03.05.2014 Views

Number Systems with Simplicity Hierarchies: A ... - Ohio University

Number Systems with Simplicity Hierarchies: A ... - Ohio University

Number Systems with Simplicity Hierarchies: A ... - Ohio University

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

1232 PHILIP EHRLICH<br />

it being understood that x is simpler than y just in case x is a predecessor of y in<br />

the tree.<br />

In [15], the just-described simplicity hierarchy was brought to the fore2 and made<br />

part of an algebraico-tree-theoretic definition of No. In the pages that follow, we<br />

introduce a novel class of structures whose properties generalize those of No so<br />

construed and explore some of the relations that exist between No and this more<br />

general class of s-hierarchical ordered structures as we call them. In ? 1 we define a<br />

number of types of s-hierarchical ordered structures groups, fields, vector spacesas<br />

well as a corresponding type of s-hierarchical mapping, identify No as a complete<br />

s-hierarchical ordered group (s-hierarchical ordered field; s-hierarchical ordered<br />

vector space), and show that there is one and only one s-hierarchical mapping of<br />

an s-hierarchical ordered structure into No (or any complete s-hierarchical ordered<br />

structure, more generally). These mappings are found to be embeddings of their<br />

respective kinds whose images are initial subtrees of No, and this together <strong>with</strong><br />

the completeness of No enables us to characterize No, up to isomorphism, as<br />

the unique complete as well as the unique nonextensible and the unique universal,<br />

s-hierarchical ordered group (s-hierarchical ordered field; s-hierarchical ordered<br />

vector space). Following this, in ?2 and ?4 we turn our attention to uncovering<br />

the spectrum of s-hierarchical ordered structures. Given the nature of No alluded<br />

to above, this reduces to revealing the spectrum of initial substructures of No, i.e.,<br />

the subgroups, subfields, subspaces of No (considered as an s-hierarchical ordered<br />

algebraic structure) that are initial subtrees of No. Included among our findings are<br />

the following two results that were originally stated as conjectures by the author at<br />

the AMS special session on Surreal <strong>Number</strong>s in January of 1989.<br />

I. Every divisible ordered abelian group is isomorphic to an initial subgroup of No.<br />

II. Every real-closed orderedfield is isomorphic to an initial subfield of No.<br />

In ?3, as part of the groundwork for the proof of II, we provide novel proofs that each<br />

surreal number x can be represented by a unique formal sum which may be treated<br />

as a canonicalproper name of x and the closely related fact that No considered as<br />

an ordered field is isomorphic to the formal power series field JR (No)On.<br />

In ?5, we generalize and amplify Conway's theories of ordinals and omnific integers<br />

by showing that every nontrivial s-hierarchical ordered group (s-hierarchical<br />

ordered field) A contains a cofinal, canonical subsemigroup (subsemiring) On(A)<br />

the ordinalpart of A which in turn is contained in a discrete, canonical subgroup<br />

2More specifically, in [15], following a suggestion of Conway, the just-described simplicity hierarchy<br />

was brought to the fore and thereby freed from the ambiguity that befalls it in Conway's own treatment<br />

in [7]. The ambiguity arises because remarks made in [7] make it possible (if not more likely) to interpret<br />

"x is simpler than y" as x has an earlier birthday than y, rather than in the manner specified above as<br />

Conway had intended (Private Conversation: see [15, pp. 257-258: note 1]). For some purposes the<br />

ambiguity is of little consequence. For example, one may show that No has precisely one automorphism<br />

that preserves simplicity regardless of which one of the above two interpretations of the simpler than<br />

relation is adopted [4], [5], [15]. On the other hand, as the succeeding pages only begin to show, from<br />

the standpoint of exploring the internal structure of No, it the tree-theoretic interpretation that is the<br />

more revealing. For treatments of No in which "x is simpler than y" is interpreted as x has an earlier<br />

birthday than y, see, for example, [4], [5], and [6].

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!