25.01.2015 Views

A General Theory of Adaptive Vitality, and Its Communication

A General Theory of Adaptive Vitality, and Its Communication

A General Theory of Adaptive Vitality, and Its Communication

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Draft -- Submitted March 2010 for publication in Cognitive Semiotics.<br />

Embodied Human Intersubjectivity<br />

Acting Imaginatively To Create <strong>and</strong> Share Meaning<br />

Colwyn Trevarthen,<br />

University <strong>of</strong> Edinburgh<br />

What Is Embodiment What Is Intersubjectivity How Does Embodied Intersubjectivity<br />

Motivate Cultural Learning<br />

I take 'embodiment <strong>of</strong> mind' to mean having an animal body intent on moving, <strong>and</strong> knowing how to<br />

use the experience <strong>of</strong> moving well – a body feeling alive as one integrated Self. The embodied self<br />

is aware <strong>of</strong> the immediate prospects <strong>of</strong> moving its different members. It perceives the layout <strong>of</strong><br />

surroundings where it is, taking in knowledge <strong>of</strong> the 'affordances' <strong>of</strong> a particular place with certain<br />

objects in a single present time (von Uexküll, 1957; Gibson, 1979). It also recalls items <strong>of</strong> this<br />

experience for future use in a 'narrative <strong>of</strong> events' or <strong>of</strong> 'episodes' (Tulving, 2002; Stern, 2004). This<br />

body also shows emotions as expressions <strong>of</strong> the vital values <strong>of</strong> action felt within that changing<br />

experience (Darwin, 1872; Panksepp, 1998a, b). It has appetites, fears <strong>and</strong> satisfactions,<br />

excitements, pains <strong>and</strong> pleasures. It makes responses to defend a self-confidence that is attempting<br />

to adapt to <strong>and</strong> remember what happened according to the emotions excited. To live in a body is to<br />

move <strong>and</strong> feel it moving, <strong>and</strong> then to know <strong>and</strong> care about a drama <strong>of</strong> acting in the world. Even an<br />

earthworm can have a rudimentary self with these functions as "liabilities <strong>of</strong> mobility" (Merker,<br />

2005), <strong>and</strong> even show a simple practical intelligence (Darwin, 1881).<br />

'Inter-subjective embodiment', sharing <strong>of</strong> action between selves, requires pairs or groups <strong>of</strong><br />

individuals to move in an engagement <strong>of</strong> their intelligent vitalities, each one recognizing or<br />

"sympathizing with" the life <strong>of</strong> the other beings who perceive one another as agents, <strong>and</strong> who move<br />

with bodies that manifest intentions <strong>and</strong> emotions known entirely from how they move. Selves<br />

become "subjects" <strong>of</strong> the intentions <strong>and</strong> interests <strong>of</strong> other selves by a mysterious process <strong>of</strong> shared<br />

embodiment <strong>and</strong> mutual awareness <strong>of</strong> agency. Thus is brought to life forms <strong>of</strong> cooperative moving<br />

regulated by imitative <strong>and</strong> emotionally sympathetic responses between agents who take up<br />

expressions <strong>of</strong> intention <strong>and</strong> emotion in one another's actions, making responses that have the<br />

possibility <strong>of</strong> identifying common objects, <strong>and</strong> then <strong>of</strong> creating awareness <strong>of</strong> intentions in a society<br />

<strong>and</strong> an exp<strong>and</strong>ing knowledge <strong>and</strong> imagination <strong>of</strong> a common world (Baldwin, 1894; Trevarthen,<br />

1979, 1988, 1989a, 1998a, b, 1999a, 2005a, 2006, 2009a, 2010; Donald, 2001; Donaldson, 1992;<br />

1


Stern, 2000; Whitehead, 2008).<br />

Thus a human subject, a "person", is the reflected product <strong>of</strong> life with others in active<br />

intersubjective awareness, <strong>of</strong> a story <strong>of</strong> how other human selves know one's intentions <strong>and</strong><br />

emotions, <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> one's responses to their evaluations (Trevarthen, 2006, 2010). The "I", alone, felt<br />

as one sentient <strong>and</strong> sensitive agent in wilful action, <strong>and</strong> with its emotional feelings about a memory<br />

<strong>of</strong> doing alone, is the Self -- not a subject. Others' potential awareness <strong>of</strong> this self makes the<br />

awareness <strong>of</strong> "Me", <strong>and</strong> stimulates self-conscious explanations <strong>of</strong> how I act, <strong>of</strong> my knowledge <strong>and</strong><br />

skills, <strong>and</strong> evaluations <strong>of</strong> the emotional quality <strong>of</strong> my cultivated "personality". There is an old <strong>and</strong><br />

frequently rediscovered underst<strong>and</strong>ing that we come alive as subjects or persons only in relation<br />

with others, by being innately sensitive to their actions toward us (Hutcheson, 1755; Smith, 1759;<br />

Buber, 1937; Macmurray, 1961; Thompson, 2001; Trevarthen, 1993a, 2006, 2009a, 2010; Reddy,<br />

2008). This, however, is not the common underst<strong>and</strong>ing <strong>of</strong> Psychology, which, pressured by<br />

empiricism, has come to regard human beings as subjects with cognitively managed experiences<br />

who learn how to behave in society <strong>and</strong> with its rules <strong>of</strong> cooperation <strong>and</strong> cultivated skills <strong>and</strong><br />

explanations that 'represent' <strong>and</strong> 'classify' reality.<br />

Why has the process <strong>of</strong> interpersonal "moral" evaluation in a story <strong>of</strong> engagement, the primordial<br />

part <strong>of</strong> being human with human intelligence, become so problematic in empirical psychology <strong>and</strong><br />

rational philosophy We are born having already engaged with an other or others – with a past<br />

experience <strong>of</strong> being in physical <strong>and</strong> physiological intimacy with the body <strong>and</strong> vital functions <strong>of</strong> our<br />

mother (Lecanuet et al., 1995; Trevarthen et al., 2006), some <strong>of</strong> us even having been capable <strong>of</strong><br />

contact <strong>and</strong> tentative engagement in utero with the body <strong>and</strong> actions <strong>of</strong> a twin (Piontelli, 2002).<br />

Then, immediately after birth, each <strong>of</strong> us seeks to enter into what Stout (1903) called "The Growth<br />

<strong>of</strong> Intersubjective Intercourse", an adaptive psychological intimacy with the intentions <strong>and</strong> emotions<br />

<strong>of</strong> a sympathetic human other, <strong>and</strong> by moving in expressive ways <strong>and</strong> responding to their visible,<br />

audible <strong>and</strong> tangible expressions we are able to join in an imitative <strong>and</strong> expectant dialogue regulated<br />

by emotion (Trevarthen, 1998a; Kugiumutzakis, 1998, 1999; Nagy <strong>and</strong> Molnár, 1994; Nagy, 2010).<br />

All being well, we become willing <strong>and</strong> capable in a very few weeks to have a rich dialogic<br />

intentionality in rhythm with another human person's expressive vocal, facial <strong>and</strong> gestural actions,<br />

taking these acts <strong>of</strong> emotion as symptoms <strong>of</strong> their intelligent minds, <strong>and</strong> responding to the feelings<br />

in them, playing games with the acting <strong>and</strong> feeling <strong>and</strong> learning expressive rituals (Bateson, 1979;<br />

Trevarthen, 1979, 1998a, b, 2005 a, b, 2008; 2009b, 2010; Stern, 1985, 2010; Hobson, 2002;<br />

Gratier <strong>and</strong> Trevarthen, 2008; Reddy, 2008). In a few months, before we speak, our<br />

intersubjectivity begins to be "cultural" as our personal intimacies turn into a commerce <strong>of</strong> interests<br />

<strong>and</strong> actions in a shared material world <strong>of</strong> places <strong>and</strong> objects, which become known as conventional<br />

uses, meanings <strong>and</strong> ways <strong>of</strong> underst<strong>and</strong>ing ideal, humanly fabricated things – the rituals, tools,<br />

2


symbols, <strong>and</strong> artistic <strong>and</strong> technical practices <strong>of</strong> the culture in which we live <strong>and</strong> learn (Trevarthen<br />

<strong>and</strong> Hubley, 1978; Trevarthen, 1988, 1992, 2009a, 2004a b). This is how an individual human mind<br />

in human intersubjectivity starts its unique development towards competence in a "cultural mind"<br />

(Donald, 2001).<br />

To underst<strong>and</strong> why the fundamental embodied inter-mindedness <strong>and</strong> the active search for meaning,<br />

by the infant <strong>and</strong> by the adult, have been so resisted in scientific psychology <strong>and</strong> so confused in<br />

philosophy – why intentions <strong>and</strong> emotions have been conceived not as the causes or origin <strong>of</strong><br />

consciousness, as they naturally must be, but the products <strong>of</strong> acquiring 'facts about reality', <strong>of</strong><br />

imitating acts <strong>of</strong> meaning, <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> thinking <strong>and</strong> talking about them with the aid <strong>of</strong> intricately<br />

artificial alphabets, notations, scriptures, scores, institutions <strong>and</strong> monuments, we will have to take a<br />

psycho-biological perspective. We need to look back, as Darwin did, on what it requires to be an<br />

animal self in animal society (Darwin, 1872). Then we must observe the unique ways human selves<br />

in their bodies act <strong>and</strong> know in self-made time <strong>and</strong> in the practices <strong>of</strong> a community, with or without<br />

language (Key, 1980; Bolinger, 1983; Turner, 1982; Turner <strong>and</strong> Bruner, 1986; Donald, 2001;<br />

Whitehead, 2008; Trevarthen, 2009c). We need to observe how this playful, creative, or<br />

'generative', activity in company develops in the "present moment" <strong>of</strong> infancy (Merleau-Ponty,<br />

1962; Husserl, 1964; Stern, 2004) before its thoughts, purposes <strong>and</strong> imaginings or beliefs about<br />

absent things can be spoken about with others symbolically, 'as if' they were real, "Once Upon a<br />

Time".<br />

The progress is rapid. A one year old has already gained some habits <strong>of</strong> a particular culture,<br />

accepting 'proper' manners, customs, clothes <strong>and</strong> the use <strong>of</strong> tools to eat, drink <strong>and</strong> wash, making<br />

declarations <strong>and</strong> dem<strong>and</strong>s with gesture <strong>and</strong> vocalisation in "protolanguage" (Halliday, 1975, 1979).<br />

In two more years a toddler has become a member <strong>of</strong> an artful <strong>and</strong> "literary" world (Turner, 1996),<br />

inventing celebrations <strong>of</strong> musical play (Bjørkvold, 1992), categorizing things <strong>and</strong> actions so they<br />

can be symbolised by words <strong>and</strong> recalled as narrations (Bruner, 1983, 1990). All this has evolved<br />

from the embodied vitality <strong>of</strong> animal intelligence, <strong>and</strong> its sociability.<br />

A <strong>General</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Adaptive</strong> <strong>Vitality</strong><br />

"The doctrine which I am maintaining is that the whole concept <strong>of</strong> materialism only applies<br />

to very abstract entities, the products <strong>of</strong> logical discernment. The concrete enduring<br />

entities are organisms, so that the plan <strong>of</strong> the whole influences the very characters <strong>of</strong> the<br />

various subordinate organisms which enter into it. In the case <strong>of</strong> an animal, the mental<br />

states enter into the plan <strong>of</strong> the total organism <strong>and</strong> thus modify the plans <strong>of</strong> successive<br />

subordinate organisms until the ultimate smallest organism, such as electrons, are reached."<br />

3


(p. 100)<br />

"There are thus two sides to the machinery involved in the development <strong>of</strong> nature. On the<br />

one side there is a given environment with organisms adapting themselves to it ... The other<br />

side <strong>of</strong> the evolutionary machinery, the neglected side, is expressed by the word<br />

creativeness. The organisms can create their own environment. For this purpose the single<br />

organism is almost helpless. The adequate forces require societies <strong>of</strong> cooperating<br />

organisms. But with such cooperation <strong>and</strong> in proportion to the effort put forward, the<br />

environment has a plasticity which alters the whole ethical aspect <strong>of</strong> evolution." (p. 138)<br />

(A. N. Whitehead, Science <strong>and</strong> the Modern World, 1926)<br />

Whitehead is defining the limitations <strong>of</strong> rational, 'realistic' <strong>and</strong> 'material' explanations <strong>of</strong> life<br />

processes that consider only external physical causes <strong>and</strong> assumes that intelligences are<br />

constructed by combination <strong>of</strong> discrete elements from stimulation, neglecting innate 'creative'<br />

<strong>and</strong> 'cooperative' causes. Plants <strong>and</strong> animals are products <strong>of</strong> nature that create their destiny with<br />

vital processes – their lives contain their own causes. They are organisms with 'horizontal<br />

cooperative control' <strong>of</strong> their component living cells, organs <strong>and</strong> mobile or sensory parts to form<br />

a vital whole (Packard, 2006), that grow with prospective energy <strong>and</strong> adaptive components<br />

coordinated for future use, anticipating maintenance <strong>of</strong> a coherent vitality in a particular<br />

environment. They have evolved, not by stochastic selection <strong>of</strong> collections <strong>of</strong> DNA variants in<br />

chains <strong>of</strong> structural genes, but by modification <strong>of</strong> the epigenetic developmental strategy by<br />

homeotic regulators <strong>of</strong> gene expression that create epigenetic transformations in the form <strong>and</strong><br />

function <strong>of</strong> parts in whole bodies from embryo stages (Lewis, 1994). They are prepared as<br />

wholes to perceive <strong>and</strong> act against possible environmental threats, <strong>and</strong> to direct awareness <strong>and</strong><br />

productive engagements with what the environment may <strong>of</strong>fer as benefits to life (von Uexküll,<br />

1957). As they develop, they actively acquire more effective activities <strong>and</strong> ways <strong>of</strong> protecting<br />

the living body in response to new environmental conditions.<br />

Plants grow proactive roots, leaves <strong>and</strong> chloroplasts in anticipation <strong>of</strong> specific dynamic<br />

interactions with soil, air, water, <strong>and</strong> sunlight, <strong>and</strong> they have protective parts <strong>and</strong> processes to<br />

survive harsh conditions. They are adapted to find <strong>and</strong> 'negotiate' a tolerable place with other<br />

species that have different life forms, having adaptations for cooperation in a communal<br />

ecology. With lavishly advertised <strong>and</strong> specially engineered flowers <strong>and</strong> fruits they variously<br />

exploit water, the wind, insects <strong>and</strong> birds to accomplish reproduction <strong>and</strong> a dispersion <strong>of</strong> seeds,<br />

spores, etc. to suitable places for their <strong>of</strong>fspring to grow with their inherited adaptations.<br />

Animals move. They have prospective, 'knowing' control <strong>of</strong> motor agency (Lee, 2005;<br />

4


Trevarthen, 2007). They are intentional <strong>and</strong> conscious <strong>of</strong> their world <strong>and</strong> possess special<br />

sensitivity for the activities <strong>of</strong> other animals. They excite their muscles in intricately regulated<br />

patterns to displace their bodies <strong>and</strong> body parts in effective ways that promote their life, acting<br />

as whole selves that evaluate the prospects <strong>of</strong> what they do by emotions. With spontaneously<br />

active nervous systems that map their body form <strong>and</strong> that are set to perceive the body-related<br />

layout <strong>of</strong> world in which they move, they maintain integrated behaviour <strong>and</strong> well-being in<br />

creative, sentient ways, choosing objectives to take nourishment <strong>and</strong> acting to escape injury or<br />

discomfort, guided by emotions. And they form cooperative communities that share intentions<br />

<strong>and</strong> emotions in socially elaborated ways.<br />

Science has found important principles <strong>of</strong> this inbuilt animal intelligence by experimenting<br />

with how central nervous systems are organised to integrate actions <strong>of</strong> the body with their<br />

sensory effects, <strong>and</strong> to maintain well-being by adjusting actions. Prospective regulation <strong>of</strong><br />

muscle activity in an animal body is achieved by proprioceptive, exteroceptive <strong>and</strong> visceral<br />

neural systems that provide 'feedback' or 'reafference' to confirm the sensory effects <strong>of</strong> moving;<br />

both inside the body among the vital organs, <strong>and</strong> on its surface in contact with the world.<br />

In Sherrington's terms (Sherrington, 1906, Lecture IX), all experience or knowledge acquired<br />

by learning depends on motivation for moving in adaptive, expectant ways dependent on these<br />

different modes <strong>of</strong> self awareness <strong>of</strong> the body in action:-<br />

On "proprio-ception", or dynamic awareness <strong>of</strong> the forces in the body (Sherrington called<br />

this the "material me" in movement).<br />

On "extero-ception", an activity that detects <strong>and</strong> discriminates goals for adaptive action at<br />

a distance from the body with "projicience", the imaginative function <strong>of</strong> object<br />

identification that expects confirmation <strong>of</strong> benefits or risks by the "affective appraisal" <strong>of</strong><br />

"consummatory reactions", when the object is brought in contact with the body or taken<br />

into it.<br />

On "viscero-ception" within an autonomic nervous system that regulates <strong>and</strong> protects<br />

inner energy resources, integrating the maintenance <strong>of</strong> vital physiological functions in<br />

balance with assertive acts against the environment <strong>and</strong> appreciation <strong>of</strong> their beneficial or<br />

damaging effects.<br />

Our underst<strong>and</strong>ing <strong>of</strong> all this has exp<strong>and</strong>ed with research into the functions <strong>of</strong> limbic system<br />

(MacLean, 1990), the affective nervous system <strong>of</strong> the core <strong>of</strong> the brain that defines emotional<br />

tendencies throughout all levels (Panksepp, 1998a), <strong>and</strong> the visceral nervous system in the<br />

brain stem that excites <strong>and</strong> senses vital functions 'autonomically' <strong>and</strong> communicates their needs<br />

socially (Porges, 2001, 2007). Research on the retentive capacities <strong>of</strong> the cerebral cortex <strong>of</strong> the<br />

5


larges brains does not reveal the whole picture.<br />

Social cooperation in a community <strong>of</strong> animals, to reproduce or perform collective actions <strong>of</strong><br />

foraging <strong>and</strong> hunting, or <strong>of</strong> defense against predators or rival groups, requires special<br />

transformation <strong>of</strong> body form <strong>and</strong> movement for communicating <strong>and</strong> coordinating all these<br />

adaptive intentions between individuals so they are able to move well together in a shared<br />

world, while sustaining their individual vital functions. Thus societies <strong>and</strong> communities <strong>of</strong><br />

animals become larger adaptive organisms, <strong>and</strong> knowledge <strong>of</strong> the environment is increased by<br />

collective experience, <strong>and</strong> imitation.<br />

The processes <strong>of</strong> sympathetic initiation <strong>of</strong> actions, <strong>of</strong> shared projicience for object perception<br />

<strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> sympathetic affective appraisal eluded Sherrington's physiology, <strong>and</strong> remain<br />

challenging to our neuropsychology <strong>and</strong> functional brain science, in spite <strong>of</strong> spectacular<br />

advances <strong>of</strong> the past decade or two. It is clear we need, first, to make sense <strong>of</strong> what the brain<br />

does in communication, <strong>of</strong> how motives, feelings <strong>and</strong> inner regulations pass to other brains.<br />

We need a new kind <strong>of</strong> biology <strong>of</strong> intentions <strong>and</strong> emotions, one which does not assume that the<br />

cause <strong>of</strong> behaviour is in the nature <strong>of</strong> the physical stimuli that impinge on the sensory<br />

equipment <strong>of</strong> the subject, on information coming in. We need one that allows that motives<br />

cause perceptions, intelligent actions <strong>and</strong> adjustments <strong>of</strong> vital state by setting their purposes<br />

from within. Second, we need a theory <strong>of</strong> sympathetic transfer <strong>of</strong> intentions, interests, <strong>and</strong><br />

affect appraisals between brains, by detection <strong>of</strong> these from the purposes <strong>and</strong> emotions made<br />

explicit in other individuals' movements.<br />

Forty years ago I collected information about the growth <strong>and</strong> form <strong>of</strong> the central nervous<br />

systems <strong>of</strong> vertebrates to explain how the "behavioural field" <strong>of</strong> awareness is conceived <strong>and</strong><br />

used by these animal selves as they go about their world <strong>and</strong> make selective actions in it to<br />

secure benefits or avoid harm (Figure 1A). Guided by inspiring predecessors (James, 1890;<br />

Sherrington, 1906; Lashley, 1951; Sperry, 1952; von Uexküll, 1957; von Holst <strong>and</strong> von Saint-<br />

Paul, 1961; Gibson, 1966; Bernstein, 1967), I concluded that each vertebrate brain, in every<br />

species, is formed as a natural source or generator <strong>of</strong> a singular intentional consciousness that<br />

'knows' in a general way what its movement will do or lead to, that 'expects' the effects <strong>of</strong><br />

stimuli in a 'body-centred world', <strong>and</strong> that can 'project' or 'associate' internal autonomic<br />

regulations <strong>of</strong> vital state onto items <strong>of</strong> experience to give situations <strong>and</strong> objects affecting<br />

qualities. The evidence was that embryogenesis creates maps <strong>of</strong> integrative neural mechanism<br />

adapted to generate prospective movement in a 'field <strong>of</strong> behaviour', one fitting the form <strong>and</strong><br />

functions <strong>of</strong> the body with its effectors <strong>and</strong> receptors <strong>and</strong> internal needs (Trevarthen, 1968a).<br />

Later, I developed the theory <strong>of</strong> a functionally divided behaviour field to distinguish several<br />

6


innate adaptive modes <strong>of</strong> activity <strong>and</strong> awareness in brains that differed in relation to a set <strong>of</strong><br />

complementary functions enacted by moving bodies: namely, sustaining physiological wellbeing;<br />

guiding locomotion through the media <strong>of</strong> the surrounding world; performing selective<br />

attention to local objects that may be identified for their life-giving or dangerous potentialities;<br />

<strong>and</strong> also eliciting cooperation in vital activities from social partners (Trevarthen, 1968b, 1978).<br />

An important conclusion was that any cooperation between individual animals, coordinating<br />

their intentional behaviours to achieve more than a single self could do, must have evolved by<br />

making the intentions, interests <strong>and</strong> states <strong>of</strong> internal vitality in single selves apparent <strong>and</strong><br />

available to others. This requires transmission <strong>of</strong> evidence in behavour as 'symptoms' <strong>of</strong> the<br />

special generative properties <strong>of</strong> movements in congruent body forms. I called this<br />

'intersubjective motor control' (Trevarthen, 1986) <strong>and</strong> described the essential dimensions <strong>of</strong> the<br />

communication as 'kinematic' (concerned with the rhythmic dynamics <strong>of</strong> movements),<br />

'energetic' (varations in the intensity, force or power <strong>of</strong> actions), <strong>and</strong> 'physiognomic' (changes<br />

in the shape <strong>of</strong> the body, organising postural, gestural, facial or vocal settings in distinct<br />

categories related to the subject's changing interests <strong>and</strong> purposes). All three give information<br />

on intrinsic autonomic/emotional states. "These three complementary dimensions <strong>of</strong> expressive<br />

movement form a primary level <strong>of</strong> organisation that is largely innate. They are united by<br />

processes that control serial ordering <strong>and</strong> strategic patterning <strong>of</strong> movements in adaptive<br />

sequences. The development <strong>of</strong> the latter, higher order, organisation <strong>of</strong> communication is more<br />

dependent on experience <strong>and</strong> learning." (Trevarthen, 1986, p. 209)<br />

Given evidence that all animal movements are regulated sequentially in pulses <strong>of</strong> time by<br />

internally generated processes (Lashley, 1951; von Holst, 1954), with prescribed rhythms <strong>and</strong><br />

self-synchrony between movements <strong>of</strong> body parts, <strong>and</strong> that the directed movements <strong>of</strong> parts<br />

carrying special sense organs are deployed in ways that correlate with their adaptive initiatives<br />

<strong>and</strong> preferences, it seemed that communication between similarly motivated <strong>and</strong> similarly<br />

formed subjects, with the same kind <strong>of</strong> brain <strong>and</strong> the same rhythms <strong>and</strong> forms <strong>of</strong> attending, had<br />

evolved by brains taking up <strong>and</strong> engaging with, or resonating to, the timing, aim <strong>and</strong> style <strong>of</strong><br />

the intentions that made the movements initiated by other brains. This coupling <strong>of</strong> motive<br />

impulses between individuals is especially evident in human conversational behaviour in which<br />

speech, gesture <strong>and</strong> other body movements are coordinated, demonstrating inter-synchrony <strong>of</strong><br />

rhythms, with imitation (Condon <strong>and</strong> Ogston, 1966; Kendon, 1980; Key, 1980).<br />

Animal <strong>and</strong> human communication, must be an adaptation deriving from the ways motives,<br />

intentions <strong>and</strong> feelings are generated <strong>and</strong> mediated in movement for integrated selves, how the<br />

power <strong>of</strong> activity is distributed efficiently between body parts in one time, rhythmically, <strong>and</strong><br />

7


especially from how inquisitive orienting or seeking movements <strong>of</strong> head, eyes, ears, or limbs<br />

turn to anticipate a future selective contact with items in the world. Movements <strong>of</strong> bodies <strong>and</strong><br />

their parts are evolved into "advertising" signals that move other selves in their bodies,<br />

employing "biosemiosis" according to principles <strong>of</strong> semiosis that had been defined by the<br />

brilliant <strong>and</strong> eccentric logician Charles Saunders Peirce (Buchler, 1940; Sebeok <strong>and</strong> Umiker-<br />

Sebeok, 1992; Trevarthen, 1990a, 1994).<br />

Collective action <strong>and</strong> joint attention involving "inter-synchrony" between the motive impulses<br />

<strong>of</strong> individuals is clearly evident in swarms <strong>of</strong> insects, schools <strong>of</strong> fish, flocks <strong>of</strong> birds <strong>and</strong> herds<br />

<strong>of</strong> mammals. Looking, listening or reaching for objects shows how they are being selected by<br />

an active self in the shared world, <strong>and</strong> these actions may become signals in "ritualised"<br />

encounters for many kinds <strong>of</strong> social cooperation. Animal signalling commonly involves<br />

accentuation <strong>of</strong> expectant orienting movements <strong>of</strong> the ears, head or limbs, <strong>and</strong> postural<br />

adjustments <strong>of</strong> head or tail that indicate impending directions <strong>of</strong> movement, <strong>and</strong> these body<br />

part adjustments, <strong>and</strong> their emotional significance indicated by the rapidity or frequency <strong>of</strong><br />

their movements, are <strong>of</strong>ten made more visible or audible by adornments -- colour patterns <strong>of</strong><br />

plumage or pelage, or sound making organs (Darwin, 1872; Hingston, 1933; Tinbergen, 1951;<br />

Lorenz, 1966).<br />

All dynamic forms <strong>of</strong> communicative gestures <strong>of</strong> animals that transmit purposes <strong>and</strong> feelings<br />

between individuals "musically" (Wallin, Merker <strong>and</strong> Brown, 2000) – head bobbing <strong>and</strong> h<strong>and</strong><br />

waving <strong>of</strong> lizards, singing <strong>of</strong> whales or nightingales, cries <strong>of</strong> migrating geese, or their<br />

confidential honks in a flock as they "comment" on an approaching person, squeaking or<br />

"laughter" <strong>of</strong> mice (Panksepp <strong>and</strong> Burgdorf, 2003), status setting grunts <strong>of</strong> baboons (Cheney et<br />

al., 1995) – are derivative <strong>of</strong> movements that are self-regulatory (felt within the body or guided<br />

by interested subjective attention to objects <strong>and</strong> events in the world) <strong>and</strong> adapted for acting in<br />

social communication, intersubjectively (Darwin 1872; MacLean, 1990; Porges, 2003;<br />

Rodriguez & Palacios 2007; Panksepp, 1998b, 2000; Panksepp & Trevarthen 2009). They are<br />

manifested intentions with feelings in forms that can be sensed by other individuals as<br />

emotional signs or symptoms <strong>of</strong> the motives <strong>and</strong> self-regulating processes that generate them.<br />

They all may be said to exhibit the features that define "Communicative Musicality" (Malloch<br />

<strong>and</strong> Trevarthen, 2009; see below).<br />

8


The Special <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>of</strong> Human <strong>Vitality</strong> In Action, <strong>and</strong> In Cultural <strong>Communication</strong> <strong>and</strong><br />

Elaboration<br />

We possess … the ability topursue our goals with great tenacity. This tenacity has a<br />

number <strong>of</strong> sources, but prominentamong them is the fact that our purposes are apt to be<br />

accompanied by very powerfulfeelings. Thus they become important to us; <strong>and</strong> in the<br />

extreme case they can become moreimportant than life itself. … In spite <strong>of</strong> these facts <strong>of</strong><br />

experience <strong>and</strong> observation, a number <strong>of</strong> serious attempts have beenmade to account for<br />

human behaviour without having recourse to the notion <strong>of</strong> intention orpurpose at all. The<br />

notion, however, is one that tends to reappear in some guise or otherwithin psychology, no<br />

matter how hard one tries to keep it out. And it is ironic that the attempt to keep it out is<br />

generally itselfsustained by a passionate aim: the aim <strong>of</strong> being 'scientific' in a manner<br />

modelled upon theactivity <strong>of</strong> the physicists.<br />

…<br />

The devising <strong>of</strong> novel purposes comes readily to us because we have brains that are good<br />

atthinking <strong>of</strong> possible future states - at considering not merely what is but what might be.<br />

We exist in a world <strong>of</strong> 'hard fact', but we can imagine it as changed; <strong>and</strong> from a very early<br />

agewe know that, within certain limits, we are able to change it. … In this context 'the<br />

world' includes other people as amost important component. And, if we have any wisdom,<br />

it also includes ourselves.<br />

(Margaret Donaldson, Human Minds, 1992)<br />

At the same time as I was collecting thoughts about the pre-functional growth in the embryo<br />

vertebrate brain <strong>of</strong> adaptive neural systems that mapped 'somato-topic' fields for movement <strong>and</strong><br />

perception coupled in register by what my teacher Roger Sperry (1965) called "the<br />

embryogenesis <strong>of</strong> behavioural nerve nets", <strong>and</strong> applying information gained from research with<br />

Sperry about how integrated intentions to move channelled awareness in left <strong>and</strong> right<br />

hemispheres <strong>of</strong> the cerebral cortex <strong>of</strong> a split brain monkey (Trevarthen, 1962, 1965), I became<br />

interested in a search for the intentional talents <strong>of</strong> human infants. This change <strong>of</strong> direction in<br />

my research was encouraged by Jerome Bruner who <strong>of</strong>fered me a post at the Harvard Center<br />

for Cognitive Studies in his new Laboratory for Infant Cognition.<br />

From the start <strong>of</strong> this project -- in which Bruner wanted to devise ways to accurately record<br />

how infants could modify freely chosen movements <strong>and</strong> selective engagements with objects to<br />

regulate <strong>and</strong> 'categorize' their knowledge -- it became clear that the new "cognitive" sensory-<br />

9


motor theory, striving to explain how cognition <strong>and</strong> learning serve to 'construct' human actions<br />

in culturally adaptive ways, was seriously undervaluing the adaptive anticipations <strong>of</strong> innate<br />

human motives, imagination <strong>and</strong> emotions (Bruner, 1968). And quickly it also became<br />

apparent that infants are particularly attracted to stimuli arising from human movement,<br />

catching <strong>and</strong> engaging with the motives in them from birth (see Nagy, 2010).<br />

The Cognitive Revolution had just taken <strong>of</strong>f, propelled by computer engineering <strong>and</strong> theories<br />

about reactive control systems (Miller, Galanter <strong>and</strong> Pribram, 1960; Miller, 2003), without<br />

keeping an eye on the fact that all consciousness <strong>and</strong> all communication, including the 'digital'<br />

codes <strong>of</strong> language, depend on creative <strong>and</strong> adaptive purposes <strong>of</strong> movement in whole living<br />

subjects, <strong>and</strong> on how these purposes are regulated by emotion <strong>and</strong> may be shared socially by<br />

detecting 'metaphorically' the 'analogic' patterns <strong>of</strong> controlled vitality evident in sequences <strong>of</strong><br />

movement.<br />

With others attending to the communicative powers <strong>of</strong> infants <strong>and</strong> young children (see<br />

Bullowa, 1979), I began to wonder whether language itself, the logic <strong>of</strong> its grammar <strong>and</strong><br />

productivity, were not anticipated in the special adaptations <strong>of</strong> the human body <strong>and</strong> mind for<br />

complex combining <strong>and</strong> sequencing <strong>of</strong> movements with awareness, <strong>and</strong> for giving affective<br />

appraisal to rhythmic plans for action, to the prosody <strong>of</strong> intonation, <strong>and</strong> to sequential, 'phrased'<br />

or 'discursive' perception <strong>of</strong> the environment (Lashley, 1951; Turner <strong>and</strong> Pöppel 1999; Fonagy,<br />

2001; Miall <strong>and</strong> Dissanayake, 2003; Br<strong>and</strong>t, 2009). Could young infants be 'expecting', in the<br />

ways they seek engagement <strong>and</strong> build trust in shared games, a cultural life <strong>of</strong> fictive<br />

evaluations in activity <strong>and</strong> story-making talk with other human beings Could symbols be<br />

symptoms or metaphors <strong>of</strong> sympathy in intentional behaviour <strong>and</strong> an imaginative sense <strong>of</strong><br />

being in a community <strong>of</strong> embodied minds Answers to these questions came clearer in the<br />

1970s<br />

Human beings are animals that move the most complex <strong>of</strong> bodies purposefully, with coherent<br />

inquisitive, constructive <strong>and</strong> imaginative intelligence. And we communicate interests, actions <strong>and</strong><br />

feelings by a most complex 'extravagant motility', using this highly articulated body to transmit the<br />

knowledge <strong>and</strong> skills that are ritualised in the arts, technology <strong>and</strong> languages -- that build elaborate<br />

cultural forms <strong>of</strong> adaptation imbued with aesthetic <strong>and</strong> moral qualities we sense intuitively, <strong>and</strong><br />

which we cultivate to make endlessly re-valued codes <strong>of</strong> appreciation <strong>and</strong> conduct. Human<br />

collective action transforms more than human minds. It transforms the environment in pr<strong>of</strong>itable<br />

ways over many generations, making traditional paths <strong>and</strong> l<strong>and</strong>scapes <strong>of</strong> life for growing<br />

populations <strong>and</strong> constructing material civilizations, which are increasingly costly <strong>and</strong> global -- <strong>and</strong>,<br />

as Whitehead implied, when he wrote <strong>of</strong> cooperative life changing the "ethical aspect <strong>of</strong> evolution",<br />

10


increasingly threatening to the resources <strong>of</strong> the natural world (Whitehead, 1926, p. 138).<br />

The adaptations <strong>of</strong> body <strong>and</strong> mind for this cultural/ritual way <strong>of</strong> life are present in infants in a way<br />

that seemed to have escaped scientific attention when I began my infancy research with Martin<br />

Richards <strong>and</strong> Berry Brazelton in Bruner's Center for Cognitive Studies in 1967. I believe that the<br />

generative adaptation <strong>of</strong> human nature, with its motives <strong>and</strong> affective appraisals, is still not<br />

assimilated by cognitive psychology or cognitive neuroscience, which conceive models <strong>of</strong> the mind<br />

that are computational <strong>and</strong> logical, in touch with reality, but out <strong>of</strong> touch with motives <strong>and</strong><br />

emotions.<br />

There are three mysterious powers active in young infants that challenge the rational <strong>and</strong> reductive<br />

assumptions <strong>of</strong> these sciences, with important implications for education <strong>and</strong> care <strong>of</strong> children, <strong>and</strong><br />

the promotion <strong>of</strong> a healthy <strong>and</strong> creative life for human beings <strong>of</strong> all ages in all societies. They call<br />

into question some <strong>of</strong> the central assumptions <strong>of</strong> the scientific method itself, <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> the language <strong>of</strong><br />

science (Whitehead, 1926; Halliday, 2006), leading to a different appreciation <strong>of</strong> the function <strong>of</strong> the<br />

imaginative arts in sustaining human companionship. They require neuroscientists to give more<br />

attention to the motivating <strong>and</strong> affective core <strong>of</strong> the brain, <strong>and</strong> to the regulatory influence these<br />

"intrinsic motive formations" <strong>and</strong> their emotions have over the development <strong>and</strong> functioning <strong>of</strong> the<br />

environment-related intelligence that our ever curious experience builds in the vast array <strong>of</strong><br />

neocortical circuits (Trevarthen <strong>and</strong> Aitken, 1994; Panksepp, 2003; Gallagher, 2008; Panksepp <strong>and</strong><br />

Trevarthen, 2009). Infants are born intentional creatures with coherent self-awareness; they move<br />

<strong>and</strong> experience with a sense <strong>of</strong> time corresponding to that which governs the agency <strong>and</strong> awarenss<br />

<strong>of</strong> adults; <strong>and</strong> they immediately seek intimate engagement with the expressions <strong>of</strong> agency <strong>and</strong><br />

emotion in a parent, responding <strong>and</strong> taking initiative in playful ways that go beyond needs for<br />

protection <strong>and</strong> care <strong>of</strong> vital functions. They are active, feelingful, intersubjective persons from the<br />

start (Trevarthen, 2010)<br />

Knowledge <strong>of</strong> conventional meaning, the skills <strong>of</strong> manipulative <strong>and</strong> manufacturing intelligence, <strong>and</strong><br />

the pragmatics <strong>of</strong> language in society all require re-interpretation in the light <strong>of</strong> the evidence we<br />

now have <strong>of</strong> infant's consciousness <strong>and</strong> its special awareness <strong>of</strong> interpersonal phenomena <strong>and</strong> their<br />

emotional values, <strong>and</strong> the realisation that the intuitive "romantic" <strong>and</strong> "trusting" foundations <strong>of</strong><br />

education <strong>and</strong> responsible functioning in society are not replaced as more disciplined ways <strong>of</strong><br />

thought, underst<strong>and</strong>ing <strong>and</strong> behaviour are acquired (Whitehead, 1929; Erickson, 1950; Bruner,<br />

1960; Donaldson, 1978, 1992). Our cognitive apprehensions are judged to be important <strong>and</strong><br />

acceptable, or irrelevant <strong>and</strong> undesirable, by aesthetic sensibilities (feeling that things are made<br />

well, or done well) <strong>and</strong> moral criteria (perceivng their relationship to other persons' interests, needs<br />

<strong>and</strong> feelings) to which a child is sensitive before acquiring language to describe, justify or discipline<br />

11


what they take to be true (Reddy, 2008; Trevarthen, 2009a, Frank <strong>and</strong> Trevarthen, 2010).<br />

I will summarise the findings about the intersubjective psychobiology <strong>of</strong> human intentions<br />

from the past four decades <strong>of</strong> research in infant psychology using three key words to define the<br />

essential powers <strong>of</strong> the unschooled human mind <strong>and</strong> its quest for, <strong>and</strong> evaluation <strong>of</strong>, meaning<br />

shared with others: namely, Self, Rhythm <strong>and</strong> Sympathy.<br />

SELF: Being a Single Wilful, Conscious Agent, Moving In <strong>Its</strong> Body<br />

"The unknown cerebral patterns in psychic experience must necessarily involve excitation<br />

patterns so designed that they intermesh in intimate fashion with motor <strong>and</strong> premotor<br />

patterns. ... It follows that the more we learn about the motor <strong>and</strong> premotor mechanisms,<br />

the more restrictions we add to the working picture <strong>of</strong> the unknown mental patterns, <strong>and</strong><br />

hence the closer our speculation will have to converge towards an accurate description <strong>of</strong><br />

their true nature."<br />

(Sperry, 1952, p. 300).<br />

"Since a great number <strong>of</strong> reflexes can be elicited in the young infantwhile 'higher' brain<br />

activity cannot yet be observed, the conclusion has been drawn that the infant's brain<br />

activity consists only <strong>of</strong>reflexes. This opinion does not at all do justice to the facts. At<br />

eachstage <strong>of</strong> development there exist functions that occur without external stimulation . . .<br />

During their inactivity the centers have beencharged <strong>and</strong> finally press for a discharge 'by<br />

themselves', i.e.,without external stimulation."<br />

(Peiper, 1963, p. 248)<br />

The Self is a well-governed 'intentional' (i. e. activity-creating) entity from conception, <strong>and</strong><br />

develops more powerful anticipatory activity from this simple state <strong>of</strong> vitality to greatly exp<strong>and</strong> the<br />

prospects <strong>of</strong> moving with feeling. This development depends on the formation <strong>of</strong> an integrative<br />

central nervous system.<br />

Building on Sherrington's discovery <strong>of</strong> the neural mechanisms <strong>of</strong> proprioception <strong>and</strong> his theory to<br />

explain how the reflex actions <strong>of</strong> a many body parts are integrated by the brain into movements <strong>of</strong> a<br />

single coherent actor, the Russian physiologist Nikolai Bernstein (1967) made a brilliant analysis <strong>of</strong><br />

how human movements are imagined in the brain. His six laws <strong>of</strong> 'biodynamic structures' that make<br />

adaptive movements explain how excitations <strong>of</strong> muscular activity are controlled to produce highly<br />

12


efficient rhythmic actions <strong>of</strong> one Self with a heavy body <strong>of</strong> many parts <strong>and</strong> many biomechanical<br />

'degrees <strong>of</strong> freedom', <strong>and</strong> how these centrally generated actions are adapted to work in collaboration<br />

with peripheral circumstances. The following is a summary <strong>of</strong> Bernstein's Laws (from Trevarthen,<br />

1984):<br />

1. Movements caused by changes in equilibria betweenmuscle tensions cannot be in one-to-one<br />

relationship to excitatory neuralimpulses or forces <strong>of</strong> muscular contraction.<br />

2. Events at the periphery <strong>of</strong> a moving member generate external, non-neurogenic or mechanical<br />

forces that may contribute substantially to themovement while it is happening (the "peripheral cycle<br />

<strong>of</strong> interaction").<br />

3. Peripheral force vectors must be responded to accurately <strong>and</strong> smoothlywith the aid <strong>of</strong><br />

proprioceptive relay <strong>of</strong> their effects into the motor centres,if there is to be "adequate coordination<br />

<strong>and</strong> correspondence <strong>of</strong> the movementto the animal's intention".<br />

4. The regulation <strong>of</strong> movement in plastic response to sensory feedbackrequires a central structure<br />

that can perform accurate anticipatory tracking<strong>of</strong> peripheral stimuli in or at the surface <strong>of</strong> the body,<br />

by changing responsiveness in the motor centres, orby comm<strong>and</strong>ing a change in aim or sensitivity<br />

<strong>of</strong> the receptors. (Thiscoordination <strong>of</strong> sensory input with excitation <strong>of</strong> motor activity cannot be<br />

reflexive. The time taken tointegrate new information from receptors into a movement, at least 50<br />

milliseconds <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong>ten as long as 250 milliseconds, is much longer than theduration <strong>of</strong> some large<br />

force changes in the system. Reflexive correctionwould come too late <strong>and</strong> it must function only as a<br />

corrective when intentional prediction fails.)<br />

5. Well-coordinated movements have a regular, automatic, rhythmic oroscillatory structure<br />

(manifest in the small number <strong>of</strong> harmonic components<strong>of</strong> force curves), in relation to which events<br />

in all moving segments <strong>of</strong> thebody are virtually interdependent. Cooperative reciprocities <strong>of</strong> motion<br />

<strong>and</strong>support in linked segments <strong>and</strong> the smooth flow <strong>of</strong> forces down the kinematicsystem, such as<br />

from trunk, down arms to h<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> fingers, rely upon this 'orchestration' <strong>of</strong> the force momenta<br />

which is necessaryto, <strong>and</strong> an expression <strong>of</strong>, the accurate anticipation <strong>of</strong> resultant mechanicalevents<br />

at the periphery by the centre.<br />

6. Adjustments to a change in goal or tempo for a limb movement must involvegeneration <strong>of</strong> a<br />

new force program transmitted throughout the body, since change<strong>of</strong> movement in one segment<br />

alters the relationships between forces everywhere.<br />

Bernstein's theory <strong>of</strong> the a complex 'imaginative' dynamic organization<strong>of</strong> excitation in motor<br />

centres, which exploit the peripheral mechanisms prospectively <strong>and</strong> respond to theirsignals, is<br />

incorporated in contemporary theory <strong>of</strong> "embodied cognition" (Varela, Thompson <strong>and</strong> Rosch, 1991;<br />

13


Clark, 1997, 1999; Lak<strong>of</strong>f <strong>and</strong> Johnson, 1999) <strong>and</strong> in a neuroscience <strong>of</strong> the awareness <strong>of</strong> body<br />

activities (Damasio, 1999; Gallese, 2005), <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> emotions that evaluate actions (Panksepp, 1998b,<br />

2000) <strong>and</strong> communicate them socially (Porges, 2001). Pro<strong>of</strong> that a prospect-generating 'motor<br />

image' is essential to the efficiency <strong>of</strong> even the simplest movement opens the way to an explanation<br />

<strong>of</strong> imagination, perceptual discrimination <strong>and</strong> memory as necessary parts <strong>of</strong> the anticipations <strong>of</strong><br />

actions. A dynamic motor image <strong>of</strong> the movements <strong>of</strong> the whole body, with effective opposition to<br />

the changing force <strong>of</strong> gravity <strong>and</strong> assimilation <strong>of</strong> the inertial properties <strong>of</strong> the moving body parts,<br />

<strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> the masses <strong>and</strong> displacements <strong>of</strong> media, surfaces <strong>and</strong> objects that the body comes in contact<br />

with or takes hold <strong>of</strong>, must underlie any conscious image <strong>of</strong> the Self <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> what it perceives as<br />

experience <strong>of</strong> the world. This theory that 'motor <strong>and</strong> pre-motor' processes must be taken into<br />

consideration to explain cognitions was clearly stated by Roger Sperry (1952), before Bernstein's<br />

work <strong>of</strong> the 1920s <strong>and</strong> '30s was known in English.<br />

A theory <strong>of</strong> internal 'intuitive' rhythmic processes that generate movement <strong>and</strong> experience is<br />

supported by research that detects brain activity in advance <strong>of</strong> movement (Kornhuber <strong>and</strong> Deecke,<br />

1965), <strong>and</strong> that shows how neural activity preparatory to action, or in imaginative experience <strong>of</strong><br />

action, invades widespread structures including those structured to receive, identify <strong>and</strong> recall the<br />

effects <strong>of</strong> stimulation by both proprioceptors <strong>and</strong> exteroceptors (Jeannerod, 1994). The coherence <strong>of</strong><br />

this action requires coherence in time <strong>of</strong> the many sources <strong>of</strong> rhythmic activity throughout the brain<br />

(Buzsaki, 2006), a productive temporal integrity <strong>of</strong> coordinated rhythms that may be called<br />

"musical", <strong>and</strong> that shows strong motoric <strong>and</strong> emotional responses to music (Sacks, 2007; Panksepp<br />

<strong>and</strong> Trevarthen, 2009; Turner <strong>and</strong> Ioannides, 2009; Trevarthen, 2009c).<br />

A human being moving as one agent strives to maintain a single focus <strong>of</strong> interest, <strong>and</strong> a single sense<br />

<strong>of</strong> passing time, while perceiving in several modalities. We see with two separate optical systems,<br />

but from one locus coincident with the centre <strong>of</strong> rotation <strong>of</strong> the head. Saccadic eye movements<br />

couple the two eyes to direct gaze to single points <strong>of</strong> interest for 'focal' discrimination in extracorporal<br />

space without a sense that orientation <strong>of</strong> the self has changed, meanwhile the 'ambient'<br />

field <strong>of</strong> interest is stable (Trevarthen 1968b). Each head rotation changes self-orientation. Attention<br />

movements <strong>of</strong> the eyes are coordinated or integrated with reaching, touching <strong>and</strong> manipulation<br />

movements <strong>of</strong> the h<strong>and</strong>s. We make skilful, precise finger movements directed by high-resolution<br />

foveal vision, as well as touch, the stereoscopic disparity between the eyes serving to accurately<br />

control the distance <strong>of</strong> digital contact from the body. When walking on an irregular surface we<br />

monitor the movements with gaze cast ahead to fix each place where the next step will fall.<br />

When speaking we accompany the thoughts to be expressed with gestures that may anticipate the<br />

utterances, <strong>and</strong> in conversation the listener's gaze, head movements, gestures <strong>and</strong> speech as well as<br />

14


changes <strong>of</strong> emotional expression in face <strong>and</strong> voice, are perceived as a single sequence <strong>of</strong> messages.<br />

The perception <strong>of</strong> another person's interests <strong>and</strong> feelings <strong>and</strong> the direction <strong>of</strong> their intended<br />

movements can be perceived by all the senses together, or by any one <strong>of</strong> them separately. We<br />

experience them as 'owning' a single intelligence, which is transmitted by how they make sounds,<br />

show expressive appearances, <strong>and</strong> touch or embrace our bodies.<br />

These are all manifestations in movement <strong>of</strong> the intentions <strong>of</strong> an integrated conscious Self.<br />

They entail prospective monitoring <strong>of</strong> what Björn Merker (2005) calls 'the liabilities <strong>of</strong><br />

mobility', by a proportionally large brain that has comprehensive proprioceptive sense for the<br />

positions <strong>and</strong> displacements <strong>of</strong> the trunk, head <strong>and</strong> limbs, actively sensing the forces generated<br />

in the muscles <strong>and</strong> tendons, the rotations <strong>of</strong> joints, the accelerations <strong>of</strong> the head, with additional<br />

guidance from the exteroceptive senses <strong>of</strong> sight, hearing <strong>and</strong> touch, <strong>and</strong> that monitors its<br />

internal well-being <strong>and</strong> safety (Porges, 2001).<br />

Physiological research has found that this body-form-<strong>and</strong>-motion sensing is carried out by<br />

afferent nerves to the motor apparatus, both somatic <strong>and</strong> visceral, <strong>and</strong> by comparison <strong>of</strong><br />

reafferent 'feed-back' information about the effects <strong>of</strong> each act with a 'motor image' that<br />

predicts what they will be. Highly skilled, learned movements require complex <strong>and</strong> rapid<br />

anticipatory activity specified in the cerebral cortex, but all coordination <strong>of</strong> motor activity with<br />

its effects in the world <strong>and</strong> within the body depends on the integrated processes <strong>of</strong> the<br />

subcortex that mediate <strong>and</strong> integrate primary intentions <strong>and</strong> self-awareness. This Intrinsic<br />

Motive Formation (IMF) <strong>of</strong> the human brain (Trevarthen <strong>and</strong> Aitken, 1994) includes<br />

elaborations <strong>of</strong> the basal ganglia, cerebellum <strong>and</strong> brain stem <strong>of</strong> the mammalian brain that<br />

provide essential integrative background <strong>and</strong> timing to the direction <strong>of</strong> learned skills by the<br />

neocortical system, principally by the frontal motor cortex, which is informed both from<br />

perceptual discriminations made in occipito-parietal cortex <strong>and</strong> from the sub-cortical<br />

autonomic system. All cortical processes <strong>of</strong> intention <strong>and</strong> awareness are regulated by the core<br />

neural systems <strong>of</strong> the IMF. These regulations include both autonomic viscero-motor<br />

adjustments <strong>of</strong> the physiological functions inside the body in response to needs signalled by the<br />

viscero-ceptive nervous system, <strong>and</strong> emotional expressions <strong>of</strong> contentment or distress,<br />

confidence or doubt <strong>and</strong> liking <strong>and</strong> disliking that give essential dynamic support <strong>and</strong> evaluation<br />

<strong>of</strong> the subject's self-conscious agency <strong>and</strong> engagement in communication with other subjects.<br />

15


Human Face, Eyes <strong>and</strong> Voice Are Adapted To Express a Lively Spirit Seeking Company<br />

When primitive vertebrates evolved as active predators, the anterior end <strong>of</strong> the body became an<br />

independently mobile head, with receptors for sensing the world, jaws for taking food <strong>and</strong> gill<br />

arches for gas exchange. Simultaneously a forebrain developed to coordinate a more vigorous life<br />

with more foresightful intelligence (Gans <strong>and</strong> Northcutt, 1983). In protochordates, surviving<br />

ancestors <strong>of</strong> vertebrates, the environment-sensing brain rests above a center <strong>of</strong> the neuro-hormonal<br />

system for self-regulation, the hypothalamus. This arrangement remains a central coordinative<br />

feature <strong>of</strong> the human brain (Trevarthen et al., 2006).<br />

In socially intelligent higher vertebrates, the head additions, with the autonomic system, have<br />

become the expressive/receptive systems <strong>of</strong> the face, throat, eyes <strong>and</strong> ears (Porges, 1997;<br />

Trevarthen, 2001). The communication <strong>of</strong> psychological expectations between subjects by<br />

expressive movements integrates internal visceral regulations with environment-directed somatic<br />

ones (Trevarthen, 1989b; Trevarthen et al., 2006). In reptiles, birds <strong>and</strong> mammals ancient<br />

mechanisms evolved to signal bodily needs <strong>and</strong> to attract parental care, have been transformed to<br />

add mechanisms <strong>of</strong> sympathetic mind-engagement, for expressions <strong>of</strong> emotion <strong>and</strong> interest, <strong>and</strong> for<br />

vocal communication <strong>of</strong> purposes, needs <strong>and</strong> desires (MacLean, 1990; Porges, 1997; Panksepp,<br />

1998b), culminating in articulate speech <strong>and</strong> language (Fonagy, 2001).<br />

Systems that emerge in the human embryo brain as regulators <strong>of</strong> morphogenesis in cognitive<br />

systems become core regulatory systems <strong>of</strong> interneurons in the brainstem that direct orientations <strong>of</strong><br />

attention, coordinate purposeful movements <strong>of</strong> the body <strong>and</strong> its parts, <strong>and</strong> mediate the equilibria<br />

between autonomic <strong>and</strong> exploratory or executive states (Hess, 1954; MacLean, 1990; Nauta <strong>and</strong><br />

Domesick, 1982; Trevarthen, 2001; Trevarthen et al., 2006). An important output from this<br />

Intrinsic Motive Formation (IMF; Trevarthen <strong>and</strong> Aitken, 1994) controls the 'sensory-accessory<br />

motor systems' <strong>of</strong> the special receptors <strong>of</strong> the head <strong>and</strong> h<strong>and</strong>s. The eyes, the ears <strong>and</strong> cochlear, the<br />

lips <strong>and</strong> tongue <strong>and</strong> the palms <strong>and</strong> fingers are separately aimable <strong>and</strong> tuneable. Their movements<br />

rhythmically 'aim' <strong>and</strong> 'censor' the uptake <strong>of</strong> perceptual information in different modalities <strong>of</strong> high<br />

sensitivity <strong>and</strong> resolution, <strong>and</strong> these motor adjustments occur in the exploratory <strong>and</strong> focusing phases<br />

<strong>of</strong> attending to the outside world, before the final commitment <strong>of</strong> a 'consummatory act'. They<br />

therefore exhibit advance information to an observer about emerging impulses <strong>of</strong> the subject,<br />

signalling awareness <strong>and</strong> intentions (Panksepp, 1998b; Trevarthen, 1993b, 1997). All the organs <strong>of</strong><br />

human linguistic expression are recruited from this accessory motor set (Trevarthen, 2001).<br />

Directed attention links brainstem <strong>and</strong> cortex, <strong>and</strong> emotions arise as centrally generated states<br />

involving all levels <strong>of</strong> the brain. Two centers have been identified as essential for relating emotions<br />

to social experience <strong>and</strong> for the development <strong>of</strong> a reflective (cognitive) underst<strong>and</strong>ing <strong>and</strong> voluntary<br />

16


control <strong>of</strong> emotions; in the amygdala <strong>and</strong> temporal mesocortex (Aggleton, 1993; Bachevalier, 1994;<br />

LeDoux, 1992; Rolls, 1992) <strong>and</strong> in the orbito-frontal cortex (Cummings, 1993; Dawson, 1994;<br />

Goldman-Rakic 1992). Orbito-frontal <strong>and</strong> temporal pole cortex develop extensively after birth <strong>and</strong><br />

are presumed to modulate the activities <strong>of</strong> the infant’s brainstem emotional system (Schore, 1994).<br />

Both regions develop asymmetries (Davidson <strong>and</strong> Fox, 1982); Davidson <strong>and</strong> Hugdahl, 1995).<br />

Left <strong>and</strong> Right Asymmetries <strong>of</strong> Gesture <strong>and</strong> Motive States: Not Just For Language<br />

Cerebral asymmetry was discovered first in relation to language, <strong>and</strong> it has been assumed that the<br />

neocortical areas essential for articulate speech <strong>and</strong> for hearing speech in the left hemisphere are the<br />

origin <strong>of</strong> cultural intelligence <strong>and</strong> the distinctive features <strong>of</strong> human consciousness. However,<br />

asymmetries in the central nervous system are <strong>of</strong> ancient origin, <strong>and</strong> they serve many<br />

complimentary processes <strong>of</strong> motivation, emotion, learning <strong>and</strong> communication in human beings,<br />

from before birth (Trevarthen, 1984, 1993c; 1995; 1996).<br />

Neonates show a right ear preference for speech, but a left ear preference for heartbeat or music.<br />

Microanalyses <strong>of</strong> films <strong>of</strong> protoconversations <strong>and</strong> photographic records showed that at 2 months,<br />

protoconversational utterances <strong>of</strong> cooing <strong>and</strong>/or 'prespeech' (articulations <strong>of</strong> lips <strong>and</strong> tongue) were<br />

most <strong>of</strong>ten accompanied by raised right h<strong>and</strong> gestures, <strong>and</strong> extending the h<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> pointing with the<br />

fingers was frequently precisely synchronous with the oral gesture. When they were distressed <strong>and</strong><br />

in more reflective <strong>and</strong> observant phases, infants held their left h<strong>and</strong>s toward their bodies <strong>and</strong><br />

sometimes touched or fingered their clothes. They appear to be more 'assertive' with their right<br />

h<strong>and</strong>s, <strong>and</strong> more receptive or 'apprehensive' when moving their left h<strong>and</strong>s (Trevarthen, 1996).<br />

Asymmetries <strong>of</strong> psychological function <strong>and</strong> behavior that are elaborated by learning through<br />

childhood (Trevarthen, 1990b; 2004c), but their development is regulated by anatomical <strong>and</strong><br />

neurochemical asymmetries in systems found in all levels <strong>of</strong> the human brain from prenatal stages<br />

(Cynader et al., 1981; Huttenlocher, 1994; Trevarthen, 1996). Manual preference observed in<br />

thumb-sucking in individual fetuses <strong>of</strong> 15 weeks gestational age correlate with h<strong>and</strong> preferences<br />

seen in the second year after birth (Hepper, 1995).. The human neocortex is visibly asymmetric in<br />

fetal stages (Rakic, 1991). The right hemisphere is more advanced than the left in surface features<br />

from about the 25th week, <strong>and</strong> this bias persists until the left hemisphere shows a post-natal growth<br />

spurt starting in the second year when language <strong>and</strong> other articulate skills are acquired (Thatcher,<br />

Walker <strong>and</strong> Giudice, 1987). The asymmetric areas are crucial in all culture-related processes <strong>of</strong> the<br />

adult human brain, <strong>and</strong> their development is affected by practice <strong>of</strong> skills <strong>and</strong> all "collective<br />

representations" (Schlaug et al. 2005; Turner <strong>and</strong> Whitehead, 2008). The telling <strong>of</strong> stories in any<br />

form <strong>of</strong> art give the space <strong>of</strong> the narrative an asymmetry related to how we confront the world <strong>and</strong><br />

17


move in it with other persons (Trevarthen, 1995).<br />

Human H<strong>and</strong>s Became Their Own Selves <strong>and</strong> Cooperative Agents <strong>of</strong> Technical Invention<br />

The motor-intentional possibilities <strong>of</strong> human upper limbs, <strong>and</strong> therefore their dem<strong>and</strong>s for<br />

elaborate cerebral imaginative control, are very great, because the jointed lever system <strong>of</strong> arms,<br />

palms, <strong>and</strong> fingers has many biomechanical ‘degrees <strong>of</strong> freedom’ (Bernstein, 1967), <strong>and</strong><br />

because the cerebral programming <strong>of</strong> the combinations <strong>of</strong> rotation about the many joints is<br />

extremely refined <strong>and</strong> informed by many sensitive receptors (Trevarthen, 1986; Trevarthen et<br />

al., 2010). H<strong>and</strong>s <strong>of</strong> adults can be projected from the body with high velocity to transmit large<br />

forces, moved with exquisite temporal <strong>and</strong> spatial precision <strong>of</strong> guidance in an extensive<br />

reaching field, <strong>and</strong> rotated to contact surfaces <strong>of</strong> objects with accuracy in any direction while<br />

responding to light touch, modulating pressure. Fingers are extended or flexed in an infinite<br />

number <strong>of</strong> combinations to palpate, push, poke, punch, pat, twist, tear etc. The two h<strong>and</strong>s<br />

cooperate, performing complementary tasks in climbing, in manipulation <strong>of</strong> objects, <strong>and</strong> in<br />

expressive movements that may be cultivated as a language <strong>of</strong> signs (Goldin-Meadow <strong>and</strong><br />

McNeill, 1999).<br />

Many h<strong>and</strong> actions are Self-adjusting: carriage <strong>of</strong> food to the mouth, scratching <strong>of</strong> itches,<br />

removing <strong>of</strong> thorns, brushing <strong>of</strong>f dirt, rubbing hot, cold or sore parts, pulling on or <strong>of</strong>f clothes;<br />

<strong>and</strong> h<strong>and</strong>s contribute to adjustment <strong>of</strong> body state through stroking, touching <strong>and</strong> holding,<br />

transmitting warmth <strong>and</strong> stimulating autonomic responses. H<strong>and</strong>s participate in postural<br />

balance <strong>and</strong> locomotion, as forelimbs do in other mammals, but primate h<strong>and</strong>s are particularly<br />

adapted to reach from the body to grasp <strong>and</strong> manipulate objects, <strong>and</strong> human h<strong>and</strong>s exp<strong>and</strong> this<br />

power <strong>of</strong> manipulation greatly – they are capable <strong>of</strong> new combinations <strong>of</strong> movement, <strong>and</strong> they<br />

are directed by greatly increased powers <strong>of</strong> imagination, memory <strong>and</strong> thought-regulated skill<br />

(Poizner et al., 1987; McNeill, 1992). Thus they may show intentions for selecting, exploring<br />

<strong>and</strong> transforming objects in the environment, while the trunk is active only in providing a<br />

dynamic anti-gravity support.<br />

How Motor Intentions Grow <strong>and</strong> Become Carriers <strong>and</strong> Receivers <strong>of</strong> Imitated Meaning<br />

Human infants are born with most <strong>of</strong> the above capacities for self-regulated movement<br />

coordinating the limbs <strong>and</strong> senses, <strong>and</strong> their h<strong>and</strong>s show elaborate autonomous agency, guided<br />

by cerebral processes still little studied <strong>and</strong> not well understood (Trevarthen, 1986, 2007;<br />

Trevarthen et al., 2010). Contrary to the assumptions <strong>of</strong> the constructivist cognitive theory <strong>of</strong><br />

18


Jean Piaget, who sought only to explain how concepts <strong>of</strong> the body <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> objects are created by<br />

egocentrically learning the effects <strong>of</strong> actions on them (Piaget, 1954), we are, as Albrecht Peiper<br />

(1963) illustrated in his Cerebral Function In Infancy <strong>and</strong> Childhood, not just reflex organisms<br />

at birth, although there are strong reflex systems in a newborn that serve coordination <strong>of</strong><br />

movements with reaction to external stimuli that assist parental carrying or feeding, or that<br />

protect the body. The flowing movements <strong>of</strong> the body <strong>of</strong> a well-supported, alert newborn give<br />

evidence <strong>of</strong> an integrated proprioception, <strong>and</strong> indeed <strong>of</strong> the function <strong>of</strong> movement to sustain,<br />

explore <strong>and</strong> extend sensations <strong>of</strong> coherent activity (Prechtl, 1984; Trevarthen, 1984; Cioni <strong>and</strong><br />

Castellaci, 1990). The complexity <strong>of</strong> intentional movement <strong>of</strong> eyes, head, <strong>and</strong> h<strong>and</strong>s is not a<br />

consequence <strong>of</strong> assembly <strong>of</strong> reflex systems originally separate. It is an innate coordinative<br />

property <strong>of</strong> the growing human self. And it is fundamental to the infants powers <strong>of</strong> engagement<br />

with the body movements <strong>and</strong> minds <strong>of</strong> other persons.<br />

Human foetuses tentatively touch the placenta, umbilicus <strong>and</strong> the uterine wall with their h<strong>and</strong>s<br />

at 11 weeks. They make jaw movements <strong>and</strong> swallow amniotic fluid, expressing pleasure or<br />

disapproval at tastes injected into it by sucking <strong>and</strong> smiling or grimacing with disgust.<br />

Complex movements <strong>of</strong> trunk, arms <strong>and</strong> legs position the body, <strong>and</strong> may react to the mother’s<br />

body movements <strong>and</strong> the contractions <strong>of</strong> the muscles <strong>of</strong> her uterus (Lecanuet, et al., 1995;<br />

Piontelli, 2002; Trevarthen, et al., 2006). During gestation, sensory inputs are incorporated or<br />

integrated to guide movement, first by proprioception, monitoring displacement <strong>of</strong> body parts<br />

relative to one another or in the gravitational field, then by touch exteroception <strong>and</strong> exproprioception,<br />

sensing immediate surroundings outside the body <strong>and</strong> changes with body<br />

displacement. The h<strong>and</strong> movements fetuses make at around 20 weeks are engaging with<br />

sensory feedback <strong>and</strong> 'feeling' newly developed proprioceptive <strong>and</strong> somesthetic monitoring<br />

systems (Piontelli, 2010).<br />

From the beginning <strong>of</strong> human activity in the embryo, therefore, movements, though they lack<br />

awareness <strong>of</strong> external goals, are coherent 'sensible' actions, <strong>and</strong> they are made more effective by<br />

steps in development <strong>of</strong> feed-back <strong>of</strong> feeling that is anticipated by the restless spirit <strong>of</strong> vitality<br />

(Trevarthen <strong>and</strong> Aitken, 1994). Each new form <strong>of</strong> movement <strong>of</strong> the limbs is supported by growth <strong>of</strong><br />

new sensory capacity, so the consequence <strong>of</strong> the movement is recorded, confirmed <strong>and</strong> adjusted to<br />

sustain <strong>and</strong> elaborate a self-sensing unity <strong>of</strong> purpose in the central nervous system (Piontelli, 2010).<br />

After 20 weeks h<strong>and</strong> movements explore the foetus’ own body <strong>and</strong> surroundings <strong>and</strong> eyes turn in<br />

coordination with head movements, <strong>and</strong> twin foetuses touch one another <strong>and</strong> adjust positions in the<br />

confined space. ‘Temperamental' differences between twins in activity <strong>and</strong> reactivity recorded in<br />

ultra-sound movies around mid gestation persist through to several years after birth (Piontelli,<br />

2002). Foetuses hear from 20 weeks, <strong>and</strong> tests <strong>of</strong> babies' recognition <strong>of</strong> their mother’s voice<br />

19


immediately after birth prove that a baby can distinguish her speech or singing from that <strong>of</strong> another<br />

woman (DeCasper <strong>and</strong> Spence, 1986; Hepper, 1988). A pregnant woman feels the life <strong>of</strong> her foetus<br />

from mid gestation, <strong>and</strong> this prompts her to imagine the baby she will meet at birth, <strong>and</strong> sometimes<br />

she talks to the expected one.<br />

Interest in the outside world grows quickly. The sensitive motility that has developed before<br />

birth is capable <strong>of</strong> orienting to <strong>and</strong> tracking external objects perceived by sight in the first<br />

hours after birth, <strong>and</strong> a newborn infant seeks engagement with intimate <strong>and</strong> affectionate signals<br />

from a parent (Brazelton, 1979; Nagy, 2010). Evidence that a premature newborn can be<br />

conscious comes from observing how an 'aroused' baby can move in coordinated ways <strong>and</strong><br />

with selective orientation to events outside the body (Lecanuet et al., 1995). The power <strong>and</strong><br />

‘grace’ <strong>of</strong> these movements signal regulation <strong>of</strong> the risks <strong>and</strong> benefits <strong>of</strong> moving as these are<br />

detected by the newborn’s ‘affective consciousness’ (Panksepp, 2000). They are important<br />

clinical signs <strong>of</strong> neurological health (Lecanuet et al., 1995; Trevarthen & Aitken, 2003). And a<br />

two-month-old premature baby is capable <strong>of</strong> coordinating simple "coo" vocalizations with a<br />

parent in an intimate dialogue that has the rhythmic timing <strong>of</strong> the syllables <strong>and</strong> phrases <strong>of</strong> adult<br />

speech (Trevarthen, 2003, 2008, 2009a).<br />

Paediatric practice has been transformed by demonstrations <strong>of</strong> the psychological capacities <strong>of</strong><br />

neborn infants (Brazelton, 1973/1984, 1979). A full term newborn turns to track <strong>and</strong> may point<br />

or vocalize to a moving object nearby, or to the sound <strong>of</strong> a mother’s voice. A touch on the<br />

cheek attracts the mouth for suckling. The heart slows with intent looking or listening.<br />

Blinking <strong>and</strong> conjugate saccades above a few degrees are well-developed <strong>and</strong> newborns can<br />

look to a gentle voice in the dark. Vision has low resolution at first, but acuity develops rapidly<br />

in the first few months (Trevarthen & Aitken, 2003). There are many so-called 'postural<br />

reflexes' by which a newborn can compensate for imposed tilts <strong>of</strong> the body. These prove that<br />

the whole body is capable <strong>of</strong> adapting the forces <strong>of</strong> mobility to changes <strong>of</strong> position <strong>and</strong><br />

orientation <strong>of</strong> limbs in the gravitational field.<br />

Cognitive psychologists propose that infants are born with 'core concepts' or strategies for<br />

learning that are adapted to perceive natural phenomena (Lacerda, von H<strong>of</strong>sten & Heimann,<br />

2001). The exercise <strong>and</strong> development <strong>of</strong> these concepts depends, as Piaget demonstrated, on<br />

the initiatives <strong>of</strong> the infant to engage with <strong>and</strong> investigate the phenomena by moving in<br />

controlled ways. Moreover, the "concepts" are never simply rational, but are coloured by<br />

affective appraisals which determine how they will be remembered <strong>and</strong> recalled. Papoušek<br />

noted that infants a few months old acting as operators in an experiment to test their powers <strong>of</strong><br />

perceptual prediction <strong>of</strong> attractive <strong>and</strong> changing stimuli, express emotions <strong>of</strong> satisfaction when<br />

20


"correct" <strong>and</strong> disappointment when they go "wrong" <strong>and</strong> fail to anticipate the effect <strong>of</strong> their<br />

actions (Papoušek, 1967). Piaget (1962) had described expressions <strong>of</strong> "pleasure in mastery"<br />

when an infant is playing with effects in this way.<br />

Age-related changes in body <strong>and</strong> brain transform what the infant may be aware <strong>of</strong> <strong>and</strong> what is<br />

attempted or sought for, <strong>and</strong> this is not only a development <strong>of</strong> powers <strong>of</strong> action <strong>and</strong> perception<br />

– the pleasure in games emotional relations with companions are also changing (Stern,<br />

1985/2000; Trevarthen, 1980,1992; Trevarthen <strong>and</strong> Aitken, 2003). Once a child is a mobile<br />

toddler the interest <strong>of</strong> the world has become a consuming interest in the meanings that can be<br />

shared with others (Hubley <strong>and</strong> Trevarthen, 1979; Trevarthen <strong>and</strong> Hubley, 1978; Trevarthen,<br />

1988, 1989a). Before a language is learned the child is becoming a thinker <strong>and</strong> actor in cultural<br />

ways. The motivation for this learned transformation in activities <strong>and</strong> experience appears to be<br />

a direct outgrowth <strong>of</strong> the integrated mobility <strong>and</strong> intelligence with which the infant was born,<br />

<strong>and</strong> among the principles retained is a human sense <strong>of</strong> time.<br />

RHYTHM: Moving to the Pulse <strong>of</strong> the Mind<br />

Organisms, with the adaptive morphology <strong>of</strong> their bodies that defines for each species an integrated<br />

Self in its spaces <strong>of</strong> growth <strong>and</strong> activity, have vital rhythms that give measure to the time <strong>of</strong> their<br />

life, both within the body, <strong>and</strong> in motor engagements with the world. The "biochronology" <strong>of</strong> life,<br />

confirmed by the science <strong>of</strong> "chronobiology", demonstrates rhythms <strong>of</strong> plants <strong>and</strong> animals that are<br />

adapted to respond <strong>and</strong> adjust to the diurnal <strong>and</strong> seasonal cycles <strong>of</strong> events in the environment, over<br />

periods that may extend through years to the phases <strong>of</strong> a life-time (Foster <strong>and</strong> Kreitzman, 2004;<br />

Osborne, 2009a; Trevarthen, 2009c).<br />

Animals as individuals exhibit a coherence <strong>of</strong> timing in all they do <strong>and</strong>, therefore, in all they<br />

experience. This temporal integrity <strong>of</strong> an animal's activity requires 'self-synchrony' coupling<br />

pacemakers in the vital organs inside their body, <strong>and</strong> in the centres <strong>of</strong> their brain that direct somatic<br />

movements <strong>of</strong> limbs <strong>and</strong> the whole body, <strong>and</strong> that sense the environment accordingly. For<br />

conscious intelligence, actions <strong>of</strong> mobile parts <strong>and</strong> the uptake <strong>of</strong> information by different modalities<br />

<strong>of</strong> sense must be orchestrated in one time (Pöppel, 1994; Pöppel <strong>and</strong> Wittmann, 1999), <strong>and</strong> brains at<br />

all levels <strong>of</strong> complexity are rhythm-generating <strong>and</strong> coordinating systems in dynamic<br />

communication with the effectors <strong>and</strong> sensors <strong>of</strong> the body (Buzsaki, 2006).<br />

The energy expending efforts <strong>of</strong> the limbs <strong>and</strong> body to act in adaptive ways in the environment are<br />

supported by changes in autonomic activity <strong>of</strong> internal organs that take sources <strong>of</strong> energy from the<br />

environment to supply the tissues <strong>and</strong> organs with substances essential to their health, as well as<br />

defending against stress, injury <strong>and</strong> infection by pathogenic organisms. The autonomic nervous<br />

21


system has its own rhythms (Delamont et al, 1998), which are integrated with somatic rhythms in<br />

the affective nervous system (Panksepp <strong>and</strong> Trevarthen, 2009), the emotions <strong>of</strong> which regulate the<br />

intensity <strong>and</strong> goals <strong>of</strong> action, <strong>and</strong> balance exertions against recuperation. Thus is set up a hierarchy<br />

<strong>of</strong> times, a 'biochronological spectrum', by which both intentional actions <strong>and</strong> the vital functions <strong>of</strong><br />

the body are kept efficient <strong>and</strong> well (Trevarthen, 1999b; 2009c).<br />

Emergence <strong>of</strong> Life Times Before Birth<br />

Human embryos have beating hearts from the first month after conception when the body is 5 mm<br />

long <strong>and</strong> before there are any motor nerves to activate the muscles (Trevarthen, 2004c). From 6<br />

weeks, before there are any sensory inputs to the spinal cord, they perform rhythmically paced<br />

whole body movements, bending the spine. Foetuses, with the first core motivating systems <strong>of</strong><br />

neurones linking up the different motor centres <strong>of</strong> the brain stem <strong>and</strong> spinal cord, show, with<br />

increasing frequency between 10 <strong>and</strong> 14 weeks, periods <strong>of</strong> more differentiated <strong>and</strong> guided cyclic<br />

movements <strong>of</strong> the now well-developed <strong>and</strong> clearly human eyes, facial muscles, jaws <strong>and</strong> h<strong>and</strong>s.<br />

These movements, which appear to be directional <strong>and</strong> self-sensing, are rhythmic..<br />

As the body grows through cycles <strong>of</strong> differentiation <strong>of</strong> parts <strong>and</strong> reintegration <strong>of</strong> the whole, so the<br />

coherence <strong>of</strong> movements changes. Around three months <strong>of</strong> gestation there are many anarchic<br />

twitches <strong>and</strong> startles <strong>of</strong> parts <strong>of</strong> the body, presumably originating in the rapidly developing brain<br />

stem, <strong>and</strong> these become integrated again by 18 weeks into flowing patterns. At 20 weeks fetuses are<br />

active approximately 25% <strong>of</strong> the time, moving about once every minute. Heart rate responses to<br />

sound also begin at about 20 weeks (Lecanuet, et al., 1995; Parncutt, 2006). From this stage until<br />

term at 40 weeks fetal heart rate slows appreciably <strong>and</strong> becomes more variable due to increasing<br />

parasympathetic maturation. Respiratory movements <strong>and</strong> amniotic breathing appear several weeks<br />

before birth, <strong>and</strong> heart rate changes have been coordinated with phases <strong>of</strong> motor activity from 24<br />

weeks (James, Pillai, & Smoleniec, 1995). This is indicative <strong>of</strong> the formation <strong>of</strong> a prospective<br />

control <strong>of</strong> autonomic state coupled to readiness for episodes <strong>of</strong> muscular activity engaging with the<br />

environment, a feature <strong>of</strong> brain function that Jeannerod (1994) has cited as evidence for the<br />

formation <strong>of</strong> cerebral 'motor images' underlying conscious awareness <strong>and</strong> purposeful movement.<br />

Research on the behavior, psychology <strong>and</strong> physiology <strong>of</strong> the fetus indicates that in the last trimester<br />

functions are established in anticipation <strong>of</strong> an active post-natal life, <strong>and</strong> especially for assimilating<br />

<strong>and</strong> collaborating with maternal care (Lecanuet et al., 1995). Motor coordinations exist that are<br />

obviously adapted for visual exploration, reaching <strong>and</strong> grasping, walking, <strong>and</strong> for expressive<br />

communication, by facial expression <strong>and</strong> gesture (de Vries, Visser & Prechtl, 1984; Prechtl, 1984).<br />

22


The Processes <strong>of</strong> Life Time Express Narratives <strong>of</strong> 'Musicality'; In Self Regulation, In Self<br />

Awareness <strong>and</strong> In <strong>Communication</strong><br />

The gracefully coupled rhythms <strong>of</strong> a newborn infant's movement unfold in time like a melody,<br />

usually with no detectable 'practical' purpose. One presumes that is why they have been called not<br />

merely "involuntary" but "r<strong>and</strong>om". The adaptive value <strong>of</strong> this 'musicality' <strong>of</strong> human body<br />

movement, what it is controlled to do, soon becomes apparent in communication, when its powers<br />

<strong>of</strong> attracting attentive others to move in counterpoint or synchrony <strong>and</strong> to entrain <strong>and</strong> respond to<br />

their separate interests in a emotional narrative <strong>of</strong> purposes <strong>and</strong> experiences become obvious<br />

(Trevarthen et al, 2010). "Communicative musicality" is an elaboration <strong>of</strong> the polyrhythmic<br />

harmony <strong>of</strong> movement <strong>of</strong> a human body capable <strong>of</strong> acting with versatile grace to negotiate the<br />

spaces <strong>of</strong> a complex world. It is an evolutionary elaboration for cultural semiosis, a form <strong>of</strong> selfexpression<br />

that other humans are equipped to share, enjoy <strong>and</strong> educate in artful performances <strong>of</strong><br />

collective polyrhythmia (Malloch <strong>and</strong> Trevarthen, 2009). The rhythmic, musical time <strong>of</strong> human<br />

movement has a unique narrative power, inviting shared learning. That is its meaning (Kühl, 2007)<br />

SYMPATHY: Detecting Company <strong>and</strong> Synchronising Actions to Make Shared Meaning<br />

Time <strong>and</strong> measure are to instrumental Music what order <strong>and</strong> method are to discourse; they<br />

break it into proper parts <strong>and</strong> divisions, by which we are enabled both to remember better<br />

what has gone before, <strong>and</strong> frequently to foresee somewhat <strong>of</strong> what is to come after: we<br />

frequently foresee the return <strong>of</strong> a period which we know must correspond to another which<br />

we remember to have gone before; <strong>and</strong> according to the saying <strong>of</strong> an ancient philosopher<br />

<strong>and</strong> musician, the enjoyment <strong>of</strong> Music arises partly from memory <strong>and</strong> partly from<br />

foresight.<br />

Adam Smith ([1777] 1982: 204)<br />

Human life time is adapted to make cultural narratives about a human-made world <strong>and</strong> its history.<br />

From birth the rhythm <strong>of</strong> life, <strong>and</strong> 'stories <strong>of</strong> human vitality', are shared, building in imagination <strong>and</strong><br />

memory a "proto-habitus" or companionship in meaning (Gratier <strong>and</strong> Trevarthen, 2008). We live<br />

together in the times we make.<br />

In 1974, William Condon <strong>and</strong> Lou S<strong>and</strong>er reported in Science that the gestures <strong>of</strong> a newborn may<br />

respond in coordinated precision to the prosodic rhythm <strong>of</strong> an adult voice (Condon & S<strong>and</strong>er,<br />

1974). The claim was greeted with skepticism by psychologists <strong>and</strong> paediatricians convinced that<br />

such temporal coordination with another person was beyond the psychological or neurological<br />

23


powers <strong>of</strong> a newborn, deemed to be at the mercy <strong>of</strong> reflex reactions to stimuli <strong>and</strong> incapable even <strong>of</strong><br />

such precise coordination in time for their own body movements. However, the phenomenon, as<br />

well as the authors' suggestion that the intersubjective timing <strong>and</strong> expression is important for<br />

language acquisition, has been confirmed by subsequent studies <strong>of</strong> how communication with infants<br />

develops with the aid <strong>of</strong> rhythmic vocalizations <strong>and</strong> gestures synchronized both within the infant<br />

<strong>and</strong> in engagements with others (Stern, 1971; Jaffe, Stern <strong>and</strong> Peery, 1973; Bateson, 1975, 1979;<br />

Trevarthen, 1979, 1986, 2009b; Beebe, Stern <strong>and</strong> Jaffe, 1979; Stern <strong>and</strong> Gibbon, 1980; Tronick, Als<br />

<strong>and</strong> Brazelton, 1980; Beebe et al., 1985; Jaffe et al., 2001; Stern, 1985, 2010).<br />

Daniel Stern (2010) has developed a science <strong>of</strong> the "vitality dynamics" <strong>of</strong> infants' actions, <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong><br />

their sympathetic responses to the vitality <strong>and</strong> mutual "attunement" <strong>of</strong> movements in dialogues <strong>and</strong><br />

games with a partner. He demonstrates that these mutually regulated dynamics, mediated by<br />

"intermodal fluency" in a common sense <strong>of</strong> time, have a major role in deciding the fate <strong>of</strong><br />

communications in therapy, <strong>and</strong> the aesthetic powers <strong>of</strong> all the temporal arts – dance, music, theatre<br />

<strong>and</strong> film (Stern, 1974a, b, 1985, 1992, 1999, 2004, 2010). Nigel Osborne (2009b) reviews a wide<br />

experience <strong>of</strong> how active music, by engaging with the impulses <strong>of</strong> movement <strong>of</strong> performers may be<br />

used as therapy for individuals traumatised by war, helping the regulation <strong>of</strong> their physiological<br />

functions <strong>and</strong> inspiring self-confidence <strong>and</strong> pleasure in companionship. Clearly it is part <strong>of</strong> human<br />

biology to move in time with others for well-being <strong>and</strong> for learning.<br />

Proto-Conversational Beginnings<br />

"The study <strong>of</strong> timing <strong>and</strong> sequencing showed that certainly the mother <strong>and</strong> probably the<br />

infant, in addition to conforming in general to a regular pattern, were acting to sustain it or to<br />

restore it when it faltered, waiting for the expected vocalization from the other <strong>and</strong> then after<br />

a pause resuming vocalization, as if to elicit a response that had not been forthcoming. These<br />

interactions were characterized by a sort <strong>of</strong> delighted, ritualized courtesy <strong>and</strong> more or less<br />

sustained attention <strong>and</strong> mutual gaze. Many <strong>of</strong> the vocalizations were <strong>of</strong> types not described in<br />

the acoustic literature on infancy, since they were very brief <strong>and</strong> faint, <strong>and</strong> yet were crucial<br />

parts <strong>of</strong> the jointly sustained performances."<br />

(Bateson, 1979, p. 65).<br />

Mary Catherine Bateson, an anthropologist <strong>and</strong> linguist with an interest in ritual, described in these<br />

words her experience <strong>of</strong> what she called a "proto-conversation" between a mother <strong>and</strong> her 9-weekold<br />

infant recorded on film <strong>and</strong> studied by her at MIT in 1974. She broke fertile new ground when<br />

she accepted this communication as mutually motivated <strong>and</strong> preparatory to human language <strong>and</strong><br />

ritual culture.<br />

24


Bateson used her knowledge <strong>of</strong> animal ethology, <strong>and</strong> her father's theory <strong>of</strong> the "ecology <strong>of</strong> mind"<br />

(Bateson, 1972), to propose that, "human behavioral <strong>and</strong> adaptive diversity provide the prime<br />

argument against innate knowledge, unless we can express that knowledge as an innate, perhaps<br />

highly specific, ability to learn. In fact, imprinting <strong>and</strong> other such innate learning <strong>and</strong> teaching<br />

mechanisms are what we should expect to find in human learning, because imprinting is precisely a<br />

way <strong>of</strong> taking advantage <strong>of</strong> the economies <strong>of</strong> genotypic programming in species whose patterns <strong>of</strong><br />

adaptation require flexibility <strong>and</strong> variation." (p. 67). Her description <strong>of</strong> how a mother is attracted to<br />

support the infant's interest in joint performance <strong>and</strong> learning how to enrich it anticipates Bruner's<br />

proposal that any Language Aquisition Device, needs a Language Support System (Bruner, 1983).<br />

Bateson's account is incompatible with Skinner's language learning theory, <strong>and</strong> also with Noam<br />

Chomsky's theory <strong>of</strong> a special genetic language acquisition device adapted to make infinite<br />

messages out <strong>of</strong> digital elements in a way unrelated to the communicative powers <strong>of</strong> other animals,<br />

<strong>and</strong> Stephen Pinker's theory that song <strong>and</strong> music are for emotional gratification only <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> no<br />

significance for a theory <strong>of</strong> "the language instinct". Researchers <strong>of</strong> the song <strong>and</strong> dance-like<br />

behaviours <strong>of</strong> animals, <strong>and</strong> the special motivation for their learning, are convinced that there are<br />

antecedents there for the evolution <strong>of</strong> the grammatical flexibility <strong>and</strong> semantic productivity <strong>of</strong> both<br />

music <strong>and</strong> language in human education (Wallin et al., 2000; Merker, 2009a; Cross <strong>and</strong> Morley,<br />

2009; Dissanayake, 2009).<br />

Bateson concludes her richly theorized account <strong>of</strong> the mutual motivation for protoconversation as<br />

follows:<br />

"… we are suggesting that in addition to the advantages for learning given by intense<br />

attention <strong>and</strong> pleasure, the infant's participation sets the stage for learning: once he knows the<br />

'rules <strong>of</strong> the game' <strong>and</strong> can anticipate patterns, he can also deliberately <strong>and</strong> playfully vary<br />

them <strong>and</strong> he has a 'h<strong>and</strong>le' on what he is trying to underst<strong>and</strong>. Here at the prelinguistic level<br />

we can see the child playing a 'grammatical' game. This should cast new light on our data on<br />

games playing, imitation <strong>and</strong> mother-child interaction at later stages <strong>of</strong> development. Indeed,<br />

it provides an analogy for underst<strong>and</strong>ing a wide variety <strong>of</strong> interactions in which change or<br />

learning takes place, from psychotherapy to religious ritual to the ordinary pleasures <strong>of</strong><br />

conversation, <strong>and</strong> the general phenomenon <strong>of</strong> active participatory learning."<br />

(Bateson, 1979, p. 76).<br />

Play Stretches the Intersubjective Space, Inspiring Meanings <strong>and</strong> Rituals, Inprovising Ambitious<br />

25


<strong>and</strong> Provocative Form<br />

Increasingly playful, provocative negotiation seems to be a key element in the serious business <strong>of</strong><br />

the mature language <strong>and</strong> intelligence (Bateson, 1955; Turner, 1982; Whitehead, 2008; Reddy,<br />

2008). Provocative irregularity <strong>of</strong> composition, twisting conventional expectations, is also central to<br />

the creativity <strong>of</strong> the arts, as Stravinski explained in his lectures on The Poetics <strong>of</strong> Music –<br />

"But just as the eye completes the lines <strong>of</strong> a drawing, which the painter has knowingly left<br />

incomplete, just so the ear may be called upon to complete a chord <strong>and</strong> cooperate in its<br />

resolution. ... Dissonance, in this instance, plays the part <strong>of</strong> an allusion. … All music is<br />

nothing more than a succession <strong>of</strong> impulses that converge towards a definite point <strong>of</strong> repose.<br />

That is as true <strong>of</strong> Gregorian chant as it is <strong>of</strong> a Bach fugue, as true <strong>of</strong> Brahms's music as it is <strong>of</strong><br />

Debussy's. … This general law <strong>of</strong> attraction is satisfied in only a limited way by the<br />

traditional diatonic system, for that system possesses no absolute value."<br />

(Igor Stravinsky, 1947. Poetics <strong>of</strong> Music in the Form <strong>of</strong> Six Lessons. Cambridge, MA:<br />

Harvard University Press, pp. 34 to 36).<br />

Bateson's account <strong>of</strong> the foundations <strong>of</strong> human communication <strong>and</strong> her theory <strong>of</strong> its importance as a<br />

"species specific mechanism for learning" <strong>of</strong> language <strong>and</strong> cultural rituals were supported by<br />

contemporary studies <strong>of</strong> musical sensibilities in games <strong>and</strong> dialogues with young infants in New<br />

York (Stern, 1974a, b, 1977, 1985; Stern et al., 1977), at Harvard, Cambridge, UK, <strong>and</strong> Edinburgh<br />

(Brazelton, 1973, 1979; Brazelton et al., 1977; Richards <strong>and</strong> Dunn (Bernal), 1971; Richards, 1973;<br />

Trevarthen, 1974a, b, 1977, 1979), in Munich (Papoušek <strong>and</strong> Papoušek, 1977) <strong>and</strong> in Toronto<br />

(Trehub, 1973) <strong>and</strong> has been richly confirmed by a host <strong>of</strong> studies <strong>of</strong> the last 3 decades. Human<br />

beings come to life with an "innate intersubjectivity" embodied in the forms <strong>and</strong> rhythms <strong>of</strong> human<br />

expression in intimate communication when there is no language, <strong>and</strong> this talent is foundational for<br />

learning language <strong>and</strong> for the propagation <strong>of</strong> culture.<br />

Human Semiosis: Embodied Intentions, With Their Feelings, Become Dis-Embodied Rituals,<br />

Symbols <strong>and</strong> Logic, In the Metaphorical 'Play' <strong>of</strong> Culture<br />

Animal social life is full <strong>of</strong> 'drama', <strong>of</strong> performance in 'play' <strong>of</strong> actions done to display vitality <strong>of</strong><br />

intentions that are 'not true', <strong>and</strong> to 'trick' or 'tease' in engagement (Bateson, 1956, 1972; Byrne <strong>and</strong><br />

Whiten, 1988; Cheney et al., 1995; Bek<strong>of</strong>f <strong>and</strong> Byers, 1998; Bråten, 2009; de Waal, 2009). Human<br />

play is, from infancy, seeking negotiation <strong>of</strong> new forms <strong>of</strong> play, <strong>of</strong> ritual theatrical performances in<br />

which expectations are tested in narratives where imaginative goals <strong>and</strong> personalities come alive<br />

(Turner, 1982; Reddy, 2008), "an intermediate area <strong>of</strong> experiencing, to which inner reality <strong>and</strong><br />

26


external life both contribute" (Winnicott, 1958, p. 2). An action song that intrigues a six-month-old<br />

is a ritual narrative with rhythmic cycles <strong>of</strong> display that repeats, with teasing variations, forms <strong>of</strong><br />

action <strong>and</strong> sound passed on from ancestors -- a performance it is memorable as something shared<br />

with affection (Trevarthen, 1995, 1999b, 2005a, b; Eckerdal <strong>and</strong> Merker, 2009). Play is full <strong>of</strong><br />

energy, fantasy <strong>and</strong> self-gratification <strong>and</strong>, with laughter it brings joy to strengthen relationships<br />

(Panksepp, 2000; Panksepp <strong>and</strong> Burgdorf, 2003). It can energise the whole body to run <strong>and</strong> jump,<br />

shout with excitement, or be shared with a rising intonation, a wink or a shrug. It is a display <strong>of</strong><br />

self-consciousness full <strong>of</strong> invention that appeals to others, inviting co-creation <strong>of</strong> meaning<br />

(Whitehead, 2008). <strong>Communication</strong> in play is by means <strong>of</strong> extravagant <strong>and</strong> ritualised motility,<br />

using the body not to perform essential acts within the environment or to use it, but made for<br />

display to others, <strong>and</strong> attentive their response <strong>and</strong> appreciation. It is made up <strong>of</strong> actions not needed<br />

at all for the self, or <strong>of</strong> self-regulations made in an exaggerated 'inessential' way.<br />

Sophisticate adult life, ruled as it is by intangible facts, beliefs <strong>and</strong> rules encoded in totally<br />

conventional <strong>and</strong> immaterial language, is at the same time full <strong>of</strong> playful, 'theatrical' extravagance.<br />

For example preparing or eating a complicated meal when you are not hungry, <strong>and</strong> dressing<br />

elaborately for it; looking about 'significantly' when not interested in seeing anything; calling out<br />

incredulously at impossible stories, or at a missed tennis shot; pretending to listen 'respectfully'<br />

when not interested; running about when not going anywhere, as in sport; <strong>and</strong>, if one is a TV<br />

presenter or politician, waiving h<strong>and</strong>s about when one has nothing to say. Every encounter with<br />

others is regulated by the special intensities or emphasis <strong>and</strong> timing <strong>of</strong> actions, as in courteous or<br />

persuasive conversation, in a 'match' with an opponent in sport, when 'acting' in a performance for<br />

an audience.<br />

Human artefacts, too, have playful or pretentious beauty (sometimes heavily tempered by the logic<br />

<strong>and</strong> technique <strong>of</strong> construction or composition in sophisticated media), exhibiting the care <strong>and</strong><br />

artfulness with which they were manufactured <strong>and</strong> crafted, or comm<strong>and</strong>ing significance for a ritual<br />

purpose that requires 'proper' performance <strong>and</strong> may engender intensely shared feelings. Works <strong>of</strong><br />

art are received as having aesthetic or moral values that are inferred from the manner <strong>of</strong> their<br />

execution or from the stories they relate.<br />

Morality, the display <strong>of</strong> emotions that regulate relationships, status in the group, <strong>and</strong><br />

cooperative purposes between actors, beyond the needs <strong>of</strong> parental care or sex, is apparent in<br />

animal societies (e. g. Cheney et al., 1995). The more elaborate cultural achievements <strong>of</strong><br />

human society, as well as children's mastery <strong>of</strong> work <strong>and</strong> play in families <strong>and</strong> schools, depend<br />

on modulation <strong>of</strong> expressions <strong>of</strong> self-satisfaction <strong>and</strong> modesty, all engagements being acted<br />

with care for feelings in a "continuum between pride <strong>and</strong> shame" (Scheff, 1988; Barnes, 2000;<br />

27


Trevarthen, 2005b). This moral regulation gives meaning <strong>and</strong> value to the "underst<strong>and</strong>ing <strong>of</strong><br />

intentions" <strong>and</strong> "theory <strong>of</strong> mind" (Melz<strong>of</strong>f, 1995; Tomasello, et al., 2005), now conceived to be<br />

the distinctive achievement <strong>of</strong> human intelligence by cognitive psychology.<br />

The Psychobiology <strong>of</strong> Intrinsic Aesthetic <strong>and</strong> Moral Values <strong>of</strong> Culture<br />

Human vocalizations <strong>and</strong> gestures mediate in the creation <strong>of</strong> a unique cultural world where<br />

motives are shared in narrations <strong>of</strong> movement expressive <strong>of</strong> inventions in thinking <strong>and</strong> acting.<br />

Organized sequences <strong>of</strong> actions convey original thoughts, intentions, imaginary or remembered<br />

experiences, <strong>and</strong> these actions are made, not only with logical order to perform some task in<br />

the world, but with feeling for the drama <strong>of</strong> changing experience (Gratier & Trevarthen 2008;<br />

Trevarthen, 2009a, b). Gestural expressions, with their innate timing <strong>and</strong> combination in<br />

narrations, are the foundation for learning all the forms <strong>and</strong> values <strong>of</strong> the elaborate cultural<br />

conventions <strong>of</strong> art, technology <strong>and</strong> language (Gentilucci & Corballis 2006).<br />

Contemporary brain science is helping us accept that intersubjective communication <strong>of</strong> intentions<br />

with emotions is part <strong>of</strong> the adaptive design <strong>of</strong> our cerebral physiology (Gallese 2003; Gallese,<br />

Keysers & Rizzolatti 2004). Nevertheless, while it is evident that expressions <strong>of</strong> the voice <strong>and</strong><br />

gestures <strong>of</strong> the h<strong>and</strong>s function by engaging primitive ‘generative’ process <strong>of</strong> sympathy, how the<br />

dynamics <strong>of</strong> brain activity transmit between persons, remains mysterious, <strong>and</strong> controversial. We<br />

cannot explain how the gestural motive evolving in one brain becomes a message that motivates<br />

another brain to pick up the process in a particular imitative or complementary way. Presumably it<br />

is by way <strong>of</strong> sensitivity to parameters <strong>of</strong> the control processes <strong>of</strong> self-awareness in others similar to<br />

those <strong>of</strong> our own individual self-awareness that we become aware <strong>of</strong> others' intentions <strong>and</strong> feelings,<br />

<strong>and</strong> can participate in them. Presumably the representation <strong>of</strong> the Self is similar to but distinct from<br />

the representation <strong>of</strong> the Other, as proposed by Stein Bråten (1988, 1992, 2009).<br />

Moreover, there must be an adaptive enhancement <strong>of</strong> the evidence in movements, beyond what is<br />

required to guide the actions <strong>of</strong> the self, to sustain efficient 'on line' communication, such as that<br />

Bateson describes between a mother <strong>and</strong> a young infant. And there must be an immediate appraisal<br />

<strong>of</strong> the quality <strong>of</strong> engagement, <strong>and</strong> a process that can regulate it between the representations <strong>of</strong><br />

communicating subjects. Indeed there is abundant evidence for a special 'extravagance <strong>and</strong><br />

adornment' <strong>of</strong> movements <strong>and</strong> actions to serve communication <strong>of</strong> complex <strong>and</strong> rapid mental<br />

activities, <strong>and</strong> a set <strong>of</strong> powerful emotions that evaluate the coupling <strong>of</strong> their motivations in separate<br />

individuals.<br />

28


How Feelings Revealed To Others Are Adjusted To Promote a 'Solidarity <strong>of</strong> Underst<strong>and</strong>ing' In<br />

Companionship<br />

In social life, the distinction between a movement or posture made ‘in communication’ <strong>and</strong><br />

therefore a ‘gesture’, as opposed to one not intended for communication but entirely for<br />

individual purposes may be unclear. It would appear to depend on the abilities <strong>of</strong> one<br />

individual to ‘feel with’ the motives that cause <strong>and</strong> direct any kind <strong>of</strong> action <strong>of</strong> the other, aided<br />

by a special hypertrophy <strong>of</strong> motives that makes that kind <strong>of</strong> action more conspicuous or<br />

'public', <strong>and</strong> more sensitive to responses <strong>of</strong> other agents, hence 'self-conscious' <strong>and</strong> 'playful'<br />

(Bateson, 1955, 1956, 1972; Reddy, 2008; Whitehead, 2008). The process will gain direction<br />

<strong>and</strong> subtlety by learning in real life communication, but this learning itself would appear to<br />

require innate adaptations for immediate intersubjective 'self-other-conscious' awareness, one<br />

that is active from the start <strong>of</strong> life with others <strong>and</strong> that can appreciate "good quality" or<br />

"sensitive" responses, emotionally (Trevarthen, 1998a, b, 1999a, 2004a, d, 2009a, 2010; Beebe<br />

et al. 2005; Zlatev et al. 2008).<br />

Attachment theory focuses attention on the emotions between infant <strong>and</strong> parent that serve to<br />

care for <strong>and</strong> protect the infant, <strong>and</strong> research has shown how important for the infant's emotional<br />

attachment to the mother is her sensitivity for the infant's needs, <strong>and</strong> the damaging effects <strong>of</strong><br />

deficiencies in sympathetic response on either side (Bowlby, 1951, 1988; Ainsworth et al.,<br />

1978; Klaus <strong>and</strong> Kennel, 1976; Parkes, et al., 1982; Fonagy et al., 1991; Beebe et al., 2010).<br />

But from the neonate stage, infants <strong>and</strong> mothers may gain joy from imitative companionship<br />

that leads to creative <strong>and</strong> cooperative play, <strong>and</strong> in which the infant can be proactive or<br />

"provocative" (Nagy <strong>and</strong> Molnár, 1994; Nagy, 2010; Reddy, 2008; Bråten <strong>and</strong> Trevarthen,<br />

2007; Trevarthen, 2001, 2005a, 2006, 2009a, b, 2010). This is the kind <strong>of</strong> motivation that, as<br />

Mary Catherine Bateson proposed, leads to cultural learning.<br />

Motives <strong>and</strong> emotions are communicated between persons by an immediate sympathetic perception<br />

<strong>of</strong> their dynamic features – i.e. by assimilation <strong>of</strong> their proprioceptive feelings <strong>and</strong> exteroceptive<br />

interests by others into altero-ceptive regulation (Trevarthen, 1986). This interpersonal regulation<br />

in the moment <strong>of</strong> communicating opens the way to further <strong>and</strong> more enduring levels or fields <strong>of</strong><br />

regulation for actions, their manners <strong>and</strong> goals. What may be called socio-ceptive regulation <strong>of</strong><br />

actions in relationships <strong>and</strong> communities leads to development <strong>of</strong> collective ways <strong>of</strong> behaving that<br />

become an environment <strong>of</strong> common underst<strong>and</strong>ings or a ‘habitus’ for cooperative life (Frank <strong>and</strong><br />

Trevarthen, 2010). Further elaboration <strong>of</strong> conventional customs, rituals, structures, tools,<br />

institutions, symbols <strong>and</strong> beliefs, <strong>and</strong> languages, gives cooperative works trans-generational<br />

meaning in an iconoceptive regulation <strong>of</strong> human cultural behaviour.<br />

29


These distinctions <strong>of</strong> how actions are regulated for different purposes are important in the sharing <strong>of</strong><br />

the creativity <strong>and</strong> exuberance <strong>of</strong> art, <strong>and</strong> in any educational or therapeutic practice designed to<br />

strengthen the participation <strong>of</strong> persons, children or adults, in affectionate <strong>and</strong> meaningful<br />

relationships with others. All art <strong>and</strong> therapy depends on respect for altero-ceptive <strong>and</strong> ‘higher’,<br />

more contrived forms <strong>of</strong> regulation. When a learner experiences difficulties in underst<strong>and</strong>ing <strong>and</strong><br />

practice <strong>of</strong> a culturally valued behaviour, such as appropriate social manners, speech or<br />

performance <strong>of</strong> sport or music, it is not sufficient to identify a fault <strong>and</strong> try to treat it as if the<br />

affected individual were a physical system or a form <strong>of</strong> life without human sympathies. ‘Intent<br />

participation’ in new experience with a teacher is required (Rog<strong>of</strong>f, 2003).<br />

Emotional Disorders Are Disorders <strong>of</strong> Relating<br />

Because human minds naturally seek to live in relationships, disorders <strong>of</strong> motives <strong>and</strong> emotions,<br />

<strong>and</strong> therefore <strong>of</strong> learning, thinking <strong>and</strong> communicating with or without language are disorders <strong>of</strong><br />

processes between persons, in a ‘system’ <strong>of</strong> engagements (S<strong>and</strong>er 1983; Tronick 2007). Dealing<br />

with a diagnosed fault in an individual leads to recognition that the effect <strong>of</strong> the fault is between that<br />

person <strong>and</strong> others. Emotion is not simply the regulating <strong>of</strong> states <strong>of</strong> arousal, nor just the building <strong>of</strong><br />

schemas for objects <strong>and</strong> relationships, but the regulating <strong>of</strong> acting with intentions that have both<br />

defined goals <strong>and</strong> creativity <strong>of</strong> interpretation. Actions are evaluated by the emotions that accompany<br />

their motives as forces within the human psyche, which learning <strong>of</strong> language <strong>and</strong> other cultural<br />

skills channel <strong>and</strong> elaborate. All these functions <strong>of</strong> human gesture are evident in the first two years<br />

<strong>of</strong> life before a child can speak with the special shared intelligence <strong>of</strong> language (Stern 1985/2000).<br />

They show their beginnings before birth, <strong>and</strong> after birth they create, in collaboration with<br />

sympathetic companions, what we have called a "communicative musicality" (Malloch &<br />

Trevarthen 2009).<br />

The argument against sophisticated constructivism to explain interpersonal consciousness is lucidly<br />

set out in recent text by Vasudevi Reddy (2008), who reviews, with skillful <strong>and</strong> systematically<br />

examined observations, the complex, engaging nature <strong>of</strong> human infants <strong>and</strong> their remarkable,<br />

hitherto largely unremarked, perceptive <strong>and</strong> intentional social awareness, rich in self-conscious<br />

humour. In her opening chapters, Reddy proposes that infants, like adults, experience the<br />

subjectivity <strong>of</strong> another through ‘second-person’ inter-personal inter-action. She sets presents a logic<br />

that knowing the subjectivity, or mind, <strong>of</strong> another entails engaging with their expressions directly,<br />

forming the so-called second-person perspective, i.e. one that is neither first-person (from within an<br />

isolated individual mind) nor third-person (by an observing other, empathically), but an engaging<br />

self-with-other, sympathetically.<br />

30


From this position, neglected by developmental psychologists seeking more rational <strong>and</strong><br />

representational explanations, but shared by the ‘folk’ psychologies <strong>of</strong> mothers the world over, we<br />

can see that knowing <strong>and</strong> sharing with another mind is not just about communicating with volitional<br />

calculation, or what Whitehead describes as ‘products <strong>of</strong> rational discernment’ (Whitehead 1926, p.<br />

100), but it is about awareness <strong>of</strong> another through direct, shared experience <strong>of</strong> living, creatively <strong>and</strong><br />

with passion. Felt intersubjective activity is the knowing we have <strong>of</strong> one another. Perinatal care that<br />

confirms the intuitions <strong>of</strong> new parents that their unsophisticated child is a conscious a human person<br />

brings great pleasure to them, <strong>and</strong> strengthens the bonds with their infant <strong>and</strong> with one another<br />

(Brazelton, 1993).<br />

Beauty <strong>and</strong> Technique in Manufacture <strong>of</strong> Valued Artefacts, <strong>and</strong> the Performance <strong>of</strong> Musical <strong>and</strong><br />

Dramatic Actions, <strong>and</strong> Works <strong>of</strong> Plastic Art<br />

In every human community people make things that are not essential for practical purposes, but that<br />

are greatly valued for their beauty <strong>and</strong> symbolic significance (Turner, 1991). Beauty is a property <strong>of</strong><br />

the making, <strong>and</strong> it is a neurally mediated quality expected to be shared (Trevarthen, 1995; Panksepp<br />

<strong>and</strong> Trevarthen, 2009). Beauty is valued simply because it can be shared. It makes human works<br />

<strong>and</strong> natural objects ‘special’ in intimacy, <strong>and</strong> in the community (Dissanayake 1988, 2000, 2009).<br />

The appreciation <strong>of</strong> beauty in visible or audible art is extended to objects or places not human made,<br />

but similar in qualities <strong>of</strong> form, proportion, colour, melody or harmony.<br />

When we appreciate a picture, we sense <strong>and</strong> evaluate the work <strong>and</strong> feelings <strong>of</strong> the artist who made<br />

it, <strong>and</strong> the same is true for a song or a performance <strong>of</strong> instrumental music (Br<strong>and</strong>t, 2009). Art is<br />

concerned with the direct communication <strong>of</strong> the pleasure <strong>of</strong> creating shareable experiences <strong>and</strong><br />

objects. It enhances rituals <strong>and</strong> ‘stories’ <strong>of</strong> performance without regard for practical products; that is<br />

what distinguishes it from ‘technique’. However, the skills <strong>of</strong> advanced artistic performance<br />

combine art <strong>and</strong> technique, doing things well (Flohr <strong>and</strong> Trevarthen, 2008; Bannan <strong>and</strong> Woodward,<br />

2009; Rodrigues et al., 2009). Playful arts <strong>and</strong> rituals have special value for development <strong>of</strong> the<br />

child’s brain <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> skills that are valued in vital societies (Opie <strong>and</strong> Opie, 1960; Trevarthen, 1995;<br />

Bruce, 2001; d’Aquili <strong>and</strong> Newberg 1999; Whitehead, 2008). Early education in active, enjoyable<br />

musical experience, with opportunities to acquire <strong>and</strong> share fluent emotive expressions <strong>of</strong><br />

musicality, may have pr<strong>of</strong>ound positive consequences for the rest <strong>of</strong> a child’s mental apparatus <strong>and</strong><br />

for overall development (Bjørkvold, 1992; Flohr <strong>and</strong> Trevarthen, 2008; Bannan <strong>and</strong> Woodward,<br />

2009; Custodero, 2009).<br />

Can Meaning Leave the Body<br />

31


There appears to be a paradox between the generation <strong>and</strong> the substance <strong>of</strong> cultural meaning.<br />

However dependent a meaning may be on embodied expressions <strong>of</strong> imaginative feeling for its<br />

creation <strong>and</strong> for its appreciation, once it becomes accepted as a metaphor it is beginning to leave the<br />

body, to take on an ethereal, timeless power to signify, to become a symbolic 'thing'. This symbol<br />

may be an object, a mark on paper, a car, a electronic pattern in a computer. Surely the logical<br />

meanings <strong>of</strong> symbols, though they are made explicit by human action, have no embodiment. Do<br />

they not become part <strong>of</strong> an ideal repository <strong>of</strong> material information, accepted as 'true', that can last<br />

through many lifetimes <strong>and</strong> be distributed beyond the limits <strong>of</strong> individual human mobility<br />

But symbols have no meaning without live embodiment <strong>of</strong> underst<strong>and</strong>ing. Every signifying form<br />

has to be taken up by a correctly educated mind <strong>and</strong> 're-incarnated' in ideas, thoughts, opinions <strong>and</strong><br />

actions rich in practical utility <strong>and</strong>/or emotional potency (Donald, 2001; Turner <strong>and</strong> Whitehead,<br />

2008). Every symbol has two parts, an intersubjective motivation as well as a referential connection<br />

with an object, event or action <strong>of</strong> human interest (Trevarthen, 1994, 2009a). Regulations or rules '<strong>of</strong><br />

behaviour' are essential in ritual culture – there is 'proper' way to go hunting, elect a leader, pray to<br />

the gods, tell a story, play tennis or a children's game, conduct an election, drive (or walk) in a city<br />

(Durkheim, 1912/1995; Opie <strong>and</strong> Opie, 1960; Radcliffe-Brown, 1961; Turner, 1969, 1982; Merker,<br />

2009b). Language is essential to the building <strong>and</strong> empowerment <strong>of</strong> extensive rational meaning in a<br />

large community <strong>and</strong> must obey rules <strong>of</strong> grammar (Bourdieu, 1991). A song or symphony can be<br />

written in a conventional score. Both music <strong>and</strong> language in symbolic form attend embodied<br />

activation. Both wait to be brought to life in execution, <strong>and</strong> then their manner is open to rational,<br />

aesthetic <strong>and</strong> moral appreciations that can only be imagined or felt by living persons who know<br />

what was intended by their authors. Thus a "social mind", "habitus" or "sociosphere" is generated<br />

by human cooperative play (Durkheim, 1912/1995; Bourdieu, 1990) <strong>and</strong> a symbol or ritual can only<br />

be made to have meaning by a commitment to cause it to 'make sense' in embodied use or<br />

performance <strong>and</strong> in experience shared with others (Frank <strong>and</strong> Trevarthen, 2010).<br />

When a child goes to school he or she learns how to behave in many ways, how to know many<br />

things <strong>and</strong> how to perform many skills. These abilities are learned by sharing embodied<br />

underst<strong>and</strong>ing in "intent participation" with a teacher, (Rog<strong>of</strong>f, 2003; Rog<strong>of</strong>f et al., 2003).<br />

Eventually the knowledge, good behavior <strong>and</strong> skills become employed in a cooperative adult world<br />

in which each agent has an accepted place. From time to time, however, pleasure is required from<br />

the performance <strong>of</strong> less practical activities <strong>of</strong> "recreation" <strong>and</strong> artful performance. As the wisest<br />

philosophers <strong>of</strong> education have insisted, the romantic, trustful <strong>and</strong> inquisitive communication in live<br />

play, which starts the process <strong>of</strong> learning conventional culture, remains as a foundation for the most<br />

practical <strong>and</strong> rational occupations. In the end, all products <strong>of</strong> intersubjectivity remain embodied.<br />

32


References:<br />

Aggleton J.P. (1993) The contribution <strong>of</strong> the amygdala to normal <strong>and</strong> abnormal emotional states.<br />

Trends in the Neurosciences, 16: 328-333.<br />

Ainsworth, M. D. S., Blehar, M. C., Waters, E., & Wall, S. (1978). Patterns <strong>of</strong> Attachment: A<br />

Psychological Study <strong>of</strong> the Strange Situation. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.<br />

Bachevalier, J. (1994) Medial temporal lobe structures <strong>and</strong> autism: A review <strong>of</strong> clinical <strong>and</strong><br />

experimental findings. Neuropsychologia, 32: 627-648.<br />

Baldwin, J. M. (1894). Mental Development in the Child <strong>and</strong> the Race. New York: Macmillan.<br />

Bannan, N. <strong>and</strong> Woodward, S. (2009). Spontaneity in the musicality <strong>and</strong> music learning <strong>of</strong> children.<br />

In S. Malloch, <strong>and</strong> C. Trevarthen, (eds), Communicative Musicality: Exploring the Basis <strong>of</strong><br />

Human Companionship, 465-494. Oxford: Oxford University Press.<br />

Barnes, B. (2000). Underst<strong>and</strong>ing Agency: Social <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>and</strong> Responsible Action. Beverley Hills<br />

<strong>and</strong> London: Sage.<br />

Bateson, G (1955) A theory <strong>of</strong> play <strong>and</strong> fantasy. Psychiatric Research Reports, Series A, 2, 39-51<br />

Bateson, G. (1956). The message 'This is play'. In B. Schaffer (Ed.), Group Processes. New York,<br />

Josiah Macy Foundation.<br />

Bateson, G. (1972). Steps to an Ecology <strong>of</strong> Mind New York: Ballantine.<br />

Bateson, M. C. (1975). Mother-infant exchanges: The epigenesis <strong>of</strong> conversational interaction. In<br />

D. Aaronson <strong>and</strong> R. W. Rieber (Eds.), Developmental Psycholinguistics <strong>and</strong> <strong>Communication</strong><br />

Disorders; Annals <strong>of</strong> the New York Academy <strong>of</strong> Sciences, Vol. 263, (pp. 101-113). New<br />

York: New York Academy <strong>of</strong> Sciences<br />

Bateson, M. C. (1979). The epigenesis <strong>of</strong> conversational interaction: A personal account <strong>of</strong><br />

research development. In M. Bullowa (Ed.), Before Speech: The Beginning <strong>of</strong> Human<br />

<strong>Communication</strong>. (pp. 63-77). London: Cambridge University Press.<br />

Beebe, B. Jaffe, J., Markese, S., Buck, K., Chen, H., Cohen, P., Bahrick, L., Andrews, H. <strong>and</strong><br />

Feldstein, S. (2010). The origins <strong>of</strong> 12-month attachment: A microanalysis <strong>of</strong> 4-month<br />

mother–infant interaction. Attachment & Human Development, 12 (1 & 2), 3 – 141<br />

Beebe, B., Jaffe, J., Feldstein, S., Mays, K. <strong>and</strong> Alson, D. (1985) Inter-personal timing: The<br />

application <strong>of</strong> an adult dialogue model to mother-infant vocal <strong>and</strong> kinesic interactions. In<br />

F.M Field <strong>and</strong> N. Fox (Eds.), Social Perception in Infants. (pp. 217-248) Norwood, N.J.:<br />

Ablex.<br />

Beebe, B., Knoblauch, S., Rustin, J. & Sorter, D. (2005). Forms <strong>of</strong> intersubjectivity in infant<br />

research <strong>and</strong> adult treatment. New York: Other Press.<br />

Beebe, B., Stern, D. <strong>and</strong> Jaffe, J. (1979) The kinesic rhythm <strong>of</strong> mother-infant interactions. In: A.<br />

W. Siegman <strong>and</strong> S. Feldstein (Eds.) Of Speech <strong>and</strong> Time; Temporal Speech Patterns in<br />

Interpersonal Contexts. (pp. 23-34) Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.<br />

Bek<strong>of</strong>f, M. <strong>and</strong> Byers, J. A. (1998). Animal play: Evolutionary, comparative <strong>and</strong> ecological<br />

approaches. New York: Cambridge University Press.<br />

Bernstein, N. (1967) Coordination <strong>and</strong> Regulation <strong>of</strong> Movements. New York: Pergamon.<br />

Bjørkvold, J.-R. (1992). The Muse Within: Creativity <strong>and</strong> <strong>Communication</strong>, Song <strong>and</strong> Play from<br />

Childhood through Maturity. New York: Harper Collins.<br />

Bolinger D (1983). Intonation <strong>and</strong> Gesture. American Speech, 58(2), 156-174.<br />

Bourdieu, P. (1990), The Logic <strong>of</strong> Practice (Palo Alto, CA: Stanford University Press).<br />

33


Bourdieu, P. (1991): Language <strong>and</strong> Symbolic Power. Cambridge: Polity Press.<br />

Bowlby, J. (1951). Maternal Care <strong>and</strong> Mental Health. Geneva: WHO; London: HMSO; New Your:<br />

Columbia University Press.<br />

Bowlby, J. (1988). A Secure Base: Parent-Child Attachment <strong>and</strong> Healthy Human Development.<br />

New York: Basic Books.<br />

Br<strong>and</strong>t PA (2004). Spaces, domains, <strong>and</strong> meaning. Essays in cognitive semiotics. Series European<br />

Semiotics, 4. Peter Lang, Bern, Switzerl<strong>and</strong>.<br />

Br<strong>and</strong>t, P. A. (2009). Music <strong>and</strong> how we became human — a view from cognitive semiotics:<br />

Exploring imaginative hypotheses. In S. Malloch, <strong>and</strong> C. Trevarthen, (eds), Communicative<br />

Musicality: Exploring the Basis <strong>of</strong> Human Companionship, 31-44. Oxford: Oxford<br />

University Press.<br />

Bråten, S. (1988). Between dialogical mind <strong>and</strong> monological reason: Postulating the virtual other.<br />

In M. Campanella (Ed.), Between Rationality <strong>and</strong> Cognition, (pp. 205-235). Turin: Albert<br />

Meynier.<br />

Bråten, S. (1992). The virtual other in infants' minds <strong>and</strong> social feelings. In A. H. Wold (Ed.) The<br />

Dialogical Alternative (Festschrift for Ragnar Rommetveit). (pp. 77-97) Oslo/Oxford:<br />

Sc<strong>and</strong>anavian University Press/Oxford University Press.<br />

Bråten, S. (2009). The Intersubjective Mirror in Infant Learning <strong>and</strong> Evolution <strong>of</strong> Speech.<br />

Amsterdam/Philadelphia: John Benjamins.<br />

Bråten, S.. <strong>and</strong> Trevarthen, C. (2007). Prologue: From infant intersubjectivity <strong>and</strong> participant<br />

movements to simulations <strong>and</strong> conversations in cultural common sense. In S. Bråten (Ed.)<br />

On Being Moved: From Mirror Neurons to Empathy, pp. 21-34. Amsterdam/Philadelphia:<br />

John Benjamins.<br />

Brazelton, T. B. (1973). Neonatal Behavioural Assessment Scale (Clinics in Developmental<br />

Medicine, 50. Spastics International Medical Publications). London: Heinemann Medical<br />

Books.<br />

Brazelton, T. B. (1979). Evidence <strong>of</strong> communication during neonatal assessment. In: M. Bullowa<br />

(Ed.), Before speech: The beginning <strong>of</strong> human communication. pp. 79-88. London,<br />

Cambridge University Press.<br />

Brazelton, T. B. (1984). Neonatal Neurobehavioural Assessment Scale. Clinics in Developmental<br />

Medicine, No. 88. (revised edition). Philadelphia: Lippincott.<br />

Brazelton, T. B. (1993) Touchpoints: Your Child's Emotional <strong>and</strong> Behavioral Development. New<br />

York: Viking.<br />

Brazelton, T. B., Koslowski, B., <strong>and</strong> Main, M. (1974). The origins <strong>of</strong> reciprocity: the early motherinfant<br />

interaction. In: M. Lewis <strong>and</strong> L. A. Rosenblum (Eds.), The Effect <strong>of</strong> the Infant On <strong>Its</strong><br />

Caregiver, pp. 49-76. New York/London: Wiley<br />

Bruce, T. (2001). Learning Through Play - Babies, Toddlers <strong>and</strong> the Foundation Years. London:<br />

Hodder <strong>and</strong> Stoughton.<br />

Bruner, J. S. (1960). The Process <strong>of</strong> Education, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.<br />

Bruner, J. S. (1968). Processes <strong>of</strong> Cognitive Growth: Infancy. (Heinz Werner Lectures, 1968)<br />

Worcester, Mass: Clark University Press with Barri Publishers.<br />

Bruner, J. S. (1983). Child's Talk. Learning to Use Language. New York: Norton.<br />

Bruner, J. S. (1990). Acts <strong>of</strong> Meaning. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.<br />

Bruner, J. S. (1996). The Culture <strong>of</strong> Education. Cambridge, MA.: Harvard University Press.<br />

34


Buber, M. (1937) I <strong>and</strong> thou (First English edition, translated by R. G. Smith). Edinburgh: T. <strong>and</strong><br />

T. Clark Ltd.<br />

Buchler, J. (ed.) (1940) The Philosophy <strong>of</strong> Peirce: Selected Writings. London: Routledge <strong>and</strong><br />

Kegan Paul.<br />

Bullowa, M. (ed.), (1979). Before Speech: The Beginning <strong>of</strong> Human <strong>Communication</strong>. London,<br />

Cambridge University Press.<br />

Buzsaki, G. (2006). Rhythms <strong>of</strong> the Brain. New York: Oxford University Press / Cambridge,<br />

Mass.: MIT Press<br />

Byrne, R. W. <strong>and</strong> Whiten, A. (1988). Machiavellian intelligence. Oxford: Oxford University Press<br />

Cheney, D. L., Seyfarth, R. M. <strong>and</strong> Silk, J. B. (1995). The role <strong>of</strong> grunts in reconciling opponents<br />

<strong>and</strong> facilitating interactions among adult female baboons. Anim Behav 50:249–257<br />

Cioni, G. <strong>and</strong> Castellaci, A. M. (1990) Development <strong>of</strong> fetal <strong>and</strong> neonatal motor activity:<br />

implications for neurology. In H. Block <strong>and</strong> B. Bertenthal (Eds.) Sensory-Motor<br />

Organization <strong>and</strong> Development in Infancy <strong>and</strong> Early Childhood, pp. 135-144. Dordrecht:<br />

Kluwer<br />

Clark, A. (1997). Being There: Putting Brain, Body <strong>and</strong> World Together Again. Cambridge, MA:<br />

MIT Press.<br />

Clark, A. (1999). An embodied cognitive science Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 3(9): 345-351.<br />

Condon WS <strong>and</strong> Ogston W(1966). Sound film analysis <strong>of</strong> normal <strong>and</strong> pathological behavior<br />

patterns. Journal <strong>of</strong> Nervous <strong>and</strong> Mental Disorders, 14, 338–347.<br />

Condon, W. S. <strong>and</strong> S<strong>and</strong>er, L. S. (1974). Neonate movement is synchronized with adult speech:<br />

Interactional participation <strong>and</strong> language acquisition. Science, 183, 99-101.<br />

Cross, I. <strong>and</strong> Morley, I. (2009). The evolution <strong>of</strong> music: Theories, definitions <strong>and</strong> the nature <strong>of</strong> the<br />

evidence. In Malloch, S. <strong>and</strong> Trevarthen, C. (Eds.) Communicative Musicality: Exploring the<br />

Basis <strong>of</strong> Human Companionship, 61-81. Oxford: Oxford University Press.<br />

Cummings, J. L. (1993) Frontal-subcortical circuits <strong>and</strong> human behavior. Archives <strong>of</strong> Neurology,<br />

50: 873-880.<br />

Custodero, L. A. (2009). Intimacy <strong>and</strong> reciprocity in improvisatory musical performance:<br />

Pedagogical lessons from adult artists <strong>and</strong> young children. In Malloch, S. <strong>and</strong> Trevarthen, C.<br />

(Eds.) Communicative Musicality: Exploring the Basis <strong>of</strong> Human Companionship., 513-<br />

530.<br />

Cynader, M. Lepore, F., Guillemot, J.P. (1981) Inter-hemispheric competition during postnatal<br />

development. Nature, 290, 139-140.<br />

d’Aquili, E. G. <strong>and</strong> Newberg, A. B. (1999). The Mystical Mind: Probing the Biology <strong>of</strong> Religious<br />

Experience. Minneapolis, MN: Fortress<br />

Damasio, A. R. (1999). The Feeling <strong>of</strong> What Happens: Body, Emotion <strong>and</strong> the Making <strong>of</strong><br />

Consciousness. London: Heinemann.<br />

Darwin C. (1872) The Expression <strong>of</strong> Emotion in Man <strong>and</strong> Animals. London, Methuen.<br />

Darwin, C. (1981). The Formation <strong>of</strong> Vegetable Mould through the Action <strong>of</strong> Worms, With<br />

Observations on their Habits. London : John Murray<br />

Davidson R. J. <strong>and</strong> Fox N. A. (1982) Asymmetric brain activity discriminates between positive <strong>and</strong><br />

negative affective stimuli in human infants. Science 218:1235-1237<br />

Davidson, R. J., <strong>and</strong> Hugdahl, K. (Eds.) (1995). Brain Asymmetry. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.<br />

35


Dawson, G. (1994) Development <strong>of</strong> emotional expression <strong>and</strong> emotion regulation in infancy:<br />

Contributions <strong>of</strong> the frontal lobes. In Human behavior <strong>and</strong> the developing brain (G. Dawson,<br />

K.W. Fischer, eds) The Guilford Press, New York, pp. 346-379.<br />

de Vries, J. I. P., Visser, G. H. A. <strong>and</strong> Prechtl, H. F. R. (1984) Fetal motility in teh first half <strong>of</strong><br />

pregnancy. In H. F. R. Prechtl (Ed.) Continuity <strong>of</strong> Neural Functions from Prenatal to<br />

Postnatal Life. (pp. 46-64) Oxford: Blackwell.<br />

de Waal, F. (2009). Primates <strong>and</strong> Philosophers: How Morality Evolved (Ed. S. Macedo & J. Ober).<br />

Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.<br />

DeCasper, A. J. <strong>and</strong> Spence, M. J. (1986). Prenatal maternal speech influences newborns'<br />

perception <strong>of</strong> speech sounds. Infant Behavior <strong>and</strong> Development, 9: 133-150.<br />

DeCasper, A. J. <strong>and</strong> Spence, M. J. (1986). Prenatal maternal speech influences newborns'<br />

perception <strong>of</strong> speech sounds. Infant Behavior <strong>and</strong> Development, 9: 133-150.<br />

Delamont, R. S., Julu, P. O. O. <strong>and</strong> Jamal, G. A. (1999). Periodicity <strong>of</strong> a noninvasive measure <strong>of</strong><br />

cardiac vagal tone during non-rapid eye movement sleep in non-sleep-deprived <strong>and</strong> sleepdeprived<br />

normal subjects. Journal <strong>of</strong> Clinical Neurophysiology, 16(2), 146–153.<br />

Dissanayake, E. (1988). What is Art For Seattle: University <strong>of</strong> Washington Press.<br />

Dissanayake, E. (2000). Art <strong>and</strong> Intimacy: How the Arts Began. University <strong>of</strong> Washington Press,<br />

Seattle <strong>and</strong> London.<br />

Dissanayake, E. (2009a). Bodies swayed to music: The temporal arts as integral to ceremonial<br />

ritual. In Malloch, S. <strong>and</strong> Trevarthen, C. (Eds.) Communicative Musicality: Exploring the<br />

Basis <strong>of</strong> Human Companionship., 533-544.<br />

Dissanayake, E. (2009b). Root, leaf, blossom, or bole: Concerning the origin <strong>and</strong> adaptive function<br />

<strong>of</strong> music. In Malloch, S. <strong>and</strong> Trevarthen, C. (Eds.) Communicative Musicality: Exploring the<br />

Basis <strong>of</strong> Human Companionship., 17-30. Oxford: Oxford University Press.<br />

Donald, M. (2001). A Mind So Rare: The Evolution <strong>of</strong> Human Consciousness. New York, NY<br />

<strong>and</strong> London, Engl<strong>and</strong>: Norton<br />

Donaldson, M. (1978). Children's Minds. Glasgow: Fontana/Collins.<br />

Donaldson, M. (1992). Human Minds: An Exploration. London: Allen Lane/Penguin Books.<br />

Durkheim, É. (1912/1995). The Elementary Forms <strong>of</strong> Religious Life. Free Press, New York<br />

Eckerdal, P. <strong>and</strong> Merker, B. (2009). 'Music' <strong>and</strong> the 'action song' in infant development: An<br />

interpretation. In Malloch, S. <strong>and</strong> Trevarthen, C. (Eds.) Communicative Musicality:<br />

Exploring the Basis <strong>of</strong> Human Companionship, 241-262. Oxford: Oxford University Press.<br />

Erikson, E. H. (1950). Childhood <strong>and</strong> Society. New York: Norton.<br />

Flohr, J. <strong>and</strong> Trevarthen, C. (2008). Music learning in childhood: Early developments <strong>of</strong> a musical<br />

brain <strong>and</strong> body. In W. Gruhn <strong>and</strong> F. Rauscher (eds.) Neurosciences In Music Pedagogy, pp.<br />

53-100. New York: Nova Biomedical Books.<br />

Fonagy, I (2001). Languages within language. An evolutive approach. Foundations <strong>of</strong> Semiotics<br />

13. John Benjamins, Amsterdam/Philadelphia.<br />

Fonagy, P., Steele, M., Steele, N., Moran, G. S. <strong>and</strong> Higgitt, A. C. (1991) The capacity for<br />

underst<strong>and</strong>ing mental states: the reflective self in parent <strong>and</strong> child <strong>and</strong> its significance for<br />

security <strong>of</strong> attachment. Infant Mental Health Journal, 12(3): 201-218.<br />

Foster, R. G. <strong>and</strong> Kreitzman, L. (2004). Rhythms <strong>of</strong> Life: The Biological Clocks That Control the<br />

Daily Lives <strong>of</strong> Every Living Thing. Pr<strong>of</strong>ile Books, London.<br />

Frank, B. <strong>and</strong> Trevarthen, C. (2010). Intuitive eaning: Supporting impulses for interpersonal life in<br />

the sociosphere <strong>of</strong> human knowledge, practice <strong>and</strong> language. In, A. Foolen, U. Lüdtke, J.<br />

36


Zlatev <strong>and</strong> T. Racine, Eds. Moving Ourselves, Moving Others: The Role <strong>of</strong> (E)Motion For<br />

Intersubjectivity, Consciousness <strong>and</strong> Language. (in preparation)<br />

Gallagher, S. (2008). How to undress the affective mind: An interview with Jaak Panksepp.<br />

Journal <strong>of</strong> Consciousness Studies, 15(2)<br />

Gallese, V. (2003). The roots <strong>of</strong> empathy: The shared manifold hypothesis <strong>and</strong> the neural basis <strong>of</strong><br />

intersubjectivity. Psychopathology, 36(4), 171-180.<br />

Gallese, V. (2005). Embodied simulation: From neurons to phenomenal experience.<br />

Phenomenology <strong>and</strong> the Cognitive Sciences, 4: 23–48.<br />

Gallese, V., Keysers, C., <strong>and</strong> Rizzolatti, G. (2004) A unifying view <strong>of</strong> the basis <strong>of</strong> social cognition.<br />

TRENDS in Cognitive Sciences 8: 9, 396–403.<br />

Gans, C., <strong>and</strong> Northcutt, R. G. (1983). Neural crest <strong>and</strong> the origin <strong>of</strong> vertebrates: A new head.<br />

Science, 220, 268-274<br />

Gentilucci, M. <strong>and</strong> Corballis, M. C. (2006). From manual gesture to speech: A gradual transition.<br />

Neuroscience <strong>and</strong> Biobehavioral Reviews 30: 949– 60.<br />

Gibson, J. J. (1966) The Senses Considered as Perceptual Systems. Boston: Houghton Mifflin.<br />

Gibson, J. J. (1979) The Ecological Approach to Visual Perception. Boston: Houghton Mifflin.<br />

Goldin-Meadow, S. & McNeill, D. (1999). The role <strong>of</strong> gesture <strong>and</strong> mimetic representation in<br />

making language. In M. C. Corballis & E. G. Lea (eds.), The Descent <strong>of</strong> Mind:<br />

Psychological Perspectives on Hominid Evolution, (pp. 155–72). Oxford: Oxford University<br />

Press.<br />

Goldman-Rakic, P. (1992) Dopamine mediated mechanisms <strong>of</strong> the prefrontal cortex. Seminars in<br />

the Neurosciences, 4: 149-60.<br />

Gratier, M. & Trevarthen, C. (2008). Musical narrative <strong>and</strong> motives for culture in mother-infant<br />

vocal interaction. The Journal <strong>of</strong> Consciousness Studies, 15(10-11), October/November,<br />

2008, pp. 122-158.<br />

Halliday M. A. K (2006). The Language <strong>of</strong> Science (Volume 5 in the Collected Works <strong>of</strong> M.a.K.<br />

Halliday, J. J. Webster (Editor). London/New York: Continuum International Publishing<br />

Group<br />

Halliday, M. A. K. (1975). Learning How to Mean: Explorations in the Development <strong>of</strong><br />

Language. London: Edward Arnold.<br />

Halliday, M. A. K. (1979). One child's protolanguage. In M. Bullowa (Ed.), Before Speech: The<br />

Beginning <strong>of</strong> Human <strong>Communication</strong>, (pp. 171-190). London: Cambridge University Press.<br />

Hepper, P. G. (1988). Foetal "soap" addiction. Lancet 1988 11th June:1347-1348.<br />

Hepper, P. G. (1995). The behavior <strong>of</strong> the fetus as an indicator <strong>of</strong> neural functioning. In J.-P.<br />

Lecanuet, W. P. Fifer, N. A. Krasnegor <strong>and</strong> W. P. Smotherman (Eds.), Fetal Development: A<br />

Psychobiological Perspective, (pp. 405-417). Hillsdale NJ: Erlbaum.<br />

Hess, W. R. (1954) Diencephalon: Autonomic <strong>and</strong> Extrapyramidal Functions. Orl<strong>and</strong>o, FL: Grune<br />

<strong>and</strong> Stratton.<br />

Hingston, R. W. G. (1933). Animal Colour <strong>and</strong> Adornment. London: E. Arnold & Co.<br />

Hobson, P. (2002) The Cradle <strong>of</strong> Thought: Exploring the Origins <strong>of</strong> Thinking. London:<br />

Macmillan.<br />

Hubley, P. <strong>and</strong> Trevarthen C. (1979) Sharing a task in infancy. In I. Uzgiris (Ed.) Social<br />

Interaction During Infancy: New Directions for Child Development, 4, 57-80. San Francisco:<br />

Jossey-Bass.<br />

37


Husserl, E. (1964). The Phenomenology <strong>of</strong> Internal Time-Consciousness. (J. S. Churchill, Trans.).<br />

Bloomington: Indiana University Press.<br />

Hutcheson, F. (1755). A System <strong>of</strong> Moral Philosophy: In Three Books. Glasgow.<br />

Huttenlocher P.R. (1994) Synaptogenesis in human cerebral cortex. In Human behavior <strong>and</strong> the<br />

developing brain (G. Dawson, K.W. Fischer, eds) The Guilford Press, New York, pp. 137-<br />

152.<br />

Jaffe, J. Beebe, B., Felstein, S., Crown, C. <strong>and</strong> Jasnow, M. D. (2001) Rhythms <strong>of</strong> dialogue in<br />

infancy: Coordinated timing <strong>and</strong> social development. Society <strong>of</strong> Child Development<br />

Monographs, Serial No. 264, Vol. 66(2). Oxford: Blackwell. (Introduction, pp. 1-7).<br />

Jaffe, J., Stern, D. N., <strong>and</strong> Peery, J. C. (1973). Conversational coupling <strong>of</strong> gaze behavior in<br />

prelinguistic human development. Journal <strong>of</strong> Psycholinguistic Research, 2, 321-330<br />

James, D., Pillai, M., Smoleniec, J. (1995) Neurobehavioral development in the human fetus. In<br />

Fetal Development: A Psychobiological Perspective. ( J.-P. Lecanuet, W.P. Fifer, N.A.<br />

Krasnegor, W.P. Smotherman, eds) Erlbaum, Hillsdale NJ, pp. 101-128.<br />

James, W. (1890) The Principles <strong>of</strong> Psychology. New York: Henry Holt <strong>and</strong> Co.<br />

Jeannerod, M. (1994) The representing brain: Neural correlates <strong>of</strong> motor intention <strong>and</strong> imagery.<br />

Behavioral <strong>and</strong> Brain Sciences, 17: 187-245.<br />

Kendon, A. (1980) Gesticulation <strong>and</strong> speech: Two aspects <strong>of</strong> the process <strong>of</strong> utterance. In M. R.<br />

Key (Ed.) The Relationship <strong>of</strong> Verbal <strong>and</strong> Nonverbal <strong>Communication</strong>. New York: Mouton.<br />

Key, M. R. (Ed.) (1980). The Relationship <strong>of</strong> Verbal <strong>and</strong> Nonverbal <strong>Communication</strong>. New York:<br />

Mouton.<br />

Klaus, M. H., <strong>and</strong> Kennel, J. H. (1976). Parent-to-infant attachment. In: D. Hull (Ed.), Recent<br />

Advances in Paediatrics. pp. 129-152. Edinburgh: Churchill Livingstone.<br />

Kornhuber, H.H.; Deecke, L. (1965). Hirnpotentialänderungen bei Willkürbewegungen und<br />

passiven Bewegungen des Menschen: Bereitschaftspotential und reafferente Potentiale.<br />

Pflügers Arch 284: 1–17<br />

Kugiumutzakis, G. (1998). Neonatal imitation in the intersubjective companion space. In S.<br />

Bråten, (Ed.), Intersubjective <strong>Communication</strong> <strong>and</strong> Emotion in Early Ontogeny, (pp. 63-88).<br />

Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.<br />

Kugiumutzakis, G. (1999) Genesis <strong>and</strong> development <strong>of</strong> early infant mimesis to facial <strong>and</strong> vocal<br />

models. In J. Nadel <strong>and</strong> G. Butterworth (eds),. Imitation in infancy. (pp. 127-185)<br />

Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.<br />

Kühl, O. (2007). Musical semantics. (European Semiotics: Language, Cognition <strong>and</strong> Culture. No.<br />

7). Peter Lang, Bern.<br />

Lacerda, F., von H<strong>of</strong>sten, C. <strong>and</strong> Heimann, M. (Eds.) (2001). Emerging Cognitive abilities in early<br />

infancy. Hillsdale, N.J.: Erlbaum.<br />

Lak<strong>of</strong>f, G., <strong>and</strong> Johnson, M. (1999). Philosophy in the Flesh, The Embodied Mind <strong>and</strong> <strong>Its</strong><br />

Challenges to Western Thought. New York, Basic Books.<br />

Lashley, K. S. (1951). The problems <strong>of</strong> serial order in behavior. In: L. A. Jeffress (Ed.),. Cerebral<br />

Mechanisms in Behavior, pp. 112-136. New York: Wiley.<br />

Lecanuet, J.-P. (1996) Prenatal auditory experience. In I. Deliege <strong>and</strong> J. Sloboda (Eds.), Musical<br />

Beginnings : Origins <strong>and</strong> Development <strong>of</strong> Musical Competence, (pp. 3-34). Oxford, New<br />

York, Tokyo: Oxford University Press.<br />

Lecanuet, J.-P., Fifer, W. P., Krasnegor, N. A. <strong>and</strong> Smotherman, W. P. (1995) Fetal<br />

Development: A Psychobiological Perspective. Hillsdale, NJ/ Hove,UK: Erlbaum.<br />

38


LeDoux J.E. (1992) Brain mechanisms <strong>of</strong> emotion <strong>and</strong> emotional learning, Current Opinion in<br />

Neurobiology, 2: 191-197.<br />

Lee, D. N. (2005). Tau in Action in Development. In J. J. Rieser, J. J. Lockman <strong>and</strong> C. A. Nelson<br />

(eds.), Action as an Organizer <strong>of</strong> Learning <strong>and</strong> Development (pp. 3–49). Hillsdale, NJ:<br />

Erlbaum.<br />

Lewis, E. B. (1994). Homeosis: The first 100 years. Trends in Genetics, 10(10), 341-343.<br />

Republished in H. D. Lipshitz (Ed.), Genes, development <strong>and</strong> cancer: The life <strong>and</strong> work <strong>of</strong><br />

Edward B. Lewis (pp. 475-480). Dordrecht: Kluwer.<br />

Lorenz, Konrad Z. (1966) Evolution <strong>of</strong> ritualization in the biological <strong>and</strong> cultural spheres. In<br />

Julian Huxley (ed.) A Discussion <strong>of</strong> Ritualization <strong>of</strong> Behaviour in Animals <strong>and</strong> Man<br />

Philosophical Transactions <strong>of</strong> the Royal Society <strong>of</strong> London, Series B. Biological Sciences,<br />

772/251, 273-284.<br />

MacLean, P.D. (1990). The Triune Brain in Evolution, Role in Paleocerebral Functions. New<br />

York, Plenum Press.<br />

Macmurray, J. (1961) Persons in Relation (Vol. II <strong>of</strong> The Form <strong>of</strong> the Personal) London: Faber <strong>and</strong><br />

Faber.<br />

Malloch, S. <strong>and</strong> Trevarthen, C. (2009). (eds) Communicative Musicality: Exploring the Basis <strong>of</strong><br />

Human Companionship, Oxford: Oxford University Press.<br />

McNeill, D. (1992). H<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> Mind: What Gestures Reveal About Thought. Chicago: University<br />

<strong>of</strong> Chicago Press.<br />

Meltz<strong>of</strong>f, A. N. (1995). Underst<strong>and</strong>ing the intentions <strong>of</strong> others: Re-enactment <strong>of</strong> intended acts by<br />

18-month-old children. Developmental Psychology, 31, 838-850.<br />

Merker, B. (2005). The liabilities <strong>of</strong> mobility: A selection pressure for the transition to<br />

consciousness in animal evolution. Consciousness & Cognition 14(1), 89-114.<br />

Merker, B. (2009a). Returning language to culture by way <strong>of</strong> biology. (Invited commentary on<br />

Evans, N. & Levinson, S.C. (2009). The myth <strong>of</strong> language universals: Language diversity<br />

<strong>and</strong> its importance for cognitive science.) Behavioral <strong>and</strong> Brain Sciences 32, 460-461.<br />

Merker, B. (2009b). Ritual foundations <strong>of</strong> human uniqueness. In Malloch, S. <strong>and</strong> Trevarthen, C.<br />

(Eds.) Communicative Musicality: Exploring the Basis <strong>of</strong> Human Companionship., 45-60.<br />

Oxford: Oxford University Press.<br />

Merleau-Ponty, M. (1962). Phenomenology <strong>of</strong> Perception. London : Routledge & Kegan Paul<br />

Miall DS <strong>and</strong> Dissanayake E (2003). The poetics <strong>of</strong> babytalk. Human Nature, 14(4), 337–64.<br />

Miller, G. A. (2003). The cognitive revolution: a historical perspective. TRENDS in Cognitive<br />

Sciences, 7(3), March, 141-144.<br />

Miller, GA, Galanter, E., & Pribram, KA (1960). Plans <strong>and</strong> the structure <strong>of</strong> behavior. New York:<br />

Holt, Rhinehart, & Winston.<br />

Nagy, E., <strong>and</strong> Molnár, P. (1994) Homo imitans or Homo provocans Abstract, International<br />

Journal <strong>of</strong> Psychophysiology, 18(2), 128.<br />

Nauta, W. J. H. <strong>and</strong> Domesick, V. B. (1982) Neural associations <strong>of</strong> the limbic system. In The<br />

neural basis <strong>of</strong> behavior (A.L. Beckman, ed) SP Medical <strong>and</strong> Scientific Books, New York,<br />

pp. 175-206.<br />

Opie, I. <strong>and</strong> Opie, P. (1960). The Lore <strong>and</strong> Language <strong>of</strong> Schoolchildren. Oxford University Press,<br />

Oxford<br />

39


Osborne, N. (2009a). Towards a chronobiology <strong>of</strong> musical rhythm. In Malloch, S. <strong>and</strong> Trevarthen,<br />

C. (Eds.) Communicative Musicality: Exploring the Basis <strong>of</strong> Human Companionship, 545-<br />

564. Oxford: Oxford University Press<br />

Osborne, N. (2009b). Music for children in zones <strong>of</strong> conflict <strong>and</strong> post-conflict: A psychobiological<br />

approach. In Malloch, S. <strong>and</strong> Trevarthen, C. (Eds.) Communicative Musicality: Exploring<br />

the Basis <strong>of</strong> Human Companionship, 331-356. Oxford: Oxford University Press.<br />

Packard, A. (2006). Contribution to the whole (H). Can squids show us anything that we did not<br />

know already Biology <strong>and</strong> Philosophy (2006) 21:189–211<br />

Panksepp, J. (1998a). Affective Neuroscience.: The Foundations <strong>of</strong> Human <strong>and</strong> Animal<br />

Emotions. New York: Oxford University Press.<br />

Panksepp, J. (1998b). "The periconscious substrates <strong>of</strong> consciousness: Affective states <strong>and</strong> the<br />

evolutionary origins <strong>of</strong> the self". Journal <strong>of</strong> Consciousness Studies, 5, 566-582.<br />

Panksepp, J. (1998). Affective Neuroscience.: The Foundations <strong>of</strong> Human <strong>and</strong> Animal Emotions.<br />

New York: Oxford University Press.<br />

Panksepp, J. (2000). Affective consciousness <strong>and</strong> the instinctual motor system, The neural sources<br />

<strong>of</strong> sadness <strong>and</strong> joy. R. Ellis <strong>and</strong> N. Newton (Eds.)The Caldron <strong>of</strong> Consciousness, Motivation,<br />

Affect <strong>and</strong> Self-organization (Vol 16, pp. 27-54), Advances in Consciousness Research,<br />

Amsterdam, John Benjamins Pub. Co.<br />

Panksepp, J. (2003). At the interface between the affective, behavioral <strong>and</strong> cognitive<br />

neurosciences: Decoding the emotional feelings <strong>of</strong> the brain. Brain <strong>and</strong> Cognition, 52, 4–14.<br />

Panksepp, J. <strong>and</strong> Burgdorf, J. (2003) ‘‘Laughing’’ rats <strong>and</strong> the evolutionary antecedents <strong>of</strong> human<br />

joy Physiology <strong>and</strong> Behavior, 79: 533– 547.<br />

Panksepp, J. <strong>and</strong> Trevarthen, C. (2009). The neuroscience <strong>of</strong> emotion in music. In Malloch, S. <strong>and</strong><br />

Trevarthen, C. (eds), Communicative Musicality: Exploring the Basis <strong>of</strong> Human<br />

Companionship, 105-146. Oxford: Oxford University Press.<br />

Papoušek H (1967) Experimental studies <strong>of</strong> appetitional behaviour in human newborns <strong>and</strong> infants.<br />

In: H. W. Stevenson, E. H. Hess <strong>and</strong> H. L. Rheingold (Eds) Early Behaviour: Comparative<br />

<strong>and</strong> Developmental Approaches. New York, John Wiley, pp 249-277.<br />

Papoušek, H., <strong>and</strong> Papoušek, M. (1977). Mothering <strong>and</strong> cognitive head start: Psychobiological<br />

considerations. In H. R. Schaffer (ed.), Studies in Mother-Infant Interaction: The Loch<br />

Lomond Symposium, pp. 63-85. London, Academic Press.<br />

Parkes, C. M., Stevenson-Hinde J. <strong>and</strong> Marris P. (Eds.) (1982) Attachment Across the Life Cycle.<br />

(pp. 93-114) London: Tavistock.<br />

Parncutt, R. (2006). Prenatal development. In G. E. McPherson (ed.) The Child As Musician, pp. 1-<br />

31. Oxford: Oxford University Press.<br />

Peiper, A. (1963). Cerebral Function in Infancy <strong>and</strong> Childhood. New York: Consultants Bureau.<br />

Piaget, J. (1954) The Construction <strong>of</strong> Reality in the Child (M. Cook, Trans.) New York: Basic<br />

Books.<br />

Piaget, J. (1962) Play, Dreams <strong>and</strong> Imitation in Childhood. London: Routledge <strong>and</strong> Kegan Paul.<br />

Piontelli, A. (2002). Twins : From Fetus to Child. London : Routledge.<br />

Piontelli, A. (2010). Development <strong>of</strong> Normal Fetal Movements: The First 25 Weeks <strong>of</strong> Gestation.<br />

Amsterdam: Springer Verlag<br />

Poizner, H. R., Klima, E. S. <strong>and</strong> Bellugi, U. (1987) What the H<strong>and</strong>s Reveal About the Brain. The<br />

MIT Press, Cambridge .<br />

40


Pöppel, E. (1994) Temporal mechanisms in perception. International Review <strong>of</strong> Neurobiology,<br />

37: 185-202.<br />

Pöppel, E. <strong>and</strong> Wittmann, M. (1999). Time in the Mind. In R. Wilson <strong>and</strong> F. Keil (eds),., The MIT<br />

encyclopedia <strong>of</strong> the cognitive sciences. (pp.836-837). Cambridge, Massachusetts: The MIT<br />

Press.<br />

Porges, S. W. (1997). "Emotion: An evolutionary by-product <strong>of</strong> the neural regulation <strong>of</strong> the<br />

autonomic nervous system", In. C. S. Carter, I. I. Lederhendler <strong>and</strong> B. Kirkpatrick (eds),.,<br />

The integrative neurobiology <strong>of</strong> affiliation. (pp. 62-78) (Annals <strong>of</strong> the New York Academy<br />

<strong>of</strong> Sciences, 807). New York: New York Academy <strong>of</strong> Sciences.<br />

Porges, S. W. (2001). The Polyvagal <strong>Theory</strong>: Phylogenetic substrates <strong>of</strong> a social nervous system.<br />

International Journal <strong>of</strong> Psychophysiology, 42, 123-146.<br />

Porges, S.W. (2003). Social engagement <strong>and</strong> attachment: A phylogenetic perspective. Roots <strong>of</strong><br />

Mental Illness in Children, Annals <strong>of</strong> the New York Academy <strong>of</strong> Sciences, 1008, 31-47.<br />

Prechtl, H. F. R. (1984). Continuity <strong>and</strong> change in early neural development. In H. F. R. Prechtl<br />

(Ed.) Continuity <strong>of</strong> neural functions from prenatal to postnatal life. London : MacKeith<br />

Press, pp1-15.<br />

Radcliffe-Brown, A. R. (1961). Structure <strong>and</strong> Function in Primitive Society. Free Press, Glencoe,<br />

IL<br />

Rakic, P. (1991) Development <strong>of</strong> the primate cerebral cortex. In M. Lewis Ed. Child <strong>and</strong><br />

Adolescent Psychiatry: A Comprehensive Textbook. (pp. 11-28) Baltimore: Williams <strong>and</strong><br />

Wilkins.<br />

Reddy, V. (2008). How Infants Know Minds. Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press.<br />

Richards, M. P. M. (1973). The development <strong>of</strong> psychological communication in the first year <strong>of</strong><br />

life. In J.S. Bruner & F.J. Connolly (eds.) The Growth <strong>of</strong> Competence. Academic Press.<br />

Richards, M.P.M. <strong>and</strong> Dunn (Bernal), J. F. (1971). Social interaction in the first days <strong>of</strong> life. In H.<br />

Schaffer (ed.) The Origins <strong>of</strong> Human Social Relations. London: Academic Press. 1971.<br />

Rodrigues, H. M., Rodrigues, P. M. <strong>and</strong> Correia, J. S. (2009). Communicative musicality as<br />

creative participation: From early childhood to advanced performance. In Malloch, S. <strong>and</strong><br />

Trevarthen, C. (Eds.) Communicative Musicality: Exploring the Basis <strong>of</strong> Human<br />

Companionship., 585-610. Oxford: Oxford University Press.<br />

Rodrıguez, C. & Palacios, P. (2007). Do private gestures have a self-regulatory function A case<br />

study. Infant Behavior <strong>and</strong> Development 30: 180–94.<br />

Rog<strong>of</strong>f, B. (2003). The cultural nature <strong>of</strong> human development. Oxford: OUP.<br />

Rog<strong>of</strong>f, B., Paradise, R., Arauz, R. M., Correa-Chávez, M., <strong>and</strong> Angelillo, C. (2003) Firsth<strong>and</strong><br />

learning through intent participation. Annual Review <strong>of</strong> Psychology, 54: 175-203.<br />

Rolls, E.T. (1992) Neurophysiological mechanisms underlying face processing within <strong>and</strong> beyond<br />

the temporal visual cortical areas. Philosophical Transactions <strong>of</strong> the Royal Society <strong>of</strong><br />

London, ser. B, 335, 11-21.<br />

Sacks, O. (2007). Musicophilia: Tales <strong>of</strong> Music <strong>and</strong> the Brain. R<strong>and</strong>om House, New York/Picador,<br />

London<br />

S<strong>and</strong>er, L. W. (1983). Polarity, paradox, <strong>and</strong> the organizing process <strong>of</strong> development. In Frontiers<br />

<strong>of</strong> Infant Psychiatry, ed. J. D. Call, E. Galenson, <strong>and</strong> R. L. Tyson. New York: Basic Books,<br />

pp. 333–345<br />

Scheff, T. J. (1988). Shame <strong>and</strong> conformity: the deference-emotion system. Sociological Review,<br />

53, 395–406.<br />

41


Schlaug, G., Norton, A., Overy, K. <strong>and</strong> Winner, E. (2005). Effects <strong>of</strong> music training on the child’s<br />

brain <strong>and</strong> cognitive development. Annals <strong>of</strong> the New York Academy <strong>of</strong> Sciences, 1060:<br />

219–230.<br />

Schore, A. N. (1994) Affect Regulation <strong>and</strong> the Origin <strong>of</strong> the Self: The Neurobiology <strong>of</strong> Emotional<br />

Development. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.<br />

Sebeok, T. A., <strong>and</strong> Umiker-Sebeok, J., (eds.) (1992): Biosemiotics. The Semiotic Web 1991.<br />

Berlin <strong>and</strong> New York: Mouton de Gruyter<br />

Sherrington, C. S. (1906). The Integrative Action <strong>of</strong> the Nervous Sysytem. New Haven: Yale<br />

University Press<br />

Smith, A. (1759) The <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>of</strong> Moral Sentiments. Edinburgh: A. Kinkaid & J. Bell. (Modern<br />

Revised Edition: D. D. Raphael <strong>and</strong> A.L. Macfie , <strong>General</strong> Editors, Glasgow Edition.<br />

Oxford: Clarendon, 1976. Reprint, Indianapolis: Liberty Fund, 1984).<br />

Smith, A. ([1777] 1982). Of the Nature <strong>of</strong> that Imitation which takes place in what are called the<br />

Imitative Arts. In W. P. D. Wightman & J. C. Bryce (eds.) with Dugald Stewart’s account <strong>of</strong><br />

Adam Smith (ed. I. S. Ross), D. D. Raphael & A. S. Skinner (<strong>General</strong> eds.), Essays on<br />

Philosophical Subjects (pp. 176–213). Indianapolis: Liberty Fund<br />

Sperry, R. W. (1952). Neurology <strong>and</strong> the mind-brain problem. American Scientist, 40: 291-312.<br />

Sperry, R. W. (1965) Embryogenesis <strong>of</strong> behavioral nerve nets. In: R. L. Dehaan <strong>and</strong> H. Ursprung<br />

(eds.) Organogenesis. New York: Holt, Rinehart <strong>and</strong> Winston, pp. 161-85.<br />

Stern, D. N. (1971). A micro-analysis <strong>of</strong> mother-infant interaction: Behaviors regulating social<br />

contact between a mother <strong>and</strong> her three-<strong>and</strong>-a-half-month-old twins. Journal <strong>of</strong> American<br />

Academy <strong>of</strong> Child Psychiatry, 10, 501-517.<br />

Stern, D. N. (1974a). Mother <strong>and</strong> infant at play : The dyadic interaction involving facial, vocal<br />

<strong>and</strong> gaze behaviours. In M. Lewis <strong>and</strong> L.A. Rosenblum (Eds.), The Effect <strong>of</strong> the Infant on<br />

<strong>Its</strong> Caregiver, (pp. 187-213). New York: Wiley.<br />

Stern, D. N. (1974b) The goal <strong>and</strong> structure <strong>of</strong> mother-infant play. Journal <strong>of</strong> the American<br />

Academy <strong>of</strong> Child Psychiatry, 13: 402-421.<br />

Stern, D. N. (1977). The First Relationship: Infant <strong>and</strong> Mother . Cambridge MA: Harvard<br />

University Press.<br />

Stern, D. N. (1985). The Interpersonal World <strong>of</strong> the Infant: A View from Psychoanalysis <strong>and</strong><br />

Development Psychology. Basic Books, New York.<br />

Stern, D. N. (1992). L'enveloppe prénarrative: Vers une unité fondamentale d'expérience<br />

permettant d'explorer la réalité psychique du bébé. Revue Internationale de<br />

Psychopathologie, 6, 13-63.<br />

Stern, D. N. (1999). <strong>Vitality</strong> contours: The temporal contour <strong>of</strong> feelings as a basic unit for<br />

constructing the infant's social experience. In Rochat, P. (ed.), Early social cognition:<br />

Underst<strong>and</strong>ing others in the first months <strong>of</strong> life. (pp. 67-90). Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.<br />

Stern, D. N. (2000): The Interpersonal World <strong>of</strong> the Infant: A View from Psychoanalysis <strong>and</strong><br />

Development Psychology. (Originally published in 1985. Paperback Second Edition, with<br />

new Introduction) Basic Books, New York.<br />

Stern, D. N. (2004) The Present Moment: In Psychotherapy <strong>and</strong> Everyday Life. New York:<br />

Norton.<br />

Stern, D. N. (2010). Forms <strong>of</strong> <strong>Vitality</strong>: Exploring Dynamic Experience in Psychology, the Arts,<br />

Psychotherapy <strong>and</strong> Development. Oxford: Oxford University Press.<br />

42


Stern, D. N. <strong>and</strong> Gibbon, J. (1980). Temporal expectancies <strong>of</strong> social behaviours in mother-infant<br />

play. In: E. Thoman (ed),. Origins <strong>of</strong> infant social responsiveness. (pp 409-429). New<br />

York, Erlbaum.<br />

Stern, D. N., Beebe, B., Jaffe, J., <strong>and</strong> Bennett, S. L. (1977). The infant's stimulus world during<br />

social interaction: a study <strong>of</strong> caregiver behaviors with particular reference to repetition <strong>and</strong><br />

timing. In H. R. Schaffer (Ed.), Studies in Mother-Infant Interaction, (pp. 177-202). New<br />

York: Academic Press.<br />

Stravinsky, I. (1947). Poetics <strong>of</strong> Music In the From <strong>of</strong> Six Lessons. Cambridge MA: Harvard<br />

University Press.<br />

Thatcher, R. W., Walker, R. A. <strong>and</strong> Giudice, S. (1987) Human cerebral hemispheres develop at<br />

different rates <strong>and</strong> ages. Science, 236: 1110-1113.<br />

Thompson, E. (Ed.) (2001). Between Ourselves: Second-Person Issues in the Study <strong>of</strong><br />

Consciousness. Charlottesville, VA/Thorverton, UK: Imprint Academic. (Journal <strong>of</strong><br />

Consciousness Studies, 8, Number 5-7).<br />

Tinbergen, Niko (1951) The Study <strong>of</strong> Instinct Oxford: Clarendon Press.<br />

Tomasello, M. Carpenter, M., Call, J., Behne, T. <strong>and</strong> Moll, H. (2005). Underst<strong>and</strong>ing <strong>and</strong> sharing<br />

intentions: The origins <strong>of</strong> cultural cognition Behavioral <strong>and</strong> Brain Sciences, 28, 675-691<br />

Trehub, S. E. (1973). Infants' sensitivity to vowel <strong>and</strong> tonal contrasts. Developmental Psychology,<br />

9, 91-96.<br />

Trevarthen, C. (1962). Double visual learning in split-brain monkeys. Science, 136: 258-259.<br />

Trevarthen, C. (1965). Functional interactions between the cerebral hemispheres <strong>of</strong> the split-brain<br />

monkey. In, E.G. Ettlinger (Ed.) Functions <strong>of</strong> the Corpus Callosum.<br />

Ciba Foundation Study Group, No. 20. London: Churchill, 24-40.<br />

Trevarthen, C. (1968a). Vision in fish: the origins <strong>of</strong> the visual frame for action in vertebrates. In,<br />

D. Ingle (Ed.) The Central Nervous System <strong>and</strong> Fish Behaviour. Chicago: Chicago<br />

University Press, 61-94.<br />

Trevarthen, C. (1968b). Two mechanisms <strong>of</strong> vision in primates. Psychologische Forschung, 31:<br />

299-337.<br />

Trevarthen, C. (1974a). The psychobiology <strong>of</strong> speech development. In E.H. Lenneberg (ed),<br />

Language <strong>and</strong> Brain: Developmental Aspects. Neurosciences Research Program Bulletin, 12:<br />

570-585.<br />

Trevarthen, C. (1974b). Conversations with a two-month-old. New Scientist, 2 May: 230-235.<br />

Trevarthen, C. (1977). Descriptive analyses <strong>of</strong> infant communication behavior. In: H. R. Schaffer<br />

(Ed.) Studies in Mother-Infant Interaction: The Loch Lomond Symposium. London,<br />

Academic Press, pp 227-270<br />

Trevarthen, C. (1978). Manipulative strategies <strong>of</strong> baboons <strong>and</strong> the origins <strong>of</strong> cerebral asymmetry.<br />

In, M. Kinsbourne (Ed.) Asymmetrical Function <strong>of</strong> the Brain, pp. 329-391. New York <strong>and</strong><br />

London: Cambridge University Press.<br />

Trevarthen, C. (1979). <strong>Communication</strong> <strong>and</strong> cooperation in early infancy. A description <strong>of</strong> primary<br />

intersubjectivity. In M. Bullowa (Ed.) Before Speech: The Beginning <strong>of</strong> Human<br />

<strong>Communication</strong>. London, Cambridge University Press, , 321-347.<br />

Trevarthen, C. (1980). The foundations <strong>of</strong> intersubjectivity: development <strong>of</strong> interpersonal <strong>and</strong><br />

cooperative underst<strong>and</strong>ing <strong>of</strong> infants. In: D. Olson (ed), The Social Foundations <strong>of</strong> Language<br />

<strong>and</strong> Thought: Essays in Honor <strong>of</strong> J.S. Bruner. New York: W. W. Norton, 316-342.<br />

43


Trevarthen, C. (1984). Hemispheric specialization. In, Geiger, S.R. et al (Eds.) H<strong>and</strong>book <strong>of</strong><br />

Physiology; (Section 1, The Nervous System); Volume 2, Sensory Processes (Section<br />

Editor, Darian-Smith, I.) Washington: American Physiological Society, 1129-1190.<br />

Trevarthen, C. (1986). Development <strong>of</strong> intersubjective motor control in infants. In M.G. Wade <strong>and</strong><br />

H.T.A. Whiting (Eds.) Motor Development in Children: Aspects <strong>of</strong> Coordination <strong>and</strong><br />

Control. Dordrecht, Martinus Nijh<strong>of</strong>, 209-261.<br />

Trevarthen, C. (1988). Universal cooperative motives: How infants begin to know language <strong>and</strong><br />

skills <strong>of</strong> culture. In G. Jahoda <strong>and</strong> I.M. Lewis (Eds.), Acquiring Culture: Ethnographic<br />

Perspectives on Cognitive Development, (pp. 37-90). London: Croom Helm<br />

Trevarthen, C. (1989a). Motives for culture in young children - their natural development through<br />

communication. In, Walter Koch (Ed.) The Nature <strong>of</strong> Culture. (Proceedings <strong>of</strong> the<br />

International <strong>and</strong> Interdisciplinary Symposium, Ruhr Universitat, Bochum, October 7-11,<br />

1986) Bochum: Brockmeyer, 80-119.<br />

Trevarthen, C. (1989b). Development <strong>of</strong> early social interactions <strong>and</strong> the affective regulation <strong>of</strong><br />

brain growth. In C. von Euler, H. Forssberg <strong>and</strong> H. Lagercrantz (Eds.) Neurobiology <strong>of</strong><br />

Early Infant Behaviour. (Wenner-Gren Center International Symposium Series, Vol 55). (pp.<br />

191-216) Basingstoke, Hants: Macmillan/New York : Stockton Press.<br />

Trevarthen, C. (1990a). Signs before speech. In: T. A. Sebeok <strong>and</strong> J. Umiker-Sebeok (Eds.), The<br />

Semiotic Web, 1989. Berlin, New York, Amsterdam: Mouton de Gruyter, 689-755.<br />

Trevarthen, C. (1990b). Growth <strong>and</strong> education <strong>of</strong> the hemispheres. In C. Trevarthen (Ed.), Brain<br />

Circuits <strong>and</strong> Functions <strong>of</strong> the Mind: Essays in Honour <strong>of</strong> Roger W. Sperry. (pp. 334-363)<br />

New York: Cambridge University Press.<br />

Trevarthen, C. (1992b). An infant's motives for speaking <strong>and</strong> thinking in the culture. In: A. H.<br />

Wold (ed),. The Dialogical Alternative: Towards a <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>of</strong> Language <strong>and</strong> Mind<br />

(Festschrift for Ragnar Rommetveit). (pp. 99-137). Oslo/Oxford: Sc<strong>and</strong>anavian University<br />

Press/Oxford University Press.<br />

Trevarthen, C. (1993b). The function <strong>of</strong> emotions in early infant communication <strong>and</strong> development.<br />

In J. Nadel <strong>and</strong> L. Camaioni (Eds.) New Perspectives in Early Communicative Development.<br />

(pp. 48-81) London: Routledge.<br />

Trevarthen, C. (1993a). The self born in intersubjectivity: An infant communicating. In U. Neisser<br />

(Ed.), The Perceived Self: Ecological <strong>and</strong> Interpersonal Sources <strong>of</strong> Self-Knowledge, (pp. 121-<br />

173). New York: Cambridge University Press.<br />

Trevarthen, C. (1993c). Brain science <strong>and</strong> the human spirit. In: James B. Ashcr<strong>of</strong>t (ed.) Brain,<br />

Culture <strong>and</strong> the Human Spirit: Essays From an Emergent Evolutionary Perspective. Lanham,<br />

Md.: University Press <strong>of</strong> America, 129-181. [Revised version <strong>of</strong> paper: Brain science <strong>and</strong> the<br />

human spirit. Zygon, Journal <strong>of</strong> Religion <strong>and</strong> Science, 21(2) June 1986: 161-200.]<br />

Trevarthen, C. (1994). Infant semiosis. In W. Noth (Ed.), Origins <strong>of</strong> Semiosis,, (pp. 219-252).<br />

Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.<br />

Trevarthen, C. (1995). Mother <strong>and</strong> baby - seeing artfully eye to eye. In: R. Gregory, J. Harris, D.<br />

Rose <strong>and</strong> P. Heard (eds.) The Artful Eye. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 157-200.<br />

Trevarthen, C. (1996). Lateral asymmetries in infancy: Implications for the development <strong>of</strong> the<br />

hemispheres. Neuroscience <strong>and</strong> Biobehavioral Reviews, 20 (4): 571-586.<br />

Trevarthen, C. (1997). Foetal <strong>and</strong> neonatal psychology: Intrinsic motives <strong>and</strong> learning behaviour.<br />

In F. Cockburn (Ed.), Advances in Perinatal Medicine, (pp. 282-291). (Proceedings <strong>of</strong> the<br />

XVth European Congress <strong>of</strong> Perinatal Medicine, Glasgow, 10-13 September, 1996). New<br />

York/Carnforth, Lancs., UK: Parthenon.<br />

44


Trevarthen, C. (1998a). The concept <strong>and</strong> foundations <strong>of</strong> infant intersubjectivity. In S. Bråten (Ed.),<br />

Intersubjective <strong>Communication</strong> <strong>and</strong> Emotion in Early Ontogeny, (pp. 15-46). Cambridge:<br />

Cambridge University Press.<br />

Trevarthen, C. (1998b) The nature <strong>of</strong> motives for human consciousness. Psychology: The Journal <strong>of</strong><br />

the Hellenic Psychological Society (Special Issue: "The Place <strong>of</strong> Psychology in Contemporary<br />

Sciences", Part 2. Guest Editor, T. Velli), 4(3), 187-221.<br />

Trevarthen, C. (1999). Musicality <strong>and</strong> the Intrinsic Motive Pulse: Evidence from human<br />

psychobiology <strong>and</strong> infant communication. In "Rhythms, musical narrative, <strong>and</strong> the origins <strong>of</strong><br />

human communication". Musicae Scientiae, Special Issue, 1999-2000, pp. 157-213. Liège:<br />

European Society for the Cognitive Sciences <strong>of</strong> Music.<br />

Trevarthen, C. (2001) Intrinsic motives for companionship in underst<strong>and</strong>ing: Their origin,<br />

development <strong>and</strong> significance for infant mental health. Infant Mental Health Journal, 22 (1-<br />

2) 95-131<br />

Trevarthen, C. (2003). Neuroscience <strong>and</strong> intrinsic psychodynamics: Current knowledge <strong>and</strong><br />

potential for therapy. J. Corrigall <strong>and</strong> H. Wilkinson (Eds.) Revolutionary Connections:<br />

Psychotherapy <strong>and</strong> Neuroscience. (pp. 53-78). London/New York: Karnak<br />

Trevarthen, C. (2004a). How infants learn how to mean. In, M. Tokoro <strong>and</strong> L. Steels (eds.) A<br />

Learning Zone <strong>of</strong> One's Own. (SONY Future <strong>of</strong> Learning Series). Amsterdam: IOS Press.<br />

pp. 37-69.<br />

Trevarthen, C. (2004b). Language development: Mechanisms in the brain. In: G. Adelman<br />

<strong>and</strong> B. H. Smith (eds) Encyclopedia <strong>of</strong> Neuroscience, 3rd Edition, with CD-ROM.<br />

Article Number 397. Amsterdam: Elsevier Science.<br />

Trevarthen, C. (2004c). Brain development. In, R.L. Gregory (Ed.) Oxford Companion to the<br />

Mind, 2 nd Edition. Oxford & New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 116-127.<br />

Trevarthen, C. (2004d). Infancy, mind in. In, R.L. Gregory (Ed.) Oxford Companion to the<br />

Mind, 2 nd Edition. Oxford & New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 455-464.Trevarthen,<br />

C. (2005a). Action <strong>and</strong> emotion in development <strong>of</strong> the human self, its sociability <strong>and</strong> cultural<br />

intelligence: Why infants have feelings like ours. In J. Nadel, & D. Muir (Eds.), Emotional<br />

Development. (pp. 61-91). Oxford: Oxford University Press.<br />

Trevarthen, C. (2005a). Action <strong>and</strong> emotion in development <strong>of</strong> the human self, its sociability <strong>and</strong><br />

cultural intelligence: Why infants have feelings like ours. In J. Nadel, & D. Muir (Eds.),<br />

Emotional Development. (pp. 61-91). Oxford: Oxford University Press.<br />

Trevarthen, C. (2005b). Stepping away from the mirror: Pride <strong>and</strong> shame in adventures <strong>of</strong><br />

companionship Reflections on the nature <strong>and</strong> emotional needs <strong>of</strong> infant intersubjectivity. In<br />

C.S. Carter, L. Ahnert, et al. (Eds.), Attachment <strong>and</strong> Bonding: A New Synthesis. Dahlem<br />

Workshop Report 92. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.<br />

Trevarthen, C. (2006). First things first: infants make good use <strong>of</strong> the sympathetic rhythm <strong>of</strong><br />

imitation, without reason or language. Journal <strong>of</strong> Child Psychotherapy, 31(1), 91–113.<br />

Trevarthen, C. (2007). Moving experiences: Perceiving as action with a sense <strong>of</strong> purpose. In G.-J.<br />

Pepping <strong>and</strong> M. Grealy (Eds.) Closing the Gap: The Scientific Writings <strong>of</strong> David N. Lee, pp<br />

1-20. Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.<br />

Trevarthen, C. (2008). The musical art <strong>of</strong> infant conversation: Narrating in the time <strong>of</strong> sympathetic<br />

experience, without rational interpretation, before words. Musicae Scientiae, Special Issue,<br />

2008, pp. 11-37.<br />

Trevarthen, C. (2009a). The intersubjective psychobiology <strong>of</strong> human meaning: Learning <strong>of</strong> culture<br />

depends on interest for co-operative practical work <strong>and</strong> affection for the joyful art <strong>of</strong> good<br />

company. Psychoanalytic Dialogues, 19(5), 507-518.<br />

45


Trevarthen, C. (2009b). The functions <strong>of</strong> emotion in infancy: The regulation <strong>and</strong> communication <strong>of</strong><br />

rhythm, sympathy, <strong>and</strong> meaning in human development. In Diana Fosha, Daniel J. Siegel,<br />

<strong>and</strong> Marion F. Solomon, eds. The Healing Power <strong>of</strong> Emotion: Affective Neuroscience,<br />

Development, <strong>and</strong> Clinical Practice, pp. 55-85. New York: Norton.<br />

Trevarthen, C. (2009c). Human biochronology: on the source <strong>and</strong> functions <strong>of</strong> ‘musicality’. In R.<br />

Haas <strong>and</strong> V. Br<strong>and</strong>es, (eds.), Music That Works: Contributions <strong>of</strong> biology, neurophysiology,<br />

psychology, sociology, medicine <strong>and</strong> musicology, Chapter 18, pp. 221-265. Vienna/New<br />

York: Springer. (Proceedings <strong>of</strong> the Mozart & Science Conference "Wie Musik wirkt" (The<br />

Impact <strong>of</strong> Music), Organised by the International Music <strong>and</strong> Art Research Association<br />

Austria, 1 – 4 October 2006, Baden near Vienna, Austria.)<br />

Trevarthen, C. (2010). What is it like to be a person who knows nothing Defining the active<br />

intersubjective mind <strong>of</strong> a newborn human being. For "The Intersubjective Newborn", Infant<br />

<strong>and</strong> Child Development, Special Issue, Edited by Emese Nagy, in press 2009<br />

Trevarthen, C. <strong>and</strong> Aitken, K. J. (1994). Brain development, infant communication, <strong>and</strong> empathy<br />

disorders: intrinsic factors in child mental health. Development <strong>and</strong> Psychopathology, 6:599-<br />

635<br />

Trevarthen, C. <strong>and</strong> Aitken, K. J. (2003). Regulation <strong>of</strong> brain development <strong>and</strong> age-related changes<br />

in infants’ motives: the developmental function <strong>of</strong> “regressive” periods. In: Regression<br />

Periods in Human Infancy, Heimann M,, ed. Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum, pp. 107-184<br />

Trevarthen, C. <strong>and</strong> Hubley, P. (1978) Secondary intersubjectivity: confidence, confiding <strong>and</strong> acts<br />

<strong>of</strong> meaning in the first year. In: Action, Gesture <strong>and</strong> Symbol: The Emergence <strong>of</strong> Language,<br />

Lock A, ed. London, New York, San Francisco: Academic Press, pp. 183-229.<br />

Trevarthen, C., Aitken, K. J., V<strong>and</strong>ekerckhove , M., Delafield-Butt, J. & Nagy, E. (2006).<br />

Collaborative regulations <strong>of</strong> vitality in early childhood: Stress in intimate relationships <strong>and</strong><br />

postnatal psychopathology. In, D. Cicchetti & D. J. Cohen (Eds.) Developmental<br />

Psychopathology, Volume 2, Developmental Neuroscience, Second Edition. New York:<br />

Wileys, pp 65-126<br />

Trevarthen, C., Delafield-Butt, J. <strong>and</strong> Schögler, B. (2010). Psychobiology <strong>of</strong> musical gesture:<br />

Innate rhythm, harmony <strong>and</strong> melody in movements <strong>of</strong> narration. In Gritten, A <strong>and</strong> King, E.,<br />

(eds.), Music <strong>and</strong> Gesture 2. Aldershot, UK: Ashgate.<br />

Tronick, E. (2007). The Neurobehavioral <strong>and</strong> Social Emotional Development <strong>of</strong> Infants <strong>and</strong><br />

Children. New York: Norton.<br />

Tronick, E. Z., Als H., <strong>and</strong> Brazelton T. B. (1980). Monadic phases: A structural description<br />

analysis <strong>of</strong> infant-mother face-to-face interaction. Merrill-Palmer Quarterly, 26, 3-24.<br />

Tulving, E. (2002). Episodic Memory: From Mind to Brain. Annual Review <strong>of</strong> Psychology, 253,<br />

1-25.<br />

Turner, F. (1991) Beauty: The Value <strong>of</strong> Values. Charlottesville: University Press <strong>of</strong> Virginia.<br />

Turner, F. <strong>and</strong> Pöppel, E. (1999). The neural lyre: poetic meter, the brain <strong>and</strong> time. In R. S.<br />

Gwynn, ed. New Expansive Poetry, pp. 86-119. Story Line Press, Ashl<strong>and</strong> Oreg.<br />

Turner, M. (1996). The Literary Mind: The Origins <strong>of</strong> Thought <strong>and</strong> Language. New<br />

York/Oxford: Oxford University Press.<br />

Turner, R. & Whitehead, C. (2008). How collective representations can change the structure <strong>of</strong> the<br />

brain. Journal <strong>of</strong> Consciousness Studies; 15 (10/11): 43-57<br />

Turner, R. <strong>and</strong> Ioannides, A. (2009). Brain, music <strong>and</strong> musicality: Inferences from neuroimaging.<br />

In Malloch, S. <strong>and</strong> Trevarthen, C. (Eds.) Communicative Musicality: Exploring the Basis <strong>of</strong><br />

Human Companionship, 147-181. Oxford: Oxford University Press.<br />

46


Turner, V. W. (1969). The Ritual Process. Aldine, Hawthorne, New York.<br />

Turner, V. W. (1982). From Ritual to Theatre: The Human Seriousness <strong>of</strong> Play. New York: PAJ<br />

Publications.<br />

Turner, V. W. <strong>and</strong> Bruner, E. M. (1986). The Anthropology <strong>of</strong> Experience. University <strong>of</strong> Illinois<br />

Press<br />

Varela, F. J., Thompson, E. <strong>and</strong> Rosch, E. (1991). The Embodied Mind. Cambridge, MA/London,<br />

UK: The MIT Press.<br />

von Holst, E. (1954). Relations between the central nervous system <strong>and</strong> the peripheral organs.<br />

British Journal <strong>of</strong> Animal Behaviour, 2, 89–94.<br />

von Holst, E. <strong>and</strong> von Saint-Paul, U. (1961) On the Functional Organization <strong>of</strong> Drives. Animal<br />

Behavior 11:1-20<br />

von Uexküll, J. (1957). A Stroll Through the Worlds <strong>of</strong> Animals <strong>and</strong> Men: A Picture Book <strong>of</strong><br />

Invisible Worlds. In Claire H. Schiller, ed. <strong>and</strong> trans. Instinctive Behavior: The Development<br />

<strong>of</strong> a Modern Concept. New York: International Universities Press, Inc., pp. 5–80.<br />

Wallin, N. L., Merker, B. <strong>and</strong> Brown, S. (eds.) (2000). The Origins <strong>of</strong> Music. Cambridge, MA:<br />

MIT Press.<br />

Whitehead, A. N. (1929). The Aims <strong>of</strong> Education <strong>and</strong> Other Essays. New York: Macmillan<br />

Whitehead, A. N. (1926). Science <strong>and</strong> the Modern World, Cambridge: Cambridge University<br />

Press.<br />

Whitehead, C. (2008) The neural correlates <strong>of</strong> work <strong>and</strong> play: What brain imaging research <strong>and</strong><br />

animal cartoons can tell us about social displays, self-consciousness, <strong>and</strong> the evolution <strong>of</strong> the<br />

human brain. Journal <strong>of</strong> Consciousness Studies, 15 (10/11): 93-121.<br />

Winnicott, D. W. (1958) Playing <strong>and</strong> Reality. London: Tavistock.<br />

Zlatev, J., Racine, T. P.. Sinha C. <strong>and</strong> Itkonen, E. (eds.). (2008). The Shared Mind: Perspectives<br />

on Intersubjectivity. Amsterdam: Benjamins.<br />

47

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!