04.01.2014 Views

Equal Opportunities Work - Theories about Practice

Equal Opportunities Work - Theories about Practice

Equal Opportunities Work - Theories about Practice

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

<strong>Equal</strong> <strong>Opportunities</strong> <strong>Work</strong><br />

GOTEBORG UNIVERSITY 2OO2<br />

ii,ii j,ili.i:ri;:;.i.r';,i,;rl:,<br />

i'i'",:":,';,1;,t,;,:::'.i'rt:<br />

1'1,;,iji;<br />

i:. , ,-l1,,, ;.l,1,; i ,,11 ;;1,;;;;;.,,;,;it,t ,<br />

,. 1,''. ;:,, ; :' i,., r, :' ;;=,;, :',L.t,:,r'.: i,;,<br />

;1, ;,; ;,<br />

1.,1 ;:.:,,<br />

i :::;::':i<br />

ii.: i';, i i,:; 1<br />

:,. :,,,<br />

i.it,,i 1;,: ;<br />

;:,;,::; ,;;,:t,',i:1i ,,,:,;;t,t,,',,t,,,,,' ,',,1i,,, r,:',,' ,,<br />

',i,.t t , ,r.,i, :,,,r;,:it.,;:;;;.;;;.;;::::,11,<br />

;;1, , '<br />

',',,,, 1i,t, . l'. '.,.,,;.-.-,i', i,<br />

.;,'.i;',<br />

cOrpsoRc<br />

UNIVERSITY


Printed in Sweden<br />

Elanders Graphic Systems AB 2002


<strong>Equal</strong> <strong>Opportunities</strong> <strong>Work</strong><br />

<strong>Theories</strong> <strong>about</strong> <strong>Practice</strong><br />

By Eua Mark<br />

GOTEBoRG UNIVERSITY 2OO2


Foreword ............ ............r. ...........2<br />

<strong>Work</strong>ing for equal opportunities, fair treatment and quality........ 4<br />

1. Introduction............ ...............4<br />

2. Arguments put forward by the Swedish national authorities in favor of an equal<br />

opportunities policy ............4<br />

3. <strong>Work</strong>ing for equal opportunities.............. .................7<br />

4. <strong>Equal</strong> opportunities work as a matter of quality ........................ S<br />

5. <strong>Equal</strong> opportunities, quality and the male norm ...................... 10<br />

6. <strong>Equal</strong> opportunities work and the differences between the sexes<br />

7. <strong>Equal</strong> opportunities as a matter of justice...<br />

t2<br />

t7<br />

The gender perspective and equal opportunities work................. 20<br />

1. Introduction............ ..........20<br />

2. The gender perspective, research quality and equal opportunities..............................22<br />

3. Gender research, awareness of sex and gender and education ............ ......29<br />

Sexual harassment and equal opportunities work........................,32<br />

1. Introduction............ .............32<br />

2. Theory and practice................ ...............32<br />

3. What is sexual harassment?............... ......................33<br />

4. Sexuallv offensive behavior... ................35<br />

5. <strong>Equal</strong> opportunities work and the |aw............. ..........37<br />

6. Sexual harassment and the gender perspective ......40<br />

7. Power in the structural and phenomenological senses .............41<br />

8. Gender. socialization and autonomy. 43


Foreword<br />

What makes equal opportunities work so difficult to accomplish? The answer, of<br />

course, has to do with various kinds of resistance and exercising of power. But<br />

effective, efficient equal opportunities work also requires clear thinking. I hope<br />

this text might contribute to dispelling some confusion.<br />

It is difficult to pursue equal opportunities work today for many reasons,<br />

including the fact that the terms and concepts used are vague and require<br />

clearer definitions, and that the arguments put forward tend not to be<br />

sufficiently well thought-through and that traditional arguments may be<br />

repeated without critical consideration. This text attempts to sharpen the terms<br />

and the arguments, taking equal opportunities work in practice as its point of<br />

departure. If we are to work effectively in the area of equality of opportunity<br />

we do need to think <strong>about</strong> it more clearly. However, that will not be sufficient<br />

in itself.<br />

The notions and arguments analyzed below were taken from two fields of<br />

practical work with equal opportunities - the political and the organizational.<br />

As the title implies, this text proposes theories <strong>about</strong> what practitioners are<br />

doing. All such terms and ways of reasoning are, of course, national by nature,<br />

and must be seen in their respective contexts. In our increasingly globalized<br />

world, we must also learn to consider our national phenomena in an<br />

international perspective. This helps us to understand them more thoroughly.<br />

This text has been translated from Swedish into English in hopes of triggering<br />

a dialogue on equal opportunities work in an international context.<br />

Studies of universities and other institutes of higher education have confirmed<br />

the notion that they are "bastions of masculinity". A number of efforts have been<br />

made to produce policies promoting equal opportunities between women and<br />

men, with a view to counteracting this situation. These policies have focused on<br />

bringing <strong>about</strong> institutional reform and achieving organizations where greater<br />

equality prevails.<br />

However, progress in this area is slow, and today our universities and<br />

institutes of higher education are still anything but models of equality. What<br />

can we do, in reality, to bring <strong>about</strong> changes so our organizations better reflect<br />

equal opportunities? What should our action plans contain, and how should


esponsibilities be delegated? The time has come to make a critical<br />

examination of different ways of pursuing equal opportunities, and to debate<br />

how we should work in this field. We need to know more <strong>about</strong> the various<br />

interpretations of the problem complex surrounding equality, <strong>about</strong> different<br />

perspectives on the impediments to equality within organizations, <strong>about</strong> the<br />

different ways in which efforts to achieve equal opportunities between women<br />

and men have been institutionalized at universities and institutes of higher<br />

education, and <strong>about</strong> what measures need to be taken so that existing policies<br />

produce results.<br />

One of the aims of this booklet is to begin building up a theoretical<br />

foundation for work in the area of equal opportunities, to draw up theories on<br />

the basis of a survey of practices. I hope that these theories will provide a<br />

justification for the implementing of strategic measures, which should, in turn,<br />

provide greater opportunities for the underrepresented sex. This, in turn,<br />

should motivate both sexes to participate in further work to promote equality.<br />

Another aim underlying this booklet is to produce a constructive analysis of<br />

the contradictions in the information available in official (Swedish<br />

government) publications on the subject of equal opportunities between<br />

women and men.<br />

I wish to stress that this text is not an attempt to draw up a specific equal<br />

opportunities policy. Rather, it is my aspiration to provide material for<br />

discussion, useful as a tool in furthering equal opportunities work at the<br />

reader's own level. Such discussions must always be rooted in practical<br />

experience, and this experience may also serve as implicit arguments.


<strong>Work</strong>ing for equal opportunities, fair treatment and quality<br />

1. Introduction<br />

Why should any organizatton put effort into improving its equal opportunities<br />

policy? Simply in order to comply with the legislation? Out of a desire to<br />

abolish prevailing injustices? As part of an overall reform and development<br />

program for the organization in question?<br />

It is crucial that everyone involved in work with equal opportunities policy<br />

think through personal answers to those questions. In fact, doing so is a<br />

prerequisite to being able to accomplish anything in relation to those efforts.<br />

This is true not least because working with equality issues often implies having<br />

one's views subjected to skeptical scrutiny. This makes it all the more<br />

important to be able to motivate what we are doing, for ourselves and others.<br />

This presentation is based on a description of how equal opportunities<br />

policies are justified by the powers that be in Sweden. We examine their<br />

argumentation, highlight their hidden agendas and assumptions, and examine<br />

different possible interpretations. The aim of this booklet is to provide a<br />

platform for discussion of why any organization should put time and energy<br />

into developing and pursuing an equal opportunities policy.<br />

2. Arguments put forward by the Swedish national authorities in favor of<br />

an equal opportunities policy<br />

A Swedish government document entitled Jiimstrilldhetspolitiken ( "F;qual<br />

Opportunity Policy " 1996/97:41) states the following objectives for an equal<br />

opportunities policy:<br />

The objectives for an equal opportunities policy have been<br />

established. They are that women and men are to have the same<br />

options, rights and obligations in all the significant spheres of human<br />

life. An even distribution of power and influence between women and<br />

men also means that they should have the same potential for financial<br />

independence, and be subject to the same terms and conditions with<br />

regard to entrepreneurship, employment and working life, as well as<br />

the same opportunities for further training and skill enhancement at<br />

I


work. It also means equal access to education, and possibilities for<br />

self-fulfillment, pursuing interests and talents, and sharing<br />

responsibility for the home and children, as well as the absence of<br />

sexualized (sex/gender-related) violence in their lives.r<br />

The overarching motivation underlying this equal opportunities policy is thus<br />

justice -- fair treatment -- and its main points of departure are: the prevailing<br />

imbalance of power between women and men, the imbalance between them with<br />

regard to financial independence, and the imbalance between them with regard<br />

to responsibility for children and the home. The aim is to achieve a structural<br />

transformation of society, includes a redistribution of rights and obligations in<br />

favor of the underrepresented sex would take place. The need for this<br />

transformation is based on insights regarding the different living conditions that<br />

apply to men and women today: a picture of society reflecting a division by<br />

sexes.<br />

The justice-based argument for equal opportunities is underpinned in<br />

another way by the powers that be in their formulation of the application of<br />

equal opportunities to comprehensive school education. A report from the<br />

Ministry of Education on equal opportunities states:<br />

<strong>Equal</strong> opportunities at school means that girls and boys are to have<br />

equivalent terms and conditions to discover, test and develop their full<br />

potential as human beings. For this to be possible, knowledge must be<br />

made available as to the differences and similarities between the<br />

sexes, and as to the impact of sex role affiliation on education.2<br />

In this context, equal opportunities are seen as meaning that both sexes have an<br />

equal chance to develop their human potential. A prime prerequisite for equal<br />

opportunities at school is a deeper understanding of the impact of sex role<br />

affiliation, and its pedagogical consequences for the individual. Thus equal<br />

opportunities become both a subject for study, and a matter for consideration in<br />

terms of teaching methods.3 Once again, the prime mover is justice, but with a<br />

1 Swedish government circular 1996197:41 Jiimstiilldhetspolitiken,("<strong>Equal</strong> <strong>Opportunities</strong> Policy", p. 5). See also<br />

Draft bill 1993194:147 Delad makt, delat ansvar ("Shared Power, Shared Responsibility"), Government circular<br />

l999l2O0O:24 Jtimstiilldhetspolitiken infdr 2000talet, ('Equat <strong>Opportunities</strong> Policy Entering the Twenty-First<br />

Century", p. 6).<br />

2 Offi.iul communication from government ministries 1994:98 Vi iir alla olika, ("We'reAll Different," p. 20).<br />

" This view is repeated in the draft bill:1994/95:164 Jtimsttilldhet mellan kvinnor och mrin inom<br />

utbildningsomrddet, ("<strong>Equal</strong> <strong>Opportunities</strong> Between Women and Men in the Field of Education, p. l2).


substantially different argument in terms of comprehensive schooling than in<br />

other areas of society.<br />

It should be clear from the above both that the Swedish authorities' view of<br />

equal opportunities in public education is based on the assumption that there<br />

are fundamental differences between the sexes, and also that this view is at<br />

least somewhat differently motivated than the general justification for an equal<br />

opportunities policy. In the general policy, the focus is more at the structural<br />

level. But when it comes to equal opportunities at school, the focus is<br />

completely individual.<br />

In the discussion pursued by the Swedish authorities of equal opportunities<br />

at universities and institutes of higher education, a third justification for an<br />

equal opportunities policy arises. There, it is seen not only as a democratic<br />

right, and thus a matter of justice, but also as a matter of quality. Briefly:<br />

having an equal opportunities policy is a means of improving quality.a<br />

What this means, concretely, in the sphere of higher education, is that<br />

working for equal opportunities is said to improve the quality of scientific,<br />

scholarly and educational performance.5 Efforts being made in terms of equal<br />

opportunities are also to be included when the Swedish National Agency for<br />

Higher Education makes quality assessments. This makes equal opportunities<br />

work justifiable not only from the point of view of justice, but also of costbenefit.6<br />

How, then, should equal opportunities work be justified within any<br />

organization? As we have seen, the two main arguments of the Swedish<br />

authorities are the justice argument and the quality argument. What differences<br />

result when each of these arguments is implemented? What do discussions<br />

<strong>about</strong> equal opportunities policies actually mean in relation to quality? Isn't the<br />

justice argument sufficient in itself?<br />

4 <strong>Equal</strong> opportunities work as a quality issue is one of the main themes of the final report from the<br />

"JAST"<br />

group (the <strong>Work</strong>ing Group on <strong>Equal</strong> <strong>Opportunities</strong> in Higher Education and Research. See Official<br />

communication from government ministries 1997:56 Jiimstiilldhet ft)r kunskap, insikt och kvalitet ("<strong>Equal</strong><br />

opportunities for knowledge, insights and quality". Further, see Official communication from government<br />

ministries 1994:l3O Kaftlciggning och utviirdering av jiimstiilldhetsprojekt inom universitet och hdgskolor<br />

("Surveying and Assessing the Quality of <strong>Equal</strong> <strong>Opportunities</strong> Projects at Universities and Other Institutes of<br />

Higher Education", pp. l -15).<br />

5 Offi.iul communication from government ministrie s 1997.56 Jrimsttiltdhet fbr kunskap, insikt och kvalitet,<br />

("<strong>Equal</strong> <strong>Opportunities</strong> for Knowledge, Insights and Quality". p.100).<br />

6 One additional way ofjustifying work for equal opportunities from a cost-benefit point of view is to clarify<br />

that equal opportunities work is profitbearing. See report from Nutek (the Swedish National Board for Industrial<br />

and Technical Development) 1999: 19 Jcimstrilldhet & linsamhet (<strong>Equal</strong> <strong>Opportunities</strong> and Profitability'). This<br />

particular argument for equal opportunities work falls beyond the scope ofthis article.


3. <strong>Work</strong>ing for equal opportunities<br />

Before going into the details of and discussing the different arguments for equal<br />

opportunities, let us examine how work for equal opportunities is pursued. In the<br />

Swedish government commission report on equal opportunities, different<br />

approaches are described.<br />

One is implementing active measures to ensure that all existing<br />

organizations comply fully with the <strong>Equal</strong> <strong>Opportunities</strong> Act. Another is<br />

regarding equal opportunities work as one aspect of the vital changes that need<br />

to be brought <strong>about</strong> in organizations, with a view to making each workplace a<br />

fairer place, and to improving quality.<br />

In the first case, the structure of each existing organization is taken as a<br />

given, as the basis from which change may be achieved. For instance, one<br />

ambition might be to increase the representation of the underrepresented sex in<br />

management or leadership positions, but without calling the traditional role of<br />

the management into questionT. The second case is more idyllic or utopian, and<br />

sees equal opportunities as one of the things that could characteri ze a more<br />

perfect organization, i.e. that it would acknowledge the equal right to existence<br />

of both sexes.<br />

In other words, we must distinguish between efforts to increase equality of<br />

opportunity for both sexes within the framework of existing society, and<br />

efforts to achieve equality of opportunity in a future, but presently non-existent<br />

society, with a different paradigm of values relating to sex and gender. In the<br />

first case, working for equal opportunities often implies adapting women to the<br />

world of men, and marginalizing "female experience". Society is being guided<br />

in a male direction, and male thinking is what determines what aims and<br />

positions are worth striving for. The way of life of men is regarded as the<br />

general, gender-neutral norm. One pertinent example is the way girls and<br />

women are encouraged to adapt and to apply for admission to programs in<br />

technology.<br />

.| ' It is necessary to distinguish between increased representation, in numbers, of the underrepresented sex, and<br />

the distribution of the underrepresented sex in the organizational hierarchy. Better representation of the<br />

underrepresented sex may reflect the intention and desire ofthe organization to create even distribution of<br />

women and men, while the distribution of the underrepresented sex in the organizational hierarchy reflects the<br />

representation of women and men at different levels in the organization, and thus reflects career potential. The<br />

recruitment policy of an organization may reflect equal opportunities, but still not enable womenand men to<br />

climb the career ladder equally. See report from Nutek (the Swedish National Board for Industrial and Technical<br />

Development) 1999:19 Jiimstiilldhet & Ldnsamhet (<strong>Equal</strong> <strong>Opportunities</strong> and Profitability").


There has long been strong emphasis on education, preferably in<br />

technology or the natural sciences, in order to fulfill the needs of trade<br />

and industry. Substantial resources have also been invested in<br />

persuading girls and young women to make "non-traditional" choices<br />

in terms of what they would study. such campaigns have been<br />

described as a way of promoting equal opportunities. At the same<br />

time, a large number of other areas of competence in which women<br />

have traditionally been dominant, have ceased to be considered<br />

important enough to be worth studying. Nor have there been nearly as<br />

many drives to encourage young men to make non-traditional<br />

choices.8<br />

Thus it becomes clear that working for a utopian kind of equal opportunities<br />

means touching on fundamental organizational changes, focusing on new, nontraditional<br />

norns and patterns evolving from the experience and conditions of<br />

life of both women and men.<br />

This requires fundamental change, not just increasing the numbers of the<br />

underrepresented sex in any existing organization or the value of female ideas<br />

in a structure defined by men, or enabling the underrepresented sex to more<br />

easily be promoted to high positions in an existing organization.<br />

who benefits from efforts to improve equality of opportunity? The<br />

underrepresented sex? Everyone in an organization? Although there is no<br />

question that a majority of the underrepresented sex, the sex that may be<br />

subject to harassment or discrimination, is in favor of such work, there are<br />

strong arguments for the idea that equal opportunities work can benefit<br />

everyone working at an organization. Seen in this way, equal opportunities<br />

work is one aspect of change, contributing to making new, different<br />

organizations that are better for both women and men.<br />

4. <strong>Equal</strong> opportunities work as a matter of quality<br />

What arguments can be put forward for equal opportunities? Various kinds of<br />

quality arguments are often used in this context, so let us examine them. They<br />

give rise to the following type of questions:'Does the assertion hold water that<br />

working for equal opportunities is one aspect of quality development at a<br />

university? Can efforts to achieve equality of collaboration between women and<br />

men really improve the quality of the work carried out at an organization? After<br />

8 Gunne.ud, E., & Werners son, Vad lever vi fi)r? Om jcimstciltdhet som frihet eller ndng,SOU (Swedish<br />

Government Commission Report 1997:158, p. 106 What are We Living for? On <strong>Equal</strong> <strong>Opportunities</strong> as Freedom<br />

or Coercion")


examining these issues, we move on to equal opportunities as a matter of<br />

justice.e<br />

To begin with the concept of "quality" is defined in different ways:<br />

L Quality in the descriptive, value-judgmental sense. Attributing quality to<br />

something may be an expression of a value judgment, an assessment of<br />

something, be it an object or a phenomenon or an individual, on a given<br />

scale of values. In everyday speech, we speak of things as being of good<br />

or poor quality, and use words like "quality improvement,', etc.<br />

2. Quality in the sense of a characteristic of things or processes.<br />

3. Primary and secondary qualities. Philosophers distinguish between<br />

primary and secondary qualities. Democritos (500 B.C.) was the first<br />

philosopher to distinguish between regarding characteristics as being<br />

inherent to the thing itsell or primary, and dependent for their existence<br />

on a subjective comprehension of the thing, or secondary. Primary<br />

characteristics include scope, strength, movement and size, white<br />

secondary characteristics include color, sound, smell and taste. Secondary<br />

characteristics have a subjective existence, and come into being in our<br />

consciousness as a result of the interplay between the primary<br />

characteristics of the thing and our organs of sensory perception.<br />

So if we assume that equal opportunities work in an organization is part of the<br />

quality development work of that organization, what are we implying that the<br />

equal opportunities work is meant to contribute to developing?<br />

Considering quality in the value-judgmental sense, one relevant answer to<br />

that question would be that it is the quality of whatever the organization<br />

produces that is meant to be improved. Universities and institutes of higher<br />

education produce cumulative products: spoken or written processes. In other<br />

words, it is the quality of these processes that is to be improved. In addition to<br />

which there is quality improvement in the organization itself, such as improved<br />

management.<br />

Thus we are dealing with quality in the sense of positive evaluations and of<br />

the characteristics of a process. What characteristics are we talking <strong>about</strong>? The<br />

fundamental thought is that the perspective that includes the views of both<br />

sexes is better than a single-sex perspective. The experience of both sexes is to<br />

be drawn upon, and this will generate more issues and more potential solutions<br />

to problems, as well as taking the values of both women and men into account<br />

9 In ty view, it is essential not to be misted by the discussion on quality, and thus to neglect the link between<br />

equal opportunities and justice. The cost-benefit argument must not be allowed to gain the upper hand, at the<br />

expense of respect for basic human values. What value would the cost-benefit argument have in a recession?<br />

t0


and promoting a critical stance. Quite simply, equality of opportunities gives<br />

rise to a creative climate, and one that encourages learning. <strong>Equal</strong>ity of<br />

opportunities also has a pedagogical dimension. Good teaching is teaching that<br />

is able to integrate new experience, and add new knowledge to the existing<br />

worldview. For this reason, it is vital for the students to be able to relate what<br />

they are being taught to themselves and their own experience. And for this to<br />

be possible, the experience of both sexes must somehow be present in the<br />

teaching situation.<br />

Another quality-related argument is referred to as the "argument for the<br />

talent repository". <strong>Work</strong> with equal opportunities generates additional qualityraising<br />

features in that it means additional competence. If both sexes a.re<br />

permitted to work and operate on equal terms in the organization, it draws on<br />

the talent repository of the underrepresented sex that remains latent in<br />

organizations where equal opportunities do not prevail. Thus the quality level<br />

of the knowledge process is raised. If everyone involved in a creative process<br />

is aware of the perspective of both sexes, the quality of the process improves.<br />

Moreover, more individuals in the organization will be acknowledged as<br />

possessing useful talents.<br />

5. <strong>Equal</strong> opportunities, quality and the male norm<br />

It is necessary to justify equal opportunities work in other ways than in relation<br />

to justice, because privileged groups tend to obstruct redistribution or reequilibration<br />

of power.<br />

Seeing work for equal opportunities as a process that improves the quality of<br />

research and education provides utility arguments for such work being<br />

important and being a matter relevant to all the members of an organization. In<br />

other words, achieving equality between women and men is not only desirable<br />

for the underrepresented sex, the sex that is being infringed upon or<br />

discriminated against. It is not in the interest of any specific group, but in the<br />

interest of all. We would like to believe that true equality of opportunity is of<br />

benefit to all, for instance in that it improves the atmosphere at the workplace,<br />

and makes it both more creative and more dvnamic. l0<br />

l0 Equul opportunities are a matter ofboth give and take. A society characterized by equal opportunities<br />

assumes that both women and men are prepared to refrain from power and privilege. For instance, women will<br />

have to divest themselves of power in the home so that men can take their share, and men will have to be<br />

prepared to refrain from some power and influence in both working life and politics so that women can take their<br />

share: In these two cases, however, the kinds ofpower in question are different and cannot immediately be<br />

compared.<br />

1l


Certainly, this makes the quality argument seductive at first glance. But one<br />

obvious question is: why do we still have an imbalance of power, working<br />

duties and perspectives if equality of opportunity would raise the quality of our<br />

workplaces?<br />

Quality arguments are not as self-evident in the context of equal<br />

opportunities as they are often made out to be. We have seen that quality<br />

assessments are based on values. What values? Whose? Values that have long<br />

been regarded as part of the male nonn have governed our societies, and thus<br />

there is a clear risk that the definition of quality on which quality assessments<br />

are based will be a "male" one. In that case, high quality would mean whatever<br />

worked to the benefit of the perspective of the powers that be.<br />

We might say of quality as is said of beauty, that it is in the eye of the<br />

beholder. Because male values have long been the norm, the concept<br />

of quality has also been defined on male terms. People in positions of<br />

power generally consider it a safeguard of high quality that their own<br />

definition of quality be the accepted one. As most decision-makers are<br />

men, male values are thus upheld.ll<br />

This insight may be associated with the difference between primary and<br />

secondary qualities presented above. We found there that secondary qualities<br />

have subjective existences, contingent upon our way of perceiving phenomena<br />

in the world around us.<br />

Let us apply a subjectivist view of values: values are an expression of a<br />

subjective attitude belonging to the subject. The idea that values are subjective<br />

and attributed to occurrences is at the core of the discussion <strong>about</strong> equal<br />

opportunities work as a quality issue, because it contains a clear risk -- that all<br />

the talk <strong>about</strong> quality is actually judgments pronounced by a party with a<br />

vested interest, and based on subjective assessments and on the male nonn.<br />

If, without thinking the matter through, we allow equal opportunities work<br />

to be part of general quality improvement work, without being responsive to<br />

the fact that high quality is often defined in a way that favors the perspective of<br />

the powers that be, what we are actually doing is promoting a situation in<br />

which diversity is being reduced, and a single-gender interpretative privilege is<br />

being further consolidated. We have seen how arguing that equal opportunities<br />

have a quality-promoting effect on the operations of the organization as a<br />

1l Offi.iul communication from government ministries 1997:56 Jiimstrilldhet fdr kunskap, insikt och kvalitet,<br />

("<strong>Equal</strong> <strong>Opportunities</strong> for Knowledge, Insight and Quality" p. 34.)<br />

72


whole is one way of justifying work for equal opportunities, but if this way of<br />

reasoning is to have any other effect than to uphold the existing absence of<br />

equal opportunities, one qualification must be added: the content of the<br />

organization must already bear traces of two sexes.<br />

The claim that equal opportunities improve quality in the sense of providing<br />

an increased diversity of perspective, views on knowledge, research disciplines<br />

and competence rests on the assumption that power is already reasonably<br />

evenly distributed between women and men, and that this fairer delegation of<br />

power has had an impact on the organization.<br />

6. <strong>Equal</strong> opportunities work and the differences between the sexes<br />

The equating, on the part of the Swedish national authorities, of equal<br />

opportunities and quality improvements rests on yet another, not nearly so<br />

obvious premise: the assumption that women and men are essentially different.l2<br />

This is expressed in different ways. One example is the assumption that female<br />

leadership is qualitatively different from that of men.r3 Another is that the kind<br />

of experience and perspectives women represent differs from that represented by<br />

men.<br />

Should successful pursuit of equality of opportunity be based on the<br />

similarities or the differences between women and men? The answer to this<br />

question is that it is logically possible to base equal opportunities work on<br />

other assumptions. Moreover, there is a link between the arguments we prefer<br />

and our choice with regard to whether we see the similarities or the differences<br />

between the sexes as uppermost.<br />

The expression "equality" readily leads us to think that in order for equality<br />

to be possible, people must already be equal. And there may be more than a<br />

grain of truth to that thought. Women and men both belong to the species<br />

"human being", rather than<br />

"animal", &S Aristotle pointed out. Their very<br />

humanity endows them with a common value; they are thinking, feeling,<br />

acting, self-conscious beings. <strong>Equal</strong>ity, in the sense of equality between the<br />

sexes, may be justified on this account.<br />

12 thi, can be further divided both empirically and normatively. There is a difference berween the idea that<br />

women and men are different and that women and men should be different.<br />

l3 Cun *" know what female management style is? Are there not too few women in managerial positions for<br />

them to have been able to formulate their own kind of leadership? See Wahl, A., Ftiretagsi-edning som<br />

konstruktion av manlighet, Kvinnovetensl


But equal opportunities are also compatible with the assumption that there<br />

are fundamental differences between the sexes: women and men are different<br />

but have equal value and are to have the same rights and obligations. Thus<br />

working for equal opportunities can also be motivated on basis of the need to<br />

respect our differences. la<br />

Returning to the arguments for equal opportunities put forward by the<br />

Swedish authorities, we can see a link with the assumption that the sexes are<br />

different. Basically, Swedish equal opportunities policy is rooted in the<br />

assumption that there are fundamental differences between women and men in<br />

that they live under different terms and conditions of existence. For instance,<br />

women have substantially less power, social influence and financial<br />

independence. Here, the differences between the sexes are described in tenns<br />

of their factual situations. Women and men live in different spheres of<br />

economic and social reality.<br />

When the national authorities argue for equal opportunities at school, the<br />

assumption that the sexes are different takes on a slightly different meaning.<br />

There, it is assumed that boys and girls, men and women, are different by<br />

"nature"l5, and they have the right to be treated someone differently, because<br />

of these differences in their "natures".<br />

In the first case, when differences between the sexes are described<br />

in terms<br />

of factual circumstances and living conditions, the aim of working for equal<br />

opportunities is expressed as a "striving for likeness" and equal rights and<br />

status. Ideally, the sexes should live under equivalent conditions, meaning<br />

"shared power and shared responsibility" which, appropriately, was the title of<br />

the Swedish government's draft bill on equal opportunities policy, put for ward<br />

in 199311994.<br />

In the other case, however, when it is assumed that the differences between<br />

the sexes are explained by their being different by nature, equality of<br />

opportunity is <strong>about</strong> respecting the dffirences in ways such as knowing <strong>about</strong><br />

and using the difference between the sexes so that girls and boys can be given<br />

the educational stimuli they require.<br />

14 Th"." are at least two problem complexes here:<br />

l. What is the basis of this difference? Is it ontological, or the result of social construction, or a combination?<br />

2. How is this difference described? Is the female described as a deviation from the male norm?<br />

15 I huu" found it difficult to describe this thought exactly and adequately. Using the term<br />

"nature" brings to<br />

mind something based in biology. Speaking of human nature in sense of a social construction is inappropriate<br />

because the basic ring to the term is biological. However, it is beyond the scope of this paper to take a stand on<br />

whether sex is biological or socially constructed.<br />

r4


A third variation on the theme of equal opportunities work as a quality issue<br />

is sometimes also raised. This is that our sexual affiliation has an impact on<br />

our experience, ways of thinking, and ideals. The consequence is that men and<br />

women develop different perspectives, and think differently. And if these<br />

differences are allowed to interact in a fertile, dynamic process, creativity in<br />

the formation and transfer of knowledge will be promoted.<br />

In one sense, it is unproblematic to address the differences between the<br />

sexes as factual differences. Society is not permeated by equality today, these<br />

differences exist and have been proven time and again. Generally speaking, the<br />

aim of all efforts to achieve equality of opportunity is that women and men<br />

should have the same rights, obligations and options in their private lives, in<br />

their family situations, and professionally. This is a formal enunciation of<br />

equal opportunities, and, with a view to achieving it, many formal obstacles<br />

have also been abolished through legislation and explicit political efforts. But<br />

the indisputable fact remains: our society is far from equal. For this reason, it<br />

is essential to stress that men and women are not only meant to have the same<br />

rights, but also the same access to these formal rights, and that men must<br />

become aware of both the explicit and the implicit strategies that counteract<br />

equal opportunities.<br />

However, equal opportunities policies often rest on the unspoken premise<br />

that women should live as men have been living, that a society permeated by<br />

equality will be a society where the living conditions of women are similar to<br />

the living conditions of men today. From a political point of view, for<br />

example, it has been regarded as more important to get women onto the labor<br />

market than to get men to stay home and look after the children. Once again,<br />

the male norrn has been taken for granted, as a kind of gender-neutral truism.<br />

In the field of education, equal opportunities have been linked to the<br />

differences between the sexes, with girls being assumed to be different by<br />

nature from boys, and women being assumed to be different by nature from<br />

men, being assumed to be different by nature and therefore to have the right to<br />

different treatment in school, each being approached on the basis of his or her<br />

respective prerequisites. In this light, an understanding of the differences<br />

between the sexes and the pedagogical consequences of these differences are<br />

seen to be necessary to working for equal opportunities.<br />

Another point of departure for regarding working for equal opportunities as<br />

part of the general quality development work at any organization is that there<br />

are fundamental differences between the sexes in life experience and ways of<br />

thinking. The quality discussion is based on the idea that the two sexes are<br />

I5


complementary, and can bring different things to a workplace. (Here, there is<br />

an undertone of social construction, a hint that our sexual affiliation results in<br />

our encountering different attitudes and thus being shaped by different<br />

experience).<br />

The government level debate on equal opportunities is thus intimately<br />

intertwined with various assumptions <strong>about</strong> the differences between the sexes.<br />

How, then, are we to see the relationship between equal opportunities work<br />

and the issue of the similarities and differences between the sexes?<br />

To begin with, let us state that both the justice and the quality arguments<br />

may be based on assumptions either of inherent similarity or difference<br />

between the sexes.<br />

If we begin with justice, we may point out the similarity between the sexes,<br />

we may even call descriptions of difference mythologizing. This would<br />

indicate that there are no differences between the sexes, and that they must<br />

therefore have equal rights. However, this argument is associated with the risk<br />

that the underrepresented sex will be forced into the same traps as the other.<br />

It is equally possible to argue for equal opportunities as a matter of justice<br />

by highlighting the differences between the sexes and simultaneously<br />

demanding that they be regarded as of equal value, and have equal rights.<br />

However, there are also risks associated with seeing equality of opportunity as<br />

meaning respect for differences between the sexes, as this may lead to freezing<br />

stereotypical gender roles into place. Claming that it is important to be<br />

responsive to each individual may result in locking both sexes into their own<br />

respective traps, and inhibiting individuals from crossing traditional genderrelated<br />

boundaries. The sexes are different, and, it is understood, should<br />

remain so.<br />

As we have seen, the discussion of quality is based mainly on the idea that<br />

the sexes are different. It is, though, perfectly possible to construct a quality<br />

argument on the basis of the similarity between the sexes. The "talent<br />

repository" argument is one such example.<br />

We have seen that the assumptions both of similarity and of difference<br />

between the sexes may be used to justify equal opportunities work. In my<br />

opinion, both these views lead to restricted freedom of choice for both women<br />

and men.<br />

Another way of seeing equal opportunities work is to see it as primarily a<br />

matter of the freedom and rights of the individual to choose a lifestyle, to<br />

T6


define him or herself.r6 In line with this view, equal opportunities work<br />

provides individuals of both sexes with greater opportunities for self-fulfillment,<br />

not because they are valued either differently or similarly, in accordance with<br />

patriarchal patterns, but by having greater freedom to test sides of themselves<br />

and to experiment in life. A society permeated by equal opportunities is a<br />

society that allows different people to have different extents of personal<br />

masculinity and femininity, and to have the freedom to create their own<br />

personal way of life.<br />

16 Gunn"rud, E., & Wernersson, Vad lever vi frir? Om jiimstalldhet som frihet eller tving, SOU 1997:158, s.<br />

106. (Swedish Government Commission Report 1997:158, p. 106 (What are We Living for? On <strong>Equal</strong><br />

<strong>Opportunities</strong> as Freedom or Coercion").<br />

T7


7. <strong>Equal</strong> opportunities as a matter of justice<br />

What are the implications of seeing equal opportunities work as a matter of<br />

justice? This question is addressed below, the point of departure being that<br />

working for equality of opportunity means aiming to increase the freedom of<br />

self-definition of each individual. This gives rise to the corollary question: what<br />

is the relationship between equal opportunities, justice and personal freedom?<br />

It is a basic tenet of liberalism that there is a relationship between justice<br />

and freedom. On the one hand, we have the inviolable right of the individual to<br />

free choice in matters of life and living. The freedom to manage one's own life<br />

is a fundamental freedom, but the state may also have the right to restrict this<br />

freedom. On what grounds? Examples often used are when the rights of one<br />

individual violate those of another. or when an individual voluntarily waives<br />

certain rights.<br />

One way of describing justice is to call it the free right of an individual to<br />

choose a course of action. Naturally, this right is bound by certain limitations,<br />

such as that this choice must not violate the basic rights of others. Justice and<br />

respect for an individual's freedom of choice with regard to course of action<br />

are thus interlinked with the rights of all individuals to freely fulfill<br />

themselves.<br />

Let us go on to assume that the aim of equal opportunities work is to<br />

increase the freedom of the individual. What does that mean?r1 A human being<br />

is an agent, a thinking, feeling and acting being, who acts in a context. In<br />

thinking, feeling and acting, we are constantly relating to the world around us.<br />

As agents, we are beings in the world, we exist in situations that determine our<br />

actions to some extent, and restrict their potential, as well as the extent to<br />

which we are self-determining.<br />

We possess a certain amount of freedom and we are "relatively" selfdetermining<br />

beings. But if we return to the idea that we act in a context, it<br />

becomes clear that we are only "relatively" free and only "relatively" selfdetermining.<br />

Self-determining actions are also contingent on things beyond the<br />

control of the agent. Take an example as simple as the fact that we require<br />

opportunities. We are able to act with self-determination, but in order to<br />

exercise this ability, the opportunities and circumstances must be such that we<br />

are able to utilize our capacities to the fullest. Beyond this, many of our self-<br />

17 B.lo*, I use an individual perspective, rather than discussing the relationship between the agent and his or<br />

her fellow human beings. Increased freedom for one agent may, ofcourse, mean reduced freedom for another.<br />

18


determined decisions cannot be implemented owing to circumstances beyond<br />

our control.<br />

In our capacities as acting beings, we make different life choices, we weight<br />

up different courses of action against one another and decide how we will act.<br />

Or we may throw ourselves headlong and without much reflection into a<br />

course of action. Alternately, forces we neither know of nor believe we possess<br />

may subconsciously guide us.<br />

The freedom to create oneself is, of course, also relative to a given context.<br />

Our environment shapes us, our social circumstances, our societal situation,<br />

but we also shape ourselves. We cannot choose to be absolutely anything at all,<br />

because the context in which we live does not permit a full range of choices.<br />

Neither, however, are we predestined to be a certain way, but we do have a<br />

certain scope of freedom of choice to create and recreate ourselves. The aim is<br />

to be able to affirm different sides of ourselves, and allow these sides to crossfertilize.<br />

So what does all this talk of greater freedom actually mean? One way of<br />

describing greater freedom is simply to say that the individual has more<br />

options. The more choices I have, the freer I am. <strong>Equal</strong>ity of opportunity in an<br />

organization may be seen as one way of increasing the number of options<br />

available to those working there. Let us link this to the difference between<br />

thinking <strong>about</strong> equal opportunities work in existing and in hypothetical future<br />

otganizations. There is a major difference between working to have the<br />

underrepresented sex given greater freedom of choice in an existing structure,<br />

an actual organization, and working to ensure that in a future, not yet existing<br />

organization, both sexes will have more options available to them. This future<br />

organtzation would offer freedom of choice in a way that does not exist today.<br />

Let us now assume that the aim of equal opportunities endeavors is to<br />

increase individual freedom in terms of way of life and self-definition. Seen in<br />

this way, does equal opportunities work become a question of individuality or<br />

an issue of equal importance to both sexes?<br />

Our universities are examples of male-dominated structures, organizations<br />

shaped by men on men's terms. one way of justifying equality of opportunity,<br />

if the aim of equal opportunities work is seen as improving the situation of the<br />

underrepresented sex in an existin g organization, is to say that it will increase<br />

individual freedom, meaning greater freedom of choice for the<br />

underrepresented sex. For instance, giving the underrepresented sex more<br />

career options.<br />

T9


Is there not, then, a risk in this case that working for equal opportunities will<br />

increase male dominance in the organization -- at the level of content -- even if<br />

the number of people of the underrepresented sex in the organization<br />

increases? In that case, there is not necessarily a change in the stereotypical<br />

patterns of the traditional gender structure, and the assertion will be that<br />

whether or not to work within the structure is the free choice of each<br />

individual. The individual does have more options, but in terms of content the<br />

various options are still defined on the basis of male terms and conditions.<br />

Thus at the structural level. male dominance is further consolidated.ls<br />

Another way of looking at equal opportunities work is to see it as a step<br />

towards creating a future organization structured so as to bear traces of both<br />

sexes. The asymmetrical power relationship between the sexes would be done<br />

away with, and there would be greater freedom of choice for both sexes. The<br />

scope of opportunities for every individual would expand. It would then be<br />

possible to violate the contemporary stereotypical gender order, which is so<br />

restrictive today in terms of enabling the individual to develop him or herself<br />

completely freely.<br />

18 Th" fo[o*ing question then arises: If the number of people of the underrepresented sex in an organization<br />

increases, does this necessarily mean that the content of the organization also changes so that it bears structural<br />

traces of two sexes? Or is what happens that the male norm is simply upheld?<br />

20


The gender perspective and equal opportunities work<br />

1. Introduction<br />

This text is a study of the different relationships between gender research and<br />

equal opportunities work in practice. At least at first glance it may seem<br />

surprising that we would wish to examine the problem complex relating to<br />

gender analysis and equal opportunities work, since from a historical point of<br />

view gender research grew out of women's studies and research into equal<br />

opportunities. However, development in both these disciplines has given rise to<br />

a situation in which we must, in fact, re-examine the various ties that bind them.<br />

The three standpoints expressed by the Swedish powers that be and described<br />

below form the point of departure for this section:<br />

1. The Swedish authorities maintain that gender research raises the quality<br />

of all research, for two reasons: firstly because it expands perspectives in<br />

scholarly research, contributes new knowledge, etc. and secondly because<br />

gender research encourages equality of opportunity.le<br />

2. The Swedish authorities maintain that encouraging coursework with a<br />

gender perspective is one way of putting equal opportunities into practice. The<br />

Higher Education Agency, for example, was commissioned by the government<br />

to draw up courses relating to gender for the undergraduate degree programs in<br />

law and economics. The government also encourages the application of the<br />

gender perspective in studies in all undergraduate disciplines.2o<br />

3. The Swedish authorities also maintain that it is possible to formulate<br />

equal opportunities work both with and without a gender perspective.<br />

These three assertions indicate three problem complexes that are often<br />

confused with one another. Each of them contains, in its turn, a number of<br />

conceptual difficulties. This text goes on to analyze these conceptual issues<br />

and to discuss questions of the following type: Is it implicit in equal<br />

opportunities work to encourage courses and research with a gender<br />

perspective? Is offering courses with a gender perspective one way of<br />

19 Offi"iul government communicatio n 1999120(nl:24, Jiimstiilldhetspolitiken inf6r 2000-taler, (.<strong>Equal</strong><br />

<strong>Opportunities</strong> Entering the Twenty-First Century" p. 65).<br />

20 rura. p. os.<br />

2l


improving recruitment statistics for the underrepresented sex? And what is the<br />

relationship between gender research and equal opportunities work in practice.<br />

22


2. The gender perspective, research quality and equal opportunities<br />

A retrospective look at the arguments put forward by the powers that be in<br />

Sweden in justification of the three assertions given above provides a point of<br />

departure for discussing them.<br />

In relation to the first assertion, the assumption that gender research<br />

increases the overall quality of research, there are two main lines of<br />

argument:21<br />

a. Gender research increases general research quality because research using<br />

that perspective broadens the area of knowledge covered by any given<br />

discipline, enriches the self-awareness of science, expands the theoretical<br />

core of research, generates new knowledge and new approaches, and<br />

increases the number of relevant questions.22<br />

b. Gender research increases overall research quality because it contributes<br />

to greater equality of opportunity.23 This can, in turn, be justified in different<br />

ways:<br />

(i) Research based on a gender perspective makes women visible, increases<br />

their self-esteem and provides them with female role models. Gender research<br />

creates disciplines marked by greater equality of opportunity because it<br />

increases the number of women researchers.<br />

(ii) Gender research exposes sex-or-gender-related power hierarchies and<br />

identifies obstacles to equal opportunities, as well as contributing to enabling<br />

us to abolish these impediments to equal opportunities.2a<br />

The second point above touches on the relationship between a gender<br />

perspective, coursework and equal opportunities work. What makes<br />

encouraging the development of courses with a gender perspective part of<br />

equal opportunities work in practice? The idea is that by introducing the<br />

gender perspective in courses, we take a step towards equality of opportunity,<br />

because we contribute in an important way to fairer recruitment of women and<br />

men to all disciplines, and to efforts to break down the sexgregated labor<br />

market.25<br />

2l Offi.iul communication from government ministrie s 1996:26 Genusperspektiv i forskningen (Gender<br />

Perspective in Research)<br />

)) -- Ibid. p. 9-19.<br />

'r2,<br />

"" Ibid. p. 9-19.<br />

24 ruia. p. u.<br />

25 Offi.iut government communicatio n 199912000:24, s.65, Jiimstiilldhetspolitiken infdr 2000-taler, ("<strong>Equal</strong><br />

<strong>Opportunities</strong> Entering the Twenty-First Century" p. 65).<br />

23


The third point touches on the relationship between gender research and<br />

equal opportunities work. The idea is that equal opportunities work can both be<br />

formulated using a gender perspective, and without using it. Thus we must<br />

distinguish between gender studies and equal opportunities work in practice.<br />

Sometimes gender becomes abuzz word in the public debates, and is uses<br />

interchangeably with equal opportunities This results in misunderstandings and<br />

ambiguities, which is why the <strong>Work</strong>ing Group on <strong>Equal</strong> <strong>Opportunities</strong> in<br />

Higher Education and Research ( known in Swedish as the "JAST" group, an<br />

acronym which also means "yeast") insists on the necessity of distinguishing<br />

between these terms. Gender is primarily a theoretical concept, and a tool for<br />

the analysis and description of power relationships between men and women,<br />

or the male and the female, at different levels in society, culture and history.<br />

<strong>Equal</strong> opportunities is a matter of fair representation of women and men, and<br />

of allowing the knowledge, experience and perspectives of both women and<br />

men to penetrate education and research to equivalent extents. 26<br />

These arguments are discussed one at a time below, beginning with the idea that<br />

research on gender improves the overall quatity of research.<br />

How is "gender research" defined? Gender research is an umbrella<br />

term used to denote an extensive, dynamic research field. Gender<br />

research distinguishes between research <strong>about</strong> women and men, where<br />

women or the feminine and men or the masculine are the objects of<br />

research, and research carried out from a gender perspective. The<br />

problem of how to define a gender perspective is inherent to this field<br />

of research, and there are various, sometimes contradictorv.<br />

solutions.2T<br />

However, the word "gender" is frequently used to designate an analytical<br />

tool applicable to a large number of phenomena, such as our identity,<br />

otganizations, relationships, institutions, laws, and texts, just to mention a few.<br />

In the particular context of equal opportunities, a gender perspective is often<br />

defined as the perspective relating to sex and power. The links between these<br />

26 Offi"iuf communication from government ministrie s 1997.56, Jiimstiilldhetfiir kunskap, insikt och kvalitet,<br />

(<strong>Equal</strong> <strong>Opportunities</strong> for Knowledge, Insight and euality, p.35).<br />

11 "'<br />

Gothlin, E., Kcin eller Genus, Nationella sekretariatetftr genusforskning,2O00. "Sex or Gender", a booklet<br />

based on a lecture Eva Gothlin held at the conference entitled "The gender perspective in research and<br />

education" (Kdnsperspektiv iforskning och underttisnlng) in Gciteborg in 1999.<br />

24


two terms ate highlighted, including the asymmetrical, hierarchically<br />

structured relationships between men and women or between what is<br />

considered "feminine" and what is considered "masculine". In the latter case,<br />

the feminine and the masculine are regarded as structures that can be borne by<br />

both women and men, thus shifting the focus from the individual to the<br />

structural level. Applying a gender perspective to equal opportunities work<br />

means studying the relationships between power and sex in contexts such as<br />

organizations. Below, the term gender perspective is used in that sense.<br />

Let us now return to the two lines of argument <strong>about</strong> how a gender<br />

perspective promotes research and raises its quality. There are two different<br />

ways used of legitimatising gender research: one is that its research perspective<br />

allows neglected areas to come to the fore, gives us new approaches, new<br />

knowledge, etc. The other is that gender research promotes equal<br />

opportunities.<br />

It should be clear that these two ways of legitimatizing gender research must<br />

not be confused. In the first case, what is being discussed is the significance of<br />

gender research within science and scholarship, in the second case it is a<br />

matter of one potential field of application of gender reseurch: using the<br />

knowledge gained through it in equal opportunities work in practice. I hesitate<br />

to claim, a priori, that gender research has an overall positive impact on<br />

research quality. Of course it is a good thing when research expands to new<br />

fields and new problem complexes. But what determines the quality of<br />

research is, in my view, more the content of its hypotheses and arguments,<br />

methods, empirical tools and analyses than its subject matter. This is as true of<br />

gender research as of any other research discipline.<br />

Is it appropriate to use equal opportunities to legitimatize gender research?<br />

Is doing gender research also doing equal opportunities work? Above, it is<br />

clear that gender research is legitimatised through equal opportunities work in<br />

at least two ways: in that it contributes to equality of opportunity at<br />

universities, and in that it provides a theoretical foundation for wellfunctioning<br />

equal opportunities work.<br />

The connection between promoting gender research and recruiting the<br />

underrepresented sex is not a perfectly obvious one, and it is questionable how<br />

much weight this argument can tolerate. Gender research may be seen as one<br />

way of improving equality of opportunity, in that carrying out gender research<br />

is one way of promoting greater equality in the research environment, and the<br />

recruitment of more female research scholars. However, the extension of this<br />

argument is based on the preconception that women should do their research<br />

25


from a gender perspective. Not all women researchers are gender theorists, nor<br />

should they be. This truism must be borne in mind. The general problem of the<br />

need to recruit more women into research neither can nor should be solved by<br />

earmarking funding for gender research. Female researchers should not, any<br />

more than male researchers, be isolated to any particular pigeonhole, to<br />

separate problems or disciplines. Nor should they be primarily financed with<br />

"separate" funding. Why should women have less freedom of choice? There is<br />

another obvious risk, that this women's niche will be sidestepped in relation to<br />

"mainstream" research, regarded as peripheral and far from the cutting edge of<br />

research.<br />

Moreover, the matter of who does gender research should be a genderneutral<br />

one. The field should be equally open to men as to women.<br />

Another way of using equal opportunities to Iegitimatize gender research<br />

arises because the results of gender research are eminently useful in equal<br />

opportunities work in practice. Gender research deepens our insights into the<br />

problem complexes surrounding equal opportunities work, which is far more<br />

than simply a matter of bringing an influence to bear on attitudes and<br />

achieving fairer representation of both sexes, it is also vital to learn more abut<br />

the underlying mechanisms. And not until that knowledge is applied in<br />

practice can we find well-functioning strategies and methods for practical<br />

work with equal opportunities.<br />

This does not, however, mean that gender research is part of equal<br />

opportunities work, but rather that the results of gender research are applicable<br />

to equal opportunities work. In other words: the findings from gender research<br />

provide a point of departure for carrying out successful equal opportunities<br />

work .28<br />

This insight, that the findings from gender research provide a point of<br />

departure for carrying out successful equal opportunities work but that they<br />

must not be seen as part of the work itself, is probably the underlying<br />

assumption of the statement of the <strong>Work</strong>ing Group on <strong>Equal</strong> <strong>Opportunities</strong> in<br />

Higher Education and Research to the effect that it is essential to distinguish<br />

between gender research and equal opportunities work. In the quotation above,<br />

gender as a research perspective is distinguished from equal opportunities<br />

work in practice, the latter being described as a political activity the aim of<br />

which is to achieve fair representation between the sexes, in such a way that<br />

2^8^fn"." is a more powerful thesis claiming that gender research is an essential prerequisite for well-functioning,<br />

effective equal opportunities work. Personally, I am inclined to agree.<br />

26


oth women and men will be able to leave their mark on education and<br />

research.<br />

The quotation referred to above also leads us to ask whether or not gender<br />

research is normative. I discuss this question below, passing first through the<br />

area where the question of how to define a feminist researcher is discussed.<br />

Ulla M. Holm provides the following answer:<br />

A feminist researcher declares her stance in terms of women's politics,<br />

i.e., she takes feminist stands and is a spokesperson for ieminist<br />

issues. Her research has explicitly normative aims. Her political<br />

involvement means speaking out in favor of the liberation of *o*1<br />

from various forms of oppression and discrimination. Her theoretical<br />

considerations rest on this involvement and are an indispensable part<br />

of this liberation process.2e<br />

Here, Holm intertwines two ideas that may also be separated, In her view, a<br />

feminist researcher is characterized by her political involvement, and in doing<br />

feminist research she strives for women's liberation. Thus, the aim of her<br />

research is emancipative. Moreover, a feminist's research is based on<br />

analytical or theoretical perspectives rooted in her politicat involvement.<br />

According to Holm, this is a theoretical gender perspective. All feminists reject<br />

androcentric perspectives, and some feminists also want to see gynocentric<br />

perspectives developed.3o<br />

Let us now make an analytical distinction between basing one's research on<br />

some kind of theoretical gender perspective and working for women's political<br />

or social rights in society. We might initially call these two activities<br />

"feminism in research theory" and<br />

"feminism in politics".<br />

These two terms may be combined in four different ways, characterizing<br />

four kinds of researchers:<br />

1. Researchers who are feminists in both the theoretical and the political<br />

senses, and whose research often has explicitly emancipative aims.<br />

29 Hot., lJ., Modrande och praxis,Daidalos 1993, (..Mothering and praxis,,, p.33).<br />

30 ruia. p.tz.<br />

In this quotation, it is understood that women researchers are being discussed. Can a man be a feminist? Cannot<br />

both women and men make analyses on the basis of a gender persfective and work to promote equality of<br />

opportunity? Or is it necessary.to have personal experience ofbeing subordinated owing to on"', ,"* in order to<br />

call oneself a feminist, in which case men are excluded. Shall we .u=y tnut feminism."qoir., personal experience<br />

but that there can be gender researchers of both sexes?<br />

27


2. Researchers who are feminists in relation to theory but not in a political<br />

sense. They will tend to make descriptive analyses based on a<br />

perspective of gender theory, without normative objectives.<br />

3. Researchers who are not feminists in either sense.<br />

4. Researchers who are not feminists in the theoretical sense but who are<br />

feminists in the political sense. Their research is not emancipative in its<br />

objectives, but these researchers wish to work to promote women's<br />

liberation and the fulfillment of women's rights in other ways, for<br />

instance through different kinds of equal opportunities work, through<br />

joining women's networks, acting as mentors, etc.<br />

It should be pointed out this set of analytical distinctions. In reality, most people<br />

who refer to themselves as feminists are probably both theoretically and<br />

politically engaged. Calling oneself a feminist is a declaration of political<br />

ambitions. Still, the distinctions have their function.<br />

It is important to keep these four categories clear and not to confuse them.<br />

To begin with, let us state that gender researchers are not necessarily intent on<br />

working for equal opportunities. Gender research rtray have entirely different<br />

aims. It is perfectly possible, and in my view quite suitable, to have a term<br />

such as "gender research" that does not contains specifically normative aims.<br />

Not until we do will we be able to highlight the problem complex containing<br />

the field of tension between gender analysis and equal opportunities work.<br />

There is no doubt that gender analyses do have their uses in equal<br />

opportunities work in practice, and can provide a solid foundation for such<br />

work. But gender research per se does not have to be normative. It can be<br />

carried out as the pure pursuit of knowledge.<br />

In summary, the results of gender research both can and should be applied to<br />

equal opportunities work in practice. However, there is some question as to<br />

whether equal opportunities work in practice must encourage gender research.<br />

In practice, equal opportunities work requires not only the gender perspective<br />

but other perspectives as well. <strong>Equal</strong> opportunities work rests on an eclectic<br />

theoretical foundation that also includes organizational theory, didactics,<br />

sociology and psychology.<br />

What, then, does it mean to pursue equal opportunities work from a gender<br />

perspective? For example, the results of gender research may be used to<br />

confirm that power is unfairly distributed to the advantage of men, that<br />

women's reality is often described as an exception to the male norm, and that<br />

the relationship between the sexes is in flux. And not until we have that<br />

background can we make it clear why equal opportunities work is necessary,<br />

28


or explain what fundamental changes in society would have to take place if we<br />

were to introduce a fair distribution of power between the sexes. Although our<br />

gender analysis was not performed to promote equal opportunities, it still gives<br />

rise to questions such as the following: Why is there inequality today? Should<br />

things not change? What would the consequences of such changes be?<br />

<strong>Equal</strong> opportunities work without a gender perspective often means that the<br />

number of people of the underrepresented sex in the (existing) organization in<br />

question increases, for example through recruitment campaigns. As we have<br />

seen, such measures may be justified both in terms of justice and of quality<br />

improvements.<br />

Imposing a gender perspective on equal opportunities work means working<br />

to ensure changes with a view to altering the structure of the organization and<br />

throwing its established norms and aims into question. This is a deeper<br />

approach, in which equal opportunities work is based on an understanding of<br />

both the lack of equality in society and of the mechanisms that pose obstacles<br />

to equality and that uphold unfair relationships between the sexes. This<br />

understanding is vital to achieving sustainable equality of opportunity-and real<br />

change in an organization.<br />

What are the actual differences between working with equal opportunities<br />

with and without a gender perspective? We can elucidate this by examining an<br />

example, using an explanatory model known as " the male as normative".<br />

<strong>Equal</strong> opportunities work without a gender perspective can, for instance, mean<br />

not taking account of the male norm. The practical consequence is often that<br />

the "shortcomings" of women or girls are highlighted: their lack of interest in<br />

technology and the natural sciences, their inability to "help themselves to their<br />

fair share", their disinterest in holding management positions, ad infinitum.<br />

And it would then be these "faults" that were used to determine how equal<br />

opportunities work in practice was formulated. Networks of mentors would be<br />

set up, recruitment campaigns waged with a view to rectifying the problems<br />

and thus increasing the numbers of the underrepresented sex, just to mention a<br />

few examples.<br />

<strong>Work</strong>ing with equal opportunities on the basis of a gender perspective, on<br />

the other hand, would mean considering the problem complex surrounding the<br />

male norm, and would cast an entirely different light on the matter. The<br />

problem would no longer be regarded as a problem of women as individuals,<br />

but rather as a problem in the organization and the surrounding society. This<br />

would open people's eyes to the general structural discrimination of women<br />

and women's experience. The aim of equal opportunities work would then be<br />

29


to bring <strong>about</strong> comprehensive changes in the organization as one step in an indepth<br />

transformation of society.<br />

To me, it seems indubitably to be the case that the gender perspective<br />

provides a foundation for well-functioning equal opportunities work. However,<br />

we must not place blind faith in this perspective. As mentioned above,<br />

effective equal opportunities work that successfully increases the room for<br />

rnaneuver of the underrepresented sex also requires perspectives from<br />

disciplines other than gender research, such as organizational theory and<br />

individual psychology.<br />

3. Gender research, awareness of sex and gender and education<br />

To begin with, let us consider what it means to be aware of sex and gender<br />

when teaching, to organize the teaching situation with that awareness in<br />

mind.31<br />

It is often maintained in this context that there must be equal and equally<br />

self-evident room for both female and male perspectives in every teaching<br />

situation. This requires awareness of elements that may be sexually<br />

discriminating, on the part of teachers and students, in textbooks and in the<br />

classroom situation, and of the invisibility (and masking) of women's<br />

knowledge and perspectives in the textbooks as well as in the classroom<br />

situation. Awareness of sex and gender in the classroom means ensuring that<br />

the reading list contains works by both men and women, as well as ensuring<br />

that the students have teachers of both sexes. In addition, the roles of both<br />

female and male researchers and their work in the discipline must be clarified,<br />

and teaching forms and methods must take the learning needs, knowledge gaps<br />

and learning strategies of both women and men into account.<br />

How should the integration of awareness of sex and gender in teaching be<br />

motivated? It can be done both in terms of equal opportunities, and without<br />

referring to equality of opportunity at all. One way of justifying the need for<br />

this awareness without factoring in equal opportunities is to be purely didactic<br />

<strong>about</strong> it. Above, we have described the view that different educational<br />

3 I In this context, the authorities use expressions like<br />

"teaching with a gender perspective", see, for example,<br />

Official Government Communication l999l2OC{J -24, Jrimstiilldhetspolitiken inftir 2000+aler, ('<strong>Equal</strong><br />

<strong>Opportunities</strong> Policy for the Twenty-first Century'', p. 65). My reasoning is based on a distinction between<br />

organizing teaching with an awareness ofsex and gender, in other words taking sex/gender into account when<br />

planning teaching, and teaching with a gender perspective. These mean two different things. One is teaching<br />

<strong>about</strong> gender research, the other is analyzing the teaching situation from a gender perspective.<br />

30


approaches need to be used for girls and women than for boys and men, so that<br />

they can develop their competence and learn in the optimal way. Taking<br />

awareness of sex and gender into account in the teaching situation is also<br />

rooted in the idea that the needs of the two sexes are different in the classroom<br />

situation. Girls define problems differently than boys, ask different questions<br />

and imagine different solutions, and so they also need different educational<br />

approaches.<br />

Another didactic argument for being aware of sex and gender in the teaching<br />

situation is based on the insight that good teaching is teaching that integrates<br />

new experience and knowledge with a previously existing worldview. In other<br />

words, the student or pupil must be able to relate what the teacher is driving at<br />

to him or herself and to personal experience. To do this I must feel that the<br />

experience of my sex is represented in the classroom. This is also a<br />

prerequisite for my being able to be sure of my own perspective, to come to<br />

know that basis of my own thinking and argumentation. If I am not familiar<br />

with it, I will not be able to develop into an independent, critical thinker.<br />

It is also possible to justify the importance of awareness of sex and gender<br />

in the teaching situation by saying that it promotes equality of opportunity.<br />

<strong>Equal</strong> opportunities as a matter of justice require that school be a place where<br />

girls and are treated equivalently. In this respect, equivalent treatment means<br />

having respect for the fact that girls and women need to be taught in different<br />

ways than do boys and men. This, too, requires awareness of sex and gender in<br />

the teaching situation. As we saw in the section on equal opportunities, quality<br />

and justice, it is possible to argue that equality of opportunity generates higher<br />

quality in that it leads to skill enhancement. Introducing an awtueness of sex<br />

and gender into the classroom situation can also be seen as a way of utilizing<br />

the female competence the society of the future will need. Female competence<br />

is an unexploited reserve on the labor market. And this is precisely how the<br />

powers that be justify the introduction of gender into schools, as a way of<br />

recruiting the underrepresented sex.<br />

It is worth pointing out how the differences between the sexes are, once<br />

again, a theme in the arguments relating to awareness of sex and gender and<br />

education. Does this eventually turn into a trap, when we insist on justifying<br />

awareness of sex and gender in the classroom in terms of the inherent<br />

differences between the sexes?<br />

Let us distinguish between awareness of sex and gender in the classroom<br />

and investigating the teaching situation with a gender perspective. How do we<br />

define the latter? In my view, there are at least two options: teaching <strong>about</strong><br />

3I


gender research and analyzing the teaching situation through a gender<br />

perspective, for example regarding a certain subject area through the gender<br />

perspective or analyzing the classroom situation through the gender<br />

perspective, by which I mean applying the perspective of power relations to<br />

the sexes in the contexts of seminar culture, knowledge dissemination, reading<br />

lists, etc. This is a way of shedding light on the problem complex of sex and<br />

gender instead of (unreflectingly?) taking fundamental differences between the<br />

sexes for granted. New light is shed on the differences between the sexes by<br />

using the explanatory model of the male norm, for instance.<br />

Both teaching <strong>about</strong> gender research and examining the teaching situation<br />

through the gender perspective may be related back to equal opportunities<br />

work, because both these activities pave the way for gender awareness and<br />

insights <strong>about</strong> the need for equal opportunities work. They also pave the way<br />

for critical attitudes and approaches, which, in turn, encourage independent,<br />

critical thinking of all kinds.<br />

32


Sexual harassment and equal opportunities<br />

work<br />

l.Introduction<br />

On I July 1998 the provisions of the Swedish <strong>Equal</strong> <strong>Opportunities</strong> Act<br />

regulating the obligation of an employer to prevent and counteract sexual<br />

harassment at the workplace were made more stringent. In short, the aim of this<br />

amendment was to accentuate the fact that sexual harassment in working life is<br />

not acceptable, to introduce a definition of sexual harassment. and to stress the<br />

obligations of the employer to implement active measures to prevent, counteract<br />

and deal with sexual harassment. A regulation was added making the employer<br />

liable to pay damages if no measures are taken in relation to reports of sexual<br />

harassment.<br />

This means that work to prevent sexual harassment is, today, a legislated<br />

aspect of equal opportunities work in Sweden. But what should an individual<br />

actively working with equal opportunities do when the problem of sexual<br />

harassment arises? Is it a legal issue? A comprehensive problem in the work<br />

environment? A matter of knowledge? Or is it a question of knowing how to<br />

handle and report sexual harassment?<br />

2. Theory and practice<br />

The aim of this text is to discuss sexual harassment against the backdrop of<br />

working with equal opportunities in practice.<br />

How does one formulate a theory <strong>about</strong> what happens in practice? This is a<br />

highly problematic question. It is easy, for instance, either to<br />

overintellectualize the matter, to shroud it in mystification, or to oversimplify<br />

it in terms of black-and-white dichotomies. How can such pitfalls -- the gross<br />

dichotomies, the oversimplified views, and the altogether-too-heady<br />

expositions <strong>about</strong> practices -- be avoided? They are often related to some kind<br />

of theoretical block, such as trying to use one's pet theory as too sweeping a<br />

point of departure, or not modifying an initial hypothesis after an encounter<br />

with concrete experience.<br />

To formulate a useable theory <strong>about</strong> practice, one should oscillate between<br />

practical and theoretical endeavors, as well as testing various theories on the<br />

same phenomenon. It is vital to take account of the full range of concrete<br />

experience to be analyzed, rather than disregarding that which may be in<br />

33


conflict with the theory being applied. I prefer an eclectic method in which<br />

different theories are used to deal with different aspects of the experience<br />

under study.<br />

Sometimes it is necessary to combine concepts from different areas in<br />

creative ways, or to invent new ones, in order to develop an appropriate<br />

conceptual apparatus. It may be necessary to "start from scratch", by using<br />

concrete experience as the platform and then "designing" the analysis so<br />

different aspects of this experience is reflected and described. The objective is<br />

to analyze the practice in a manner that both does justice to the empirical<br />

factors and avoids both overintellectualizaton and over simplifications.<br />

The expression "sexual harassment" is used, as described below, to<br />

designate a large number of extremely varied phenomena. In my view, this<br />

makes it vital to put forward a multifaceted analysis before formulating an<br />

action plan, if it is to work in practice. Moreover, this analysis must be much<br />

more than the product of deskwork. It must emanate from experience of people<br />

working with sexual harassment.<br />

3. What is sexual harassment?<br />

How is sexual harassment defined? We find the following definition in section 6<br />

of the Swedish <strong>Equal</strong> <strong>Opportunities</strong> Act:<br />

It is incumbent upon the employer to take measures to prevent and<br />

counteract any employee's being subjected to sexual harassment or to<br />

the negative consequences of someone's being reported for sexual<br />

harassment. Sexual harassment is defined as any unwelcome behavior<br />

related to sex and gender or unwelcome behavior of a sexual nature<br />

that violates the integrity of the employee at the workplace.32<br />

The expression<br />

"sexual harassment" is used to denote two different phenomena:<br />

sex-or-gender-related insults and offensive actions of a sexual nature. One<br />

example of the first type of sexual harassment is when someone is bullied, made<br />

invisible, not take seriously, worked against, or ignored owing to his or her sex.<br />

Offensive actions of a sexual nature may include sexual allusions in comments,<br />

sexual jokes, touching, offensive looks or requests for sexual favors in exchange<br />

for reward or payment.<br />

32 Th" content of this section is based on the preparatory work for a Swedish government draft bill 1997 /98:55<br />

Kv innofrid ("Protection of Women").<br />

34


The core of the definition of sexual harassment lies in the actions being<br />

unwelcome by the individual at whom they are aimed. It is not possible to state<br />

exactly how the person affected should indicate that the behavior of the other<br />

party is not desirable. It may be done verbally or in writing. In some cases,<br />

however, it is clear even without anything being done by the person affected<br />

that the behavior of the subjecting party is undesirable and entails sexual<br />

harassment.<br />

The definition of sexual harassment is based on a subjective criterion: it is<br />

up to the person being subjected to the behavior to decide whether or not it is<br />

desirable and what is offensive. This subjective criterion is based on the right<br />

of every individual to integrity and self-determination.<br />

Why do we legislate <strong>about</strong> sexual harassment at all? Sexual harassment<br />

violates the right of the individual to personal integrity and self-determination.<br />

This does not only affect the person being subjected to it, but impacts on the<br />

entire workplace. Harassment leads to tension in the atmosphere, and to many<br />

people feeling insecure. People are upset, sense that there is some kind of<br />

abusive situation, and withdraw. At such a workplace, not only the person<br />

being subjected to the behavior in question works less than optimally -- even<br />

his or her workmates' capacities to perform at work are affected. In other<br />

words: productivity and creativity diminish.<br />

Men harass women, women harass men, men harass men and women harass<br />

women. Studies, however, indicate that the most frequent type of sexual<br />

harassment is when men harass women. For this reason it is asserted in the<br />

preparatory work for a draft bill submitted to the Swedish parliament and<br />

entitled Kvinnofrid ("Protection of Women") that it is important to consider<br />

sexual harassment from the perspective of sex/gender and power relations.<br />

Sexual harassment is an abuse of power on the part of the perpetrator, and it is<br />

also one aspect of more systematic oppression of women. This is what<br />

distinguishes it from bullying in general. Sexual harassment is a means of<br />

keeping women subordinate. For this reason, too, sexual harassment is<br />

considered an issue related to equal opportunities, which explains why the law<br />

on sexual harassment is an amendment to the <strong>Equal</strong> <strong>Opportunities</strong> Act.<br />

It is incumbent upon every employer to take measures to prevent and<br />

counteract any employee's being subjected to sexual harassment. Moreover,<br />

the employer may be held liable to pay damages if he does not institute an<br />

investigation when someone is reported for sexual harassment. The employer<br />

must clearly take the stand that sexual harassment will not be tolerated at the<br />

35


workplace. There must be a policy and routines for how reports of sexual<br />

harassment are to be dealt with, and the employees must know it.<br />

It is first and foremost up to the person who has been subjected to ensure<br />

that the employer is aware that sexual harassment has occurred. However,<br />

many people fear that they will not be believed. For this reason, it may be up<br />

to a workmate or a trade union representative to make what is going on known<br />

to the employer. If the employer is to be obligated by law to act, on pain of<br />

being held liable, the person who has been subjected must at least confirm the<br />

occuffence of the sexual harassment.<br />

In the preparatory work for the <strong>Equal</strong> <strong>Opportunities</strong> Act, it is pointed out<br />

that what measures should be taken when an individual experiences that he or<br />

she is begin sexually harassed must be determined from case to case. However,<br />

in all cases, the employer must immediately speak with the parties concerned<br />

with a view to clarifying the circumstances surrounding the alleged<br />

harassment. It is also stated that the employer must try to obtain some idea of<br />

the veracity of the information given by both parties, and decide what<br />

measures are needed to prevent further occurrences.<br />

4. Sexually offensive behavior<br />

Let us now reexamine the definition of sexual harassment in somewhat greater<br />

detail, focusing on three of its main components:<br />

"harassment","unwelcome"<br />

and "unwelcome behavior related to sex./gender".<br />

The verb "to harass" normally implies conscious and intentional subjection<br />

of an individual to ongoing discomfort. At any workplace, there are, however,<br />

always actions of a sexually harassing nature but where the person performing<br />

them does not intentionally mean to harass. The conscious intention may be<br />

"to be nice" or to seek contact. But even when the conscious intention is<br />

"to be<br />

nice", the function of the action may be an offensive one, keeping the person<br />

toward whom it is aimed from accomplishing things and from being<br />

comfortable at the workplace. Although sexual harassment may be perfectly<br />

conscious, it is often unconscious behaviot'3, and it is important to<br />

acknowledge the gray zone of possible unconscious behavior. And the<br />

intention of the harassing party may also be misinterpreted by the person at<br />

whom it is aimed. For instance, there are cases where the one party has had no<br />

33 Fo, u more detailed discussion of conscious and unconscious aspects of sexual harassment, see Mark, E., Vad<br />

dr sexuella trakasserier? ( "What is Sexual Harrassment?" in) Hriften ftr kritiska studier no.4, 1997 .<br />

35


scxual intention at all, but where the action has been interpreted as sexual by<br />

tbc person toward whom it was aimed, possibly as a kind of wish fulfillment.<br />

When an action is said to be unwelcome, this does not always mean it was<br />

not desired by the person at whom it was aimed. And what <strong>about</strong> the person<br />

who is being insulted -- does he or she always feel offended? Probably not. It<br />

is not uncommon that a person subjected to sexual harassment considers that<br />

behavior a natural part of the patriarchal culture, while an outsider may think it<br />

would be perfectly in order for that person to feel harassed. It is also possible<br />

that the person who was subjected will, later in life, retrospectively change his<br />

or her opinion and decide that he or she was truly being insulted at the time.3a<br />

In that case, has the subjective criterion been fulfilled? The person being<br />

harassed will absolutely not want to file either an informal or a formal report.<br />

This happens very frequently<br />

Unwelcome behavior relating to a persons' se>r/gender may be referred to as<br />

"sexually offensive behavior". Sexually offensive behavior is not usually a<br />

conscious intent to offend, is not always physical behavior, and is not always<br />

perceived as offensive by the person at whom it is aimed. Nonetheless,<br />

sexually offensive behavior is a serious problem in the work environment. Yet<br />

it is not always regarded as such. Such behavior often consists of quite small<br />

comments and innuendos, not per se always serious enough to be very upset<br />

<strong>about</strong>. Moreover, it is so common that we cannot reasonably be expected to<br />

react to every single occunence. Often, sexually offensive behavior is even<br />

part of the workplace culture and climate. But an individual who is<br />

consistently or frequently subjected to sexually offensive behavior is deeply<br />

affected by it in the long run, irrespective of the extent to which he or she is<br />

aware of it at the time. He or she may simply react with a feeling of not being<br />

happy at the workplace, of fatigue, of lack of energy, of sensing that he or she<br />

is unwelcome, of diminished self-confidence, etc. Small insults have<br />

cumulative effects, and eventually the reaction is explosive, at which point<br />

others may react with surprise and uncertainty: isn't this person exaggerating?<br />

The small incident that triggered the reaction may not have been very serious.<br />

However, it must be seen as part of a cumulative series of sexual insults and<br />

innuendos.<br />

This kind of sexually offensive behavior is not what one normally associates<br />

with sexual harassment. In "Protection of Women", the expression "sexual<br />

harassment" is described as sometimes misleading. It must be recalled that in<br />

34 ttid. p. zt.<br />

37


this context "sexual" means related both to an individual's sex/gender and to<br />

the sex act, as well as related to gender, and includes everything from sexually<br />

offensive behavior and language to any number of insulting actions somehow<br />

having to do with sex/gender and sexual affitiation. This accepted term is also<br />

used in the present context, in awareness of its limitations.<br />

Clearly, there are problems associated with using it. Not only may the word<br />

"sexual" exacerbate communication <strong>about</strong> contexts where non-sexual acts fall<br />

under the umbrella of a concept including the word sexual, but in addition this<br />

may make working with sexual harassment more difficult, in that it is often a<br />

matter of dealing with innuendo than with specifically sex-or-gender-related<br />

acts. There is also a risk of temptation to oversexualize the problem in efforts<br />

to be taken seriously.<br />

The main issue at our workplaces is related not to sexual acts but to more or<br />

less conscious sexually offensive behavior, often more of a verbal than a<br />

physical nature. This also makes it difficult to rectify, since the change would<br />

have to involve a basic attitude shift, perhaps not at the workplace so much as<br />

in society as a whole.<br />

Sexually offensive behavior, sometimes unconsciously performed and<br />

sometimes not even perceived by the person at whom it is aimed, is an<br />

expression of institutionalized attitudes and power relations. It is subtle but<br />

highly effective, and makes it more difficult for the underrepresented sex to be<br />

free and unencumbered at the workplace. In reality, sexually offensive<br />

behavior undermines equality between the sexes and this, in my view, is what<br />

should be accentuated when working to defeat sexual harassment.<br />

5. <strong>Equal</strong> opportunities work and the law<br />

Like much other legislation, the legal stipulations prohibiting sexual harassment<br />

give rise to difficulties of interpretation when they are implemented. As do most<br />

legal acts, it contains ambiguities which have to be clarified in concrete cases<br />

when the law is to be applied. Praxis is what defines this kind of prohibition. Is<br />

the fact that the law is based on a subjective criterion to be seen to mean that the<br />

person against whom the offense has been committed also has to admit feeling<br />

sexually harassed? The main rule applied in the administration of justice is that<br />

every individual must take responsibility for his or her own actions. But that is<br />

on the assumption that we act consciously and intentionally, and there are<br />

exceptions to this rule, laws in relation to which we nray be held responsible<br />

even for unintentional, unconscious actions. The ban on sexual harassment is<br />

38


particularly problematic, because such harassment takes place in situations<br />

where the parties involved have highly differing opinions regarding what is<br />

going on along the spectrum ranging from kind, encouraging attitudes to<br />

sexually offensive behavior. How are matters decided in a court of law when<br />

one person's word stands against another's?<br />

The preparatory work for the <strong>Equal</strong> <strong>Opportunities</strong> Act indicates that it is to<br />

be up to the person being subjected to the behavior to decide whether or not it<br />

is acceptable, and to define what is offensive. Are we to read this as meaning<br />

that the way one human being approaches another may only be defined as<br />

sexual harassment if and only if the one party goes on trying to approach the<br />

other after an initial rejection? And if so, what are we to do <strong>about</strong> the very<br />

common reaction among people who are subjected to such behavior: feelings<br />

of guilt and shame and the concomitant silence?<br />

Although the legal complexities of these issues are beyond the scope of this<br />

booklet, let us make a cursory examination of the relationship between the law<br />

and equal opportunities work. Of course, pursuing equal opportunities work at<br />

one's organization includes ensuring that the <strong>Equal</strong> <strong>Opportunities</strong> Act is<br />

complied with. But that is not sufficient. We must also see the legislation as an<br />

opening to work with all sex and gender related problems in the work<br />

environment, in the broadest and deepest sense of the terms. If an unwelcome<br />

approach cannot be regarded as a violation of the law, does that necessarily<br />

make it unproblematic in terms of equality of opportunity? Of course not.<br />

Another intention stated in the preliminary work for the legislation is that<br />

the Act is to safeguard individual integrity at work and in the workplace.<br />

Although sexually offensive behavior that takes place outside the workplace is<br />

not criminaltzed under the <strong>Equal</strong> <strong>Opportunities</strong> Act, it may be punishable by<br />

law pursuant to the Penal Code. If a teacher is at a party with his or her<br />

students, is he or she on duty? If he or she makes a sexual approach to a<br />

student, is that criminal, if not as a violation of the <strong>Equal</strong> <strong>Opportunities</strong> Act<br />

then perhaps under the heading of "sexual molestation"? And if it is not<br />

punishable by law at all, what can we do <strong>about</strong> it in our capacity as equal<br />

opportunities officials at our places of work?<br />

<strong>Work</strong>ing with sexual harassment must mean more than ensuring that the<br />

<strong>Equal</strong> <strong>Opportunities</strong> Act is complied with. In my view, it is vital that we not<br />

become fixated with the idea of filing formal reports or making informal<br />

verbal ones, or with wondering <strong>about</strong> what punishment might fit the offense,<br />

or with identifying the perpetrator. All these things may, of course, be<br />

necessary, but truly comprehensive equal opportunities work must focus on<br />

39


pteventiott, on intotncration, asd os creatrng a gsod. scsrk e\xiron$\ent tor both<br />

sexes.<br />

Let us return for a moment to the example of the teacher who attends a party<br />

with his or her students. Even if it is not punishable by law to approach a<br />

student it is, nevertheless, often eminently inappropriate in the given situation.<br />

No one can forbid two consenting adults from falling in love, but because a<br />

student is in a dependency relation to his or her teacher, it is certainly in order<br />

to discuss the inappropriateness of that kind of relationship. Is a pupil or a<br />

student able to say no to a teacher?<br />

What are the best ways of pursuing equal opportunities work? In the section<br />

above on equal opportunities, quality and justice, I stated that one way is by<br />

implementing concrete measures to ensure compliance with the <strong>Equal</strong><br />

<strong>Opportunities</strong> Act at any existing organization. Another is to regard equal<br />

opportunities work as one part of the process of reforming an organization.<br />

<strong>Equal</strong> opportunities work as part of a process of change is basically a matter of<br />

dissemination of knowledge.<br />

Changing an organization so that it better reflects equality of opportunity is<br />

often a matter of training the people who work there so they become aware of<br />

the structures and relationships to which they have previously been blind:<br />

introducing a perspective relating to unfair treatment of people on the basis of<br />

their sex/gender with a view to creating an organization the content of which<br />

reflects traces of two sexes, and where work is carried out under terms and<br />

conditions established by both sexes. What knowledge, then, is required in<br />

order to pursue successful equal opportunities work?<br />

To a large extent, the relations between the sexes at any given workplace are<br />

largely unconscious and unconsidered rather than being part of any thoughtthrough<br />

approach. Concrete measures taken with a view to improving equality<br />

of opportunity have very little effect as long as this remains the case.<br />

<strong>Work</strong>places need to develop knowledge processes that raise awareness of these<br />

unconscious attitudes, and until they do so there will be no motivation for<br />

implementing measures to improve equal opportunities. This essential and also<br />

preventive work entails explaining the often covert mechanisms underlying<br />

sexually offensive behavior and comments. We need to investigate the<br />

mechanisms that lead to inequality being maintained, and to take an open stand<br />

against the abuse of power associated with sexual harassment. Another field of<br />

knowledge that is a prerequisite for equal opportunities work is gender<br />

analysis, the ability to see the world from the perspectives of sex/gender and<br />

power.<br />

40


6. Sexual harassment and the gender perspective<br />

Regarding sexual harassment from a gender perspective (defined as a sex/gender<br />

and power perspective) is rewarding in many ways. Such a perspective sees<br />

sexual harassment as a way for the overrepresented sex to exercise power over<br />

the underrepresented sex, and to keep its members in a subordinate position. The<br />

common denominator is the very idea that sexual harassment entails various<br />

means of exercising power. It is oppression of a member of the underrepresented<br />

sex so that he or she feels insulted, threatened, frightened, humiliated, powerless<br />

and compelled into obedience. As we have seen above, this is not always<br />

intentional, conscious exercise of power, but can just as easily be unintentional<br />

and unconscious.<br />

Sexual harassment often takes place in a situation where power is unevenly<br />

distributed between the sexes, and where the male sex is hierarchically<br />

superior to the female sex. As men tend to be more often in power positions,<br />

they are most often also the ones to commit sexual harassment. Moreover, the<br />

person subjected to the harassment is often in a dependency relation to the<br />

individual doing the harassing, who may be an advisor, a teacher, a supervisor<br />

or someone in a managerial position. These are also often people who are in<br />

the know and whose jobs include helping others to develop and learn. These<br />

individuals are often automatically treated with respect and trust, as well as<br />

sometimes admiration simply by virtue of their positions, and it is easy to take<br />

advantage of such a position.3s<br />

In equal opportunities contexts, the debate around sex/gender has often<br />

focused on the hypothesis that there is a supra-individual level, a "gender<br />

order". One central idea in this context is that the structures a"re stronger than<br />

the individual, and if the individual is replaced, the structures will remain. This<br />

may reveal itself, for instance, in the fact that women in management positions<br />

sometimes also prove to be harassers, as well as men. Quite simply, it is<br />

inherent to the structure for people in managerial positions to behave in a<br />

certain way. A structural gender perspective provides one explanation of how<br />

harassment can be "passed down" at a workplace, that certain ways of acting<br />

and behaving are tied to a particular position.<br />

If an individual is subjected to sexual harassment and brings it up, either<br />

formally or informally, it is common for the management to react by claiming<br />

35 Th"r. may, however, be an element of sexual harassment in other relationships as well, for instance the<br />

harassing party may be the subordinate one, for instance when a students harasses his or her teacher.<br />

41


that the person in question is particularly problematic. The gender perspective<br />

shows that, instead, the problem is <strong>about</strong> the general structure of the<br />

workplace.<br />

People involved in working to combat sexual harassment know from<br />

experience that the main problem is not the one people tend to be concerned<br />

<strong>about</strong> -- that there will be unfounded reports of sexual harassment. Instead, the<br />

main problem is the compact silence of the sexually harassed. Many fewer<br />

repofts of sexual harassment are lodged than would be reflective of the actual<br />

occurence of harassment. This silence can also be at least partially explained<br />

through the gender perspective as a perspective relating to sex/gender and<br />

power. The harassed individual is often in a dependency position in relation to<br />

the harasser, is often in a subordinate position in the power relationship. The<br />

fear of retaliation is great in such a situation. But other perspectives than<br />

simply the gender perspective are necessary if we are to analyze sexual<br />

harassment in a way that opens up for equal opportunities work in practice.<br />

An institutionalized position may be held by different individuals. The<br />

position is a socially-established pattern of action and must be distinguished<br />

from the individual holding it. Although there is something to be said for<br />

highlighting the institutionalized position rather than the individual, it may be<br />

jut as fruitful to do the opposite, and emphasize the role of the individual at the<br />

expense of the institutionalized position.<br />

Although it is true that, consciously or unconsciously, we do take over<br />

attitudes associated with different institutionalized positions, there is also a<br />

personal dimension in terms of how the individual responds to the expectations<br />

associated with different social positions. We have the freedom to choose our<br />

way of relating to social expectations: we may adopt them unthinkingly, we<br />

may consciously accept them, we may revolt against them, etc.<br />

In awareness of the ambiguity of this situation, let us then distinguish<br />

between the gender perspective in a structural sense and gender as an aspect of<br />

our identity, and let us also distinguish between power in a structural sense and<br />

power in a phenomenological sense.<br />

7. Power in the structural and phenomenological senses<br />

Imposing a gender perspective means using se>


analysis of sexual harassment to use the gender perspective at the structural level<br />

in the form of a perspective relating to sex/gender and power.<br />

This reveals a structural imbalance between the sexes in an organization.<br />

The organization is run by men and is shaped on the basis of their needs.<br />

Sexual harassment is one of the mechanisms underpinning the maintenance of<br />

this male supremacy, and is an example of what happens when the freedom of<br />

maneuver of the underrepresented sex is reduced and controlled. What we are<br />

now discussing is sex/gender at the structural level, although there are, of<br />

course, individual women and men whose actions will not correspond to this<br />

description.<br />

Human identity is extremely complex. We are corporeal beings,<br />

autonomous agents, social, communicators, etc.36 When we relate gender to<br />

our identity, we must examine the relationship between sex/gender and each of<br />

these aspects. And they must be examined both individually and in their<br />

interrelations. For instance, regarding the relationship between gender and<br />

socialization gives rise to other analytical problems than examining the<br />

relationship between gender and autonomy. In addition, we must distinguish<br />

between gender in the structural sense and gender as one aspect of human<br />

identity.<br />

Above, we have discussed power at the structural level, for instance power<br />

in its capacity as the influence of the organization on its members when it<br />

comes to jargon or the social atmosphere. Sexual harassment is often, in fact,<br />

part of that jargon or atmosphere.<br />

Moving on to examine sex/gender as one aspect of our identity at the level<br />

of the individual psyche, the discussion of power shifts to a different level.<br />

Here, what is at issue is how we experience power, i.e. power as apprehended<br />

"from inside". This may be referred to as power in the phenomenological<br />

sense, power as perceived through our experience. Let us now link power in<br />

the phenomenological sense to sexual harassment. How is this form of exercise<br />

of power experienced<br />

"from inside"?<br />

Naturally, a person subjected to sexual harassment may react in any number<br />

of different ways, and there are risks associated with generalizing. However, it<br />

is not unusual for the situation to be experienced as uncertain and vague, in<br />

spite of the belief that we "know" what things are like for the underrepresented<br />

sex in an organization characterized by inequality. A person subjected to<br />

harassment often loses his or her footing and becomes confused. He or she<br />

36 See Mark, Eva., Siiitvbilder och jagkonstitution,Acta Philosophica Gothoburgensia, no.7, 1998. ("Selfimages<br />

and Ego Constitution")<br />

43


turns the blame inward, is ashamed, is afraid of reprisals, does not trust her or<br />

her own experience, and protects the perpetrator. There may also be some<br />

resistance to admitting that one is a "victim" of unfair treatment. It is both a<br />

difficult and a painful insight in itself to admit that one is being treated<br />

unjustly. Human beings also possess a certain healthy resistance to being<br />

defined as victims.<br />

A frequent result of resisting the insight that one is being subjected to<br />

structural injustice is that one ceases to trust one's own observations, feelings<br />

and thoughts, and begins to regard some side of oneself -- such as poor selfconfidence,<br />

the idea that one is incompetent, etc. -- as being at the root of the<br />

problem.<br />

The relatively small number of both formal reports and informal complaints<br />

lodged is mainly attributed to the fact that the person being subjected to the<br />

harassment faults him or herself with the problem. Another factor is the way in<br />

which sexual harassment has become a more or less accepted element of an<br />

organization's culture, so the person often feels there will be no help<br />

forthcoming.<br />

8. Gender, socialization and autonomy<br />

One consequence of using gender in the structural sense is that superiority and<br />

subordination of positions in a hierarchy are accentuated, and the exercise of<br />

power associated with this phenomenon becomes clear. The following<br />

stereotype appears: the female is subordinate, powerless and subjected to<br />

various forms of more or less covert exercise of power. The male is typically<br />

superior, has freedom of action, and is in possession of both formal and informal<br />

power.<br />

There is a clear risk in this respect that the gender perspective will result in<br />

an exaggeration of the way we discuss women as victims: the victims of<br />

oppression, the victims of failure, limitations and narrow options. In addition<br />

to which we will regard the surrounding society as oppressive and<br />

discriminating.<br />

We live in a world permeated by neither justice nor equality. If we are to<br />

achieve a society where equal opportunities reign, there is no question that we<br />

must point out the incongruities and develop satisfactory tools with which to<br />

analyze them. The gender perspective in the structural sense is one such<br />

instrument. But the result of such analyses must not be a policy of discontent<br />

which lacks clout and is associated with bitterness over lost opportunities.<br />

44


In this context, gender must be highlighted as one aspect of our identity, and<br />

we must see its relationship to the autonomy aspect of the ego of every<br />

individual. We must also stress that woman is a human being with freedom to<br />

act, an independent agent who can bring an influence to bear. We must then<br />

see that sexual harassrnent is, precisely, an impediment to action, a restriction<br />

on freedom of action.<br />

Our behavior is rooted both in socialization and autonomy, to different<br />

extents and in different ways for every individual. Certain socially-determined<br />

positions imply very little autonomy. There are occasions on which we<br />

unreflectingly fulfill the expectations of others and act as if we were virtually<br />

"socially determined". But there are other occasions on which we act with<br />

great independence and in violation of social conventions and expectations.<br />

Of course, not everything is possible. We live in a world that restricts our<br />

options for action. To some extent, these restrictions are attributable to the<br />

unequal conditions applying to women and men. This is the context in which<br />

we, as agents, can act. But we can also change the context in which we<br />

operate. This is the aim of working with sexual harassment: to change the<br />

work environment to one in which such offenses do not occur.<br />

It is possible to reform basic structures, both in an organization and in<br />

society as a whole. But doing so is extremely demanding and requires<br />

accepting the notion that things could be different, analyzing the situation and<br />

being able to see its opportunities, possessing the capacity to bring <strong>about</strong><br />

change, and having the opportunity to utilize this ability.<br />

To a large extent, equal opportunities work with a view to combating sexual<br />

harassment is <strong>about</strong> circulating information that will enable every individual to<br />

personally analyze the situation in order to open up to efforts to achieve<br />

change. Such an analysis can give a person who is being harassed the power<br />

and the energy to act instead of remaining in an enervating state of confusion.<br />

And it may sow the seeds of self-insight in the harasser.<br />

+>


References<br />

Ds 1994:98 Vi rir alla olika<br />

Ds 1994: l3O Kartkiggning och uniirdering av jcimstrilldhetsprojekt inom<br />

univ ersitet och hd g skolor<br />

Ds 1996:26, Genusperspektiv i forskningen<br />

Ds 1997:56 Jrimstrilldhetfdr kunskap, insikt och kvalitet<br />

Gannerud, E., & wernersson, vad lever vi f6r? omjiimsfiilldhet som frihet<br />

eller tving, SOU 1997:158<br />

Gothlin, E., Kcin eller Genus, Nationella sekretariatetf6r genusforskning,<br />

2000. Skriften bygger pi en fcirel[sning av Eva Gothlin som framfordes<br />

vid konferensen Kdnsperspektiv iforskning och undervisning i Gdteborg<br />

1999.<br />

Holm, U., Modrande och praxis, Daidalos 1993<br />

Mark, E., Vad iir sexuella trakasserier? Hdften ft)r kritiska studier, nr.4, 7997<br />

Mark, 8., Sj cilvbilde r o ch j agkonstitution, Acta philosophica<br />

Gothoburgensia, m.7, 1998<br />

Nutek R 1999:19, Jiimstrilldhet & Lonsamhet<br />

Proposition 1993194:147 Delad makt, delat ansvar<br />

Proposition 1994195:164 Jrimstcilldhet mellan kvinnor och mrin inom<br />

utbildningsomr&det<br />

Proposition 1997 /98:55 Kvinnofrid.<br />

Re g erin gens skrivel se 1996 / 97 : 4 | J rims t iill dhe t s p o lit iken<br />

Regeringens skrivelse 199912000:24 Jiimstrilldhetspolitiken infdr 2000-talet<br />

Wahl, A., Fdretagsledning som konstruktion av manlighet,<br />

Kv innov e t ens kapli g tidskrift, 1996l t<br />

46


GOTEBORG<br />

UNIVERSITY

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!