30.03.2015 Views

Aristotle, Metaphysics Book Zeta (VII) Commentary ... - CATpages

Aristotle, Metaphysics Book Zeta (VII) Commentary ... - CATpages

Aristotle, Metaphysics Book Zeta (VII) Commentary ... - CATpages

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

<strong>Aristotle</strong>, <strong>Metaphysics</strong>, <strong>Zeta</strong><br />

problem stated in them is useful for our inquiries<br />

concerning substance. I mean this<br />

problem:--wherein can consist the unity of that,<br />

the formula of which we call a definition, as for<br />

instance, in the case of man, 'two-footed animal';<br />

for let this be the formula of man. Why, then, is<br />

this one, and not many, viz. 'animal' and<br />

'two-footed'? For in the case of 'man' and 'pale'<br />

there is a plurality when one term does not<br />

belong to the other, but a unity when it does<br />

belong and the subject, man, has a certain<br />

attribute; for then a unity is produced and we<br />

have 'the pale man'. In the present case, on the<br />

other hand, one does not share in the other; the<br />

genus is not thought to share in its differentiae<br />

(for then the same thing would share in<br />

contraries; for the differentiae by which the<br />

genus is divided are contrary). And even if the<br />

genus does share in them, the same argument<br />

applies, since the differentiae present in man are<br />

many, e.g. endowed with feet, two-footed,<br />

featherless. Why are these one and not many?<br />

Not because they are present in one thing; for on<br />

this principle a unity can be made out of all the<br />

attributes of a thing. But surely all the attributes<br />

in the definition must be one; for the definition is<br />

a single formula and a formula of substance, so<br />

that it must be a formula of some one thing; for<br />

substance means a 'one' and a 'this', as we<br />

maintain.<br />

We must first inquire about definitions<br />

reached by the method of divisions. There is<br />

nothing in the definition except the first-named<br />

and the differentiae. The other genera are the first<br />

genus and along with this the differentiae that are<br />

taken with it, e.g. the first may be 'animal', the<br />

next 'animal which is two-footed', and again<br />

'animal which is two-footed and featherless', and<br />

similarly if the definition includes more terms.<br />

And in general it makes no difference whether it<br />

includes many or few terms,-nor, therefore,<br />

whether it includes few or simply two; and of the<br />

two the one is differentia and the other genus;<br />

e.g. in 'two-footed animal' 'animal' is genus, and<br />

the other is differentia.<br />

The issue in this chapter concerns the status of natural<br />

kinds. <strong>Aristotle</strong> is convinced that there are natural kinds.<br />

A human being is a different kind of thing than a horse, and<br />

a horse a different kind of thing than a beetle, etc. Thus it<br />

is not an arbitrary matter that we say that Richard Field and<br />

Bill Clinton are the same kind of thing in a way that they<br />

are different from, say, Secretariat (a horse). But there is<br />

this puzzle co ncerning natural kinds: a natural kind is<br />

something that can be defined, as humanity or horse can be<br />

defined. A definition refers to a set of characteristics<br />

found in all things of a certain kind, as, say, the definition<br />

of human might be "two-footed animal" or a set of two<br />

characteristics: "animality" and "two-footedness" (note that<br />

<strong>Aristotle</strong> does not say this is the true definition of<br />

human--he offers this hypothetically). But a definition<br />

cannot be simply any set of characteristics, since if it were,<br />

any set of things wo uld constitute a natural kind, since all<br />

things share some characteristics. Thus we could say<br />

"brown-haired footed living thing" is a definition of a<br />

natural kind, and say that a brown-haired dog and a<br />

brown-haired human being are the same kind of thing, and<br />

both are different than a blond-haired human being. This<br />

would und ermine the view that there are natural kinds in<br />

the first place. What we must say, then, is that a definition<br />

is a set of characteristics having some special type of unity<br />

not found in all sets of characteristics--but then we have the<br />

question: What sort of unity is this?<br />

<strong>Aristotle</strong> finds the answer in the method of defining<br />

natural kinds--the method of division. We start with a<br />

broad class of things, a genus, such as living things. We<br />

then ask: What sorts of characteristics divide these things<br />

into different types--these characteristics are the<br />

differentiae--such as "capable of motion" divides animals<br />

from plants. T hen within the more restricted genera (pl.<br />

genus), we again divide the types into subtypes by<br />

differentiae. What we find in this process is that the lower<br />

genera and the species (the lowest natural class) are<br />

defined in terms of differentiae that are specifications of<br />

the differentiae of higher genera. Thus, considering<br />

<strong>Aristotle</strong>'s actual definition of humanity offered elsewhere<br />

(De Anima), an animal is something that perceives and acts<br />

(moves) and desires, and a human being, a "rational<br />

animal," is something that can understand what it perceives<br />

and can think about what it desires and how to achieve it.<br />

Thus the difference of the human being, "rational,"<br />

presupposes the differentiae of the the genus animal, which<br />

establishes the so rt of unity that <strong>Aristotle</strong> is looking for to<br />

explain natural kinds.<br />

19

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!