10.07.2015 Views

Muguerza, Javier - The Tanner Lectures on Human Values

Muguerza, Javier - The Tanner Lectures on Human Values

Muguerza, Javier - The Tanner Lectures on Human Values

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

<str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g> Alternative of DissentJAVIER MUGUERZATranslated by Philip SilverTHE TANNER LECTURES ON HUMAN VALUESDelivered at<str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g> Instituto de Derechos <strong>Human</strong>osof<str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g> Universidad Complutense de MadridApril 19 and 20, 1988


[MUGUERZA] <str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g> Alternative of Dissent 77admirably focuses <strong>on</strong> the heart of the matter and which is prefacedby the author with some twenty-odd pages dedicated to guaranteeingits plausibility. 3 Thus, although it amounts to a stipulati<strong>on</strong>,his proposal is by no means a “Humpty-Dumpty definiti<strong>on</strong>,” sinceit rests both <strong>on</strong> a lexicographical study of the linguistic limits ofthe defined term and <strong>on</strong> something even more important, that is,a c<strong>on</strong>ceptual circumscripti<strong>on</strong> of its c<strong>on</strong>text.In additi<strong>on</strong>, Pérez Luño is well aware of the merits of hisdefiniti<strong>on</strong>, which he believes avoids some of the more qualifiedcharges against the very attempt to define human rights. 4In thefirst place his definiti<strong>on</strong> is not “tautological,” as a definiti<strong>on</strong> wouldbe that read: “the rights of man are those that bel<strong>on</strong>g to him byvirtue of his being a man,” since his definiti<strong>on</strong> not <strong>on</strong>ly specifiesa series of human “requirements” but also menti<strong>on</strong>s the historicalcharacter of this “specificity.” Sec<strong>on</strong>d, neither is it a “formalist”definiti<strong>on</strong>, for example, “the rights of man are those that bel<strong>on</strong>gor ought to bel<strong>on</strong>g to all men, and of which no man may bedeprived,” since Pérez Luño’s definiti<strong>on</strong>, in referring to the activerecogniti<strong>on</strong> of such rights in the legal statutes, leaves enoughmargin for both the normative aspects of the “process of positivesupport in laws,” or legal recogniti<strong>on</strong>, and the techniques of protecti<strong>on</strong>and guarantees as to their actual implementati<strong>on</strong>. Thirdand last, the definiti<strong>on</strong> means to avoid being “teleological,” aswould be the case with definiti<strong>on</strong>s that allude to preserving ultimatevalues, <strong>on</strong>es ordinarily susceptible to diverse and c<strong>on</strong>testedinterpretati<strong>on</strong>s, of the kind: “the rights of man are those necessaryfor the perfecting of human beings, for social progress or thedevelopment of civilizati<strong>on</strong>, and so <strong>on</strong>.” However, in my view itis by no means clear that Pérez Luño’s definiti<strong>on</strong> manages to avoidthis third charge, if that is what it is, with as much ease or as3 Ibid., chap. 1.4 On p. 25 the author draws <strong>on</strong> Norberto Bobbio‘s “L‘illusi<strong>on</strong> du f<strong>on</strong>dementabsolu,” in the joint volume, Les f<strong>on</strong>dement des droits de l’homme (Florence, 1966),3-9; see also 49ff.


78 <str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>Tanner</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>Lectures</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>on</strong> <strong>Human</strong> <strong>Values</strong>much success as the previous <strong>on</strong>es. 5That is, I do not think that“dignity,” “liberty,” and “equality” are values any less susceptibleto diverse interpretati<strong>on</strong>s, or any less c<strong>on</strong>tested, than “the perfectingof the human being,” “social progress,” or “the developmentof civilizati<strong>on</strong>,” although, as we will see, I believe that from anethical point of view they are rather more fundamental than thelatter.But my major disagreement with Pérez Luño’s definiti<strong>on</strong> hasto do with the general meaning he attributes to it. In his opini<strong>on</strong>,“the proposed definiti<strong>on</strong> is intended to unite the two main dimensi<strong>on</strong>sof the general noti<strong>on</strong> of human rights, that is, the jusnaturalistrequirement as to their grounding and the techniques of itspositive support in law and protecti<strong>on</strong> that assure their enjoyment.”6Of course, Pérez Luño has every right, natural or not, toextract jusnaturalist implicati<strong>on</strong>s from his definiti<strong>on</strong>, but not allof us who accept his definiti<strong>on</strong> can be expected to accept theburden of those implicati<strong>on</strong>s.From his definiti<strong>on</strong> it follows - or, more exactly, it is understood- that the demands of human dignity, liberty, and equalityalluded to are prior to the process of positive support in law andthat the reas<strong>on</strong> why they ought to be legally recognized providesthe grounding for the rights in questi<strong>on</strong>. But is that all? Jusnaturalism,as we will see, is nowhere in view, or at least not unless<strong>on</strong>e acknowledges beforehand - as a jusnaturalist would undoubtedlybe inclined to do -that the fact that those demandsare prior to the process of legal recogniti<strong>on</strong> makes them naturalrights.To me such a presuppositi<strong>on</strong> seems gratuitous. But beforetaking up this point, I want to deal with another, less important,<strong>on</strong>e. That is, the presuppositi<strong>on</strong> that values such as dignity,5In any case the supposed charge was not so much leveled at the “teleological”character of the definiti<strong>on</strong> - that is, at its goal of saving ultimate values - as at thevagueness and imprecisi<strong>on</strong> of the values in questi<strong>on</strong>.6 Pérez Luño, Derechos humanos, 51.


[MUGUERZA] <str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g> Alternative of Dissent 79liberty, or equality are the exclusive patrim<strong>on</strong>y of the jusnaturalisttraditi<strong>on</strong>.To c<strong>on</strong>centrate for the moment <strong>on</strong> the first of these, who wouldassert that the jusnaturalist traditi<strong>on</strong> and the traditi<strong>on</strong> of humanrights are coextensive? Pérez Luño adduces the case of SamuelPufendorf, whose system of human rights indeed rests <strong>on</strong> the ideaof the dignitus of man. 7 And there is no doubt about Pufendorf’srepresenting an important stage in the history of modern naturallaw. But, <strong>on</strong> the other hand, it is not as clear that we can discernthe same jusnaturalist filiati<strong>on</strong> in the Kantian noti<strong>on</strong> of Würde,nor in Kant’s philosophy of law. 8 And the case of Kant is of particularinterest to us here.No <strong>on</strong>e would deny that there are abundant traces of jusnaturalistinfluence in Kant, just as it is impossible to deny that thegeneral divisi<strong>on</strong> of the Rechtslehre, or “system of the principlesof law,” that he espouses opposes natural law (Naturrecht),which is based <strong>on</strong> a priori principles, to positive, or statutory, law(statutarisches Recht), which depends <strong>on</strong> the will of the legislator.9But Kant’s so-called “rati<strong>on</strong>al law” (Vernunftrecht) cannotsimply be identified with traditi<strong>on</strong>al natural law, even of arati<strong>on</strong>alist lineage, not even if we find that it does not mind assuming- <strong>on</strong> the basis of quite different suppositi<strong>on</strong>s - some of thelatter’s functi<strong>on</strong>s, which it c<strong>on</strong>sequently inherits. l0And, especially,I do not believe we can or should interpret in a jusnatu-7 Ibid. In this c<strong>on</strong>necti<strong>on</strong> see Hans Welzel’s classic Die Naturrechtslehre SamuelPufendorfs, 2d ed. (Berlin, 1958).8 On this subject, see J, G. Murphy, Kant: <str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g> Philosophy of Right (L<strong>on</strong>d<strong>on</strong>,1970); S. Goyard-Fabre, Kant et le problème du droit (Paris, 1975); Z. Batscha, ed,.Materialien zu Kants Rechtsphilosophie (Frankfurt am Main, 1976) ; F. Kaulbach,Studien zur späten Rechtsphilosophie Kants (Wiirzburg, 1982) ; H.-G. Deggau,Die Aporien der Rechtslehre Kants (Stuttgart, 1983).9 I. Kant, Metaphysik der Sitten. I. Metaphysische Anfangsgründe der Rechtslehre,Werke, Akademie Ausgabe, vol. 6, p. 237. All references to Kant’s worksare to this editi<strong>on</strong>.10 See below, in c<strong>on</strong>necti<strong>on</strong> with Jürgen Habermas’s interpretati<strong>on</strong> of Kant’s“rati<strong>on</strong>al law.”


80 <str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>Tanner</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>Lectures</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>on</strong> <strong>Human</strong> <strong>Values</strong>ralistic sense Kant’s fundamental distincti<strong>on</strong> between “morality”(Moralität and also Sittlichkeit) , <strong>on</strong> the <strong>on</strong>e hand, and “legality”(Gesetzmlissigkeit or Legalitat) , <strong>on</strong> the other, a distincti<strong>on</strong> towhich we will presently return. 11In my view, Pérez Luño has too generous a noti<strong>on</strong> of jusnaturalism,which leads him to swell unnecessarily the number of itsadepts, even though he does indeed menti<strong>on</strong> that the “open”definiti<strong>on</strong> of it that he holds helps him avoid the danger of makinga “Procrustean bed” of his c<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong>: 12 it is not such a bed —if this is understood in the sense intended by that legendary bandit,who, in order to fit his victims exactly to the bed, wouldshorten the protrusi<strong>on</strong>s of the taller <strong>on</strong>es or violently stretch thelimbs of the shorter <strong>on</strong>es until he dislocated them; but, “generouslyunderstood,” this Procrustean bed could c<strong>on</strong>tain a devicethat, as the occasi<strong>on</strong> demanded, allowed the bed itself, and not thevictims, to be made larger or smaller, so that whoever laid himselfdown there would run the risk of waking up a “jusnaturalist.”But I do not want my friendly discussi<strong>on</strong> with Pérez Luño toseem an obsessive tirade. My aim is simply that my defense ofethics - the declared object of this lecture - not be in any wayc<strong>on</strong>fused with the defense of a supposed natural law, a c<strong>on</strong>fusi<strong>on</strong>I fear he is guilty of himself, since he writes that “<strong>on</strong>ly from thejusnaturalist point of view does it make sense to pose the problemof the grounding of human rights.” 13 This c<strong>on</strong>fusi<strong>on</strong> in fact isnot infrequent in the panorama of c<strong>on</strong>temporary philosophy, asthe case of Ernst Bloch makes clear in an exemplary way, whichforces me to c<strong>on</strong>cede that Pérez Luño is ultimately in very goodcompany.From the title of Bloch’s Naturrecht und menschliche Wurdeto its last page, we are always impressed, even deeply so, by the11Kant, Metaphysik. der Sitten, 219.12 Pérez Luño, Derechos humanos, 136-37.13 Ibid.


[MUGUERZA] <str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g> Alternative of Dissent 81undoubted ethical pathos of his thought,14 even though Blochnever speaks there of “ethics,” but always of “natural law,” perhaps,it seems to me, because, in the Marxist traditi<strong>on</strong>, it is easierto fly in the teeth of Marx’s “prejudices” about human rights 15than to overcome the embarrassment, disguised as akribeia, thatkept him and his followers from acknowledging that at timeswhat he was doing was simply ethics.For my part I would say, in synthesis, that the “demands” ofdignity, liberty, and equality included in Pérez Luño’s definiti<strong>on</strong>of human rights - demands that, according to his definiti<strong>on</strong>,“ought to be” legally recognized - are “moral demands,” and Iwould add that they should be awarded full status as human rightswhen they have passed the extra test of their legal recogniti<strong>on</strong>. Inmy case, I am not sure such a coarse and crude duality would bewillingly accepted under the banner of the highly regarded “dualtheory” of those rights. 16 Like all dualisms that are too abrupt,perhaps mine too gives the impressi<strong>on</strong> of suffering from an obviousschizophrenia, the same <strong>on</strong>e - c<strong>on</strong>sisting of separatingmorality and legality - that Hegel <strong>on</strong>ce accused Kant of, followingwhich he reduced ethics, now changed to “ethicity,” to hisphilosophy of law (which, in any case, proves that Kant’s schizophreniais preferable to Hegel’s paranoia, which was capable ofswallowing up and “going bey<strong>on</strong>d” in his philosophical systemwhat Hegel was in the habit of referring to disdainfully as “mere14E. Bloch, Naturrecht und menschliche Wiirde, Gesamtausgabe, vol. 6 (Frank-furt am Main, 1961).1983).15 See in this regard Manuel Atienza, Marx y los derechos humanos (Madrid,16 <str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g> “dualistic c<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong>” of human rights, which - as opposed to jusnaturalistsand juspositivists - attempts to “integrate” their c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong> as “values”(prior to their recogniti<strong>on</strong> in any legal text) with their c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong> as valid “legalnorms” (<strong>on</strong>ce legally recognized), has been maintained by Gregorio Peces-Barba inhis Derechos fundamentales (Madrid, 1983), 24-27, 28ff.; in c<strong>on</strong>necti<strong>on</strong> with oursubject see also, by the same author, Introducción a la filosofía del derecho (Madrid,1983), esp. 305-30; Los valores superiores (Madrid, 1984); and Escritos sobrederechos fundamentales (Madrid, 1988), esp. 215-26.


82 <str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>Tanner</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>Lectures</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>on</strong> <strong>Human</strong> <strong>Values</strong>morality.”) 17Be that as it may, the moral demands in questi<strong>on</strong>would be “potential” human rights, whereas the human rightswould in their turn be moral demands, “satisfied” from a legalpoint of view. And I would not give too much importance topurely verbal questi<strong>on</strong>s, since I am well aware that “humanrights,” especially with this name, are such a powerful weap<strong>on</strong>today that it would be foolish to reduce their effectiveness bygiving them the less usual name of “moral demands.” 18If wemust, therefore, be c<strong>on</strong>fr<strong>on</strong>ted by the Janus face of human rights<strong>on</strong>eof whose sides has an ethical profile and the other a legalprofile - I would be c<strong>on</strong>tent simply to request that, in the firstcase, we c<strong>on</strong>sider them “rights” in a merely metaphorical sense,just as, for that matter, jusnaturalism has always d<strong>on</strong>e in speakingof “natural rights.”What I would not so readily agree to is the ambiguous andc<strong>on</strong>fusing name of “moral rights” that they are so often given17 See <strong>on</strong> this point Amelia Valcbrcel, Hegel y la ética (Sobre la superaciön dela “mera moral”), prologue by J. <str<strong>on</strong>g>Muguerza</str<strong>on</strong>g> (Barcel<strong>on</strong>a, 1988).18 Another reas<strong>on</strong> not to do this is the insistence with which the detractors ofhuman rights - and not just their ideology - reject even the name, by invokingagainst them the well-known statement of such an illustrious reacti<strong>on</strong>ary as Joseph deMaistre: “<str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g>re is no man in the world. In my lifetime I have seen Frenchmen, Italians,and Russians. I also know, thanks to M<strong>on</strong>tesquieu, that <strong>on</strong>e can be Persian: but asto man, I swear I have never met <strong>on</strong>e in my life” (this text, which comes from hisC<strong>on</strong>sidérati<strong>on</strong>s sur la France of 1791, is quoted by A. de Benoist and G. Faye in thedossier <strong>on</strong> Les droits de l’homme that appeared in Eléments 37 [1981]: 5-35. This“nati<strong>on</strong>al-communitarian” point of view would allow for “the rights of [certain]men” (French, Italian, Russian, etc.) but not “the rights of man,” which, nevertheless,need not be-in c<strong>on</strong>trast to what de Maistre believed-an abstract “universalman,” but rather Tom, Dick, or Harry, that is, a c<strong>on</strong>crete “individual,” whosec<strong>on</strong>creteness always outweighs his membership in a specific community, whethernati<strong>on</strong>al or not. For a criticism of what he correctly calls the “fallacy of the c<strong>on</strong>creteman” of de Maistre and his outdated c<strong>on</strong>temporary followers, see LeszekKolakowski, “Warum brauchen wir Kant?” Merkur 9-10 (1981) : 915-24. In histurn, and from a positi<strong>on</strong> not at all sympathetic to human rights understood as “subjectiverights,” Michel Villey has argued interestingly for the “nominalist” andindividualistic origin of this latter noti<strong>on</strong> in “La genèse du droit subjectif chezGuillaume de Occam,” Archives de Philosophie du Droit 9 (1964): 97ff., andLa formati<strong>on</strong> de la pensie juridique moderne (Paris, 1968), chaps. 4 and 5, a thesisI would have no trouble subscribing to if <strong>on</strong>ly I were allowed to see virtue whereverthe author sees vice.


[MUGUERZA] <str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g> Alternative of Dissent 83today, which is something I want to deal with apart from the questi<strong>on</strong>of jusnaturalism. I prefer to do it this way because not allwho use the name are in debt to, nor would accept the designati<strong>on</strong>of, jusnaturalists. 19And it seems to me at least questi<strong>on</strong>able thata c<strong>on</strong>temporary champi<strong>on</strong> of “moral rights” like R<strong>on</strong>ald Dworkin,so often catalogued this way, should or could be included inthe list.I will not say, as Jeremy Bentham did of natural rights, that“moral rights” are a n<strong>on</strong>sense up<strong>on</strong> stilts, 20 but I will say thatthey are at least a c<strong>on</strong>tradicti<strong>on</strong>. 21 Perhaps neither syntactic norsemantic, as when <strong>on</strong>e speaks of “a square circle” or of “woodenir<strong>on</strong>,” but rather pragmatic, like the <strong>on</strong>e that would pertain if wewere to speak, let us suppose, of “laws of traffic” without therebeing any actual highway code. Before such existed, it wouldmake no sense to say that the small sedan traveling the road “hasthe right” to cross ahead of a big truck approaching from the left.Yet the truth is that according to certain current interpretati<strong>on</strong>s,moral rights are c<strong>on</strong>ceived of precisely as “prior to” any possiblerecogniti<strong>on</strong> of them in legal statutes. Is such an interpretati<strong>on</strong>defensible? Whether it is or not, <strong>on</strong>e must acknowledge that ithas in its favor our use of such expressi<strong>on</strong>s as “I have a rightto . . .” in ordinary language, expressi<strong>on</strong>s that we most often usewithout intending an appeal to any article of the legal statutes.And, despite old Bertrand Russell’s warning about the ordinarinessof being bound by analyses of ordinary language, perhaps it would19 I am not certain, to quote a few examples of philosopher-compatriots, ifProfessor Eusebio Fernandez would at all approve of such a cataloguing (see hisTeoría de la justicia y derechos humanos [Madrid, 1984], esp. 104ff.), but I knowthat Professor Francisco Laporta (see his “Sobre el c<strong>on</strong>cepto de derechos humanos,”in Actas de Ias X Jornadas de Filosofia Juridica y Social, Alicante, December 1987,[in press]) would be vexed with me if I listed him as a jusnaturalist.italics.]20 [<str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g> words “n<strong>on</strong>sense up<strong>on</strong> stilts” were in English in the original; J.M.’s21 J. Bentham, Anarchical Fallacies, Being an Examinati<strong>on</strong> of the Declarati<strong>on</strong>of Rights Issued during the French Revoluti<strong>on</strong>, in Works, ed. John Bowring (Edinburgh,1838; repr. New York, 1962), 2:500.


84 <str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>Tanner</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>Lectures</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>on</strong> <strong>Human</strong> <strong>Values</strong>not be beside the point to notice what we usually mean when wesay, “I have a right to an explanati<strong>on</strong> (a satisfacti<strong>on</strong>, a redress,or anything else).” In many instances, “I have a right to something”is simply another way of saying that “I require (demand,ask for, etc.) that something,” where the noti<strong>on</strong> of right plays nopart. But of course <strong>on</strong> occasi<strong>on</strong> the first expressi<strong>on</strong>, “I have a rightto something,” would require a paraphrase like “I deserve thatsomething” or “I am owed such and such a thing,” where theparaphrase might cause difficulties if we took ad pedem litteraethe so-called thesis of the “correlativity of rights and duties” heldby Wesley Hohfeld am<strong>on</strong>g others. 22To put it in too sketchy terms, the thesis of correlativity canbe summed up in the asserti<strong>on</strong> that the idea of a “right-holder”(sujeto de derecho) and that of a “duty-bearer” (sujeto de [elcorresp<strong>on</strong>diente] deber) are coimplicating ideas. Now then, thissort of correlati<strong>on</strong> seems to functi<strong>on</strong> more clearly in the case ofinstituti<strong>on</strong>al rights and duties - for example, with legal rightsand duties -than in the case of n<strong>on</strong>instituti<strong>on</strong>al <strong>on</strong>es, as wouldpresumably be the case with moral rights and duties. If it is mylegal right that Peter fulfill what is stipulated in a c<strong>on</strong>tract wehave signed, Peter has a legal duty or obligati<strong>on</strong> to fulfill it. Andvice versa. But the relevancy of the “vice-versa” clause herebecomes less clear when we move from the legal plane to themoral <strong>on</strong>e. I am not sure that the preceding descripti<strong>on</strong> wouldalso serve to describe the reciprocal pacts Robins<strong>on</strong> Crusoe andFriday agreed to, so that Friday would be authorized to infer thathe “has a right to such and such” from the declarati<strong>on</strong> that “Robins<strong>on</strong>owes him such and such.” At least I am not certain that thisinference would be of much use to him in the absence of a judge<strong>on</strong> the island to oversee compliance with such pacts. But, in anycase, it does seem clear that the phrase “X owes Y such and such”22 For a review and an up-to-date discussi<strong>on</strong> of Hohfeld’s thesis, see Carl Wellman,A <str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g>ory of Rights: Pers<strong>on</strong>s under Laws, Instituti<strong>on</strong>s, and Morals (Totowa,N.J., 1985).


[MUGUERZA] <str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g> Alternative of Dissent 85does not always imply that “Y has the (moral) right to receivesuch and such from X.” For example, I am absolutely c<strong>on</strong>vincedthat we humans have “moral duties” regarding animals and wouldwelcome their having “legal rights” that were recognized in asociety that c<strong>on</strong>siders itself civilized. But I would not allow thatfrom the fact that we humans have moral duties regarding animalsit follows that the latter have moral rights. An animal may wellbe a right-holder in the legal sense when humans bestow this c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong><strong>on</strong> it, but no animal will ever be a moral subject. Moralityis the prerogative of men and, of course, women - that is, ofhuman beings - and I do not believe the partisans of moral rightswould be willing to c<strong>on</strong>sider animals holders of such rights, asthey would have to be, however, if those partisans wished topursue the questi<strong>on</strong>able thesis of the correlativity of duties andrights to its final c<strong>on</strong>sequences. But <strong>on</strong>e never knows: in a heateddiscussi<strong>on</strong> I <strong>on</strong>ce heard an American friend, who was a member ofthe Animal Liberati<strong>on</strong> Fr<strong>on</strong>t, speak of “animals’ human rights”(derechos humanos de los animales).But, in c<strong>on</strong>cluding our excursus into ordinary language, Iwould <strong>on</strong>ly like to menti<strong>on</strong> an expressi<strong>on</strong> that <strong>on</strong> the c<strong>on</strong>traryseems to me extremely revealing of certain aspects of the moralphenomenology involved here, an expressi<strong>on</strong> that is furthermorean integral, and colloquial, turn of phrase. I refer, of course, tothe expressi<strong>on</strong> “You’ve no right,” which we so often use independentlyof any legal c<strong>on</strong>text: the expressi<strong>on</strong> “You’ve no right(for example, to treat some<strong>on</strong>e in a manner we judge reprehensible)”is usually accompanied by a feeling of moral indignati<strong>on</strong>which in our example might be a translati<strong>on</strong> of the c<strong>on</strong>victi<strong>on</strong>that “it is denigrating to treat any<strong>on</strong>e that way” or that“such treatment violates his dignity.” But I already warned amoment ago that we would do well to separate the treatment ofhuman dignity from that of the supposed natural rights, and I feelthe same about supposed moral rights, which counsels that wepostp<strong>on</strong>e that subject until the proper time comes.


86 <str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>Tanner</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>Lectures</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>on</strong> <strong>Human</strong> <strong>Values</strong>Nevertheless, all we have said thus far regarding moral rightsfails to do complete justice-I hasten to say- to the aforementi<strong>on</strong>edpositi<strong>on</strong> of Dworkin. For Dworkin speaks not <strong>on</strong>ly ofmoral rights but of moral principles, which is something quitedistinct and of a much higher ethical caliber. In his work <strong>on</strong>enotices a determined effort to bring law (and not <strong>on</strong>ly its philosophy,the philosophy of law) closer to ethics, an effort I can<strong>on</strong>ly fervently applaud. 23 And <strong>on</strong> each occasi<strong>on</strong> <strong>on</strong>e notices acriticism of positivism with which, minor differences aside, I c<strong>on</strong>fessI also fundamentally agree. In c<strong>on</strong>necti<strong>on</strong> with his critiqueit has been observed, and not without reas<strong>on</strong>, that the formertargets a c<strong>on</strong>cept of legal positivism that is too narrow, as in thecase of the so-called “positivism of the law” so magnificentlysummed up in K. Bergbohm’s frightening sentence: “<str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g> mostinfamous law must be deemed applicable provided it was promulgatedin a formally correct manner.” But it is nevertheless truethat Dworkin goes somewhat bey<strong>on</strong>d that restricted c<strong>on</strong>cept ofpositivism, as his polemic with Professor Herbert Hart over therole of key norm of the so-called “rule of recogniti<strong>on</strong>” shows. 24If I refer here to this often-menti<strong>on</strong>ed questi<strong>on</strong> it is because I amc<strong>on</strong>vinced that its import is much greater than is usually thought.In his criticism of what he calls the “model of norms,” Dworkincriticizes the positivists for their inability to distinguish between“a law” (ana ley) and “the law” (el derecho), but the point ofhis reproach is to show the insufficiency of a c<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong> of the lawas a system of laws or norms the identity of whose parts would bedue to the functi<strong>on</strong>ing of the aforesaid “key norm.” Taken as sucha key norm, Hart’s rule of recogniti<strong>on</strong> would have the task oflaying down which laws or norms would make up the law, just asArticle 1 of our Civil Code determines what laws and norms23R. Dworkin, Taking Rights Seriously (Cambridge, Mass., 1977) ; A Matterof Principle (Cambridge, Mass., 1985) ; Law’s Empire (Cambridge, Mass., 1986).24 See H. L. A. Hart, <str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g> C<strong>on</strong>cept of Law (Oxford, 1961), 89ff., and R. Dworkin,Taking Rights Seriously, chaps. 2 and 3.


[MUGUERZA] <str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g> Alternative of Dissent 87bel<strong>on</strong>g to that current legal or normative system. 25 Now then, thissort of criteri<strong>on</strong> of identificati<strong>on</strong> might well seem inane whenfaced with what Dworkin calls “difficult cases,” where we comeup against the problem of finding a norm that is applicable. Insuch cases of legal indeterminacy, it is Hart’s opini<strong>on</strong> that the casewould have to be left to the discreti<strong>on</strong> of the judge, whereas forDworkin this would amount to c<strong>on</strong>ceding him the undesirablepower of “creating law,” with the added difficulty that the judgewould be empowered to legislate retroactively. In his opini<strong>on</strong>what the judge would have to do in such cases, and what he infact does in such cases, is to go bey<strong>on</strong>d the norms - that is, thenormative model - and turn to principles (or, alternatively, to“political directives”) , principles - this would be Dworkin’schoice - that c<strong>on</strong>tain the requisites of justice, equity, or othermoral requirements. In the example Dworkin himself so oftenuses, 26a judge rejects the perfectly legal bequest of an inheritancebecause of the fact that the testator was murdered by the inheritorand by appealing to the principle - legally unstated, but validin the judge’s view - that “no <strong>on</strong>e may (strictly speaking, oughtto) benefit from their own crime.” Pers<strong>on</strong>ally I w<strong>on</strong>der, however,if Dworkin’s recourse to principles does not allow the judges atleast as much “discreti<strong>on</strong>ality” as Hart does in the absence of anyexact norm. Not to menti<strong>on</strong> the possibility that those judges takeas principles the political directives relative to objects held to besocially beneficial (utilitarianism seems to me just as detestable amoral philosophy as it does to Dworkin, but <strong>on</strong>e cannot discardthe possibility that some utilitarian judge might discover a veinof moral principles in it) or that judges might simply disguisethe strangest and most varied ideological prejudices as principles.For example, <strong>on</strong>e could adduce in this regard an old bit of courtreporting in a Madrid newspaper that - the differences between25 Dworkin, Taking Rights Seriously, chap. 3, § 6.26 I refer to the well-known case of Riggs versus Palmer, which Dworkinexamines in Taking Rights Seriously, chap. 2, § 3,


88 <str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>Tanner</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>Lectures</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>on</strong> <strong>Human</strong> <strong>Values</strong>our judicial system and the Anglo-Sax<strong>on</strong> <strong>on</strong>e aside - will illustratewhat I’m saying. If I remember correctly, a dead husbandleft a will-our examples run to wills-making his wife soleheir <strong>on</strong> the c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong> that she never remarry (in truth the kindestthing <strong>on</strong>e can say about certain testators is that they are betterdead); but <strong>on</strong>e day the wife, who for a number of years hadscrupulously adhered to this c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong> of the will, was discoveredto be pregnant (which, naturally, provoked a suit <strong>on</strong> the part ofthe dead man’s nearest relatives); the tribunal charged with decidingthe case declared the will null and void, since it found that, ifthe last will of the testator had been to guarantee his wife’s fidelityafter his death, he would have disapproved a fortiori a situati<strong>on</strong>like the present <strong>on</strong>e that added licentious c<strong>on</strong>duct to infidelity(since I cannot imagine that such an extraordinary decisi<strong>on</strong> couldbe literally based <strong>on</strong> any legal text, no matter how peculiar itsc<strong>on</strong>tent, I am inclined to attribute the tribunal’s acti<strong>on</strong> to therepository of their “moral principles”). 27 But of course this unfortunateanecdote doesn’t reduce the importance of Dworkin’sinvocati<strong>on</strong> of moral principles. For, as has been correctly pointedout, 28that invocati<strong>on</strong> is not so much directed at Hart’s normativemodel and its rule of recogniti<strong>on</strong> as it is at the latter’s c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>as key norm. And, in this sense, against any other key norms ofthe same family, whether Hans Kelsen’s fundamental norm orJohn Austin’s sovereign’s command, that is, against the supposedpositivist self-sufficiency of the law, which can hardly c<strong>on</strong>tain itsown grounding.For our purposes the preceding c<strong>on</strong>clusi<strong>on</strong> is important. Fora good positivist would never lose sleep over the questi<strong>on</strong> of an27 Although I cannot document this reference now, I seem to remember readingthis article in the Madrid daily ABC back in the fifties, when I was just enteringa now-distant adolescence, during the heyday of the Franco regime, which undoubtedlyexplains many details of the case.28 See Albert Calsamiglia, “Ensayo sobre Dworkin” (prologue to the Spanishtranslati<strong>on</strong> of Taking Rights Seriously [Los derechos en serio] Barcel<strong>on</strong>a, 1984,7-29), and “¿Por qués importante Dworkin?” Doxa 2 (1985): 159-66.


[MUGUERZA] <str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g> Alternative of Dissent 89extralegal grounding of the law, even in the case of human rights.Once incorporated into the legal statutes - for example, in theform of fundamental rights or anything similar - why inquirefurther into their “grounding” or foundati<strong>on</strong>? But, as I said,human rights offered us a Janus face and were moral demandsbefore being recognized as such rights. As moral demands theyc<strong>on</strong>stituted presumed rights - something quite different from supposedrights, where the adjective would serve to disqualify ratherthan just to qualify - or, if <strong>on</strong>e prefers, they might be c<strong>on</strong>sideredassumed rights, that is, demands assumed “as if” they were rights.But how justify our assumpti<strong>on</strong> or presumpti<strong>on</strong> of these rightswithout inquiring into their grounding ? Whatever the positivistmay say, questi<strong>on</strong>s about this grounding are far from idle and wemust c<strong>on</strong>tinue to ask them.But, despite my insistence <strong>on</strong> ethics, I intend that our treatmentof grounding or foundati<strong>on</strong> be as realistic as possible. And,when I speak of realism, I also mean this in the sense of legalrealism, which, as we know, need not be a dirty realism - unlikethe latest United States novels. At least, Judge Oliver WendellHolmes’s scandalous definiti<strong>on</strong>, according to which law is nothingbut the set of “the predicti<strong>on</strong>s about what the judges will do infact,” a definiti<strong>on</strong> that amounted to the birth notice of Americanlegal realism, has never seemed scandalous to me, nor has thecircumscripti<strong>on</strong> of legal validity to the judges’ c<strong>on</strong>duct, which AlfRoss and the Scandinavian realists c<strong>on</strong>tributed to the theorizingabout “law in force,” ever seemed scandalous to me either. 29 Toput it in the briefest terms, it is a questi<strong>on</strong> of recognizing, in c<strong>on</strong>trastto any doctrinaire view of jurisprudence, that judges maysometimes decide - although they will not always, or necessarily,do so-not by virtue of reas<strong>on</strong>s that allow them to adduce anappropriate legal rule for their decisi<strong>on</strong>, but just the reverse, thatis, by first deciding and then choosing - as with a “rati<strong>on</strong>aliza-29 See Dworkin, Taking Rights Seriously, chap. 1, and Liborio Hierro, Elrealismo jurídico escandinavo (Valencia, 1981).


90 <str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>Tanner</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>Lectures</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>on</strong> <strong>Human</strong> <strong>Values</strong>ti<strong>on</strong>” - the aforementi<strong>on</strong>ed rule. In the classical model of predicti<strong>on</strong>attributed to Hempel and Popper, the predicti<strong>on</strong> of aphenomen<strong>on</strong> is merely an explanati<strong>on</strong> of it before it happens.This calls for <strong>on</strong>e or more general laws, as well as the specificati<strong>on</strong>of a series of relevant c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s, and, based <strong>on</strong> these premises,the predicti<strong>on</strong> of the phenomen<strong>on</strong>, or its explanati<strong>on</strong> inadvance, would then be derived as the c<strong>on</strong>clusi<strong>on</strong> of a deductiveor inductive-probabilistic argument. For example, the law that“all metals enlarge when heated,” together with a specificati<strong>on</strong>of the c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s of temperature being applied to a metal objectand of the coefficient of enlargement of the metal in questi<strong>on</strong>,will enable us ultimately to predict that said object will becomeenlarged at a given moment (or explain why it became enlargedthe instant following its having d<strong>on</strong>e so, since the explanati<strong>on</strong> ofa phenomen<strong>on</strong>, in its turn, is nothing other than its predicti<strong>on</strong>post eventum, or its retrodicti<strong>on</strong>). And the same thing thathappens with this phenomen<strong>on</strong> could occur, mutatis mutandis,with another phenomen<strong>on</strong> like a judge’s decisi<strong>on</strong>, despite the factthat in this case we have an individual and, therefore, an intenti<strong>on</strong>alacti<strong>on</strong>, which would tend to put in questi<strong>on</strong> the Hempel-Popper model as well as the symmetry of “explanati<strong>on</strong>-predicti<strong>on</strong>”that their model supports.30 Be that as it may, the <strong>on</strong>ly thing thatlegal realism urges us to do, and it is quite a worthy recommendati<strong>on</strong>,is not to look exclusively for the premises of our explanati<strong>on</strong>sand/or predicti<strong>on</strong>s in legal texts but in the real social life ofthe judiciary, which is the reality most likely to provide us withthe repertory of more or less general laws and more or less relevantc<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s that we will need in order not to lose sight of thelatter. (I would not even like to imagine, for example, the “relevantc<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s” that would have to be specified in order to explainand/or predict the c<strong>on</strong>duct of judges like the magistrates in the30 See <strong>on</strong> this subject my paper “La versatilidad de la explicación científica,”in A ciencia incierta (in preparati<strong>on</strong>).


92 <str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>Tanner</str<strong>on</strong>g> Lectutres <strong>on</strong> <strong>Human</strong> <strong>Values</strong>cal <strong>on</strong>e. 33This led Bobbio solemnly to pr<strong>on</strong>ounce that “we d<strong>on</strong>ot c<strong>on</strong>sider the problem of grounding to be n<strong>on</strong>existent butrather, in a certain sense, as solved, so that there is no further needto c<strong>on</strong>cern ourselves with its soluti<strong>on</strong>.” To which he added:“Indeed, now we can say that the problem of founding humanrights was solved by the Universal Declarati<strong>on</strong> of <strong>Human</strong> Rightsthat the General Assembly of the United Nati<strong>on</strong>s approved <strong>on</strong>December 10, 1948.” 34Which is to say that this Declarati<strong>on</strong>would be the best possible proof that a system of values is deemedto have a grounding and thus be recognized as, in short, “the proofof the general c<strong>on</strong>sensus as to its validity.” In Bobbio’s view thereare three primary ways of founding such values. One way c<strong>on</strong>sistsin deducing them from some invariable objective datum such as,for example, human nature (which is what jusnaturalism has alwaysd<strong>on</strong>e and what in <strong>on</strong>e way or another will have to c<strong>on</strong>tinueto do in order to avoid debasing itself to the point where it admitsto any interpretati<strong>on</strong> we wish to make of it; but the truth is thathuman nature can be imagined in many different ways and anappeal to it can serve to justify extremely divergent and even c<strong>on</strong>tradictoryvalue systems, so that the “right to dignity, liberty andequality” would be just as natural as the “right of the str<strong>on</strong>gest”).A sec<strong>on</strong>d way c<strong>on</strong>siders the values in questi<strong>on</strong> to be self-evidenttruths (but an appeal to evidence is no more promising than theappeal to human nature, since what at <strong>on</strong>e moment in time isc<strong>on</strong>sidered evident may not be at another moment: in the eighteenthcentury property was c<strong>on</strong>sidered “sacred and inviolable,”a view which is certainly not held today, whereas the “evidence”today that “torture is intolerable” was no impediment to its beingc<strong>on</strong>sidered a normal legal procedure in the past, nor does it keep33 N. Bobbio, “Presente e avvenire dei diritti dell’uomo,” La ComunitàInternati<strong>on</strong>ale23 (1968): 3-18. I have quoted from the Spanish translati<strong>on</strong> of thistext, delivered the previous year at the Royaum<strong>on</strong>t Colloquia, by A. Ruiz Miguel,“Presente y porvenir de los derechos humanos,” Anuario de Derechos <strong>Human</strong>os 1(1982) : 7-28.34Bobbio, “Presente e avvenire,” 10.


[MUGUERZA] <str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g> Alternative of Dissent 93it from being practiced today extralegally). A third way is the<strong>on</strong>e held by Bobbio when he tries to justify values by dem<strong>on</strong>stratingthat the latter are supported by c<strong>on</strong>sensus and that thereforea value will have a str<strong>on</strong>ger grounding the more widely it is shared(in the argument from c<strong>on</strong>sensus, 35 the proof of the “objectivity”of values-held to be impossible or, at least, extremely uncertain- has been replaced by that of “intersubjectivity,” a proofthat <strong>on</strong>ly provides a “historical” and “n<strong>on</strong>absolute” grounding,which nevertheless is the <strong>on</strong>ly <strong>on</strong>e capable of being “factually”proven). So the declarati<strong>on</strong> of 1948 - together with all the legislati<strong>on</strong>it engendered, whether at the internati<strong>on</strong>al or at the variousnati<strong>on</strong>al levels - c<strong>on</strong>stitutes the str<strong>on</strong>gest historical proof ever ofa c<strong>on</strong>sensus omnium gentium, that is, of a real universal c<strong>on</strong>sensusas to a given value system: that is, the system of human rights.But perhaps things are not as clear as Bobbio thinks, and intruth his proclamati<strong>on</strong> can be objected to <strong>on</strong> several fr<strong>on</strong>ts. Atleast, and within the same factual point of view in which he siteshis argument, <strong>on</strong>e could object that the “universal c<strong>on</strong>sensus” <strong>on</strong>human rights is not as universal as it seems, besides the fact that -as Bobbio himself would admit - the process of recogniti<strong>on</strong>, andeven of creati<strong>on</strong>, of these rights is “a process that is under way”and nothing and no <strong>on</strong>e guarantees the perpetuati<strong>on</strong> of the corresp<strong>on</strong>dingc<strong>on</strong>sensus, especially when some of these rights -such as the so-called “ec<strong>on</strong>omic and social rights”- become ab<strong>on</strong>e of c<strong>on</strong>tenti<strong>on</strong> between c<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong>s of human rights as differentas the liberals’ and socialists’ c<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong>s. It has also beenargued from a juridical point of view whether or not the declarati<strong>on</strong>of 1948 is a “juridically c<strong>on</strong>sistent document,” a c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>which Kelsen would deny - however positively he might evaluateit from other perspectives - but which many lawyers c<strong>on</strong>cede,albeit to varying degrees and <strong>on</strong> the basis of quite different suppositi<strong>on</strong>s.But, naturally, the objecti<strong>on</strong>s that interest us the most35 Ibid., 11ff.


94 <str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>Tanner</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>Lectures</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>on</strong> <strong>Human</strong> <strong>Values</strong>are those made from a philosophical point of view. And so wewill examine <strong>on</strong>e such possible objecti<strong>on</strong>, which, in view of ourinterest, is of decisive importance.During the decade of the sixties, when Bobbio wrote the textwe have been discussing, his thought passed from a preferably“coactivist” c<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong> of the law - the view of the legal statuteas an apparatus whose functi<strong>on</strong>ing is ultimately guaranteed by thepossible use of force - to a preferably “c<strong>on</strong>sensualist” view ofthe same. 36And c<strong>on</strong>sensulism, in the history of ideas, is indissolublylinked to c<strong>on</strong>tractualism, that is, to the different versi<strong>on</strong>s -at least to the different classical versi<strong>on</strong>s - of the theory of thesocial c<strong>on</strong>tract. Bobbio and his disciples have dedicated subtle,penetrating historiographical studies to this theory, but theiraccounts often stress too much, in my view, the resemblancebetween the classical theories of the c<strong>on</strong>tract and c<strong>on</strong>temporary orimmediately prior theories of natural law. 37 In c<strong>on</strong>trast, and forreas<strong>on</strong>s we will so<strong>on</strong> see, I am especially c<strong>on</strong>cerned to emphasizethe counterexample of Jean- Jacques Rousseau, the Rousseau ofOn the Social C<strong>on</strong>tract. As I already remarked in c<strong>on</strong>necti<strong>on</strong> withKant, in Rousseau too there is unquesti<strong>on</strong>ably a clear trace of jusnaturalism-studiedwith authority and care by Robert Derathé —but the Rousseau theorist of the c<strong>on</strong>tract is in no way a jusnaturalist.38On the c<strong>on</strong>trary, faithful in this to the remote origins ofc<strong>on</strong>tractualism, Rousseau takes c<strong>on</strong>venti<strong>on</strong>alism, which is just theopposite of jusnaturalism, as his positi<strong>on</strong>. For, as every<strong>on</strong>e knows,36 See Alf<strong>on</strong>so Ruiz Miguel, Filosofía y derecho en Norberto Bobbio (Madrid,1983), 297ff.37See, for example, Norberto Bobbio and Michelangelo Bovero, Società e stat<strong>on</strong>ella filosofia politica moderna (Milan, 1979); see also N. Bobbio and M. Bovero,Origen y fundamentos del poder politico, selecti<strong>on</strong> and translati<strong>on</strong> of texts by bothauthors by José Fernández Santillán (Mexico City, 1985).38R. Derathe, Jean-Jacques Rousseau et la science politique de s<strong>on</strong> temps, 2d ed.(Paris, 1970).


[MUGUERZA] <str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g> Alternative of Dissent 95the tie between “c<strong>on</strong>venti<strong>on</strong>alism” and “c<strong>on</strong>tractualism” datesfrom many centuries ago. 39However, in our case we have no need to go back to the distincti<strong>on</strong>of the Greek Sophists between “nature” (physis) and“c<strong>on</strong>venti<strong>on</strong>” (nomos), a distincti<strong>on</strong> whose applicability in thedomain of politics Aristotle rejected when he defined man as“by nature a political animal.” To Rousseau, without going anyfurther back, it was quite obvious that the grounding of the socialorder represented by the c<strong>on</strong>tract was not to be sought in nature -“nature,” he wrote, “produces no law” - but instead was theproduct of a c<strong>on</strong>venti<strong>on</strong>. 40Quite another matter is Rousseau’sestablishing at <strong>on</strong>ce a distincti<strong>on</strong> between “legitimate” and “illegitimate”c<strong>on</strong>venti<strong>on</strong>s - according to his thesis, no agreementcould ever legitimize the voluntary submissi<strong>on</strong> of <strong>on</strong>e man toanother or of a whole people to a despot - but this involves thedistinct questi<strong>on</strong> of legitimacy, to which we will return at theproper time.Regarding our present interest, and if we interpret the UnitedNati<strong>on</strong>s declarati<strong>on</strong> of 1948 in c<strong>on</strong>tractualist terms, the c<strong>on</strong>sensusof which Bobbio speaks is no more than what is called a “factualc<strong>on</strong>sensus” or merely c<strong>on</strong>tingent agreement, that is, what we calleda “c<strong>on</strong>venti<strong>on</strong>,” for such a c<strong>on</strong>sensus - to which Bobbio entrustedthe definitive de facto soluti<strong>on</strong> of the problem of groundinghuman rights, but which he himself offered as no more than asimple historical fact - might express no more than a strategiccompromise of the interested parties instead of being the result ofa rati<strong>on</strong>al discussi<strong>on</strong> between them (remember Maritain’s anecdoteof which we spoke at the beginning: the delegates of the countriesrepresented <strong>on</strong> the commissi<strong>on</strong> were “in agreement” as to the list39 See J. W. Gough, <str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g> Social C<strong>on</strong>tract: A Critical Study of Its Development,2d ed. (Oxford, 1957).40J.-J. Rousseau, Du c<strong>on</strong>trat social, Oeuvres complètes, Bibliothèque de laPleiade, vol. 3 (Paris, 1964), 353ff.


96 <str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>Tanner</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>Lectures</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>on</strong> <strong>Human</strong> <strong>Values</strong>of human rights to be approved, but <strong>on</strong> c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong> they not beasked Why? that is, For what “reas<strong>on</strong>”?).In which case, Bobbio’s trust might well be betrayed, and hewould risk the charge - a charge that c<strong>on</strong>temporary ethics of discourse,or “communicative ethics,” levels at any c<strong>on</strong>venti<strong>on</strong>alistpositi<strong>on</strong> more or less inspired in the traditi<strong>on</strong> of the social c<strong>on</strong>tract- that no factual collective agreement, not even a true c<strong>on</strong>sensusomnium gentium, can c<strong>on</strong>tain its own rati<strong>on</strong>al grounding,since the factuality of such agreements would never by itself be aguarantee of their rati<strong>on</strong>ality. As is well known, the cultivatorsof this communicative ethics tend to believe that a factual c<strong>on</strong>sensusof this sort can be c<strong>on</strong>sidered “rati<strong>on</strong>al” <strong>on</strong>ly to the extentthat the means of obtaining it approximate those that the membersof an ideal assembly-presumably less subject to spuriousc<strong>on</strong>siderati<strong>on</strong>s than the United Nati<strong>on</strong>s General Assembly -would have to follow to obtain, in uninhibited communicati<strong>on</strong>and by no other means than “discourse” or cooperative discussi<strong>on</strong>,a similarly ideal and even counterfuctual c<strong>on</strong>sensus, <strong>on</strong>e whoserati<strong>on</strong>ality would be above suspici<strong>on</strong>. For - as is also wellknown - discourse or communicative ethics is extremely sensitiveto the “theory of rati<strong>on</strong>ality,” and with good reas<strong>on</strong>, since itattempts to offer itself as a theory of practical reas<strong>on</strong>, which iswhat ethics amounts to for many of us.If we wish to put it this way, the “theory of c<strong>on</strong>sensus” thatthis sort of ethics of discourse or communicative ethics defends,tries in some sense to go “bey<strong>on</strong>d the social c<strong>on</strong>tract,” 41 as theseextracts from the chef d’oeuvre of <strong>on</strong>e of its representatives show:<str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g> free acceptance undertaken by human beings <strong>on</strong>ly c<strong>on</strong>stitutesa necessary, but not a sufficient, c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong> of the moralvalidity of norms, Immoral norms can also be accepted by menas obligatory, out of error or <strong>on</strong> the assumpti<strong>on</strong> that <strong>on</strong>ly41 I refer the reader to my paper “Más allá del c<strong>on</strong>trato social (Venturas ydesventuras de la ética comunicativa),” chap. 7 of Desde la perplejidad (Madrid,in press).


[MUGUERZA] <str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g> Alternative of Dissent 97others (<strong>on</strong>ly the weakest!) will have to obey them: as, forexample, the presumed duty to offer human sacrifice to thegods, or the legal norm that subordinates all social c<strong>on</strong>siderati<strong>on</strong>sto the free play of ec<strong>on</strong>omic competiti<strong>on</strong> - or to thebiological selecti<strong>on</strong> of the fittest. It is true that to be bindingevery c<strong>on</strong>tract presupposes the free acceptance of authentic,that is, moral, norms by both parties, but the moral validityof the presupposed norms cannot be grounded in the fact oftheir acceptance, that is, following the model of the setting upof a c<strong>on</strong>tract. 42To which questi<strong>on</strong> he returns later:<str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g> sense of moral argument might be adequately expressedwith a principle that is by no means new: that is, that all man’snecessities that can be accommodated to the necessities ofothers through discussi<strong>on</strong> . . . must be the c<strong>on</strong>cern of the “idealcommunity of communicati<strong>on</strong>.” With this I believe I have outlinedthe grounding principle of an ethics of communicati<strong>on</strong>which, at the same time, also c<strong>on</strong>stitutes the grounding . . .of an ethics of the democratic formati<strong>on</strong> of the will, achievedby means of agreement or “c<strong>on</strong>venti<strong>on</strong>.” <str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g> basic norm outlinedhere does not derive its obligatory character from itsfactual acceptance by those who arrive at an agreement based<strong>on</strong> the “c<strong>on</strong>tractual model,” but rather it obliges those whohave achieved communicative competency through the processof socializati<strong>on</strong> to reach an understanding with the object ofarriving at a solidary formati<strong>on</strong> of the will <strong>on</strong> every affair thataffects the interests of others. 43Regarding the two texts just quoted, both from a justly famousessay by Karl-Otto Apel, <strong>on</strong>e can be as ir<strong>on</strong>ic as <strong>on</strong>e likes abouttheir aprioristic “community of communicati<strong>on</strong>” that sets up shopin the One-way Castle of philosophical transcendentalism, to42 Karl-Otto Apel, Tranformati<strong>on</strong> der Philosophie, 2 vols. (Frankfurt am Main,1973), 2: chap. 7, “Das Apriori der Kommunikati<strong>on</strong>sgemeinschaft und die Grundlagender Ethik,” 415–16.43 Apel, Transformati<strong>on</strong>, 425-26.


98 <str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>Tanner</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>Lectures</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>on</strong> <strong>Human</strong> <strong>Values</strong>which there are certainly as many access roads as there have beentranscendental philosophers throughout history, but not <strong>on</strong>e returnroad, because n<strong>on</strong>e of these philosophers has ever returned. Orit might be compared, as I <strong>on</strong>ce did, to the “communi<strong>on</strong> of saints,”bey<strong>on</strong>d the reach of any mortals except those Tibetan m<strong>on</strong>ks towhom Kant attributed a certain familiarity with the Versammlungaller Heiligen. 44Or, finally, <strong>on</strong>e might allege the unlikelihood ofdiscovering the grounding we seek for human rights in that sortof angelic community, where it is by no means clear that we arelikely to find anything truly human. But Apel’s allegati<strong>on</strong> againstc<strong>on</strong>venti<strong>on</strong>alism must be taken seriously, which really means “takingethics seriously,” inasmuch as it is no less deserving of seriousnessthan rights or the law. For, all ir<strong>on</strong>y aside, the moral of histexts is c<strong>on</strong>clusive. If our c<strong>on</strong>venti<strong>on</strong>s will serve equally to supportjust and unjust norms, they will also serve to ground humanand inhuman rights, from which it follows that such c<strong>on</strong>venti<strong>on</strong>swill not serve our purposes.45 And, as for the accusati<strong>on</strong> of idealism,it should not be forgotten that in those texts Apel alsospeaks of quite realistic and even material things, such as “interests’’and “needs,” even though he reminds us that both requirelinguistic expressi<strong>on</strong> in order to be shared in communicati<strong>on</strong>.But this last is something that even so prominent a theoreticianof needs as Agnes Heller makes no b<strong>on</strong>es about recognizing, indialog, furthermore, with an equally prominent theoretician ofthe ethics of discourse, or communicative ethics, Jürgen Habermas,when she writes that even though the Habermasian theory cannotspeak to people with any more authority than its rivals about whattheir “interests and needs” are, at least “it can tell <strong>on</strong>e thatwhatevertheir interests and needs - people must argue com-44 Kant, Zum ewigen Frieden, Werke, 8:359–60n.45 For a more detailed evaluati<strong>on</strong> of Apel’s critique of c<strong>on</strong>venti<strong>on</strong>alism, seemy c<strong>on</strong>tributi<strong>on</strong>, “El aposteriori de la comunidad de comunicación y la ética sinfundamentos,” to Estudios sobre la filosofía de Karl-Otto Apelí ed. Adela Cortina(in preparati<strong>on</strong>).


[MUGUERZA] <str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g> Alternative of Dissent 99municatively in favor of them,” that is, “must relate them tovalues by means of rati<strong>on</strong>al arguments.” 46Nor is the advent of Habermas and his ethics of discourse atall fortuitous at this point.47 His positi<strong>on</strong>, as every<strong>on</strong>e knows,is close to Apel’s, albeit with certain important differences ofnuance (for example, a c<strong>on</strong>siderable reducti<strong>on</strong> in degree of transcendentalism),And, like Dworkin, he is interested in bringingethics closer to law (Habermas’s ethics is clearly influenced byKant, but it also c<strong>on</strong>tains certain Hegelian features that are worthkeeping in mind). As to the first, Habermas holds that thecriteri<strong>on</strong> for grounding a norm can <strong>on</strong>ly be a c<strong>on</strong>sensus obtainedthrough rati<strong>on</strong>al discourse, a c<strong>on</strong>sensus, then, that is a rati<strong>on</strong>alc<strong>on</strong>sensus, the obtaining of which depends <strong>on</strong> a series of hypotheticalc<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s - the well-known, hypothesis of the “idealspeech situati<strong>on</strong>” - such as that all those involved in the dialogenjoy a symmetrical distributi<strong>on</strong> of the opportunities to intervene,and that the dialog proceed with no more coerci<strong>on</strong> than that imposedby the quality of the arguments (c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s which obviouslyought to be called “counterfactual,” that is, c<strong>on</strong>trary to fact, ratherthan hypothetical, for in reality they never arise -with the probableexcepti<strong>on</strong> of the discussi<strong>on</strong> sessi<strong>on</strong>s that will follow the readingof this lecture). As to the sec<strong>on</strong>d - that is, the liais<strong>on</strong>, Iwould not want to say at this point whether hereuse or dangereuse,between ethics and law - perhaps it would be better to let Habermashimself speak. We are told that “the counterpositi<strong>on</strong> betweenthe areas regulated respectively by morality and politics would berelativized, and the validity of all norms would then depend <strong>on</strong>the communicative formati<strong>on</strong> of the will of those potentially interested,”given that “(even if) this does not alter the need to46 A. Heller, “Habermas and Marxism,” in Habermas: Critical Debates,ed. J. B. Thomps<strong>on</strong> and D. Held (Cambridge, Mass., 1982), 21-41, 32.47 For the most complete expositi<strong>on</strong> of his ethics of discourse, see J. Habermas,“Diskursethik: Notizen su einem Begründungsprogram,” in Moralbewusstsein andkornmunikatives Handeln (Frankfurt am Main, 1983), 53-124.


100 <str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>Tanner</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>Lectures</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>on</strong> <strong>Human</strong> <strong>Values</strong>establish coactive norms, because no <strong>on</strong>e can know - at least notat present - to what degree it is possible to reduce aggressi<strong>on</strong> andachieve a voluntary recogniti<strong>on</strong> of the ‘principle of discourse,’ . . .<strong>on</strong>ly in this latter case, which for the moment is no more than ac<strong>on</strong>struct, would morality become strictly universal, in which caseit would also cease to be ‘mere morality’ in the sense of the usualdistincti<strong>on</strong> between law and morality.” 48(<str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g>re is no need toinsist <strong>on</strong> the Hegelian overt<strong>on</strong>es of these paragraphs, where -rather than bringing ethics closer to law-it would be moreproper to speak of their mixture, with politics included, <strong>on</strong>ce theaforementi<strong>on</strong>ed mere morality had been overcome.)Habermas has reiterated his viewpoint in a recent essay-“Wie ist Legitimität durch Legalität möglich?” (1987)- where,in the course of attempting to answer the questi<strong>on</strong> “how can legitimacybe achieved through legality?” the general sense of his positi<strong>on</strong><strong>on</strong> the problems of grounding that we have been discussingis c<strong>on</strong>siderably clarified. 49Habermas takes them up in the process of defending the thesisthat the aut<strong>on</strong>omizati<strong>on</strong> of law-effected in modern times withthe help of rati<strong>on</strong>al law (the Kantian Vernunftrecht), whichrendered possible the introducti<strong>on</strong> of differences into the previouslysolid block of morality, law, and politics-cannot meana complete divorce between law and morality, <strong>on</strong> the <strong>on</strong>e hand,or politics, <strong>on</strong> the other, since law that has become positive cannotdo without its inner relati<strong>on</strong>ship with either of the two. Habermas,then, c<strong>on</strong>siders Austin’s or Kelsen’s c<strong>on</strong>cept of juridical aut<strong>on</strong>omy(to which we referred a short while ago) indefensible, and hethen asks how the aforementi<strong>on</strong>ed aut<strong>on</strong>omizati<strong>on</strong> of law waseffected. <str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g> turning point comes with modern rati<strong>on</strong>al law,which-in c<strong>on</strong>necti<strong>on</strong> with the theory of the social c<strong>on</strong>tract48 J. Habermas, Legitimati<strong>on</strong>sprobleme in Spätkapitalismus (Frankfurt am Main,1973), 87.49 Habermas, “Wie ist Legitimität durch Legalität möglich?” Kritische Justiz 20(1987): 1-16.


[MUGUERZA] <str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g> Alternative of Dissent 101(Kant’s, but before him, Rousseau’s) - reflected the articulati<strong>on</strong>of a new posttraditi<strong>on</strong>al state of moral c<strong>on</strong>science, which in turnwould eventually serve as a model of procedural rati<strong>on</strong>ality forlaw. As Habermas writes elsewhere:In modern times we have learned to distinguish with greaterclarity between theoretical and practical arguments. Withregard to questi<strong>on</strong>s of a practical nature, which c<strong>on</strong>cern thejustificati<strong>on</strong> of norms and acti<strong>on</strong>s, Rousseau introduces theformal principle of Reas<strong>on</strong>, which takes the role formerlyplayed by material principles such as Nature or God. . . .Now, since ultimate reas<strong>on</strong>s are no l<strong>on</strong>ger theoretically plausible,the formal c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s of justificati<strong>on</strong> end by taking <strong>on</strong> alegitimizing force of their own, that is, the procedures andthe premises of the rati<strong>on</strong>al agreement acquire the status ofprinciples. . . . (That is), the formal c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s for the possiblereaching of a rati<strong>on</strong>ai c<strong>on</strong>sensus replace the ultimate reas<strong>on</strong>s intheir capacity as legitimizing f orce.” 50Of course, there can be theories of c<strong>on</strong>tracts of very different stripe,and obviously Hobbes’s is very different from Kant’s. Whereasfor Hobbes, for example, in the last analysis law becomes aninstrument at the service of political dominati<strong>on</strong>, law for Kant -including positive law - retains its essentially moral character,which leads Habermas to assert that law (and the same could besaid of politics) “is reduced by Kant to the c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong> of a deficientkind of morality [Recht wird zu einem defizienten Modus derMoral herabgestuft].”51 According to Habermas, the reas<strong>on</strong> forthis is the tendency of Kantian rati<strong>on</strong>al law to occupy the placevacated by the old natural law. In Kantian terms, as interpretedby Habermas at least, the positivati<strong>on</strong> of law would amount tothe realizati<strong>on</strong> in the empirical or phenomenal political world (respublica phaenomen<strong>on</strong>) of rati<strong>on</strong>al juridical principles - which50 J. Habermas, Zur Rek<strong>on</strong>strukti<strong>on</strong> des historischen Materialismus (Frank-furt am Main, 1976), 250.51 Habermas, “Wie ist Legitimität,” 7.


102 <str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>Tanner</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>Lectures</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>on</strong> <strong>Human</strong> <strong>Values</strong>supposedly would corresp<strong>on</strong>d to a moral or noumenal politicalworld (res publica noumen<strong>on</strong>)-principles derived from, anddependent up<strong>on</strong>, imperatives (moral imperatives) of reas<strong>on</strong>(practical reas<strong>on</strong>). But according to this metaphysical doctrineof the two worlds or “two kingdoms (Zwei-Reiche-Lehre),” bothlaw and politics would in fact lose their positivity, thereby threatening,still according to Habermas, to destroy the very viabilityof the distincti<strong>on</strong> we spoke of before between legality (of a positivelaw within an also positive c<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong> of politics) andmorality.Be that as it may, the dynamics of modern social life seemsto flow through quite different channels from those foreseen, ordreamed of, in Kantian ethics. And the dogmatics of private law,as well as of public law, would c<strong>on</strong>tradict Kant’s juridical c<strong>on</strong>struct,according to which positive politics and positive law wouldhave to be subordinate to the moral imperatives of rati<strong>on</strong>al law.Now, if <strong>on</strong> the <strong>on</strong>e hand, the moral foundati<strong>on</strong>s of positive lawcould no l<strong>on</strong>ger be modeled <strong>on</strong> a Kantian subordinati<strong>on</strong> to rati<strong>on</strong>allaw, <strong>on</strong> the other hand it is also clearly impossible to deal with,or avoid either, without first having found a substitute for rati<strong>on</strong>allaw itself. Habermas quotes the dictum of the German juristG. F. Puchta, who in the last century proclaimed that the creati<strong>on</strong>of law could not be exclusively the work of political legislators,since in that case the state could not be founded <strong>on</strong> law, that is,not be a state of law, where “state of law” is offered precisely asa substitute for rati<strong>on</strong>al law. 52But, in additi<strong>on</strong> to the questi<strong>on</strong> ofstrict legality, the idea of a state of law poses the problem of“legitimacy,” unless <strong>on</strong>e wants to interpret in strictly positivisticterms a no less famous dictum, which another jurist, H. Heller,quoted during the Weimar Republic: “In a state of law the lawsare the totality of the juridical norms promulgated by the Parlia-52 Ibid., 8ff.


(MUGUERZA) <str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g> Alternative of Dissent 103ment.” 53<str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g>refore, the definiti<strong>on</strong> of legality neither resolves theproblem of legitimacy nor allows us to dismiss it. And, accordingto Habermas, the plus required by the demands of legitimacywould have to be supplied by the introducti<strong>on</strong> “in the interior ofpositive law itself (im inneren des positiven Rechts selbst),” andnot by subordinati<strong>on</strong> to something exterior, “of the moral pointof view of an impartial formati<strong>on</strong> of the will (der moralischeGesichtpunkt einer unparteilichen Willensbildung),” so that “themorality nested in law would have . . . the transcendent capacityof a self-regulating procedure charged with c<strong>on</strong>trolling its ownrati<strong>on</strong>ality [die ins positive Recht eingebaute Moralitat hat . . , dietranszendierende Kraft eines sich selbst regulierenden Verfahrens,das seine eigene Vernunftigkeit k<strong>on</strong>trolliert) .” 54Let us try to clear a path through Habermas’s dense prose inorder to see what he means. <str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g> rati<strong>on</strong>ality Habermas speaks ofis nothing but the “procedural rati<strong>on</strong>ality” that was alreadypresaged in the eighteenth century, when Kant, basing himself<strong>on</strong> Rousseau, liked to repeat that the ultimate proof of the legalityof any judicial norm lay in asking <strong>on</strong>eself “if it could have arisenas a result of the joint will of a whole people.” 55Now then, whatare we to understand, when this sort of criteri<strong>on</strong> is proposed, by“the joint will of a whole people”? Obviously, for Kant, thatwill had much more to do with Rousseau’s “general will” thanwith the plain and unadorned “will of all,” which is the <strong>on</strong>ly willthat plain and unadorned c<strong>on</strong>venti<strong>on</strong>alism takes into account. 56And this would also appear to be the choice of the “rati<strong>on</strong>al will”to which Habermas refers - a will produced by “an impartialformati<strong>on</strong> of the will,” that is, of the collective will - a will that,53 Ibid., 9.54 Ibid.55 Ibid., 10; see Kant, Rechtslehre, part 2, and Über den Gemeinspruch: Dasmag in der <str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g>orie richtig sein, taugt aber nicht fiir die Praxis, Werke, 8:273–313.56 See Howard Williams, Kant’s Political Philosophy (Oxford, 1983), 161ff.


104 <str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>Tanner</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>Lectures</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>on</strong> <strong>Human</strong> <strong>Values</strong>like the general will, would not be c<strong>on</strong>tent with a c<strong>on</strong>sensus thatmerely reflected the total of a series of individual interests but<strong>on</strong>e that shed light <strong>on</strong> the general interest of the community, thatis, the “generalizable interests” of its members, by means, as wesaw, of a rati<strong>on</strong>al c<strong>on</strong>sensus. Naturally, the Habermasian versi<strong>on</strong>of c<strong>on</strong>sensualism - an heir of Rousseau’s general will - faces nofewer problems than c<strong>on</strong>venti<strong>on</strong>alism, some of which we will menti<strong>on</strong>presently. But, for the moment, let us deal with Habermas’sinsistence <strong>on</strong> procedural rati<strong>on</strong>ality.According to Habermas, procedural rati<strong>on</strong>ality gains c<strong>on</strong>siderati<strong>on</strong>“with the proof of its capacity for generalizati<strong>on</strong> of interests(durch die Prufung der Verallgemeinerungsfähigkeit v<strong>on</strong>Interessen).” 57 This would provide a critical standard for theanalysis and evaluati<strong>on</strong> of the political reality of a state of law,a state, in other words, “that derives its legitimacy from a rati<strong>on</strong>alityof the procedures for the promulgati<strong>on</strong> of laws andthe administrati<strong>on</strong> of justice designed to guarantee impartiality(der seine Legitimitat aus einer Unparteilichkeit verbürgendenRati<strong>on</strong>alitat v<strong>on</strong> Gesetzgebungs- und Rechtsprechungsverfahrenzieht).” 58As a matter of fact, the procedural rati<strong>on</strong>ality thatpresides over Habermas’s ethics of discourse is naturally nostranger to law, to positive law. We must look, therefore, to the“rati<strong>on</strong>ality of law” for an answer to the questi<strong>on</strong> of how legitimacyis achieved through legality. Now, Habermas does notagree with Max Weber’s belief that the rati<strong>on</strong>ality inherent in thelaw as such provides - aside from all kinds of moral presuppositi<strong>on</strong>sand implicati<strong>on</strong>s - the ground for the legitimizing force oflegality : in Habermas’s opini<strong>on</strong>, the legitimizing force would corresp<strong>on</strong>drather to the procedures charged with instituti<strong>on</strong>alizingthe foundati<strong>on</strong>al demands of the current legality, as well as to theargumentative resources available to achieve those demands. 59<str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g>57 Habermas, “Wie ist Legitimitat,” 11.58 Ibid.59 Ibid., 12.


[MUGUEFZA] <str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g> Alternative of Dissent 105“source of legitimati<strong>on</strong>,” therefore, should not be sought unilaterallyin such places as political legislati<strong>on</strong> or the administrati<strong>on</strong>of justice. For example, the grounding of norms - no less thantheir applicati<strong>on</strong> - presupposes the idea of impartiality. Andthis “idea of impartiality,” which in turn is strictly dependent <strong>on</strong>the idea of the “moral point of view,” 60c<strong>on</strong>stitutes, Habermasrecalls, the very root of practical reas<strong>on</strong>, forming part of communicativeethics and of any other ethical theories (Habermasmenti<strong>on</strong>s those of John Rawls and Lawrence Kohlberg) that c<strong>on</strong>sistof providing a procedure with which to meet practical problemsfrom the moral point of views. 61 In Habermas’s communicativeethics, it is already quite clear just what that procedure is:“Whoever takes part in the praxis of argumentati<strong>on</strong>,” Habermasc<strong>on</strong>cludes, “must assume pragmatically that, as a matter of principle,all of the potentially interested parties can and may participatefreely and equally in a cooperative search for truth, where the<strong>on</strong>ly coerci<strong>on</strong> is in advancing a better argument [Jeder Teilnehmeran einer Argumentati<strong>on</strong>spraxis muss namlich pragmatisch voraussetzen,dass im Prinzip alle moglicherweise Betro ff en als Freieund Gleiche an einer kooperatiuen Wahrheitssuche teilnehmenk<strong>on</strong>nten, bei der einzig der Zwang des besseren Argumentes zumZuge kommen darf].” 62Pers<strong>on</strong>ally I would object, in such a characterizati<strong>on</strong>, to theblatant cognitivism of the allusi<strong>on</strong> to the “cooperative search fortruth.” In practical discourse, as a matter of fact, “truths” are not60 [<str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g> words “moral point of view” were in English in the original.]61 Habermas, “Wie ist Legitimität,” 12. According to Jose Luis L. Aranguren,“Sobre la etica de Kant,” in Kant después de Kant (En el segundo centenavio de laCritica de la Raz<strong>on</strong> Practica), ed. J. <str<strong>on</strong>g>Muguerza</str<strong>on</strong>g> and R. Rodriguez Aramayo (Madrid,in press), “proceduralism” - that is, the reducti<strong>on</strong> of practical reas<strong>on</strong> to proceduralreas<strong>on</strong>ing - is a “neokantian” characteristic of those trends in c<strong>on</strong>temporary ethics,and is the result, am<strong>on</strong>g other things, of an extreme assimilati<strong>on</strong> of ethics by law(this assimilati<strong>on</strong> is, in fact, more neokantian than Kantian, since it is scarcely inline with the spirit of Kant’s distincti<strong>on</strong> between legality and morality). For mypart, I have already pointed out that in Habermas’s case the same assimilati<strong>on</strong> alsoincludes a good bit of “neohegelianism.”62 Habermas, “Wie ist Legitimität,” 13.


106 <str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>Tanner</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>Lectures</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>on</strong> <strong>Human</strong> <strong>Values</strong>sought (even “truths by c<strong>on</strong>sensus”) and the best refutati<strong>on</strong> of acognitivist positi<strong>on</strong> such as this is the <strong>on</strong>e developed by PaulLorenzen, who encapsulates it in the precept “You ought to seek<strong>on</strong>ly the truth,” where the “ought” removes us from the cognitivistperspective and places us in a normative and, finally, anethical <strong>on</strong>e. 63But, in fact, there would be no problem - that is,no new problem-if, for the phrase “cooperative search fortruth,” we simply substituted “search for a c<strong>on</strong>sensus.” With thecharacterizati<strong>on</strong> understood this way, we can also understandbetter why Habermas wants to c<strong>on</strong>sider “juridical proceduralism”as c<strong>on</strong>tinuous with ethical proceduralism. “It is not a questi<strong>on</strong>,”he tells us, “of c<strong>on</strong>fusing law and ethics (Freilich dürfen dieGrenzen zwischen Recht und Moral nicht vermischt werden) .” 64As instituti<strong>on</strong>alized procedures, the juridical <strong>on</strong>es may aspire to a“completeness” that would not be attainable for ethical procedures,whose rati<strong>on</strong>ality is always an “incomplete rati<strong>on</strong>ality”that depends <strong>on</strong> the perspectives of the interested parties. Not tomenti<strong>on</strong> the greater degree of “publicity” of juridical procedures,compared with the “privacy” of an internalized and aut<strong>on</strong>omousmorality; or the instrumental c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong> of law when used toachieve this or that political goal, which locates law “betweenethics and politics.” But, be that as it may, there is also, he warnsus, an “ethics of political resp<strong>on</strong>sibility,” and law and ethics “not<strong>on</strong>ly complement each other but <strong>on</strong>e can even speak of theirmutual coupling,” such that “procedural law and proceduralizedmorality could c<strong>on</strong>trol <strong>on</strong>e another.” 65But what is the ultimatemeaning of this “c<strong>on</strong>trol <strong>on</strong>e another”?As he himself says, Habermas does not c<strong>on</strong>fuse ethics andlaw, but he does mix them when he speaks not <strong>on</strong>ly of their“complementarity” (Ergänzung) but also of their “mutual cou-63P. Lorenzen, Normative Logic and Ethics (Mannheim, 1969), 74.64 Habermas, “Wie ist Legitimität,” 13.65 Ibid., 14-15.


[MUGUERZA] <str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g> Alternative of Dissent 107pling” (Verschränkung) . And I am not at all certain if we canexpect much from this mixture to which I previously referred.For Habermas ends up not so much with “the moralizati<strong>on</strong> ofLaw” or “the juridicalizati<strong>on</strong> of Ethics” as with the politicizati<strong>on</strong>of both elements.In what is thus far the can<strong>on</strong>ical versi<strong>on</strong> of his ethics of discourse,66Habermas has been able to encapsulate it as the proposalof a communicative transformati<strong>on</strong> of the Kantian “principleof universalizati<strong>on</strong>,” that is, <strong>on</strong>e of the formulati<strong>on</strong>s ofKant’s categorical imperative. Where the former prescribed, “Act<strong>on</strong>ly according to that maxim by which you can at the same timewill that it should become a universal law,” Habermas’s versi<strong>on</strong>prescribes instead, “Rather than ascribing as valid for all othersany maxim that I can will to be a universal law, I must submitmy maxim to all others for the purpose of communicatively testingits claim to universality,” where “communicatively” simplymeans “democratically.” 67In the essay we have been commenting<strong>on</strong>, Habermas closes with this affirmati<strong>on</strong>: “No aut<strong>on</strong>omous lawwithout real democracy [Kein aat<strong>on</strong>omes Recht ohne verwirklicheDemokratie].” 68 He might have said the same about ethics, for,in the end, we not <strong>on</strong>ly find law between ethics and politics, butalso ethics between politics and law (for a graphic idea of theirmutual relati<strong>on</strong>s, <strong>on</strong>e has <strong>on</strong>ly to c<strong>on</strong>ceive of ethics, law, andpolitics as the three sides of a triangle). Habermas does not tellus what kind of “democracy” this would be, in keeping with hisreservati<strong>on</strong>s elsewhere which led him to write, “it is a questi<strong>on</strong>of finding mechanisms that will serve to ground the suppositi<strong>on</strong>66Ibid., 14-15 n. 45.67 Habermas, “Diskursethik,” 77. As Habermas acknowledges, the reformulati<strong>on</strong>of the principle of universalizati<strong>on</strong>, within the ethics of discourse, was inspiredby a versi<strong>on</strong> of his own thought by Thomas McCarthy, <str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g> Critical <str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g>ory ofJürgen Habermas (Cambridge, Mass., 1978; 2d ed., L<strong>on</strong>d<strong>on</strong>, 1981), 326.68 Habermas, “Wie ist Legitimität,” 16. See, in c<strong>on</strong>necti<strong>on</strong> with this point, thepaper by Maria Herrera, “Etica, derecho y democracia en J. Habermas,” in the collectivevolume Teorías de la democracia (Mexico City, in press).


108 <str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>Tanner</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>Lectures</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>on</strong> <strong>Human</strong> <strong>Values</strong>that the basic instituti<strong>on</strong>s of society and the fundamental politicaldecisi<strong>on</strong>s would be willingly approved by all those affected bythem if the latter were able to participate - freely and equally -in the processes of the communicative formati<strong>on</strong> of the will,[but] democratizati<strong>on</strong> cannot mean an a priori preference for aspecific type of organizati<strong>on</strong>.” 69But whether we are dealing witha participatory or a representative democracy, or with a combinati<strong>on</strong>of the two, the collective decisi<strong>on</strong>s that are made there willhave to recognize in some way or other the prevalence of someversi<strong>on</strong> of the “rule of the majority,” something that, with goodreas<strong>on</strong>, Professor Elías Díaz never tires of reminding us of in ourcountry. 70Still, as Díaz is the first to recognize, the rule of the majorityis far from guaranteeing the justice of the decisi<strong>on</strong>s it enables. Intruth, nothing excludes the possibility that the decisi<strong>on</strong> of a givenmajority may be unjust, and the fact that decisi<strong>on</strong>s that are notmajority <strong>on</strong>es may also be unjust - and, very likely, or certainly,even more unjust - does not provide us with any ethical solace,especially if what we hope to do is use Habermas’s imperative(or the Habermasian versi<strong>on</strong> of the Kantian principle of universalizati<strong>on</strong>)to ground human rights. When it comes to puttingit into practice, the sophisticated c<strong>on</strong>sensualism of Habermas, orof Apel, unfortunately does not seem much more useful than c<strong>on</strong>venti<strong>on</strong>alism,or, if <strong>on</strong>e prefers, Bobbio’s c<strong>on</strong>sensualism.Take, for example, those human rights having to do with therequirements of liberty and equality of which I spoke at the beginningof this lecture. Habermas seemed to take them for grantedwhen he affirmed that in argumentative praxis we would have toc<strong>on</strong>sider the possibility, even the necessity, that all those potentiallyinterested participate (precisely as free and equal and in noother way) in the cooperative search for c<strong>on</strong>sensus. In which case,69 Habermas, Zur Rek<strong>on</strong>strukti<strong>on</strong>, 252.70E. Diaz, Da la maldad estatal y la soberanía popular (Madrid, 1984), 57ff.


[MUGUERZA] <str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g> Alternative of Dissent 109freedom and equality would be something like transcendental,or quasi-transcendental, c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s of possibility for discourseitself. And, when we descended from this transcendental or quasitranscendentalplane to the miserable sublunary world of dailypolitical realities, those c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s would not be sufficient to excludethe possibility that a majority decisi<strong>on</strong> might infringe <strong>on</strong>the freedom and/or equality of a number of people, such as thoseforming an oppressed and/or exploited minority (for our purposesit would be too much if it infringed <strong>on</strong> the freedom and/orequality of even <strong>on</strong>e individual). Just as it could happen that thisdecisi<strong>on</strong> might infringe <strong>on</strong> the dignity of those people if, forinstance, to their oppressi<strong>on</strong> and/or exploitati<strong>on</strong>, humiliati<strong>on</strong> andeven the denial of their c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong> as human beings were added.<str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g> preceding observati<strong>on</strong>s-I hasten to add in order toreassure Díaz - are by no means intended to disqualify democracy,which undoubtedly is made legitimate to an acceptable degreewith Habermas’s procedural rati<strong>on</strong>ality, in additi<strong>on</strong> to a series ofcomplementary elements (respect and protecti<strong>on</strong> of minorities,safeguards for the rights of the individual, guarantees as to theextensi<strong>on</strong> of the c<strong>on</strong>cept of democracy bey<strong>on</strong>d the mechanicalfuncti<strong>on</strong>ing of the rule of the majority, etc.) , elements that wouldbe important to Habermas and that are included in the noti<strong>on</strong> oflegitimacy that Díaz suggests we call “critical legitimacy.” 71But the questi<strong>on</strong> that we are c<strong>on</strong>cerned to clarify here iswhether this procedural rati<strong>on</strong>ality, with as many complementaryelements as we wish to add, completely exhausts the domain ofpractical reas<strong>on</strong>, which is to say the domain of ethics: the answer,I believe, would be in the negative, since thus far (“thus far,” ofcourse, simply means “until this moment in my lecture”) practical71 See ibid., 21ff., 127-48, as well as his postscript, “La justificación de lademocracia,” Sistema 66 (1985): 3-23. For Habermas’s view, see also “DieSchrecken der Aut<strong>on</strong>omie,” <strong>on</strong> the disqualificati<strong>on</strong> of democracy by Carl Schmittand his present curious revival, in Eine Art Schadensabwicklung (Frankfurt amMain, 1987), 101–14.


110 <str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>Tanner</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>Lectures</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>on</strong> <strong>Human</strong> <strong>Values</strong>reas<strong>on</strong> still has not managed to provide us with the desired foundati<strong>on</strong>of human rights that we seek.In order to explore a different strategy, I want to turn to adifferent formulati<strong>on</strong> of Kant’s categorical imperative, <strong>on</strong>e whoseethical importance - for our purposes undoubtedly superior tothat of the principle of universalizati<strong>on</strong> - has been pointed outby several c<strong>on</strong>temporary philosophers, by Ernst Tugendhat forinstance. 72Although my approach to this formulati<strong>on</strong> is not thesame as his, I too have had recourse more than <strong>on</strong>ce to the prescripti<strong>on</strong>“Act in such a way that you always treat humanity,whether in your own pers<strong>on</strong> or in that of any other, never simplyas a means but always at the same time as an end.” And <strong>on</strong> <strong>on</strong>esuch occasi<strong>on</strong> I called that imperative the imperative of dissidence,73with the understanding that - unlike the principle ofuniversalizati<strong>on</strong>, which was meant to promote subscripti<strong>on</strong> tovalues such as dignity, liberty, and equality - what this imperativewould really have to do was to ground the possibility of sayingno to situati<strong>on</strong>s where indignity and a lack of liberty or equalityprevailed.To put it succinctly, we ought to ask ourselves if - after somuch insistence <strong>on</strong> factual or counterfactual c<strong>on</strong>sensus with regardto human rights - it would not be more advantageous toattempt a “grounding” <strong>on</strong> the basis of dissensus, that is, a “negative”foundati<strong>on</strong> for human rights, which I will term “the alternativeof dissent.”72 See E. Tugendhat, Probleme der Ethik (Stuttgart, 1984). See Tugendhat’s“Retraktati<strong>on</strong>en” (1983), included in this book (132-76) and written in reacti<strong>on</strong> tothe criticism Ursula Wolf (Das Problem des moralisches Sollens, Berlin, 1984)leveled at his earlier “Drei Vorlesungen iiber Probleme der Ethik’ (1981), 57-131.For other views of this questi<strong>on</strong>, see P. Haezrahi, “<str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g> C<strong>on</strong>cept of Man as Endin-Himself,”in Kant: A Collecti<strong>on</strong> of Critical Essays, ed. R. P. Wolff (L<strong>on</strong>d<strong>on</strong>,1968), 291-313; T. E. Hill, “<strong>Human</strong>ity as an End in Itself,” Ethics 91 (1980):84-99; and, especially, Albrecht Wellmer, Ethik und Dialog: Elemente des moralischenUrteilsbei Kant und in der Diskursethik (Frankfurt am Main, 1986).73 For instance, in my paper “La obediencia a1 Derecho y el imperativo de ladisidencia (Una intrusión en un debate),” Sistema 70 (1986): 27-40.


[MUGUERZA] <str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g> Alternative of Dissent 111In fact, the idea here of recourse to “dissensus” instead ofc<strong>on</strong>sensus hardly seems wr<strong>on</strong>gheaded if we notice that the historicalphenomenology of the political struggle for the c<strong>on</strong>quest ofhuman rights, of whatever variety, has always had to do with thedissent of individuals or groups of individuals with respect to aprior c<strong>on</strong>sensus - usually written into the current legislati<strong>on</strong> -that in <strong>on</strong>e way or another denied them their intended c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>of subjects of those rights. Although historical accounts of humanrights often go back to the beginnings of time, if we located thestart of this struggle in modern times, it would not be hard tofind - behind each and every <strong>on</strong>e of the documents that servesas a precedent for the Universal Declarati<strong>on</strong> of <strong>Human</strong> Rights of1948 (from the English Bill of Rights of 1689, or that of theGood People of Virginia of 1776, or the Déclarati<strong>on</strong> des droits del’homme et du citoyen of the French Nati<strong>on</strong>al Assembly of 1789,by way of our own C<strong>on</strong>stituti<strong>on</strong> of Cádiz of 1812, to the MexicanC<strong>on</strong>stituti<strong>on</strong> of 1917, or the Declarati<strong>on</strong> of Rights of the WorkingPeople of the Soviet Uni<strong>on</strong> of 1919) - either the vindicati<strong>on</strong>sthat accompanied the rise of the bourgeoisie in the sixteenth,seventeenth, and eighteenth centuries, or the workers’ movementsin the nineteenth and twentieth centuries, just as the anticol<strong>on</strong>ialiststruggles of our own era are to be found behind this declarati<strong>on</strong>of 1948. Nor would it be hard to identify the c<strong>on</strong>temporary socialmovements directly or indirectly resp<strong>on</strong>sible for the Internati<strong>on</strong>alPact <strong>on</strong> Civil and Political Rights, and the Internati<strong>on</strong>al Pact <strong>on</strong>Ec<strong>on</strong>omic, Social, and Cultural Rights, both dating from 1966,which are an outgrowth of the UN declarati<strong>on</strong> and together withit, in the c<strong>on</strong>text of the United Nati<strong>on</strong>s’ efforts to coordinate legislati<strong>on</strong>,make up what is known as the <strong>Human</strong> Rights Today,indeed, we will have to look to the so-called “new social movements”- pacifist, ecologist, feminist, and so <strong>on</strong> - for any future74 See Derecbo positivo de los Derechos <strong>Human</strong>os, ed. Gregorio Peces-Barba(Madrid, 1987), and Historia de losDerechos <strong>Human</strong>os, ed. E. Fernández, G. Peces-Barba, A. E. Pérez Luño, and L. Prieto (in preparati<strong>on</strong>).


112 <str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>Tanner</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>Lectures</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>on</strong> <strong>Human</strong> <strong>Values</strong>advances in the struggle for those rights, which, as we hope andpresume, will <strong>on</strong>e day be added to the appropriate legislati<strong>on</strong>,however indifferent to them the present legislati<strong>on</strong> now is.In this perspective, the social and political history of mankind- with its perpetual, <strong>on</strong>e could almost say Sisyphean, c<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong>and destructi<strong>on</strong> of prior c<strong>on</strong>sensuses broken by dissentand later restored <strong>on</strong> different bases, <strong>on</strong>ly to be struck down byother dissents in an infinite successi<strong>on</strong> - is rather like the descripti<strong>on</strong>of the history of science that we owe to Thomas Kuhn, withits characteristic alternating periods of “normal science” under thehegem<strong>on</strong>y of a given scientific paradigm, and its periods of “scientificrevoluti<strong>on</strong>.” As Michael Walzer remarked somewhat acidly,the applicati<strong>on</strong> of Kuhn’s schemata to the history of human mores“is more melodrama than realistic history.” 75 But perhaps humanhistory is somewhat melodramatic, if not something worse - asShakespeare well knew - since it is normally, or revoluti<strong>on</strong>arily(in the Kuhnian as well as the usual sense), written in blood.And if there is any doubt that the history of mores involves discoveryand inventi<strong>on</strong> just as the history of science and technologydoes, the inventi<strong>on</strong> of human rights ought to serve to dispel thismisapprehensi<strong>on</strong>, inasmuch as human rights c<strong>on</strong>stitute “<strong>on</strong>e of thegreatest inventi<strong>on</strong>s of our civilizati<strong>on</strong>,” in exactly the same sensethat scientific discoveries or technological inventi<strong>on</strong>s do, accordingto Carlos Santiago Nino.76 But as to my remark that the historicalphenomenology of the struggle for these rights has involved atleast as much dissent as it has c<strong>on</strong>sensus-if not more- thetruth is that I am unable to develop this line further. I am neithera historian nor a sociologist of c<strong>on</strong>flict, nor do I have any otherprofessi<strong>on</strong>al qualificati<strong>on</strong>s in this respect, and I do not wish toburden the thesis I will be defending with the inevitable accusa-13-17.75 M. Walzer, Interpretati<strong>on</strong> and Social Criticism (Cambridge, Mass., 1987), 26.76 C. S. Nino, “Introducción,” Ética y derechos humanos (Buenos Aires, 1984),


[MUGUERZA] <str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g> Alternative of Dissent 113ti<strong>on</strong> that I am guilty of some versi<strong>on</strong> of the “genetic fallacy,” of ahistoricist or sociologistic variety, because I attempted to derivephilosophical c<strong>on</strong>clusi<strong>on</strong>s from the historical development ofevents or from this or that circumstance of social reality.On the other hand, <strong>on</strong>e would indeed have to keep in mindthat, when viewed in a strictly philosophical perspective, theimperative I called <strong>on</strong>e of dissidence - from which Kant drewhis idea of “a kingdom of ends” (ein Reich der Zwecke) , tendingto be promoted by the establishing of “perpetual peace” <strong>on</strong> theface of the earth-demands to be c<strong>on</strong>nected not <strong>on</strong>ly with Kantianethics but also with Kant’s much less sublime political thoughtand, especially, with his disturbing idea of mankind’s “unsociablesociability” (ungesellige Geselligkeit ) , which barely disguises ac<strong>on</strong>siderably c<strong>on</strong>flictual visi<strong>on</strong> of history and society. 77Nevertheless, in the remainder of this lecture I will c<strong>on</strong>centrate<strong>on</strong> the ethical aspects of this questi<strong>on</strong> and pass over itspolitical-philosophical <strong>on</strong>es with the sole observati<strong>on</strong> that theimperative of dissidence might allow us to p<strong>on</strong>der the importance,together with the critical legitimacy of which we spoke before,of the critique of legitimacy, that is, of any legitimacy that triesto ignore the c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong> of ends in themselves which that imperativeassigns to human beings. 78Now, moving <strong>on</strong> to the final point, this sec<strong>on</strong>d imperative ofthe Foundati<strong>on</strong> of the Metaphysics of Morals rested, according toKant, <strong>on</strong> the c<strong>on</strong>victi<strong>on</strong>, which he solemnly affirmed in this work,that “man exists as an end in himself” and, as he added in theCritique of Practical Reas<strong>on</strong>, that “he can never be used by any<strong>on</strong>e(not even God) <strong>on</strong>ly as a means, without at the same time being77Kant, Grundlegung der Metaphysik der Sitten, Werke, 4:433ff.; Zum ewigenFrieden; Idee zu einer allgemeinen Gescbichte in welteburgerlicbe Absicht, Werke,8:20ff. On this point see my paper “Habermas en el reino de 10s fines: Variaci<strong>on</strong>essobre un tema kantiano,” in Esplendor y miseria de la ética kantiana, ed. EsperanzaGuisin (Barcel<strong>on</strong>a, 1988), 97-139.78Here see my paper “¿Legithidad critica o critica de la legitimidad?” inElogio del disenso (in preparati<strong>on</strong>),


114 <str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>Tanner</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>Lectures</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>on</strong> <strong>Human</strong> <strong>Values</strong>an end.”79 As I suggested before, our imperative has in somesense a negative character, since - behind its apparent grammaticalaffirmati<strong>on</strong> - it does not actually tell us “just what” we oughtto do but instead what we “ought not to do,” that is, not treatourselves, or any<strong>on</strong>e, solely as an instrument. Kant is definite <strong>on</strong>this point when he affirms that the end that man is, is not <strong>on</strong>e ofthose specific ends that we can decide to achieve with our acti<strong>on</strong>sand that are generally means to achieve other ends, as, for example,well-being or happiness. Man is not an end to be effected.As far as man as an end is c<strong>on</strong>cerned, Kant warns, “end is not tobe thought of here as an end to be effected, but as an independentend and therefore in a purely negative way, that is, as somethingthat should never be acted against.” 80“Ends to be effected,” asspecific ends, are, according to Kant, “<strong>on</strong>ly relative ends.” Andfor this reas<strong>on</strong> they cannot give rise to “practical laws” or morallaws, but at most serve as a basis for “hypothetical imperatives,”such as those dictated by prudent c<strong>on</strong>siderati<strong>on</strong> when we say, “ifwe want to remain healthy, we shall have to follow this or thatmedical advice.” But, according to him, the <strong>on</strong>ly specificallymoral end or “independent end” we have - that is, human beinginvested with “absolute value” - requires no less than a “categoricalimperative” such as ours. 81In this sense, and while therelative ends amount to no more than “subjective ends” such asany of us might attempt to realize, men as ends, that is, “pers<strong>on</strong>s,”Kant calls “objective ends,” as in a famous passage from theFoundati<strong>on</strong> of the Metaphysics of Morals that I cannot help butquote:Those beings whose existence does not depend <strong>on</strong> our will,but <strong>on</strong> nature, have, in the case of irrati<strong>on</strong>al beings, a merelyrelative value, as ends, and for that reas<strong>on</strong> are called things;79 Kant, Grundlegung, 428; Kant, Kritik der praktischen Vernunft, Werke,5:132.80 Kant, Grundlegung, 437.81Ibid., 439ff.


[MUGUERZA] <str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g> Alternative of Dissent 115by c<strong>on</strong>trast, rati<strong>on</strong>al beings are called pers<strong>on</strong>s because theirnature already distinguishes them as ends in themselves, thatis, as something that cannot be used merely as a means andwhich, thereby, checks any caprice (and is an object of respect).<str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g> latter are not, therefore, mere subjective ends,whose existence, as an effect of our acti<strong>on</strong>, has a value for us,but are objective ends, that is, things whose existence is initself an end.” 82This is why, Kant adds in another equally famous passage fromthe same work, man has “dignity” instead of a “price”: “Whatc<strong>on</strong>stitutes the c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong> that makes something an end in itself,has not merely a relative value or price, but instead an intrinsicvalue, that is, dignity.” 83<str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g>se are indeed moving words, butwhy should every<strong>on</strong>e accept Kant’s proclaiming that man exists asan end in himself?That this is not self-evident is proven, to give a single counterexample,by the difficulty of arguing in favor of Kant’s asserti<strong>on</strong>oreven understanding it - that those would have who hold thatrati<strong>on</strong>ality can <strong>on</strong>ly be instrumental reas<strong>on</strong>, that is, a reas<strong>on</strong>capable of c<strong>on</strong>cerning itself <strong>on</strong>ly with making the “means” adequateto the “ends” pursued by human acti<strong>on</strong>, and incapable ofc<strong>on</strong>cerning itself with “ultimate ends” that do not serve as meansfor achieving other ends. This, of course, renders such reas<strong>on</strong> incapableof assuring that man be an end in himself, a point thatmust never have bothered Heinrich Himmler, inasmuch as in hisbulletins to the SS he emphatically insisted - according to HannahArendt - <strong>on</strong> “the futility of posing questi<strong>on</strong>s about ends in themselves.”84<str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g>oreticians of instrumental rati<strong>on</strong>ality, <strong>on</strong> the otherhand, would c<strong>on</strong>sequently deny that <strong>on</strong>e can speak of a practical82 Ibid., 428.83 Ibid., 434-35.84 Quoted by H. Arendt in <str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g> Origins of Totalitarianism (New York, 1968).I have quoted from the Spanish translati<strong>on</strong> by G. Solana (Los orígines del totalitarismo),3 vols., Madrid, 1982, 3:440, n. 33.


116 <str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>Tanner</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>Lectures</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>on</strong> <strong>Human</strong> <strong>Values</strong>reas<strong>on</strong>, but - if we refuse to accept, as we are free to do, that the“rati<strong>on</strong>ality” of human “praxis” can be reduced to “instrumentalrati<strong>on</strong>ality”- we would at least be authorized to examine thepossibility of arguing in favor of the Kantian asserti<strong>on</strong> that man isan end in himself.In my opini<strong>on</strong>, the author who has most c<strong>on</strong>vincingly advancedthe possibility of this sort of argument is Tugendhat, whenhe c<strong>on</strong>siders it an “empirical fact” - the recogniti<strong>on</strong> of which isaided by the study of the process of socializati<strong>on</strong> - that regardingour lives and those of others we enjoy relati<strong>on</strong>s of mutual esteem(and its opposite), which make us feel that each of us is “<strong>on</strong>eam<strong>on</strong>g many” and subject in this way to a comm<strong>on</strong> morality(unless, that is, we suffer a Lack of moral sense, 85 a state thatTugendhat is inclined to c<strong>on</strong>sider “pathological”) 86 Up<strong>on</strong> sucha fact <strong>on</strong>e could go <strong>on</strong> to build a “morality of mutual respect,”a morality Tugendhat feels, in my opini<strong>on</strong> correctly, to be the“basic nucleus” of all other morality. This does not mean thatevery morality must needs be restricted to this nucleus, since evenKant’s own ethics - especially in c<strong>on</strong>necti<strong>on</strong> with his idea of the“supreme good” - could be derived from sources other than“respect.” 87But it certainly would be significant if the moralityof mutual respect - according to which the members of a moralcommunity would treat <strong>on</strong>e another as ends - were discoveredas a matter of fact at the base of every morality, which wouldrender it truly universal. 88 And, of course, Tugendhat’s positi<strong>on</strong>represents an advance over all those - this writer included -who have ever felt like c<strong>on</strong>ceding that the Kantian affirmati<strong>on</strong>that man is an end in himself is no more than a “humanitarianitalics.]85 [<str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g> words “lack of moral sense’’ were in English in the original; J.M.’s86 Tugendhat, Probleme der Ethik, 150ff., esp. 154-55, 156ff.87 See Jose G6mez Caffarena, “Respeto y Utopia: ¿Dos fuentes de la moralkantiana? “Pensamiento 34 (1978): 259–76.88 Tugendhat, Probleme der Ethik, 163–64.


[MUGUERZA] <str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g> Alternative of Dissent 117superstiti<strong>on</strong>,” albeit a fundamental <strong>on</strong>e if we are to go <strong>on</strong> speakingof ethics. 89Still, has Tugendhat really managed to c<strong>on</strong>vince us? Howeverc<strong>on</strong>vincing his thesis, and it does have c<strong>on</strong>siderable force,he himself would say it was doubtful that it could c<strong>on</strong>vince any<strong>on</strong>ewho lacked moral sensibility, since with such a pers<strong>on</strong>, he c<strong>on</strong>fesses,“discussi<strong>on</strong> would be impossible.” 90 But if, as indeed isthe case, it is a questi<strong>on</strong> of discussing or arguing, this is preciselythe case where discussi<strong>on</strong> ought to be most relevant.In my view, Tugendhat’s reas<strong>on</strong>ing unfolds in such a way thatthe imperative of dissidence would have to presuppose the principleof universalizati<strong>on</strong>, since this lies at the root of his c<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong>of the morality of mutual respect, valid at the same time for<strong>on</strong>e and all. But perhaps this presuppositi<strong>on</strong> is not indispensable,since the imperative of dissidence could in principle hold <strong>on</strong>ly for<strong>on</strong>e pers<strong>on</strong>, that is, for the dissenter who upheld the morality ofmutual respect, understood as a resoluti<strong>on</strong> never to tolerate beingtreated, nor c<strong>on</strong>sequently ever treat any<strong>on</strong>e, merely as a means,that is, as a mere instrument (where the resolve “never to toleratebeing treated merely as a means” would in some way claim a priusover the c<strong>on</strong>sequent resolve “not ever to treat any<strong>on</strong>e merely as ameans,” that is, it would be prior to the reciprocity and not <strong>on</strong>lythe principle of universalizati<strong>on</strong>). Naturally, from what I havesaid it is clear that ethical individualism is not the same as animpossible ethical solipsism and is obligated to entertain the questi<strong>on</strong>of what happens to the other individuals.But before returning to this point, and to clarify what I meanto understand by “individual,” I will indulge in a brief detourthrough John Rawls’s “Justice as Fairness: Political Not Meta-89 <str<strong>on</strong>g>Muguerza</str<strong>on</strong>g>, “Habermas en el reino, de losfines,’’ 126–28.90 Tugendhat, Probleme der Ethik, 155: “Wenn das Individuum, . . . dieMoral, und das heisst die moralische Sankti<strong>on</strong> überhaupt, in dem Sinn in Zweifelstellt, dass es fur diese Sankti<strong>on</strong> kein Sensorium hat, lässt sich nicht argumentieren”(italics mine).


118 <str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>Tanner</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>Lectures</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>on</strong> <strong>Human</strong> <strong>Values</strong>physical” (1985), where - in explaining the ultimate sense ofhis “theory of justice” - Rawls specifies, in passing, the ultimate,or near ultimate, sense of his own individualism. 91 With agreat deal more clarity than in the essay by Habermas that I quotedfrom earlier, Rawls begins by pointing out that his proceduralc<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong> refers <strong>on</strong>ly to our present democratic societies and inthis light we are to interpret the c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong> of the c<strong>on</strong>tractualpartners (that is, “free and equal subjects”) in his mental experimentc<strong>on</strong>cerning the original positi<strong>on</strong>. (With or without the “veilof ignorance,” they are the citizens whom we daily meet and whotake part in our day-to-day political life, in additi<strong>on</strong>, of course, topers<strong>on</strong>ifying the “liberal political doctrine.”) 92 And this is whyRawls’s c<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong> of the individual or the pers<strong>on</strong> needs no morethan the overlapping c<strong>on</strong>sensus 93which, in a society that is pluralisticas to religious beliefs and ideology in general, allows thecitizens to agree <strong>on</strong> certain “basic principles of justice.” Moreoverhe is saved from having to c<strong>on</strong>template - as Rawls himselfexplicitly admits - any “str<strong>on</strong>ger” c<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong>s of the “subject,”such as the Kantian <strong>on</strong>e. 94As Rawls himself acknowledges, “when [in his theory ofjustice] we simulate being in the original positi<strong>on</strong>, our reas<strong>on</strong>ingno more commits us to a metaphysical doctrine about the nature ofthe self than our playing a game like M<strong>on</strong>opoly commits us tothink that we are landlords engaged in a desperate rivalry, winnertake all.” 95We may be, then, the same in real life as in the originalRawlsian positi<strong>on</strong>, just as Saul of Tarsus remained in some sense91 J. Rawls, “Justice as Fairness: Political Not Metaphysical,” Philosophy andPublic Affairs 14 (1985) : 223-51.italics.]92 Rawls, “Justice as Fairness,” 231ff.93 [<str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g> words “overlapping c<strong>on</strong>sensus” were in English in the original; J.M.’s94 Ibid., 245ff.95 Ibid., 239.


[MUGUERZA] <str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g> Alternative of Dissent 119“the same” when he became the apostle Paul <strong>on</strong> the road toDamascus. But it is more likely that in real life <strong>on</strong>e feels lessequal and less free than in Rawls’s mental experiment. And, bethat as it may, it still seems reas<strong>on</strong>able to say that, after all, a littledaily “metaphysics” keeps the doctor away.Of course, I have no intenti<strong>on</strong> here of reviving the Kantiandoctrine of the two kingdoms, the empirical or phenomenal andthe moral or noumenal <strong>on</strong>es. But <strong>on</strong>e could still maintain that the“moral subject” and the “empirical subject” are not completelycoextensive. Of course, with this we are not saying that the moralsubject and the empirical subject are actually distinct, but ratherthat the first <strong>on</strong>e is the integral subject, but a subject that is farfrom being reducible to just its empirical manifestati<strong>on</strong>s. Forexample, even the most hardened criminal could never be reducedto his observable c<strong>on</strong>duct, since the latter does not allow us toscrutinize his most secret motivati<strong>on</strong>s and intenti<strong>on</strong>s, and this factis a powerful reas<strong>on</strong> never to cease treating him as a moral subject,which is like saying, as “an end in himself.” Another example:as empirical subjects we humans are different as to talent, strength,beauty, and so <strong>on</strong>, but n<strong>on</strong>e of that keeps us from c<strong>on</strong>sidering ourselves“equals” as moral subjects. Just as, to give a final example,the fact that we, as empirical subjects, may have to suffer a wholeset of natural or sociohistorical c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s does not allow us to saythat we are thus kept from being “free,” unless at the same timewe renounce our status as moral subjects. Our self-c<strong>on</strong>sciousnessand our self-determinati<strong>on</strong> as an indissoluble unit are derived fromthat moral subjectivity which seems to be the seat of “humandignity,” that is, what makes us “subjects” and not “objects.” 9696 <str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g> thesis of the indissolubility of “self-c<strong>on</strong>sciousness” and “self-determinati<strong>on</strong>”has been brilliantly defended by Tugendhat in his study Selbstbewusstsein undSelbstbestimmung (Frankfurt am Main, 1979). As Tugendhat points out, AndreasWildt - in Aut<strong>on</strong>omie und Anerkennung (Stuttgart, 1982) -was the first to givehis c<strong>on</strong>siderati<strong>on</strong>s an explicitly moral-theoretical meaning, an interpretati<strong>on</strong> UrsulaWolf also stresses (Das Probleme das moralisches Sollens), and in his turn, he hasdeveloped this point in his Probleme der Ethik, 137ff., discussing the thesis of


120 <str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>Tanner</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>Lectures</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>on</strong> <strong>Human</strong> <strong>Values</strong>Perhaps today it is difficult to accept the idea that the moral subjectand the empirical subject do not entirely coincide, but theimpossibility of reducing the subject to its manifest properties wasat least part of what the Greeks meant when they termed the subjecthypokeimen<strong>on</strong>. 97<str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g> moral subject exemplifies par excellencethe subject understood in this way, and this is also the reas<strong>on</strong> forthe distance separating the moral subject from the so-called “subjectof rights” (sujeto de derechos), which is, am<strong>on</strong>g others, avariety of the empirical subject. For the rest, not all subjects ofrights are moral subjects, since a moral subject is always an individual,while the subjects of rights might well be “impers<strong>on</strong>alsubjects,” such as collective bodies or instituti<strong>on</strong>s, from a businessall the way to the state itself. And even when, by analogy withmoral subjects, we allow <strong>on</strong>e of these impers<strong>on</strong>al subjects such asa social class or a nati<strong>on</strong> the capacity for “self-c<strong>on</strong>sciousness” andfor “self-determinati<strong>on</strong>,” we must not forget that in any case bothdepend <strong>on</strong> the self-c<strong>on</strong>sciousness and self-determinati<strong>on</strong> of thecorresp<strong>on</strong>ding individuals. Now then, moral subjects can, and infact do, aspire to recogniti<strong>on</strong> as subjects of rights. And of thoseaspirati<strong>on</strong>s <strong>on</strong>e of the most fundamental is the aspirati<strong>on</strong> to recogniti<strong>on</strong>as “subjects of human rights.” In a certain sense, this wouldbe the first human right and even the quintessence of any otherhuman right; in other words, the right to be a subject of rights.But to the questi<strong>on</strong> of who or what would c<strong>on</strong>cede them thisright, prior to any possible recogniti<strong>on</strong> of rights, I would answerthat nothing and no <strong>on</strong>e has to c<strong>on</strong>cede it to a moral subject infull command of his faculties but that it must be the subject him-“morality” as a necessary c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong> for the “(practical) identity of the self.” Forsuch an interpretati<strong>on</strong> of Kant’s idea of man as “an end in himself,” see my“Habermas en el reino, de losfines,” 123ff.97 In a somewhat similar vein, Tugendhat speaks of a pers<strong>on</strong>’s “being <strong>on</strong>eself”(Selbstsein), which he identifies with <strong>on</strong>e’s “existence” (Existenz), as a “quasiproperty”( Quasi-Eigenschaft), which according to him has to do - rather thanwith a substantial property that is different from the accidental <strong>on</strong>es -with theKantian noti<strong>on</strong> of “end in itself.”


[MUGUERZA] <str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g> Alternative of Dissent 121self who appropriates it by affirming his c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong> as human being.“I am a man,” said the signs carried by the followers of MartinLuther King. And how could <strong>on</strong>e deny the human c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong> tosome<strong>on</strong>e who asserts that he has it, even if for the present it isnot recognized in law.<str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g> denial of this c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>, that is, the reducti<strong>on</strong> of a subjectto an object, was what Marx, the critic of the ideology of humanrights, called “alienati<strong>on</strong>,” and the struggle for human rights -be it said in his h<strong>on</strong>or - is, ir<strong>on</strong>ically, nothing but the struggleagainst the multiple forms of alienati<strong>on</strong> that man has known andsuffered.To this end, the subject must begin by being c<strong>on</strong>sciously asubject, that is, by unalienating itself. Or, in the words of thelater Foucault, by freeing itself of the “subjecti<strong>on</strong>” that keeps <strong>on</strong>efrom being a subject or imposes <strong>on</strong> <strong>on</strong>e an unwanted subjectivity. 98No subject can aspire to be recognized as a subject of rights unlesshe or she is first of all a subject plain and simple - which means,am<strong>on</strong>g other things, being a moral subject. For this reas<strong>on</strong> Rousseaucorrectly saw that the prior theory of the social c<strong>on</strong>tract wasc<strong>on</strong>tradictory, in allowing for the possibility of a pacturn subjecti<strong>on</strong>is,since no subject could rightfully renounce being a subjectthrough any kind of legal agreement. 99But, in additi<strong>on</strong>, thereare many other “states” of subjecti<strong>on</strong>, very different from thosecharacterized by Jellinek with that technical expressi<strong>on</strong>. 100And inthe grip of all of them, subjects, just as they find occasi<strong>on</strong>s tostruggle against alienati<strong>on</strong>, will also find occasi<strong>on</strong>s to exercisedissent.98 Michel Foucault, “Why Study Power: <str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g> Questi<strong>on</strong> of the Subject,” in hisafterword, “<str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g> Subject and Power,” to Hubert L. Dreyfus and Paul Rabinow,Michel Foucault: Bey<strong>on</strong>d Structuralism and Hermeneutics (Chicago, 1982), 208-26.99 Rousseau, Du c<strong>on</strong>trat social, 359, 432-33.100 Georg Jellinek, System der subjektiuen öffentlichen Rechte, 2d ed. (1919;repr., Aalen, 1964); for his four-part classificati<strong>on</strong> of the status of Public Law -status subiecti<strong>on</strong>is or pasivusstatus libertatis or negativus, status civitatis or positivus,status activae civitatis or activus - see 81ff.


122 <str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>Tanner</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>Lectures</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>on</strong> <strong>Human</strong> <strong>Values</strong>And what is even more important, they will discover occasi<strong>on</strong>sto exercise this dissent, not <strong>on</strong>ly by and for themselves, but by andfor other moral subjects, inasmuch as the imperative of dissidence- which did not need to presuppose the principle of universalizati<strong>on</strong>- is capable, in c<strong>on</strong>trast, of incorporating it intoitself. Sartre’s versi<strong>on</strong> of this last principle read, “when I choose,I choose for all mankind,” since individual acts already carrywithin them a potential universality (l’act individuel engage toutel'humanité). 101But equally when I dissent I can dissent for allmankind, even for those who cannot dissent, either because theyare biologically or psychologically unable to do so (as with childrenor mental patients, for example), or because they are unableto do so for sociopolitical reas<strong>on</strong>s (that is, because they suffer astate of subjecti<strong>on</strong> that at the moment cannot be removed). 102And, of course, when I dissent I can, by the same token, dissentwith others (but without such dissensi<strong>on</strong> causing us to lose sightof the fact that, although often exercised by “groups of individuals,”it is still exercised by “groups of indiuiduals”). 103 <str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g>dissenter is always an individual subject and-no matter howmuch solidarity there is in his decisi<strong>on</strong> to dissent - his dissidenceis ultimately solitary, that is to say, the result of a decisi<strong>on</strong> takenin the solitude of an individual c<strong>on</strong>science.If we now correlate the categories of moral and empirical subjectswith those of ends and means, c<strong>on</strong>sidered before, we could101 Jean-Paul Sartre, L’existencialisme est un humanisme (Paris, 1946), 17ff.102 Despite the “negativeness” of dissent, we must not forget that it too may bethreatened by the shadow of “paternalism” and no <strong>on</strong>e ought “to be forced todissent” anymore than they should be forced to c<strong>on</strong>sent (for an examinati<strong>on</strong> ofpaternalism, see Paternalism, ed. Rolf Sartorius (Minneapolis, 1983) and ErnestoGarz<strong>on</strong>ValdCs, “¿Es éticamente justificable el paternalismo?” in Actas del I IEncuentro Hispano-Mexican0 de Filosofía (Filosofia Moral y Political, ed. J. A.Gimbernat and J. M. G<strong>on</strong>zález García (Madrid, in press).103 In any case, ethical individualism, not to be c<strong>on</strong>fused with the so-called“methodological individualism,” vindicates <strong>on</strong>ly the aut<strong>on</strong>omy of the moral subjectand not its autarchy (for the difference, see Domingo Blanco, “Aut<strong>on</strong>omia yautarquia,” in Kant después de Kant, and also my paper “¿Qué es el individualismoetico?" in EIogio del disenso).


[MUGUEFZA] <str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g> Alternative of Dissent 123say that-unlike a means, which in a certain sense is of measurablemagnitude (for example, in terms of “instrumentalefficiency”) - an end in itself, that is, a moral subject, admitsno such “comparative measurability.” Like Aristotle’s substance -with which, nevertheless, it must not be c<strong>on</strong>fused, since for themoral subject perpetually in fieri <strong>on</strong>e would have to say that “thesubject is not substance” - subjectivity does not admit of degreesand <strong>on</strong>e could perfectly well say that all subjects have the sameimport as to their moral demands of dignity, liberty, and equalityand, in general, as to their aspirati<strong>on</strong>s to be subjects of rights.In this way, any human right could be accessible to any subject,with the proviso that in being accessible to <strong>on</strong>e subject it wouldbe no less so for all the others. For, as far as those rights are c<strong>on</strong>cerned,there is a sort of principle of U-tubes that, so to say, levelsthe legal statas of the subjects - at least potentially. <str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g> popularsaying “No <strong>on</strong>e is any more a pers<strong>on</strong> than any<strong>on</strong>e else” has sometimesbeen presented as the fruit of an objecti<strong>on</strong>able attitude ofresentment that rejects all excellence, but the meaning of that sayingcould perhaps be made clearer by saying, “No <strong>on</strong>e is any lessa pers<strong>on</strong> than any<strong>on</strong>e else,” if human beings are taken as endsin themselves.By way of c<strong>on</strong>cluding, it might be well to recall that forBentham speculati<strong>on</strong> about the foundati<strong>on</strong> of human rights wasnothing but a string of anarchical fal1acies. 104 As far as my specuti<strong>on</strong>sare c<strong>on</strong>cerned, I would like to think that they cannot berefuted as “fallacious,” but I realize they are somewhat “anarchic,”at least in the etymological sense of this sec<strong>on</strong>d adjective. For,in truth, to entrust the grounding of those rights to the individualis in a way to bet <strong>on</strong> behalf of an-archy, at least to the degree that104 In Bentham’s favor, it must be said that he was more careful in his disqualificati<strong>on</strong>of such speculati<strong>on</strong>s as “fallacies” than, in our own day, was AlasdairMacIntyre, After Viriue (Notre Dame, 1984), when he maintains that humanrights “do not exist and to believe in them is like believing in witches and unicorns,”a statement that will disturb <strong>on</strong>ly those who insist <strong>on</strong> defending these rightsfrom a positi<strong>on</strong> akin to ethical cognitivism.


124 <str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>Tanner</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>Lectures</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>on</strong> <strong>Human</strong> <strong>Values</strong>ethical individualism lies at the opposite pole from any ethicalfundamentalism. 105In c<strong>on</strong>sequence, I do not believe any jusnaturalist will be preparedto assume a positi<strong>on</strong> such as this, which I would like to seego by the name of “ethical individualism.” But, just in case any<strong>on</strong>eshould try to lay it <strong>on</strong> that sort of Procrustean bed, I willsimply offer <strong>on</strong>e argument or, better still, counterargument. I havebeen asked <strong>on</strong> occasi<strong>on</strong> if, for example, what I call the “imperativeof dissidence” would not, in the end, be similar to the traditi<strong>on</strong>alright of resistance. 106My answer is a categorical no. Ashas been pointed out more than <strong>on</strong>ce, and in a magisterial way byProfessor Felipe G<strong>on</strong>zález Vicén, l07 the so-called “right of resistance”is a fairy tale created by jusnaturalism. To be precise,it was invented by the latter as the sole recourse, the sole naturalright, capable of opposing the natural right to oppress that jusnaturalismitself awarded to those in power. As such, G<strong>on</strong>zálezVicén has quite correctly termed it “a juridical m<strong>on</strong>ster” and hascalled attenti<strong>on</strong> to Kant’s perspicacity in rejecting it as though itwere a c<strong>on</strong>tradictio in adiecto.108 But <strong>on</strong>e should add that for105On the late Foucaultian “subject,” Reiner Schiirmann, “Se c<strong>on</strong>stituer soimemecomme sujet anarchique,” Etudes philosophiques, October-December 1986,451-71, speaks of an “an-archic” subject in a sense of “anarchy” similar to the <strong>on</strong>ewe have used, since the former would have to be the builder of the different “formsof subjectivity” (or “subject situati<strong>on</strong>s”) that in each case c<strong>on</strong>stitute it.106 See Eusebio Fernández, La obediencia a1 Derecho (Madrid: Ed. Civitas,1987), 109-15, as well as my paper “Sobre el exceso de obediencia y otros excesos,”in Actas de las X Jornadas de Filosofía Jurídica y Social.107See F. G<strong>on</strong>zález Vicén, “Kant y el derecho de resistencia,” in Kant despuísde Kant, where his approach to the problem of the right of resistance - with whichhe also dealt in chapter 5 of his early Teoría de la revolución (Valladolid, 1932) -echoes the views from his m<strong>on</strong>ograph La filosofia del estado en Kant (La Laguna,1952), included as part of his De Kant a Marx (Valencia, 1984). In my opini<strong>on</strong>,G<strong>on</strong>zalez Vicén’s interpretati<strong>on</strong> competes to its advantage with other interpretati<strong>on</strong>sof Kant’s attitude to this supposed right. See, to give <strong>on</strong>ly three examples of differentapproaches, Robert Spaemann, “Kants Kritik des Widerstandsrechts,” andDieter Heinrich, “Kant über die Revoluti<strong>on</strong>,” both in Batscha, Materialien zu KantsRechtsphilosophie, 347-58, 359–65, as well as Hans Reiss, “Kant and the Right ofRebelli<strong>on</strong>,” Journal of the History of ldeas 17 (1956).105 G<strong>on</strong>zilez Vicen, La filosofía del estado en Kant, 92ff.


[MUGUERZA] <str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g> Alternative of Dissent 125Kant the rejecti<strong>on</strong> of the right to resistance was perfectly compatiblewith the positive, even enthusiastic, value he placed <strong>on</strong> thepolitical revoluti<strong>on</strong>s of his day, from the American Revoluti<strong>on</strong> tothe French Revoluti<strong>on</strong> or the Irish Rebelli<strong>on</strong>. From my point ofview, which I would not dare attribute either to Kant or to G<strong>on</strong>zálezVicén, what the dissenter ought to do when faced with alegally unjust situati<strong>on</strong>, with “unjust law,” is not to invoke someright to resist but simply to resist.<str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g> renaissance of jusnaturalism following the Sec<strong>on</strong>d WorldWar was due largely to the argumentum ad hominem - or to thereductio ad Hitlerum, as it has also been called - used by partisansof the former against juspositivism, an argument accordingto which the m<strong>on</strong>strous outrage against human rights of the Naziregime was the fault of legal positivism. 109But as Ernesto Garzón Valdés has recently reminded us, jusnaturalism- take the by no means unusual case of Hans HelmuthDietze’s Naturrecht der Gegenwart - was not far behind juspositivismin serving as a legitimizing ideological cover for Nazism. 110And, of what use, in the face of so much abject submissi<strong>on</strong> to theestablished order, would it have been to invoke any right of resistance?In c<strong>on</strong>trast to such empty invocati<strong>on</strong>s, an authenticresister like the Protestant theologian Dietrich B<strong>on</strong>hoeffer - impris<strong>on</strong>edand finally hanged for participating in the c<strong>on</strong>spiracyleading to the attempt <strong>on</strong> Hitler’s life <strong>on</strong> July 20, 1944 - simplyinvoked, as we read in his Ethics, “the voice of c<strong>on</strong>science,” that109 See in this regard the book by E. Garzón Valdés, Derecho y “naturaleza delas cosas” (Análisis de una nueua versión del derecho natural en el pensamientojuridico alemán c<strong>on</strong>temporáneo), 2 vols. (Cordoba [Argentina], 1970-71).110 See the previous work and his resp<strong>on</strong>se to the poll by Doxa 1 (1985),“Problemas abiertos en la Filosofía del Derecho,” 95-97, where he writes: “Becauseof my Kelsenian formati<strong>on</strong>, I was not a little disturbed by the severe accusati<strong>on</strong>sthat were leveled at legal positivism (in the post-War era), . . . which was virtuallyheld resp<strong>on</strong>sible for the establishment of Nati<strong>on</strong>al Socialism. . . . <str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g> discovery ofH. H. Dietze’s book (B<strong>on</strong>n, 1936) . . . put an end to that turn of events, since itwas clear proof of the ideological importance of jusnaturalism in the justificati<strong>on</strong>of the regime in power in Germany from 1933 to 1945.”


126 <str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>Tanner</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>Lectures</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>on</strong> <strong>Human</strong> <strong>Values</strong>is, “a voice that, originating at a depth well bey<strong>on</strong>d <strong>on</strong>e’s ownwill and <strong>on</strong>e’s own reas<strong>on</strong>, calls human existence to a unity withitself.” 111Unfortunately for me - although, given the proporti<strong>on</strong>s thislecture is assuming, I am not sure I may include the reader here -I have time to menti<strong>on</strong> <strong>on</strong>ly a few points that might be developedas corollary paths leading off from what we have seen thus far.<str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g> first is c<strong>on</strong>nected with the curious fact that the distincti<strong>on</strong> -c<strong>on</strong>ceptual, not real, but more or less metaphysical (in the sense,at least, of a “moral metaphysics”) -between moral and empiricalsubjects demands rather than excludes an empirical investigati<strong>on</strong>(to be undertaken, for example, by the social sciences) intohow dissidence in fact arises and how it might serve to reduce thedistance between the two subjects and, especially, the moral subjectand the subject of rights. <str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g> sociologist Barringt<strong>on</strong> Moore hassuggested a directi<strong>on</strong> this investigati<strong>on</strong> might take, in a book—written at the same time as Rawls’s <str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g>ory of Justice, which theauthor declined to read in manuscript so as to avoid “c<strong>on</strong>taminating”the writing of his own text - titled, significantly, Injustice:<str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g> Social Basis of Obedience and Revolt. 112 What is decisive inexplaining the origin and the effects of dissidence (quite a differentmatter from its justificati<strong>on</strong>, which would be the job ofethics) is not, according to Moore, the Rawlsian “sense of justice,”111 D. B<strong>on</strong>hoeffer, Ethik (Munich, 1949), 257. To be fair to B<strong>on</strong>hoeffer, <strong>on</strong>eshould point out that, as a good theologian, he further takes into account “thegreat transformati<strong>on</strong> [that] takes place at the moment when the unity of humanc<strong>on</strong>science no l<strong>on</strong>ger c<strong>on</strong>sists in its aut<strong>on</strong>omy, but rather, thanks to the miracle offaith, is discovered bey<strong>on</strong>d the Self and its law, in Jesus Christ” (see Tiemo RainerPeters, Die Prasenz des Politischen in der <str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g>ologie Dietrich B<strong>on</strong>hoeffers [Munich,1976], 6lff.). But, he adds, for just that reas<strong>on</strong> (B<strong>on</strong>hoeffer, Ethik, 258–59):“When Nati<strong>on</strong>al Socialism says that the Führer is my c<strong>on</strong>science, it is an attemptto ground the unity of the Self bey<strong>on</strong>d itself. This has as c<strong>on</strong>sequence a loss ofaut<strong>on</strong>omy in favor of an absolute heter<strong>on</strong>omy, which in turn is <strong>on</strong>ly possible if theother man in whom I seek the unity of my life serves as my redeemer. This wouldbe the closest secular parallel as well as the most blatant c<strong>on</strong>tradicti<strong>on</strong> with Christiantruth.”112 B. Moore, Jr., Injustice (New York, 1978).


[MUGUERZA] <str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g> Alternative of Dissent 127but a “sense of injustice,” which undoubtedly corresp<strong>on</strong>ds toanother c<strong>on</strong>stellati<strong>on</strong> in the phenomenology of moral life. <str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g>sec<strong>on</strong>d point has to do with the problem of “civil disobedience,”which ought perhaps to be treated as a secti<strong>on</strong> or chapter of dissidencein general. As Jorge Malem maintains in his excellentstudy, C<strong>on</strong>cept and Justificati<strong>on</strong> of Civil Disobedience, it has beennormal from Hugo Adam Bedau forward (as in the case, forexample, of Peter Singer’s Democrucy and Disobedience) to c<strong>on</strong>sidercivil disobedience as a group of c<strong>on</strong>scious, public, n<strong>on</strong>violent,and illegal acts carried out with the intenti<strong>on</strong> of frustrating thelaws, programs, or decisi<strong>on</strong>s of a government, while accepting (atleast within the c<strong>on</strong>text of a representative democratic society)the current c<strong>on</strong>stituti<strong>on</strong>al order.113 <str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g> drawback of this kind ofcharacterizati<strong>on</strong> of civil disobedience is that it leaves somewhat inthe dark the relati<strong>on</strong> between this and other forms of disobedience- from “ethical disobedience of the law” to “revoluti<strong>on</strong>arydisobedience” - not forgetting that what we call “democracy”in our present democratic societies has not always existed nor canit be said to exist today in countries like South Africa where civildisobedience is practiced. And, what is even more serious, wecannot even be certain that this democracy will survive in a “totallyadministered world,” to use Horkheimer’s terrifying expressi<strong>on</strong>,toward which we are most probably headed and in which disobediencewill be - in any of its now known, or future, guises -more necessary than ever. But, as I said, we cannot treat thesethemes, which bel<strong>on</strong>g in their own right to an ethics of resistancethat has still to be written for our times.I cannot help but pause, however briefly, over a third and finalcorollary, with which I would like to close. <str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g> main moral, if<strong>on</strong>e may speak of a moral, that might perhaps be derived from113 In additi<strong>on</strong> to the text by J. Malem (Barcel<strong>on</strong>a: in press), see those ofH. A. Bedau, Civil Disobedience: <str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g>ory and Practice (New York, 1969) andP. Singer (Oxford, 1973), as well as the study by J. A. Estévez Araujo, “El sentidode la desobediencia civil,’’ in Filosofía Política, ed. J. M. G<strong>on</strong>zález García andF. Quesada, a special issue of Arbor 503–4 (1987): 129-38.


128 <str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>Tanner</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>Lectures</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>on</strong> <strong>Human</strong> <strong>Values</strong>these hasty reflecti<strong>on</strong>s <strong>on</strong> the imperative of dissidence - the imperative,please remember, that prescribes that we say no to theunjust law (or at least authorizes us to do so), no matter howmuch c<strong>on</strong>sensus lies behind it - would have to be that we are allthe protag<strong>on</strong>ists of the life of the law or at least should be. Toparody a very famous thesis, <strong>on</strong>e might say that the jusphilosophershave thus far <strong>on</strong>ly theorized about human rights (which,by the way, is the <strong>on</strong>ly thing they could do and should keep <strong>on</strong>doing). But it is the task of every human being as human being(and not <strong>on</strong>ly of jurists, whether jusphilosophers or not) to fightfor the juridical realizati<strong>on</strong> of those demands of dignity, liberty,and equality that make each human being a human being. Justas it is the task of every<strong>on</strong>e to fight to preserve and protect thosedemands that are already satisfied as rights, keeping them frombeing emptied of meaning, and avoiding their degenerati<strong>on</strong> tomere rhetoric <strong>on</strong>ce they have been incorporated into the corresp<strong>on</strong>dinglegal texts.What remains to be said is <strong>on</strong>ly that this struggle to effectwhat Bloch <strong>on</strong>ce called “justice from beneath” forms an extremelyimportant part of the dissent from the not infrequent inhumanityof the law, which is no less unfortunate and dangerous in its c<strong>on</strong>sequencesthan the absence of any law. (<str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g> above-menti<strong>on</strong>ed“justice from beneath” would be a justice, to borrow from Dworkin’smythology, that ought to be left to the pygmies that wemortals are - the children, like Antaeus, of Mother Earth -and not to an excepti<strong>on</strong>al judge like Hercules, endowed, as hisname suggests, with uncomm<strong>on</strong> faculties.) 114But perhaps it would be best in this regard to let Bloch havethe last word: “Justice, whether retributive or distributive, answers114 Dworkin, Taking Rights Seriously, chap. 4, §§ 5-6 (I c<strong>on</strong>fess that myantipathy for Hercules the judge, always able to come up with the “right answer,”is due in no small measure to his kinship with that old friend the Rati<strong>on</strong>al Chooser(Preferidor Raci<strong>on</strong>al), with whom I was obliged to deal in my book La razón sinesperanza, 2d ed. [Madrid: Ed. Taurus, 1986], 69-100, 227ff.).


[MUGUERZA] <str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g> Alternative of Dissent 129to the formula of the suum cuique, that is, it presupposes the headof the family, the father of his country, who dispenses to all fromabove their share of punishment or of social well-being, earningsand positi<strong>on</strong>. . . . <str<strong>on</strong>g>The</str<strong>on</strong>g> scale that, even in the Zodiac sign of Libra,rises all the way up so as to perform from there, is quite in accordwith this ideal of justice seated <strong>on</strong> thr<strong>on</strong>es. . . . [But] real justice,inasmuch as it is justice from below, usually rebels against suchjustice, against the essential injustice that reserves exclusively foritself the role of justice.” 115115 Bloch, Naturrecht und menschliche Würde, 228-29.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!