11.07.2015 Views

Conceptual Art 1962-1969: From the Aesthetic of Administration to ...

Conceptual Art 1962-1969: From the Aesthetic of Administration to ...

Conceptual Art 1962-1969: From the Aesthetic of Administration to ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

OCTOBERBy contrast, Graham's work argued for an analysis <strong>of</strong> (visual) meaning thatdefined signs as both structurally constituted within <strong>the</strong> relations <strong>of</strong> language'ssystem and grounded in <strong>the</strong> referent <strong>of</strong> social and political experience. Fur<strong>the</strong>r,Graham's dialectical conception <strong>of</strong> visual representation polemically collapsed<strong>the</strong> difference between <strong>the</strong> spaces <strong>of</strong> production and those <strong>of</strong> reproduction (whatSeth Siegelaub would, in <strong>1969</strong>, call primary and secondary information).lg Anticipating<strong>the</strong> work's actual modes <strong>of</strong> distribution and reception within its verystructure <strong>of</strong> production, Homes for America eliminated <strong>the</strong> difference between <strong>the</strong>artistic construct and its (pho<strong>to</strong>graphic) reproduction, <strong>the</strong> difference between anexhibition <strong>of</strong> art objects and <strong>the</strong> pho<strong>to</strong>graph <strong>of</strong> its installation, <strong>the</strong> differencebetween <strong>the</strong> architectural space <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> gallery and <strong>the</strong> space <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> catalogue and<strong>the</strong> art magazine.Joseph Kosuth's Tau<strong>to</strong>logiesIn opposition <strong>to</strong> this, Kosuth was arguing, in <strong>1969</strong>, precisely for <strong>the</strong> continuationand expansion <strong>of</strong> modernism's positivist legacy, and doing so with whatmust have seemed <strong>to</strong> him at <strong>the</strong> time <strong>the</strong> most radical and advanced <strong>to</strong>ols <strong>of</strong> thattradition: Wittgenstein's logical positivism and language philosophy (he emphaticallyaffirmed this continuity when, in <strong>the</strong> first part <strong>of</strong> "<strong>Art</strong> after Philosophy," hestates, "Certainly linguistic philosophy can be considered <strong>the</strong> heir <strong>to</strong> empiricism. . ."). Thus, even while claiming <strong>to</strong> displace <strong>the</strong> formalism <strong>of</strong> Greenberg andFried, he in fact updated modernism's project <strong>of</strong> self-reflexiveness. For Kosuthstabilized <strong>the</strong> notion <strong>of</strong> a disinterested and self-sufficient art by subjecting both-<strong>the</strong> Wittgensteinian model <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> language game as well as <strong>the</strong> Duchampianmodel <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> readymade -<strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong> strictures <strong>of</strong> a model <strong>of</strong> meaning that operatesin <strong>the</strong> modernist tradition <strong>of</strong> that paradox Michel Foucault has called modernity's"empirico-transcendental" thought. This is <strong>to</strong> say that in 1968 artisticproduction is still <strong>the</strong> result, for Kosuth, <strong>of</strong> artistic intention as it constitutes itselfabove all in self-reflexiveness (even if it is now discursive ra<strong>the</strong>r than perceptual,epistemological ra<strong>the</strong>r than essentialist).*O19. "For many years it has been well known that more people are aware <strong>of</strong> an artist's workthrough (1) <strong>the</strong> printed media or (2) conversation than by direct confrontation with <strong>the</strong> art itself. Forpainting and sculpture, where <strong>the</strong> visual presence-color, scale, size, location-is important <strong>to</strong> <strong>the</strong>work, <strong>the</strong> pho<strong>to</strong>graph or verbalization <strong>of</strong> that work is a bastardization <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> art. But when artconcerns itself with things not germane <strong>to</strong> physical presence, its intrinsic (communicative) value is notaltered by its presentation in printed media. The use <strong>of</strong> catalogues and books <strong>to</strong> communicate (anddisseminate) art is <strong>the</strong> most neutral means <strong>to</strong> present <strong>the</strong> new art. The catalogue can now act as <strong>the</strong>primary information for <strong>the</strong> exhibition, as opposed <strong>to</strong> secondary information about art in magazines,catalogues, etc. and in some cases <strong>the</strong> 'exhibition' can be <strong>the</strong> 'catalogue."' (Seth Siegelaub, "OnExhibitions and <strong>the</strong> World at Large" [interview with Charles Harrison], Studio International, [December<strong>1969</strong>1.)20. This differentiation is developed in Hal Foster's excellent discussion <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se paradigmaticdifferences as <strong>the</strong>y emerge first in Minimalism in his essay "The Crux <strong>of</strong> Minimalism," in Individuals(Los Angeles: The Museum <strong>of</strong> Contemporary <strong>Art</strong>, 1986), p. 162- 183.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!