11.01.2015 Views

Abstracts - Centre for Speech, Language and the Brain - University ...

Abstracts - Centre for Speech, Language and the Brain - University ...

Abstracts - Centre for Speech, Language and the Brain - University ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

<strong>Abstracts</strong><br />

14th Annual Conference on<br />

Architectures <strong>and</strong> Mechanisms <strong>for</strong><br />

<strong>Language</strong> Processing<br />

4-6 September 2008<br />

Cambridge, UK


Academic Programme<br />

Wednesday 3 rd September<br />

15.00-17.00 Pre-conference registration, <strong>Centre</strong> <strong>for</strong> <strong>Speech</strong>, <strong>Language</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Brain</strong><br />

Sir William Hardy Building, Downing Street<br />

18.30-20.30 Welcome reception, Newnham College<br />

Thursday 4 th September<br />

08.00-09.10 Registration, Queens’ College<br />

09.10-09.20 Welcome<br />

Session 1 – Syntactic processes in comprehension - 1<br />

Chair: Fern<strong>and</strong>a Ferreira<br />

09.20-09.40 O1 Sturt, P., Keller, F., & Dubey, A. Syntactic priming in comprehension<br />

without lexical repetition<br />

09.40-10.00 O2 Huettig, F., Chen, J., Bowerman, M., & Majid, A. Linguistic relativity:<br />

Evidence from M<strong>and</strong>arin speakers’ eye-movements<br />

10.00-10.20 O3 Yoshida, M., Dickey, M-W., & Sturt, P. Sluicing <strong>and</strong> syntactic<br />

prediction in online sentence processing<br />

10.20-10.50 Coffee<br />

Session 2 –<br />

Discourse constraints in comprehension<br />

Chair: Alan Garnham<br />

10.50-11.10 O4 Kreiner, H., Mohr, S., Kessler, K., & Garrod, S. The interaction<br />

between discourse constraints <strong>and</strong> gender agreement in lexical <strong>and</strong><br />

stereotypical role nouns: Evidence from ERP<br />

11.10-11.30 O5 Ferguson, H.J., & Breheny, R. Investigating <strong>the</strong> automaticity of<br />

predicting deception in a <strong>the</strong>ory of mind task<br />

11.30-11.50 O6 Arnold, J.E., & Lao, S-Y.C. Non-joint attention influences pronoun<br />

comprehension<br />

11.50-12.10 O7 Richardson, D.C., Dale, R., Kirkham, N.Z., & Tomlinson, J.<br />

Conversation, common ground <strong>and</strong> gaze coordination<br />

1


12.10-14.30 Lunch <strong>and</strong> Poster Session 1<br />

14.30-15.30 KN1 Rebecca Gómez<br />

Constraining children’s generalizations: Processing constraints on language<br />

learning<br />

Introduced <strong>and</strong> chaired by Lorraine K Tyler<br />

Session 3 –<br />

Visual language processing<br />

Chair: Pienie Zwitserlood<br />

15.30-15.50 O8 Thompson, R.L., Vinson, D.P., Jin, M., Pickering, M.J, & Vigliocco,<br />

G. Seeing <strong>the</strong> world through a visual language: Visual word paradigm in<br />

British Sign <strong>Language</strong><br />

15.50-16.10 O9 Orfanidou, E., Adam, R., & McQueen, J.M. Are non-lexical transitions<br />

between signs a segmentation cue in British Sign <strong>Language</strong><br />

16.10-16.40 Coffee<br />

Session 4 –<br />

<strong>Speech</strong> perception<br />

Chair: Mat<strong>the</strong>w Davis<br />

16.40-17.00 O10 Mattys, S.L., & Cooke, M. Effects of perceptual <strong>and</strong> cognitive loads<br />

on speech segmentation<br />

17.00-17.20 O11 Reinisch, E., Jesse, A., & McQueen, J.M. Speaking rate affects <strong>the</strong><br />

perception of word boundaries in online word recognition<br />

17.20-17.40 O12 Snoeren, N.D., Gaskell, G., & Di Betta, A.M. The perception of<br />

assimilation in newly learned novel words<br />

Friday 5 th September<br />

08.00-09.20 Registration, Queens’ College<br />

Session 5 – <strong>Language</strong> Production – 1<br />

Chair: Martin Pickering<br />

09.20-09.40 O13 Shafto, M.A., Stamatakis, E.A., Tam, P.P., & Tyler, L.K. Senior<br />

moments <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> brain: Convergent measures <strong>and</strong> an aging network<br />

09.40-10.00 O14 Hartsuiker, R.J., & Anton-Mendez, I. Interaction <strong>and</strong> interactivity in<br />

language production<br />

10.00-10.20 O15 Vernice, M., & Hartsuiker, R.J. Determinants of function assignment<br />

in language production: Is conceptual accessibility enough<br />

2


10.20-10.50 Coffee<br />

Session 6 – Syntactic processes in comprehension – 2<br />

Chair: Patrick Sturt<br />

10.50-11.10 O16 Apel, J., Henderson, J.M., & Ferreira, F. The perceptual span during<br />

regressions in garden path sentences<br />

11.10-11.30 O17 Tily, H., Hem<strong>for</strong>th, B., Arnon, I., Shuval, N., Snider, N., & Wasow, T.<br />

Eye movements reflect comprehenders’ knowledge of syntactic structure<br />

probability<br />

11.30-11.50 O18 Arai, M., & Keller, F. The use of verb-specific in<strong>for</strong>mation <strong>for</strong><br />

prediction in sentence processing<br />

11.50-12.10 O19 Kuperman, V., Vitoria, P., & Schreuder, R. Bridging locality <strong>and</strong> antilocality<br />

effects in <strong>the</strong> processing of long-distance syntactic dependencies<br />

12.10-14.30 Lunch <strong>and</strong> Poster Session 2<br />

14.30-15.30 KN2 William Marslen-Wilson<br />

The neurobiological foundations of spoken language comprehension<br />

Introduced <strong>and</strong> chaired by Kathleen Rastle<br />

Session 7 –<br />

Lexical semantics<br />

Chair: Gabriella Vigliocco<br />

15.30-15.50 O20 Ford, M.A., R<strong>and</strong>all, B., Taylor, K.I., Devereux, B.J., & Tyler, L.K.<br />

Semantic features <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> computation of word meaning: A large<br />

correlational semantic decision study<br />

15.50-16.10 O21 Vinson, D.P., Skinner, R., Thompson, R.L., & Vigliocco, G. The link<br />

between meaning <strong>and</strong> <strong>for</strong>m in British Sign <strong>Language</strong>: Role of iconic<br />

properties in lexical <strong>and</strong> conceptual processing<br />

16.10-16.40 Coffee<br />

Session 8 –<br />

<strong>Language</strong> acquisition<br />

Chair: Rebecca Gómez<br />

16.40-17.00 O22 Bannard, C., Lieven, E.V.M., & Tomasello, M. Evaluating<br />

constructivist <strong>the</strong>ory via Bayesian modeling of children’s early grammatical<br />

development<br />

17.00-17.20 O23 Franck, J., Millotte, S., & Frauenfelder, U.H. Early word order<br />

representation: Evidence against <strong>the</strong> lexical hypo<strong>the</strong>sis<br />

17.20-17.40 O24 Rabagliati, H.A., Lin, T., Gelf<strong>and</strong>, H., Marcus, G.F., & Pylkkänen, L.<br />

Development at <strong>the</strong> syntax-semantics interface: When do children<br />

underst<strong>and</strong> implicit ontological shifts<br />

19.00 Conference Dinner, St John’s College<br />

3


Saturday 6 th September<br />

08.00-09.20 Registration, Queens’ College<br />

Session 9 – <strong>Language</strong> Production – 2<br />

Chair: Victor Ferreira<br />

09.20-09.40 O25 Huettig, F., & Hartsuiker, R.J. External vs. internal verbal selfmonitoring:<br />

Speakers listen to <strong>the</strong>ir own external, but not internal, speech in<br />

speech production<br />

09.40-10.00 O26 Carbary, K.M., & Tanenhaus, M.K. Syntactic priming <strong>and</strong> message<br />

encoding in unscripted dialogue<br />

10.00-10.20 O27 Langus, A., & Nespor, M. Communication <strong>and</strong> grammar do not rely<br />

on <strong>the</strong> same cognitive system<br />

10.20-10.50 Coffee<br />

Session 10 –<br />

Lexical processing: Phonology <strong>and</strong> morphology<br />

Chair: William Marslen-Wilson<br />

10.50-11.10 O28 Bozic, M., Tyler, L.K., & Marslen-Wilson, W.D. Neuro-cognitive<br />

systems supporting derivational morphology<br />

11.10-11.30 O29 WITHDRAWN - Reilly, E., Solomyak, O., Marantz, A., & Badecker,<br />

W. Full parsing versus dual route models of morphological processing:<br />

Assessing surface frequency effects on response time using MEG<br />

11.30-11.50 O30 Salverda, A.P., & Tanenhaus, M.K. Orthographic <strong>and</strong> phonological<br />

in<strong>for</strong>mation in <strong>the</strong> printed-words paradigm<br />

11.50-12.10 O31 Rastle, K., Havelka, J., & Wydell, T. The cross-script length effect on<br />

reading aloud: Fur<strong>the</strong>r challenges <strong>for</strong> PDP models<br />

12.10-14.30 Lunch <strong>and</strong> Poster Session 3<br />

14.30-15.30 KN3 Jonathan Grainger<br />

Cracking <strong>the</strong> orthographic code<br />

Introduced <strong>and</strong> chaired by James McQueen<br />

Session 11 –<br />

Discourse processes<br />

Chair: Jennifer Arnold<br />

15.30-15.50 O32 San<strong>for</strong>d, A.J., Bohan, J., San<strong>for</strong>d, A.J.S., & Leuthold, H. Fit-to-context<br />

as a controller of <strong>the</strong> extent of semantic processing during discourse<br />

comprehension.<br />

4


15.50-16.20 Coffee<br />

Session 11 continued<br />

16.20-16.40 O33 Barr, D.J. Evidence <strong>for</strong> a dissociation between pragmatic <strong>and</strong> semantic<br />

constraint in lexical processing<br />

16.40-17.00 O34 Paterson, K.B., Filik, R., Mousoulidou, M., & Moxey, L.M.<br />

Interpreting quantifiers in context<br />

17.00-17.10 Concluding remarks<br />

5


Poster Sessions<br />

Poster Session 1 - Thursday 4 th September (12.10-14.30)<br />

P1<br />

P2<br />

P3<br />

P4<br />

P5<br />

P6<br />

P7<br />

P8<br />

P9<br />

P10<br />

P11<br />

P12<br />

P13<br />

P14<br />

P15<br />

P16<br />

P17<br />

P18<br />

P19<br />

P20<br />

P21<br />

P22<br />

Rol<strong>and</strong>, D. Relative clauses <strong>and</strong> surprisal<br />

Dikker, S., Rabagliati, H.A., Farmer, T.A., & Pylkkänen, L. Sensitivity to syntax in<br />

visual cortex: The role of phonological typicality<br />

Moat, S., Corley, M., & Hartsuiker, R.J. Exchange rate woes <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> spreading<br />

activation model too: A large-scale investigation<br />

Weighall, A.R., & Altmann, G.T.M. Explaining disruption in children's processing<br />

of interrupted main clauses: Discourse entities or similarity-interference<br />

Mitchell, L.M., & Rastle, K. Exploring <strong>the</strong> rules of stress assignment in disyllabic<br />

nonwords<br />

Sturt, P., & Yoshida, M. The speed of relative clause attachment<br />

Martin, A.E., & McElree, B. Susceptibility to retroactive interference in verb-phrase<br />

ellipsis<br />

Ferreira, F., & Jones, M.W. Good-enough language processing in a communicative<br />

situation<br />

WITHDRAWN - Kovacs, A.M., & Mehler, J. Extracting repetition-based patterns<br />

from noise in infancy<br />

Ivanova, I., Pickering, M.J., Branigan, H.P., McLean, J., & Costa, A.M. Mary exists<br />

a ball to John: Structural priming from wrong or nonce verbs exists<br />

Haigh, M., Stewart, A., & Kidd, E. Constraints on <strong>the</strong> construction of counterfactual<br />

situation representations during comprehension: An examination of on-line<br />

suppositional processing<br />

Myachykov, A., Garrod, S., & Scheepers, C. A unified priming account of structural<br />

choice in sentence production<br />

Brunellière, A.B., & Frauenfelder, U.H. Morpho-syntactic priming effects in spoken<br />

language processing<br />

Thomas, J.D., & Forster, K.I. A cross-task comparison of masked priming effects<br />

<strong>for</strong> differing semantic prime-target relationships<br />

Taylor, D., Lewis, R., & Badecker, W. Individual differences in agreement<br />

planning: The role of working-memory control<br />

Bannard, C., & Mat<strong>the</strong>ws, D.E. 2- <strong>and</strong> 3-year-olds' accuracy in repeating 4-word<br />

sequences is predicted by familiarity, positional variability <strong>and</strong> latent semantic<br />

classes<br />

Ferguson, H.J., Scheepers, C., & San<strong>for</strong>d, A.J. Be positive! The effect of negation<br />

on factual <strong>and</strong> counterfactual language processing<br />

Thompson, R.L., Vinson, D.P., & Vigliocco, G. The link between <strong>for</strong>m <strong>and</strong> meaning<br />

in British Sign <strong>Language</strong>: Lexical processing effects in semantic <strong>and</strong> phonological<br />

decisions<br />

Wang, L., Schlesewsky, M., & Bornkessel-Schlesewsky, I. Topicality <strong>and</strong> animacy<br />

interact to determine word order preferences in Chinese<br />

V<strong>and</strong>ekerckhove, B., & S<strong>and</strong>ra, D. An exemplar-based model of <strong>the</strong>matic fit<br />

Bohan, J., San<strong>for</strong>d, A.J., Glen, K., Clark, F., & Martin, E. Focus <strong>and</strong> emphasis<br />

devices modulate depth of processing as reflected in semantic anomaly detection<br />

Heide, J., Bartels, L., Lorenz, A., & Burchert, F. Lexical decision on German<br />

prefixed verbs: Full <strong>for</strong>m <strong>and</strong> root frequency effects<br />

6


P23<br />

P24<br />

P25<br />

P26<br />

P27<br />

P28<br />

P29<br />

P30<br />

P31<br />

P32<br />

P33<br />

P34<br />

P35<br />

P36<br />

P37<br />

P38<br />

P39<br />

P40<br />

P41<br />

P42<br />

P43<br />

P44<br />

P45<br />

P46<br />

Pliatsikas, C., & Marinis, T. Processing of regular <strong>and</strong> irregular past tense<br />

morphology in highly proficient L2 learners of English: A self-paced reading study<br />

Raffray, C.N., Scheepers, C., & Myachykov, A. Lexical overlap effects on syntactic<br />

priming: Evidence against a privileged status of verbs<br />

Whiting, C.M., Shtyrov, Y., & Marslen-Wilson, W.D. Processing derivational <strong>and</strong><br />

inflectional morphology in visual word recognition<br />

Kim, C.S., Gunlogson, C., Tanenhaus, M.K., & Runner, J.T. Focus alternatives <strong>and</strong><br />

contextual domain restriction: An eye-tracking study on <strong>the</strong> interpretation of “only”<br />

Coco, M.I., & Keller, F. Competition of visual <strong>and</strong> linguistic resources: Effects of<br />

intonational breaks <strong>and</strong> salience on <strong>the</strong> interpretation of structurally ambiguous<br />

sentences<br />

Raffray, C.N., Pickering, M.J., & Branigan, H.P. Event structure coordination in<br />

dialogue: Evidence from coercion<br />

Jackson, C., & Roberts, L. Animacy affects <strong>the</strong> processing of subject/object<br />

ambiguities in <strong>the</strong> L2<br />

WITHDRAWN - Coppock, E.E. Capturing <strong>the</strong> productivity of <strong>the</strong> double object<br />

construction<br />

Arai, M., Keller, F., & Demberg, V. Evidence <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> prediction of modifiers during<br />

sentence processing<br />

Cummins, C.R. Scrambled word recognition: Implications <strong>for</strong> position coding<br />

Jin, Y-S., Logie, R., & Corley, M. Translation takes place be<strong>for</strong>e utterance in a<br />

reading <strong>for</strong> translation task - evidence from two self-paced reading studies<br />

Traxler, M.J. Evidence <strong>for</strong> determinate attachment of relative clause modifiers<br />

Mat<strong>the</strong>ws, D.E., Lieven, E.V.M., & Tomasello, M. What’s in a manner of speaking<br />

Children’s sensitivity to partner specific referential precedents<br />

Carminati, M.N., & van Gompel, R.P.G. Lexical boost effects in comprehension<br />

priming<br />

Brouwer, S.M., Mitterer, H., & Huettig, F. Listeners make optimal use of speaker<br />

<strong>and</strong> discourse in<strong>for</strong>mation when recognizing reduced <strong>for</strong>ms<br />

Ding, G., R<strong>and</strong>all, B., Devereux, B.J., Shestakova, A., & Tyler, L.K. Dynamically<br />

resolving syntactic <strong>and</strong> semantic ambiguity in comprehending spoken language: A<br />

MEG study<br />

Filipović Đurđević, D. Balance of sense probabilities affects processing: Evidence<br />

from naming<br />

WITHDRAWN - Stockall, L., de Almeida, R., Cook, G., & von Grunau, M. Early<br />

visual compound constituent detection: Distinct roles <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> right <strong>and</strong> left<br />

hemisphere<br />

Leonard Cook, A., Corley, M., Ota, M., & Sorace, A. Implicit learning of second<br />

language structures<br />

Dorjee Khenchen, D., Garrett, M.F., & Glisky, E.L. Frontal mechanisms in language<br />

pragmatics: Evidence from older adults processing implicitures<br />

Lau, K.Y.D. The development of morphological processing in reading Chinese<br />

Andonova, E., & Coventry, K. Perspective priming in spatial descriptions<br />

Zhuang, J., Marslen-Wilson, W.D., R<strong>and</strong>all, B., Ford, M.A., & Tyler, L.K. The<br />

effect of cohort competition <strong>and</strong> semantics in spoken word recognition: An fMRI<br />

study<br />

Myachykov, A., Branigan, H.P., & Scheepers, C. Structural priming of voice <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

repetition of <strong>the</strong> phonological verb <strong>for</strong>m<br />

7


P47<br />

P48<br />

P49<br />

P50<br />

Corrêa, L.M.S., Augusto, M.A.R., Mir<strong>and</strong>a, F.V., & Marcilese, M. Avoiding<br />

processing cost: Differential strategies in <strong>the</strong> production of restrictive relative<br />

clauses<br />

Janssen, N., Melinger, A., Mahon, B.Z., Finkbeiner, M., & Caramazza, A. The<br />

grammatical class effect in <strong>the</strong> picture-word interference paradigm<br />

Rodrigues, E. dos Santos. The effect of argument status of PP modifiers on subjectverb<br />

agreement errors in Portuguese<br />

Smolka, E., Aviles, A., & Carreiras, M. When h<strong>and</strong>s convey <strong>the</strong> concreteness of<br />

words: <strong>Language</strong> production in cued speech<br />

Poster Session 2 - Friday 5 th September (12.10-14.30)<br />

P51<br />

P52<br />

P53<br />

P54<br />

P55<br />

P56<br />

P57<br />

P58<br />

P59<br />

P60<br />

P61<br />

P62<br />

P63<br />

P64<br />

P65<br />

P66<br />

P67<br />

WITHDRAWN - Imada, M., Matsui, H., Miyamoto, E.T., Subacheva, I.P., &<br />

Tagawa, T. Effects of phonological length in <strong>the</strong> processing of scrambling in<br />

Japanese<br />

Van Assche, E., Duyck, W., Hartsuiker, R.J., & Diependaele, K. Does bilingualism<br />

change native-language reading Cognate effects in sentence context<br />

Huettig, F., & McQueen, J.M. Retrieval <strong>and</strong> use of components of lexical<br />

knowledge depend on situational dem<strong>and</strong>s<br />

Siyanova, A., Conklin, K., & Schmitt, N. Evidence <strong>for</strong> different processes<br />

underlying idiom comprehension in L1 <strong>and</strong> L2: An eye-tracking study<br />

Kraljic, T., Siu, Y., & Ferreira, V.S. Rapid effects of linguistic alignment on<br />

communication<br />

Delogu, F., & San<strong>for</strong>d, A.J. Intensionality in sentence <strong>and</strong> discourse processing<br />

Wu, F., & Kaiser, E. Animacy effects in Chinese relative clauses processing<br />

Jacob, G., & von Gompel, R.P.G. The processing of lexical <strong>and</strong> subcategorization<br />

in<strong>for</strong>mation from newly acquired verbs<br />

Augurzky, P. Prosodic balance constrains argument structure interpretation in<br />

German<br />

Grewe, T., Schlesewsky, M., & Bornkessel-Schlesewsky, I. Caught between <strong>the</strong><br />

fields: Evidence <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> neural reality of topological distinctions in <strong>the</strong><br />

comprehension of word order permutations<br />

Gualmini, A., Meroni, L., & Zondervan, A. Experiments on <strong>the</strong> role of focus<br />

triggered by different types of QUDs in <strong>the</strong> computation of scalar implicatures<br />

Devereux, B.J., Taylor, K.I., R<strong>and</strong>all, B., Ford, M.A., & Tyler, L.K. The influence<br />

of conceptual structure in lexical <strong>and</strong> semantic decision on spoken words<br />

Kreysa, H., Pickering, M.J., Haywood, S.L., & Henderson, J.M. Linked visual<br />

attention between speakers <strong>and</strong> listeners: Effects on <strong>the</strong> comprehension of object<br />

descriptions<br />

Tzeng, A.K. ERPs study on lateralization of semantic repetition blindness<br />

Hanne, S., Sekerina, I.A., Vasishth, S., Burchert, F., & De Bleser, R. Processing of<br />

noncanonical sentences in German agrammatic aphasia: Evidence from eye<br />

movements<br />

Hochmann, J-R., & Mehler, J. Identifying <strong>and</strong> using function words: An eyetracking<br />

study with 17-month-olds<br />

Tydgat, I., Hartsuiker, R.J., & Pickering, M.J. Self-monitoring in speech: Where do<br />

we stop our erroneous utterances<br />

8


P68 Merkx, M.M., Rastle, K., & Davis, M.H Learning morphemes: Insights from skilled<br />

readers<br />

P69 Stolterfoht, B., Gese, H., & Maienborn, C. Syntactic category conversion causes<br />

processing costs: Evidence from adjectival passives<br />

P70 Bohan, J., San<strong>for</strong>d, A.J., Cochrane, S., & San<strong>for</strong>d, A.J.S. Direct <strong>and</strong> indirect speech<br />

modulates depth of processing<br />

P71 Holl<strong>and</strong>, R., Brindley, L., Tavabi, K., Pulvermüller, F., Patterson, K., & Shtyrov, Y.<br />

Are past-tense verbs special Evidence from a mismatch negativity study<br />

P72 Mirkovic, J., Trenkic, D., & Altmann, G.T.M. Processing of determiners: Task<br />

differences in <strong>the</strong> ‘visual world’ paradigm<br />

P73 Andrews, M.W., Vigliocco, G., & Vinson, D.P. Integrating statistics from <strong>the</strong> world<br />

<strong>and</strong> from language to learn semantic representations<br />

P74 Koornneef, A.W., Wijnen, F., & Reul<strong>and</strong>, E. Bridging <strong>the</strong> gap between linguistics<br />

<strong>and</strong> psycholinguistics: The case of anaphora<br />

P75 Rosenberg, J., Pusch, K., Dietrich, R., & Cajochen, C. Diurnal variations in<br />

language per<strong>for</strong>mance<br />

P76 Wonnacott, E., Per<strong>for</strong>s, A., & Tenenhaum, J.B. Higher order inference in verb<br />

argument structure acquisition<br />

P77 Spalek, K., & Damian, M.F. Of blue bottles <strong>and</strong> blue flowers: Phonological<br />

representations of L1 are active when producing words in L2<br />

P78 Allured, G., Conklin, K., & van Heuven, W.J.B. Processing overt <strong>and</strong> zero pronouns<br />

in M<strong>and</strong>arin Chinese<br />

P79 Diependaele, K., S<strong>and</strong>ra, D., & Grainger, J. Lexical <strong>and</strong> sublexical morphological<br />

influences in visual word recognition<br />

P80 Weber, K.M., & Indefrey, P. Shared syntactic in<strong>for</strong>mation in German-English<br />

bilinguals: An fMRI repetition suppression study<br />

P81 Garcia Castro, Y., Strijkers, K., Costa, A.M., & Alario, X. When cat competes with<br />

dog but not with perro: Evidence from <strong>the</strong> semantic competitor paradigm<br />

P82 Shukla, M., & Nespor, M. The vocalic tier constrains statistical computations over<br />

<strong>the</strong> consonantal tier<br />

P83 Taylor, K.I., R<strong>and</strong>all, B., Ford, M.A., Devereux, B.J., & Tyler, L.K. The statistical<br />

properties of semantic features influence spoken word recognition: Evidence from<br />

neuroimaging<br />

P84 Uzule, K., Wheeldon, L.R., & Meyer, A.S. Priming local syntactic structure in<br />

speech production: An online study<br />

P85 Dubey, A., Sturt, P., & Keller, F. Delays in <strong>the</strong> use of discourse in<strong>for</strong>mation in<br />

syntactic ambiguity resolution<br />

P86 Schwarzkopf, S., Müller, D., Weldle, H., & Konieczny, L. Grammatical person<br />

controls perspective taking in embodied simulation semantics<br />

P87 Staum Casasanto, L., Futrell, R., & Sag, I.A. Extra complementizers increase<br />

syntactic predictability<br />

P88 Moxey, L.M., & San<strong>for</strong>d, A.J. When are two characters a set Using scenariomapping<br />

as a guide to equivalence<br />

P89 Race, D.S., Klein, N.M., Hare, M.L., & Tanenhaus, M.K. The role of event<br />

knowledge in verb interpretation<br />

P90 Mir<strong>and</strong>a, F.V., & Corrêa, L.M.S. Resumptive pronouns in relative clauses: A last<br />

resource processing strategy in sentence production<br />

P91 Thornton, R., & Bye, J. Syntactic category ambiguity in sentence production<br />

P92 Rogers, J.C., Marslen-Wilson, W.D., & Davis, M.H. The effect of lexical ambiguity<br />

on spoken word recognition: Homographs versus homophones<br />

9


P93 Kim, C.S., & Runner, J.T. Verb phrase ellipsis: Discourse effects in syntax <strong>and</strong><br />

syntactic effects in discourse<br />

P94 Klein, M., Frank, S., van Jaarsveld, H., ten Bosch, L.F.M., & Boves, L.<br />

Unsupervised learning of conceptual representations – a computational neural model<br />

P95 Heller, D., Skovbroten, K., & Tanenhaus, M.K. Joint effects of knowledge overlap<br />

(bias) <strong>and</strong> strength of memory representations<br />

P96 Nilsenová, M., & van Amelsvoort, M.A.A. Testing <strong>the</strong> alignment model: Syntaxlexicon<br />

& syntax-phonology<br />

P97 Lindsay, S., Sedin, L., & Gaskell, G. Acquiring novel words <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir tenses:<br />

Evidence from lexical effects on phonetic categorisation with undegraded <strong>and</strong><br />

degraded stimuli<br />

P98 Pattamadilok, C., Perre, L., Dufau, S., & Ziegler, J. On-line orthographic influences<br />

on spoken language in a semantic task<br />

P99 Kaiser, E. Priming pronoun interpretation without using pronouns: Eye-tracking<br />

evidence <strong>for</strong> coherence<br />

P100 Davis, M.H., Longtin, C-M., & Rastle, K. Is a whisker some one who whisks Tests<br />

of route-emphasis in morphological processing<br />

Poster Session 3 - Saturday 6 th September (12.10-14.30)<br />

P101 Garagnani, M., Shtyrov, Y., Kujala, T., Wennekers, T., & Pulvermüller, F.<br />

Neurocomputational <strong>and</strong> neurophysiological investigations of brain interactions of<br />

language <strong>and</strong> attention<br />

P102 Wagner, V., & Jescheniak, J.D. On <strong>the</strong> flexibility of advance planning during<br />

sentence production: Effects of task dem<strong>and</strong>s on multiple lexical access<br />

P103 Meteyard, L., & Patterson, K. How do you find it: An analysis of speech production<br />

in <strong>the</strong> context of a deteriorating semantic system<br />

P104 Burigo, M., & Lorusso, M.L. Spatial meaning congruity effect with abstract <strong>and</strong><br />

concrete words<br />

P105 Davidson, D.J. Event-related spectral changes associated with morphosyntactic<br />

processing<br />

P106 Strijkers, K., & Costa, A.M. <strong>Language</strong> control in bilingual speech production: A<br />

blocked naming study<br />

P107 De Jong, N.H., Schoonen, R., & Hulstijn, J.H. The origin of pausing <strong>and</strong> speech rate<br />

in second language speech production<br />

P108 Kaiser, E. Evidence <strong>for</strong> priming on <strong>the</strong> level of referential dependencies<br />

P109 Kazanina, N. Morphological decomposition <strong>and</strong> selection of word meaning<br />

P110 Oppermann, F., Görges, F., Jescheniak, J.D., & Schriefers, H. The activation of<br />

multiple phonological codes during <strong>the</strong> naming of an object in context<br />

P111 Perniss, P., Vinson, D.P., Vigliocco, G., & Seifart, F. Modality vs. typology effects:<br />

Investigating <strong>the</strong> divide<br />

P112 O’Seaghdha, P.G., Santiago, J., Chen, J-Y., Roman, A., & Knicely, J. Syllables are<br />

chunks in M<strong>and</strong>arin, not in Spanish or English<br />

P113 Hirschfeld, G., Dobel, C., & Zwitserlood, P. Simulating perceptual features during<br />

language comprehension<br />

P114 Gram, L., & Buttery, P. Integrating simulation <strong>and</strong> experiment: A study of Japanese<br />

second language acquistion<br />

10


P115<br />

P116<br />

P117<br />

P118<br />

P119<br />

P120<br />

P121<br />

P122<br />

P123<br />

P124<br />

P125<br />

P126<br />

P127<br />

P128<br />

P129<br />

P130<br />

P131<br />

P132<br />

P133<br />

P134<br />

P135<br />

P136<br />

P137<br />

Tsai, S-H., Hsu, C-C., Yang, C-L., & Chen, J-Y. The classifier-noun agreement in<br />

M<strong>and</strong>arin Chinese is both semantic <strong>and</strong> syntactic: An event-related-potential (ERP)<br />

study<br />

Lebib, R., & Krott, A. Correctly used rule-governed morphemes elicit left anterior<br />

negativities<br />

Shen, X., & Damian, M.F. Role of phonology in <strong>the</strong> generation of h<strong>and</strong>written<br />

responses<br />

Morgan, J.L., & Weighall, A.R. How do we get from print to meaning: SMS<br />

shortcuts are not so gr8 at fstr lexical access<br />

Frank, R., & Badecker, W. SRNs <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> learning of grammatical agreement: The<br />

effect of target-source order <strong>and</strong> class overlap<br />

Andersson, R., Ferreira, F., & Henderson, J.M. The Visual World paradigm in a<br />

complex world<br />

Szlachta, Z., R<strong>and</strong>all, B., & Tyler, L.K. Selecting <strong>and</strong> producing names to common<br />

nouns: The role of <strong>the</strong> LIFG in <strong>the</strong> ageing brain<br />

Roehm, D., & Sorace, A. ERP signatures of auxiliary selection in German<br />

Thornton, R., Klein, N., Llewellyn, E., & Hackl, M. Integrating <strong>the</strong> spatial semantics<br />

of verbs <strong>and</strong> prepositions during sentence processing<br />

Yuen, I., Rastle, K., & Brysbaert, M. An EPG investigation of auditory interference<br />

on speech execution<br />

Webman, R., Fodor, J.D., & Fernández, E.M. Prosody <strong>and</strong> attachment in a double-<br />

PP construction in Hebrew<br />

Bögels, S., Schriefers, H., Vonk, W., Chwilla, D.J., & Kerkhofs, R. The role of<br />

prosody in on- <strong>and</strong> off-line sentence processing: The case of subject- <strong>and</strong> objectcontrol<br />

verbs<br />

Mohr, S., Kreiner, H., Kessler, K., & Garrod, S. Processing differences between<br />

anaphora <strong>and</strong> cataphora: Evidence from oscillatory brain activity<br />

Cai, Z., Pickering, M.J., & Sturt, P. The filler may be a gentleman: Local coherence<br />

effect in long-distance dependency processing<br />

Bordag, D., Trompelt, H., & Pechmann, T. (Ir)regularity of verbs revisited:<br />

Evidence <strong>for</strong> a lexical entry complexity based account<br />

Schimke, S. The processing of negated sentences in Turkish learners of French: A<br />

preference <strong>for</strong> scope-to-<strong>the</strong>-right<br />

Langus, A., Marchetto, E., Bion, R.A.H., & Nespor, M. The role of prosody in<br />

discovering hierarchical structure in continuous speech<br />

Anderson, S.E., Zuares, S.N., & Spivey, M.J. Perceptual simulations of negated<br />

binary-state sentences<br />

Loncke, M., Van Laere, S., & Desmet, T. Priming of syntactic attachment between<br />

prepositional phrases <strong>and</strong> relative clauses<br />

Kim, S., Mauner, G., & Koenig, J-P. Verb repetition is not required <strong>for</strong> structural<br />

priming in L2 English production in Japanese-English bilinguals<br />

Crepaldi, D., Marelli, M., & Luzzatti, C. Mental representation <strong>and</strong> processing of<br />

nominal compounds: Evidence from constituent priming in Italian<br />

Severens, E., & Hartsuiker, R.J. Do readers try to salvage incorrect sentences An<br />

ERP-study<br />

Marinis, T., Chondrogianni, V., & Firat, H. Self-paced listening with picture<br />

verification: A new paradigm to investigate on-line sentence processing in children<br />

<strong>and</strong> adults<br />

11


P138<br />

P139<br />

P140<br />

P141<br />

P142<br />

P143<br />

P144<br />

P145<br />

P146<br />

P147<br />

P148<br />

Bernolet, S., Bressers, M., Hartsuiker, R.J., & Pickering, M.J. The representation of<br />

L2 syntax is influenced by second-language proficiency: Evidence from crosslinguistic<br />

syntactic priming<br />

Demberg, V., & Keller, F. A <strong>the</strong>ory of processing difficulty based on syntactic<br />

prediction<br />

Shaher, R.F., Logacev, P., Engelmann, F., Vasishth, S., & Srinivasan, N. Clefting,<br />

topicalization <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> given-new preference: Eyetracking evidence from Hindi<br />

Bejjanki, V.R., Clayards, M., Knill, D.C., & Aslin, R.N. <strong>Speech</strong> perception involves<br />

statistically optimal multi-modal integration<br />

De Vries, M.H., Barth, A., Knecht, S., Zwitserlood, P., & Floeel, A. Stimulation of<br />

Broca’s area causes better error detection in an artificial language: A tDCS study<br />

Kamide, Y. The locus of attention in <strong>the</strong> mapping of motion events onto a visual<br />

world<br />

Schütze, C.T., Gollan, T.H., & Champion, M.K. Does 'you' help you retrieve 'ewe'<br />

TOT evidence on frequency inheritance<br />

Ilkin, Z., & Sturt, P. Negation reveals preferences in long distance dependency<br />

<strong>for</strong>mation<br />

Zawiszewski, A., Fernández, B., & Laka, I. Native versus non-native processing<br />

symmetries in noun/verb morphology<br />

Qiao, X., & Forster, K.I. Object relatives ARE easier than subject relatives in<br />

Chinese<br />

Frank, S.C., Dubey, A., & Keller, F. Syntactic priming between non-identical noun<br />

phrase structures<br />

12


<strong>Abstracts</strong> - Keynote Presentations<br />

13


KN1<br />

Rebecca Gómez<br />

<strong>University</strong> of Arizona, USA<br />

E-mail: rgomez@u.arizona.edu<br />

Constraining children’s generalizations: Processing constraints on<br />

language learning<br />

Recent findings with artificial languages demonstrate remarkable learning abilities in infants <strong>and</strong><br />

young children. With such extraordinary abilities how is learning constrained I will discuss three<br />

classes of constraint. The first arises from <strong>the</strong> learning process itself. The second two arise from<br />

naturally occurring memory processes of consolidation <strong>and</strong> reconsolidation. With respect to learning<br />

constraints, I will present research suggesting that learning is a dynamically guided process, arising in<br />

<strong>the</strong> interaction of internal <strong>and</strong> external constraints. Moreover, learners, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> structure <strong>the</strong>y can<br />

acquire, change as a function of experience. Next, I will discuss two memory processes that constrain<br />

learning. One demonstrates a type of memory consolidation (occurring with sleep) that results in<br />

generalization to novel cases. Ano<strong>the</strong>r demonstrates how reconsolidation enables memory change.<br />

Both memory processes are important <strong>for</strong> underst<strong>and</strong>ing how children sustain sensitivity to prior<br />

knowledge while incorporating new in<strong>for</strong>mation in complex learning scenarios such as those involved<br />

in acquiring language.<br />

Notes<br />

14


KN2<br />

William D. Marslen-Wilson<br />

MRC Cognition <strong>and</strong> <strong>Brain</strong> Sciences Unit, Cambridge, UK<br />

E-mail: william.marslen-wilson@mrc-cbu.cam.ac.uk<br />

The neurobiological foundations of spoken language comprehension<br />

The scientific study of speech <strong>and</strong> language is in a process of fundamental change <strong>and</strong> transition,<br />

driven by <strong>the</strong> development of new techniques <strong>for</strong> imaging <strong>the</strong> cognitive activities of <strong>the</strong> intact human<br />

brain, <strong>and</strong> by strong inputs from neurobiological sources. Neurobiological constraints, deriving from<br />

insights into <strong>the</strong> properties of related brain systems in non-human primates, are proving to be<br />

particularly influential. Numerous studies confirm <strong>the</strong> relevance of <strong>the</strong> basic primate model <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

higher-order structure of <strong>the</strong> speech underst<strong>and</strong>ing process, with evidence <strong>for</strong> multiple processing<br />

streams emerging in parallel from auditory cortex <strong>and</strong> from surrounding areas specialised <strong>for</strong><br />

processing complex auditory inputs, <strong>and</strong> with a major impact on current <strong>the</strong>ories of <strong>the</strong> functional<br />

architecture of <strong>the</strong> human neuro-cognitive language system.<br />

This cross-disciplinary perspective provides <strong>the</strong> framework <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> approach to spoken language<br />

presented here, which distinguishes a left lateralised fronto-temporal system that is critical <strong>for</strong> key<br />

linguistic processes of morpho-syntactic analysis, <strong>and</strong> a more distributed bi-hemispheric system that<br />

supports <strong>the</strong> computation of <strong>the</strong> broader semantic <strong>and</strong> pragmatic interpretation of <strong>the</strong> incoming<br />

utterance, as well as more basic processes of lexical access from speech – as reflected in<br />

complementary evidence from neuropsychological <strong>and</strong> neuroimaging research. This leads to a range<br />

of specific questions about <strong>the</strong> processing <strong>and</strong> representational properties of <strong>the</strong> basic bilateral<br />

system, <strong>and</strong> how <strong>the</strong>se relate to more specialized linguistic processing functions supported by <strong>the</strong> left<br />

perisylvian system.<br />

Notes<br />

15


KN3<br />

Jonathan Grainger<br />

CNRS & Université de Provence, France<br />

E-mail: jonathan.grainger@univ-provence.fr<br />

Cracking <strong>the</strong> orthographic code<br />

I will present a <strong>the</strong>ory of orthographic processing that makes a key distinction between a coarsegrained<br />

<strong>and</strong> a fine-grained orthographic code. The coarse-grained code provides a fast-track to<br />

semantics by optimizing use of limited visual in<strong>for</strong>mation to constrain lexical identity. The finegrained<br />

code provides accurate in<strong>for</strong>mation about letter sequences that is used to generate a prelexical<br />

phonological code. The starting point <strong>for</strong> both routes is a bank of letter detectors that per<strong>for</strong>m parallel,<br />

independent letter identification. Visual features are mapped onto retinotopic letter detectors that in<br />

turn serve as input to two types of location-invariant orthographic code: a relative-position code (<strong>for</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> fast-track to semantics) <strong>and</strong> a graphemic code (<strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> phonological route). The relative-position<br />

code represents combinations of letters in <strong>the</strong> correct order in <strong>the</strong> stimulus but not necessarily in<br />

adjacent positions. Thus <strong>the</strong> word “table” would be coded as a set of letter combinations such as TA,<br />

TB, TL, TE, AB, AL, etc. The activation level of each bigram is determined by <strong>the</strong> visibility of each<br />

of its component letters, which vary as a function of <strong>the</strong> position of <strong>the</strong> letters in <strong>the</strong> string <strong>and</strong> eye<br />

fixation location in <strong>the</strong> string (<strong>the</strong>se two factors determine variations in visual acuity <strong>and</strong> crowding).<br />

Changes in word location cause a complete change in activity in retinotopic letter detectors, but only<br />

modify <strong>the</strong> relative activation levels of <strong>the</strong> same set of bigram units. This flexible orthographic code<br />

allows <strong>the</strong> system to rapidly home-in on a single word identity, while <strong>the</strong> more fine-grained<br />

graphemic code is being computed. Contrary to <strong>the</strong> bigram code, <strong>the</strong> graphemic code requires precise<br />

in<strong>for</strong>mation concerning which letters are next to which in <strong>the</strong> string. This graphemic parsing enables<br />

prelexical phonological activation (a string of phonemes) which provides an additional constraint on<br />

word identity. The <strong>the</strong>ory accounts <strong>for</strong> why it is easy to read words with letters that have been<br />

jubmled, insernted, or remved, <strong>and</strong> explains why such effects arise early in <strong>the</strong> process of word<br />

identification relative to effects of fonology. Behavioral experiments will be reported that investigate<br />

various <strong>for</strong>ms of orthographic <strong>and</strong> phonological priming, <strong>and</strong> event-related potentials (ERPs) will be<br />

used to track <strong>the</strong> time-course of <strong>the</strong> putative underlying processes.<br />

Notes<br />

16


<strong>Abstracts</strong> – Oral Presentations<br />

17


O1<br />

Syntactic priming in comprehension without lexical repetition<br />

Patrick Sturt 1 , Frank Keller 1 , & Amit Dubey 2<br />

1 <strong>University</strong> of Edinburgh, UK, 2 <strong>University</strong> of Dundee, UK<br />

E-mail: patrick.sturt@ed.ac.uk<br />

Previous research has shown evidence <strong>for</strong> a parallelism preference in <strong>the</strong> processing of coordinated<br />

structures. Frazier et al. (JPR 2000) found that <strong>the</strong> second of two conjoined NPs is processed faster<br />

when it has <strong>the</strong> same syntactic structure as <strong>the</strong> first conjunct than when it did not (e.g., "<strong>the</strong> [tall] boy<br />

<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> young girl"). However, Frazier et al. failed to find a similar speedup if <strong>the</strong> conjunction is<br />

replaced with a verb (e.g., "<strong>the</strong> [tall] boy noticed <strong>the</strong> young girl"), which <strong>the</strong>y take as evidence against<br />

an explanation of <strong>the</strong> parallelism effect in terms of general syntactic priming.<br />

Here, we report two reading eye-tracking experiments which look in more detail at <strong>the</strong> relation<br />

between parallelism <strong>and</strong> priming. Unlike Frazier et al.'s studies, we used syntactic alternates with<br />

equivalent semantics. Experiment 1 used alternates like (1):<br />

(1) a. a difficult to read article (Adj)<br />

b. an article that is difficult to read (Rel)<br />

Exp 1 used coordination ("NP1 <strong>and</strong> NP1"), where <strong>the</strong> structures of NP1 <strong>and</strong> NP2 (Adj or Rel) were<br />

crossed in <strong>the</strong> design. A significant speedup was found in total time if <strong>the</strong> structures of <strong>the</strong> two NPs<br />

were identical (NP1 x NP2 interaction), replicating Frazier et al.'s results.<br />

Exp 2 used a sentence frame that did not involve coordination (e.g., "NP1 said that NP2").<br />

Additionally, we used less marked structures (e.g., Adj: "a difficult article" vs. Rel: "an article that is<br />

difficult"), to rule out <strong>the</strong> possibility that priming is limited to conditions involving marked structures.<br />

Again, a reliable interaction of NP1 x NP2 was observed in total time.<br />

This shows that <strong>the</strong> parallelism effect can be found in syntactic environments o<strong>the</strong>r than coordination,<br />

a result which is compatible with an explanation of <strong>the</strong> effect in terms of syntactic priming. The<br />

results provide new insight into <strong>the</strong> processes underlying syntactic priming in comprehension.<br />

Pickering <strong>and</strong> V. Ferreira (in press, PsychBull) observe that syntactic priming in comprehension<br />

appears to be weaker than priming in production; in nearly all current studies, some extra "boost" is<br />

required to obtain <strong>the</strong> effect (e.g., extensive repetition of structure, lexical overlap of content words<br />

between prime <strong>and</strong> target, or prime presented simultaneously with target using fast priming).<br />

However, none of <strong>the</strong>se "boosts" were present in <strong>the</strong> current experiments.<br />

Notes<br />

18


Linguistic relativity: Evidence from M<strong>and</strong>arin speakers’ eye-movements<br />

O2<br />

Falk Huettig 1 , Jidong Chen 2 , Melissa Bowerman 1 , & Asifa Majid 1<br />

1 Max Planck Institute <strong>for</strong> Psycholinguistics, Nijmegen, The Ne<strong>the</strong>rl<strong>and</strong>s, 2 Cali<strong>for</strong>nia State <strong>University</strong>, USA<br />

E-mail: falk.huettig@mpi.nl<br />

If a M<strong>and</strong>arin speaker had walked past two rivers <strong>and</strong> wished to describe how many he had seen, he<br />

would have to say “two tiao river”, where tiao designates long, rope-like objects such as rivers,<br />

snakes <strong>and</strong> legs. Tiao is one of several hundred classifiers – a grammatical category in M<strong>and</strong>arin. In<br />

two eye-tracking studies we presented M<strong>and</strong>arin speakers with simple M<strong>and</strong>arin sentences through<br />

headphones while monitoring <strong>the</strong>ir eye-movements to objects presented on a computer monitor. The<br />

crucial question is what participants look at while listening to a pre-specified target noun. If classifier<br />

categories influence general conceptual processing <strong>the</strong>n on hearing <strong>the</strong> target noun participants should<br />

look at objects that are also members of <strong>the</strong> same classifier category – even when <strong>the</strong> classifier is not<br />

explicitly present. For example, on hearing scissors, M<strong>and</strong>arin speakers should look more at a picture<br />

of a chair than at an unrelated object because scissors <strong>and</strong> chair share <strong>the</strong> classifier ba. This would be<br />

consistent with a Strong Whorfian position, according to which language is a major determinant in<br />

shaping conceptual thought (Sapir, 1921; Whorf, 1956). A weaker influence of language-on-thought<br />

could be predicted, where language shapes cognitive processing, but only when <strong>the</strong> language-specific<br />

category is actively being processed (Slobin, 1996). According to this account, eye-movements are<br />

not necessarily drawn to chair when a participant hears scissors, but <strong>the</strong>y would be on hearing ba<br />

scissors. This is because hearing ba activates <strong>the</strong> linguistic category that both scissors <strong>and</strong> chair<br />

belong to. A third logical possibility is that classifiers are purely <strong>for</strong>mal markers (cf. Greenberg,<br />

1972; Lehman, 1979) that do not influence attentional processing even when <strong>the</strong>y are explicitly<br />

present.<br />

The data showed that when participants heard a spoken word from <strong>the</strong> same classifier category as a<br />

visually depicted object (e.g. scissors-chair), but <strong>the</strong> classifier was not explicitly presented in <strong>the</strong><br />

speech, overt attention to classifier-match objects (e.g. chair) <strong>and</strong> distractor objects did not differ<br />

(Experiment 1). But when <strong>the</strong> classifier was explicitly presented (e.g. ba, Experiment 2), participants<br />

shifted overt attention significantly more to classifier-match objects (e.g. chair) than to distractors.<br />

These data are incompatible with <strong>the</strong> Strong Whorfian hypo<strong>the</strong>sis. Instead <strong>the</strong> findings support <strong>the</strong><br />

Weak Whorfian hypo<strong>the</strong>sis that linguistic distinctions <strong>for</strong>ce attention to properties of <strong>the</strong> world but<br />

only during active linguistic processing of that distinction (cf. Slobin, 1996).<br />

Notes<br />

19


O3<br />

Sluicing <strong>and</strong> syntactic prediction in online sentence processing<br />

Masaya Yoshida 1 , Michael-Walsh Dickey 2 , & Patrick Sturt 1<br />

1 <strong>University</strong> of Edinburgh, UK, 2 <strong>University</strong> of Pittsburgh, USA<br />

E-mail: y-masaya@ta2.so-net.ne.jp<br />

Recent psycholinguistic studies have shown that <strong>the</strong> sentence processor is predictive ([1,2]).<br />

However, it has never been clear what exactly is predicted during realtime processing. This study<br />

investigates how much structure can be predicted in sentences like (1), <strong>and</strong> also investigates what<br />

types of structure are built online.<br />

(1)a. John sold some pictures, but I don't know which picture of himself.<br />

(1)b.*John sold some pictures, but I don't know which picture of himself Mary bought.<br />

The contrast in (1) suggests that an anaphor in wh-phrase can be bound by <strong>the</strong> subject in <strong>the</strong> first<br />

clause if <strong>the</strong> sentence involves a sluicing structure. Given that <strong>the</strong> anaphor requires a local antecedent,<br />

syntactic <strong>the</strong>ories suggest that <strong>the</strong>re is a hidden antecedent in <strong>the</strong> elided structure in sluicing ([3]).<br />

Taking advantage of this property, we investigate whe<strong>the</strong>r (i) <strong>the</strong> parser can recognize <strong>the</strong> possibility<br />

of sluicing <strong>and</strong> (ii) use <strong>the</strong> in<strong>for</strong>mation from <strong>the</strong> sluiced structure to establish a binding relation. 32<br />

participants read <strong>the</strong> sentences in (2a) <strong>and</strong> (2b), in a word-by-word moving window study.<br />

(2) Nicole’s fa<strong>the</strong>r heard several stories during <strong>the</strong> holiday party, but it's not clear<br />

a. which story of himself/herself from <strong>the</strong> party her gr<strong>and</strong>fa<strong>the</strong>r/gr<strong>and</strong>mo<strong>the</strong>r became so<br />

terribly upset over.<br />

b. over which story of himself/herself from <strong>the</strong> party her gr<strong>and</strong>fa<strong>the</strong>r/gr<strong>and</strong>mo<strong>the</strong>r<br />

became so terribly upset over.<br />

The gender of <strong>the</strong> anaphor <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> type of wh-phrase are manipulated as factors in <strong>the</strong> 2*2 design. If<br />

<strong>the</strong> parser predicts <strong>the</strong> upcoming sluicing structure upon encountering <strong>the</strong> wh-phrase, <strong>and</strong> if <strong>the</strong> parser<br />

tries to complete anaphor binding as soon as possible ([4,5,6]), <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> gender mismatched anaphor<br />

in (2a) should show a reading time slowdown, where a sluicing structure can potentially be <strong>the</strong><br />

continuation. On <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r h<strong>and</strong>, in (2b), <strong>the</strong>re is no possibility of sluicing because of <strong>the</strong> prepositional<br />

wh-phrase, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>re<strong>for</strong>e no such slowdown is expected. We found that <strong>the</strong> word immediately<br />

following <strong>the</strong> anaphor exhibits <strong>the</strong> interaction of wh-type <strong>and</strong> gender (p's


The interaction between discourse constraints <strong>and</strong> gender agreement in<br />

lexical <strong>and</strong> stereotypical role nouns: Evidence from ERP<br />

O4<br />

Hamutal Kreiner 1 , Sibylle Mohr 2 , Klaus Kessler 2 , & Simon Garrod 2<br />

1 <strong>University</strong> of Edinburgh,UK, 2 <strong>University</strong> of Glasgow, UK<br />

E-mail: hamutal@psy.gla.ac.uk<br />

When anaphors (herself) refer to antecedents (minister) that mismatch in gender [a] readers<br />

experience processing difficulty as shown in both eye-tracking (ET) (Sturt, 2003) <strong>and</strong> ERP<br />

(Osterhout, Bersick & McLaughlin, 1997) studies. In a recent ET study Kreiner, Sturt & Garrod<br />

(2008) used anaphora [a] <strong>and</strong> cataphora [b] sentences to contrast definitional nouns (king) in which<br />

gender is recovered from <strong>the</strong> lexicon with stereotypical nouns (minister) where gender is inferred<br />

from discourse or world knowledge (Carreiras, Garnham, Oakhill & Cain, 1996). The findings show<br />

that in cataphora [b], where a gender-marked reflexive precedes its co-referential noun, <strong>the</strong> mismatchcost<br />

<strong>for</strong> stereotypical gender is eliminated, suggesting that unlike definitional-gender stereotypical<br />

gender is susceptible to discourse constraints. This dissociation seems inconsistent with previous<br />

findings showing similar ERP (P600) effects <strong>for</strong> both noun types, suggesting a syntactic ra<strong>the</strong>r than<br />

discourse clash between <strong>the</strong> pronoun <strong>and</strong> antecedent in anaphora (Osterhout et al, 1997).<br />

[a] Yesterday <strong>the</strong> KING (MINISTER) left London after reminding HIMSELF (HERSELF) about <strong>the</strong><br />

letter.<br />

[b] After reminding HIMSELF (HERSELF) about <strong>the</strong> letter, <strong>the</strong> KING (MINISTER) immediately<br />

went to <strong>the</strong> meeting.<br />

We investigated this seeming discrepancy in two EEG experiments contrasting definitional <strong>and</strong><br />

stereotypical gender in anaphora (Exp. 1) <strong>and</strong> cataphora (Exp.2). Consistent with previous ERP<br />

findings, anaphora sentences show a reliable mismatch effect <strong>for</strong> both types of antecedent nouns with<br />

a positive pick at 600 ms from <strong>the</strong> pronoun onset. The cataphora sentences show a smaller mismatch<br />

effect only <strong>for</strong> definitional gender. We interpret <strong>the</strong>se differences in terms of <strong>the</strong> interface between<br />

grammatical gender agreement <strong>and</strong> discourse constraints. While anaphora <strong>and</strong> cataphora are similar in<br />

terms of <strong>the</strong> gender agreement constraints, <strong>the</strong>y critically differ in terms of discourse constraints. In<br />

anaphora [a] <strong>the</strong> gender of <strong>the</strong> discourse character is determined when <strong>the</strong> role noun is encountered<br />

based on <strong>the</strong> lexical or stereotypical gender in<strong>for</strong>mation associated with it, <strong>and</strong> this leads to <strong>the</strong> gender<br />

clash when a mismatching pronoun is subsequently encountered. In contrast, in cataphora [b] <strong>the</strong><br />

gender of <strong>the</strong> discourse character is determined by <strong>the</strong> pronoun be<strong>for</strong>e <strong>the</strong> role noun is encountered;<br />

as stereotypical gender may be inferred from <strong>the</strong> discourse <strong>the</strong> gender clash is prevented. The findings<br />

will be discussed in view of recent models of language related EEG findings <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> underlying<br />

processes associated with <strong>the</strong>m.<br />

Notes<br />

21


O5<br />

Investigating <strong>the</strong> automaticity of predicting deception in a <strong>the</strong>ory of<br />

mind task<br />

Hea<strong>the</strong>r J. Ferguson, & Richard Breheny<br />

<strong>University</strong> College London, UK<br />

E-mail: h.ferguson@ucl.ac.uk<br />

The ability to underst<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> predict o<strong>the</strong>r peoples’ behaviour by attributing independent mental<br />

states to <strong>the</strong>m is commonly referred to as <strong>the</strong>ory of mind (ToM). Several <strong>the</strong>orists have argued that<br />

inferences about o<strong>the</strong>rs’ beliefs are made automatically during language processing (1,2). However,<br />

this view is limited due to a lack of experimental research into <strong>the</strong> on-line processes involved in<br />

representing o<strong>the</strong>rs’ beliefs. Indeed, a recent false belief reaction time study (3) provided evidence<br />

against an automatic ToM processor since comprehenders showed increased response times to belief<br />

compared to reality probe questions only when <strong>the</strong>y were not explicitly instructed to track <strong>the</strong><br />

person’s beliefs. However, reaction time methods such as this only provide a limited insight into <strong>the</strong><br />

time course of language processing. There<strong>for</strong>e, <strong>the</strong> issue we examined was how <strong>the</strong> beliefs of o<strong>the</strong>rs<br />

are processed on-line as <strong>the</strong> current sentence is unfolding.<br />

Here we report a visual world study investigating <strong>the</strong> time-course of language-mediated eye<br />

movements towards objects in a scene within contexts that set up ‘reality’ [1a] <strong>and</strong> ‘secret’ [1b]<br />

scenarios. The critical second sentence [2] in each passage was presented aurally toge<strong>the</strong>r with a<br />

picture showing, amongst o<strong>the</strong>r things, a reality-consistent referent (pink car) <strong>and</strong> a secret-consistent<br />

referent (green car).<br />

[1a] John is always telling people that his favourite colour is pink.<br />

[1b] John doesn’t want anyone to know that his favourite colour is pink.<br />

[2] Last week John bought a new *car <strong>and</strong> he deliberately chose a [green/pink] car.<br />

Relative proportions of anticipatory eye-movements (i.e. eye-movements that started reliably be<strong>for</strong>e<br />

<strong>the</strong> onset of <strong>the</strong> target word “green” or “pink”) indicated a context-dependent bias towards <strong>the</strong><br />

appropriate referent from 1000msec prior to target word onset. Fur<strong>the</strong>r, examination of <strong>the</strong> effects<br />

revealed contextually-lead biases emerging from <strong>the</strong> first mention of <strong>the</strong> neutral referent (shown by *<br />

in [2]). These results demonstrate that readers quickly make use of in<strong>for</strong>mation about o<strong>the</strong>rs’ beliefs<br />

to interpret <strong>and</strong> predict o<strong>the</strong>r peoples’ subsequent actions. We discuss how <strong>the</strong>se results fit with<br />

previous accounts of ToM processing.<br />

References<br />

(1) Stone, V.E., Baron-Cohen, S., & Knight, R.T. (1998). Frontal lobe contributions to <strong>the</strong>ory of<br />

mind. J. Cogn. Neurosci., 10, 640-656.<br />

(2) Sperber, D. & Wilson, D. (2002). Pragmatics, modularity <strong>and</strong> mindreading. Mind & <strong>Language</strong>,<br />

17, 3-23.<br />

(3) Apperly, I.A., Riggs, K.J., Simpson, A., Samson, D., & Chiavarino, C. (2006). Is belief reasoning<br />

automatic Psych. Science, 17, 841-844.<br />

Notes<br />

22


O6<br />

Non-joint attention influences pronoun comprehension<br />

Jennifer E. Arnold, & Shin-Yi C. Lao<br />

<strong>University</strong> of North Carolina at Chapel Hill, USA<br />

E-mail: jarnold@email.unc.edu<br />

Pronoun comprehension is facilitated <strong>for</strong> referents that are “accessible.” Accessibility has been<br />

described in terms of attention (e.g., Brennan, 1995, LCP; Gundel et al., 1993, <strong>Language</strong>), but few<br />

studies have explicitly tested this idea. Reference can be directed by eye gaze, a social cue to joint<br />

attention (Hanna & Brennan, 2007, JML; Nappa & Arnold, AMLaP abstract). But internal attentional<br />

mechanisms are likely involved. We hypo<strong>the</strong>sized that even non-public cues to attention may<br />

modulate discourse cues to accessibility.<br />

Experiment 1. Listeners were eyetracked while listening to a story about two gender-matched<br />

characters (Birdy picked apples with Doggy…He was wearing a hat) <strong>and</strong> decided if it matched <strong>the</strong><br />

scene. The pronoun referred to ei<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> first (N1) or second (N2) character (depending on who had<br />

<strong>the</strong> hat in <strong>the</strong> scene). A capture cue attracted visual attention to <strong>the</strong> location of one character at trial<br />

onset. The design was thus 2 (N1 vs. N2 referent) by 2 (N1 vs. N2 cued). Participants did not notice<br />

<strong>the</strong> capture cue, so it was not a cue to joint attention.<br />

On 71% of trials <strong>the</strong> capture cue was effective (cued character fixated be<strong>for</strong>e <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r character<br />

within 1000 msec). On <strong>the</strong>se trials, we analyzed fixations following <strong>the</strong> pronoun <strong>and</strong> be<strong>for</strong>e <strong>the</strong><br />

disambiguating word (e.g., hat). Participants were more likely to fixate N1 than N2 in <strong>the</strong> ambiguous<br />

region, revealing <strong>the</strong> expected N1 bias (Arnold et al., 2000, Cognition). Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, <strong>the</strong> cued was<br />

fixated more than <strong>the</strong> noncued character. That is, visual attention at <strong>the</strong> trial onset influenced later<br />

pronoun interpretation preferences. In fact, actual initial attention guided post-pronoun fixations even<br />

when it went against <strong>the</strong> capture cue. In all analyses trials with target or competitor fixations at<br />

pronoun onset were excluded.<br />

Experiment 2. Attention at trial onset may be critical to adopting a perspective on <strong>the</strong> story. If so,<br />

trial-initial fixations might drive pronoun processing, regardless of <strong>the</strong> capture manipulation. The role<br />

of trial-initial attention was tested by placing a capture cue (a yellow flash) in <strong>the</strong> middle of <strong>the</strong> first<br />

sentence, ra<strong>the</strong>r than at trial onset. Fixations following <strong>the</strong> pronoun increased <strong>for</strong> initially-attended<br />

characters, regardless of <strong>the</strong> capture cue. All participants were aware of <strong>the</strong> capture cue, <strong>and</strong> yet <strong>the</strong><br />

relevant factor was <strong>the</strong> participants’ internal decisions about where to attend at trial onset.<br />

In sum, visual attention modulated on-line pronoun processing – even though visual attention was<br />

driven by egocentric preferences, not public, joint cues to attention.<br />

Notes<br />

23


O7<br />

Conversation, common ground <strong>and</strong> gaze coordination<br />

Daniel C. Richardson 1 , Rick Dale 2 , Natasha Z. Kirkham 3 , & Jack Tomlinson 4<br />

1 <strong>University</strong> of Reading, UK, 2 <strong>University</strong> of Memphis, USA<br />

3 CBCD, Birkbeck College, <strong>University</strong> of London, UK, 4 <strong>University</strong> of Cali<strong>for</strong>nia Santa Cruz, USA<br />

E-mail: dcr@eyethink.org<br />

When two people look at a shared visual scene <strong>and</strong> talk to each o<strong>the</strong>r, <strong>the</strong>ir gaze patterns are coupled<br />

(Richardson, Dale & Kirkham, 2007). The degree to which <strong>the</strong>ir eye movements are coordinated is<br />

causally related to <strong>the</strong> knowledge that <strong>the</strong>y share, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> degree to which <strong>the</strong>y underst<strong>and</strong> each o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

(Richardson & Dale, 2005). In this study, we examined <strong>the</strong> role of visual context in conversation <strong>and</strong><br />

gaze coordination. In a new paradigm, we separated <strong>the</strong> fact that a visual scene was shared or not <strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> belief that a visual scene was shared or not. We quantified <strong>the</strong> effects of <strong>the</strong>se factors upon joint<br />

attention by measuring <strong>the</strong> coordination between conversants’ eye movements. Participants had a<br />

conversation about a controversial topic, such as <strong>the</strong> Iraq war. The discussion was first framed by four<br />

short videos of actors espousing tendentious views. Participants discussed <strong>the</strong>ir own views while <strong>the</strong>y<br />

looked at ei<strong>the</strong>r a blank screen or pictures of <strong>the</strong> four actors. Each believed (correctly or not) that <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

partner was ei<strong>the</strong>r looking at a blank screen or <strong>the</strong> same images. We found that both <strong>the</strong> presence of<br />

<strong>the</strong> visual scene <strong>and</strong> beliefs about its presence <strong>for</strong> ano<strong>the</strong>r influenced participants’ discussion <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

coordination of <strong>the</strong>ir joint attention.<br />

Notes<br />

24


Seeing <strong>the</strong> world through a visual language: Visual world paradigm in<br />

British Sign <strong>Language</strong><br />

O8<br />

Robin L. Thompson 1 , David P. Vinson 1 , Michael Jin 2 , Martin J. Pickering 2 ,<br />

& Gabriella Vigliocco 1<br />

1 <strong>University</strong> College London, UK, 2 <strong>University</strong> of Edinburgh, UK<br />

E-mail: robin.thompson@ucl.ac.uk<br />

While processing spoken language, people look towards relevant objects in a visual scene, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

time course of <strong>the</strong>ir gaze(s) can in<strong>for</strong>m us about online language processing (Tanenhaus et al, 1995).<br />

For sign language users however, attention must be divided between contextual real-world clues <strong>and</strong><br />

visually perceived language input. We used eye-tracking to measure <strong>the</strong> time course of eye gaze<br />

during sign language (BSL) processing. While a visual world paradigm has shown that people rapidly<br />

exploit linguistic <strong>and</strong> non-linguistic in<strong>for</strong>mation during spoken utterance comprehension (Huettig &<br />

Altmann, 2005), we ask to what extent division of ‘visual labor’ during BSL input might alter <strong>the</strong><br />

time course <strong>and</strong> nature of language processing when a visually-presented sign is displayed with a<br />

visual world. Subjects viewed scenes with pictures of objects <strong>and</strong> were asked to indicate whe<strong>the</strong>r a<br />

BSL sign (presented in <strong>the</strong> center of <strong>the</strong> screen) matched one of four pictures by pushing a button (yes<br />

or no). In each trial, one picture was related to <strong>the</strong> sign, ei<strong>the</strong>r semantically (e.g. target: cow,<br />

distracter: rat) or phonologically (e.g. target: radio, distracter: clown; BSL minimal pairs differing in<br />

location). On ‘yes’ trials, a picture matching <strong>the</strong> sign <strong>and</strong> 2 unrelated pictures also appeared. ‘No’<br />

trials contained 3 unrelated pictures with <strong>the</strong> related distracter. Overall, sign perceivers were adept at<br />

dividing attention between visual <strong>and</strong> language input, looking at <strong>the</strong> signer 46% <strong>and</strong> making decisions<br />

an average of 328ms after <strong>the</strong> offset of <strong>the</strong> video. In <strong>the</strong> no condition gaze was more often toward <strong>the</strong><br />

related distracter. When a semantically related distracter was present in a yes trial, gaze was<br />

significantly more often directed toward it than unrelated distracters. For phonological distracters<br />

gaze was more frequently towards minimal pairs differing in movement features, but not more often<br />

<strong>for</strong> pairs differing along h<strong>and</strong>shape or location features. The findings have important methodological<br />

<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>oretical implications. Methodologically, <strong>the</strong>y reveal split visual attention (needed <strong>for</strong> online<br />

sign language processing) permits use of visual world paradigms to investigate <strong>the</strong> time course of sign<br />

language processing despite <strong>the</strong> m<strong>and</strong>atory presence of a visual linguistic stimulus. Theoretically,<br />

<strong>the</strong>y reveal important aspects of lexical access, concerning <strong>the</strong> role of lexical variables (semantic<br />

condition) <strong>and</strong> relative time course of access to different phonological parameters (phonological<br />

condition). We discuss <strong>the</strong>se results in <strong>the</strong> context of language processing in different modalities.<br />

Notes<br />

25


O9<br />

Are non-lexical transitions between signs a segmentation cue in British<br />

Sign <strong>Language</strong><br />

Eleni Orfanidou 1 , Robert Adam 1 , & James M. McQueen 2<br />

1 <strong>University</strong> College London <strong>and</strong> City <strong>University</strong> London, UK,<br />

2 Max Planck Institute <strong>for</strong> Psycholinguistics, Nijmegen, The Ne<strong>the</strong>rl<strong>and</strong>s<br />

E-mail: e.orfanidou@ucl.ac.uk<br />

A substantial body of research has examined segmentation in speech comprehension, that is, how<br />

listeners recognize words in continuous speech. Less is known about sign-language segmentation. A<br />

modality-specific feature of signed languages is that, during continuous signing, <strong>the</strong>re are transitions<br />

between <strong>the</strong> locations in space <strong>and</strong> on <strong>the</strong> body where signs are articulated. These non-lexical<br />

transitions are not part of <strong>the</strong> signs <strong>the</strong>mselves. We asked here if British Sign <strong>Language</strong> (BSL)<br />

comprehenders use non-lexical transitions to segment continuous BSL.<br />

We used <strong>the</strong> sign-spotting task, based on <strong>the</strong> word-spotting task (Cutler & Norris, 1988). Ninety-six<br />

BSL signs were each preceded by a nonsense sign, articulated ei<strong>the</strong>r in <strong>the</strong> same location as <strong>the</strong> real<br />

sign, or involving a small or large transition to ano<strong>the</strong>r location. Half of <strong>the</strong> transitions of each type<br />

were within <strong>the</strong> same major body area/location (e.g. head) <strong>and</strong> half were across body areas/locations.<br />

Participants were asked to press a button as fast as possible when <strong>the</strong>y spotted real BSL signs. If<br />

signers use <strong>the</strong> non-lexical transitions between signs as segmentation cues, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong>y should be faster<br />

to detect signs when a transition is present. But if signers are sensitive to location-based lexical<br />

constraints, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong>y should be faster to detect signs when both <strong>the</strong> nonsense <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> real sign are<br />

articulated in <strong>the</strong> same location (i.e. <strong>the</strong>y might consider only <strong>the</strong> “cohort” of signs beginning in that<br />

location).<br />

Twenty-three Deaf adult native BSL signers <strong>and</strong> sixteen Deaf adult nonnative signers were<br />

significantly faster <strong>and</strong> more accurate to detect target signs when <strong>the</strong>re was no location transition<br />

between <strong>the</strong> nonsense sign <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> real sign than when <strong>the</strong>re was. When a transition was present,<br />

however, both groups per<strong>for</strong>med better when transitions were to a different body area than when <strong>the</strong>y<br />

were within <strong>the</strong> same area. This effect was larger <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> nonnative group. There were also additive<br />

effects of <strong>the</strong> size <strong>and</strong> type of transition <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> nonnative group.<br />

These results suggest that sign segmentation does not depend on boundaries cued by non-lexical<br />

transitions. Similar to spoken language, segmentation is guided by sublexical in<strong>for</strong>mation <strong>and</strong><br />

phonotactics. Sublexical location features appear to be used to narrow <strong>the</strong> lexical search space.<br />

Phonotactic constraints (e.g. a transition to a different location cannot occur within a single sign;<br />

Battison, 1978) are also used in sign segmentation, mainly by <strong>the</strong> nonnative group, consistent with<br />

previous results on <strong>the</strong> effects of age of acquisition in sign comprehension.<br />

Notes<br />

26


Effects of perceptual <strong>and</strong> cognitive loads on speech segmentation<br />

O10<br />

Sven L. Mattys 1 , & Martin Cooke 2<br />

1 <strong>University</strong> of Bristol, UK, 2 <strong>University</strong> of Sheffield, UK<br />

E-mail: sven.mattys@bris.ac.uk<br />

Listeners segment connected speech using both lexically- <strong>and</strong> acoustically-driven mechanisms. Here,<br />

we explored <strong>the</strong> effect of perceptual <strong>and</strong> cognitive loads on listeners' relative reliance on those two<br />

types of mechanisms. Phrases bearing a conflict between lexical <strong>and</strong> acoustic segmentation cues, e.g.,<br />

"mild option" realized as "mile doption," with <strong>the</strong> latter being lexically unacceptable, were played in a<br />

background of babble noise made of 8 talkers (N8) vs. 1 talker (N1). While both loads reduced<br />

segmentation accuracy, N8 babble led to greater reliance on acoustic than lexical cues. N1 babble did<br />

not. However, when <strong>the</strong> N1 babble was replaced with speech-modulated noise, which removes <strong>the</strong><br />

linguistic content of <strong>the</strong> babble while preserving its temporal intensity fluctuations <strong>and</strong> long-term<br />

spectral envelope, an acoustic bias appeared. Thus, <strong>the</strong> linguistic nature of a perceptual load affects<br />

<strong>the</strong> way in which a concurrent speech stream is segmented, with unintelligible background noise<br />

causing relatively greater reliance on acoustically-driven segmentation. When <strong>the</strong> target phrases <strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> N1 babble were played dichotically, listeners showed a lexical bias. A similar pattern was found<br />

when <strong>the</strong> cognitive load was mnemonic ra<strong>the</strong>r than attentional. Thus, cognitive loads cause listeners<br />

to <strong>for</strong>go acoustic details <strong>and</strong> rely more heavily on lexical knowledge.<br />

These findings show that: (1) speech segmentation is penetrable by perceptual <strong>and</strong> cognitive loads,<br />

(2) perceptual loads favor acoustically-driven segmentation unless <strong>the</strong> load is intelligible, in which<br />

case attention is re-directed to lexical processes, (3) cognitive loads favor lexically-driven<br />

segmentation. The acoustic bias under perceptual load suggests that failure to identify component<br />

words in <strong>the</strong> stream causes listeners to fall back on juncture-relevant acoustic cues peeking through<br />

<strong>the</strong> babble. The modulation of this bias by <strong>the</strong> intelligibility of <strong>the</strong> load indicates that <strong>the</strong> effect of<br />

perceptual load is not entirely signal-driven or due to energetic masking. Instead, <strong>the</strong> in<strong>for</strong>mational<br />

content of <strong>the</strong> load can direct attention to acoustic vs. lexical features of <strong>the</strong> signal. Finally, <strong>the</strong> lexical<br />

bias under cognitive load is in line with research showing that, in case of conflict between<br />

segmentation cues, listeners assign greater weight to those that have communicative value, e.g.,<br />

lexical knowledge <strong>and</strong> syntactic-semantic inferences. These findings constitute <strong>the</strong> first attempt to<br />

link speech segmentation to general cognition <strong>and</strong>, in doing so, to bring speech-segmentation models<br />

closer to ecological validity.<br />

Notes<br />

27


O11<br />

Speaking rate affects <strong>the</strong> perception of word boundaries in online word<br />

recognition<br />

Eva Reinisch, Alex<strong>and</strong>ra Jesse, & James M. McQueen<br />

Max Planck Institute <strong>for</strong> Psycholinguistics, Nijmegen, The Ne<strong>the</strong>rl<strong>and</strong>s<br />

E-mail: Eva.Reinisch@mpi.nl<br />

The perception of durational cues in speech depends on speaking rate (e.g. Repp et al. 1978). But<br />

most studies have used offline categorization or goodness rating tasks to demonstrate this effect.<br />

Durational cues, however, are also used in online word recognition. For example, given <strong>the</strong> Dutch<br />

sequence eens peer ("once peach"), <strong>the</strong> extent to which an [s]-initial word spuit ("syringe") competes<br />

<strong>for</strong> recognition with <strong>the</strong> target peer depends on <strong>the</strong> duration of <strong>the</strong> [s] (Shatzman & McQueen 2006).<br />

The longer <strong>the</strong> [s], <strong>the</strong> more it sounds word initial, so <strong>the</strong> stronger <strong>the</strong> competition is. Since <strong>the</strong><br />

perceived duration of sounds depends on <strong>the</strong> speaking rate of <strong>the</strong> preceding context, we predicted that<br />

speaking rate would affect online word recognition, specifically, that <strong>the</strong> rate of a carrier sentence<br />

would affect <strong>the</strong> strength of a target word’s competitors.<br />

This prediction was addressed using eye tracking. In Experiment 1, Dutch listeners' looks to four<br />

printed words were tracked as <strong>the</strong>y listened to sentences of <strong>the</strong> type Ze heeft wel eens peer gezegd<br />

("She once said peach"). Listeners had to click on <strong>the</strong> target word (peer). The display consisted of <strong>the</strong><br />

target, an [s]-initial competitor (e.g., speen, "pacifier"), <strong>and</strong> two phonologically unrelated distractors.<br />

The critical [s] was set to a duration that was ambiguous between whe<strong>the</strong>r or not <strong>the</strong> second word of<br />

<strong>the</strong> phrase started with an [s]. Listeners looked more at [s]-initial competitors when targets followed<br />

fast carrier sentences than when targets followed slow carriers. Correspondingly, <strong>the</strong>y tended to look<br />

earlier at targets in slow than in fast contexts. They thus apparently perceived <strong>the</strong> [s] as being longer<br />

when <strong>the</strong> preceding context was faster, leading to more competition from <strong>the</strong> [s]-initial word. As<br />

predicted, <strong>the</strong> pattern of results reversed when <strong>the</strong> target was [s]-initial (e.g., schade, "harm") but <strong>the</strong><br />

competitor was not (e.g., chaos, "chaos"). Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, <strong>the</strong>se rate effects were not dependent on<br />

whe<strong>the</strong>r targets were members of minimal pairs such as eens (s)peer ("once peach/spear").<br />

In Experiment 2, similar effects of speaking rate in online word recognition were found <strong>for</strong> ano<strong>the</strong>r<br />

durational boundary cue (stop closure duration in ambiguous sequences such as nooit (t)aal, "never<br />

language/eel"). Both experiments show that lexical competition, <strong>and</strong> hence <strong>the</strong> perception of word<br />

boundaries, is modulated by fine-grained phonetic in<strong>for</strong>mation. Critically, <strong>the</strong>y show that durational<br />

in<strong>for</strong>mation does not provide absolute cues to word boundaries but instead is perceived relative to <strong>the</strong><br />

phonetic context in which it appears.<br />

Notes<br />

28


O12<br />

The perception of assimilation in newly learned novel words<br />

Natalie D. Snoeren 1 , Gareth Gaskell 2 , & Anna Maria Di Betta 3<br />

1 LIMSI-CNRS, Orsay, France, 2 <strong>University</strong> of York, UK, 3 <strong>University</strong> of Sheffield,UK<br />

E-mail: ndsnoeren@gmail.com<br />

How listeners recognize spoken words in spite of regular variations in <strong>the</strong> speech signal has been a<br />

major research question in <strong>the</strong> psycholinguistic study of speech perception over <strong>the</strong> past decade.<br />

Uncertainty remains over <strong>the</strong> extent to which compensation <strong>for</strong> assimilation depends on lexical<br />

knowledge, largely because most comparisons between words <strong>and</strong> nonwords may involve a confound<br />

with articulatory factors. In <strong>the</strong> present study, we investigated levels of perceptual processing in<br />

compensation <strong>for</strong> assimilation using two sets of novel words learned on consecutive days. This kind<br />

of design avoid potential confounds by manipulating lexical status within <strong>the</strong> same physical stimuli.<br />

Exposure took place through a phoneme decision task in which <strong>the</strong> isolated canonical spoken <strong>for</strong>m of<br />

novel words (e.g., decibot) was presented repeatedly. In a subsequent phoneme monitoring test,<br />

participants were asked to monitor <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> underlying word-final phoneme of an assimilated novel<br />

word. Here, <strong>the</strong> novel words were presented with word-final alternations (e.g., decibop) in carrier<br />

sentences that ei<strong>the</strong>r licensed assimilation (viable context: Our decibop behaved badly) or did not<br />

(unviable context: Our decibop does very well). For instance, a participant might have to monitor <strong>for</strong><br />

/t/ in a sentence like Our decibop behaved badly, where /t/ in decibop is present only in <strong>the</strong> underlying<br />

representation generated from <strong>the</strong> labial surface <strong>for</strong>m /p/. In order to respond, <strong>the</strong> listener must infer a<br />

coronal place of articulation, possibly making use of lexical <strong>and</strong>/or contextual in<strong>for</strong>mation. Response<br />

proportions to <strong>the</strong> underlying <strong>for</strong>m (e.g., /t/) showed that targets provoked more responses<br />

corresponding to <strong>the</strong> underlying <strong>for</strong>m in viable than in unviable contexts. This viability effect was<br />

equivalent <strong>for</strong> novel words learned on <strong>the</strong> same day <strong>and</strong> on <strong>the</strong> previous day, but crucially was absent<br />

<strong>for</strong> unexposed control items, demonstrating <strong>the</strong> importance of lexical knowledge in compensation <strong>for</strong><br />

assimilation. Additionally, analyses of RTs showed a main effect of learning, with overall faster<br />

reaction times to novel words learned on <strong>the</strong> previous day than on <strong>the</strong> day of testing, suggesting a<br />

sleep-consolidated lexicalization. The processing difference between exposed <strong>and</strong> control novel<br />

words supports <strong>the</strong> idea that listeners can compensate <strong>for</strong> assimilation in novel words <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>re<strong>for</strong>e<br />

suggest that listeners perceive newly acquired speech at a more abstract level. These results can be<br />

accounted <strong>for</strong> by hybrid episodic/abstractionist models of speech perception, plus a two component<br />

process of lexicalization.<br />

Notes<br />

29


O13<br />

Senior moments <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> brain: Convergent measures <strong>and</strong> an<br />

aging network<br />

Meredith A. Shafto, Emmanuel A. Stamatakis, Phyllis P. Tam, & Lorraine K. Tyler<br />

<strong>University</strong> of Cambridge, UK<br />

E-mail: mshafto@csl.psychol.cam.ac.uk<br />

One of <strong>the</strong> best-documented findings from language research with older adults is an increase in wordfinding<br />

problems, perhaps most clearly observed in <strong>the</strong>ir increasingly frequent tip-of-<strong>the</strong>-tongue states<br />

(TOTs) - temporary inabilities to retrieve a familiar name. Behavioral data localize <strong>the</strong> cause of TOTs<br />

to deficits retrieving <strong>the</strong> phonology of words, deficits which increase in old age (e.g., Burke & Shafto,<br />

2004).<br />

However, <strong>the</strong> neural underpinnings of this age effect have not been examined, despite <strong>the</strong> finding that<br />

normal aging is accompanied by wide-ranging loss of grey <strong>and</strong> white matter in regions that are<br />

important <strong>for</strong> language processing.<br />

We address this issue in an ongoing program of research using converging neuroimaging <strong>and</strong><br />

behavioural methods. Our results demonstrate that normal aging does not fundamentally affect <strong>the</strong><br />

network of brain regions underpinning language production. Instead, grey <strong>and</strong> white matter loss in old<br />

age appears to affect older adults’ ability to regulate this network to prevent or overcome retrieval<br />

failures.<br />

Evidence that grey matter loss underpins word finding failures comes from a study correlating<br />

increasing TOTs across <strong>the</strong> lifespan with decreasing grey matter in left insula, a region important <strong>for</strong><br />

phonological retrieval (Shafto et al., 2007). A follow-up fMRI study (Shafto et al., submitted)<br />

demonstrates that during TOTs compared to successful naming, younger adults generate a “boost” of<br />

activity in <strong>the</strong> left insula. Older adults do not generate a significant activity boost during TOTs,<br />

indicating that older adults’ grey matter loss impairs <strong>the</strong>ir ability to modulate activity levels during<br />

difficult word retrieval. This modulation requires interaction between brain regions involved in<br />

language production, which are connected by white matter tracts. The importance of white matter<br />

connections during word retrieval is demonstrated using Diffusion Tensor Imaging (DTI): age-related<br />

increases in TOT rates are associated with deteriorating white matter integrity in a region of <strong>the</strong><br />

superior longitudinal fasciculus, a structure important <strong>for</strong> connecting regions involved in processing<br />

language (Stamatakis et al., submitted). This finding indicates that white matter deterioration in old<br />

age may affect <strong>the</strong> ability of different language regions to interact with each o<strong>the</strong>r. This possibility is<br />

tested using magnetoencephalography (MEG), a technique which provides fine-grained time course<br />

in<strong>for</strong>mation about <strong>the</strong> activation of regions in <strong>the</strong> language network during successful <strong>and</strong> failed<br />

retrieval.<br />

Notes<br />

30


O14<br />

Interaction <strong>and</strong> interactivity in language production<br />

Robert J. Hartsuiker 1 , & Ines Anton-Mendez 2<br />

1 Ghent <strong>University</strong>, Belgium, 2 Utrecht <strong>University</strong>, The Ne<strong>the</strong>rl<strong>and</strong>s<br />

E-mail: Robert.Hartsuiker@ugent.be<br />

Theories of language production differ in <strong>the</strong>ir assumptions about <strong>the</strong> in<strong>for</strong>mation flow between<br />

levels. The marking <strong>and</strong> morphing model of <strong>the</strong> production of subject-verb number agreement<br />

(Eberhard, Cutting, & Bock, 2005) assumes a serial in<strong>for</strong>mation flow, with conceptual factors<br />

affecting one level, <strong>and</strong> morphophonological factors affecting a subsequent level. In contrast,<br />

interactive models allow meaning-based <strong>and</strong> <strong>for</strong>m-based processes to interact. This study asks<br />

whe<strong>the</strong>r (a) meaning-based <strong>and</strong> <strong>for</strong>m-based processes have additive or non-additive effects on<br />

proportions of agreement errors; (b) <strong>the</strong> results are consistent with serial models of agreement<br />

production.<br />

A sentence-completion experiment elicited subject-verb agreement errors in Dutch. We varied<br />

notional number of <strong>the</strong> subject NP <strong>and</strong> number-ambiguity of <strong>the</strong> head noun’s determiner. We<br />

operationalized notional number by presenting distributed (1a -1b) or non-distributed phrases (2a –<br />

2b); in distributed phrases, “ashtray” (“menu”) is notionally plural, because <strong>the</strong>re is an ashtray (menu)<br />

on each of several tables. Number ambiguity was varied by presenting singular subject head nouns<br />

with common-gender (which take <strong>the</strong> number-ambiguous determiner “de” in Dutch (1a <strong>and</strong> 2a) or<br />

with neuter-gender (which take <strong>the</strong> number-unambiguous determiner “het” (1b <strong>and</strong> 2b).<br />

(1a)<br />

(1b)<br />

(2a)<br />

(2b)<br />

De asbak op de tafels (<strong>the</strong> ashtray on <strong>the</strong> tables)<br />

Het menu op de tafels (<strong>the</strong> menu on <strong>the</strong> tables)<br />

De boot van de vissers (<strong>the</strong> boat of <strong>the</strong> fishermen)<br />

Het schip van de vissers (<strong>the</strong> ship of <strong>the</strong> fishermen)<br />

Agreement occurred more frequently in <strong>the</strong> distributive than <strong>the</strong> non-distributive condition, <strong>and</strong> more<br />

frequently in <strong>the</strong> number-ambiguous than in <strong>the</strong> number-unambiguous condition. These factors<br />

interacted, with an overadditive number of errors in <strong>the</strong> distributive, number-ambiguous condition. In<br />

principle, <strong>the</strong>se results would seem to support interactive models of language production.<br />

Next, we report simulations with a Dutch implementation of <strong>the</strong> marking <strong>and</strong> morphing model, which<br />

we validated on earlier Dutch data. Although <strong>the</strong> model is serial, <strong>and</strong> thus predicts additive effects of<br />

our manipulations on underlying number specifications, it provided an excellent fit with our data.<br />

This is so because <strong>the</strong> model assumes a non-linear mapping rule between mental representations (of<br />

plurality) <strong>and</strong> overt behaviors (proportions of verbs that are plural). Our study, <strong>the</strong>re<strong>for</strong>e,<br />

demonstrates <strong>the</strong> danger of using additive-factors logic to arbitrate between serial <strong>and</strong> interactive<br />

models of language production. Interactions don’t prove interactivity.<br />

Notes<br />

31


O15<br />

Determinants of function assignment in language production: Is conceptual<br />

accessibility enough<br />

Mirta Vernice 1 , & Robert J. Hartsuiker 2<br />

1 <strong>University</strong> of Pavia, Italy, 2 Ghent <strong>University</strong>, Belgium<br />

E-mail: mirta.vernice@unipv.it<br />

Studies on language production suggest that speakers tend to assign <strong>the</strong> highest syntactic role to <strong>the</strong><br />

element with <strong>the</strong> highest conceptual accessibility (Bock, 1985). An event with an animate agent <strong>and</strong><br />

an inanimate patient should elicit more actives than ano<strong>the</strong>r with inanimate agent <strong>and</strong> animate patient,<br />

because <strong>the</strong> more accessible (animate) element is more likely to win <strong>the</strong> competition <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> subject<br />

slot. The implication tested here is that events with agents <strong>and</strong> patients of <strong>the</strong> same animacy (both<br />

animate or inanimate) should elicit comparable numbers of actives, because in nei<strong>the</strong>r of <strong>the</strong>se cases<br />

is <strong>the</strong> competition <strong>for</strong> subject slot influenced by a difference in <strong>the</strong> animacy of agent <strong>and</strong> patient.<br />

We conducted five picture naming experiments on 200 Italian speakers. We orthogonally manipulated<br />

<strong>the</strong> animacy of agent <strong>and</strong> patient, leading to four between-item conditions. The baseline preference<br />

<strong>for</strong> active vs. passive was manipulated between-subjects using syntactic priming. Prime sentences<br />

were presented ei<strong>the</strong>r interspersed with <strong>the</strong> critical pictures (short-term priming) or in a separate block<br />

be<strong>for</strong>e <strong>the</strong> experiment (long-term priming). To control <strong>for</strong> differences in verb bias or in saliency of<br />

<strong>the</strong> elements, we analyzed a subset of 32 (out of 72) targets that were matched on <strong>the</strong>se variables.<br />

The experiments showed clear effects of priming. Targets with animate agents <strong>and</strong> inanimate patients<br />

elicited more actives than those with inanimate agents <strong>and</strong> animate patients. The proportion of actives<br />

was higher when agent <strong>and</strong> patient were both animate than when both were inanimate. This difference<br />

was 21% in <strong>the</strong> condition with no syntactic priming, 8% with short-term active priming, 15% with<br />

short-term passive priming, 4% with long-term active priming, <strong>and</strong> 19% with long-term passive<br />

priming. Importantly, <strong>the</strong> animacy of <strong>the</strong> agent is a more potent determinant of structural choice than<br />

<strong>the</strong> animacy of <strong>the</strong> patient.<br />

We simulated <strong>the</strong>se data with a ma<strong>the</strong>matical model that computes active proportions as a function of<br />

(1) general bias <strong>for</strong> active; (2) changes to this bias from priming; (3) changes to this bias from<br />

differences in agent/patient accessibility (i.e., animacy). Model fit improved when a fur<strong>the</strong>r parameter<br />

was included, which specified a preference to assign subjecthood to animate agents.<br />

We suggest that a full account of function assignment needs to consider conceptual accessibility of<br />

<strong>the</strong> elements participating in <strong>the</strong> event, but also <strong>the</strong>ir <strong>the</strong>matic role status. More accessible elements<br />

tend to become subjects, but this effect is enhanced when this element is an agent.<br />

Notes<br />

32


The perceptual span during regressions in garden path sentences<br />

O16<br />

Jens Apel, John M. Henderson, & Fern<strong>and</strong>a Ferreira<br />

<strong>University</strong> of Edinburgh, UK<br />

E-mail: J.Apel@sms.ed.ac.uk<br />

The perceptual span during normal reading extends approximately 12-15 characters to <strong>the</strong> right <strong>and</strong> 3-<br />

4 characters to <strong>the</strong> left of a current fixation. In <strong>the</strong> present study we investigate whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> perceptual<br />

span <strong>for</strong> regressions is asymmetric to <strong>the</strong> left. We used a contingent display-change paradigm to<br />

investigate whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> perceptual span extends to <strong>the</strong> left right be<strong>for</strong>e (<strong>and</strong> presumably during) a<br />

regression. We also sought to examine <strong>the</strong> scan patterns <strong>for</strong> regressions made during <strong>the</strong> reading of<br />

garden path sentences.<br />

In <strong>the</strong> current experiment, when <strong>the</strong> region beyond <strong>the</strong> 4th character (associated with <strong>the</strong> normal<br />

reading span) of <strong>the</strong> breakdown region (BR) (region in brackets in 1-4) was fixated, material to <strong>the</strong><br />

left was ei<strong>the</strong>r changed or left intact. In condition (1), <strong>the</strong> word immediately to <strong>the</strong> left of <strong>the</strong> BR<br />

changed to incorrect characters; in condition (2), <strong>the</strong> second word left of <strong>the</strong> BR was changed; in (3),<br />

both were altered; <strong>and</strong> in (4), nei<strong>the</strong>r was changed, providing <strong>the</strong> baseline condition. We also assessed<br />

whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> changes affect <strong>for</strong>ward as well as backwards eye movements; <strong>the</strong> prediction is that <strong>the</strong>y<br />

will only affect regressions, because only movements to <strong>the</strong> left should be affected by manipulations<br />

to material left of fixation.<br />

1. While <strong>the</strong> motorist parked <strong>the</strong> lorry that was so cvlzq cat[apulted] along <strong>the</strong> high street.<br />

2. … was zv noisy cat[apulted] …<br />

3. … was zv cvlzq cat[apulted]…<br />

4. … was so noisy cat[apulted] …<br />

We found significantly shorter regressive saccades in conditions 1 <strong>and</strong> 3 (ps < .01) in comparison to<br />

condition 4. Forward saccades were entirely unaffected by <strong>the</strong> manipulations. There<strong>for</strong>e, we conclude<br />

that <strong>the</strong> perceptual span during reading changes depending on <strong>the</strong> direction of <strong>the</strong> eye movements. If<br />

people are about to move left because <strong>the</strong>y have programmed a regression, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> left side of <strong>the</strong><br />

perceptual span exp<strong>and</strong>s. In addition, we replicated a finding we reported earlier that most regressions<br />

are no more than one word to <strong>the</strong> left, so that any syntactically critical region must be reached via<br />

successive regressive sweeps. The pattern of data as a whole suggests that regressions made during<br />

<strong>the</strong> reanalysis of garden-path sentences are typically short <strong>and</strong> not intelligently targeted, but <strong>the</strong>y are<br />

programmed on <strong>the</strong> basis of preview in<strong>for</strong>mation obtained from a directionally flexible perceptual<br />

span.<br />

Notes<br />

33


O17<br />

Eye movements reflect comprehenders' knowledge of syntactic<br />

structure probability<br />

Harry Tily 2 , Barbara Hem<strong>for</strong>th 1 , Inbal Arnon 2 , Noa Shuval 1 , Neal Snider 2 , & Tom Wasow 2<br />

1 CNRS, Université Paris Descartes, France, 2 Stan<strong>for</strong>d <strong>University</strong>, USA<br />

E-mail: barbara.hem<strong>for</strong>th@univ-paris5.fr<br />

<strong>Language</strong> comprehension is guided by expectation. In this study we show that verb bias influences<br />

listeners’ expectations about upcoming referents. We look at <strong>the</strong> dative alternation:<br />

1. The nurse will feed <strong>the</strong> soup to <strong>the</strong> patient DO-bias, PO realization<br />

2. The nurse will feed <strong>the</strong> patient <strong>the</strong> soup DO-bias, DO realization<br />

3. The nurse will bring <strong>the</strong> soup to <strong>the</strong> patient PO-bias, PO realization<br />

4. The nurse will bring <strong>the</strong> patient <strong>the</strong> soup PO-bias, DO realization<br />

We used Bresnan & al.’s (2007) model of <strong>the</strong> dative in spontaneous conversational speech to<br />

determine <strong>the</strong> syntactic bias of dative verbs toward <strong>the</strong> PO construction: <strong>the</strong> model's Best Linear<br />

Unbiased Predictors estimate <strong>the</strong> bias of <strong>the</strong> verb, while regressing out <strong>the</strong> effects of all of <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

contextual factors on construction choice. Using this estimate of verb bias, we chose 7 verbs that were<br />

biased towards PO, <strong>and</strong> 7 verbs that were biased towards DO. These verbs were paired to allow <strong>the</strong><br />

construction of sentences like (1) <strong>and</strong> (3) or (2) <strong>and</strong> (4) which only differ in <strong>the</strong> bias of <strong>the</strong> verb.<br />

Using each verb twice, we constructed 28 items, each with an inanimate patient <strong>and</strong> an animate<br />

recipient. We registered 18 participants’ fixations on three objects corresponding to <strong>the</strong> subject<br />

(nurse) <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> two arguments (soup <strong>and</strong> patient) while <strong>the</strong>y listened to <strong>the</strong> sentences (see Altmann &<br />

Kamide, 1999). We removed prosodic cues to realization by using a subject <strong>and</strong> verb spliced from a<br />

DO recording in half of <strong>the</strong> PO stimuli, <strong>and</strong> vice versa. If listener’s expectations reflect verb-bias,<br />

<strong>the</strong>y will fixate on <strong>the</strong> first argument faster (earlier) when verb-bias matches <strong>the</strong> realization (2 faster<br />

than 4, 3 faster than 1).<br />

The results showed <strong>the</strong> expected effect; in <strong>the</strong> given example, participants were faster to fixate <strong>the</strong><br />

first argument when <strong>the</strong> verb bias corresponded to <strong>the</strong> construction spoken (‘<strong>the</strong> soup’ when <strong>the</strong> verb<br />

was biased towards a PO realization, ‘<strong>the</strong> patient’ after DO-biased verbs) (ps


O18<br />

The use of verb-specific in<strong>for</strong>mation <strong>for</strong> prediction in sentence processing<br />

Manabu Arai, & Frank Keller<br />

<strong>University</strong> of Edinburgh, UK<br />

E-mail: manabu.arai@ed.ac.uk<br />

Recent research has shown that language comprehenders make predictions about upcoming linguistic<br />

in<strong>for</strong>mation using various sources of in<strong>for</strong>mation (Altmann & Kamide, Cognition 1999; Arai et al.,<br />

CogPsy 2007; Staub & Clifton, JEP 2006). An important question is whe<strong>the</strong>r lexically-specific<br />

in<strong>for</strong>mation can be used <strong>for</strong> prediction. Such a finding would support both constraint-based<br />

(MacDonald et al., PsyRev 1994) <strong>and</strong> probabilistic models of processing (Jurafsky, Cogsci 1996).<br />

We conducted two experiments to address this issue using <strong>the</strong> visual world paradigm. In Exp 1, we<br />

compared transitive verbs such as "scold" to intransitive verbs such as "shout" <strong>and</strong> examined whe<strong>the</strong>r<br />

<strong>the</strong> verb's subcategorization in<strong>for</strong>mation is used <strong>for</strong> predicting a direct object. Participants heard<br />

sentences such as (1) while looking at a picture that included a rugby player, a shop assistant, <strong>and</strong> a<br />

distractor. The results showed that participants looked more quickly <strong>and</strong> frequently at <strong>the</strong> direct object<br />

picture (i.e., <strong>the</strong> shop assistant) while <strong>the</strong>y heard "scolded" in (1a), compared to "shouted" in (1b).<br />

This indicates that <strong>the</strong>y predicted an upcoming direct object <strong>for</strong> transitive verbs, but not <strong>for</strong><br />

intransitive ones.<br />

1a. Surprisingly, <strong>the</strong> rugby player scolded <strong>the</strong> shop assistant.<br />

1b. Surprisingly, <strong>the</strong> rugby player shouted at <strong>the</strong> shop assistant.<br />

Exp 2 examined whe<strong>the</strong>r listeners can predict <strong>the</strong> correct syntactic analysis using verb frequency<br />

in<strong>for</strong>mation (e.g., Trueswell, JML 1996). We contrasted verbs that are infrequent in <strong>the</strong> past participle<br />

<strong>for</strong>m (e.g., "watch") with ones that are frequent in that <strong>for</strong>m (e.g., "select"). Participants heard<br />

sentences like (2) while looking at a picture that depicted all <strong>the</strong> objects referred to. The reduced<br />

relative clause condition was compared to an unreduced control (including "that is").<br />

2a. The videotape (that is) watched by <strong>the</strong> student was found under <strong>the</strong> chair.<br />

2b. The camera (that is) selected by <strong>the</strong> ballerina was more expensive than <strong>the</strong> bicycle.<br />

We found that during "watched", <strong>the</strong> reduced <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> unreduced condition differed in <strong>the</strong> number of<br />

looks to <strong>the</strong> correct subject picture (student in (2a), ballerina in (2b)), reflecting processing difficulty<br />

due to ambiguity. However, <strong>the</strong>re was no such difference during "selected", suggesting that<br />

participants used <strong>the</strong> frequency in<strong>for</strong>mation to predict <strong>the</strong> correct subject, thus resolving <strong>the</strong><br />

ambiguity.<br />

Taken toge<strong>the</strong>r, Exps 1 <strong>and</strong> 2 confirm that listeners can <strong>and</strong> do make predictions about upcoming<br />

syntactic structures using verb-specific in<strong>for</strong>mation such as subcategorization frame <strong>and</strong><br />

morphological frequency.<br />

Notes<br />

35


O19<br />

Bridging locality <strong>and</strong> anti-locality effects in <strong>the</strong> processing of<br />

long-distance syntactic dependencies<br />

Victor Kuperman, Piai Vitoria, & Robert Schreuder<br />

Radboud <strong>University</strong>, Nijmegen, The Ne<strong>the</strong>rl<strong>and</strong>s<br />

E-mail: victor.kuperman@mpi.nl<br />

Current <strong>the</strong>ories of sentence comprehension offer opposite predictions with respect to <strong>the</strong> processing<br />

of long-distance syntactic dependencies (e.g., "send off" in "She sent <strong>the</strong> kids off to school"). The<br />

locality <strong>the</strong>ories (e.g., Gibson, 1998) argue that <strong>the</strong> fur<strong>the</strong>r apart <strong>the</strong> dependent elements are, <strong>the</strong> more<br />

resources are required <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> processing of <strong>the</strong> distant element. Conversely, <strong>the</strong> expectation-based<br />

<strong>the</strong>ory (Levy, 2008) claims that <strong>the</strong> longer distance between <strong>the</strong> dependent elements allows readers to<br />

lower <strong>the</strong> surprisal of <strong>the</strong> upcoming words <strong>and</strong> hence <strong>the</strong> actual processing of "off" may be easier, <strong>the</strong><br />

fur<strong>the</strong>r away that word is from "sent".<br />

We report new evidence <strong>for</strong> both locality <strong>and</strong> anti-locality effects stemming from two large regression<br />

studies on phrasal verbs in Dutch <strong>and</strong> English. The eye-tracking study of Dutch phrasal verbs (60<br />

sentences with different phrasal verbs, 25 participants) <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> self-paced reading study of English<br />

phrasal verbs (130 sentences, 20 participants) manipulated <strong>the</strong> distance between <strong>the</strong> main verb<br />

(“send”) <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> particle (“off”), as well as <strong>the</strong> Cloze predictability of <strong>the</strong> particle in <strong>the</strong> sentential<br />

context. Both studies showed main effects of distance <strong>and</strong> predictability, <strong>and</strong>, crucially, an interaction<br />

between <strong>the</strong>se two predictors. For more predictable particles, a robust anti-locality effect emerged,<br />

i.e., <strong>the</strong> larger distance in <strong>the</strong> dependency came with shorter reading times. However, <strong>for</strong> particles<br />

with a low Cloze predictability we found a locality effect: <strong>the</strong> increase in <strong>the</strong> distance came with <strong>the</strong><br />

increase in <strong>the</strong> processing time. These findings suggest a processing trade-off between <strong>the</strong><br />

probabilistic assessment of upcoming words <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> dem<strong>and</strong>s of <strong>the</strong> short-term memory. We discuss<br />

implications of <strong>the</strong>se findings <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong>ories of sentence processing.<br />

Our data question <strong>the</strong> claim of Levy (2008) that <strong>the</strong> word’s surprisal in context exclusively<br />

determines <strong>the</strong> word’s processing difficulty. We show that several distributional measures quantifying<br />

<strong>the</strong> relationship between <strong>the</strong> main verb <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> particle in phrasal verbs (semantic transparency of<br />

phrasal verbs, morphological family of <strong>the</strong> main verb, <strong>the</strong> frequency of <strong>the</strong> phrasal verb as a whole,<br />

etc.) make independent contributions to <strong>the</strong> ease of processing. Apparently, <strong>the</strong> estimates of surprisal<br />

(typically derived from probabilistic grammars) need to rely on a broader range of lexical variables.<br />

References<br />

Gibson, E. (1998). Linguistic complexity: Locality of syntactic dependencies. Cognition, 68, 1–76.<br />

Levy, R. (2008). Expectation-based syntactic comprehension. Cognition, 106, 112<br />

Notes<br />

36


Semantic features <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> computation of word meaning: A large<br />

correlational semantic decision study<br />

O20<br />

Michael A. Ford, Billi R<strong>and</strong>all, Kirsten I. Taylor, Barry J. Devereux, & Lorraine K. Tyler<br />

<strong>University</strong> of Cambridge, UK<br />

E-mail: m<strong>for</strong>d@csl.psychol.cam.ac.uk<br />

Distributed feature-based models of semantic memory claim that variation in <strong>the</strong> distributional<br />

properties of features across semantic space, feature distinctiveness <strong>and</strong> feature correlation, determine<br />

conceptual processing. (McRae et al, 1997; Tyler et al, 2000). Distinctive features,<br />

() are highly diagnostic of particular concepts whereas highly shared features<br />

() provide category level in<strong>for</strong>mation <strong>for</strong> concepts (Taylor et al, 2008). Features<br />

that co-occur systematically across concepts (, ), mutually activate one<br />

ano<strong>the</strong>r thus feature correlation has a strong influence on <strong>the</strong> initial computation of word meaning<br />

(McRae et al, 1997). The studies providing <strong>the</strong> basis this <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong>se claims however, have typically<br />

used factorial designs which are potentially susceptible to <strong>the</strong> kinds of retrospective effects that can<br />

influence semantic priming (Besner et al, 2005). A fur<strong>the</strong>r more pertinent limitation is that many of<br />

<strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>oretically interesting variables are correlated both with each o<strong>the</strong>r <strong>and</strong> with o<strong>the</strong>r variables<br />

such as word-frequency. The consequences of <strong>the</strong>se limitations are that variation between conditions<br />

has not always been adequately controlled <strong>and</strong> cell sizes have been small, potentially causing<br />

problems of statistical power. The current study used a large correlational visual semantic decision<br />

design to assess <strong>the</strong> influence of <strong>the</strong> distributional properties of semantic features on access to word<br />

meaning. Eighteen <strong>for</strong>m, lexical <strong>and</strong> semantic variables were reduced to six orthogonal vectors using<br />

PCA <strong>and</strong> correlation with <strong>the</strong>se vectors was partialled out from measures of feature distinctiveness<br />

<strong>and</strong> correlation. Analysis with linear mixed effect models showed that when semantic decisions were<br />

easy, <strong>the</strong> more shared <strong>the</strong> features of a concept, <strong>the</strong> faster response times. This suggests that responses<br />

were made based on broad category level in<strong>for</strong>mation ra<strong>the</strong>r than concept specific in<strong>for</strong>mation. When<br />

semantic decisions were difficult, strong facilitatory effects of feature correlation were found,<br />

suggesting that concept specific in<strong>for</strong>mation was necessary in such cases. This study supports<br />

previous claims <strong>the</strong> feature correlations play an important part in <strong>the</strong> computation of word meaning,<br />

but also that previous findings may have been influenced by <strong>the</strong> necessity of unique concept<br />

identification. Recent claims of predominant role <strong>for</strong> distinctive features in <strong>the</strong> computation of word<br />

meaning (Cree et al, 2006) were not supported in this study.<br />

Notes<br />

37


O21<br />

The link between meaning <strong>and</strong> <strong>for</strong>m in British Sign <strong>Language</strong>:<br />

Role of iconic properties in lexical <strong>and</strong> conceptual processing<br />

David P. Vinson, Robert Skinner, Robin L. Thompson, & Gabriella Vigliocco<br />

DCAL, <strong>University</strong> College London, UK<br />

E-mail: d.vinson@ucl.ac.uk<br />

In signed languages, a high proportion of sign<strong>for</strong>ms contain iconic elements which visually reflect<br />

some aspect of <strong>the</strong>ir referents. For example in British Sign <strong>Language</strong> (BSL), <strong>the</strong> sign LION reflects a<br />

lion's outstretched claws. Despite <strong>the</strong> prevalence of iconicity, <strong>the</strong> extent to which it affects sign<br />

language processing remains unclear. Initial evidence1 suggests that sign iconicity facilitates<br />

per<strong>for</strong>mance in a linguistic task (picture-sign/word matching), suggesting that iconic properties of<br />

signs may have privileged status in signers' semantic or conceptual representations, in line with<br />

linguistic relativity hypo<strong>the</strong>ses. In three experiments contrasting BSL signers to nonsigners we<br />

explore <strong>the</strong> extent of this facilitatory effect, contrasting iconic properties of BSL signs (e.g. lion's<br />

claws) with noniconic ones (e.g. lion's mane). Experiment 1 replicated our previous study1 in BSL,<br />

<strong>and</strong> also manipulated <strong>the</strong> general salience of iconic properties (based on English semantic feature<br />

norms2) to test whe<strong>the</strong>r iconicity effects are modulated by a property's general salience (e.g. an<br />

elephant's trunk appeared often in feature norms <strong>and</strong> thus is highly salient to English speakers, while<br />

a lion's claws are not2). We contrasted pictures where <strong>the</strong> iconic property was salient (e.g. a lion with<br />

prominent claws) vs. those where it was not (e.g. a lion with prominent mane <strong>and</strong> claws not visible).<br />

As in 1, BSL signers responded faster when <strong>the</strong> iconic property was salient, while English speakers<br />

showed no such advantage, <strong>and</strong> this effect was not modulated by properties' general salience.<br />

Experiment 2 used a non-linguistic task (visual property verification) where participants were<br />

presented with a picture (e.g. lion) followed by a picture of a visual property (e.g. claws), <strong>and</strong> pressed<br />

a button to indicate whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> picture <strong>and</strong> its property matched. BSL signers showed no temporal<br />

advantage in identifying <strong>the</strong> iconic property compared to nonsigners. Experiment 3 used a similar task<br />

conducted entirely in English (<strong>the</strong> signers' second language); again <strong>the</strong> signers showed no advantage<br />

<strong>for</strong> iconic properties. These results show that <strong>the</strong> facilitatory effect of sign iconicity does not extend to<br />

conceptual representations as would be predicted by strong linguistic relativity hypo<strong>the</strong>ses, but<br />

instead is extremely constrained, applying only to a linguistic task where <strong>the</strong> iconic property is<br />

relevant.<br />

References<br />

1 Thompson, R, Vinson, D & Vigliocco G (submitted), The link between <strong>for</strong>m <strong>and</strong> meaning in<br />

American Sign <strong>Language</strong>: Lexical processing effects.<br />

2 McRae, K, et al (2005), Behav Res Methods, 37: 547-55<br />

Notes<br />

38


O22<br />

Evaluating constructivist <strong>the</strong>ory via Bayesian modeling of children’s early<br />

grammatical development<br />

Colin Bannard, Elena V.M. Lieven, & Michael Tomasello<br />

Max Planck Institute <strong>for</strong> Evolutionary Anthropology, Leipzig, Germany<br />

E-mail: bannard@eva.mpg.de<br />

Theories of grammatical development differ in how much abstract knowledge <strong>the</strong>y attribute to young<br />

children. While it has long been popular to discuss early linguistic competence in terms of abstract<br />

categories <strong>and</strong> rules, a number of researchers have recently argued that in <strong>the</strong> absence of commitment<br />

to UG, it is inappropriate to pre-empirically assume continuity with adult language (e.g. Tomasello,<br />

2003). Such usage-based researchers have proposed that children's speech <strong>for</strong> at least <strong>the</strong> first 2 years<br />

of multiword speech is very restricted, with constructions being verb-specific <strong>and</strong> utterances being<br />

built from lexically-specific frames. We here report on a series of experiments in which we use a<br />

computational model to evaluate <strong>the</strong> explanatory power of such a model of early production.<br />

We recorded 2 English-speaking children <strong>for</strong> 30 hours each over 6 weeks immediately following both<br />

<strong>the</strong>ir 2nd <strong>and</strong> 3rd birthdays. We employed a Bayesian procedure to extract grammars from <strong>the</strong> child’s<br />

(not caregiver’s) speech in <strong>the</strong> first 28 hours of transcriptions at each age. Our basic grammars were<br />

<strong>for</strong>mally equivalent to context-free grammars (Chomsky, 1956). However <strong>the</strong>y crucially involved no<br />

abstract categories <strong>and</strong> consisted entirely of lexically-specific schematic patterns, words <strong>and</strong><br />

multiword sequences.<br />

In a first experiment we used <strong>the</strong>se grammars to parse all <strong>the</strong> child’s unique multiword utterances<br />

from <strong>the</strong> remaining two hours of speech <strong>for</strong> each child at each age. At 2 years <strong>the</strong> children's<br />

productions were accounted <strong>for</strong> effectively (as much as 87% coverage) <strong>and</strong> perspicuously (as much as<br />

65% of utterances requiring application of two rewrite rules or less). In a second experiment we<br />

examined <strong>the</strong> explanatory value of positing that <strong>the</strong> children have productive morphology <strong>and</strong><br />

knowledge of abstract categories. At age 2 this had, with <strong>the</strong> exception of <strong>the</strong> noun category, very<br />

little effect on coverage. At age 3 <strong>the</strong> addition of abstract in<strong>for</strong>mation over verbs also markedly<br />

improved per<strong>for</strong>mance. These results are consistent with experimental findings regarding children’s<br />

early knowledge of linguistic categories (Olguin <strong>and</strong> Tomasello, 1993). Our results support an<br />

account of development in which abstract linguistic knowledge develops gradually.<br />

References<br />

Chomsky N (1956) Three models <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> description of language. IEEE Trans. on In<strong>for</strong>m. Theory<br />

2:113–124.<br />

Olguin R <strong>and</strong> Tomasello M (1993) Twenty-five-month-old children do not have a grammatical<br />

category of verb. Cognitive Development 8:245–272.<br />

Tomasello M (2003) Constructing a language, Harvard <strong>University</strong> Press.<br />

Notes<br />

39


O23<br />

Early word order representation: Evidence against <strong>the</strong> lexical hypo<strong>the</strong>sis<br />

Julie Franck, Séverine Millotte, & Ulrich H. Frauenfelder<br />

<strong>University</strong> of Geneva, Switzerl<strong>and</strong><br />

E-mail: julie.franck@pse.unige.ch<br />

One major controversy in <strong>the</strong> field of language development concerns <strong>the</strong> nature of children’s initial<br />

grammatical knowledge. This paper focuses on <strong>the</strong> nature of <strong>the</strong>ir initial representation of word order.<br />

According to <strong>the</strong> grammatical hypo<strong>the</strong>sis, word order develops through <strong>the</strong> operation of a mechanism<br />

of parameter-setting that is triggered early by <strong>the</strong> input <strong>and</strong> that rapidly yields an abstract<br />

representation of <strong>the</strong> mapping between <strong>the</strong> positions of words in <strong>the</strong> sentence <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir <strong>the</strong>matic role.<br />

The lexical hypo<strong>the</strong>sis assumes that children’s initial representation of word order develops from<br />

lexically specific schemas <strong>for</strong>med around frequent items <strong>and</strong> only slowly becomes abstract.<br />

Many of <strong>the</strong> studies favouring <strong>the</strong> lexical hypo<strong>the</strong>sis have been based on <strong>the</strong> weird word order<br />

paradigm. Although we have replicated <strong>the</strong>se results on two groups of French-speaking children <strong>and</strong><br />

confirmed <strong>the</strong> reliability of <strong>the</strong> data, we question <strong>the</strong>ir validity <strong>and</strong> provide a critical analysis of <strong>the</strong><br />

general conclusions drawn involving three arguments. First, we claim that <strong>the</strong> per<strong>for</strong>mance elicited in<br />

<strong>the</strong> weird word order task involves non-grammatical, inferential processes. Second, <strong>the</strong>se studies<br />

discard much missing data that critically depend up on <strong>the</strong> variables manipulated <strong>and</strong> are <strong>the</strong>re<strong>for</strong>e not<br />

Missing At R<strong>and</strong>om. Third, even in <strong>the</strong> original analyses that exclude missing data, patterns emerge<br />

that were not interpreted by <strong>the</strong> authors: (a) Young children rarely re-use <strong>the</strong> modelled ungrammatical<br />

order, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>y do, <strong>the</strong>y fail to show <strong>the</strong> signs of grammatical processing observed in <strong>the</strong>ir correct<br />

sentences; (b) They more easily re-use correct word orders than incorrect ones, even with novel verbs<br />

<strong>and</strong> when <strong>the</strong>y change incorrect orders <strong>the</strong>y always convert <strong>the</strong>m to <strong>the</strong> correct order <strong>and</strong>, critically,<br />

<strong>the</strong>y never change correct orders; (c) Verb familiarity influences <strong>the</strong> production of ungrammatical<br />

orders in older children like young ones. In sum, critical inspection of <strong>the</strong>se studies including our own<br />

replication shows that <strong>the</strong>y not only fail to provide evidence <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> lexical hypo<strong>the</strong>sis, but that <strong>the</strong>y<br />

actually support <strong>the</strong> alternative, grammatical hypo<strong>the</strong>sis.<br />

References<br />

Abbot-Smith, K., Lieven, E., & Tomasello, M. (2001). Cognitive Development, 16, 679-692.<br />

Akhtar, N. (1999). Journal of Child <strong>Language</strong>, 26, 339-356.<br />

Akhtar, N., & Tomasello, M. (1997). Developmental Psychology, 33, 952-965.<br />

Mat<strong>the</strong>ws, D., Lieven, E., Theakston, A., & Tomasello, M. (2005). Cognitive Development, 20, 121-<br />

136.<br />

Mat<strong>the</strong>ws, D., Lieven, E., Theakston, A., & Tomasello, M. (2007). Journal of Child <strong>Language</strong>, 32(2),<br />

381-409<br />

Notes<br />

40


Development at <strong>the</strong> syntax-semantics interface: When do children<br />

underst<strong>and</strong> implicit ontological shifts<br />

O24<br />

Hugh A. Rabagliati, Tracie Lin, Hanna Gelf<strong>and</strong>, Gary F. Marcus, & Liina Pylkkänen<br />

New York <strong>University</strong>, USA<br />

E-mail: hugh@nyu.edu<br />

Ordinary language underst<strong>and</strong>ing frequently requires listeners to shift <strong>the</strong> basic meaning of a<br />

constituent, as in (1) <strong>and</strong> (2).<br />

1. The boy began <strong>the</strong> book [Complement-coercion]<br />

2. The CD was loud [Metonymy]<br />

In (1), <strong>the</strong> event-selecting verb begin receives an object-denoting complement. Since objects do not<br />

'begin', we might expect <strong>the</strong> sentence to be uninterpretable. Instead adult listeners “coerce” <strong>the</strong> object<br />

into <strong>the</strong> appropriate ontological category, an event interpretation (eg began reading <strong>the</strong> book). In (2),<br />

<strong>the</strong> adjective loud predicates not on <strong>the</strong> meaning of CD as a physical object but ra<strong>the</strong>r on an enriched<br />

meaning of CD in terms of its abstract contents.<br />

What do children know about such ontological shifts, <strong>and</strong> when are <strong>the</strong>y acquired compared to o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

aspects of natural language We present <strong>the</strong> first experimental investigation of <strong>the</strong> development of<br />

children’s underst<strong>and</strong>ing of coercion <strong>and</strong> metonymy. Under <strong>the</strong> guise of a game with an ignorant<br />

robot, 32 children (3 groups: 7) <strong>and</strong> 17 adult controls answered predicability questions<br />

(could an X be Y) to assess children’s underst<strong>and</strong>ing of 4 common shifts:<br />

A. Object-> Event [1]<br />

B. Object-> Abstract Content [2]<br />

C. Container-> Contents [4]<br />

D. Institution-> Person [eg Could a hospital call <strong>the</strong> lady]<br />

Each shift was assessed by 5 sets of 4 questions, such as<br />

3. Could a pot be cracked (Yes)<br />

4. Could a pot be stirred (Yes/No)<br />

5. Could some soup be stirred (Yes)<br />

6. Could some soup be cracked (No)<br />

The critical condition was (4), which subjects would be less likely to deny if <strong>the</strong>y could use <strong>the</strong> shift<br />

than if <strong>the</strong>y could not. Sentences like 6 served as a control, <strong>the</strong>se impossible shifts would be denied<br />

unless subjects were confused about <strong>the</strong> distinctions between <strong>the</strong> ontological sorts tested (cf Keil<br />

1979).<br />

A shift was considered acquired (ie adult-like) if accuracy on <strong>the</strong> impossible shift (6) was both above<br />

chance, <strong>and</strong> higher than <strong>the</strong> possible shift condition (4). By <strong>the</strong>se criteria, adults had mastered all four<br />

types of shifts. In addition, all four groups were above chance (p event (complement-coercion)<br />

shift [A] was <strong>the</strong> first to be acquired (p


O25<br />

External vs. internal verbal self-monitoring: Speakers listen to <strong>the</strong>ir own<br />

external, but not internal, speech in speech production<br />

Falk Huettig 1 , & Robert J. Hartsuiker 2<br />

1 Max Planck Institute <strong>for</strong> Psycholinguistics, Nijmegen, The Ne<strong>the</strong>rl<strong>and</strong>s, 2 Ghent <strong>University</strong>, Belgium<br />

E-mail: falk.huettig@mpi.nl<br />

When we speak we can listen to ourselves, <strong>and</strong> so we can use speech perception to monitor our own<br />

overt speech <strong>for</strong> deviations from plan. Theories of verbal self-monitoring generally assume an<br />

internal (pre-articulatory) monitoring channel, but <strong>the</strong>re is debate about whe<strong>the</strong>r this channel relies<br />

on speech perception or on production-internal mechanisms. Perception-based <strong>the</strong>ories predict that<br />

listening to one's own inner speech has similar behavioral consequences as listening to someone<br />

else's speech.<br />

To test whe<strong>the</strong>r internal monitoring engages speech perception, we registered eye-movements while<br />

speakers named objects, hypo<strong>the</strong>sizing that hearing ourselves should influence eye-movements<br />

similarly as hearing o<strong>the</strong>rs. Participants viewed displays containing a target object to be named <strong>and</strong><br />

three written-word distractors. In <strong>the</strong> critical condition, one of <strong>the</strong>se words was phonologically<br />

related to <strong>the</strong> name of <strong>the</strong> object <strong>and</strong> two words were unrelated. Of interest was <strong>the</strong> pattern of<br />

fixations to <strong>the</strong> phonologically related distractors prior to <strong>and</strong> after <strong>the</strong> onset of overt articulation. A<br />

perceptually-based <strong>the</strong>ory of internal monitoring predicts that speech perception is already engaged<br />

in <strong>the</strong> time interval be<strong>for</strong>e overt articulation (e.g., Hartsuiker & Kolk, 2001; Indefrey & Levelt,<br />

2004).<br />

Our data show that listening to one's own speech drives eye- movements in <strong>the</strong> visual world in a very<br />

similar way as listening to someone else's speech (Huettig & McQueen, 2007). In both modalities,<br />

shortly after <strong>the</strong> acoustic onset of a word, participants fixate phonologically-related written words<br />

more often than unrelated words. Importantly, <strong>the</strong> time-course of fixating phonological competitors<br />

was very similar in self-perception <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r-perception, even though perceptually-based monitoring<br />

<strong>the</strong>ories predict that phonological in<strong>for</strong>mation is available much earlier (145 - 250 ms) in selfperception<br />

than o<strong>the</strong>r-perception. We <strong>the</strong>re<strong>for</strong>e conclude that <strong>the</strong> internal monitoring channel does<br />

not rely on speech perception; <strong>the</strong> data are more compatible with production-based monitoring<br />

<strong>the</strong>ories (e.g., Laver, 1980; see Postma, 2000 <strong>for</strong> review).<br />

Notes<br />

42


Syntactic priming <strong>and</strong> message encoding in unscripted dialogue<br />

O26<br />

Kathleen M. Carbary, & Michael K. Tanenhaus<br />

<strong>University</strong> of Rochester, USA<br />

E-mail: kcarbary@bcs.rochester.edu<br />

We examined how context <strong>and</strong> priming interact to determine referential <strong>for</strong>m in unscripted dialogue,<br />

in order to evaluate whe<strong>the</strong>r syntactic priming affects <strong>the</strong> content of message encoding. We also<br />

asked whe<strong>the</strong>r priming effects are stronger in dialogue than monologue, as has been recently<br />

suggested [1, 2].<br />

Pairs of naïve participants sat at separate computers, <strong>and</strong> took turns describing a target from a set of<br />

pictures to <strong>the</strong>ir partner, whose task was to click on <strong>the</strong> target. In some cases, contrast sets (e.g. two<br />

cats) required <strong>the</strong> use of an adjective to accurately describe <strong>the</strong> target (e.g. <strong>the</strong> striped cat). Effects<br />

were evaluated using mixed-effects logit models. Experiment 1 replicated st<strong>and</strong>ard priming effects:<br />

when participants used an adjective, <strong>the</strong>y were biased to repeat <strong>the</strong> syntactic structure (pre- or postnominal)<br />

just used by <strong>the</strong>ir partner. If priming affects structure at <strong>the</strong> level of message planning, <strong>the</strong><br />

prime structure should also increase adjective use, even when <strong>the</strong> context doesn’t require it. This was<br />

not <strong>the</strong> case. Although participants were more likely to repeat <strong>the</strong> prime structure than to choose an<br />

alternative structure when <strong>the</strong>y modified, primes had only minimal effects on modification rates when<br />

context did not require it. Thus, although priming affects <strong>the</strong> availability of alternative structures, it<br />

does not affect <strong>the</strong> content of <strong>the</strong> message.<br />

In a second experiment, primes were produced by an interlocutor, or pre-recorded <strong>and</strong> played over<br />

headphones. For trials where modification was used, priming was significantly more likely in<br />

response to primes produced by a dialogue participant than in response to pre-recorded primes.<br />

However, <strong>the</strong> impact of prime type was small: when all trials were included in <strong>the</strong> model, <strong>the</strong>re was<br />

no effect of dialogue on priming. This suggests that priming may not play a special role in dialogue.<br />

In addition, when added to a mixed-effects model along with contrast <strong>and</strong> prime type, trial order did<br />

not predict priming, indicating that priming did not increase as <strong>the</strong> dialogue unfolded.<br />

We conclude that syntactic priming affects <strong>the</strong> availability of alternative syntactic <strong>for</strong>ms, but has little<br />

influence on message content. Moreover, priming effects during unscripted dialogue are only slightly<br />

stronger than priming in an o<strong>the</strong>rwise identical non-dialogue context.<br />

References<br />

1. Pickering & Garrod (2004). Toward a mechanistic psychology of dialogue. Behavioral & <strong>Brain</strong><br />

Sciences, 27, 169-226.<br />

2. Branigan, Pickering, McLean, & Clel<strong>and</strong> (2007). Participant role <strong>and</strong> syntactic alignment in<br />

dialogue. Cognition, 104, 163-97.<br />

Notes<br />

43


O27<br />

Communication <strong>and</strong> grammar do not rely on <strong>the</strong> same cognitive system<br />

Alan Langus 1 , & Marina Nespor 2<br />

1<br />

SISSA, Trieste, Italy, 2 <strong>University</strong> Milano Bicocca, Italy<br />

E-mail: langus@sissa.it<br />

Our underst<strong>and</strong>ing of <strong>the</strong> uniqueness of human language is primarily based on syntaxctic properties<br />

(e.g. reursivity). However, besides adhering to <strong>the</strong> computationally precise syntactic rules <strong>and</strong><br />

structures, human language serves also as a powerful tool <strong>for</strong> communication. We present 3<br />

experiments that dissociate communication from grammar <strong>and</strong> show that <strong>the</strong> two aspects of human<br />

language rely on different cognitive mechanisms.<br />

In <strong>the</strong> 1st Experiment, Italian native speakers were asked to use only gestures when describing simple<br />

scenarios consisting of a Subject, an Object <strong>and</strong> a Verb. The results show a strong preference to place<br />

gestures of Subjects <strong>and</strong> Objects be<strong>for</strong>e those of Actions – an order which is ungrammatical in Italian,<br />

suggesting that we are observing structural biases in communication in <strong>the</strong> absence of grammar.<br />

In order to test whe<strong>the</strong>r this bias is strong enough to elicit language like constructions, in <strong>the</strong> 2nd<br />

Experiment, Italian native speakers were asked to use only gestures when describing complex<br />

scenarios consisting of a Main Clause <strong>and</strong> a Subordinate Clause. The results show that participants<br />

could not elicit language like structures that would be based on <strong>the</strong> SOV order <strong>and</strong> reverted to <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

native grammar to communicate complex constructions instead.<br />

In <strong>the</strong> 3rd Experiment, we investigated <strong>the</strong> costs <strong>and</strong> benefits of <strong>the</strong>se biases in comprehension.<br />

Participants saw digitally edited video clips of simple gesture strings that differed only in <strong>the</strong> order of<br />

<strong>the</strong> Subjects, Objects <strong>and</strong> Verbs. We measured participants’ reaction times in a <strong>for</strong>ced choice task<br />

between two images: one of which described <strong>the</strong> video-clip just seen <strong>and</strong> ano<strong>the</strong>r that did not.<br />

Participants were faster in choosing <strong>the</strong> correct image when <strong>the</strong> clips followed a consistent order<br />

across trials. Interestingly, participants were also significantly faster in choosing <strong>the</strong> correct image<br />

when <strong>the</strong> clips were in <strong>the</strong> SOV order (dominant in gesture production but ungrammatical Italian)<br />

than when <strong>the</strong> clips followed <strong>the</strong> native SVO order.<br />

The results are discussed in <strong>the</strong> framework of possible <strong>for</strong>ces influencing <strong>the</strong> nature of human<br />

language production <strong>and</strong> comprehension.<br />

Notes<br />

44


O28<br />

Neuro-cognitive systems supporting derivational morphology<br />

Mirjana Bozic 1 , Lorraine K. Tyler 2 , & William D. Marslen-Wilson 1<br />

1 MRC Cognition & <strong>Brain</strong> Sciences Unit, Cambridge, UK, 2 <strong>University</strong> of Cambridge, UK<br />

E-mail: mirjana.bozic@mrc-cbu.cam.ac.uk<br />

<strong>Speech</strong> comprehension is primarily supported by bilateral fronto-temporal language processing<br />

networks. The existing evidence suggests that <strong>the</strong>se networks consist of a general bilateral component<br />

<strong>and</strong> a more specialised left hemisphere subsystem, which have different functional roles: <strong>the</strong> bilateral<br />

system supports access to stored semantic representations <strong>for</strong> simple words (e.g. dog, house), while<br />

<strong>the</strong> processing of linguistically more complex inputs shifts <strong>the</strong> hemispheric balance towards <strong>the</strong> leftlateralised<br />

subsystem (Marslen-Wilson & Tyler, 2007). Previous research with inflectionally complex<br />

words suggests that it is specifically <strong>the</strong>ir morpho-phonological complexity (i.e., as stems +<br />

inflectional affixes) that triggers left-lateralised processing. Compared to simple words, regular <strong>and</strong><br />

pseudoregular inflected items (e.g. played or trade) activate left-lateralised frontal areas, while<br />

general lexical-semantic processing complexity (e.g. competition due to presence of embedded stems,<br />

claim/clay) engages fronto-temporal regions bilaterally.<br />

The current efMRI experiment asked whe<strong>the</strong>r similar hemispheric patterns hold <strong>for</strong> derivationally<br />

complex words, where <strong>the</strong> stem-affix relationship is more strongly lexicalised <strong>and</strong> less semantically<br />

predictable than <strong>for</strong> regular inflection. In a set of single spoken words we manipulated <strong>the</strong> presence of<br />

embedded stems <strong>and</strong> derivational suffixes with varying degrees of productivity. Words were<br />

contrasted against a baseline that has <strong>the</strong> complex auditory properties of speech but does not trigger a<br />

speech percept (envelope-shaped ‘musical rain’, Uppenkamp et al, 2006). We found that stem<br />

competition generated by derivational lexical complexity (e.g., warmth/warm) engages bilateral<br />

fronto-temporal language regions; however <strong>the</strong> presence of derivational affixes did not trigger <strong>the</strong><br />

strong hemispheric dissociation seen <strong>for</strong> inflections. This is arguably because derivational affixes do<br />

not trigger decompositional processes in <strong>the</strong> same way as inflectional affixes. We suggest a neurocognitive<br />

account of <strong>the</strong> representation <strong>and</strong> processing of derivationally complex <strong>for</strong>ms in English.<br />

References<br />

Marslen-Wilson, W. & Tyler, L. K. (2007). Morphology, language <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> brain: The<br />

decompositional substrate <strong>for</strong> language comprehension. Philosophical Transactions of <strong>the</strong> Royal<br />

Society: Biological Sciences, 362, 823-836.<br />

Uppenkamp, S., Johnsrude, I. S., Norris, D., Marslen-Wilson, W. & Patterson, R. D. (2006). Locating<br />

speech-specific processes in human temporal cortex. NeuroImage, 31, 1284-1296.<br />

Notes<br />

45


O29<br />

Full parsing versus dual route models of morphological processing:<br />

Assessing surface frequency effects on response time using MEG<br />

Ehren Reilly 1 , Olla Solomyak 2 , Alec Marantz 2 , & William Badecker 1<br />

1 Johns Hopkins <strong>University</strong>, USA, 2 New York <strong>University</strong>, USA<br />

E-mail: reilly@cogsci.jhu.edu<br />

In a visual lexical decision experiment based on Baayen, Dijkstra & Schreuder (1997), but using<br />

concurrent magnetoencephalography (MEG) recording, we contrasted parallel dual-route models of<br />

lexical processing with full parsing models. We measured neural activity at each stage of processing<br />

prior to reaction time to determine <strong>the</strong> stage of processing at which surface frequency effects arise.<br />

Our behavioral results concur with Baayen et al (Fig. 1).<br />

Figure 1. Interacting effects of affixedness <strong>and</strong> affix-dominance<br />

Dominance-Affixedness Interaction<br />

RT (ms)<br />

790<br />

740<br />

690<br />

640<br />

unaffixed<br />

affixed<br />

Aff-Rec 678 750<br />

Affix- 673 700<br />

Dom<br />

However our MEG data suggest that <strong>the</strong>se surface frequency effects did not arise during lexical<br />

access, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>y are <strong>the</strong>re<strong>for</strong>e not lexical. We used <strong>the</strong> latency of <strong>the</strong> M350 response as an index of<br />

initial access to lexical representations. The M350 has been identified as <strong>the</strong> earliest MEG response<br />

that is sensitive to lexical frequency in <strong>the</strong> lexical decision task (Embick et al 2001), <strong>and</strong> our results<br />

replicated that finding (Table 1).<br />

Table 1. M350 latency <strong>for</strong> high & low frequency stems.<br />

M350 Peak Latency SE<br />

High Stem Freq. 343 3.57<br />

Low Stem Freq. 372 4.52<br />

The effect of affix-dominance of <strong>the</strong> lemma that we found behaviorally <strong>for</strong> affixed words was not<br />

reflected in <strong>the</strong> M350. That is, although lexical frequency effects were already present at <strong>the</strong> M350,<br />

surface frequency effects did not manifest until after <strong>the</strong> M350 response: They were only reflected in<br />

RT (Fig. 2).<br />

46


Figure 2: RT <strong>and</strong> M350 peak latency plotted by affixedness <strong>and</strong> affix-dominance.<br />

800<br />

750<br />

Dominance-Affixedness Interaction at RT; No Dominance-Affixedness<br />

Interaction at M350<br />

Response Latency (ms)<br />

700<br />

650<br />

600<br />

550<br />

500<br />

450<br />

400<br />

350<br />

300<br />

unaffixed<br />

affixed<br />

Affix-Rec (RT)<br />

Affix-Dom (RT)<br />

Affix-Rec (M350)<br />

Affix-Dom (M350)<br />

We also found that highly affix-recessive words cause higher amplitude in <strong>the</strong> M170 response. We<br />

believe this effect is attributable to statistical properties of <strong>the</strong> visual word<strong>for</strong>ms <strong>the</strong>mselves, ra<strong>the</strong>r<br />

than of <strong>the</strong>ir corresponding lexical entries. Our M170 findings are evidence of an early, pre-lexical<br />

stage of modality-specific word<strong>for</strong>m processing, one which is sensitive to transitional probabilities<br />

between morphemes, but not to <strong>the</strong> lexical properties of <strong>the</strong> morphemes.<br />

Taken toge<strong>the</strong>r, our M170 <strong>and</strong> M350 result support a model of lexical-morphological processing<br />

featuring:<br />

1) A decompositional mode of lexical access, whereby <strong>the</strong> parsed-out stems of morphologically<br />

complex words are accessed in <strong>the</strong> lexicon.<br />

2) An inventory of modality-specific n-gram representations, whose activation is a precursor to full<br />

lexical access.<br />

References<br />

Baayen, H., Dijkstra, T., & Schreuder, R. (1997). Singulars <strong>and</strong> plurals in Dutch: Evidence <strong>for</strong> a<br />

parallel dual route model. JML, 37, 94-117.<br />

Embick, D., Hackl, M., Schaeffer, J., Kelepir, M. & A. Marantz. (2001). A magnetoencephalographic<br />

component whose latency reflects lexical frequency. Cog. <strong>Brain</strong> Res., 10(3), 3.<br />

Notes<br />

47


O30<br />

Orthographic <strong>and</strong> phonological in<strong>for</strong>mation in <strong>the</strong> printed-words<br />

paradigm<br />

Anne Pier Salverda, & Michael K. Tanenhaus<br />

<strong>University</strong> of Rochester, USA<br />

E-mail: asalverda@bcs.rochester.edu<br />

In visual world studies of spoken word recognition, participants typically follow spoken instructions<br />

to manipulate pictures in a visual display. Eye movements to pictures provide insight into <strong>the</strong><br />

activation of lexical c<strong>and</strong>idates as <strong>the</strong> input unfolds. But how are participants able to so rapidly link<br />

spoken words to pictures One hypo<strong>the</strong>sis is that perceptual in<strong>for</strong>mation activated by <strong>the</strong> unfolding<br />

word draws attention to a matching referent (Dahan & Tanenhaus, 2005). Ano<strong>the</strong>r is that fixations are<br />

mediated by phonological in<strong>for</strong>mation associated with <strong>the</strong> picture—i.e., its name.<br />

Two recent studies replaced pictures with printed words. McQueen <strong>and</strong> Viebahn (2007) find <strong>the</strong> same<br />

pattern of fixations as with pictures (e.g., Allopenna et al., 1998); Huettig <strong>and</strong> McQueen (2007) find<br />

that phonological similarity effects precede visual/semantic effects--which <strong>the</strong> authors interpret as<br />

evidence that <strong>the</strong> earliest effects are phonologically mediated. However, it has long been known that<br />

orthographic representations are accessed when a spoken word is heard (cf. Seidenberg & Tanenhaus,<br />

1979), though we know little about <strong>the</strong> time course of this process. Because McQueen <strong>and</strong> colleagues<br />

used Dutch, which has a fairly transparent orthography, <strong>the</strong>ir results do not distinguish between a<br />

phonological <strong>and</strong> an orthographic linking hypo<strong>the</strong>sis. We conducted two experiments in English,<br />

which has an opaque orthography, to dissociate <strong>the</strong> role of orthography <strong>and</strong> phonology.<br />

Participants heard a spoken instruction, e.g. "Click on <strong>the</strong> word bead". As in <strong>the</strong> McQueen studies,<br />

<strong>the</strong> display with four printed words appeared 200ms be<strong>for</strong>e target word onset. The display included<br />

<strong>the</strong> target, a competitor <strong>and</strong> two distractors. In Experiment 1, orthographic overlap between <strong>the</strong> target<br />

<strong>and</strong> competitor was ei<strong>the</strong>r high (target bead, competitor bear) or low (target bead, competitor bare).<br />

Phonological overlap between <strong>the</strong> target <strong>and</strong> each competitor was low <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> same <strong>for</strong> each type of<br />

competitor. We found more fixations to high-overlap orthographic competitors than to low-overlap<br />

orthographic competitors. In Experiment 2, phonological overlap was high (target bead, competitor<br />

bean) or low (target bead, competitor bear), with each competitor matched <strong>for</strong> orthographic overlap<br />

with <strong>the</strong> target. Participants were equally likely to fixate each type of competitor.<br />

The results suggest that orthographic in<strong>for</strong>mation <strong>for</strong> lexical c<strong>and</strong>idates is activated as a spoken word<br />

unfolds <strong>and</strong> fixations to <strong>the</strong> printed words reflect a visual search <strong>for</strong> a matching orthographic <strong>for</strong>m.<br />

Notes<br />

48


O31<br />

The cross-script length effect on reading aloud: Fur<strong>the</strong>r challenges <strong>for</strong><br />

PDP models<br />

Kathleen Rastle 1 , Jelena Havelka 2 , & Taeko Wydell 3<br />

1 Royal Holloway, <strong>University</strong> of London, UK, 2 <strong>University</strong> of Leeds, UK, 3 Brunel <strong>University</strong>, UK<br />

E-mail: kathy.rastle@rhul.ac.uk<br />

One of <strong>the</strong> key controversies in psycholinguistics concerns <strong>the</strong> nature of processing in <strong>the</strong> reading<br />

aloud system. While PDP models of reading aloud make <strong>the</strong> a priori claim that <strong>the</strong> orthography-tophonology<br />

trans<strong>for</strong>mation is accomplished solely using parallel processing, <strong>the</strong> DRC <strong>and</strong> CDP+<br />

models posit that this trans<strong>for</strong>mation is accomplished using a combination of parallel <strong>and</strong> serial<br />

processes. This controversy has been hard to resolve experimentally, because it has been difficult to<br />

demonstrate that <strong>the</strong> various serial effects that have been reported arise in <strong>the</strong> orthography-tophonology<br />

trans<strong>for</strong>mation itself, instead of in peripheral visual or articulatory processes that everyone<br />

agrees have a serial component. Our research resolves this issue by using <strong>the</strong> special properties of <strong>the</strong><br />

Serbian <strong>and</strong> Japanese writing systems to investigate <strong>the</strong> interaction between length <strong>and</strong> lexical status.<br />

This interaction reflects <strong>the</strong> fact that length effects on reading aloud are much larger <strong>for</strong> nonwords<br />

than <strong>the</strong>y are <strong>for</strong> words, <strong>and</strong> has been one of <strong>the</strong> key findings used in support of serial models of<br />

reading aloud.<br />

Experiment 1 examined <strong>the</strong> interaction between length <strong>and</strong> lexical status in Japanese Kana, with<br />

stimuli across <strong>the</strong> manipulation of lexical status being phonologically identical. Participants were<br />

presented with Hiragana <strong>and</strong> Katakana words varied on length. The manipulation of lexical status was<br />

achieved by presenting <strong>the</strong>se words (a) as orthographically-familiar <strong>for</strong>ms in <strong>the</strong> script in which <strong>the</strong>y<br />

normally appear; or (b) as orthographically-unfamiliar <strong>for</strong>ms transcribed into <strong>the</strong> script in which <strong>the</strong>y<br />

never appear. Experiment 2 examined <strong>the</strong> interaction between length <strong>and</strong> lexical status in Serbian,<br />

with stimuli across <strong>the</strong> manipulation of lexical status being orthographically identical. Participants<br />

were presented with Roman <strong>and</strong> Cyrillic bivalent stimuli varied on length. Bivalent stimuli are<br />

typically words if interpreted in one alphabet <strong>and</strong> pronounceable nonwords (with a different<br />

pronunciation) if interpreted in ano<strong>the</strong>r alphabet. Thus, <strong>the</strong> manipulation of lexical status was<br />

achieved by asking participants to interpret <strong>the</strong> bivalent stimuli (a) in <strong>the</strong> alphabet in which <strong>the</strong>y were<br />

words; or (b) in <strong>the</strong> alphabet in which <strong>the</strong>y were nonwords. Results of both experiments showed a<br />

larger length effect when stimuli were treated as nonwords than when <strong>the</strong>y were treated as words.<br />

These results offer strong support to models of reading aloud that postulate a serial process in <strong>the</strong><br />

trans<strong>for</strong>mation of orthography to phonology.<br />

Notes<br />

49


O32<br />

Fit-to-context as a controller of <strong>the</strong> extent of semantic processing during<br />

discourse comprehension<br />

Anthony J. San<strong>for</strong>d 1 , Jason Bohan 1 , Alison J.S. San<strong>for</strong>d 2 , & Hartmut Leuthold 1<br />

1 <strong>University</strong> of Glasgow, UK, 2 <strong>University</strong> of Strathclyde, UK<br />

E-mail: a.san<strong>for</strong>d@psy.gla.ac.uk<br />

Although readers usually notice semantic anomalies in discourse, this depends upon anomalous words<br />

having a poor fit to general context (e.g., “Mary likes her tea with socks”.). When a word has a good<br />

fit to global context, it is often not detected as anomalous, even though it has a local poor fit (“After<br />

<strong>the</strong> aircrash, <strong>the</strong> authorities had to decide where to bury <strong>the</strong> survivors”; Barton & San<strong>for</strong>d, 1993).<br />

Here survivors is a word that is common in <strong>the</strong> context of an aircrash, <strong>and</strong> is well-fitting, unlike socks<br />

in <strong>the</strong> first case.<br />

The experiments bring new evidence to bear on differences between processing words with good <strong>and</strong><br />

poor fits to global context. In Experiments 1 <strong>and</strong> 2, we use eyetracking to probe whe<strong>the</strong>r anomalous<br />

words that have a good fit are in fact detected at a systems-level, but do not register in awareness, or<br />

whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>re is no evidence <strong>for</strong> unconscious detection. There was little evidence <strong>for</strong> unconscious<br />

detection in ei<strong>the</strong>r experiment. Only in cases of conscious detection was <strong>the</strong>re an effect on tracking<br />

pattern. We conclude that unconscious detection of an anomaly is highly unlikely.<br />

Experiments 3 <strong>and</strong> 4 used ERPs. Two interesting results emerged. While anomalous words with a<br />

poor fit to global context produced an N400 effect, anomalous words with a good fit produced no<br />

N400 effect: They produced a late positive complex. This supports <strong>the</strong> distinction between <strong>the</strong> two<br />

types of anomaly, <strong>and</strong> fits with o<strong>the</strong>r literature on late positivities (Kuperberg, 2007). There was also<br />

no evidence <strong>for</strong> unconscious recognition in <strong>the</strong> ERP pattern. The late positivity emerged only on trials<br />

where <strong>the</strong>re was an overt detection of <strong>the</strong> anomaly. In Experiment 3 (auditory presentation) <strong>the</strong>re was<br />

no difference between <strong>the</strong> ERPs to nonanomalous controls <strong>and</strong> undetected anomalies. In Experiment<br />

4 (visual presentation) <strong>the</strong>re was a reduced positivity in <strong>the</strong> case of undetected anomalies compared to<br />

control. This effect is likely due to judgment confidence.<br />

We have demonstrated differences in <strong>the</strong> way contextually predictable words are processed over less<br />

predictable words (reflected in ERPs), <strong>and</strong> have provided evidence that semantic processing is more<br />

shallow in <strong>the</strong> case of <strong>the</strong> predictable terms. We argue that a mechanism supporting such effects is<br />

optimal <strong>for</strong> normal language processing.<br />

References<br />

Barton, S.B & San<strong>for</strong>d, A. J. (1993). A case-study of anomaly detection: Shallow semantic<br />

processing <strong>and</strong> cohesion establishment. Memory <strong>and</strong> Cognition, 21, 477-487.<br />

Kuperberg, G. (2007) Neural mechanisms of language comprehension: Challenges to syntax. <strong>Brain</strong><br />

Research, 1146:23-49.<br />

Notes<br />

50


O33<br />

Evidence <strong>for</strong> a dissociation between pragmatic <strong>and</strong> semantic constraint in<br />

lexical processing<br />

Dale J. Barr<br />

<strong>University</strong> of Cali<strong>for</strong>nia, Riverside, USA<br />

E-mail: dale.barr@ucr.edu<br />

When listeners interpret a speaker's references, <strong>the</strong>y consider privileged in<strong>for</strong>mation that is<br />

unavailable to <strong>the</strong> speaker. This finding has launched a longst<strong>and</strong>ing debate over listeners' use of<br />

speaker perspective during language comprehension. Some have suggested that listeners process<br />

language "egocentrically" by default <strong>and</strong> consider speaker in<strong>for</strong>mation only to monitor <strong>and</strong> repair<br />

misunderst<strong>and</strong>ings (Keysar, Barr, Balin, & Brauner, 2000). However, inconsistent with this view,<br />

listeners show early effects of common ground during reference resolution, suggesting that<br />

knowledge of <strong>the</strong> speaker's perspective imposes a partial constraint on processing (Hanna, Tanenhaus,<br />

& Trueswell, 2003).<br />

One possibility that has been neglected in this debate is that listeners try to use common ground, but<br />

are unable to fully do so due to processing limitations: Listeners may unsuccessfully attempt to<br />

restrict attention to in<strong>for</strong>mation in common ground prior to hearing a referring expression, but find<br />

<strong>the</strong>mselves unable to inhibit activation of this in<strong>for</strong>mation because low-level processing systems<br />

operate independently of this knowledge. Thus, "early" effects of common ground may reflect<br />

anticipation, but not integration, of pragmatic knowledge.<br />

To test this hypo<strong>the</strong>sis, listeners viewed pictures <strong>and</strong> interpreted speakers' references to a target<br />

picture (e.g., click on <strong>the</strong> bucket) while <strong>the</strong>ir eyes were tracked. A critical picture was ei<strong>the</strong>r of a<br />

competitor (e.g., buckle) or noncompetitor (e.g., stepladder). The picture could be ruled out by a<br />

constraint that was ei<strong>the</strong>r pragmatic (<strong>the</strong> picture was privileged) or semantic (<strong>the</strong> picture was an<br />

implausible object of <strong>the</strong> verb; e.g., <strong>the</strong> verb "empty" in "empty <strong>the</strong> bucket" rules out both a buckle<br />

<strong>and</strong> a stepladder, which can't be emptied). It was found that semantic constraint eliminated competitor<br />

interference, while pragmatic constraint produced anticipation without any reduction in interference.<br />

This is consistent with a processing-limitations account but not with an egocentrism or a constraintbased<br />

view.<br />

References<br />

Hanna, J., Tanenhaus, M. K., & Trueswell, J. C. (2003). The effects of common ground <strong>and</strong><br />

perspective on domains of referential interpretation. Journal of Memory <strong>and</strong> <strong>Language</strong>, 49, 43-61.<br />

Keysar, B., Barr, D. J., Balin, J. A., & Brauner, J. S. (2000). Taking perspective in conversation: The<br />

role of mutual knowledge in comprehension. Psychological Science, 11, 32-38.<br />

Notes<br />

51


O34<br />

Interpreting quantifiers in context<br />

Kevin B. Paterson 1 , Ruth Filik 2 , Marilena Mousoulidou 1 , & Linda M. Moxey 2<br />

1 <strong>University</strong> of Leicester, UK, 2 <strong>University</strong> of Glasgow, UK<br />

E-mail: kbp3@le.ac.uk<br />

An important goal of research into discourse comprehension is to explain how noun-phrases are<br />

understood relative to <strong>the</strong> discourse context. Recent research has focused on <strong>the</strong> interpretation of<br />

quantifiers, such as “three ships”. Such phrases often are ambiguous. For instance, in “Six ships were<br />

on <strong>the</strong> horizon. Three ships…” “three ships” can refer to a subset of an established referent (i.e., three<br />

of <strong>the</strong> six ships) or introduce a new referent into <strong>the</strong> discourse. Research suggests that <strong>the</strong> subset<br />

reading is preferred but is unclear as to how this preference emerges on-line. Never<strong>the</strong>less, two<br />

accounts exist. One proposes that a syntactic principle of “minimal-lowering” creates a preference <strong>for</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> subset reading of ambiguous quantifiers (e.g., Frazier, 1999). The o<strong>the</strong>r account attributes this<br />

preference to <strong>the</strong> avoidance of costs associated with establishing a new referent, <strong>and</strong> proposes that<br />

such costs emerge late in processing (Kaan et al., 2007). We report two eye-tracking experiments that<br />

assessed <strong>the</strong>se claims.<br />

Experiment 1 used short discourses such as <strong>the</strong> following:<br />

1. The fishermen saw six ships appear on <strong>the</strong> horizon. Apparently, three ships had been bombarded by<br />

enemy fire.<br />

2. The fishermen saw two ships appear on <strong>the</strong> horizon. Apparently, three ships had been bombarded<br />

by enemy fire.<br />

These included a quantifier (e.g., “three ships”) that was ambiguous or unambiguous. Ambiguous<br />

quantifiers could (e.g., 1) or could not (e.g., 2) receive a subset reading, <strong>and</strong> unambiguous stimuli<br />

were created by including a determiner that required a subset reading (e.g., "Of <strong>the</strong>se, three ships…")<br />

or new set reading (e.g., "Ano<strong>the</strong>r three ships…"). Eye movement data showed no evidence of a<br />

preference <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> subset reading of an ambiguity during early processing. But, in line with Kaan et<br />

al., <strong>the</strong>re was a late processing cost <strong>for</strong> ambiguous <strong>and</strong> unambiguous quantifiers that introduced a new<br />

referent.<br />

Experiment 2 fur<strong>the</strong>r investigated <strong>the</strong> timing of this effect by including stimuli in which <strong>the</strong> subset<br />

reading was both obligatory <strong>and</strong> impossible (e.g., "The fishermen saw two ships appear on <strong>the</strong><br />

horizon. Of <strong>the</strong>se, three ships…"). Although this semantic contradiction had effects in early<br />

processing measures, effects associated with introducing a new referent still emerged late. We<br />

conclude that this late effect reflects integration <strong>and</strong> storage costs associated with <strong>the</strong> establishment of<br />

a new discourse referent.<br />

References<br />

Frazier, L. (1999). On sentence interpretation. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic.<br />

Kaan, E. et al. (2007). Processing bare quantifiers in discourse. <strong>Brain</strong> Research, 11<br />

Notes<br />

52


<strong>Abstracts</strong> – Poster Presentations<br />

53


P1<br />

Relative clauses <strong>and</strong> surprisal<br />

Douglas Rol<strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>University</strong> at Buffalo, USA<br />

E-mail: drol<strong>and</strong>@buffalo.edu<br />

Surprisal, or <strong>the</strong> negative log probability of a word given its context, has been shown to account <strong>for</strong><br />

processing difficulties <strong>and</strong> reading times in a wide variety of situations ranging from <strong>the</strong> reading<br />

times of specific structures (e.g., Hale, 2001; Levy, 2008) to <strong>the</strong> reading times of words in running<br />

text (e.g., Boston et al., 2008; Demberg & Keller, 2008).<br />

While surprisal is able to account <strong>for</strong> relative clause processing difficulties in a variety of languages<br />

where o<strong>the</strong>r accounts fail (e.g., <strong>the</strong> anti-locality effects observed in head final languages), current<br />

models predict <strong>the</strong> wrong locations <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> difficulties in English relative clauses, <strong>and</strong> do not capture<br />

<strong>the</strong> effects of animacy, pronominal status of NPs, discourse structure, or o<strong>the</strong>r factors which have<br />

been shown to affect <strong>the</strong> processing of relative clauses (e.g., Gennari & MacDonald, 2008; Mak et al.,<br />

2008; Reali & Christiansen, 2007; Traxler et al., 2005).<br />

To illustrate why surprisal models fail on English relative clauses, we present data from participantpaced<br />

moving window experiments examining <strong>the</strong> influence of discourse context on relative clause<br />

processing.<br />

We find that when object relative clauses are preceded by a Topic context (1), where <strong>the</strong> embedded<br />

NP is <strong>the</strong> topic of <strong>the</strong> preceding discourse, <strong>the</strong> processing difficulties are reduced compared to <strong>the</strong><br />

Neutral case (3). This is because in natural use, object relatives nearly always contain old in<strong>for</strong>mation<br />

<strong>and</strong> are typically used to relate <strong>the</strong> modified noun back to <strong>the</strong> topic of discourse (Fox & Thompson,<br />

1990).<br />

When object relative clauses are preceded by a Mention context (2), <strong>the</strong> embedded NP 'writer' is read<br />

more slowly than in ei<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> Topic or Neutral case, but <strong>the</strong> remainder of object relative clause (at<br />

both <strong>the</strong> embedded verb <strong>and</strong> main verb region) is faster than when following <strong>the</strong> Neutral context. This<br />

suggests that <strong>the</strong>re is initial surprise at 'writer', since 'publisher' is expected, but that this is still better<br />

than when <strong>the</strong>re is no preceding referent.<br />

We argue that <strong>the</strong> problem with current surprisal models is that <strong>the</strong>y rely only on structure-based<br />

contextual probabilities, <strong>and</strong> that <strong>the</strong>ir ability to account <strong>for</strong> human per<strong>for</strong>mance is improved as <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

models of context are improved.<br />

Examples of Object Relative Clauses preceded by:<br />

(1) Topic Context: The writer was very friendly. The agent that <strong>the</strong> writer trusted …<br />

(2) Mention Context: The publisher sent <strong>the</strong> writer a check every month. The agent that <strong>the</strong> writer<br />

trusted …<br />

(3) Neutral Context: Publishing a book is a very complicated process. The agent that <strong>the</strong> write …<br />

Notes<br />

54


Sensitivity to syntax in visual cortex: The role of phonological typicality<br />

P2<br />

Suzanne Dikker 1 , Hugh A. Rabagliati 1 , Thomas A. Farmer 2 , & Liina Pylkkänen 1<br />

1 New York <strong>University</strong>, USA, 2 Cornell <strong>University</strong>, USA<br />

E-mail: suzanne.dikker@nyu.edu<br />

Introduction<br />

Surprisingly, syntactic violations can affect event-related potentials as early as 120ms (e.g., <strong>the</strong><br />

ELAN, 1). Recently, (2) demonstrated in MEG that reading violations of syntactic expectations<br />

increases <strong>the</strong> amplitude of <strong>the</strong> visual M100 component, generated in visual cortex at ~130ms. This<br />

finding suggests that fine-grained <strong>for</strong>m estimates based on syntactic context are available to sensory<br />

cortices, potentially a key element <strong>for</strong> underst<strong>and</strong>ing how language processing can be so remarkably<br />

fast. Specifically, in 2 experiments an M100 modulation is reported <strong>for</strong> word category violations, but<br />

only if <strong>the</strong> unanticipated element contained a closed-class category-marking morpheme (prepositions<br />

<strong>and</strong> participles with –ed). No M100 effect was found <strong>for</strong> bare stems (e.g., report) or lexically<br />

unambiguous nouns (e.g., tree). This suggested that closed-class morphemes have a special status in<br />

early syntactic processing.<br />

In this study we evaluate an alternative hypo<strong>the</strong>sis—in terms of phonological typicality. It has<br />

previously been shown that phonologically typical nouns are read faster than less typical nouns (3).<br />

We tested whe<strong>the</strong>r an M100 effect of expectedness would be elicited <strong>for</strong> phonologically typical<br />

monomorphemic nouns, which would show that closed-class morphology is, in fact, not necessary <strong>for</strong><br />

this early effect of expectedness.<br />

Method/Design<br />

We evaluated this hypo<strong>the</strong>sis by splitting <strong>the</strong> monomorphemic unambiguous noun targets of (2) into<br />

phonologically typical <strong>and</strong> phonologically neutral conditions (<strong>the</strong> latter sharing features with both<br />

nouns <strong>and</strong> verbs), using <strong>the</strong> typicality scores of (3).<br />

TYPICAL<br />

NEUTRAL<br />

The monster was in <strong>the</strong> horrid STORY<br />

* The monster was in <strong>the</strong> horridly STORY<br />

The bird was behind <strong>the</strong> clean WINDOW<br />

* The bird was behind <strong>the</strong> cleanly WINDOW<br />

Analysis/results<br />

Dipole analysis of <strong>the</strong> M100 peak—consistently localizing in visual cortex—revealed that an M100<br />

effect of expectedness is, in fact, elicited <strong>for</strong> phonologically typical monomorphemic nouns (p=.04).<br />

No such effect was found <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> phonologically neutral nouns.<br />

Conclusion<br />

These findings show that closed-class morphemes are not necessary <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> visual M100 effect of<br />

syntactic expectations: even a probabilistic cue to word category such as phonological typicality is<br />

sufficient <strong>for</strong> this effect to emerge.<br />

References<br />

(1) Friederici AD TiCS 2002<br />

(2) Dikker S, Rabagliati H, Pylkkänen L subm<br />

(3) Farmer TA, Christiansen MH, Monaghan P PNAS 2006<br />

Notes<br />

55


P3<br />

Exchange rate woes <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> spreading activation model too:<br />

A large-scale investigation<br />

Susannah Moat 1 , Martin Corley 1 , & Robert J. Hartsuiker 2<br />

1 PPLS, <strong>University</strong> of Edinburgh, UK, 2 Ghent <strong>University</strong>, Belgium<br />

E-mail: h.s.moat@sms.ed.ac.uk<br />

The spreading activation model proposed by Dell (1986) to account <strong>for</strong> a wide variety of speech error<br />

results has been highly influential. However, some of <strong>the</strong> evidence which <strong>the</strong> model was based on has<br />

recently been questioned. In particular, Nooteboom (2005) has highlighted inadequacies in his<br />

previous corpus calculations of anticipation <strong>and</strong> exchange proportions. We <strong>the</strong>re<strong>for</strong>e used 6 corpora<br />

of speech errors to determine upper <strong>and</strong> lower limits on proportions of anticipations, perseverations,<br />

exchanges <strong>and</strong> non-contextual errors, <strong>and</strong> tested <strong>the</strong> ability of a 50 word model with word, phoneme<br />

<strong>and</strong> feature layers to meet <strong>the</strong>se limits.<br />

To avoid restricting our conclusions to behaviour at an arbitrary point in parameter space, we<br />

orthogonally varied parameter settings, taking into account those used by 5 o<strong>the</strong>r published<br />

simulation studies based on Dell (1986). We were also interested in <strong>the</strong> effect of connectivity settings,<br />

<strong>and</strong> tested <strong>the</strong> model with <strong>and</strong> without phoneme to word feedback, phoneme to feature cascade <strong>and</strong><br />

feature to phoneme feedback. Combining <strong>the</strong>se parameter <strong>and</strong> connectivity settings resulted in 21,870<br />

simulations, each involving 10,000 productions of r<strong>and</strong>omly selected two word utterances.<br />

Results revealed that 96.8% of simulations did not generate enough exchanges. Across simulations,<br />

an average of only 0.87% of contextual word pair errors were exchanges. The models which did<br />

display enough exchanges nearly all generated too many non-contextual errors. 40% of <strong>the</strong>se were<br />

governed by intrinsic noise, with low connection weights, high decay <strong>and</strong> long processing stages. The<br />

o<strong>the</strong>r 60% were flooded with activation, with high connection weights, feedback from features to<br />

phonemes, low decay, <strong>and</strong> high activation dependent noise. 5% of <strong>the</strong>se latter models generated an<br />

appropriate proportion of non-contextual errors, but ei<strong>the</strong>r no perseverations, or less than 85% correct<br />

utterances, depending on <strong>the</strong> presence of phoneme to word feedback.<br />

Both experimental <strong>and</strong> computational future research into phonological encoding needs to take into<br />

account <strong>the</strong> highly surprising but extensive difficulties of this important speech error model in<br />

accounting <strong>for</strong> this basic behaviour pattern.<br />

References<br />

Dell, G. S. (1986). A spreading-activation <strong>the</strong>ory of retrieval in sentence production. Psychological<br />

Review, 93, 283–321.<br />

Nooteboom, S. G. (2005). Listening to oneself: Monitoring in speech production. In R. Hartsuiker, R.<br />

Bastiaanse, A. Postma, & F. Wijnen (Eds.), Phonological encoding <strong>and</strong> monitoring in normal <strong>and</strong><br />

pathological speech (pp. 167–186). Hove, UK: Psychology Press.<br />

Notes<br />

56


P4<br />

Explaining disruption in children's processing of interrupted main clauses:<br />

Discourse entities or similarity-interference<br />

Anna R. Weighall 1 , & Gerry T.M. Altmann 2<br />

1 Sheffield Hallam <strong>University</strong>, UK, 2 <strong>University</strong> of York, UK<br />

E-mail: a.r.weighall@shu.ac.uk<br />

Given a sentence like The cat that bumped <strong>the</strong> bear will hug <strong>the</strong> cow deciding who hugged <strong>the</strong> cow is<br />

difficult <strong>for</strong> children, whereas knowing that <strong>the</strong> cat bumped <strong>the</strong> bear is less error prone (Weighall &<br />

Altmann, 2001). We investigated whe<strong>the</strong>r this disruption is specific to structures containing relative<br />

clauses, or whe<strong>the</strong>r it generalises to any construction where <strong>the</strong> main clause is interrupted by a<br />

subordinate clause (e.g. prepositional phrases or adjectival comments). Two experiments will be<br />

reported that used an auditory comprehension task with 6- to 8- year-olds (N=60; 30 in each<br />

experiment). Children responded to comprehension questions about <strong>the</strong> main clause of structurally<br />

different centre-embedded sentences, <strong>the</strong> mean correct responses (%) <strong>for</strong> each sentence type are<br />

shown below.<br />

Experiment 1 Experiment 2<br />

_________________________________________________________________<br />

SS that bumped <strong>the</strong> bear 27 that bumped <strong>the</strong> lamppost 59<br />

PP next to <strong>the</strong> bear 28 next to <strong>the</strong> lamppost 53<br />

ADJ with <strong>the</strong> striped tail 67 with <strong>the</strong> striped tail 58<br />

__________________________________________________________________<br />

Experiment 1 revealed equal disruption <strong>for</strong> SS <strong>and</strong> PP sentences, suggesting that <strong>the</strong> disruption is not<br />

limited just to relative clauses. Disruption did not extend to all interruption types as per<strong>for</strong>mance in<br />

<strong>the</strong> adjectival comment condition was significantly better. These results could be explained by <strong>the</strong><br />

integration cost account (Gibson, 1994) which suggests that <strong>the</strong> number of unique discourse referents<br />

intervening between a filler <strong>and</strong> attachment site determines processing difficulty. Under this account,<br />

<strong>the</strong> properties of a given entity (e.g., animacy, frequency) do not fur<strong>the</strong>r contribute to processing cost.<br />

However, <strong>the</strong> results of Experiment 1 are also compatible with <strong>the</strong> similarity-based interference<br />

account (Gordon, Hendrick & Johnson, 2001) which suggests that <strong>the</strong> confusability of entities has an<br />

important role to play in sentence complexity. These accounts were contrasted in Experiment 2 by<br />

constructing PP <strong>and</strong> SS sentences maintaining <strong>the</strong> number of discourse entities, but reducing <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

confusability by including an inanimate object in <strong>the</strong> interruption. The data indicate that reducing<br />

confusability greatly improved processing of <strong>the</strong> interrupted main clause, consistent with <strong>the</strong><br />

similarity-based interference account. We conclude that this account can be extended to children’s<br />

syntactic processing <strong>and</strong> that children, who have reduced cognitive capacity compared to adults, may<br />

be particularly susceptible to such interference.<br />

Notes<br />

57


P5<br />

Exploring <strong>the</strong> rules of stress assignment in disyllabic nonwords<br />

Lesley M. Mitchell, & Kathleen Rastle<br />

Royal Holloway, <strong>University</strong> of London, UK<br />

E-mail: l.m.mitchell@rhul.ac.uk<br />

When faced with reading disyllabic English words aloud, how does <strong>the</strong> reader know which syllable to<br />

stress Readers can rely on lexical in<strong>for</strong>mation <strong>for</strong> words that <strong>the</strong>y know, but how is stress assignment<br />

achieved <strong>for</strong> printed nonwords Our work explored this question in <strong>the</strong> context of <strong>the</strong> dual-route<br />

model of reading aloud. Previous research has suggested a number of cues that may play a role in <strong>the</strong><br />

nonlexical assignment of stress, including <strong>the</strong> length of <strong>the</strong> vowel in each syllable, <strong>the</strong> phonological<br />

weight of each syllable, <strong>the</strong> orthographic weight of each syllable, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> presence of prefixes in <strong>the</strong><br />

string. Five experiments that examined <strong>the</strong> reading aloud of disyllabic nonwords were conducted to<br />

test <strong>the</strong> influence of each of <strong>the</strong>se cues. Experiment 1 examined <strong>the</strong> influence of vowel length, <strong>the</strong><br />

rule being that long vowels draw stress. Experiment 2 examined <strong>the</strong> influence of phonological weight,<br />

<strong>the</strong> rule being that syllables with more phonemes draw stress. Experiments 3 <strong>and</strong> 4 examined <strong>the</strong><br />

influence of orthographic weight, <strong>the</strong> rule being that syllables with more letters draw stress. Finally,<br />

Experiment 5 examined <strong>the</strong> influence of morphology, <strong>the</strong> rule being that prefixes repel stress. Results<br />

showed effects of all of <strong>the</strong>se variables on <strong>the</strong> assignment of stress. However, <strong>the</strong> phonological<br />

variables (vowel length <strong>and</strong> phonological weight) had a much more limited influence than did <strong>the</strong><br />

orthographic variables (orthographic weight <strong>and</strong> morphology). Results are discussed in terms of<br />

models of reading aloud.<br />

Notes<br />

58


P6<br />

The speed of relative clause attachment<br />

Patrick Sturt, & Masaya Yoshida<br />

<strong>University</strong> of Edinburgh, UK<br />

E-mail: patrick.sturt@ed.ac.uk<br />

Studies in head final languages has shown that a fully connected syntactic structure is built be<strong>for</strong>e <strong>the</strong><br />

phrasal head is reached in <strong>the</strong> input, contra Pritchett 1992; Abney 1986. This study investigates<br />

whe<strong>the</strong>r a similarly eager parsing strategy is applied in English. Because heads in English normally<br />

occur soon after phrasal onsets, much of <strong>the</strong> existing evidence <strong>for</strong> early structural commitment could<br />

be compatible with a head-driven parsing strategy. A second aim of this research was to examine <strong>the</strong><br />

extent to which a globally coherent syntactic unit is maintained during processing; is each new word<br />

immediately incorporated into a syntactic structure (indicating a strong top-down component to <strong>the</strong><br />

parsing strategy), or is processing better viewed as a sequence of local integrations, which are later<br />

pieced toge<strong>the</strong>r into a global structure, as predicted by more bottom-up parsing strategies.<br />

We focus on <strong>the</strong> processing of post-modifiers, where structural relations are sometimes thought to be<br />

established with delay (e.g. Frazier & Clifton, 1996: Construal).<br />

36 participants read sentences like 1a,b, while <strong>the</strong>ir eye-movements were monitored:<br />

1a Tony doesn't believe it, but Vanity Fair is a film which I ever/never really want to see.<br />

1b Tony doesn't believe that Vanity Fair is a film which I ever/never really want to see.<br />

The critical word "ever"/"never" was varied as a factor in <strong>the</strong> 2x2 design. In 1a, a negative element c-<br />

comm<strong>and</strong>s, thus licenses, "ever" <strong>and</strong>, but not in 1b, where processing difficulty is expected <strong>for</strong> "ever".<br />

Conversely, "never" is expected to exhibit processing difficulty in 1b relative to 1a, because due to<br />

<strong>the</strong> configuration where 'never' must be interpreted under ano<strong>the</strong>r negation operator. This predicted<br />

interaction of Word x Structure was found in regression-path times at <strong>the</strong> critical word, as well as at<br />

<strong>the</strong> following adverb (p's < .05). Because <strong>the</strong> regression-path measure reflects processing be<strong>for</strong>e<br />

following words have been fixated, this result indicates that <strong>the</strong> structural relations necessary <strong>for</strong><br />

computing <strong>the</strong> scope of negation (e.g. c-comm<strong>and</strong>) were available early during <strong>the</strong> processing of <strong>the</strong><br />

relative clause; certainly be<strong>for</strong>e its verbal head had been processed. Thus, <strong>the</strong> modifier was<br />

immediately incorporated into <strong>the</strong> structure. Moreover, <strong>the</strong> relevant structural relation spanned<br />

multiple clauses, supporting <strong>the</strong> notion that <strong>the</strong> syntactic structure is maintained as a globally coherent<br />

unit. A self-paced reading experiment reaching <strong>the</strong> same conclusions with a similar design will be<br />

described as well.<br />

Notes<br />

59


P7<br />

Susceptibility to retroactive interference in verb-phrase ellipsis<br />

Andrea E. Martin, & Brian McElree<br />

New York <strong>University</strong>, USA<br />

E-mail: aem357@nyu.edu<br />

Nonadjacent dependency resolution crucially relies on access to memory representations outside <strong>the</strong><br />

current focus of attention. Unlike many dependencies, <strong>the</strong> antecedent of a verb-phrase ellipsis (VPE)<br />

is fully integrated in its local context, <strong>and</strong> is not grammatically marked. Thus, subsequent retrieval of<br />

<strong>the</strong> antecedent cannot be predicted, precluding <strong>the</strong> engagement of special stacks or buffers in<br />

memory.<br />

Martin <strong>and</strong> McElree (2008) argued that VPE antecedents are content-addressable <strong>and</strong> directly<br />

accessed via a pointer, not a backward search. However, <strong>the</strong>ir data are not incompatible with a<br />

<strong>for</strong>ward search, where <strong>the</strong> search <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> antecedent is launched from <strong>the</strong> beginning of <strong>the</strong> sentence.<br />

We contrasted two retrieval contexts: 1) with interfering material occurring be<strong>for</strong>e <strong>the</strong> onset of <strong>the</strong><br />

antecedent (proactive interference; PI) <strong>and</strong> 2) with material intervening between antecedent <strong>and</strong> VPE<br />

(retroactive interference; RI). In a <strong>for</strong>ward search, PI should slow processing relative to RI, as more<br />

material must be searched to find <strong>the</strong> antecedent. We varied <strong>the</strong> type of interfering material (see<br />

below) in case <strong>the</strong> search operates over a restricted set, endeavoring to test <strong>for</strong> a <strong>for</strong>ward search <strong>and</strong> to<br />

investigate potential sources of interference. We used <strong>the</strong> speed-accuracy tradeoff procedure, where<br />

participants responded (yes/no acceptability) at multiple times during processing, allowing derivation<br />

of accuracy functions over time.<br />

Contra a search process, no differences in processing speed were found. Type of interfering material<br />

did not affect speed or accuracy. However, RI significantly lowered accuracy relative to PI,<br />

suggesting that susceptibility to interference sensitizes comprehenders to <strong>the</strong> recency of <strong>the</strong><br />

antecedent, <strong>and</strong> that comprehension depends on successful retrieval.<br />

PI<br />

1 Sometime in <strong>the</strong> early morning yesterday, Claudia filed a complaint. Ron did too.<br />

2 Even though Claudia was not particularly angry, she filed a complaint. Ron did too.<br />

3 Even though Claudia did not write an angry letter, she filed a complaint. Ron did too.<br />

4 Claudia wrote an angry letter, <strong>and</strong> she also filed a complaint. Ron did too.<br />

RI<br />

5 Claudia filed a complaint. Sometime in <strong>the</strong> early morning yesterday, Ron did too.<br />

6 Claudia filed a complaint. Even though he was not particularly angry, Ron did too.<br />

7 Claudia filed a complaint. Even though he did not write an angry letter, Ron did too.<br />

8 Claudia filed a complaint <strong>and</strong> she also wrote an angry letter. Ron did too.<br />

References<br />

Martin, A. E., & McElree, B. (2008). A content-addressable pointer underlies comprehension of verbphrase<br />

ellipsis. J Mem Lang, 58, 879-906.<br />

Notes<br />

60


P8<br />

Good-enough language processing in a communicative situation<br />

Fern<strong>and</strong>a Ferreira, & Manon W. Jones<br />

<strong>University</strong> of Edinburgh, UK<br />

E-mail: fern<strong>and</strong>a.ferreira@ed.ac.uk<br />

Recent evidence suggests that <strong>the</strong> language comprehension system does not consistently create<br />

accurate <strong>and</strong> detailed representations. Sentence reading experiments show that garden-path (GP)<br />

sentences are sometimes only partially reanalyzed (Christiansen et al., 2001) <strong>and</strong> lead to shallow<br />

processing of material presented after <strong>the</strong> disambiguator (Ferreira & Jones, 2008). Such effects occur<br />

even though <strong>the</strong> tasks allow processing to be extended indefinitely.<br />

In an eye-tracking experiment, we focus on <strong>the</strong> arguably more typical communicative situation in<br />

which input is auditory <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> comprehender has little control over how it is presented. Any limit on<br />

how much time is devoted to processing <strong>and</strong> reanalyzing already presented material is not selfimposed,<br />

but arises from <strong>the</strong> need to deal with new material or generate a response.<br />

We used <strong>the</strong> Visual World Paradigm, in which participants were required to execute an action based<br />

on an ambiguous (GP) or unambiguous (non-GP) auditory instruction (excluding or including <strong>the</strong><br />

word “that’s”). Our measures were per<strong>for</strong>mance accuracy <strong>and</strong> eye movements.<br />

Distractor object Distractor location Click object<br />

e.g., Put <strong>the</strong> book (that’s) on <strong>the</strong> chair into <strong>the</strong> bin. Then click on <strong>the</strong> dress.<br />

Target object<br />

Target location<br />

We predicted that in <strong>the</strong> ambiguous condition, participants would show evidence of difficulty<br />

processing <strong>the</strong> initial instruction, leading to a trade-off in processing post-disambiguating material.<br />

Results supported this prediction. In <strong>the</strong> ambiguous condition, participants showed explicit evidence<br />

of being garden-pa<strong>the</strong>d: They made significantly more errors in picking up <strong>the</strong> distractor object <strong>and</strong><br />

dropping it onto <strong>the</strong> distractor location. Participants also successfully reanalysed <strong>the</strong> sentence on 71%<br />

of <strong>the</strong>se trials (following <strong>the</strong> initial error, <strong>the</strong>y picked up <strong>the</strong> correct target <strong>and</strong> placed it on <strong>the</strong> correct<br />

location). Interestingly, even on correctly-executed trials, participants made a longer first fixation<br />

(associated with cognitive load) to <strong>the</strong> distractor location in <strong>the</strong> ambiguous condition. Moreover, <strong>the</strong><br />

initial processing cost of <strong>the</strong> first instruction led to a trade-off on later material: On postdisambiguator<br />

objects, (target location <strong>and</strong> click object), participants were slower to fixate <strong>and</strong> made<br />

fewer fixations on <strong>the</strong>se regions.<br />

These experiments show that in a typical communicative situation, one or more difficulties during<br />

comprehension leads to shallow processing of later material. We argue that <strong>the</strong> processor’s limited<br />

capacity necessitates this trade-off, such that processing is often just ‘good enough’ to accomplish <strong>the</strong><br />

task at h<strong>and</strong>.<br />

Notes<br />

61


P9<br />

Extracting repetition-based patterns from noise in infancy<br />

Agnes M. Kovacs 1 , & Jacques Mehler 2<br />

1<br />

SISSA, Hungarian Academy of Science, 2 SISSA, Italy<br />

E-mail: agikov1@yahoo.co.uk<br />

In <strong>the</strong> course of language acquisition infants have to learn not only <strong>the</strong> vocabulary of <strong>the</strong>ir native<br />

language, but also its underlying grammatical rules. To extract a specific regularity from <strong>the</strong> rich<br />

linguistic signal infants must possess <strong>the</strong> ability to disregard patterns <strong>the</strong>y cannot yet interpret.<br />

Previous studies suggest that preverbal infants can learn rule-like regularities from artificial minilanguages<br />

(Marcus et al., 1999; Gerken, 2006). In <strong>the</strong>se studies infants could discriminate repetitionbased<br />

regularities when trained with speech-like stimuli that all followed <strong>the</strong> same pattern (e.g.,<br />

AAB). However, in natural environments infants are exposed to a ‘noisy’ linguistic input that<br />

contains multiple regularities. Moreover, <strong>for</strong> an efficient learning one has to go beyond discrimination<br />

<strong>and</strong> integrate <strong>the</strong> extracted patterns into o<strong>the</strong>r representations.<br />

In two experiments we explore whe<strong>the</strong>r preverbal infants can extract regularities from a noisy input,<br />

which contains more than one regularity. Using a TOBII 1750 eye-tracker we investigate how infants<br />

integrate patterns of varying complexity (e.g., adjacent <strong>and</strong> non-adjacent repetitions) into differential<br />

anticipatory eye-movements. This procedure also allows us to directly compare adjacent identity<br />

relations against non-adjacent ones in terms of processing dem<strong>and</strong>s. In Experiment 1, we found that<br />

7-month-old infants generalized <strong>the</strong> AAB patterns (monotonous trisyllabic non-words with repeated<br />

syllables in <strong>the</strong> beginning) but not <strong>the</strong> ABA ones (non-adjacent repetitions), after <strong>the</strong>y were<br />

familiarized with both AAB <strong>and</strong> ABA patterns. Experiment 2 investigated whe<strong>the</strong>r non-adjacent<br />

repetitions (ABA patterns) can be learned when contrasted with r<strong>and</strong>om ABC structures. In this case<br />

7-month-old infants could generalize ABA patterns <strong>and</strong> disregard <strong>the</strong> ABC ones. Infants thus could<br />

extract <strong>the</strong> non-adjacent relations when this was <strong>the</strong> salient regularity.<br />

The data suggests that adjacent repetitions are computationally preferred over non-adjacent<br />

repetitions. Infants seem to consider non-salient patterns as noise <strong>and</strong> successfully ignore it. The<br />

results show that preverbal infants posses powerful abilities to extract regularities from a ‘noisy’<br />

linguistic signal, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> presence of o<strong>the</strong>r patterns does not impair learning.<br />

References<br />

Gerken, L. A. (2006). Decisions, decisions: infant language learning when multiple generalizations<br />

are possible, Cognition 98, 67–74.<br />

Marcus, G. F., Vijayan, S., B<strong>and</strong>i Rao, S., & Vishton, P. (1999). Rule- learning in seven-month-old<br />

infants. Science, 283, 77–80.<br />

Notes<br />

62


Mary exists a ball to John: Structural priming from wrong or nonce<br />

verbs exists<br />

P10<br />

Iva Ivanova 1 , Martin J. Pickering 2 , Holly P. Branigan 2 , Janet McLean 2 , & Albert M. Costa 1<br />

1 Universitat de Barcelona, Spain, 2 <strong>University</strong> of Edinburgh, UK<br />

E-mail: aivichka@yahoo.com<br />

In conversation, speakers tend to repeat <strong>the</strong>ir own <strong>and</strong> each o<strong>the</strong>r’s linguistic choices, which<br />

facilitates communication (a phenomenon known as “alignment”: Pickering & Garrod, 2004). Among<br />

o<strong>the</strong>r things, people are known to repeat sentence structure (e.g., Branigan, Pickering & Clel<strong>and</strong>,<br />

2000; Gries, 2005). Is alignment affected, however, when part of <strong>the</strong> input from <strong>the</strong> interlocutor is<br />

erroneous or incomprehensible, as in <strong>the</strong> frequent case when we converse with non-native speakers of<br />

our language More specifically, we ask if <strong>the</strong> linguistic processor can recognise a sentence structure<br />

when <strong>the</strong> verb a) occurs with wrong morphology; b) is not associated with any semantic in<strong>for</strong>mation;<br />

or c) is associated with wrong semantic <strong>and</strong> structural in<strong>for</strong>mation.<br />

Three structural priming experiments with native English speakers using <strong>the</strong> dative alternation were<br />

conducted to answer <strong>the</strong>se questions. Experiment 1 revealed that a prime sentence containing an<br />

incorrectly regularised past tense (1a) produced <strong>the</strong> same lexical boost as <strong>the</strong> correct <strong>for</strong>m in 1b (<strong>the</strong>re<br />

was more priming from 1a <strong>and</strong> 1b than from 1c). Experiment 2 showed that a sentence containing a<br />

nonce verb (2a) did prime, <strong>and</strong> it primed to <strong>the</strong> same extent as <strong>the</strong> “different verb” prime (2c), in <strong>the</strong><br />

presence of a lexical boost (2b primed more than 2a <strong>and</strong> 2c). In Experiment 3, an existing but strictly<br />

intransitive verb used in <strong>the</strong> ditransitive construction (3a) also produced priming, which was again <strong>the</strong><br />

same as <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> “different verb” condition (2c).<br />

Taken toge<strong>the</strong>r, our results indicate that a structure is recognised <strong>and</strong> can influence subsequent<br />

production even in <strong>the</strong> absence of (correct) semantic <strong>and</strong> structural in<strong>for</strong>mation associated with <strong>the</strong><br />

verb. Our findings are consistent with a view of language representation, in which syntactic frames<br />

carry <strong>the</strong>ir own meanings which are independent of verb meanings. Our results also suggest that, even<br />

though non-native speakers of our language might be having vocabulary or grammar problems, we<br />

still align with <strong>the</strong>m.<br />

Experiment 1<br />

Primes (here DO versions only):<br />

1a. The waitress gived <strong>the</strong> boxer <strong>the</strong> banana.<br />

1b. The waitress gave <strong>the</strong> boxer <strong>the</strong> banana.<br />

1c. The waitress tossed <strong>the</strong> boxer <strong>the</strong> banana.<br />

Target:<br />

1d. nun GIVES ball soldier<br />

Experiment 2<br />

Primes:<br />

2a. The waitress brunks <strong>the</strong> boxer <strong>the</strong> banana.<br />

2b. The waitress gives <strong>the</strong> boxer <strong>the</strong> banana.<br />

2c. The waitress tosses <strong>the</strong> boxer <strong>the</strong> banana.<br />

Target: As in Exp.1<br />

Experiment 3<br />

3a. The waitress exists <strong>the</strong> boxer <strong>the</strong> banana.<br />

3b. The waitress gives <strong>the</strong> boxer <strong>the</strong> banana.<br />

3c. The waitress tosses <strong>the</strong> boxer <strong>the</strong> banana.<br />

Target: As in Exp.1<br />

63


P11<br />

Constraints on <strong>the</strong> construction of counterfactual situation representations<br />

during comprehension: An examination of on-line suppositional processing<br />

Mat<strong>the</strong>w Haigh, Andrew Stewart, & Evan Kidd<br />

<strong>University</strong> of Manchester, UK<br />

E-mail: Andrew.J.Stewart@manchester.ac.uk<br />

In two self-paced reading experiments we examined how readers construct counterfactual situation<br />

representations associated with subjunctive conditionals (e.g., If Darren had been athletic, he could<br />

have tried out <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> rugby team.) While <strong>the</strong>re has been much research on how conditionals are<br />

interpreted in <strong>the</strong> context of reasoning (Evans & Over, 2004), <strong>the</strong> means by which <strong>the</strong>y are<br />

comprehended on-line has not received a similar level of attention in <strong>the</strong> psycholinguistic literature<br />

(but see Ferguson & San<strong>for</strong>d, in press).<br />

We develop an account of suppositional processing that is grounded in <strong>the</strong> literature on reasoning. In<br />

Experiment 1 we manipulated <strong>the</strong> degree of congruency between <strong>the</strong> antecedent of a conditional <strong>and</strong><br />

preceding context (e.g., whe<strong>the</strong>r prior context describes ‘Darren’ as being a<strong>the</strong>ltic or not athletic), <strong>and</strong><br />

whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> conditional was presented in subordinate-main or main-subordinate clause order. The<br />

predictions of two accounts of suppositional processing were tested. A clause order-sensitive account<br />

predicts a congruency effect, but only <strong>for</strong> subordinate-main clause order conditionals. In contrast, a<br />

clause order-invariant account predicts a congruency effect <strong>for</strong> both subordinate-main <strong>and</strong> <strong>for</strong> mainsubordinate<br />

clause order conditionals. We found an interaction between clause order <strong>and</strong> congruency<br />

on reading times (F1(1,35)=9.25, p


A unified priming account of structural choice in sentence production<br />

P12<br />

Andriy Myachykov 1 , Simon Garrod 2 , & Christoph Scheepers 2<br />

1 <strong>University</strong> of Edinburgh, UK, 2 <strong>University</strong> of Glasgow, UK<br />

E-mail: a.myachykov@ed.ac.uk<br />

When people speak, <strong>the</strong>y have to make rapid structural choices taking into account constantly<br />

changing discourse-relevant parameters, stretching from perceptual properties of <strong>the</strong> described<br />

entities to <strong>the</strong> availability of lexical <strong>and</strong> structural in<strong>for</strong>mation. Independent contributions of<br />

perceptual, lexical, <strong>and</strong> structural priming on <strong>the</strong> speaker’s dynamic choice of grammatical structure<br />

are well documented. However, <strong>the</strong>re is a lack of studies exploring interactions between priming<br />

effects associated with different production stages. Such studies are necessary <strong>for</strong> a unified account of<br />

priming of structural choices.<br />

Four Experiments investigated English transitive sentence production using a combination of priming<br />

manipulations associated with different production stages. In each study, participants were presented<br />

with a prime <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong>y described target pictures of transitive events. Perceptual priming was<br />

operationalized as a visual cue to ei<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> Agent or <strong>the</strong> Patient. Structural priming was achieved by<br />

presenting ei<strong>the</strong>r active or passive voice prime sentences. Verb overlap between primes <strong>and</strong> targets<br />

ensured lexical priming. Experiment 1 used all <strong>the</strong> three priming manipulations. Experiment 2 used<br />

only <strong>the</strong> perceptual priming manipulation. Experiment 3 paired perceptual <strong>and</strong> lexical (verb overlap)<br />

priming. Experiment 4 contrasted perceptual <strong>and</strong> structural priming (no verb overlap).<br />

Our results revealed three independent priming effects: speakers were more likely to produce passive<br />

voice sentence when <strong>the</strong>ir attention was directed to <strong>the</strong> Patient. There was also a reliable structural<br />

priming effect. Finally, speakers were more likely to alternate toward passives when <strong>the</strong> verb was<br />

repeated from prime to target. Importantly, interactions between <strong>the</strong>se priming components only<br />

emerged between ‘neighbouring’ production stages. For example, perceptual priming interacted with<br />

lexical priming, which in turn interacted with structural priming while <strong>the</strong>re was no interaction<br />

between <strong>the</strong> perceptual <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> structural priming effects <strong>and</strong> no three-way interaction. This pattern,<br />

first demonstrated in Experiment 1 (including all three priming manipulations), was successfully<br />

replicated in Experiment 3 <strong>and</strong> 4, which tested possible interaction pairs separately. Our findings<br />

provide initial support <strong>for</strong> a unified priming <strong>the</strong>ory of perceptual, lexical, <strong>and</strong> structural determinants<br />

of structural choice in sentence production. The observed interaction patterns suggest differential<br />

decay functions <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> priming effects associated with different production stages.<br />

Notes<br />

65


P13<br />

Morpho-syntactic priming effects in spoken language processing<br />

Angèle B. Brunellière, & Ulrich H. Frauenfelder<br />

<strong>University</strong> of Geneva, Switzerl<strong>and</strong><br />

E-mail: angele.brunelliere@pse.unige.ch<br />

It has often been observed that words in context are recognised more rapidly <strong>and</strong> easily than isolated<br />

words. Although many studies have investigated semantic context effects, <strong>the</strong> literature on morphosyntactic<br />

context effects is sparse. Moreover, <strong>the</strong>re are serious doubts about whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> latter really<br />

reflect automatic processes during word recognition or whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>y are more strategic in nature. This<br />

study addresses this issue with grammatical priming experiments in which participants made lexical<br />

decisions on target items that are preceded by a single item that provides different types of<br />

grammatical context. All involved pairs of primes (pronoun vs. neutral) <strong>and</strong> targets (verb vs. pseudoverb)<br />

producing three contexts: grammatically pronoun congruent (nous chantons), pronoun<br />

incongruent (*vous chantons) or neutral (zous chantons). Three experiments were conducted; <strong>the</strong> first<br />

two involved auditory intramodal priming <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> third crossmodal (visual-auditory) priming. The<br />

two experiments with auditory intramodal priming had ISI durations of 50 <strong>and</strong> 500 ms respectively. A<br />

long ISI was used to determine whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> morpho-syntactic context effects were strategic. A<br />

decrease in <strong>the</strong> size of priming effect at a long ISI with respect to <strong>the</strong> short ISI suggests no strategic<br />

involvement (following <strong>the</strong> same approach as Radeau, Morais & Segui, 1995 <strong>and</strong> Luce, Goldinger,<br />

Auer & Vitevitch, 2000). The results at <strong>the</strong> short ISI showed that <strong>the</strong> pronoun facilitated or inhibited<br />

<strong>the</strong> lexical decision on <strong>the</strong> verb depending on <strong>the</strong> relation (congruent or incongruent) between <strong>the</strong><br />

pronoun <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> verb. In addition, with pseudo-verb targets, faster reaction times (RTs) in <strong>the</strong><br />

pronoun incongruent context were found with respect to <strong>the</strong> neutral <strong>and</strong> pronoun congruent contexts.<br />

No interaction was obtained between grammatical context <strong>and</strong> ISI. The fact that <strong>the</strong> size of morphosyntactic<br />

context effects did not decrease <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> longer ISI suggests that <strong>the</strong>se effects were strategic<br />

<strong>and</strong> already present at short ISI. In <strong>the</strong> third experiment which aims to determine <strong>the</strong> type of strategy<br />

is involved, no effects of context were observed <strong>for</strong> verb targets <strong>and</strong> only slower RTs <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> neutral<br />

context were found with respect to <strong>the</strong> pronoun incongruent context <strong>for</strong> pseudo-verb targets. These<br />

latter results indicate that <strong>the</strong> strategies which develop in intramodal stimulus presentations involved<br />

an expectancy of verbal inflection from <strong>the</strong> pronoun prime on <strong>the</strong> target at sub-lexical level.<br />

Notes<br />

66


P14<br />

A cross-task comparison of masked priming effects <strong>for</strong> differing semantic<br />

prime-target relationships<br />

J. Denard Thomas, & Kenneth I. Forster<br />

<strong>University</strong> of Arizona, USA<br />

E-mail: jdt1@email.arizona.edu<br />

Recent studies have shown that <strong>the</strong>re is a differential priming effect <strong>for</strong> prime-target pairs with<br />

different types of semantic relationships (Bueno & Frenck-Mestre, 2002). In <strong>the</strong> present study, we<br />

sought to investigate <strong>the</strong> extent to which masked semantic priming is an automatic process <strong>and</strong><br />

whe<strong>the</strong>r its effects vary depending upon <strong>the</strong> type of stimuli used. Here, we compared <strong>the</strong> effects of<br />

synonym, antonym, <strong>and</strong> associatively related non-exemplar prime-target pairs in a semantic<br />

categorization task using a masked priming paradigm. These results were contrasted with those seen<br />

when using <strong>the</strong> same stimuli in a lexical decision task. Though an overall semantic priming effect was<br />

obtained when collapsing over all three types of semantic relations in both tasks, significant priming<br />

<strong>for</strong> individual semantic prime-target relationships were only seen in <strong>the</strong> lexical decision task.<br />

Subsequent analysis of <strong>the</strong> data, however, indicates that <strong>the</strong> pattern of priming seen across prime <strong>and</strong><br />

task type vary as a function of participants’ “partial awareness” of <strong>the</strong> prime (Kouider & Dupoux,<br />

2004). As a result, <strong>the</strong> present study demonstrates that masked semantic priming consists of both an<br />

automatic component <strong>and</strong> a strategic component such that it yields differential effects depending on<br />

<strong>the</strong> context of prime exposure.<br />

References<br />

Bueno, S., & Frenck-Mestre, C. (2002). Rapid activation of <strong>the</strong> lexicon: A fur<strong>the</strong>r investigation with<br />

behavioral <strong>and</strong> computational results. <strong>Brain</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Language</strong>, 81(1), 120-130.<br />

Kouider, S., & Dupoux, E. (2004). Partial awareness creates <strong>the</strong> “illusion” of subliminal semantic<br />

priming. Psychological Science, 15(2), 75-81.<br />

Notes<br />

67


P15<br />

Individual differences in agreement planning: The role of<br />

working-memory control<br />

David Taylor 1 , Richard Lewis 2 , & William Badecker 1<br />

1 Johns Hopkins <strong>University</strong>, USA, 2 <strong>University</strong> of Michigan, USA<br />

E-mail: badecker@jhu.edu<br />

We present agreement production data bearing on <strong>the</strong>ories of individual differences in working<br />

memory (WM). Retaining several words in memory elicits more agreement attraction errors—<strong>and</strong><br />

more so <strong>for</strong> participants with low verbal span (attributed by some to WM capacity differences [2]).<br />

We argue such per<strong>for</strong>mance differences follow instead from variation in acquired skills engaged in<br />

<strong>the</strong> efficient control of WM during sentence <strong>for</strong>mulation [3,4]. Our account has <strong>the</strong> advantage that it<br />

is grounded in a detailed computational model of both WM architecture <strong>and</strong> its control structure,<br />

along with explicit hypo<strong>the</strong>ses about what constitutes efficient control.<br />

Participants generated sentences with subjects containing subject relatives (Sub-RCs: <strong>the</strong> lawyer that<br />

— saw <strong>the</strong> men) or object relatives (Obj-RCs: <strong>the</strong> lawyer that <strong>the</strong> men saw —). Afterwards, <strong>the</strong>y<br />

per<strong>for</strong>med a reading span task [1]. More agreement errors occurred with Obj-RCs (8% of scorable<br />

responses) than Sub-RCs (2.6%). Resource limitation <strong>the</strong>ories predict more attraction errors <strong>for</strong> low<br />

span participants because by hypo<strong>the</strong>sis <strong>the</strong>y have reduced WM capacity to devote to <strong>the</strong> agreement<br />

calculation; but errors were in fact more common <strong>for</strong> high-span participants (16%) than <strong>for</strong> low span<br />

participants (4%).<br />

Our computational <strong>the</strong>ory of WM <strong>and</strong> its control suggests that <strong>the</strong> effect may be due to differences in<br />

production control strategies. The <strong>the</strong>ory posits two control tactics that characterize efficient<br />

processing in <strong>the</strong> face of severe WM constraints. One, <strong>the</strong> Minimal-Lag Strategy, maintains a tight<br />

parallelism between syntactic <strong>and</strong> phonological processing. But in this context, <strong>the</strong> strategy interacts<br />

with a key independent property of WM (i.e., retrieval interference) to yield poorer per<strong>for</strong>mance.<br />

More specifically, adhering more closely to <strong>the</strong> ideal Minimal-Lag means that elements of <strong>the</strong> relative<br />

clause are planned be<strong>for</strong>e <strong>the</strong> matrix verb’s agreement values are calculated. Accordingly, retrieving<br />

<strong>the</strong> agreement source (<strong>the</strong> matrix subject) is more likely to be impeded by similarity-based<br />

interference from <strong>the</strong> local noun phrase (<strong>the</strong> subject of <strong>the</strong> relative clause), an effect <strong>for</strong> which <strong>the</strong>re is<br />

independent evidence. In short, more skilled <strong>and</strong> efficient processors are more likely to produce<br />

attraction errors on this construction, consistent with <strong>the</strong> empirical finding <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> assumption that <strong>the</strong><br />

high-span participants are more highly skilled.<br />

References<br />

[1] Daneman & Carpenter 1980, JVLVB19 450-466.<br />

[2] Hartsuiker & Barkhuysen 2006, Lang&CogProc21 181-204.<br />

[3] Lewis 2006, PhD Thesis, CMU.<br />

[4] MacDonald & Christiansen 2002, PsyRev109 35-54.<br />

Notes<br />

68


P16<br />

2- <strong>and</strong> 3-year-olds' accuracy in repeating 4-word sequences is predicted by<br />

familiarity, positional variability <strong>and</strong> latent semantic classes<br />

Colin Bannard 1 , & Danielle E. Mat<strong>the</strong>ws 2<br />

1 Max Planck Institute <strong>for</strong> Evolutionary Anthropology, Leipzig, Germany,<br />

2 <strong>University</strong> of Manchester, UK<br />

E-mail: bannard@eva.mpg.de<br />

Two studies set out to test recent accounts of <strong>the</strong> development of grammar (Tomasello, 2003), which<br />

propose that children 1) remember utterances <strong>the</strong>y hear <strong>and</strong> 2) draw on <strong>the</strong>se to <strong>for</strong>m <strong>the</strong>ir earliest<br />

syntactic generalizations, which are limited-scope constructions with productive slots (e.g. 'A piece of<br />

X') extracted from familiar sequences of words (e.g. 'A piece of toast'). To test <strong>the</strong> first proposal, in<br />

study 1, we used a newly-available, dense corpus of child directed speech (1.7 million words of<br />

maternal input over 0.3 million utterances) to identify frequently-occurring chunks in <strong>the</strong> input (e.g. a<br />

drink of milk) <strong>and</strong> matched, infrequent sequences (e.g. a drink of tea). We tested preschoolers’ ability<br />

to produce <strong>the</strong>se sequences in a sentence repetition test. Twenty-one 3-year-olds <strong>and</strong> 17 2-year-olds<br />

were significantly more likely to correctly repeat frequent than infrequent sequences. Moreover, 3-<br />

year-olds were significantly faster to repeat <strong>the</strong> first 3 words of an item if <strong>the</strong>y <strong>for</strong>med part of a chunk<br />

(e.g. quicker to say 'a drink of' when followed by 'milk' than 'tea'). Study 2 tested <strong>the</strong> proposal that<br />

children draw on stored utterances to extract basic syntactic generalizations in <strong>the</strong> <strong>for</strong>m of lexically<br />

specified constructions (e.g. on <strong>the</strong> basis of knowing 'A piece of toast', 'A piece of cheese' <strong>and</strong> 'A<br />

piece of jigsaw' one might produce a less familiar expression 'A piece of brick'). This study tests <strong>the</strong><br />

hypo<strong>the</strong>ses that children are most likely to detect a productive slot in <strong>the</strong> final position of a four-word<br />

construction if 1) <strong>the</strong> final word is unpredictable given <strong>the</strong> first three words (high slot entropy, or<br />

variability cf. Gomez, 2002) <strong>and</strong> 2) <strong>the</strong> words observed in <strong>the</strong> final position are semantically similar<br />

(high semantic density; measured using a distributional proxy, cf Mirman <strong>and</strong> Magnusson, 2006).<br />

Twenty-eight 2-year-olds <strong>and</strong> 31 3-year-olds were significantly more likely to correctly repeat<br />

unfamiliar variants (e.g. 'A piece of brick') of frequent constructions (e.g. 'A piece of X') if that<br />

construction had high slot entropy <strong>and</strong> semantic density. These results illustrate how plausible<br />

statistical inference might give rise to <strong>the</strong> kind of representations proposed in usage-based accounts of<br />

language acquisition.<br />

References<br />

Gomez, R. L. (2002). Variability <strong>and</strong> detection of invariant structure. Psychological Science, 13(5),<br />

431-436<br />

Mirman, D. <strong>and</strong> Magnuson, J.S. (2006). The Impact of Semantic Neighborhood Density on Semantic<br />

Access. In Proceedings of Cogsci, 1823-1828.<br />

Tomasello, M. (2003). Constructing a <strong>Language</strong>. Harvard <strong>University</strong> Press.<br />

Notes<br />

69


P17<br />

Be positive! The effect of negation on factual <strong>and</strong> counterfactual<br />

language processing<br />

Hea<strong>the</strong>r J. Ferguson 1 , Christoph Scheepers 2 , & Anthony J. San<strong>for</strong>d 2<br />

1 <strong>University</strong> College London, UK, 2 <strong>University</strong> of Glasgow, UK<br />

E-mail: h.ferguson@ucl.ac.uk<br />

Though <strong>the</strong>y are plentiful, previous studies of negation (3) have not lead to a clear account on <strong>the</strong><br />

mechanisms <strong>and</strong> constraints associated with representing negated in<strong>for</strong>mation. Specifically, negation<br />

raises two important processing questions: how quickly is factual knowledge negated, <strong>and</strong> when is an<br />

alternative mental model created It is often reported that negation leads to a delay in processing as<br />

comprehenders must first integrate <strong>the</strong> falsity of <strong>the</strong> negated entity (1,2). However, this suggestion is<br />

difficult to accept in cases where negation is used to affirm a factual proposition. Thus, we examined<br />

<strong>the</strong> relative effects of factuality <strong>and</strong> negation on peoples’ ability to interpret an unfolding spoken<br />

sentence on-line.<br />

Here we report a visual world study investigating <strong>the</strong> time-course of language-mediated eye<br />

movements towards objects in a scene within contexts that set up factual <strong>and</strong> counterfactual scenarios<br />

that ei<strong>the</strong>r did or did not include a negation operator. Linguistic contexts crossed factuality (factual vs<br />

counterfactual) <strong>and</strong> negation (negative vs affirmative) to create four conditions, as in [1a] to [1d]. The<br />

critical second sentence [2] in each passage was presented aurally toge<strong>the</strong>r with a picture showing,<br />

amongst o<strong>the</strong>r things, a factually consistent referent (fish) <strong>and</strong> a counterfactually consistent referent<br />

(carrots).<br />

[1a] If cats were vegetarians...<br />

[1b] If cats were not carnivores...<br />

[1c] Because cats are carnivores...<br />

[1d] Because cats are not vegetarians...<br />

[2] Families could/can feed <strong>the</strong>ir cat something special <strong>and</strong> listen to it purr happily.<br />

Relative proportions of eye-movements to ei<strong>the</strong>r of <strong>the</strong>se referents indicated a lasting factualitydependent<br />

bias towards <strong>the</strong> appropriate factually or counterfactually consistent referent from<br />

1140msec prior to target word onset, e.g.“something special” in [2]. Fur<strong>the</strong>r examination of <strong>the</strong><br />

timing <strong>and</strong> strength of <strong>the</strong>se preferences showed that negated in<strong>for</strong>mation is more difficult to process<br />

than affirmative, unless it confirms our factual knowledge [1d]. However, even in a factual utterance,<br />

negation leads to intrusion from <strong>the</strong> negated concept during language processing.<br />

References<br />

(1) Giora, R. 2006. Anything negatives can do affirmatives can do just as well, except <strong>for</strong> some<br />

metaphors. Journal of Pragmatics,38,981-1014.<br />

(2) Kaup,B. et al. 2006. Processing negated sentences with contradictory predicates: Is a door that is<br />

not open mentally closed Journal of Pragmatics,38,1033-1050.<br />

(3) Kaup,B. et al. In press. The experiential view of language comprehension: How is negated text<br />

in<strong>for</strong>mation represented<br />

Notes<br />

70


P18<br />

The link between <strong>for</strong>m <strong>and</strong> meaning in British Sign <strong>Language</strong>: Lexical<br />

processing effects in semantic <strong>and</strong> phonological decisions<br />

Robin L. Thompson, David P. Vinson, & Gabriella Vigliocco<br />

<strong>University</strong> College London, UK<br />

E-mail: robin.thompson@ucl.ac.uk<br />

Signed languages exploit <strong>the</strong> visual/gestural modality to create iconic expression across a wide range<br />

of basic conceptual structures in which <strong>the</strong> phonetic resources of <strong>the</strong> language are built up into an<br />

analogue of a mental image. Previously, we demonstrated an advantage when <strong>the</strong>re is an iconic link<br />

between phonological <strong>for</strong>m <strong>and</strong> meaning <strong>for</strong> signers of American Sign <strong>Language</strong> (ASL). While<br />

per<strong>for</strong>ming a picture-word matching task signers were faster to make a decision when a specific<br />

property of an object was represented visually in an ASL sign, providing evidence that a strong<br />

relationship between iconic properties of a sign <strong>and</strong> features of an object/picture can aid lexical<br />

retrieval (Thompson, Vinson, Vigliocco, submitted).<br />

Here we ask at which level(s) of representation iconicity plays a role. Signers of British Sign<br />

<strong>Language</strong> were asked to make ei<strong>the</strong>r semantic judgments (object/non-object), or phonological<br />

judgments (does <strong>the</strong> sign have straight or bent fingers). If iconicity facilitates processing at <strong>the</strong> level<br />

of meaning only, it should affect per<strong>for</strong>mance in semantic decision, but not in phonological decisions<br />

where <strong>the</strong> meaning of signs is unimportant. Subjects' response latencies were subjected to multiple<br />

regression with iconicity entered after familiarity <strong>and</strong> age of acquisition ratings. For phonological<br />

decisions, iconicity was a significant predictor (st<strong>and</strong>ardized beta = .065, t=2.135, p=.033,<br />

rpartial=.055): more iconic signs led to slower responses. However, in <strong>the</strong> semantic condition<br />

iconicity ratings did not predict response times (st<strong>and</strong>ardized beta = -.016, p>.5). The significant<br />

effect of iconicity in <strong>the</strong> phonological condition indicates that iconicity affects processing<br />

automatically: if meaning related properties are activated because <strong>the</strong>y are iconically represented in<br />

<strong>the</strong> <strong>for</strong>m, <strong>the</strong>y can render judgments on o<strong>the</strong>r dimensions more difficult. The lack of iconicity effects<br />

on semantic decision can be explained in terms of lack of direct relevance between <strong>the</strong> specific<br />

decision (object/non-object) <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> iconic link being activated (i.e., that <strong>the</strong> sign <strong>for</strong> CAT is iconic of<br />

cat’s whiskers gives no clues about whe<strong>the</strong>r it is an object or not). The findings are discussed in terms<br />

of <strong>the</strong> relationship between language <strong>and</strong> imagery (including how language can be influenced by<br />

modality, i.e., speech/sign) <strong>and</strong> more generally between language <strong>and</strong> cognition.<br />

References<br />

Thompson, R. L., Vinson, D. P., Vigliocco, G. (submitted).The link between <strong>for</strong>m <strong>and</strong> meaning in<br />

American Sign <strong>Language</strong>: Lexical processing effects<br />

Notes<br />

71


P19<br />

Topicality <strong>and</strong> animacy interact to determine word order preferences<br />

in Chinese<br />

Luming Wang 1 , Matthias Schlesewsky 2 , & Ina Bornkessel-Schlesewsky 1<br />

1<br />

Max Planck Institute <strong>for</strong> Human Cognitive <strong>and</strong> <strong>Brain</strong> Sciences, Leipzig, Germany,<br />

2 Johannes Gutenberg <strong>University</strong>, Mainz, Germany<br />

E-mail: bornke@cbs.mpg.de<br />

Word order preferences are among <strong>the</strong> most robust phenomena in sentence comprehension. For<br />

example, <strong>the</strong> tendency to analyse an ambiguous first argument as <strong>the</strong> subject of <strong>the</strong> sentence has been<br />

observed in several languages including Dutch, German, Italian <strong>and</strong> Turkish. Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, previous<br />

findings from German <strong>and</strong> Turkish suggest that <strong>the</strong> “subject-preference” is independent of animacy<br />

(Schlesewsky et al., 2000; Demiral et al., 2008).<br />

To examine whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>se properties generalise cross-linguistically, we investigated word order<br />

preferences in M<strong>and</strong>arin Chinese. Chinese has been described as a “topic prominent” language, in<br />

which grammatical generalisations are better described via <strong>the</strong> notion of topic ra<strong>the</strong>r than subject.<br />

This might lead to an object-preference given <strong>the</strong> right contextual setting. Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, analyses of<br />

Chinese often highlight <strong>the</strong> importance of semantics/pragmatics. Hence, features like animacy may<br />

influence word order preferences.<br />

These issues were investigated by means of an auditory ERP study, in which native Chinese speakers<br />

(N=25) listened to question-answer pairs as in (1). OSV/SOV word orders are possible in Chinese<br />

when a context is provided. We employed a context which is possible <strong>for</strong> all <strong>the</strong> conditions but favors<br />

an OSV word order. The two preverbal arguments always differed in animacy <strong>and</strong> word order was<br />

disambiguated by <strong>the</strong> clause-final verb.<br />

(1) Literal translations of <strong>the</strong> Chinese conditions<br />

Context: What about <strong>the</strong> detective<br />

a. Detective bullet kept. (“The detective kept <strong>the</strong> bullet.”)<br />

b. Detective bullet hit. (“The bullet hit <strong>the</strong> detective.”)<br />

Context: What about <strong>the</strong> bullet<br />

c. Bullet detective kept. (“The detective kept <strong>the</strong> bullet.”)<br />

d. Bullet detective hit. (“The bullet hit <strong>the</strong> detective.”)<br />

ERPs at <strong>the</strong> disambiguating verb showed an interaction of order <strong>and</strong> animacy. Sentences with initial<br />

inanimate NPs (1c/d) showed an anterior negativity (450-850 ms) <strong>for</strong> SOV (1d) vs. OSV (1c). By<br />

contrast, sentences with initial animates (1a/b) showed a somewhat less pronounced, but reversed<br />

effect, i.e. a negativity <strong>for</strong> OSV (1b) vs. SOV (1a).<br />

Our results suggest that <strong>the</strong> processing system strongly prefers an OSV analysis when it is supported<br />

by animacy. In case of a conflict between animacy <strong>and</strong> word order, by contrast, <strong>the</strong> animacy cue<br />

dominates, thus leading to an SOV-preference. However, <strong>the</strong> smaller ERP effect points to some<br />

residual processing cost <strong>for</strong> (1a) in comparison to <strong>the</strong> optimal (1c).<br />

We conclude that word order preferences during online sentence comprehension are crucially<br />

influenced by language-specific characteristics.<br />

Notes<br />

72


P20<br />

An exemplar-based model of <strong>the</strong>matic fit<br />

Bram V<strong>and</strong>ekerckhove, & Dominiek S<strong>and</strong>ra<br />

<strong>University</strong> of Antwerp, Belgium<br />

E-mail: bram.v<strong>and</strong>ekerckhove@ua.ac.be<br />

This study presents an exemplar-based model that learns Thematic Fit between noun phrases <strong>and</strong><br />

verbs, i.e. <strong>the</strong> plausibility that <strong>the</strong> noun phrase is <strong>the</strong> agent or patient of <strong>the</strong> verb, from a text corpus.<br />

Thematic Fit is one of <strong>the</strong> constraints that have been said to play a role in <strong>the</strong> resolution of <strong>the</strong> wellinvestigated<br />

main verb / reduced relative ambiguity (MacDonald & Seidenberg, 2006). The model<br />

presented here <strong>for</strong>ms <strong>the</strong> first step in <strong>the</strong> development of an exemplar-based model of human sentence<br />

comprehension. Exemplar-based models of language processing (Daelemans & Van den Bosch,<br />

2005) explicitly store every language experience in memory. New linguistic tasks are solved on <strong>the</strong><br />

basis of similarity-based analogies with <strong>the</strong>se stored experiences. The relatively recent success of<br />

exemplar-based parsers in computational linguistics (Bod, 2006) opens up opportunities <strong>for</strong><br />

exemplar-based language processing as an explanatory model of human sentence processing.<br />

We will discuss <strong>the</strong> results of ongoing simulations in which an exemplar-based learning mechanism<br />

assigns verb-noun pairs (e.g. arrest–cop) to semantic roles. These test items were taken from a<br />

number of Thematic Fit rating studies. The training set <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> exemplar-based learner consists of<br />

verb-noun pairs extracted from a large text corpus that has been automatically enriched with semantic<br />

role labels. The model predicts that Relative Support <strong>for</strong> a semantic role among <strong>the</strong> exemplars in<br />

memory that are semantically most similar to <strong>the</strong> test item (i.e. <strong>the</strong> relative frequency of that semantic<br />

role among <strong>the</strong> nearest neighbors) correlates well with <strong>the</strong> mean participant ratings <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> assignment<br />

of <strong>the</strong> test item to that semantic role (Thematic Fit). We use dependency-based word similarity (Lin,<br />

1998) as a measure of semantic similarity. Preliminary simulations with a smaller training set suggest<br />

that exemplar-based generalization could indeed be a good model of human semantic role<br />

preferences.<br />

References<br />

Bod, R. (2006). Exemplar-based syntax: How to get productivity from examples. The Linguistic<br />

Review, 23, 275-290.<br />

Daelemans, W. & Van den Bosch, A. (2005). Memory-based language processing. Cambridge:<br />

Cambridge <strong>University</strong> Press.<br />

Lin, D. (1998). Automatic retrieval <strong>and</strong> clustering of similar words. In: Proceedings of<br />

COLING/ACL-98 (pp. 768-774). Montreal.<br />

MacDonald, M. C. & Seidenberg, M. S. (2006). Constraint satisfaction accounts of lexical <strong>and</strong><br />

sentence comprehension. In: M. J. Traxler, & M. A. Gernsbacher (Eds.), H<strong>and</strong>book of<br />

psycholinguistics (pp. 581-611). Amsterdam: Academic Press.<br />

Notes<br />

73


P21<br />

Focus <strong>and</strong> emphasis devices modulate depth of processing as reflected in<br />

semantic anomaly detection<br />

Jason Bohan, Anthony J. San<strong>for</strong>d, Kirsten Glen, Fiona Clark, & Emily Martin<br />

<strong>University</strong> of Glasgow, UK<br />

E-mail: j.bohan@psy.gla.ac.uk<br />

The failure to detect that Moses is anomalous in “How many animals did Moses take on <strong>the</strong> Ark”<br />

(Noah built <strong>the</strong> Ark), has been ascribed to shallow semantic analysis (Erickson & Matteson, 1981;<br />

San<strong>for</strong>d & Sturt, 2002). There is also some evidence that when a word is in linguistic focus, it is<br />

af<strong>for</strong>ded more extensive semantic processing (Bredart & Modolo, 1988; Bredart & Docquier, 1989),<br />

but <strong>the</strong> evidence is very restricted. We present three experiments that support <strong>and</strong> extend <strong>the</strong>se<br />

findings.<br />

Participants judged whe<strong>the</strong>r stories contained an anomalous word or not <strong>and</strong> reported anomalies<br />

reported to <strong>the</strong> experimenter. In all experiments, critical words were rendered anomalous or coherent<br />

through a manipulation of context, as in (1):<br />

(1) (Scenario: A hijacked plane) The authorities {negotiated/communicated} with <strong>the</strong> scared<br />

hostages <strong>and</strong> helped calm <strong>the</strong>m down.<br />

The critical word, hostages, was rendered anomalous in <strong>the</strong> context negotiated, <strong>and</strong> coherent in <strong>the</strong><br />

context communicated.<br />

First, it was found that <strong>the</strong> rate of detection was higher when an anomalous word was placed within<br />

<strong>the</strong> scope of focus in an it-cleft sentence (Experiment 1), <strong>and</strong> when attention was focussed through <strong>the</strong><br />

use of typographical devices such as bold or uppercase lettering (Experiments 2 <strong>and</strong> 3). This supports<br />

earlier work. Secondly, it was shown (Experiment 2) that uppercase emphasis increased detection rate<br />

whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> context word or <strong>the</strong> target word was emphasized, showing that shallow processing of<br />

context words can occur. Finally, in Experiment 3 reading time data was recorded, <strong>and</strong> participants<br />

rated how confident <strong>the</strong>y were in <strong>the</strong>ir own judgment of whe<strong>the</strong>r an anomaly was present or absent.<br />

These data was partitioned into instances of detected <strong>and</strong> undetected anomalies. Detected anomalies<br />

were read faster when focused, but undetected anomalies were read more slowly when focussed.<br />

Confidence was lower <strong>for</strong> undetected anomalies that were focussed. The results independently<br />

suggest that focus controls attention deployment, <strong>and</strong> that detection/non-detection states may be on a<br />

continuum ra<strong>the</strong>r than all-or-none,<br />

References<br />

Brédart, S., &Modolo, K. (1988). Moses strikes again: Focalization effect on a semantic illusion. Acta<br />

Psychologica: International Journal of Psychonomics, 67, 135-144.<br />

Erickson, T.D., & Mattson, M.E. (1981) From Words to Meaning: A Semantic Illusion. Journal of<br />

Verbal Learning <strong>and</strong> Behaviour, 20, 540-551.<br />

San<strong>for</strong>d, A.J. & Sturt, P. (2002). Depth of processing in language comprehension: not noticing <strong>the</strong><br />

evidence. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 6, 382-386.<br />

Notes<br />

74


Lexical decision on German prefixed verbs: Full <strong>for</strong>m <strong>and</strong> root<br />

frequency effects<br />

P22<br />

Judith Heide, Luise Bartels, Antje Lorenz, & Frank Burchert<br />

<strong>University</strong> of Potsdam, Germany<br />

E-mail: burchert@ling.uni-potsdam.de<br />

One possibility to determine whe<strong>the</strong>r a complex word’s full <strong>for</strong>m <strong>and</strong>/ or its constituent morphemes<br />

are accessed when <strong>the</strong>y are processed is to test <strong>for</strong> frequency effects. While effects of surface<br />

frequency are commonly interpreted as evidence <strong>for</strong> full listing models, root frequency effects<br />

support parsing <strong>the</strong>ories. Diverging evidence led to <strong>the</strong> development of dual route models, <strong>and</strong><br />

several lexical parameters have been proposed to determine which route is activated when processing<br />

a complex word. One of <strong>the</strong>se parameters is surface frequency <strong>and</strong> it is suggested that high frequent<br />

words are processed holistically while low frequent full <strong>for</strong>ms undergo morphological<br />

(de)composition (e.g. Baayen & Dijkstra, 2003).<br />

The aim of <strong>the</strong> present study was to investigate if <strong>and</strong> how <strong>the</strong> processing of German derived words is<br />

influenced by <strong>the</strong> items’ root <strong>and</strong> surface frequency. Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, we tested whe<strong>the</strong>r masked<br />

morphological priming is equally effective <strong>for</strong> items with high <strong>and</strong> low frequent roots <strong>and</strong> full <strong>for</strong>ms.<br />

We used two sets of German ver-prefixed verbs (e.g. verarmen ~ to impoverish): In Set 1, items were<br />

matched <strong>for</strong> root frequency <strong>and</strong> surface frequency was ei<strong>the</strong>r high or low. In Set 2, surface frequency<br />

was comparable but <strong>the</strong> root was ei<strong>the</strong>r high or low frequent. 64 native speakers of German took part<br />

in <strong>the</strong> experiment. Targets were presented toge<strong>the</strong>r with various fillers in a visual lexical decision<br />

task. Masked morphological priming was applied using a 66 ms prime which was ei<strong>the</strong>r a related or<br />

unrelated root or a related or unrelated combination of root <strong>and</strong> suffix (-en).<br />

Response latencies revealed that both surface <strong>and</strong> root frequency influence <strong>the</strong> processing of German<br />

ver-prefixed verbs. Items with high root or surface frequencies are processed faster than <strong>the</strong>ir low<br />

frequent counterparts. To explain such a pattern, Taft (1979) suggested that root frequency effects<br />

reflect access to <strong>the</strong> lemma level while surface frequency effects suggest how easily <strong>the</strong> stem can be<br />

combined with its affixes. A decompositional account is supported by <strong>the</strong> fact that we found<br />

morpheme-based priming effects. However, priming was more effective <strong>for</strong> low frequent than <strong>for</strong><br />

high frequent full <strong>for</strong>ms, which points to dual route processing.<br />

References<br />

Baayen, H. & Dijkstra, T.R. (2003). Frequency effects in regular inflectional morphology: revisiting<br />

Dutch plurals. In H. Baayen & R. Schreuder (Eds.), Morphological structure in language<br />

processing (pp. 355-390), Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.<br />

Taft, M. (1979). Recognition of affixed words <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> word frequency effect. Memory & Cognition,<br />

7, 262-272.<br />

Notes<br />

75


P23<br />

Processing of regular <strong>and</strong> irregular past tense morphology in highly<br />

proficient L2 learners of English: A self-paced reading study<br />

Christos Pliatsikas, & Theodoros Marinis<br />

<strong>University</strong> of Reading, UK<br />

E-mail: c.pliatsikas@reading.ac.uk<br />

According to dual-models of processing, e.g., Pinker (1999), processing of English past-tense<br />

morphology involves two distinct routes: regular verbs involve <strong>the</strong> application of a rule, whereas<br />

irregular verbs are retrieved directly from <strong>the</strong> mental lexicon.<br />

For <strong>the</strong> processing of past-tense morphology in Second <strong>Language</strong> (L2) learners, Ullman (2001)<br />

suggested that <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> processing of regular verbs, L2 learners should rely more on memory ra<strong>the</strong>r<br />

than rule application. This was recently supported in a masked priming experiment with L2 learners<br />

of English (Silva & Clahsen, in press).<br />

The present study investigates <strong>the</strong> processing of regularly <strong>and</strong> irregularly inflected verbs along with<br />

regularised <strong>and</strong> irregularised verbs embedded in sentences using <strong>the</strong> self-paced reading paradigm.<br />

Regular <strong>and</strong> irregular verbs were matched on frequency, length <strong>and</strong> neighbourhood density. 30 native<br />

speakers of English <strong>and</strong> 60 highly proficient Greek learners of English completed this task along with<br />

an English proficiency test. Half of <strong>the</strong> Greek participants were living in <strong>the</strong> UK <strong>and</strong> had exposure to<br />

English in a naturalistic environment, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r half were living in Greece <strong>and</strong> had no naturalistic<br />

exposure to English. Participants pressed a button to read each phrase <strong>and</strong> at <strong>the</strong> end of <strong>the</strong> sentence<br />

<strong>the</strong>y had to answer a comprehension question.<br />

All groups were equally accurate in answering <strong>the</strong> comprehension questions. Reaction Time (RT)<br />

data at <strong>the</strong> critical segment revealed that overall native speakers had shorter RTs than L2 learners.<br />

Irregularized verbs showed longer RTs than irregular verbs across all groups, but regularised were<br />

slower than regulars only <strong>for</strong> L2 learners. Finally, regular verbs showed longer RTs than irregular<br />

verbs in all three groups. This suggests that similarly to native speakers, highly proficient L2 learners<br />

of English are capable of using combinatorial processing of morphologically complex words when<br />

<strong>the</strong>y process verbs embedded in sentences irrespectively of <strong>the</strong>ir exposure to <strong>the</strong> L2.<br />

References<br />

Pinker, S. (1999). Words <strong>and</strong> Rules: The ingredients of language. London: Weidenfeld & Nicolson.<br />

Silva, R. & Clahsen, H. (in press): Morphologically Complex Words in L1 <strong>and</strong> L2 Processing:<br />

Evidence from Masked Priming Experiments in English, Bilingualism: <strong>Language</strong> <strong>and</strong> Cognition.<br />

Ullman, M. T. (2001): The neural basis of lexicon <strong>and</strong> grammar in first <strong>and</strong> second language: <strong>the</strong><br />

declarative/procedural model. Bilingualism: <strong>Language</strong> <strong>and</strong> Cognition 4: 105-122.<br />

Notes<br />

76


P24<br />

Lexical overlap effects on syntactic priming: Evidence against a privileged<br />

status of verbs<br />

Claudine N. Raffray 1 , Christoph Scheepers 1 , & Andriy Myachykov 2<br />

1 <strong>University</strong> of Glasgow, UK, 2 <strong>University</strong> of Edinburgh, UK<br />

E-mail: c.raffray@psy.gla.ac.uk<br />

Research on PO/DO priming in production has shown enhanced priming when <strong>the</strong> verb is repeated<br />

between prime <strong>and</strong> target (e.g., Pickering & Branigan, 1998; Branigan et al., 2000; Corley &<br />

Scheepers, 2002). Such effects have been explained in relation to combinatorial in<strong>for</strong>mation linked to<br />

verbs (e.g. Pickering & Branigan, 1998). However, to date it remains unclear whe<strong>the</strong>r such lexical<br />

boost effects are indeed specific to verb-repetition or whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>y also occur with repetition of non-<br />

VP-heads.<br />

We report an experiment (60 participants, 80 items) examining <strong>the</strong> degree to which lexical overlap<br />

effects on PO/DO priming are bound to verb repetition, <strong>and</strong> measured <strong>the</strong> contribution of verbarguments<br />

to such effects. Using <strong>the</strong> Potter <strong>and</strong> Lombardi (1990, 1998) sentence recall paradigm,<br />

participants were presented with PO/DO sentences <strong>for</strong> production. Following a nested pattern of<br />

presentation <strong>and</strong> recall, participants first read aloud <strong>the</strong> target (e.g., The editor gave <strong>the</strong> critic <strong>the</strong><br />

manuscript), followed by <strong>the</strong> prime (e.g., The cardinal sent <strong>the</strong> envelope to <strong>the</strong> jury). They were <strong>the</strong>n<br />

prompted to verbally recall <strong>the</strong> prime followed by <strong>the</strong> target. (The reverse prompting order was<br />

employed in 100 out of 120 fillers.) We manipulated three factors: Prime Structure (PO vs. DO),<br />

Target Structure (PO vs. DO), <strong>and</strong> Lexical Overlap (no overlap vs. agent vs. verb vs. <strong>the</strong>me vs.<br />

recipient overlap).<br />

Results showed an overall tendency to repeat prime structure during target recall, exceeding chance<br />

by 7% (ps < .01). Crucially, <strong>the</strong>re was also an interaction between Lexical Overlap <strong>and</strong> amount of<br />

structural repetition (ps < .03): both <strong>the</strong> no overlap <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> agent overlap conditions produced scant<br />

priming, whereas <strong>the</strong> verb, <strong>the</strong>me, <strong>and</strong> recipient overlap conditions elicited above-chance priming.<br />

Contrasts with <strong>the</strong> no overlap condition revealed no effect of agent overlap (ps > .3), but reliable<br />

effects of verb overlap, <strong>the</strong>me overlap, <strong>and</strong> recipient overlap (ps < .05); <strong>the</strong> latter three were roughly<br />

equal in magnitude (9% priming compared to <strong>the</strong> baseline).<br />

Hence, <strong>the</strong> verb does not enjoy a privileged status with respect to lexical overlap effects since<br />

repetition of VP-internal arguments (<strong>the</strong>me or recipient) yields <strong>the</strong> same boost in priming. In contrast,<br />

repeating <strong>the</strong> VP-external subject (agent) does not enhance priming. In line with Chang et al. (2006),<br />

we argue that repeated content words serve as memory cues to <strong>the</strong> syntax of <strong>the</strong> prime. However, <strong>the</strong><br />

effectiveness of such cues is constrained by syntactic constituency, as lexical repetition of a VPexternal<br />

agent does not boost PO/DO priming.<br />

Notes<br />

77


P25<br />

Processing derivational <strong>and</strong> inflectional morphology in visual word<br />

recognition<br />

Caroline M. Whiting, Yury Shtyrov, & William D. Marslen-Wilson<br />

MRC Cognition & <strong>Brain</strong> Sciences Unit, Cambridge, UK<br />

E-mail: caroline.whiting@mrc-cbu.cam.ac.uk<br />

The role of morphological complexity during word recognition was assessed in a series of<br />

behavioural <strong>and</strong> electrophysiological experiments. Previous research has argued <strong>for</strong> an early<br />

decomposition stage based on <strong>the</strong> presence of morpho-orthographic cues, even in <strong>the</strong> absence of any<br />

semantic relationship between <strong>the</strong> stem <strong>and</strong> whole <strong>for</strong>m (corn-er as well as farm-er). This raises<br />

issues about <strong>the</strong> structure of lexical representations <strong>and</strong> access to <strong>the</strong> meanings of complex <strong>for</strong>ms<br />

through visual <strong>and</strong> auditory input. This work aimed to compare processing of inflectionally <strong>and</strong><br />

derivationally complex <strong>for</strong>ms, focusing on visual word recognition. Within <strong>the</strong> masked priming<br />

paradigm, we found equivalent priming <strong>for</strong> complex (blink-ed, farm-er) <strong>and</strong> pseudo-complex (corner)<br />

<strong>for</strong>ms, but not <strong>for</strong> words that share <strong>for</strong>m overlap (scan-dal). Using magnetoencephalography<br />

(MEG), we examined <strong>the</strong> precise time course of morphological processing <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> stages involved in<br />

decomposing potential complexity. Source analysis using L2-minimum-norm estimates (MNE)<br />

revealed a largely left-lateralised fronto-temporal network activated during word recognition. At <strong>the</strong><br />

M170, complex <strong>and</strong> pseudo-complex words could be differentiated from words containing <strong>for</strong>m<br />

overlap. Lexicality effects were found at approximately 200 ms, indicating <strong>the</strong> initiation of lexical<br />

access. At 400 ms, pseudo-complex <strong>for</strong>ms showed greater activation than complex <strong>for</strong>ms in left<br />

frontal <strong>and</strong> superior temporal regions. These data are consistent with <strong>the</strong> hypo<strong>the</strong>sis that additional<br />

processing at a post-lexical stage is required to access <strong>the</strong> appropriate meaning of incorrectly<br />

segmented words. Our findings support recent behavioural <strong>and</strong> imaging results pointing to a<br />

processing stage during visual word recognition that is sensitive to orthographic complexity.<br />

Notes<br />

78


P26<br />

Focus alternatives <strong>and</strong> contextual domain restriction: An eye-tracking<br />

study on <strong>the</strong> interpretation of “only”<br />

Christina S. Kim, Christine Gunlogson, Michael K. Tanenhaus, & Jeffrey T. Runner<br />

<strong>University</strong> of Rochester, USA<br />

E-mail: ckim@bcs.rochester.edu<br />

Interpreting sentences with focus-sensitive items like only requires <strong>the</strong> context to restrict <strong>the</strong> domain<br />

of alternatives <strong>for</strong> evaluating <strong>the</strong> focused expression [1]. But what in<strong>for</strong>mation sources do listeners<br />

actually use Two visual world eyetracking experiments show <strong>the</strong>y use both preceding linguistic<br />

context (Exp1) <strong>and</strong> implicit conceptual knowledge about <strong>the</strong> world (Exp2).<br />

Exp1. How does preceding discourse context affect only interpretion Participants heard a context<br />

sentence mentioning 2 items <strong>and</strong> a target sentence mentioning a target item that was ei<strong>the</strong>r discoursenew<br />

or previously mentioned; <strong>the</strong> target sentence contained only or not (1). Eye movements were<br />

tracked as <strong>the</strong>y listened to <strong>the</strong> target sentence <strong>and</strong> clicked on Sue’s items in a 4-picture display.<br />

Earlier target disambiguation was predicted when Mention or Only created an expectation that <strong>the</strong><br />

focused word corresponded to <strong>the</strong> target.<br />

There was a main effect of Mention (all p


P27<br />

Competition of visual <strong>and</strong> linguistic resources: Effects of intonational<br />

breaks <strong>and</strong> salience on <strong>the</strong> interpretation of structurally ambiguous<br />

sentences<br />

Moreno I. Coco, & Frank Keller<br />

<strong>University</strong> of Edinburgh, UK<br />

E-mail: M.I.Coco@sms.ed.ac.uk<br />

Visual world experiments have shown that speech processing <strong>and</strong> visual attention are closely<br />

timelocked, <strong>and</strong> that both visual <strong>and</strong> linguistic in<strong>for</strong>mation can be used <strong>for</strong> disambiguation during<br />

utterance comprehension (e.g., Tanenhaus et al., 1995; Crocker, 2006). However, it is currently<br />

unclear how <strong>the</strong>se two sources of in<strong>for</strong>mation interact; it is conceivable, <strong>for</strong> instance, that low-level<br />

visual in<strong>for</strong>mation is used rapidly, be<strong>for</strong>e any linguistic knowledge can be brought to bear.<br />

Alternatively, an interactive view is possible that assumes all in<strong>for</strong>mation sources are used<br />

concurrently.<br />

We present two visual world studies that address this issue by investigating <strong>the</strong> assignment of<br />

referents in a syntactically ambiguous context. Experiment 1 tested <strong>the</strong> role of intonational breaks in<br />

<strong>the</strong> resolution of PP attachments ambiguities in sentences such as "The girl will put <strong>the</strong> orange on <strong>the</strong><br />

tray in <strong>the</strong> bowl". These sentences were presented in a fully ambiguous visual context (depicting, e.g.,<br />

an orange on <strong>the</strong> tray, a tray in <strong>the</strong> bowl, <strong>and</strong> a tray). The design crossed <strong>the</strong> number of visual<br />

referents (one or two oranges) with <strong>the</strong> position of <strong>the</strong> intonational break, ei<strong>the</strong>r at <strong>the</strong> NP modifier<br />

(break after "orange") or at <strong>the</strong> PP goal modifier (break after "on <strong>the</strong> tray"). The results show that <strong>the</strong><br />

intonational in<strong>for</strong>mation facilitates <strong>the</strong> resolution of <strong>the</strong> attachment ambiguity, both in <strong>the</strong> onereferent<br />

<strong>and</strong> in <strong>the</strong> two-referent condition.<br />

Experiment 2 tested <strong>the</strong> effect of visual saliency on ambiguity resolution. Saliency (e.g., Itti et al.,<br />

1998) is a low-level measure of visual prominence. It can be computed automatically based on image<br />

features such as color, intensity, <strong>and</strong> orientation. This experiment crossed <strong>the</strong> one/two referent<br />

condition from Experiment 1 with a saliency manipulation analogous to <strong>the</strong> intonation condition:<br />

ei<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> NP modifier or <strong>the</strong> PP goal modifier were visually salient. A no-saliency baseline was also<br />

included. The results show that saliency influences ambiguity resolution, though its effect differs<br />

from that of intonation. Intonational breaks mainly influence <strong>the</strong> time course over which competing<br />

syntactic representations are maintained, while saliency in<strong>for</strong>mation can resolve competition by<br />

making it possible to anticipate continuations of syntactic structure. This finding suggets a model in<br />

which low-level visual features are used be<strong>for</strong>e linguistic in<strong>for</strong>mation such as intonation is brought to<br />

bear.<br />

References<br />

Crocker, P. K. M. W. (2006). The coordinated interplay of scene, utterance, <strong>and</strong> world knowledge:<br />

Evidence from eye tracking. Cognitive Science, 30 , 481-529.<br />

Itti, L., Koch, C., & Niebur, E. (1998). A model of saliency-based visual attention <strong>for</strong> rapid scene<br />

analysis. IEEE Transactions on Pattern Analysis <strong>and</strong> Machine Intelligence, 20 , 1254-1259.<br />

Tanenhaus, M. K., Spivey-Knowlton, M. J., Eberhard, K. M., & Sedivy, J. C. (1995). Integration of<br />

visual <strong>and</strong> linguistic in<strong>for</strong>mation in spoken language comprehension. Science, 268, 1632-1634.<br />

Notes<br />

80


Event structure coordination in dialogue: Evidence from coercion<br />

P28<br />

Claudine N. Raffray, Martin J. Pickering, & Holly P. Branigan<br />

<strong>University</strong> of Edinburgh, UK<br />

E-mail: claudine.raffray@ed.ac.uk<br />

Verbs such as 'begin' semantically select <strong>for</strong> event complements. Where <strong>the</strong>y occur with entity nouns,<br />

<strong>the</strong> complement undergoes semantic type coercion to <strong>the</strong> event associated with that NP (Jackendoff,<br />

2001). The elided semantic content ('writing' in '<strong>the</strong> author began <strong>the</strong> book') is provided by <strong>the</strong> NP<br />

complement’s lexical representation (Pustejovsky, 1995).<br />

We report two experiments that investigated whe<strong>the</strong>r speakers align abstract event structure in<br />

dialogue. In a confederate-scripting paradigm (Branigan et al., 2000), pairs of speakers took turns to<br />

describe unrelated pictures to each o<strong>the</strong>r. One speaker was a confederate who produced scripted<br />

coerced <strong>and</strong> non-coerced Prime descriptions. We examined <strong>the</strong> <strong>for</strong>m of participants' subsequent<br />

Target descriptions. Experiment 1 involved three prime conditions: coerced NP, full-VP or [noncoerced]<br />

event NP (1). Targets comprised a subject NP followed by a coercing verb, allowing a<br />

coerced or full-VP (event-argument) completion (2). Results showed a reliable effect of Prime (ps <<br />

.001); <strong>the</strong> event-NP condition was significantly different from both <strong>the</strong> coerced <strong>and</strong> full-VP<br />

conditions (all ps < .05). Hence participants tended both to repeat syntactic structure (V NP structure)<br />

but also semantic structure in <strong>the</strong> absence of syntactic repetition.<br />

Experiment 2 manipulated Form (coerced vs. full-VP) <strong>and</strong> (coerced) Verb (same vs. different<br />

between prime <strong>and</strong> target) (3, 4). The coercing verb was held constant between prime <strong>and</strong> target.<br />

Results again showed reliable priming (ps < .001), <strong>and</strong> a significant Form x Verb interaction (ps ≤<br />

.005). The coerced-/same <strong>and</strong> coerced-/different conditions differed significantly from each o<strong>the</strong>r (ps<br />

< .05). This suggests that even if speakers choose not to make explicit <strong>the</strong> underlying predicate<br />

('playing' in 'playing <strong>the</strong> bagpipes'), <strong>the</strong> event structure associated with that predicate never<strong>the</strong>less<br />

influences <strong>the</strong> subsequent grammatical choice of <strong>the</strong>ir interlocutor. We discuss <strong>the</strong>se findings in <strong>the</strong><br />

context of <strong>the</strong>ories of production <strong>and</strong> dialogue.<br />

1. Prime: The author began [<strong>the</strong> book/writing <strong>the</strong> book/<strong>the</strong> speech]<br />

(coerced NP/full-VP/event NP)<br />

2. Target: The guest began…[<strong>the</strong> pudding/eating <strong>the</strong> pudding]<br />

(coerced NP/full-VP)<br />

3. Prime: The busker enjoyed [<strong>the</strong> bagpipes/playing <strong>the</strong> bagpipes/<strong>the</strong> cigar/smoking <strong>the</strong> cigar]<br />

(coerced NP, same verb/full-VP, same verb/coerced NP, different verb/full-VP,<br />

different verb)<br />

4. Target: The entertainer enjoyed…[ <strong>the</strong> piano/ playing <strong>the</strong> piano] (coerced NP/full-VP)<br />

Notes<br />

81


P29<br />

Animacy affects <strong>the</strong> processing of subject/object ambiguities in <strong>the</strong> L2<br />

Carrie Jackson 1 , & Leah Roberts 2<br />

1 Penn State <strong>University</strong>, USA,<br />

2 Max Planck Institute <strong>for</strong> Psycholinguistics, Nijmegen, The Ne<strong>the</strong>rl<strong>and</strong>s<br />

E-mail: cnj1@psu.edu<br />

One debate in L2 sentence processing is whe<strong>the</strong>r learners can anticipate upcoming structure in <strong>the</strong><br />

absence of lexical/semantic in<strong>for</strong>mation (cf. Clahsen & Felser, 2006). A previous self-paced reading<br />

study with German L2 learners of Dutch (Havik et al., in press) found that L2 learners did not exhibit<br />

an on-line preference <strong>for</strong> subject-first word order with subject/object ambiguities like ‘Dat is de<br />

vrouw die de meisjes heeft/hebben gezien’ (that is <strong>the</strong> woman who has seen <strong>the</strong> girls/who <strong>the</strong> girls<br />

have seen) although both German <strong>and</strong> Dutch native speakers do (Konieczny et al., 1997; Mak, 2001).<br />

The present study compared 24 advanced German L2 learners of Dutch to 24 Dutch controls in a selfpaced<br />

reading task in which <strong>the</strong> animacy of one of <strong>the</strong> NPs was manipulated, as in ‘De peuters die de<br />

muziek hebben/heeft gehoord/beziggehouden’ (<strong>the</strong> kids who listened to <strong>the</strong> music/<strong>the</strong> music which<br />

occupied <strong>the</strong> kids)(cf. Mak, 2001). As in Havik et al., <strong>the</strong> NPs were ambiguous until number<br />

in<strong>for</strong>mation on <strong>the</strong> auxiliary determined <strong>the</strong>ir syntactic roles. Thus, this study measured whe<strong>the</strong>r early<br />

access to semantic in<strong>for</strong>mation would bias <strong>the</strong> L2 learners to make an on-line commitment to a<br />

particular analysis.<br />

The reading times of <strong>the</strong> Dutch controls indicated that having an animate subject in <strong>the</strong> dispreferred<br />

object-first word order eased <strong>the</strong> processing burden from <strong>the</strong> lexical verb (beziggehouden) onwards.<br />

The L2 learners exhibited a similar pattern, although <strong>the</strong> animacy x word order interaction appeared<br />

immediately at <strong>the</strong> auxiliary verb. Among L2 learners, later segments revealed only a main effect of<br />

animacy, suggesting a semantic bias, in which <strong>the</strong>y dispreferred an inanimate subject, regardless of<br />

word order.<br />

We conclude that (1) L2 learners can use semantic in<strong>for</strong>mation in real-time to build syntactic<br />

structure <strong>and</strong> (2) <strong>the</strong>y can do so without early access to <strong>the</strong> lexical verb, which is particularly relevant<br />

given that most L2 processing studies to date have relied on materials in which <strong>the</strong> lexical verb<br />

appears early on.<br />

References<br />

Clahsen, H., & Felser, C. (2006). Grammatical processing in language learners. Applied<br />

Psycholinguistics, 27(1), 3-42.<br />

Havik, E., Roberts, L., van Hout, R., Schreuder, R., & Haverkort, M. (in press). Processing subjectobject<br />

ambiguities in L2 Dutch. <strong>Language</strong> Learning.<br />

Konieczny, L., Hem<strong>for</strong>th, B., Scheepers, C., & Straube, G. (1997). The role of lexical heads in<br />

parsing: Evidence from German. <strong>Language</strong> <strong>and</strong> Cognitive Processes, 12, 307-348.<br />

Mak, W. (2001). Processing relative clauses, effects of pragmatic, semantic <strong>and</strong> syntactic variables.<br />

PhD, KU Nijmegen<br />

Notes<br />

82


P30<br />

Capturing <strong>the</strong> productivity of <strong>the</strong> double object construction<br />

Elizabeth E. Coppock<br />

Stan<strong>for</strong>d <strong>University</strong>, USA<br />

E-mail: coppock@stan<strong>for</strong>d.edu<br />

Ditransitivity is productive: When a new verb with an appropriate meaning enters <strong>the</strong> English<br />

language, it can be used ditransitively (e.g. "text me your address"). Yet <strong>the</strong>re are certain verbs that<br />

are relatively unacceptable as ditransitives, <strong>for</strong> apparently historical reasons (e.g. *"donate <strong>the</strong>m<br />

money"). If <strong>the</strong>se restrictions must be memorized individually, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> learner of English must store<br />

a great amount of detail about <strong>the</strong> usage of individual words. This paper demonstrates that verbs like<br />

"donate" are subject to a general restriction, which obviates <strong>the</strong> need <strong>for</strong> such storage. Evidence<br />

comes from two nonce word experiments, building on Gropen et al.’s (1989) finding that<br />

monosyllabic nonce words like "moop" are more acceptable as ditransitives than trisyllabic ones like<br />

"dorfinize". Several possible factors governing <strong>the</strong> productivity of <strong>the</strong> ditransitive construction are<br />

compared:<br />

(i) prosodic weight, measured in metrical feet ra<strong>the</strong>r than syllable (Grimshaw <strong>and</strong> Prince 1986,<br />

Grimshaw 2005)<br />

(ii) morphological complexity (e.g. Harley 2006)<br />

(iii) <strong>the</strong> lexicon (or lexical stratum) to which a verb belongs; English speakers are hypo<strong>the</strong>sized<br />

to have one which allows ditransitives <strong>and</strong> one which does not (Grimshaw 2005).<br />

Experiment 1 tests whe<strong>the</strong>r prosodic weight alone can account <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> effect, <strong>and</strong> shows that it cannot.<br />

Experiment 2 replicates Gropen et al.'s (1989) result <strong>and</strong> investigates <strong>the</strong> role of syllable count,<br />

morphological complexity, <strong>and</strong> perceived etymology on <strong>the</strong> acceptability of ditransitive uses. The<br />

degree to which a given nonce word is perceived as deriving from Latin was found to be <strong>the</strong> only<br />

predictor of ditransitivity, controlling <strong>for</strong> number of syllables. This finding supports <strong>the</strong> hypo<strong>the</strong>sis<br />

that speakers classify words into two lexical strata based on <strong>the</strong>ir perceived etymology, <strong>and</strong> more<br />

generally, <strong>the</strong> view that speakers do not need to store arbitrary exceptions to productive patterns.<br />

References<br />

Grimshaw, J. (2005). Words <strong>and</strong> Structure. CSLI Publications, Stan<strong>for</strong>d.<br />

Grimshaw, J. <strong>and</strong> Prince, A. (1986). A prosodic account of <strong>the</strong> to-dative alternation. Ms., Rutgers<br />

<strong>University</strong>.<br />

Gropen, J., Pinker, S., Holl<strong>and</strong>er, M., Goldberg, R., <strong>and</strong> Wilson, R. (1989). The learnability <strong>and</strong><br />

acquisition of <strong>the</strong> dative alternation in English. <strong>Language</strong>, 65(2):203--257.<br />

Harley, H. (2006). The bipartite structure of verbs cross-linguistically (or Why Mary can't exhibit<br />

John her paintings). Ms., <strong>University</strong> of Arizona.<br />

Notes<br />

83


P31<br />

Evidence <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> prediction of modifiers during sentence processing<br />

Manabu Arai, Frank Keller, & Vera Demberg<br />

<strong>University</strong> of Edinburgh, UK<br />

E-mail: manabu.arai@ed.ac.uk<br />

A number of studies have shown that comprehenders anticipate upcoming material on <strong>the</strong> basis of<br />

only part of a sentence. However, all experimental evidence <strong>for</strong> prediction to date has only dealt with<br />

<strong>the</strong> prediction of grammatical heads <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir complements (Altmann & Kamide, Cognition 1999;<br />

Arai et al., CogPsy 2007; Staub & Clifton, JEP 2006; Van Berkum et al., JEP 2005). Here, we<br />

address <strong>the</strong> question of whe<strong>the</strong>r people also predict modifiers, syntactically non-obligatory elements.<br />

Previous work investigated discourse-based effects on <strong>the</strong> processing of modifiers (e.g., Altmann et<br />

al., JML 1998; Spivey-Knowlton & Sedivy, Cognition 1995), but in <strong>the</strong>se studies, context effects<br />

were only observed after content words in a modifier were encountered. It is <strong>the</strong>re<strong>for</strong>e impossible to<br />

determine whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> modifier was made easier to integrate by <strong>the</strong> supportive context or whe<strong>the</strong>r is<br />

was predicted <strong>and</strong> thus processed faster.<br />

We conducted an eye-tracking reading experiment to examine whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> processing of a postnominal<br />

relative clause is facilitated when it can be predicted. We contrasted two preceding contexts;<br />

one introduces two referents of <strong>the</strong> same type (two eggs in (1a)) <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r one introduces only one<br />

referent of that type (one egg <strong>and</strong> one sausage in (1b)). These two contexts were crossed with two<br />

target conditions: In <strong>the</strong> first one (see (2a)), <strong>the</strong>re was a relative clause that modified <strong>the</strong> target noun,<br />

while in <strong>the</strong> second condition (see (2b)), <strong>the</strong>re was a while-clause instead.<br />

1a. Mary boiled an egg <strong>and</strong> Peter fried an egg.<br />

1b. Mary boiled an egg <strong>and</strong> Peter fried a sausage.<br />

2a. Max ate <strong>the</strong> egg which Mary boiled.<br />

2b. Max ate <strong>the</strong> egg while Mary slept.<br />

We observed a significant interaction between context (one or two referents) <strong>and</strong> modifier type<br />

(relative clause or while-clause) at <strong>the</strong> word following <strong>the</strong> target noun (i.e., "which"/"while"). In <strong>the</strong><br />

two referent condition, "which", a relative pronoun that is consistent with a modifier prediction, was<br />

processed faster than "while", a conjunction inconsistent with that prediction. Importantly, this was<br />

observed in a first-pass measure (regression path time), i.e., <strong>the</strong> effect occurred be<strong>for</strong>e readers saw<br />

any content words of <strong>the</strong> modifier.<br />

This is <strong>the</strong> first demonstration of <strong>the</strong> prediction of non-argument modifiers in sentence processing.<br />

The result has important <strong>the</strong>oretical implications, e.g., it is compatible with a surprisal-based view of<br />

processing complexity (Hale, NAACL 2001), but not with Gibson's (Cognition 1998) notion of<br />

prediction memory cost, which only applies to heads.<br />

Notes<br />

84


P32<br />

Scrambled word recognition: Implications <strong>for</strong> position coding<br />

Chris R. Cummins<br />

RCEAL, <strong>University</strong> of Cambridge, UK<br />

E-mail: crc37@cam.ac.uk<br />

Various proposals have been made regarding 'position coding' in human visual word recognition - that<br />

is, how <strong>the</strong> in<strong>for</strong>mation about <strong>the</strong> positions of letters within <strong>the</strong> word is processed <strong>and</strong> exploited. Our<br />

ability to resolve typographical errors without being conscious of <strong>the</strong>m indicates that letter position<br />

in<strong>for</strong>mation is somewhat redundant. The so-called Scrambler effect purports to show that permuting<br />

medial letters within a word does not impede recognition, although this is an oversimplification.<br />

Position coding proposals (e.g. Wickelgren 1969, Whitney <strong>and</strong> Berndt 1999, Grainger <strong>and</strong> van<br />

Heuven 2003) vary in how well <strong>the</strong>y are able to explain such effects.<br />

This paper proposes a novel methodology <strong>for</strong> evaluating <strong>the</strong>se proposals, based on 'pop-out' anagram<br />

solutions. 'Pop-out' solutions are those which are subjectively sudden. Such solutions are widespread,<br />

especially among expert solvers (Novick <strong>and</strong> Sherman 2003), <strong>and</strong> appear to rely upon a similar<br />

process to that underlying typo correction in skilled reading.<br />

Using this methodology I test a number of expert anagram solvers, obtaining high rates of pop-out<br />

solutions. The speed <strong>and</strong> reliability with which <strong>the</strong>se solutions arise is shown to depend on how <strong>the</strong><br />

word is disarranged. These levels of disarrangement can be quantified in terms of position coding<br />

proposals.<br />

Broadly, Wickelgren's (1969) approach is shown to make <strong>the</strong> most reliable predictions, in that <strong>the</strong><br />

loss of trigrams greatly impedes solution accuracy <strong>and</strong> speed. 'Open bigram' approaches - involving<br />

<strong>the</strong> relative position of letter pairs - do not appear to make such reliable predictions. The spatial<br />

coding schema discussed by Davis <strong>and</strong> Bowers (2006) is also consistent with <strong>the</strong>se data, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> data<br />

may help constrain <strong>the</strong> hypo<strong>the</strong>ses we make within that schema.<br />

Notes<br />

85


P33<br />

Translation takes place be<strong>for</strong>e utterance in a reading <strong>for</strong> translation task -<br />

evidence from two self-paced reading studies<br />

Ya-Shyuan Jin, Robert Logie, & Martin Corley<br />

<strong>University</strong> of Edinburgh, UK<br />

E-mail: ys.jin@ed.ac.uk<br />

In translation <strong>the</strong>ories (Gerver, 1976; Seleskovitch, 1976), it is commonly assumed that a sourcelanguage<br />

(SL) discourse has to go through stages such as comprehension <strong>and</strong> linguistic code<br />

switching be<strong>for</strong>e it is rendered in a target language (TL). But <strong>the</strong>re is a disagreement between two<br />

<strong>the</strong>ories on <strong>the</strong> seriality of <strong>the</strong>se processes. Horizontal translation argues that translators engage in<br />

partial re<strong>for</strong>mulation in a TL during text comprehension, whereas vertical translation maintains that<br />

re<strong>for</strong>mulation only starts after comprehension is completed (de Groot, 1997). Recently, Ruiz, Paredes,<br />

Macizo <strong>and</strong> Bajo (in press) found that translators’ reading times were longer in read-to-translate but<br />

not in read-to-repeat conditions when <strong>the</strong> word orders were incongruent between SL <strong>and</strong> TL. This<br />

interaction between reading purposes <strong>and</strong> word order congruency was taken as an evidence <strong>for</strong><br />

horizontal translation.<br />

In this present study, we conducted two experiments in an attempt to replicate Ruiz et al.’s<br />

congruency effect <strong>and</strong> also explore <strong>the</strong> role of working memory in <strong>the</strong> reading <strong>for</strong> translation task. In<br />

experiment one, we recorded 24 Chinese-English late bilinguals' reading times under four conditions,<br />

composed of congruency (congruent vs. incongruent) <strong>and</strong> reading purposes (repeat vs. translate). In<br />

addition, we also measured <strong>the</strong>ir Chinese reading span. Our results seemed to support Ruiz et al.’s<br />

argument, but did not establish a relation between working memory <strong>and</strong> reading time.<br />

In experiment two, we used dual-task paradigm to test our hypo<strong>the</strong>sis that horizontal translation <strong>and</strong><br />

serial digit recall might share <strong>the</strong> same working memory resource during <strong>the</strong> encoding phase.<br />

Participants were presented with a list of digits be<strong>for</strong>e self-paced reading a sentence, after which <strong>the</strong>y<br />

had to serially recall <strong>the</strong> digit list <strong>and</strong> finally translate <strong>the</strong> sentence from Chinese into English. If our<br />

hypo<strong>the</strong>sis was supported, in addition to <strong>the</strong> main effects in congruency <strong>and</strong> preload, we would expect<br />

to find an interaction. 18 Chinese-English late bilinguals’ reading times were recorded in six<br />

conditions composing of congruency (congruent vs. incongruent) <strong>and</strong> digit preload (no load, 5 digits,<br />

7 digits). We found an effect of congruency <strong>and</strong> preload, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> two factors interacted. Surprisingly,<br />

<strong>the</strong> interaction showed <strong>the</strong> opposite pattern from our prediction, i.e. digit preload seemed to reduce<br />

reading time. Our results suggest that <strong>the</strong> impact of congruency on translation does not reflect<br />

dem<strong>and</strong>s on verbal working memory.<br />

Notes<br />

86


Evidence <strong>for</strong> determinate attachment of relative clause modifiers<br />

P34<br />

Mat<strong>the</strong>w J. Traxler<br />

<strong>University</strong> of Cali<strong>for</strong>nia, Davis, USA<br />

E-mail: mjtraxler@ucdavis.edu<br />

Some parsing <strong>the</strong>ories, such as <strong>the</strong> Garden-path, Construal, <strong>and</strong> Constraint-based accounts propose<br />

that comprehenders routinely complete syntactic analysis, even <strong>for</strong> complicated structures. By<br />

contrast, Good-Enough Parsing proposes that comprehenders routinely underspecify <strong>the</strong> syntax of<br />

sentences <strong>and</strong> sometimes adopt syntactic analyses that are not licensed by <strong>the</strong> grammar. For example,<br />

an unlicensed parse may occur when people interpret "baby" as <strong>the</strong> object of "washed" in (1):<br />

(1) While Susan washed <strong>the</strong> baby slept.<br />

An indeterminate parse may occur in sentences with an attachment ambiguity, as in (2) (Swets et al.,<br />

in press):<br />

(2) The daughter of <strong>the</strong> princess who wore a blue dress enjoyed <strong>the</strong> party.<br />

Good-Enough parsing proposes that <strong>the</strong> processing advantage observed in sentences like (2),<br />

compared to semantically disambiguated controls, is <strong>the</strong> result of readers underspecifying <strong>the</strong><br />

syntactic representation of (2) (but cf. Traxler et al., 1998). Good-Enough parsing proposes fur<strong>the</strong>r<br />

that readers adopt a determinate analysis of sentences like (2) if <strong>the</strong>y are motivated by comprehension<br />

questions that focus on <strong>the</strong> ambiguity.<br />

Two eye-tracking experiments tested whe<strong>the</strong>r readers underspecify <strong>the</strong> syntactic structure of<br />

sentences like (2). Both experiments contrasted sentences like (3a) with controls like (3b):<br />

(3a) The bro<strong>the</strong>r of <strong>the</strong> mayor that was populated with young people phoned.<br />

(3b) The bro<strong>the</strong>r of <strong>the</strong> mayor that was popular with young people phoned.<br />

Pre-testing confirmed that (3a) was semantically implausible, starting at "populated", while (3b) was<br />

plausible throughout. The adjectives in <strong>the</strong> critical position (e.g., "populated" <strong>and</strong> "popular") were<br />

matched <strong>for</strong> length <strong>and</strong> frequency. O<strong>the</strong>r control conditions were run so that readers could not<br />

determine that <strong>the</strong> sentence would be implausible simply by assessing <strong>the</strong> selection restrictions of <strong>the</strong><br />

adjective.<br />

Good-enough parsing predicts that readers should not notice <strong>the</strong> implausibility of (3a) unless<br />

comprehension questions focus <strong>the</strong>ir attention on <strong>the</strong> ambiguity. If so, <strong>the</strong>re should be no observable<br />

difference in processing of sentences like (3a) <strong>and</strong> sentences like (3b).<br />

In <strong>the</strong> first eye-tracking experiment, st<strong>and</strong>ard two-option comprehension questions were asked after<br />

some, but not all, of <strong>the</strong> test <strong>and</strong> filler sentences. Eye-movements indicated substantial disruption of<br />

processing in (3a) shortly after readers fixated <strong>the</strong> critical adjective (populated).<br />

In <strong>the</strong> second eye-tracking experiment, <strong>the</strong> same sentences were tested, but <strong>the</strong> secondary task was<br />

plausibility judgment. The eye-tracking results were essentially <strong>the</strong> same as Experiment 1.<br />

So, readers did adopt a determinate syntactic analysis of sentences like (3a) <strong>and</strong> (3b) <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>y did so<br />

under two secondary task conditions that did not focus on <strong>the</strong> ambiguity. Hence, <strong>the</strong> eye-movement<br />

results likely reflect processes routinely that are routinely undertaken during reading.<br />

87


P35<br />

What’s in a manner of speaking Children’s sensitivity to partner specific<br />

referential precedents<br />

Danielle E. Mat<strong>the</strong>ws 1 , Elena V.M. Lieven 2 , & Michael Tomasello 2<br />

1 <strong>University</strong> of Manchester, UK, 2 Max Planck Institute <strong>for</strong> Evolutionary Anthropology, Leipzig, Germany<br />

E-mail: danielle.mat<strong>the</strong>ws@manchester.ac.uk<br />

Do young children <strong>for</strong>m ‘referential pacts’ If a person has referred to an object with a term (e.g., ‘<strong>the</strong><br />

horse’), will children expect this person to use this term with reference to <strong>the</strong> same object in <strong>the</strong><br />

future but allow o<strong>the</strong>rs a different expression (e.g., ‘<strong>the</strong> pony’) 128 children aged 3 <strong>and</strong> 5 years cooperated<br />

with an experimenter (E1) to move toys to new locations on a shelf. E1 established<br />

referential terms <strong>for</strong> all toys in a warm up game (e.g. car, pony, girl). Then, ei<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> original<br />

partner, E1, or a new partner, E2, played a second game with <strong>the</strong> same toys. In this game, toys were<br />

referred to with ei<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>ir original terms from <strong>the</strong> warm up or with new terms (e.g. truck, horse,<br />

lady). Reaction times were recorded from <strong>the</strong> onset of <strong>the</strong> critical referring expression to <strong>the</strong> time <strong>the</strong><br />

child reached into <strong>the</strong> target box to retrieve <strong>the</strong> referent (fig1). All children were significantly slower<br />

to react to new terms than old. This difference in reaction times was significantly greater in <strong>the</strong><br />

original partner condition (but only <strong>the</strong> first time a new term was used, suggesting that once a<br />

referential history has been broken children no longer expect precedents to be maintained – see fig2).<br />

We discuss <strong>the</strong> finding that 3-year-olds show partner-specific sensitivity to referential precedents in<br />

<strong>the</strong> context of recent cue-based explanations in <strong>the</strong> adult literature (Kronmüller & Barr, 2007;<br />

Metzing & Brennan, 2003; Shintel & Keysar, 2007). The main developmental difference from early<br />

childhood to adulthood is that young children have difficulty processing new terms no matter who<br />

produces <strong>the</strong>m. This suggests that referential precedents are processed with both partner specific <strong>and</strong><br />

partner independent expectations in mind, with older children <strong>and</strong> adults being quicker to apply<br />

partner specific in<strong>for</strong>mation. Analysis of children’s regular protests at <strong>the</strong> use of new terms (e.g., ‘It’s<br />

not a tree, it’s a bush!’) fur<strong>the</strong>r suggests that it is possible to show sensitivity to referential pacts<br />

without underst<strong>and</strong>ing that different terms might be equally valid from different perspectives.<br />

Difference in reaction time to original <strong>and</strong> new<br />

expressions<br />

2.5<br />

Difference (seconds)<br />

2<br />

1.5<br />

1<br />

0.5<br />

Original Partner<br />

New Partner<br />

Fig1. Coding RTs.<br />

0<br />

Trial 1 Trial 2 Trial 1 Trial 2<br />

3yrs N = 62 5yrs N = 64<br />

Fig2. Difference in RTs.<br />

References<br />

Kronmüller, E., & Barr, D. (2007). Perspective-free pragmatics: Broken precedents <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> recoveryfrom-preeemption<br />

hypo<strong>the</strong>sis. JML, 56(3), 436-455.<br />

Metzing, C., & Brennan, S. E. (2003). When conceptual pacts are broken: Partner-specific effects on<br />

<strong>the</strong> comprehension of referring expressions. JML, 49, 201-213.<br />

Shintel, H., & Keysar, B. (2007). You said it be<strong>for</strong>e <strong>and</strong> you'll say it again: expectations of<br />

consistency in communication. JEP:LMC, 33(2), 357-369.<br />

88


P36<br />

Lexical boost effects in comprehension priming<br />

Maria Nella Carminati, & Roger P.G. van Gompel<br />

<strong>University</strong> of Dundee, UK<br />

E-mail: m.n.carminati@dundee.ac.uk<br />

Most studies on structural priming in comprehension have found priming only when <strong>the</strong> verb in prime<br />

<strong>and</strong> target is <strong>the</strong> same, but not when it is different (Branigan et al., 2005; Traxler & Pickering, 2005;<br />

Arai et al., 2007, but cf. Thothathiri & Snedeker, in press). This suggests that comprehension priming<br />

is more lexically-dependent than production priming, where priming also occurs when <strong>the</strong> verb is<br />

different. However, <strong>the</strong> precise nature of <strong>the</strong> lexical boost effect in comprehension priming is still to<br />

be determined. In production, Pickering & Branigan (1998) have suggested that this boost is specific<br />

to syntactic heads. In contrast, according to Chang et al.(2006), <strong>the</strong> boost is due to an explicit memory<br />

mechanism. In <strong>the</strong> latter account, not only verbs, but also nouns (i.e. any content word) are assumed<br />

to act as effective retrieval cues in short-term memory.<br />

Two visual world eye-tracking studies investigated <strong>the</strong> nature of <strong>the</strong> lexical boost effect in<br />

comprehension in order to test whe<strong>the</strong>r it is specific to syntactic heads, in our case, <strong>the</strong> main verb.<br />

Experiment 1 explored whe<strong>the</strong>r repeating <strong>the</strong> subject noun enhanced priming in cases where <strong>the</strong> verb<br />

was also repeated. Participants first read ei<strong>the</strong>r a DO (The Indian will h<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> politician <strong>the</strong> petition)<br />

or a corresponding PO prime sentence. Next, <strong>the</strong>y listened to an auditorily presented ditransitive<br />

target while <strong>the</strong>ir eye-movements to objects in a scene were recorded. We observed clear priming<br />

effects (as in previous studies, cf. Arai et al.). Importantly, priming was stronger when <strong>the</strong> subject was<br />

repeated than when it was not.<br />

Experiment 2 explored whe<strong>the</strong>r repeating only <strong>the</strong> subject noun, <strong>and</strong> not repeating <strong>the</strong> verb, results in<br />

a lexical boost. There were no priming effects nor interactions. This shows that subject repetition<br />

alone is not an effective retrieval cue leading to comprehension priming (unlike verb repetition).<br />

This evidence is inconsistent with both Chang et al. (2006) <strong>and</strong> Pickering & Branigan (1998): subject<br />

repetition results in a lexical boost but only if <strong>the</strong> verb is repeated. The results show that <strong>the</strong> verb (i.e.<br />

<strong>the</strong> head) plays a central role in comprehension priming. When listeners process <strong>the</strong> target verb, <strong>the</strong>y<br />

reactivate <strong>the</strong> structure used with this verb in <strong>the</strong> prime sentence. Moreover, reactivation is facilitated<br />

if <strong>the</strong> subject is also repeated. This suggests that structural in<strong>for</strong>mation is associated both with <strong>the</strong><br />

verb <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> subj + verb combination. We discuss <strong>the</strong>se findings in relation to recent results obtained<br />

in our lab investigating similar lexical boost effects in production.<br />

Notes<br />

89


P37<br />

Listeners make optimal use of speaker <strong>and</strong> discourse in<strong>for</strong>mation when<br />

recognizing reduced <strong>for</strong>ms<br />

Susanne M. Brouwer, Holger Mitterer, & Falk Huettig<br />

Max Planck Institute <strong>for</strong> Psycholinguistics, Nijmegen, The Ne<strong>the</strong>rl<strong>and</strong>s<br />

E-mail: susanne.brouwer@mpi.nl<br />

In casual speech, words often differ severely from <strong>the</strong>ir citation <strong>for</strong>m pronunciation, such that<br />

'computer' might be pronounced as 'pjuter'. Our previous work showed that such reductions, taken<br />

from a spontaneous speech corpus, make word recognition harder, even if presented within <strong>the</strong><br />

conversational turn in which <strong>the</strong>y had been produced. In a series of new experiments we examined to<br />

what extend speaker <strong>and</strong> discourse in<strong>for</strong>mation mediates how listeners process <strong>the</strong>se reductions. We<br />

tracked participants' eye movements to four printed words on a computer screen, while <strong>the</strong>y listened<br />

to conversational turns from a casual speech corpus containing reduced <strong>for</strong>ms. We displayed <strong>the</strong><br />

target word (e.g., computer), an "underlying" competitor phonologically similar to <strong>the</strong> unreduced<br />

<strong>for</strong>m (e.g., companion), a "surface" competitor similar to <strong>the</strong> reduced <strong>for</strong>m (e.g., pupil), <strong>and</strong> a<br />

completely unrelated distractor (e.g., holiday). The participants' task was to click on <strong>the</strong> word <strong>the</strong>y<br />

heard in <strong>the</strong> utterance. Critically, we varied <strong>the</strong> context in which <strong>the</strong> reduced <strong>for</strong>ms occurred. The<br />

reduced <strong>for</strong>m was presented within <strong>the</strong> conversational turn (control condition) or with an additional<br />

context that provided discourse <strong>and</strong>/or speaker in<strong>for</strong>mation.<br />

In Experiment 1, reduced <strong>for</strong>ms were presented with at least 5s of preceding discourse context. We<br />

observed that <strong>the</strong> discourse context facilitated recognition of <strong>the</strong> reduced <strong>for</strong>ms <strong>and</strong> decreased <strong>the</strong><br />

degree of competition from phonologically similar words in comparison with <strong>the</strong> control condition.<br />

Experiment 1, however, left open which aspect of <strong>the</strong> discourse context aided word recognition: <strong>the</strong><br />

pragmatic <strong>and</strong> semantic cues or speaker in<strong>for</strong>mation. In Experiment 2, we presented <strong>the</strong> same<br />

reductions as in Experiment 1, but now preceded by 5s of speech from <strong>the</strong> same speaker but from a<br />

different discourse. This context hence provided speaker in<strong>for</strong>mation but no pragmatic or semantic<br />

cues to <strong>the</strong> intended word. The data showed that speaker in<strong>for</strong>mation on its own facilitated word<br />

recognition to a lesser degree than discourse context. Moreover, speaker in<strong>for</strong>mation did not reduce<br />

<strong>the</strong> amount of competition from phonologically similar words.<br />

In conclusion, our eye movement data reveal that listeners make optimal use of both speaker <strong>and</strong><br />

discourse in<strong>for</strong>mation while processing reduced <strong>for</strong>ms. If both cues are available, listeners tend to<br />

focus primarily on discourse in<strong>for</strong>mation which leads to less phonological competition. If speaker<br />

in<strong>for</strong>mation is <strong>the</strong> only available cue, however, listeners maximize <strong>the</strong> use of bottom-up in<strong>for</strong>mation.<br />

Notes<br />

90


P38<br />

Dynamically resolving syntactic <strong>and</strong> semantic ambiguity in comprehending<br />

spoken language: A MEG study<br />

Guosheng Ding, Billi R<strong>and</strong>all, Barry J. Devereux, Anna Shestakova, & Lorraine K. Tyler<br />

<strong>University</strong> of Cambridge, UK<br />

E-mail ding@csl.psychol.cam.ac.uk<br />

Ambiguity is a ubiquitous property of language <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> question of when <strong>and</strong> how ambiguity is<br />

resolved has generated much research in psycholinguistics. In <strong>the</strong> case of both semantic <strong>and</strong> syntactic<br />

ambiguity, a key issue has been whe<strong>the</strong>r only a single reading is ever activated or whe<strong>the</strong>r all possible<br />

analyses are activated <strong>and</strong> one is subsequently selected. In spite of many behavioural studies, this<br />

issue remains contentious.<br />

In <strong>the</strong> present study, we aimed to address this issue by using magnetoencephalography (MEG) to<br />

determine both <strong>the</strong> time-course <strong>and</strong> brain regions involved in <strong>the</strong> processing of syntactic or semantic<br />

ambiguity. In a previous fMRI study (Rodd et al, 2004), we found that <strong>the</strong> activity in <strong>the</strong> left posterior<br />

middle temporal gyrus (LpMTG) <strong>for</strong> syntactic ambiguity was modulated by <strong>the</strong> strength of <strong>the</strong><br />

preference <strong>for</strong> one syntactic reading vs ano<strong>the</strong>r, suggesting that subjects had constructed a single<br />

parse which was overturned when it mismatched <strong>the</strong> subsequent input. While <strong>the</strong> fMRI study was<br />

suggestive, it did not provide conclusive data concerning <strong>the</strong> issue of single vs multiple activated<br />

representations since fMRI is relatively insensitive to <strong>the</strong> temporal dynamics of processing.<br />

The present study was designed as a more direct test of <strong>the</strong> single vs multiple parse hypo<strong>the</strong>ses, by<br />

probing <strong>the</strong> moment-by-moment processing of sentences containing semantic or syntactic<br />

ambiguities. Subjects listened to spoken sentences containing two-word phrases; <strong>the</strong>se phrases were<br />

ei<strong>the</strong>r semantically ambiguous, semantically unambiguous, syntactically ambiguous or syntactically<br />

unambiguous. In all sentences <strong>the</strong> two-word phrase was immediately followed by a verb which<br />

disambiguated <strong>the</strong> ambiguous phrases (e.g. incredible muscles taste, playing cards is, burning <strong>for</strong>ests<br />

are). The verb to be was always <strong>the</strong> disambiguating verb in <strong>the</strong> syntactic condition (appearing as<br />

ei<strong>the</strong>r is or are).<br />

In <strong>the</strong> present study, participants passively listened to <strong>the</strong> sentences while we recorded <strong>the</strong> activity<br />

using MEG. MEG epochs were aligned to <strong>the</strong> onset of each of <strong>the</strong> words in <strong>the</strong> ambiguous phrase.<br />

The distributed model of <strong>the</strong> source reconstruction implemented to localize <strong>the</strong> sources of <strong>the</strong> neural<br />

activity. We found sensitivity to ambiguity resolution later in <strong>the</strong> sentence with peak amplitudes<br />

occurring after <strong>the</strong> disambiguating word, suggesting that some subjects only carried out a single<br />

parse of <strong>the</strong> sentence, which was later overturned by <strong>the</strong> subsequent disambiguating input. We will<br />

discuss <strong>the</strong> implications of <strong>the</strong>se results <strong>for</strong> models of sentence processing.<br />

Notes<br />

91


P39<br />

Balance of sense probabilities affects processing: Evidence from naming<br />

Dusica Filipović Đurđević<br />

<strong>University</strong> of Belgrade, Serbia<br />

E-mail: dmfilipo@f.bg.ac.yuu<br />

Rodd <strong>and</strong> colleagues (2002) demonstrated that facilitatory lexical ambiguity effect was bound to<br />

polysemy. They showed that an increase in number of related senses was followed by a decrease in<br />

processing latencies. Filipović Đurđević <strong>and</strong> Kostić (2006) demonstrated that in addition to number<br />

of senses, balance of sense probabilities also affected processing time. In a lexical decision task,<br />

polysemous words with balanced sense probabilities took less time to process. Balance of sense<br />

probabilities was described as redundancy of sense probability distribution. Number of senses <strong>and</strong><br />

redundancy were succesfully combined in a unique In<strong>for</strong>mation Theory measure of entropy,<br />

demonstrating that <strong>the</strong> greater uncertainty of a word's true sense was followed by shorter reaction<br />

time (as anticipated by Gilhooly & Logie, 1980).<br />

In this study, in order to bring additional evidence of <strong>the</strong> effect of balance of sense probabilities, <strong>the</strong><br />

set of stimuli from Filipović Đurđević <strong>and</strong> Kostić study was presented in a st<strong>and</strong>ard naming task.<br />

Fifty-five participants were presented with 150 polysemous Serbian nouns <strong>for</strong> which number of<br />

senses, <strong>and</strong> sense probabilities were collected in a previous norming study. While controlling <strong>for</strong><br />

several psycholinguistic variables, a special attention was paid to <strong>the</strong> effect of number of senses <strong>and</strong><br />

redundancy (balance of sense probabilities).<br />

Linear mixed effect regression of log reaction times, with participants as r<strong>and</strong>om effects, revealed<br />

significant linear fixed effects of word length in letters, (log) lemma frequency, word familiarity, <strong>and</strong><br />

importantly, both number of senses <strong>and</strong> redundancy (balance of sense probabilities). On <strong>the</strong> one h<strong>and</strong>,<br />

this finding demonstrates <strong>the</strong> effect of semantic variables on naming in a language with transparent<br />

orthography, <strong>and</strong> on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r h<strong>and</strong> it brings additional evidence of relevance of sense probabilities in<br />

processing polysemous words.<br />

References:<br />

Filipović Đurđević, D. & Kostić, A. (2006). The Balance of Sense Probabilities Affects Processing of<br />

Polysemous Words. The 12th Annual Conference on Architectures <strong>and</strong> Mechanisms <strong>for</strong><br />

<strong>Language</strong> Processing, Nijmegen, Ne<strong>the</strong>rl<strong>and</strong>s: Max Planck Institute <strong>for</strong> Psycholinguistics, 30<br />

August - 1 September, 2006, 61.<br />

Gilhooly, K.J. & Logie, R.H.(1980). Age-of-acquisition, imagery, concreteness, familiarity, <strong>and</strong><br />

ambiguity measures <strong>for</strong> 1,944 words. Behavior Research Methods & Instrumentation, Vol. 12(4),<br />

395-427.<br />

Rodd, J. M., Gaskell, M. G., & Marslen-Wilson, W. D. (2002). Making sense of semantic ambiguity:<br />

Semantic competition in lexical access. Journal of Memory <strong>and</strong> <strong>Language</strong>, 46, 245–266.<br />

Notes<br />

92


P40<br />

Early visual compound constituent detection: Distinct roles <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> right<br />

<strong>and</strong> left hemisphere<br />

Linnaea Stockall, Roberto de Almeida, Gina Cook, & Michael von Grunau<br />

Concordia <strong>University</strong>, Canada<br />

E-mail: linnaea.s@gmail.com<br />

Zweig <strong>and</strong> Pylkkänen (in press) used MEG to find a significant effect of morphological complexity<br />

peaking at ~170ms after <strong>the</strong> presentation of a visual letter string. Suffixed <strong>and</strong> prefixed words evoked<br />

greater amplitudes than monomorphemic controls. Interestingly, Z&P found that this effect was<br />

generated by <strong>the</strong> right hemisphere mid-fusi<strong>for</strong>m gyrus <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> suffixed words, <strong>and</strong> bilaterally <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

prefixed words. Z&P hypo<strong>the</strong>size that this surprising right lateralization of early lexical processing<br />

my be due to <strong>the</strong> fact that <strong>the</strong> visual hemifield boundary roughly aligned with <strong>the</strong> stem-suffix<br />

boundary, such that <strong>the</strong> stem would initially have been routed to right visual processing areas.<br />

We more rigorously investigated <strong>the</strong> role of <strong>the</strong> right hemisphere in morphological constituency<br />

detection by systematically manipulating <strong>the</strong> alignment of <strong>the</strong> visual hemifield boundary <strong>and</strong> possible<br />

morpheme boundaries. We investigated <strong>the</strong> recognition of visual compounds by presenting <strong>the</strong>m<br />

briefly (74 ms) <strong>and</strong> centered on <strong>the</strong> screen, with <strong>the</strong> point of visual convergence falling ei<strong>the</strong>r at <strong>the</strong><br />

constituent boundary (e.g., BATH+ROOM) or one character off <strong>the</strong> boundary (e.g., BATHR+OOM).<br />

This technique allows <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> early processing separation of modifier <strong>and</strong> head constituents of<br />

bimorphemic compounds.<br />

In Experiment 1, we compared transparent compounds (bathroom), pseudocompounds (scarcity) <strong>and</strong><br />

undecomposable monomorphs (straight) in a lexical decision task. We found a significant RT<br />

advantage <strong>for</strong> transparent compounds presented with visual hemifield aligned morphological<br />

boundaries, as compared to misaligned boundaries, a non-significant disadvantage <strong>for</strong><br />

pseudocompounds with aligned vs. misaligned boundaries, <strong>and</strong> a main effect of morphological<br />

complexity. When <strong>the</strong> initial routing of visual in<strong>for</strong>mation is supportive of <strong>the</strong> correct morphological<br />

analysis of a word, subsequent lexical processing is facilitated, moreover, when <strong>the</strong> initial routing<br />

encourages an incorrect parse, we observe a trend towards to a lexical garden path effect.<br />

In Experiment 2, we used MEG to measure <strong>the</strong> neuromagnetic responses evoked by processing <strong>the</strong><br />

materials from exp 1. Results (N=18) show that participants exhibit a significant bilateral<br />

M170/VWFA response, which varies in its strength in response to both <strong>the</strong> potential morphological<br />

complexity <strong>and</strong> visual hemifield alignment of <strong>the</strong> stimuli as predicted. We thus confirm a role <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

right fusi<strong>for</strong>m gyrus in early morphological constituent detection <strong>and</strong> provide support <strong>for</strong> a view in<br />

which morphological decomposition is early <strong>and</strong> automatic(Taft & Forster, 1975).<br />

Notes<br />

93


P41<br />

Implicit learning of second language structures<br />

Anna Leonard Cook, Martin Corley, Mitsuhiko Ota, & Antonella Sorace<br />

<strong>University</strong> of Edinburgh, UK<br />

E-mail: s9901404@sms.ed.ac.uk<br />

Contingencies between adjacent sequential elements can be used to segment continuous speech<br />

streams, or to distinguish grammatical <strong>and</strong> ungrammatical letter strings (Reber, 1989; Saffran et al.,<br />

1996). Introducing an intervening element reduces per<strong>for</strong>mance; two intervening elements prevent<br />

learning (Cleeremans & McClell<strong>and</strong>, 1991; Newport & Aslin, 2004). Second language learners also<br />

acquire local contingencies implicitly (Robinson, 2005; Williams, 1999), but <strong>the</strong> effect of intervening<br />

elements has not been investigated systematically.<br />

This paper investigates whe<strong>the</strong>r second language learners acquire contingencies between nonadjacent<br />

elements. Participants were exposed to modified versions of Persian or Basque, with subjectverb<br />

agreement as <strong>the</strong> target structure. In <strong>the</strong> Persian experiment, <strong>the</strong> subject <strong>and</strong> verb were separated<br />

by one word. In <strong>the</strong> Basque materials <strong>the</strong>re were two intervening words. Participants were exposed to<br />

written <strong>and</strong> spoken representations of each item <strong>and</strong> written translations, followed by a sourceidentification<br />

task where <strong>the</strong>y identified <strong>the</strong> supposed speaker.<br />

The measurement of implicit learning was based on Ellis (2005). Participants took part in a timed<br />

grammaticality judgement task. Participants who had acquired explicit knowledge of <strong>the</strong> contingency<br />

were eliminated from fur<strong>the</strong>r consideration using a correction test in which <strong>the</strong>y identified how to<br />

make ungrammatical strings con<strong>for</strong>m to <strong>the</strong> grammar. Two criteria were used to identify implicit<br />

knowledge. First, as it is accessed more quickly than its explicit counterpart, it should be available<br />

under time constraints (Bialystok, 1979). Second, it develops <strong>and</strong> is accessed as an automatic byproduct<br />

of input processing (Cleeremans et al., 1998), so responses should become less accurate after<br />

exposure to incorrect judgement test items making effects smaller in <strong>the</strong> second part of <strong>the</strong> test (c.f.<br />

Don et al, 2003).<br />

Consistent with <strong>the</strong>se criteria, participants in <strong>the</strong> Persian experiment were sensitive to <strong>the</strong> test items'<br />

grammaticality in <strong>the</strong> first part of <strong>the</strong> test but not <strong>the</strong>reafter. Thus, a subject-verb contingency could<br />

be acquired when <strong>the</strong>re was one intervening word. In contrast, when <strong>the</strong>re were two intervening<br />

words, <strong>the</strong> Basque participants showed no evidence of relevant implicit knowledge.<br />

Participants acquired implicit knowledge of <strong>the</strong> shorter but not <strong>the</strong> longer contingency, as has been<br />

found in <strong>the</strong> statistical learning <strong>and</strong> artificial grammar learning paradigms. This is consistent with <strong>the</strong><br />

interpretation that domain-general statistical mechanisms can acquire certain aspects of a second<br />

language.<br />

Notes<br />

94


P42<br />

Frontal mechanisms in language pragmatics: Evidence from older adults<br />

processing implicitures<br />

Dusana Dorjee Khenchen 1 , Merrill F Garrett 2 , & Elizabeth L Glisky 2<br />

1 <strong>University</strong> of Bristol, UK, 2 <strong>University</strong> of Arizona, USA<br />

E-mail: dusana.rybarova@bristol.ac.uk<br />

In everyday communication, processes of language comprehension <strong>and</strong> production closely interact<br />

with in<strong>for</strong>mation about our intentions, world knowledge, <strong>and</strong> representations of situational context.<br />

Integration of in<strong>for</strong>mation from <strong>the</strong>se different sources, likely mediated by frontal lobes, is important<br />

<strong>for</strong> context-appropriate language use – language pragmatics. This study examined <strong>the</strong> role of frontal<br />

lobes in context-free <strong>and</strong> context-dependent interpretation of st<strong>and</strong>ardized pragmatic inferences called<br />

‘implicitures’ (Bach, 1994) in an aging population.<br />

Decline in working memory <strong>and</strong> executive processes of <strong>the</strong> frontal lobes with age has been shown to<br />

have negative impact on text comprehension abilities of older adults (Van der Linden et al., 1999;<br />

DeBeni, Borella, & Carretti, 2007; Ferstl, 2006). There is also some evidence about age-specific<br />

decline in comprehension of metaphors <strong>and</strong> humor (Zanini et al., 2005). But, studies investigating <strong>the</strong><br />

relationship between frontal function <strong>and</strong> age-related changes in processing of specific pragmatic<br />

elements are scarce.<br />

In this study, 27 normal older adults over <strong>the</strong> age of 65 were first tested on a battery of<br />

neuropsychological tests assessing frontal function. Subsequently, <strong>the</strong>ir comprehension of<br />

implicitures was tested in a two alternative <strong>for</strong>ced choice task. Implicitures have preferred implied<br />

interpretations - <strong>for</strong> example, presented context-free, <strong>the</strong> impliciture ‘I’ve had breakfast’ is usually<br />

understood as referring to ‘today’s breakfast’ <strong>and</strong> not to some indefinite past event. The first<br />

experiment tested per<strong>for</strong>mance of older adults on interpretation of implicitures without context. In <strong>the</strong><br />

second experiment, implicitures were presented in two counterbalanced context conditions, ei<strong>the</strong>r<br />

supporting <strong>the</strong> context free meaning or cancelling it. The relationship between participants’ frontal<br />

scores <strong>and</strong> correct per<strong>for</strong>mance on impliciture comprehension was assessed in both experiments.<br />

Results revealed a strong negative correlation between frontal scores <strong>and</strong> errors in cancelling<br />

contexts. Nei<strong>the</strong>r context free nor supporting context conditions showed such effects. Based on results<br />

of o<strong>the</strong>r studies using <strong>the</strong> same measures of frontal function (e.g. Glisky & Kong, 2008), we suggest<br />

that a decline in <strong>the</strong> integration processes of working memory, ra<strong>the</strong>r than different executive<br />

functions, might be responsible <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> observed results. We speculate that processes of <strong>the</strong> episodic<br />

buffer (Baddley, 2000) might play an important role in integration of in<strong>for</strong>mation from different<br />

sources in language pragmatics.<br />

Notes<br />

95


P43<br />

The development of morphological processing in reading Chinese<br />

Kai Yan Dustin Lau<br />

<strong>University</strong> of Hong Kong<br />

E-mail: dustin@graduate.hku.hk<br />

Morphological awareness is important <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> development of reading. Base on <strong>the</strong> studies of<br />

morphological processing in reading, three processing models were proposed: <strong>the</strong> Interactive<br />

Constituency Model (Tan & Perfetti, 1999), Taft, Liu, & Zhu’s (1999) Interactive-Activation Model<br />

(hereafter referred to as <strong>the</strong> IAM model) <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> processing model suggested by Zhou & Marslen-<br />

Wilson (2000). The constructions of <strong>the</strong>se three processing models are similar in that <strong>the</strong>y all assume<br />

a triangular relation between orthography, phonology <strong>and</strong> semantics, <strong>and</strong> that both whole-word <strong>and</strong><br />

decomposed processing are involved in decoding complex words. They also have similar predictions<br />

in terms of <strong>the</strong> accuracy <strong>and</strong> latency of decoding morphologically complex words of different<br />

frequency levels <strong>and</strong> morphological productivity. In contrast, <strong>the</strong> IAM model is <strong>the</strong> most distinctive<br />

in (1) predicting that free morphemes facilitate word recognition, <strong>and</strong> (2) proposing a mechanism of<br />

development based on print exposure. The aim of <strong>the</strong> current study is to verify <strong>the</strong>se two distinctive<br />

features of <strong>the</strong> IAM model. To achieve this, two steps were involved. The first step is <strong>the</strong><br />

establishment of a data corpus of primary school Chinese words with morphological analysis which<br />

allows careful control of morphological properties, including word <strong>and</strong> morphemic frequencies,<br />

boundness <strong>and</strong> productivity, of stimuli in a developmental perspective. The second step is that<br />

children from Grade 2, 4 & 6 were recruited to read frequency-controlled bi-morphemic Chinese<br />

words with different boundness <strong>and</strong> productivity. Results showed that significant boundness effect<br />

<strong>and</strong> productivity effects were observed in Grade 6 which is comparable with <strong>the</strong> per<strong>for</strong>mance<br />

predictions of <strong>the</strong> IAM model. Results from Grade 2 & 4 not only support <strong>the</strong> developmental<br />

mechanism proposed by <strong>the</strong> model but also provide insightful in<strong>for</strong>mation on <strong>the</strong> development of<br />

boundness awareness. Theoretical <strong>and</strong> educational implications were discussed.<br />

References<br />

Taft, M., Liu, Y., & Zhu, X. (1999). Morphemic Processing in Reading Chinese. In J. Wang, A.<br />

Inhoff & H.-C. Chen (Eds.), Reading Chinese Scripts: A cognitive analysis (pp. 91-114). N.J.:<br />

Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.<br />

Tan, L. H., & Perfetti, C. A. (1999). Phonological activation in visual identification of Chinese twocharacter<br />

words. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, <strong>and</strong> Cognition, 25(2),<br />

382-393.<br />

Zhou, X., & Marslen-Wilson, W. (2000). Lexical representation of compound words: Cross-linguistic<br />

evidence. Psychologia, 43, 47-66.<br />

Notes<br />

96


P44<br />

Perspective Priming in Spatial Descriptions<br />

Elena Andonova 1 , & Kenny Coventry 2<br />

1 <strong>University</strong> of Bremen, Germany, 2 Northumbria <strong>University</strong> UK<br />

E-mail: e<strong>and</strong>onova@gmail.com<br />

Variability in perspective is an important feature of spatial language. Previous findings point to <strong>the</strong><br />

role of a number of individual, environmental, <strong>and</strong> learning factors as a source of variability in<br />

perspective choices <strong>and</strong> in perspective switching behavior. It remains unclear, however, to what<br />

extent individuals’ choices can be affected by verbal perspective priming <strong>and</strong> perspective switching.<br />

This was <strong>the</strong> goal of our study in which we used a confederate paradigm to prime choices of survey<br />

vs. route/o<strong>the</strong>r perspective in descriptions of routes. A route <strong>and</strong> an environment are described from<br />

an ‘external’ or allocentric view in a survey (S) perspective, <strong>and</strong> from an embedded, or egocentric<br />

view in a route (R) perspective. In this study, 43 participants took turns with a confederate in<br />

producing route directions in four blocks of four routes each in response to schematic maps. The 1st<br />

<strong>and</strong> 3rd block were described by <strong>the</strong> confederate who followed one of four possible scripts while<br />

participants produced responses on <strong>the</strong> 2nd <strong>and</strong> 4th block. The confederate scripts included route<br />

directions in a spatial perspective that was ei<strong>the</strong>r consistent (route or survey only) or inconsistent<br />

across <strong>the</strong> two confederate blocks yielding four priming conditions based on confederates’<br />

perspective in describing <strong>the</strong> 1st <strong>and</strong> 3rd block of stimuli (SS, RR, RS, SR). Participants’ responses<br />

were transcribed <strong>and</strong> coded <strong>for</strong> spatial perspective as survey, route, or mixed, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> ratio of survey<br />

perspective choices out of all valid responses was calculated. Route descriptions dominated overall<br />

while survey descriptions averaged 28.67% on <strong>the</strong> early block <strong>and</strong> 32.74% on <strong>the</strong> later block.<br />

Significantly, participants’ choices of spatial perspective were influenced by <strong>the</strong> perspective <strong>the</strong><br />

confederate used on <strong>the</strong> preceding trials – more responses in <strong>the</strong> survey perspective were produced on<br />

<strong>the</strong> early block if <strong>the</strong> confederate had just used <strong>the</strong> survey than <strong>the</strong> route perspective (41.27% vs.<br />

15.48%; t=2.26, p


P45<br />

The effect of cohort competition <strong>and</strong> semantics in spoken word<br />

recognition: An fMRI study<br />

Jie Zhuang 1 , William D. Marslen-Wilson 2 , Billi R<strong>and</strong>all 1 , Michael A. Ford 1 ,<br />

& Lorraine K. Tyler 1<br />

1 <strong>University</strong> of Cambridge, UK, 2 MRC Cognition <strong>and</strong> <strong>Brain</strong> Sciences Unit, Cambridge, UK<br />

E-mail: jzhuang@csl.psychol.cam.ac.uk<br />

Spoken word recognition involves <strong>the</strong> activation of multiple word c<strong>and</strong>idates based on <strong>the</strong> initial<br />

speech input - <strong>the</strong> “cohort” - <strong>and</strong> selection amongst <strong>the</strong>se competitors. Selection may be purely a<br />

sensory process or it may be facilitated by o<strong>the</strong>r aspects of lexical representation, such as a word’s<br />

meaning (Marslen-Wilson, 1987). Here we tested this latter hypo<strong>the</strong>sis in an fMRI study by<br />

presenting subjects with words <strong>and</strong> pseudo-words <strong>for</strong> lexical decision. In a factorial design we<br />

manipulated (a) cohort competition (high/low competitive cohorts where <strong>the</strong>re is high/low<br />

competition amongst c<strong>and</strong>idates), <strong>and</strong> (b) <strong>the</strong> word’s meaning (high/low imageability). In a previous<br />

behavioural study (Tyler et al., 2000), we found that imageability facilitated word recognition but<br />

only <strong>for</strong> words in high competitive cohorts. In <strong>the</strong> imaging study, we found greater activity in left<br />

inferior parietal lobule with increased cohort competition, an imageability effect in right posterior<br />

superior temporal gyrus (STG) <strong>and</strong> precentral gyrus, <strong>and</strong> a significant interaction between<br />

imageability <strong>and</strong> cohort competition in left STG. In words with high competitive cohorts, high<br />

imageability words generated stronger activity than low imageability words, whereas <strong>for</strong> words in<br />

low competitive cohorts, <strong>the</strong>re was no difference in <strong>the</strong> amount of activity generated by high or low<br />

imageability words. These results support <strong>the</strong> behavioural data in showing that selection processes do<br />

not rely solely on <strong>the</strong> sensory input but ra<strong>the</strong>r that <strong>the</strong> meaning of c<strong>and</strong>idate words facilitates<br />

discrimination between competitors.<br />

References:<br />

Marslen-Wilson, W. D. (1987). Functional parallelism in spoken word-recognition. Cognition, 25,<br />

71-102.<br />

Tyler, L. K., Voice, J. K., & Moss, H. E. (2000). The interaction of meaning <strong>and</strong> sound in spoken<br />

word recognition. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review, 7(2), 320-326.<br />

Notes<br />

98


Structural priming of voice <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> repetition of <strong>the</strong> phonological<br />

verb <strong>for</strong>m<br />

P46<br />

Andriy Myachykov 1 , Holly P. Branigan 1 , & Christoph Scheepers 2<br />

1 <strong>University</strong> of Edinburgh, UK, 2 <strong>University</strong> of Glasgow, UK<br />

E-mail: a.myachykov@ed.ac.uk<br />

Research on syntactic priming in production has shown that speakers are more likely to produce a<br />

passive ra<strong>the</strong>r than an active sentence after having produced a passive in a previous trial (e.g., Bock,<br />

1986; Bock & Loebell, 1990). Priming materials in <strong>the</strong>se <strong>and</strong> similar studies were ei<strong>the</strong>r in active or<br />

in passive voice <strong>and</strong> subsequent target responses (descriptions of transitive pictures) were accordingly<br />

coded as active or passive. In reality target responses may show considerable additional variation. For<br />

example, speakers may produce targets comprising <strong>the</strong> same structure as <strong>the</strong> prime, such as, (1) “The<br />

clown is kicked by <strong>the</strong> boxer”, (2) “The clown is being kicked by <strong>the</strong> boxer” as well as sentences in<br />

active voice: (3) “The boxer is kicking <strong>the</strong> clown” or (4) “The boxer kicked <strong>the</strong> clown”. Note that <strong>the</strong><br />

(finite, active) verb in target (4) does not share morphological features with <strong>the</strong> (non-finite, passive)<br />

verb in <strong>the</strong> prime, yet it repeats <strong>the</strong> prime verb’s phonological <strong>for</strong>m (“-ed”). Such phonological<br />

repetition may be non-accidental, but independent of structural priming (cf. Clel<strong>and</strong> & Pickering,<br />

2003).<br />

We tested this prediction in a study that used <strong>the</strong> same design as Bock (1986). English speaking<br />

participants read prime sentences in ei<strong>the</strong>r active (e.g., “The student is chasing <strong>the</strong> lecturer”) or<br />

passive (e.g., “The lecturer is being chased by <strong>the</strong> student”) voice <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>y later described<br />

semantically unrelated pictures of transitive events. They were instructed to describe <strong>the</strong> target<br />

pictures any way <strong>the</strong>y wanted, using a single sentence. We coded responses <strong>for</strong> structure (active vs.<br />

passive) <strong>and</strong> repetition of phonological verb <strong>for</strong>m alone. A classical structural priming effect was<br />

found. There was also repetition of phonological verb <strong>for</strong>m, but crucially, it did not interact with<br />

structural priming. Hence, repetition of phonological verb <strong>for</strong>m occurs independently of <strong>the</strong> structural<br />

priming effect. We conclude that active/passive priming is independent of repeated phonological<br />

verb-features between prime <strong>and</strong> target.<br />

Notes<br />

99


P47<br />

Avoiding processing cost: Differential strategies in <strong>the</strong> production of<br />

restrictive relative clauses<br />

Letícia M.S. Corrêa 1 , Marina A.R. Augusto 2 , Fern<strong>and</strong>a V. Mir<strong>and</strong>a 1 , & Mercedes Marcilese 1<br />

1 Catholic <strong>University</strong> of Rio de Janeiro, Brazil, 2 Estate <strong>University</strong> of Rio de Janeiro, Brazil<br />

E-mail: lscorrea@puc-rio.br<br />

This paper is concerned with <strong>the</strong> production of relative clauses (RCs). It aims at verifying <strong>the</strong> extent<br />

to which production strategies reflect <strong>the</strong> dem<strong>and</strong>s of <strong>the</strong> internal processing of RCs as defined by<br />

focus (<strong>the</strong> grammatical function of <strong>the</strong> relativized element in <strong>the</strong> RC, according to Keenan &<br />

Comrie´s (1977) Accessibility Hierarchy) <strong>and</strong> planning condition. It relates to <strong>the</strong> connectivity<br />

problem (Bianchi 2002) <strong>and</strong> to <strong>the</strong> depth-of-embedding <strong>the</strong>ory (Ishizuka 2005). A model of RC online<br />

computation is proposed, which takes into account two competing linguistic analyses: The Head<br />

Raising (HRA) (Kayne 1994), which assumes that <strong>the</strong> relative head undergoes movement from inside<br />

<strong>the</strong> RC - <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Matching Analysis (MA) (Sauerl<strong>and</strong> 1998, 2003; Citko 2001), which proposes that<br />

<strong>the</strong> head is based-generated in a CP external position. From <strong>the</strong> point of view of sentence production,<br />

<strong>the</strong> first one would account <strong>for</strong> fully planned restrictive RCs, whereas <strong>the</strong> MA would also be<br />

compatible with a planning situation in which <strong>the</strong> need <strong>for</strong> a restrictive modifier is noticed as <strong>the</strong> DP<br />

is produced. Three possible RC <strong>for</strong>mation strategies are considered: st<strong>and</strong>ard (S) (<strong>the</strong>re is a gap in <strong>the</strong><br />

position of <strong>the</strong> relativized element in <strong>the</strong> RC <strong>and</strong> pied piping is required); gapped (G) (<strong>the</strong>re is a gap<br />

but nei<strong>the</strong>r pied piping nor preposition str<strong>and</strong>ing) <strong>and</strong> resumptive (R) (a pronoun fills in <strong>the</strong> gap). A<br />

production task elicited by preamble was per<strong>for</strong>med by Portuguese speaking adults in two conditions<br />

(fully planned (FP); planned on-line (OL)). They were presented to two pictures <strong>and</strong> a sentence<br />

containing additional in<strong>for</strong>mation about one of <strong>the</strong>m in a screen. The preamble was a transitive<br />

sentence with a missing object DP. Participants were requested to read it aloud <strong>and</strong> to continue it,<br />

making reference to one of <strong>the</strong> pictures. 24 test trials <strong>and</strong> 56 distractors were r<strong>and</strong>omly presented. In<br />

<strong>the</strong> test trials, <strong>the</strong> two pictures were identical. Referring to <strong>the</strong> target would require creating an RC<br />

with <strong>the</strong> additional in<strong>for</strong>mation provided. In FP, <strong>the</strong> additional in<strong>for</strong>mation was available from <strong>the</strong><br />

beginning; in OL, it was provided after <strong>the</strong> production of <strong>the</strong> preamble had started. 4 types of relatives<br />

were elicited, varying as a function of focus – direct object, indirect object with functional<br />

preposition; IO with lexical preposition <strong>and</strong> genitive. The dependent variables were <strong>the</strong> number of S,<br />

G <strong>and</strong> R responses which were submitted to ANOVAs. The results are in accord to <strong>the</strong> predictions<br />

showing that <strong>the</strong> dem<strong>and</strong>s of focus are enhanced in <strong>the</strong> OL condition giving rise to more non-st<strong>and</strong>ard<br />

strategies.<br />

Notes<br />

100


P48<br />

The grammatical class effect in <strong>the</strong> picture-word interference paradigm<br />

Niels Janssen 1 , Alissa Melinger 2 , Brad<strong>for</strong>d Z. Mahon 3 , Mat<strong>the</strong>w Finkbeiner 4 ,<br />

& Alfonso Caramazza 3<br />

1 CNRS & Université de Provence, France, 2 Dundee <strong>University</strong>, UK,<br />

3 Harvard <strong>University</strong>, USA, 4 Macquarie <strong>Centre</strong> <strong>for</strong> Cognitive Science, Australia<br />

E-mail: niels.janssen@univ-provence.fr<br />

A common assumption in current models of language production is that lexical selection is<br />

competitive <strong>and</strong> grammatically constrained (e.g., Levelt, 1989). Major support <strong>for</strong> this assumption<br />

comes from <strong>the</strong> grammatical class effect in <strong>the</strong> picture-word interference paradigm reported by<br />

Pechmann <strong>and</strong> Zerbst (2002): A distracter’s grammatical class affected picture naming latencies in a<br />

sentence frame, but not in a bare noun naming condition. The absence of <strong>the</strong> effect in <strong>the</strong> bare noun<br />

condition ruled out a simple semantic interpretation <strong>and</strong> suggests an effect of grammatical class per<br />

se. However, <strong>the</strong> interpretation of this result is complicated by <strong>the</strong> fact that <strong>the</strong> manipulation of<br />

grammatical class was confounded with distracter word imageability, <strong>and</strong> that distracter word<br />

imageability has been shown to affect naming latencies <strong>the</strong> picture-word interference paradigm (e.g.,<br />

Lupker, 1979). Thus, <strong>the</strong> question whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>re is a grammatical class effect in <strong>the</strong> picture-word<br />

interference paradigm remains unresolved. In order to fur<strong>the</strong>r investigate this issue, in Experiment 1,<br />

distracter grammatical class (nouns vs verbs) was crossed with distracter imageability (high versus<br />

low), <strong>and</strong> pictures of common objects were named in bare noun <strong>and</strong> sentence frame contexts. Both<br />

naming contexts revealed main effects of distracter imageability, but not of grammatical class, <strong>and</strong> no<br />

interaction. To fur<strong>the</strong>r investigate <strong>the</strong> discrepancy between our results <strong>and</strong> those of Pechmann <strong>and</strong><br />

colleagues, we attempted to replicate <strong>the</strong>ir main results. Surprisingly, in Experiment 2, we failed to<br />

establish <strong>the</strong> reliability of <strong>the</strong>ir data. These results undermine <strong>the</strong> use of <strong>the</strong> grammatical class effect<br />

in <strong>the</strong> PWI paradigm as supportive of <strong>the</strong> hypo<strong>the</strong>sis of grammatically constrained lexical selection.<br />

The results are consistent with <strong>the</strong> assumption that lexical selection is grammatically constrained but<br />

not competitive (e.g., Dell, 1986).<br />

Notes<br />

101


P49<br />

The effect of argument status of PP modifiers on subject-verb agreement<br />

errors in Portuguese<br />

Erica dos Santos Rodrigues<br />

Catholic <strong>University</strong> of Rio de Janeiro, Brazil<br />

E-mail: ericasr@puc-rio.br<br />

It is well-established that agreement errors occur when <strong>the</strong>re is a number mismatch between a head<br />

noun <strong>and</strong> a local noun within a PP (cf. Bock & Eberhard, 1993; Harsuiker et al. 2003). Never<strong>the</strong>less,<br />

<strong>the</strong> role of <strong>the</strong> argument status of PP modifiers on attraction errors is not clear. We investigated this<br />

factor in Brazilian Portuguese speakers, by means of an error elicitation experiment in which <strong>the</strong> head<br />

noun transitivity was manipulated. Two conditions were contrasted: (i) a condition in which <strong>the</strong> head<br />

was a transitive deverbal noun <strong>and</strong> its modifier was an argument PP <strong>and</strong> (ii) a condition in which <strong>the</strong><br />

head was a non-transitive noun <strong>and</strong> its modifier was an adjunct PP. In order to increase errors<br />

occurrence, we enlarged <strong>the</strong> modifier length by adding an adjective after <strong>the</strong> local noun. The<br />

preposition “de” was used to link <strong>the</strong> NP <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> PP modifier - see examples (A) e (B). The results<br />

show an argumenthood effect, with more agreement errors after PP arguments than after PP adjuncts.<br />

We explain <strong>the</strong> errors based on a language production model that incorporates a monitoring-parser<br />

which works in parallel to <strong>the</strong> speech <strong>for</strong>mulation. We analyze <strong>the</strong> plural interference of <strong>the</strong> local<br />

noun as occurring after <strong>the</strong> NP subject has been produced. The NP subject representation would be<br />

maintained in <strong>the</strong> working memory after its production <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> verb number would be predicted based<br />

on this representation. The predominance of errors <strong>for</strong> local nouns in PP arguments is explained as a<br />

function of <strong>the</strong>ir markedness <strong>and</strong> of <strong>the</strong> way PP arguments <strong>and</strong> adjuncts are attached to <strong>the</strong> syntactic<br />

tree. Adopting <strong>the</strong> adjunction analyses from Hornstein & Nunes (2006), arguments would necessarily<br />

require being part of labeled structures <strong>and</strong> adjuncts may not invoke labeled structures <strong>and</strong> could be<br />

attached to <strong>the</strong> structure simply through a concatenation procedure, being its output interpreted as a<br />

conjunction at <strong>the</strong> Conceptual Intentional Interface. These differences could interfere in <strong>the</strong> local<br />

noun accessibility. Assuming that elements would be more accessible in labeled structures than in<br />

non-labeled ones, we suggest that local nouns within PP arguments would be more prone to interfere<br />

in <strong>the</strong> verb morphophonological encoding. There<strong>for</strong>e <strong>the</strong>y would induce more agreement errors than<br />

adjuncts, which would have a weaker accessibility.<br />

(A) A restauração de quadros valiosos ... (PP argument)<br />

pl. noun + adjective<br />

“The restoration of valuable pictures …”<br />

(B) O apartamento de cômodos pequenos... (PP adjunct)<br />

pl. noun + adjective<br />

“The small rooms’ apartment…”<br />

Notes<br />

102


P50<br />

When h<strong>and</strong>s convey <strong>the</strong> concreteness of words: <strong>Language</strong> production in<br />

cued speech<br />

Eva Smolka, Alberto Aviles, & Manuel Carreiras<br />

<strong>University</strong> of La Laguna, Tenerife, Spain<br />

E-mail: esmolka@ull.es<br />

Concrete words usually show a processing advantage when compared with abstract words. However,<br />

this effect has been established only in <strong>the</strong> oral domain. This study examined whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong><br />

concreteness of words is represented via <strong>the</strong> h<strong>and</strong> gestures that accompany <strong>the</strong> language production of<br />

Cued <strong>Speech</strong> (CS). CS is a speechreading supplement <strong>for</strong> deaf people that represents <strong>the</strong> phonemes of<br />

<strong>the</strong> spoken language in a visual mode. Similarly looking articulatory movements (e.g., /be/ <strong>and</strong> /pi/)<br />

are assigned different h<strong>and</strong> shapes (consonants) <strong>and</strong> h<strong>and</strong> placements (vowels) to produce a visually<br />

clear <strong>and</strong> unambiguous representation of <strong>the</strong> phoneme. The additional in<strong>for</strong>mation via h<strong>and</strong>s in CS<br />

thus provides <strong>for</strong> unequivocal speechreading of phonemes.<br />

Given that CS represents <strong>the</strong> phonemes of a spoken language, research so far has concentrated on <strong>the</strong><br />

phonological skills that are enhanced via CS. The present study examined whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> supplementary<br />

h<strong>and</strong> gestures become part of <strong>the</strong> motor program in <strong>the</strong> production of CS. If <strong>the</strong> manual cues in CS do<br />

not only represent phonemic in<strong>for</strong>mation but also convey <strong>the</strong> semantic in<strong>for</strong>mation of word concepts,<br />

we may expect a concreteness effect similar to <strong>the</strong> one observed in oral languages.<br />

We recorded <strong>the</strong> production of abstract <strong>and</strong> concrete words of high- <strong>and</strong> low-frequency in a CS<br />

speaker. For each word, we measured both <strong>the</strong> onset of <strong>the</strong> first h<strong>and</strong> movement <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> onset of <strong>the</strong><br />

h<strong>and</strong> shape signifying <strong>the</strong> first consonant. Results showed that <strong>the</strong> onset of <strong>the</strong> first consonant was<br />

produced significantly faster in concrete words than in abstract words. However, word frequency did<br />

not affect cue production. The finding of a concreteness effect in CS indicates that <strong>the</strong> motor program<br />

of h<strong>and</strong> gestures becomes part of language representation. That is, <strong>the</strong> manual cues of CS do not only<br />

supplement phonemic in<strong>for</strong>mation but also convey <strong>the</strong> conceptual in<strong>for</strong>mation of words. We discuss<br />

<strong>the</strong> implications of <strong>the</strong>se findings <strong>for</strong> models on <strong>the</strong> role of gestures in speech.<br />

Notes<br />

103


P51<br />

Effects of phonological length in <strong>the</strong> processing of scrambling in Japanese<br />

Mizuho Imada, Haruko Matsui, Edson T. Miyamoto, Inna P. Subacheva,<br />

& Takumi Tagawa<br />

<strong>University</strong> of Tsukuba, Japan<br />

E-mail: etm@lingua.tsukuba.ac.jp<br />

According to one model advocating <strong>the</strong> influence of syntactic complexity on comprehension, distance<br />

should be measured taking into account structure (Hawkins, 1994, 2004). We argue that length effects<br />

in OSV orders in Japanese are better captured by phonological length.<br />

Most of Hawkins’ points can be made with a simpler metric based on phonological length (e.g.,<br />

number of moras in Japanese) <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>re are various problems with his metric <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> evidence<br />

supporting it. First, <strong>the</strong> metric is not incremental as <strong>the</strong> ratio proposed can only be calculated when<br />

<strong>the</strong> entire constituent has been read. Second, although data on an impressive range of languages are<br />

reported, <strong>the</strong> sample <strong>for</strong> each language is small.<br />

Third, Hawkins claims that his metric correctly predicts <strong>the</strong> word order <strong>for</strong> 95% of sentences in<br />

Japanese collected from three novels. But it only does so when it overwhelmingly favors SOV over<br />

OSV. An example of a counter-intuitive prediction is that SOV should be favored if <strong>the</strong> subject is<br />

three (or more) words long regardless of <strong>the</strong> length of <strong>the</strong> object. But this does no better than ignoring<br />

length <strong>and</strong> always predicting SOV over OSV. These points will be illustrated with counts from <strong>the</strong><br />

Kyoto Corpus (Kurohashi & Nagao, 1997).<br />

We also conducted a self-paced reading experiment with native Japanese speakers using SOV <strong>and</strong><br />

OSV sentences where <strong>the</strong> subject is modified by constituents that are long or short phonologically,<br />

such as soyana-tukurino isuno dezaina (‘designer of <strong>the</strong> chair with a rough built’, 10 moras) <strong>and</strong><br />

sensaina-kouzouno hondanano dezaina (‘designer of <strong>the</strong> bookcase with a delicate structure’, 14<br />

moras; independent measures detected no differences in terms of plausibility, frequency or<br />

familiarity; all Fs


Does bilingualism change native-language reading Cognate effects in<br />

sentence context<br />

P52<br />

Eva Van Assche, Wouter Duyck, Robert J. Hartsuiker, & Kevin Diependaele<br />

Ghent <strong>University</strong>, Belgium<br />

E-mail: eva.vanassche@ugent.be<br />

This study on bilingual language processing investigated how knowledge of a second language (L2)<br />

influences native language (L1) sentence reading. In isolated (out-of-context) word recognition, Van<br />

Hell <strong>and</strong> Dijkstra (2002) showed that Dutch-English cognates (words with identical meanings <strong>and</strong><br />

similar spellings across languages, e.g., <strong>the</strong> Dutch-English translation pair 'schip-ship') were<br />

processed faster than noncognates by bilinguals per<strong>for</strong>ming a lexical decision task in <strong>the</strong>ir native<br />

language. In Experiment 1 of <strong>the</strong> present study, we replicated this L1 cognate facilitation effect.<br />

These results show that L2 lexical in<strong>for</strong>mation influences processing in <strong>the</strong> first language <strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong>re<strong>for</strong>e suggests language-nonselective activation of words in <strong>the</strong> bilingual lexicon. It is unclear<br />

however, whe<strong>the</strong>r this finding generalizes to words in a sentence context. The language of <strong>the</strong><br />

sentence may be used as a cue to guide lexical access <strong>for</strong> upcoming words. This would indeed be a<br />

very efficient strategy to speed up word recognition, because this would limit lexical search to lexical<br />

entries of only one language.<br />

We addressed this question by investigating <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> first time cross-lingual activations in native<br />

language sentence reading by bilinguals. The cognates <strong>and</strong> control words of Experiment 1 were<br />

presented in <strong>the</strong> same low constraint sentence contexts (e.g. Zijn jongste zoontje wou zich al seen<br />

PILOT/KONIJN verkleden voor carnival [His youngest son wanted to dress up as a PILOT/RABBIT<br />

<strong>for</strong> carnival]). A sentence completion study made sure each cognate <strong>and</strong> control word was equally<br />

(low) predictable on <strong>the</strong> basis of <strong>the</strong> sentence context. Subjects were instructed to silently read <strong>the</strong><br />

sentences appearing on <strong>the</strong> screen while eye movements were measured. This method allows <strong>for</strong><br />

normal reading <strong>and</strong> does not require intervening tasks that may disrupt <strong>the</strong> reading process. Results<br />

show a cognate advantage on first fixation durations <strong>and</strong> gaze durations.<br />

This study provides a very conservative test of a truly non-selective language system, because we<br />

tested <strong>for</strong> an influence of <strong>the</strong> non-dominant L2 on <strong>the</strong> native L1. The presence of a cognate effect in<br />

native sentence processing proves that representations of a non-dominant language get activated<br />

strongly enough to affect word recognition in <strong>the</strong> mo<strong>the</strong>r tongue.<br />

References<br />

Van Hell, J.G., & Dijkstra, A. (2002). Foreign language knowledge can influence native language<br />

per<strong>for</strong>mance in exclusively native contexts. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review, 9, 780-789.<br />

Notes<br />

105


P53<br />

Retrieval <strong>and</strong> use of components of lexical knowledge depend on<br />

situational dem<strong>and</strong>s<br />

Falk Huettig, & James M. McQueen<br />

Max Planck Institute <strong>for</strong> Psycholinguistics, Nijmegen, The Ne<strong>the</strong>rl<strong>and</strong>s<br />

E-mail: falk.huettig@mpi.nl<br />

Eye movements during language-mediated visual search depend on establishing matches between<br />

in<strong>for</strong>mation extracted from <strong>the</strong> visual display <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> speech signal. Huettig <strong>and</strong> McQueen (2007)<br />

found that <strong>the</strong>se matches can be made at phonological, visual-feature <strong>and</strong> semantic levels.<br />

Importantly, fixations were determined by <strong>the</strong> type of in<strong>for</strong>mation in <strong>the</strong> display. When it contained<br />

pictures, <strong>the</strong>re was a tug of war among fixations determined by all three knowledge types. But when<br />

<strong>the</strong> pictures were replaced with printed words (<strong>the</strong>ir names), preferential fixations were based only on<br />

phonological matches. Eye movements thus appear to depend on situational dem<strong>and</strong>s: when<br />

participants see print, <strong>the</strong>y use only <strong>for</strong>m-based lexical knowledge, but when <strong>the</strong>y see pictures, <strong>the</strong>y<br />

also use conceptual (visual-feature <strong>and</strong> semantic) knowledge.<br />

In two experiments we asked whe<strong>the</strong>r conceptual knowledge can ever be used to direct visual<br />

attention to a printed word array. The materials in Experiment 1 were <strong>the</strong> same as in Huettig <strong>and</strong><br />

McQueen (2007), except that <strong>the</strong> phonological competitors were replaced with unrelated distractors.<br />

The printed-word arrays <strong>the</strong>re<strong>for</strong>e consisted of semantic <strong>and</strong> visual-feature competitors of critical<br />

spoken words, <strong>and</strong> two unrelated distractors. We observed significant shifts in eye gaze towards <strong>the</strong><br />

semantic but not <strong>the</strong> visual-feature competitors. In Experiment 2 we replaced <strong>the</strong> semantic<br />

competitors with a fur<strong>the</strong>r set of unrelated distractors. The only match between <strong>the</strong> spoken word <strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> printed words was now one involving <strong>the</strong> typical visual <strong>for</strong>m of <strong>the</strong> spoken word's referent. There<br />

was no hint of preferential fixations towards <strong>the</strong> visual competitors. This is surprising because<br />

fixations in response to exactly <strong>the</strong> same spoken materials included looks to <strong>the</strong>se visual competitors<br />

when <strong>the</strong>y were presented as pictures.<br />

The task situation <strong>the</strong>re<strong>for</strong>e appears to mediate visual-world behavior. Although participants<br />

confronted with print arrays are encouraged to focus on <strong>for</strong>m-based knowledge, <strong>the</strong>y can use semantic<br />

knowledge to direct attention when phonological matches are impossible. But <strong>the</strong>y do not seem to be<br />

able to use visual-feature knowledge to direct attention to arrays of printed words. Retrieval of<br />

conceptual knowledge <strong>the</strong>re<strong>for</strong>e appears not to be an automatic consequence of exposure to printed<br />

words (Stolz & Besner, 1999; cf. Norris et al., 2006, with respect to spoken input). We argue that<br />

both <strong>the</strong> retrieval of components of lexical knowledge <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir use in directing visual attention<br />

depend on <strong>the</strong> situation in which participants find <strong>the</strong>mselves.<br />

Notes<br />

106


P54<br />

Evidence <strong>for</strong> different processes underlying idiom comprehension in L1<br />

<strong>and</strong> L2: An eye-tracking study<br />

Anna Siyanova, Kathy Conklin, & Norbert Schmitt<br />

<strong>University</strong> of Nottingham, UK<br />

E-mail: aexas7@nottingham.ac.uk<br />

This study investigates processing of frequently occurring idioms in a first <strong>and</strong> second language. The<br />

meaning of an idiom is not usually literal <strong>and</strong>, <strong>the</strong>re<strong>for</strong>e, cannot be understood from <strong>the</strong> meaning of<br />

its constituent words (‘kick <strong>the</strong> bucket’ does not mean strike a pale with a foot). Because its meaning<br />

cannot be computed, researchers have proposed that such expressions are stored holistically in <strong>the</strong><br />

mental lexicon. This study investigates whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>re is a processing advantage <strong>for</strong> idioms over<br />

control phrases <strong>and</strong> <strong>for</strong> idioms’ figurative uses over literal ones.<br />

In <strong>the</strong> experiment, participants’ eye movements were monitored while reading short stories which<br />

contained idioms used figuratively (‘a breath of fresh air’ – something new <strong>and</strong> refreshing), literally<br />

(‘a breath of fresh air’ – brea<strong>the</strong> in some fresh air), or control phrases (‘a breath of clean air’). When<br />

idioms were presented, <strong>the</strong> discourse context clearly biased <strong>the</strong> reader towards ei<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> figurative or<br />

literal meaning.<br />

Most of <strong>the</strong> research on idiom comprehension to date has been carried out with native speakers. Very<br />

little is known about <strong>the</strong> way nonnative speakers process idiomatic expressions on-line. Our results<br />

showed that monolinguals made fewer <strong>and</strong> shorter fixations to idioms than to control phrases.<br />

Monolinguals also read idioms used figuratively equally fast as idioms used literally. On <strong>the</strong> contrary,<br />

bilingual fixation durations <strong>and</strong> fixation count <strong>for</strong> literal uses were found to be significantly shorter<br />

<strong>and</strong> fewer than <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir figurative counterparts. Fur<strong>the</strong>r, nei<strong>the</strong>r of <strong>the</strong> two idiom senses was found to<br />

be different from control phrases.<br />

Monolingual results indicate a processing advantage <strong>for</strong> fixed expressions over novel language,<br />

irrespectively of <strong>the</strong> intended meaning. They also suggest that literal idiom uses are not processed any<br />

slower than figurative ones, as has been suggested in literature. Because <strong>the</strong> literal meaning, which is<br />

completely compositional, was processed faster than <strong>the</strong> matched control, <strong>and</strong> at <strong>the</strong> same time it was<br />

processed with <strong>the</strong> same speed as its figurative equivalent, it seems plausible to suggest that while <strong>the</strong><br />

figurative meaning is represented in <strong>the</strong> lexicon of a native speaker, <strong>the</strong> literal use also benefits from<br />

this mental representation. Nonnative participants, on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r h<strong>and</strong>, appear to process idioms akin to<br />

novel language (‘a breath of fresh air’ = ‘a breath of clean air’). Bilingual results fur<strong>the</strong>r point to <strong>the</strong><br />

conclusion that, unlike native speakers, <strong>the</strong>se participants may not have idioms’ figurative meanings<br />

stored in <strong>the</strong>ir mental lexicon.<br />

Notes<br />

107


P55<br />

Rapid effects of linguistic alignment on communication<br />

Tanya Kraljic, Yanny Siu, & Victor S. Ferreira<br />

<strong>University</strong> of Cali<strong>for</strong>nia, San Diego, USA<br />

E-mail: ferreira@psy.ucsd.edu<br />

Recent research has vigorously investigated syntactic priming: The tendency <strong>for</strong> speakers to repeat<br />

structures <strong>the</strong>y previously produced or heard <strong>the</strong>ir interlocutors previously produce. Does syntactic<br />

priming cause communicative benefits At least one <strong>the</strong>oretical framework suggests so: The<br />

Interactive Alignment Model (Pickering & Garrod, 2004) claims that when a syntactic structure is<br />

used to express features of meaning, that structure is automatically primed, facilitating re-access of<br />

those features of meaning. This makes a simple prediction: If a conversational participant uses a<br />

particular syntactic structure to express a meaning, <strong>the</strong>y should underst<strong>and</strong> a subsequent sentence<br />

faster if it uses that same structure to express that meaning, compared to a sentence that uses a<br />

different structure.<br />

To test this prediction, we had subject-confederate pairs take turns describing pictures from a<br />

computer screen so that <strong>the</strong>ir partners could select <strong>the</strong>m from pairs shown on <strong>the</strong>ir own computer<br />

screens. On prime trials, subjects described pictures to confederates; on subsequent target trials,<br />

subjects selected pictures described by confederates. Interspersed among filler trials were two types<br />

of critical trials: Lexical trials (to confirm procedural sensitivity), where described pictures admitted<br />

two different labels (fishtank or aquarium), <strong>and</strong> syntactic trials, where described pictures admitted<br />

two syntactic structures (The boxer gave [<strong>the</strong> hat] [to <strong>the</strong> boxer] or [<strong>the</strong> boxer] [<strong>the</strong> hat]). On lexical<br />

trials, subjects heard from confederates descriptions <strong>for</strong> objects on target trials that were <strong>the</strong> same or<br />

<strong>the</strong> opposite of a description <strong>the</strong>y just gave <strong>for</strong> that same object on <strong>the</strong> preceding prime sentence. On<br />

syntactic trials, subjects heard sentences from confederates on target trials that had <strong>the</strong> same or<br />

different structure as <strong>the</strong>y had just used <strong>for</strong> a different picture on <strong>the</strong> preceding prime sentence<br />

(primes <strong>and</strong> targets shared verbs). Results revealed lexical priming: Subjects selected pictures 217 ms<br />

faster when confederates used <strong>the</strong> same label subjects used compared to when confederates used<br />

opposite labels. Critically, priming occurred on syntactic trials: Subjects selected pictures 118 ms<br />

faster when confederates used <strong>the</strong> same structures as subjects compared to when <strong>the</strong>y used opposite<br />

structures. And so <strong>the</strong> Interactive Alignment Model prediction is confirmed: Conversational<br />

participants comprehend sentences faster if <strong>the</strong>y have <strong>the</strong> same structure as <strong>the</strong>y have just used, even<br />

when <strong>the</strong> two sentences describe different content (though with <strong>the</strong> same verb).<br />

Notes<br />

108


P56<br />

Intensionality in sentence <strong>and</strong> discourse processing<br />

Francesca Delogu 1 , & Anthony J. San<strong>for</strong>d 2<br />

1 <strong>University</strong> of Trento, Italy, 2 <strong>University</strong> of Glasgow, UK<br />

E-mail: francesca.delogu@unitn.it<br />

In this paper, we report three eyetracking experiments designed to investigate <strong>the</strong> processing of socalled<br />

intensional transitive verbs <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir role in anaphoric bridging processes. There is wide<br />

agreement that intensional verbs like want <strong>and</strong> need take a proposition-denoting argument which is<br />

realized in syntax through clausal complementation. However, <strong>the</strong>y are natural <strong>and</strong> grammatical when<br />

combined with a direct object, as in John wants a beer. In such cases, different analyses have been<br />

proposed (e.g. Pustejovsky 1995; Larson 2002) that show a tendency to treat such strings as requiring<br />

richer representations than <strong>the</strong> corresponding extensional ones. Consequently, we predicted a cost to<br />

be elicited by strings like wanted a beer compared to drank a beer. This hypo<strong>the</strong>sis was supported by<br />

reading time patterns <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> first sentence in (a), (b) <strong>and</strong> (c). In Experiments 1 <strong>and</strong> 2, first-pass <strong>and</strong><br />

total reading times demonstrated a cost in <strong>the</strong> verb region <strong>for</strong> intensional verbs (wanted) compared to<br />

extensional ones (drank). In <strong>the</strong> object region (a beer), total reading times were significantly slower<br />

following wanted than drank. In Experiment 3, first-pass times were significantly slower in <strong>the</strong> object<br />

region following wanted than wanted to drink.<br />

We also investigated <strong>the</strong> role of intensionality in anaphoric bridging processes. Previous work<br />

(Havil<strong>and</strong> & Clark, 1974, Experiment 2) showed that reading times <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> second sentence of (a)<br />

were significantly slower following an intensional than an extensional context, since readers need to<br />

draw a bridging inference in order to build a coherent text representation (e.g. “Ed got a beer!”). We<br />

predicted that this processing cost should emerge in <strong>the</strong> regions following <strong>the</strong> definite NP, when it<br />

becomes clear that <strong>the</strong> sentence is about <strong>the</strong> actual ra<strong>the</strong>r than a desire world. Surprisingly, we did not<br />

find any clear evidence of bridging processes ei<strong>the</strong>r in Experiment 1 or in Experiment 2 (where <strong>the</strong><br />

anaphoric accessibility of <strong>the</strong> indefinite NP was manipulated by introducing a relative clause).<br />

Finally, Experiment 3 showed that <strong>the</strong> cost elicited by intensional transitive constructions did not<br />

result from a general difficulty in integrating <strong>the</strong> second sentence, since it was independent of<br />

whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> second sentence was an easy or a difficult continuation.<br />

(a) Ed drank/wanted a beer after a walk. The beer was warm (Exp 1- Italian)<br />

(b) Ed drank/wanted a beer after a walk/that was in his refrigerator. The beer was warm (Exp 2-<br />

English)<br />

(c) Ed wanted/wanted to drink a beer. The beer was warm./He was very thirsty. (Exp 3- Italian)<br />

Notes<br />

109


P57<br />

Animacy effects in Chinese relative clauses processing<br />

Fuyun Wu, & Elsi Kaiser<br />

<strong>University</strong> of Sou<strong>the</strong>rn Cali<strong>for</strong>nia, USA<br />

E-mail: fuyunwu@usc.edu<br />

Recent corpus work on relative clauses (RC) found correlations between RC type <strong>and</strong> head noun<br />

animacy: Subject-gapped (s-gap) RCs frequently occur with animate head nouns (1a), whereas objectgapped<br />

(o-gap) RCs occur almost exclusively with inanimate heads (1b, e.g. Rol<strong>and</strong> et al 2007, Mak<br />

et al 2002, Pu 2007).<br />

(1a) [<strong>the</strong> man]HEAD who _ read <strong>the</strong> book (s-gap, head=RC-subj)<br />

(1b) [<strong>the</strong> book]HEAD that <strong>the</strong> man read _ (o-gap, head=RC-obj)<br />

This pattern fits with <strong>the</strong> processing disadvantage observed <strong>for</strong> o-gap RCs with animate heads in<br />

English (Traxler et al 2002, 2005) <strong>and</strong> German (Mak et al 2002, 2006).<br />

In head-initial languages like English, s-gap RCs are easier to process than o-gaps (e.g. King & Just<br />

1991, Traxler et al 2002, Frazier 1987). However, <strong>for</strong> Chinese head-final RCs some studies found s-<br />

gap easier <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs found o-gap easier (e.g. Hsiao & Gibson 2003, Lin & Bever 2005). We<br />

investigated how animacy, which was not directly manipulated in previous psycholinguistic studies of<br />

Chinese RCs, influences processing ease.<br />

CORPUS. Our analysis of <strong>the</strong> animacy patterns in 364 transitive RCs (Chinese Treebank corpus)<br />

corroborates findings from o<strong>the</strong>r languages: most s-gap RCs have animate heads (>70%); o-gap RCs<br />

have inanimate heads (>90%). We also found an animacy distance effect: <strong>the</strong> animacy of <strong>the</strong> head<br />

tends to contrast with <strong>the</strong> animacy of <strong>the</strong> embedded noun.<br />

SELF-PACED READING. We conducted 3 self-paced reading studies to test whe<strong>the</strong>r animacy<br />

influences processing of Chinese RCs in real-time.<br />

Exp1 investigated s-gap RCs; Exp2 investigated o-gap RCs. In both, we manipulated <strong>the</strong> animacy<br />

(animate/inanimate) of (i) head noun <strong>and</strong> (ii) embedded noun, resulting in 4 conditions. Exp1 shows<br />

that in s-gap RCs (head=RCsubj, emb noun= RCobj), an animate head + an inanimate embedded<br />

noun is processed faster than <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r conditions. Exp2 shows that in o-gap RCs (head=RCobj,<br />

embedded noun = RCsubj) inanimate head + animate embedded noun was processed fastest.<br />

EXP.3 tested both s-gap <strong>and</strong> o-gap RCs. We manipulated (i) gap position, <strong>and</strong> (ii) animacy of head<br />

noun <strong>and</strong> embedded noun. We focused on situations where <strong>the</strong> nouns differ in animacy (head=anim,<br />

emb=inanim vs. head=inanim, emb=anim). RTs show effects of gap position (s-gap faster than o-<br />

gap), animacy, <strong>and</strong> a gap position x animacy interaction.<br />

Our findings show that animacy, as well as structural gap position, plays an important role in<br />

influencing ease of processing of Chinese RCs <strong>and</strong> needs to be considered when assessing <strong>the</strong><br />

processing load imposed by s-gap vs. o-gap RCs.<br />

Notes<br />

110


P58<br />

The processing of lexical <strong>and</strong> subcategorization in<strong>for</strong>mation from newly<br />

acquired verbs<br />

Gunnar Jacob, & Roger P.G. van Gompel<br />

<strong>University</strong> of Dundee, UK<br />

E-mail: G.Jacob@dundee.ac.uk<br />

Recent research has investigated both how people process newly acquired lexical items (e.g., Gaskell<br />

& Dumay, 2003) <strong>and</strong> new syntactic structures (e.g., Kaschak & Glenberg, 2004). The present study<br />

combined <strong>the</strong>se approaches by investigating how readers process newly learnt verbs as well as<br />

recently acquired subcategorization frames <strong>for</strong> those verbs, with <strong>the</strong> aim to establish whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>re are<br />

differences in how <strong>the</strong>y process new words <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir subcategorization frames. In a self-pacedreading<br />

experiment, participants read learning trials such as (1a) or (1b), in which a new verb was<br />

introduced with ei<strong>the</strong>r a transitive (1a) or intransitive (1b) subcategorization frame.<br />

(1a)<br />

(1b)<br />

The manager indushed <strong>the</strong> secretary again. Instructing people in such a pedantic way seemed<br />

quite normal <strong>for</strong> him.<br />

The manager indushed again. Instructing in such a pedantic way seemed quite normal <strong>for</strong><br />

him.<br />

Each learning trial was immediately followed by a garden-path target sentence such as (2a) or (2b), in<br />

which <strong>the</strong> artificial verb from <strong>the</strong> learning trial was ei<strong>the</strong>r repeated (2a) or not repeated (2b).<br />

(2a)<br />

(2b)<br />

When <strong>the</strong> teacher indushed <strong>the</strong> learners who were very motivated became furious <strong>and</strong><br />

confused.<br />

When <strong>the</strong> teacher acceeded <strong>the</strong> learners who were very motivated became furious <strong>and</strong><br />

confused.<br />

Research has shown that readers typically experience difficulty while reading such structures, because<br />

<strong>the</strong>y incorrectly analyse <strong>the</strong> intransitive subordinate clause (When <strong>the</strong> teacher indushed) as transitive<br />

(e.g., Frazier & Rayner, 1982; Ferreira & Henderson, 1991). If readers make use of subcategorization<br />

in<strong>for</strong>mation from <strong>the</strong> newly acquired verb in <strong>the</strong> learning trial, this should affect reading difficulty <strong>for</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> target sentences, making <strong>the</strong> target sentences easier after learning trial (1b) than after (1a).<br />

Word-by-word self-paced reading results showed a main effect of verb repetition at <strong>the</strong> artificial verb,<br />

with reading times being faster when <strong>the</strong> verb had previously been encountered in <strong>the</strong> learning trial.<br />

However, we found no effects of transitivity or interactions between transitivity <strong>and</strong> verb repetition in<br />

any segments.<br />

Thus, <strong>the</strong> results suggest that single exposure to a new verb facilitates subsequent processing of that<br />

verb, but that single exposure to subcategorization in<strong>for</strong>mation associated with that verb is not<br />

sufficient to facilitate subsequent processing. We conclude that lexical in<strong>for</strong>mation from a new verb<br />

can be acquired <strong>and</strong> used relatively quickly, whereas <strong>the</strong> acquisition of subcategorization in<strong>for</strong>mation<br />

of new verbs requires more exposure.<br />

Notes<br />

111


P59<br />

Prosodic balance constrains argument structure interpretation in German<br />

Petra Augurzky<br />

Institute <strong>for</strong> Natural <strong>Language</strong> Processing, <strong>University</strong> of Stuttgart, Germany<br />

E-mail: petra.augurzky@ims.uni-stuttgart.de<br />

A central topic in prosodic research concerns <strong>the</strong> relation between prosodic phrasing <strong>and</strong> syntactic<br />

disambiguation. Recently, prosodic phrasing has been shown to be sensitive to balancing dem<strong>and</strong>s<br />

(Fodor, 2002). Until now, studies on <strong>the</strong> interplay between disambiguation <strong>and</strong> balance<br />

predominantly focus on adjunct attachment. However, prosodic phrasing might be more tightly<br />

related to <strong>the</strong> processing of sentential core elements (Schafer et al., 2000). Moreover, balance as an<br />

experimental factor has often been ra<strong>the</strong>r vaguely defined (but see Shaked, 2007).<br />

The present studies explored <strong>the</strong> interaction between balance <strong>and</strong> argument structure in German. First,<br />

a sentence production experiment examined unambiguous sentences. Depending on verbal<br />

transitivity, targets could be interpreted as two-argument- or as possessive constructions. For<br />

satisfying balance, <strong>the</strong> accent stucture in (1) should give rise to an early boundary between <strong>the</strong> DPs in<br />

(1), but to a late boundary following DP2 in (2) (cf. Selkirk, 2000).<br />

(1) ... dass géstern der Fáhrer # der Ríchterin ✓gedróht / gególft hat.<br />

... that yesterday <strong>the</strong> driver <strong>the</strong> judge threatened TR / golfed INTR has<br />

... "that <strong>the</strong> driver threatened <strong>the</strong> judge yesterday." / "that <strong>the</strong> driver of <strong>the</strong> judge golfed<br />

yesterday"<br />

(2) ... dass der Fáhrer der Ríchterin # zum wiederhólten Mal gedróht / ✓gególft hat.<br />

... that <strong>the</strong> driver <strong>the</strong> judge to-<strong>the</strong> repeated time threatened TR / golfed INTR has<br />

... "that <strong>the</strong> driver has threatened <strong>the</strong> judge repeatedly" /"that <strong>the</strong> driver of <strong>the</strong> judge has<br />

golfed repeatedly."<br />

Whereas an early break is associated with a one-argument reading, a late break corresponds to a<br />

possessive interpretation, leading to a potential tension between balance <strong>and</strong> argument structure.<br />

Acoustic analyses revealed that, in accordance with <strong>the</strong> need to signal argument structure, a prosodic<br />

boundary was realized early in <strong>the</strong> two-argument condition, but following DP2 in <strong>the</strong> possessive<br />

condition. Thus, arguments seem to be planned toge<strong>the</strong>r with <strong>the</strong>ir respective heads. Additionally,<br />

balance affected phrasing: N2 duration <strong>and</strong> F0 were increased when accent structure biased toward a<br />

late break, as in (2).<br />

The second experiment, a reading study with globally ambiguous targets, revealed that, besides a<br />

preference <strong>for</strong> an argument interpretation, balance affected ambiguity resolution: The number of<br />

transitive choices was significantly decreased when accentual in<strong>for</strong>mation biased toward an<br />

intransitive reading.<br />

The present results thus suggest that prosodic balance affects argument processing both in production<br />

as well as in silent reading.<br />

Notes<br />

112


P60<br />

Caught between <strong>the</strong> fields: Evidence <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> neural reality of topological<br />

distinctions in <strong>the</strong> comprehension of word order permutations<br />

Tanja Grewe 1 , Matthias Schlesewsky 2 , & Ina Bornkessel-Schlesewsky 3<br />

1 <strong>University</strong> of Applied Sciences, Idstein, Germany, 2 Johannes Gutenberg-Universität, Mainz, Germany,<br />

3 Max Planck Institute <strong>for</strong> Human Cognitive <strong>and</strong> <strong>Brain</strong> Sciences, Leipzig, Germany<br />

E-mail: grewe@fh-fresenius.de<br />

Theoretical approaches to <strong>the</strong> structure of Germanic languages have long assumed a subdivision of<br />

<strong>the</strong> clause into different “topological fields”, which correlate with distinct syntactic properties. In <strong>the</strong><br />

domain of sentence processing, <strong>the</strong> notion of topological fields can account <strong>for</strong> distinctions between<br />

different types of word order permutations, e.g. <strong>the</strong> observation that object-initial orders are easier to<br />

process when <strong>the</strong> initial object resides in <strong>the</strong> clause-initial prefield as opposed to <strong>the</strong> clause-medial<br />

middlefield (cf. Bader & Meng, 1999). Moreover, topological fields play a central role in a recent<br />

computational model of sentence processing (Vosse & Kempen, 2008). The aim of <strong>the</strong> present fMRI<br />

study was to examine whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>se <strong>the</strong>oretical distinctions are reflected in <strong>the</strong> functional<br />

neuroanatomy of sentence processing. To this end, we compared object-initial <strong>and</strong> subject-initial<br />

word orders in German in which <strong>the</strong> object was ei<strong>the</strong>r in <strong>the</strong> prefield (OVS vs. SVO, “topicalisation”)<br />

or <strong>the</strong> middlefield (OSV vs. SOV; “scrambling”). To ensure maximal comparability, all critical<br />

sentences were realised as subordinate clauses embedded by “bridge verbs”, which allow both verbsecond<br />

<strong>and</strong> verb-final complements. We observed two main results: (a) both object-initial word<br />

orders engendered increased activation in a subregion (BA44) of <strong>the</strong> left inferior frontal gyrus<br />

(LIFG); (b) object-initial orders involving <strong>the</strong> prefield engendered additional activation in a different<br />

portion of <strong>the</strong> LIFG (BA45) <strong>and</strong> in left temporal regions. The first of <strong>the</strong>se findings supports <strong>the</strong><br />

proposal that, in <strong>the</strong> domain of word order processing, BA44 is primarily responsible <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> relative<br />

ordering between arguments (e.g. Bornkessel et al., 2005; Grewe et al., 2006). More importantly <strong>for</strong><br />

present purposes, <strong>the</strong> second finding provides converging evidence <strong>for</strong> a neuroanatomically separable<br />

role of <strong>the</strong> prefield <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> middlefield in <strong>the</strong> processing of word order permutations. Strikingly, <strong>the</strong><br />

topicalised object-initial order, which is more acceptable (as supported by ratings collected in <strong>the</strong><br />

scanner), easier to comprehend behaviourally <strong>and</strong> more frequent, was <strong>the</strong> one to yield additional<br />

activation. This may be due to <strong>the</strong> fact that verb-second orders are generally assumed to be derived<br />

from an underlying verb-final order in German. The present results thus support <strong>the</strong> psychological<br />

<strong>and</strong> neural reality of topological fields <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir interaction with word order phenomena. They<br />

<strong>the</strong>reby serve to underscore <strong>the</strong> importance of incorporating <strong>the</strong>se distinctions into models of<br />

language comprehension.<br />

Notes<br />

113


P61<br />

Experiments on <strong>the</strong> role of focus triggered by different types of QUDs in<br />

<strong>the</strong> computation of scalar implicatures<br />

Andrea Gualmini, Luisa Meroni, & Arjen Zondervan<br />

Utrecht <strong>University</strong>, The Ne<strong>the</strong>rl<strong>and</strong>s<br />

E-mail: gualmini@gmail.com<br />

This paper provides experimental support <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> claim that scalar implicatures (SIs, e.g. <strong>the</strong> inference<br />

from some to some but not all <strong>and</strong> from or to or but not <strong>and</strong>) depend on <strong>the</strong> focus structure of <strong>the</strong><br />

sentence, which is in turn related to <strong>the</strong> Question Under Discussion (QUD) of <strong>the</strong> context. The<br />

experiments show that this focus dependency of SIs extends encompasses both explicit <strong>and</strong> implicit<br />

questions.<br />

Recent work by Zondervan (2007) tested <strong>the</strong> predictions made by <strong>the</strong>oretical accounts by Van Rooij<br />

(2002) <strong>and</strong> Van Kuppevelt (1996) (i.a.), that SIs only arise when <strong>the</strong> scalar term is (part of) <strong>the</strong> focus<br />

of <strong>the</strong> sentence. Zondervan (2007) found that <strong>the</strong> percentage of SIs <strong>for</strong> or in sentences like (1), was<br />

significantly higher when (1) followed <strong>the</strong> question (2a) than following (2b).<br />

(1) Harry brought bread or chips.<br />

(2a) What did Harry bring<br />

(2b) Who brought bread or chips<br />

This difference in SIs calculation was predicted because only in response to (2b) <strong>the</strong> scalar term (or)<br />

was in <strong>the</strong> constituent that answered <strong>the</strong> question, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>re<strong>for</strong>e had focus.<br />

Zondervan et al. (2008) tested whe<strong>the</strong>r this generalization also holds <strong>for</strong> focus structures triggered by<br />

yes/no questions. They found that <strong>for</strong> sentences like (3), containing <strong>the</strong> scalar term some, adult<br />

speakers of English more often calculate <strong>the</strong> not all SI, when (3) is presented as an answer to (4a)<br />

than when it follows (4b).<br />

(3) I think some hotdogs were delivered.<br />

(4a) Were all <strong>the</strong> hotdogs delivered<br />

(4b) Were some hotdogs delivered<br />

These results support <strong>the</strong> focus hypo<strong>the</strong>sis, because only following (4a), some is focused. Following<br />

(4b), <strong>the</strong> sentence as a whole is unfocused, as <strong>the</strong>re is no part that provides no new in<strong>for</strong>mation.<br />

In <strong>the</strong> present study, we tested whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> observed results <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> yes/no questions of Zondervan et<br />

al. (2008), also emerges when <strong>the</strong> questions are implicit, though can be inferred on <strong>the</strong> basis of <strong>the</strong><br />

prosody. 31 adult speakers of English participated in a TVJT with sentences similar to (3), after a<br />

story in which all <strong>the</strong> hotdogs were delivered. In one condition some was stressed (corresponding to<br />

<strong>the</strong> focus structure (3) gets following (4b)), while in <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r condition it was not stressed<br />

(corresponding to <strong>the</strong> focus structure (3) gets following (4a)). We found that when some was not<br />

stressed, subjects always accepted <strong>the</strong> target sentence, whereas when some was stressed <strong>the</strong><br />

acceptance rate dropped to 50% (32/64). These results complete <strong>the</strong> paradigm <strong>for</strong> focus dependency<br />

of SIs: More SIs are calculated when a scalar term has focus, which can be triggered by both explicit<br />

<strong>and</strong> implicit questions.<br />

Notes<br />

114


P62<br />

The influence of conceptual structure in lexical <strong>and</strong> semantic decision on<br />

spoken words<br />

Barry J. Devereux, Kirsten I. Taylor, Billi R<strong>and</strong>all, Michael A. Ford, & Lorraine K. Tyler<br />

<strong>University</strong> of Cambridge, UK<br />

E-mail: barry@csl.psychol.cam.ac.uk<br />

According to distributed <strong>the</strong>ories of conceptual knowledge such as <strong>the</strong> Conceptual Structure Account<br />

(CSA), concepts are represented across a network of units representing distinct semantic features,<br />

with <strong>the</strong> processing of concepts involving patterns of activation across this distributed featural<br />

network. Feature units differ in terms of how many concepts share that feature (i.e. sharedness) <strong>and</strong> in<br />

terms of how likely <strong>the</strong>y are to co-occur in concepts (i.e. correlation strength). Concepts also differ<br />

with respect to <strong>the</strong>se CSA variables (i.e., in <strong>the</strong> mean sharedness <strong>and</strong> correlation strength of <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

features). In light of earlier studies (see Moss et al, 2007, <strong>for</strong> a review) we predicted that high mean<br />

sharedness <strong>and</strong> high mean correlation strength would tend to facilitate conceptual processing. We<br />

investigated this possibility in two experiments using auditorily-presented concrete concept words.<br />

The first experiment involved lexical decision on <strong>the</strong> concept words <strong>and</strong> phonetically-valid non-word<br />

fillers. The second task involved semantic decision; participants decided whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> concepts were<br />

bigger than or smaller than a shoebox. We posited that <strong>the</strong> semantic task would involve deeper<br />

conceptual processing <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>re<strong>for</strong>e illicit stronger effects of <strong>the</strong> CSA variables. Both experiments<br />

utilized a correlational design, in order to use a large sample of 443 concepts (in a factorial design,<br />

only a small subset of <strong>the</strong>se could have been used). The data were analyzed with linear mixed effect<br />

models. Predictor variables included 10 nuisance variables (phonological, lexical <strong>and</strong> semantic<br />

variables not relevant to testing effects of conceptual structure), which were projected onto 5<br />

orthogonal PCA components to reduce <strong>the</strong> dimensionality of <strong>the</strong> models. Mean sharedness <strong>and</strong><br />

correlation strength were residualized against <strong>the</strong>se 10 nuisance variables, to control <strong>for</strong> potential<br />

confounds with those variables. The results <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> lexical decision experiment revealed a predicted<br />

facilitatory effect of sharedness (p = 0.04), indicating that conceptual structure influences response<br />

times in lexical decision, even when effects of o<strong>the</strong>r psycholinguistic variables are accounted <strong>for</strong>. In<br />

semantic decision, as we predicted, <strong>the</strong>re was a stronger, highly significant facilitatory effect of<br />

sharedness (p < 0.01), indicating that concepts with relatively shared features are processed faster in<br />

semantic decision than concepts with more distinctive features. Such findings are consistent with<br />

evidence from previous studies <strong>and</strong> offer fur<strong>the</strong>r support <strong>for</strong> distributed <strong>the</strong>ories of conceptual<br />

knowledge.<br />

Notes<br />

115


P63<br />

Linked visual attention between speakers <strong>and</strong> listeners: Effects on <strong>the</strong><br />

comprehension of object descriptions<br />

Helene Kreysa, Martin J. Pickering, Sarah L. Haywood, & John M. Henderson<br />

<strong>University</strong> of Edinburgh, UK<br />

E-mail: h.kreysa@sms.ed.ac.uk<br />

In language production, eye movements precede object mention by about 800ms, so <strong>the</strong>y contain<br />

useful in<strong>for</strong>mation about future speech content (cf. Griffin & Bock, 2000, PsycSci). For this reason,<br />

gaze direction can act as a visual pointer to upcoming referents (Hanna & Brennan, 2007, JML). In<br />

<strong>the</strong> gaze projection paradigm, we record speakers’ speech <strong>and</strong> eye-movements while <strong>the</strong>y describe<br />

objects in a photographic scene. <strong>Speech</strong> is played back to listeners along with a moving green dot<br />

representing <strong>the</strong> speaker’s gaze; listeners mouse-click on <strong>the</strong> objects <strong>the</strong> speaker describes.<br />

In Exp 1, listeners who saw <strong>the</strong> dot fixated objects 1880ms earlier than listeners who did not. They<br />

were twice as likely to per<strong>for</strong>m anticipatory gazes to upcoming objects (61% of trials vs. 33%), <strong>and</strong><br />

roughly 2 seconds faster to click on <strong>the</strong>m (all p < .01). In Exp 2, we manipulated pre-task in<strong>for</strong>mation<br />

about what <strong>the</strong> dot represented (speaker’s gaze “during speaking” vs. “during a subsequent memory<br />

task”), but found no top-down effect on listener eye-movements or clicks (all p > .3); mean latencies<br />

replicated <strong>the</strong> dot condition of Exp 1. This suggests that <strong>the</strong> facilitation observed <strong>for</strong> comprehension<br />

(click-times) is due to <strong>the</strong> visual salience of <strong>the</strong> dot, which attracts attention to <strong>the</strong> location of<br />

upcoming objects.<br />

We are currently conducting a stronger test of <strong>the</strong> integration of visual <strong>and</strong> auditory in<strong>for</strong>mation by<br />

shifting <strong>the</strong> dot <strong>for</strong>wards <strong>and</strong> backwards in time, relative to <strong>the</strong> speech stream. We expect that first<br />

fixations will shift by <strong>the</strong> same amount, whereas click times may also be influenced by <strong>the</strong><br />

in<strong>for</strong>mativeness of <strong>the</strong> dot: <strong>the</strong> natural lag between a speaker’s gaze <strong>and</strong> mention may prove optimal<br />

<strong>for</strong> predicting upcoming speech. On <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r h<strong>and</strong>, a dot which is fur<strong>the</strong>r ahead in time could be even<br />

more useful, as long as <strong>the</strong> connection with <strong>the</strong> following speech can still be established. In contrast,<br />

<strong>the</strong> in<strong>for</strong>mativity of a delayed dot should be reduced, leading to longer click-times.<br />

Clearly, <strong>the</strong> dot can be used to artificially coordinate visual attention between speakers <strong>and</strong> listeners.<br />

Following <strong>the</strong> Interactive Alignment account, this should increase coordination at o<strong>the</strong>r levels of<br />

representation as well (Pickering & Garrod, 2004, BBS). Implications <strong>for</strong> language comprehension,<br />

production, <strong>and</strong> memory will be discussed.<br />

Notes<br />

116


P64<br />

ERPs study on lateralization of semantic repetition blindness<br />

Angela K. Tzeng<br />

Chung-Yuan Christian <strong>University</strong>, Taiwan<br />

E-mail: angelat@cycu.edu.tw<br />

Repetition Blindness (RB) refers to <strong>the</strong> failure to report <strong>the</strong> 2nd occurrence (C2) of a repeated item in<br />

RSVP paradigm. RB at <strong>the</strong> perceptual level was very robust. RB was found if C1 <strong>and</strong> C2 shared<br />

perceptual similarity (phonological or visual). On <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r h<strong>and</strong>, semantic RB was not consistent in<br />

<strong>the</strong> literature. In general, words showed very little semantic RB, whereas pictures yielded strong<br />

semantic RB. Several hypo<strong>the</strong>ses have been proposed to account <strong>for</strong> this effect, but none of <strong>the</strong>m<br />

seem to be sufficient yet. In current study, we would like to (1) include both behavioral <strong>and</strong> ERPs<br />

data <strong>for</strong> investigation on semantic RB. (2) Both pictures <strong>and</strong> Chinese words were used as <strong>the</strong> stimuli<br />

<strong>for</strong> comparison. And (3) split visual field paradigm (exp 3 <strong>and</strong> 4) was introduced to discuss <strong>the</strong><br />

possible reasons <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> inconsistent result in pictures <strong>and</strong> words. Four experiments were conducted.<br />

Exp 1 was a semantic repetition study. Both behavioral <strong>and</strong> N400 data confirmed semantic priming<br />

effect. In Exp 2, semantic-related pictures (2A) <strong>and</strong> words (2B) were presented at <strong>the</strong> center of <strong>the</strong><br />

screen. The result was consistent with <strong>the</strong> literature: No RB was found in words <strong>and</strong> significant RB<br />

was found in pictures. N400 data confirmed this finding. The N400 of C2 in pictures was not as<br />

negative as C2 in words. In exp 3, pictures showed semantic RB in both visual fields. Semantic RB in<br />

RVF was significantly stronger than LVF. N400 also confirmed this result with less negative<br />

brainwave <strong>for</strong> C2 in RVF than in LVF. In exp 4, words were presented by RVF <strong>and</strong> LVF. No<br />

semantic RB was found in ei<strong>the</strong>r visual fields. However, N400 <strong>for</strong> C2 in RVF was more negative than<br />

in LVF. Three main conclusions were <strong>the</strong>n drawn. First of all, Semantic RB did exist with pictures.<br />

Secondly, behavioral <strong>and</strong> N400 data were consistent. Finally, <strong>the</strong> lateralization paradigm provides <strong>the</strong><br />

base <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> discussion of <strong>the</strong> difference in semantic RB of words <strong>and</strong> pictures.<br />

Notes<br />

117


P65<br />

Processing of noncanonical sentences in German agrammatic aphasia:<br />

Evidence from eye movements<br />

S<strong>and</strong>ra Hanne 1 , Irina A. Sekerina 2 , Shravan Vasishth 1 , Frank Burchert 1 , & Ria De Bleser 1<br />

1 <strong>University</strong> of Potsdam, Germany, 2 City <strong>University</strong> of New York, USA<br />

E-mail: hanne@uni-potsdam.de<br />

Broca aphasics are often at chance at comprehension of reversible noncanonical sentences<br />

(Grodzinsky 1995, Burchert et al. 2003). The Trace-Deletion-Hypo<strong>the</strong>sis (Grodzinsky 1995) argues<br />

that patients erroneously assign <strong>the</strong>matic roles based on an agent-first heuristic. In an eye-tracking<br />

study, Dickey et al. (2007) observed a mismatch between aphasics’ online sentence processing <strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong>ir offline responses: While patients exhibit normal-like online processing, <strong>the</strong>y often do not<br />

succeed in offline comprehension.<br />

We conducted a sentence-picture-matching experiment with 8 controls <strong>and</strong> 7 German Broca aphasics.<br />

We used German canonical SVO sentences (1) <strong>and</strong> noncanonical OVS sentences (2).<br />

(1) Der Sohn fängt den Vater.<br />

(2) Den Sohn fängt der Vater.<br />

Two pictures were presented side-by-side simultaneously with <strong>the</strong> spoken sentence: <strong>the</strong> target (agent<br />

<strong>and</strong> patient acting according to <strong>the</strong> sentence) <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> foil picture (semantically reversed action).<br />

Accuracy, reaction times <strong>and</strong> eye-movements were recorded.<br />

For accuracy, controls were at ceiling <strong>for</strong> both conditions (SVO: 98%, OVS: 95%) while patients<br />

were impaired <strong>for</strong> SVO (80%) <strong>and</strong> at chance <strong>for</strong> OVS (46%). Patients were twice as slow as controls<br />

but SVO was processed faster than OVS in both groups. Controls’ eye movements reflected a<br />

preference <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> target picture from <strong>the</strong> der/den-NP region onwards in both conditions. Patients’<br />

fixation patterns in <strong>the</strong> canonical SVO condition were very similar. When we analyzed all trials<br />

(correct <strong>and</strong> wrong ones) <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> noncanonical OVS condition, we observed a persistent preference<br />

<strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> foil picture. This might suggest <strong>the</strong> application of an agent-first heuristic. Following Dickey et<br />

al. (2007), we looked at correct trials separately <strong>and</strong> found that patients, just like controls, showed an<br />

early preference <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> target picture. This is new evidence <strong>for</strong> a dissociation between patients’<br />

online processing <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir offline per<strong>for</strong>mance, similar to what was recently claimed <strong>for</strong> children<br />

(Sekerina et al. 2004).<br />

References<br />

Burchert, F, De Bleser, R & Sonntag, K (2003) Does morphology make <strong>the</strong> difference Agrammatic<br />

sentence comprehension in German. <strong>Brain</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Language</strong> 87, 323-342.<br />

Dickey, MW, Choy, JJ & Thompson, CK (2007) Real-time comprehension of wh-movement in<br />

aphasia: Evidence from eyetracking while listening. <strong>Brain</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Language</strong> 100, 1-22.<br />

Grodzinsky, Y (1995) A Restrictive Theory of Agrammatic Comprehension. <strong>Brain</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Language</strong> 50,<br />

27-51.<br />

Sekerina, IA, Stromswold, K & Hestvik, A (2004) How do adults <strong>and</strong> children process differentially<br />

ambiguous pronouns J. Child Lang. 31, 123-152.<br />

Notes<br />

118


Identifying <strong>and</strong> using function words: An eye-tracking study with<br />

17-month-olds<br />

P66<br />

Jean-Remy Hochmann, & Jacques Mehler<br />

SISSA, Trieste, Italy<br />

E-mail: hochmann@sissa.it<br />

In this study, we shortly exposed infants to a <strong>for</strong>eign language <strong>and</strong> assessed how <strong>the</strong>y behave when<br />

two words from that language, one frequent <strong>and</strong> one infrequent, are later associated to an object. If<br />

frequency helps infant discover function words, we predict that <strong>the</strong>y should preferentially associate<br />

<strong>the</strong> object to <strong>the</strong> infrequent word ra<strong>the</strong>r than to <strong>the</strong> frequent one.<br />

Our experiment consisted of three phases: a familiarization phase, a word-object pairing phase, <strong>and</strong> a<br />

test phase. During familiarization we presented Italian17-month old infants with short sentences in<br />

French, a language that <strong>the</strong>y never heard. All sentences contained two frequent French determiners,<br />

"ce" <strong>and</strong> "vos", <strong>and</strong> several infrequent content words. The stimuli were recorded by a natural speaker.<br />

The 3 minutes of familiarization were followed by <strong>the</strong> word-object pairing phase. In this phase, a<br />

visual object (hereafter referred as <strong>the</strong> familiar object) was presented toge<strong>the</strong>r with a bisyllabic phrase<br />

consisting of a determiner <strong>and</strong> a noun (e.g., "ce chat"), both taken from <strong>the</strong> familiarization corpus.<br />

Finally, in <strong>the</strong> test, we assessed which of <strong>the</strong> two words (e.g., “ce” or “chat”) <strong>the</strong> infants associated<br />

more strongly with <strong>the</strong> object. To this end, we simultaneously presented <strong>the</strong> familiar object <strong>and</strong> a<br />

novel object on <strong>the</strong> computer screen <strong>and</strong>, using a Tobii eye-tracker, we observed <strong>the</strong> infants’ looking<br />

behavior in two different conditions: <strong>the</strong> determiner condition <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> noun condition.<br />

In <strong>the</strong> determiner condition, infants heard <strong>the</strong> determiner used during <strong>the</strong> word-object pairing<br />

associated to a novel noun (e.g., “ce met”).<br />

In <strong>the</strong> noun condition, infants heard <strong>the</strong> noun used during <strong>the</strong> word-object pairing associated to a<br />

novel determiner (e.g., "vos chat”).<br />

Results show that infants attended to <strong>the</strong> familiar object in <strong>the</strong> noun condition (see Figure 2 (a) in<br />

red), <strong>and</strong> to <strong>the</strong> novel object in <strong>the</strong> determiner condition (see Figure 2 (a) in green).<br />

Importantly, in a control group, we removed <strong>the</strong> familiarization phase <strong>and</strong> found no preference <strong>for</strong><br />

ei<strong>the</strong>r object in any of <strong>the</strong> two conditions (see Figure 2 (b)).<br />

Our findings suggest that 17-month-old infants successfully used <strong>the</strong> available cues, i.e. high<br />

frequency, possibly interacting with acoustical properties, to extract <strong>the</strong> two determiners in <strong>the</strong><br />

familiarization <strong>and</strong> were unlikely to later assign a referent object to <strong>the</strong>m. This fits well with <strong>the</strong> fact<br />

that function words (in contrast to content words) typically carry little meaning. This phenomenon,<br />

uncovered <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> first time, may <strong>for</strong>m <strong>the</strong> basis of function word acquisition <strong>and</strong> use in later infancy.<br />

Notes<br />

119


P67<br />

Self-monitoring in speech: Where do we stop our erroneous utterances<br />

Ilse Tydgat 1 , Robert J. Hartsuiker 1 , & Martin J. Pickering 2<br />

1 Ghent <strong>University</strong>, Belgium, 2 <strong>University</strong> of Edinburgh, UK<br />

E-mail: Ilse.Tydgat@UGent.be<br />

<strong>Speech</strong> self-monitoring is <strong>the</strong> set of processes by which we detect errors, stop speaking, <strong>and</strong> adjust<br />

our speech when things go wrong. This study investigated where we stop our erroneous utterances.<br />

One possibility is that we do this as a function of <strong>the</strong> moment of error detection (Nooteboom, 1980).<br />

However, Levelt (1989) suggested that <strong>the</strong> interruption is ra<strong>the</strong>r meant to be a message from <strong>the</strong><br />

speaker to <strong>the</strong> listener, signalling that an internally interrupted word was an error, while a completed<br />

word was correctly delivered. To study this issue experimentally, a similar paradigm as that of<br />

Hartsuiker, Pickering, <strong>and</strong> de Jong (2005) was used, <strong>and</strong> 35 participants each named 1200 pictures of<br />

coloured shapes – such as brown cube. In about 13% of <strong>the</strong> cases, a picture was rapidly replaced by a<br />

new picture that had changed in colour (yellow cube) or shape (brown disc). Then participants were to<br />

try to stop naming <strong>the</strong> first picture <strong>and</strong> make <strong>the</strong> repair as quickly as possible. The time interval<br />

between both pictures was also varied, in four steps, from 400 ms to 850 ms. We found that wordinternal<br />

interruptions – such as bro… or cu… – depended on <strong>the</strong> time of error detection, χ²=71.26,<br />

df=3, p


P68<br />

Learning morphemes: Insights from skilled readers<br />

Marjolein M. Merkx 1 , Kathleen Rastle 1 , & Mat<strong>the</strong>w H. Davis 2<br />

1 Royal Holloway, <strong>University</strong> of London, UK, 2 MRC Cognition <strong>and</strong> <strong>Brain</strong> Sciences Unit, Cambridge, UK<br />

E-mail: marjolein.merkx@rhul.ac.uk<br />

Affix knowledge plays an important role in visual word recognition <strong>and</strong> word comprehension (e.g.<br />

<strong>the</strong> word darkness is interpreted by splitting it into <strong>the</strong> units dark <strong>and</strong> ness). But how are orthographic<br />

<strong>and</strong> semantic representations of affixes learned We examined this question by teaching participants<br />

novel affixes in combination with a number of existing word stems. These novel words (e.g.<br />

sleepnule) were presented to <strong>the</strong> participants visually <strong>and</strong> aurally be<strong>for</strong>e <strong>the</strong>y typed each word. As no<br />

fur<strong>the</strong>r indication of morphological structure was given, only <strong>the</strong> use of each affix in several different<br />

contexts <strong>and</strong> participants’ knowledge of <strong>the</strong> stems promoted <strong>the</strong> idea that <strong>the</strong>se letter groups were<br />

morphological units. Form learning was compared with semantic learning in which participants were<br />

given definitions <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> novel words. These definitions were based on a consistent meaning <strong>for</strong> each<br />

novel affix combined with a familiar stem (e.g. sleepnule relates to ‘a participant in a study about <strong>the</strong><br />

effects of napping’ where <strong>the</strong> novel affix nule is defined by ‘a person that does [stem]’). Tests of<br />

recognition memory per<strong>for</strong>med two days after learning showed that participants had good explicit<br />

knowledge of <strong>the</strong> novel words with semantic learning resulting in better stem <strong>and</strong> stem plus affix<br />

knowledge. A segmentation task revealed that participants in both learning conditions used<br />

knowledge of <strong>the</strong> novel affixes to segment untrained ambiguous letter strings (e.g. segmenting<br />

barnule into bar+nule, ra<strong>the</strong>r than barn+ule). Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, participants in <strong>the</strong> semantic learning<br />

condition were able to generalise <strong>the</strong>ir affix knowledge to choose <strong>the</strong> correct meaning <strong>for</strong> new stem<br />

plus trained novel affix words (e.g. <strong>for</strong> sailnule participants would choose ‘a person who excels in<br />

open sea catamaran racing’ over ‘<strong>the</strong> hourly cost of learning how to navigate a yacht’) showing that<br />

participants have acquired abstract knowledge of <strong>the</strong> meaning of <strong>the</strong>se affixes. However, a speeded<br />

lexical decision task attempting to assess online use of <strong>the</strong> novel affixes did not show strong effects of<br />

learning. Comparing responses to nonwords containing untrained novel affixes (e.g. famlabe) with<br />

those to nonwords containing trained novel affixes (e.g. yealnule), <strong>for</strong>m learning yielded no<br />

significant differences <strong>and</strong> semantic learning yielded only a marginal effect in error rates. This study<br />

shows that after simple <strong>for</strong>m <strong>and</strong> semantic learning, novel affixes are treated as independent<br />

orthographic <strong>and</strong> semantic units in offline tasks, though evidence <strong>for</strong> rapid, online-segmentation is<br />

limited.<br />

Notes<br />

121


P69<br />

Syntactic category conversion causes processing costs: Evidence from<br />

adjectival passives<br />

Britta Stolterfoht, Helga Gese, & Claudia Maienborn<br />

<strong>University</strong> of Tuebingen, Germany<br />

E-mail: britta.stolterfoht@uni-tuebingen.de<br />

In a self-paced reading study, we investigated syntactic category conversion, a very productive<br />

grammatical process which converts a word of category A in one of category B. If you look at <strong>the</strong><br />

famous ambiguous sentences in (1), this kind of process has clear consequences <strong>for</strong> sentence<br />

interpretation.<br />

(1) Flying planes can be dangerous.<br />

(2a) If you walk too near <strong>the</strong> runway, l<strong>and</strong>ing planes ...<br />

(2b) If you’ve been trained as a pilot, l<strong>and</strong>ing planes ...<br />

Tyler & Marslen-Wilson (1977) looked at <strong>the</strong> processing of sentences like (2) <strong>and</strong> found that context<br />

triggers <strong>the</strong> conversion of <strong>the</strong> verb 'to l<strong>and</strong>' to ei<strong>the</strong>r an adjective in (2a) or a noun in (2b). But it is<br />

still an open question whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> category conversion itself causes processing costs.<br />

To answer this question, we investigated <strong>the</strong> processing of adjectival passives in German. It is widely<br />

assumed that <strong>the</strong> participle (verschüttet ‘spilled’) in (3a) is converted into an adjective resulting in a<br />

copula-adjective construction (e.g., Kratzer, 2000). No such conversion is necessary <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> eventive<br />

passive in (3b).<br />

(3a) Die Milch war verschüttet und ...<br />

The milk was(COPULA) spilled <strong>and</strong><br />

(3b) Die Milch wurde verschüttet und ...<br />

The milk was(AUX) spilled <strong>and</strong><br />

(4a) Die Milch war sauer und ...<br />

The milk was(COPULA) sour <strong>and</strong><br />

(4b) Die Milch wurde sauer und ...<br />

The milk became sour <strong>and</strong><br />

If conversion causes processing cost, longer reading times should be found on <strong>the</strong> participle<br />

'verschüttet' (spilled) in (3a) in comparison to (3b). To avoid wrap-up effects, <strong>the</strong> sentences continued<br />

with a sentence coordination after <strong>the</strong> critical word. To control <strong>for</strong> effects of different lexical material<br />

preceding <strong>the</strong> critical word, we also tested sentences with genuine adjectives like in (4), <strong>for</strong> which no<br />

additional process is predicted. Thus we shouldn’t find any reading time difference on <strong>the</strong> adjective in<br />

<strong>the</strong>se sentences.<br />

Our results revealed significantly longer reading times <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> participle in (3a) compared to (3b). By<br />

contrast, we found no significant difference <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> sentences with adjectives.<br />

To exclude an alternative explanation of <strong>the</strong> reading time difference in terms of frequency, we<br />

conducted a corpus search which revealed clear frequency differences between <strong>the</strong> two syntactic<br />

environments <strong>for</strong> both participles <strong>and</strong> genuine adjectives.<br />

Our results demonstrate that adjectival conversion is a costly process. Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore this is, as far as we<br />

know, <strong>the</strong> first psycholinguistic study that found evidence <strong>for</strong> such a conversion in processing<br />

adjectival passives.<br />

122


P70<br />

Direct <strong>and</strong> indirect speech modulates depth of processing<br />

Jason Bohan 1 , Anthony J. San<strong>for</strong>d 1 , Sally Cochrane 1 , & Alison J.S. San<strong>for</strong>d 2<br />

1 <strong>University</strong> of Glasgow, UK, 2 <strong>University</strong> of Strathclyde, UK<br />

E-mail: j.bohan@psy.gla.ac.uk<br />

Two quite different ways in which speech may be conveyed in written discourse is through Direct (1)<br />

<strong>and</strong> Indirect (2) <strong>Speech</strong>:<br />

John said “I needed some nine-inch nails so I went to B&Q”.<br />

John said he needed some nine-inch nails so he went to B&Q.<br />

In studies of narrative style, it is considered that that direct speech is somehow more faithful to <strong>the</strong><br />

“facts” (Leech & Short, 2007; Semino & Short, 2004), <strong>and</strong> is more vivid <strong>and</strong> immediate, somehow<br />

involving <strong>the</strong> reader more closely (Buhler, 1982). Despite its prominence in stylistics, <strong>the</strong>re has been<br />

little if any attempt to relate <strong>the</strong>se ideas to in<strong>for</strong>mation processing. We report a text-change detection<br />

study in which examples like (1) <strong>and</strong> (2) were compared. Participants saw two presentations of<br />

materials containing a sentence with direct or indirect speech. On <strong>the</strong> second presentation, 50% of <strong>the</strong><br />

time <strong>the</strong> verb was changed (e.g., went to B&Q walked to B&Q). Detection of changes was much<br />

higher <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> direct speech case, indicating deeper semantic processing of <strong>the</strong> verbs under this<br />

condition.<br />

Two explanations are considered. First, that first-person pronouns provide a lower processing load<br />

than third person pronouns (e.g., AJS San<strong>for</strong>d et al., 2006). This is deemed unlikely since <strong>the</strong><br />

sentences used here are active declarative. The second (speculative) view is based on <strong>the</strong> idea that<br />

first person pronouns invoke a personal perspective that facilitates comprehension. Such a view fits<br />

well with recent developments in <strong>the</strong> underst<strong>and</strong>ing of empathy (e.g., Decety & Lamm, 2006). Like<br />

o<strong>the</strong>r aspects of style, variants of direct <strong>and</strong> indirect presentation, so central in stylistics, are ripe <strong>for</strong><br />

study in psycholinguistics.<br />

References<br />

Buhler, K. (1982). The deictic field of language <strong>and</strong> deictic words. In R. Jarvella & W. Klein (Eds.)<br />

<strong>Speech</strong>, Place <strong>and</strong> Action: Studies in Deixis <strong>and</strong> related topics. NewYork: Wiley.<br />

Decety, J., & Lamm, C. (2006). Human empathy through <strong>the</strong> lens of social neuroscience. The<br />

Scientific World Journal, 6, 1146–1163.<br />

Leech, G. & Short, M. H. (2007). Style in Fiction. London: Longman<br />

San<strong>for</strong>d, A J S, San<strong>for</strong>d, A J, Filik, R. & Molle, J. (2005). Depth of lexical-semantic processing <strong>and</strong><br />

sentential load. Journal of Memory <strong>and</strong> <strong>Language</strong>, 53, 378-396.<br />

Semino, E. & Short, M. (2004). Corpus stylistics: Writing <strong>and</strong> thought presentation in a corpus of<br />

English writing. Routledge: London.<br />

Notes<br />

123


P71<br />

Are past-tense verbs special Evidence from a mismatch negativity study<br />

Rachel Holl<strong>and</strong>, Lisa Brindley, Kambiz Tavabi, Friedemann Pulvermüller,<br />

Karalyn Patterson, & Yury Shtyrov<br />

MRC Cognition <strong>and</strong> <strong>Brain</strong> Sciences Unit, Cambridge, UK<br />

E-mail: rachel.holl<strong>and</strong>@mrc-cbu.cam.ac.uk<br />

The processing of regular <strong>and</strong> irregular past-tense verbs, by both normal <strong>and</strong> aphasic speakers, has<br />

attracted substantial attention in recent years. Some patients with nonfluent aphasia following stroke<br />

are especially impaired on regular past-tense <strong>for</strong>ms like “played”, whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> task requires<br />

production (e.g. Ullman et al., 1997), comprehension (e.g. Tyler et al., 2002) or even <strong>the</strong> judgement<br />

that “played” sounds different from “play” (Bird et al., 2003). Within a dual-mechanism account of<br />

inflectional morphology, <strong>the</strong>se deficits reflect disruption to knowledge/implementation of <strong>the</strong> regular<br />

+ed rule; but <strong>the</strong> fact that <strong>the</strong> patients are also impaired at detecting <strong>the</strong> difference in phonologically<br />

similar but morphological unrelated pairs like “tray” <strong>and</strong> “trade” suggests an important role <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

phonological as well as <strong>the</strong> morphological characteristics of <strong>the</strong> regular past tense.<br />

We used <strong>the</strong> MEG correlate of <strong>the</strong> mismatch negativity (MMN) to investigate <strong>the</strong> spatio-temporal<br />

patterns of neural memory trace activation <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> spoken deviant word “played” in <strong>the</strong> context of <strong>the</strong><br />

st<strong>and</strong>ard word “play”. Additional critical contrasts included phonologically matched pairs of<br />

monomorphemic words (“tray” – “trade”), pseudowords (“kway” – “kwade”) <strong>and</strong> signal correlated<br />

noise. This experimental design allows <strong>for</strong> full control of acoustic factors, while systematically<br />

modulating linguistic variables.<br />

Initial results (N=13) from young healthy controls reveal a large-amplitude MMN response to all of<br />

<strong>the</strong> deviants listed above. This response, measured at sensors over <strong>the</strong> temporal lobe, was bilateral but<br />

larger in <strong>the</strong> left hemisphere. There was no overall difference between <strong>the</strong> activations elicited by<br />

“trade” relative to “tray” vs. “played” relative to “play”, although <strong>the</strong>re was a tendency <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

inflected <strong>for</strong>m to produce stronger laterality.<br />

References<br />

Bird, H.,et al. (2003). Deficits in phonology <strong>and</strong> past-tense morphology: What's <strong>the</strong> connection<br />

Journal of Memory <strong>and</strong> <strong>Language</strong>, 48(3), 502-526.<br />

Tyler, L. K. et al.. (2002). Dissociations in processing past tense morphology: Neuropathology <strong>and</strong><br />

behavioral studies. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 14(1), 79-94.<br />

Ullman, M. T. et al. (1997). A neural dissociation within language: Evidence that <strong>the</strong> mental<br />

dictionary is part of declarative memory, <strong>and</strong> that grammatical rules are processed by <strong>the</strong><br />

procedural system. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 9(2), 266-276.<br />

Notes<br />

124


P72<br />

Processing of determiners: Task differences in <strong>the</strong> ‘visual world’ paradigm<br />

Jelena Mirkovic, Danijela Trenkic, & Gerry T.M. Altmann<br />

<strong>University</strong> of York UK<br />

E-mail: j.mirkovic@psych.york.ac.uk<br />

In a typical visual world study (VW) participants view a scene <strong>and</strong> listen to speech containing<br />

reference to it, while <strong>the</strong>ir eye movements are monitored. There are 3 task variants within <strong>the</strong><br />

paradigm: participants are instructed to ei<strong>the</strong>r a) manipulate physical objects <strong>the</strong>y are presented with<br />

(Tanenhaus et al. 1995); or b) interact with objects presented on a computer screen using a mouse<br />

(Allopenna et al. 1998); or c) listen to descriptions of pictures presented on a computer screen <strong>and</strong><br />

answer questions about <strong>the</strong>m (Altmann & Kamide, 1999). Each of <strong>the</strong> tasks has contributed major<br />

insights into <strong>the</strong> time-course of spoken language processing, from isolated words to discourse.<br />

However, <strong>the</strong>re has been little systematic research into how <strong>the</strong>se different tasks influence <strong>the</strong><br />

findings. Are all VW tasks equally suited to address all time-course questions, about all linguistic<br />

variables<br />

We compared <strong>the</strong> 3 tasks in a study investigating how linguistic <strong>and</strong> pragmatic af<strong>for</strong>dances interact in<br />

reference resolution. In Experiment 1 participants heard sentences that manipulated <strong>the</strong> definiteness<br />

of <strong>the</strong> target noun phrase, e.g. “The pirate will put <strong>the</strong> cube inside <strong>the</strong>/a can”. Definite noun phrases<br />

require <strong>the</strong>ir referents to be uniquely identifiable, while referential indefinites are used when more<br />

than one referents of <strong>the</strong> same description are available. Participants saw pictures containing, among<br />

o<strong>the</strong>r objects, 2 open cans (2 referent condition) or 2 cans only one of which was open (1 referent<br />

condition). They were instructed to click on <strong>the</strong> place where <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>me object was going to end<br />

(“clicking task”). Interaction between grammatical in<strong>for</strong>mation (<strong>the</strong> definiteness of <strong>the</strong> noun phrase)<br />

<strong>and</strong> pragmatic af<strong>for</strong>dances (<strong>the</strong> number of compatible referents) was found: in <strong>the</strong> 1 referent<br />

condition, reference resolution occurred sooner when <strong>the</strong> NP was definite <strong>and</strong> in <strong>the</strong> 2 referent<br />

condition when <strong>the</strong> NP was indefinite. These findings replicated <strong>the</strong> findings originally obtained<br />

using <strong>the</strong> object manipulation task by Chambers et al. (2002), which served as <strong>the</strong> starting point <strong>for</strong><br />

our study.<br />

In Experiment 2 participants viewed <strong>the</strong> same scene <strong>and</strong> heard <strong>the</strong> same sentences as in Experiment 1,<br />

but were instructed just to listen to <strong>the</strong> sentences <strong>and</strong> relate <strong>the</strong>m to <strong>the</strong> pictures (“look’n’listen task”).<br />

The findings were replicated <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> 1 referent condition but not <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> 2 referent condition.<br />

The implications of <strong>the</strong> task differences <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> time-course of processing of linguistic in<strong>for</strong>mation at<br />

different granularities will be discussed.<br />

Notes<br />

125


P73<br />

Integrating statistics from <strong>the</strong> world <strong>and</strong> from language to learn semantic<br />

representations<br />

Mark W. Andrews, Gabriella Vigliocco, & David P. Vinson<br />

<strong>University</strong> College London, UK<br />

E-mail: m.<strong>and</strong>rews@ucl.ac.uk<br />

Statistical data from <strong>the</strong> world, perceived as sensory-motor data, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> distributional statistics of<br />

language represent two distinct data-types from which we can learn semantic representations. In<br />

previous literature, it has been repeatedly demonstrated that semantic representations can be learned<br />

from ei<strong>the</strong>r sensory-motor based statistics alone, e.g. McRae, deSa <strong>and</strong> Seidenberg (1997), Vigliocco,<br />

Vinson, Lewis <strong>and</strong> Garrett (2004), McClell<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> Rogers (2003), or from language based statistics<br />

alone, e.g. Lund <strong>and</strong> Burgess (1996), L<strong>and</strong>auer <strong>and</strong> Dumais (1997), Griffiths, Steyvers <strong>and</strong><br />

Tenenbaum (2007). However, <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> most part throughout this literature, <strong>the</strong> contribution of any one<br />

of <strong>the</strong>se data types had been considered independently <strong>and</strong> to <strong>the</strong> exclusion of <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r. The objective<br />

of this work is to describe <strong>the</strong> extent to which <strong>the</strong> in<strong>for</strong>mation available from <strong>the</strong>se two sources<br />

represent two complementary data-types <strong>and</strong> how semantic representations can be <strong>for</strong>med from <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

combination. Using a data-set of speaker-generated feature norms to represent sensory-motor<br />

statistical data, <strong>and</strong> using <strong>the</strong> British National Corpus as a sample of text, we provide a set of<br />

Bayesian probabilistic models that learn semantic representations from ei<strong>the</strong>r sensory-motor data<br />

alone, language data alone, or from both in combination. From this, we demonstrate how <strong>the</strong> semantic<br />

representations that are learned from sensory-motor data <strong>and</strong> language data are of a qualitatively<br />

distinct nature. Moreover, we also demonstrate that <strong>the</strong> semantic representations learned from both<br />

data-types in combination are richer <strong>and</strong> more comprehensive than could be learned from ei<strong>the</strong>r<br />

source alone. We show that this result is not simply from summing, or averaging, toge<strong>the</strong>r two datasets.<br />

Nor is it simply <strong>the</strong> result of using a quantitatively larger training data-set. By comparing <strong>the</strong><br />

semantic-representations learned by <strong>the</strong>se models to human-based data (e.g. word-association norms,<br />

lexical-substitution errors, semantic priming <strong>and</strong> picture-word interference data) we show that<br />

representations learned by combining sensory-motor <strong>and</strong> language based statistical data most<br />

accurately reflect human semantic representations. Finally, we conclude by showing that combining<br />

<strong>the</strong>se two complementary data-sets permits better generalization of <strong>the</strong> semantic knowledge acquired<br />

from statistical data, that it facilitates <strong>the</strong> acquisition of new lexical items <strong>and</strong> that its grounds in <strong>the</strong><br />

sensory-motor realm o<strong>the</strong>rwise abstract or encyclopedic knowledge.<br />

Notes<br />

126


P74<br />

Bridging <strong>the</strong> gap between linguistics <strong>and</strong> psycholinguistics: The case of<br />

anaphora<br />

Arnout W. Koornneef, Frank Wijnen, & Eric Reul<strong>and</strong><br />

UIL-OTS Institute, Utrecht <strong>University</strong>, The Ne<strong>the</strong>rl<strong>and</strong>s<br />

E-mail: Arnout.Koornneef@let.uu.nl<br />

Syntactic restrictions on <strong>the</strong> use of different anaphoric expressions have traditionally been described<br />

through Binding Theory (Chomsky, 1981). However, <strong>the</strong> Primitives of Binding (POB) model<br />

(Reul<strong>and</strong>, 2001) is a better linguistic descriptor of grammaticality patterns of anaphoric dependencies.<br />

The main feature of <strong>the</strong> POB model is an economy hierarchy that governs <strong>the</strong> division of labor<br />

between syntax, semantics <strong>and</strong> discourse: syntactic processes are more economic than semantic<br />

processes <strong>and</strong>, similarly, semantic processes are more economic than discourse process.<br />

We will present <strong>the</strong> results of three eye-tracking experiments that are consistent with this economy<br />

hierarchy. In Experiment 1, <strong>the</strong> Dutch reflexive zich (himself/herself) was placed in two different<br />

syntactic structures. In one condition zich was a ‘coargument reflexive’ <strong>and</strong> could only be resolved in<br />

<strong>the</strong> syntactic module, whereas in <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r condition zich was a ‘logophor’ <strong>and</strong> could only be<br />

interpreted extra-syntactically. The results showed that readers spent more time reading a logophor<br />

(i.e. syntax < semantics/discourse).<br />

In Experiment 2, we compared semantic <strong>and</strong> discourse anaphoric dependencies. The results showed a<br />

processing advantage <strong>for</strong> pronouns that depended on c-comm<strong>and</strong>ing antecedents <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

interpretation. Since semantic dependencies can only emerge if an antecedent c-comm<strong>and</strong>s <strong>the</strong><br />

anaphoric element, this finding suggests that semantic dependencies are indeed more economic than<br />

discourse dependencies.<br />

In Experiment 3, we examined whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>re is a preference <strong>for</strong> a semantic dependency when a<br />

sentence is ambiguous between a semantic or discourse interpretation. For example, in (1) Oscar is<br />

ei<strong>the</strong>r thinking about his own abilities as a cook (semantic), or about Alfred’s abilities as a cook<br />

(discourse).<br />

(1) Alfred thinks that he is good cook, but Oscar doesn’t.<br />

Dutch versions of (1) were placed within a context that was highly biased towards ei<strong>the</strong>r a semantic<br />

or a discourse interpretation. As predicted by <strong>the</strong> economy hierarchy, various first <strong>and</strong> second pass<br />

reading times suggested a strong preference <strong>for</strong> semantic dependencies: readers initially construct a<br />

semantic interpretation, independent of <strong>the</strong> context.<br />

Our results show that <strong>the</strong> POB model presents a promising new way to look at <strong>the</strong> structural<br />

constraints underlying anaphora resolution <strong>and</strong>, moreover, we deem <strong>the</strong> attempts to incorporate<br />

Chomsky’s Principles into a real-time processing architecture obsolete.<br />

References<br />

Chomsky (1981). Lectures on Government <strong>and</strong> Binding. Dordrecht: Foris<br />

Reul<strong>and</strong> (2001). Primitives of binding. Linguistic Inquiry, 32, 439-492<br />

Notes<br />

127


P75<br />

Diurnal variations in language per<strong>for</strong>mance<br />

Jessica Rosenberg 1 , Kathrin Pusch 1 , Rainer Dietrich 1 , & Christian Cajochen 2<br />

1 Humboldt <strong>University</strong> of Berlin, Germany, 2 <strong>Centre</strong> <strong>for</strong> Chronobiology, Basel, Switzerl<strong>and</strong><br />

E-mail: jessica.rosenberg@charite.de<br />

Although circadian rhythms are well characterized on a physiological level, little is known about <strong>the</strong><br />

circadian oscillation of higher cognitive activities. Especially, <strong>the</strong> present study investigated circadian<br />

modulations of language per<strong>for</strong>mance.<br />

The circadian master oscillator emits signals that trigger organ-specific oscillators <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>re<strong>for</strong>e<br />

constitutes a basic biological process which enables organisms to anticipate to daily environmental<br />

changes by adjusting behaviour, physiology <strong>and</strong> gene regulation. A small number of studies,<br />

investigating <strong>the</strong> idea of an diurnal variation in language per<strong>for</strong>mance, reported contradictory results.<br />

Importantly, <strong>the</strong> “time-of-day design” <strong>the</strong>se few studies have been using is flawed because it cannot<br />

eliminate masking effects on an internally generated circadian variation in language per<strong>for</strong>mance. A<br />

constant-routine design on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r is better suited to control external <strong>and</strong> internal factors (Blatter &<br />

Cajochen, 2007).<br />

There<strong>for</strong>e, <strong>the</strong> present study was conducted under constant routine conditions. We addressed <strong>the</strong><br />

question of circadian variation in language per<strong>for</strong>mance at <strong>the</strong> level of minimal syntactic processing<br />

with a focus on gender agreement. Participants per<strong>for</strong>med syntactic decisions on German noun<br />

phrases.<br />

The results replicated <strong>the</strong> expected Gender Congruency Effect (Friederici & Jacobsen, 1999), namely<br />

that an incongruent gender marking of a determiner slows down <strong>the</strong> processing of <strong>the</strong> following noun<br />

relative to a congruent marking. Concerning diurnal variations of this task, language per<strong>for</strong>mance<br />

displays an internally generated circadian rhythm. In particular, language processing was slower<br />

during <strong>the</strong> night with a nadir in <strong>the</strong> early morning. Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, language accuracy was more errorprone<br />

during <strong>the</strong> night.<br />

Additionally, tests of general attention <strong>and</strong> sensori-motor per<strong>for</strong>mance were embedded in <strong>the</strong> constant<br />

routine protocol. Here, participant’s per<strong>for</strong>mance slowed down during <strong>the</strong> night as well but<br />

interestingly, language per<strong>for</strong>mance featured some distinct modulations. Importantly, <strong>the</strong> results<br />

cannot just be explained by an increase of sleepiness or a decrease of general attention.<br />

References<br />

Blatter, K., & Cajochen, C. (2007). Circadian rhythms in cognitive per<strong>for</strong>mance: methodological<br />

constraints, protocols, <strong>the</strong>oretical underpinnings. Physiology & Behaviour, 90, 196-208.<br />

Friederici, A. D., & Jacobsen, T. (1999). Processing grammatical gender during language<br />

comprehension. Journal of Psycholinguistic Research, 28, 467-484.<br />

Notes<br />

128


P76<br />

Higher order inference in verb argument structure acquisition<br />

Elizabeth Wonnacott 1 , Amy Per<strong>for</strong>s 2 , & Joshua B. Tenenhaum 2<br />

1 <strong>University</strong> of Ox<strong>for</strong>d, UK, 2 Massachusetts Institute of Technology, USA<br />

E-mail: elizabeth.wonnacott@psy.ox.ac.uk<br />

Successful language learning combines generalization <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> acquisition of lexical constraints. The<br />

conflict is particularly clear <strong>for</strong> verb argument structures, as certain verbs resist generalization (*he<br />

carried her <strong>the</strong> ball). Wonnacott, Newport & Tanenhaus (WNT) 2008 demonstrated that learners<br />

could acquire verb-based constraints in artificial languages with no semantic (or o<strong>the</strong>r) cues.<br />

Participants showed signature statistical learning effects in real-time processing <strong>and</strong> frequency-based<br />

entrenchment. However <strong>the</strong> tendency to generalize a verb to an alternative structure was also affected<br />

by higher level distributional in<strong>for</strong>mation: <strong>the</strong> extent to which verbs across <strong>the</strong> language alternated<br />

between structures. Although this level of learning has not previously been considered, abstracting<br />

inferences about feature variability has proved important in o<strong>the</strong>r domains, <strong>and</strong> is <strong>the</strong> focus of recent<br />

computational research (Kemp, Per<strong>for</strong>s & Tenebaum (KPT) 2007). The current work explores <strong>the</strong><br />

learning of constraints on structure variability both experimentally <strong>and</strong> computationally.<br />

Two new artificial languages were created in order to replicate <strong>and</strong> extend a critical WNT<br />

experiment. Both had two synonymous argument structures (VSO <strong>and</strong> VOS-Particle) <strong>and</strong> 8 verbs. In<br />

<strong>Language</strong>1 4 verbs occurred only in VSO <strong>and</strong> 4 occurred only in VOS-Particle. In <strong>Language</strong>2 all<br />

verbs occurred in both constructions. A 2 day learning procedure was used, with production tests after<br />

both sessions. In one test, learners produced sentences with ‘new’ verbs which had been introduced in<br />

sentences presented just prior to <strong>the</strong> test. Within <strong>the</strong>se pre-test sentences, each verb had been heard 4<br />

times, <strong>and</strong> always in <strong>the</strong> same sentence structure. Replicating WNT, learners with different linguistic<br />

backgrounds differed greatly in <strong>the</strong>ir use of this small amount of lexically consistent in<strong>for</strong>mation:<br />

<strong>Language</strong>1 learners produced <strong>the</strong> verbs in structure in which <strong>the</strong>y had occurred in <strong>the</strong> 4 sentences;<br />

<strong>Language</strong>2 learners generalized across both structures. In this experiment we also examined<br />

individual patterns of production with *entirely* novel verbs. Again, we saw an influence of higher<br />

level learning: <strong>Language</strong>1 learners tended to r<strong>and</strong>omly assign a structure to a particular verb <strong>and</strong> use<br />

it consistently (across both days) while <strong>Language</strong> 2 learners showed variable usage. This is strong<br />

evidence that learners made <strong>the</strong> correct higher-order inferences. We demonstrate that <strong>the</strong>se data are<br />

consistent with a hierarchical Bayesian model, originally developed by KPT to capture <strong>the</strong> emergence<br />

of feature biases in word learning.<br />

Notes<br />

129


P77<br />

Of blue bottles <strong>and</strong> blue flowers: Phonological representations of L1 are<br />

active when producing words in L2<br />

Katharina Spalek 1 , & Markus F. Damian 2<br />

1 Humboldt <strong>University</strong> Berlin, Germany, 2 <strong>University</strong> of Bristol, UK<br />

E-mail: katharina.spalek@staff.hu-berlin.de<br />

Studies of monolingual speakers show phonological priming within an adjective noun phrase when<br />

both constituents start with <strong>the</strong> same phoneme (e.g., Damian & Dumay, 2007), that is, “blue bottle”<br />

<strong>and</strong> “green glass” are produced faster than “green bottle” <strong>and</strong> “blue glass”. In <strong>the</strong> present study, <strong>the</strong><br />

paradigm was used to investigate <strong>the</strong> extent to which speakers’ native language is active when <strong>the</strong>y<br />

speak a <strong>for</strong>eign language. In this bilingual version, a group of L2 speakers of English whose native<br />

language was German named coloured line drawings with adjective <strong>and</strong> noun. Two types of adjective<br />

noun phrases were used: 1. adjective <strong>and</strong> noun were related in <strong>the</strong> target language (e.g., “blue<br />

bottle”); 2. adjective <strong>and</strong> noun were related in <strong>the</strong> speakers’ native language (e.g., “blue flower” =<br />

“blaue Blume”). We replicated <strong>the</strong> monolingual priming effect, that is, faster reaction times <strong>for</strong><br />

overlapping noun <strong>and</strong> adjective onset. This 20-ms effect was slightly less reliable than <strong>for</strong> native<br />

speakers <strong>and</strong> it correlated negatively with <strong>the</strong> age at which L2 was learnt.<br />

More interestingly, we found a reverse effect <strong>for</strong> phrases like “blue flower”: Participants were<br />

significantly slower (by 26 ms) to produce phrases like “blue flower” than “green flower”. A<br />

phonological effect of <strong>the</strong> language that is not spoken, shows that <strong>the</strong> phonological representation of<br />

<strong>the</strong> native language translation is always co-activated. This finding is in line with earlier studies like<br />

Colomé (2001). We assume that <strong>the</strong> effect is inhibitory, because, in <strong>the</strong> case of “blaue Blume”,<br />

phonological overlap primes <strong>the</strong> underlying German representation, making it harder to reject in<br />

favour of <strong>the</strong> target language than <strong>the</strong> unprimed phrase “grüne Blume” (“green flower”). Fur<strong>the</strong>r<br />

experiments currently explore whe<strong>the</strong>r phonological overlap in both language will reduce <strong>the</strong> priming<br />

in <strong>the</strong> target language (caused by an interaction of target language priming <strong>and</strong> native language<br />

inhibition) or whe<strong>the</strong>r it will lead to “hyper”-priming of <strong>the</strong> target phrase.<br />

We argue that <strong>the</strong> present paradigm is a welcome extension to existing paradigms in <strong>the</strong> field of<br />

bilingual speech production.<br />

References<br />

Colomé, À. (2001). Lexical activation in bilinguals’ speech production: <strong>Language</strong>-specific or<br />

language-independent Journal of Memory <strong>and</strong> <strong>Language</strong>, 45, 721-736.<br />

Damian, M. F. & Dumay, N. (2007). Time pressure <strong>and</strong> phonological advance planning in spoken<br />

production. Journal of Memory <strong>and</strong> <strong>Language</strong>, 57, 195-209.<br />

Notes<br />

130


P78<br />

Processing overt <strong>and</strong> zero pronouns in M<strong>and</strong>arin Chinese<br />

Georgina Allured, Kathy Conklin, & Walter J.B. van Heuven<br />

<strong>University</strong> of Nottingham, UK<br />

E-mail: kathy.conklin@nottingham.ac.uk<br />

Most work in <strong>the</strong> area of anaphor resolution has been done on English. Recent work indicates that<br />

despite linguistic differences between English <strong>and</strong> M<strong>and</strong>arin, order of mention <strong>and</strong> ambiguity show a<br />

similar processing pattern. M<strong>and</strong>arin also makes use of zero pronouns. Using a measure of whole<br />

sentence reading time, Yang et al. (1999) found that in ambiguous sentences <strong>the</strong>re was no effect of<br />

zero vs. overt pronouns in ei<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> first or second mention conditions.<br />

Two experiments fur<strong>the</strong>r explored <strong>the</strong>se basic findings using a region-by-region moving window<br />

paradigm to give a more fine grained measure of <strong>the</strong> processing ef<strong>for</strong>t required in pronoun resolution.<br />

We presented sentences from Yang et al. using simplified Chinese characters in regions, indicated by<br />

slash marks below. The first sentence introduced two characters having <strong>the</strong> same gender (ambiguous<br />

condition) or different genders (unambiguous condition). The second sentence began with a pronoun<br />

in <strong>the</strong> overt condition or verb in <strong>the</strong> zero pronoun condition. The zero <strong>and</strong> overt pronouns ei<strong>the</strong>r<br />

referred to <strong>the</strong> first or second mentioned entity from <strong>the</strong> previous sentence.<br />

Similar to Yang et al. <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> literature on English, Exp. 1 indicates that overt pronouns, in<br />

unambiguous contexts where <strong>the</strong>y provide a gender agreement cue, are processed quickly in both first<br />

<strong>and</strong> second mention conditions. However, processing is significantly slower in ambiguous contexts in<br />

regions |2-3| when referring to a second ra<strong>the</strong>r than a first mentioned entity. Exp. 2 looked at <strong>the</strong><br />

processing of zero <strong>and</strong> overt pronouns referring to first <strong>and</strong> second mentioned entities in ambiguous<br />

contexts. In contrast to Yang et al.'s Exp. 3, our results indicate that when referring to a first<br />

mentioned entity contexts with zero pronouns require significantly more processing time at region |2|.<br />

When referring to a second mentioned entity, contexts with zero pronouns require significantly more<br />

processing time in regions |2-3|. These findings indicate that in ambiguous sentences in both <strong>the</strong> first<br />

<strong>and</strong> second mention conditions overt pronouns provide a better cue than zero pronouns <strong>for</strong><br />

determining an antecedent. The results will be discussed in terms of a model of anaphoric reference in<br />

discourse processing.<br />

| 大 雄 | 见 到 | 宋 华 在 百 货 公 司 旁 边 摆 地 摊 .<br />

DaXiong (male) saw SongHua (male) selling things on <strong>the</strong> street in front of a store.<br />

|1| 她 /Ø |2| 没 想 到 会 有 |3| 同 学 去 摆 地 摊 .<br />

He didn't realize that his classmate sells things on <strong>the</strong> street.<br />

References<br />

Yang, Gordon, Hendrick, & Wu. (1999). Comprehension of referring expressions in Chinese.<br />

<strong>Language</strong> <strong>and</strong> Cognitive processes, 14, 715-7<br />

Notes<br />

131


P79<br />

Lexical <strong>and</strong> sublexical morphological influences in visual word recognition<br />

Kevin Diependaele 1 , Dominiek S<strong>and</strong>ra 2 , & Jonathan Grainger 3<br />

1 Ghent <strong>University</strong>, Belgium, 2 <strong>University</strong> of Antwerp, Belgium, 3 CNRS & Université de Provence, France<br />

E-mail: kevin.diependaele@ugent.be<br />

Several recent priming studies propound that morphemic representations are activated early on during<br />

visual processing, regardless of lexical variables such as semantic transparency <strong>and</strong> familiarity. They<br />

show that with sufficiently short prime durations, lexical decision latencies <strong>for</strong> free stems are<br />

facilitated to an equal extent following transparent, opaque as well as unfamiliar suffixed primes (e.g.,<br />

Longtin & Meunier, 2005). The presence of a suffix appears to be critical in this, since non-suffixed<br />

<strong>for</strong>m primes induce less facilitation.<br />

In order to gain fur<strong>the</strong>r insight in <strong>the</strong>se effects, we compared lexical decisions <strong>for</strong> stems following<br />

transparent prefixed primes (rename-name), opaque prefixed primes (remain-main) <strong>and</strong> non-prefixed<br />

primes (entail-tail) in Dutch. Primes were masked <strong>and</strong> presented <strong>for</strong> 67ms. We consistently observed<br />

larger facilitation with opaque primes than with non-prefixed primes, indicating that affixes in general<br />

mediate sublexical stem processing, regardless of <strong>the</strong>ir relative position. With mixed visual <strong>and</strong><br />

auditory lexical decision we found no effects of semantic transparency. However, transparent primes<br />

did induce larger priming effects in pure visual lexical decision. Since this difference is likely due to<br />

enhanced visual attention in a pure visual context, lexical influences on morpheme processing seem to<br />

require more extensive processing. Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, our data question <strong>the</strong> strict interdependence between<br />

lexical <strong>and</strong> sublexical influences, since sublexical stem processing even became more evident in <strong>the</strong><br />

presence of a transparency effect.<br />

Our second series of experiments (with 40 <strong>and</strong> 50ms primes) showed that familiar Dutch bimorphemic<br />

compounds facilitated lexical decisions <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir constituents to <strong>the</strong> same degree as<br />

unfamiliar compounds (bookshop-book vs. bookroad-book <strong>and</strong> bookshop-shop vs. barnshop-shop).<br />

We never<strong>the</strong>less found a small but reliable advantage with familiar compounds when we removed <strong>the</strong><br />

bigram at <strong>the</strong> morpheme boundary (boo__hop-book vs. boo__oad-book <strong>and</strong> boo__hop-shop vs.<br />

bar__hop-shop). We propose that in visual masked priming lexical influences only require a wholeword<br />

<strong>for</strong>m representation of <strong>the</strong> prime to become sufficiently active relative to o<strong>the</strong>r lexical <strong>for</strong>m<br />

activations. With degraded primes like boo__hop this relative activation level can be attained more<br />

rapidly since <strong>the</strong> competing lexical <strong>for</strong>m representations will be activated to a lesser degree.<br />

References<br />

Longtin, C.-M. & Meunier, F. (2005). Morphological decomposition in early visual word processing.<br />

Journal of Memory <strong>and</strong> <strong>Language</strong>, 53, 26–41.<br />

Notes<br />

132


P80<br />

Shared syntactic in<strong>for</strong>mation in German-English bilinguals: An fMRI<br />

repetition suppression study<br />

Kirsten M. Weber, & Peter Indefrey<br />

F.C. Donders <strong>Centre</strong> <strong>for</strong> Cognitive Neuroimaging, Radboud <strong>University</strong> Nijmegen, The Ne<strong>the</strong>rl<strong>and</strong>s<br />

E-mail: Kirsten.Weber@fcdonders.ru.nl<br />

A longst<strong>and</strong>ing question in bilingualism is whe<strong>the</strong>r syntactic in<strong>for</strong>mation is shared between <strong>the</strong> two<br />

language processing systems. We used an fMRI repetition suppression paradigm (Noppeney & Price,<br />

2004) to investigate syntactic priming (Bock, 1986: Schoonbaert, Hartsuiker, Pickering, 2007) in<br />

reading comprehension in German-English late-acquisition bilinguals. In comparison to conventional<br />

subtraction analyses in bilingual experiments, repetition suppression has <strong>the</strong> advantage of being able<br />

to detect neuronal populations that are sensitive to properties that are shared by consecutive stimuli.<br />

In this case, we manipulated <strong>the</strong> syntactic structure between prime <strong>and</strong> target sentences. A sentence<br />

with a passive sentence structure in English was preceded ei<strong>the</strong>r by a passive or by an active sentence<br />

in English or German. We looked <strong>for</strong> repetition suppression effects in left inferior frontal <strong>and</strong> left<br />

middle temporal regions of interest. These regions were defined by a contrast of all non-target<br />

sentences in German <strong>and</strong> English versus <strong>the</strong> baseline of sentence-<strong>for</strong>mat consonant strings. We found<br />

decreases in activity (repetition suppression effects) in <strong>the</strong>se regions of interest following <strong>the</strong><br />

repetition of syntactic structure from <strong>the</strong> first to <strong>the</strong> second language <strong>and</strong> within <strong>the</strong> second language.<br />

Moreover, a separate behavioural experiment using a word-by-word reading paradigm similar to <strong>the</strong><br />

fMRI experiment showed faster reading times <strong>for</strong> primed compared to unprimed English target<br />

sentences regardless of whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>y were preceded by an English or a German sentence of <strong>the</strong> same<br />

structure.<br />

We conclude that <strong>the</strong>re is some interaction between <strong>the</strong> language processing systems <strong>and</strong> that at least<br />

some syntactic in<strong>for</strong>mation is shared between a bilingual’s languages.<br />

References<br />

Bock, K. (1986). Syntactic persistence in language production Cognitive Psychology, 18(3), 355-387.<br />

Noppeney, U., & Price, C. J. (2004). An fMRI study of syntactic adaptation. Journal of Cognitive<br />

Neuroscience, 16(4), 702-713.<br />

Schoonbaert, S., Hartsuiker, R. J., & Pickering, M. J. (2007). The representation of lexical <strong>and</strong><br />

syntactic in<strong>for</strong>mation in bilinguals: Evidence from syntactic priming. Journal of Memory <strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>Language</strong>, 56(2), 153-171.<br />

Notes<br />

133


P81<br />

When cat competes with dog but not with perro: Evidence from <strong>the</strong><br />

semantic competitor paradigm<br />

Yol<strong>and</strong>a Garcia Castro 1 , Kristof Strijkers 1 , Albert M. Costa 1 , & Xavier Alario 2<br />

1 Universidad de Barcelona, Spain, 2 Université de Provence, France<br />

E-mail: Kristof_Strijkers@hotmail.com<br />

Bilinguals are quite efficient in keeping <strong>the</strong>ir two languages separate during speech. This raises <strong>the</strong><br />

question whe<strong>the</strong>r words between <strong>the</strong> two languages compete <strong>for</strong> selection or whe<strong>the</strong>r only words in<br />

<strong>the</strong> target language are considered <strong>for</strong> production. In <strong>the</strong> present study we investigated this issue<br />

making use of an interesting <strong>and</strong> new paradigm, <strong>the</strong> semantic competitor paradigm. With this<br />

paradigm it is found that subjects’ naming latencies are slowed down (25 ms) every time <strong>the</strong>y name a<br />

picture which belongs to <strong>the</strong> same semantic category as a previously named picture (Howard, 2006).<br />

In experiments 1 <strong>and</strong> 2 high-proficient Spanish-Catalan bilinguals per<strong>for</strong>med a picture naming task in<br />

<strong>the</strong>ir L1 (experiment 1) <strong>and</strong> L2 (experiment 2) making use of this semantic competitor paradigm. The<br />

results replicate prior data of semantic accumulation, <strong>and</strong> show that lexical interference is of similar<br />

magnitude in L1 <strong>and</strong> L2. For experiments 3 <strong>and</strong> 4 we combined this semantic competitor paradigm<br />

with a predictable switch task, in which target items (items of <strong>the</strong> same semantic category) alternated<br />

between L1 responses <strong>and</strong> L2 responses. Results seem to indicate <strong>the</strong> presence of <strong>the</strong> semantic<br />

competition effect within each language, but not between languages. Implications of <strong>the</strong>se<br />

experiments are discussed in light of different bilingual language control models.<br />

Notes<br />

134


P82<br />

The vocalic tier constrains statistical computations over <strong>the</strong><br />

consonantal tier<br />

Mohinish Shukla 1 , & Marina Nespor 2<br />

1 <strong>University</strong> of Rochester, USA,<br />

2 <strong>University</strong> of Milano Bicocca <strong>and</strong> Centro Beniamino Segre Accademia dei Lincei, Italy<br />

E-mail: mohinish.s@gmail.com<br />

Sensitivity to <strong>the</strong> distributional properties of speech sounds provides cues to word boundaries in an<br />

unfamiliar language. Infants <strong>and</strong> adults have been shown to segment artificial, fluent speech in which<br />

<strong>the</strong> statistical structure (transition probabilities, TPs) between syllables is <strong>the</strong> sole cue to word<br />

boundaries (Saffran, Aslin & Newport, 1996, Saffran, Newport & Aslin, 1996, Aslin, Saffran &<br />

Newport, 1998, Peña, Bonatti, Nespor & Mehler, 2002). More recently, it has been demonstrated that<br />

such statistical mechanisms are constrained. For example, high-TP sequences that straddle boundaries<br />

of large prosodic constituents (Intonational Phrases, IPs) are not efficiently extracted, when compared<br />

to high-TP sequences that are IP-internal (Shukla, Nespor & Mehler, 2007). In addition, it has been<br />

shown that, while TPs can be computed over non-adjacent syllables, <strong>the</strong>y are readily computed over<br />

(phonetically) non-adjacent consonants but not vowels (Peña, Bonatti, Nespor & Mehler, 2002,<br />

Newport & Aslin, 2004, Bonatti, Peña, Nespor & Mehler, 2005).<br />

In this study, we show that <strong>the</strong> computation of TPs over <strong>the</strong> consonantal tier can itself be constrained<br />

by in<strong>for</strong>mation in <strong>the</strong> vocalic tier. The vocalic tier is intimately linked to prosody. Inside prosodic<br />

constituents that are most closely related to words, phonological processes like vowel harmony<br />

diminish <strong>the</strong> qualitative distinctions between <strong>the</strong> vowels. As a result, similar vowels might group<br />

syllables into prosodic units. Here, we ask if a sequence in which all vowels are identical is perceived<br />

as a single ‘prosodic’ unit.<br />

In a series of experiments, we expose adult participants to artificial speech streams, <strong>and</strong> in subsequent<br />

(2-alternative <strong>for</strong>ced choice) tests, we pit trisyllabic sequences that share <strong>the</strong> same vowel (V-words)<br />

against trisyllabic sequences that are statistically coherent at <strong>the</strong> consonantal level (C-words) – <strong>the</strong><br />

latter having higher TPs over <strong>the</strong>ir constituent syllables <strong>and</strong> consonants than <strong>the</strong> <strong>for</strong>mer. First, we<br />

show that V-words are preferred over C-words. In a subsequent experiment we demonstrate that<br />

participants do not simply acquire a preference <strong>for</strong> sequences with identical vowels. Finally, we show<br />

that <strong>the</strong>se TP computations are restricted to syllable sequences that share <strong>the</strong> same vowel.<br />

Our results provide fur<strong>the</strong>r empirical evidence that, in adults, TP computations are constrained by<br />

regularities that signal constituency. This raises <strong>the</strong> possibility that infants too can use in<strong>for</strong>mation in<br />

<strong>the</strong> vocalic tier to constrain segmentation of words from fluent speech.<br />

Notes<br />

135


P83<br />

The statistical properties of semantic features influence spoken word<br />

recognition: Evidence from neuroimaging<br />

Kirsten I. Taylor, Billi R<strong>and</strong>all, Michael A. Ford, Barry J. Devereux, & Lorraine K. Tyler<br />

<strong>University</strong> of Cambridge, UK<br />

E-mail: ktaylor@csl.psychol.cam.ac.uk<br />

How are <strong>the</strong> meanings of concepts neurally represented <strong>and</strong> processed Distributed <strong>the</strong>ories of<br />

conceptual representations posit that concepts are represented in a distributed system composed of<br />

units representing semantic properties, <strong>and</strong> where <strong>the</strong> processing of a concept corresponds to<br />

overlapping patterns of activation across units representing <strong>the</strong> concept. The Conceptual Structure<br />

Account makes specific claims about how <strong>the</strong> statistical properties of features (e.g., <strong>the</strong> degree to<br />

which features are distinctive to a particular concept or shared by many concepts <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> degree to<br />

which two features co-occur (correlational strength)) determine <strong>the</strong> representational structure of<br />

concepts <strong>and</strong> how <strong>the</strong>se are processed. We tested <strong>the</strong> neural implications of <strong>the</strong>se claims by<br />

determining whe<strong>the</strong>r conceptual structure variables modulate functional brain activity associated with<br />

spoken word recognition. In a sparse event-related fMRI imaging study, participants per<strong>for</strong>med<br />

lexical decisions to spoken concrete words <strong>and</strong> phonotactically legal non-words, <strong>and</strong> high/low tone<br />

decisions in a baseline task. A principal components analysis of a large number of psycholinguistic<br />

variables <strong>and</strong> target conceptual structure variables produced eight orthogonalized principal<br />

components (phonology, cohort size, lexical, production frequency of features, distinctiveness,<br />

sharedness, correlational strength, <strong>and</strong> a variable representing <strong>the</strong> relationship between correlational<br />

strength <strong>and</strong> distinctiveness). The residualized length of <strong>the</strong> auditory words, nuisance factors, <strong>the</strong>n<br />

conceptual structure factors were entered into fMRI models as parametric modulators of activity<br />

associated with lexical decisions to auditory words to assess <strong>the</strong> influence of conceptual structure<br />

factors independent of lower-level processes. Lexical decisions to words compared to <strong>the</strong> baseline<br />

task generated activity in <strong>the</strong> left-lateralized fronto-temporal language network, as predicted.<br />

Critically, after <strong>the</strong> effects of lower-level acoustic <strong>and</strong> psycholinguistic factors had been accounted<br />

<strong>for</strong>, conceptual structure variables still significantly modulated functional activity both within <strong>the</strong><br />

frontotemporal language network (inferior frontal gyrus, middle <strong>and</strong> superior temporal gyri) <strong>and</strong> by<br />

engaging <strong>the</strong> attentional system (anterior cingulate/middle frontal gyrus). These findings demonstrate<br />

that conceptual structure variables, derived from cognitive models, significantly affect how concepts<br />

are neurally processed, consistent with a distributed model of conceptual representation <strong>and</strong><br />

processing.<br />

Notes<br />

136


P84<br />

Priming local syntactic structure in speech production: An online study<br />

Kristine Uzule, Linda R. Wheeldon, & Antje S. Meyer<br />

<strong>University</strong> of Birmingham, UK<br />

E-mail: kxu578@bham.ac.uk<br />

In two sentence production experiments, we examined whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> processor can reuse structurally<br />

identical local in<strong>for</strong>mation while encoding <strong>the</strong> next sentence when <strong>the</strong> two sentences have different<br />

global syntactic frames (Examples 1-3).<br />

1. Target: [The tap <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> kite] move toge<strong>the</strong>r<br />

2. Related prime: [The frog <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> book] move above <strong>the</strong> sock.<br />

3. Unrelated prime: [The cup] moves below <strong>the</strong> saw.<br />

In Experiment 1, participants read prime sentences <strong>and</strong> produced target utterances as descriptions of<br />

moving objects. In Experiment 2, all utterances were produced in response to moving objects. In each<br />

experiment, 32 target utterances <strong>and</strong> 24 undergraduate participants were tested. Error rates <strong>and</strong> speech<br />

onset latencies (SOL) <strong>for</strong> correct utterances were measured.<br />

The results of <strong>the</strong> two experiments were strikingly different. In Experiment 1 (written primes), related<br />

primes significantly facilitated <strong>the</strong> production of targets relative to unrelated primes (Means: Table.<br />

SOL: F 1 (1, 23)=8.23, MSError=1867, p


P85<br />

Delays in <strong>the</strong> use of discourse in<strong>for</strong>mation in syntactic ambiguity resolution<br />

Amit Dubey 1 , Patrick Sturt 2 , & Frank Keller 2<br />

1 <strong>University</strong> of Dundee, UK, 2 <strong>University</strong> of Edinburgh, UK<br />

E-mail: adubey@inf.ed.ac.uk<br />

Studies investigating <strong>the</strong> interaction between referential context <strong>and</strong> syntactic ambiguity resolution in<br />

reading often find differing degrees of interaction: some show modifier supporting contexts can<br />

prevent garden pathing (Spivey <strong>and</strong> Tanenhaus, 1998 JEP), while o<strong>the</strong>rs show weak or delayed<br />

effects of context (Binder et al, 2001 JML). One possible reason <strong>for</strong> this variability is that contextual<br />

in<strong>for</strong>mation may sometimes simply be unavailable in early stages of processing. Ano<strong>the</strong>r possibility<br />

is that contextual in<strong>for</strong>mation is available, but syntactic processing sometimes fails to make use of it,<br />

e.g., due to resource dem<strong>and</strong>s.<br />

Here, we investigate two issues: (a) <strong>the</strong> time-course of <strong>the</strong> interaction between context <strong>and</strong> ambiguity,<br />

<strong>and</strong> (b) <strong>the</strong> influence exerted by <strong>the</strong> difficulty of <strong>the</strong> contextual inference on this interaction. We<br />

investigate (a) by comparing early <strong>and</strong> late eye-tracking measures in reading, <strong>and</strong> (b) by using (across<br />

experiments) different degrees of lexical overlap between context <strong>and</strong> target.<br />

We present two experiments using a reduced relative ambiguity. In Exp 1, <strong>the</strong> relative-supporting<br />

(RS) context involved both noun <strong>and</strong> verb repetition, while <strong>the</strong> neutral context did not (1a-c). Exp 2<br />

used a RS context (2) where nei<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> noun nor verb were repeated (RS/NV).<br />

Reduced relative conditions were compared with unreduced baselines. Both experiments showed a<br />

garden path (GP) cost on <strong>the</strong> critical region "carried by", in first-pass measures, <strong>and</strong>, independently of<br />

this, both showed an early (first fixation) facilitation <strong>for</strong> RS contexts, even where integration requires<br />

inference (Exp 2). However, despite <strong>the</strong> early availability of contextual in<strong>for</strong>mation, it was only in<br />

later measures that context led to a reduction in GP cost, <strong>and</strong> only when <strong>the</strong>re was lexical repetition<br />

from <strong>the</strong> context (Exp 1).<br />

These findings support <strong>the</strong> view that contextual in<strong>for</strong>mation is available at <strong>the</strong> earliest stages of<br />

processing, even when contextual inference is required. However, <strong>the</strong> use of contextual in<strong>for</strong>mation<br />

<strong>for</strong> syntactic ambiguity resolution can be delayed <strong>and</strong> depends on <strong>the</strong> difficulty of <strong>the</strong> contextual<br />

inference.<br />

(1) a. RS context:<br />

Several reporters had applied <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> vacancy, but <strong>the</strong> management only interviewed one reporter.<br />

b. Neutral context:<br />

The newspaper was doing quite well, <strong>and</strong> was looking <strong>for</strong> additional staff to cover local news.<br />

c. Target sentence:<br />

The reporter (who was)/ interviewed by/ <strong>the</strong> editor was unfit <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> job, though.<br />

(2) RS/NV context:<br />

The editor had received several applications, but only decided to speak with one of <strong>the</strong> applicants.<br />

Notes<br />

138


P86<br />

Grammatical person controls perspective taking in embodied simulation<br />

semantics<br />

Sarah Schwarzkopf, Daniel Müller, Helmut Weldle, & Lars Konieczny<br />

<strong>Centre</strong> <strong>for</strong> Cognitive Science, <strong>University</strong> of Freiburg, Germany<br />

E-mail: sarah.schwarzkopf@cognition.uni-freiburg.de<br />

Embodied language processing <strong>the</strong>ories assume comprehension as simulation of perceptual <strong>and</strong> motor<br />

interactions. Glenberg & Kaschak (2002) found empirical support with <strong>the</strong> action-sentence<br />

compatibility effect (ACE): Sentences describing directed action influence <strong>the</strong> execution of<br />

corresponding real actions. Bergen & Wheeler (2005) argued that motor processes are even engaged<br />

when <strong>the</strong> reader is not addressed in <strong>the</strong> sentence. Zwaan (2004) integrated such findings in a model<br />

that describes language comprehension as situation simulation from <strong>the</strong> perspective of a joining<br />

observer.<br />

In this study we addressed <strong>the</strong> question, which linguistic features control perspective taking, by using<br />

German sentences describing directed actions with different possible perspective simulations. Factor<br />

1 (sentence type) varied interacting grammatical persons <strong>and</strong> roles: Third to third person (1), first to<br />

third person (2), third to first person (3). Factor 2 (compatibility) relates <strong>the</strong> described action verb to<br />

<strong>the</strong> actually executed action, being ei<strong>the</strong>r compatible or incompatible. Stimuli were presented on a<br />

computer screen using rapid serial visual presentation. After a complete sentence, participants had to<br />

judge its acceptability as fast as possible by pushing buttons that were placed along <strong>the</strong> requested<br />

action axis.<br />

(1) The drunkard attacks <strong>the</strong> card player.<br />

(2) I attack <strong>the</strong> card player.<br />

(3) The drunkard attacks me.<br />

We found a highly significant interaction of reaction times between sentence type <strong>and</strong> compatibility.<br />

Pairwise comparisons revealed that participants reacted reliably faster on sentence type 2 <strong>for</strong><br />

compatible action. On <strong>the</strong> contrary, participants showed significantly slower reactions in <strong>the</strong><br />

compatible case <strong>for</strong> sentence type 3 where <strong>the</strong> first person is <strong>the</strong> sentence object. We did not find a<br />

compatibility effect <strong>for</strong> sentences with only third person agents. The results suggest that an observer<br />

centered perspective is induced by grammatical person in <strong>the</strong> first or <strong>the</strong> second person, independent<br />

of <strong>the</strong>matic role or sentence focus. Third person situations possibly only work with just one agent, as<br />

in <strong>the</strong> study by Bergen & Wheeler (2005).<br />

References<br />

Bergen, B. & Wheeler, K. (2005). Sentence underst<strong>and</strong>ing engages motor processes. CogSci 05.<br />

Glenberg, A. & Kaschak, M. (2002). Grounding language in action. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review,<br />

9, 558-565.<br />

Zwaan, R. (2004). The immersed experiencer: toward an embodied <strong>the</strong>ory of language<br />

comprehension. In B. Ross (ed.). The psychology of learning <strong>and</strong> motivation. New York:<br />

Academic Press, 35-62.<br />

Notes<br />

139


P87<br />

Extra complementizers increase syntactic predictability<br />

Laura Staum Casasanto, Richard Futrell, & Ivan A. Sag<br />

Stan<strong>for</strong>d <strong>University</strong>, USA<br />

E-mail: laura.staum@gmail.com<br />

Staum Casasanto <strong>and</strong> Sag (2008) report that repeating <strong>the</strong> complementizer ‘that’ can help<br />

comprehenders underst<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> complement clause in verb-complement structures, when <strong>the</strong> subject<br />

of <strong>the</strong> embedded clause is displaced from <strong>the</strong> first complementizer by a long adverbial. They propose<br />

that ra<strong>the</strong>r than being generated by <strong>the</strong> grammar, repeated complementizers are a production strategy<br />

<strong>for</strong> reducing processing difficulty by reactivating syntactic expectations <strong>for</strong> a complement clause <strong>and</strong><br />

its constituents immediately be<strong>for</strong>e <strong>the</strong> embedded subject appears. However, extra ‘that’ also appears<br />

be<strong>for</strong>e <strong>the</strong> subjects of clauses that were not originally introduced by ‘that’:<br />

(1) It seems like, <strong>the</strong>oretically, that it would be possible to travel along in <strong>the</strong> middle of a tornado <strong>and</strong><br />

survive. (Google)<br />

In <strong>the</strong>se cases, <strong>the</strong> extra ‘that’ is also ungrammatical, but it cannot be interpreted as a repetition – it<br />

must be independently generated. Is this extra complementizer also motivated by reducing processing<br />

difficulty in <strong>the</strong> embedded clause<br />

A moving-window self-paced reading experiment investigated whe<strong>the</strong>r an extra that would help<br />

comprehenders read <strong>the</strong> embedded clause even when it did not match <strong>the</strong> original clause-introducer.<br />

Participants read sentences like (2), in which <strong>the</strong> clause was originally introduced by ei<strong>the</strong>r 'because'<br />

or 'like'; each sentence appeared ei<strong>the</strong>r with or without an extra 'that' (in parens):<br />

(2) She lived in mortal terror because after undergoing <strong>the</strong> experimental surgical procedure after her<br />

fourteenth birthday party celebration (that) she became paranoid of massive medical conspiracies.<br />

The extra complementizer helped participants read <strong>the</strong> embedded clause, resulting in faster reading<br />

times on <strong>the</strong> embedded subject compared to <strong>the</strong> st<strong>and</strong>ard, single-complementizer version of <strong>the</strong><br />

sentence (t(1,45)=1.73, p


When are two characters a set Using scenario-mapping as a guide to<br />

equivalence<br />

P88<br />

Linda M. Moxey, & Anthony J. San<strong>for</strong>d<br />

<strong>University</strong> of Glasgow, UK<br />

E-mail: linda@psy.gla.ac.uk<br />

When two individual characters are introduced in discourse it is often, but not always possible to refer<br />

to <strong>the</strong>m using a plural pronoun (e.g. <strong>the</strong>y). In some contexts such as (1), plural reference is clearly<br />

preferred, while o<strong>the</strong>r contexts such as (2) make plural reference awkward.<br />

(1) Paul <strong>and</strong> Carol went into <strong>the</strong> city centre.<br />

(2) Paul went into <strong>the</strong> city centre with Carol.<br />

Semantic <strong>and</strong> pragmatic factors also influence <strong>the</strong> ease with which a plural pronoun successfully<br />

refers to two characters mentioned individually in previous text.<br />

According to Kamp & Reyle’s Equivalence hypo<strong>the</strong>sis <strong>the</strong> circumstances under which plural<br />

pronominal reference is possible depends on <strong>the</strong> equivalence of <strong>the</strong> characters (Kamp & Reyle, 1993).<br />

Various factors have been suggested as contributing towards equivalence (Carreiras, 1997; Koh &<br />

Clifton, 2002). Our aim is to use Scenario-mapping <strong>the</strong>ory (San<strong>for</strong>d & Garrod, 1981; 1998) to guide<br />

our search <strong>for</strong> what might be considered “equivalent”. In this paper we present two sentence<br />

completion experiments which show that <strong>the</strong> roles played by <strong>the</strong> characters within a scenario are key<br />

in determining character equivalence. In Experiment 1 we manipulate <strong>the</strong> status of <strong>the</strong> character with<br />

respect to <strong>the</strong> scenario associated with <strong>the</strong> verb phrase, <strong>and</strong> show that if <strong>the</strong> status of <strong>the</strong> characters<br />

differs participants are less likely to use a plural pronoun in continuations. In <strong>the</strong> Experiment 2 we<br />

manipulate both physical location <strong>and</strong> action per<strong>for</strong>med by <strong>the</strong> character, <strong>and</strong> show that while<br />

physical proximity is a predictor of plural reference, per<strong>for</strong>ming <strong>the</strong> same action (regardless of<br />

location) is a much stronger predictor of plural pronominal reference. We conclude that scenariomapping<br />

<strong>the</strong>ory provides a basis <strong>for</strong> equivalence.<br />

References<br />

Carreiras, M. (1997). Plural pronouns <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> representation of <strong>the</strong>ir antecedents. European Journal of<br />

Cognitive Psychology 9(1):53-87<br />

Kamp, H. & Reyle, U. (1993) From discourse to logic. Dordrecht, Kluwer.<br />

Koh, S. & Clifton, C. (2002). Resolution of <strong>the</strong> antecedent of a plural pronoun: Ontological categories<br />

<strong>and</strong> predicate symmetry. Journal of Memory <strong>and</strong> <strong>Language</strong> 46, 830-844.<br />

San<strong>for</strong>d, A. J. & Garrod, S. C. (1981) Underst<strong>and</strong>ing written language. John Wiley & sons.<br />

San<strong>for</strong>d, A. J. & Garrod, S. C. (1998) The role of scenario mapping in text comprehension. Discourse<br />

Processes, 26, 159-190.<br />

Notes<br />

141


P89<br />

The role of event knowledge in verb interpretation<br />

David S. Race 1 , Natalie M. Klein 1 , Mary L. Hare 2 , & Michael K. Tanenhaus 1<br />

1 <strong>University</strong> of Rochester, USA, 2 Bowling Green State <strong>University</strong>, USA<br />

E-mail: drace@bcs.rochester.edu<br />

We propose that <strong>the</strong> fit of an argument to a verb’s <strong>the</strong>matic roles is based on <strong>the</strong> event <strong>the</strong> verb<br />

describes in context. Bicknell et al. (2008) found that comprehenders showed more processing<br />

difficulty in sentences where an o<strong>the</strong>rwise good patient <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> verb was made less plausible by <strong>the</strong><br />

combination of verb <strong>and</strong> agent noun (The boss fired <strong>the</strong> rifle). We argue that such results are due to<br />

expectations about <strong>the</strong> underlying event, ra<strong>the</strong>r than agent-specific lexical knowledge about <strong>the</strong> verb.<br />

The agent can strongly influence <strong>the</strong> interpretation of <strong>the</strong> verb (<strong>and</strong> thus <strong>the</strong> event) in single<br />

sentences, but is integrated with prior context when available. Context should thus override<br />

expectancies that <strong>the</strong> agent might elicit in isolation. We conducted two self-paced reading<br />

experiments to test this claim.<br />

In Expt. 1, we created 20 sentences with sense-ambiguous verbs <strong>and</strong> with agents biasing toward<br />

different senses, but continuing identically (one lifeguard/shopper saved a woman...). RTs at <strong>the</strong><br />

patient were faster in <strong>the</strong> Agent Consistent condition, replicating Bicknell et al. In Expt. 2, <strong>the</strong> same<br />

items were preceded by short discourse contexts that were ei<strong>the</strong>r consistent or inconsistent with <strong>the</strong><br />

continuation. If <strong>the</strong> agent always activates a specific verb sense, <strong>the</strong>n RTs should be faster in <strong>the</strong><br />

Agent Consistent conditions, as <strong>the</strong>y were in isolated sentences. However, if <strong>the</strong> event structure is<br />

key, <strong>the</strong>n RTs should be faster in <strong>the</strong> Context Consistent conditions, regardless of agent.<br />

Results support this account: RTs at <strong>the</strong> patient were faster after consistent than inconsistent contexts,<br />

with no effect of agent consistency <strong>and</strong> no interaction. We conclude that context at various levels<br />

influences comprehenders’ interpretation of <strong>the</strong> event being described <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> roles that event<br />

participants will play.<br />

Context Consistent<br />

Yesterday, a fire broke out inside Swami's Surf Shop, near Malibu Beach. Everyone was scrambling<br />

to get out of <strong>the</strong> building.<br />

Context Inconsistent<br />

Swami's Surf Shop held its famous yearly sale down at <strong>the</strong> beach yesterday. Everyone looks <strong>for</strong>ward<br />

to it, because <strong>the</strong> prices are so good.<br />

Agent Consistent – One lifeguard saved a woman who was almost trampled by <strong>the</strong> crowd in <strong>the</strong> rush<br />

to escape/when <strong>the</strong> doors opened.<br />

Agent Inconsistent – One shopper saved a woman who was almost trampled by…<br />

References<br />

Bicknell, K., Elman, J. L., Hare, M., McRae, K., & Kutas, M. (2008). Online expectations <strong>for</strong> verbal<br />

arguments conditional on event knowledge. To appear in <strong>the</strong> Proceedings of <strong>the</strong> Cognitive<br />

Science Society, Hillsdale, N.J.: Erlbaum.<br />

Notes<br />

142


Resumptive pronouns in relative clauses: A last resource processing<br />

strategy in sentence production<br />

P90<br />

Fern<strong>and</strong>a V. Mir<strong>and</strong>a, & Leticia M.S. Corrêa<br />

Catholic <strong>University</strong> of Rio de Janeiro, Brazil<br />

E-mail: lscorrea@puc-rio.br<br />

Resumptive pronouns have been presented in <strong>the</strong> linguistic literature as <strong>the</strong> result of a last resort<br />

strategy. The gap in <strong>the</strong> relative clause (RC) would be filled in by a pronoun in order to rescue a<br />

derivation o<strong>the</strong>rwise fated to crash (Engdahl 1985; Rizzi 1990; Shlonsky 1992; Grolla, 2005). This<br />

paper investigates whe<strong>the</strong>r this last resource strategy can be taken to correspond to a last resource<br />

processing strategy in sentence production. In this case, resumptive pronouns would be more likely to<br />

occur in those RCs whose internal processing is more dem<strong>and</strong>ing. Processing dem<strong>and</strong> was defined as<br />

a function of focus (<strong>the</strong> position of <strong>the</strong> gap in <strong>the</strong> RC), following <strong>the</strong> Accessibility Hierarchy (AH)<br />

(Keenan & Comrie, 1977). And an incremental model of on-line computation allowing <strong>the</strong> production<br />

of a complement DP be<strong>for</strong>e <strong>the</strong> syntactic <strong>for</strong>mulation of <strong>the</strong> RC attached to it is completed defines <strong>the</strong><br />

processing condition that would facilitate an eventual crash in <strong>the</strong> sentence computation. As elicited<br />

production task was created. Participants had to report a message expressed by a sentence with a<br />

st<strong>and</strong>ard RC (visually presented <strong>for</strong> 500ms), introduced to <strong>the</strong>m as something that had been told by<br />

“John”. They would recover that message from memory when answering to <strong>the</strong> question such as<br />

What has John told orally presented in a female voice. The answer should contain a completive<br />

sentence with a RC. Focus (subject (S), direct object (DO), indirect object (IO), genitive (GEN)) <strong>and</strong><br />

embedding (center-embedded (CE) <strong>and</strong> right-branching (RB)) were manipulated in <strong>the</strong> visually<br />

presented sentence. More responses showing <strong>the</strong> recasting of <strong>the</strong> original sentence by means of a<br />

resumptive pronoun were predicted to occur in <strong>the</strong> RB condition <strong>and</strong> in <strong>the</strong> focus conditions lower in<br />

<strong>the</strong> AH. The test was conducted with 22 adult native speakers of Brazilian Portuguese, a language<br />

requiring pied-piping, no preposition str<strong>and</strong>ing <strong>and</strong> allowing null objects. Significant main effects of<br />

focus <strong>and</strong> embedding were obtained in <strong>the</strong> predicted direction. The results suggest that resumptive<br />

pronouns in RCs are due to a last resource strategy in <strong>the</strong> most dem<strong>and</strong>ing production conditions (OI<br />

<strong>and</strong> GEN). The extent to which linguistic (minimalist) hypo<strong>the</strong>ses can be transferred to <strong>the</strong><br />

psycholinguistic domain in discussed.<br />

Notes<br />

143


P91<br />

Syntactic category ambiguity in sentence production<br />

Robert Thornton, & Jeffrey Bye<br />

Pomona College, USA<br />

E-mail: rt004747@pomona.edu<br />

Many words are syntactically ambiguous, appearing as ei<strong>the</strong>r a noun or a verb (e.g., plant, fly, drink).<br />

In English, plural nouns are marked with an –s affix, whereas <strong>for</strong> verbs, <strong>the</strong> –s is added <strong>for</strong> singulars.<br />

Thus, plants is not only category ambiguous, but number ambiguous as well (plural noun or singular<br />

verb). We exploited this number ambiguity to examine how <strong>the</strong> time-course of lexical ambiguity<br />

affects higher level sentence production.<br />

In (1a), plants could be ei<strong>the</strong>r a plural noun or a singular verb, although in <strong>the</strong> context it can only be a<br />

noun. In (1b), trees is unambiguous as a plural noun.<br />

(1a) The soil around <strong>the</strong> plants<br />

(1b) The soil around <strong>the</strong> trees<br />

In two experiments, we examined how this difference affected agreement error rates by having<br />

participants produce complete sentences from such fragments (e.g., Bock & Miller, 1991). Agreement<br />

studies have shown that when <strong>the</strong> number of <strong>the</strong> local noun mismatched <strong>the</strong> head, participants<br />

produced more agreement errors than when both nouns matched in number. If <strong>the</strong> verb interpretation<br />

of <strong>the</strong> local noun in (1a) becomes active during production, <strong>the</strong> singular verb meaning might compete<br />

with <strong>the</strong> plural noun meaning, reducing <strong>the</strong> interference of <strong>the</strong> mismatching number, which would<br />

result in lower agreement error rates relative to (1b). In Experiment 1, although <strong>the</strong>re were<br />

significantly more agreement errors when <strong>the</strong> local noun mismatched in number, this effect was not<br />

modulated by syntactic ambiguity, with exactly <strong>the</strong> same agreement error rate regardless of<br />

ambiguity.<br />

Experiment 2 provided a more stringent test by using collective head nouns. Haskell & MacDonald<br />

(2003) demonstrated that subtle constraints on agreement can be obscured by stronger number<br />

constraints. Whereas most count nouns strongly constrain agreement patterns, collective head nouns<br />

(e.g., family, group) are more variable in agreement. Thus, having count nouns in Experiment 1 may<br />

have obscured <strong>the</strong> effect of ambiguity. Experiment 2 used collective heads, which less strongly<br />

constrain agreement:<br />

(2a) The family of plants<br />

(2b) The family of trees<br />

With collective heads, we saw a significant effect of ambiguity in <strong>the</strong> predicted direction: participants<br />

made fewer agreement errors when <strong>the</strong> local noun was category ambiguous than when it was not.<br />

These results indicate that <strong>the</strong> semantics of <strong>the</strong> verb meaning become active during sentence<br />

production even though <strong>the</strong> word is being produced unambiguously as a noun. The results will be<br />

discussed in terms of <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>oretical importance <strong>for</strong> models of agreement <strong>and</strong> production more<br />

generally.<br />

Notes<br />

144


P92<br />

The effect of lexical ambiguity on spoken word recognition: Homographs<br />

versus homophones<br />

Jack C. Rogers, William D. Marslen-Wilson, & Mat<strong>the</strong>w H. Davis<br />

MRC Cognition <strong>and</strong> <strong>Brain</strong> Sciences Unit, Cambridge, UK<br />

E-mail: jack.rogers@mrc-cbu.cam.ac.uk<br />

A number of reports have shown faster visual lexical decisions <strong>for</strong> semantically ambiguous words<br />

versus unambiguous controls, a result of feedback from multiple semantic representations. However,<br />

more recent lexical decision experiments have suggested two opposite effects of lexical ambiguity:<br />

polysemous words (twist) with multiple related meanings show an ambiguity advantage whereas<br />

homographs with multiple unrelated meanings (bark) delay word recognition, due to semantic<br />

competition¹. This remains controversial due to inconsistent results across studies, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> subjective<br />

nature of <strong>the</strong> distinction between related <strong>and</strong> unrelated meanings of ambiguous words.<br />

Testing <strong>for</strong> effects of ambiguity on responses to spoken words allows us to use homophones<br />

(knight/night) <strong>for</strong> which two separate lexical representations exist. In a speeded auditory lexical<br />

decision task, 21 subjects responded to 72 homographs, 72 homophones <strong>and</strong> 72 single-meaning<br />

controls matched <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> number of senses, as well as overall frequency, number of phonemes <strong>and</strong><br />

number of syntactic classes. We also computed a semantic entropy measure <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> homographs <strong>and</strong><br />

homophones as a way of quantifying <strong>the</strong> degree of competition between different word meanings. If<br />

ambiguity results from competition between meanings <strong>the</strong>n responses <strong>for</strong> items with higher semantic<br />

entropy will be slower.<br />

Results show significantly slowed response times (RTs) <strong>for</strong> both groups of ambiguous words versus<br />

matched controls (F1 (2, 40)=24.03, p


P93<br />

Verb phrase ellipsis: Discourse effects in syntax <strong>and</strong> syntactic effects in<br />

discourse<br />

Christina S. Kim, & Jeffrey T. Runner<br />

<strong>University</strong> of Rochester, USA<br />

E-mail: ckim@bcs.rochester.edu<br />

Recent work on verb phrase ellipsis (VPE) have shown sentence acceptability (1) depends on <strong>the</strong><br />

extent of syntactic mismatch between <strong>the</strong> antecedent <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> elided material [1,2,3]. Comparing VPE<br />

where strict syntactic identity is violated reveals that acceptability varies among cases that are<br />

uni<strong>for</strong>mly ungrammatical on previous accounts. E.g. 1b contains a Voice mismatch, but using <strong>the</strong><br />

connective so can improve acceptability [5]. The current study asks to what extent discourse<br />

structural relations between <strong>the</strong> antecedent <strong>and</strong> ellipsis clauses can account <strong>for</strong> patterns of<br />

acceptability in coordinate structures (1), <strong>and</strong> at <strong>the</strong> discourse level (2).<br />

Exp1 compared <strong>the</strong> effect of syntactic mismatch on VPE acceptability where antecedent <strong>and</strong> ellipsis<br />

were related by Resemblance (‘<strong>and</strong>’) or Cause-Effect (‘so’). According to Kehler [4], Resemblance<br />

depends on alignment of syntactic arguments <strong>and</strong> should be sensitive to mismatch; in contrast, Cause-<br />

Effect relates sentences at <strong>the</strong> propositional level <strong>and</strong> should be insensitive to mismatch. Ellipsis-<br />

Mismatch cases (1b-c) were compared to both Matched (1a) <strong>and</strong> NoEllipsis controls (1d). There was<br />

an Ellipsis-Mismatch interaction: Mismatch was judged worse than Match only with Ellipsis<br />

(F(1,23)=103,p


P94<br />

Unsupervised learning of conceptual representations – a computational<br />

neural model<br />

Michael Klein 1 , Stefan Frank 2 , Henk van Jaarsveld 1 , Louis F.M. ten Bosch 1 , & Lou Boves 1<br />

1 CLST, Radboud <strong>University</strong>, Nijmegen, The Ne<strong>the</strong>rl<strong>and</strong>s,<br />

2 ILLC, <strong>University</strong> of Amsterdam, The Ne<strong>the</strong>rl<strong>and</strong>s<br />

E-mail: M.Klein@nici.ru.nl<br />

Levelt, Roelofs, <strong>and</strong> Meyer (1999) argue that concepts cannot be represented as feature clusters, but<br />

need to be represented as non-decompositional conceptual units. One major reason <strong>for</strong> this is <strong>the</strong><br />

hypernym/hyponym problem: if concepts are represented as feature clusters, <strong>the</strong> conceptual<br />

representation of any word has at least all <strong>the</strong> features of its hypernym. It would <strong>the</strong>re<strong>for</strong>e be<br />

impossible to activate, e.g., <strong>the</strong> word “mo<strong>the</strong>r” without triggering <strong>the</strong> word “parent” at <strong>the</strong> same time.<br />

However, if concepts are indeed represented as non-decompositional units, at least two o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

problems remain to be solved (given that <strong>the</strong> input to <strong>the</strong> semantic system are perceptual features): (i)<br />

explaining <strong>the</strong> emergence of such units during <strong>the</strong> acquisition of conceptual knowledge <strong>and</strong> (ii)<br />

preventing <strong>the</strong> analogue to <strong>the</strong> hypernym/hyponym problem to occur at <strong>the</strong> conceptual level, i.e., <strong>the</strong><br />

problem that <strong>the</strong> input features leading to <strong>the</strong> activation of conceptual unit [[mo<strong>the</strong>r]] would also<br />

trigger <strong>the</strong> activation of [[parent]].<br />

We present a computational neural model that solves both problems using a competitive-layer<br />

architecture. We ran a number of simulations using 77 different (binary) semantic features as input to<br />

<strong>the</strong> model during training <strong>and</strong> testing. Over 4900 training episodes, <strong>the</strong> features were presented in<br />

combinations that allowed <strong>the</strong> model to learn 49 concepts. These concepts could be grouped into 7<br />

semantically related families. The maximum depth of <strong>the</strong> conceptual hierarchy was 3 (e.g., [[animal]],<br />

[[bird]], [[robin]]). We show that <strong>the</strong> model develops 49 conceptual units, each of which activates <strong>the</strong><br />

strongest when <strong>the</strong> feature set that defines <strong>the</strong> concept is presented to <strong>the</strong> model. There<strong>for</strong>e, our model<br />

can be regarded as a potential computational neural <strong>the</strong>ory of how non-decompositional conceptual<br />

units emerge in <strong>the</strong> brain.<br />

During <strong>the</strong> phase of concept acquisition, <strong>the</strong> model displays overgeneralizations (e.g., <strong>the</strong> use of <strong>the</strong><br />

[[dog]] concept <strong>for</strong> everything with four legs) <strong>and</strong> undergeneralizations (e.g., <strong>the</strong> use <strong>the</strong> of [[dog]]<br />

concept <strong>for</strong> only <strong>the</strong> dog of <strong>the</strong> neighbours), which are in accord with data reported in <strong>the</strong> literature<br />

(e.g., Clark, 1973). After training, <strong>the</strong> presentation of an input vector of perceptual features always<br />

maximally activates <strong>the</strong> most precise concept: when <strong>the</strong> features of [[mo<strong>the</strong>r]] are presented, <strong>the</strong><br />

[[mo<strong>the</strong>r]] concept is activated more strongly than <strong>the</strong> [[parent]] concept, <strong>and</strong> vice versa, despite <strong>the</strong><br />

strong overlap in features. This shows that <strong>the</strong> conceptual analogue of <strong>the</strong> hypernym/hyponym<br />

problem does not occur.<br />

Notes<br />

147


P95<br />

Joint effects of knowledge overlap (bias) <strong>and</strong> strength of memory<br />

representations<br />

Daphna Heller, Kirsten Skovbroten, & Michael K. Tanenhaus<br />

<strong>University</strong> of Rochester, USA<br />

E-mail: daphna.heller@gmail.com<br />

The felicity of referring expressions depends on interlocutors’ knowledge states <strong>and</strong> how <strong>the</strong>y differ<br />

from each o<strong>the</strong>r. For example, speakers are expected to use a name (<strong>and</strong> not a longer description) to<br />

refer to an entity whenever one is available, in accordance with Grice’s cooperative principle.<br />

Crucially, a name can only be used felicitously if it is shared by both interlocutors. How interlocutors<br />

keep track of what in<strong>for</strong>mation is shared <strong>and</strong> what is privileged remains an open question. On one<br />

extreme, interlocutors might have complete knowledge about shared vs. privileged in<strong>for</strong>mation. The<br />

o<strong>the</strong>r extreme assumes that assigning each piece of in<strong>for</strong>mation a shared vs. privileged status is<br />

computationally intensive, <strong>and</strong> instead interlocutors employ a global strategy, estimating <strong>the</strong> overall<br />

in<strong>for</strong>mation overlap. We show that while overall bias plays a role in speakers’ assessment of <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

addressee’s knowledge state, speakers also keep track of <strong>the</strong> status of specific pieces of in<strong>for</strong>mation<br />

as shared or privileged when <strong>the</strong>se categories are structured similar to real-world in<strong>for</strong>mation.<br />

Pairs of naïve participants per<strong>for</strong>med a referential communication task adapted from Wu & Keysar<br />

(2007, Cognitive Science). Participants learned names <strong>for</strong> 24 novel shapes. Two factors were<br />

manipulated in training. Overlap manipulated whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> participants learned eighteen (high) or six<br />

(low) names toge<strong>the</strong>r. The speaker <strong>the</strong>n learned <strong>the</strong> names <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> rest of <strong>the</strong> shapes alone, while <strong>the</strong><br />

addressee was playing a computer game. Structure manipulated whe<strong>the</strong>r or not <strong>the</strong> last six shapes<br />

constituted a category. In <strong>the</strong> structured condition, names started with [fl]. After training, participants<br />

communicated across a network, sitting in front of different computers. The speaker was presented<br />

with one shape (shared, privileged or new), <strong>and</strong> instructed <strong>the</strong> addressee, who saw three shapes,<br />

which to click on.<br />

Speaker’s instructions were coded as to whe<strong>the</strong>r or not <strong>the</strong>y used a name in referring to <strong>the</strong> shape.<br />

Structure increased sensitivity (<strong>the</strong> ratio of hits/false alarms), indicating that structuring <strong>the</strong><br />

in<strong>for</strong>mation enabled speakers to keep better track of <strong>the</strong> shared vs. privileged status of particular<br />

pieces of in<strong>for</strong>mation. Overlap affected bias to use a name: <strong>the</strong> greater <strong>the</strong> overlap, <strong>the</strong> greater <strong>the</strong> bias<br />

<strong>for</strong> speakers to use names <strong>for</strong> both shared (hits) <strong>and</strong> privileged (false alarms) shapes. Speakers<br />

combine a global estimate of <strong>the</strong> amount of shared in<strong>for</strong>mation with a local estimate of <strong>the</strong> evidence<br />

about shared vs. privileged status when deciding whe<strong>the</strong>r to use a name or a description.<br />

Notes<br />

148


Testing <strong>the</strong> alignment model: Syntax-lexicon & syntax-phonology<br />

P96<br />

Marie Nilsenová, & Marije A.A. van Amelsvoort<br />

Tilburg <strong>University</strong>, The Ne<strong>the</strong>rl<strong>and</strong>s<br />

E-mail: m.nilsenova@uvt.nl<br />

According to <strong>the</strong> interactive alignment model of Pickering & Garrod (2004), dialogue partners who<br />

align on a syntactic level also align at <strong>the</strong> level of phonology (<strong>and</strong> vice versa) <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> link between<br />

<strong>the</strong> syntactic <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> phonological representation is assumed to be direct, sidestepping <strong>the</strong> lexical<br />

entry. We tested <strong>the</strong> prediction in an experimental task similar to <strong>the</strong> confederate priming task of<br />

Branigan et al. (2000), but involving non-existing verbs, with Dutch native speakers. Participants<br />

were asked to create new verbs to describe activities depicted on a picture <strong>and</strong> use <strong>the</strong>m in a<br />

grammatical sentence; <strong>the</strong>y took turns with a confederate who alternatively primed <strong>the</strong>m with<br />

PO/DO-constructions <strong>and</strong> non-existing verbs with a systematically varied phonological structure<br />

(mono- vs. disyllabic items; varied in terms of <strong>the</strong> manner of articulation <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> consonants in <strong>the</strong><br />

onset of <strong>the</strong> initial syllable + <strong>the</strong> complex coda of <strong>the</strong> monosyllabic verbs or <strong>the</strong> onset of <strong>the</strong> second<br />

syllable in <strong>the</strong> disyllabic primes). The collected data were also compared to a task involving <strong>the</strong><br />

construction of new verbs in <strong>the</strong> absence of confederate primes. The results of <strong>the</strong> experiment support<br />

<strong>the</strong> prediction of <strong>the</strong> alignment model (Pickering & Garrod 2004).<br />

In a related experiment, we tested <strong>the</strong> link between <strong>the</strong> lexicon <strong>and</strong> syntax, established <strong>for</strong> English by<br />

Branigan <strong>and</strong> colleagues but, to our knowledge, not yet tested in o<strong>the</strong>r languages. In <strong>the</strong> experiment,<br />

we compared <strong>the</strong> level of local syntactic alignment (involving PO/DO verbal constructions in<br />

immediately following turns) between participants who had to align lexically (e.g., <strong>the</strong>y were<br />

instructed to use <strong>the</strong> verb ‘GIVE’ after being primed with a construction involving <strong>the</strong> verb ‘GIVE’)<br />

<strong>and</strong> participants who had to use a different verb (e.g., <strong>the</strong>y were instructed to use <strong>the</strong> verb ‘SELL’<br />

after being primed with <strong>the</strong> verb ‘GIVE’). The results of <strong>the</strong> experiment are similar to <strong>the</strong> results <strong>for</strong><br />

English, again offering support <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> alignment model. In addition, we compared <strong>the</strong> level of<br />

between-speaker alignment with “self-alignment”, i.e., <strong>the</strong> natural tendency to use <strong>the</strong> same<br />

construction over several of speaker’s own turns, disregarding <strong>the</strong> production (prime) uttered by <strong>the</strong><br />

o<strong>the</strong>r interlocutor. The data support <strong>the</strong> conclusion that between-speaker alignment is stronger than<br />

<strong>the</strong> tendency to reuse own constructions.<br />

References<br />

Branigan, H., Pickering, M.J., Clel<strong>and</strong>, A.A. (2000) Syntactic co-ordination in dialogue, Cognition<br />

75, B13-25.<br />

Pickering, M.J. & Garrod, S. (2004) Toward a mechanistic psychology of dialogue, Behavioral <strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>Brain</strong> Sciences 27.<br />

Notes<br />

149


P97<br />

Acquiring novel words <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir tenses: Evidence from lexical effects on<br />

phonetic categorisation with undegraded <strong>and</strong> degraded stimuli<br />

Shane Lindsay, Leanne Sedin, & Gareth Gaskell<br />

<strong>University</strong> of York, UK<br />

E-mail: sl574@york.ac.uk<br />

This research addresses <strong>the</strong> question of how novel words come to be represented in <strong>the</strong> auditory input<br />

lexicon, <strong>and</strong> how <strong>the</strong> novel inflected <strong>for</strong>ms of such words are recognised. This was investigated in<br />

four experiments using <strong>the</strong> lexical effects on phonetic categorisation paradigm, <strong>the</strong> “Ganong Effect”<br />

(Ganong, 1980). Participants were exposed to novel phonological <strong>for</strong>ms in phoneme monitoring <strong>and</strong><br />

tense generation tasks. Ambiguous phonemes were categorised consistent with learnt items (whole<br />

word condition) or past tense inflected <strong>for</strong>ms of learnt items (stem condition). Lexical effects on<br />

categorisation were present after a week (Experiment 1) <strong>and</strong> immediately (Experiment 2) following<br />

exposure to <strong>the</strong> novel words. In a fur<strong>the</strong>r two studies which attempted to replicate <strong>and</strong> extend <strong>the</strong>se<br />

findings, stimuli were degraded in <strong>the</strong> categorisation task, in order examine <strong>the</strong> emergence of lexical<br />

effects on phonetic categorisation in <strong>the</strong> presence of noise.<br />

These findings are taken as evidence <strong>for</strong> an account of lexicalisation in which novel <strong>for</strong>m in<strong>for</strong>mation<br />

is stored very quickly, as novel phonological <strong>for</strong>ms were able to influence <strong>the</strong> categorisation of word<br />

final ambiguous phonemes in those novel phonological <strong>for</strong>ms. The effects immediate after exposure<br />

present a challenge to <strong>the</strong> model of lexicalisation of Gaskell <strong>and</strong> Dumay (2003), suggesting that some<br />

aspects of lexicalisation are completed almost immediately following exposure to novel phonological<br />

<strong>for</strong>ms, <strong>and</strong> that lexicalisation is not dependent on sleep. Implications <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong>ories of <strong>the</strong> representation<br />

of inflectional <strong>for</strong>ms <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> time course of lexicalisation are discussed.<br />

References<br />

Ganong, W. F. (1980). Phonetic categorization in auditory word perception. Journal of Experimental<br />

Psychology: Human Perception <strong>and</strong> Per<strong>for</strong>mance, 6, 110-125.<br />

Gaskell, M. G., & Dumay, N. (2003). Lexical competition <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> acquisition of novel words.<br />

Cognition, 89, 105-132.<br />

Notes<br />

150


P98<br />

On-line orthographic influences on spoken language in a semantic task<br />

Chotiga Pattamadilok 1 , Laetitia Perre 2 , Stephane Dufau 2 , & Johannes Ziegler 2<br />

1 Universite Libre de Bruxelles, Belgium, 2 Aix-Marseille Université, France<br />

E-mail: cpattama@ulb.ac.be<br />

Literacy changes <strong>the</strong> way <strong>the</strong> brain processes spoken language. Most psycholinguists believe that<br />

orthographic effects on spoken language are ei<strong>the</strong>r strategic or restricted to meta-phonological tasks.<br />

We used event-related brain potentials (ERPs) to investigate <strong>the</strong> locus <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> time course of<br />

orthographic effects on spoken word recognition in a semantic task. Participants were asked to decide<br />

whe<strong>the</strong>r a given word belonged to a semantic category (body parts). On Nogo-trials, words were<br />

presented that were ei<strong>the</strong>r orthographically consistent or inconsistent. Orthographic inconsistency<br />

(i.e., multiple spellings of <strong>the</strong> same phonology) could occur ei<strong>the</strong>r in <strong>the</strong> first or <strong>the</strong> second syllable.<br />

The ERP data showed a clear orthographic consistency effect that preceded lexical access <strong>and</strong><br />

semantic effects. Moreover, <strong>the</strong> onset of <strong>the</strong> orthographic consistency effect was time-locked to <strong>the</strong><br />

arrival of <strong>the</strong> inconsistency in a spoken word, which suggests that orthography influences spoken<br />

language in a time-dependent manner. The present data join recent evidence from brain imaging<br />

showing orthographic activation in spoken language tasks. Our results extend those findings by<br />

showing that orthographic activation occurs early <strong>and</strong> affects spoken word recognition in a semantic<br />

task that does not require <strong>the</strong> explicit processing of orthographic or phonological structure.<br />

Notes<br />

151


P99<br />

Priming pronoun interpretation without using pronouns: Eye-tracking<br />

evidence <strong>for</strong> coherence<br />

Elsi Kaiser<br />

<strong>University</strong> of Sou<strong>the</strong>rn Cali<strong>for</strong>nia, USA<br />

E-mail: emkaiser@usc.edu<br />

The cognitive underpinnings of pronoun resolution are not fully understood. Kehler02 claims it is a<br />

by-product of general inferencing about inter-clause coherence relations. A SUBJECT interpretation<br />

of 'him' (ex1) is more likely with a CAUSE-EFFECT relation (a) than with RESEMBLANCE (b)<br />

(cf.Miltsakaki03, Wolf etal04, Rohde etal07).<br />

1 Phil tickled Stan <strong>and</strong> Tom poked him.<br />

a…<strong>and</strong> (as a result) Tom poked him[Phil=SUBJ]<br />

b…<strong>and</strong> (similarly) Tom poked him[Stan=OBJ]<br />

Coherence-based inferences exist independently of pronouns. Crucially, Kehler's approach predicts<br />

that pronoun resolution <strong>and</strong> coherence inferences involve overlapping cognitive representations. We<br />

tested this:<br />

With priming <strong>and</strong> visual-world eye-tracking, we tested if coherence relations prime pronoun<br />

resolution. We used LINGUISTIC (Exp1, 14Ss) <strong>and</strong> NONLINGUISTIC PRIMES (Exp2, 14Ss) of 3<br />

types: cause-effect, resemblance, neutral/nei<strong>the</strong>r. Ling primes were 2-clause sentences (eg.The<br />

children left toys scattered all over <strong>the</strong> room <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> babysitter tripped, cause-effect). Non-ling primes<br />

were silent videos (eg. square bumps circle which falls off ledge). Primes (normed <strong>for</strong> coherence) had<br />

no subj/obj pronouns. The 15 TARGETS (same in Exp1&2) were scenes with 3 same-sex characters;<br />

participants heard sentences with ambiguous obj pronouns (ex2). Nonce verbs eliminated verb<br />

effects. The task was to click on <strong>the</strong> last-mentioned person.<br />

2 Peter skrilled Mike <strong>and</strong> Greg mericked him.<br />

If pronoun resolution <strong>and</strong> coherence-based inferences share abstract representations, we predict that<br />

activation from primes can influence interpretation of 'him' <strong>and</strong> lead to more consideration of SUBJ<br />

after CAUSE than after RESEMB/NEUT. We used ling <strong>and</strong> non-ling primes to see if effects go<br />

beyond ling input.<br />

CLICKS<br />

Off-line clicks show a strong obj preference in all conditions.<br />

EYE-MOVEMENTS/TARGETS<br />

Ling <strong>and</strong> non-ling RESEMB primes resulted in an early <strong>and</strong> persistent obj preference (p's


Is a whisker some one who whisks Tests of route-emphasis in<br />

morphological processing<br />

P100<br />

Mat<strong>the</strong>w H. Davis 1 , Ca<strong>the</strong>rine-Marie Longtin 1 , & Kathleen Rastle 2<br />

1 MRC Cognition <strong>and</strong> <strong>Brain</strong> Sciences Unit, Cambridge, UK, 2 Royal Holloway <strong>University</strong> of London, UK<br />

E-mail: matt.davis@mrc-cbu.cam.ac.uk<br />

Word recognition can be characterised by two systems: (1) a lexicon that stores whole words <strong>and</strong> (2)<br />

sub-lexical processes that combine smaller units. During reading aloud <strong>the</strong>se can be dissociated since<br />

test settings that emphasize lexical processing makes <strong>for</strong> slower reading of pseudowords like jult,<br />

whereas emphasizing sub-lexical processing leads participants to read pint so it rhymes with hint<br />

(Zevin & Balota, 2000). In <strong>the</strong> present study, we tested whe<strong>the</strong>r analogous lexical <strong>and</strong> sub-lexical<br />

processes can be dissociated in accessing <strong>the</strong> meaning of morphologically-complex words.<br />

We conducted a series of behavioural experiments in which participants make speeded responses to<br />

visually-presented, complex words that are: (1) semantically-opaque e.g. corner, (2) semanticallytransparent<br />

e.g. darkness, or (3) interpretable pseudowords e.g. quickify which can be understood but<br />

are not attested in corpora. Items in <strong>the</strong>se three categories were presented in blocks to emphasize<br />

whole-word recognition (by including a majority of opaque items) or morphemic combination<br />

processes (including a large proportion of pseudowords). Blocking of opaque items should enhance<br />

whole word processing <strong>and</strong> suppress morphemic combination since a corner is not someone who<br />

corns. Conversely, blocks of pseudowords like quickify should enhance morphemic combination <strong>and</strong><br />

suppress whole-word recognition since participants lack pre-existing word representations <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong>se<br />

items. We used a variety of speeded tasks (sensicality judgement, lexical decision <strong>and</strong> semantic<br />

relatedness judgment) to assess changes in processing strategies due to blocked presentation of <strong>the</strong>se<br />

groups of items.<br />

Across four experiments we failed to see differences in <strong>the</strong> speed or accuracy of word recognition <strong>and</strong><br />

semantic access under conditions in which whole-word or morpheme-based processes should be<br />

emphasised. These results suggest that lexical <strong>and</strong> sub-lexical processing of complex words are not<br />

functionally separate processes under <strong>the</strong> strategic control of participants. Such results challenge<br />

conventional dual-route accounts of morphological processing in which whole-word <strong>and</strong><br />

decompositional processing are distinct <strong>and</strong> independent mechanisms <strong>and</strong> favour distributed<br />

connectionist models in which whole word <strong>and</strong> morphemic processes arise from <strong>the</strong> operation of a<br />

single, unified system.<br />

References<br />

Zevin, J.D. & Balota, D.A. (2000) Priming <strong>and</strong> attentional control of lexical <strong>and</strong> sublexical processes<br />

during naming. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory <strong>and</strong> Cognition, 26, 121-<br />

135.<br />

Notes<br />

153


P101<br />

Neurocomputational <strong>and</strong> neurophysiological investigations of brain<br />

interactions of language <strong>and</strong> attention<br />

Max Garagnani 1 , Yury Shtyrov 1 , Teija Kujala 2 , Thomas Wennekers 3 ,<br />

& Friedemann Pulvermüller 1<br />

1 MRC Cognition <strong>and</strong> <strong>Brain</strong> Sciences Unit, Cambridge, UK, 2 <strong>University</strong> of Helsinki, Finl<strong>and</strong>,<br />

3 <strong>University</strong> of Plymouth, UK<br />

E-mail: Max.Garagnani@mrc-cbu.cam.ac.uk<br />

Recent EEG/MEG studies revealed that brain responses to <strong>the</strong> same speech sounds differ if <strong>the</strong><br />

stimuli are presented in different task contexts. When subjects are not paying attention to <strong>the</strong> auditory<br />

input, <strong>the</strong>ir mismatch negativity (MMN) brain response is greater <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> words than <strong>for</strong> matched<br />

meaningless pseudowords. In contrast, greater late N400 responses to pseudowords than to words<br />

emerge in tasks where subjects have to attend to <strong>the</strong> language stimuli. Current cognitive or neural<br />

models are unable to explain <strong>the</strong>se data using a single, unifying account. We investigated <strong>the</strong> neural<br />

mechanisms underlying <strong>the</strong>se opposite effects through neurocomputational <strong>and</strong> neurophysiological<br />

studies.<br />

Firstly, we built a neuroanatomically-grounded neural network model of <strong>the</strong> left perisylvian cortex,<br />

<strong>and</strong> used it to simulate early word acquisition processes by means of synaptic-weight adaptation<br />

based on a neurobiologically-realistic (Hebbian) learning rule. The trained networks were able to<br />

replicate both <strong>the</strong> MMN <strong>and</strong> N400 brain responses. In particular, variation of one of <strong>the</strong> model’s<br />

parameters (<strong>the</strong> area-specific inhibition, mediating <strong>the</strong> strength of competition between coactive<br />

representations) differently modulated <strong>the</strong> network response to words <strong>and</strong> pseudowords: strong<br />

inhibition (simulating passive, inattentive listening) produced larger responses to words than to<br />

pseudowords, whereas weak inhibition (simulating attentive conditions) produced <strong>the</strong> opposite result.<br />

Thus, <strong>the</strong> model explains <strong>the</strong> divergence between MMN <strong>and</strong> N400 results, providing a first unifying<br />

account, at <strong>the</strong> cortical-circuit level, of <strong>the</strong>se data. In addition, it makes strong predictions on how<br />

attention processes modulate event-related brain responses to speech stimuli.<br />

Secondly, in order to experimentally test <strong>the</strong> validity of this model, we recorded neurophysiological<br />

responses to words <strong>and</strong> pseudowords when <strong>the</strong> subjects were asked to attend to <strong>the</strong> spoken input or<br />

ignore it. The brain responses (peaking at around 120-140ms after critical stimulus onset) were<br />

significantly larger to pseudowords than to words when subjects were attending to <strong>the</strong> stimuli; <strong>the</strong><br />

opposite pattern (words ≥ pseudowords) emerged (within <strong>the</strong> same time window) in <strong>the</strong> ignore<br />

condition. In addition, words responses were not significantly modulated by attention, indicating a<br />

robust activation of word-specific memory traces. These data confirm <strong>the</strong> predictions of <strong>the</strong> model<br />

<strong>and</strong> provide fur<strong>the</strong>r evidence supporting earlier suggestions that initial stages of lexical processing are<br />

not affected by attentional dem<strong>and</strong>s <strong>and</strong> may thus be automatic.<br />

Notes<br />

154


P102<br />

On <strong>the</strong> flexibility of advance planning during sentence production: Effects<br />

of task dem<strong>and</strong>s on multiple lexical access<br />

Valentin Wagner, & Jörg D. Jescheniak<br />

<strong>University</strong> of Leipzig, Germany<br />

E-mail: vwagner@uni-leipzig.de<br />

There is some discussion in <strong>the</strong> area of sentence production whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> scope of advance planning<br />

during grammatical encoding <strong>and</strong> lexical access is of phrasal or of clausal size, <strong>and</strong> corresponding<br />

studies have yielded conflicting results. In a series of picture-word interference experiments we tested<br />

<strong>the</strong> hypo<strong>the</strong>sis that this scope of advance planning is flexible, depending on <strong>the</strong> cognitive load<br />

currently imposed on <strong>the</strong> system. When participants produced simple sentences of <strong>the</strong> <strong>for</strong>m “<strong>the</strong> frog<br />

is next to <strong>the</strong> mug” in response to two-object displays, both nouns were found to be lexicalsemantically<br />

activated to similar degrees at speech onset, as indexed by similarly sized interference<br />

effects from semantic distractors related to ei<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> first or <strong>the</strong> second noun, in line with <strong>the</strong> clausal<br />

view (<strong>and</strong> replicating Meyer, 1996). When task dem<strong>and</strong>s were enhanced, by introducing an additional<br />

conceptual decision task <strong>and</strong> variable utterance <strong>for</strong>mats (with / without color adjective), <strong>the</strong><br />

interference effect <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> noun in position 2 was strongly attenuated <strong>and</strong> eventually disappeared, in<br />

line with a phrasal view. Interestingly, if task dem<strong>and</strong>s were increased by introducing a secondary<br />

working memory task to be per<strong>for</strong>med during speech planning, <strong>the</strong> relative interference pattern <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

first <strong>and</strong> second noun remained unchanged, suggesting that cognitive load induced by processes<br />

outside <strong>the</strong> speech planning process proper has a different effect as cognitive load related to some<br />

composite subprocess of <strong>the</strong> speech planning process. In all, <strong>the</strong> data suggest that <strong>the</strong> scope of<br />

advance planning during grammatical encoding in sentence production is flexible, ra<strong>the</strong>r than<br />

structurally fixed.<br />

Notes<br />

155


P103<br />

How do you find it: An analysis of speech production in <strong>the</strong> context of a<br />

deteriorating semantic system<br />

Lotte Meteyard, & Karalyn Patterson<br />

MRC Cognition <strong>and</strong> <strong>Brain</strong> Sciences Unit, Cambridge, UK<br />

E-mail: meteyard@gmail.com<br />

Naturally occuring speech errors have a long history in research into language production (e.g.<br />

Garrett, 1980), <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> errors produced by populations with particular deficits has proven a fruitful<br />

way to explore <strong>the</strong> architecture of <strong>the</strong> language production system (e.g. Rapp & Goldrick, 2000).<br />

Here we present an analysis of errors that occurred in <strong>the</strong> connected speech (taken from<br />

autobiographical interviews) of 8 patients with Semantic Dementia, a progressive neurological<br />

condition characterised by a fairly selective deterioration of semantic in<strong>for</strong>mation across all<br />

modalities, both verbal <strong>and</strong> non-verbal (Hodges & Patterson, 2007). The errors are compared to those<br />

found in similar interviews with 8 controls, allowing <strong>the</strong> abnormal error patterns to be defined against<br />

a baseline.<br />

Patients show more omissions of closed class items, as well as more semantically related substitution<br />

errors of open class words, <strong>and</strong> related substitution errors of closed class words (i.e. preposition <strong>for</strong><br />

preposition, pronoun <strong>for</strong> pronoun etc.). Patients also substitute more inappropriate complex<br />

morphological <strong>for</strong>ms than controls (e.g. 'cried' <strong>for</strong> 'cry' <strong>and</strong> 'closely' <strong>for</strong> 'close'). An analysis of<br />

sentence level errors shows that patients have problems in initiating <strong>and</strong> maintaining sentence level<br />

structures, with misordering of items, simplification of event descriptions, unreferenced pronouns,<br />

<strong>and</strong> semantically <strong>and</strong> syntactically anomolous utterances. Phonological errors, exchange errors <strong>and</strong><br />

morpheme str<strong>and</strong>ing errors are notably rare in <strong>the</strong> corpus.<br />

Whilst some of <strong>the</strong> errors can be attributed to <strong>the</strong> expected problems patients have in<br />

retrieving/selecting <strong>the</strong> intended item (anomia), <strong>the</strong> errors also demonstrate <strong>the</strong> necessary role that <strong>the</strong><br />

semantic system plays in supporting an intermediate stage in which both open <strong>and</strong> closed class words<br />

are retrieved <strong>and</strong> organised into <strong>the</strong> correct heirarchical strucutres (syntactic planning) be<strong>for</strong>e<br />

phonological in<strong>for</strong>mation is retrieved <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> utterance is serialised <strong>for</strong> production. Semantic<br />

Dementia thus provides a unique window onto <strong>the</strong> early stages of production.<br />

References<br />

Garrett, M.F. (1980) Levels of processing in sentence production. In B. Butterworth (Ed.) <strong>Language</strong><br />

production (Vo1. 1): <strong>Speech</strong> <strong>and</strong> talk (pp. 177-220). New York: Academic Press.<br />

Hodges, J.R. & Patterson, K. (2007) Semantic dementia: a unique clinicopathological syndrome.<br />

Lancet Neurology, 6, 1004-14<br />

Rapp, B. & Goldrick, M. (2000) Discreteness <strong>and</strong> interactivity in spoken word production.<br />

Psychological Review, 107, 460-99.<br />

Notes<br />

156


Spatial meaning congruity effect with abstract <strong>and</strong> concrete words<br />

P104<br />

Michele Burigo, & Maria Luisa Lorusso<br />

IRCSS. “E. Medea”, Bosisio Parini, Italy<br />

E-mail: michele.burigo@bp.lnf.it<br />

There is a growing body of evidence showing that people process abstract concepts through<br />

conceptual metaphors (Lakoff, 1993; Boroditsky, 2001). Most of <strong>the</strong>se are grounded on embodied<br />

experience derived from sensorimotor activity, <strong>and</strong> are used as a substrate to represent abstract<br />

concepts. Casasanto & Lozano (2007) have recently shown that abstract concepts with a spatial<br />

denotation such as temperature, grades, price, etc., showed a motor-meaning congruity effect that<br />

influences <strong>the</strong> gestures related to <strong>the</strong> concept. Similar interactions were found between <strong>the</strong><br />

horizontal/vertical nature of verb-related image schemas <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> position of visual stimuli, providing<br />

support <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> perceptual-motor character of abstract concept representation (Richardson, Spivey,<br />

Barsalou, McRae, 2003). The current study explores whe<strong>the</strong>r abstract entities that have no spatial<br />

instantiation in <strong>the</strong> world, but which are associated with vertical spatial metaphors (e.g., angry, hero,<br />

surprise, offence, etc.), convey in<strong>for</strong>mation about <strong>the</strong> embodied knowledge independently of motor<br />

activity. A semantic priming experiment showed a word as a prime <strong>and</strong> a black arrow as target. The<br />

prime was a concrete/abstract word with a covert directional denotation: up (i.e., hero, eagle) down<br />

(i.e., sadness, chute) or neutral (i.e., nature, dust). Participants were instructed to judge whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong><br />

arrow was pointing up or down as quick as possible. It was expected that congruent trials, i.e. trials<br />

where <strong>the</strong> direction of <strong>the</strong> prime matches <strong>the</strong> direction of <strong>the</strong> arrow, would be processed faster than<br />

incongruent trials (trials showing a word with a direction neutral or opposite to <strong>the</strong> target). More<br />

important, this experiment aims to test <strong>the</strong> hypo<strong>the</strong>sis that abstract concepts are mediated by<br />

embodied knowledge, similarly to concrete concepts. The results show that only concrete words<br />

generated a significant priming effect (spatial meaning congruity effect), suggesting that <strong>the</strong><br />

directional in<strong>for</strong>mation contained in <strong>the</strong> abstract words cannot be acquired only through embodied<br />

experience (Gibbs, 2006).<br />

Notes<br />

157


P105<br />

Event-related spectral changes associated with morphosyntactic processing<br />

Douglas J. Davidson<br />

Max Planck Institute <strong>for</strong> Psycholinguistics & F.C. Donders <strong>Centre</strong> <strong>for</strong> Cognitive Neuroimaging,<br />

Radboud <strong>University</strong> Nijmegen, The Ne<strong>the</strong>rl<strong>and</strong>s<br />

E-mail: D.Davidson@fcdonders.ru.nl<br />

The recognition of morphosyntactic features during sentence processing has been linked to a left<br />

anterior negative (LAN) effect using electrophysiology. This LAN effect has been explained in terms<br />

of ei<strong>the</strong>r a violation-detection or a working-memory related process [1].<br />

In addition to ERP effects like <strong>the</strong> LAN, EEG can also be analyzed to measure event-related changes<br />

in spectral power using time-frequency analysis. Working memory tasks have been associated with<br />

<strong>the</strong>ta b<strong>and</strong> (4-7 Hz) amplitude changes using this type of measure.<br />

Previous work has shown that both <strong>the</strong>ta <strong>and</strong> alpha (8-13 Hz) b<strong>and</strong> amplitude changes can be<br />

observed in sentence processing under <strong>the</strong> same conditions that lead to an N400 effect during<br />

semantic integration, or a P600 effect during <strong>the</strong> reanalysis or revision of a grammatical violation.<br />

However, event-related power changes have not been reported is association with <strong>the</strong> LAN effect, so<br />

it is not clear which frequency b<strong>and</strong> will be responsive.<br />

If <strong>the</strong> LAN effect is linked to working memory processes, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong>re should be some relationship<br />

between <strong>the</strong> magnitude of <strong>the</strong> LAN ERP effect <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> magnitude of <strong>the</strong>ta-b<strong>and</strong> power on individual<br />

trials. If <strong>the</strong>re is no association, this would weaken <strong>the</strong> hypo<strong>the</strong>sis that <strong>the</strong> LAN effect is linked to<br />

general working memory.<br />

In <strong>the</strong> present study, a violation-control paradigm involving German declension was used to<br />

investigate this issue. Native German speakers (n=20) read short prepositional phrases (1) presented<br />

serially as text <strong>and</strong> classified <strong>the</strong>m as grammatically correct or not.<br />

(1) ohne das kleine/*kleines Kind<br />

without <strong>the</strong> small child<br />

The critical adjective within <strong>the</strong> phrase was ei<strong>the</strong>r correctly inflected <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> case <strong>and</strong> gender<br />

constraints within <strong>the</strong> phrase, or it was incorrectly inflected <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> strong declension.<br />

The violations were associated with a larger negative potential 300 to 500 ms after <strong>the</strong> onset of <strong>the</strong><br />

adjective over left frontal electrodes, consistent with a LAN effect. A wavelet analysis indicated<br />

greater amplitude power to <strong>the</strong> violations compared to <strong>the</strong> controls at a wavelet scale within <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ta<br />

b<strong>and</strong>. A quartile analysis showed that <strong>the</strong>ta b<strong>and</strong> power variability in single trials was not associated<br />

with <strong>the</strong> magnitude of <strong>the</strong> LAN effect. These results suggest that <strong>the</strong> LAN effect is not intrinsically<br />

linked to working memory mechanisms.<br />

References<br />

1 Kutas, M., Van Petten, C. K. & Kluender, R. (2006). Psycholinguistics electrified II (1994-2005).<br />

M.A. Gernsbacher & M. Traxler (Eds.) H<strong>and</strong>book of Psycholinguistics, 2nd edition. New York:<br />

Elsevier.<br />

Notes<br />

158


P106<br />

<strong>Language</strong> control in bilingual speech production: A blocked naming study<br />

Kristof Strijkers, & Albert M. Costa<br />

Universidad de Barcelona, Spain<br />

E-mail: Kristof_Strijkers@hotmail.com<br />

An important question in bilingualism is how bilingual speakers are able to control <strong>for</strong> intrusions<br />

from one language while speaking in <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r language. In <strong>the</strong> this study we investigated how<br />

bilinguals are able to control <strong>the</strong>ir language production by looking at <strong>the</strong> impact of naming a picture<br />

in one language which previously (previous block) has been named in <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r language. In<br />

experiment 1 22 high-proficient Spanish-Catalan bilinguals first named pictures in <strong>the</strong>ir L1 <strong>and</strong><br />

afterwards named pictures in <strong>the</strong>ir L2 (blocked naming). Crucially when participants changed to<br />

blocked naming in L2, half of <strong>the</strong> pictures were <strong>the</strong> same <strong>and</strong> half of <strong>the</strong> pictures were different <strong>the</strong>n<br />

<strong>the</strong> blocked naming part in L1. In experiment 2 22 high-proficient Spanish-Catalan bilinguals<br />

per<strong>for</strong>med <strong>the</strong> same experiment as in experiment 1, but started with naming in L2. In both<br />

experiments an interaction between old-new (previously named picture or not) <strong>and</strong> cognate status was<br />

found: For non-cognates old pictures were named slower than new ones. For cognates <strong>the</strong> opposite<br />

result was found: New pictures were named slower than old ones. Results are discussed in function of<br />

<strong>the</strong> distinct bilingual production models.<br />

Notes<br />

159


P107<br />

The origin of pausing <strong>and</strong> speech rate in second language speech<br />

production<br />

Nivja H. De Jong, Rob Schoonen, & Jan H. Hulstijn<br />

<strong>University</strong> of Amsterdam, The Ne<strong>the</strong>rl<strong>and</strong>s<br />

E-mail: n.h.dejong@uva.nl<br />

In this study, we investigated <strong>the</strong> origin of fluency in terms of pausing <strong>and</strong> speech rate <strong>for</strong> second<br />

language speech compared to first language speech. Based on previous research (e.g., DeWaele &<br />

Furnham, 2000), we expect that <strong>the</strong> personality characteristic Extraversion will predict L2 fluency.<br />

Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, we predict that individual differences in fluency may originate from individual<br />

differences in ease of processing in <strong>the</strong> conceptualizer, <strong>for</strong>mulator <strong>and</strong>/or articulator (e.g., Levelt,<br />

1989). If we assume that conceptualizing a message is preverbal, we may also expect that some of <strong>the</strong><br />

characteristics of L1 fluency will transfer to L2 fluency.<br />

In Experiment 1, we investigated <strong>the</strong> relationship between fluency <strong>and</strong> ease of processing in <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong>for</strong>mulator (<strong>and</strong> articulator). Non-native speakers (n = 195) <strong>and</strong> native speakers (n = 50) of Dutch<br />

per<strong>for</strong>med 8 speaking tasks <strong>and</strong> we computed measures <strong>for</strong> pausing <strong>and</strong> speech rate. Participants also<br />

per<strong>for</strong>med language knowledge (vocabulary <strong>and</strong> grammar) <strong>and</strong> language processing (lexical retrieval,<br />

articulatory speed, sentence production) tasks, tapping processes in <strong>the</strong> <strong>for</strong>mulator (<strong>and</strong> articulator).<br />

Also, participants filled out <strong>the</strong> Eysenck’s personality questionnaire. Regression analyses revealed<br />

that (1) pausing <strong>and</strong> speech rate are predicted differently by <strong>the</strong> linguistic variables <strong>and</strong> Extraversion<br />

<strong>and</strong> that (2) <strong>the</strong>se predictions differ qualitatively between L1 <strong>and</strong> L2 speakers.<br />

In Experiment 2, we fur<strong>the</strong>r investigated <strong>the</strong> relation between L1 <strong>and</strong> L2 fluency, i.e., whe<strong>the</strong>r<br />

individual differences in L2 fluency can be predicted by individual differences in L1 fluency. Fortyfive<br />

Turkish <strong>and</strong> English speakers who per<strong>for</strong>med <strong>the</strong> 8 speaking tasks in <strong>the</strong>ir L2 (Dutch) came back<br />

to our lab to per<strong>for</strong>m 8 similar speaking tasks in <strong>the</strong>ir L1 (i.e., in Turkish or English). Regression<br />

analyses revealed that pausing in L2 speech is related to pausing in L1 speech, which may reflect<br />

individual differences in ease of processing in <strong>the</strong> preverbal conceptualizer.<br />

The results show that L2 fluency is a result of individual linguistic knowledge <strong>and</strong> skills of <strong>the</strong> second<br />

language toge<strong>the</strong>r with individual characteristics in speech that are transferred from first-language to<br />

second-language speech. We will discuss implications of <strong>the</strong>se results with respect to <strong>the</strong>ories of<br />

speech production.<br />

References<br />

Dewaele, J.-M., & Furnham, A. (2000). Personality <strong>and</strong> speech production: a pilot study of second<br />

language learners. Personality <strong>and</strong> individual differences, 28(2), 355 - 365.<br />

Levelt, W. J. M. (1989). Speaking: from intention to articulation. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.<br />

Notes<br />

160


Evidence <strong>for</strong> priming on <strong>the</strong> level of referential dependencies<br />

P108<br />

Elsi Kaiser<br />

<strong>University</strong> of Sou<strong>the</strong>rn Cali<strong>for</strong>nia, USA<br />

E-mail: emkaiser@usc.edu<br />

Priming is a valuable tool <strong>for</strong> investigating abstract representations in syntactic processing. We report<br />

3 experiments that test <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> existence of priming in ano<strong>the</strong>r domain, pronoun interpretation, to see<br />

whe<strong>the</strong>r priming can shed light on <strong>the</strong> representations used in processing referential dependencies.<br />

Exp1: 24 Ss saw sentences on a computer screen. In PRIMES, gender <strong>for</strong>ced a subj (1a) or obj<br />

interpretation (1b) of <strong>the</strong> pronoun. Neutral primes ended in intransitives (1c). Interpretation of<br />

ambiguous obj pronouns in TARGETS (2) was probed by questions. (Questions followed all<br />

targets/primes/fillers.) Nonce verbs eliminated verb effects.<br />

1 William swooked Betty <strong>and</strong> Kevin…<br />

a) brucked him. [S]<br />

b) brucked her. [O]<br />

c) brucked. [N]<br />

2 Stephen tulvered Peter <strong>and</strong> Diane churbited him. [QUEST: Diane churbited _ ]<br />

An obj-preference is expected due to parallelism. If REFERENTIAL PRIMING exists, <strong>the</strong> objpreference<br />

is predicted to be WEAKER after S primes than O primes. If only SYNTACTIC<br />

PRIMING is at play, no difference is predicted (S <strong>and</strong> O primes have <strong>the</strong> same syntactic structure).<br />

Primes had an effect: There were roughly twice as many subj-responses after S primes as after O or N<br />

primes (p's2000ms).<br />

Exp2 used two cues (GENDER+CONNECTIVES) to prime subj (3a) or obj (3b) (see Wolf etal04).<br />

Neutrals were included (3c). Targets <strong>and</strong> method were <strong>the</strong> same as Exp1, 24 new participants.<br />

3 William swooked Betty <strong>and</strong>…<br />

a) AS A RESULT Kevin brucked him. [S]<br />

b) SIMILARLY Kevin brucked her. [O]<br />

c) Kevin brucked. [N]<br />

Primes had a weaker effect on subj-response rate in Exp2 than Exp1–but RTs were influenced by<br />

primes: Subj-responses were drastically faster after S primes (~800ms) than O primes (>1200ms), inbetween<br />

after N.<br />

If <strong>the</strong>se effects are due to activation of abstract referential dependency representations, <strong>the</strong>y are<br />

predicted to be general, not specific to obj pronouns. Exp3 tested pronouns in SUBJ position, with<br />

gender priming subj or obj (ex4). Subj-responses were faster (p


P109<br />

Morphological decomposition <strong>and</strong> selection of word meaning<br />

Nina Kazanina<br />

<strong>University</strong> of Bristol, UK<br />

E-mail: nina.kazanina@bristol.ac.uk<br />

At an early stage of processing morphologically complex words are decomposed into morphemes,<br />

e.g. teacher is split into teach + -er (Longtin et al. 2003; Rastle et al., 2004). Decomposition also<br />

affects <strong>for</strong>ms that only seemingly are polymorphemic such as bro<strong>the</strong>r (≠ broth + -er, yet is<br />

decomposed into <strong>the</strong>se morphemes). The question is what this ‘spurious’ decomposition of pseudo<br />

morphologically-complex words entails <strong>for</strong> a later stage of lexical processing at which <strong>the</strong> meaning of<br />

<strong>the</strong> word bro<strong>the</strong>r is accessed.<br />

This issue was examined using a visual-visual masked-priming task in Russian with three conditions:<br />

- morpho-semantically related condition: <strong>the</strong> target was derived from <strong>the</strong> prime via prefixation<br />

(e.g., beg ‘running’ – zabeg ‘race’, zabeg = prefix za- + beg);<br />

- pseudo-morphologically related condition: <strong>the</strong> target <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> prime seemed to be<br />

morphologically related via prefixation but in fact were not (pas ‘pass’ – zapas ‘supply’,<br />

zapas ≠ prefix za- + pas)<br />

- orthographically-related condition: <strong>the</strong> prime again was contained inside <strong>the</strong> target but could<br />

not possibly be related to it morphologically (bar ‘bar’ – ambar ‘grain storage’; am is not a<br />

prefix in Russian).<br />

Each target was also paired with an unrelated prime that matched <strong>the</strong> related prime in length <strong>and</strong><br />

frequency. 42 Russian speakers per<strong>for</strong>med a lexical decision task to <strong>the</strong> target (<strong>the</strong> prime was 48 ms<br />

long <strong>and</strong> not consciously perceivable). For each condition we calculated an effect of <strong>the</strong> related prime<br />

on target processing relative to <strong>the</strong> unrelated prime.<br />

We found no effect of <strong>the</strong> related prime in <strong>the</strong> orthographically related condition. A highly<br />

statistically robust facilitation was found in <strong>the</strong> morpho-semantically related conditions (28 ms). In<br />

<strong>the</strong> pseudo morphologically-related condition a significant facilitatory effect of 18 ms was found.<br />

These results suggest that <strong>the</strong> output of early morphological decompositional affect a later stage of<br />

processing at which <strong>the</strong> word meaning is determined (even in cases where <strong>the</strong> output morphemes are<br />

not semantically related to <strong>the</strong> whole word). The results are most readily compatible with a singleroute<br />

decomposition model whereby real <strong>and</strong> pseudo morphologically-complex words alike are<br />

represented in <strong>the</strong> lexicon as morpheme combinations (<strong>the</strong>y differ in whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> meaning is<br />

compositionally derivable from constituent morphemes or stored idiosyncratically). We also discuss<br />

repercussions of our findings <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> process of meaning selection in dual route models where <strong>the</strong><br />

parser follows a decompositional <strong>and</strong> a whole-word route in parallel.<br />

Notes<br />

162


P110<br />

The activation of multiple phonological codes during <strong>the</strong> naming of an<br />

object in context<br />

Frank Oppermann 1 , Frauke Görges 1 , Jörg D. Jescheniak 1 , & Herbert Schriefers 2<br />

1 <strong>University</strong> of Leipzig, Germany, 2 Radboud <strong>University</strong> Nijmegen, The Ne<strong>the</strong>rl<strong>and</strong>s<br />

E-mail: oppermann@uni-leipzig.de<br />

Recent studies explored whe<strong>the</strong>r visually presented context objects are phonologically activated when<br />

participants name a target object. While some studies presented evidence in favour of such a view,<br />

o<strong>the</strong>r studies failed to do so. But which factors affect <strong>the</strong> lexical activation of context objects In two<br />

picture-word interference experiments <strong>the</strong> authors demonstrate that a semantic-categorical relation<br />

between a target object <strong>and</strong> a context object (e.g., target: flute, context object: harp) promotes <strong>the</strong><br />

phonological activation of <strong>the</strong> to-be-ignored context object (as indexed by interference from a<br />

distractor phonologically related to <strong>the</strong> context object, e.g., heart). No such activation is observed if<br />

<strong>the</strong> objects are semantically unrelated. In contrast to recent picture-picture interference experiments,<br />

<strong>the</strong> results provide direct evidence that <strong>the</strong> amount of phonological activation, which a context object<br />

receives, is dependent on its semantic processing. At a more general level, this observation fur<strong>the</strong>r<br />

supports <strong>the</strong> notion that <strong>the</strong> possibility to establish a coherent representation among multiple objects<br />

affects <strong>the</strong> in<strong>for</strong>mation flow in <strong>the</strong> conceptual-lexical system during speech planning (cf., Oppermann<br />

et al., 2008).<br />

Notes<br />

163


P111<br />

Modality vs. typology effects: Investigating <strong>the</strong> divide<br />

Pamela Perniss 1 , David P. Vinson 1 , Gabriella Vigliocco 1 , & Frank Seifart 2<br />

1 DCAL, <strong>University</strong> College London, UK, 2 <strong>University</strong> of Regensburg, Germany<br />

E-mail: p.perniss@ucl.ac.uk<br />

There is evidence that <strong>the</strong> difference in language modality between signed <strong>and</strong> spoken languages<br />

leads to differences in language processing, especially related to <strong>the</strong> involvement of imagery <strong>and</strong><br />

visuospatial cognition (e.g. Vigliocco et al. 2005). These differences are attributed to <strong>the</strong> differential<br />

treatment of spatial semantic domains across language modalities, under <strong>the</strong> assumption that <strong>the</strong><br />

modality of signed, but not spoken, languages af<strong>for</strong>ds <strong>and</strong> even requires <strong>the</strong> encoding of spatial<br />

in<strong>for</strong>mation about referents. Although this assumption may be true <strong>for</strong> English (where most research<br />

on this topic has been conducted), some spoken languages do systematically encode spatial<br />

in<strong>for</strong>mation about referents. For example, in Bora, a Witotoan language spoken in parts of Columbia<br />

<strong>and</strong> Peru (cf. Seifart 2005), visuospatial properties of size <strong>and</strong> dimension are obligatorily marked on<br />

nominal <strong>and</strong> pronominal <strong>for</strong>ms to encode meanings like flat/square <strong>and</strong> long/thin. These distinctions<br />

are comparable to those typically reflected in h<strong>and</strong>shape in sign languages like British Sign <strong>Language</strong><br />

(BSL) (e.g. a flat h<strong>and</strong> used to represent a table). This suggests that spoken languages that encode<br />

visuospatial dimensions (like Bora) may be more similar to signed languages (like BSL) than to<br />

spoken languages (like English) despite <strong>the</strong> modality difference. We investigate this question by<br />

means of a meaning similarity judgment task. Speakers of Bora <strong>and</strong> English listened to triads of<br />

words (in <strong>the</strong>ir own language) <strong>and</strong> were asked to decide which two words were most similar to each<br />

o<strong>the</strong>r in meaning. Triads were created such that only one of <strong>the</strong> three possible word pairs shared<br />

spatial properties. Bora speakers picked <strong>the</strong> word pair that preserved spatial in<strong>for</strong>mation significantly<br />

more often than English speakers (t(32)=2.24, p


Syllables are chunks in M<strong>and</strong>arin, not in Spanish or English<br />

P112<br />

Padraig G. O’Seaghdha 1 , Julio Santiago 2 , Jenn-Yeu Chen 3 , Antonio Roman 2 ,<br />

& Jordan Knicely 1<br />

1 Lehigh <strong>University</strong>, USA, 2 <strong>University</strong> of Granada, Spain, 3 National Cheng Kung <strong>University</strong>, Taiwan<br />

E-mail: pat.oseaghdha@Lehigh.EDU<br />

Uncertainty still characterizes <strong>the</strong> role of syllables in language production within <strong>and</strong> across<br />

languages. We examined <strong>the</strong> hypo<strong>the</strong>ses that syllables channel phonological encoding in European<br />

languages, perhaps more strongly in Romance than in Germanic languages, <strong>and</strong> that syllables are<br />

<strong>the</strong>mselves primary encoding units in Chinese. We report parallel disyllable word-pair recitation<br />

experiments in three languages using variants of a classic design in which first syllable alignment is<br />

crossed with phonological overlap (e.g., aligned CVC: ham.let ham.per; unaligned CV ma.lice<br />

mag.net). We coded number of correct word pair productions in a fixed interval (output) as well as<br />

errors. We examined three issues:<br />

1. No overlap conditions: Are speakers sensitive to syllable structure In English, only<br />

number of segments regardless of structural congruence affected output, contrary to <strong>the</strong> well<br />

known syllable congruence result of Sevald, Dell & Cole (1995). In Spanish, we found an<br />

unexpected reverse preference <strong>for</strong> structural alternation (different first syllables better than<br />

same first syllables). In M<strong>and</strong>arin, speakers were oblivious to syllable internal structure.<br />

2. Aligned overlap: Does sharing a first syllable have an overall cost Yes, <strong>the</strong>re was a<br />

“tongue twister” cost in output <strong>for</strong> all three languages. However, given 1) <strong>and</strong> 3), <strong>the</strong> effect is<br />

clearly mediated by syllable units only in M<strong>and</strong>arin.<br />

3. Unaligned overlap: Is difficulty modulated when first syllables share segments but are<br />

not aligned Surprisingly, alignment did not matter in English or Spanish, <strong>and</strong> in M<strong>and</strong>arin,<br />

<strong>the</strong> difficulty of production was greater with misaligned (e.g., sha.jun shan.zhuang) than<br />

aligned syllables, despite <strong>the</strong> absence of a structural effect in 1).<br />

Our findings provisionally speak against <strong>the</strong> hypo<strong>the</strong>sis that syllable structure guides word encoding<br />

in European languages. We will assess this conclusion in light of o<strong>the</strong>r evidence in <strong>the</strong> literature <strong>and</strong><br />

qualitative error analysis. For M<strong>and</strong>arin, we present an explicit model in which syllables are primary<br />

phonological encoding units. We explain <strong>the</strong> indifference to syllable internal structure in M<strong>and</strong>arin by<br />

<strong>the</strong> fact that syllables are whole units, <strong>the</strong> difficulty engendered by repeating first syllables as due to<br />

difficulty in selecting competing second syllable units, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> unexpected greater difficulty with<br />

unaligned overlap as due to competition between <strong>the</strong> first syllables <strong>the</strong>mselves. Selection of syllable<br />

tokens emerges as a key cross-linguistic difference between Chinese <strong>and</strong> Indo-European languages.<br />

Notes<br />

165


P113<br />

Simulating perceptual features during language comprehension<br />

Gerrit Hirschfeld, Christian Dobel & Pienie Zwitserlood<br />

<strong>University</strong> of Münster, Germany<br />

E-mail: gerrit.hirschfeld@uni-muenster.de<br />

The ultimate goal of language is to "shape events in each o<strong>the</strong>rs brains" (Pinker, 1994). The research<br />

reported here investigates what kind of in<strong>for</strong>mation <strong>the</strong>se events entail <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir neurobiological<br />

correlates.<br />

The N400 (Kutas & Hilyard, 1980) is often used as a tool to investigate (amodal) semantic<br />

representations in language processing. Recent <strong>the</strong>ories suggest a perceptual basis of <strong>the</strong>se<br />

representations (Barsalou, 1999). In line with this idea, recent ERP studies show earlier (< 200 ms)<br />

effects of language processing on perceptual processes (Hirschfeld, Jansma, Bölte, & Zwitserlood, in<br />

press). We report a behavioral <strong>and</strong> an MEG experiment investigating how specific <strong>the</strong>se effects are.<br />

Participants read/listened (behavioral experiment/MEG experiment) sentences <strong>and</strong> had to verify if a<br />

following picture depicted an object mentioned in <strong>the</strong> sentence or not. We used 84 pictures of 42<br />

different objects each photographed in two shapes (e.g. a flying duck vs. a sitting duck) as targets.<br />

Target pictures (e.g. <strong>the</strong> flying duck) appeared in three contexts; (1) a match sentence about a duck in<br />

<strong>the</strong> air, (2) a mismatch sentence about a swimming duck, <strong>and</strong> (3) an unrelated sentence without any<br />

ducks.<br />

Our behavioral study replicated previous results (Zwaan, Stanfield, & Yaxley, 2002), showing<br />

significantly faster reactions when <strong>the</strong> sentence matched <strong>the</strong> picture, as compared to <strong>the</strong> mismatch<br />

condition.<br />

As <strong>the</strong> MEG experiment is <strong>the</strong> first of its kind into this effect, our analysis targeted several ERF<br />

components related to object processing. Our analysis so far shows that both <strong>the</strong> unrelated <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

mismatch condition reliably differ from <strong>the</strong> match condition. ERFs differed in <strong>the</strong> st<strong>and</strong>ard N400 time<br />

window <strong>and</strong> at earlier latencies, indicating that not only post-lexical semantic integration is affected<br />

but also perceptual processes.<br />

Taken toge<strong>the</strong>r our results fur<strong>the</strong>r validate <strong>and</strong> detail models of how language is grounded in<br />

perceptual processes.<br />

References<br />

Barsalou, L. W. (1999). Perceptual symbol systems. BEHAVIOR BRAIN SCIENCES, 22, 577-660.<br />

Hirschfeld, G., Jansma, B., Boelte, J., & Zwitserlood, P. (in press). Interference <strong>and</strong> facilitation in<br />

overt speech production investigated with erps. NEUROREPORT.<br />

Kutas, M., & Hillyard, S. a. (1980). Reading senseless sentences - brain potentials reflect semantic<br />

incongruity. Science, 207(4427), 203-205.<br />

Pinker, S. (1994). The language instinct: How <strong>the</strong> mind creates language. NY: HarperCollins.<br />

Zwaan, R., Stanfield, R., & Yaxley, R. (2002). Do language comprehenders mentally represent <strong>the</strong><br />

shapes of objects PSYCHOLOGICAL SCIENCE<br />

Notes<br />

166


Integrating simulation <strong>and</strong> experiment: A study of Japanese second<br />

language acquistion<br />

P114<br />

Lu Gram, & Paula Buttery<br />

<strong>University</strong> of Cambridge, UK<br />

E-mail: pjb48@cam.ac.uk<br />

Previous work has used a connectionist approach to model <strong>the</strong> incidental learning of a Japanese-like<br />

language by native English speakers [1]. We show that a computationalist (symbol-manipulating)<br />

approach is also able to model this data. We represent <strong>the</strong> target language as a Combinatory<br />

Categorial Grammar which we analyse with a probabilistic shift-reduce parser [2]. This models <strong>the</strong><br />

per<strong>for</strong>mance of <strong>the</strong> participants. The original experiment considered grammaticality judgements from<br />

two groups. The first group per<strong>for</strong>med a semantic plausibility test on a set of sentances from <strong>the</strong><br />

target language prior to making grammaticality judgements. Whereas <strong>the</strong> second (control) group<br />

per<strong>for</strong>med <strong>the</strong> judgements without previous exposure. Our parser accounts <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> per<strong>for</strong>mance of<br />

both groups using <strong>the</strong> rules of function application, function composition <strong>and</strong> generalised weakpermutation.<br />

Imperfect learning (such as inattention to <strong>the</strong> input) is modelled by introducing r<strong>and</strong>om<br />

failure during acquisition <strong>and</strong> parsing. We provide a rationale <strong>for</strong> this modelling approach through a<br />

discussion of its benefits <strong>and</strong> its applicability to o<strong>the</strong>r data sets.<br />

References<br />

[1] Williams, N.; Kuribara, C., "Comparing a nativist <strong>and</strong> emergentist approach to <strong>the</strong> initial stage of<br />

SLA: An investigation of Japanese scrambling", LINGUA, 2007.<br />

[2] Briscoe, T.; Buttery. P., "Linguistic Adaptions <strong>for</strong> Resolving Ambiguity" in Smith, A. D. M.,<br />

Smith, K., & Ferrer i Cancho, R. (eds). The Evolution of <strong>Language</strong>: Proceedings of <strong>the</strong> 7th<br />

International Conference (EVOLANG7), Barcelona, 2008. Singapore: World Scientific Press.<br />

Notes<br />

167


P115<br />

The classifier-noun agreement in M<strong>and</strong>arin Chinese is both semantic <strong>and</strong><br />

syntactic: An event-related-potential (ERP) study<br />

Shu-Hua Tsai 1 , Chun-Chieh Hsu 1 , Chin-Lung Yang 2 , Jenn-Yeu Chen 1<br />

1 National Cheng Kung <strong>University</strong>, Taiwan, 2 <strong>University</strong> of Hong Kong<br />

E-mail: psyjyc@mail.ncku.edu.tw<br />

The semantic nature of <strong>the</strong> classifier-noun agreement in M<strong>and</strong>arin Chinese has been demonstrated in<br />

several linguistic <strong>and</strong> psycholinguistic studies (e.g., Tai & Wang, 1990; Chen & Wang, 2003). In <strong>the</strong><br />

present study, we re-examined <strong>the</strong> classifier-noun agreement with brain event-related potentials<br />

(ERPs) using a 128-channel EGI system. Experiment 1 used simple noun phrases. Chinese<br />

participants had to determine if a given classifier-noun pairing was adequate (e.g., a zhang chair vs. a<br />

zhi chair). They also judged, in a category task, whe<strong>the</strong>r a member <strong>and</strong> a category went toge<strong>the</strong>r (e.g.,<br />

furniture-chair vs. animal-chair), <strong>and</strong>, in a part-of-speech task, whe<strong>the</strong>r a modifier-noun pair (e.g.,<br />

new-chair or very-chair) was grammatical. A N400 component with a central focus was elicited in all<br />

three tasks. The magnitude of <strong>the</strong> effect was in <strong>the</strong> order of mention. No LAN or P600 component<br />

was elicited in ei<strong>the</strong>r task. Experiment 2 used complex noun phrases, in which an object-gapped<br />

relative clause was inserted between <strong>the</strong> classifier <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> head noun. The classifier ei<strong>the</strong>r (1)<br />

matched <strong>the</strong> long-distance head noun but not <strong>the</strong> adjacent noun in <strong>the</strong> relative clause (Match-<br />

LongDistance), or (2) matched nei<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> long-distance head noun nor <strong>the</strong> adjacent noun (Mismatch).<br />

In <strong>the</strong> third (3) condition, <strong>the</strong> subject noun in <strong>the</strong> relative clause included a matching classifier, which<br />

was not associated with <strong>the</strong> head noun (Match-ShortDistance). Each noun phrase was embedded in a<br />

sentence, which was presented one word at at time. Participants judged <strong>the</strong> grammaticality of <strong>the</strong><br />

sentence. The ERPs to <strong>the</strong> head noun were analyzed. A N4-P6 complex was elicited in <strong>the</strong> Mismatch<br />

condition relative to <strong>the</strong> Match-LongDistance <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Match-ShortDistance conditions, which elicited<br />

a P600 component <strong>and</strong> a N400 component, respectively. The results of <strong>the</strong> two experiments suggest<br />

that processing of <strong>the</strong> classifier-noun agreement is both semantic <strong>and</strong> syntactic, <strong>the</strong> latter being<br />

engaged later <strong>and</strong> only when long-distance dependency is involved.<br />

Examples from Experiment 2:<br />

(1) Match-LongDistance<br />

Yi-ke<br />

[ linju zhongzhi de ] guoshu…<br />

one-CL(tree) neighbor planted DE fruit-tree “a fruit-tree which <strong>the</strong> neighbor planted’<br />

(2) Mismatch<br />

Yi-duo [ linju zhongzhi de ] guoshu ...<br />

one-CL(flower) neighbor planted DE fruit-tree<br />

(3) Match-ShortDistance<br />

Yi-wei [ linju zhongzhi de ] guoshu ...<br />

one-CL(person) neighbor planted DE fruit-tree<br />

Notes<br />

168


P116<br />

Correctly used rule-governed morphemes elicit left anterior negativities<br />

Riadh Lebib, & Andrea Krott<br />

<strong>University</strong> of Birmingham, UK<br />

E-mail: r.lebib@bham.ac.uk<br />

The storage <strong>and</strong> processing of morphologically complex words in <strong>the</strong> mental lexicon is still a matter<br />

of controversial discussion in psycholinguistics. One important issue is whe<strong>the</strong>r morphologically<br />

complex words are processed via parsing or via retrieval from memory (parsing <strong>for</strong> regular <strong>for</strong>ms <strong>and</strong><br />

storage <strong>for</strong> irregular <strong>for</strong>ms), <strong>and</strong> whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>se processes are supported by a single or by a dual<br />

mechanism.<br />

In behavioural studies, effects of full-<strong>for</strong>m frequency on response times <strong>for</strong> both irregular <strong>and</strong> regular<br />

word<strong>for</strong>ms have been taken as evidence <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> storage of both irregular <strong>and</strong> regular word<strong>for</strong>ms <strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong>re<strong>for</strong>e <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> existence of a single processing mechanism. In contrast, findings of event-related<br />

brain potential (ERP) studies ra<strong>the</strong>r support dual-route models. Using violation paradigms, <strong>the</strong>y have<br />

demonstrated a left anterior negativity (LAN) response in a 300-700ms range when morpho-syntactic<br />

rules were misapplied to irregular stems (i.e. attaching a regular suffix), but not when regular stems<br />

were “irregularized” (i.e. attaching an irregular suffix). This effect argues <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> storage of irregular<br />

(but not regular) verb <strong>for</strong>ms as full-<strong>for</strong>ms.<br />

Yet ERP studies have mainly focused on low-frequency word<strong>for</strong>ms. Like irregular word<strong>for</strong>ms, which<br />

are believed to be stored irrespectively of <strong>the</strong>ir frequency, high-frequency regular word<strong>for</strong>ms are<br />

assumed to be also stored <strong>and</strong> might <strong>the</strong>re<strong>for</strong>e be processed like irregular word<strong>for</strong>ms.<br />

Using both behavioural <strong>and</strong> ERP techniques, <strong>the</strong> present study examined whe<strong>the</strong>r frequency interacts<br />

with regularity. Participants read German verb participles embedded in sentences. Correctness<br />

judgements on <strong>the</strong> verbs revealed only an effect of frequency, not regularity, with less frequent <strong>for</strong>ms<br />

being responded to slower <strong>and</strong> less accurately. Yet electrophysiological data were distinct <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> two<br />

verb categories, with correct regular verbs eliciting a LAN when compared to correct irregular verbs.<br />

While low frequency led to an N400 effect, it did not modulate <strong>the</strong> LAN.<br />

In contrast to <strong>the</strong> behavioural results, <strong>the</strong> ERP data suggest processing differences <strong>for</strong> regular <strong>and</strong><br />

irregular German participles. If high-frequency regular <strong>for</strong>ms are indeed stored, <strong>the</strong>ir storage does not<br />

affect <strong>the</strong> occurrence of a LAN. Moreover, LANs appear not only to be a cerebral index <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

misapplication of rules, but can also be elicited by <strong>the</strong> processing of correctly used rule-governed<br />

morphemes. More generally, <strong>the</strong>se results stress <strong>the</strong> importance of techniques that provide more<br />

detailed in<strong>for</strong>mation about morphologically processes, such as electrophysiological measurements.<br />

Notes<br />

169


P117<br />

Role of phonology in <strong>the</strong> generation of h<strong>and</strong>written responses<br />

Xingjia Shen, & Markus F. Damian<br />

<strong>University</strong> of Bristol, UK<br />

E-mail: r.x.shen@bris.ac.uk<br />

Three accounts of written production have been proposed: 1) a phonological code has to be retrieved<br />

be<strong>for</strong>e a word can be written (phonological mediation; e.g., Luria, 1970), 2) graphemic<br />

representations can be directly accessed from conceptual codes (orthographic autonomy; e.g., Rapp et<br />

al., 1997), 3) h<strong>and</strong>writing is supported both by a direct semantic-graphemic route <strong>and</strong> an indirect<br />

route via phonology (e.g., Bonin et al., 2001). Two experiments tackled this issue using <strong>the</strong> implicit<br />

priming task adopted from <strong>the</strong> spoken production literature (e.g., Meyer, 1991) in which<br />

speakers/writers generate responses based on small sets of prompt-response pairs (“match-c<strong>and</strong>le”)<br />

which <strong>the</strong>y memorise prior to an experimental block. The basic finding with spoken responses is that<br />

if all response words within a block share word-initial phonological content, responses are facilitated<br />

compared to when one or more of <strong>the</strong> responses begin with a different sound. We adopted <strong>the</strong> task to<br />

<strong>the</strong> written domain: participants wrote responses on a graphic tablet which measured response onset<br />

times (i.e., first contact of <strong>the</strong> stylus with <strong>the</strong> pad). Experiment 1 included 3 conditions: homogeneous<br />

(cobra, climate, c<strong>and</strong>le), heterogeneous (cobra, giant, c<strong>and</strong>le), <strong>and</strong> inconsistent such that while <strong>the</strong><br />

initial grapheme was homogeneous, <strong>the</strong> initial phoneme was not (cobra, city, c<strong>and</strong>le). The results<br />

showed significant priming in <strong>the</strong> homogeneous (603ms (SD167)) relative to <strong>the</strong> heterogeneous<br />

(642ms (SD143)), <strong>and</strong> crucially, a similar priming in <strong>the</strong> inconsistent (594ms (SD142)). Experiment 2<br />

included in <strong>the</strong> inconsistent condition words <strong>for</strong> which <strong>the</strong> initial grapheme was heterogeneous while<br />

<strong>the</strong> initial phoneme was not (cobra, kayak, c<strong>and</strong>le). Again, significant priming was found between <strong>the</strong><br />

homogeneous (697ms (SD120)) <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> heterogeneous (730ms (SD135)), but <strong>the</strong> inconsistent (722ms<br />

(SD116)) showed no such priming. The results indicate a limited role of phonology in <strong>the</strong> generation<br />

of written responses, <strong>and</strong> are in line with <strong>the</strong> predictions from <strong>the</strong> orthographic autonomy view.<br />

References<br />

Bonin, P., Peereman, R., & Fayol, M. (2001). Do phonological codes constrain <strong>the</strong> selection of<br />

orthographic codes in written picture naming Journal of Memory <strong>and</strong> <strong>Language</strong>, 45, 688-720.<br />

Luria, A. R. (1970). Traumatic aphasia. The Hague: Mouton.<br />

Meyer, A. S. (1991). The time course of phonological encoding in language production: phonological<br />

encoding inside a syllable. Journal of Memory <strong>and</strong> <strong>Language</strong>, 30, 69-89.<br />

Rapp, B., Benzing, L., & Caramazza, A. (1997). The autonomy of lexical orthography. Cognitive<br />

Neuropsychology, 14, 71-104.<br />

Notes<br />

170


P118<br />

How do we get from print to meaning: SMS shortcuts are not so gr8 at fstr<br />

lexical access<br />

Jane L. Morgan, & Anna R. Weighall<br />

Sheffield Hallam <strong>University</strong>, UK<br />

E-mail: j.l.morgan@shu.ac.uk<br />

A series of exploratory experiments were run which investigated whe<strong>the</strong>r SMS shortcuts are<br />

processed in <strong>the</strong> same way as real words. These stimuli are of interest because <strong>the</strong>y subvert <strong>the</strong> usual<br />

psycholinguistic rules yet in many cases seem to access <strong>the</strong> lexicon effectively. SMS shortcut stimuli<br />

can be constructed such that single graphemes or numbers are used to replace phonological segments<br />

(e.g., L8, nta – <strong>for</strong> late <strong>and</strong> enter); or are straight<strong>for</strong>ward abbreviations of <strong>the</strong> base word (e.g., msg,<br />

fwd <strong>for</strong> message <strong>and</strong> <strong>for</strong>ward). Theoretically <strong>the</strong>y provide an interesting tool to investigate <strong>the</strong><br />

relative contribution of orthography <strong>and</strong> phonology to visual word recognition. Given <strong>the</strong> shortcuts do<br />

not directly correspond to existing orthographic representations <strong>the</strong> questions of how one gets from<br />

print to sound <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> extent to which position coding of individual letters is important in word<br />

recognition arise. Such issues have divided current <strong>the</strong>ories (e.g., Col<strong>the</strong>art et al., 2001; Frost, 1998;<br />

Whitney, 2001). These issues were explored using masked priming with a lexical decision task.<br />

Initially, an identity priming experiment was conducted to establish whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> SMS shortcut L8<br />

primes LATE to <strong>the</strong> same extent as <strong>the</strong> real word late, compared to an unrelated SMS shortcut or real<br />

word prime ne1, anyone. We found that <strong>the</strong> SMS shortcut primes behaved differently to <strong>the</strong> real word<br />

primes as indicated by a significant interaction between prime type <strong>and</strong> relatedness. The interaction<br />

reflected a negative difference between <strong>the</strong> means in <strong>the</strong> related <strong>and</strong> unrelated conditions when <strong>the</strong><br />

SMS shortcut primes were presented (-9 ms) versus a positive 16 ms priming effect <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> real<br />

words. There<strong>for</strong>e, we found <strong>the</strong> classic identity priming effect <strong>for</strong> real words primes but not when<br />

SMS shortcut primes were used. We concluded that <strong>the</strong> orthographic irregularity of <strong>the</strong> SMS<br />

shortcuts disrupted any priming effect. Surprisingly, when we explored phonological <strong>and</strong> semantic<br />

relationships we did not observe <strong>the</strong> classic priming effects even <strong>for</strong> real words. However, our stimuli<br />

set were constrained by <strong>the</strong> everyday vocabulary used in SMS communication. Our data suggest that<br />

factors such as frequency have an important effect upon whe<strong>the</strong>r classic priming effects can be<br />

observed <strong>and</strong> fur<strong>the</strong>rmore highlight <strong>the</strong> difficulties in extending pure psycholinguistic paradigms to<br />

everyday language use.<br />

Notes<br />

171


P119<br />

SRNs <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> learning of grammatical agreement: The effect of<br />

target-source order <strong>and</strong> class overlap<br />

Robert Frank, & William Badecker<br />

Johns Hopkins <strong>University</strong>, USA<br />

E-mail: rfrank@jhu.edu<br />

As a structurally mediated relation, agreement provides an important test <strong>for</strong> models of language<br />

learning, such as Simple Recurrent Networks (SRNs), that eschew explicit representations of<br />

syntactic structure <strong>and</strong> morphosyntactic class (MC). Learning agreement requires identifying which<br />

classes of lexical items co-vary in which contexts. Elman (1993) showed that SRNs learn to predict<br />

properly agreeing verbs following complex subjects when trained to per<strong>for</strong>m word prediction. Since<br />

MCs may be constant (or overlap) across different agreement relations, learners must be able to<br />

generalize a word’s MC from one agreement relation to ano<strong>the</strong>r. We tested <strong>the</strong> ability of SRNs to<br />

generalize MC across different agreement relations by training on a corpus of transitive sentences<br />

with English word order that included two MCs of nouns (singular <strong>and</strong> plural) each inducing subjectverb<br />

agreement (SVA) <strong>and</strong> determiner-noun agreement (DNA). The corpus included three<br />

determiners: two number-agreeing indefinite determiners (a/some), <strong>and</strong> a number-invariant definite<br />

determiner. During training, we withheld one singular noun from subject position (though<br />

in<strong>for</strong>mation about its number was available from its occurrence as an object with <strong>the</strong> determiner a).<br />

When tested on examples with <strong>the</strong> held-out noun in subject position with a definite determiner, <strong>the</strong><br />

trained networks failed to consistently predict <strong>the</strong> correct class of verbs, indicating that MC<br />

in<strong>for</strong>mation in determiner-noun agreement was not used to guide SVA. This failure derives from <strong>the</strong><br />

split between <strong>the</strong> progressive relation in SVA between <strong>the</strong> subject noun <strong>and</strong> its target verb versus <strong>the</strong><br />

regressive relation in DNA. In <strong>the</strong> prediction task, progressive agreement yields similar weights from<br />

input units to hidden units <strong>for</strong> inputs of <strong>the</strong> same MC, whereas regressive agreement is encoded in<br />

weights between hidden units <strong>and</strong> output units. The SRN architecture imposes no linkage between<br />

<strong>the</strong>se weights, so it cannot generalize from one agreement type to <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r. (The analysis was<br />

verified by inverting <strong>the</strong> order of <strong>the</strong> determiner <strong>and</strong> noun to yield two progressive agreement<br />

relations, which yielded generalization from DNA to SVA as expected.) We obtained similar results<br />

when <strong>the</strong> MCs relevant in DNA <strong>and</strong> SVA were overlapping ra<strong>the</strong>r than identical. Our results from<br />

<strong>the</strong>se <strong>and</strong> related studies raise basic questions about <strong>the</strong> parallelism between progressive <strong>and</strong><br />

regressive agreement relations <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> ability of SRNs to model our capacity to abstract identical <strong>and</strong><br />

overlapping MCs from different agreement relations.<br />

Notes<br />

172


P120<br />

The Visual World paradigm in a complex world<br />

Richard Andersson 1 , Fern<strong>and</strong>a Ferreira 2 , & John M. Henderson 2<br />

1 Lund <strong>University</strong>, Sweden, 2 <strong>University</strong> of Edinburgh, UK<br />

E-mail: richard.<strong>and</strong>ersson@sol.lu.se<br />

The Visual World Paradigm is probably <strong>the</strong> most powerful method today to explore <strong>the</strong> integration of<br />

language, vision <strong>and</strong> real-world knowledge. Using this paradigm, researchers have found evidence <strong>for</strong><br />

tightly time-locked language-driven gaze (Tanenhaus et al 1995), antifipatory eye-movements<br />

(Altmann & Kamide 1999), integration of real-world knowledge (Altmann & Kamide 2007), <strong>and</strong><br />

more. However, all experimental setups up until today have used relatively simple stimuli involving a<br />

limited number of objects coupled with fairly simple sentences. In order <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong>se results to generalize<br />

into <strong>the</strong> real world, <strong>the</strong>y must be tested under conditions more similar to <strong>the</strong> real-world.<br />

We present <strong>the</strong> results of an experiment which explored <strong>the</strong> capacity of <strong>the</strong> human cognitive system<br />

to integrate language <strong>and</strong> vision during high in<strong>for</strong>mation load. Subjects were told to look at <strong>the</strong><br />

images, listen to <strong>the</strong> utterances <strong>and</strong> afterwards answer <strong>the</strong> questions. The images presented were<br />

complex real-world scenes with many objects, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> utterances consisted of three sentences of<br />

which <strong>the</strong> middle sentence mentioned four objects. The main question <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> experiment was<br />

whe<strong>the</strong>r participants, given complex scenes <strong>and</strong> heavy sentences, would still show a strong drive to<br />

gaze at all <strong>the</strong> objects mentioned, which is <strong>the</strong> corner-stone of <strong>the</strong> Visual World Paradigm.<br />

To <strong>the</strong> relief of visual world psycholinguists, <strong>the</strong> results show that <strong>the</strong> participants were very<br />

determined to integrate <strong>the</strong> visual in<strong>for</strong>mation with <strong>the</strong> utterance by fixating <strong>the</strong> mentioned objects.<br />

This drive to integrate <strong>the</strong> in<strong>for</strong>mation was so strong that probabilities of fixation peaked as late as<br />

around three seconds after <strong>the</strong> onset of <strong>the</strong> object (c.f. 250 ms in Tanenhaus et al 1995). Results also<br />

show that when <strong>the</strong> processing dem<strong>and</strong>s become too great, <strong>the</strong> integration is down-prioritized <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

probability of fixation drops.<br />

References<br />

Tanenhaus, M. K., Spivey-Knowlton, M. J., Eberhard, K. M., Sedivy, J. C. 1995. Integration of visual<br />

<strong>and</strong> linguistic in<strong>for</strong>mation in spoken language comprehension. Science (268) pp. 1632.<br />

Altmann, G. T. M., Kamide, Y. 1999. Incremental interpretation at verbs: restricting <strong>the</strong> domain of<br />

subsequent reference. Cognition (73) pp. 247-264.<br />

Altmann, G. T. M., Kamide, Y. 2007. The real-time mediation of visual attention by language <strong>and</strong><br />

world knowledge: Linking anticipatory (<strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r) eye movements to linguistic processing.<br />

Journal of Memory <strong>and</strong> <strong>Language</strong> (57) pp. 502-518.<br />

Notes<br />

173


P121<br />

Selecting <strong>and</strong> producing names to common nouns: The role of <strong>the</strong> LIFG in<br />

<strong>the</strong> ageing brain<br />

Zanna Szlachta, Billi R<strong>and</strong>all, & Lorraine K. Tyler<br />

<strong>University</strong> of Cambridge, UK<br />

E-mail: billi@csl.psychol.cam.ac.uk<br />

The processes involved in selecting between competing alternatives have been closely associated with<br />

<strong>the</strong> left inferior frontal gyrus (LIFG) (Thompson-Schill et al, 1997). Evidence from neuroimaging<br />

studies suggests that this part of <strong>the</strong> brain becomes more engaged when selection dem<strong>and</strong>s are high –<br />

when competing or prepotent responses must be overcome (Moss et al, 2005). Similarly,<br />

neuropsychological studies link damage in <strong>the</strong> LIFG with poorer per<strong>for</strong>mance when selection<br />

dem<strong>and</strong>s are high (Thompson-Schill et al, 1998).<br />

Across <strong>the</strong> normal lifespan, frontal cortex begins to atrophy earlier than many o<strong>the</strong>r parts of <strong>the</strong> brain<br />

(Sowell et al, 2003). This leads to <strong>the</strong> hypo<strong>the</strong>sis that selection dem<strong>and</strong>s will be less successfully met<br />

with increasing age. An alternative view is that cognitive per<strong>for</strong>mance across <strong>the</strong> life span may be<br />

preserved through <strong>the</strong> process of functional reorganization - with <strong>the</strong> recruitment of additional brain<br />

regions, possibly in homologous regions in <strong>the</strong> right hemisphere, or regions surrounding LIFG.<br />

We tested <strong>the</strong> hypo<strong>the</strong>sis that <strong>the</strong> LIFG is involved in selection dem<strong>and</strong>s by measuring per<strong>for</strong>mance<br />

in a speeded naming task to pictures denoting 72 common nouns <strong>for</strong> 35 adults aged 20-86 years. We<br />

measured <strong>the</strong> difficulty in selecting an appropriate response <strong>for</strong> each picture using <strong>the</strong> H-statistic<br />

(Snodgrass & V<strong>and</strong>erwart, 1980), which reflects variation in name agreement <strong>and</strong> can be taken as an<br />

index of selection difficulty. For each participant we obtained naming latencies <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> pictures which<br />

we correlated with <strong>the</strong>ir respective HStat statistics. This correlation served as our measure of<br />

sensitivity to competition in <strong>the</strong> imaging analyses – <strong>the</strong> higher <strong>the</strong> correlation, <strong>the</strong> greater <strong>the</strong><br />

sensitivity to competition. We <strong>the</strong>n related this selection per<strong>for</strong>mance to age-related neural changes<br />

by correlating it with signal intensity derived from voxel based morphometry of MR scans <strong>for</strong> each<br />

subject. This method has been previously used to correlate brain <strong>and</strong> behaviour (Tyler et al)<br />

We found that neural atrophy across <strong>the</strong> brain increased with age, as has been reported previously.<br />

Naming latencies also increased with age (r(32)=0.37; p


P122<br />

ERP signatures of auxiliary selection in German<br />

Dietmar Roehm 1 , & Antonella Sorace 2<br />

1 Max Planck Institute <strong>for</strong> Human Cognitive <strong>and</strong> <strong>Brain</strong> Sciences, Leipzig, Germany,<br />

2 <strong>University</strong> of Edinburgh, UK<br />

E-mail: roehm@cbs.mpg.de<br />

The selection of perfective auxiliaries haben ‘have’ <strong>and</strong> sein ’be’ with intransitive verbs in German<br />

depends on a combination of syntactic, lexical, <strong>and</strong> semantic factors (Levin & Rappaport Hovav<br />

1995, 2005; van Valin 1990). Recent research has shown that preferences <strong>for</strong> one auxiliary or <strong>the</strong><br />

o<strong>the</strong>r systematically vary in strength depending on <strong>the</strong> semantic type of main verb <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> context in<br />

which <strong>the</strong> auxiliary-verb combination appears (Sorace 2000; Keller & Sorace 2003). Sorace (2000,<br />

2003) has proposed that intransitive verbs are organized in a Split Intransitivity Hierarchy, defined by<br />

two key factors (telicity <strong>and</strong> agentivity) whose interaction affects <strong>the</strong> syntax of split intransitivity <strong>and</strong><br />

creates gradient auxiliary preferences, ranging from categorical to highly variable.<br />

In two ERP experiments we investigated this hypo<strong>the</strong>sis. Exp. 1 focused on <strong>the</strong> role of telicity <strong>and</strong><br />

addressed <strong>the</strong> difference between lexically telic verbs ("core unaccusative", e.g. abreisen) <strong>and</strong> atelic<br />

agentive verbs ("core unergative", e.g. arbeiten), <strong>and</strong> between telicity inherently encoded in <strong>the</strong> verb’s<br />

argument structure (e.g. ankommen) <strong>and</strong> telicity morphologically induced by <strong>the</strong> presence of a prefix<br />

(e.g. verwelken). Auxiliary selection violations showed a biphasic N400/P600 pattern which was<br />

most pronounced <strong>for</strong> core verbs. The violations induced a longer positivity <strong>for</strong> core unergative than<br />

<strong>for</strong> core unaccusative verbs, indicating a stronger link between BE <strong>and</strong> telicity than between HAVE<br />

<strong>and</strong> atelicity. Unprefixed change of state verbs showed no effect, consistent with <strong>the</strong> interpretation of<br />

<strong>the</strong>se verbs as indeterminate with respect to telicity. Moreover, <strong>the</strong> N400 was smaller <strong>for</strong> prefixed<br />

change of state verbs than <strong>for</strong> change of location verbs, suggesting a difference between inherent <strong>and</strong><br />

compositional telicity. Exp. 2 focused on <strong>the</strong> role of volitional control (subject animacy) <strong>and</strong> also<br />

investigated <strong>the</strong> difference between verbs denoting a telic change (e.g. abreisen) <strong>and</strong> those denoting a<br />

state (e.g. liegen). Stative verbs <strong>and</strong> verbs of uncontrolled process elicited a N400/P600 <strong>for</strong> sein.<br />

Verbs of controlled motion only elicited a N400 <strong>for</strong> haben indicating that both auxiliaries are<br />

acceptable with this verb class but with associated interpretive differences. Animacy effects were<br />

obtained only <strong>for</strong> stative verbs <strong>and</strong> verbs of uncontrolled process.<br />

The results are consistent with previous behavioural evidence of gradient variation in auxiliary<br />

selection (Keller & Sorace, 2003) <strong>and</strong> provide a first picture of <strong>the</strong> neurocognitive correlates of<br />

auxiliary selection during real-time processing.<br />

Notes<br />

175


P123<br />

Integrating <strong>the</strong> spatial semantics of verbs <strong>and</strong> prepositions during<br />

sentence processing<br />

Robert Thornton 1 , Natalie Klein 2 , Elspeth Llewellyn 3 , Martin Hackl 1<br />

1 Pomona College, USA, 2 <strong>University</strong> of Rochester, USA, 3 Scripps College<br />

E-mail: rt004747@pomona.edu<br />

Psycholinguistic studies of semantic processing often focus on how semantics influences syntactic<br />

processing, but we know little about how comprehenders build a componential semantic<br />

representation in real time. Several recent studies have addressed this issue by examining enriched<br />

semantic composition, a process in which <strong>the</strong> meaning of a word is coerced to meet <strong>the</strong> semantic<br />

restrictions of o<strong>the</strong>r words in <strong>the</strong> sentence (e.g., McElree et al., 2001; Piñango et al., 1999). We built<br />

on that work by examining how spatial in<strong>for</strong>mation from verbs <strong>and</strong> prepositions is integrated,<br />

enriched, <strong>and</strong> interpreted in real time. We focused specifically on how one source of spatial<br />

in<strong>for</strong>mation, directionality, determines spatial interpretation.<br />

In English, two main classes of locative PPs can be distinguished: PATH PPs, which provide<br />

directional meaning by specifying a path along which an event unfolds, <strong>and</strong> PLACE PPs, which<br />

simply specify a location. Similarly, motion VPs can ei<strong>the</strong>r be directional, requiring a PATH to be<br />

specified, or non-directional, without that requirement. In a self-paced reading experiment, we<br />

examined how spatial in<strong>for</strong>mation is integrated by manipulating VP <strong>and</strong> PP directionality.<br />

(1) Directional VPs:<br />

a. PATH PP: To protect her nest, <strong>the</strong> bird darted to <strong>the</strong> hunter just now.<br />

b. PLACE PP: To protect her nest, <strong>the</strong> bird darted at <strong>the</strong> hunter just now.<br />

(2) Non-directional VPs:<br />

a. PATH PP: Because he woke up early, <strong>the</strong> child w<strong>and</strong>ered to <strong>the</strong> school last Tuesday.<br />

b. PLACE PP: Because he woke up early, <strong>the</strong> child w<strong>and</strong>ered at <strong>the</strong> school last Tuesday.<br />

Of particular interest is what happens when <strong>the</strong> spatial type of <strong>the</strong> PP <strong>and</strong> VP mismatch, as in 1b <strong>and</strong><br />

2a. For example, "at" is typically non-directional, specifying a PLACE. However, in <strong>the</strong> phrase<br />

"darted at," <strong>the</strong> VP is inherently directional <strong>and</strong> requires a PATH. On a coercion account, "darted"<br />

coerces <strong>the</strong> meaning of "at" into specifying a bounded path along which <strong>the</strong> agent traveled, resulting<br />

in a processing cost. An alternative is that "at" is ambiguous <strong>and</strong> can accommodate ei<strong>the</strong>r<br />

interpretation easily with no cost.<br />

We found significantly longer RTs at <strong>the</strong> preposition <strong>for</strong> both mismatch conditions. We ruled out a<br />

number of frequency-based explanations of our data leaving semantic coercion (e.g., Jackendoff,<br />

1997; Pustejovsky, 1995) as <strong>the</strong> only explanation <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> RT increase. The fact that a mismatch in<br />

directionality causes semantic coercion suggests that in cases of mismatch directionality always wins,<br />

supporting <strong>the</strong> idea that directionality is built from simpler spatial representations.<br />

Notes<br />

176


An EPG investigation of auditory interference on speech execution<br />

P124<br />

Ivan Yuen, Kathleen Rastle, & Marc Brysbaert<br />

Royal Holloway, <strong>University</strong> of London, UK<br />

E-mail: ivan.yuen@rhul.ac.uk<br />

Evidence regarding <strong>the</strong> relationship between phonological encoding <strong>and</strong> motor execution in speech<br />

production is conflicting. Damian (2003) argued <strong>for</strong> a staged model of speech production, whereas<br />

Goldrick & Blumstein (2006) <strong>and</strong> Kello, Plaut & MacWhinney (2000) favoured a cascaded view. Our<br />

study contributed to this debate by using electropalatography to examine <strong>the</strong> effect of unselected<br />

auditory distractors (e.g., /tup/) on <strong>the</strong> production of visually-presented nonword targets (e.g.,<br />

KOOP).<br />

On each trial of our experiment, participants heard a sequence of five 50ms beeps at regular intervals<br />

of 500 ms. They were presented with a target nonword on <strong>the</strong> fourth beep <strong>and</strong> were instructed to<br />

produce it on <strong>the</strong> fifth beep. This target was preceded immediately by a congruent or incongruent<br />

auditory distractor. Targets always began with a /k/ or /s/. Incongruent distractors began with /t/ <strong>and</strong><br />

shared <strong>the</strong> rime of <strong>the</strong> target stimuli, while congruent distractors comprised a perfect match to <strong>the</strong><br />

target. Tongue-palate contact <strong>for</strong> target productions was measured during <strong>the</strong> closure of /k/ <strong>and</strong> during<br />

<strong>the</strong> frication of /s/. Results showed a statistically significant effect of <strong>the</strong> auditory distractors on <strong>the</strong><br />

degree of tongue-palate contact <strong>for</strong> both targets, with <strong>the</strong> incongruent /t/ distractors inducing greater<br />

contact in <strong>the</strong> alveolar region <strong>for</strong> productions of /k/ <strong>and</strong> /s/. This effect was restricted to early portions<br />

of <strong>the</strong> annotated regions.<br />

These findings support <strong>the</strong> cascaded view because <strong>the</strong>y show that in<strong>for</strong>mation about unselected<br />

auditory distractors can ‘leak’ to <strong>the</strong> motor system during <strong>the</strong> execution of a planned speech target.<br />

Fur<strong>the</strong>r, <strong>the</strong> findings suggest that <strong>the</strong> interference effect occurred fairly early in <strong>the</strong> planned<br />

movement, <strong>and</strong> was possibly corrected by some ‘control’ mechanism later on.<br />

References<br />

Damian, M. (2003). Articulatory duration in single-word speech production. Journal of Experimental<br />

Psychology, 29, 416-431.<br />

Goldrick, M., & Blumstein, S. (2006). Cascading activation from phonological planning to<br />

articulatory processes: Evidence from tongue twisters. <strong>Language</strong> <strong>and</strong> Cognitive Processes, 21,<br />

649-683.<br />

Kello, C., Plaut, D., & MacWhinney, B. (2000). The task dependence of staged versus cascaded<br />

processing: an empirical <strong>and</strong> computational study of Stroop interference in speech production.<br />

Journal of Experimental Psychology, 129, 340-360.<br />

Notes<br />

177


P125<br />

Prosody <strong>and</strong> attachment in a double-PP construction in Hebrew<br />

Ronit Webman, Janet D. Fodor, & Eva M. Fernández<br />

The Graduate Center, City <strong>University</strong> of New York, USA<br />

E-mail: rwebman@gc.cuny.edu<br />

Experimental studies have begun to map out regularities at <strong>the</strong> syntax-prosody interface. Our research<br />

contributes data from Hebrew on a construction rarely studied from this perspective. It has a sequence<br />

of two prepositional phrases in which PP1 must attach low, inside <strong>the</strong> preceding NP, but PP2<br />

attachment is ambiguous.<br />

1. Dana VP[teara et ha-kšayim PP1[be-nisue-ha PP2[la-šadran (ha-mefursam)<br />

Dana described <strong>the</strong> difficulties in marriage her to <strong>the</strong> broadcaster (<strong>the</strong> famous)<br />

PP2 can attach maximally high to VP (as an argument of “described”) or maximally low to <strong>the</strong> NP<br />

inside PP1 (modifying “marriage”). For <strong>the</strong> high attachment reading, alignment principles (Selkirk<br />

2000) predict an intermediate prosodic phrase boundary at <strong>the</strong> left of PP2 due to syntactic right edges<br />

<strong>the</strong>re (closure of direct object <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> PP1 <strong>and</strong> NP inside it). For <strong>the</strong> low attachment reading, no<br />

boundary is predicted at <strong>the</strong> left of PP2 unless it is induced by o<strong>the</strong>r factors (e.g., constituent length).<br />

We examined this hypo<strong>the</strong>sis in a combined production-comprehension study, with target sentences<br />

like (1)—whose two meanings were judged equi-plausible in pre-tests—with PP2 ei<strong>the</strong>r short (1<br />

prosodic word) or long (2-3 prosodic words). Items (24 targets, 48 fillers) were presented on a single<br />

line of a computer screen. Native speakers (N=40) read each sentence aloud, <strong>the</strong>n saw two phrases<br />

(“described to broadcaster”; “marriage to broadcaster”), <strong>and</strong> chose <strong>the</strong> one most closely related to <strong>the</strong><br />

meaning of <strong>the</strong> sentence. Two trained listeners assessed <strong>the</strong> location of prosodic breaks using ToBIlike<br />

coding.<br />

PP2 length had a strong effect on <strong>the</strong> produced prosody. Of <strong>the</strong> target sentences uttered with a<br />

prosodic break anywhere in <strong>the</strong> sentence (N=635, 66% of all recordings), short-PP2 materials favored<br />

a break be<strong>for</strong>e PP1 (68.0%), while long-PP2 materials favored a break be<strong>for</strong>e PP2 (88.7%).<br />

PP2 length affected comprehension as well. High attachment of PP2 was more likely <strong>for</strong> long-PP2<br />

(56.4%) than short-PP2 materials (46.4%), replicating length effects observed with o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

constructions <strong>and</strong> in o<strong>the</strong>r languages.<br />

But comprehension was also closely related to produced prosody, even more strongly than to PP2-<br />

length. Utterances produced with a break only be<strong>for</strong>e PP1 had a substantially smaller high attachment<br />

rate (39.7%) than utterances produced with a break only be<strong>for</strong>e PP2 (60.3%).<br />

Subsequent investigation will confirm cause <strong>and</strong> effect in this relationship, but <strong>the</strong> current data<br />

suggest that attachee-length affects prosodic phrasing, <strong>and</strong> prosodic phrasing affects attachment<br />

preference.<br />

Notes<br />

178


P126<br />

The role of prosody in on- <strong>and</strong> off-line sentence processing: The case of<br />

subject- <strong>and</strong> object-control verbs<br />

Sara Bögels 1 , Herbert Schriefers 1 , Wietske Vonk 2 , Doro<strong>the</strong>e J. Chwilla 1 , & Roel Kerkhofs 3<br />

1 NICI, Radboud <strong>University</strong> Nijmegen, The Ne<strong>the</strong>rl<strong>and</strong>s, 2 Max Planck Institute <strong>for</strong> Psycholinguistics,<br />

Nijmegen, The Ne<strong>the</strong>rl<strong>and</strong>s, 3 CLS, Radboud <strong>University</strong> Nijmegen, The Ne<strong>the</strong>rl<strong>and</strong>s<br />

E-mail: S.bogels@nici.ru.nl<br />

Locally ambiguous sentences, containing two different types of control verbs, were presented<br />

auditorily in an off-line fragment completion (up to*) <strong>and</strong> an on-line ERP study:<br />

1. a) De leerling bekende de leraar te hebben*gespiekt.<br />

The pupil confessed to <strong>the</strong> teacher to have cheated.<br />

b) De leerling bekende de leraar te hebben*opgesloten.<br />

The pupil confessed to have locked <strong>the</strong> teacher up.<br />

2. a) De chirurg adviseerde de vrouw te*slapen.<br />

The surgeon advised <strong>the</strong> woman to sleep<br />

b) De chirurg adviseerde de vrouw te*ondersteunen.<br />

The surgeon advised to support <strong>the</strong> woman.<br />

A subject-control (SC) verb (as in (1), confess) has a subject (<strong>the</strong> pupil) that is also <strong>the</strong> understood<br />

subject of <strong>the</strong> disambiguating infinitival verb. An object-control (OC) verb (as in (2), advise) has an<br />

object (<strong>the</strong> woman in (2a) or implicit in (2b)) that is <strong>the</strong> understood subject of <strong>the</strong> disambiguating<br />

verb. All sentences ei<strong>the</strong>r contained a prosodic break (PB) after <strong>the</strong> control verb or not. In (a), a PB<br />

suggests that <strong>the</strong> teacher or <strong>the</strong> woman is NOT <strong>the</strong> indirect object of <strong>the</strong> control verb, but this<br />

syntactic expectation is eventually contradicted by <strong>the</strong> fact that <strong>the</strong> verbs cheat <strong>and</strong> sleep are<br />

intransitive. By contrast, in (b), a PB agrees with <strong>the</strong> eventual syntactic analysis, because <strong>the</strong> verbs<br />

lock up <strong>and</strong> support are obligatorily transitive.<br />

The fragment completion study revealed a large preference <strong>for</strong> intransitive completions in OC<br />

sentences <strong>and</strong> a smaller preference <strong>for</strong> transitive completions in SC sentences. Moreover, <strong>the</strong> PB<br />

shifted <strong>the</strong> preference slightly to more transitive completions in both cases.<br />

The ERP study showed a Closure Positive Shift in response to <strong>the</strong> PB. Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, SC sentences<br />

yielded an N400 effect <strong>for</strong> intransitive as compared to transitive disambiguating verbs, both <strong>for</strong><br />

sentences with <strong>and</strong> without a PB. This result suggests that <strong>the</strong> default preference <strong>for</strong> subject-control<br />

verbs goes in <strong>the</strong> same direction as <strong>the</strong> effect of <strong>the</strong> PB. In contrast, OC sentences also yielded an<br />

N400 effect <strong>for</strong> intransitive as compared to transitive disambiguating verbs, however, only when a PB<br />

was present. This indicates that a PB can be sufficient to determine <strong>the</strong> syntactic analysis of a<br />

sentence. These results show that SC <strong>and</strong> OC verbs are processed differently, <strong>and</strong> thus extend<br />

previous work by Steinhauer et al. (1999) who studied similar sentences in German, but implicitly<br />

assumed that SC <strong>and</strong> OC verbs are processed in <strong>the</strong> same way.<br />

References<br />

Steinhauer, K., Alter, K., & Friederici, A. D. (1999). <strong>Brain</strong> potentials indicate immediate use of<br />

prosodic cues in natural speech processing. Nature Neuroscience, 2, 191-196.<br />

Notes<br />

179


P127<br />

Processing differences between anaphora <strong>and</strong> cataphora: Evidence from<br />

oscillatory brain activity<br />

Sibylle Mohr, Hamutal Kreiner, Klaus Kessler, & Simon Garrod<br />

<strong>University</strong> of Glasgow, UK<br />

E-mail: s.mohr@psy.gla.ac.uk<br />

Both anaphora [a] <strong>and</strong> cataphora [b] establish a relationship between a pronoun <strong>and</strong> a noun. However,<br />

<strong>the</strong>y obviously differ regarding <strong>the</strong> order in which pronoun <strong>and</strong> co-referential noun appear, entailing<br />

an important difference in discourse alignment (Kazanina et al., 2007). This difference may restrict<br />

<strong>the</strong> referential search mechanisms <strong>for</strong> an optimal antecedent in cataphoric vs. anaphoric contexts.<br />

Kazanina et al. (2007) suggests that <strong>the</strong> parser initiates an active search <strong>for</strong> an optimal antecedent<br />

when processing intra-sentential cataphora, similar to <strong>the</strong> Active Filler Strategy proposed <strong>for</strong> fillergap<br />

dependencies (Frazier <strong>and</strong> Clifton, 1989). In two EEG-experiments, we investigated processing<br />

differences between anaphora <strong>and</strong> cataphora using a gender mismatch manipulation ([a], [b]),<br />

previously shown to illuminate <strong>the</strong> processes underlying reference resolution (e.g. van Gompel &<br />

Liversedge, 2003; Osterhout et al.,1997).<br />

[a] Yesterday <strong>the</strong> ‘king’ left London after reminding ‘himself/herself’ about <strong>the</strong> letter.<br />

[b] After reminding ‘himself/herself’ about <strong>the</strong> letter, <strong>the</strong> ‘king’ immediately went to <strong>the</strong><br />

meeting at <strong>the</strong> office.<br />

Stimulus-specific modulations of EEG oscillations in certain frequency b<strong>and</strong>s have been shown to<br />

reflect cognitive parameters in language processing (van Berkum et al., 2005; Hagoort et al., 2004).<br />

We examined brain responses to gender mismatches (‘king’-‘herself’ compared with ‘king’-<br />

‘himself’) by means of Time-Frequency-Representations (TFRs) to determine whe<strong>the</strong>r distinctive<br />

oscillatory modulations are linked to context-dependent resolution strategies in anaphora vs.<br />

cataphora. Experiment 1 used anaphora sentences [a] <strong>and</strong> showed increased oscillatory activity in<br />

frontal electrodes in <strong>the</strong> gamma (30-80 Hz) range <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> mismatching compared to <strong>the</strong> matching<br />

condition. Experiment 2 used cataphora sentences [b] <strong>and</strong> showed a comparable increase in <strong>the</strong> same<br />

b<strong>and</strong>, but here <strong>the</strong> mismatch effect was much stronger <strong>and</strong> was confined to central electrodes.<br />

Analyses of power spectrum <strong>and</strong> TFR <strong>the</strong>re<strong>for</strong>e reveal distinctive patterns <strong>for</strong> anaphora <strong>and</strong> cataphora<br />

sentences associated with distinct amplitudes <strong>and</strong> electrode locations. Induced gamma-b<strong>and</strong> activity<br />

may reflect underlying feature-binding processes (‘binding’ gamma rhythm; Engel & Singer, 2001)<br />

<strong>and</strong> has been related to arousal, perceptual integration, working memory, <strong>and</strong> language processing.<br />

Our findings suggest a qualitative difference in feature-binding between cataphora <strong>and</strong> anaphora.<br />

Notes<br />

180


P128<br />

The filler may be a gentleman: Local coherence effect in long-distance<br />

dependency processing<br />

Zhenguang Cai, Martin J. Pickering, & Patrick Sturt<br />

<strong>University</strong> of Edinburgh, UK<br />

E-mail: s0782345@sms.ed.ac.uk<br />

In <strong>the</strong> literature of long-distance dependency processing, it is relatively uncontroversial that <strong>the</strong> parser<br />

integrates a filler into <strong>the</strong> string as soon as possible1, 2. Also, it has been demonstrated that <strong>the</strong> parser<br />

is reluctant to reanalyze3. However, a recent study4 shows that <strong>the</strong> parser tends to reanalyze its initial<br />

analysis when <strong>the</strong>re is a locally coherent, though globally incompatible, structure, e.g., reanalyze <strong>the</strong><br />

object <strong>the</strong> player in “The coach smiled at <strong>the</strong> player tossed a frisbee” as <strong>the</strong> subject of tossed. The<br />

present study presents a similar local coherence effect in long-distance dependency processing. We<br />

examined sentences like (1a), where <strong>the</strong> filler John is <strong>the</strong> object of <strong>the</strong> verb threatened, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> NP <strong>the</strong><br />

neighbour is <strong>the</strong> subject of <strong>the</strong> main clause. According to current <strong>the</strong>ories, <strong>the</strong> filler John would be<br />

integrated as <strong>the</strong> object as soon as <strong>the</strong> verb threatened is encountered, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> neighbour would be<br />

treated as <strong>the</strong> subject of a new clause <strong>and</strong> would not be considered as <strong>the</strong> object of <strong>the</strong> preceding verb.<br />

We conducted a self-paced reading experiment (48 subjects, 24 items) with a 2 (construction: <strong>the</strong><br />

ambiguous object cleft (1a,b) vs <strong>the</strong> unambiguous subject cleft (1c,d)) * 2 (comma) design. We<br />

predicted that if <strong>the</strong> parser considers <strong>the</strong> neighour as <strong>the</strong> object of threatened, <strong>the</strong>re will be a filled-gap<br />

effect at <strong>the</strong> region <strong>the</strong> neighbour in (1a) but not in <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r conditions. ANOVAs show that at <strong>the</strong><br />

neighbour <strong>the</strong>re is an interaction between construction <strong>and</strong> comma (p1=.077, p2=.009). The<br />

interaction is driven by longer RTs in (1a) (849 ms) than in (1c) (755 ms) (p1=.04, p2=.013); <strong>the</strong>re is<br />

no significant difference between (1b) (709 ms) <strong>and</strong> (1d) ) (725 ms) (Fs


P129<br />

(Ir)regularity of verbs revisited: Evidence <strong>for</strong> a lexical entry complexity<br />

based account<br />

Denisa Bordag 1 , Helena Trompelt 2 , & Thomas Pechmann 1<br />

1 <strong>University</strong> of Leipzig, Germany, 2 <strong>University</strong> of Potsdam, Germany<br />

E-mail: trompelt@uni.leipzig.de<br />

According to <strong>the</strong> Dual-Route Model (Pinker, 1998; Clahsen, 1999), regular <strong>for</strong>ms are composed of a<br />

stem <strong>and</strong> suffixes whereas irregular <strong>for</strong>ms are stored as ready-made entries. We investigated three<br />

groups of German verbs in past <strong>and</strong> present to test whe<strong>the</strong>r (ir)regularity effects are bound to<br />

individual <strong>for</strong>ms or whole inflectional paradigms.<br />

German regular verbs (spielen [play], spielt, spielte) have only one stem <strong>and</strong> completely regular<br />

conjugation. Irregular verbs have several stems <strong>and</strong> irregular <strong>for</strong>ms in both tenses (brechen [break],<br />

bricht, brach). Mixed verbs also have several stems, but <strong>the</strong>ir present conjugation is completely<br />

regular, while <strong>the</strong>ir past <strong>for</strong>ms are irregular (singen [sing], singt, sang).<br />

In Experiment 1, participants produced <strong>the</strong> 3rd person singular of regular, mixed, <strong>and</strong> irregular verbs<br />

(in a sentential context) in <strong>the</strong> tense that was triggered by <strong>the</strong> colour of <strong>the</strong> presented infinitive.<br />

The analyses revealed that regular verbs in <strong>the</strong> present tense were significantly faster than all <strong>the</strong><br />

o<strong>the</strong>r groups. Irregular verbs in <strong>the</strong> present <strong>and</strong> past tense <strong>and</strong> mixed verbs in <strong>the</strong> past (i.e. <strong>the</strong> groups<br />

with <strong>the</strong> irregular <strong>for</strong>ms) were slowest <strong>and</strong> did not differ statistically from each o<strong>the</strong>r. Regular verbs<br />

in <strong>the</strong> past <strong>and</strong> mixed verbs in <strong>the</strong> present tense did not differ from each o<strong>the</strong>r, but differed both from<br />

<strong>the</strong> fastest group <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> three slowest groups.<br />

In Experiment 2 we replicated <strong>the</strong> findings with a picture naming paradigm – a task that involves<br />

conceptualisation <strong>and</strong> avoids possible priming between <strong>the</strong> presented <strong>and</strong> elicited <strong>for</strong>ms. The results<br />

corresponded to those of Experiment 1 with differences expected due to <strong>the</strong> changes of <strong>the</strong> paradigm.<br />

Crucially, <strong>the</strong> present <strong>for</strong>ms of both mixed <strong>and</strong> irregular verbs were produced more slowly (<strong>and</strong> did<br />

not differ statistically) than <strong>the</strong> regular present <strong>for</strong>ms of <strong>the</strong> regular verbs.<br />

We argue that postulating two different mechanisms <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> processing of regular <strong>and</strong> irregular<br />

inflection cannot account <strong>for</strong> all data, in particular not <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> fact that even regular <strong>for</strong>ms of mixed<br />

verbs are produced more slowly than regular <strong>for</strong>ms of <strong>the</strong> regular verbs. We propose that <strong>the</strong> crucial<br />

explanatory factor is <strong>the</strong> complexity of <strong>the</strong> lexical entry: If a verb has multiple stems (irregular <strong>and</strong><br />

mixed verbs), <strong>the</strong> retrieval of <strong>the</strong> appropriate one takes longer than <strong>the</strong> retrieval of a single stem entry<br />

(regular verbs).<br />

References<br />

Clahsen, H. (1999). Lexical entries <strong>and</strong> rules of language: A multi-disciplinary study of German<br />

inflection. Behavioral <strong>and</strong> <strong>Brain</strong> Sciences, 22, 991-1060.<br />

Pinker, S. (1998). Words <strong>and</strong> rules. Lingua, 106, 219<br />

Notes<br />

182


P130<br />

The processing of negated sentences in Turkish learners of French: A<br />

preference <strong>for</strong> scope-to-<strong>the</strong>-right<br />

Sarah Schimke<br />

Max Planck Institute <strong>for</strong> Psycholinguistics, Nijmegen, The Ne<strong>the</strong>rl<strong>and</strong>s<br />

E-mail: sarah.schimke@mpi.nl<br />

In verb-raising languages such as French, finite verbs precede <strong>the</strong> negator (1a), which <strong>the</strong>n has scope<br />

to <strong>the</strong> left. This placement has been shown to be difficult <strong>for</strong> beginning adult learners: <strong>the</strong>y often<br />

produce pre-verbal negation in utterances with (ungrammatical) non-finite main verbs (1d), <strong>and</strong><br />

occasionally also with finite verbs (1b). This preference was also found in learners whose first<br />

language has no pre-verbal negation, as Turkish. In line with this observation, Schimke (2008) found<br />

that beginning Turkish learners were slower in processing post- than pre-verbal negation in a selfpaced<br />

listening study in German, in which equivalents of sentences 1a-d were used. Native speakers<br />

were slower when listening to sentences 1c-d than 1a.<br />

The current study tested <strong>the</strong> same sentence types in a self-paced listening task with Turkish learners<br />

of French. In contrast to German, infinitives are not homophone with any finite verb <strong>for</strong>m in French,<br />

so that <strong>the</strong>y cannot be perceived as agreement errors as might have been <strong>the</strong> case in <strong>the</strong> study on<br />

German. Moreover, in French, less elements can be introduced between <strong>the</strong> verb <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> negator than<br />

in German, which might favour <strong>the</strong> acquisition of post-verbal negation <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> ease of its processing<br />

in French.<br />

Results show that both learners <strong>and</strong> a native speaker control group listened more slowly to <strong>the</strong> verb<br />

<strong>and</strong> negator-region in 1b/d than 1a/c. On <strong>the</strong> following segments however, native speakers were faster<br />

after post-verbal negation with finite, but after pre-verbal negation with non-finite verbs. Learners<br />

were slower on <strong>the</strong> segments following post- than pre-verbal negation irrespective of verb type, as<br />

had been <strong>the</strong> case in <strong>the</strong> study on German. We suggest that <strong>the</strong> slower processing of <strong>the</strong> segments<br />

following post-verbal negation is due to learners having difficulties in finding <strong>the</strong> elements that are in<br />

<strong>the</strong> scope of <strong>the</strong> negator. In contrast, <strong>the</strong> interaction effect <strong>for</strong> native speakers suggests that <strong>the</strong>y are<br />

influenced by grammaticality ra<strong>the</strong>r than scope-direction. Finally, <strong>the</strong> initial slow-down in sentence<br />

types 1b <strong>and</strong> d suggests that frequencies of word orders also influence processing ease.<br />

1a Le garcon écrit (fin) pas à sa tante.<br />

The boy writes not to his aunt.<br />

1b *Le garçon pas écrit à sa tante.<br />

1c *Le garçon écrire pas à sa tante.<br />

1d *Le garçon pas écrire (inf) à sa tante.<br />

References<br />

Schimke, S. (2008). Grammatical versus semantically transparent word order in negated sentences:<br />

Comparing production, imitation,<strong>and</strong> processing in Turkish learners of German. Poster at 21st<br />

CUNY Conference on human sentence processing.<br />

Notes<br />

183


P131<br />

The role of prosody in discovering hierarchical structure in<br />

continous speech<br />

Alan Langus 1 , Erika Marchetto 1 , Ricardo A.H. Bion 1 , & Marina Nespor 2<br />

1<br />

SISSA, Trieste, Italy, 2 <strong>University</strong> Milano Bicocca, Italy<br />

E-mail: langus@sissa.it<br />

Processes triggered by <strong>the</strong> speech signal play a central role in <strong>the</strong> acquisition of spoken language<br />

(Morgan & Demuth, 1996). It has, never<strong>the</strong>less, been assumed that <strong>the</strong> acoustic properties of human<br />

speech do not contain transparent cues <strong>for</strong> different syntactic levels <strong>and</strong> are <strong>the</strong>re<strong>for</strong>e insufficient <strong>for</strong><br />

acquiring <strong>the</strong> hierarchical structure of syntactic representations (e.g. Shaffran & Wilson, 2003).<br />

Consistent <strong>and</strong> systematic cues <strong>for</strong> some syntactic structures do however exist in prosody (Nespor &<br />

Vogel, 1986) <strong>and</strong> infants as young as 10-months have been shown to exploit Intonational as well as<br />

Phonological Phrase boundaries to constrain lexical access (e.g. Gout, Christophe & Morgan, 2004).<br />

Never<strong>the</strong>less, in order to develop an account of signal driven acquisition of syntax, it is additionally<br />

important to show that humans can use <strong>the</strong> prosodic cues also <strong>for</strong> keeping track of <strong>the</strong> hierarchical<br />

structure present in <strong>the</strong> continuous speech stream.<br />

To test this possibility, we habituated adult native speakers of Italian with an artificial stream of<br />

nonsense syllables <strong>for</strong> two minutes. The stream was structured both at <strong>the</strong> level of “words” as well as<br />

“sentences”. The “words” were tri-syllabic nonsense sequences following long-distance dependency<br />

rules, while <strong>the</strong> “sentences” contained two “words” <strong>and</strong> adhered to different sets of long-distance<br />

dependencies. Importantly, <strong>the</strong> “words” <strong>and</strong> “sentences” could only be extracted in case participants<br />

made use of <strong>the</strong> prosodic in<strong>for</strong>mation that marked: (a) each word by an increase in duration of <strong>the</strong><br />

word-final syllable, <strong>and</strong> (b) each sentence with a declining pitch contour.<br />

In <strong>the</strong> test phase of <strong>the</strong> experiments, participants were queried ei<strong>the</strong>r <strong>for</strong> words or sentences with a<br />

<strong>for</strong>ced choice between two sequences of syllables: (a) one following <strong>the</strong> long-distance dependency<br />

rule, but with a novel surface <strong>for</strong>m; <strong>and</strong> (b) one that violated both <strong>the</strong> long-distance dependency, but<br />

was present in <strong>the</strong> habituation stream.<br />

Our results show that participants chose significantly more syllable sequences that followed <strong>the</strong> longdistance<br />

dependency rule (that could only be extracted using <strong>the</strong> prosodic cues), than syllable<br />

sequences <strong>the</strong>y actually heard during <strong>the</strong> habituation violating <strong>the</strong> rule. These findings demonstrate<br />

that humans are finely tuned to processing prosodic in<strong>for</strong>mation, keeping track of both segmental as<br />

well as hierarchical in<strong>for</strong>mation. The results are discussed in <strong>the</strong> light of recent advances in <strong>the</strong><br />

underst<strong>and</strong>ing of <strong>the</strong> role prosody plays in <strong>the</strong> bootstrapping of syntax.<br />

Notes<br />

184


P132<br />

Perceptual simulations of negated binary-state sentences<br />

Sarah E. Anderson 1 , Simone N. Zuares 2 , & Michael J. Spivey 1<br />

1 <strong>University</strong> of Cali<strong>for</strong>nia, USA, 2 Cornell <strong>University</strong>, USA<br />

E-mail: sec57@cornell.edu<br />

Experimental findings support that comprehension of textual in<strong>for</strong>mation is tied to <strong>the</strong> creation of<br />

perceptual simulations (Barsalou, 1999; Zwaan et al., 2002), but <strong>the</strong> comprehension of negated<br />

sentences does not seem to use <strong>the</strong>se perceptual simulations in <strong>the</strong> same way. Kaup et al. (2007)<br />

presented participants with sentences like, “The eagle was not in <strong>the</strong> sky,” <strong>and</strong> asked participants to<br />

make judgments about whe<strong>the</strong>r a subsequently presented picture was mentioned in <strong>the</strong> sentence <strong>the</strong>y<br />

had just read. If <strong>the</strong> perceptual simulation process can implement negation on its own, <strong>the</strong>n<br />

participants should be quicker to respond “yes” to pictures that match <strong>the</strong> sentence, i.e., an eagle with<br />

its wings folded. Quite <strong>the</strong> opposite, <strong>the</strong>y found that when participants read negated sentences,<br />

response times to a picture that did not match <strong>the</strong> negated sentence (showing <strong>the</strong> eagle in <strong>the</strong> air) were<br />

faster than pictures that did match <strong>the</strong> negated sentence, suggesting that a perceptual simulation of <strong>the</strong><br />

affirmative version of <strong>the</strong> situation was being created in response to a negated sentence.<br />

However, it may be <strong>the</strong> case that when participants read a negated sentence, <strong>the</strong>y do create a<br />

perceptual simulation of <strong>the</strong> negation, but <strong>the</strong> pictures <strong>the</strong>y were asked to respond to did not capture<br />

that simulation. For example, instead of simulating an eagle with its wings folded, perhaps<br />

participants simulate one of a number of o<strong>the</strong>r activities <strong>the</strong> eagle per<strong>for</strong>ms when not in <strong>the</strong> air. In <strong>the</strong><br />

current research, we tested this hypo<strong>the</strong>sis using <strong>the</strong> same experimental paradigm used by Kaup et al.<br />

(2007), but using items that can only be in one of two states, such as a coin that can be heads up or<br />

tails up only. If participants can incorporate negation into <strong>the</strong>ir perceptual simulation, such binary<br />

state objects should constrain <strong>the</strong> range of perceptual simulations possible, <strong>and</strong> we should see faster<br />

reaction times to pictures of <strong>the</strong> negated situation. We found a reliable interaction in which<br />

affirmative sentences elicited faster reaction times to pictures that corresponded to that described state<br />

(e.g., Zwaan et al., 2002) <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> negated versions of those same sentences elicited <strong>the</strong> reverse pattern<br />

<strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> same pairs of pictures, F(1,29)=p


P133<br />

Priming of syntactic attachment between prepositional phrases <strong>and</strong><br />

relative clauses<br />

Maaike Loncke, Sébastien Van Laere, & Timothy Desmet<br />

Ghent <strong>University</strong>, Belgium<br />

E-mail: Maaike.Loncke@ugent.be<br />

Recently, it was shown that <strong>the</strong> (high vs. low) attachment in a relative clause attachment ambiguity<br />

(“Someone shot <strong>the</strong> servant of <strong>the</strong> actress who was on <strong>the</strong> balcony”) is susceptible to priming. Using<br />

sentence completion, Scheepers (Cognition2003) <strong>and</strong> Desmet <strong>and</strong> Declercq (JML2006) found that<br />

participants produced more high-attached relative clauses in target sentences after high-attachment<br />

primes than after low-attachment primes.<br />

The syntactic in<strong>for</strong>mation related to relative clause attachment ambiguity cannot be tied to specific<br />

lexical entries <strong>and</strong> should <strong>the</strong>re<strong>for</strong>e be represented at a more abstract syntactic level. Scheepers (2003)<br />

suggested that people keep a mental record of <strong>the</strong> exact sequence in which <strong>the</strong> phrase structure rules<br />

are applied. Desmet <strong>and</strong> Declercq (2006) suggested that <strong>the</strong> effect could be due to activation of more<br />

general sentence processing principles, such as late closure or predicate proximity, which are not<br />

necessarily tied to specific phrase structure rules.<br />

The present experiment aimed to discriminate between <strong>the</strong>se two explanations. If priming of general<br />

processing principles underlies <strong>the</strong> relative clause attachment priming effect, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> application of<br />

<strong>the</strong>se principles in ano<strong>the</strong>r syntactic structure should also prime relative clause attachments. However,<br />

if <strong>the</strong> priming effect is caused by <strong>the</strong> activation of sequences of specific syntactic phrase structure<br />

rules, <strong>the</strong>n we should not find a priming effect over syntactic structures, as <strong>the</strong>se rules differ between<br />

structures.<br />

We tested whe<strong>the</strong>r a prepositional phrase attachment could prime an ambiguous relative clause<br />

attachment as well as ano<strong>the</strong>r relative clause attachment could. We used prime sentences that <strong>for</strong>ced<br />

to attach ei<strong>the</strong>r a relative clause or a prepositional phrase <strong>and</strong> to attach it ei<strong>the</strong>r high or low. Target<br />

sentences contained an ambiguous relative pronoun, <strong>and</strong> could thus be completed with a high as well<br />

as a low attached relative clause.<br />

Targets were completed more often with a high attachment relative clause after a high attachment<br />

prime (M = 29.36%) than after a low attachment prime (M = 22.64%), F1(1,43) = 4.27, p = .045;<br />

F2(1,23) = 12.70, p = .002. Target attachment was not influenced by prime structure (prepositional<br />

phrase vs. relative clause), Fs < 1. There was no interaction between prime attachment <strong>and</strong> prime<br />

structure (F1(1,43) = 1.34, p = .253; F2(1,23) = 1.06, p = .313).<br />

These results can be explained by <strong>the</strong> activation of more general syntactic procedures (Desmet &<br />

Declercq, 2006) but not by <strong>the</strong> activation of sequences of phrase structure rules (Scheepers, 2003).<br />

Notes<br />

186


P134<br />

Verb repetition is not required <strong>for</strong> structural priming in L2 English<br />

production in Japanese-English bilinguals<br />

Sunfa Kim, Gail Mauner, & Jean-Pierre Koenig<br />

The State <strong>University</strong> of New York at Buffalo, USA<br />

E-mail: sunfakim@buffalo.edu<br />

Repetition of verbs is typically not required to observe structural priming in language production. For<br />

example, Flett et al. (2004) observed L2 to L2 structural priming <strong>for</strong> Spanish actives <strong>and</strong> passives in<br />

English-Spanish bilinguals when verbs varied across primes <strong>and</strong> targets. However, Matsumoto <strong>and</strong><br />

Yamashita (2006) observed L2 to L2 structural priming <strong>for</strong> English double object <strong>and</strong> dative<br />

sentences in Japanese-English bilinguals only when verbs were repeated across primes <strong>and</strong> targets.<br />

Matsumoto <strong>and</strong> Yamashita proposed that <strong>for</strong> Japanese-English bilinguals, L2 English syntactic<br />

in<strong>for</strong>mation is not shared across verbs but ra<strong>the</strong>r is stored on individual verbs. One crucial difference<br />

between <strong>the</strong>se studies is that English (L1) has active <strong>and</strong> passive constructions while Japanese (L1)<br />

has a dative but no double object construction. In cases where constructional alternation does not<br />

exist in L1, L2 learners may represent L2 constructions on a verb by verb basis as Tomasello (2001)<br />

has proposed <strong>for</strong> children’s early syntactic acquisition. We investigated whe<strong>the</strong>r L2 to L2 structural<br />

priming would be observed <strong>for</strong> English active <strong>and</strong> passive sentences in Japanese-English bilinguals<br />

when verbs vary across primes <strong>and</strong> targets. Both Japanese (L1) <strong>and</strong> English (L2) have active <strong>and</strong><br />

passive constructions. Structural priming should only be observed if syntactic representations are<br />

shared across verbs in L2. In addition, we examined whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>matic role assignment influences<br />

sentence <strong>for</strong>mulation in bilinguals as it does in monolinguals (Melinger, 2006). Specifically, we<br />

examined whe<strong>the</strong>r more passives would be produced after unaccusative primes (patient subject: The<br />

teacher arrived early) <strong>and</strong> more actives after unergative primes (agent subject: The girl skated<br />

gracefully).<br />

Japanese-English bilinguals <strong>and</strong> English monolinguals read aloud English active, passive,<br />

unaccusative, or unergative prime sentences <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>n described a 2-participant picture in English<br />

using an auditorily presented verb which differed from <strong>the</strong> prime verb. Both groups produced more<br />

passive structures after passive primes than after active primes, but only L1 English speakers<br />

produced more passives after unaccusative primes. Thus Japanese-English bilinguals demonstrated<br />

sensitivity to <strong>the</strong> syntactic structure of English prime sentences but not to <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>matic roles assigned<br />

to subject NPs. These results indicate that when a syntactic alternation is present in both L1 <strong>and</strong> L2,<br />

L2 syntactic representations are shared across verbs in L2 even though surface word order differs<br />

dramatically between Japanese <strong>and</strong> English.<br />

Notes<br />

187


P135<br />

Mental representation <strong>and</strong> processing of nominal compounds: Evidence<br />

from constituent priming in Italian<br />

Davide Crepaldi 1 , Marco Marelli 2 , & Claudio Luzzatti 2<br />

1 Royal Holloway <strong>University</strong> of London, UK, 2 Universita’ di Milano-Bicocca, Italy<br />

E-mail: davide.crepaldi@rhul.ac.uk<br />

Most studies on compound processing were per<strong>for</strong>med in English <strong>and</strong> Dutch, languages that admit<br />

only head-final compounds: as a consequence, <strong>the</strong> effect of headedness might have been confounded<br />

with that of constituent position (but see [1]). Italian is ideally suited to address this issue, as Noun-<br />

Noun compounds can be ei<strong>the</strong>r head-initial or head-final, with nei<strong>the</strong>r structure being clearly<br />

dominant over <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r. The present study aims at disentangling <strong>the</strong> roles of semantic transparency,<br />

headedness <strong>and</strong> constituent position in <strong>the</strong> processing of Italian compound nouns.<br />

Thirty-two neurologically intact subjects participated in a priming experiment (SOA=300ms) with a<br />

lexical decision task. Forty-eight Noun-Noun compounds were selected as probes; <strong>the</strong>y were ei<strong>the</strong>r<br />

transparent or opaque (e.g., fotocopia, photocopy, vs boccaporto, hatch, lit. mouth+harbour) <strong>and</strong><br />

head-initial or head-final (e.g., fotocopia vs capob<strong>and</strong>a, ring-leader, lit. chief+gang). The four groups<br />

of probes were matched <strong>for</strong> length, surface frequency <strong>and</strong> stem frequency. Each compound probe was<br />

primed by both its initial <strong>and</strong> its final constituent in separate runs; constituent primes were matched<br />

with orthographically similar control words (e.g., capo, chief vs. caso, chance) <strong>for</strong> length, surface<br />

frequency, stem frequency <strong>and</strong> orthographic neighbourhood.<br />

The ANOVA showed a first-level priming effect, with no significant interaction. The<br />

planned-comparison t-tests showed that <strong>the</strong> facilitation effect is modulated by headedness <strong>and</strong><br />

constituent position, i.e. <strong>the</strong>re is no difference when <strong>the</strong> head or <strong>the</strong> modifier were primed in<br />

head-initial compounds, while <strong>the</strong> head elicited a greater effect in head-final compounds (see Figure).<br />

The presence of a priming effect with all kinds of targets suggests that constituents of Italian Noun-<br />

Noun compounds are automatically accessed, independently of semantic transparency, constituent<br />

position <strong>and</strong> headedness. However, <strong>the</strong> latter two factors do modulate constituent priming, with<br />

greater effects elicited by <strong>the</strong> morphological head in head-final compounds; this seems to indicate that<br />

while head-final compounds have a hierarchical head-modifier representation, head-initial<br />

compounds do not.<br />

References<br />

[1] Jarema G. et al. (1999). Processing compounds: A crosslinguistic study. <strong>Brain</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Language</strong>, 68,<br />

362–369.<br />

188


FIGURE: Priming effect plotted against <strong>the</strong> position of <strong>the</strong> primed constituent (X axis) <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

compound type (separate lines).<br />

90<br />

70<br />

t(46) = 0.98<br />

n.s.<br />

Priming effect (ms)<br />

50<br />

t(46) = 2.12<br />

p


P136<br />

Do readers try to salvage incorrect sentences An ERP-study<br />

Els Severens, & Robert J. Hartsuiker<br />

Ghent <strong>University</strong>, Belgium<br />

E-mail: els.severens@ugent.be<br />

Errors of subject-verb number agreement sometimes occur in spontaneous speech <strong>and</strong> writing, <strong>and</strong><br />

thus readers can encounter errors like “<strong>the</strong> bag with <strong>the</strong> letters were printed with <strong>the</strong> logo of <strong>the</strong> Royal<br />

Mail”. How does <strong>the</strong> language comprehension system react when confronted with a verb that does not<br />

match with <strong>the</strong> subject in number It is possible that <strong>the</strong> reader computes agreement with <strong>the</strong> first<br />

noun phrase, which is <strong>the</strong> subject in canonical sentences of English <strong>and</strong> Dutch, detects a number<br />

clash, <strong>and</strong> perceives an error. However, it is also possible that upon detection of <strong>the</strong> number clash, <strong>the</strong><br />

parser adopts an alternative, non-canonical analysis, which would (temporarily) salvage grammatical<br />

correctness. This is possible <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> Dutch translation of “<strong>the</strong> bag with <strong>the</strong> letters were...”, which can<br />

be completed with a post-verbal subject (“...<strong>the</strong>y missing", meaning "<strong>the</strong>y were missing <strong>the</strong> bag with<br />

<strong>the</strong> letters"). According to this account, error perception can be delayed until <strong>the</strong> sentence is<br />

disambiguated between canonical/erroneous <strong>and</strong> noncanoncial/correct (“printed” in <strong>the</strong> example).<br />

To test this, we presented participants with Dutch sentences containing agreement errors <strong>and</strong><br />

measured <strong>the</strong> on-line effects on comprehension using EEG. We used a distributive (De postzegel op<br />

de brieven is/zijn bedrukt [The stamp on <strong>the</strong> letters is/are printed]) or nondistributive subject (De<br />

fietstas met de brieven is/zijn bedrukt [The bag with <strong>the</strong> letters is/are printed]). Distributive sentences,<br />

in which <strong>the</strong> subject is notionally plural, elicit more errors (plural verbs) than non-distributive<br />

sentences in production (e.g., Vigliocco et al., 1996); one thus might expect this factor to modulate<br />

<strong>the</strong> brain response to agreement errors in comprehension (with a weaker response <strong>for</strong> distributive<br />

sentences). But importantly, a self-paced reading pretest demonstrated that it is easier to process postverbal<br />

subjects following <strong>the</strong> non-distributive noun phrases. If readers can adopt such an analysis to<br />

salvage grammatical well-<strong>for</strong>medness, <strong>the</strong>y should be more likely to do so in <strong>the</strong> non-distributive<br />

condition. This instead predicts delayed brain responses to violations in non-distributive sentences.<br />

In <strong>the</strong> distributive condition we found a LAN <strong>and</strong> a P600 <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> incorrect verbs compared to <strong>the</strong><br />

correct verbs, consistent with o<strong>the</strong>r ERP studies that presented morphosyntactic violations.<br />

Importantly, in <strong>the</strong> non-distributive condition (which more readily allows a post-verbal subject) <strong>the</strong>re<br />

was no LAN or P600, but <strong>the</strong>re was a LAN on <strong>the</strong> (disambiguating) word following <strong>the</strong> incorrect<br />

verb. These findings thus confirm <strong>the</strong> view that <strong>the</strong> parser ra<strong>the</strong>r adopts a noncanonical but<br />

grammatically correct analysis, than a canonical analysis with a grammatical violation.<br />

References<br />

Vigliocco, G., Hartsuiker, R. J., Jarema, G., & Kolk, H. H. J. (1996). One or more labels on <strong>the</strong><br />

bottles Notional concord in Dutch <strong>and</strong> French. <strong>Language</strong> <strong>and</strong> Cognitive Processes, 11(4), 407-<br />

442.<br />

Notes<br />

190


Self-paced listening with picture verification: A new paradigm to<br />

investigate on-line sentence processing in children <strong>and</strong> adults<br />

P137<br />

Theodoros Marinis, Vasiliki Chondrogianni, & Halit Firat<br />

<strong>University</strong> of Reading, UK<br />

E-mail: t.marinis@reading.ac.uk<br />

This paper presents a novel paradigm that was designed to provide a child-friendly procedure to<br />

investigate on-line sentence comprehension in typically <strong>and</strong> atypically developing monolingual (L1)<br />

<strong>and</strong> bilingual (L2) children. The task combines self-paced listening with picture verification.<br />

Participants first see a picture on <strong>the</strong> computer screen in order to create a mental representation of <strong>the</strong><br />

scene. Then <strong>the</strong>y listen to a sentence in a segment-by-segment fashion by pressing a button while <strong>the</strong><br />

picture remains on <strong>the</strong> computer screen. Reaction Times (RTs) are recorded <strong>for</strong> each segment<br />

similarly to a self-paced listening task. Half of <strong>the</strong> sentences match <strong>the</strong> picture <strong>and</strong> <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r half<br />

<strong>the</strong>re is a mismatch between <strong>the</strong> sentence <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> picture. At <strong>the</strong> end of each sentence, participants are<br />

asked whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>re was a match or a mismatch between <strong>the</strong> sentence <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> picture. This keeps<br />

participants on task, <strong>and</strong> provides off-line data on how accurate <strong>the</strong>y are in comprehending <strong>the</strong><br />

sentences.<br />

We used this task to investigate how L1 <strong>and</strong> L2 children <strong>and</strong> adults process actives/passives <strong>and</strong><br />

pronouns/reflexives in real-time. Match/mismatch was compared through a minimal pair. In <strong>the</strong> task<br />

with actives/passives, this involved <strong>the</strong> inflectional suffixes of <strong>the</strong> present/past participle, as shown in<br />

(1) <strong>and</strong> (2) below.<br />

(1) I think/that/<strong>the</strong> zebra/was kissing/<strong>the</strong> camel/at <strong>the</strong> zoo/last Monday<br />

(2) I think/that/<strong>the</strong> zebra/was kissed/by <strong>the</strong> camel/at <strong>the</strong> zoo/last Monday<br />

Until <strong>the</strong> verb, it is ambiguous as to whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>re is a match or mismatch between <strong>the</strong> picture <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

sentence. The disambiguating in<strong>for</strong>mation is encoded in <strong>the</strong> inflectional suffix of <strong>the</strong> participle (–<br />

ing/–ed) which constitutes <strong>the</strong> critical segment in this experiment. The rationale of <strong>the</strong> task is that RTs<br />

in <strong>the</strong> mismatch condition of <strong>the</strong> critical segment will be longer than in <strong>the</strong> matching condition if<br />

participants process <strong>the</strong> morpho-syntactic in<strong>for</strong>mation <strong>and</strong> assign <strong>the</strong>matic roles rapidly be<strong>for</strong>e <strong>the</strong><br />

end of <strong>the</strong> sentence. This was borne out in both experiments. In <strong>the</strong> critical segment, mismatch<br />

conditions showed significantly longer RTs than matching conditions. The present talk will introduce<br />

<strong>the</strong> task, present data on actives/passives <strong>and</strong> pronouns/reflexives from 20 adults, 30 6;9-8;9 year old<br />

English L1 children, <strong>and</strong> 28 6;10-8;8 year-old children with English as L2, <strong>and</strong> will discuss <strong>the</strong><br />

advantages <strong>and</strong> disadvantages of this task compared to o<strong>the</strong>r tasks (word-monitoring, self-paced<br />

listening, cross-modal priming) that have been used in <strong>the</strong> past to investigate on-line sentence<br />

processing in children.<br />

Notes<br />

191


P138<br />

The representation of L2 syntax is influenced by second-language<br />

proficiency: Evidence from cross-linguistic syntactic priming<br />

Sarah Bernolet 1 , Marloes Bressers 2 , Robert J. Hartsuiker 1 , & Martin J. Pickering 3<br />

1 Ghent <strong>University</strong>, Belgium, 2 Radboud <strong>University</strong> Nijmegen, The Ne<strong>the</strong>rl<strong>and</strong>s,<br />

3 <strong>University</strong> of Edinburgh, UK<br />

E-mail: sarah.bernolet@ugent.be<br />

Evidence from cross-linguistic syntactic priming suggests that bilinguals can share syntactic<br />

representations across languages (e.g., Bernolet, Hartsuiker & Pickering, 2007; Hartsuiker, Pickering<br />

& Veltkamp, 2004). The current study investigates how <strong>the</strong>se shared representations are established<br />

in late learners of a second language. Specifically, are representations of syntactic structures in a<br />

second language (L2) immediately collapsed with similar structures of <strong>the</strong> first language (L1) when<br />

<strong>the</strong>y are learned or are <strong>the</strong>y initially represented separately<br />

In order to investigate this question, we studied within- <strong>and</strong> between-language syntactic priming <strong>for</strong><br />

English genitives (<strong>the</strong> ball of <strong>the</strong> boy is green (of-genitive) vs. <strong>the</strong> boy’s ball is green (Saxon<br />

genitive)) in late Dutch-English bilinguals. The bilinguals in our study learned <strong>the</strong>ir L2 around <strong>the</strong><br />

same age <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>y all lived in an L1 dominant environment. They only differed in <strong>the</strong>ir level of selfrated<br />

L2 proficiency, on <strong>the</strong> basis of which <strong>the</strong>y were divided in two proficiency groups. Experiment<br />

1 (L2-L2) showed within-language priming of English genitives <strong>for</strong> both less proficient (48.7%<br />

priming) <strong>and</strong> more proficient bilinguals (54.5% priming). In Experiment 2 (L1-L2), <strong>the</strong> English<br />

genitives were primed with Dutch genitives that are identical to <strong>the</strong>ir English equivalent or slightly<br />

different: The of-genitive is identical in both languages (<strong>the</strong> ball of <strong>the</strong> boy – de bal van de jongen),<br />

while <strong>the</strong> Dutch <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> English Saxon genitive differ in <strong>the</strong>ir realization of <strong>the</strong> possessive marker<br />

(<strong>the</strong> boy’s ball – de jongen zijn bal). In this experiment, <strong>the</strong> between-language priming effect<br />

interacted with <strong>the</strong> participant’s proficiency level: For less proficient bilinguals, no between-language<br />

priming was observed (1.5%), while <strong>for</strong> more proficient bilinguals, significant cross-linguistic<br />

priming (25.9%) between Dutch <strong>and</strong> English genitives was obtained. Hence, our results indicate that<br />

<strong>the</strong>re is a shift from separate syntactic representations <strong>for</strong> L2 structures in less proficient late<br />

bilinguals to shared representations in more proficient late bilinguals.<br />

References<br />

Bernolet, S., Hartsuiker, R. J., & Pickering, M. J. (2007). Shared syntactic representations in<br />

bilinguals: Evidence <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> role of word-order repetition. Journal of Experimental Psychology:<br />

Learning, Memory, <strong>and</strong> Cognition, 33, 931-949.<br />

Hartsuiker, R. J., Pickering, M. J., & Veltkamp, E. (2004). Is syntax separate or shared between<br />

languages Cross-linguistic syntactic priming in Spanish-English bilinguals. Psychological<br />

Science, 15, 409-414.<br />

Notes<br />

192


A <strong>the</strong>ory of processing difficulty based on syntactic prediction<br />

P139<br />

Vera Demberg, & Frank Keller<br />

The <strong>University</strong> of Edinburgh, UK<br />

E-mail: v.demberg@ed.ac.uk<br />

Recent work in sentence processing suggests that comprehenders make predictions while <strong>the</strong>y process<br />

language: not only do <strong>the</strong>y integrate new words incrementally with previous input, but <strong>the</strong>y also<br />

anticipate upcoming linguistic material (Kamide et al., JML 2003). We propose a model of syntactic<br />

processing difficulty based on <strong>the</strong> explicit prediction of syntactic categories. The model is word-byword<br />

incremental <strong>and</strong> assumes that fully connected syntactic structures are built. Alternative<br />

structures <strong>for</strong> ambiguous input are processed in parallel, with a search beam to capture memory<br />

limitations. The assumptions of <strong>the</strong> proposed model are:<br />

* At each word, a set E of syntactic expectations e is generated; an expectation is an incomplete<br />

syntactic structure that denotes <strong>the</strong> categories needed to build a grammatical sentence from <strong>the</strong><br />

current input.<br />

* Expectations are held in memory in parallel, <strong>and</strong> have a probability P(e).<br />

* Decay is modeled by a decay function f which takes into account <strong>the</strong> timestamp t corresponding<br />

to when a structure was first predicted, or last activated.<br />

* Processing difficulty is incurred ei<strong>the</strong>r when expectations become incompatible with <strong>the</strong> current<br />

input (denoted by <strong>the</strong> set of discarded structures E_d; this bears similarities to analyses changing<br />

ranks as in Jurafsky, Cogsci J 1996), or when successful integration takes place (denoted by <strong>the</strong><br />

set of integrated structures E_i).<br />

We can <strong>the</strong>n <strong>for</strong>malize <strong>the</strong> processing difficulty D_w at word w as:<br />

D_w = SUM{e:E_i} f(1/P(e)) + SUM{e:E_d} f(P(e))<br />

To implement this model, we use an incremental version of tree-adjoining grammar (TAG), as<br />

proposed by Demberg & Keller (TAG Conf 2008).<br />

The proposed model is attractive because it incorporates cognitive concepts such as memory<br />

limitations <strong>and</strong> decay <strong>and</strong> accounts <strong>for</strong> a wide range of empirical phenomena:<br />

* locality effects (Gibson, Cognition 1998): <strong>the</strong> more dependents are integrated (E_i), <strong>the</strong> more<br />

processing cost is incurred, subject to a distance-based decay function f;<br />

* surprisal effects (Hale, NAACL 2001): <strong>the</strong> more expectations are discarded (E_d), <strong>the</strong> more<br />

processing cost in incurred;<br />

* digging-in effects (Tabor & Hutchins, JEP 2004): discarding expectations that have been<br />

maintained longer is more costly (decay function f).<br />

* prediction (Staub & Clifton, JEP 2006): syntactic categories are predicted explicitly as part of <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong>for</strong>malism;<br />

* ambiguity resolution <strong>and</strong> garden paths: accounted <strong>for</strong> by probabilistically ranked parallelism as<br />

proposed by Jurafsky (1996).<br />

Notes<br />

193


P140<br />

Clefting, topicalization <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> given-new preference: Eyetracking<br />

evidence from Hindi<br />

Rukshin F. Shaher 1 , Pavel Logacev 1 , Felix Engelmann 1 , Shravan Vasishth 1 ,<br />

& Narayanan Srinivasan 2<br />

1 <strong>University</strong> of Potsdam, Germany, 2 <strong>University</strong> of Allahabad, India<br />

E-mail: vasishth@acm.org<br />

Readers detect focused in<strong>for</strong>mation more quickly <strong>and</strong> accurately, <strong>and</strong> remember it better than nonfocused<br />

in<strong>for</strong>mation. E.g., in a probe recognition <strong>and</strong> naming task Birch <strong>and</strong> Garnsey (1995) showed<br />

that clefted nouns ('It was a…') can be named faster than non-clefted ones. This facilitation due to<br />

focusing implies that in<strong>for</strong>mation-structure marking can exert an influence on <strong>the</strong> activation of items<br />

in memory, independent of working memory factors such as decay <strong>and</strong>/or interference. Indeed, using<br />

a speed-accuracy tradeoff study <strong>and</strong> an eyetracking experiment Foraker & McElree (2007) show that<br />

clefting a noun improves its availability in online sentence comprehension.<br />

We extend this work by showing that: (i) <strong>the</strong>re is an initial processing cost (ENCODING COST)<br />

associated with encoding a focused element; (ii) but this results in richer encoding, which facilitates<br />

later processing (INTEGRATION ADVANTAGE); <strong>and</strong> (iii) <strong>the</strong> integration advantage interacts with<br />

<strong>the</strong> well-known given-be<strong>for</strong>e-new ordering preference: <strong>the</strong> clefted (sentence-initial) element is easier<br />

to process when it is new (not previously mentioned) ra<strong>the</strong>r than given.<br />

A Hindi eyetracking study (n=32) was carried out that involved Hindi clefted sentences read in<br />

context; <strong>the</strong> factors clefting <strong>and</strong> given-new order were manipulated. We found that clefting a noun<br />

resulted in higher first-pass regression probability at <strong>the</strong> noun (ENCODING COST) but faster rereading<br />

time at <strong>the</strong> noun as well as at a subsequent integration region (INTEGRATION<br />

ADVANTAGE). In addition, although whole sentence total reading time showed a given-new<br />

advantage (confirming <strong>the</strong> received opinion that given-new order is easier to process), <strong>the</strong> clefted<br />

word itself was read faster when it was new ra<strong>the</strong>r than given.We replicated <strong>the</strong> above findings<br />

through a second eyetracking experiment (n=32) involving Hindi left-dislocated topicalizations that<br />

superficially resemble clefts but have a different in<strong>for</strong>mation-structuring function (topic-shifting).<br />

In sum, we present new evidence from online sentence comprehension that syntactic in<strong>for</strong>mationstructure<br />

markers such as clefts <strong>and</strong> left-dislocated topics serve to enhance <strong>the</strong> availability of <strong>the</strong><br />

clefted/topicalized element, although an initial cost is incurred in encoding focused/topicalized words.<br />

We also argue that <strong>the</strong> given-new preference may apply only in later integrative processes that occur<br />

after parsing completes.<br />

References<br />

Birch & Garnsey 1995. Journal of Memory <strong>and</strong> <strong>Language</strong>.Volume 34.<br />

Foraker & McElree 2007. Journal of Memory <strong>and</strong> <strong>Language</strong>.Volume 56.<br />

Notes<br />

194


P141<br />

<strong>Speech</strong> perception involves statistically optimal multi-modal integration<br />

Vikranth R. Bejjanki, Meghan Clayards, David C. Knill, & Richard N. Aslin<br />

<strong>University</strong> of Rochester, USA<br />

E-mail: vrao@bcs.rochester.edu<br />

During speech perception, visual in<strong>for</strong>mation conveyed by <strong>the</strong> speaker’s facial movements has a<br />

significant effect on <strong>the</strong> perception of auditory in<strong>for</strong>mation. Indeed, a large body of evidence suggests<br />

that speech perception involves <strong>the</strong> integration of in<strong>for</strong>mation from <strong>the</strong> visual <strong>and</strong> auditory<br />

modalities. What is <strong>the</strong> computational principle that governs such integration Previous work on<br />

multi-modal integration along continuous perceptual dimensions (e.g. position or size) has suggested<br />

that a statistically optimal strategy called Maximum Likelihood Estimation (MLE) is a good<br />

description of human per<strong>for</strong>mance in many tasks. In particular, studies have consistently found that<br />

participants weight in<strong>for</strong>mation from each of several cues, by that cue’s reliability relative to <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

cues.<br />

We propose that human per<strong>for</strong>mance in multi-modal, categorical speech perception is also well<br />

described by an MLE model. Behavioral experiments were designed to provide a quantitative<br />

estimate of in<strong>for</strong>mation integration during speech perception. We measured participants’ per<strong>for</strong>mance<br />

in separate unimodal phonetic labelling tasks (/ba/ or /da/ labelling) using ei<strong>the</strong>r visual in<strong>for</strong>mation<br />

provided by a video of a virtual speaker or audio in<strong>for</strong>mation provided by syn<strong>the</strong>sized phonemes,<br />

from a ba-da continuum. We used <strong>the</strong> slopes of <strong>the</strong> psychometric functions associated with each<br />

modality to construct an MLE estimator to predict <strong>the</strong> optimal combination of visual <strong>and</strong> auditory<br />

inputs in a bi-modal phonetic labelling task. We compared participants’ per<strong>for</strong>mance in <strong>the</strong> same bimodal<br />

task to <strong>the</strong> predictions of <strong>the</strong> MLE estimator. The MLE model reliably predicted human<br />

per<strong>for</strong>mance in our task – weights assigned to each modality depended on <strong>the</strong> modality’s relative<br />

reliability.<br />

We <strong>the</strong>n tested a stronger prediction of <strong>the</strong> MLE model. Decreasing <strong>the</strong> reliability of a modality<br />

should decrease <strong>the</strong> weight assigned to that modality <strong>and</strong> increase <strong>the</strong> weight assigned to <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

modality. We accomplished this by blurring <strong>the</strong> visual stimuli <strong>and</strong> testing participants, using <strong>the</strong>se<br />

new stimuli, in <strong>the</strong> unimodal <strong>and</strong> bi-modal labelling tasks. Per<strong>for</strong>mance was again well predicted by<br />

<strong>the</strong> MLE model. Assigned weights to <strong>the</strong> visual modality accurately tracked visual reliability – even<br />

on a trial by trial basis. We conclude that humans are dynamically optimal in perceiving speech from<br />

visual <strong>and</strong> auditory in<strong>for</strong>mation.<br />

Acknowledgements<br />

We thank Dominic Massaro <strong>for</strong> providing <strong>the</strong> original visual stimuli. This work was supported by<br />

ONR-MURI research grant (N000140510834).<br />

Notes<br />

195


P142<br />

Stimulation of Broca’s area causes better error detection in an artificial<br />

language: a tDCS study<br />

Meinou H. De Vries, André Barth, Stefan Knecht, Pienie Zwitserlood, & Agnes Floeel<br />

<strong>University</strong> of Münster, Germany<br />

E-mail: mdevries@uni-muenster.de<br />

Artificial grammar learning (AGL) is a <strong>for</strong>m of cognitive implicit learning, <strong>and</strong> Broca’s area (BA<br />

44/45) is generally identified as <strong>the</strong> neural circuitry underlying this. The AGL paradigm involves a<br />

visual presentation of a series of letter strings generated by a finite state grammar. After being<br />

presented to <strong>the</strong>se strings, people can distinguish new strings on whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>y are <strong>for</strong>med by this<br />

grammar or not – although <strong>the</strong>y cannot verbalize what <strong>the</strong>y just have learned. These classification<br />

judgments are based on <strong>the</strong> implicit knowledge of <strong>the</strong> rule system, as well as on how familiar <strong>the</strong> new<br />

items look to <strong>the</strong> trained items.<br />

In this pilot study, we investigated <strong>the</strong> role of Broca’s area in <strong>the</strong> classical AGL paradigm, by<br />

stimulating Broca’s area by anodal tDCS (transcranial direct current stimulation). We tested 10<br />

participants, of which 5 received stimulation, <strong>and</strong> 5 were in <strong>the</strong> sham condition. All strings were<br />

controlled <strong>for</strong> string familiarity.<br />

In our analysis, we had to exclude one participant due to extremely slow reaction times. Our results<br />

reveal only a slight improvement in <strong>the</strong> general learning success (% correct responses) <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> tDCS<br />

group. However, <strong>the</strong> nature of responding significantly differs in both groups. There is a general<br />

tendency <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> sham group to base <strong>the</strong>ir judgments more often on superficial similarity of <strong>the</strong> strings<br />

than in <strong>the</strong> tDCS group, suggesting that <strong>the</strong> latter was better able to extrapolate <strong>the</strong> grammatical rules<br />

that <strong>the</strong>y just had learned. However, this effect was significant only in <strong>the</strong> case of correct error<br />

detection: <strong>the</strong> tDCS group per<strong>for</strong>med significantly better on correct rejections, even when <strong>the</strong>se were<br />

highly familiar with <strong>the</strong> strings that <strong>the</strong>y had been trained on. Overall, this leads to significantly<br />

different d’ scores, indeed indicating a better per<strong>for</strong>mance <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> tDCS group on artificial grammar<br />

learning.<br />

Afterwards, <strong>the</strong> participants were instructed to per<strong>for</strong>m a transfer task, making grammatical<br />

judgments on 20 strings that followed <strong>the</strong> same grammar, but contained different letters (i.e., without<br />

superficial similarity). The differences between <strong>the</strong> tDCS group <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> sham group <strong>for</strong> correct<br />

rejections became even bigger: whereas <strong>the</strong> tDCS group was still able to per<strong>for</strong>m remarkably well on<br />

correct error detection, <strong>the</strong> sham group dropped down fur<strong>the</strong>r in per<strong>for</strong>mance, indicating <strong>the</strong> ability to<br />

extrapolate rules as a prerequisite <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> transfer task.<br />

We have shown that stimulating Broca’s area when learning an artificial grammar results in a better<br />

ability to extrapolate rules, resulting in better error detection.<br />

Notes<br />

196


P143<br />

The locus of attention in <strong>the</strong> mapping of motion events onto a visual world<br />

Yuki Kamide<br />

<strong>University</strong> of Dundee, UK<br />

E-mail: y.kamide@dundee.ac.uk<br />

In recent years, a growing amount of research has explored <strong>the</strong> mechanism by which linguistic <strong>and</strong><br />

visual in<strong>for</strong>mation interact in language comprehension. In particular, several studies have focused on<br />

<strong>the</strong> question of how representations of a motion event are mapped onto listeners’ mental space (e.g.,<br />

Richardson & Matlock, 2007; Zwaan et al., 2004). Such studies have implications <strong>for</strong> accounts<br />

claiming that language comprehension involves mental simulations of states/events described in <strong>the</strong><br />

linguistic input (Barsalou, 1999; Glenberg, 1997).<br />

Previously, Kamide (2007; AMLaP Poster) showed that <strong>the</strong> locus of listeners’ attention can be<br />

modulated by <strong>the</strong> trajectory implied by a verb. In a signal detection experiment, participants were<br />

presented with a picture containing two objects (e.g., a ball, a bin lying on <strong>the</strong> floor) <strong>and</strong> an auditory<br />

sentence containing a verb ei<strong>the</strong>r implying an upwards-curving trajectory, or a straight one (e.g., ‘The<br />

ball will be thrown/rolled into <strong>the</strong> bin.’). At verb offset, a very small signal was presented <strong>for</strong> 50 ms<br />

on a motion path plausible <strong>for</strong> one of <strong>the</strong> two verbs. Results suggested that <strong>the</strong> signal was detected<br />

faster when <strong>the</strong> position of <strong>the</strong> signal roughly matched <strong>the</strong> (implied) motion path than when it didn’t.<br />

Thus, it was suggested that listeners shifted <strong>the</strong>ir attention along <strong>the</strong> path of <strong>the</strong> object implied by <strong>the</strong><br />

verb.<br />

The present experiment investigates ano<strong>the</strong>r type of semantic in<strong>for</strong>mation in English motion verbs:<br />

instead of <strong>the</strong> shape of trajectory, <strong>the</strong> specificity of <strong>the</strong> trajectory is examined. Verbs that imply a<br />

specific trajectory (e.g., roll) were contrasted with those that don’t (e.g., take). It can be argued that<br />

“non-specific” verbs place linguistic focus on <strong>the</strong> end state of <strong>the</strong> motion event, ra<strong>the</strong>r than <strong>the</strong><br />

object’s trajectory. The present experiment examines <strong>the</strong> time-course of application of such subtle<br />

semantic in<strong>for</strong>mation using <strong>the</strong> same technique as Kamide (2007). Two sentences were created <strong>for</strong><br />

each of <strong>the</strong> original visual scenes (e.g., ‘The ball will be rolled/taken into <strong>the</strong> bin,’). Signals were<br />

presented at verb offset ei<strong>the</strong>r on <strong>the</strong> motion path or near <strong>the</strong> goal object. Results showed that <strong>the</strong><br />

matching conditions (roll/path; take/goal) elicited faster detection times than <strong>the</strong> mismatching<br />

conditions (roll/goal; take/path), indicating listeners’ rapid attention shifts in accordance with motion<br />

in<strong>for</strong>mation implied by <strong>the</strong> verb. The findings will be discussed in <strong>the</strong> light of recent accounts <strong>and</strong><br />

experimental studies (e.g., Papafragou et al., 2008).<br />

Notes<br />

197


P144<br />

Does 'you' help you retrieve 'ewe' TOT evidence on frequency inheritance<br />

Carson T. Schütze 1 , Tamar H. Gollan 2 , & Mary K. Champion 2<br />

1 <strong>University</strong> of Cali<strong>for</strong>nia, Los Angeles, USA, 2 <strong>University</strong> of Cali<strong>for</strong>nia, San Diego, USA<br />

E-mail: cschutze@humanities.ucla.edu<br />

Frequency is a powerful predictor of retrieval success, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> nature of frequency effects in language<br />

production is vigorously debated. On one view <strong>the</strong>y arise at <strong>the</strong> level of word <strong>for</strong>m, independent of<br />

word meaning; evidence <strong>for</strong> this is that homophones (e.g. EWE) may inherit <strong>the</strong> frequency of <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

higher frequency counterparts (YOU; Jescheniak & Levelt 1994). But recent work challenges <strong>the</strong><br />

existence of homophone frequency inheritance (e.g., Caramazza et al. 2001). We bring novel<br />

evidence to bear on this question by eliciting tip-of-<strong>the</strong>-tongue (TOT) states <strong>for</strong> very low frequency<br />

(LF) homophone targets (e.g., bicycle SPOKE). TOTs allow consideration of <strong>the</strong> possibility that<br />

frequency inheritance may be more easily detected among <strong>the</strong> least frequent words—where small<br />

frequency differences have large effects—<strong>and</strong> when retrieval fails.<br />

TOTs increase as frequency decreases; thus, if homophones share a single <strong>for</strong>m representation, <strong>the</strong>y<br />

should elicit fewer TOTs than matched LF controls. On <strong>the</strong> opposing view, TOT likelihood should<br />

correlate with <strong>the</strong> specific frequency of target homophones alone. To test <strong>the</strong>se predictions we created<br />

56 triplets with homophone targets (e.g., URN), specific frequency-matched “LF controls” (WICK),<br />

<strong>and</strong> cumulative frequency-matched “HF controls” (VAN). These were used to elicit TOTs from<br />

monolingual English speakers using definitions, pictures, or both. Response measures included TOT<br />

rates, correct response rates (GOTs), failed recognition rates (postDKs), <strong>and</strong> reaction times (RTs) <strong>for</strong><br />

correct responses. Homophones elicited significantly more TOTs, fewer GOTs, slower correct RTs,<br />

<strong>and</strong> more postDKs than HF controls (all ps < .01). Unexpectedly, homophones also showed more<br />

TOTs <strong>and</strong> fewer GOTs than LF controls (ps < .05). However, subsequent analyses factoring out<br />

independently-rated effectiveness of TOT stimuli <strong>for</strong> eliciting target words left no differences<br />

between homophones <strong>and</strong> LF controls on any measure (ps > .30); differences from HF controls<br />

remained (ps < .01). Correlational analyses showed that specific frequency predicts homophone<br />

retrievability (ps < .05) but cumulative frequency does not (ps > .25). Our results demonstrate that<br />

only <strong>the</strong> specific link between meaning <strong>and</strong> <strong>for</strong>m predicts retrieval success.<br />

References<br />

Caramazza, A., Costa, A., Miozzo, M., & Bi, Y. (2001). The specific-word frequency effect:<br />

Implications <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> representation of homophones. JEP:LMC 27, 1430–1450.<br />

Jescheniak, J.D., & Levelt, W.J.M. (1994). Word frequency effects in speech production: Retrieval of<br />

syntactic in<strong>for</strong>mation <strong>and</strong> of phonological <strong>for</strong>m. JEP:LMC 20, 824–843.<br />

Notes<br />

198


P145<br />

Negation reveals preferences in long distance dependency <strong>for</strong>mation<br />

Zeynep Ilkin, & Patrick Sturt<br />

<strong>University</strong> of Edinburgh, UK<br />

E-mail: z.ilkin@ed.ac.uk<br />

Humans show a preference <strong>for</strong> <strong>for</strong>ming long-distance dependencies at <strong>the</strong> first potential gap position<br />

(Frazier&Clifton,1989) However in head final structures like; [Filler...Gap1...[...Gap2...V2]...V1]<br />

<strong>the</strong> embedded verb (V2) precedes <strong>the</strong> main verb (V1), so Gap2 is <strong>the</strong> first gap position that will allow<br />

a <strong>the</strong>matic role assignment of <strong>the</strong> filler, although it is structurally <strong>the</strong> most distant. Here we report 2<br />

reading time studies <strong>and</strong> a sentence completion test exploring <strong>the</strong> time course of gap projection. In<br />

Turkish a neg(ative) NP (“Nobody”) needs neg morphology on its licensing verb. If a neg NP is an<br />

embedded verb argument, <strong>the</strong>re will be processing difficulty if <strong>the</strong> embedded verb lacks neg<br />

morphology, but if <strong>the</strong> NP is interpreted as a main clause argument, a similar effect should be found<br />

at <strong>the</strong> main verb. We orthogonally manipulated <strong>the</strong> ambiguous dative NPs, (“Nobody” vs.<br />

“Somebody”), <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>for</strong>m of <strong>the</strong> embedded <strong>and</strong> main verbs (if subordinate verb was neg, <strong>the</strong> main<br />

verb was affirmative, <strong>and</strong> vice-versa). In exp 1 <strong>the</strong> ambiguous dative NP was sentence initial, in exp 2<br />

it followed <strong>the</strong> matrix subject but preceded <strong>the</strong> embedded subject.<br />

In exp1 <strong>and</strong> exp2 at <strong>the</strong> embedded verb, <strong>the</strong>re was no hint of an interaction so no evidence <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

embedded clause interpretation. However, <strong>the</strong> main verb showed an interaction; (affirmative verbs<br />

were slow following “Nobody” <strong>and</strong> vice versa <strong>for</strong> neg verbs): clear preference <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> main-clause<br />

interpretation. Again, in <strong>the</strong> off-line completion data, dative NPs were overwhelmingly associated<br />

with <strong>the</strong> matrix predicates ra<strong>the</strong>r than <strong>the</strong> embedded predicates, regardless of <strong>the</strong> negative NP's<br />

position However <strong>the</strong>re was some evidence of neg priming on <strong>the</strong> embedded verbs, despite clear<br />

matrix-clause disambiguation.<br />

In similar constructions in Japanese, Aoshima et al (AeA) (2004, JML) found that sentence-initial<br />

dative wh-NPs were associated with <strong>the</strong> embedded verb on-line, in contrast to our results. One<br />

interpretation of AeA's results might be that <strong>the</strong> parser tries to satisfy morphological requirements as<br />

soon as possible, leading to an embedded clause interpretation (Japanese has an obligatory scopemarking<br />

question-particle, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> embedded verb is <strong>the</strong> first opportunity to place it). However, our<br />

results don't support this: <strong>the</strong> Turkish requirement <strong>for</strong> neg verbal morphology didn't lead to an<br />

embedded clause interpretation. It is possible that AeA's embedded clause preference reflects some<br />

special property of wh-questions. Future work with Turkish wh-questions (which don't have questionparticles)<br />

will examine this issue fur<strong>the</strong>r.<br />

Notes<br />

199


P146<br />

Native versus non-native processing asymmetries in noun/verb morphology<br />

Adam Zawiszewski 1 , Beatriz Fernández 2 , & Itziar Laka 2<br />

1 Max Planck Institute <strong>for</strong> Human Cognitive <strong>and</strong> <strong>Brain</strong> Sciences, Leipzig, Germany,<br />

2 <strong>University</strong> of <strong>the</strong> Basque Country, Spain<br />

E-mail: zawis@cbs.mpg.de<br />

Very proficient non-native speakers (Age of Acquisition 1 to 5) process some aspects of grammar<br />

unlike native speakers [1], but <strong>the</strong> extent to which specific components of grammar show<br />

maturational effects is still not well-known. Here we present <strong>the</strong> results of an Event-Related <strong>Brain</strong><br />

potentials (ERP) study on noun <strong>and</strong> verb morphology in Basque: our results show a maturational<br />

effect <strong>for</strong> noun morphology (case) but not <strong>for</strong> verb morphology (agreement). In our ungrammatical<br />

(*) stimuli (1) <strong>the</strong> subject of <strong>the</strong> sentence lacks case morphology (suffix –k) <strong>and</strong> in <strong>the</strong> ungrammatical<br />

condition in (2) <strong>the</strong> auxiliary verb does not contain <strong>the</strong> required object agreement morpheme (prefix<br />

na-):<br />

1. Goiz-ean ogia erosi d-u-t ni-k /*ni denda-n.<br />

Morning-in bread-Obj bought it-have-I I-Subj/*I-Obj shop-in<br />

‘In <strong>the</strong> morning I bought bread in <strong>the</strong> shop’<br />

2. Zu-k ni hondartza-ra eramaten na-u-zu /*d-u-zu batzuetan<br />

You-Subj I-Obj beach-to take me-have-you/*it-have-you sometimes<br />

‘Sometimes you take me to <strong>the</strong> beach’<br />

Previous ERP studies have shown (a) that in native <strong>and</strong> very proficient non-native speakers,<br />

morpohosyntactic violations elicit a P600 component, usually preceded by a Left Anterior Negativity<br />

(LAN) <strong>and</strong> (b) that regarding <strong>the</strong> late processing effects (P600) early proficient non-natives show no<br />

difference with respect to natives [2].<br />

The results of our study revealed no significant differences in verb morphology processing between<br />

natives <strong>and</strong> very proficient non-natives (AoA 3yrs); however, non-natives responded differently to<br />

noun morphology violations in comparison to <strong>the</strong> native group – <strong>the</strong>y did not show a P600<br />

component. These findings were confirmed by <strong>the</strong> behavioural data: non-natives made significantly<br />

more errors than natives in noun morphology violations, but not in <strong>the</strong> verb morphology condition.<br />

Our results show different maturational effects <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong>se two types of morphological processes <strong>and</strong><br />

suggest that within <strong>the</strong> morphological component of grammar, age of acquisition may have an<br />

asymmetrical impact, independent of proficiency <strong>and</strong> dependent on <strong>the</strong> type of grammatical process<br />

at play, in this case, nominal versus verbal morphology.<br />

References<br />

[1] Weber-Fox, Ch., Neville, H. (1996). Maturational Constraints on Functional Specializations <strong>for</strong><br />

<strong>Language</strong> Processing: ERP <strong>and</strong> Behavioural Evidence in Bilingual Speakers. Journal of Cognitive<br />

Neuroscience, 8 (3), 231-256.<br />

[2] Kotz, S., Holcomb, Ph., Osterhout, L. (in press). ERPs reveal comparable syntactic sentence<br />

processing in native <strong>and</strong> non-native readers of English. Acta Psychologica<br />

Notes<br />

200


Object relatives ARE easier than subject relatives in Chinese<br />

P147<br />

Xiaomei Qiao, & Kenneth I. Forster<br />

<strong>University</strong> of Arizona, USA<br />

E-mail: xqiao@email.arizona.edu<br />

It has been claimed that it is universally true that subject-extracted relative clauses are easier to<br />

process than object-extracted relative clauses. However, contradictory results have been found in<br />

prenominal languages, <strong>for</strong> example Chinese. Hsiao <strong>and</strong> Gibson (2003) found that object relatives<br />

were easier to process than subject relatives, while Lin (2006) found <strong>the</strong> opposite. Both experiments<br />

used self-paced reading. One major disagreement concerns <strong>the</strong> region where <strong>the</strong> difficulty arises. In<br />

this study, a “maze” task was used to localize processing difficulty by requiring participants to make a<br />

choice between two alternatives at every single position of <strong>the</strong> sentence. This task has been shown to<br />

be sensitive to a number of phenomena associated with processing difficulty (Nicol, Forster, & Veres,<br />

1997; Forster, Guerrera, & Elliott, submitted), including <strong>the</strong> greater ease of processing subjectrelatives<br />

in English. Applied to <strong>the</strong> problem of measuring <strong>the</strong> difficulty of subject- <strong>and</strong> objectrelatives<br />

in Chinese, this task confirmed that object relatives are indeed easier than corresponding<br />

subject relatives in <strong>the</strong> relative clause region, although this difference is reversed in<br />

<strong>the</strong> subsequent relative marker region. No difference was found in <strong>the</strong> head noun position. It is argued<br />

that <strong>the</strong>se results depend on <strong>the</strong> fact that <strong>the</strong> task <strong>for</strong>ced participants to adopt a strict incremental<br />

processing mode, whereas self-paced reading allows more freedom. For example, a “wait-<strong>and</strong>-see”<br />

strategy is possible in tasks such as self-paced reading <strong>and</strong> eye tracking, but not in a maze task. This<br />

implies that <strong>the</strong> findings may depend on what kind of task is chosen. It is also argued that a maze task<br />

has <strong>the</strong> advantage that it is not necessary to include comprehension questions to make sure that<br />

participants are underst<strong>and</strong>ing <strong>the</strong> sentence. This is useful in that it allows <strong>for</strong> more st<strong>and</strong>ardized<br />

conditions of testing.<br />

Notes<br />

201


P148<br />

Syntactic priming between non-identical noun phrase structures<br />

Stella C. Frank, Amit Dubey, & Frank Keller<br />

<strong>University</strong> of Edinburgh, UK<br />

E-mail: s.c.frank@sms.ed.ac.uk<br />

Syntactic priming is known to occur between two instances of <strong>the</strong> same syntactic construction (e.g.,<br />

Bock, CogPsy 1986). Here we investigate priming effects between non-identical syntactic<br />

constructions using a corpus study. We find that priming, in <strong>the</strong> <strong>for</strong>m of increased production<br />

likelihood, occurs between NPs of different <strong>for</strong>ms, <strong>and</strong> that priming strength is linked to <strong>the</strong> similarity<br />

of <strong>the</strong> two NPs.<br />

Adaptation (Church, COLING 2000) measures <strong>the</strong> increase in probability that results from priming; it<br />

has been used to measure structural priming in corpora (Dubey et al., EMNLP 2005). We use a new<br />

version of adaptation, cross-adaptation, <strong>for</strong> which <strong>the</strong> prime <strong>and</strong> target may differ. In particular, we<br />

compare <strong>the</strong> cross-adaptation between two structures X <strong>and</strong> Y with <strong>the</strong> adaptation between two<br />

occurrences of X (self-adaptation).<br />

We measure cross-adaptation between NPs in three conditions: in adjacent sentences, within <strong>the</strong> same<br />

sentence, <strong>and</strong> within a coordination, using two parsed corpora, one of written text (<strong>the</strong> Brown corpus)<br />

<strong>and</strong> one of unscripted spoken text (a section from <strong>the</strong> BNC). In both corpora we find cross-adaptation<br />

strength to be of a similar magnitude as self-adaptation, which indicates that syntactic priming is not<br />

restricted to identically-structured constituents.<br />

Next, we examine whe<strong>the</strong>r adaptation strength is linked to construction similarity. We represent an<br />

NP as <strong>the</strong> right-h<strong>and</strong> side of <strong>the</strong> context-free grammar rule that generates it, e.g., "DT NN" <strong>for</strong> "<strong>the</strong><br />

dog". The similarity of two NPs can <strong>the</strong>n be measured as <strong>the</strong> Euclidean distance between two vectors<br />

of part-of-speech tags. We find a strong <strong>and</strong> significant correlation (all ps < 0.0001) between NP<br />

similarity <strong>and</strong> adaptation strength over both corpora <strong>and</strong> in all three conditions (s. Table). Matching<br />

pairs (self-adaptation) were excluded from this dataset. This result generalizes to o<strong>the</strong>r similarity<br />

measures, e.g., edit distance.<br />

We conclude that <strong>the</strong> occurrence of a structure primes not only <strong>the</strong> re-occurrence of that exact<br />

structure, but also <strong>the</strong> occurrence of a set of similar structures. This leads to <strong>the</strong> prediction that<br />

priming of similar constructions should also lead to facilitation in an experimental setting, as<br />

decreased processing time or increased frequency. This prediction remains to be tested in future work.<br />

Condition<br />

Correlation<br />

BNC (spoken) r N<br />

Between-Sentence 0.51 16682<br />

Within-Sentence 0.50 15996<br />

Within-Coordinate 0.41 233<br />

Brown (written) r N<br />

Between-Sentence 0.45 101856<br />

Within-Sentence 0.45 85335<br />

Within-Coordinate 0.44 1392<br />

Notes<br />

202


203


Author index<br />

Adam, R. ...................................................... O9<br />

Alario, X. ..................................................... P81<br />

Allured, G. ................................................... P78<br />

Altmann, G.T.M. .......................................... P4, P72<br />

Anderson, S.E. ............................................. P132<br />

Andersson, R. ............................................... P120<br />

Andonova, E. ............................................... P44<br />

Andrews, M.W. ............................................ P73<br />

Anton-Mendez, I. ......................................... O14<br />

Apel, J. ......................................................... O16<br />

Arai, M. ........................................................ O18, P31<br />

Arnold, J.E. .................................................. O6<br />

Arnon, I. ....................................................... O17<br />

Aslin, R.N. ................................................... P141<br />

Augurzky, P. ................................................ P59<br />

Augusto, M.A.R. .......................................... P47<br />

Aviles, A. ..................................................... P50<br />

Badecker, W. ................................................ O29, P15, P119<br />

Bannard, C. .................................................. O22, P16<br />

Barr, D.J. ...................................................... O33<br />

Bartels, L. ..................................................... P22<br />

Barth, A. ....................................................... P142<br />

Bejjanki, V.R. .............................................. P141<br />

Bernolet, S. ................................................... P138<br />

Bion, R.A.H. ................................................ P131<br />

Bögels, S. ..................................................... P126<br />

Bohan, J. ....................................................... O32, P21, P70<br />

Bordag, D. .................................................... P129<br />

Bornkessel-Schlesewsky, I. ......................... P19, P60<br />

Boves, L. ...................................................... P94<br />

Bowerman, M. ............................................. O2<br />

Bozic, M. ...................................................... O28<br />

Branigan, H.P. .............................................. P10, P28, P46<br />

Breheny, R. .................................................. O5<br />

Bressers, M. ................................................. P138<br />

Brindley, L. .................................................. P71<br />

Brouwer, S.M. .............................................. P37<br />

Brunellière, A.B. .......................................... P13<br />

Brysbaert, M. ............................................... P124<br />

Burchert, F. .................................................. P22, P65<br />

Burigo, M. .................................................... P104<br />

Buttery, P. .................................................... P114<br />

Bye, J. ........................................................... P91<br />

Cai, Z. ........................................................... P128<br />

Cajochen, C. ................................................. P75<br />

Caramazza, A. .............................................. P48


Carbary, K.M. .............................................. O26<br />

Carminati, M.N. ........................................... P36<br />

Carreiras, M. ................................................ P50<br />

Champion, M.K. .......................................... P144<br />

Chen, J. ......................................................... O2<br />

Chen, J-Y. .................................................... P112, P115<br />

Chondrogianni, V. ........................................ P137<br />

Chwilla, D.J. ................................................ P126<br />

Clark, F. ....................................................... P21<br />

Clayards, M. ................................................. P141<br />

Cochrane, S. ................................................. P70<br />

Coco, M.I. .................................................... P27<br />

Conklin, K. ................................................... P54, P78<br />

Cooke, M. ..................................................... O10<br />

Corley, M. .................................................... P3, P33, P41<br />

Corrêa, L.M.S. ............................................. P47, P90<br />

Costa, A.M. .................................................. P10, P81, P106<br />

Coventry, K. ................................................. P44<br />

Crepaldi, D. .................................................. P135<br />

Cummins, C.R. ............................................. P32<br />

Dale, R. ........................................................ O7<br />

Damian, M.F. ............................................... P77, P117<br />

Davidson, D.J. .............................................. P105<br />

Davis, M.H. .................................................. P68, P92, P100<br />

De Bleser, R. ................................................ P65<br />

De Jong, N.H. ............................................... P107<br />

De Vries, M.H. ............................................. P142<br />

Delogu, F. ..................................................... P56<br />

Demberg, V. ................................................. P31, P139<br />

Desmet, T. .................................................... P133<br />

Devereux, B.J. .............................................. O20, P38, P62, P83<br />

Di Betta, A.M. .............................................. O12<br />

Dickey, M-W. .............................................. O3<br />

Diependaele, K. ............................................ P52, P79<br />

Dietrich, R. ................................................... P75<br />

Dikker, S. ..................................................... P2<br />

Ding, G. ........................................................ P38<br />

Dobel, C. ...................................................... P113<br />

Dorjee Khenchen, D. .................................... P42<br />

Dubey, A. ..................................................... O1, P85, P148<br />

Dufau, S. ...................................................... P98<br />

Duyck, W. .................................................... P52<br />

Engelmann, F. .............................................. P140<br />

Farmer, T.A. ................................................. P2<br />

Ferguson, H.J. .............................................. O5, P17<br />

Fernández, B. ............................................... P146<br />

Fernández, E.M. ........................................... P125<br />

Ferreira, F. .................................................... O16, P8, P120<br />

Ferreira,V.S. ................................................. P55<br />

Filik, R. ........................................................ O34


Filipović Đurđević, D. ................................. P39<br />

Finkbeiner, M. .............................................. P48<br />

Firat, H. ........................................................ P137<br />

Floeel, A. ...................................................... P142<br />

Fodor, J.D. .................................................... P125<br />

Ford, M.A. .................................................... O20, P45, P62, P83<br />

Forster, K.I. .................................................. P14, P147<br />

Franck, J. ...................................................... O23<br />

Frank, R. ....................................................... P119<br />

Frank, S. ....................................................... P94<br />

Frank, S.C. ................................................... P148<br />

Frauenfelder, U.H. ....................................... O23, P13<br />

Futrell, R. ..................................................... P87<br />

Garagnani, M. .............................................. P101<br />

Garcia Castro, Y. .......................................... P81<br />

Garrett, M.F. ................................................ P42<br />

Garrod, S. ..................................................... O4, P12, P127<br />

Gaskell, G. ................................................... O12, P97<br />

Gelf<strong>and</strong>, H. ................................................... O24<br />

Gese, H. ........................................................ P69<br />

Glen, K. ........................................................ P21<br />

Glisky, E.L. .................................................. P42<br />

Gollan, T.H. ................................................. P144<br />

Gómez, R. .................................................... KN1<br />

Görges, F. ..................................................... P110<br />

Grainger, J. ................................................... KN3, P79<br />

Gram, L. ....................................................... P114<br />

Grewe, T. ..................................................... P60<br />

Gualmini, A. ................................................. P61<br />

Gunlogson, C. .............................................. P26<br />

Hackl, M. ..................................................... P123<br />

Haigh, M. ..................................................... P11<br />

Hanne, S. ...................................................... P65<br />

Hare, M.L. .................................................... P89<br />

Hartsuiker, R.J. ............................................ O14, O15, O25, P3, P52, P67, P136, P138<br />

Havelka, J. .................................................... O31<br />

Haywood, S.L. ............................................. P63<br />

Heide, J. ....................................................... P22<br />

Heller, D. ...................................................... P95<br />

Hem<strong>for</strong>th, B. ................................................ O17<br />

Henderson, J.M. ........................................... O16, P63, P120<br />

Hirschfeld, G. ............................................... P113<br />

Hochmann, J-R. ........................................... P66<br />

Holl<strong>and</strong>, R. ................................................... P71<br />

Hsu, C-C. ..................................................... P115<br />

Huettig, F. .................................................... O2, O25, P37, P53<br />

Hulstijn, J.H. ................................................ P107<br />

Ilkin, Z. ......................................................... P145<br />

Imada, M. ..................................................... P51<br />

Indefrey, P. ................................................... P80


Ivanova, I. .................................................... P10<br />

Jackson, C. ................................................... P29<br />

Jacob, G. ....................................................... P58<br />

Janssen, N. ................................................... P48<br />

Jescheniak, J.D. ............................................ P102, P110<br />

Jesse, A. ....................................................... O11<br />

Jin, M. .......................................................... O8<br />

Jin, Y-S. ....................................................... P33<br />

Jones, M.W. ................................................. P8<br />

Kaiser, E. ...................................................... P57, P99, P108<br />

Kamide, Y. ................................................... P143<br />

Kazanina, N. ................................................. P109<br />

Keller, F. ...................................................... O1, O18, P27, P31, P85, P139, P148<br />

Kerkhofs, R. ................................................. P126<br />

Kessler, K. .................................................... O4, P127<br />

Kidd, E. ........................................................ P11<br />

Kim, C.S. ...................................................... P26, P93<br />

Kim, S. ......................................................... P134<br />

Kirkham, N.Z. .............................................. O7<br />

Klein, M. ...................................................... P94<br />

Klein, N. ....................................................... P123<br />

Klein, N.M. .................................................. P89<br />

Knecht, S. ..................................................... P142<br />

Knicely, J. .................................................... P112<br />

Knill, D.C. .................................................... P141<br />

Koenig, J-P. .................................................. P134<br />

Konieczny, L. ............................................... P86<br />

Koornneef, A.W. .......................................... P74<br />

Kraljic, T. ..................................................... P55<br />

Kreiner, H. ................................................... O4, P127<br />

Kreysa, H. .................................................... P63<br />

Krott, A. ....................................................... P116<br />

Kujala, T. ..................................................... P101<br />

Kuperman, V. ............................................... O19<br />

Laka, I. ......................................................... P146<br />

Langus, A. .................................................... O27, P131<br />

Lao, S-Y.C. .................................................. O6<br />

Lau, K.Y.D. .................................................. P43<br />

Lebib, R. ....................................................... P116<br />

Leonard Cook, A. ......................................... P41<br />

Leuthold, H. ................................................. O32<br />

Lewis, R. ...................................................... P15<br />

Lieven, E.V.M. ............................................. O22, P35<br />

Lin, T. ........................................................... O24<br />

Lindsay, S. ................................................... P97<br />

Llewellyn, E. ................................................ P123<br />

Logacev, P. ................................................... P140<br />

Logie, R. ....................................................... P33<br />

Loncke, M. ................................................... P133<br />

Longtin, C-M. .............................................. P100


Lorenz, A. .................................................... P22<br />

Lorusso, M.L. ............................................... P104<br />

Luzzatti, C. ................................................... P135<br />

Mahon, B.Z. ................................................. P48<br />

Maienborn, C. .............................................. P69<br />

Majid, A. ...................................................... O2<br />

Marantz, A. .................................................. O29<br />

Marchetto, E. ................................................ P131<br />

Marcilese, M. ............................................... P47<br />

Marcus, G.F. ................................................ O24<br />

Marelli, M. ................................................... P135<br />

Marinis, T. .................................................... P23, P137<br />

Marslen-Wilson, W.D. ................................. KN2, O28, P25, P45, P92<br />

Martin, A.E. ................................................. P7<br />

Martin, E. ..................................................... P21<br />

Matsui, H. ..................................................... P51<br />

Mat<strong>the</strong>ws, D.E. ............................................ P16, P35<br />

Mattys, S.L. .................................................. O10<br />

Mauner, G. ................................................... P134<br />

McElree, B. .................................................. P7<br />

McLean, J. .................................................... P10<br />

McQueen, J.M. ............................................. O9, O11, P53<br />

Mehler, J. ..................................................... P66<br />

Melinger, A. ................................................. P48<br />

Merkx, M.M. ................................................ P68<br />

Meroni, L. .................................................... P61<br />

Meteyard, L. ................................................. P103<br />

Meyer, A.S. .................................................. P84<br />

Millotte, S. ................................................... O23<br />

Mir<strong>and</strong>a, F.V. ............................................... P47, P90<br />

Mirkovic, J. .................................................. P72<br />

Mitchell, L.M. .............................................. P5<br />

Mitterer, H. ................................................... P37<br />

Miyamoto, E.T. ............................................ P51<br />

Moat, S. ........................................................ P3<br />

Mohr, S. ....................................................... O4, P127<br />

Morgan, J.L. ................................................. P118<br />

Mousoulidou, M. .......................................... O34<br />

Moxey, L.M. ................................................ O34, P88<br />

Müller, D. ..................................................... P86<br />

Myachykov, A. ............................................. P12, P24, P46<br />

Nespor, M. ................................................... O27, P82, P131<br />

Nilsenová, M. ............................................... P96<br />

O’Seaghdha, P.G. ......................................... P112<br />

Oppermann, F. ............................................. P110<br />

Orfanidou, E. ................................................ O9<br />

Ota, M. ......................................................... P41<br />

Paterson, K.B. .............................................. O34<br />

Pattamadilok, C. ........................................... P98<br />

Patterson, K. ................................................. P71, P103


Pechmann, T. ............................................... P129<br />

Per<strong>for</strong>s, A. .................................................... P76<br />

Perniss, P. ..................................................... P111<br />

Perre, L. ........................................................ P98<br />

Pickering, M.J. ............................................. O8, P10, P28, P63, P67, P128, P138<br />

Pliatsikas, C. ................................................. P23<br />

Pulvermüller, F. ........................................... P71, P101<br />

Pusch, K. ...................................................... P75<br />

Pylkkänen, L. ............................................... O24, P2<br />

Qiao, X. ........................................................ P147<br />

Rabagliati, H.A. ........................................... O24, P2<br />

Race, D.S. .................................................... P89<br />

Raffray, C.N. ................................................ P24, P28<br />

R<strong>and</strong>all, B. ................................................... O20, P38, P45, P62, P83, P121<br />

Rastle, K. ...................................................... O31, P5, P68, P100, P124<br />

Reilly, E. ...................................................... O29<br />

Reinisch, E. .................................................. O11<br />

Reul<strong>and</strong>, E. ................................................... P74<br />

Richardson, D.C. .......................................... O7<br />

Roberts, L. .................................................... P29<br />

Rodrigues, E. dos Santos ............................. P49<br />

Roehm, D. .................................................... P122<br />

Rogers, J.C. .................................................. P92<br />

Rol<strong>and</strong>, D. .................................................... P1<br />

Roman, A. .................................................... P112<br />

Rosenberg, J. ................................................ P75<br />

Runner, J.T. .................................................. P26, P93<br />

Sag, I.A. ....................................................... P87<br />

Salverda, A.P. .............................................. O30<br />

S<strong>and</strong>ra, D. ..................................................... P20, P79<br />

San<strong>for</strong>d, A.J. ................................................ O32, P17, P21, P56, P70, P88<br />

San<strong>for</strong>d, A.J.S. ............................................. O32, P70<br />

Santiago, J. ................................................... P112<br />

Scheepers, C. ................................................ P12, P17, P24, P46<br />

Schimke, S. .................................................. P130<br />

Schlesewsky, M. .......................................... P19, P60<br />

Schmitt, N. ................................................... P54<br />

Schoonen, R. ................................................ P107<br />

Schreuder, R. ................................................ O19<br />

Schriefers, H. ............................................... P110, P126<br />

Schütze, C.T. ................................................ P144<br />

Schwarzkopf, S. ........................................... P86<br />

Sedin, L. ....................................................... P97<br />

Seifart, F. ...................................................... P111<br />

Sekerina, I.A. ............................................... P65<br />

Severens, E. .................................................. P136<br />

Shafto, M.A. ................................................. O13<br />

Shaher, R.F. .................................................. P140<br />

Shen, X. ........................................................ P117<br />

Shestakova, A. ............................................. P38


Shtyrov, Y. ................................................... P25, P71, P101<br />

Shukla, M. .................................................... P82<br />

Shuval, N. ..................................................... O17<br />

Siu, Y. .......................................................... P55<br />

Siyanova, A. ................................................. P54<br />

Skinner, R. ................................................... O21<br />

Skovbroten, K. ............................................. P95<br />

Smolka, E. .................................................... P50<br />

Snider, N. ..................................................... O17<br />

Snoeren, N.D. ............................................... O12<br />

Solomyak, O. ............................................... O29<br />

Sorace, A. ..................................................... P41, P122<br />

Spalek, K. ..................................................... P77<br />

Spivey, M.J. ................................................. P132<br />

Srinivasan, N. ............................................... P140<br />

Stamatakis, E.A. ........................................... O13<br />

Staum Casasanto, L. ..................................... P87<br />

Stewart, A. ................................................... P11<br />

Stolterfoht, B. ............................................... P69<br />

Strijkers, K. .................................................. P81, P106<br />

Sturt, P. ......................................................... O1, O3, P6, P85, P128, P145<br />

Subacheva, I.P. ............................................. P51<br />

Szlachta, Z. ................................................... P121<br />

Tagawa, T. ................................................... P51<br />

Tam, P.P. ...................................................... O13<br />

Tanenhaus, M.K. .......................................... O26, O30, P26, P89, P95<br />

Tavabi, K. ..................................................... P71<br />

Taylor, D. ..................................................... P15<br />

Taylor, K.I. ................................................... O20, P62, P83<br />

ten Bosch, L.F.M. ........................................ P94<br />

Tenenhaum, J.B. .......................................... P76<br />

Thomas, J.D. ................................................ P14<br />

Thompson, R.L. ........................................... O8, O21, P18<br />

Thornton, R. ................................................. P91, P123<br />

Tily, H. ......................................................... O17<br />

Tomasello, M. .............................................. O22, P35<br />

Tomlinson, J. ................................................ O7<br />

Traxler, M.J. ................................................. P34<br />

Trenkic, D. ................................................... P72<br />

Trompelt, H. ................................................. P129<br />

Tsai, S-H. ..................................................... P115<br />

Tydgat, I. ...................................................... P67<br />

Tyler, L.K. .................................................... O13, O20, O28, P38, P45, P62, P83, P121<br />

Tzeng, A.K. .................................................. P64<br />

Uzule, K. ...................................................... P84<br />

van Amelsvoort, M.A.A. .............................. P96<br />

Van Assche, E. ............................................. P52<br />

van Gompel, R.P.G. . .................................... P36, P58<br />

van Heuven, W.J.B. ..................................... P78<br />

van Jaarsveld, H. .......................................... P94


Van Laere, S. ................................................ P133<br />

V<strong>and</strong>ekerckhove, B. ..................................... P20<br />

Vasishth, S. .................................................. P65, P140<br />

Vernice, M. .................................................. O15<br />

Vigliocco, G. ................................................ O8, O21, P18, P73, P111<br />

Vinson, D.P. ................................................. O8, O21, P18, P73, P111<br />

Vitoria, P. ..................................................... O19<br />

von Gompel, R.P.G. ..................................... P58<br />

Vonk, W. ...................................................... P126<br />

Wagner, V. ................................................... P102<br />

Wang, L. ....................................................... P19<br />

Weber, K.M. ................................................ P80<br />

Webman, R. ................................................. P125<br />

Weighall, A.R. ............................................. P4, P118<br />

Weldle, H. .................................................... P86<br />

Wennekers, T. .............................................. P101<br />

Wheeldon, L.R. ............................................ P84<br />

Whiting, C.M. .............................................. P25<br />

Wijnen, F. ..................................................... P74<br />

Wonnacott, E. ............................................... P76<br />

Wu, F. ........................................................... P57<br />

Wydell, T. .................................................... O31<br />

Yang, C-L. ................................................... P115<br />

Yoshida, M. .................................................. O3, P6<br />

Yuen, I. ......................................................... P124<br />

Zawiszewski, A. ........................................... P146<br />

Zhuang, J. ..................................................... P45<br />

Ziegler, J. ..................................................... P98<br />

Zondervan, A. .............................................. P61<br />

Zuares, S.N. .................................................. P132<br />

Zwitserlood, P. ............................................. P113, P142

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!