

c5,c8,c11,c12<br />

c13,c14,c15,c16<br />

c17,c18,c19,c20<br />

29 4 16 -<br />

c6,c7,c9,c10 c1,c2,c3,c4<br />

c5,c8,c11,c12<br />

c13,c14,c15,c16<br />

c17,c18,c19,c20<br />

30 11 9 -<br />

c1,c3,c4,c5,c6 c2,c7,c12,c13,c14<br />

c8,c9,c10,c11 c15,c18,c19,c20<br />

c16,c17<br />

31 3 17 -<br />

c7,c10,c11 c1,c2,c3,c4<br />

c5,c6,c8,c9<br />

c12,c13,c14,c15<br />

c16,c17,c18,c19<br />

c20<br />

32 - 20 -<br />

c1-c20<br />

33 3 17 -<br />

c7,c10,c11 c1,c2,c3,c4<br />

Cont<strong>in</strong>ued on next page


B.3 Tables 219<br />

Table B.2: Results of crucial sets of examples<br />

Consultant Number: 20<br />

examples sg pl both<br />

c5,c6,c8,c9<br />

c12,c13,c14,c15<br />

c16,c17,c18,c19<br />

c20<br />

34 3 17 -<br />

c7,c10,c11 c1,c2,c3,c4<br />

c5,c6,c8,c9<br />

c12,c13,c14,c15<br />

c16,c17,c18,c19<br />

c20


Appendix C<br />

Orig<strong>in</strong>al Questionnaires <strong>in</strong> <strong>Greek</strong>


Predicate Argument <strong>Agreement</strong> Questionnaires<br />

QUESTIONNAIRE 1<br />

SINGULAR NOUNS<br />

Choose any one or two of the follow<strong>in</strong>g items that might fill <strong>in</strong> the gaps!<br />

1. Το τραπέζι και το γραφείο είναι πολύ .................... . Θα ....... µεταφέρω.<br />

a. µεγάλο b. µεγάλοι c. µεγάλα<br />

a. τον b. τα c. τους<br />

2. Ο ηρωισµός και ο θάνατος είναι ....................... στο χώµα της Ελλάδος.<br />

a. χαραγµένος b. χαραγµένα c. χαραγµένοι<br />

3. Ο πίνακας και ο καναπές είναι .................. γι’αυτό το δωµάτιο.<br />

a. µεγάλες b. µεγάλοι c. µεγάλα<br />

4. Η βιβλιοθήκη και η τραπεζαρία είναι ........................<br />

a. διαφορετικοί b. διαφορετικές c. διαφορετικά<br />

5. Η ελευθερία και η πίστη είναι .....................<br />

a. ταυτόσηµες b. ταυτόσηµα c. Tαυτόσηµοι<br />

6. Ο αγώνας και η αυτοθυσία ήταν ................... κατα το 1821.<br />

a. κυρίαρχες b. κυρίαρχοι c. κυρίαρχα<br />

7. Ο θάνατος και η ελευθερία είναι ..............................<br />

a. σηµαντικές b. σηµαντικά c. σηµαντικοί<br />

8. Ο δρόµος και η πλατεία είναι .....................<br />

a. καθαρές b. καθαρά c. καθαροί<br />

9. Ο καναπές και η πολυθρόνα είναι .................<br />

a. άνετες b. άνετοι c.άνετα<br />

10. Η δικαιοσύνη και ο φιλελευθερισµός ήτανε .......................<br />

a. πρωτόγονες b. πρωτόγονοι c. πρωτόγονα<br />

11. Η καρέκλα και ο καναπές είναι ………………..<br />

α. άσπρες b. άσπροι c. άσπρα<br />

12. Ο έρωτας και το πάθος είναι .................. στη ζωή µας. .......... ζεί κανείς λίγες φορές.<br />

a. απαραίτητος b. απαραίτητα c. απαραίτητοι<br />

a. τα b. τις c. το<br />

13. Η προσπάθεια και το πείσµα είναι ...........................<br />

a. αποτελεσµατικές b. αποτελεσµατικοί c. αποτελεσµατικά


14. Ο Πέτρος και ο Γιάννης είναι ...................... Η δουλειά τους έχει εκσαντλήσει.<br />

a. κουρασµένος b. κουρασµένοι c. Κουρασµένα<br />

15. Το αγόρι και το κορίτσι βρίσκονται .......................... πίσω.<br />

a. καθισµένοι b. καθισµένα c. καθισµένες<br />

16. Το παιδί και το µωρό ήταν ………………….. στο δωµάτιο<br />

a. κλειδωµένες b. κλειδωµένοι c. κλειδωµένα<br />

17. Ο πατέρας και η µητέρα είναι ................... Η ζωή τους είναι δύσκολη και απαιτητική.<br />

a. κουρασµένες b. κουρασµένοι c. κουρασµένα<br />

18. Ο Κώστας και το κορίτσι είναι ................. για αναχώρηση.<br />

a. έτοιµοι b. έτοιµες c. έτοιµα<br />

19. Ο πατέρας και το παιδί βρέθηκαν .......................<br />

a. δολοφονηµένες b. δολοφονηµένοι c. δολοφονηµένα<br />

20. Ο Κώστας και το µωρό είναι ................. για αναχώρηση.<br />

a. έτοιµοι b. έτοιµες c. έτοιµα<br />

21. Η Μαρία και το κορίτσι έιναι ................ για την καινούργια τους ζωή.<br />

a. ενθουσιασµένοι b. ενθουσιασµένες c. ενθουσιασµένα<br />

22. Η µητέρα και το µωρό της είναι ...................<br />

a. χαρούµενοι b. χαρούµενες c. χαρούµενα<br />

23. Η Μαρία και το µωρό (αγόρι) της είναι ..................βλέπεις και ........ θαυµάζεις.<br />

a. όµορφοι b. όµορφες c. όµορφα<br />

a. τούς b. τίς<br />

a. τούς b. τίς<br />

24. Η Μαρία και το µώρο (κορίτσι) της είναι ................... ....... βλέπεις και ........<br />

θαυµάζεις.<br />

a. όµορφοι b. όµορφες c. όµορφα<br />

a. τούς b. τίς<br />

a. τούς b. τίς<br />

25. Η Μαρία και το άτοµο µε τη φούστα είναι ..........................<br />

a. περίεργες b. περίεργα c. περίεργοι<br />

Please write your name: …………………………


QUESTIONNAIRE 2<br />

PLURAL NOUNS<br />

Choose any one or two of the follow<strong>in</strong>g items that might fill <strong>in</strong> the gaps!<br />

1. Οι γιαγιάδες και τα εγγόνια ήταν ............................<br />

α. χαρούµενα β. χαρούµενοι γ. χαρούµενες<br />

2. Οι άνδρες και οι γυναίκες ήταν .............................<br />

α. έτοιµες β. έτοιµοι γ. έτοιµα<br />

3. Οι παππούδες και τα εγγόνια είναι ...........................<br />

α. χαρούµενα β. χαρούµενοι γ. χαρούµενες<br />

4. Οι γιαγιάδες και τα κορίτσια είναι πολύ............................<br />

α. γελαστοί β. γελαστά γ. γελαστές<br />

5. Τα κορίτσια και οι γιαγιάδες είναι ............................<br />

α. χαρούµενοι β. χαρούµενες γ. χαρούµενα<br />

6. Τα παδιά και οι µαµάδες είναι πολύ ...............................<br />

α. χαρούµενα β. χαρούµενοι γ. χαρούµενες<br />

7. Τα παιδιά και οι µπαµπάδες είναι πολύ .............................<br />

α. δεµένοι β. δεµένα γ. δεµένες<br />

8. Οι µπαµπάδες και τα αγόρια είναι πολύ .................................<br />

α. δεµένοι β. δεµένα γ. δεµένες<br />

9. Τα αγόρια και τα κορίτσια είναι ………………….<br />

α. χαρούµενοι β. χαρούµενες γ. χαρούµενα<br />

10. Οι παππούδες και οι πατεράδες είναι ………………<br />

α. αγαπηµένοι β. αγαπηµένες γ. αγαπηµένα<br />

11. Οι πίνακες και οι καναπέδες είναι .......................<br />

α. αταίριαστοι β. αταίριαστες γ. αταίριαστα<br />

12. Οι καυγάδες και οι χωρισµοί είναι …………για την ψυχολογία των παιδιών.<br />

α. σηµαντικές β. σηµαντικά γ. σηµαντικοί<br />

13. Οι κουζίνες και οι τουαλέτες είναι ..............................<br />

α. καθαρές β. καθαρά γ. καθαροί<br />

14. Οι φιλοσοφίες και οι θρησκείες ήταν ........................ για τους λαούς<br />

α. καθοριστικοί β. καθοριστικά γ. καθοριστικές


15. Οι δρόµοι και οι πλατείες ήταν ............................ κόσµο<br />

α. γεµάτοι β. γεµάτα γ. γεµάτες<br />

16. Οι τυφώνες και οι πληµµύρες ήταν .............................. για την Ταϊλάνδη<br />

α. καταστροφικές β. καταστροφικά γ. καταστροφικοί<br />

17. Οι δρόµοι και τα σοκάκια ήταν .......................... κόσµο<br />

α. γεµάτοι β. γεµάτα γ. γεµάτες<br />

18. Οι διαµαρτυρίες και τα παράπονα είναι ................... σ’ αυτήν τη περίπτωση.<br />

α. άχρηστες β. άχρηστοι γ. Άχρηστα<br />

19. Οι πλατείες και οι δρόµοι ήταν ............................ κόσµο.<br />

α. γεµάτοι β. γεµάτα γ. γεµάτες<br />

20. Τα εστιατόρια και οι πλατείες ήταν ........................... κόσµο<br />

α. γεµάτες β. γεµάτα γ. γεµάτοι<br />

21. Τα σοκάκια και οι πεζόδροµοι ήταν ............................<br />

α. άδειοι β. άδεια γ. άδειες<br />

22. Τα σπίτια και τα αυτοκίνητα είναι πιο ...................... απο εδώ και πέρα.<br />

α. ακριβά β. ακριβοί γ. ακριβές<br />

Please write your name: .................................................


QUESTIONNAIRE 3<br />

SG & PL IN/ANIMATE NOUNS<br />

Choose any one or two of the follow<strong>in</strong>g items that might fill <strong>in</strong> the gaps!<br />

1. Το αγόρι και η µητέρα ήταν ................................<br />

α. χαρούµενοι β. χαρούµενες γ. χαρούµενα<br />

2. Η µητέρα και το κορίτσι είναι πολύ ........................µεταξύ τους.<br />

α. δεµένοι β. δεµένες γ. δεµένα<br />

3. Ο κόπος και η προσπάθεια είναι ..................... για να προοδεύσει κανείς.<br />

α. απαραίτητοι β. απαραίτητες γ. απαραίτητα<br />

4. Η κουζίνα και ο πάγκος είναι πολύ ............................<br />

α. βρώµικοι β. βρώµικες γ. βρώµικα<br />

5. Οι καυγάδες και τα µπλεξίµατα είναι ....................στις µέρες µας.<br />

α. επικίνδυνοι β. επικίνδυνες γ. επικίνδυνα<br />

6. Τα µυστήρια και οι θάνατοι παραµένουν .............................<br />

α. ανεξιχνίαστοι β. ανεξιχνίαστες γ. ανεξιχνίαστα<br />

7. Οι απερισκεψίες και τα λάθη είναι ............................για την επιτυχία.<br />

α. καταστροφικοί β. καταστροφικά γ. καταστροφικές<br />

8. Τα παράπονα και οι διαµαρτυρίες είναι .................. σ’ αυτή την περίπτωση<br />

α. άχρηστοι β. άχρηστα γ. άχρηστες<br />

9. Τα τραπέζια και τα θρανία θα βαφτούν ........................<br />

α. άσπροι β. άσπρες γ.άσπρα<br />

10. Οι καθρέφτες και οι νιπτήρες είναι .........................<br />

α. βρώµικοι β. βρώµικες γ. βρώµικα<br />

11. Το παιδί και η γιαγιά είναι .......................<br />

α. αγαπηµένοι β. αγαπηµένες γ.αγαπηµένα<br />

12. Τα αιτήµατα και οι απαιτήσεις είναι ..................... αυτή την ώρα.<br />

α. ανούσιες β. ανούσια γ.ανούσιοι<br />

13. Τα κορίτσια και οι µαµάδες είναι ............................<br />

α. χαρούµενοι β. χαρούµενες γ. χαρούµενα<br />

14. Οι άνδρες και τα κορίτσια είναι ...................................<br />

α. αγαπηµένα β. αγαπηµένες γ. αγαπηµένα


15. Η ελευθερία και ο θάνατος ήταν ……………. το 1821<br />

α. σηµαντικά β. σηµαντικοί γ. σηµαντικές<br />

16. Η αγάπη και το πάθος είναι ………………. στη ζωή µας.<br />

α. απαραίτητα β. απαραίτητες γ.απαραίτητοι<br />

17. Ο καναπές και το τραπέζι είναι .......................<br />

α. άσπρα β. άσπρες γ. άσπροι<br />

18. Οι µαµάδες και τα κορίτσια είναι …………………….<br />

α. αγαπηµένοι β. αγαπηµένες γ.αγαπηµένα<br />

Please write your name: ………………


QUESTIONNAIRE 4<br />

SG & PL IN/ANIMATE NOUNS<br />

Fill <strong>in</strong> the correct form of the adjective<br />

1. Η γιαγιά και το εγγόνι ήταν γελαστ…………………<br />

2. Η γυναίκα και ο άνδρας είναι ερωτευµέν………………<br />

3. Η καρέκλα και η πολυθρόνα είναι άνετ……………...<br />

4. Η πίστη και η θρησκεία ήταν απαραίτητ…............για την Ελλάδα.<br />

5. Ο καθρέφτης και ο νιπτήρας είναι καθαρ....................<br />

6. Ο τρόµος και ο φόβος ήταν µεγάλ....................... για τους κατοίκους.<br />

7. Η ελευθερία και ο θάνατος ήταν σηµαντικ..............το 1821.<br />

8. Οι γυναίκες και οι άνδρες είναι σκληρά εργαζόµεν..................<br />

9. Τα αγόρια και τα κορίτσια είναι έτοιµ................ για τον αγώνα<br />

10. Τα αγόρια και οι µαµάδες είναι πολύ δεµέν.....................<br />

11. Τα κορίτσια και οι µαµάδες δεν είναι πολύ ...................... αντιθέτως.<br />

12. Οι γυναίκες και τα παιδιά ήταν χαρούµεν……………..<br />

13. Οι δρόµοι και οι πλατείες ήταν γεµάτ...................... κόσµο.<br />

14. Οι πλατείες και τα σοκάκια της Πάρου ήταν άδει............χθές.<br />

15. Οι πλατείες και οι πεζόδροµοι ήταν πολύ βρώµικ........... µετά τη διαδήλωση.<br />

16. Οι φιλοσοφίες και οι θρησκείες ήταν καθοριστικ......... για τους λαούς.<br />

17. Οι τυφώνες και οι πληµµύρες ήταν καταστροφικ....... για την Ταιλάνδη.<br />

18. Οι καυγάδες και οι χωρισµοί είναι καθοριστικ............... γιατις ανθρώπινες σχέσεις.<br />

19. Οι απιστίες και οι χωρισµοί είναι συνηθισµέν................... σήµερα.<br />

20. Οι αποφάσεις και οι νόµοι αυτής της κυβέρνησης είναι ασύµβατ...............<br />

Please write your name: ………………


Disjunctive Coord<strong>in</strong>ate <strong>Noun</strong>s Questionnaires<br />

QUESTIONNAIRE 1<br />

DISJUNCTION<br />

Choose any one or two of the follow<strong>in</strong>g items that might fill <strong>in</strong> the gaps!<br />

1. Ο Κώστας ή η Μαρία θα µε πάρει/πάρουν µε το αυτοκίνητο.<br />

2. Το αγόρι ή το κορίτσι προσπαθεί /προσπαθούν να καταστείλει /καταστείλουν τα<br />

συναισθήµατα<br />

3. Η γυναίκα ή το παιδί έχει/έχουν προτεραιότητα για το εµβόλιο κατά της γρίπης<br />

4. Το αγόρι ή το κορίτσι έχει/έχουν κούραση από το διάβασµα.<br />

5. Ο Κώστας ή ο Γιώργος έχει/έχουν συγγενή την Μαρία<br />

6. Ο γιατρός ή ο οδοντίατρος µπορεί/µπορούν να γράψει/γράψουν φάρµακα<br />

7. Η Μαρία ή η Κατερίνα έχει/έχουν σχέση µε τον Κώστα<br />

8. Ο δικηγόρος ή ο συµβολαιογράφος παρευρίσκεται/παραβρίσκονται στην υπογραφή<br />

συµβολαίων<br />

9. Ο φοιτητής ή η φοιτήτρια που είναι σίγουρος/σίγουρη/σίγουροι για κάθε επιλογή θα<br />

πετύχει/πετύχουν<br />

10. Ο πατέρας ή η µητέρα είναι ενήµερος/ενήµερη/ενήµεροι για την κατάσταση<br />

11. Ο άνδρας ή η γυναίκα που είναι ανήσυχος/ανήσυχη/ ανήσυχοι να<br />

µείνει/µείνουν εδώ.<br />

12. Η φοιτήτρια ή ο φοιτητής που είναι σίγουρος/ σίγουρη/σίγουροι για κάθε επιλογή θα<br />

πετύχει/πετύχουν<br />

13. Ο µαθητής ή η µαθήτρια µπορεί/µπορούν να ενηµερωθεί/ενηµερωθούν από τους γονείς<br />

για την αιτία.<br />

14. Ο γιος ή η κόρη χρειάζεται/χρειάζονται βοήθεια.<br />

15. Η µητέρα ή το αγόρι ετοιµάζεται/ετοιµάζονται για έξοδο;<br />

16. Eτοιµάζεται/ετοιµάζονται η µητέρα ή το αγόρι για έξοδο;<br />

17. Η µητέρα ή το αγόρι είναι έτοιµη/έτοιµο/έτοιµοι για έξοδο;<br />

18. Είναι έτοιµη/έτοιµο/έτοιµοι η µητέρα ή το αγόρι για έξοδο;<br />

19. Ο άνδρας ή η γυναίκα είναι έτοιµος/έτοιµη/έτοιµοι να ξεκινήσει/ξεκινήσουν;<br />

20. Ο µαθητής ή η µαθήτρια είναι πρόθυµος/πρόθυµη/πρόθυµοι να συνεχίσει/συνεχίσουν τη<br />

δουλειά;<br />

21. Εγώ ή εσύ θα χρειαστώ/χρειαστείς/χρειαστούµε βοήθεια.


22. Εγώ ή ο Κώστας θα αναλάβω/αναλάβει/αναλάβουµε τη δουλειά.<br />

23. Εσύ ή ο Γιώργος θα αποφασίσεις/αποφασίσει/αποφασίσετε για το σπίτι.<br />

24. Εσύ ή η Μαρία θα πας/πάει/πάµε στο γιατρό;<br />

25. Εγώ ή ο Κώστας θα πάρω/πάρει/πάρουµε την επιχείρηση;<br />

26. Εσύ ή εγώ θέλεις/θέλω/θέλουµε βοήθεια;<br />

27. Θα πας/πάει/πάµε εσύ ή η Μαρία στο γιατρό;<br />

28. Θα αναλάβω/αναλάβεις/αναλάβουµε εγώ ή εσύ την εταιρεία;<br />

29. Το αυτοκίνητο ή τα µηχανάκια θα πουληθεί/πουληθούν σύντοµα.<br />

30. Το µωρό ή τα παιδιά χρειάζεται/χρειάζονται πιο πολύ προσοχή;<br />

31. Ο πρόεδρος ή οι υπουργοί θα µιλήσει/µιλήσουν στο συνέδριο;<br />

32. Οι γάτες σου ή ο σκύλος µου έφαγε/έφαγαν τα λουλούδια µου;<br />

33. Τα κορίτσια ή ο γιος θα κληρονοµήσει/κληρονοµήσουν το σπίτι.<br />

34. Οι καρέκλες ή το τραπέζι θέλει/θέλουν βάψιµο;<br />

35. Οι ποδοσφαιριστές ή ο διαιτητής κερδίζει/κερδίζουν πολλά χρήµατα<br />

36. Οι αδελφές ή ο αδελφός σου είναι ταχτοποιηµένοι/ταχτοποιηµένες/ταχτοποιηµένος<br />

37. Ο αδελφός ή οι αδελφές σου έχει/έχουν δουλειά;<br />

38. Ο πατέρας ή οι κόρες είναι υπεύθυνος/υπεύθυνοι/υπεύθυνες για την εταιρεία.<br />

39. Οι κόρες ή ο πατέρας είναι υπεύθυνος/υπεύθυνοι/υπεύθυνες για την εταιρεία.<br />

40. Ετοιµάζεται/ετοιµάζονται το κορίτσι ή τα αγόρια σου για τις εξετάσεις;<br />

41. Ετοιµάζεται/ετοιµάζονται τα κορίτσια ή το αγόρι σου για τις εξετάσεις;<br />

NAME:………………………………………………………………………<br />

THANKS A LOT FOR YOUR HELP!!!


QUESTIONNAIRΕ 2<br />

DISJUNCTION<br />

Choose any one or two of the follow<strong>in</strong>g items!<br />

1. Ή ο γιος ή η κόρη µου θα πάρει/πάρουν µέρος στο διαγωνισµό.<br />

2. Ή η µητέρα ή η γιαγιά θα αναλάβει/αναλάβουν την επιµέλεια<br />

3. Ή το αγόρι ή το κορίτσι θα αντιµετωπίσει/αντιµετωπίσουν τα σηµερινά προβλήµατα.<br />

4. Ή ο πατέρας ή η µητέρα είναι υπεύθυνοι/υπεύθυνος/υπεύθυνη για την επιµέλεια του παιδιού.<br />

5. Ή ο γιος ή η κόρη είναι ικανός/ικανοί/ικανή να δώσουν συµβουλές.<br />

6. Ή ο αδελφός ή η αδελφή µου θα περάσει/περάσουν στο πανεπιστήµιο.<br />

7. Ή ο θείος ή η θεία µου θα αναλάβει/αναλάβουν το µαγαζί.<br />

8. Ή εγώ ή εσύ έχω/έχεις/έχουµε δικαίωµα συµµετοχής στον αγώνα.<br />

9. Ή εγώ ή εσύ θα αναλάβω/αναλάβεις/αναλάβουµε την επιχείρηση.<br />

10. Ή εσύ ή ο πατέρας θα υπογράψεις/υπογράψετε/υπογράψει τα χαρτιά.<br />

11. Ή εσύ ή η Μαρία έχεις/έχετε/έχει την ευθύνη για τη δουλειά.<br />

12. Έχεις/έχουν/έχει ή εσύ ή η Μαρία την ευθύνη για τη δουλειά;<br />

13. Θέλεις/θέλω/θέλουµε ή εγώ ή εσύ να πάρεις/πάρω/πάρουµε τη δουλειά;<br />

14. Ή εσύ ή αυτός θα πάρει/πάρεις/πάρετε µετεγγραφή.<br />

15. Ή οι κόρες ή η µητέρα θα πάει/πάνε εκδροµή.<br />

16.. Ή εµείς ή αυτοί θα συνεργαστούµε/συνεργαστούν µαζί τους.<br />

17. Ή τα µωρά ή το παιδί θα πάρει/πάρουν δώρο φέτος.<br />

18. Ή ο πατέρας ή τα παιδιά θα δουλέψει/δουλέψουν στην επιχείρηση.<br />

19. Ή εγώ ή αυτός αγαπάω/αγαπάει/αγαπάµε την δουλειά του/µάς.<br />

20. Ή εσείς ή τα παιδιά θα αποφασίσετε/αποφασίσουν για την επόµενη χρονιά.<br />

21. Ούτε το αγόρι ούτε το κορίτσι είναι έτοιµο/έτοιµα γι αυτήν την αλλαγή.<br />

22. Ούτε ο πατέρας ούτε ο γιος ενέκρινε/ενέκριναν την αγορά της εταιρείας.<br />

23. Ούτε ο άνδρας ούτε η γυναίκα συµβιβάζεται/συµβιβάζονται την σηµερινή εποχή.<br />

24. Ούτε ο πατέρας ούτε η µητέρα είναι χαρούµενη/χαρούµενος/χαρούµενοι µε αυτή τη<br />

κατάσταση.<br />

25. Ούτε ο πελάτης ούτε η πελάτισσα είναι ικανοποιηµένος/ικανοποιηµένη/ικανοποιηµένοι µε


την άνοδο στις τιµές.<br />

26. Ούτε εσύ ούτε αυτός θα δεχτείς/δεχτεί/δεχτείτε την προσφορά<br />

27. Ούτε εσύ ούτε εγώ χρειάζοµαι/χρειάζεσαι/χρειαζόµαστε βοήθεια.<br />

28. Ούτε τα κορίτσια ούτε η µητέρα είναι σύµφωνη/σύµφωνες για τη µετακόµιση.<br />

NAME:………………………………………………………………………<br />

THANKS A LOT FOR YOUR HELP!!!


Bibliography<br />

Alonso-Ovalle, Luis. 2006. Disjunction <strong>in</strong> Alternative Semantics. Ph.D. thesis, University<br />

of Massachusetts Amherst.<br />

Ambrose, Alice and Morris Lazerowitz. 1962. Fundamentals of Symbolic Logic. New York:<br />

Holt, R<strong>in</strong>ehart and W<strong>in</strong>ston.<br />

Aust<strong>in</strong>, Peter K. 2001. Lexical Functional Grammar. In N. Smelser and P. Baltes, eds.,<br />

International Encyclopedia of the Social and Behavioural Sciences, pages 8748–8754.<br />

http://www.l<strong>in</strong>guistics.unimelb.edu.au/contact/staff/petter/Elsevier.pdf: Elsevier.<br />

Bach, Emmon. 1989. Informal Lectures on Formal Semantics. Albany, NY: State University<br />

of New York Press.<br />

Badecker, William. 2007. A feature pr<strong>in</strong>ciple for partial agreement. L<strong>in</strong>gua 117:1541–1565.<br />

Badecker, William. 2008. Gender resolution: The role of markedness and feature uniformity<br />

<strong>in</strong> agreement with conjo<strong>in</strong>ed noun phrases. John Hopk<strong>in</strong>s University, Draft.<br />

Barker, Stephen. 1985. The Elements of Logic. New York: McGraw-Hill.<br />

Barret, Robert B. and Alfred J. Stanner. 1971. The myth of the exclusive ‘or’. M<strong>in</strong>d<br />

80(317):116–121.<br />

Bateman, Nicoleta and Maria Pol<strong>in</strong>sky. 2005. Rumanian as a two-gender language. Unpublished<br />

LSA handout.<br />

Benor, Sarah B. and Roger Levy. 2006. The chicken or the egg? A probabilistic analysis<br />

of English b<strong>in</strong>om<strong>in</strong>als. Language 82(2):233–278.<br />

Bloomfield, Leonard. 1962. Language. New York: Holt, Re<strong>in</strong>hart and W<strong>in</strong>ston.<br />

Bresnan, Joan. 1997. Mixed categories as head shar<strong>in</strong>g constructions. In M. Butt and<br />

T. H. K<strong>in</strong>g, eds., On-l<strong>in</strong>e Proceed<strong>in</strong>gs of the LFG97 Conference. Stanford, CA: CSLI<br />

Publications.<br />

Bresnan, Joan. 2001. Lexical-Functional Syntax. Oxford: Blackwell Publish<strong>in</strong>g Ltd.<br />

Bresnan, Joan. 2001c. Optimal syntax. In J. Dekkers, F. van der Leeuw, and J. van de<br />

Weijer, eds., Optimality Theory: Phonology, Syntax and Acquisition, chap. 10. Oxford:<br />

Oxford University Press.<br />

Bresnan, Joan, Ronald Kaplan, and Peter Peterson. 1985b. Coord<strong>in</strong>ation and the flow of<br />

<strong>in</strong>formation through phrase structure. Palo Alto, CA: Xerox Park.<br />

Brody, Baruch A. 1973. Logic: Theoretical and Applied. Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-<br />

Hall.


BIBLIOGRAPHY 233<br />

Chomsky, Noam. 1957. Syntactic Structures. The Hague: Mouton.<br />

Clairis, Christos, George D. Bab<strong>in</strong>iotis, (<strong>in</strong> cooperation with Amalia Mozer, Aikater<strong>in</strong>i<br />

Bakakou-Orfanou, and Stavro Skopetea). 2004. A Grammar of <strong>Modern</strong> <strong>Greek</strong>: a<br />

Structural-Functional-Communicative Approach. Athens: Ell<strong>in</strong>ika Grammata.<br />

Copi, Irv<strong>in</strong>g M. 1971. Introduction to Logic. New York: Macmillan.<br />

Corbett, Greville G. 1979. The <strong>Agreement</strong> Hierarchy. Journal of L<strong>in</strong>guistics 15:203–224.<br />

Corbett, Greville G. 1983a. Hierarchies, Targets and Controllers: <strong>Agreement</strong> Patterns <strong>in</strong><br />

Slavic. London: Croom Helm Ltd.<br />

Corbett, Greville G. 1983b. Resolution rules: <strong>Agreement</strong> <strong>in</strong> person, number and gender. In<br />

G. Gazdar, E. Kle<strong>in</strong>, and G. K. Pullum, eds., Order, Concord and Constituency, pages<br />

175–206. Dordrecht: Foris.<br />

Corbett, Greville G. 1991. Gender. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.<br />

Corbett, Greville G. 2000. Number. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.<br />

Corbett, Greville G. 2001. <strong>Agreement</strong>: Terms and boundaries. In William Griff<strong>in</strong>, ed.,<br />

The Role of <strong>Agreement</strong> <strong>in</strong> Natural Language: Proceed<strong>in</strong>gs of the 2001 Texas L<strong>in</strong>guistic<br />

Society Conference, pages 109–122. Aust<strong>in</strong>, Texas.<br />

Corbett, Greville G. and Norman M. Fraser. 1993. Network morphology: a DATR account<br />

of Russian nom<strong>in</strong>al <strong>in</strong>flection. Journal of L<strong>in</strong>guistics 29:113–142.<br />

Corbett, Greville G. and A. D. Mtenje. 1987. Gender agreement <strong>in</strong> Chichewa. Studies <strong>in</strong><br />

African L<strong>in</strong>guistics 18:1–38.<br />

Dalrymple, Mary. 2001. Lexical Functional Grammar, vol. 42 of Syntax and Semantics<br />

Series. Stanford, CA: Academic Press.<br />

Dalrymple, Mary, Helge Dyvik, and Tracy H. K<strong>in</strong>g. 2004a. Copular complements: closed or<br />

open? In M. Butt and T. H. K<strong>in</strong>g, eds., On-l<strong>in</strong>e Proceed<strong>in</strong>gs of the LFG04 Conference,<br />

pages 188–198. Stanford, CA: CSLI Publications.<br />

Dalrymple, Mary and Bozhil Hristov. 2010. <strong>Agreement</strong> patterns and coord<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>in</strong> Lexical<br />

Functional Grammar. In M. Butt and T. H. K<strong>in</strong>g, eds., Proceed<strong>in</strong>gs of the LFG10<br />

Conference, pages 186–206. Stanford, CA: CSLI Publications.<br />

Dalrymple, Mary and Ronald Kaplan. 2000. Feature <strong>in</strong>determ<strong>in</strong>acy and feature resolution.<br />

Journal of Language 76(4):759–798.<br />

Dalrymple, Mary, Ronald Kaplan, and Tracy H. K<strong>in</strong>g. 2004b. L<strong>in</strong>guistic generalisations<br />

over descriptions. In M. Butt and T. H. K<strong>in</strong>g, eds., On-l<strong>in</strong>e Proceed<strong>in</strong>gs of the LFG04<br />

Conference, pages 199–208. Stanford, CA: CSLI Publications.<br />

Dalrymple, Mary, Ronald Kaplan, John T. Maxwell, and Annie Zaenen, eds. 1995. Formal<br />

Issues <strong>in</strong> Lexical-Functional Grammar. Stanford, CA: CSLI Publications.<br />

Dalrymple, Mary, John Lamp<strong>in</strong>g, Fernando Pereira, and Vijay Saraswat. 2002. L<strong>in</strong>ear logic<br />

for mean<strong>in</strong>g assembly. In S. Manandhar, G. P. Lopes, and W. Nutt, eds., Proceed<strong>in</strong>gs of<br />

Computational Logic for Natural Language Process<strong>in</strong>g. Ed<strong>in</strong>burgh.<br />

Dalrymple, Mary and Irena Nikolaeva. 2006. Syntax of natural and accidental coord<strong>in</strong>ation:<br />

evidence from agreement. Language 82(4):824–849.


BIBLIOGRAPHY 234<br />

de Swart, Henriette. 1998. Introduction to Natural Language Semantics. Stanford, CA:<br />

CSLI Publications.<br />

Dougherty, Ray C. 1970. A grammar of coord<strong>in</strong>ate conjo<strong>in</strong>ed structures, Part I. Language<br />

46(4):850–898.<br />

Dougherty, Ray C. 1971. A grammar of coord<strong>in</strong>ate conjo<strong>in</strong>ed structures, Part II. Language<br />

47(2):298–339.<br />

Eggert, Randall. 2002. Disconcordance: The Syntax, Semantics and Pragmatics of or-<br />

<strong>Agreement</strong>. Ph.D. thesis, University of Chicago, Chicago: Ill<strong>in</strong>ois.<br />

Falk, Yehuda N. 1984. The English auxiliary system: A Lexical-Functional analysis. Language<br />

60(3):483–509.<br />

Falk, Yehuda N. 2001. Lexical-Functional Grammar: An Introduction to Parallel<br />

Constra<strong>in</strong>t-based Syntax. Stanford, CA: CSLI Publications.<br />

Farkas, Donka F. 1990. Two cases of underspecification <strong>in</strong> morphology. L<strong>in</strong>guistic Inquiry<br />

4(21):539–550.<br />

Farkas, Donka F. and D. Zec. 1995. <strong>Agreement</strong> and pronom<strong>in</strong>al reference. In G. C<strong>in</strong>que and<br />

G. Giusti, eds., Advances <strong>in</strong> Rumanian L<strong>in</strong>guistics, pages 83–101. Philadelphia: John<br />

Benjam<strong>in</strong>s.<br />

Fassi-Fehri, Abdelkader. 1981. Complémentation et Anaphore en Arabe <strong>Modern</strong>e: Une<br />

Approche Lexicale Fonctionelle. Ph.D. thesis, Univeristé de Paris III, Paris, France.<br />

Flouraki, Maria and Desp<strong>in</strong>a Kazana. 2009. Constra<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g disjunctive constructions <strong>in</strong><br />

<strong>Modern</strong> <strong>Greek</strong>. In M. Butt and T. H. K<strong>in</strong>g, eds., On-l<strong>in</strong>e Proceed<strong>in</strong>gs of the LFG09<br />

Conference, pages 282–296. Stanford, CA: CSLI Publications.<br />

Fowler, Henry W. 1926. A Dictionary of <strong>Modern</strong> English Usage. London: Oxford University<br />

Press.<br />

Francis, Ela<strong>in</strong>e J. and Laura A. Michaelis. 2000. Approaches to mismatch: <strong>in</strong>troduction.<br />

In M. Butt and T. H. K<strong>in</strong>g, eds., Proceed<strong>in</strong>gs of the BFG00 Conference Workshops. The<br />

University of California, Berkeley: CSLI Publications.<br />

Gazdar, Gerald. 1980. A cross-categorial semantics for coord<strong>in</strong>ation. L<strong>in</strong>guistics and Philosophy<br />

3(3):407–409.<br />

Genesereth, Michael R. and Nils J. Nilson. 1987. Logical Foundations of Artificial Intelligence.<br />

San Mateo, CA: Morgan Kaufmann Publishers.<br />

Georgakakos, George. 1979. Elementary Formal Logic. New York.<br />

Givon, Talmy. 1970. The resolution of gender conflicts <strong>in</strong> Bantu conjunction: when syntax<br />

and semantics clash. In Papers from the Sixth Regional Meet<strong>in</strong>g Chicago L<strong>in</strong>guistic<br />

Society, pages 250–261. Chicago: Chicago L<strong>in</strong>guistic Society.<br />

Greenberg, Joseph. 1966. Language Universals: With Special Reference to Feature Hierarchies.<br />

The Hague: Mouton.<br />

Haspelmath, Mart<strong>in</strong>. 2004a. Coord<strong>in</strong>at<strong>in</strong>g Constructions. Amsterdam: John Benjam<strong>in</strong>s.<br />

Haspelmath, Mart<strong>in</strong>. 2007. Coord<strong>in</strong>ation. In T. Shopen, ed., Language Typology and<br />

Syntactic Description, vol. 2, pages 1–51. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2nd<br />

edn.


BIBLIOGRAPHY 235<br />

Heycock, Carol<strong>in</strong>e and Roberto Zamparelli. 1999. Toward a unified analysis of DP conjunction.<br />

In P. Dekker, ed., Proceed<strong>in</strong>gs of the Twelfth Amsterdam Colloquium, pages<br />

127–132. University of Amsterdam: ILLC.<br />

Heycock, Carol<strong>in</strong>e and Roberto Zamparelli. 2000. Friends and colleagues: plurality and<br />

NP coord<strong>in</strong>ation. In M. Hirotani, A. Coetzee, N. Hall, and J.-Y. Kim, eds., Proceed<strong>in</strong>gs<br />

of the 30th Annual Meet<strong>in</strong>g of the North Eastern L<strong>in</strong>guistic Society, vol. 30. Rutgers<br />

University.<br />

Heycock, Carol<strong>in</strong>e and Roberto Zamparelli. 2003. Coord<strong>in</strong>ated bare def<strong>in</strong>ites. L<strong>in</strong>guistic<br />

Inquiry 34(3):443–469.<br />

Heycock, Carol<strong>in</strong>e and Roberto Zamparelli. 2005. Friends and colleagues: plurality, coord<strong>in</strong>ation<br />

and the structure of DP. Natural Language Semantics 13(3):201–270.<br />

Hoeksema, Jack. 1988. The semantics of non-Boolean ‘AND’. Journal of Semantics<br />

6(1):19–40.<br />

Holton, David, Peter Mackridge, and Irene Philippaki-Warburton. 1997. <strong>Greek</strong>: A Comprehensive<br />

Grammar of the <strong>Modern</strong> Language. London: Routledge.<br />

Horrocks, Geoffrey. 1987. Generative Grammar. London: Longman.<br />

Hurford, James R. 1974. Exclusive or <strong>in</strong>clusive disjunction. Foundations of Language<br />

11(3):409–411.<br />

Jenn<strong>in</strong>gs, Ray E. 1966. Or. Analysis 26:181–184.<br />

Jenn<strong>in</strong>gs, Ray E. 1994. The Genealogy of Disjunction. USA: Oxford University Press.<br />

Johannessen, Janne Bondi. 1996. Partial agreement and coord<strong>in</strong>ation. L<strong>in</strong>guistic Inquiry<br />

27(4):661–676.<br />

Joseph, Brian D. and Irene Philippaki-Warburton. 1987. <strong>Modern</strong> <strong>Greek</strong>. Croom Helm<br />

Descriptive Grammar Series. London: Routledge Kegan and Paul.<br />

Kameyama, M. 1985. Zero Anaphora: The Case of Japanese. Ph.D. thesis, Stanford<br />

University.<br />

Kamp, Hans and Uwe Reyle. 1993. From Discourse to Logic: An Introduction to Model<br />

Theoretic Semantics of Natural Language, Formal Logic and Discourse Representation<br />

Theory, vol. 1,2 of Studies <strong>in</strong> L<strong>in</strong>guistics and Philosophy. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic<br />

Publishers.<br />

Kaplan, Ronald. 1995. The formal architecture of Lexical-Functional Grammar. In M. Dalrymple,<br />

R. Kaplan, J. T. M. III, and A. Zaenen, eds., Formal Issues <strong>in</strong> Lexical-Functional<br />

Grammar, pages 7–27. Stanford, CA: CSLI Publications.<br />

Kaplan, Ronald and Joan Bresnan. 1982. Lexical Functional Grammar: A formal system<br />

for grammatical representation. In J. Bresnan, ed., The Mental Representation of<br />

Grammatical Relations, chap. 4, pages 173–281. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.<br />

Kaplan, Ronald and John T. Maxwell. 1988. Constituent coord<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>in</strong> Lexical-<br />

Functional Grammar. In Proceed<strong>in</strong>gs of the 12th International Conference on Computational<br />

L<strong>in</strong>guistics (COLING88), vol. 1, pages 303–305. Budapest.


BIBLIOGRAPHY 236<br />

Kathol, Andreas. 1999. <strong>Agreement</strong> and the syntax-morphology <strong>in</strong>terface <strong>in</strong> HPSG. In<br />

R. Lev<strong>in</strong>e and G. Green, eds., Studies <strong>in</strong> Contemporary Phrase Structure Grammar.<br />

New York: Cambridge University Press.<br />

Kazana, Desp<strong>in</strong>a. 2007. Gender resolution <strong>in</strong> <strong>Modern</strong> <strong>Greek</strong>. In Essex Graduate Student<br />

Papers <strong>in</strong> Language and L<strong>in</strong>guistics, vol. 9, pages 39–56. University of Essex: Department<br />

of Language and L<strong>in</strong>guistics.<br />

Kearns, Kate. 2000. Semantics. <strong>Modern</strong> L<strong>in</strong>guistics Series. England: Macmillan.<br />

Keenan, Edward L. and Leonard M. Faltz. 1985. Boolean Semantics for Natural Language.<br />

Studies <strong>in</strong> L<strong>in</strong>guistics and Philosophy. Boston: D. Reidel.<br />

K<strong>in</strong>g, Tracy H. and Mary Dalrymple. 2004. Determ<strong>in</strong>er agreement and noun conjunction.<br />

Journal of L<strong>in</strong>guistics 40(1):69–104.<br />

Kokkonidis, Miltiadis. 2005. Why glue a donkey to an f-structure when you can constra<strong>in</strong><br />

it and b<strong>in</strong>d it <strong>in</strong>stead? In M. Butt and T. H. K<strong>in</strong>g, eds., On-l<strong>in</strong>e Proceed<strong>in</strong>gs of the<br />

LFG05 Conference, pages 238–252. Stanford, CA: CSLI Publications.<br />

Kuhn, Jonas and Louisa Sadler. 2007. S<strong>in</strong>gle conjunct agreement and the formal treatment<br />

of coord<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>in</strong> LFG. In M. Butt and T. H. K<strong>in</strong>g, eds., On-l<strong>in</strong>e Proceed<strong>in</strong>gs of the<br />

LFG07 Conference, pages 302–322. Stanford, CA: CSLI Publications.<br />

Lakoff, Rob<strong>in</strong>. 1971. If’s, and’s and but’s about conjunction. In Fillmore and Langendeon,<br />

eds., Studies <strong>in</strong> L<strong>in</strong>guistic Semantics, pages 115–149. New York: Holt, Re<strong>in</strong>hart and<br />

W<strong>in</strong>ston.<br />

Lambrecht, Knud. 1984. Formulaicity, frame semantics and pragmatics <strong>in</strong> German b<strong>in</strong>omial<br />

expressions. Language 60(4):753–796.<br />

Langendoen, D. Terence. 1970. Essentials of English Grammar. New York: Holt, R<strong>in</strong>ehart,<br />

W<strong>in</strong>ston.<br />

Larson, Richard. 1985. On the syntax of disjunction scope. Natural Language and L<strong>in</strong>guistic<br />

Theory 3(2):217–264.<br />

Lumsden, John. 1992. Undespecification <strong>in</strong> grammatical and natural gender. L<strong>in</strong>guistic<br />

Inquiry 3(23):469–86.<br />

Mackridge, Peter. 1985. The <strong>Modern</strong> <strong>Greek</strong> Language. Oxford: Oxford University Press.<br />

Malouf, Robert. 1998. Categories, prototypes and default <strong>in</strong>heritance. In G. Bouma, G.-J.<br />

Kruijff, and R. Oehrle, eds., Proceed<strong>in</strong>gs of the Jo<strong>in</strong>t Conference on Formal Grammar,<br />

Head-Driven Phrase Structure Grammar and Categorial Grammar, pages 207–216. Saarbrucken.<br />

Manicas, Peter T. 1976. Logic: The Essentials. New York: McGraw-Hill.<br />

McCloskey, James. 1986. Inflection and conjunction <strong>in</strong> <strong>Modern</strong> Irish. Natural Language<br />

and L<strong>in</strong>guistic Theory 4(2):245–282.<br />

M<strong>in</strong>assian, Martiros. 1980. Grammaire d’ Armenien Oriental. Delmar, NY: Caravan.<br />

Montague, Richard. 1973. The proper treatment of quantification <strong>in</strong> English. In P. Suppes,<br />

J. Moravcsik, and J. H<strong>in</strong>tikka, eds., Approaches to Natural Language. Dordrecht: Reidel.


BIBLIOGRAPHY 237<br />

Moosally, Michelle. 1998. <strong>Noun</strong> Phrase Coord<strong>in</strong>ation: Ndebele <strong>Agreement</strong> Patterns and<br />

Cross-L<strong>in</strong>guistic Variation. Ph.D. thesis, University of Texas at Aust<strong>in</strong>, Aust<strong>in</strong>.<br />

Moosally, Michelle. 1999. Subject and object coord<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>in</strong> Ndbele: An HPSG analysis.<br />

In S. Bird, A. Carnie, J. D. Haugen, and P. Norquest, eds., Proceed<strong>in</strong>gs of the WCCFL<br />

18 Conference. Somerville, MA: Cascadilla Press.<br />

Morgan, Jerry. 1972. Verb agreement as a rule of English. In P. Peranteau, J. Levi,<br />

and G. Phares, eds., Papers from the Eighth Regional Meet<strong>in</strong>g of the Chicago L<strong>in</strong>guistic<br />

Society, pages 278–286. Chicago: Chicago L<strong>in</strong>guistic Society.<br />

Morgan, Jerry. 1984. Some problems of agreement <strong>in</strong> English and Albanian. In C. Brugman<br />

and M. Macaulay, eds., Proceed<strong>in</strong>g of the Berkeley L<strong>in</strong>guistic Society, vol. 10, pages 233–<br />

247. Berkeley: Berkeley L<strong>in</strong>guistics Society.<br />

Morgan, Jerry. 1985. Some problems of determ<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>in</strong> English number agreement. In<br />

G. Alvarez, B. Brondie, and T. McCoy, eds., Proceed<strong>in</strong>g of the First Eastern States<br />

Conference on L<strong>in</strong>guistics, pages 69–78. Columbus, Ohio: Ohio State University.<br />

Moyse-Faurie, Claire and John Lynch. 2004. Coord<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>in</strong> Oceanic languages and Proto<br />

Oceanic. In M. Haspelmath, ed., Coord<strong>in</strong>at<strong>in</strong>g Constructions, pages 445–498. Amsterdam:<br />

John Benjam<strong>in</strong>s.<br />

Nordl<strong>in</strong>ger, Rachel and Joan Bresnan. To appear. Lexical-Functional Grammar: Interactions<br />

between morphology and syntax. In R. D. Borsley and K. Börjars, eds., Non-<br />

Transformational Syntax: A Guide to Current Models. Oxford: Blackwells.<br />

Nunberg, Geoffrey. 1977. The Pragmatics of Reference. Ph.D. thesis, City University of<br />

New York, New York.<br />

Nunberg, Geoffrey. 1995. Transfers of mean<strong>in</strong>g. Journal of Semantics 12(2):109–132.<br />

Nunberg, Geoffrey. 2005. The pragmatics of deferred <strong>in</strong>terpretation. In L. R. Horn and<br />

G. Ward, eds., The Handbook of Pragmatics, chap. 15, pages 344–364. UK: Blackwell.<br />

Parker, Frank. 1983. Number <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>def<strong>in</strong>ite pronouns and correlatives. University of South<br />

Florida Language Quarterly 22(1-2):13–16.<br />

Partee, Barbara H., Alice ter Meulen, and Robert E. Wall. 1993. Mathematical Methods<br />

<strong>in</strong> L<strong>in</strong>guistics. Studies <strong>in</strong> L<strong>in</strong>guistics and Philosophy. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic<br />

Publishers, 2nd edn.<br />

Partridge, Eric. 1956. Usage and Abusage: A Guide to Good English. London: Hamish<br />

Hamilton.<br />

Pelletier, Francis J. 1978. Or. Theoretical L<strong>in</strong>guistics 4(1).<br />

Peterson, Peter. 1986. Establish<strong>in</strong>g verb agreement with disjunctively conjo<strong>in</strong>ed subjects:<br />

strategies vs. pr<strong>in</strong>ciples. Australian Journal of L<strong>in</strong>guistics 6(2):231–249.<br />

Pollard, Carl and Ivan A. Sag. 1994. Head-Driven Phrase Structure Grammar. Chicago:<br />

The University of Chicago Press.<br />

Pr<strong>in</strong>ce, Alan and Paul Smolensky. 2002. Optimality Theory: Constra<strong>in</strong>t Interaction <strong>in</strong><br />

Generative Grammar. Maden, MA: Blackwell.<br />

Qu<strong>in</strong>e, William V. 1972. Methods of Logic. New York: Holt, R<strong>in</strong>ehart and W<strong>in</strong>ston.


BIBLIOGRAPHY 238<br />

Quirk, Randolph and Sidney Greenbaum. 1973. A University Grammar of English. London:<br />

Longman.<br />

Rub<strong>in</strong>, Ronald and Charles M. Young. 1989. Formal Logic: a Model of English. California:<br />

Mayfield Publish<strong>in</strong>g Co.<br />

Sadler, Louisa. 1997. Clitics and the structure-function mapp<strong>in</strong>g. In M. Butt and T. H.<br />

K<strong>in</strong>g, eds., On-l<strong>in</strong>e proceed<strong>in</strong>gs of the LFG97 Conference. Stanford, CA: CSLI Publications.<br />

Sadler, Louisa. 1999. Non-distributive features and coord<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>in</strong> Welsh. In M. Butt<br />

and T. H. K<strong>in</strong>g, eds., On-l<strong>in</strong>e proceed<strong>in</strong>gs of the LFG99 Conference. Stanford, CA: CSLI<br />

Publications.<br />

Sadler, Louisa. 2003. Coord<strong>in</strong>ation and asymmetric agreement <strong>in</strong> Welsh. In M. Butt<br />

and T. H. K<strong>in</strong>g, eds., Nom<strong>in</strong>als: Inside and Out, pages 85–118. Stanford, CA: CSLI<br />

Publications.<br />

Sadler, Louisa. 2006. Gender resolution <strong>in</strong> Rumanian. In M. Butt, M. Dalrymple, and T. H.<br />

K<strong>in</strong>g, eds., Intelligent L<strong>in</strong>guistic Architectures: Variations on Themes by Ron Kaplan,<br />

pages 437–454. Stanford, CA: CSLI Publications.<br />

Sadock, Jerrold M. 1991. Autolexical Syntax. Chicago: Chicago University Press.<br />

Schalley, Andrea C. and Dietmar Zaefferer, eds. 2007. Ontol<strong>in</strong>guistics: How Ontological<br />

Status Shapes the L<strong>in</strong>guistics Cod<strong>in</strong>g Concepts. Trends <strong>in</strong> L<strong>in</strong>guistics: Studies and<br />

Monographs. Berl<strong>in</strong>: Mouton de Gruyer.<br />

Schane, Sanford A. 1970. Phonological and morphological markedness. In M. Bierwisch<br />

and K. E. Heidolph, eds., Progress <strong>in</strong> L<strong>in</strong>guistics, pages 286–294. The Hague: Mouton.<br />

Schwarzschild, Roger. 1996. Pluralities. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.<br />

Siewierska, Anna. 2004. Person. Cambridge Textbooks <strong>in</strong> L<strong>in</strong>guistics. Cambridge, UK:<br />

Cambridge University Press.<br />

Simons, Mandy. 1998. Or: Issues <strong>in</strong> the Semantics and Pragmatics of Disjunction. Ph.D.<br />

thesis, Cornell University.<br />

Spencer, Andrew. 2002. Gender as an <strong>in</strong>flectional category. Journal of L<strong>in</strong>guistics 38:279–<br />

312.<br />

Stassen, Leon. 2000. AND-languages and WITH-languages. L<strong>in</strong>guistic Typology 4(1):1–54.<br />

Tapscott, Bangs L. 1976. Elementary Applied Symbolic Logic. New Jersey: Prentice-Hall,<br />

Englewoods Cliffs.<br />

Tarski, Alfred. 1941. Introduction to Logic and to the Methodology of Deductive Sciences.<br />

New York: Oxford University Press, Revised 1946.<br />

Triantaphyllidis, Manolis. 1994. Neo-elleniki Grammatiki. Athens: Organismos Ekdoseon<br />

Didaktikon Biblion.<br />

Triantaphyllidis, Manolis. 2005. Neoelleniki Grammatiki tis Dimotikis. Thessaloniki: Aristotle<br />

University of Thessaloniki, Institute of Manolis Triantafillidis, 2nd edn.


BIBLIOGRAPHY 239<br />

Villavicencio, Al<strong>in</strong>e, Louisa Sadler, and Doug Arnold. 2005. An HPSG account of closest<br />

conjunct agreement <strong>in</strong> NP coord<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>in</strong> Portuguese. In S. Muller, ed., The Proceed<strong>in</strong>gs<br />

of the 12th International Conference on Head-Driven Phrase Structure Grammar, pages<br />

427–447. Stanford, CA: CSLI Publications.<br />

V<strong>in</strong>cent, Nigel and Kersti Börjars. 2000. Feature resolution and the content of features. In<br />

M. Butt and T. H. K<strong>in</strong>g, eds., On-l<strong>in</strong>e proceed<strong>in</strong>gs of the LFG00 Conference. Stanford,<br />

CA: CSLI Publications.<br />

Wälchli, Bernhard. 2005. Co-compounds and Natural Coord<strong>in</strong>ation. Oxford: Oxford University<br />

Press.<br />

Wechsler, Stephen. 2009. ‘Elsewhere’ <strong>in</strong> gender resolution. In K. Hanson and S. Inkelas,<br />

eds., The Nature of the Word-Essays <strong>in</strong> Honor of Paul Kiparsky, pages 567–586.<br />

Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.<br />

Wechsler, Stephen and Larisa Zlatić. 2000. A theory of agreement and its application to<br />

Serbo-Croatian. Language 76(4):799–832.<br />

Wechsler, Stephen and Larisa Zlatić. 2003. The Many Faces of <strong>Agreement</strong>. Stanford, CA:<br />

CSLI Publications.<br />

W<strong>in</strong>ter, Yoad. 1997. Choice functions and the scopal semantics of <strong>in</strong>def<strong>in</strong>ites. L<strong>in</strong>guistics<br />

and Philosophy 20(4):399–467.<br />

Yatabe, Shûichi. 2004. A comprehensive theory of coord<strong>in</strong>ation of unlikes. In S. Muller, ed.,<br />

The Proceed<strong>in</strong>gs of the 11th International Conference on Head-Driven Phrase Structure<br />

Grammar. Stanford, CA: CSLI Publications.<br />

Zwicky, Arnold M. 1977. Hierarchies of person. In W. A. Beach, S. E. Fox, and S. Philosoph,<br />

eds., Papers from the Thirteenth Regional Meet<strong>in</strong>g, Chicago L<strong>in</strong>guistic Society, pages<br />

714–733. Chicago.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!