26.01.2014 Views

existence: semantics and syntax - Institut für Linguistik/Germanistik ...

existence: semantics and syntax - Institut für Linguistik/Germanistik ...

existence: semantics and syntax - Institut für Linguistik/Germanistik ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

TOWARDS ADYNAMIC ACCOUNT OF BE IN ENGLISH 35<br />

by an index on the metavariable: BE SK . 34 The lexical entry for is is therefore as<br />

shown in (28).<br />

(28) is<br />

IF ?Ty(e → t)<br />

THEN go(〈↑ 1 〉); put(Tns(PRES)); go(〈↓ 1 〉);<br />

put(Ty(e → t), Fo(BE SK ), ?∃x.Fo(x))<br />

ELSE ABORT<br />

3.1. Ellipsis <strong>and</strong> the Existential Focus Construction<br />

The analysis of be as a predicate underspecified for content allows us to tackle the<br />

bewildering variety of copular constructions in English in a uniform manner, the<br />

burden of explanation shifting from considerations of the core ‘meaning’ of be as<br />

denoting <strong>existence</strong> or identity to an account of inference in context that derives the<br />

correct interpretations of sentences. Assuming that the copula does project underspecified<br />

content, the value of the metavariable, BE SK , that it projects must be<br />

established. This, like all other values for metavariables, may be freely identified in<br />

context which gives us a way to account for certain types of ellipsis involving the<br />

copula, as illustrated in (29). 35<br />

(29) a. John’s really happy, John is.<br />

b. A. Who was at the meeting?<br />

B. Mary was.<br />

Under the assumption that be projects a metavariable, the elliptical utterances in<br />

(29) will be well-formed because the preceding utterance includes an accessible<br />

(<strong>and</strong> relevant) one-place predicate which can substitute for the metavariable in the<br />

normal way. The situation resulting from parsing the second clause in (29b) is<br />

shown in Figure 11 up to the point of substitution. The resulting formula is, as<br />

required, Fo(At ′ (Mary ′ ,(ɛ,y, Meeting ′ (y)))). 36<br />

34 Note that this is not defined in terms of a LINK structure. In fact, the annotation would be best<br />

construed as a K-state variable, so that BE SK might be better interpreted as λx.BE(ɛ, e, S K (e))(x).<br />

However, in the absence of a coherent theory of events within DS, I leave this possibility to one side.<br />

35 For more details about DS analyses of ellipsis in general, see Purver et al. 2006, Cann et al. to<br />

appear <strong>and</strong> Kempson et al. 2006.<br />

36 I do not in this paper pursue constraints on which predicates may be selected for substitution.<br />

Clearly, potential substituends must be recently articulated <strong>and</strong> easily accessible. They are not, however,<br />

restricted to primary predicates since (contrary to the claim by one of the referees of this paper) ellipsis<br />

on secondary predicates is perfectly acceptable in English, as shown by (i):<br />

i. Mary came home from work tired. John was, too. (So they skipped the party.)<br />

There is, however, a linearity effect. Preposed secondary predicates are often less acceptable than final<br />

ones (ii), but even these are not completely rejected by native speakers of English <strong>and</strong> (iii) is judged<br />

as more acceptable than (ii). Note that the parsing perspective of DS should enable an account of the<br />

difference in accessibility between the two positions. I do not, however, pursue this further here.<br />

ii. ?* Exhausted but elated, John finished the marathon in just over three hours. Mary was too.<br />

iii. % Drunk, John gatecrashed the party. Mary was, too (<strong>and</strong> it all went downhill from there).

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!