21.02.2014 Views

Pages 25-48 - Oswestry School

Pages 25-48 - Oswestry School

Pages 25-48 - Oswestry School

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

THE DECIMUS SOCIETY<br />

FLESH, BEING CIVILIZED AND THE<br />

HIERARCHY OF EXPERIENCE<br />

by<br />

NF Lambkin MPhil, BA (Hons), PGCE<br />

Revised paper presented to the Decimus Society<br />

February 2008<br />

I, Niall Francis Lambkin, hereby assert and give notice of my right under Section 77 of the Copyright, Design and Patents Act 1988, to be identified as the author of this essay.<br />

ABSTRACT<br />

There has been a historical debate in a number of an essentially utilitarian view regarding our relations with nonhuman<br />

creatures focussing on the principle of equal consideration<br />

philosophical/religious traditions over the issue of man’s<br />

relationship with the rest of the animal kingdom… In of interests. I premise my argument on what I take to be the entirely<br />

modern times in the West the debate centres round issues relating reasonable assumption that non-human animals are sentient, in<br />

to [1] animals being bred and killed for food, [2] animals being some cases self-conscious, and in the case of the latter that such<br />

used for medical experiments, [3] animals being used for testing non-humans have interests and in some instances may have projects<br />

cosmetics, detergents and other non-medical goods, [4] breeding and aspirations analogous to human projects and aspirations. My<br />

and killing animals for their fur, and finally [5] hunting and killing conclusion is that we do not have good reasons to exclude such<br />

animals for sport and the breeding and training of animals for non-human creatures from the moral community and that our<br />

entertainment…<br />

moral good standing is put at serious risk if we fail to consider<br />

In this paper I restrict my comments largely to the animal rights animals as legitimate objects and subjects of moral consideration.<br />

debate as it presently exercises western philosophical minds. I take<br />

ASTORY HAS IT that Pythagoras was tragically undone<br />

by his vegetarianism: having upset a crowd by his teaching,<br />

he fled in haste, gasping and panting, beaded forehead<br />

dripping, the very picture of philosophical perplexity. Alas, a bean<br />

field appeared directly in the path of his retreat and rather than<br />

trample the vegetables underfoot he stopped, lungs bursting,<br />

thoughts somersaulting, and was duly killed by the indignant mob. i<br />

His extraordinary attitude towards beans strikes the modern<br />

mind as eccentric and perhaps not a little mad—as indeed it<br />

probably is in view of what we now know of the life of beans; it<br />

is a relatively simple and uncomplicated affair. But Pythagoras had<br />

his reasons; his attitude was entirely rational it should be said,<br />

though we would also say misguided. ii The point is that rationality<br />

must necessarily lie at the root of conviction if any particular<br />

conviction is to be worthwhile and not the object of simple ridicule<br />

and contempt. Any arguments we have for holding the convictions<br />

we do should be logically sound and compelling if they are to<br />

deserve our respect. But whether arguments are sound or not does<br />

not depend upon logic alone; our reasoning may be deductively<br />

or inductively valid but our major and minor premises may be<br />

implausible, or indeed false, our general scientific laws intrinsically<br />

flawed, and therefore our conclusions unacceptable. It follows that<br />

in addition to logic we must look also to our state of knowledge,<br />

and perhaps also our imaginative faculties, if we are to produce<br />

arguments that serve to advance our understanding of what it is<br />

to live a rational and moral life in this, our quagmire of experience.<br />

In sixth-century BC the notion of kinship of all living things may<br />

have been a good enough reason for supposing beans to be treated<br />

with respect, and such a notion, coupled with the belief in<br />

metempsychosis, conspired to produce a certain compelling reason<br />

for treating beans with exceptional respect. But today the argument<br />

seems incredible in view of our biological understanding and our<br />

perception of degrees of biological and neurological complexity.<br />

So, the question I wish to address in this paper is this: given what<br />

we now know about the biological constitution of varieties of life,<br />

and given our understanding of distinctions to be made between<br />

human persons, non-human persons and the merely conscious and<br />

sentient, and given additionally our understanding of fundamental<br />

moral principles, can vegetarianism be given sufficient credibility<br />

and compelling moral force to transform the general carnivorous<br />

habits of contemporary Western man? The answer is probably yes<br />

if it is possible to restrict our behaviour by moral reasoning alone,<br />

but doubtful if we take into account also our irrational nature. It<br />

is the mixture of rationality and irrationality in the human mind<br />

that makes for the existential quagmire that is human existence<br />

and sees us stumbling and falling into one moral swamp and bog<br />

after another.<br />

What I want to do in this paper, therefore, is briefly outline the<br />

largely superficial reasons modern human persons have for taking<br />

up vegetarianism and then offer a more detailed and unusual<br />

consideration of why vegetarianism, under certain circumstances,<br />

is compellingly the most civilized moral stance to take with regard<br />

to our relation to non-human creatures.<br />

Certain modern vegetarians have been responsible for the<br />

caricature which begs mockery and ridicule, but the ancient<br />

philosophical roots of vegetarianism, and the fact that<br />

vegetarianism is still of philosophical, political and economic<br />

interest today, means that as a ‘form of living’ it needs to be looked<br />

The Oswestrian <strong>25</strong>


THE DECIMUS SOCIETY<br />

at seriously This means that our minds should be open to the<br />

cogency or otherwise of the arguments that underlie it.<br />

The vegetarian perspective can be traced back to at least 1000<br />

BC where it was given voice in the Hindu Upanishads as a<br />

consequence of the doctrine of reincarnation. Buddha taught<br />

compassion for all sentient beings and Buddhist monks were not<br />

allowed to eat animals or to eat flesh if they knew that the animal<br />

had been especially killed for their sake. The Jains iii follow a rule<br />

of non-violence towards any living creature and so accordingly do<br />

not eat meat.<br />

The Western tradition begins with Book 1 of the Bible (Genesis)<br />

where it is suggested that Man’s initial state was one of<br />

vegetarianism and that permission to eat meat was not granted till<br />

after the Flood. After that, however, Jewish, Christian and Islamic<br />

scriptures are not enthusiastic about a vegetable diet. As mentioned<br />

already, philosophical vegetarianism was a respectable stance in<br />

ancient Greece, especially among the pre-Socratics, but vegetarian<br />

sympathies can be found in the works of Plato also. Plutarch’s essay<br />

On Eating Flesh iv makes interesting reading, arguing that we should<br />

refrain from eating meat on grounds of justice and the humane<br />

treatment of animals.<br />

The 19th century saw a revival in vegetarian fortunes on<br />

grounds of health and humanity towards animals. Prominent<br />

vegetarians included the poet Percy Bysshe Shelley, Henry Salt v<br />

and George Bernard Shaw. In Germany Schopenhauer remarked<br />

that ethically we should all become vegetarian but for the fact that<br />

the human race cannot exist without meat—‘in the north’ as he<br />

put it. It seems that in this respect at least, for Schopenhauer taste<br />

and gastronomic pleasure transcended demonstrable ethical<br />

imperatives and points to the notion that imperatives are at least<br />

sometimes contingent on physical circumstances.<br />

The late 20th century, however, from the 1970s to the present,<br />

has seen in the Western world a significant rise in the number of<br />

vegetarians. There are principally four reasons for this increase:<br />

health, ecology, sentimentality and a deeper concern for the welfare<br />

of animals. I shall deal briefly with each of these in turn and then<br />

turn to the deeper philosophical considerations that are a sine qua<br />

non of coherent moral experience.<br />

HEALTH<br />

This is a fairly simple scientific issue at root. Not eating meat is<br />

either beneficial to health on the whole, or it is not. That is, if the<br />

nutrition required by the human body can be provided by eating<br />

non-flesh products, and can be so provided in a qualitatively<br />

superior manner, then it would make good sense from the point<br />

of view of bodily (and perhaps mental) health to take up<br />

vegetarianism. There could be a moral dimension here if good<br />

health is seen as an intrinsic ‘good’. If health were viewed in this<br />

way (ie, if a healthy body and mind were perceived to be necessary<br />

parts of a good vi life) then it would be the moral duty of the<br />

individual (and perhaps of society) to deliberately seek it vii .<br />

ECOLOGY<br />

Like the health issue the ecological arguments against eating flesh<br />

are largely scientific in nature, but may be given an ethical slant.<br />

The main concern arises out of the well documented inefficiency<br />

of animal-raising. Intensive farming methods come in for particular<br />

criticism because grain is grown on good agricultural land and is<br />

fed to animals confined indoors, or in the case of cattle, in crowded<br />

feed halls. It is suggested that much of the nutritional value of the<br />

grain is lost in the process and in addition this particular form of<br />

animal production is energy-intensive. Inefficient use of land and<br />

energy make for clear ecological incompetence. If ecological<br />

competence is to be desired meat production of this sort should<br />

be reformed or cut out altogether. In addition there is the issue of<br />

third world impoverishment and hunger, in part sustained by first<br />

world meat production. These ecological considerations can take<br />

on political and economic attitudes such that they become<br />

ideological. However, the possible ethical slant is significant. It<br />

might be thought that efficiency (a) is good in itself, or perhaps a<br />

justified means towards some recognized good end. If this is the<br />

case then vegetarianism may take on an imperative character.<br />

Likewise, the preservation of an environment which is as near<br />

natural as possible may be seen as a ‘good’ (b), and if vegetarianism<br />

entails a greater degree of preservation than meat production then<br />

the imperative character creeps in once more; that is to say, if (a)<br />

and (b) are ‘goods’ and vegetarianism promotes them, then we are<br />

morally obliged to stop eating meat. However, in reality it is difficult<br />

to see why efficiency, or a state of nature, or near state of nature,<br />

should be considered in themselves as goods. We can be efficient<br />

about a whole range of things we do not approve of—for example,<br />

ethnic cleansing. Viruses are natural objects, but we do not wish<br />

particularly to preserve them. It is for this reason that ethical<br />

considerations grounded in economics and ecology are not<br />

persuasive. Concern for the preservation of land, for widespread<br />

hunger, for energy conservation—these are important concerns<br />

but in themselves they have a political or economic flavour to them.<br />

To produce more philosophical concerns, the ethics of the situation<br />

have to be grounded in something more radical and fundamental,<br />

like animal rights and more profoundly the general importance of<br />

quality of experience.<br />

ANIMAL RIGHTS<br />

Animal rights is a highly contentious issue. What precisely the<br />

concept might mean is a complex matter in itself, even before we<br />

attempt to make decisions about how we ought to behave towards<br />

animals which might be said to enjoy such rights. For example, the<br />

concepts of duty and responsibility are usually linked with that of<br />

rights such that one enjoys a right if one is responsible and willing<br />

and able to carry out one’s duty towards others who might also<br />

enjoy such a right ie, show sufficient respect which accords dignity<br />

on the individual. Such rights are conferred by some authority. It<br />

is a hopeless confusion, however, to confer a right to a stone because<br />

a stone is not something which might reasonably be said to be<br />

willing and able to take up responsibilities and carry out its duties.<br />

Extrapolate with respect to the animal kingdom and we find the<br />

same confusion is likely to hold if we attempt to confer rights on<br />

slugs and rats and sloths. It might just begin to make sense with<br />

respect to the higher primates and cetaceans—but the idea remains<br />

unconvincing.<br />

It might be argued, however, that the rights which animals<br />

allegedly have are in fact ‘natural’; they are conferred by Nature<br />

and are therefore inalienable and must be respected. But here<br />

again, it is difficult to see what precisely a natural right could be;<br />

what is the authority of Nature in this context? Bentham said that<br />

the very idea of Nature creating moral imperatives was just plain<br />

confusion, claiming that ‘natural rights is simple nonsense; natural<br />

and imprescriptible rights, rhetorical nonsense—nonsense upon<br />

stilts’ viii .<br />

It is enough to say that although the animal rights issue is still<br />

open, it is quickly closing as coherent thinking is brought to bear<br />

upon this central ethical issue. It can be stated as it presently stands<br />

fairly simply. If some animals have rights, or are entitled to have<br />

their interests given equal consideration with the similar interests<br />

of human beings (staying alive, for example—reproduction, the<br />

avoidance of unnecessary pain and suffering etc.) then it is not<br />

difficult to see that eating animals may have serious ethical<br />

implications. It would be difficult to see where our right to eat meat<br />

26 The Oswestrian


THE DECIMUS SOCIETY<br />

deliberately killed for our benefit, could consistently come from.<br />

The force of the ethical vegetarian argument is that (1) by killing<br />

some animals for our food we violate their rights (interests), and<br />

(2) that on utilitarian grounds we cause more suffering through the<br />

animal industry than we gain pleasure by eating animal flesh.<br />

I find none of the above reasons for vegetarianism, formulated<br />

as they are, in the least compelling. What is lacking is a carefully<br />

formulated general rationale, already hinted at, that will guide us<br />

through difficult practical moral issues—a fundamental moral<br />

principle, in our case, that will allow us to arrive at sound<br />

conclusions regarding the moral status of animals. If we can<br />

produce such a principle then we shall be in a position to give<br />

weight to the idea that our present attitude towards certain nonhuman<br />

creatures is morally questionable.<br />

THE PRINCIPLE OF THE EQUAL<br />

CONSIDERATION OF INTERESTS ix<br />

A pre-ethical position might be this: act only according to one’s<br />

own interests—that is to say, given a choice of action decide on<br />

the course which is most likely to realize your personal interest,<br />

regardless of what consequences there might be for the interests<br />

of others. In such a pre-ethical state I simply put my needs before<br />

yours, or anyone else’s, and it is precisely this bias that makes my<br />

position pre-ethical because behaving ethically entails that I do<br />

not give preference either to myself or any designated group. To<br />

take an ethical stance is crucially to move beyond mere personal<br />

interests or the interests of any particular group (a group in which<br />

one might have a vested interest). In other words, to take a moral<br />

stance is to move beyond the individual and particular to the<br />

universal—to take an impartial view of states of affairs by achieving<br />

an ‘objective’ standpoint outside the world of particular interests.<br />

At the level of human intercourse it seems straightforward: the<br />

principle of equal consideration of interests states that I must not<br />

put either my interests or that of a preferred group above the<br />

interests of other individuals or groups; I must treat all interests<br />

with equal impartiality. This means that from my individual position<br />

I am accepting that my own interests cannot count for more than<br />

the interests of anyone else simply because these interests are mine;<br />

if they are to count for more then there must be other compelling<br />

reasons that this should be so.<br />

This leads me to take up a fundamentally utilitarian position<br />

(though not necessarily so) regarding how I make decisions<br />

regarding conflicting courses of action. In the context of whether<br />

I should kill non-human creatures (or allow this to happen) and<br />

eat their flesh, I may, according to the specific circumstances, take<br />

a classic utilitarian approach or one that is based on maximizing<br />

preference for the satisfaction of interests x . My simple question is<br />

therefore this: keeping in mind the universalisability of ethical<br />

judgements: am I ethically justified in killing non-human creatures<br />

(or condoning others doing so) in order that I might unnecessarily<br />

eat their flesh?<br />

PHILOSOPHICAL OVERVIEW xi<br />

Contrary to what Descartes believed, animals are living, feeling<br />

centres of consciousness and in many cases self-consciousness xii .<br />

This fact is disregarded by factory farmers, vivisectionists, furriers,<br />

big business. And this disregard is of the same logical type that<br />

underpins the moral dereliction that allows humans to be<br />

outrageously maltreated in pogroms and other ethnic cleansing<br />

exercises. It is also the same failure of the imagination that allows<br />

us to attend to our personal and desirable immediate physical<br />

welfare (often to excessive measure xiii ) whilst millions of our fellow<br />

human creatures throughout the globe go hungry or without the<br />

other basic requirements of elementary welfare. Whilst we might<br />

be obviously failing in our moral duty towards our fellow humans,<br />

it is not immediately obvious that we are similarly failing in our<br />

moral duties towards non-human creatures. The issue of what<br />

precisely our relationship should be towards the non-human animal<br />

world has become sharply that of whether such non-human<br />

creatures can be considered part of the moral community. If they<br />

are not included then our present treatment of them seems to be<br />

justified, at least in a rather thoughtless kind of way (one would<br />

think that natural sympathies might suggest ‘humane’ attitudes xiv );<br />

if they are included then this will entail radical changes to how we<br />

morally conduct ourselves in the biosphere.<br />

In order to continue to treat animals in the way we presently<br />

do, and do so with a clear conscience, we have only to deny that<br />

non-human creatures are, or even can be in principle, members<br />

of the moral community. Michael Fox xv made a prima facie plausible<br />

case for denial of membership along the following lines: animals<br />

are not members of the moral community and so humans have<br />

no moral obligations to them because animals cannot in principle<br />

be members of such a community for they do not possess the<br />

required qualities that are a sine qua non of membership. Fox<br />

stipulates that “a moral community is a social group composed of<br />

interacting autonomous beings where moral concepts and precepts<br />

can evolve and be understood. It is also a social group in which<br />

the mutual recognition of autonomy and personhood exist” (Fox,<br />

1986a, p 50). According to Fox an autonomous person is one who<br />

is critically self-aware, able to manipulate complex concepts,<br />

capable of using sophisticated language, and has the capacity to<br />

plan, choose, and accept responsibility for actions. Even a superficial<br />

reading of such a stipulation clearly rules out the possibility of<br />

membership for all non-human animals we know of on this<br />

particular planet (given our present understanding) xvi . In Fox’s<br />

words “full members of the moral community may use less valuable<br />

species, which lack some or all of these traits as means to their<br />

ends for the simple reason that they have no obligation not to do<br />

so” (p 88).<br />

Fox argues in a fashion with a well worn tradition in<br />

demarcation; x is y if and only if x possesses z which is a necessary<br />

and sufficient condition of y. Herein lies the problem of<br />

differentiation and careful definition; witness Descartes’ stipulation<br />

that possession of a soul was at least necessary for moral<br />

consideration to be taken into account. We can discount Descartes’<br />

position because there is no reason to suppose it is true and if we<br />

insist on taking it as true we must do so on irrational grounds (that<br />

of faith). Such grounds are not logically respectable (unless<br />

argument is impotent without it) so if we wish to differentiate<br />

ourselves from the rest of the animal kingdom we must do so on<br />

measurable grounds, à la Fox. The problem here is that for each x<br />

that claims to be a y there is at least one x that lacks the stipulated<br />

qualities and yet continues to claim to be y (by other xs) xvii . If it is<br />

the case that a sloth (for example) is not a member of the moral<br />

community because it cannot manipulate language, say, and cannot<br />

therefore take up propositional attitudes such as ‘desires’, ‘beliefs’<br />

or ‘intentions’, then it is entirely arbitrary to suppose some other<br />

creature who lacks that same language competence is, nevertheless,<br />

a legitimate member of that community. But this is the position<br />

we take when we allow human infants (or the severely mentally<br />

infirm) membership despite their lack of language competence.<br />

Our refusal [a] to deny membership to such humans, and refusal<br />

[b] to accept membership to non-human individuals who do match<br />

the criterion, rests upon our bias in favour of our species. This is<br />

a form of prejudice known as speciesism and is on a logical par<br />

with such unacceptable attitudes as racism and sexism. It has been<br />

suggested (by Fox in recognition of this problem) that deficient<br />

human individuals should be included in the moral community<br />

The Oswestrian 27


THE DECIMUS SOCIETY<br />

because “charity, benevolence, humaneness and prudence” demand<br />

that the moral community includes “undeveloped, deficient or<br />

seriously impaired human beings” (Fox, 1986a; pp 61-63). But<br />

contrary to Fox’s intention this logic forces us (correctly) to accept<br />

all creatures for whom we are capable of feeling sympathy (human<br />

and non-human) as legitimate members of the moral community.<br />

Fox came eventually to believe “that our basic moral obligations<br />

to avoid causing harm to other people should be extended to<br />

animals, and since I could not see any justification for our benefiting<br />

from harm caused to other humans, I inferred it would likewise<br />

be wrong for us to benefit from the suffering of animals”. (Fox,<br />

1986b; 1987)<br />

Frey xviii draws a slightly different conclusion from the notion<br />

that if a creature is capable of suffering then it must be included<br />

in the moral community, though status within that community will<br />

depend upon the precise nature of the individual member’s<br />

capacity for suffering and quality of life. He assumes that a fully<br />

functioning adult human person who enjoys complete autonomy<br />

has a greater quality of life than that possessed by a non-human<br />

individual or a human who is deficient. Given this not unreasonable<br />

assumption Frey concludes that it cannot be the case that we are<br />

justified in invariably using non-human creatures in preference to<br />

what he refers to as ‘marginal’ humans: “…the only way we could<br />

justifiably do this is if we could cite something that always, no<br />

matter what, cedes human life greater value than animal life. I<br />

know of no such things”. (Frey, 1988; p 197)<br />

If it is the case that all creatures who have the capacity for<br />

suffering should be included in the moral community (even if after<br />

Frey there is a hierarchy of membership which may have<br />

unfortunate consequences for those occupying the lower levels)<br />

then we might begin to talk in terms of rights governing the<br />

behaviour of one member with respect to another. What could we<br />

mean by such ‘rights’ in these circumstances? Regan suggests the<br />

following: beings that have rights are beings that possess inherent<br />

value xix . To possess inherent value is to possess value regardless of<br />

goodness or usefulness to others, and a right is what protects such<br />

value from being harmed or violated. The possessors of inherent<br />

value are what Regan calls ‘subjects-of-a-life’ and such subjects are<br />

self-conscious beings who have beliefs and desires, can conceive of<br />

the future and entertain goals. According to Regan all mentally<br />

normal mammals of a year or more are such self-conscious beings<br />

and so possess inherent value and have the right for such selfpossessed<br />

value to be protected from unnecessary violation. These<br />

rights are moral and universal (because moral), that is they are<br />

extended to all members of the moral community regardless of<br />

their sex, colour, race, nationality and species. According to Regan<br />

all beings that possess inherent value possess it equally.<br />

Here I meet a problem: am I to suppose that the inherent value<br />

I possess as a subject-of-a-life is of the same order as the inherent<br />

value possessed by my dog qua subject-of-a-life? Whilst it may be<br />

true that my dog is self-conscious in the manner required to be a<br />

member of the moral community, is it to be supposed that my<br />

desire to develop an education system that would properly prepare<br />

students for an ethically responsible life carries no more weight<br />

than my dog’s desire to eat the meaty bone in its kennel? Despite<br />

my desire to extend the moral community and respect all its<br />

members, I am left with the forceful notion that there is a reasonable<br />

hierarchy of membership and that normal mentally robust human<br />

beings occupy the upper levels xx . However, whilst there are<br />

problems with this notion of rights we can see in what sort of way<br />

members of the moral community need to be governed in order<br />

to preserve respect for inherent value, even in a hierarchical system<br />

which always carries with it the danger of the upper levels imposing<br />

unacceptably upon the lower. The question becomes: what precisely<br />

is my relation to all members of the moral community and how<br />

should I subsequently conduct myself ?<br />

A wholly egalitarian moral community founded on the<br />

assumption of inherent value possessed by all subjects-of-a-life<br />

living lives that are undifferentiated in terms of value, seems deeply<br />

flawed for the reasons I have just outlined. It seems utterly<br />

reasonable to point to differences in members of the community<br />

and attempt to formulate sound protocols that allow members to<br />

treat each other appropriately according to where each member<br />

sits in the hierarchy. Where a member sits is determined by what<br />

qualities it possesses and these qualities will determine how a<br />

member should treat another (assuming the presence of the faculty<br />

for reasoned and reflective thought in that member) and how in<br />

return that member should be treated by other members. It follows<br />

that the higher up the hierarchy the member sits the greater his<br />

responsibilities towards those lower down xxi . Let us accept Regan’s<br />

view that a sine qua non of membership of the moral community is<br />

the individual’s ability to experience the world in a particular way<br />

ie, qua subject-of-a-life—and also Bentham’s utilitarian argument<br />

that all members fundamentally possess the capacity for suffering xxii .<br />

On this view we can acknowledge that the hierarchy has an<br />

egalitarian foundation: all members have the capacity for suffering;<br />

all members are subjects-of-a-life and therefore possess inherent<br />

value; all members are to be respected qua subjects-of-a-life; all<br />

members have their inherent value protected by rights xxiii . If we<br />

accept this then how might we now reasonably proceed in our<br />

inter-member relations?<br />

A utilitarian position is one which does not allow arbitrary or<br />

prejudicial attitudes to colour our moral judgements, and surely<br />

this is something we would wish for in our extended (or even in<br />

our present contracted-humans only) moral community. At root<br />

lies the principle that all like interests are counted: “If a being<br />

suffers, there can be no moral justification for refusing to take that<br />

suffering into consideration. No matter what the nature of the<br />

being, the principle of equality requires that its suffering be counted<br />

equally with like suffering—in so far as rough comparisons can be<br />

made—of any other being”. (Practical Ethics, Singer, P Cambridge<br />

University Press, 1993, p 57.) I can conceive, however, of situations<br />

in which classic utilitarianism will entail a fully functioning nonhuman<br />

being given preference over a human operating at less than<br />

his best—a chronic depressive, for example. Here’s the situation:<br />

I am undergoing extensive treatment for my bipolar condition and<br />

this is costing the public purse a significant amount of money; I<br />

have not had a happy thought for many years and I am not<br />

responding very well to my treatment, consequently my<br />

contribution to the gross sum of happiness in the moral<br />

community’s hedonic coffers is minimal (I have at least one friend<br />

who is glad that I am at least alive and his gladness is a positive<br />

contribution due in part to me, in part to his good nature). An<br />

audit is made of the public purse and a decision must be made as<br />

to whether I should continue to receive my treatment.<br />

Unfortunately for me there is a publicly subsidized zoo with a<br />

strong ecological interest used extensively for educational purposes<br />

(under-privileged, inner-city children regularly visit and leave with<br />

a sense of renewed wonder at nature); the animals are well cared<br />

for and, all things being equal, are content and clearly bring<br />

significant pleasure to visitors. The zoo could not survive without<br />

its subsidy—the animals would have to be destroyed and with this<br />

the benefit of the institution to the moral community would clearly<br />

disappear. However, the public purse cannot support both my<br />

treatment and the zoo. The felicific calculus clearly dictates that<br />

my treatment must be withdrawn and the zoo allowed to continue<br />

its good work in the community xxiv .<br />

Such withdrawal of treatment seems intuitively and rationally<br />

28 The Oswestrian


THE DECIMUS SOCIETY<br />

wrong because my perspective qua subject-of-a-life places me higher<br />

up the hierarchy than any of the zoo animals and suggests that the<br />

inherent value of a chronic human depressive is worth more than<br />

the inherent value of any of the zoo inhabitants xxv . Classic<br />

utilitarianism does not, therefore, seem to get me anywhere when<br />

considering what protocols should operate within the moral<br />

community. Singer opines that preference utilitarianism might do<br />

so. He suggests that self-conscious, rational human beings are<br />

capable of having a specific preference for continued existence. In<br />

my case, despite my chronic depression I still have a preference for<br />

continued existence because I have many valuable projects I wish<br />

to complete, valuable in themselves and valuable also from the<br />

point of view of the commonwealth. It is not immediately clear<br />

that the sloths, the aardvarks, the rhinoceros and hippopotami in<br />

the zoo have a preference for continued existence so that similarly<br />

valuable projects can be realized (they have given no one reason<br />

to suppose that they do). So, Singer’s utilitarian position appears<br />

to make sense given our strong impression that the life of a fully<br />

functioning human is worth (all things being equal) more than the<br />

life of a fully functioning non-human (to the best of our present<br />

knowledge). It might also help us decide how we should respond<br />

ethically to difficult cases of how humans in varying degrees of<br />

‘completeness’ (those who cannot survive independently) be treated<br />

given limited resources of public funds.<br />

Regarding how those who occupy the higher levels in the<br />

hierarchy should view members of the moral community lower<br />

down as possible food sources, the matter seems fairly clear and<br />

unproblematic: rights theorists and preference utilitarians both<br />

have strong vegetarian urges and for good reasons. The former<br />

will not eat meat because to do so is clearly to violate the inherent<br />

value of members of the moral community xxvi . The latter will not<br />

eat meat if the process that is used to raise the non-human members<br />

of the moral community involves a net balance of suffering. If these<br />

non-human members of the community live happy (as far as we<br />

can honestly tell), stress-free natural lives before they are painlessly<br />

killed, then the preference utilitarian may not object to their use as<br />

food.<br />

In the case of the higher level members using the lower level<br />

members for experimentation (vivisection), rights protocol would<br />

clearly say that such practices are simply not permissible and should<br />

be abolished because they are, like the eating of lower members’<br />

flesh, a clear violation of inherent value. The preference utilitarian,<br />

on the other hand, is not quite so theoretically blinkered and allows<br />

in theory at least the possibility of higher level beings experimenting<br />

on lower level beings if it can be demonstrated beyond all<br />

reasonable doubt that there is a clear and unambiguous benefit<br />

derived from such activity. However, in practice Singer’s position<br />

is sceptical of such clear benefit: “in extreme circumstances,<br />

absolutist answers always break down…if a single experiment<br />

could cure a major disease, that experiment would be justifiable.<br />

But in actual life the benefits are always much, much more remote<br />

and more often than not they are non-existent…an experiment<br />

cannot be justifiable unless the experiment is so important that the<br />

use of a retarded human being would also be justifiable” xxvii .<br />

The position we are left with is, I suggest, this: a moral<br />

community consisting of subjects-of-a-life and a hierarchy of selfconscious<br />

experience that helps us differentiate between members<br />

of the community in rational and ethical terms. I hinted at the<br />

beginning of this paper that reasoned argument was not sufficient<br />

to arrive at an acceptable ethical position, for we must look to our<br />

premises if we are to be confident that our logic is leading us in<br />

the right direction (one that feels right when all is honestly<br />

[disinterestedly] taken into consideration). This disinterested<br />

direction is what I call the civilized stance. We are not in a position<br />

to be certain that our actions are ever ethically coherent, but we<br />

are in a position to take all things (presently understood) into<br />

account and disinterestedly judge that our behaviour is of the highest<br />

ethical order we can presently manage. Logic attending to spurious<br />

premises can lead us seriously astray, so the question now is: how<br />

do we ensure that our premises are worthy of logical attendance?<br />

How can we minimize our stumbling into ethical swamps and<br />

moral bogs?<br />

Lori Gruen suggests that one way we might move forward the<br />

debate regarding the use of non-humans is to look to the concept<br />

of sympathy so that it might temper the sharpness of reason<br />

alone xxviii . A dog is not just a dog but also a personal pet that one<br />

knows and loves, for example. Kinship and closeness, she says, are<br />

very important elements in thinking about virtually every feature<br />

of our daily lives and cannot help but impinge on our judgements<br />

and decisions; this is what it is to be human and to balance reason<br />

with sympathy is our moral condition. But the key is to achieve a<br />

sound balance. Emotion without reason is chaotic and arbitrary,<br />

a forceful maelstrom of irrationality. Reason without emotion is a<br />

cold place with stalactite ice shafts. The achievement of balance<br />

is problematic, however: Fisher xxix suggests that beings with whom<br />

we can sympathize must be morally considered. We can sympathize<br />

with beings if we can recognize in them traits that in some respects<br />

correspond to our own (in the higher mammals this would not be<br />

surprising given our common evolutionary heritage), and if we<br />

can so sympathize then this sympathy ought to inform the manner<br />

in which we treat these beings. But consider beings with whom we<br />

cannot sympathize because they are too unfamiliar to us, yet possess<br />

high degrees of self-consciousness we do not or cannot recognize xxx .<br />

We breed these because we enjoy the taste of their flesh and when<br />

we process their bones we derive valuable oil. Can this be right?<br />

Lack of sympathy (because the sympathy cannot be felt) cannot<br />

be a good reason for ill-treatment. Gruen’s point, of course, is that<br />

if we do not include emotion in our ethical decision making then<br />

we run the risk of removing ourselves too far from the state of<br />

affairs under ethical consideration—in this case the killing of and<br />

subsequent eating of non-human flesh. If as individuals we are<br />

removed from the process of killing and flesh preparation then we<br />

have allowed ourselves to become distanced from our moral<br />

responsibilities, and being so distanced we fail to appreciate the<br />

moral content of our subsequent actions (eating flesh—<br />

unnecessarily). So, for an ordinary human being with ordinary<br />

sympathetic faculties and an understanding of ethical principles<br />

of the sort discussed in this paper, to visit a slaughter house and<br />

witness the process of turning a living self-conscious creature into<br />

steak and mushed tissue, would surely be enough to convince that<br />

individual that there was something morally dubious about the<br />

meat processing industry.<br />

CIVILIZED BEHAVIOUR AND THE<br />

HIERARCHY OF EXPERIENCE<br />

To illustrate the universal nature of ethics, the principle of equal<br />

consideration of interests, and the impact of self-consciousness<br />

and sentience on the manner in which non-humans are treated by<br />

humans I shall reference the thoughts occurring in the mind of a<br />

young would-be vegetarian as he works in a slaughter house. He<br />

is there for two reasons: he wishes to see the meat production<br />

process close up so that his musings do not slide into sentimentality<br />

and mere abstraction, and he has no immediate economic option<br />

but to be ground under the yoke.<br />

The primary business of this place is to kill animals, bolt<br />

their brains into insentience, often inefficiently, and turn<br />

their red-blooded flesh into attractive and palatable food<br />

The Oswestrian 29


THE DECIMUS SOCIETY<br />

for humans, the likes of me! The product must not in any<br />

sense resemble the source; the steak, or the shredded flesh<br />

must not resemble in any crude and vulgar way the animal<br />

whose flesh it is. The mind has to be focused on this end,<br />

and to some extent be numbed by it. My mind is numbed<br />

by it. I stand operating my process machine in a kind of<br />

stupor, an idiot working the levers and switches, pushing<br />

the mushy tissue into the grinders. What am I doing?<br />

Chillingly, the means towards this end had originally to be<br />

carefully designed (conceived in someone’s mind and then<br />

discussed in an office presumably, or someone’s study; and<br />

then all the machines designed by engineers, detailed plans<br />

drawn up on a draughtsman’s board) so that it was efficient<br />

(at least sometimes) and economic, nothing less. Such<br />

designers would have been focused on every stage of the<br />

manufacture of the product; but the real meaning of what<br />

was being designed and built would never, surely, at any<br />

time, have been reflected upon in the manner of some<br />

philosophy—except the unconscious, simplistic one which<br />

places man irresponsibly at the peak of a thoughtless<br />

hierarchical pyramid of being xxxi . At no stage would<br />

questions of ethics and meaning ever be raised. The whole<br />

process would have been understood as a series of discrete<br />

actions, in themselves entirely innocuous, and so the<br />

significance of the means would have been missed, lost in<br />

a sea of negligence, of omissions, of incogitancy! It is not<br />

so much a case of the end justifying the means because<br />

there is insufficient consciousness of the means. I look<br />

around me and I know that this is true. What I push<br />

through the cage mesh into the grinding teeth is a lifeless<br />

substance which can be turned into something attractive<br />

to eat. That it is flesh and was living but a short while ago,<br />

and was deliberately killed to satisfy a specific gastronomic<br />

desire (was this the creature I saw mad-eyed and trembling<br />

an hour ago as it was led into the Process Hall?); that once<br />

this flesh in its living and whole form had eaten grass and<br />

grazed contentedly in fields and meadows—all this is lost<br />

in the discrete consciousness of the job (don’t think of the<br />

whole process—concentrate only on the part designated<br />

to you [push the red spongy stuff through the mesh and<br />

into the teeth, pull the lever, press the switch and repeat]).<br />

And this is why the job is possible. To get the job done I<br />

have to forget the significance of the means, to suspend<br />

my critical faculties, to become a no-man. I cannot allow<br />

myself to question the value of the end. This I must simply<br />

accept as a given. In focusing on my trivial task—pushing<br />

this meat into the grinding hopper—I lose sight of the<br />

whole process. It is the focusing upon the whole that<br />

reveals the true nature of the action and allows<br />

the reflective mind to bear rational witness.<br />

If I am to carry on here (keeping the malignant<br />

supervisor off my back) what has to be resisted is the<br />

temptation to view the animals trucked here for processing<br />

as more than mere objects. The temptation is there because<br />

we possess natural faculties of sympathy—but the end<br />

product of the abattoir is so desirable (what culinary<br />

aromas of the roast, the kebab and fast-food joint) we must<br />

make an initial effort to slip out of reflective consciousness<br />

so that we can clock in each morning with a clear<br />

conscience. The man on the machine next to mine, a<br />

machine that relies upon the output of my machine, has<br />

dead eyes; his face is a hollow shell. He speaks, but does<br />

so with only papery life. He is more dead than alive, all<br />

desiccated being. He is the no-man who makes the whole<br />

grizzly enterprise possible. At the end of the day he takes<br />

home a plastic bag filled with the guts of the animal he<br />

has processed (his perquisite) and gives it to his wife to cook<br />

for his supper. He licks his lips as it’s placed on his dinner<br />

plate and he says “delicious, luv, really delicious”.<br />

Our ability to concentrate on the discrete parts of the<br />

whole blinds us to the significance of the whole, or indeed<br />

blinds us to the very existence of a whole at all. If the<br />

cow is viewed as something more than mere<br />

object then we understand it differently. It becomes<br />

possible to ask the question: does my desire to eat meat,<br />

not for purposes of health but purely for gastronomic<br />

pleasure, justify the slaughter of the animal, a sentient<br />

being, a subject-of-a-life? The answer may be yes. But if<br />

this is the case it is not obviously so. The question reduces<br />

to this: does my gustatory pleasure justify the death of the<br />

cow? The fact that I frame the question in this way suggests<br />

that the life of the cow carries at least some moral weight<br />

deserving of my attention. There may well be some<br />

circumstances where the value of the cow’s life outweighs<br />

my desire to carry out some action. For example, a cow<br />

might be blocking my way but instead of ramming it with<br />

my car I try to lead it away (who would not do this?)—<br />

(maybe I just don’t want to damage my car)—(I lead the<br />

cow out of danger and then condone its slaughter later<br />

that day in the abattoir; I eat a burger which I have to<br />

admit is delicious). However, my desire for the taste of meat<br />

entails that the cow is slaughtered. What is it about my<br />

gustatory pleasure that makes it more valuable than the<br />

cow’s life, if indeed it is? Would the life of the cow accrue<br />

more value if a perfect meat substitute were available which<br />

provided all the gustatory delights desired? Could I still<br />

justify the slaughter?<br />

My unease with all this comes from its brutality (I<br />

understand that the meat process entails unnecessary<br />

suffering on the part of the beasts being processed). That<br />

is, the nature of the task brutalizes. It brutalizes me! To<br />

forget the meaning of the whole—any whole—<br />

even for an instant, is to be instantaneously<br />

brutalized. It means that I see the animal merely as<br />

object and cannot see beyond this. That is why I can kill<br />

the creature and not feel its anguish and pain, (I mean not<br />

recognize its anguish and pain) for as a mere object it<br />

experiences nothing of significance (how could it—a mere<br />

Cartesian automaton?). And in my specifically individual<br />

task I forget that there ever was a sentient creature at all.<br />

In my gustatory delight I forget this fact (the creature’s<br />

variable breathing and other physiological signs of distress<br />

at the time of slaughter remind me of the fact). What<br />

makes the task objectionable, or the delight objectionable,<br />

is therefore the uncivilized nature of it. It is that the task<br />

or delight hold me back from perceiving the animal as<br />

more than mere object; that is, as a conscious being. As a<br />

conscious being it surely lays claim to certain treatment<br />

and such treatment cannot involve unnecessary pain or<br />

suffering (could my taste for meat ever justify unnecessary<br />

suffering?). Of course suffering is unavoidable in some<br />

form or other in the nature of being, but the moral weight<br />

that conscious existence entails demands that such suffering<br />

is minimized. Surely this is obvious. The no-man sniffs and<br />

drags his shirt sleeve across his nose.<br />

I look down at the concrete floor of the Further<br />

Process. It is wet and sweating. The hum and buzz of<br />

machines echo in the hall; the heavy-duty plastic curtain<br />

30 The Oswestrian


THE DECIMUS SOCIETY<br />

flaps separating the process halls swing stiffly as bloodstained<br />

operatives make their somniferous way around the<br />

factory. The no-man’s suppurating thoughts fill the<br />

chamber, filling the place with unconscious miasma; and<br />

I am here, an enemy in the enemy camp, without a gas<br />

mask. This red mess on the floor by my feet, at the base<br />

of the crunching hopper, used to be flesh and bone of a<br />

conscious being and the moral weight which that being<br />

ought to have commanded has gone unrecognized, or been<br />

ignored; it has certainly been violated (argue otherwise and<br />

persuasively). In the cold fluorescent light of the meat plant<br />

the refrigerated air hums and trembles with the vibration<br />

of machines and the noise of human intercourse, and it is<br />

like a form of madness: that is, the carelessness of the<br />

activity is madness. Considerable thought is employed to<br />

sustain this place. But it is not considered, rational, reflective<br />

thought. It is rather the calculating reflection of desire and<br />

profit in the absence of moral imagination. It is not the<br />

creative and speculative metaphysical thought which<br />

specifically divides man from the sub-man. Here, in the<br />

processing plant, all thought is dim, somnific and<br />

wearisome; there is absolutely no questioning of activity.<br />

Activity is carried on in the absence of understanding. The<br />

whole has been sponged out and there is<br />

consequently sub-mentality everywhere, like a<br />

miasma; like a no-man’s dream.<br />

At the root of moral consideration across species lies<br />

the inherent undesirability of pain and suffering; that is,<br />

whether I take a creature’s moral status into consideration<br />

depends largely upon whether I take that creature to be<br />

capable of suffering (and there may be other reasons why<br />

I should want to take a special moral interest in the<br />

creature). If I jam a sharpened stake into the flanks of a<br />

cow I interpret its subsequent squeals, and its jumping and<br />

kicking and its mad rolling of its eyes, as compelling<br />

evidence that it feels distress (owing to my actions)—(how<br />

else could I reasonably interpret such behaviour—it is not<br />

behaving as if it were in distress, but in fact is not; what<br />

Cartesian madness would that be?). Imaginatively, I<br />

empathize with the cow (I know what it must be like to<br />

have a sharpened stake jammed into my flank—even<br />

though no such thing has ever happened—I take it that<br />

there is a shared phenomenology [I have no good reason<br />

to think otherwise for there is a shared basic neurological<br />

model—this much is reasonable, surely]). So, if it is true<br />

that a cow can feel pain then it has an interest to avoid<br />

such pain; and if it is true that I too can feel pain then I<br />

also have an interest to avoid such pain. If the cow’s pain<br />

is qualitatively similar to mine then I have no good reason<br />

to distinguish my pain from that of the cow’s, except on<br />

an inter-subjective level. The moral point is that I ought<br />

to give equal consideration to interests, all things being<br />

equal. What could be clearer? But the moral temperature<br />

of the slaughter house is as cold as the refrigerated air that<br />

is pumped around its processing halls. So, what is being<br />

missed? The principle is simple: If pain can be avoided<br />

then it should be so avoided; and whose pain it is is<br />

irrelevant, regardless of species.<br />

In the great machine cavern where I work, my back<br />

aching from bending over the burger compressor, the<br />

unspoken and un-thought opinion is that the distress of<br />

the cow counts for very little or nothing at all. Human<br />

pleasure is the end and any possible pain the cow might<br />

conceivably suffer is mere means to that end. My pleasure<br />

at having meat in my mouth has, therefore, high aesthetic<br />

value and justifies the pain and death of the animal this<br />

flesh once was. This is the unreflective notion. The<br />

utilitarian principle is constrained in this respect: human<br />

pleasure is worth significantly more than animal pleasure<br />

and so human pleasure derived through animal distress<br />

(because the former is so great) can be justified (because<br />

the latter [granted Descartes was wrong] is gossamer in<br />

comparison). What benefits human beings is therefore<br />

permissible! I wipe my red hands upon my almost white<br />

abattoir lab coat. My supervisor is on an efficiency-profit<br />

mission, patrolling the processing halls and tells me to work<br />

harder—the no-man, waiting on my performance, is<br />

getting fidgety and irritable; he reminds me again he can’t<br />

do his job unless I do my mine, and he’s after a bonus and<br />

wants to get home early to his “that’s delicious, luv”—the<br />

principle of the equal consideration of interests is an<br />

obscure irrelevance to him.<br />

How is it that this meat processing exists in an age and<br />

place where a balanced diet need not include animal flesh?<br />

Can my gustatory pleasure justify this? Yes, if the animal’s<br />

life counts for little or nothing. But pain is pain after all. Is<br />

it possible to say that my pain is qualitatively different to<br />

that of a cow; that is, that my pain is more painful, more<br />

of a pain than that of the cow and that this fact lies in<br />

inherent differences between the cow and me? Can this<br />

possibly be maintained seriously? Is it only human pain<br />

that must count in the hedonic calculus? Surely there is<br />

meaning behind the look that comes into the bovine face<br />

when the bolt is placed carelessly against the bovine<br />

temple? Knowledge of bovine neurology, coupled with a<br />

theory of mind, surely suggests fear. This is not sentimental<br />

anthropomorphism—the taking pity on what is not a<br />

suitable object of pity. Surely the bovine experience must<br />

be taken into any hedonic account in similar manner as<br />

the meaning behind the human wince when I am clumsily<br />

syringed in a doctor’s surgery! But as to qualitative<br />

differentials the meaning is obscure: My pain or the cow’s?<br />

Which is worth more moral consideration? Prima facie my<br />

pain counts for more. By virtue of the fact that I have<br />

managed to form the question, while the cow has done no<br />

more than squeal places me on a higher level of the<br />

pyramid. It counts for more because it is mine and<br />

everything which is not mine is peripheral to me and in<br />

some obscure way not real. Isn’t this where scepticism<br />

leads—to the problem of other minds? I just can’t be sure<br />

of what lies outside of me—so in the end I count for<br />

everything—even if I grant the probability of other minds.<br />

It’s my centrality and level of consciousness in the end that<br />

dominates my horizon. If it’s my pain versus the cow’s then<br />

let the cow suffer. About this there is no obscurity; so, in<br />

the general calculus bovine suffering and happiness count<br />

for less than mine or other persons. However, consider:<br />

what if in some dark circumstance my suffering (not to any<br />

great degree) could save a multitude of non-persons from<br />

pain (cumulatively greater then mine) xxxii . Would I be<br />

morally obliged to undergo pain for the sake of the greater<br />

balance of happiness—the hedonic commonwealth? The<br />

answer is not clear. But what if I am being racked, and my<br />

screaming on the rack and my mercy-pleading and<br />

whimpering are awful; what if all this could extinguish the<br />

pain of the non-persons? What then? My suffering is<br />

excruciating and in the calculus must be balanced against<br />

the weight of non-person suffering multiplied a hundred<br />

The Oswestrian 31


THE DECIMUS SOCIETY<br />

fold. How could this predicament be calculated? What<br />

moral weight could the non-person command? Would I<br />

accept my suffering for the sake of cows but not of rats or<br />

cockroaches or ticks? As I approach the lower levels of the<br />

hierarchy of experience (subjects-of-a-life) the more obscure<br />

and meaningless the problem becomes. Perhaps I should<br />

not have mentioned rats in this context: it is a prejudice of<br />

mine. After all, rats are not unintelligent; nor dare I say<br />

are roaches, but it is not easy to grasp the meaning of<br />

‘suffering roaches’, and therefore not easy to understand<br />

what it might mean to sympathize with them. But can that<br />

mean that my inability to sympathize with such creatures<br />

entails my treatment of them lies outside the moral sphere?<br />

There is a good case for saying that rats come above cows<br />

in the pyramid. Would I then, or should I then, suffer in<br />

some degree if such suffering could extinguish the pain of<br />

a significant number of non-person creatures? Do I have a<br />

free, moral free, hand in how I treat creatures for which I<br />

have no sympathy? When a child (who understands the<br />

limits of normal moral constraints) pulls the wings off a<br />

fly or incinerates ants in an incandescent beam of a lensfocussed<br />

sun, is such a childish act (or equivalent adult act)<br />

morally reprehensible? It might well be. It might well be—<br />

for it diminishes the agent of destruction in the eyes of the<br />

civilized eye; not to live according to the perception of this<br />

eye is part of what it means to live in a kind of moral<br />

dereliction—assuming the eye perceives according<br />

to rational moral imperatives xxxiii .<br />

Sympathy can also be depressed by ideology.<br />

I look into the face of a cow and see its large eyes which<br />

resemble to some extent my own, and they regard me with<br />

some interest and curiosity; the udders swing large and full<br />

beneath a rectangular body of monstrous angular bones.<br />

The bovine curiosity does not last long. The large head<br />

tilts back and the snout reaches out for a smell of me and<br />

then dips down and the mouth rips grass and the teeth<br />

grind and chew. There is undoubted intelligence and<br />

consciousness here. And then I stick it with a knife, in the<br />

neck, and blood comes pouring out and this I catch in a<br />

vessel and drink for the benefit I believe it will bring me.<br />

The cow flinches and is suddenly wary. But it doesn’t shout<br />

abuse at me and it doesn’t scream in any way I should<br />

recognize as outrage. It seems that what I have caused the<br />

cow to feel has not been understood by it at all. This is not<br />

a person I have stuck and its reaction to me is at least<br />

ambiguous. I see no tears in its eyes and hear no<br />

whimpering. The look in its eyes is bolting but constant.<br />

But I do not deny that some discomfort has been<br />

experienced and this counts for something. I justify my<br />

action by saying that the nourishment I gain from drinking<br />

the animal’s blood is necessary for my health, and my<br />

welfare (over that of the cow’s) is demanded by my position<br />

on the hierarchical pyramid of consciousness. My<br />

consciousness is self-reflective and if lesser forms of<br />

consciousness suffer to ensure my continuity then that<br />

seems entirely right. Lesser forms—the principle appears<br />

to say—may be used to support the continuity of higher<br />

forms, and so I drink the cow’s blood and eat its flesh.<br />

Necessity of continuity lies at the root of this<br />

particular justification. If I did not need the flesh but<br />

just had a taste for it, then the moral justification would<br />

begin to look tenuous. I tell this telepathically to the noman<br />

who is boring his precipitate eyes into my back. He<br />

grunts. He understands nothing but the ‘that’s delicious<br />

luv, can I have a bit more gravy on this?’.<br />

If it’s protein I need I have fewer problems with roaches<br />

(bar disgust at the thought) and roasting a nest of these<br />

and serving them up in a casserole. If it’s about necessity<br />

roach consciousness (such as it might be) must give way to<br />

my far superior self-conscious decision to roast the nest.<br />

And even in the case of non-necessity and the simple<br />

pursuit of new tastes, my roasting of the roaches and my<br />

consumption of them is more easily acceptable than my<br />

slaughter and consumption of the cow on the basis of taste<br />

alone. This is the principle. Should I move further up the<br />

pyramid to more equivocal levels, say to that of the great<br />

apes and that of cetaceans, I begin to be more anxious<br />

about my decisions, even in the case of clear necessary<br />

consumption. Would I be justified in killing an ape or a<br />

dolphin to ensure my continuity? Perhaps, but not<br />

obviously so. Could I, with moral justification, cause pain<br />

to or kill a fully functioning fellow human in order to ensure<br />

my personal continuity? Here I run against a more<br />

obviously severe storm of outrage. As a matter of principle<br />

(it seems) I must not benefit through the suffering of fellow<br />

human persons where the identity of those persons is<br />

unequivocal unless there are compelling reasons why I<br />

should do so (even then doubtful) (assuming the state of<br />

personhood is not in doubt) (what could these reasons be?)<br />

(The equal consideration of interests) (Am I similarly<br />

constrained with respect to non-humans similarly<br />

constituted?). I might, therefore, hesitantly accept the pain<br />

of the dolphin in my favour (because I lack the information<br />

that would clearly establish one way or the other the<br />

dolphin’s moral status—are its interests on a par with<br />

mine?). The dolphin might speak (via an interpreter) and<br />

claim violation of the liberties of the moral community.<br />

What then? Only the imaginatively inert could not see the<br />

point. Whether the creature involved in my predatory<br />

activity is a member of the moral community or not is of<br />

great importance—and whether it is a person or not, it<br />

seems to me, is of even greater importance. Important also<br />

is whether or not my activity is based on necessity or mere<br />

taste and convention. Necessity springs from the differential<br />

of consciousness; thus, if it is necessary that the lower<br />

levels suffer in order to ensure the continuity of<br />

the upper then that suffering is justified (a horse<br />

may die in the necessary interests of a man—but<br />

what precisely constitutes ‘necessary’ is all<br />

important) xxxiv .<br />

And what does this speculation matter in this place,<br />

the chilly Further Process of no-men acting out their part<br />

in accordance with the design of moral incertitude?<br />

Surely quality of consciousness is not purely a matter<br />

of biology but of nurture also, at least amongst the<br />

community of self-conscious beings. It is surely possible to<br />

move from one level of consciousness to the next above<br />

through sheer dint of hard moral work. The true seeker<br />

of wisdom will train his mind in the arts and sciences so<br />

that his powers of discrimination lift him up, as it were, to<br />

a higher plain. He now sees beauty where once he saw the<br />

mundane. He now sees order where once he perceived<br />

confusion; anxiety and anguish, puzzlement and frustration<br />

become springboards for spiritual growth rather than<br />

precipices above despair. This transportation from the<br />

valley floor to the mountain slopes can be self-generated,<br />

surely. It does not happen spontaneously but demands a<br />

journey upon a path of re-invention of self, and this is not<br />

32 The Oswestrian


THE DECIMUS SOCIETY<br />

to everyone’s liking; not the liking of the no-man and his<br />

considerate missus. The path (there is no reason to suppose<br />

it does not exist) must first be perceived to be taken. It is<br />

there for each individual to take if he chooses to seek it.<br />

Some do but reject its rigours. Such beings fall back into<br />

what becomes an odious mire of experience in the light of<br />

their new realization, and they sink steadily into cynicism<br />

and self-pity xxxv . Others cannot conceive of such a path<br />

(are blind to it when it opens yawning up before them) and<br />

these live the life of the no-man. If the utilitarian principle<br />

is right, and it is right also that lower level consciousness<br />

can legitimately suffer to benefit higher level consciousness<br />

no matter what the benefit, then those on the valley floor<br />

can be sacrificed in favour of those on the mountain peaks.<br />

Should human persons accept this conclusion? Is this<br />

morally acceptable?<br />

‘I reject this thesis’, I beam to the no-man. He swears<br />

and spits on the concrete floor below the fluorescent strip<br />

lights.<br />

Consider this: What if we, a technologically and<br />

scientifically developed and sophisticated self-conscious<br />

species, a species that subordinates all non-human animals<br />

to our needs and desires, were presently being observed<br />

by an extra-terrestrial species whose level of self-conscious<br />

and technological and scientific development was as far in<br />

advance of ours as ours is in advance of cows. This species<br />

has certain needs and desires and for reasons which are<br />

unimportant and beyond our understanding, destroying<br />

the whole of Earth’s biosphere would satisfy those needs<br />

and desires. Would this species be justified in carrying out<br />

its act of destruction? xxxvi Let us suppose that the degree<br />

and intensity of happiness this species would experience<br />

as a result of its action would far surpass, qualitatively, the<br />

totality of happiness on Earth experienced by the planet’s<br />

biosphere. The classical utilitarian calculus tells us that we<br />

would have to give way. It is something we can ethically<br />

and intellectually understand. But would we understand<br />

it on some other level—the instinctive, say? It is more likely<br />

that our sense of outrage would be unbounded. We would<br />

fight and die as we proclaimed our right to live and live in<br />

well-being, despite anything the hedonic calculus might<br />

suggest. It would almost certainly appear to us that<br />

satisfaction of the alien need and their subsequent pleasure<br />

was perversely negative and wholly immoral—such a race<br />

would be one of sadistic tormentors bent on satisfying<br />

unjustifiable desires (this would be clear to us, would it<br />

not?).<br />

If pain and distress is eradicated would I then be<br />

justified in killing and processing the animal? There is, it<br />

seems, no clean distinction to be made between me and<br />

other animals—and I am an animal, lest that be forgotten.<br />

Certainly there is an unmistakable difference of form; but<br />

my genetic material is of the same kind which informs all<br />

animal and insect life, and the form of patterning and<br />

organization is similar also—different only in degree. I sit<br />

atop the hierarchical evolutionary pyramid, but the levels<br />

below me are not strictly discrete; in biological terms I am<br />

connected to all the sub-levels and differ more in form than<br />

in kind (I am at one end of a continuum of being, the single<br />

cell at the other) xxxvii . The cow, therefore, is my biological<br />

cousin, made of genes and flesh and blood and bones and<br />

nerve cells and complex electrochemical activity. It is<br />

sentient certainly, conscious (perhaps self-conscious) and I<br />

am self-conscious (unambiguously so) and so it seems I am<br />

obliged—qua responsible member of the moral<br />

community—not to slaughter it and eat its flesh, but offer<br />

it instead a kind of generous benevolence, a sympathetic<br />

accommodation without extending to it the full spectrum<br />

of human expectations. That is, I extend to it a benefit of<br />

any doubt concerning its existential status. That is, if I<br />

am in a position to do so. A cow is not a human but<br />

it does not follow from this that it should be treated in an<br />

inhuman fashion. I may slaughter and eat its flesh if I have<br />

no other reasonable option and I justify doing so by<br />

pointing out the consciousness differential and the natural<br />

tendency to protect oneself and members of one’s own<br />

species. If it came to the crunch I’d kill the cow rather than<br />

another human being (all things being equal), if one or the<br />

other had to die xxxviii .<br />

What is there about living beings of a relatively high<br />

order, besides their experience, which is relevant to how<br />

they should be treated—how we should treat them? Inner<br />

life or inner being is a strange thing; one can never be<br />

completely sure something is going on in the inside. To<br />

deny inner being to humans would be insane (I think thrice<br />

about the no-man); but would it not be insane also to deny<br />

it to higher animals?<br />

Descartes once spoke of animals as mere automata xxxix .<br />

How could he ever have thought this? He was searching<br />

for the grail of demon-proof certainty and can perhaps<br />

be forgiven for confusing in the end the whisperings of his<br />

own methodology of scepticism with unsound ontological<br />

conclusions. He must have been in an excitable frame of<br />

mind to so downgrade animals. This is what comes from<br />

separating the mind from the body and we get all confused<br />

by the problem of other minds and the desire for objectivity.<br />

There is the objective school of animal behaviourists who<br />

temper their automatic and natural tendencies to interpret<br />

behaviour patterns as indicating real consciousness by<br />

exercising reasonable caution. It is so easy to be fooled, to<br />

draw false conclusions, they say. Better it is to affect a stand<br />

of near perfect objectivity and be content merely to<br />

describe what one can see and can measure. rather than<br />

allow natural, but possibly spurious, interpretations to creep<br />

in. Hence, animal behaviour must be described in terms<br />

of physiochemical states and reactions. Animals after all<br />

turn out, on analysis, to be nothing but rather wonderful<br />

biological machines, and the notion that there is any inside<br />

life is too obscure an idea to be taken seriously, they say.<br />

But from a more modern perspective it is only the<br />

ideologically blind who can accept this position; only<br />

zoophobics can relish it and only those who have never<br />

lived with animals can grant such a position dignity. (What<br />

does the behaviourist deduce from observing his own<br />

behaviour, which is not dissimilar in significant ways from<br />

the behaviour of the dog he feeds surreptitiously under<br />

the table during his wife’s dinner parties?)<br />

The inner being makes the difference and is the thing<br />

that matters over and above mere experience. The absence<br />

of pain and of any kind of distress does not therefore make<br />

a difference to the rightness or otherwise of the slaughter<br />

if self-consciousness is the issue. What is true of me is true<br />

also of the animal, in kind if not in degree. So, if it is wrong<br />

to inflict needless pain on me (for some reason) then it must<br />

also be similarly wrong to inflict needless pain on a being<br />

of similar constitution.<br />

Suppose that without warning I am seriously<br />

incapacitated through an accident of some kind, or through<br />

The Oswestrian 33


THE DECIMUS SOCIETY<br />

the contraction of some disabling disease: then I can no<br />

longer be the way I wish or desire to be. The suppositional<br />

is important. I have, in fact, certain projects, certain wants<br />

and needs which are integral to me being the being I am,<br />

but as a result of my suppositional invalidity I can no longer<br />

realize these. My suppositional impuissance, therefore,<br />

strikes me as an evil—its coming is not so much<br />

malevolence but an ignoble fact which interferes in a<br />

profoundly negative manner with my conceptions and<br />

dreams. This new impotence diminishes me in such a way<br />

that I can no longer be the being I was or become the one<br />

I once desired to be. I am completely changed by the event.<br />

And the unexpected nature of the tragedy makes it all the<br />

more poignant for me, for if I had known it was coming I<br />

might have prepared and made the necessary personal<br />

transformations. But it strikes out of the blue, and it strikes<br />

hard and cruelly, biting deep into the very idea of my self,<br />

disfiguring my vision of what it is to be a human creature<br />

in this world. To be human, I now see very clearly, it is<br />

necessary to act out one’s desires and needs freely within<br />

reasonable limits, and any kind of unreasonable restriction<br />

I now understand clearly an as evil. Hence, to kill me, even<br />

painlessly, constitutes a total restriction on my freedom to<br />

be as I desire and need to be, and this restricting evil has<br />

nothing to do with experiences. The case is that the evil<br />

arises out of the obstruction to my personal vision. This<br />

vision lies snug beneath my experience and shapes it<br />

meaningfully and as such constitutes the foundation of my<br />

moral status: I must not be killed or restricted in<br />

any unreasonable way because such limits to my<br />

freedom take from me all that is personally<br />

important.<br />

The same can be said of certain animals. That is not<br />

to say that all animals have personal desires and dreams<br />

and visions of paradise, but as conscious beings they all have<br />

needs and desires appropriate to their kind. One of you,<br />

in your more enlightened moments, might object and claim<br />

that such animal needs and inclinations are merely<br />

instinctive. But are not ours in this sense equally so? My<br />

desire to save my child from the burning house may be<br />

viewed as instinctive, but my decision to enter the house<br />

depends upon the extent of the blaze, the quick calculation<br />

of the chances of reaching her in time, the realization of<br />

my own possible demise; all this is judgement based in<br />

reason and in lightning quick time. And so too for the nonhuman<br />

animal watching its young being washed away in<br />

the flood; the instinctive impulse to throw herself into the<br />

maelstrom and cataracts, tempered by the judgement that<br />

this is perhaps not a good idea after all—better to run down<br />

the bank to a bridging point and take the chances there. I<br />

should suffer badly if I found myself in this awful position.<br />

Why should not the non-human animal? But let us grant<br />

the differential of intensity, for consciousness is more a<br />

matter of degree than of kind; the animal suffers in the<br />

same kind of way as do I but perhaps less intensely.<br />

The ability to abstract oneself from the meaning of<br />

one’s surroundings is interesting. It suggests a fragmentation<br />

of the self which prevents the whole picture—that is the<br />

whole of one’s circumstances—from ever being perceived.<br />

Take the hierarchical pyramid. Where on this do we<br />

actually sit? I can identity three moral statuses derived from<br />

one’s position on the pyramid and each is determined by<br />

a fragmentary view of the self or being xl . Status 1 is as<br />

you would expect at the very top and relates to a being<br />

which may not be sacrificed or harmed in any way for the<br />

sake of another organism. Status 2 relates to a being<br />

which may indeed be sacrificed or harmed for the sake of<br />

another organism but only for organisms which enjoy status<br />

1. Status 2 beings must not be sacrificed or harmed for the<br />

sake of other status 2 beings. Finally there are status 3<br />

creatures. These are, not surprisingly, the most unfortunate<br />

of all for they may be sacrificed or harmed for the sake of<br />

organisms above themselves or at the same level as<br />

themselves.<br />

On this scale where am I? Where are you? We are not<br />

(it seems) status (3) organisms, yet the Nazi concentration<br />

camp experience suggests that the level at which we occupy<br />

the experiential pyramid is a matter of mere perception,<br />

or whim, or ideology, rather than a matter of fact or truth.<br />

Each sane human individual in full control of his faculties<br />

knows that it would be wrong to treat another human as<br />

a status (3) being. It is prima facie the case that qua humans<br />

we occupy the peak of the hierarchy and our justification<br />

for using lower status beings for our purposes derives from<br />

this ‘exalted’ position. But on further thought perhaps it<br />

is not so obvious that we are status (1) organisms; think<br />

again of that race of advanced extra-terrestrials who<br />

recognize our intellectual and spiritual faculties, but only<br />

as we recognize the intellectual and spiritual faculties of<br />

apes. Or think of the alleged omnipotent Creator who has<br />

fashioned His Creation for His own inscrutable Purposes.<br />

Perhaps, on reflection, we are status (2) creatures,<br />

constrained not to harm each other (although we do), and<br />

to remain beings bound forever (if unwillingly) to be<br />

sacrificed according to the desires of those persons who<br />

occupy higher positions on the hierarchy of experience.<br />

Might not we, then, become the cattle in the sheds and<br />

slaughter houses of those who perceive us as means towards<br />

some unfathomable non-human end?<br />

Final words. It seems that this experiential pyramid<br />

image is therefore all wrong; at least in its present form; it<br />

permits undue interference with the biosphere and assumes<br />

discrete levels of rank and degree of moral constraint.<br />

It’s really all a matter of being civilized and recognizing<br />

the ultimate kinship of biological forms. This is why flesh<br />

eaters surf the waves of fiery Acheron, burning cruelly as<br />

they go. They surf the fiery waters and hover about the<br />

banks in the Stygian gloom of the lower world, sustaining<br />

the crude hierarchical pyramid; feeding their vested interest<br />

in fragmentation and division in the biosphere, leading us<br />

all precisely in the wrong direction. A metaphor<br />

pointing to interdependence and interconnection<br />

would be more appropriate—something like a<br />

circulatory system with ‘being’ flowing through<br />

and nourishing all the organic parts. In such a<br />

system it would be impossible to say that one organ in itself<br />

commanded more authority and privilege than the others.<br />

In this image maybe humans can be likened to the brain<br />

of an organism—the whole biosphere; its being informs<br />

and instructs all the organs and is at the same time<br />

supported by them. Here there is interdependence and<br />

interconnection—a complex relation of mutual respect<br />

producing greater degrees of global harmony. This image<br />

is more useful I think.<br />

It is not a simple question of is it right to eat meat or not.<br />

Anybody who reduces the issue to such simple terms has simply<br />

not grasped the issue. The metaphor of the pyramid is not entirely<br />

34 The Oswestrian


THE DECIMUS SOCIETY<br />

without use, however. To the best of our knowledge humans are at<br />

the peak of the biological pyramid—at least in this restricted part<br />

of the cosmos. If it is necessary to eat the flesh of creatures lower<br />

down the hierarchy in order to maintain a healthy existence for<br />

those above, then so be it. The onus is on the flesh-eater to<br />

demonstrate that this is the case (there will always be exceptions).<br />

However, if it is the case that humans can maintain good health<br />

without eating the flesh of lesser creatures (those on lower<br />

hierarchical levels), then it is incumbent upon them to do so (for<br />

the utilitarian reasons argued for). It is merely a question of<br />

civilization, of being civilized. It is a question of spiritual growth.<br />

I maintain that anyone who has not grasped this notion cannot be<br />

taken seriously in his general moral posturing; and this is an<br />

important point, for such a person has not thought through his<br />

position regarding the moral relevance of sentience, consciousness<br />

and self-consciousness—his moral pronouncements are<br />

consequently rendered impotent; they are maimed and palsied,<br />

reduced to gimcrackery—pronouncements utterly unworthy of<br />

our acceptance. In other words, anyone who eats flesh must be in<br />

a position to defend his position in cast-iron fashion: he must<br />

demonstrate that eating flesh is a necessary part of his existence<br />

and demonstrate further that his continued existence justifies the<br />

cessation of some other creature’s existence! Therein lies the moral<br />

challenge for the barbarians.<br />

Notes<br />

i It was a significant event and illustrative of<br />

the power of principle to override the<br />

dictates of the sympathetic nervous<br />

system.<br />

ii Pythagoras (c550-c500 BC): founder of a<br />

religious school or community<br />

characterized by common beliefs and<br />

observances. Very little is known of him.<br />

Earliest sources regard him as a magician<br />

of sorts—an occultist. He asserted<br />

‘metempsychosis’—a doctrine of repeated<br />

incarnation of souls, with punishments<br />

and rewards for behaviour in previous<br />

lives.It is this doctrine (along with a<br />

concern for health) which probably lies<br />

behind his vegetarianism. There was, for<br />

Pythagoras, a kinship of all living<br />

things—and this idea, although ancient, is<br />

vibrant today in several forms.<br />

iii Jainism: Atheistic school of Indian<br />

philosophy (c ninth century BC) older than<br />

Buddhism. The ethical principle of nonviolence<br />

is taken in Jainism to an extreme<br />

in both practice and theory. The Jains do<br />

not believe in an omnipotent supreme<br />

being but rather in an eternal universe<br />

governed by natural laws. Souls are<br />

caught in an endless cycle of<br />

transmigration and can only break out of<br />

the cycle by practising detachment<br />

through rational perception, rational<br />

knowledge and rational conduct.<br />

Compassion for all life, human and<br />

non-human, is central to Jainism. Human<br />

life is valued especially as a unique and<br />

rare opportunity to achieve<br />

enlightenment. To kill any person, no<br />

matter what crime they committed, is<br />

considered unimaginatively abhorrent. It<br />

is the only ‘religion’ that requires monks<br />

and laity alike, from all its sects and<br />

traditions, to be vegetarian.<br />

iv Plutarch (c50 AD-c120) Middle Platonist:<br />

anticipates Plotinus in his concern to find<br />

a unified and simple supreme pinnacle of<br />

the hierarchy of reality.<br />

v Salt wrote a pioneering treatise entitled<br />

Animals’ Rights.<br />

vi ‘good’ here means moral good—that<br />

towards which we ought to aim.<br />

vii This point would have interesting moral<br />

implications for those who choose<br />

deliberately to pursue life styles that<br />

damage individual health, such as<br />

smoking, or the over indulgence of<br />

alcohol or illegal drugs. The adoption of<br />

such life styles spills negatively into the<br />

commonwealth when the treatment for<br />

the negative consequences of such life<br />

styles is paid for by the common purse. In<br />

these two regards (negative individual<br />

consequences and negative spill into the<br />

community) the individual who chooses to<br />

pursue a less than healthy life style could<br />

be viewed as being morally derelict.<br />

viii “Critique of the Doctrine of Inalienable,<br />

Natural Rights” in Anarchical Fallacies, vol.<br />

2 of Bowring (ed.) Works, 1843<br />

ix The following argument is taken from<br />

Practical Ethics (second edition) Singer P.<br />

CUP 1993<br />

x The classical utilitarian position states that<br />

an action is right if it maximizes pleasure<br />

and minimizes pain. See Bentham/Mill<br />

xi See Animals by Lori Gruen in A Companion to<br />

Ethics ed. Peter Singer, Blackwells 1997.<br />

xii Descartes argued (fatuously) that animals<br />

have no souls (he believed humans<br />

possessed these) or minds and are nothing<br />

but complex automata that act as if they<br />

had minds, feelings, preferences etc. This<br />

position has all the hallmarks of<br />

ideological (in this case Catholic)<br />

imperatives rather than reason acting<br />

upon experience.<br />

xiii Witness the consumerist excesses of<br />

Western life (in 2007 in the UK an<br />

estimated £53 billion (on average £900<br />

per head of population—61,000,000<br />

[source: The Big Tent; Scotland’s Festival<br />

of Stewardship]) was spent at Christmas<br />

in addition to normal spending levels<br />

which already allow UK living to be<br />

experienced well beyond the level of<br />

‘comfortable’ (regular food in one’s belly,<br />

heat, a roof over one’s head, health care,<br />

sanitation and education).<br />

xiv Vegetarianism based on natural sympathy<br />

alone is bound to be sentimental and<br />

unconvincing, though such sympathy<br />

might well play an important<br />

‘humanizing effect’ when working out the<br />

rational foundation of the moral<br />

community and the subsequent treatment<br />

of non-human animals in the light of<br />

such a community.<br />

xv The case for Animal Experimentation (Berkeley:<br />

University of California Press, 1986a)<br />

xvi Note that the stipulation does not rule out<br />

non-human animals per se. It is entirely<br />

possible that research on the higher<br />

primates and some cetaceans may reveal<br />

high levels of autonomy and conceptual<br />

competence belonging naturally to these<br />

non-humans and that reciprocity may not<br />

be beyond their capacity to engage in a<br />

moral community. Even if this turns out<br />

not to be the case one can easily imagine<br />

the existence of extra-terrestrial nonhuman<br />

life that would easily measure up<br />

to the criteria.<br />

xvii A human might not possess the ability to<br />

manipulate complex concepts (or any<br />

concepts), or formulate precepts and<br />

follow these, or plan a course of action<br />

and choose amongst a variety of options,<br />

or be in a position to accept responsibility<br />

for actions (the mentally infirm, or new<br />

born etc) and yet still be considered a<br />

member of the moral community by the<br />

rest of that community who do measure<br />

up to the sine qua non criteria.<br />

xviii Frey, R. G: ‘Moral Standing, the value of<br />

lives, and speciesism’, Between the Species, 4,<br />

no. 3 (Summer 1988), 191-201<br />

xix Regan, T: The Case for Animal Rights<br />

(Berkeley: University of California Press,<br />

1983).<br />

xx I do not say ‘the top levels’ because it is<br />

conceivable that there are creatures (as yet<br />

unknown to us) who possess greater<br />

weight of value than do we by virtue of<br />

their more advanced being (I leave open<br />

in what respects such creatures might be<br />

more advanced, but a single look at the<br />

imperfections of Man might give us some<br />

idea).<br />

The Oswestrian 35


THE DECIMUS SOCIETY<br />

xxi Clearly such responsibility can only kick in<br />

when a certain level of competence is<br />

reached—it is not to be supposed that<br />

dogs have responsibilities towards those<br />

members below them, say field mice.<br />

xxii “The day may come when the rest of the<br />

animal creation may acquire those rights<br />

which never could have been withholden<br />

from them but by the hand of tyranny.<br />

The French have already discovered that<br />

the blackness of the skin is no reason why<br />

a human being should be abandoned<br />

without redress to the caprice of the<br />

tormentor. It may one day come to be<br />

recognized that the number of the legs,<br />

the villosity of the skin, or the<br />

termination of the os sacrum are reasons<br />

equally insufficient for abandoning a<br />

sensitive being to the same fate. What else<br />

is it that should trace the insuperable line?<br />

Is it the faculty of reason, or perhaps the<br />

faculty of discourse? But a full-grown<br />

horse or dog is beyond comparison a<br />

more rational, as well as a more<br />

conversable animal, than an infant of a<br />

day or a week, or even a month, old. But<br />

suppose they were otherwise, what would<br />

it avail? The question is not, Can they<br />

reason? nor Can they talk? but Can they<br />

suffer?” (Introduction to the Principles of<br />

Morals and Legislation, Chapter 17,<br />

footnote.)<br />

xxiii These are the rights referred to by activists<br />

and theorists when they speak of ‘animal<br />

rights’. In the context of my ‘hierarchy of<br />

experience’ within the moral community<br />

I prefer not to imply differentiation at this<br />

level—so, the term ‘right’ in this context<br />

refers to the fundamental right of all<br />

members of the community to have their<br />

inherent value protected in an<br />

appropriate way.<br />

xxiv With my treatment withdrawn I could slip<br />

into irreversible depression and that the<br />

felicific calculus could (in principle)<br />

dictate I was put out of my misery and<br />

everyone else’s, for the benefit of the<br />

commonwealth; I am killed and the zoo<br />

animals live because their positive<br />

contribution to the general sum of<br />

welfare (happiness) in the community is<br />

greater than mine. The same calculus<br />

could also be employed to justify all sorts<br />

of (presently) ethically dubious practices<br />

such as widespread euthanasia—killing<br />

off (painlessly) the old and infirm (a huge<br />

drain on the public purse) and other<br />

undesirables such as criminals. Such acts<br />

would be acceptable if and only if it could<br />

be shown that [a] classical utilitarianism is<br />

coherent, and [b] it could be<br />

demonstrated that such acts would result<br />

in an overall net gain in happiness for the<br />

commonwealth.<br />

xxv A note of warning here: it would be easy<br />

for some human individuals or groups of<br />

individuals to argue that their position in<br />

the hierarchy was above that of other<br />

humans and groups (human and nonhuman).<br />

Whilst it would be possible to<br />

plausibly argue (on utilitarian grounds)<br />

that certain individuals and groups were<br />

indeed higher placed and for good reason<br />

(fully functioning adult humans above<br />

new born humans), it would be<br />

intolerable and illegitimate for any<br />

individual or group to argue for a higher<br />

place on grounds of mere race, or sex, or<br />

species. A careful reading of history will<br />

show that the positions occupied in the<br />

hierarchy must be argued for cogently<br />

and soundly.<br />

xxvi Human cannibalism would be wrong for<br />

the same reason.<br />

xxvii Singer, P: Animal Liberation (1975); 2nd end<br />

(New York: New York Review/Random<br />

House, 1990).<br />

Singer’s point here is that if we want to know<br />

something about the human condition<br />

from the biological, physiological,<br />

neurological point of view it would make<br />

more logical (not necessarily ethical)<br />

sense to use human beings with similar<br />

abilities to the presently vivisectionally<br />

used non-humans; such humans may give<br />

us the information the vivisectionists<br />

pursue. To use the non-human in<br />

preference to the human is speciesist and<br />

being speciesist is unethical, in the same<br />

way being sexist or racist is unethical—<br />

this is Singer’s point. Note that on this<br />

view, in theory at least, beings occupying<br />

the higher hierarchical levels might (if the<br />

circumstances allow) use beings on the<br />

lower levels if and only if it can be clearly<br />

demonstrated that beings on those higher<br />

levels will significantly benefit. Let us<br />

hope that from our own perspective that<br />

there are no beings in the universe who<br />

occupy a higher level than us.<br />

xxviii Op. cit.<br />

xxix Fisher, J: “Taking Sympathy Seriously”,<br />

Environmental Ethics, 9, no. 3 (Fall 1987),<br />

197-215.<br />

xxx These beings are too far removed from us<br />

to recognize their value—see Lem, S.<br />

Fiasco Andre Deutsche, London, 1987. In<br />

this novel the beings are destroyed; they<br />

are so far removed from human<br />

experience that they are not even<br />

perceived; they are in effect invisible.<br />

xxxi The design of the Nazi death camps such<br />

as Auschwitz-Birkenau could only have<br />

been achieved by leaving behind normal<br />

faculties of sympathy and understanding<br />

and conceiving the beings to be processed<br />

as being far removed from the beings that<br />

would carry out the processing.<br />

xxxii Perhaps I shouldn’t use the term ‘nonperson’<br />

because of its obscurity; ‘nonhuman’<br />

would be clearer—but it’s not<br />

really what I mean. I mean by ‘nonperson’<br />

a consciousness which is not<br />

reflective and therefore relative to<br />

‘persons’ stands upon a lower level on the<br />

pyramid of consciousness. Such nonpersons<br />

can be happy—but they will not<br />

know they are happy.<br />

xxxiii There is no obvious way in which our<br />

present education system attempts to<br />

teach and cultivate this moral eye; instead<br />

we rely upon a rather murky ad hoc<br />

approach to building civilization; we tend<br />

to make things up as we go along.<br />

xxxiv According to the principle of equal<br />

considerations of interests it may well be<br />

acceptable for me to eat a fellow human<br />

in order to ensure my survival if the<br />

circumstances are such that would, on<br />

utilitarian grounds, allow consumption of<br />

my companion i.e, applying the principle<br />

of equal consideration of interests it<br />

becomes clear that my interest in this case<br />

(to survive in order to satisfy future desires<br />

[I am not yet dying and know that in all<br />

probability a rescue party is being<br />

organized and will arrive within a<br />

month]) carries more moral weight than<br />

that of my fellow human who lies dying<br />

in the Andean snow (he is terminally<br />

injured and will be dead within twentyfour<br />

hours; his desire being a reluctance<br />

not to be eaten—he will die and not have<br />

the opportunity to satisfy any remaining<br />

interests he has). Will I have needlessly<br />

thrown away my life (something I don’t<br />

want to do) if I do not eat the body of my<br />

dead companion? What could the moral<br />

justification be if both of us die when it<br />

was possible for one of us to survive? I<br />

could not prevent the death of my<br />

companion, but I could prevent the death<br />

of myself. How could a third party<br />

coherently justify my death through my<br />

non-consumption of my companion?<br />

xxxv Hear echoes of Plato’s cave allegory:<br />

Republic<br />

xxxvi A la Hitchhiker’s Guide to the Galaxy Adams,<br />

D, BBC Radio 4 1978<br />

xxxvii Whilst humans do not formally resemble<br />

insects it should not be assumed that<br />

humans and insects have nothing in<br />

common.<br />

xxxviii This could be justified on the grounds<br />

that the human had the possibility of<br />

realizing more interests than the cow.<br />

However, if matters were not equal (the<br />

case of the cow is too obvious) then<br />

different decisions might be made. For<br />

example, perhaps it were a chimpanzee<br />

that was involved (our nearest genetic<br />

cousin). The chimpanzee is normal in<br />

every respect but the human is severely<br />

intellectually and emotionally disabled (on<br />

objective assessment the chimpanzee is<br />

considerably in advance of the human in<br />

the ‘personhood’ stakes). Under such<br />

circumstances it would be right to forfeit<br />

the life of the human according to the<br />

principle of equal consideration of<br />

interests.<br />

36 The Oswestrian


TWO SCHOOL CLUBS<br />

Chess Club<br />

THE SCHOOL’s chess club has had another successful<br />

year, following the established pattern. In the<br />

Michaelmas term we concentrated on improving<br />

everyone’s game by studying techniques and strategy as<br />

well as playing plenty of practice games.<br />

In the Lent term we participated in the UK Land Chess<br />

Challenge, now the world’s largest chess competition with<br />

around 75,000 competitors. We played the school-based<br />

rounds, in which Sam Skubala triumphed and took the<br />

trophy, despite one surprise defeat at the hands of Kyle Real.<br />

Furthermore, four players qualified for the regional<br />

megafinal in Hereford. They were Richard Herbert, Richard<br />

Christie, George Tomley and Sam Skubala.<br />

The megafinal took place on Saturday 3 May and it<br />

welcomed around 200 players from a large area of Wales<br />

and the English border counties. Competition was very keen<br />

and three of our players, Richard H, Richard C and George<br />

played around the mid-level of the tournament.<br />

Sam Skubala was more successful still, scoring four out<br />

of six points. This meant that he qualified for the next stage<br />

of the tournament, which was the northern semi-final (called<br />

Richard Christie, Richard Herbert, Sam Skubala and George Tomley<br />

the gigafinal) in Manchester and which took place in July.<br />

CR Hooper<br />

Metal Modelling Club<br />

ITOOK OVER the metal modelling club when I arrived<br />

in January 1993 and it has been a popular club for year<br />

7 and year 8 pupils ever since. The group photo on page<br />

2 is just a selection of past and present pupils who were<br />

metal modellers in their day!<br />

When I was first asked to run the club I had visions of<br />

large pieces of metal and a welding torch. Of course it was<br />

nothing like that! Last year, when I visited Ireland for a<br />

I’d heard how good metal modelling club was and I<br />

was really looking forward to it when I moved into<br />

year 7. I was not disappointed—it has been fantastic!<br />

At first we had to learn about safety. Then it was on<br />

to the really exciting bit—making the models!<br />

I chose to make the British foot soldiers and the<br />

French cavalry. To make a model you first need to<br />

prepare the mould by dusting it on the inside with<br />

talcum powder. This helps the alloy to fill all of the<br />

mould. Next you melt a small piece of the metal bar<br />

in a pan. I love the smell as it melts and like watching<br />

the molten metal as it runs around the pan. Once it<br />

has all melted you pour it into the mould and wait<br />

for it to set. One of the best bits is seeing how your<br />

model turns out. The highlight for me was making<br />

26 perfect model foot soldiers in one hour!<br />

Matthew Masters<br />

Every Thursday after school for the last two terms<br />

Mrs Hart, our science teacher, has been taking some<br />

students for the metal modelling club. Around twelve<br />

year 7 and 8 students attended each week and made<br />

numerous metal models ranging from the 82nd<br />

Highlanders to Napoleon’s army. These models<br />

included men, weapons, treasure, some students even<br />

complete chess sets!<br />

Some students decided to leave their models<br />

unpainted as they looked great all silvery and<br />

polished, and others decided to paint their models so<br />

they looked bright and shiny. Either way they looked<br />

great!<br />

Sadly Mrs Hart is leaving at the end of term, and<br />

all of us in the metal modelling club wish her well<br />

in her retirement!<br />

Charles Fryer-Stevens<br />

holiday, I discovered that the Prince August factory (where<br />

the metal and the moulds originally come from) was en route<br />

to the Dingle Peninsula, so I stopped off to have a look<br />

round. As it was a Saturday the factory was unfortunately<br />

closed but I did buy some new moulds that were no longer<br />

available from the Hobbies craft shop in London. I do hope<br />

that the club will continue to flourish!<br />

M Hart<br />

The Oswestrian 37


Academic<br />

The Library<br />

“I have always imagined that Paradise will be a kind of<br />

library.”<br />

Samuel Johnson (1709-1784)<br />

“I find television very educational. The minute somebody<br />

turns it on, I go to the library and read a good book.”<br />

Groucho Marx (1890-1977)<br />

Conor Roche, Freddie Kynaston-Evans and Sam Johnson at Fuse<br />

IT HAS BEEN an exceptional year for the library. The<br />

physical environment has been dramatically improved<br />

thanks to the PA’s investment in tables, tub chairs,<br />

pictures and curtains, and new computers have<br />

revolutionized the speed of internet access. We hope our<br />

library has always been as functional and inspirational a<br />

place as those of Samuel Johnson and Groucho Marx. Now<br />

it is comfortable and up to date as well. A library for the<br />

young people of the 21st century.<br />

Normal library activities have continued. High points<br />

were a Tudor costume history and dance session, the annual<br />

book exchange in March for World Book Day and a jazz<br />

session with regular library visitors Eddie Matthews and<br />

Jenny Miller, who usually perform at the Mytton and<br />

Mermaid in Atcham.<br />

Last year the 1407 and all That literary and living history<br />

event was so well received by the seven to thirteen-yearolds<br />

who were involved that we decided to establish an<br />

annual book festival and include writers and storytellers to<br />

work with all the age groups in the school. Finding suitable<br />

and inspirational educators and performers to work with<br />

children from the age of two and young people up to the<br />

age of 19 was a demanding task but the response we got<br />

from pupils of all ages repaid the effort involved.<br />

The Booked Up festival ran from 5 May to 9 May. The<br />

youngest children in the school had storytelling sessions<br />

from Helen East, a local performer with a national<br />

reputation. Pupils from years 3 to 7 learnt how to write a<br />

non-fiction book with children’s author John Malam, met<br />

football detective series author Tom Palmer and competed<br />

in a quiz and penalty shootout session with him, learnt about<br />

Framed by Frank Cottrell Boyce (the book voted by the<br />

people of <strong>Oswestry</strong> to be the summer’s “big read”), had<br />

talks from Peter Edwards—school governor and National<br />

Portrait Gallery exhibited artist—and Heather Rodenhurst<br />

from the public library, and were educated and entertained<br />

with the stories of the Firebird and Jason and the Argonauts<br />

by storytelling group Annamation.<br />

Pupils from years 8 to 13 had a different show performed<br />

by Annamation. Aimed at a teenage audience, the Tongue<br />

and Groove show effortlessly conveyed the folk stories of a<br />

hundred different cultures and had the audience on the edge<br />

of their seats. Then year 9 had interpretative workshops with<br />

members of the group, year 10 and 11 had comic writing<br />

workshops with Dave Smith—a comedian with a track<br />

record from Jongleurs and the Comedy Club—and years 12<br />

and 13 had creative writing workshops with Dave<br />

Armstrong, an <strong>Oswestry</strong> author with a national readership.<br />

With John Malam<br />

38 The Oswestrian


THE LIBRARY<br />

In the library during World Book Day<br />

The pictures say it all, and I wish there was room to print<br />

more! The event was varied, demanding and inspirational.<br />

We discovered some previously unknown talents for comic<br />

prose (the best probably from George Hugheston-Roberts)<br />

and the power of the written and spoken word was<br />

highlighted for the whole school and our visitors from<br />

Richard Herbert in Tudor costume<br />

Morda, the Meadows, Trefonen, St John the Baptist and Ysgol<br />

Bro Cynllaith primary schools and the Marches and Rhyn<br />

Park. The book week will be an annual event. All suggestions<br />

for authors and storytellers for next year will be gratefully<br />

received!<br />

A Gonzalez<br />

Charles Fryer-Stevens, Cian Roche, Mr Stockdale, Isabelle Makin and<br />

Lucy Whitthread during Private Peaceful day<br />

Promoting Private Peaceful<br />

As part of <strong>Oswestry</strong>’s “Big Read”, promoting the<br />

National Year of Reading, <strong>Oswestry</strong> <strong>School</strong><br />

championed Private Peaceful, by Michael Morpurgo. Set<br />

during the first world war the book tells the story of Private<br />

Thomas “Tommo” Peaceful, who lied about his age in order<br />

to join up. Tommo wants to be with his older brother,<br />

Charlie, who was bullied into enlisting by the spiteful local<br />

squire. Michael Morpurgo is one of the country’s foremost<br />

children’s authors and was Children’s Laureate from 2003-<br />

2005. Here are the comments of some of the students:<br />

Private Peaceful is a gripping novel by the fantastic writer<br />

Michael Morpurgo. It is set in the First World War. It is a<br />

story of innocence, love, courage and cowardice.<br />

Lucy Whitthread<br />

In the library<br />

Private Peaceful was Michael Morpurgo’s 100th book. It<br />

is a great novel told through the voice of a young soldier<br />

called Tommo Peaceful. My personal rating gives it *****.<br />

Charles Fryer-Stevens<br />

No matter how many times I read it I still cry. I really<br />

thought I was with Tommo all the way. I taste his first mug<br />

of sweet tea in the stinking, dilapidated trench, I smell the<br />

deadly mustard gas, I hear the sound of silence waiting for<br />

the Germans to attack. The best book I have ever read!<br />

Isabelle Makin<br />

From when I first opened this book I knew I would find<br />

it hard to put it down. You could swear the account was<br />

coming straight from the mouth of an actual grunt down in<br />

the trenches. I found this book highly enjoyable and look<br />

forward to reading more Michael Morpurgo.<br />

Cian Roche<br />

The Oswestrian 39


ART<br />

Art<br />

THIS YEAR, Mrs Stonehill, head of art, ran the third<br />

summer art exhibition in the gym. The second<br />

exhibition formed part of the sexcentenary<br />

celebrations and revealed some unusual pieces and living<br />

sculpture. Gyles Brandreth, the guest speaker at Speech Day,<br />

was so impressed by the range and diversity of the artwork<br />

and the living statues that he was still talking about it on his<br />

way to the BBC the next day! A film crew televised the art<br />

installation for its summer series of broadcasts.<br />

This year the exhibition revealed many large scale<br />

sculptures inspired by the works of Claes Oldenburg. It was<br />

again very popular with parents and friends who visited in<br />

extremely large numbers.<br />

The department also made many visits during the course<br />

of the year, including ones to life-drawing courses both in<br />

school and at the Tate Gallery in Liverpool. Further visits to<br />

the Clothes Show in Birmingham and to the DLA Piper<br />

Series (an exhibition at the Tate Gallery) provided varied<br />

and unusual inspiration for the pupils.<br />

A Stonehill<br />

Pupils, parents and governors at the 2008 summer exhibition<br />

From the Bellan art workshop<br />

Bellan pupils visit Mrs Stonehill’s classroom for an art workshop<br />

Living statues at the 2007 art exhibition in the gym<br />

From the summer exhibition<br />

Story teller Michael Quinn with the art gifted and talented group<br />

40 The Oswestrian


ART<br />

Kristina Kingolts’ work at the 2008 summer exhibition<br />

A sculpture set in the school grounds by Abigail Jones<br />

Kristina Kingolts<br />

Polly Morgan at the Tate Gallery<br />

Abigail Jones preparing for the summer exhibition<br />

Vivien Lee<br />

Mr Fred Rowson by Luke Broster<br />

Victoria Martoccia<br />

The Oswestrian 41


MATHEMATICS<br />

Mathematics<br />

MANY STUDENTS throughout the school were<br />

once again involved this year in the National<br />

Mathematics Challenge competitions and World<br />

Maths Day.<br />

On World Maths Day on 5 March 2008 we contributed<br />

44,586 correct answers to the new world record of<br />

182,455,169 correct answers that were completed in one day<br />

around the world. 172 students participated in one of the<br />

four individual challenges. A team of year 8 and year 9<br />

pupils represented the school at the regional final of the<br />

junior team challenge and, for the first time, four members<br />

of the sixth form (Ajeeratul Abdullah, Elizabeth Ashby,<br />

Norhanisah Haji Abd Rani and George Read) competed in<br />

the new senior team challenge competition, coming fourth<br />

in the regional final at Wolverhampton University.<br />

Why don’t you try some of the questions yourself at the<br />

bottom of the page? Calculators are not allowed!<br />

EM Scott<br />

SENIOR MATHEMATICAL CHALLENGE<br />

SILVER Gao Wen (Best in <strong>School</strong>), Iqbal Caesar, George Read,<br />

Desiree Wong, George Yu, Jialong Yu<br />

BRONZE Ajeeratul Abdullah, Elizabeth Ashby, Carlos Ip,<br />

Martin Menzel, Renee Poon, Martha Twigg<br />

INTERMEDIATE MATHEMATICAL CHALLENGE<br />

TEAM CHALLENGE Y8 AND Y9<br />

REGIONAL FINAL (11th place) Emily Bromage, Rhys<br />

Gaynor-Johnson, Natalie Renwick, Victoria Whittingham<br />

SENIOR TEAM CHALLENGE Y12 AND Y13<br />

REGIONAL FINAL (4th place) Ajeeratul Abdullah, Elizabeth<br />

Ashby, Norhanisah Haji Abd Rani, George Read<br />

GOLD Geraint Jones (Best in <strong>School</strong>), Rebecca Long, Sam<br />

Wong<br />

SILVER Callum Morris, Natalie Renwick, Ruth Reynolds<br />

BRONZE Leo Banks, Catherine Bateman, Emily Bromage,<br />

Ben Chan, Sean Crompton, Anastasia Derzhiruchenko,<br />

Millie Evans, Laurence Huang, Annie Keogh, Jonathan<br />

Molesworth, Zak Real, James Rogers, Charlie Underhill,<br />

David Ward, Victoria Whittingham, Lucy Williams,<br />

Viktor Yushyn<br />

JUNIOR MATHEMATICAL CHALLENGE<br />

GOLD Matthew Henderson, Leon Parkes<br />

SILVER Emily Bromage, Joe Collinge, Emma Duncombe,<br />

Henry James, Ryan Morris, Jack Nyhan, Daniel Renwick,<br />

Daisy Tickner<br />

BRONZE Christian Blount-Powell, Louis Fisher, Charles<br />

Fryer-Stevens, Edward Green, Matilda Hicklin, Isabelle<br />

Makin, Matteo O’Mahoney, Samuel Skubala<br />

EUROPEAN PINK KANGAROO (by invitation only) MERIT CERTIFICATE Geraint Jones<br />

1. The equilateral triangle XYZ is fixed in position. Two<br />

of the four small triangles are to be painted black and<br />

the other two are to be painted white. In how many<br />

different ways can this be done?<br />

A 3 B 4 C 5 D 6 E more than 6<br />

X<br />

Y<br />

Z<br />

2. The square of a non-zero number is equal to 70% of<br />

the original number. What is the original number?<br />

A 700 B 70 C 7 D 0·7 E 0·07<br />

3. In a certain year, there were exactly four Tuesdays<br />

and exactly four Fridays in October. On what day of<br />

the week did Halloween, October 31st, fall that year?<br />

A Monday B Wednesday<br />

C Thursday D Saturday E Sunday<br />

4. The mean of a sequence of 64 numbers is 64. The<br />

mean of the first 36 numbers is 36. What is the mean<br />

of the last 28 numbers?<br />

A 28 B 44 C 72 D 100 E 108<br />

5. What is the largest prime number that divides exactly<br />

into the number equal to 2 + 3 + 5 × 7?<br />

A 2 B 3 C 5 D 7 E 11<br />

6. The shaded region is bounded by<br />

eight equal circles with centres at the<br />

corners and midpoints of the sides of<br />

a square. The perimeter of the square<br />

has length 8. What is the length of the<br />

perimeter of the shaded region?<br />

A π B 2π C 8 D 3π E 4π<br />

7. What is the value of 2006 × 2008 – 2007 × 2007?<br />

A –2007 B –1 C 0 D 1 E 4 026 042<br />

8. Which of the following gives the exact number of<br />

seconds in six complete weeks?<br />

A 9! B 10! C 11! D 12! E 13!<br />

{Note that n! = 1 × 2 × 3 × … × n.}<br />

9. How many whole numbers between 1 and 2007 are<br />

divisible by 2 but not by 7?<br />

A 857 B 858 C 859 D 860 E 861<br />

10. How many hexagons can be found in the diagram if<br />

each side of a hexagon must consist of all or part of<br />

one of the straight lines in the diagram?<br />

A 4 B 8 C 12 D 16 E 20<br />

1 D, 2 D, 3 A, 4 D, 5 C, 6 D, 7 B, 8 B, 9 D, 10 D<br />

42 The Oswestrian


A RESTORED HONOURS BOARD<br />

For Honours Past Received<br />

SCHOOL LIBRARIAN Arabella Gonzalez was<br />

intrigued to find out what was on the large brown<br />

gloss-painted board on the wall of the library and<br />

made arrangements with a specialist to have the board<br />

carefully stripped and for the writing revealed to be<br />

repainted. Just in time for the end of term, the honours board<br />

was returned, allowing visitors to the library on Speech Day<br />

to have a glimpse of Old Oswestrian academic success.<br />

The board is only for the years 1892 and 1893, (there is<br />

a large gap beneath the writing). This was the first year of<br />

the headmastership of John Jordan Lloyd-Williams MA, said<br />

to be a very able headmaster and a good classical scholar.<br />

In his book A History of <strong>Oswestry</strong> <strong>School</strong>, Oakley states that,<br />

under Lloyd-Williams, “there was success at the universities<br />

surpassing any other public<br />

school of the same size”.<br />

Seven different names are<br />

listed on the board. The<br />

following information has been<br />

found out about some of them.<br />

ET Baines Oakley adds<br />

only a brief “very good<br />

cricketer”.<br />

ET Davies, Tom, was the<br />

elder brother of Sir Walford<br />

Davies, Master of the King’s<br />

Music from 1934 until 1941.<br />

Oakley states that Tom was<br />

also a brilliant musician, emigrating to Australia where “he<br />

made his mark”. Wikipedia on the internet tells us that Tom<br />

“followed a family tradition by entering the ministry”.<br />

AA Maclardy was the middle of three brothers, John,<br />

Archibald and Hugh, who all came to <strong>Oswestry</strong> <strong>School</strong>. For<br />

many years, according to Oakley, AA was a master at King<br />

Edward’s <strong>School</strong>, Birmingham, probably a classics master<br />

as he is also the author of two Latin text books, first<br />

published in 1899, which are still in print today!<br />

Interestingly, the boys were the sons of John Maclardy,<br />

born in Argyllshire in 1842, who settled in Shrewsbury but<br />

moved to <strong>Oswestry</strong> where he was a portrait and animal<br />

painter, landscape and art photographer, according to<br />

Industries of Shropshire and District Business Review of<br />

1891, in premises above 4-6 Church Street, becoming a<br />

councillor in 1889 and mayor in 1902. One of Maclardy’s<br />

employees was Harry Sheldon Whitford, son of Richard<br />

Whitford, “animal painter to the Queen”.<br />

Ever wondered what people did before there was<br />

Facebook, the social networking website where people can<br />

view each other’s friends and social connections as well as<br />

their activities? In the 1860/70s there was a craze called<br />

cardomania where people traded carte de visite (CDV)<br />

amongst friends and visitors. CDVs were small, inexpensive<br />

photographs, each the size of a visiting card, which became<br />

enormously popular. Cardomania spread throughout<br />

Europe and then quickly to America. Albums for the<br />

collection and display of cards became a common fixture in<br />

Victorian parlours—sound familiar? Maclardy’s studio<br />

produced many CDVs and also postcards of local scenes.<br />

E Armitstead The Armitstead family is atypical of the<br />

gentry of east Cheshire in the late 18th and 19th centuries.<br />

The Rev John Armitstead (grandfather of E Armitstead) came<br />

from a Yorkshire family and was a clergyman. He purchased<br />

land in the Cranage area and shortly before his death in 1814<br />

he bought Cranage Hall. Three of the Armitsteads were<br />

clergymen associated with Sandbach continuously from<br />

1828-1941 and also at various times with Holmes Chapel<br />

and Goostrey.<br />

It seems that Edward and his older brother Lawrence<br />

were both educated at<br />

<strong>Oswestry</strong>—to their dismay.<br />

Here is what Kenrick<br />

Armitstead says about the<br />

brothers in The Cheshire<br />

Armitsteads:<br />

“Edward, who was born on<br />

the 10th September 1872, was<br />

educated at <strong>Oswestry</strong> <strong>School</strong>.<br />

As his elder brother John had<br />

been superannuated from<br />

Westminster <strong>School</strong> after two<br />

years, his father in a fit of pique<br />

decided to send his other sons<br />

to <strong>Oswestry</strong> Grammar <strong>School</strong>, for which, my father said,<br />

they never forgave him. He went up to Magdalen College<br />

Oxford and then succeeded his uncle Willy as vicar of<br />

Goostrey in 1907, remaining there until 1923.<br />

“In 1918 he married Cecilia Mary, daughter and heiress<br />

of John Kirkland Glazebrook of Twemlow Hall, and they<br />

moved into Jodrell Hall, as the vicarage was considered too<br />

small for them! In 1923 he became vicar of Barthomley where<br />

he made a great impression. A keen sportsman, he retired<br />

in 1936 to Richards Castle. His wife died there without issue<br />

in 1938 and he died on 15 October 1950.<br />

“Lawrence was born on 20 February 1870 and educated<br />

at <strong>Oswestry</strong> Grammar <strong>School</strong> and Magdalen College Oxford.<br />

He became rector of Malpas, Cheshire in 1894 and remained<br />

there until he retired in 1936. He was an honorary canon,<br />

and later emeritus canon, of Chester. He married Mary<br />

Elizabeth, daughter of Lt Colonel John Kennedy. He died<br />

on 19 July 1938 as a result of a road accident, leaving two<br />

sons.”<br />

It may not have just been pique that brought the boys to<br />

<strong>Oswestry</strong>; headmasters Dr Donne and his son, the Rev<br />

Stephen Donne, had brought the school an excellent<br />

reputation at this time, particularly amongst ecclesiastical<br />

families, resulting in pupils such as Col Fred Burnaby and<br />

the Rev Canon WA Spooner attending the school. There is<br />

also a link between the Armitstead family and the governors<br />

The Oswestrian 43


A FRENCH EXCHANGE TRIP<br />

of <strong>Oswestry</strong> <strong>School</strong> during this period; in 1917, Edward<br />

officiated at the wedding of his sister to the bishop of St<br />

Asaph (governor) when the best man was Sir Watkin<br />

Williams-Wynn (also a governor).<br />

An interesting fact about this family is that Edward’s<br />

uncles Willy, John and Henry were very keen cricketers and<br />

founder members of the Free Foresters Cricket Club, and it<br />

was Willy who introduced the custom of umpires wearing<br />

a white coat. During a match between the United England<br />

XI and a team of 15 Free Foresters at Manchester in 1861,<br />

Willy stopped the game, complaining that he could not see<br />

the ball against the drab figure of the umpire. The complaint<br />

was upheld, and in the words of the day “the umpire was<br />

vested in a nightshirt”.<br />

Ever since, umpires have worn white.<br />

HP Yates<br />

Modern Foreign Languages<br />

The first leg of the French exchange<br />

WHEN I RECEIVED the brown envelope<br />

containing the information about the French<br />

student I had been partnered with, I was a bit<br />

worried about what was inside. However, to my relief, Julia<br />

seemed really friendly in her letter and we had some things<br />

in common. This meant I was a lot less nervous about her<br />

arrival.<br />

On Sunday 9 March my dad and I walked down to<br />

school to meet Julia, who would be staying in our home for<br />

the following week. As we reached school, I was very<br />

anxious. This was mostly owing to the worry that we<br />

wouldn’t be able to communicate and we would spend the<br />

following week in awkward silence. After Mrs Chidlow had<br />

introduced my dad and me to Julia, I knew that this wouldn’t<br />

be the case at all, as she was lovely and friendly. At home,<br />

we had a bite to eat and got to know each other a bit more<br />

and then went to bed as she had had a long day.<br />

The following day, I did my morning routine as normal<br />

as it was important that she got a taste of our family life. At<br />

school, they came to our whole school assembly and had a<br />

tour around the school. During break there was a reception<br />

given by the headmaster in the archive room and then our<br />

partners came to the next lessons with us, which was PE for<br />

me. In France they only do the practical side of PE so it was<br />

good for Julia to see what a PE theory lesson consisted of.<br />

Each day, the French exchange students went to a<br />

different place in the area. They visited Shrewsbury, Conway,<br />

Chester, the theatre at Mold to see The Elephant Man and<br />

Liverpool. The students spent the evenings with their host<br />

families and I tried to do something different each night. We<br />

had a family meal most nights so this was a good<br />

opportunity to get to know each other a lot more.<br />

On Monday nights I play netball in the women’s league<br />

and I found out that they don’t play netball in France. This<br />

was an opportunity for Julia to see the game for herself. On<br />

Tuesday, it was my birthday so in the evening I invited<br />

Hannah, Katy and Abby and their exchange partners to<br />

come over in the evening so we could all mix and all get to<br />

know each other.<br />

A netball team meal had been planned for the<br />

Wednesday night, so Katy and I brought our exchange<br />

partners along with us and I know that they both really<br />

enjoyed themselves. Thursday night was the Songs and<br />

Scenes night at school and I know this was again really<br />

enjoyed by all the exchange students and it was good for<br />

them to see what sort of things go on at our school. Julia said<br />

that they don’t do things like that at their school in France<br />

so it was really enjoyable for her. On the Friday night, Tom<br />

Alister Talbot, Charlie Underhill and Adam Lloyd<br />

All the students and staff at Liverpool<br />

44 The Oswestrian


THE MFL DEPARTMENT<br />

Back row—Katie Hughes, Emily Middleton, Mrs Smith, Mrs Chidlow, Christopher Harvey, JJ Crawford;<br />

seated front—Nathaniel Gliksman, Kristina Kingolts, Anna Shpilman<br />

had a party, which was fun and I know that the exchange<br />

partners who went loved it because everybody made them<br />

feel welcome and they did a lot of dancing.<br />

On Saturday we all went to Liverpool. Unfortunately, it<br />

was another early start so we were all quite tired. When we<br />

arrived, we visited the Beatles Museum where we were<br />

given walkie-talkie headphones to listen to as we walked<br />

around. This was soon called to a halt when the fire alarm<br />

went off, which turned out to have gone off all around the<br />

Albert Dock. We didn’t have time to stand around so we<br />

went on to our next destination which was the Museum of<br />

Slavery. We went there because the French students were<br />

doing a project on the role of Liverpool in the growth of the<br />

slave trade.<br />

Following this, we made our way down to the ferry port<br />

where we took a boat trip on the Mersey and this is also<br />

where we ate our lunch. It wasn’t the highlight of everyone’s<br />

day as a lot of us suffered from sea sickness. Much to<br />

everyone’s delight it was shopping next but before we all<br />

went our separate ways we went down into the original<br />

Cavern Club where the Beatles started out. It was an ace<br />

little club and it was really good to see. It was now time for<br />

some shopping and we were told where to meet in the next<br />

hour and a half. We met up a little earlier so the people who<br />

didn’t finish the tour of the Beatles Museum had another<br />

chance. While they looked around it again, some of us went<br />

to the cafe next door.<br />

Our final part of the day was a trip on the Yellow Marine<br />

Duck which took us on a tour around the city and then<br />

finally it drove into the Mersey and turned into a boat. It<br />

was a really lively tour as the tour guide was a young guy<br />

who made it fun and it wasn’t at all boring. By the end of<br />

the day, we were all very tired and the rain had begun. It<br />

was time for us to return home on the coach. At home, we<br />

bought a Chinese takeaway and both had an early night as<br />

we had had a busy week.<br />

The Sunday was a family day, so my parents, Julia and<br />

I went to the waterfall at Llanrhaeadr. It was a good day to<br />

go because the waterfall and rivers were high. We went for<br />

a walk then went for a hot chocolate in the cafe. We wanted<br />

to show Julia some of the Welsh countryside and I am sure<br />

that she appreciated it. When we arrived home she also had<br />

a taste of the traditional English roast.<br />

Monday meant leaving day and it was sad but it was<br />

good to know that I would be seeing Julia again. Before they<br />

got on the coach to leave for the airport, we all said our<br />

goodbyes and it made us all excited for the second leg of<br />

our French exchange.<br />

Throughout the week, we tried to talk English to Julia<br />

because this was why she had come on this exchange. She<br />

really made an effort to contribute to different conversations<br />

and if she didn’t know how to say it English, I tried to say<br />

it in French so it was a good experience for both of us. As<br />

the week went on my confidence in speaking French<br />

improved, as hers did in English, so this made it easy for us<br />

to have conversations. We both gained so much from this<br />

week and I am very happy I agreed to take part in this<br />

exchange. Julia was absolutely lovely and I can’t wait to<br />

spend another week with her France. I think I can say on<br />

behalf of the French students that they have taken a lot home<br />

with them and they have had an amazing experience as I<br />

know we all have.<br />

Thank you, Mrs Chidlow, for arranging the exchange.<br />

Katherine Stockdale<br />

The Oswestrian 45


A MODERN LANGUAGES DAY<br />

THE MEADOWS PRIMARY SCHOOL INTERNATIONAL DAY<br />

<strong>Oswestry</strong> <strong>School</strong> was once again invited to take part in this important day. Normal lessons were cancelled<br />

for the children in Key Stages 1 and 2, who instead benefited from a better understanding of the<br />

languages and cultures of various countries.<br />

Assistant tutor Nick Jensen introduced New Zealand, while assistant tutor Martin Diaz and year 13 student<br />

Brooke Simons-Akwah spoke about Chile. Languages teacher Miss Shaw and Italian pupil Nicolo Pancini<br />

delivered lessons in Italian and Mrs Chidlow co-ordinated the smooth running of the sessions. There was a<br />

scary moment for Mrs Chidlow when she was wrongly introduced to the class as Lucy Pare, one of her former<br />

pupils who is now a primary teacher in Coventry with a special interest in Japanese.<br />

Lower sixth modern foreign languages day<br />

The day began with an early start of 7.30am, much to<br />

everyone’s delight! After having waited for the final<br />

person to arrive (who will remain nameless) we were able<br />

to set off in pursuit of expanding our knowledge of the<br />

language we were learning, and hope that we would return<br />

fluent, native speakers. These high expectations daunted us<br />

at such an early hour. However the mood of the keen<br />

linguists was lifted after Hannah Bick, a French speaker,<br />

announced to the minibus that she had several bags of<br />

Haribo for all to share.<br />

We eventually reached our destination of Market<br />

Drayton after about an hour’s journey. The group was in<br />

high spirits after playing numerous rounds of Martha<br />

Twigg’s infamous “would you rather” game.<br />

After being presented with our welcome packs and name<br />

tags we were seated in the auditorium for our welcome. The<br />

first lecture for French students involved us listening to a<br />

rather catchy and enjoyable song by Serge Gainsbourg. The<br />

next French lecture taught us about the difference between<br />

slang and formal French language. A short refreshment break<br />

preceded the next session in which all of the French students<br />

at the conference were split into several groups led by<br />

students from Keele University. Each group then had to<br />

either argue for or against the installation of a wind farm in<br />

a remote French village, the result of the debate being<br />

undetermined.<br />

A brilliant lunch of food from all over the world satisfied<br />

the hungry language learners and gave us (or rather Katy<br />

and Vicky) a chance to introduce the non-French speaking<br />

students to the song that we had learnt that morning.<br />

The afternoon’s lectures began with an informative talk<br />

on why languages are so important in successful careers, in<br />

this increasingly multilingual world.<br />

The final lectures of the day were sessions on learning<br />

the Russian and Chinese languages. These two sessions were<br />

led by wonderfully inspiring native speakers and were<br />

enjoyed extremely by all of the students.<br />

The group then left the conference on the minibus and<br />

were able to eat their second lunch of the day owing to<br />

packed lunches being provided! Katherine Stockdale was<br />

especially excited about this extra treat. We arrived back at<br />

school for the end of the day, feeling fulfilled and ambitious<br />

to learn more, as most of us were still not fluent quite yet.<br />

A special thanks must be given to our fabulous bus driver<br />

and head of MFL, Mrs Chidlow, and also to our Frenchspeaking<br />

gap-year student, Nick Jensen, who accompanied<br />

us on the trip and wowed us all with his language skills.<br />

Abigail Jones<br />

Brooke Simons-Akwah, Catherina Baum, Elizabeth Ashby, Tom Llewellyn, Liam Chambers, Katy Yates and Victoria Martoccia at the conference<br />

46 The Oswestrian


SCHOOLS IN GERMANY<br />

How German schools differ from ours<br />

Lara Hopkins, Lucy Niblock and Katherine Stockdale at the conference<br />

German student Melanie Barth, from the<br />

University of Leipzig, was welcomed into<br />

the department in September last year. She was<br />

keen to observe how languages are taught here<br />

and then teach some lessons herself as part of her<br />

teacher training course. Her lessons were always<br />

meticulously planned, highly interesting and<br />

relevant.<br />

She also worked closely with Mr and Mrs<br />

Stonehill in Guinevere boarding house, carrying<br />

out duties and helping with activities for the<br />

children and was greatly missed when her sixweek<br />

placement came to an end. We send her our<br />

grateful thanks and all good wishes for her career<br />

in education.<br />

• There are no morning assemblies. A notice board<br />

provides all the information needed.<br />

• Chatty chat chat… If there is something important that<br />

they need to hear they will be told to listen.<br />

• The day starts at 8am and finishes at 1pm. You have the<br />

rest of the afternoon to do anything, including<br />

homework.<br />

• There is a cafeteria but hardly anyone uses it—they go<br />

home for lunch.<br />

• There are in-depth discussions in class.<br />

• Students take notes, as well as referring to textbooks.<br />

• A bell commands you to leave!<br />

• A lot of girls don’t wear any make-up at all.<br />

• No chapel but church three times a year in school.<br />

• Teachers move to lessons, not pupils. This means there<br />

are fewer displays on the walls.<br />

• There are only a few whiteboards and none of the<br />

teachers have laptops.<br />

• Own clothes can be worn, anything goes.<br />

• Hair can be any length or colour.<br />

• Lessons are less formal and structured.<br />

• Most of the pupils arrive on bikes or by bus.<br />

Cian Roche<br />

What I noticed in Germany<br />

• They have really big radiators.<br />

• The light switches are bigger and squarer.<br />

• Crazy drivers.<br />

• Always trying to give you more food.<br />

• The houses are all different.<br />

• They get up very early.<br />

• BEAUTIFUL TOWNS!<br />

• They speak better English than we speak German.<br />

• Clean streets.<br />

• English adverts in the shops.<br />

• English programmes on German TV.<br />

• English songs on the radio.<br />

• Parties are later.<br />

• SAUSAGES!<br />

• The school bell.<br />

• Not as green as England—more vineyards, less grass.<br />

• Massive pillows!<br />

• The zips are the other way round.<br />

Alice Redmond<br />

Mrs Chidlow, Mrs Tickner, Nick Jensen and Mrs Payne<br />

Mrs Alison Tickner, mother of Daisy and Jasmine, and<br />

former member of staff Mrs Mary Smith, worked in<br />

the MFL department following an unfortunate accident to<br />

Mrs Jacqueline Meyer in early September. Colleagues and<br />

pupils were all most grateful for their hard work and<br />

enthusiasm during the Michaelmas and Lent terms.<br />

The Oswestrian 47


A STREAM OF CONSCIOUSNESS<br />

Spooner Cottage<br />

The following piece of writing is called a “stream of<br />

consciousness” and is written non-stop without regard to<br />

normal rules of punctuation or grammar—or anything else for<br />

that matter! Why not give it a try? You may well surprise<br />

yourself!<br />

I really enjoyed reading this piece; it reminds me of some of<br />

the old Monty Python cartoon sketches.<br />

C Eve<br />

Squirrels and dandelions dance on the mad boat to<br />

somewhere that I don’t know but I bet it’s pink and floaty<br />

and has a paddling pool the size of Manchester or Bill Gates<br />

or something but what happened if sharks lived in these<br />

waters and all smoked pipes and ate beans on toast with<br />

marmalade evil marmalade that would take over the world<br />

but luckily super pear and his sidekick the chimp were here<br />

to save the world they took a plane to England and went to<br />

their house that was made out of jelly but it wasn’t there<br />

because I ate it and it was yummy but the jellyfish didn’t<br />

think so because he was a vegetarian and this jelly was meat<br />

flavoured but the clouds liked to rain and rain and the<br />

sunshine was mad because of this so he blew up and<br />

Mrs Eve<br />

destroyed everything except king Cosmos and his brothers<br />

who were lions and the three biceps who had feet and<br />

swords so beware king Cosmos said lets make a new<br />

universe so they made a new universe using their eyelashes<br />

as paint brushes and painted a new world which was called<br />

platypus paradise until the sharks came back and they were<br />

angry they smoked their pipes inside the non-smoking areas<br />

but luckily a huge contact lens came and squashed them all<br />

God picked up the contact lens and put it back in should<br />

have gone to specsavers! Maybe the window sills will tell<br />

the future!<br />

Henry Brown<br />

<br />

<br />

<br />

<br />

<br />

<br />

<br />

<br />

<br />

<br />

<br />

<br />

<br />

<br />

<strong>48</strong> The Oswestrian

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!