16.05.2014 Views

deconstruction, secularism, and islam - Philosophy Documentation ...

deconstruction, secularism, and islam - Philosophy Documentation ...

deconstruction, secularism, and islam - Philosophy Documentation ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

DECONSTRUCTION, SECULARISM, AND ISLAM<br />

Since the early 1990s, Jacques Derrida’s<br />

growing attention to politics <strong>and</strong> religion has<br />

been abundantly noted. What has received far<br />

less attention is Derrida’s explicit secular commitments<br />

in his discussions of religion <strong>and</strong> politics.<br />

Such commitments might be seen as arising<br />

from a structural threat that religion, or at least religious<br />

dogmatism, poses to political discourse.<br />

Insofar as religion, for Derrida, is bound to appeals<br />

to the sacred, understood as the unscathed,<br />

the pure, <strong>and</strong> thus the unconditioned <strong>and</strong> absolute,<br />

it threatens what he described in “Violence<br />

<strong>and</strong> Metaphysics” as “the worst violence,” i.e.,<br />

the denial <strong>and</strong> closure of discourse. 1 Given such a<br />

threat, an appeal to secular principles to protect a<br />

democratic public space of free <strong>and</strong> critical discourse<br />

might seem to follow. In this essay I seek<br />

to unsettle such a possible perception of the relation<br />

between <strong>deconstruction</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>secularism</strong>, as<br />

well as Derrida’s own commitments to <strong>secularism</strong><br />

for democracy, by critically contrasting<br />

Derrida’s discussion of <strong>secularism</strong> <strong>and</strong> religion<br />

with the work of two recent Muslim reformers. In<br />

the work of Abdullahi An-Na‘im <strong>and</strong> Abdolkarim<br />

Soroush we find an implicit, but far-reaching,<br />

commitment to a certain logic of autoimmunity<br />

that Derrida analyzes at length in<br />

“Faith <strong>and</strong> Knowledge” <strong>and</strong> gives voice to in<br />

“Above All, No Journalists”: for the sacred or divine<br />

to “reach the light ...tophenomenalize itself,<br />

to utter itself, to manifest itself, [it] must<br />

cede to . . . ‘autoimmunity.’” 2 That is, for the sacred<br />

or divine to manifest itself, it must appear in<br />

the human space of the profane. Both of these<br />

Muslim reformers draw strong democratic consequences<br />

from the necessarily profane status of<br />

religious interpretation <strong>and</strong> knowledge. Thus,<br />

contrary to the prevailing secular conception of<br />

the proper relation between democracy <strong>and</strong><br />

religion, as well as the predominant western view<br />

of Muslim religious <strong>and</strong> political thought, they<br />

defend democratic reforms from an avowedly<br />

religious basis.<br />

Joshua Andresen<br />

Because Derrida’s commitment to <strong>secularism</strong><br />

follows from <strong>and</strong> mirrors his commitment to democracy,<br />

I will begin by reviewing the general<br />

nature of political commitment for Derrida <strong>and</strong><br />

the specific basis of his commitment to democracy.<br />

I will then examine Derrida’s strategic advocacy<br />

of <strong>secularism</strong> for democracy despite the<br />

double-bind <strong>and</strong> autoimmunity inherent to both<br />

democracy <strong>and</strong> religion. In the second half of the<br />

essay, I move to examining how An-Na‘im <strong>and</strong><br />

Soroush present critical alternatives to Derrida’s<br />

account of <strong>secularism</strong> <strong>and</strong> religion, ones that upset<br />

the presumed necessary link between<br />

<strong>secularism</strong> <strong>and</strong> democracy.<br />

Deconstruction <strong>and</strong> Democracy<br />

Derrida argues repeatedly <strong>and</strong> at great length<br />

that ethical, political, <strong>and</strong> religious commitments<br />

are all characterized by a leap beyond what can<br />

be known or generated by rational deliberation.<br />

That is, there is always an unbridgeable gap between<br />

reason <strong>and</strong> deliberation on the one h<strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>and</strong> the decision to believe or act on the other. 3 No<br />

rules or norms or even direct comm<strong>and</strong>s interpret<br />

themselves in any given situation (e.g., God to<br />

Abraham: “Kill Isaac!”—is it meant ironically?<br />

Is that exactly what I should not do? Is this a test?<br />

I must decide, always in a deficit of certainty).<br />

Thus the very question, “what should I do?” generates<br />

an infinite responsibility for whatever I do,<br />

even if I do nothing at all, because I can never<br />

fully justify whatever decision I make. 4<br />

Derrida complements the arguments for infinite<br />

responsibility with arguments that every<br />

action I take is always open to the double bind<br />

of chance <strong>and</strong> threat. 5 That is, the<br />

unknowability <strong>and</strong> essential incalculability of<br />

the future means that any decision I make <strong>and</strong><br />

action I take, regardless of how long I deliberate<br />

on it beforeh<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> how much knowledge<br />

I assemble on its behalf could end in regret.<br />

The point again is not to generate fear or inac-<br />

PHILOSOPHY TODAY WINTER 2012<br />

375


tion. On the contrary, the double bind of<br />

chance <strong>and</strong> threat <strong>and</strong> the necessary irresponsibility<br />

characterizing every decision imply,<br />

for Derrida, the urgency of deciding <strong>and</strong> doing<br />

something, as well as grappling with our responsibility<br />

for effects we can never completely<br />

control. 6<br />

As I have argued elsewhere, what these two<br />

characteristics of decisions imply for political<br />

commitments is that they are always inherently<br />

strategic. 7 That is, political commitments must be<br />

made in a specific context <strong>and</strong> for specific aims if<br />

one is even to approach the dem<strong>and</strong>s of infinite<br />

responsibility in the minimal sense of making<br />

some attempt to underst<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> act in relation to<br />

the local situation <strong>and</strong> the effects one’s commitments<br />

might generate there. 8 Thus Derrida advocates<br />

democracy, both as a political concept <strong>and</strong><br />

general type of political formation, for a variety<br />

of specific desired ends, e.g., the greater inclusion<br />

of women in politics <strong>and</strong> the extension <strong>and</strong><br />

protection of human rights. 9 Derrida explicitly<br />

advocates democracy strategically even though<br />

he is well aware that democracy can always backfire.<br />

He reminds us both that nearly all nations today,<br />

regardless of their actual political structure,<br />

present themselves as democracies, <strong>and</strong> that the<br />

fascist <strong>and</strong> Nazi regimes of the twentieth century<br />

came to power through formally democratic processes.<br />

10 Derrida thus attempts a strategic advocacy<br />

of democracy while distancing himself<br />

from the theocratic, tyrannical, military, <strong>and</strong> authoritarian<br />

democracies he also calls to our attention.<br />

11<br />

In addition to being rather limiting in its critical<br />

force, the basis of Derrida’s strategic advocacy<br />

of democracy is itself very difficult to locate.<br />

I have also argued elsewhere that Derrida’s<br />

appeal to democracy depends on the historical<br />

<strong>and</strong> linguistic resources the term affords for practical<br />

appeals of the kind he is interested in. 12 Thus<br />

Derrida suggests that appeal to the term “democracy,”<br />

<strong>and</strong> its basic sense of rule by the people,<br />

will be more effective for such ends as the greater<br />

inclusion of women in politics than alternatives<br />

such as “monarchy” or “theocracy.” We must recognize,<br />

however, that the inclusion of women in<br />

politics is not inherent—either in the concept of<br />

PHILOSOPHY TODAY<br />

376<br />

democracy or in formally democratic polities—<br />

as the history of both the use of the concept <strong>and</strong><br />

self-proclaimed democratic polities makes apparent.<br />

13 Moreover, while the inclusion of<br />

women in politics is no more inherent in the ideas<br />

of monarchy or theocracy, we might just happen<br />

to find that the societies most inclusive of women<br />

in the public <strong>and</strong> political domain are formally<br />

monarchic or theocratic (e.g., Sweden). 14<br />

Derrida is thus not appealing to the essence of democracy<br />

or something essential to democracy for<br />

the ends he seeks. On the contrary, he is specifically<br />

playing on the malleability of the concept to<br />

mobilize it for specific strategic interests. 15<br />

At least one puzzling question naturally arises<br />

here: if Derrida, or anyone else, is really interested<br />

in a political order more inclusive of<br />

women, or the protection <strong>and</strong> extension of human<br />

rights, or the maintenance of public space<br />

for the free expression of critique, why not advocate<br />

those ends directly rather than taking the indirect<br />

route of using the ambiguous <strong>and</strong> easily<br />

corruptible term “democracy” as a means to<br />

those ends? Derrida is, of course, not entirely<br />

without resources, even on his own terms. While,<br />

as we have just seen, he cannot eliminate the<br />

threat that formally democratic societies may become<br />

excluding, hierarchically ordered, or conjoined<br />

to exploitative <strong>and</strong> destabilizing economic<br />

systems, he can <strong>and</strong> does argue that the condition<br />

of the corruptibility of democracy is also the condition<br />

of its perfectibility—here not in the sense<br />

of “capable of being made perfect,” but rather in<br />

the sense of always being open to critical democratic<br />

appeals regardless of where the line of inclusion<br />

<strong>and</strong> exclusion is drawn. 16 The reciprocal<br />

aspects of democracy’s corruptibility <strong>and</strong> perfectibility<br />

are captured by the logic of “autoimmunity”<br />

that Derrida adapts from biology <strong>and</strong><br />

initially develops in relation to religion. 17 In<br />

Rogues, Derrida explicitly applies “autoimmunity”<br />

to democracy by associating it with<br />

“that expression of autoimmunity called the right<br />

to self-critique <strong>and</strong> perfectibility.” 18 Here Derrida<br />

emphasizes democracy’s autoimmune ability to<br />

attack itself in its own name <strong>and</strong> for its own ultimate<br />

protection. He goes on to argue that “democracy<br />

is the only system ...inwhich, in prin-


ciple, one has or assumes the right to criticize<br />

everything publically, including the idea of democracy,<br />

its concept, its history, <strong>and</strong> its name.” 19<br />

Democracy’s autoimmune relation to itself does<br />

not <strong>and</strong> cannot guarantee recognizably more<br />

democratic societies. The ability always to critique<br />

a democracy in the name of democracy<br />

does, however, assure the right, at least in principle,<br />

to critical politics. Given the ends Derrida associates<br />

with “democracy,” we can fairly<br />

conclude that critical politics is what Derrida<br />

would most like to preserve <strong>and</strong> that it is<br />

“democracy,” at least as he theorizes it, that best<br />

preserves that right.<br />

“Democracy to Come . . . Assumes<br />

Secularism”<br />

What do we find when we turn to Derrida’s<br />

commitment to <strong>secularism</strong> <strong>and</strong> secularization?<br />

To begin, we must retrace the same formal structure<br />

of Derrida’s relation to <strong>and</strong> advocacy of democracy<br />

also with regard to <strong>secularism</strong> <strong>and</strong> secularization.<br />

The commitment must be a kind of<br />

strategic leap subject to the same double bind of<br />

chance <strong>and</strong> threat. In what context then, to what<br />

ends, <strong>and</strong> in virtue of what resources does<br />

Derrida strategically advocate <strong>secularism</strong>?<br />

In following Derrida’s discussions of <strong>secularism</strong><br />

<strong>and</strong> secularization it becomes clear that they<br />

occur as strategic amendments to his commitment<br />

to democracy. Derrida is well aware of the<br />

religious history not only of European culture,<br />

but also of the many concepts closely associated<br />

with secular democratic movements, such as<br />

equality, freedom, <strong>and</strong> human rights. 20 Moreover,<br />

Derrida critically acknowledges the religious—<br />

often Christian—motivations at work in the globalization<br />

of the European democratic model. 21<br />

We can thus say, as a first approximation, that<br />

while acknowledging the role of religion in the<br />

formation of modern European democracy,<br />

Derrida nevertheless appeals to the secular in order<br />

to “emancipate” democracy from the<br />

influence of religion. Indeed, Derrida says as<br />

much in “Faith <strong>and</strong> Knowledge”:<br />

we . . . share, it seems to me . . .—let us designate it<br />

cautiously—an unreserved taste, if not an unconditional<br />

preference, for what, in politics, is called<br />

republican democracy as a universalizable model,<br />

binding philosophy to the public “cause,” to the res<br />

publica, to “public-ness,” once again to the light of<br />

day, once again to the “lights” of the Enlightenment<br />

[aux Lumieres], once again to the enlightened<br />

virtue of public space, emancipating it from<br />

all external power (non-lay, non-secular), for example<br />

from religious dogmatism, orthodoxy or authority<br />

(that is, from a certain rule of the doxa or of<br />

belief, which, however, does not mean from all<br />

faith). 22<br />

In this passage, Derrida contrasts the secular with<br />

a religious power “external” to democracy, the<br />

“public ‘cause,’” <strong>and</strong> a free public space of critique.<br />

Moreover, Derrida construes democracy<br />

<strong>and</strong> public space as threatened by religion, or at<br />

least by religious dogmatism. As a remedy to the<br />

perceived threat, he affirms a Kantian division of<br />

space into the public <strong>and</strong> the private. 23 That is, the<br />

public is the space of open <strong>and</strong> free discourse <strong>and</strong><br />

negotiation unfettered <strong>and</strong> undetermined by religious<br />

doxa. By contrast, the private sphere is the<br />

place to be religious.<br />

There may seem to be good reason to be cautious<br />

about attributing to Derrida the now st<strong>and</strong>ard<br />

secular reconfiguration of religion as private<br />

faith. 24 At the most general level, Derrida’s apparent<br />

appeal to a hard distinction between the<br />

public <strong>and</strong> the private in order to “emancipate”<br />

public space from the religious ought to be completely<br />

untenable by his own, deconstructive<br />

lights. To take just one example amongst many<br />

other deconstructive arguments, the basic argument<br />

we have seen concerning the infinite or unending<br />

responsibility conditioning every decision<br />

depends for its (practical) cogency on the<br />

idea that all decisions, including supposedly private<br />

decisions of faith, are implicated in a public<br />

order that generates responsibility in the first<br />

place. 25 Thus the very attempt to relegate the religious<br />

to the private sphere is immediately <strong>and</strong> irremediably<br />

disrupted by the contamination of the<br />

private by the public. Analogously, even if we<br />

were to accept religion as a purely private matter,<br />

that would not indemnify the public against contamination<br />

by the private. Such contamination is<br />

not merely a risk according to deconstructive<br />

DECONSTRUCTION, SECULARISM, AND ISLAM<br />

377


PHILOSOPHY TODAY<br />

378<br />

logic, but a condition of the very attempt to<br />

separate the public from the private.<br />

If we focus on Derrida’s greater discussion in<br />

“Faith <strong>and</strong> Knowledge,” the grounds for a strategic<br />

secular stance vis-à-vis religious doxa become<br />

even more difficult to discern. First, by<br />

evoking the language of “emancipation” <strong>and</strong> the<br />

implication that religion is a threat to democracy<br />

<strong>and</strong> the public sphere, Derrida paradoxically<br />

places the secular in the position of the religious,<br />

which, in the same essay, he goes on to analyze as<br />

that which seeks purity in the sense of being “unscathed,”<br />

free from harm, injury, or violation.<br />

Second, not only does Derrida go on to discuss<br />

both the threat <strong>and</strong> chance of religious adherence,<br />

he also radically problematizes the absolute<br />

or unconditional status of religious truth <strong>and</strong><br />

purity by developing religion’s own autoimmune<br />

relation to itself. The iterability of religious doxa<br />

that is required for its communication necessarily<br />

renders the divine in religion profane <strong>and</strong> conditional.<br />

26 As Derrida argues, “It is this terrifying<br />

but fatal logic of the auto-immunity of the unscathed<br />

that will always associate Science <strong>and</strong><br />

Religion.” 27 That is, on behalf of its own survival,<br />

religion must present itself in <strong>and</strong> through a public<br />

rational discourse. 28 Thus, rather than giving<br />

us clear reason to prefer secular politics in “Faith<br />

<strong>and</strong> Knowledge,” Derrida more clearly<br />

demonstrates religion’s reliance on public democratic<br />

space for its own propagation <strong>and</strong> survival.<br />

If we turn from the letter of Derrida’s analysis<br />

to its greater historical context, I suggest we gain<br />

some insight into his secular evocations <strong>and</strong> the<br />

remarks on Islam <strong>and</strong> Islamism scattered<br />

throughout the essay. 29 The symposium on Capri,<br />

from which “Faith <strong>and</strong> Knowledge” derives, took<br />

place in the midst of the Algerian Civil War, just<br />

three weeks after the meeting of the International<br />

Committee in Support of Algerian Intellectuals<br />

<strong>and</strong> the League of Human Rights at which<br />

Derrida presented the text, “Taking a St<strong>and</strong> for<br />

Algeria.” 30 The ongoing Algerian conflict was<br />

waged among Algeria’s official military-backed<br />

government <strong>and</strong> several Islamic guerrilla groups.<br />

It is thus not surprising that Derrida reiterates <strong>and</strong><br />

returns to some of the secular democratic principles<br />

in “Faith <strong>and</strong> Knowledge,” e.g., of “emancipating”<br />

public space from religious dogmatism,<br />

that he publicly advocated for his birth-place, Algeria,<br />

just a few weeks earlier. 31 The then palpable<br />

violence waged, in part, in the name of religion<br />

explains, I suggest, Derrida’s strategic<br />

secular stance even where the structural analysis<br />

of the double bind, iterability, <strong>and</strong> autoimmunity<br />

of the religious would leave a chance for a different<br />

approach. 32<br />

Despite the double bind, iterability, <strong>and</strong><br />

autoimmunity of the religious that Derrida analyzes<br />

in “Faith <strong>and</strong> Knowledge,” his commitment<br />

to secular principles becomes more explicit in his<br />

later work, particularly in his brief discussions of<br />

democracy <strong>and</strong> Islam. Derrida’s discussion of Islam<br />

in Rogues is generated by the observation<br />

that<br />

the only <strong>and</strong> the very few regimes, in the supposed<br />

modernity of this situation [today], that do not<br />

present themselves as democratic are those with a<br />

theocratic Muslim government. Not all of them, to<br />

be sure [i.e., some governments with an Islamic<br />

theocratic basis nevertheless present themselves as<br />

democratic], but, let me underscore this, the only<br />

regimes that do not fashion themselves to be democratic,<br />

the only ones that do not present themselves<br />

as democratic, unless I am mistaken, are statutorily<br />

linked to the Muslim faith or creed. 33<br />

Derrida goes on to call attention to the multitude<br />

of nation-states fundamentally linked to religious<br />

faith but which nevertheless present themselves<br />

as democracies, including the state of Israel<br />

<strong>and</strong> the essentially Christian democracies<br />

that he acknowledges are “too numerous to cite.”<br />

What is then interesting to Derrida is that “Islam,<br />

or a certain Islam [he refers to Saudi Arabia],<br />

would thus be the only religious or theocratic culture<br />

that can still, in fact or in principle, inspire<br />

<strong>and</strong> declare any resistance to democracy.” 34<br />

Derrida goes on to suggest that Islamic resistance<br />

to democracy may be “the greatest, if not<br />

the only, political issue of the future, the most urgent<br />

question of what remains to come for what is<br />

still called the political.” 35 Although Derrida apparently<br />

takes the issue very seriously <strong>and</strong> calls<br />

for a theoretical <strong>and</strong> historical investigation into<br />

the relation between Islam <strong>and</strong> democracy (tasks


which he claims he has neither the time nor the<br />

expertise), 36 it is clear that Derrida aligns himself<br />

with the value of secular democracy <strong>and</strong> against<br />

resistance to it. Thus, rather than attempting to<br />

analyze <strong>and</strong> think through such resistance or suspend<br />

judgment until such analysis is undertaken,<br />

Derrida responds to the urgent question of the<br />

political by calling on<br />

Whoever . . . considers him- or herself a friend of<br />

democracy in the world <strong>and</strong> not only in his or her<br />

own country . . . [to] do everything possible to join<br />

forces with all those who, <strong>and</strong> first of all in the Islamic<br />

world, fight not only for the secularization of<br />

the political (however ambiguous this secularization<br />

remains), for the emergence of a laic subjectivity,<br />

but also for an interpretation of the Koranic<br />

heritage that privileges, from the inside as it were,<br />

the democratic virtualities that are probably no<br />

more apparent <strong>and</strong> readable at first glance, <strong>and</strong><br />

readable under this name, than they were in the Old<br />

<strong>and</strong> New Testaments. 37<br />

Derrida’s address reinforces the separation of the<br />

religious from the political that he aligned himself<br />

with in “Faith <strong>and</strong> Knowledge,” while calling<br />

for the strategic mobilization of the Quran on<br />

behalf of secular democracy. Here, however, it is<br />

not the Muslim heritage per se that is invited into<br />

the political public space, but only Islamic principles<br />

insofar as they can be shown to accord<br />

with secular democratic principles. Although the<br />

religious can serve the political, <strong>and</strong> even be a<br />

source of the democratic, the religious must be<br />

separated from the political—<strong>and</strong> “friends of democracy”<br />

must “fight” for this separation—if<br />

truly democratic politics are to emerge.<br />

Derrida confirms this rather strict separation<br />

of the political <strong>and</strong> the religious in one of his last<br />

public appearances. In a public discussion with<br />

Mustapha Chérif, Derrida affirms,<br />

I believe that democracy to come . . . assumes <strong>secularism</strong>,<br />

that is, both the detachment of the political<br />

from the theocratic <strong>and</strong> the theological, thus entailing<br />

a certain <strong>secularism</strong> of the political, while at<br />

the same time, encompassing freedom of worship<br />

in a completely consistent, coherent way, <strong>and</strong> absolute<br />

religious freedom guaranteed by the State,<br />

on the condition, obviously, that the secular space<br />

of the political <strong>and</strong> the religious space are not confused.<br />

...Ibelieve that the secular today must be<br />

more rigorous with itself, more tolerant toward religious<br />

cultures <strong>and</strong> toward the possibility for religious<br />

practices to exist freely, unequivocally, <strong>and</strong><br />

without confusion. . . . The religious community<br />

can very well organize itself as a religious community,<br />

in a lay space, without invading the lay space<br />

<strong>and</strong> while respecting the freedom of the individual.<br />

38<br />

Here even as Derrida calls for a more critically<br />

aware <strong>secularism</strong>, he reinforces the sharp division<br />

between the public <strong>and</strong> the private that we<br />

have seen to be both conceptually <strong>and</strong> practically<br />

suspect. Derrida’s increasingly explicit advocacy<br />

of <strong>secularism</strong> paradoxically appeals to a<br />

public political space unscathed by religious<br />

contamination or invasion. Yet Derrida himself<br />

reminds us that “secularization is always ambiguous<br />

in that it frees itself from the religious, all<br />

the while remaining marked in its very concept<br />

by it, by the theological.” 39<br />

Thus, although<br />

Derrida clearly advocates a secular approach to<br />

politics <strong>and</strong> a political space “not confused” with<br />

religious space, nothing in his discussion directly<br />

supports his secular preference. In fact, Derrida’s<br />

structural analysis of religion <strong>and</strong> his strategic<br />

advocacy of <strong>secularism</strong> lead us to the aporia that<br />

there can be no secular without religious “violation,”<br />

<strong>and</strong> no pure secularization without the secular<br />

itself taking the form of the religious. 40<br />

There is perhaps a productive way forward if<br />

we focus more closely on what is at stake in <strong>secularism</strong><br />

<strong>and</strong> its purity for Derrida. On the one<br />

h<strong>and</strong>, he is concerned with the closing or limiting<br />

of public space, the elimination of the right to<br />

criticism, the sacrifice of individual rights <strong>and</strong><br />

the attenuation of individual freedom. On the<br />

other h<strong>and</strong>, he is concerned with the entrance of<br />

“religious dogmatism, orthodoxy or authority”<br />

into the public space. He thus construes religious<br />

absolutism as a threat to freedom <strong>and</strong> critique.<br />

When we now turn to contemporary discussions<br />

about the relation of religion to the public sphere<br />

amongst Muslim theologians, philosophers, <strong>and</strong><br />

legal theorists, we find an extraordinarily rich engagement<br />

with these very issues. Perhaps most<br />

interestingly, it is precisely an argument these<br />

DECONSTRUCTION, SECULARISM, AND ISLAM<br />

379


thinkers share with Derrida, that the religious is<br />

necessarily profaned in its manifestation <strong>and</strong><br />

propagation, that leads them to defend broadly<br />

democratic values <strong>and</strong> freedom of religion not<br />

from secular principles, but from an Islamic<br />

perspective.<br />

Autoimmunity <strong>and</strong> Shari‘a<br />

In the remainder of this essay I want to look at<br />

the work of Abdullahi An-Na‘im <strong>and</strong> Abdolkarim<br />

Soroush as two examples of approaches to<br />

Islam <strong>and</strong> politics that embrace democracy without<br />

embracing <strong>secularism</strong>. Equally interesting,<br />

these thinkers chart alternative paths to Islam <strong>and</strong><br />

politics that contrast both with Derrida’s approach<br />

<strong>and</strong> with the fundamentalist approaches<br />

that have captured so much media <strong>and</strong> public attention<br />

in Europe <strong>and</strong> America. By seeking to reposition<br />

their fellow Muslims’ own approach to<br />

<strong>and</strong> underst<strong>and</strong>ing of Islam, An-Na‘im <strong>and</strong><br />

Soroush also displace the secular view of the<br />

proper relation between religion <strong>and</strong> politics exemplified<br />

by Derrida. They thus allow for a more<br />

inclusive <strong>and</strong> pluralistic approach to politics <strong>and</strong><br />

democracy by rethinking the presumed secularreligious<br />

opposition that undermines progressive<br />

politics in so many contexts today.<br />

The legal theorist Abdullahi An-Na‘im from<br />

Sudan is motivated to theorize the reform of Islamic<br />

law in response to the reality of roughly<br />

thirty-five Muslim-majority countries that have<br />

incorporated aspects of Islamic law, or shari‘a,<br />

into their legal structure. 41 He is responding, in<br />

other words, to the advent of the modern nationstate,<br />

something that has taken place only over<br />

the last two centuries in Europe <strong>and</strong> somewhat<br />

more recently in the Arab <strong>and</strong> Muslim world,<br />

with its emphasis on constitutionalism, the transparent<br />

codification of law, <strong>and</strong> the universal application<br />

<strong>and</strong> enforcement of law by the state itself.<br />

The birth of the modern state makes the<br />

interpretation, application, <strong>and</strong> enforcement of<br />

Islamic law, or shari‘a, pressing in a way it had<br />

never been before, leading shari‘a to become<br />

st<strong>and</strong>ardized <strong>and</strong> enforced in an unprecedented<br />

way.<br />

An-Na‘im’s work is a provocative approach to<br />

the desirable relation between religion <strong>and</strong> the<br />

public sphere, as well as an interesting alternative<br />

to both Derrida’s call for the “secularization of<br />

the political” in the Muslim world, <strong>and</strong> to the<br />

more publicized Muslim fundamentalist movements.<br />

42 An-Na‘im does not seek to reform Islam<br />

from a secular position. An-Na‘im explicitly<br />

states that his aim “is to contribute to the process<br />

of changing Muslim perceptions, attitudes, <strong>and</strong><br />

policies on Islamic, not secular, grounds.” 43 Nor<br />

does he seek to insulate the public realm from<br />

religion. On the contrary, he argues,<br />

to seek secular answers is simply to ab<strong>and</strong>on the<br />

field to the fundamentalists, who will succeed in<br />

carrying the vast majority of the population with<br />

them by citing religious authority for their policies<br />

<strong>and</strong> theories. Intelligent <strong>and</strong> enlightened Muslims<br />

are therefore best advised to remain within the religious<br />

framework <strong>and</strong> endeavor to achieve the reforms<br />

that would make Islam a viable modern ideology.<br />

44<br />

An-Na‘im approaches the reform of shari‘a from<br />

<strong>and</strong> within the context of the Muslim majority<br />

countries where shari‘a, in various interpretations,<br />

is being implemented in the laws <strong>and</strong> constitutions<br />

of those countries. From within that<br />

context <strong>and</strong> as a Muslim himself, he acknowledges<br />

that he is “particularly sensitive to the religious<br />

implications of attributing inadequacy <strong>and</strong><br />

injustice to Shari‘a, which is perceived by many<br />

Muslims to be part of the Islamic faith.” 45 Knowing<br />

that many Muslims will reject his project as<br />

heresy, he nevertheless maintains that the questions<br />

he raises “must be confronted <strong>and</strong> resolved<br />

as a religious as well as a political <strong>and</strong> legal imperative<br />

if the public law of Islam is to be implemented<br />

today.” 46 His basic strategy is to distinguish<br />

the divine elements of Islam from the<br />

human <strong>and</strong> contextual. 47 He argues,<br />

Shari‘a is not the whole of Islam but instead is an<br />

interpretation of its fundamental sources as understood<br />

in a particular historical context. Once it is<br />

appreciated that Shari‘a was constructed by its<br />

founding jurists, it should become possible to think<br />

about reconstructing certain aspects of Shari‘a,<br />

provided that such reconstruction is based on the<br />

same fundamental sources of Islam <strong>and</strong> is fully<br />

PHILOSOPHY TODAY<br />

380


consistent with its essential moral <strong>and</strong> religious<br />

precepts. 48<br />

An-Na‘im here implicitly mobilizes the autoimmunity<br />

characterizing Islam’s relation to itself<br />

by thematizing the extent to which Islam’s own<br />

legal structure, which guards <strong>and</strong> guarantees<br />

what is properly Muslim, is itself a human, rather<br />

than divine, construction. By simultaneously<br />

committing himself (as a Muslim) to the divine<br />

nature of Islam’s religious sources <strong>and</strong> focusing<br />

on the human construction of shari‘a, An-Na‘im<br />

seeks to open a critical space for retheorizing<br />

shari‘a <strong>and</strong> implementing a more practically<br />

beneficial Islam.<br />

An-Na‘im’s basic approach <strong>and</strong> argument is<br />

well illustrated by his approach to the term “fundamentalist.”<br />

He objects to the term because, “insofar<br />

as it implies a commitment to the fundamentals<br />

of Islam, it would apply to such a broad<br />

spectrum of Muslims that it would cease to be<br />

useful as a tool for identifying a specific group.” 49<br />

He goes on to argue that the crucial question “is<br />

not whether a Muslim is committed to the fundamentals<br />

of Islam, because this is a sentiment<br />

shared by the vast majority of Muslims, but<br />

rather how to implement that commitment in<br />

concrete policy <strong>and</strong> legal terms today.” 50 What<br />

An-Na‘im’s observation makes clear is a fundamental<br />

disconnect between a <strong>secularism</strong> that<br />

would insulate the public sphere from religion<br />

<strong>and</strong> billions of people around the world whose religious<br />

practices cannot fit neatly into “private<br />

faith.” The disconnect is made more apparent by<br />

the fact that “early Muslim jurists ...ofShari‘a<br />

knew no distinction between public <strong>and</strong> private<br />

law.” 51 The distinctions between public, private,<br />

commercial, <strong>and</strong> other forms of law in modern<br />

European law have their roots in Roman law. An-<br />

Na‘im argues that where such distinctions have<br />

found their way into contemporary Muslim societies,<br />

they have done so due to European influence<br />

<strong>and</strong>/or colonization. The effect is that the<br />

Muslim duty to uphold shari‘a crosses the secular<br />

boundary of the public <strong>and</strong> the private. Contrary<br />

to Derrida’s call for a clear separation of the public<br />

<strong>and</strong> religious spheres, An-Na‘im maintains<br />

that for many Muslims, the dem<strong>and</strong> to limit their<br />

practice of Islam to the private realm is tantamount<br />

to a renunciation of their commitment to<br />

shari‘a <strong>and</strong> hence to Islam.<br />

An-Na‘im’s proposal is to break this impasse<br />

by insisting on the right of Muslims to self-determination<br />

as Muslims, while also insisting that<br />

shari‘a can be reformed “to adapt <strong>and</strong> adjust to<br />

the circumstances <strong>and</strong> needs of contemporary<br />

life within the context of Islam as a whole, even if<br />

this should involve discarding or modifying certain<br />

aspects of historical Shari‘a.” 52 An-Na‘im<br />

goes so far as to argue that there are manifest inadequacies<br />

of some aspects of shari‘a, particularly<br />

with respect to the equal rights of citizenship<br />

to the entire population of contemporary<br />

nation-states. 53 He nevertheless insists that the<br />

“secular public law” that was “introduced into<br />

the Muslim world with the establishment of the<br />

modern nation-state . . . will have to be Islamized<br />

in recognition of the Muslim right to selfdetermination.”<br />

54<br />

One of the most remarkable aspects of An-<br />

Na‘im’s study is his forthrightness about the “inadequacies”<br />

of some of the existing principles of<br />

shari‘a vis-à-vis secular principles. He argues, “if<br />

historical Shari‘a is applied today, the population<br />

of Muslim countries would lose the most significant<br />

benefits of secularization.” 55 He goes on to<br />

outline five political <strong>and</strong> legal issues that arise<br />

due to inconsistencies between historical shari‘a<br />

<strong>and</strong> st<strong>and</strong>ards that have become prevalent in<br />

Muslim majority countries through secularization:<br />

(1) The status of non-Muslims in Muslim<br />

majority countries: under shari‘a non-Muslim<br />

subjects of an Islamic state are not afforded legal<br />

equality with Muslim citizens. An-Na‘im suggests<br />

neither the non-Muslim population nor a<br />

significant number of the Muslim population<br />

would accept the second class status of non-Muslims.<br />

(2) The status of women: An-Na‘im suggests<br />

that “the status <strong>and</strong> rights of Muslim<br />

women under secular public law are already<br />

clearly superior to their status <strong>and</strong> rights under<br />

Shari‘a.” Thus “the restoration of the public law<br />

of Shari‘a would ...haveanegativeeffect on<br />

these women.” 56 (3) The freedom of belief, expression,<br />

<strong>and</strong> association of Muslim men: the law<br />

of apostasy <strong>and</strong> extensive powers of the ruler under<br />

Shari‘a would eliminate true freedom of be-<br />

DECONSTRUCTION, SECULARISM, AND ISLAM<br />

381


PHILOSOPHY TODAY<br />

382<br />

lief <strong>and</strong> dissent. (4) Relations between Muslim<br />

<strong>and</strong> non-Muslim states: shari‘a allows for the<br />

“aggressive use of force to propagate Islam <strong>and</strong><br />

does not recognize the equal sovereignty of non-<br />

Muslim states.” 57 And (5) the legality of slavery:<br />

historical shari‘a allows for <strong>and</strong> regulates the<br />

conditions of slavery.<br />

What is perhaps most significant about An-<br />

Na‘im’s approach is that he does not defend reforming<br />

shari‘a with respect to these five issues<br />

from secular principles. Although he acknowledges<br />

the goodness of the rights brought to non-<br />

Muslims, Muslim women, <strong>and</strong> Muslim men by<br />

secular reforms, it is not secular principles themselves<br />

to which An-Na‘im appeals, but rather the<br />

practical positive effects those principles have<br />

brought for people’s lives (i.e., it’s better for non-<br />

Muslims in Islamic states to be treated as first<br />

class, rather than second class, citizens; it’s better<br />

for Muslim women to be accorded greater equality<br />

<strong>and</strong> more civil rights; it’s better for Muslim<br />

men, <strong>and</strong> indeed all Muslims, to be able to embrace<br />

or reject Islam freely <strong>and</strong> without coercion).<br />

Likewise, with respect to international relations,<br />

An-Na‘im suggests that it is simply<br />

better for Muslim countries if they recognize the<br />

equal sovereignty of non-Muslim states. Moreover,<br />

An-Na‘im’s recourse to the practical benefit<br />

of these reforms is itself justified as Islamic<br />

since the guiding principle of establishing <strong>and</strong><br />

applying shari‘a is that is must serve the good of<br />

the people. An-Na‘im cites two historical examples<br />

from one of Muhammad’s closest companions,<br />

the second Caliph, Omar, who, for the good<br />

of the community, contradicted clear passages<br />

from the Quran <strong>and</strong> the practices of the Prophet. 58<br />

With these examples, An-Na‘im seeks to underscore<br />

the established precedent in Islam of responding<br />

to the historical <strong>and</strong> practical context of<br />

the time at h<strong>and</strong> rather than relentlessly reverting<br />

to custom for its own sake.<br />

Thus in contrast to the secular approach to reform,<br />

An-Na‘im dem<strong>and</strong>s that the reforms be<br />

justified by specific Islamic principles <strong>and</strong> historical<br />

precedent. An-Na‘im argues that the only<br />

way to reconcile the dem<strong>and</strong>s of self-determination<br />

within an Islamic context “is to develop a<br />

version of Islamic public law which is compatible<br />

with modern st<strong>and</strong>ards of constitutionalism,<br />

criminal justice, international law, <strong>and</strong> human<br />

rights.” 59 An-Na‘im approaches what is for him<br />

the necessary reform of shari‘a by further specifying<br />

its contextual <strong>and</strong> specifically human components.<br />

The main interpretive intervention he<br />

makes is to distinguish the character of the first<br />

revelations to the Prophet Muhammad while he<br />

was in Mecca, from the character of the later revelations<br />

that came after the prophet had traveled<br />

to Medina. He observes first that the difference<br />

between the Mecca <strong>and</strong> post-Hijra Medina revelations<br />

show that the revelations themselves correspond<br />

to the concrete social <strong>and</strong> political needs<br />

of the community. 60 He goes on to note that the<br />

traditional shari‘a known today was developed in<br />

the second century of Islam, in part through the<br />

principle of naskh, or supersession, by which the<br />

legal efficacy of earlier Mecca verses were abrogated<br />

in favor of later Medina verses in order to<br />

maintain consistency. 61 Following his teacher,<br />

Mahmoud Mohamed Taha, An-Na‘im argues<br />

that the present context requires the reversal of<br />

the process of abrogation in favor of the earlier<br />

Mecca revelations because they are “in fact the<br />

eternal <strong>and</strong> fundamental message of Islam, emphasizing<br />

the inherent dignity of all human beings,<br />

regardless of gender, religious belief, race,<br />

<strong>and</strong> so forth.” 62 An-Na‘im maintains that only<br />

when these ideals are properly emphasized will<br />

we arrive at a reformed shari‘a adequate to the<br />

present context <strong>and</strong> capable of resolving the five<br />

issues outlined above.<br />

Apart from the question of whether An-Na‘im<br />

is ultimately able to give a convincing account of<br />

the differences between <strong>and</strong> reasons behind the<br />

Mecca <strong>and</strong> Medina revelations, I find An-<br />

Na‘im’s approach admirable both for its forthrightness<br />

about the shari‘a issues besetting Muslim-majority<br />

countries, as well as his unapologetic<br />

approach to reform. However, there<br />

remains the more fundamental question of how<br />

to underst<strong>and</strong> his claim to have identified “the<br />

eternal <strong>and</strong> fundamental message of Islam.” His<br />

approach to reforming shari‘a was predicated on<br />

the claim that while the Quran was the divine<br />

word of God, shari‘a was a human <strong>and</strong> contextual<br />

construct <strong>and</strong> thus subject to change. In other


words, whereas shari‘a was supposed to be open<br />

to reform because the product of human interpretation<br />

to meet certain contextual needs, the Quran<br />

itself was not supposed to be open to interpretive<br />

variation in the same way. If his approach to reforming<br />

shari‘a <strong>and</strong> Islam is actually based on an<br />

innovative interpretation of the Quran, then however<br />

progressive his purposes <strong>and</strong> ends may be,<br />

he leaves himself open to the objection that he is<br />

simply manipulating the religious text to his own<br />

ends, rather than actually establishing a religious<br />

Islamic basis for his political reforms. He has<br />

also left himself open to the objection that he is<br />

simply dogmatically asserting the truth of Islam<br />

<strong>and</strong> applying it in the public political <strong>and</strong> legal<br />

spheres. Thus, far from instituting a culture of<br />

free expression <strong>and</strong> debate on religious matters,<br />

An-Na‘im could be seen as simply replacing one<br />

tradition with another. In more Derridean terms, I<br />

want to suggest that An-Na‘im does not go far<br />

enough in cultivating the iterability <strong>and</strong> autoimmunity<br />

of the sacred for the purpose of reforming<br />

Islam <strong>and</strong> shari‘a. Thus, although he is able to<br />

advocate democracy <strong>and</strong> human rights from an<br />

Islamic perspective, his claim to have identified<br />

“the eternal <strong>and</strong> fundamental message of Islam”<br />

threatens the closure of future discourse rather<br />

than encouraging a continued space of free <strong>and</strong><br />

democratic exchange.<br />

I suggest that An-Na‘im’s goals would be<br />

better served if he, like several other recent Muslim<br />

authors, more precisely <strong>and</strong> radically engaged<br />

the autoimmunity characterizing every<br />

manifestation of the divine, including the texts,<br />

such as the Quran, that are fundamental to every<br />

religion. Doing so would preclude the fundamentalist<br />

move of claiming to find or possess the truth<br />

of religion. It would also, in its place, dem<strong>and</strong> a<br />

more public <strong>and</strong> democratic discussion of the religious<br />

<strong>and</strong> its dem<strong>and</strong>s within specific historical<br />

<strong>and</strong> cultural contexts, as well as in relation to the<br />

more general dem<strong>and</strong>s of the good of society <strong>and</strong><br />

justice.<br />

Autoimmunity <strong>and</strong> Religion<br />

We find a more democratically pluralistic approach<br />

to Islam in the work of the Iranian philosopher<br />

Abdolkarim Soroush. Soroush’s approach<br />

to religion is inspired by his work in philosophy<br />

of science. He thus applies his underst<strong>and</strong>ing of<br />

the “competitive nature of science <strong>and</strong> knowledge”<br />

to his underst<strong>and</strong>ing of religiosity. 63 By<br />

doing so he separates religious knowledge from<br />

religion in a way analogous to how scientific<br />

knowledge is distinguished from “nature.” This<br />

move allows Soroush to cast religious knowledge<br />

“as a kind of human knowledge subject to the collectivity<br />

<strong>and</strong> competitiveness of the human<br />

soul.” 64 What this implies is that while religion itself<br />

in its divinity may not change, religious<br />

knowledge <strong>and</strong> religiosity does <strong>and</strong> should be expected<br />

to change, as well as admit of pluralism.<br />

Thus, far from being an essentially dogmatic or<br />

authoritarian source of discourse, Soroush argues<br />

for an underst<strong>and</strong>ing of religiosity <strong>and</strong> religious<br />

knowledge that conforms to basic democratic<br />

principles insofar as it is open, critical,<br />

public, <strong>and</strong> plural. Indeed, Soroush defends the<br />

need for democratic politics through an analysis<br />

of the nature of religion.<br />

Soroush explains his distinction between religion<br />

<strong>and</strong> religious knowledge 65 by arguing that<br />

Religion is sacred <strong>and</strong> heavenly, but the underst<strong>and</strong>ing<br />

of religion is human <strong>and</strong> earthly. That<br />

which remains constant is religion [din]; that<br />

which undergoes change is religious knowledge<br />

<strong>and</strong> insight. . . . Religious knowledge <strong>and</strong> insight<br />

that is human <strong>and</strong> incomplete ...isinconstant<br />

need of reconstruction. . . . Religious knowledge is,<br />

without a shadow of a doubt, subject to [the influences<br />

of culture]. . . .Religious knowledge is born,<br />

entirely human <strong>and</strong> subject to all the dictates of human<br />

knowledge. 66<br />

Soroush at once affirms the sacredness of religion<br />

<strong>and</strong> the profane character of all religious<br />

manifestations. He thus ensconces himself in the<br />

aporetic <strong>and</strong> autoimmune structure of religion<br />

that Derrida highlights in “Faith <strong>and</strong> Knowledge.”<br />

Although religion might appear to vanish<br />

altogether once it is assigned to the sacred <strong>and</strong><br />

heavenly, Soroush maintains that “religion”<br />

plays a similar role to that of “nature” in the natural<br />

sciences. That is, although both distinctions,<br />

between religious knowledge <strong>and</strong> religion <strong>and</strong><br />

science <strong>and</strong> nature, are vexed, the vaguely defined<br />

ideals of “religion” <strong>and</strong> “nature” neverthe-<br />

DECONSTRUCTION, SECULARISM, AND ISLAM<br />

383


less play important motivational roles in the pursuit<br />

of each. The role of “religion” in the Muslim<br />

context is perhaps more apparent when we recall<br />

that the Arabic word typically rendered by “religion”<br />

is din, which has the primary sense of<br />

“path” or “way.” We can thus underst<strong>and</strong> “religion”<br />

in the Muslim context as the path toward<br />

the good <strong>and</strong> the true, or the striving for these. In<br />

this sense, what is pursued in religious practice<br />

<strong>and</strong> study is thought not to change <strong>and</strong> thereby remains<br />

the enduring point of orientation, albeit<br />

without any specific content, in a similar way to<br />

which nature, or nature in itself, remains the enduring<br />

point of orientation of natural science.<br />

Thus although “religion” st<strong>and</strong>s for the divine<br />

truth that believers seek, it can never appear as<br />

such. It rather engenders religious knowledge<br />

marked by endless interpretation <strong>and</strong> real interpretive<br />

pluralism. Applying this idea to the<br />

Quran itself would lead us to distinguish between<br />

the divine truth it points toward <strong>and</strong> its manifestation<br />

in human language, ordered <strong>and</strong> assembled<br />

by human h<strong>and</strong>s, <strong>and</strong> interpreted <strong>and</strong> explicated<br />

by human auditors, readers, <strong>and</strong> scholars. 67<br />

Indeed Soroush maintains that even the determination<br />

of the embodiment of “religion” is “the<br />

domain of ‘religious knowledge’ <strong>and</strong>, as such,<br />

[it] follow[s] a particular interpretation of religion.”<br />

68 As a consequence, both the content <strong>and</strong><br />

the meaning of the religious are perpetually open<br />

to critical questioning <strong>and</strong> public debate.<br />

Soroush develops the analogy between religion<br />

<strong>and</strong> science further by comparing practices<br />

of religious interpretation <strong>and</strong> knowledge to the<br />

collective enterprise of scientific inquiry. Just as<br />

scientific inquiry is a collective process of the<br />

scientific community, Soroush argues that religious<br />

knowledge is a collective process like any<br />

other field of knowledge. As such, religious<br />

knowledge is not the possession of single individuals,<br />

nor can it authorize the absolute authority<br />

of any person or group of people. Rather he<br />

emphasizes,<br />

PHILOSOPHY TODAY<br />

384<br />

religious knowledge is ...abranch of human<br />

knowledge that has a collective <strong>and</strong> dynamic identity<br />

<strong>and</strong> that remains viable through the constant<br />

exchange, cooperation, <strong>and</strong> competition of scholars.<br />

As such, religious knowledge is replete with<br />

error, conjecture, <strong>and</strong> conviction. Error plays as<br />

much role in religious knowledge as does insight....<br />

It is in this sense that religious knowledge<br />

changes, evolves, contracts, exp<strong>and</strong>s, waxes, <strong>and</strong><br />

wanes. It is temporal <strong>and</strong> in constant commerce<br />

with other realms of human culture. 69<br />

Two pivotal insights follow from this passage.<br />

The first is that religious knowledge is fundamentally<br />

plural, both in its possession <strong>and</strong> in its<br />

manifestations. The second is that religious<br />

knowledge is fundamentally fallible <strong>and</strong> never<br />

absolute. Soroush maintains that “religious<br />

knowledge is, potentially, as open to criticism as<br />

scientific knowledge.” 70 The idea is that no matter<br />

how great the source or theoretical composition<br />

of a doctrine, human beings have to implement<br />

it, thus making it always susceptible to<br />

corruption <strong>and</strong> manipulation. 71<br />

Here Soroush<br />

again touches on an aspect of religion’s<br />

autoimmunity. If religion is to be held sacred, all<br />

human manifestations must be acknowledged as<br />

profane <strong>and</strong> distinguished from the religiously<br />

ideal. Any claim to divine authority would violate<br />

the very conditions of the distinction between<br />

the sacred <strong>and</strong> the profane. Thus if theologians<br />

or religious adherents claim divine<br />

knowledge or underst<strong>and</strong>ing, then they must either<br />

claim to be divine themselves, thus violating<br />

the oneness of the divine, or claim that the divine<br />

is already contained in human interpretation,<br />

thus negating the very distinction between the<br />

human <strong>and</strong> the divine. It is precisely by maintaining<br />

the distinction between the divine <strong>and</strong> the human<br />

that Soroush is able to maintain the sanctity<br />

<strong>and</strong> motivational force of the former while developing<br />

the pluralist, fallibilist, <strong>and</strong> developmental<br />

aspects of the latter. 72 Thus Soroush can argue,<br />

without any hint of loss or disappointment, that<br />

“it is the secular,” or non-sacred, “nature of the<br />

implementation of any doctrine that renders the<br />

doctrine so vulnerable.” 73 For on this view vulnerability<br />

<strong>and</strong> error are not what is to be avoided<br />

at all costs. Rather it is error that ensures the “life<br />

<strong>and</strong> longevity” of religious knowledge. 74<br />

In<br />

Derridean terms we might say that Soroush embraces<br />

the double bind <strong>and</strong> infinite perfectibility<br />

of religious knowledge as impetuses toward<br />

religious debate <strong>and</strong> renewal rather than viewing<br />

them as obstacles to religion that must be<br />

removed or defended against.<br />

Soroush’s discussion of religion resonates


most clearly with Derrida’s in his discussions of<br />

religious underst<strong>and</strong>ing <strong>and</strong> interpretation.<br />

Soroush argues that “the appeal to religious conviction<br />

cannot <strong>and</strong> should not arrest the renewal<br />

of religious underst<strong>and</strong>ing or innovative adjudication<br />

[ijtihad] in religion. Such renewal requires<br />

extrareligious data.” 75 It is here, perhaps more<br />

clearly than anywhere else, that Soroush’s approach<br />

to religion evokes a logic of autoimmunity<br />

whereby religion in its own defense,<br />

development, <strong>and</strong> communication is never pure,<br />

self-contained, or present in itself. Religion<br />

needs what is foreign <strong>and</strong> potentially threatening<br />

to it for its own vitality. Thus for Soroush an independent<br />

principle of justice is essential to the development<br />

of religious knowledge <strong>and</strong> practice.<br />

He argues that “justice is at once a prerequisite<br />

for <strong>and</strong> a requirement of religious rules. A rule<br />

that is not just is not religious.” 76 This implies that<br />

the Quran, as the basis of Islam, should never be<br />

viewed as a closed text, that it actually requires<br />

interaction with the world for any interpretation,<br />

including general principles of justice <strong>and</strong> other<br />

rational, scientific principles. 77 Thus Soroush argues,<br />

“In a religious society, it is not religion per<br />

se that arbitrates, but some underst<strong>and</strong>ing of religion<br />

which is, in turn, changing, rational, <strong>and</strong> in<br />

harmony with the consensual <strong>and</strong> accepted<br />

extrareligious criteria.” 78 For Soroush (like<br />

Kant), 79 a proper underst<strong>and</strong>ing of religion is<br />

only possible on the basis of rational criteria:<br />

disregard of rational criteria <strong>and</strong> of the necessity<br />

for the harmony of religious underst<strong>and</strong>ing <strong>and</strong> rational<br />

findings is a breach of religious responsibility.<br />

It is reason that defines truth, justice, public interest,<br />

<strong>and</strong> humanity, that attributes these<br />

properties to a particular religion (or else it would<br />

not become a rationally acceptable religion), <strong>and</strong><br />

that undertakes the task of underst<strong>and</strong>ing the<br />

teachings of religion. 80<br />

For Soroush it is reason <strong>and</strong> its fundamental concerns<br />

with “truth, justice, <strong>and</strong> humanity” that<br />

must direct our underst<strong>and</strong>ing of religion. 81 It is<br />

this coupling of religion <strong>and</strong> reason that Soroush<br />

takes to be essential to Islam <strong>and</strong> which, in turn,<br />

requires democracy for religion. 82 As he argues,<br />

“a religious society, based upon free faith, dynamic<br />

underst<strong>and</strong>ing, <strong>and</strong> individual presence<br />

before God, cannot be but democratic.” 83<br />

Soroush develops the intimate relation between<br />

democracy <strong>and</strong> religion through an examination<br />

of the relation of law to religion. Following<br />

a line of argument similar to what we have<br />

seen in An-Na‘im’s work, Soroush argues that<br />

“religious jurisprudence, however divine <strong>and</strong><br />

ahistorical its origins, inevitably becomes historical<br />

<strong>and</strong> assumes a worldly application.” 84 That is<br />

to say, granting the divinity of religion is no obstacle<br />

to recognizing the contextual <strong>and</strong> conditional<br />

status of religious law. In fact, that recognition<br />

is driven by the distinction between the<br />

(believed) divine source <strong>and</strong> the necessarily human<br />

interpretation. Again, Soroush argues that<br />

“independent moral st<strong>and</strong>ards (such as public interest<br />

<strong>and</strong> justice)” are the necessary precondition<br />

of interpreting religious law. 85 Thus, in contrast<br />

to An-Na‘im <strong>and</strong> in a way more radical than<br />

he is willing to acknowledge, Soroush acknowledges<br />

not only the necessity of human interpretation,<br />

but also the necessary use of independent<br />

humanly derived principles in making those interpretations.<br />

The complex process <strong>and</strong> set of resources<br />

that must go into interpreting <strong>and</strong> constructing<br />

religious law makes the process of<br />

articulating religious law an always ongoing, <strong>and</strong><br />

thus infinitely perfectible, endeavor that will<br />

never arrive at a final truth. In fact, Soroush presents<br />

the perfectibility of religion <strong>and</strong> religious<br />

law as analogous to the perfectibility he also<br />

finds characteristic of democracy. As with religion<br />

<strong>and</strong> religious law, Soroush maintains, “a democracy<br />

is engaged in an interminable process of<br />

choosing <strong>and</strong> examining.” 86<br />

For Soroush there is not merely an analogy<br />

between the structure of religious knowledge <strong>and</strong><br />

democracy. His analysis of the relation between<br />

religion <strong>and</strong> religious knowledge culminates in a<br />

defense of the basic democratic principles of<br />

freedom of religion <strong>and</strong> religious pluralism<br />

through open critical debate. Soroush argues,<br />

To compel individuals to confess a faith falsely; to<br />

paralyze minds by indoctrination, propag<strong>and</strong>a,<br />

<strong>and</strong> intimidation; <strong>and</strong> to shut down the gates of<br />

criticism, revision, <strong>and</strong> modification so that every-<br />

DECONSTRUCTION, SECULARISM, AND ISLAM<br />

385


PHILOSOPHY TODAY<br />

386<br />

one would succumb to a single ideology creates<br />

not a religious society but a monolithic <strong>and</strong> terrified<br />

mass of crippled, submissive, <strong>and</strong> hypocritical<br />

subjects. 87<br />

Again, on religious grounds, Soroush argues for<br />

the uncoupling of religious adherence with absolutism.<br />

He goes on to argue that “A religious<br />

society becomes more religious as it grows more<br />

free <strong>and</strong> freedom loving, as it trades diehard<br />

dogma with examined faith, as it favors inner<br />

plurality over outer mechanical <strong>and</strong> nominal<br />

unity.” 88 Although Soroush does not pursue the<br />

question of the position of those who are not religious,<br />

or are even anti-religious, in the context of<br />

majority religious societies, he does defend several<br />

of the key reforms that we saw An-Na‘im<br />

arguing for, but without making the potentially<br />

paralyzing claim of identifying the true essence<br />

of Islam, however attractive that essence might<br />

be. 89 We thus find Soroush arguing from religious<br />

principles for formally democratic principles<br />

<strong>and</strong> human rights that are generally only<br />

associated with secular societies. Most interestingly<br />

for the present study, Soroush’s distinction<br />

between religion <strong>and</strong> religious knowledge undermines<br />

the usual association of religion with absolutism.<br />

For Soroush religious faith <strong>and</strong> the very<br />

idea of the sacred come to imply both a commitment<br />

to critical public discourse <strong>and</strong> democratic<br />

pluralism. 90<br />

By examining the work of An-Na‘im <strong>and</strong><br />

Soroush, I have attempted to show both that<br />

lively debates about the relation between religion<br />

<strong>and</strong> politics are underway in the Muslim world<br />

<strong>and</strong> that many of these debates involve defending<br />

religious freedom, generally progressive policies,<br />

<strong>and</strong> democratic political forms without embracing<br />

<strong>secularism</strong>. I suggest that recognizing<br />

these debates should lead us to evaluate them not<br />

in relation to their religious appeals, but rather in<br />

terms of the politics <strong>and</strong> human relations they defend.<br />

I have also argued that Soroush goes beyond<br />

An-Na‘im by developing a more radical<br />

contextualization of the content of the Quran,<br />

<strong>and</strong> its revelations, in order to develop readings<br />

of them adequate to the present condition. At the<br />

core of the contextualization of the Quran is an<br />

explicit distinction between the divine, sacred,<br />

<strong>and</strong> eternal on the one h<strong>and</strong>, <strong>and</strong> the worldly, historical,<br />

<strong>and</strong> temporal on the other. Similar to<br />

Derrida’s analysis in “Faith <strong>and</strong> Knowledge,”<br />

“religion” for Soroush is, as object of faith,<br />

caught in the double bind of chance <strong>and</strong> threat<br />

<strong>and</strong>, as divine, capable of becoming manifest<br />

only through a process of autoimmune profanation.<br />

For Soroush, “religion” can never appear as<br />

such. “Religion” can appear only in “religious<br />

knowledge.” Thus Soroush mobilizes a certain<br />

logic of autoimmunity for a progressive approach<br />

to Quranic interpretation <strong>and</strong> reform of<br />

shari‘a. Two important implications follow: first,<br />

all religious law <strong>and</strong> institutions reflect human<br />

underst<strong>and</strong>ing; <strong>and</strong> second, because the body of<br />

religious thought reflects human underst<strong>and</strong>ing,<br />

“a religious community will always profit from<br />

the criticism of religious thought.” 91 The powerful<br />

democratic conclusion thus follows that “criticism<br />

ought to be supported <strong>and</strong> facilitated by an<br />

open atmosphere.” 92 By developing his own version<br />

of religious autoimmunity, Soroush is able<br />

to directly advocate the core democratic values of<br />

freedom, equality, <strong>and</strong> open criticism each as<br />

fundamentally religious, rather than secular<br />

goods.<br />

Soroush goes further still by emphasizing the<br />

mutual implication of religious faith <strong>and</strong> democratic<br />

pluralism. 93 For Soroush, preserving the<br />

goodness of a source, text, revelation, or tradition,<br />

i.e., having faith in it (as we might say<br />

Derrida has faith in democracy), paradoxically<br />

implies a commitment not to the perfection (perfect<br />

goodness) of that source, text, etc. but rather<br />

to the possibility of inheriting it well, for the<br />

good. This is a possibility that can, of course, always<br />

falter. For Soroush, as for Derrida, it is precisely<br />

the lack of assurance that we will decide<br />

for the good <strong>and</strong> the ever present double bind of<br />

chance <strong>and</strong> threat that dem<strong>and</strong>s a commitment to<br />

critical engagement with the tradition of<br />

interpreting whatever we place our faith in.<br />

Quite apart from the ultimate acceptability of<br />

An-Na‘im’s <strong>and</strong> Soroush’s approaches to religion<br />

<strong>and</strong> the public sphere, for both believers <strong>and</strong><br />

non-believers, their work shows that absolutism<br />

<strong>and</strong> unconditionality are not essential parts of religion,<br />

nor are freedom, equality <strong>and</strong> the right to<br />

open criticism the exclusive domain of the secu-


lar. Derrida would, of course, not have claimed<br />

otherwise. Nevertheless, even if religious commitment<br />

does not necessarily entail absolutism,<br />

we might still see the threat of religious intolerance<br />

as sufficient reason to prefer a generally secular<br />

approach to politics, one that would attempt<br />

to ensure, as Derrida says, that “the secular space<br />

of the political <strong>and</strong> the religious space are not<br />

confused.” In the course of this essay I have outlined<br />

three reasons why we might pursue a different<br />

approach to politics <strong>and</strong> religion. First,<br />

Derrida’s own structural arguments undermine<br />

the possibility of a political space purified of religion.<br />

Second, the approach to religion found in<br />

thinkers like Soroush show that religious commitment<br />

can actually serve as the basis of a commitment<br />

to free <strong>and</strong> open democratic discourse.<br />

Finally, An-Na‘im’s appeal to the right to selfdetermination<br />

highlights the secular exclusion of<br />

the religiously minded. Simply excluding the religious<br />

from the political space is not only structurally<br />

impossible, but politically unjust <strong>and</strong> strategically<br />

ill-fated. I suggest that if <strong>secularism</strong> <strong>and</strong><br />

religion are to be reformed, the intermingling of<br />

both spaces must be recognized <strong>and</strong> the critical<br />

democratic possibilities of each must be<br />

rehabilitated.<br />

1. Jacques Derrida, “Violence <strong>and</strong> Metaphysics: An Essay<br />

on the Thought of Emmanuel Levinas,” trans.<br />

Alan Bass, in Writing <strong>and</strong> Difference (Chicago: University<br />

of Chicago Press, 1978), 117. Derrida associates<br />

religion with the unscathed in “Faith <strong>and</strong> Knowledge:<br />

The Two Sources of ‘Religion’at the Limits of<br />

Reason Alone,” trans. Samuel Weber, in Acts of Religion,<br />

ed. G. Anidjar (New York: Routledge, 2002). A<br />

similar worry about the closure of legitimate discourse<br />

is also central to Habermas’<strong>and</strong> Rawls’thinking.<br />

For example, in embracing what he calls “postmetaphysical<br />

thinking,” Habermas “insists on the<br />

difference between the certainties of faith, on the one<br />

h<strong>and</strong>, <strong>and</strong> validity claims that can be publically criticized,<br />

on the other”; the latter comprise the “secular<br />

justifications” required by a liberal democratic state<br />

(see Jürgen Habermas, “Religion in the Public<br />

Sphere,” European Journal of <strong>Philosophy</strong><br />

14 [2006]: 17, 8). By contrast, Rawls is relatively<br />

more open to the legitimate use of religious reasons<br />

in public political discourse, as long as they meet his<br />

“proviso” requirement <strong>and</strong> do not take the form of<br />

“comprehensive doctrines” which claim to possess<br />

the whole truth in politics that can be imposed on all.<br />

Indeed, Rawls includes “<strong>secularism</strong>” as a possible<br />

comprehensive doctrine incompatible with the dem<strong>and</strong>s<br />

of “political liberalism.” See John Rawls,<br />

“The Idea of Public Reason Revisited,” The University<br />

of Chicago Law Review 64 (Summer 1997): 771.<br />

Cf. also John Rawls, Political Liberalism (New<br />

York; Columbia University Press, 2005), 216–18.<br />

NOTES<br />

2. Jacques Derrida, “Above All, No Journalists!” trans.<br />

Samuel Weber, in Hent de Vries <strong>and</strong> Samuel Weber,<br />

eds., Religion <strong>and</strong> Media (Stanford: Stanford University<br />

Press, 2002), 67. In Derrida’s discussion of<br />

religion in “Faith <strong>and</strong> Knowledge” <strong>and</strong> “Above All,<br />

No Journalists,” he pursues <strong>and</strong> develops the<br />

autoimmunity of religion as it appears in the contrast<br />

between the claim <strong>and</strong> concept of religion as sacred<br />

<strong>and</strong> its manifestation as necessarily profane. He also<br />

touches on, but does not develop at length, the more<br />

radical logic of autoimmunity that would bear on the<br />

concept, or the very idea, of religion as sacred, which<br />

would link the purity <strong>and</strong> inviolability of the sacred<br />

to inextricable contamination <strong>and</strong> violation, thus<br />

calling into question the very idea of sacredness as<br />

such (cf. “Faith <strong>and</strong> Knowledge,” 93, where Derrida<br />

discusses the mutual dependence of the sacred <strong>and</strong><br />

faith, credit, or trust). In what follows it should be<br />

borne in mind that while Derrida’s work would lead<br />

us to press the autoimmunity of the sacred itself, neither<br />

An-Na‘im nor Soroush, as thinkers concerned to<br />

preserve a sacred ideal in Islam, would follow<br />

Derrida in this regard. My thanks to Martin<br />

Hägglund for pressing me on this point.<br />

3. Cf. Derrida “Force of Law: The ‘Mystical Foundation<br />

of Authority,’” trans. M. Quanitance, in Acts of<br />

Religion, 251–55.<br />

4. Cf. Derrida, The Gift of Death, trans. D. Wills (Chicago:<br />

University of Chicago Press, 1995), 67–68;<br />

<strong>and</strong> Derrida, Politics of Friendship, trans. G. Collins<br />

(New York: Verso, 1997), 26–27.<br />

DECONSTRUCTION, SECULARISM, AND ISLAM<br />

387


5. On the double bind of chance <strong>and</strong> threat, cf. Derrida,<br />

Politics of Friendship, 173–74; “Faith <strong>and</strong> Knowledge,”<br />

55–57, 82–83; Derrida, Rogues: Two Essays<br />

on Reason, trans. Pascale-Anne Brault <strong>and</strong> Michael<br />

Naas (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2005),<br />

82–83.<br />

6. Cf. Derrida, “Force of Law,” 255.<br />

7. Joshua Andresen, “Deconstruction, Normativity,<br />

<strong>and</strong> Democracy to Come,” <strong>Philosophy</strong> Today<br />

54 (Summer 2010): 103–20.<br />

8. Cf. Derrida’s remarks on the “test <strong>and</strong> ordeal of the<br />

undecidable” <strong>and</strong> the need for “learning, reading, underst<strong>and</strong>ing,<br />

interpreting the rule, <strong>and</strong> even calculating”<br />

in order to attempt a just decision (“Force of<br />

Law,” 252).<br />

9. Derrida also advocates democracy for the maintenance<br />

of access to public space <strong>and</strong> public criticism,<br />

the protection of the rights of critique <strong>and</strong> critical<br />

questioning of all kinds, <strong>and</strong> even the right to <strong>deconstruction</strong><br />

itself (understood as the practice of critique<br />

<strong>and</strong> critical questioning). See, Politics of Friendship,<br />

105–06, <strong>and</strong> Rogues, 91–92. For an extended discussion<br />

of Derrida’s approach to the historical exclusion<br />

of women from politics <strong>and</strong> friendship see Joshua<br />

Andresen, “Politics Beyond Brotherhood: Experiencing<br />

the Self as Other in Politics of Friendship,” in<br />

G. Bertram, R. Celikates, C. Laudou, <strong>and</strong> D. Lauer,<br />

eds., Expérience et réflexivité (Paris: Editions<br />

L’Harmattan, 2011), 205–18. For an extended discussion<br />

of the relationship between the conceptual<br />

<strong>and</strong> the social-institutional aspects of democracy <strong>and</strong><br />

democracy to come for Derrida, see Andresen, “Deconstruction,<br />

Normativity, <strong>and</strong> Democracy to<br />

Come.”<br />

10. Derrida, Rogues, 28–29 <strong>and</strong> 33. As I examine below,<br />

the major exceptions to the democratic claim that<br />

Derrida discusses are explicitly theocratic Islamic<br />

states, such as Saudi Arabia.<br />

11. Derrida, Rogues, 26–29.<br />

12. Andresen, “Deconstruction, Normativity, <strong>and</strong> Democracy<br />

to Come,” 109–11.<br />

13. Such inclusion is also absent at the level of the<br />

conceptuality of “democracy” itself. Derrida recalls<br />

his earlier discussion of différance <strong>and</strong> applies it to<br />

“democracy” in Rogues. There he argues that there is<br />

a “semantic vacancy or indetermination at the very<br />

center of the concept of democracy” (Rogues, 24). I<br />

discuss the significance of Derrida’s conceptual<br />

analysis of “democracy” for his strategic inheritance<br />

of both the term <strong>and</strong> the political structure in<br />

PHILOSOPHY TODAY<br />

388<br />

Andresen “Deconstruction, Normativity, <strong>and</strong> Democracy<br />

to Come,” 107–08 <strong>and</strong> 113–14.<br />

14. Interestingly, in the 2008 Economist “Index of Democracy,”<br />

seven of the top ten “most democratic”<br />

countries are officially constitutional monarchies. In<br />

many of these countries, the monarch also serves as<br />

the official head of the state religion or is required to<br />

be a member of that religion or confession. See:<br />

http://graphics.eiu.com/PDF/Democracy%20Index<br />

%202008.pdf<br />

15. Derrida explicitly calls attention to the strategic nature<br />

of his invocation of “democracy” in the following:<br />

“Saying that to keep this Greek name, democracy,<br />

is an affair of context, of rhetoric or of strategy,<br />

even of polemics, reaffirming that this name will last<br />

as long as it has to but not much longer, saying that<br />

things are speeding up remarkably in these fast<br />

times, is not necessarily giving in to the opportunism<br />

or cynicism of the antidemocrat who is not showing<br />

his cards. Completely to the contrary: one keeps this<br />

indefinite right to the question, to criticism, to <strong>deconstruction</strong><br />

(guaranteed rights, in principle, in any<br />

democracy: no <strong>deconstruction</strong> without democracy,<br />

no democracy without <strong>deconstruction</strong>). One keeps<br />

the right strategically” (Politics of Friendship, 105).<br />

16. Cf. ibid., 22 <strong>and</strong> Rogues, 91.<br />

17. Derrida first develops the idea of autoimmunity at<br />

length in “Faith <strong>and</strong> Knowledge.” For Derrida’s reference<br />

to biology see “Faith <strong>and</strong> Knowledge,”<br />

80n27. For a detailed analysis of Derrida’s different<br />

uses of “autoimmunity” in relation to religion <strong>and</strong><br />

democracy, see Samir Haddad, “Derrida <strong>and</strong> Democracy<br />

at Risk,” Contretemps 4 (September 2004):<br />

29–44. For an insightful <strong>and</strong> thorough analysis of the<br />

logic of autoimmunity in relation to time, life, <strong>and</strong><br />

democracy see Martin Hägglund, Radical Atheism:<br />

Derrida <strong>and</strong> the Time of Life (Stanford: Stanford<br />

University Press, 2008), esp. chapters 1, 4, <strong>and</strong> 5.<br />

18. Derrida, Rogues, 86–87.<br />

19. Ibid., 87. Cf. Derrida, Politics of Friendship, 105.<br />

Democracy’s autoimmunity names a principle of the<br />

critical other within democracy itself, thus upsetting<br />

all purity <strong>and</strong> final presence. Cf. Derrida, “Faith <strong>and</strong><br />

Knowledge”: “This self-contesting attestation keeps<br />

the auto-immune community alive, which is to say,<br />

open to something other <strong>and</strong> more than itself: the<br />

other, the future, death, freedom, the coming or the<br />

love of the other” (87).<br />

20. Derrida, “Faith <strong>and</strong> Knowledge,” 63.<br />

21. Ibid., 86; Rogues, 28.


22. Derrida, “Faith <strong>and</strong> Knowledge,” 47, emphasis<br />

added.<br />

23. Derrida alludes to Kant’s Religion within the Limits<br />

of Mere Reason at the end of the passage <strong>and</strong> goes on<br />

to discuss Kant’s moral theology. The public-private<br />

distinction arises in Kant’s discussions <strong>and</strong> hierarchical<br />

ordering of the moral-rational basis of religion<br />

<strong>and</strong> the “pure religious faith” appropriate to it, in<br />

contrast to the historical aspect of religion <strong>and</strong> the<br />

“ecclesiastical faith” that accompanies it (Kant, Religion<br />

within the Limits of Mere Reason, trans. <strong>and</strong> ed.<br />

A. Wood <strong>and</strong> G. di Giovanni [Cambridge: Cambridge<br />

University Press], 112, 112–147). Kant explicitly<br />

argues that “inasmuch as [religion] is based<br />

on pure moral faith, religion is not a public condition”<br />

(ibid., 129). On the necessary subservience of<br />

ecclesiastical faith to pure religious faith, cf. Kant,<br />

Conflict of the Faculties, trans. Mary Gregor (Lincoln:<br />

University of Nebraska Press, 1979), 73. For an<br />

insightful interpretation of the public-private distinction<br />

in the religious context as essentially Kantian<br />

see William Connolly, Why I am Not a Secularist,<br />

(Minneapolis, Minnesota University Press, 1999),<br />

30–33.<br />

24. See, for example, Talal Asad, Formations of the Secular:<br />

Christianity, Islam, Modernity (Stanford: Stanford<br />

University Press, 2003). Asad argues at length<br />

that <strong>secularism</strong> “presupposes new concepts of ‘religion,’‘ethics,’<strong>and</strong><br />

‘politics,’<strong>and</strong> new imperatives associated<br />

with them” (1–2). He also discusses the secular<br />

location of religion outside the public sphere in<br />

the domain of private space (181–87). Cf. also Saba<br />

Mahmood, “Secularism, Hermeneutics, <strong>and</strong> Empire:<br />

The Politics of Islamic Reformation,” Public Culture<br />

18:2 (2006): 323–47, <strong>and</strong> “Religious Reason <strong>and</strong><br />

Secular Affect: An Incommensurable Divide?” Critical<br />

Inquiry 35 (Summer 2009): 836–62.<br />

25. There is, of course, also a structural side to infinite responsibility<br />

that flows simply from deciding one<br />

thing—always one thing at a time—rather than<br />

something else <strong>and</strong> never being able to justify that<br />

decision, whatever it is. The structural argument<br />

does not, at least not in principle, require any reference<br />

to others, even if some others <strong>and</strong> some<br />

heteronomy are implied by the very notion of decision<br />

itself.<br />

26. Derrida illustrates the iterability of religious doxa<br />

most vividly in his discussion tele-technoscientific<br />

transmission of religious teaching over the airways,<br />

by satellite <strong>and</strong> internet. For Derrida’s remarks on the<br />

relation between profanation <strong>and</strong> the sacred see<br />

“Faith <strong>and</strong> Knowledge,” 61n16. For an excellent discussion<br />

of Derrida’s analysis of the iterability <strong>and</strong><br />

autoimmunity of religion in “Faith <strong>and</strong> Knowledge”<br />

see Haddad, “Derrida <strong>and</strong> Democracy at Risk.”<br />

27. Derrida, “Faith <strong>and</strong> Knowledge,” 80.<br />

28. The examples that Derrida uses to illustrate religion’s<br />

autoimmunity call into question the purity of the sacred<br />

on practical grounds, while appearing to leave a<br />

place for a conceptual purity of the religious or sacred.<br />

Of course, there is a further performative contradiction<br />

in any human attempt to identify or isolate<br />

the sacred insofar as any human designation is necessarily<br />

marked by the human <strong>and</strong> therefore already<br />

scathed <strong>and</strong> profaned. As a result, the religious cannot<br />

be but also non-religious, thus making its<br />

iterability a condition of its possibility <strong>and</strong> impossibility.<br />

I will return to these issues in the second half of<br />

my essay.<br />

29. See, for example, his discussion of “wars of religion”:<br />

“What is involved is always avowed vengeance,<br />

often declared as sexual revenge: rapes, mutilated<br />

genitals or severed h<strong>and</strong>s, corpses exhibited,<br />

heads paraded, as not too long ago in France, impaled<br />

on the end of stakes (phallic processions of<br />

‘natural religions’). This is the case, for example, but<br />

it is only an example, in Algeria today, in the name of<br />

Islam, invoked by both belligerent parties, each in its<br />

own way” (Derrida, “Faith <strong>and</strong> Knowledge,” 88–89).<br />

30. See “Taking a St<strong>and</strong> for Algeria” in Acts of Religion,<br />

301–08.<br />

31. See ibid.<br />

32. For Derrida’s discussion of the double bind of religious<br />

faith see “Faith <strong>and</strong> Knowledge,” 56–57, 82–<br />

83; cf. 87. I examine Derrida’s discussion of the<br />

chance <strong>and</strong> threat of democracy in “Deconstruction,<br />

Normativity, <strong>and</strong> Democracy to Come,” 108–10.<br />

33. Derrida, Rogues, 28–29.<br />

34. Ibid., 29.<br />

35. Ibid.<br />

36. Ibid., 31.<br />

37. Ibid., 33. For a critical analysis of such appeals, particularly<br />

by U.S. foreign policy analysts, see Saba<br />

Mahmood, “Secularism, Hermeneutics, <strong>and</strong> Empire.”<br />

38. Mustafa Chérif, Islam <strong>and</strong> the West: A Conversation<br />

with Jacques Derrida (Chicago: The University of<br />

Chicago Press, 2008), 50–51, emphasis added.<br />

39. Derrida, Rogues, 28.<br />

DECONSTRUCTION, SECULARISM, AND ISLAM<br />

389


40. There are, of course still other <strong>and</strong> perhaps more immediate<br />

critical questions to raise with respect to<br />

Derrida’s approach to secularization <strong>and</strong> Islam. E.g.,<br />

why does he seem to approach Islam through its most<br />

common <strong>and</strong> sensationalized western representation?<br />

Why does he suggest one might have to dig to<br />

find Islamic ideas related to those he favors (e.g., the<br />

right to critique, critical questioning, <strong>and</strong> public<br />

space for the expression of these) or Muslims committed<br />

to either secular or democratic ideals? On<br />

these questions <strong>and</strong> topics see, for example,<br />

Abdullahi An-Na‘im, Islam <strong>and</strong> the Secular State:<br />

Negotiating the Future of Shari’a (Cambridge, MA:<br />

Harvard University Press, 2008); Mahmood, “Secularism,<br />

Hermeneutics, <strong>and</strong> Empire,” <strong>and</strong> Talal Asad,<br />

Formations of the Secular.<br />

41. Abdullahi An-Na‘im, Toward an Islamic Reformation:<br />

Civil Liberties, Human Rights, <strong>and</strong> International<br />

Law (Syracuse: Syracuse University Press,<br />

1990), xiii.<br />

42. For the purposes of this essay, I will limit my remarks<br />

almost exclusively to An-Na‘im’s more explicitly religious<br />

text of 1990, Toward an Islamic Reformation.<br />

Although he claims to build off the 1990 text in his<br />

more recent 2008 text, Islam <strong>and</strong> the Secular State,<br />

the latter combines a religious with a more explicitly<br />

secular stance.<br />

43. An-Na‘im, Toward an Islamic Reformation, 10.<br />

44. An-Na‘im, “Introduction” to Mahmoud Mohamed<br />

Taha, The Second Message of Islam, trans. with an<br />

Introduction by Abdullahi Ahmed An-Na‘im (Syracuse:<br />

Syracuse University Press, 1987), 28.<br />

45. An-Na‘im, Toward an Islamic Reformation, xiii. An-<br />

Na‘im notes that he uses “Shari‘a,” with a capital S,<br />

to refer to historical shari‘a as it has been traditionally<br />

understood <strong>and</strong> “shari‘a,” with a small s, to refer<br />

to Islamic law more generally, with its possible historical<br />

variants <strong>and</strong> reforms.<br />

46. Ibid.<br />

47. Ibid., 10, 48f.<br />

48. Ibid., xiv.<br />

49. Ibid., 3.<br />

50. Ibid.<br />

51. Ibid., 5.<br />

52. Ibid., 7.<br />

53. Ibid., 7. Interestingly, while An-Na‘im notes that the<br />

introduction of the nation-state is a Western colonial<br />

imposition on what is, from the Islamic perspective,<br />

the supposed unity of all Muslims <strong>and</strong> the supposed<br />

universal applicability of shari‘a throughout the<br />

PHILOSOPHY TODAY<br />

390<br />

Muslim world, he does not propose doing away with<br />

or reforming the nation-state. His argument relies on<br />

the acceptance of the practical necessity, if not also<br />

the inherent goodness, of the contemporary nationstate<br />

<strong>and</strong> the ideals of constitutionalism that typically<br />

follow with it. Cf. ibid., 7–8 <strong>and</strong> passim.<br />

54. Ibid., 8.<br />

55. Ibid., 8, my emphasis.<br />

56. Ibid., 9.<br />

57. Ibid.<br />

58. An-Na‘im discusses how Omar justified his actions<br />

as consistent with Islam, despite contradicting the<br />

Prophet’s practices <strong>and</strong> clear passages of the Quran,<br />

by arguing that he was acting on behalf of the needs<br />

of the community at that time in its specific context<br />

(ibid., 28–29, 60).<br />

59. Ibid.<br />

60. Ibid., 12.<br />

61. Ibid., 21.<br />

62. Ibid., 52.<br />

63. Soroush, Reason, Freedom, <strong>and</strong> Democracy in Islam:<br />

Essential Writings of Abdolkarim Soroush, ed.<br />

<strong>and</strong> trans. Mahmoud Sadri <strong>and</strong> Ahmad Sadri (Oxford:<br />

Oxford University Press, 2000), 13.<br />

64. Ibid., 15.<br />

65. Ibid., 30ff. Cf. also Soroush, “The Evolution <strong>and</strong> Devolution<br />

of Religious Knowledge” in Liberal Islam:<br />

A Sourcebook, ed. Charles Kurzman (Oxford: Oxford<br />

University Press, 1998), 244–51. The Iranian<br />

theologian Mohammad Shabestari employs an almost<br />

identical distinction in his writing between religion<br />

<strong>and</strong> religious thought <strong>and</strong> also develops several<br />

analogous inferences for critical <strong>and</strong> democratic politics.<br />

For an insightful discussion of Shabestari, see<br />

Nasr Abu Zayd, Reformation of Islamic Thought: A<br />

Critical Historical Analysis (Amsterdam: Amsterdam<br />

University Press, 2006), 68ff.<br />

66. Soroush, Reason, Freedom, <strong>and</strong> Democracy in Islam,<br />

31.<br />

67. Both Nasr Abu Zayd <strong>and</strong> Muhammad Arkoun develop<br />

the distinction between the divine elements of<br />

the Quran <strong>and</strong> its manifestations as discourse <strong>and</strong> as<br />

a “closed corpus” text, or Mushaf. Abu Zayd is particularly<br />

concerned to stress shortcomings of underst<strong>and</strong>ing<br />

the Quran as a text. See Abu Zayd, “The Dilemma<br />

of the Literary Approach to the Qur’an,” Alif<br />

23 (2003): 8–47, <strong>and</strong> Rethinking the Qur’an: Towards<br />

a Humanistic Hermeneutics (Utrecht: Humanities<br />

University Press, 2004), 9–18. Cf. Arkoun,<br />

Islam: To Reform or Subvert? (London: Saqi Books,


2006), 69–92, <strong>and</strong> Rethinking Islam: Common Questions,<br />

Uncommon Answers, trans. <strong>and</strong> ed. Robert Lee<br />

(Oxford: Westview Press, 1994), 35–9.<br />

68. Soroush, Reason, Freedom, <strong>and</strong> Democracy in Islam,<br />

32.<br />

69. Ibid., 34.<br />

70. Ibid., 137.<br />

71. Cf. Derrida’s argument that “one can always criticize,<br />

reject or combat this or that form of sacredness<br />

or of belief, even of religious authority, in the name<br />

of the most originary possibility” of religion (“Faith<br />

<strong>and</strong> Knowledge,” 93).<br />

72. On the motivational force of belief in God <strong>and</strong> the divine<br />

source of morality, cf. Kant, Religion, 33–35,<br />

115–16. Cf. also the following remark from Kant’s<br />

Conflict of the Faculties: “Religion does not differ in<br />

any point from morality, for it is concerned with duties<br />

as such. Its distinction from morality is a merely<br />

formal one: That reason in its legislation uses the<br />

Idea of God, which is derived from morality itself, to<br />

give morality influence on man’s will to fulfill all his<br />

duties” (61).<br />

73. Soroush, Reason, Freedom, <strong>and</strong> Democracy in Islam,<br />

80. Soroush argues for the non-sacred nature of<br />

all human institutions, including political ones, because<br />

they are human <strong>and</strong> fallible (61). As such, government<br />

<strong>and</strong> political institutions cannot “comm<strong>and</strong><br />

passive witness <strong>and</strong> submission,” but should rather<br />

be subject to public “rational supervision <strong>and</strong> scrutiny”<br />

(60). Soroush thereby rules out the absolutist<br />

approach to law <strong>and</strong> politics commonly associated<br />

with religious societies. He goes further in arguing,<br />

“religiosity or lack thereof do not enter the essence of<br />

government” (61). Thus he commits government to<br />

respect for religious pluralism <strong>and</strong> protection of minority<br />

interests generally associated with <strong>secularism</strong>.<br />

74. Cf. ibid., 90.<br />

75. Ibid., 128.<br />

76. Ibid., 132.<br />

77. For a historical overview of the problems <strong>and</strong> limits<br />

of specifically textual analysis of the Quran, see Abu<br />

Zayd, “The Dilemma of the Literary Approach to the<br />

Qur’an.” For Abu Zayd’s alternative approach to the<br />

Quran as “discourse,” see his Rethinking the Qur’an.<br />

78. Soroush, Reason, Freedom, <strong>and</strong> Democracy in Islam,<br />

132.<br />

79. For Kant’s arguments for the rational basis of religion<br />

see Religion, 33–36 <strong>and</strong> passim; <strong>and</strong> Conflict of<br />

the Faculties, 61–139.<br />

80. Soroush, Reason, Freedom, <strong>and</strong> Democracy in Islam,<br />

127.<br />

81. Ibid.<br />

82. Soroush goes on to argue that justice, distribution <strong>and</strong><br />

restriction of power, <strong>and</strong> human rights all have a rational<br />

rather than a religious origin <strong>and</strong> that “religion<br />

(in itself) <strong>and</strong> religious underst<strong>and</strong>ing (religion for<br />

us) rely on these rational precepts” (ibid., 133). It is<br />

on the basis of these rational elements that religion itself<br />

becomes rational. Soroush argues, “once religion<br />

is rationalized, then the way to epistemological<br />

pluralism—the centerpiece of democratic action—<br />

will be paved” (ibid., 133).<br />

83. Ibid., 143.<br />

84. Ibid., 150.<br />

85. Ibid.<br />

86. Ibid., 135. Soroush’s conception of religion <strong>and</strong> religious<br />

knowledge is formally analogous to Derrida’s<br />

own analysis of democracy’s perfectibility <strong>and</strong> characterization<br />

of it as always to come (Cf. Derrida, Politics<br />

of Friendship, 22, 306, <strong>and</strong> Rogues, 91, 86–92).<br />

In effect, Soroush shows that religion’s necessary reliance<br />

on human interpretation <strong>and</strong> articulation<br />

makes both religion <strong>and</strong> religious law always to<br />

come.<br />

87. Soroush, Reason, Freedom, <strong>and</strong> Democracy in Islam,<br />

142. Cf. Soroush’s comment that “the practice<br />

that truly violates democracy is not embracing faith,<br />

but the imposition of a particular belief or punishment<br />

of disbelief” (ibid., 135).<br />

88. Ibid., 145.<br />

89. Soroush seems, in fact, to assume a relatively homogenous<br />

religious society in his discussions of the<br />

necessarily democratic character of religious knowledge<br />

<strong>and</strong> society. It is thus unclear what role non-believers<br />

would have in debates concerning religious<br />

knowledge <strong>and</strong> law. The potential problem is made<br />

more difficult by Soroush’s refusal to give any kind<br />

of transcendent or universal epistemic st<strong>and</strong>ard of<br />

what should count as religious knowledge. To do so<br />

would violate the core idea that such st<strong>and</strong>ards, as in<br />

science more generally, are themselves contextual<br />

<strong>and</strong> evolving. One fairly straightforward remedy for<br />

the potential tyranny of the majority would be to argue,<br />

as both Soroush <strong>and</strong> An-Na‘im do, that actual<br />

religiosity cannot be coerced <strong>and</strong> thus the only way<br />

to foster genuine religiosity is to make a- <strong>and</strong><br />

antireligiosity real options. As we have seen both<br />

Soroush <strong>and</strong> An-Na‘im argue, such a position can be<br />

readily defended from basic Islamic principles.<br />

DECONSTRUCTION, SECULARISM, AND ISLAM<br />

391


90. Soroush explicitly argues that the “preconditions for<br />

democratizing religious government is historicizing<br />

<strong>and</strong> energizing the religious underst<strong>and</strong>ing by underscoring<br />

the role of reason in it. By reason I do not<br />

mean a form of isolated individual reason, but a collective<br />

reason arising from the kind of public participation<br />

<strong>and</strong> human experience that are available only<br />

through democratic methods” (ibid., 127).<br />

91. Abu Zayd, Reformation of Islamic Thought, 68. Although<br />

Abu Zayd discusses these implications in relation<br />

to Shabestari, they apply equally well to<br />

Soroush’s work.<br />

92. Ibid.<br />

93. Abdolkarim Soroush, Reason, Freedom, <strong>and</strong> Democracy<br />

in Islam, 138.<br />

American University of Beirut, Beirut, Lebanon<br />

PHILOSOPHY TODAY<br />

392

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!