12.07.2015 Views

Language Diversity in the Classroom - ymerleksi - home

Language Diversity in the Classroom - ymerleksi - home

Language Diversity in the Classroom - ymerleksi - home

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS
  • No tags were found...

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

BILINGUAL EDUCATION & BILINGUALISMSeries Editors: Nancy H. Hornberger (University of Pennsylvania,USA) and Col<strong>in</strong> Baker (Bangor University, Wales, UK)<strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong><strong>Classroom</strong>John EdwardsMULTILINGUAL MATTERSBristol • Buffalo • Toronto


For SuzanneLibrary of Congress Catalog<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> Publication DataA catalog record for this book is available from <strong>the</strong> Library of Congress.Edwards, John<strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>/John Edwards.Bil<strong>in</strong>gual Education & Bil<strong>in</strong>gualismIncludes bibliographical references and <strong>in</strong>dex.1. Education, Bil<strong>in</strong>gual–United States. 2. <strong>Language</strong>s <strong>in</strong> contact–United States. 3. Childrenwith social disabilities–Education–United States. 4. English language–Study and teach<strong>in</strong>g–United States–Foreign speakers. 5. Teach<strong>in</strong>g–Social aspects–United States. I. Title.LC3731.E49 2009370.117'50973–dc22 2009033459British Library Catalogu<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> Publication DataA catalogue entry for this book is available from <strong>the</strong> British Library.ISBN-13: 978-1-84769-226-9 (hbk)ISBN-13: 978-1-84769-225-2 (pbk)Multil<strong>in</strong>gual MattersUK: St Nicholas House, 31–34 High Street, Bristol BS1 2AW, UK.USA: UTP, 2250 Military Road, Tonawanda, NY 14150, USA.Canada: UTP, 5201 Duffer<strong>in</strong> Street, North York, Ontario M3H 5T8, Canada.Copyright © 2010 John Edwards.All rights reserved. No part of this work may be reproduced <strong>in</strong> any form or by any meanswithout permission <strong>in</strong> writ<strong>in</strong>g from <strong>the</strong> publisher.The policy of Multil<strong>in</strong>gual Matters/Channel View Publications is to use papers thatare natural, renewable and recyclable products, made from wood grown <strong>in</strong> susta<strong>in</strong>ableforests. In <strong>the</strong> manufactur<strong>in</strong>g process of our books, and to fur<strong>the</strong>r support our policy,preference is given to pr<strong>in</strong>ters that have FSC and PEFC Cha<strong>in</strong> of Custody certification.The FSC and/or PEFC logos will appear on those books where full certification has beengranted to <strong>the</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>ter concerned.Typeset by Datapage International Ltd.Pr<strong>in</strong>ted and bound <strong>in</strong> Great Brita<strong>in</strong> by <strong>the</strong> Cromwell Press Group.


ContentsChapter 1 Introduction. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1A Brief Rationale . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1Sympa<strong>the</strong>tic Voices. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 3This Book . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 9A F<strong>in</strong>al Introductory Note . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 22Chapter 2 Discourse Analysis and its Discontents . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 24Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 24Discourse Difficulties . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 28Chapter 3 Disadvantage: A Brief Overview . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 40Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 40Disadvantage and Poverty . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 46Chapter 4 Disadvantage: The Genetic Case . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 52Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 52The Genetic Case for Disadvantage . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 55Chapter 5 Disadvantage: The Environmental Case. . . . . . . . . . . . . . 77Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 77Environmental Deficiency . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 78Environmental Difference. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 82Compensatory Intervention? . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 84A Forensic Post-script . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 88Chapter 6 The <strong>Language</strong> Debate . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 93Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 93Deficient <strong>Language</strong> . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 95Different <strong>Language</strong>. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 109The Views of Teachers . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 118Read<strong>in</strong>g Matters . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 120v


vi<strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>Chapter 7 The Persistence of L<strong>in</strong>guistic Deficit . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 126Theoretical Extensions . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 126Empirical Excursions . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 139Chapter 8 Evaluative Reactions to <strong>the</strong> <strong>Language</strong>of Disadvantage . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 146<strong>Language</strong> Attitudes and <strong>the</strong> M<strong>in</strong>ority-group Reaction . . . . . . . . . 146<strong>Language</strong> Attitudes and Group Solidarity . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 149Gender Matters . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 154Teachers’ Views of ‘Disadvantaged’ <strong>Language</strong> . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 157Fur<strong>the</strong>r Ref<strong>in</strong>ements <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Study of ‘Disadvantaged’<strong>Language</strong> . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 160Chapter 9 Black English as Ebonics . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 170Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 170Ebonics. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 172Reactions to <strong>the</strong> Ebonics Debate and to BlackUnderachievement . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 179Chapter 10 ‘Foreign’ <strong>Language</strong>s <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong> . . . . . . . . . . . . . 186Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 186<strong>Language</strong> Learn<strong>in</strong>g and <strong>Language</strong> Attitudes <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong><strong>Classroom</strong> . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 189<strong>Language</strong> and ‘Empowerment’. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 195Heritage <strong>Language</strong>s <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong> . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 200Chapter 11 Multiculturalism and Multicultural Education ......206Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 206Unity and <strong>Diversity</strong> . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 208Multiculturalism <strong>in</strong> Education . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 220Strong and Weak Multiculturalism . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 226Chapter 12 Bil<strong>in</strong>gualism: A Very Brief Overview . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 234Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 234Def<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g Bil<strong>in</strong>gualism. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 234Becom<strong>in</strong>g Bil<strong>in</strong>gual . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 238Bil<strong>in</strong>gualism and Identity . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 243


ContentsviiChapter 13 Bil<strong>in</strong>gual Education . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 250Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 250Varieties of Bil<strong>in</strong>gual Education . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 252The Effectiveness of Bil<strong>in</strong>gual Education . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 258Bil<strong>in</strong>gual Education <strong>in</strong> America: In Transit to Trouble . . . . . . . . . 264Education and Politics . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 272Chapter 14 A Conclud<strong>in</strong>g Statement . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 279References . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 289Index . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 335


Chapter 1IntroductionL’école est un curieux lieu de langage. Il s’y mélange les languesofficielle, privée, scolaire, des langues maternelles, des languesétrangères, de l’argot de lycéen, de l’argot de la cité. Àconsidérertoutes ces langues qui cohabitent, je me dis que l’école est peut-être leseul lieu où elles peuvent se retrouver dans leur diversité et dansleurs chevauchements. Mais il faut être très vigilants et justement tirerpartie de cette belle hétérogénéité. (Ste<strong>in</strong>er & Ladjali, 2003: 8384)A Brief RationaleAmong my o<strong>the</strong>r academic activities and duties, I have been giv<strong>in</strong>gtalks to teachers and teachers’ organizations s<strong>in</strong>ce <strong>the</strong> early 1970s. Thesehave typically dealt with <strong>the</strong> po<strong>in</strong>ts of <strong>in</strong>tersection among education,social class, ethnol<strong>in</strong>guistic status and group identity. Such topics, withall <strong>the</strong>ir many ramifications, have always been of great <strong>in</strong>terest toteachers, s<strong>in</strong>ce <strong>the</strong>y are so obviously relevant to <strong>the</strong> daily life of an ever<strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>gnumber of classrooms. Whe<strong>the</strong>r it is a matter of accept<strong>in</strong>g orreject<strong>in</strong>g nonstandard dialects or foreign languages at school, of adapt<strong>in</strong>gclassrooms to language diversity or attempt<strong>in</strong>g to ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong> a strictmonol<strong>in</strong>gual regimen, of see<strong>in</strong>g school as a contributor to social changeor as a supporter of some ‘ma<strong>in</strong>stream’ status quo, of argu<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> meritsof ‘transitional’ versus ‘ma<strong>in</strong>tenance’ programs of bil<strong>in</strong>gual education, ofembrac<strong>in</strong>g multiculturalism or recoil<strong>in</strong>g from it <strong>in</strong> all <strong>the</strong>se matters, <strong>the</strong>knowledge, sensitivities and attitudes of teachers are of no smallimportance.And yet, over three decades or so, I have been amazed anddisappo<strong>in</strong>ted at how ill-prepared teachers typically are with regard tol<strong>in</strong>guistic and cultural variation <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> classroom. The education ofteachers generally <strong>in</strong>volves very little exposure to this sort of heterogeneity,and yet it is easy to see that it has made its presence felt <strong>in</strong>virtually every global sett<strong>in</strong>g. Even schools <strong>in</strong> ‘traditional’ and ruralareas whose populations were historically both local and stable are1


2 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>now more and more confronted with children from many differentbackgrounds. The geographical spread of Spanish speakers throughout<strong>the</strong> USA far beyond <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>itially adopted settlement areas of Floridaand <strong>the</strong> southwest is a case <strong>in</strong> po<strong>in</strong>t, as is <strong>the</strong> widen<strong>in</strong>g distribution andpermanence of <strong>the</strong> European ‘guest workers’, as is <strong>the</strong> explod<strong>in</strong>gmobility that has now brought hundreds of thousands of east Europeans,as well as African and Asian refugees, to countries <strong>in</strong> western Europe;and so on. I have also discovered that many jurisdictions have essentiallydenied a diversity that was always <strong>the</strong>re, a reflection of a sort of sociallyimposed ignorance. Thus, for example, when I began research work <strong>in</strong>Nova Scotia, it was immediately clear that prevail<strong>in</strong>g perspectives madelittle room for longstand<strong>in</strong>g groups of low social status. In some schools,<strong>the</strong>re were sizeable groups of African-Canadian youngsters, descendantsof those who came to Canada dur<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> American Civil War, along <strong>the</strong>‘underground railroad’, or who had been given land grants <strong>in</strong> return forservice <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> British army; <strong>in</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs, <strong>the</strong>re were Acadian children ofFrench-speak<strong>in</strong>g background. An <strong>in</strong>ability or an unwill<strong>in</strong>gness to seesuch groups as anyth<strong>in</strong>g o<strong>the</strong>r than very m<strong>in</strong>or aberrations <strong>in</strong> anessentially English/Celtic ma<strong>in</strong>stream had <strong>the</strong> predictable consequences.Even if <strong>the</strong>re was no great likelihood of teachers encounter<strong>in</strong>g social orl<strong>in</strong>guistic diversity <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir classrooms (<strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>gly implausible as thiswould seem), I th<strong>in</strong>k that a good case could still be made for giv<strong>in</strong>g muchmore attention to such diversity. In this book, I will argue that all goodeducation worthy of <strong>the</strong> name is multicultural and, if this is so, a logicalimplication is that any heighten<strong>in</strong>g of teachers’ cross-cultural and crosssubculturalsensitivities must be a good th<strong>in</strong>g.F<strong>in</strong>ally here, it is important to note that expanded sensibilities are notat all difficult to br<strong>in</strong>g about. The matters under discussion <strong>in</strong> this bookare not rocket science. To take one example: <strong>the</strong> evidence that BlackEnglish dialects are just as valid as any o<strong>the</strong>r English variants, that <strong>the</strong>yare just as rule-governed, that <strong>the</strong>ir patterns of pronunciation andemphasis are just as regular, that <strong>the</strong>y serve <strong>the</strong> cognitive needs of <strong>the</strong>irspeakers just as well as any o<strong>the</strong>r form of speech does all this and morecan be presented to, and understood by, anyone who has an open m<strong>in</strong>d.I know, because I have made presentations to teachers and teachers-<strong>in</strong>tra<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g,as well as to hundreds of senior students <strong>in</strong> language sem<strong>in</strong>ars.So much <strong>the</strong> worse, <strong>the</strong>n, that so many are still left to labor understereotyped, <strong>in</strong>accurate and potentially harmful illusions. As I shallshortly po<strong>in</strong>t out, poor and socially disadvantaged children have veryreal burdens to bear; it is an unnecessary fur<strong>the</strong>r tragedy that <strong>the</strong>irl<strong>in</strong>guistic and cognitive skills should be misunderstood or denigrated.


Introduction 3The consequences, <strong>in</strong> terms of impediments to learn<strong>in</strong>g, early curtailmentof formal education and reduced chances <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> world beyond <strong>the</strong>school gates can be enormous.Sympa<strong>the</strong>tic VoicesThere have been several contemporary calls for <strong>the</strong> sort of attentionI hope to highlight <strong>in</strong> this book, as well as earlier ones demonstrat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>longstand<strong>in</strong>g nature of <strong>the</strong> issue. There has, for <strong>in</strong>stance, been a numberof recent works argu<strong>in</strong>g for greater and more precise attention to <strong>the</strong>teach<strong>in</strong>g of foreign languages, and almost all <strong>the</strong>se works stress <strong>the</strong>importance of <strong>the</strong> ideological framework with<strong>in</strong> which this occurs.Unlike earlier and more l<strong>in</strong>guistically focused treatments, <strong>the</strong>se laterones encourage a broader sociol<strong>in</strong>guistic and sociocultural contextualization(e.g. Osborn, 2000; Reagan & Osborn, 2002). Their very existence,of course, testifies to a cont<strong>in</strong>u<strong>in</strong>g need. In <strong>the</strong> American context, <strong>the</strong>need is particularly evident where Hispanic children are concerned:Flores (2005) presents a ra<strong>the</strong>r chill<strong>in</strong>g chronological table <strong>in</strong> which <strong>the</strong>assessments of <strong>the</strong> 1920s a time when Spanish speakers were sometimesjudged to be mentally retarded have now become condemnationsof bil<strong>in</strong>gual education programs that prevent <strong>the</strong> most efficient acquisitionof English. (Flores’ table can be <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>gly set aga<strong>in</strong>st ano<strong>the</strong>r,provided by Baker [2006], which charts <strong>the</strong> rise and fall of languageprograms <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> USA.) A recent small-scale example demonstrates <strong>the</strong>cont<strong>in</strong>u<strong>in</strong>g tendency for alleged language deficiencies to be taken asevidence of underly<strong>in</strong>g cognitive weakness (Comm<strong>in</strong>s & Miramontes,1989). In ano<strong>the</strong>r sett<strong>in</strong>g, Hélot and Young (2005: 242244) show that,s<strong>in</strong>ce <strong>the</strong> French educational system is still largely ‘envisaged from amonol<strong>in</strong>gual po<strong>in</strong>t of view... it is difficult for most teachers to view <strong>the</strong>different languages and cultural backgrounds of <strong>the</strong>ir pupils as o<strong>the</strong>rthan problematic’. The authors suggest that, where l<strong>in</strong>guistic diversitydoes seem to be mildly encouraged by <strong>the</strong> education m<strong>in</strong>istry, this is‘ma<strong>in</strong>ly as a policy to counterbalance <strong>the</strong> hegemony of English’. Thisalerts us to <strong>the</strong> possibility that, <strong>in</strong> some contexts, concerns for ‘small’languages and cultures are more apparent than real, often mask<strong>in</strong>g o<strong>the</strong>ragendas.Work by McDiarmid (1992) and McDiarmid and Price (1990) revealsthat multicultural tra<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g programs <strong>in</strong> America seem ei<strong>the</strong>r to makelittle impact on teachers-to-be or, worse, <strong>the</strong>y actually re<strong>in</strong>force m<strong>in</strong>oritygroupstereotyp<strong>in</strong>g. Draw<strong>in</strong>g upon this, Deer<strong>in</strong>g (1997: 343) argues formore, and more effective, ways to encourage teachers’ multicultural


4 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>sensitivity towards o<strong>the</strong>r cultures, particularly among American teacherpopulations that he found to be less culturally sensitive than <strong>the</strong>ir UKcounterpart; see also Noguera (1996) on <strong>in</strong>sufficient teacher preparationfor culturally heterogeneous classrooms. Several aspects of Deer<strong>in</strong>g’sbrief report are less than completely satisfactory, however, and Burtonwoodand Bruce (1999) cast some doubt upon <strong>the</strong> allegedly greater UKsensitivity. Never<strong>the</strong>less, <strong>the</strong>y concur with <strong>the</strong> general observationsabout <strong>the</strong> need for improvement. They also rem<strong>in</strong>d us that <strong>the</strong> SwannReport (1985), which had made an argument for just such improvement,was effectively overtaken by British educational reform legislation threeyears later, reform that stressed <strong>the</strong> importance of a national curriculum(and thus, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> eyes of many observers, made less room for diversity <strong>in</strong><strong>the</strong> classroom).Later work has confirmed some of <strong>the</strong> difficulties here. Zientek (2007)has written about <strong>the</strong> general shortcom<strong>in</strong>gs of teacher-preparationprograms <strong>in</strong> America; more specifically, she discusses <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>adequate<strong>in</strong>formation provided about cultural and l<strong>in</strong>guistic diversity <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>classroom. Some of <strong>the</strong> current diversity here <strong>in</strong>volves, of course, black,Hispanic and Asian American pupils, and Tenenbaum and Ruck (2007)have demonstrated <strong>the</strong> varied expectations that teachers have of children<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>se groups: Asian pupils were expected to do best at school,followed by ‘European American’ children, <strong>the</strong>n Hispanics and, f<strong>in</strong>ally,black children. Teachers were also found to be more encourag<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir<strong>in</strong>teractions with those of whom <strong>the</strong>y expected <strong>the</strong> most. The dangers ofsuch stereotypic preconceptions are obvious, contribut<strong>in</strong>g as <strong>the</strong>y easilycan to self-fulfill<strong>in</strong>g prophecies; see also Wiggan (2007).There is even evidence that <strong>the</strong> more specific tra<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g of teachers forbil<strong>in</strong>gual education programs has been less than adequate. Gr<strong>in</strong>berg andSaavedra (2000) cite some representative comments that demonstratehow university courses lead<strong>in</strong>g to teacher certification are often of ‘littlerelevance’. One tra<strong>in</strong>ee notes: ‘In my preparation as a bil<strong>in</strong>gual educatorI was not prepared for <strong>the</strong> reality <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> school’ (Gr<strong>in</strong>berg & Saavedra,2000: 433). Ano<strong>the</strong>r observation:Liv<strong>in</strong>g here <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> heart of New Mexico, we have very fertile groundsto develop strong, effective bil<strong>in</strong>gual programs... [but] <strong>the</strong> universitydoes not have a good program to prepare teachers... <strong>the</strong>re is norigor... <strong>the</strong> content of <strong>the</strong> classes is m<strong>in</strong>imal, at a low level. (Gr<strong>in</strong>berg& Saavedra, 2000: 434)Gr<strong>in</strong>berg and Saavedra discuss <strong>the</strong> emphasis upon language per se <strong>in</strong>tra<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g courses, and <strong>the</strong> lack of time devoted to cross-cultural education


Introduction 5more broadly. The dissatisfaction noted by <strong>the</strong> first tra<strong>in</strong>ee teacher(above) is a particular problem: on <strong>the</strong> one hand, <strong>the</strong>re is <strong>in</strong>sufficientexposure to multicultural <strong>the</strong>mes; on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r, <strong>the</strong> tra<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g that doesexist under this head<strong>in</strong>g is often <strong>in</strong>adequate. This may account for <strong>the</strong>reports of Mart<strong>in</strong> (1995) and Zeichner (1994), who found that whenteachers-to-be appeared un<strong>in</strong>terested <strong>in</strong>, or resistant to, multiculturaltra<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g courses, <strong>the</strong>ir teachers characterized <strong>the</strong>m as ill-prepared or, lesscharitably, as unrepentant possessors of racist and stereotyped views. Itis not difficult to detect potential vicious circles here (see also McAllister& Irv<strong>in</strong>e, 2000).When discuss<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> ‘culture’ of <strong>the</strong> foreign-language classroom,<strong>the</strong> best of <strong>the</strong> recent books and papers give some attention to <strong>the</strong>language-dialect dist<strong>in</strong>ction and, more particularly, to <strong>the</strong> appropriateunderstand<strong>in</strong>g of <strong>the</strong> validity of nonstandard dialect varieties. Siegel(2007: 76) provides a good example with a discussion show<strong>in</strong>g just howlittle ground has been ga<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong> this area. Describ<strong>in</strong>g creoles andnonstandard dialects <strong>in</strong> education, he po<strong>in</strong>ts out that, despite severaldecades of sociol<strong>in</strong>guistic <strong>in</strong>sight, accurate depictions of such varieties‘have not filtered down to many educators and adm<strong>in</strong>istrators, or to <strong>the</strong>general public’; see also Zéphir (1997, 1999), who draws explicit parallelsbetween <strong>the</strong> educational reception of creole and that of Black English.Such treatments touch upon <strong>the</strong> most important category here.At 20-year <strong>in</strong>tervals, <strong>the</strong> American Dialect Society (1943, 1964 and1984; and Preston, 2003) published four works outl<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g ‘neededresearch’ <strong>in</strong> dialect studies. In <strong>the</strong> latest of <strong>the</strong>se, several authors writeabout <strong>the</strong> important l<strong>in</strong>guistic demonstrations of <strong>the</strong> validity of BlackEnglish and o<strong>the</strong>r nonstandard dialects, and about <strong>the</strong> useful developments<strong>in</strong> language-attitude research, ‘perceptual dialectology’ and ‘folkl<strong>in</strong>guistics’ (see later chapters). They also acknowledge, however, thatunenlightened stereotypes cont<strong>in</strong>ue <strong>the</strong>ir baleful course. There is clearlymuch more to do, particularly <strong>in</strong> educational sett<strong>in</strong>gs. In 1979, <strong>the</strong> Centerfor Applied L<strong>in</strong>guistics <strong>in</strong> Wash<strong>in</strong>gton issued five booklets devoted to‘dialects and educational equity’; <strong>the</strong>se were revised and updated <strong>in</strong> oneshort volume by Wolfram and Christian (1989). In a question-and-answerformat, <strong>the</strong> authors deal with issues raised by teachers <strong>in</strong> workshops,<strong>in</strong>-service sessions and o<strong>the</strong>r similar venues; although <strong>the</strong>re are obviouslimitations and discont<strong>in</strong>uities <strong>in</strong> such an approach, most of <strong>the</strong>important matters are at least touched upon. Wolfram and Christiannote that, while researchers and those who teach teachers agree on <strong>the</strong>importance of <strong>in</strong>formation about dialect variation <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> classroom, <strong>the</strong>yhave been h<strong>in</strong>dered by <strong>the</strong> lack of appropriate texts.


6 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>It is <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g, to say <strong>the</strong> least, that over <strong>the</strong> 20 years follow<strong>in</strong>gLabov’s (1969) classic demonstration of <strong>the</strong> ‘logic of nonstandardEnglish’ <strong>in</strong> an America where Black English was achiev<strong>in</strong>g a newvisibility no suitable teacher-tra<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g material was apparently developed.Cochran-Smith (1995: 493) was blunt, describ<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> Americaneducational system as ‘dysfunctional for large numbers of children whoare not part of <strong>the</strong> racial and language ma<strong>in</strong>stream’. She argues, as Stone(1981), Sleeter and Grant (1987) and o<strong>the</strong>rs have done, that multicultural‘education’ has often been trivialized by attention to ‘foods, folkways andhandiwork’. There are no broad strategies, Cochran-Smith asserts, fordeal<strong>in</strong>g with cultural and l<strong>in</strong>guistic diversity at school. Virtually all thosewho have written <strong>in</strong> scholarly ways about Black English have, of course,argued for <strong>the</strong> greater sensitivity to black culture and lifestyles thatshould logically accompany demonstrations of <strong>the</strong> validity of blackdialects; <strong>the</strong> work of Smi<strong>the</strong>rman (e.g. 1981a, 2006) is noteworthy here(and see also my discussion of Ebonics, below). Thus, <strong>in</strong> a review of abook on Black English, Kautzsch (2006) po<strong>in</strong>ts to <strong>the</strong> necessity for moreopen-m<strong>in</strong>ded and well-<strong>in</strong>formed teachers, and for educational systemscommitted to ‘difference’ ra<strong>the</strong>r than ‘deficit’ stances on cultural anddialect variations. And Godley et al. (2007: 124) provide a very recentclassroom demonstration of <strong>the</strong> cont<strong>in</strong>u<strong>in</strong>g assessments that equate‘standard’ with ‘correct’, and Black English with ‘<strong>in</strong>correct, ungrammaticalEnglish’. A collection by Nero (2006) is also concerned withnonstandard varieties <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> classroom; <strong>in</strong> his foreword, Elbow po<strong>in</strong>tsto <strong>the</strong> pivotal issue of reconcil<strong>in</strong>g an acknowledgement of <strong>the</strong> validity ofall varieties with <strong>the</strong> effective teach<strong>in</strong>g of more standard ones.Overall, <strong>the</strong> monograph-length treatment most similar to m<strong>in</strong>e hereis that of Corson (2001). His title is similar, and so are <strong>the</strong> areas he focusesupon: standard and nonstandard dialects, language education <strong>in</strong> itsseveral formats, and discourse ‘norms’ <strong>in</strong> relation to cultural and gendervariation. In this book, I stress ramifications of <strong>the</strong> first two, and pay lessattention to matters of gender and discourse (for reasons that will bemade clear). And, like me, Corson aims at a comprehensive overview ofthose aspects of l<strong>in</strong>guistic diversity most relevant <strong>in</strong> education. However,while his notes about <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>tended audience reveal a basic concern withadvanced social-science students and ‘experienced teachers’, and while Ihope and expect that this book will be of <strong>in</strong>terest <strong>in</strong> those quarters too,my central focus is upon teachers-to-be, those who tra<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>m, andresearchers <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> area. That is, <strong>the</strong> material between <strong>the</strong>se covers ismeant primarily to contribute to <strong>the</strong> lessen<strong>in</strong>g of mis<strong>in</strong>formation andstereotype, and to <strong>the</strong> break<strong>in</strong>g of <strong>the</strong> unfortunate circles that <strong>the</strong>y


Introduction 7ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>. There is ample evidence that <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>accurate language attitudesoften held by beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g teachers who are, after all, members ofsocieties <strong>in</strong> which stereotypes abound are re<strong>in</strong>forced <strong>in</strong> a school culturethat, like <strong>the</strong> larger community outside its gates, has traditionallyencouraged (‘privileged’ would be <strong>the</strong> word many use nowadays)what is ‘standard’. These attitudes, it has been suggested, are oftenstrong enough that new teachers will ‘hear’ m<strong>in</strong>ority-group children’sspeech as nonstandard even if, <strong>in</strong> fact, it is not. F<strong>in</strong>ally here, to makematters a little more poignant, <strong>the</strong>re is some evidence to suggest that someyounger teachers are <strong>in</strong>itially more <strong>in</strong>cl<strong>in</strong>ed to believe <strong>the</strong> ‘different-butnot-deficient’argument about nonstandard varieties: how sad, <strong>the</strong>n, ifthat encourag<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>itial <strong>in</strong>sight becomes overwhelmed by <strong>the</strong> exist<strong>in</strong>gculture of <strong>the</strong> school (see Corson, 2001; Edwards, 1986; Fasold, 1984; seealso <strong>the</strong> flesh<strong>in</strong>g-out of <strong>the</strong>se matters <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> chapters follow<strong>in</strong>g).Brouwer and Korthagen (2005) have discussed aspects of this <strong>in</strong> alengthy review. They note, at <strong>the</strong> outset, that ‘occupational socialization<strong>in</strong> schools is a known factor counteract<strong>in</strong>g attempts at educat<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>novative teachers’ (Brouwer & Korthagen, 2005: 153). This is onepole of <strong>the</strong> problem, as it were: teachers, like <strong>the</strong> rest of us, are verysusceptible to <strong>the</strong> cognitive and emotional tone of <strong>the</strong>ir surround<strong>in</strong>gs. Itis not to be doubted that such susceptibility is correlated with vaguenessor ignorance, so that <strong>the</strong> issues on which one is least <strong>in</strong>formed are likelyto be those most prone to <strong>in</strong>fluence. A corollary is that attempts toreplace ignorance with awareness are likely to act as <strong>in</strong>oculations aga<strong>in</strong>stlater susceptibility. To make this more specific: provid<strong>in</strong>g new teacherswith accurate l<strong>in</strong>guistic <strong>in</strong>formation about <strong>the</strong> competence of <strong>the</strong>ir pupilsmay disrupt a cha<strong>in</strong> of ignorance and mis<strong>in</strong>formation that is o<strong>the</strong>rwiselikely to cont<strong>in</strong>ue. This br<strong>in</strong>gs me to <strong>the</strong> second pole. As Brouwer andKorthagen (2005: 153) observe, some studies have shown that <strong>the</strong> ‘effectsof teacher education on <strong>the</strong> actual practices of teachers are generallymeager’. The implication here, <strong>the</strong>n, is that <strong>the</strong> provision of l<strong>in</strong>guistic andpsychological <strong>in</strong>formation must be done well <strong>in</strong> order to have any chanceof becom<strong>in</strong>g that ‘<strong>in</strong>oculation’. Fortunately, as I have already noted, it isnot especially difficult to present <strong>the</strong> relevant f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>in</strong> a digestiblemanner. Fortunate, but aga<strong>in</strong> a little sad, <strong>in</strong>asmuch as so much morecould have easily been accomplished already.Corson draws attention to <strong>the</strong> need for improved teacher sensitivityand to <strong>the</strong> benefits of hav<strong>in</strong>g more ethnic-group members as teachers;above all, however, he echoes one of my open<strong>in</strong>g concerns here (or, moreaccurately, one aspect of a broader concern). He remarks that ‘classroomrelatedwork on non-standard varieties is still <strong>in</strong> its <strong>in</strong>fancy’ (Corson,


8 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>2001: 79). In fact, this is a little <strong>in</strong>accurate: as <strong>the</strong> list of references <strong>in</strong> thisbook demonstrates, <strong>the</strong>re is no shortage of relevant research, much of itderiv<strong>in</strong>g from, and meant to feed back <strong>in</strong>to, <strong>the</strong> educational system. It is<strong>the</strong> lack of appropriate syn<strong>the</strong>sis, and <strong>the</strong>n of application <strong>in</strong> teachertra<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>gprograms, for <strong>in</strong>stance that is <strong>the</strong> crux of <strong>the</strong> matter. Thismakes <strong>the</strong> second of Corson’s broad observations ra<strong>the</strong>r more apposite:‘formal educational policies for <strong>the</strong> treatment of non-standard varieties <strong>in</strong>schools are conspicuous by <strong>the</strong>ir absence <strong>in</strong> most educational systems’(Corson, 2001: 68).Like Corson before <strong>the</strong>m, Quiocho and Rios (2000) consider <strong>the</strong> impactupon m<strong>in</strong>ority-group children of hav<strong>in</strong>g teachers from <strong>the</strong>ir own group.They are undoubtedly correct <strong>in</strong> po<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g out that <strong>the</strong>re are fewer suchteachers <strong>in</strong> America, <strong>the</strong> UK and elsewhere than we would like (see alsoBurtonwood & Bruce, 1999). They may also be right when <strong>the</strong>y say thatteachers who are from m<strong>in</strong>ority groups will be more likely to demonstratemulticultural sensitivity <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> classroom. But it is important topo<strong>in</strong>t out that m<strong>in</strong>ority-group members who become teachers may, bythat fact alone, be atypical of <strong>the</strong> group. Relatedly, <strong>the</strong> process of teachertra<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g may tend to accelerate <strong>the</strong>ir middle-class socialization. (From ara<strong>the</strong>r more polemical perspective, Gr<strong>in</strong>berg and Saavedra [2000: 436]note that once Lat<strong>in</strong>os and o<strong>the</strong>r m<strong>in</strong>ority-group members ‘enter <strong>the</strong>system, <strong>in</strong>ternal processes of colonization take over’.) It is by no meansclear, <strong>the</strong>n, that <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> number of teachers from particularsociocultural groups will lead to a commensurate <strong>in</strong>crease <strong>in</strong> multiculturalsensitivities <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> classroom. And <strong>the</strong>re is one fact here thatnever seems to be mentioned at all. When Quiocho, Rios and many o<strong>the</strong>rlike-m<strong>in</strong>ded scholars call for educators and <strong>in</strong>stitutions to encouragemore m<strong>in</strong>ority-group students to take up <strong>the</strong> profession of teach<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>the</strong>ymay be encourag<strong>in</strong>g a sort of self-imposed restriction that does not applyto ‘ma<strong>in</strong>stream’ <strong>in</strong>dividuals. Over <strong>the</strong> years, I have had a numberof Canadian native students <strong>in</strong> my university sem<strong>in</strong>ars, many of whomtold me that <strong>the</strong>y <strong>in</strong>tended to become teachers. As I came to know <strong>the</strong>m alittle better, it was apparent that as <strong>the</strong> (educated) m<strong>in</strong>ority with<strong>in</strong> asocioeconomically depressed m<strong>in</strong>ority <strong>the</strong>y felt a duty to ‘give back’ to<strong>the</strong>ir community. Such altruistic motives are, of course, highly commendable,but I came to realize that at least some of my students were chart<strong>in</strong>g<strong>the</strong>ir career course out of a sense of obligation, ra<strong>the</strong>r than on <strong>the</strong> basis ofpersonal preference. And it struck me that this was, <strong>in</strong> some sense, yetano<strong>the</strong>r burden that <strong>the</strong>y carried, yet ano<strong>the</strong>r limitation that <strong>the</strong>ir whitecounterparts rarely had to consider at all.


Introduction 9This BookThis book is an attempt to br<strong>in</strong>g under one roof some importantmatters largely l<strong>in</strong>guistic but also, <strong>in</strong>evitably, sociocultural that,I believe, should have greater exposure. It is not any sort of handbook or‘how-to’ manual. It does not outl<strong>in</strong>e specific activities or curriculumadaptations, and its coverage is not restricted to what might be seen asimmediately relevant <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> classroom. It deals, ra<strong>the</strong>r, with background<strong>in</strong>formation that could reasonably <strong>in</strong>form pedagogical activities andresearch. In short, this book does not tell teachers what to do <strong>in</strong> class, butit may provide some useful underp<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>gs. As implied above, goodcontextualization is central to <strong>the</strong> enhancement of cultural and l<strong>in</strong>guisticsensitivities, but <strong>the</strong>re is also a case to be made for some l<strong>in</strong>guistic andsociol<strong>in</strong>guistic basics, as noted by Brumfit (2001). Some of <strong>the</strong>seobviously relate to ‘foreign’ languages, and some to nonstandarddialects. And, as Ferguson (2006: 174) rem<strong>in</strong>ds us, <strong>the</strong>re is a thirdcategory. In a world <strong>in</strong> which English is becom<strong>in</strong>g more and moreglobalized, but where its apparently permanent <strong>in</strong>cursions are spawn<strong>in</strong>gsturdy local ‘Englishes’, teachers’ awareness of <strong>the</strong>se could ‘replaceabsolutist conceptions of what is proper and correct <strong>in</strong> language withgreater flexibility and pr<strong>in</strong>cipled pragmatism regard<strong>in</strong>g norms andmodels’. The teacher who has some awareness along <strong>the</strong>se l<strong>in</strong>es willsurely have a better understand<strong>in</strong>g of language varieties that, although<strong>the</strong>y may exist as nonstandard <strong>in</strong> American or British classrooms,<strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>gly represent Englishes that are locally or regionally standardat <strong>the</strong>ir po<strong>in</strong>ts of orig<strong>in</strong>.Andersson and Trudgill (1990: 179) make <strong>the</strong> po<strong>in</strong>t, too: ‘teachers whoare prepared to take an open-m<strong>in</strong>ded, unprejudiced attitude towards<strong>the</strong> varieties of language spoken by <strong>the</strong>ir pupils will be <strong>the</strong> ones who alsosucceed best <strong>in</strong> foster<strong>in</strong>g and develop<strong>in</strong>g children’s l<strong>in</strong>guistic <strong>in</strong>terestsand abilities’. We could expand this, <strong>in</strong> fact, and say that such teachersare likely to succeed best <strong>in</strong> develop<strong>in</strong>g all of <strong>the</strong>ir pupils’ potentials. But<strong>the</strong> observation also prompts us, of course, to consider how best wemight facilitate <strong>the</strong> development of open-m<strong>in</strong>dedness among teachers(and o<strong>the</strong>rs). It is obvious that <strong>the</strong> most important factor here <strong>in</strong>volves<strong>the</strong> presentation of <strong>the</strong> most up-to-date evidence bear<strong>in</strong>g upon l<strong>in</strong>guisticand cultural issues. This is <strong>the</strong> motivation for all <strong>the</strong> works cited <strong>in</strong> thischapter, as well as Andersson and Trudgill’s discussion of ‘bad’language, and Bauer and Trudgill’s (1998) debunk<strong>in</strong>g of a score oflanguage ‘myths’. It is also <strong>the</strong> motivation beh<strong>in</strong>d many o<strong>the</strong>r works,


10 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>most of <strong>the</strong>m more focused; for some recent examples, see Beykont(2002), Pearce (2005) and Ga<strong>in</strong>e (2005).Information should be presented as a matter of course to teachers.Although it may have positively <strong>in</strong>fluenced subsequent programs ofteacher education, I don’t th<strong>in</strong>k that <strong>the</strong> judgment <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> famous AnnArbor Black English trial (see below) that required teachers to take courses<strong>in</strong> sociol<strong>in</strong>guistics (see Labov, 1982; Lanehart, 1998) was necessarily <strong>the</strong>best precedent for future procedure. Ra<strong>the</strong>r, I believe that careful andregular attention to basic language matters is <strong>the</strong> soil <strong>in</strong> which teachersensitivities are most likely to grow and thrive. Of course, I also hope that<strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>formation here may be of some use across a range of specializations.Reagan (2006) has recently noted that educat<strong>in</strong>g language teachershas been made more difficult by <strong>the</strong> ‘balkanization’ of sub-fields, and hispo<strong>in</strong>t is very well taken and <strong>in</strong> tune with my purposes here: <strong>the</strong>re are‘artificial boundaries’ that unnecessarily restrict <strong>the</strong> effective transmissionof <strong>in</strong>formation that ought to be part and parcel of <strong>the</strong> tra<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g of allteachers. In a similar ve<strong>in</strong>, I should say that my central focus here is noton specific matters of l<strong>in</strong>guistic and dialectal detail, say, or of teach<strong>in</strong>gmethods or <strong>the</strong> technicalities of bil<strong>in</strong>gualism and bil<strong>in</strong>gual education for which many excellent treatises already exist. Ra<strong>the</strong>r, <strong>the</strong> emphasishere is upon <strong>the</strong> ramifications of social, political and l<strong>in</strong>guistic <strong>in</strong>teractionamong ethnocultural groups, particularly between majorities and m<strong>in</strong>orities,between <strong>the</strong> powerful and <strong>the</strong> powerless, between privilege andpoverty.This book should be of use and <strong>in</strong>terest to students and researchers, aswell as to teachers and educators. To that end, I have written it (I hope) <strong>in</strong>a direct and jargon-free manner, while also provid<strong>in</strong>g a great manyreferences for those <strong>in</strong>terested <strong>in</strong> fur<strong>the</strong>r and more specialized enquiry.I have also taken particular care to re-present here some earlier research,studies that have ei<strong>the</strong>r been ra<strong>the</strong>r neglected, or still have someth<strong>in</strong>g totell us, or both. It is clear, for <strong>in</strong>stance, that <strong>the</strong> discourse-analysisemphasis that has taken over from more empirical <strong>in</strong>vestigations <strong>in</strong>several language areas often has less to say than (for example) some of<strong>the</strong> ‘classic’ work <strong>in</strong> language attitudes and stereotypes: less, at least, <strong>in</strong>terms of practical and generalizable <strong>in</strong>formation of immediate <strong>in</strong>terest toteachers and o<strong>the</strong>rs. I am heartened to f<strong>in</strong>d that <strong>the</strong> careful study oflanguage beliefs and attitudes improved, of course, from <strong>the</strong> studiesof 30 years ago, often <strong>in</strong>corporat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>sights common to discourseanalysis has not quite capitulated. Collections by Milroy and Preston(1999), Kristiansen et al. (2005) and Garrett et al. (2003) are examples here.The first is noteworthy <strong>in</strong> its attempt, <strong>in</strong> five papers deal<strong>in</strong>g with


Introduction 11attitudes and stereotypes, to merge l<strong>in</strong>guistic and psychological <strong>in</strong>sights.The second is quite broad <strong>in</strong> scope, with reports from Brita<strong>in</strong>, <strong>the</strong> UnitedStates and <strong>the</strong> Nordic countries. The third focuses on Wales, but itsopen<strong>in</strong>g chapters deal with language attitudes <strong>in</strong> a general way; it is<strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g to see just how many of <strong>the</strong> references cited <strong>the</strong>re, are of <strong>the</strong>1970s v<strong>in</strong>tage (see below). Ladegaard’s cont<strong>in</strong>u<strong>in</strong>g series of studies <strong>in</strong>Denmark (Ladegaard, 1998a, 1998b, 1998c, 2000; see also Ladegaard &Sachdev, 2006) is also important.Similarly, <strong>the</strong> new or renewed emphasis upon ‘folk l<strong>in</strong>guistics’ and‘perceptual dialectology’, which often represents a desire to get to gripswith more fully fleshed language attitudes, is a vital modern subdiscipl<strong>in</strong>e;see <strong>the</strong> overviews provided by Preston (1999) and Long andPreston (2002). F<strong>in</strong>ally here, I note that Rampton’s (2006) ethnographictreatment of classroom discourse acknowledges that, while <strong>the</strong> attitud<strong>in</strong>alatmosphere at school with respect to <strong>the</strong> tolerance and treatment ofdialect variation is not <strong>the</strong> same as it was <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> 1960s and 1970s,perceptions of social class, its l<strong>in</strong>guistic reflections and <strong>the</strong> attendantpsychological stresses rema<strong>in</strong> important. Writ<strong>in</strong>g of two pupils, Ramptonnotes thatboth Hanif and N<strong>in</strong>nette had fairly clear images of <strong>the</strong> k<strong>in</strong>ds ofdisadvantaged lives <strong>the</strong>y wanted to avoid... work<strong>in</strong>g-class pupilsmight not be quite as fragile as sociol<strong>in</strong>guistics has sometimesimplied, but everyday experience and a huge non-l<strong>in</strong>guistic literatureon class provides [sic] ample reason for tak<strong>in</strong>g class-related <strong>in</strong>securitiesvery seriously. (Rampton, 2006: 320)Sensitive attention to <strong>the</strong> details of discourse and conversation can ofcourse reveal many th<strong>in</strong>gs of <strong>in</strong>terest. Studies of gender differences <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>classroom are a good case <strong>in</strong> po<strong>in</strong>t here, one <strong>in</strong> which a close analysis ofverbal exchanges can be of <strong>the</strong> greatest value: variations <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> questionand-answerpatterns of girls and boys, for <strong>in</strong>stance, or of differentialattention provided by teachers (see Carr & Pauwels, 2006; Julé, 1984;Sommers, 2000). But even its most fervent advocates admit that, <strong>in</strong> manycases, discourse studies do not reveal much that is new (Stubbs, 1984)and <strong>the</strong> level of detail <strong>in</strong> which <strong>the</strong>y often revel is unlikely to lead toameliorative action. This is an important matter, important enough tojustify fuller attention <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> next chapter.The broader message, to this po<strong>in</strong>t, is that I have tried to assemble herea useful and comprehensive comb<strong>in</strong>ation of older work (some of it dat<strong>in</strong>gto <strong>the</strong> 1960s and 1970s: a time when, for <strong>in</strong>stance, a great deal of attentionwas be<strong>in</strong>g given to describ<strong>in</strong>g and categoriz<strong>in</strong>g dialect variation) and <strong>the</strong>


12 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>most recent <strong>in</strong>sights. Apart from <strong>the</strong> cont<strong>in</strong>u<strong>in</strong>g relevance of some earlierdiscussions, it is also <strong>the</strong> case that <strong>the</strong> problems aris<strong>in</strong>g from languagediversity <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> classroom have rema<strong>in</strong>ed remarkably, if very regrettably,similar to what <strong>the</strong>y were when those discussions were first published.This, of course, is <strong>the</strong> reason for <strong>the</strong> cont<strong>in</strong>ued attention that this bookrepresents. I focus most basically here upon ‘macro’-level work, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>belief that a broad-brush knowledge has more chance of applicabilitythan f<strong>in</strong>e-gra<strong>in</strong>ed analysis. What is more likely to be of service andusefulness: a 20-page analysis of 15-m<strong>in</strong>ute samples of <strong>the</strong> speechpatterns of four Bangladeshi schoolchildren <strong>in</strong> Bradford, or an overviewof <strong>the</strong> general nature of Bengali-English language contact and <strong>in</strong>terference?And, to repeat, I am more <strong>in</strong>terested here <strong>in</strong> sociol<strong>in</strong>guistics, or<strong>the</strong> sociology/social psychology of language than (with one or twoexceptions) with l<strong>in</strong>guistics itself. This is because <strong>the</strong> vast majority ofissues that affect speakers of ‘foreign’ languages or of nonstandarddialects of <strong>in</strong>digenous varieties are psychosocial <strong>in</strong> nature: <strong>the</strong>y have todo with perceptions and prejudice, with stereotypes and assumptions,with power and subord<strong>in</strong>ation.Nonstandard-dialect and foreign-language speakers comprise <strong>the</strong> twoma<strong>in</strong> constituencies with which this book deals. There are relationshipsbetween <strong>the</strong>m, of course, and <strong>the</strong>se have allowed me some economy ofdescription. An understand<strong>in</strong>g, for example, of <strong>the</strong> social perceptionsattach<strong>in</strong>g to nonstandard English dialects of low social status will befound applicable to those associated with foreign languages, particularlythose mo<strong>the</strong>r tongues of m<strong>in</strong>ority groups whose socioeconomic cloutdoes not match that of <strong>the</strong> ma<strong>in</strong>stream.Some might <strong>in</strong>itially imag<strong>in</strong>e that speakers of foreign languages more than those whose maternal varieties are nonstandard dialects have quite specifically l<strong>in</strong>guistic problems when <strong>the</strong>y f<strong>in</strong>d <strong>the</strong>mselves <strong>in</strong>classrooms where <strong>the</strong>ir language is not used. It is, of course, true that<strong>the</strong>re are ways to improve or lessen <strong>the</strong> effectiveness of second-languagelearn<strong>in</strong>g, ways that will <strong>in</strong>volve matters l<strong>in</strong>guistic. But consider <strong>the</strong> socialcontext <strong>in</strong> which such speakers must engage <strong>in</strong> that learn<strong>in</strong>g, consider<strong>the</strong>ir own attitudes and motivations, consider <strong>the</strong> sociopolitical questionsthat swirl around <strong>the</strong> provision (or not) of some sort of extra helpfor <strong>the</strong>m at school. Should <strong>the</strong>y be left entirely to <strong>the</strong>ir own devices?Should <strong>the</strong> school, on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r hand, make some adaptations for <strong>the</strong>m?Should formal programs of bil<strong>in</strong>gual education be put <strong>in</strong> place: if so,what sort? These are all matters that range far beyond l<strong>in</strong>guisticbeg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>gs. Ultimately, <strong>the</strong>y have to do with people’s sense of who<strong>the</strong>y are and who <strong>the</strong>y want to be, with <strong>the</strong> defence of some exist<strong>in</strong>g


Introduction 13‘ma<strong>in</strong>stream’ or a will<strong>in</strong>gness to see it evolve <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> face of chang<strong>in</strong>gdemographic circumstance, with tolerance and prejudice <strong>in</strong> a word,with matters of <strong>in</strong>dividual and group identity.Educational and social disadvantage underp<strong>in</strong>ned by (among o<strong>the</strong>rth<strong>in</strong>gs) <strong>in</strong>accurate l<strong>in</strong>guistic op<strong>in</strong>ion and prejudice rema<strong>in</strong>s a greatproblem. Popular speech and language attitudes cont<strong>in</strong>ue to hold certa<strong>in</strong>dialects and accents as better or worse than o<strong>the</strong>rs. There is no realdifficulty, of course, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> possession of personal preferences, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> factthat I th<strong>in</strong>k Italian to be <strong>the</strong> most beautiful and mellifluous of languages,whereas you f<strong>in</strong>d <strong>the</strong> greatest music and poetry <strong>in</strong> Scottish Gaelic. But<strong>the</strong>re are dangers when we imag<strong>in</strong>e that we are argu<strong>in</strong>g aboutsubstantive l<strong>in</strong>guistic issues, about <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>herent properties of one varietyor ano<strong>the</strong>r, or worse still about <strong>the</strong> cognitive attributes thought toaccompany certa<strong>in</strong> language forms. In all <strong>the</strong>se ways, <strong>the</strong> so-called‘deficit’ <strong>the</strong>ory of nonstandard dialects and, <strong>in</strong>deed, of certa<strong>in</strong> foreignlanguages cont<strong>in</strong>ues to hold wide sway. The man or woman on <strong>the</strong>Clapham omnibus or <strong>the</strong> Bondi tram may not be able to articulate this<strong>the</strong>ory, may <strong>in</strong>deed be quite unaware that <strong>the</strong>y have a <strong>the</strong>ory, but it is <strong>the</strong>easiest th<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> world to demonstrate <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory’s <strong>in</strong>fluence: just askpeople about ‘correct’ and ‘<strong>in</strong>correct’ language (see Lippi-Green, 1997;Trudgill, 1975).To conclude and to reiterate: my hope is that, while this book is clearlynot a ‘how-to’ manual <strong>in</strong> any direct sense, it will prove a comprehensiveguide to important language issues for students, teachers and researchers.There are some parts of some discussions that are more tightlypresented than o<strong>the</strong>rs, of course but none, I believe, is beyond <strong>the</strong> graspof any <strong>in</strong>telligent reader. The audience will no doubt be largely ananglophone one, and it is certa<strong>in</strong>ly true that I draw most of <strong>the</strong><strong>in</strong>formation here from literature <strong>in</strong> English. However, s<strong>in</strong>ce <strong>the</strong> fundamentalissues of concern extend well beyond <strong>the</strong> anglophone world, <strong>the</strong>treatment has mutatis mutandis, as <strong>the</strong>y say a broader scope.Among <strong>the</strong> large number of references to o<strong>the</strong>r work that I make <strong>in</strong>this book, some may at first glance seem outdated. This is not so,however: <strong>the</strong> earlier publications I cite have been carefully chosen for<strong>the</strong>ir endur<strong>in</strong>g value and salience. One of my chief contentions here isthat <strong>the</strong> essential issues <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> area rema<strong>in</strong> much as <strong>the</strong>y were when <strong>the</strong>sesem<strong>in</strong>al pieces of research first appeared. I have, of course, supplemented<strong>the</strong>m freely with more up-to-date work, but only when <strong>the</strong>se laterundertak<strong>in</strong>gs have <strong>in</strong> fact added substantially to what has alreadyappeared. (Or, of course, when discuss<strong>in</strong>g matters that are, <strong>the</strong>mselves,more recent: Ebonics, for example.) A more subtle po<strong>in</strong>t <strong>in</strong> all of this is


14 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>my concern for historical and contextual embedd<strong>in</strong>g, a concern amplifiedupon read<strong>in</strong>g some of <strong>the</strong> new research, where many old wheels arepa<strong>in</strong>fully re<strong>in</strong>vented and where, relatedly, little if any attention is givento important predecessors.I should also po<strong>in</strong>t out here that, with <strong>the</strong> overall aim of provid<strong>in</strong>ga general guide, I have largely refra<strong>in</strong>ed from giv<strong>in</strong>g my own op<strong>in</strong>ions.S<strong>in</strong>ce (I hope) most of <strong>the</strong> sections <strong>in</strong> most of <strong>the</strong> chapters achievea certa<strong>in</strong> degree of roundedness, I have not thought it necessary to makeformal conclud<strong>in</strong>g observations at this level. I do, however, provide an<strong>in</strong>itial chapter overview (<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> next section), as well as a brief conclud<strong>in</strong>gstatement (<strong>in</strong> Chapter 14) <strong>in</strong> which I draw toge<strong>the</strong>r some of <strong>the</strong> ma<strong>in</strong><strong>the</strong>mes. It is here, perhaps, that my own assessments are given <strong>in</strong> clearestform. One f<strong>in</strong>al word here: it is natural <strong>in</strong> a book of this sort to emphasizenegative or, at least, problematic areas and topics, to attempt to highlightissues of cont<strong>in</strong>u<strong>in</strong>g concern, to po<strong>in</strong>t to matters that stand <strong>in</strong> need ofattention. This posture suggests a scholarly detachment (I hope, aga<strong>in</strong>)ra<strong>the</strong>r than any personal sense of hand-wr<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>g. In fact, <strong>the</strong>re have beenmany <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g and favorable alterations <strong>in</strong> attitudes and practicesrelat<strong>in</strong>g to languages at school. But one does not <strong>in</strong>tend a book like this tobe an encomium, and my task here does not <strong>in</strong>clude <strong>the</strong> dispens<strong>in</strong>g oflaurel branches.Chapter overviewIn Chapter 2, I provide a critical survey of discourse analysis. Iacknowledge that small-scale enquiries can illum<strong>in</strong>ate broader mattersand (at <strong>the</strong> beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g of Chapter 6) I also mention <strong>the</strong> implicit associationbetween most of <strong>the</strong> contemporary work <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> area and <strong>the</strong> ‘difference’position on language; to <strong>the</strong>ir credit, discourse analysts of most stripesare highly sensitive to cultural and class variations, and most unlikely tocast matters <strong>in</strong> any better-or-worse perspective. None<strong>the</strong>less, my generalcontention is that <strong>the</strong> micro-level perspective associated with discourseanalysis is not of <strong>the</strong> greatest or <strong>the</strong> most immediate value for ourpurposes here. Fur<strong>the</strong>r, I argue that discourse analysis and its variousoffspr<strong>in</strong>g have become very <strong>in</strong>ward-look<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>gly tricked out <strong>in</strong>noisome jargon and much given to <strong>the</strong> highly specialized <strong>the</strong>oriz<strong>in</strong>g anddebate that one associates with weak discipl<strong>in</strong>ary areas. There is promisehere, but at <strong>the</strong> moment <strong>the</strong> area is essentially an <strong>in</strong>cestuous preserve oflittle applied value.Hav<strong>in</strong>g begun with some necessary brush-clear<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> next threechapters I turn to <strong>the</strong> topic of disadvantage. In <strong>the</strong> first of <strong>the</strong>se, I suggest


Introduction 15that ‘disadvantage’ is an accurate and useful term, provided that it isused properly as a reflection of group difference that is, itself, a productof social discont<strong>in</strong>uity and comparison. The knowledge, attitudes and<strong>in</strong>cl<strong>in</strong>ations that arise <strong>in</strong> one sett<strong>in</strong>g, and that may represent reasonableadaptations to it, may prove <strong>in</strong>appropriate <strong>in</strong> ano<strong>the</strong>r sett<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>appropriate and dist<strong>in</strong>ctly disadvantageous. Given <strong>the</strong> nature ofstratified societies, it is obvious that poverty and social disadvantageoften go hand <strong>in</strong> hand, but <strong>the</strong>y are not synonymous. In terms of success<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> wider society, for example, it is clear that <strong>the</strong>re are many ‘good’<strong>home</strong>s <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>ner city, and many ‘poor’ ones <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> more affluentsuburbs. Still, variations <strong>in</strong> family ‘culture’ are likely to produce moredifficulties for work<strong>in</strong>g-class and m<strong>in</strong>ority-group children at school thanfor <strong>the</strong>ir middle-class counterparts; and <strong>the</strong>se may sometimes be seen as<strong>the</strong> ‘third variable’ that l<strong>in</strong>ks poverty with social disadvantage.I argue very strongly (<strong>in</strong> Chapter 4) that it is <strong>in</strong>correct to see social andeducational disadvantage as hav<strong>in</strong>g a genetic underp<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g. Over <strong>the</strong>long historical haul, this has been <strong>the</strong> most popular view, but it is wrong:it is shot through with prejudice and <strong>in</strong>accurate knowledge of <strong>the</strong> causesand ramifications of class and cultural variations. None<strong>the</strong>less, preciselybecause <strong>the</strong> genetic ‘case’ has been such a longstand<strong>in</strong>g one and, <strong>in</strong>deed,such a cont<strong>in</strong>u<strong>in</strong>gly attractive explanation for group disadvantage,I provide some detail about its more unpleasant consequences. Theoriesof mental and physical disability, of eugenic <strong>in</strong>tervention and ofimmigration control have all sprung from assumptions of genetically‘fixed’ <strong>in</strong>heritance. I also po<strong>in</strong>t out, <strong>in</strong> this chapter, how <strong>the</strong> geneticconceptions of <strong>the</strong> 19th and 20th centuries were essential foundationstones for <strong>the</strong> emerg<strong>in</strong>g discipl<strong>in</strong>es of psychology and sociology, and for<strong>the</strong> test<strong>in</strong>g ethos that is still so much a part of modern education andsociety. Well, if not nature, <strong>the</strong>n perhaps nurture; if not heredity, <strong>the</strong>nclearly environment. Chapter 5 thus <strong>in</strong>troduces environmental factors as<strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r logically possible source of disadvantage. There have been twobroad stances here: on <strong>the</strong> one hand, ‘deficit’ <strong>the</strong>orists argued that certa<strong>in</strong>social contexts produced real and longstand<strong>in</strong>g deficiencies. ‘Culturaldeprivation’ was a phrase often used <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> literature, even though amoment’s thought reveals that it must imply that a group is be<strong>in</strong>gperceived as deprived of ano<strong>the</strong>r group’s culture; after all, it hardly makessense to describe a community as be<strong>in</strong>g deprived of itself. Theimplication, <strong>in</strong> fact, was that poor and lower-class sociocultural sett<strong>in</strong>gswere deficient precisely because <strong>the</strong>y did not exhibit middle-class valuesand practices. Social difference was translated, <strong>in</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r words, <strong>in</strong>to social


16 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>deficit. In most writ<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> this ve<strong>in</strong>, <strong>the</strong> deficit here was seen to bevirtually as deep-seated as if it were genetic <strong>in</strong> orig<strong>in</strong>.The o<strong>the</strong>r environmental stance accepts <strong>the</strong> existence of importantclass and cultural differences, but it refuses to see <strong>the</strong>m as deficits.Ra<strong>the</strong>r, it attempts to understand how environmental variations produceattitud<strong>in</strong>al and behavioral ones, and resists <strong>the</strong> temptation to make moraljudgments from middle-class perspectives. I suggest that this environmental‘difference’ position is <strong>the</strong> only logically tenable one, although <strong>the</strong>force of social pressure and prejudice that can turn difference <strong>in</strong>todeficiency is admittedly very powerful. If potent ‘ma<strong>in</strong>stream’ sentimentshold that class and cultural differences are actual defects, <strong>the</strong>nacademic conceptions of right and wrong may seem ra<strong>the</strong>r <strong>in</strong>significant.Perception is everyth<strong>in</strong>g, after all. But perception can be based uponmis<strong>in</strong>formation or worse and so my argument here is that we shouldmake <strong>the</strong> different-but-not-deficient argument wherever and wheneverpossible. Social prejudice may be <strong>in</strong>evitable <strong>in</strong> stratified societies, but it isnot monolithic.In Chapter 6, I turn to language matters, where <strong>the</strong> general deficitdifferencedebate has been played out <strong>in</strong> more specific terms. Indeed, <strong>the</strong>historically prejudicial perceptions that saw class and cultural variationsas based upon real genetic or environmental deficits also saw languageand dialect variations <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> same way. I attempt to show how <strong>the</strong> workof <strong>the</strong> late Basil Bernste<strong>in</strong> whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> ‘real’ Bernste<strong>in</strong> or Bernste<strong>in</strong>mis<strong>in</strong>terpreted unfortunately provided a contemporary re<strong>in</strong>forcementof <strong>the</strong>se <strong>in</strong>accurate perceptions. Work<strong>in</strong>g-class language ‘codes’ wereseen to exemplify l<strong>in</strong>guistic deficiency or deprivation, and <strong>the</strong>ir speakersto possess a repertoire dist<strong>in</strong>ctly <strong>in</strong>ferior to that of <strong>the</strong>ir middle-classcounterparts. The implications of this <strong>the</strong>oretical position <strong>in</strong>volvejustification for a cont<strong>in</strong>ued disda<strong>in</strong> and rejection of dialectal variants,and for compensatory <strong>in</strong>terventions aimed at replac<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>m withmiddle-class forms viewed not merely as more socially acceptable but,quite simply, <strong>in</strong>tr<strong>in</strong>sically better.I naturally spend some time <strong>in</strong> this chapter demonstrat<strong>in</strong>g thatconceptions of l<strong>in</strong>guistic deprivation and deficit are profoundly misguided.They ignore <strong>the</strong> fact, for <strong>in</strong>stance, that no human group<strong>in</strong>g hasever been found with a language <strong>in</strong>adequate for its own social purposes.But we can easily see, aga<strong>in</strong>, that an acceptance of this po<strong>in</strong>t of viewhardly rules out judgments of disadvantage when members of aparticular community move beyond <strong>the</strong>ir own borders: <strong>the</strong> languagethat serves <strong>the</strong>m perfectly well may not best equip <strong>the</strong>m <strong>in</strong> alteredcircumstances. For this reason, it is entirely possible to wholeheartedly


Introduction 17reject ‘deficit’ perspectives while simultaneously endors<strong>in</strong>g programs oflanguage-repertoire expansion. These need not imply for a moment any<strong>in</strong>tr<strong>in</strong>sic defect <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> maternal variety; <strong>the</strong>y simply acknowledge thatdifferent sett<strong>in</strong>gs may call for different responses. No one will accuse afrancophone executive of hav<strong>in</strong>g an <strong>in</strong>herently flawed mo<strong>the</strong>r tonguejust because she learns English when posted to Detroit. No one shouldconsider American Black English as a flawed dialect just because it is not<strong>the</strong> sort of English that she will acquire when she gets <strong>the</strong>re.Old ideas die hard, and old prejudices are hard to dislodge,particularly when <strong>the</strong>y cont<strong>in</strong>ue to underp<strong>in</strong> quick and easy alternativesto real, dis<strong>in</strong>terested or, <strong>in</strong>deed, compassionate understand<strong>in</strong>g. So, while<strong>the</strong> preced<strong>in</strong>g chapters led up to, and illustrated, <strong>the</strong> two central po<strong>in</strong>ts of<strong>the</strong> argument social disadvantage is a product of cultural difference,only exists where comparisons are drawn, and is not simply a synonymfor deficiency; and <strong>the</strong>re are no <strong>in</strong>herently deficient or substandardlanguages or dialects Chapter 7 documents <strong>the</strong> persistence of deficitideologies. Not only do <strong>the</strong>se rema<strong>in</strong>, at some implicit level, outside <strong>the</strong>academic cloisters, <strong>the</strong>y also have a cont<strong>in</strong>u<strong>in</strong>g existence with<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>m.I dedicate some considerable space here to <strong>the</strong> formulations of JohnHoney. His writ<strong>in</strong>gs, like <strong>the</strong> earlier ones of Bernste<strong>in</strong>, have unfortunatelyre<strong>in</strong>forced popular views and prejudices by seem<strong>in</strong>gly provid<strong>in</strong>g ascholarly scaffold<strong>in</strong>g for <strong>the</strong>m. The sociological and l<strong>in</strong>guistic debateoccasioned by Honey’s work serves to illustrate, once aga<strong>in</strong>, <strong>the</strong> pivotalfeatures of <strong>the</strong> topic. In that sense, I suppose we might appreciateHoney’s <strong>in</strong>tervention, although, <strong>in</strong> a much larger sense, it is unfortunatethat so much time and energy has had to be <strong>in</strong>vested aga<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong> a fightaga<strong>in</strong>st specters that many had hoped were rapidly fad<strong>in</strong>g. The chapterconcludes with some examples of <strong>the</strong> persistent ‘applied’ <strong>in</strong>fluence ofdeficit <strong>the</strong>oriz<strong>in</strong>g.In Chapter 8, I show that all languages and dialects even those‘disadvantaged’ ones that evoke negative attitudes represent importantaspects of group identity. All languages and dialects act as markersof solidarity and belong<strong>in</strong>g and, as such, anchor group members <strong>in</strong><strong>the</strong> collective. This be<strong>in</strong>g so, it is not difficult to understand that <strong>the</strong>attachment and affection felt for particular varieties may <strong>in</strong> fact begreater when those varieties, and <strong>the</strong>ir speakers, are socially stigmatized.After all, a sense of and a desire for <strong>the</strong> security that groupmembership affords is normally heightened <strong>in</strong> circumstances of externalthreat or discomfort. It is also <strong>the</strong> case that attempts to abandon asocially non-prestigious dialect are fraught with danger; consequently,even those who aspire to upward mobility, and who imag<strong>in</strong>e that


18 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>alter<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>ir language will contribute to this, run <strong>the</strong> risk of fall<strong>in</strong>gbetween stools. In this chapter, I also discuss <strong>the</strong> phenomenon of ‘covertprestige’, whereby work<strong>in</strong>g-class or ‘disadvantaged’ speech stylesexhibit an attractiveness based upon <strong>the</strong>ir perceived qualities oftoughness and directness. This sort of prestige obviously adds to <strong>the</strong>dis<strong>in</strong>cl<strong>in</strong>ation to shift dialects, but one of its more <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g features isits appeal to middle-class speakers as well.Of course, covert prestige is largely a male phenomenon: wheremiddle-class men have been found to adopt (and over-report <strong>the</strong>ir use of)work<strong>in</strong>g-class speech patterns, middle-class women tend to claim morestandard-dialect usage. Indeed, some nonstandard-dialect speakers showevidence of ‘hypercorrection’, essentially an over-emphasis upon standardforms.I also return briefly, <strong>in</strong> Chapter 8, to <strong>the</strong> important matter of teachers’attitudes, present<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> results of a number of studies <strong>in</strong>vestigat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>various dimensions along which <strong>the</strong>se attitudes are displayed. It is clearthat speakers of low-status forms receive unfavorable assessments onmany attitud<strong>in</strong>al dimensions, some of which probe far beyond <strong>the</strong>borders of <strong>the</strong> speech samples that are typically used to evoke judges’rat<strong>in</strong>gs. It is sober<strong>in</strong>g to realize that teachers and o<strong>the</strong>rs may draw veryextensive conclusions from brief exposure to children’s language serious judgments (as I say <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> chapter) based upon <strong>in</strong>formationthat may be irrelevant to any accurate consideration of abilities andscholastic potentials. I conclude by not<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> important differencebetween attitude and belief, and by suggest<strong>in</strong>g that we need fuller andmore detailed <strong>in</strong>formation about what lies beh<strong>in</strong>d <strong>the</strong> judgments andassessments made of speech and language varieties.I devote Chapter 9 to Black English Vernacular (BEV). This cont<strong>in</strong>ues<strong>the</strong> brief treatment of that dialect <strong>in</strong> Chapter 6 where it served as anexcellent counter to misguided notions of language deficit but expandsit considerably <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> light of some important contemporary developments.The controversy swirl<strong>in</strong>g around ‘Ebonics’ highlights manyimportant features of <strong>the</strong> sociology of language: pedagogical questionsare revisited here of course, but so too are larger matters of <strong>the</strong> l<strong>in</strong>kagebetween language and identity. Quite apart from <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g debateabout <strong>the</strong> essential nature of BEV could <strong>the</strong> divergence of Ebonics fromo<strong>the</strong>r forms of English be sufficient to warrant <strong>the</strong> label of a separatelanguage? <strong>the</strong> emotionally charged rhetoric here illustrates how a‘disadvantaged’ variety of low prestige can be rejected by some of itsown speakers. At <strong>the</strong> same time as scholars were try<strong>in</strong>g to br<strong>in</strong>gl<strong>in</strong>guistic evidence to bear upon <strong>the</strong> discussions about Ebonics <strong>in</strong> school


Introduction 19districts <strong>in</strong> Michigan, California and elsewhere, prom<strong>in</strong>ent figures with<strong>in</strong><strong>the</strong> black community were decry<strong>in</strong>g what <strong>the</strong>y saw as deficient and<strong>in</strong>appropriate language. This is perhaps a demonstration of that‘m<strong>in</strong>ority-group reaction’ mentioned at <strong>the</strong> beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g of Chapter 8; <strong>in</strong>any event, it represented an unfortunate sort of solidarity betweenpopular and ill-<strong>in</strong>formed views of Black English <strong>in</strong> ma<strong>in</strong>stream America,and those held by some black speakers <strong>the</strong>mselves.In <strong>the</strong> next chapter, I consider <strong>the</strong> ways <strong>in</strong> which schools havetraditionally reacted to <strong>the</strong> presence of foreign languages <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>irclassrooms. Just as it has often been thought right to work to eradicate‘<strong>in</strong>correct’ dialects and replace <strong>the</strong>m with ‘proper’ standard ones, soschools have often considered implicitly or directly that <strong>the</strong> soonerforeign-language-speak<strong>in</strong>g pupils engage with language shift, <strong>the</strong> better.At <strong>the</strong> same time, however, schools have always understood that <strong>the</strong>expansion of l<strong>in</strong>guistic repertoires is an important facet of <strong>the</strong> educationalprocess. Many obvious tensions arise here. For example, <strong>the</strong> sameschool that values and teaches French or Spanish may do little or noth<strong>in</strong>gto recognize, adapt to, or build upon <strong>the</strong> Hausa, Turkish and Arabic thatcome <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> door with new immigrant pupils. In <strong>the</strong> eyes of <strong>the</strong> l<strong>in</strong>guist,all languages may be equal but, socially speak<strong>in</strong>g, some are more equalthan o<strong>the</strong>rs. Schools are, as well, products and reflections of <strong>the</strong> largersociety that surrounds <strong>the</strong>m: one implication is that it will be easier toteach German <strong>in</strong> Nijmegen than <strong>in</strong> Nebraska easier, and moreimmediately recognized as a useful and rational th<strong>in</strong>g to do. Suchmatters return us to questions of social realities and attitudes. It is <strong>the</strong>se,after all, and not any <strong>in</strong>herent l<strong>in</strong>guistic features, that dictate <strong>the</strong> teach<strong>in</strong>gof French and <strong>the</strong> ignor<strong>in</strong>g of Bulgarian. And it is <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>teraction ofattitudes with motivations that can make classroom language-learn<strong>in</strong>gcontexts very different from those that obta<strong>in</strong> beyond <strong>the</strong> school gates.I attempt to describe <strong>the</strong> dynamics of <strong>the</strong>se different sett<strong>in</strong>gs because among many o<strong>the</strong>r th<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>the</strong>y illum<strong>in</strong>ate <strong>the</strong> role of different types ofattitudes and motivations.I also discuss, <strong>in</strong> Chapter 10, someth<strong>in</strong>g of <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g relationshipbetween language and power. It is perfectly obvious that those who havepower can impose <strong>the</strong>ir language upon o<strong>the</strong>rs, ei<strong>the</strong>r directly or, morefrequently, through <strong>the</strong> unofficial pressures associated with <strong>the</strong> attractionsof <strong>the</strong> socially dom<strong>in</strong>ant. But, is it equally <strong>the</strong> case that improvedrecognition of hi<strong>the</strong>rto unregarded m<strong>in</strong>ority languages actually ‘empowers’<strong>the</strong>ir speakers? Will mak<strong>in</strong>g room <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> classroom for Hausa orBulgarian materially affect immigrant children from west Africa andeastern Europe? I suggest here that, contrary to <strong>the</strong> popular equation,


20 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>language is not power not <strong>in</strong>evitably, at any rate and that exercises <strong>in</strong>l<strong>in</strong>guistic ‘empowerment’ are essentially compensatory <strong>in</strong> nature. This isnot to deny that <strong>the</strong>re may be positive benefits (<strong>in</strong> terms of children’s‘self-esteem’, perhaps) of attend<strong>in</strong>g more closely to maternal varieties,but it is generally a mistake and sometimes an unrealistic elevation ofexpectations to th<strong>in</strong>k of schools as empower<strong>in</strong>g agents. None of thismeans, of course, that <strong>the</strong> teach<strong>in</strong>g of foreign languages particularly of<strong>the</strong> ‘heritage’ or ‘allophone’ variety is ei<strong>the</strong>r exceptional or <strong>in</strong>appropriate.I conclude <strong>the</strong> chapter, however, by reiterat<strong>in</strong>g that classroompractice and experience here can best be understood by reference tobroader and more powerful social currents.Such considerations lead naturally to discussions of multiculturaland bil<strong>in</strong>gual education practices. In Chapter 11, I beg<strong>in</strong> by exam<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g<strong>the</strong> nature of multiculturalism per se and, once aga<strong>in</strong>, I stress <strong>the</strong>importance of social perceptions. Multiculturalism as a social fact is not,of course, <strong>the</strong> issue: virtually all societies are <strong>in</strong>ternally diverse to somedegree, which means that virtually all must come to grips on a de factobasis with different language and cultural groups <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir midst. Butmulticulturalism as formal policy is ano<strong>the</strong>r th<strong>in</strong>g altoge<strong>the</strong>r, and itrepresents an important contemporary manifestation of very longstand<strong>in</strong>gsocial issues of pluralism, assimilation, <strong>in</strong>tegration, accommodation,conformity and many o<strong>the</strong>r reflections of <strong>the</strong> tensions that can existbetween social coherence and unity, on <strong>the</strong> one hand, and heterogeneityand diversity, on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r. Advocates of officially sponsored multiculturalismargue that it is <strong>the</strong> only fair and just way for liberaldemocracies to recognize and react to cultural diversity. Opponentsclaim that it means a dilution of a necessary and highly desirable civiccommonality. Any comprehensive coverage of <strong>the</strong>se matters is obviouslyfar beyond my scope here, but I do attempt to show some of <strong>the</strong>important bones of <strong>the</strong> arguments, as well as to comment upon historicaltendencies and present-day trends. The discussion that follows ofmulticultural adaptations at school simply puts some specificallyeducational flesh on <strong>the</strong>se bones. Aga<strong>in</strong>, much h<strong>in</strong>ges here uponassessments of <strong>the</strong> school’s potential as an agent for social change. I dosuggest, however, that at <strong>the</strong> most general level, all good education hasbeen, is now, and must be multicultural <strong>in</strong> nature: it would be a strangeand, <strong>in</strong>deed, <strong>in</strong>conceivable educational policy that reflected only itsimmediate society.Wish<strong>in</strong>g to argue for some sort of multicultural ‘middle ground’, I endChapter 11 by not<strong>in</strong>g a dist<strong>in</strong>ction between weaker and stronger forms ofmulticulturalism. I draw no particular conclusions here, but I do po<strong>in</strong>t


Introduction 21out that a recognition of <strong>the</strong> dist<strong>in</strong>ction is useful <strong>in</strong> itself, and maysuggest fur<strong>the</strong>r explorations.The last two <strong>the</strong>matic chapters deal with bil<strong>in</strong>gualism and bil<strong>in</strong>gualeducation. In Chapter 12, I provide a very brief <strong>in</strong>troduction tobil<strong>in</strong>gualism. I am chiefly concerned here to give <strong>the</strong> reader some senseof <strong>the</strong> ra<strong>the</strong>r complicated nature of <strong>the</strong> phenomenon while, at <strong>the</strong> sametime, try<strong>in</strong>g to po<strong>in</strong>t out that actually becom<strong>in</strong>g bil<strong>in</strong>gual is an unremarkableand extremely common process. The fact that so many ‘ord<strong>in</strong>ary’people, <strong>in</strong> so many different social sett<strong>in</strong>gs, are bil<strong>in</strong>gual (or better) is anobvious testament to this. Difficulties <strong>in</strong> achiev<strong>in</strong>g some competence <strong>in</strong>ano<strong>the</strong>r language are typically related to social circumstances it is notlack of <strong>in</strong>telligence or aptitude that separates learners of French <strong>in</strong>Kansas from those <strong>in</strong> Quebec. Unsurpris<strong>in</strong>gly, <strong>in</strong> this chapter, I alsospend some time discuss<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> relationship between bil<strong>in</strong>gualism andidentity. Beyond <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>strumental capacities of bil<strong>in</strong>guals whose limitedrepertoire extends only as far as social needs dictate, <strong>the</strong>re are l<strong>in</strong>guisticabilities that go much deeper. I suggest two broad possibilities here:those <strong>in</strong>dividuals who, from an early age, have a k<strong>in</strong>ship attachment tomore than one language community; and those who acquire ano<strong>the</strong>rl<strong>in</strong>guistic persona later on. Each circumstance can produce powerful andlong-last<strong>in</strong>g effects upon identities.Chapter 13 considers bil<strong>in</strong>gual education. There are many varieties,and I draw extensively upon Col<strong>in</strong> Baker’s typology here: he providesdetails along a spectrum rang<strong>in</strong>g from no bil<strong>in</strong>gual accommodation at all(<strong>the</strong> ‘s<strong>in</strong>k-or-swim’ scenario that has affected so many immigrants <strong>in</strong> somany countries), to transitional programs that aim to move children <strong>in</strong>to‘ma<strong>in</strong>stream’ classrooms as soon as l<strong>in</strong>guistically possible, to severalapproaches that emphasize <strong>the</strong> retention and development of bothlanguages. The ‘strongest’ forms of bil<strong>in</strong>gual education are, <strong>in</strong> fact,monol<strong>in</strong>gual immersion programs; for example, anglophone childrenlearn<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> and through French. How is this different from a monol<strong>in</strong>guals<strong>in</strong>k-or-swim approach <strong>in</strong> which (say) Spanish speakers f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>the</strong>mselves <strong>in</strong> English-only classrooms? Why do we call <strong>the</strong> latter‘submersion’ and not ‘immersion’? While immersion programs operate<strong>in</strong> sett<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>in</strong> which <strong>the</strong> children’s maternal variety is dom<strong>in</strong>ant and<strong>the</strong>refore not at risk and where <strong>the</strong>ir new language will thus become anaddition to <strong>the</strong>ir repertoire submersion occurs when <strong>the</strong> maternalvariety is not that of <strong>the</strong> ma<strong>in</strong>stream society, when it is at risk and when,<strong>the</strong>refore, <strong>the</strong>re is <strong>the</strong> dist<strong>in</strong>ct possibility that <strong>the</strong> new language willeventually displace <strong>the</strong> orig<strong>in</strong>al one altoge<strong>the</strong>r.


22 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>There is a large literature document<strong>in</strong>g (and debat<strong>in</strong>g) <strong>the</strong> educationaloutcomes associated with different bil<strong>in</strong>gual-education scenarios,but some of <strong>the</strong> most important aspects of <strong>the</strong> topic are, aga<strong>in</strong>, thosewhose source is outside <strong>the</strong> classroom. That is why I conclude <strong>the</strong>chapter with a discussion of <strong>the</strong> politics of bil<strong>in</strong>gual education. Thereare strong analogies here with <strong>the</strong> controversies surround<strong>in</strong>g multiculturalismand multicultural education; <strong>in</strong>deed, it is possible to seediscussion of bil<strong>in</strong>gual education as one sub-set of <strong>the</strong>se. Should aliberal-democratic recognition of cultural diversity <strong>in</strong>clude actively<strong>in</strong>clude a specific language component? Or can worries about socialcohesion and balkanization be legitimately extended to languagematters? Surveys of public op<strong>in</strong>ion <strong>in</strong> many countries have shownhow confused attitudes can be. Many people <strong>in</strong> Australia, Canada, <strong>the</strong>United States and western Europe apparently believe <strong>in</strong> a sort of officialtolerance of m<strong>in</strong>ority-group values and languages, and some wish to seetolerance replaced by more active and more positive legislated <strong>in</strong>tervention.O<strong>the</strong>rs, however, are clearly worried by alterations to <strong>the</strong> socialstatus quo, and <strong>the</strong>se worries can range all <strong>the</strong> way from a more or lessbenign regret at change, to out-and-out racism. But <strong>the</strong> most <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>gattitudes of all are those <strong>in</strong> which several strands of op<strong>in</strong>ion seem<strong>in</strong>tertw<strong>in</strong>ed, or <strong>in</strong> which a grudg<strong>in</strong>g acceptance of o<strong>the</strong>r languages ando<strong>the</strong>r cultures is accompanied by a desire for eventual assimilation andsocial ‘unity’. All po<strong>in</strong>ts of view here will naturally encompasseducational facets, even <strong>in</strong> those sett<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>in</strong> which groups arrange andunderwrite language classes outside <strong>the</strong> publicly funded arena.In Chapter 14, I provide a very brief summary statement. In fact, s<strong>in</strong>ceI have given ra<strong>the</strong>r strong h<strong>in</strong>ts <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> preced<strong>in</strong>g section of this chapter,<strong>the</strong> clos<strong>in</strong>g chapter can be even briefer and more general than it wouldo<strong>the</strong>rwise have had to be.A F<strong>in</strong>al Introductory NoteIt is both a duty and a pleasure to acknowledge <strong>the</strong> help of a numberof people: Brenda Berger, Susan Cameron, Angela Hagar, Rod Landry,Gerard MacDonald and Brenda McKenna, all members of <strong>the</strong> AngusMacDonald Library staff; Susan Hunston and Sarah Lawson, forassistance with <strong>the</strong> provision of material from <strong>the</strong> British Associationof Applied L<strong>in</strong>guistics; Nik Coupland, Peter Garrett and Adam Jaworski,colleagues <strong>in</strong> Cardiff who helped with some detective work; John White,for <strong>in</strong>formation about Galton and religion; Peter Archer, for br<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>g meup to date on Irish advances <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> study of l<strong>in</strong>guistic and social


Introduction 23disadvantage; Christopher Byrne, for some help with tertium comparationisand o<strong>the</strong>r classical matters; Édouard Langille, for one or twogrammatical niceties; Gary Brooks, for <strong>the</strong> provision of a complete run of<strong>the</strong> Journal of <strong>the</strong> History of <strong>the</strong> Behavioral Sciences; and <strong>the</strong> particularlydiligent publisher’s reader, whose many careful comments led to a muchimproved manuscript.


Chapter 2Discourse Analysis and itsDiscontentsIntroductionMidway through <strong>the</strong> last chapter, I noted that <strong>the</strong> current state ofdiscourse analysis and its related sub-fields leaves someth<strong>in</strong>g to bedesired. Their ra<strong>the</strong>r rarefied undertak<strong>in</strong>gs however engross<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>ymay be for <strong>the</strong> direct participants are worrisome on at least two counts.First, <strong>the</strong>ir <strong>in</strong>tr<strong>in</strong>sic assumptions and qualities are often dubious. Second,<strong>the</strong>ir <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>g presence <strong>in</strong> several areas of language study fortified,no doubt, by that perennial academic prejudice for <strong>the</strong> abstract over <strong>the</strong>applied dilutes attentions and energies that would be better directedelsewhere. It is <strong>the</strong>se concerns that fuel <strong>the</strong> brief treatment found <strong>in</strong> thischapter. It may not <strong>in</strong>itially appear to be of a piece with o<strong>the</strong>r parts of <strong>the</strong>discussion, but a cautionary note or two about an approach that hassteadily ga<strong>in</strong>ed ground <strong>in</strong> recent years may perhaps be useful as ageneral underp<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g for what follows.Stubbs (1984) provided an early discussion of <strong>the</strong> applicability ofdiscourse analysis to studies of language <strong>in</strong> education. Writ<strong>in</strong>g at a timewhen such analysis was a ‘recent and open-ended field’ (Stubbs, 1984:204) it is no longer so recent, of course, but it is probably even moreopen-ended he notes that contemporary l<strong>in</strong>guistics has neglectedlanguage use <strong>in</strong> specific areas (e.g. education, medic<strong>in</strong>e, law andreligion). It is not that <strong>the</strong>se areas have been entirely neglected, butra<strong>the</strong>r that l<strong>in</strong>guistics has left <strong>the</strong>m to o<strong>the</strong>r discipl<strong>in</strong>es (notablysociology). Cit<strong>in</strong>g Milroy (1984), who refers specifically to forensicmatters, Stubbs (1984: 236) claims that ‘if socially responsible l<strong>in</strong>guistsdo not do such analyses, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong>y will be done, but less well, by o<strong>the</strong>rs’.I th<strong>in</strong>k it is entirely reasonable to argue that l<strong>in</strong>guistic <strong>in</strong>sights cancomplement those from o<strong>the</strong>r vantage po<strong>in</strong>ts, but ‘less well’ is toodismissive of those o<strong>the</strong>rs (see Edwards, 2003a, on <strong>the</strong> dangers ofdiscipl<strong>in</strong>ary tunnel vision).24


Discourse Analysis and its Discontents 25Stubbs frames his argument as follows: ‘What k<strong>in</strong>d of understand<strong>in</strong>g oflanguage is relevant <strong>in</strong> teach<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> mo<strong>the</strong>r tongue or foreign languages,or <strong>in</strong> teach<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> general?’ (Stubbs, 1984: 206). Teachers certa<strong>in</strong>ly need tounderstand language: it is a truism that underp<strong>in</strong>s all educational effort.But how much, of what k<strong>in</strong>d and under which auspices? More po<strong>in</strong>tedly,how germane is <strong>the</strong> discipl<strong>in</strong>e of l<strong>in</strong>guistics <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>se regards? Atraditional po<strong>in</strong>t of rejection, based upon <strong>the</strong> perception (all toofrequently accurate), is that l<strong>in</strong>guistics per se is bound up with <strong>the</strong>oreticalmodels, tricked out <strong>in</strong> specialist jargons and too un<strong>in</strong>terested <strong>in</strong> ‘reallanguage behavior’ to be very relevant to <strong>the</strong> more immediate concernsof teachers. As Stubbs (p. 207) notes, many teachers ‘have an image of<strong>the</strong>mselves as practical and down-to-earth folks... tak<strong>in</strong>g a sensiblestand<strong>in</strong>g [sic] aga<strong>in</strong>st <strong>the</strong> impractical <strong>the</strong>oris<strong>in</strong>g of l<strong>in</strong>guists, sociologistsand psychologists of education, and all <strong>the</strong> rest’. 1 These outside<strong>in</strong>tellectuals can thus be seen as ra<strong>the</strong>r ‘s<strong>in</strong>ister figures <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> w<strong>in</strong>gs,fa<strong>in</strong>tly contemptuous, armed with <strong>the</strong> paraphernalia of expertise andtapp<strong>in</strong>g om<strong>in</strong>ously <strong>the</strong>ir research f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>gs’ (here, Stubbs is quot<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>words of Harold Rosen [1978], <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> pages of <strong>the</strong> now-defunct NewReview).Teachers are surely right to have misgiv<strong>in</strong>gs here. Indeed, beyond <strong>the</strong>po<strong>in</strong>ts already noted, <strong>the</strong>re is a fur<strong>the</strong>r, most salient one that reflects acharge often (and often fairly) levelled aga<strong>in</strong>st <strong>the</strong> social sciences: <strong>the</strong>y donot provide practitioners with new <strong>in</strong>sights so much as with old<strong>in</strong>formation, noxiously presented <strong>in</strong> pretentious bafflegab. Relatedly,although turn<strong>in</strong>g ‘unconscious’ knowledge <strong>in</strong>to more explicit andarticulated pr<strong>in</strong>ciple can be useful, ‘good teachers may justifiably feelthat it [discourse analysis] provides only a different slant on what <strong>the</strong>yalready do’ (Stubbs, 1984: 238). From <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r side, as it were, somel<strong>in</strong>guists have denied that <strong>the</strong>ir discipl<strong>in</strong>e has anyth<strong>in</strong>g substantial tooffer to language teachers, anyway (Sampson, 1980). But both Stubbsand Sampson seem to be discuss<strong>in</strong>g an awareness and sensitivity thatl<strong>in</strong>guistics might (or might not) be able to enhance for teachers oflanguage. Thus, Stubbs observes that discourse analysis could assist <strong>in</strong><strong>the</strong> structur<strong>in</strong>g of dialogues used <strong>in</strong> language-teach<strong>in</strong>g material, go<strong>in</strong>g onto cite o<strong>the</strong>r possible applications, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g heighten<strong>in</strong>g awareness ofcross-cultural differences <strong>in</strong> discursive norms.This is not quite <strong>the</strong> emphasis here, where we are more directlyconcerned with an expanded sensitivity towards language by teachersand o<strong>the</strong>rs, and with <strong>the</strong> contributions that various discipl<strong>in</strong>es mightmake towards (for example) eradicat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>accurate <strong>in</strong>formation aboutnonstandard dialects. Stubbs po<strong>in</strong>ts to <strong>the</strong> analysis of teacher-pupil


26 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong><strong>in</strong>teractions <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> classroom as ano<strong>the</strong>r possible application of discourse-analyticstudy, cites several studies focus<strong>in</strong>g upon miscommunicationand misunderstand<strong>in</strong>g, and comes closest to <strong>the</strong> present emphasiswith a brief mention of work on aborig<strong>in</strong>al nonstandard English <strong>in</strong>Australia. On this matter, Chomsky (1977: 5556) quite dismissive of asociol<strong>in</strong>guistics that he f<strong>in</strong>ds <strong>the</strong>oretically ‘evident and banal’, anundertak<strong>in</strong>g with ‘<strong>the</strong>oretical pretensions’ but one whose very existenceas a discipl<strong>in</strong>e is dubious ra<strong>the</strong>r grudg<strong>in</strong>gly concedes that work of thissort might be useful for combat<strong>in</strong>g educational mis<strong>in</strong>formation andprejudice (see also Edwards, 1994a). So, <strong>the</strong>re are possible open<strong>in</strong>gs here.Discourse analysis, for <strong>in</strong>stance, could conceivably be a diagnostic tool<strong>in</strong> highlight<strong>in</strong>g cross-cultural or cross-subcultural differences; once madesalient, <strong>the</strong>se might suggest alterations <strong>in</strong> expectations, teach<strong>in</strong>g methodsand so on. Of course, surface variety is less important here than <strong>the</strong> socialunderp<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>gs that give rise to it. As Corson (2001) observes, variations<strong>in</strong> discourse ‘norms’ imply variations <strong>in</strong> cultural values. Two of <strong>the</strong> earlyand important ethnographic/discourse studies <strong>in</strong> this connection werethose of Basso (1970) and Philips (1970, 1983). Both authors showed that<strong>the</strong> cultural norms of American Indians (<strong>the</strong> Apache of Arizona and <strong>the</strong>Sahapt<strong>in</strong> of Oregon, respectively) were sufficiently different from thoseof <strong>the</strong>ir white neighbors that reservation children often fell foul of <strong>the</strong>irteachers. The most salient difficulty was a reluctance to speak <strong>in</strong> class.Traditionally, teachers were likely to categorize <strong>the</strong>ir Indian pupils ascold and unresponsive, sullen or shy; such classroom perceptions reflectand re<strong>in</strong>force longheld stereotypes about Indian taciturnity. Thesegeneralizations are not all negative: after all, silence can be golden, and<strong>the</strong>re is <strong>the</strong> myth of <strong>the</strong> ‘noble savage’, reserved and dignified, a model ofgravitas. But <strong>in</strong> contemporary sett<strong>in</strong>gs of cultures-<strong>in</strong>-contact, <strong>the</strong>y can alsolead to assessments of l<strong>in</strong>guistic and cognitive deficiency.There are at least three unfavorable consequences of teachers’perceptions of children’s silence. First, s<strong>in</strong>ce <strong>the</strong>y will not have <strong>the</strong>type of feedback with which <strong>the</strong>y are familiar, teachers may have only apartial or <strong>in</strong>accurate sense of <strong>the</strong>ir pupils’ abilities and academicshortcom<strong>in</strong>gs. Second, teachers may gradually adapt <strong>the</strong>ir classroomprocedures so as to reduce unpleasant or uncomfortable situations; <strong>in</strong> sodo<strong>in</strong>g, however, <strong>the</strong>y may lessen <strong>the</strong>ir role as a model of ‘standard’norms and practice, a model by which nonstandard speakers typicallydevelop useful ‘bidialectal’ skills. Third, teachers may draw very<strong>in</strong>accurate conclusions about <strong>the</strong> cultures from which <strong>the</strong>ir pupilscome (see also <strong>the</strong> observations of Wax & Wax, 1971). 2


Discourse Analysis and its Discontents 27When touch<strong>in</strong>g upon conversational analysis <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> classroom <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>last chapter, I mentioned <strong>the</strong> recent work of Julé (2004). Her work withgirls is particularly timely, given recent tendencies to sw<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>educational focus from girls to boys. For quite a long time, <strong>the</strong> literaturewas full of studies describ<strong>in</strong>g ways <strong>in</strong> which <strong>the</strong> presence of boys <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>classroom was a h<strong>in</strong>drance to girls’ education; much of it demonstrated,unsurpris<strong>in</strong>gly, that patterns of male-female <strong>in</strong>teraction outside <strong>the</strong>school gates were replicated with<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>m. Now, however, <strong>in</strong>terest <strong>in</strong><strong>the</strong> education of boys seems to be grow<strong>in</strong>g: a recent popular treatmentwas titled The War Aga<strong>in</strong>st Boys (Sommers, 2000). Some have argued thatboys do not do well <strong>in</strong> a ‘fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e’ school environment, o<strong>the</strong>rs feel that amore complicated male ‘disengagement’ with education is at work, whilestill o<strong>the</strong>rs th<strong>in</strong>k that it is all someth<strong>in</strong>g of a non-issue. There rema<strong>in</strong>s,however, considerable agreement that, whatever else may be <strong>the</strong> case,boys still tend to dom<strong>in</strong>ate <strong>in</strong> verbal <strong>in</strong>teraction. Julé builds uponprevious research, not<strong>in</strong>g that male dom<strong>in</strong>ance is someth<strong>in</strong>g with whichteachers’ behavior correlates, even though <strong>the</strong>y may feel that <strong>the</strong>y ‘treat<strong>the</strong>m all <strong>the</strong> same’ (Corson, 1993: 144). Generally speak<strong>in</strong>g, boys cont<strong>in</strong>ueto ‘receive a disproportionate share of teachers’ time and attention’(Stanworth, 1981: 18), and girls may f<strong>in</strong>d <strong>the</strong>mselves <strong>in</strong> a double b<strong>in</strong>d.Spender (1980), for <strong>in</strong>stance, has noted that <strong>the</strong> approval of girls’behavior by teachers (and o<strong>the</strong>rs, of course) may depend preciselyupon <strong>the</strong> very verbal restra<strong>in</strong>t that allows <strong>the</strong> more forceful boys toma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir dom<strong>in</strong>ant position. These sorts of gender-variant f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>gsare quite general, cutt<strong>in</strong>g across class and ethnic l<strong>in</strong>es. 3Julé’s work illustrates <strong>the</strong>se matters. Her analyses reveal that teacherstypically dom<strong>in</strong>ate <strong>the</strong> ‘l<strong>in</strong>guistic space’ <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> classroom to an overwhelm<strong>in</strong>gdegree and, of <strong>the</strong> small portion available to <strong>the</strong> pupils, <strong>the</strong>ratio of girls’ to boys’ verbal contributions is on <strong>the</strong> order of 1:10. Thereare, of course, limitations <strong>in</strong> any <strong>in</strong>vestigation, but Julé’s f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>gs withyoung Punjabi Sikh children <strong>in</strong> Canada mirror a great many o<strong>the</strong>rs; hers,<strong>in</strong>deed, have a particular <strong>in</strong>terest because <strong>the</strong>y <strong>in</strong>volve <strong>the</strong> jo<strong>in</strong>t <strong>in</strong>fluenceof gender and ethnicity (a comb<strong>in</strong>ation of <strong>in</strong>fluences that Corson [2001]explicitly po<strong>in</strong>ts to as relatively neglected <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> literature). While it istrue that Punjabi Sikh culture is more open to gender equality than aresome neighbor<strong>in</strong>g societies, <strong>the</strong> author notes that ‘equity is notnecessarily <strong>the</strong> lived experience’ (p. 69). The results of Julé’s small-scalestudy may thus highlight more clearly <strong>the</strong> silenc<strong>in</strong>g of girls at school,with implications for o<strong>the</strong>r cultural variants (or heterogeneities) <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>classroom, or, <strong>in</strong>deed with subcultural variants, as, for <strong>in</strong>stance, withpopulations whose maternal dialects are nonstandard.


28 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>Discourse Difficulties<strong>Language</strong> and ethnographyA couple of years ago, I was asked to act as a discussant on anacademic panel convened <strong>in</strong> honor of Robert Kaplan, one of <strong>the</strong> lead<strong>in</strong>glights <strong>in</strong> applied l<strong>in</strong>guistics. As a friend and colleague, I was more thanhappy to do so, but I was ill-prepared for <strong>the</strong> flood of ill-advised psychol<strong>in</strong>guistico-educationalverbiage. There is a field, for <strong>in</strong>stance, called‘English for Academic Purposes’ (EAP), which obviously cannot be anysort of <strong>in</strong>dependent enquiry; recent pieces by Ferris (2005) and Johns(2005) amply demonstrate that, when it is not restat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> obvious, EAPexudes a pseudo-<strong>in</strong>tellectualism that is likely to appeal only to those<strong>in</strong>terested <strong>in</strong> ‘critical pedagogy’, or ‘critical l<strong>in</strong>guistics’ or ‘criticalfram<strong>in</strong>g’. One can also <strong>in</strong>dulge <strong>in</strong> ‘contrastive rhetoric’ or ‘contrastivediscourse analysis’ (see below), two of whose proponents (Connor &Moreno, 2005) employ <strong>the</strong> Lat<strong>in</strong> phrase tertium comparationis <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir titleand <strong>the</strong>ir text. Now, I have no Orwellian aversion to us<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> occasionalbon mot or Lat<strong>in</strong> tag, but putt<strong>in</strong>g such a generally unfamiliar phrase on<strong>the</strong> mas<strong>the</strong>ad is surely a ra<strong>the</strong>r transparent effort at impressionformation(as <strong>the</strong> social psychologists would say). 4Discourse analysis and <strong>the</strong> many ‘critical’ sub-areas with which it isoften associated have become <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>gly <strong>in</strong>ward-look<strong>in</strong>g. An excessivelove of micro-<strong>the</strong>ory has resulted <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> sort of technical sub-specializationsnoted above (see also Wodak, 2006). The general area has also becomea volatile one with much <strong>in</strong>ternal wrangl<strong>in</strong>g an <strong>in</strong>stance, perhaps, of<strong>the</strong> dictum that academic <strong>in</strong>fight<strong>in</strong>g is so vicious because <strong>the</strong> stakes areso low and an <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>g amount of jargon.Consider first <strong>the</strong> ethnographic approach, whose emphasis upon <strong>the</strong>context with<strong>in</strong> which social <strong>in</strong>teractions occur can as we have just seen produce useful cross-cultural <strong>in</strong>sights. It is a qualitative ra<strong>the</strong>r thanquantitative exercise and often relies upon close and <strong>in</strong>timate contact forits data. ‘Participant observation’ <strong>in</strong> one form or ano<strong>the</strong>r is <strong>the</strong>methodology of choice. The work of Dell Hymes (see Gumperz &Hymes, 1964) gave a specific l<strong>in</strong>guistic focus to <strong>the</strong> enterprise: hence, <strong>the</strong>‘ethnography of communication’. Opposed to <strong>the</strong> reductionist andnarrowly experimental tendencies <strong>in</strong> much social-scientific work, aphenomenological approach seemed a welcome and appropriate change.And it is true that <strong>the</strong>re have been, from <strong>the</strong> beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g, some classicstudies (e.g. Cazden, 1988; Heath, 1983). But, also from <strong>the</strong> beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>the</strong>approach began to produce its own difficulties, particularly <strong>in</strong> itsexam<strong>in</strong>ation of <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>gly narrower slices of reality. Holism, an


Discourse Analysis and its Discontents 29emphasis upon so-called ‘lived experience’ (as opposed, one surmises, tosome unlived variety), and a concern for procedural breadth and depthhave tended to give way to a new reductionism.Tust<strong>in</strong>g and Mayb<strong>in</strong> (2007: 576) have recently argued for a new termhere ‘l<strong>in</strong>guistic ethnography’ as part of an emerg<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>terdiscipl<strong>in</strong>aryreconfiguration ‘<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> contexts of late modernity and globalisation’. Thecollection to which <strong>the</strong>ir paper is an <strong>in</strong>troduction (Rampton et al., 2007)and an earlier piece (Rampton et al., 2004) flesh matters out here; <strong>the</strong>latter notes that:l<strong>in</strong>guistic ethnography generally holds that, to a considerable degree,language and <strong>the</strong> social world are mutually shap<strong>in</strong>g, and that closeanalysis of situated language use can provide both fundamental anddist<strong>in</strong>ctive <strong>in</strong>sights <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> mechanisms and dynamics of social andcultural production <strong>in</strong> everyday activity. (Rampton et al., 2004: 2)Rampton (2007: 585) goes on to say that l<strong>in</strong>guistic ethnography is bestcharacterized as a ‘site of encounter’ where various research perspectivescan come toge<strong>the</strong>r; <strong>the</strong> assumption is that ‘<strong>the</strong> contexts for communicationshould be <strong>in</strong>vestigated ra<strong>the</strong>r than assumed’. These hardly seemorig<strong>in</strong>al observations. And We<strong>the</strong>rell (2007: 668) suggests that <strong>the</strong>contributions of l<strong>in</strong>guistic ethnography to our understand<strong>in</strong>g of identitywould benefit if we dropped <strong>the</strong> latter term, replac<strong>in</strong>g it with ‘personalorder’:Personal order is derived from social order but is not isomorphicwith it. A person... is a site, like <strong>in</strong>stitutions or social <strong>in</strong>teraction,where flows of mean<strong>in</strong>g-mak<strong>in</strong>g practices or semiosis... becomeorganised. Over time particular rout<strong>in</strong>es, repetitions, procedures andmodes of practice build up to form personal style, psycho-biographyand life history, and become a guide for how to go on <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>present... In <strong>the</strong> case of personal order, <strong>the</strong> relevant practices couldbe described as ‘‘psycho-discursive’’... those which among <strong>the</strong> sumof social practices constitute a psychology, formulate a mental lifeand have consequences for <strong>the</strong> formation and representation of <strong>the</strong>person.I apologize for <strong>in</strong>flict<strong>in</strong>g so much of this on <strong>the</strong> reader, but it is importantto realize that this sort of wheel-sp<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g has come to attract more andmore adherents. If one looks back over <strong>the</strong> publications record of thosewho now seem to specialize <strong>in</strong> pseudo-<strong>in</strong>sights, one typically f<strong>in</strong>ds that<strong>the</strong>y began <strong>the</strong>ir careers by writ<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>in</strong> English, about important th<strong>in</strong>gs, <strong>in</strong>ways that reasonably <strong>in</strong>telligent people could understand. It is a great


30 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>pity that <strong>the</strong>y, and <strong>the</strong>ir fields of <strong>in</strong>terest, have been seduced by falseprophets.An enterprise that might reasonably be expected to stress <strong>the</strong> ‘macro’levels of social life (or, at least, to use more ‘micro’ optics to exemplify orcomplement wider concerns) has come more and more to devote itself toexceed<strong>in</strong>gly f<strong>in</strong>e-gra<strong>in</strong>ed matters. Its relevance to larger sett<strong>in</strong>gs classrooms, for <strong>in</strong>stance has dramatically receded. This methodologicalnarrow<strong>in</strong>g has been heightened by divisions with<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> discipl<strong>in</strong>e, with<strong>the</strong> attendant proliferation of jargon, debates over term<strong>in</strong>ology and,above all, a revived sense of <strong>the</strong> dist<strong>in</strong>ctions between ‘pure’ <strong>the</strong>ory andgrubby application. The predictable result is an <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>gly <strong>in</strong>cestuousfield <strong>in</strong> which researchers speak only to one ano<strong>the</strong>r: a replication, that isto say, of <strong>the</strong> disembodied and decontextualized sterility that <strong>the</strong>ethnographic thrust was meant to replace. In a criticism of <strong>the</strong> lack ofattention paid to race and racism <strong>in</strong> discourse studies an importantcriticism, given <strong>the</strong> stated aims of both discourse analysis and its morepo<strong>in</strong>ted relation, ‘critical discourse analysis’ (see below) Yancy (1998: 3)has noted that <strong>the</strong> field too often reflects ‘<strong>the</strong> words of white menengaged <strong>in</strong> conversation with <strong>the</strong>mselves’. Luke (1995) and Rogers et al.(2005: 385) have made similar observations; <strong>the</strong> latter remark that,beyond <strong>in</strong>adequate attention to <strong>the</strong> languages and cultures of m<strong>in</strong>oritygroups, discourse frameworks ‘have cont<strong>in</strong>ued to silence and oppresshistorically marg<strong>in</strong>alized groups of people’. This, of course, is a muchmore serious charge, although its practical force is lessened by some of<strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r characteristics of <strong>the</strong> genre, characteristics that make it unlikelythat it has any particular <strong>in</strong>fluence to ei<strong>the</strong>r advance or retard <strong>the</strong>fortunes of <strong>the</strong> marg<strong>in</strong>alized.Exam<strong>in</strong>ation of language <strong>in</strong> context, with a particular concern for <strong>the</strong>ways <strong>in</strong> which l<strong>in</strong>guistic <strong>in</strong>teractions illustrate and susta<strong>in</strong> positions ofpower and status, constitute <strong>the</strong> framework with<strong>in</strong> which discourseanalysis has arisen. This is, <strong>in</strong>deed, a framework of great potential<strong>in</strong>terest and importance. Much of <strong>the</strong> work <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> area, however, reflectsvery particular ideological assumptions about status relationships <strong>in</strong>various social sett<strong>in</strong>gs, and about <strong>the</strong> constituents of those relationships.There is a strong post-structural and post-modern accent here (seeWardhaugh, 2006). Apart from left-lean<strong>in</strong>g ideological tendencies, thismeans that <strong>the</strong> idea that <strong>the</strong>re might be objective truth unatta<strong>in</strong>able asthis may be <strong>in</strong> any complete way is speedily and ra<strong>the</strong>r happilyjettisoned <strong>in</strong> favor of a dynamic and often <strong>in</strong>determ<strong>in</strong>ate subjectivity.What were once <strong>the</strong> parlor games of French <strong>in</strong>tellectuals whosepersonal lives, despite all <strong>the</strong>ir vaunted <strong>in</strong>terest <strong>in</strong> ‘decenter<strong>in</strong>g’ and


Discourse Analysis and its Discontents 31‘deconstruction’, typically reveal a ra<strong>the</strong>r considerable center<strong>in</strong>g on<strong>the</strong>mselves have taken on a bizarre totemic status <strong>in</strong> various academicfields.Discourse analysis and its offspr<strong>in</strong>gDiscourse analysis is sometimes differentiated from conversationalanalysis; while <strong>the</strong> latter aims to assess how conversation ‘works’, <strong>the</strong>former may <strong>in</strong>volve more structural analysis (see also below). It may alsobe applied to written samples, although some use <strong>the</strong> term ‘text analysis’for this. As Stubbs (1983b) po<strong>in</strong>ted out, early on, <strong>the</strong>re is a good deal ofoverlap, not to say imprecision, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>se terms. (Consider, by way ofcomparison, <strong>the</strong> common ground often trodden by <strong>the</strong> social psychologyof language, sociol<strong>in</strong>guistics and <strong>the</strong> sociology of language.) Stubbsargued for discourse analysis as <strong>the</strong> avenue for study<strong>in</strong>g classroom<strong>in</strong>teraction, and cited an <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>g dissatisfaction with traditionalpsychological work based upon experimental manipulation; later, Stubbs(1986) provided a discussion of language and education <strong>in</strong> whichdiscourse analysis figured prom<strong>in</strong>ently (perhaps too prom<strong>in</strong>ently; seeViv Edwards, 1987). The thrust was given even more force by Potter andWe<strong>the</strong>rell (1987), who argued that discourse analysis should be at <strong>the</strong>center of <strong>the</strong> whole social-psychological enterprise: <strong>the</strong>y po<strong>in</strong>t out thatsocial life is, after all, largely a matter of discourse. Part of <strong>the</strong>irargument, however, was also to dismiss some of <strong>the</strong> traditional emphases<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> area (e.g. attitudes, particularly as elicited via questionnaires), andthis clearly struck a chord. Antaki (1988), for example, observed that <strong>the</strong>irwork could ‘rescue’ social psychology from its current laboratoryorientated‘sterility’ (see also Billig, 1988; Smith, 1988). Harré and Gillett(1994) and Harré and Stearns (1995) also discuss a new ‘discursive’psychology, meant to largely replace exist<strong>in</strong>g experimental paradigms. Ina review essay, Giles and Coupland (1989) offered a fur<strong>the</strong>r assessment.While agree<strong>in</strong>g about <strong>the</strong> potentially significant role for discourseanalysis with<strong>in</strong> social psychology, <strong>the</strong>y cautioned aga<strong>in</strong>st elevat<strong>in</strong>g ittoo highly, or too <strong>in</strong>dependently, over o<strong>the</strong>r worthwhile approaches. And<strong>in</strong>deed, we should on pr<strong>in</strong>ciple be chary about new waves, and not beoverly quick to discard exist<strong>in</strong>g methods and <strong>in</strong>sights; eclectic perspectives,ones that stress methodological triangulation, are almost alwayspreferable.A parallel development to <strong>the</strong> one advocated above has been thatwhich led from ‘ethnomethodology’ to ‘conversation analysis’, where <strong>the</strong>latter obviously converges and often overlaps with discourse analysis.


32 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>The trajectories are remarkably similar. Ethnomethodology (see Garf<strong>in</strong>kel,1967) was also <strong>in</strong>itially concerned with fuller and more realisticcontextualization of <strong>in</strong>teraction, advocat<strong>in</strong>g a more productive connectionbetween f<strong>in</strong>e-gra<strong>in</strong>ed observation and <strong>the</strong> larger social canvas. Butethnomethodological <strong>in</strong>quiry was <strong>the</strong>oretically so broad <strong>in</strong> its remit thatany discipl<strong>in</strong>ary precision soon became quite unatta<strong>in</strong>able. 5 As LewisCoser (1975) put it <strong>in</strong> his presidential address to <strong>the</strong> American SociologicalAssociation, ethnomethodology and allied undertak<strong>in</strong>gs are more likesects or cliques: closed systems <strong>in</strong> which members talk to o<strong>the</strong>r members,where <strong>in</strong>sights exist that are denied to outsiders. In l<strong>in</strong>e with what I havealready mentioned, we also expect to f<strong>in</strong>d here violent <strong>in</strong>ternec<strong>in</strong>estruggles coupled with equally violent sw<strong>in</strong>gs of focus: problems arenot dealt with <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> cumulative manner that is <strong>the</strong> hallmark of science;ra<strong>the</strong>r, old perspectives are simply replaced by newer fashions. Coser alsoremarks on <strong>the</strong> curious tendency (not limited to ethnomethodologists, ofcourse) for those professionally <strong>in</strong>terested <strong>in</strong> language and communicationto be such poor communicators <strong>the</strong>mselves. One of <strong>the</strong> mostnoticeable characteristics here is flatulent verbosity. Coser cites ahundred-word description (from Sudnow, 1972) that conveys <strong>the</strong> messagethat we should be careful when cross<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> road. In a review ofGarf<strong>in</strong>kel’s ‘sem<strong>in</strong>al’ text, Coleman (1968: 130) succ<strong>in</strong>ctly observes thatethnomethodology <strong>in</strong>volves ‘an extraord<strong>in</strong>arily high ratio of read<strong>in</strong>g timeto <strong>in</strong>formation transfer’. Just so.The particular l<strong>in</strong>guistic offspr<strong>in</strong>g of ethnomethodology is conversationanalysis. Although it is notoriously difficult to draw boundariesamong <strong>the</strong> various approaches here, conversation analysis does attendmore to <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>tricacies and mechanics of talk itself <strong>the</strong> sequenc<strong>in</strong>g ofutterances, fluency and ‘smoothness’, <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>itiation and term<strong>in</strong>ation ofconversational <strong>in</strong>terchange, <strong>the</strong> rules and practices govern<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>terruptionsand <strong>in</strong>terjections, <strong>the</strong> appropriateness of topics (and of <strong>the</strong> styles <strong>in</strong>which <strong>the</strong>y are to be discussed) and <strong>the</strong> etiquettes of turn-tak<strong>in</strong>g whereas discourse analysis is (<strong>the</strong>oretically) more likely to place suchmatters with<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> broader scope of power and status relationships.Given its emphases, conversation analysis could be of some use <strong>in</strong>understand<strong>in</strong>g classroom dynamics. As Tony Edwards (1976: 180) put it,traditional classrooms are ‘places contrived for <strong>the</strong> controlled transmissionof knowledge. This is what gives <strong>the</strong>m <strong>the</strong>ir peculiar identity assett<strong>in</strong>gs for talk’. (It should be noted here that some analysts, <strong>in</strong>sist<strong>in</strong>g on<strong>the</strong> study of ‘natural’ conversations, have seen classrooms as ‘unnatural’.This raises questions, of course, about just what we are to construe asnatural or artificial.) As well, <strong>in</strong> her study of language pathologies, Lesser


Discourse Analysis and its Discontents 33(2003) makes <strong>the</strong> reasonable claim that conversation analysis can provediagnostically useful <strong>in</strong> some studies of aphasia; this can, of course, onlyoccur with a base knowledge of <strong>the</strong> talk of ‘ord<strong>in</strong>ary’ or ‘normal’ people(see also Čmejrková & Prevignano, 2003). While this may be a goodexample of <strong>the</strong> usefulness of conversational-analytic procedures, it alsohighlights potential shortcom<strong>in</strong>gs.Conversation analysis has been applied <strong>in</strong> all sorts of sett<strong>in</strong>gs, but it isclearly of greater potential use <strong>in</strong> situations that can draw upon reflectivestudy: more applicable, <strong>the</strong>n, <strong>in</strong> cl<strong>in</strong>ical speech analyses than <strong>in</strong> (say)emergency telephone calls to police or fire departments. (Speech analystsof various stripes very much enjoy gett<strong>in</strong>g to grips with dramatic ‘realworld’exchanges.) Even scholarly <strong>in</strong>sights <strong>in</strong>to doctor-patient or lawyerclient<strong>in</strong>tercourse are likely to allow for less contemplative analysis. Toput it ano<strong>the</strong>r way: <strong>the</strong> reams of conversational-analytic literature are notlikely to come <strong>in</strong>to play <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> immediacy of important and/or highlyemotional sett<strong>in</strong>gs; <strong>the</strong>y may allow (as Lesser implies, for example) somecomparative <strong>in</strong>sights when time permits. But consider this: when timepermits, we are all pretty good at figur<strong>in</strong>g out what conversations reallymean. We have been learn<strong>in</strong>g all about this, all about read<strong>in</strong>g (orlisten<strong>in</strong>g) between <strong>the</strong> l<strong>in</strong>es, from a very early age. We typically do notemploy our more or less automatic skills here with <strong>the</strong> jargon ofacademic speech analysis, but this does not seem to have h<strong>in</strong>dered usvery much. Now, one could argue that a formalization of our <strong>in</strong>terpretativeexercises might be very useful <strong>in</strong>-depth analyses, perhaps,presented back to us <strong>in</strong> ways that ref<strong>in</strong>e and improve our skills. This is<strong>the</strong>oretically so, but s<strong>in</strong>ce conversation analysis, like its sister subdiscipl<strong>in</strong>es,has <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>gly become a rarefied parlor game for enthusiasts,we ought not to bank upon revelation any time soon.In a fur<strong>the</strong>r iteration, ‘critical discourse analysis’ (CDA) has become avery popular format for <strong>the</strong> analysis of speech and language. Blommaert(2005) tells us that it is <strong>the</strong> most ‘visible’ of <strong>the</strong> current approaches to <strong>the</strong>study of language <strong>in</strong> society. There are, of course, o<strong>the</strong>rs: anthropologicall<strong>in</strong>guistics, sociol<strong>in</strong>guistics, <strong>the</strong> sociology/social psychology of languageand o<strong>the</strong>r more traditional avenues of enquiry. But s<strong>in</strong>ce CDA is a fieldwhose ma<strong>in</strong> arenas are those of ‘political discourse, media, advertisement,ideology, racism [and] <strong>in</strong>stitutional discourse’ (Blommaert, 2005:21), it has clearly positioned itself to be timely and relevant. It is notideologically neutral, of course. Concerned with real problems <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> realworld, more specifically with <strong>the</strong> illum<strong>in</strong>ation and redress of social<strong>in</strong>equality, it was ‘perceived by many as liberat<strong>in</strong>g, because it wasupfront about its own, explicitly left-w<strong>in</strong>g, political commitment’


Discourse Analysis and its Discontents 35<strong>the</strong>ory (e.g. Giles & Coupland, 1991). The useful overview of CDAprovided by Rogers et al. (2005) will demonstrate to all but <strong>the</strong> fiercest offellow travellers some of <strong>the</strong> mundane truisms that <strong>the</strong> labors of ‘critical’<strong>the</strong>orists have produced. Overall, it should come as no surprise to learnthat criticisms of CDA focus upon its ra<strong>the</strong>r <strong>in</strong>cestuous nature and itsdecontextualized approach to <strong>the</strong> micro-exam<strong>in</strong>ation of written andspoken language both deeply ironical, given <strong>the</strong> field’s argument forsocial <strong>in</strong>cisiveness and, <strong>in</strong>deed, social action. Rogers et al. (2005: 383) notethat <strong>the</strong> analyses <strong>the</strong>y conducted of <strong>the</strong> characteristics, contexts andresults of almost four dozen CDA studies (specifically <strong>in</strong> educationalsett<strong>in</strong>gs) revealed that <strong>the</strong> work was essentially descriptive, focus<strong>in</strong>g ‘on<strong>the</strong> ways <strong>in</strong> which power is reproduced ra<strong>the</strong>r than on how it is changed,resisted, and transformed toward liberatory ends’; see also Luke (2004)on <strong>the</strong> ‘deconstructive’ ra<strong>the</strong>r than ‘reconstructive’ efforts here.Meant to overturn a sterile empiricism largely practiced by and formembers of <strong>the</strong> hegemonic ‘ma<strong>in</strong>stream’, discourse analysis and itsoffshoots have <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>gly become <strong>in</strong>troverted and isolated enterprises.Like a game of chess (but more elaborate, <strong>in</strong> that <strong>the</strong>re are <strong>in</strong>f<strong>in</strong>itepossibilities for redef<strong>in</strong>ition and realignment of <strong>the</strong> rules), <strong>the</strong>y arefasc<strong>in</strong>at<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>the</strong>ir players, but <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>gly divorced from social reality.I note that Paul Chilton (2004: x), <strong>in</strong> his recent book on politicaldiscourse, admits that ‘I do not know if discourse analysts can haveany serious impact on <strong>the</strong> genocides, oppressions and exploitations weare still witness<strong>in</strong>g’, and one of his reviewers broadens <strong>the</strong> po<strong>in</strong>t byask<strong>in</strong>g ‘what effect discourse analysts could potentially have on worldaffairs’ (Hodges, 2005: 247). The naïveté here is truly touch<strong>in</strong>g. 6 Theattention that CDA gives to <strong>the</strong> larger context is also dubious <strong>in</strong> practice,even though it is <strong>the</strong>oretically <strong>in</strong>tended to connect broader social <strong>the</strong>orywith f<strong>in</strong>e-gra<strong>in</strong>ed attention to discourse. Rogers et al. (2005) note that thisis an emphasis that dist<strong>in</strong>guishes it from <strong>the</strong> more purely ‘micro’approaches of, say, conversational analysis. Of course, how <strong>the</strong> lattercould, itself, be worth <strong>the</strong> candle without some sense of <strong>the</strong> norms andimperatives of conversational sett<strong>in</strong>gs is a question worth ask<strong>in</strong>g, even if,as Rogers et al. (2005: 378) po<strong>in</strong>t out, <strong>the</strong> idea of ‘context’ is limited: anemphasis upon <strong>the</strong> ‘here and now of <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>teraction, not what camebefore or after it’. This is an emasculated notion of ‘context’, to be sure.Putt<strong>in</strong>g aside worries about <strong>the</strong> lack of contextualization, <strong>the</strong> relatedmatter of how particular speech and language samples are chosen fromlarger ongo<strong>in</strong>g ‘<strong>in</strong>teractions’ is important. Choices are frequently madewithout any compell<strong>in</strong>g justification, rais<strong>in</strong>g questions of ‘representativeness,selectivity, partiality, prejudice and voice’ (Blommaert, 2005: 31;


36 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>see also Rogers et al., 2005). One of <strong>the</strong> consequences would seem to be apotentially endless series of fact-ga<strong>the</strong>r<strong>in</strong>g exercises, and observers havenoted <strong>the</strong> difficulties <strong>in</strong> a field <strong>in</strong> which <strong>the</strong> explanations can be so muchmore detailed (and take up so much more space) than <strong>the</strong> phenomenaunder study. Hymes (1986), for example some of whose work arguesfor and illustrates ethnographic approaches to <strong>the</strong> study of languagediversity (see above, and Hymes, 1974) has mounted some cogentcriticism.An excellent example of <strong>the</strong> matter is found <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> work of Grimshaw(1989), who devotes more than 600 pages to an analysis of a committee’sevalution of a doctoral dissertation. The actual transcript used here wasless than 300 l<strong>in</strong>es of text, represent<strong>in</strong>g about 10 m<strong>in</strong>utes of conversationamong four exam<strong>in</strong>ers! (This is clearly a great improvement on Borges’s[1999] famous map of <strong>the</strong> world on a scale of 1:1, because here we have<strong>the</strong> potential for a map of <strong>the</strong> sociol<strong>in</strong>guistic world many times largerthan <strong>the</strong> actual world itself. 7 ) A reviewer po<strong>in</strong>ted out that <strong>the</strong>re is‘excessive description at <strong>the</strong> expense of analytical relevance... overlylong and <strong>in</strong> too many places overwritten’, and that some of <strong>the</strong>descriptions are ‘impressionistic and ad hoc’ (Firth, 1996: 1489), butalso argues that Grimshaw has actually been too simplistic <strong>in</strong> places! In acompanion collection, Grimshaw (1994: 453454) admits that ‘we havecollectively produced nei<strong>the</strong>r a ‘‘comprehensive discourse analysis’’[CDA] nor a ‘‘unified <strong>the</strong>ory of sociol<strong>in</strong>guistic description’’... we have,if anyth<strong>in</strong>g, demonstrated that CDA is a chimera’. And Firth, whileacknowledg<strong>in</strong>g how could he not? that Grimshaw’s work shows‘how much can be extracted from a relatively short segment’, ends hisreview by say<strong>in</strong>g that ‘for students of spoken <strong>in</strong>teraction, such anexperience confirms what is already known’. Parturiunt montes; nasceturridiculus mus.In its various guises and emphases, discourse analysis rema<strong>in</strong>spopular <strong>in</strong> many circles, but it is hard to see that it has created abreak-through of any significance for its <strong>in</strong>tended beneficiaries. It hasdone its practitioners some considerable good, at least with<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>bredconf<strong>in</strong>es that <strong>the</strong>y <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>gly <strong>in</strong>habit. I am well aware, of course, thatmost of <strong>the</strong> work, of most social scientists, most of <strong>the</strong> time, makes verylittle direct contribution towards <strong>the</strong> societies with<strong>in</strong> which it operates.But we should surely be particularly careful when consider<strong>in</strong>g areaswhose very existence is based upon <strong>the</strong> desire to produce applicableresults, whose f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>gs are generally ga<strong>the</strong>red ‘<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> field’, but whosesense of that field is restricted, and whose production of jargon andneologism <strong>in</strong>creases at a geometric pace.


Discourse Analysis and its Discontents 37Notes1. Stubbs himself illustrates one of <strong>the</strong> dangers here. It is hard to imag<strong>in</strong>e say<strong>in</strong>gto an overworked and underpaid teacher, particularly one who hasimmediate need to deal appropriately with heterogeneity <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> classroom:Both <strong>the</strong> overall macrostructure of narratives, descriptions, explanations,and <strong>the</strong> like, and also <strong>the</strong> micropropositional development of texts fromsentence to sentence, are seen as cognitive schemas which play animportant part <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> comprehension and production of texts. (Stubbs,1984: 226)Well, you might say that Stubbs is not talk<strong>in</strong>g directly to teachers here. Butremember that his chapter and <strong>the</strong> collection of which it is a part is allabout application <strong>in</strong> real-life sett<strong>in</strong>gs. In his brief preface, <strong>the</strong> editor of <strong>the</strong> booksays that it should be of <strong>in</strong>terest to language teachers and ‘educationists’(Trudgill, 1984). And consider, f<strong>in</strong>ally, that such high-flown phras<strong>in</strong>g tends tocreep <strong>in</strong> wherever <strong>the</strong>oreticians meet practitioners.2. Mean<strong>in</strong>gful cultural variations may occur throughout <strong>the</strong> educationalprocess, and <strong>in</strong> subtle ways. When I first came to work at St Francis XavierUniversity <strong>in</strong> nor<strong>the</strong>astern Nova Scotia, I was struck by <strong>the</strong> passivity of mycharges: compared with <strong>the</strong> urban students I had been familiar with, <strong>the</strong>seseemed deferential and silent. To get any sort of classroom discussion go<strong>in</strong>gproved very difficult and, for some students, no technique of encouragementseemed to work. My expectations, like those of <strong>the</strong> white teachers onAmerican Indian reservations, were low. And yet, I soon discovered that<strong>the</strong>se students were as bright as any, that <strong>the</strong>ir written work was on a par withthat of <strong>the</strong>ir urban counterparts (not that this is say<strong>in</strong>g a great deal, of course),and that with time, and particularly <strong>in</strong> sem<strong>in</strong>ar sett<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>the</strong>y would<strong>in</strong>deed participate.I had simply been unaware of some of <strong>the</strong> cultural values of <strong>the</strong> NovaScotian Scots: traditionally committed to educational ‘improvement’, hav<strong>in</strong>g avery strong sense of place and community it is not at all unusual for localpeople to know everyth<strong>in</strong>g about <strong>the</strong>ir genealogical history, go<strong>in</strong>g back atleast to <strong>the</strong> time of <strong>the</strong> Clearances respectful to <strong>the</strong> ‘dom<strong>in</strong>ie’ and, untilfairly recently, grounded <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Scots Gaelic language.3. Coverage of <strong>the</strong> important gender issues <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> classroom is hardly exhausted<strong>in</strong> my few paragraphs here. The most important dynamics, however, can bededuced from <strong>the</strong> broader literature on women’s and men’s language (seelater chapters), for <strong>in</strong> l<strong>in</strong>guistic (and o<strong>the</strong>r) reflections of social values andpractices, <strong>the</strong> classroom is often a microcosm of <strong>the</strong> world outside <strong>the</strong> schoolgates. I should also br<strong>in</strong>g readers’ attention to Corson’s (2001) excellentsummary chapter, a section of a book whose overall purpose is broadlysimilar to that of this one.Rampton’s (2006: 70) detailed ethnographic enquiry of urban work<strong>in</strong>gclassschoolchildren also highlights ‘<strong>the</strong> broad contrast between boys talk<strong>in</strong>gand girls keep<strong>in</strong>g silent’. He notes, however, that such a rough dist<strong>in</strong>ctionmasks some complexities: <strong>the</strong>re are boys who generally keep quiet <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>classroom, and <strong>the</strong>re are girls who are vocal. The reasons for ei<strong>the</strong>r


38 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>participat<strong>in</strong>g or rema<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g silent vary greatly; <strong>the</strong> context <strong>the</strong> topic ofconversation, for example must be taken <strong>in</strong>to account; and so on.4. There is someth<strong>in</strong>g particularly ironic <strong>in</strong> us<strong>in</strong>g an unfamiliar Lat<strong>in</strong> term <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>American academic context. This, after all, is a sett<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> which facility withany language but English is uncommon, <strong>in</strong> which work <strong>in</strong> any language butEnglish is essentially disregarded, and <strong>in</strong> which titles and references <strong>in</strong> anylanguage but English must be given <strong>in</strong> translation. This seems to be true, even<strong>in</strong> circles where one might have expected a little flexibility. A few years ago, Ipublished a piece about bil<strong>in</strong>gualism (Edwards, 1999a), <strong>in</strong> a special journalissue devoted to <strong>the</strong> topic. My f<strong>in</strong>al sentence suggested that socialpsychological<strong>in</strong>vestigations were a variety of historical study, that <strong>the</strong>irf<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>gs were snapshots that should be retaken every now and <strong>the</strong>n. My f<strong>in</strong>alphrase was tempora mutantur, nos et mutamur <strong>in</strong> illis, which I felt summed up<strong>the</strong> matter very nicely, and which I also felt was a reasonably familiarobservation. In any event, it seemed to me that <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terested reader forwhom it was not familiar could very easily discover its mean<strong>in</strong>g, and mighteven enjoy be<strong>in</strong>g nudged <strong>in</strong>to a little detective work; I know that I do, whenfaced with someth<strong>in</strong>g unfamiliar. (I have just done a Google search: it turnedup almost 90,000 hits, of which <strong>the</strong> top two or three were quite satisfactory.)I had, however, to engage <strong>in</strong> prolonged correspondence with <strong>the</strong> journal’spublishers and copy-editors, who wanted me to add an English translation <strong>in</strong>paren<strong>the</strong>sis. After a certa<strong>in</strong> amount of argy-bargy, I told <strong>the</strong>m that that woulddefeat <strong>the</strong> purpose of <strong>the</strong> Lat<strong>in</strong> version, and that I would ra<strong>the</strong>r drop <strong>the</strong> wholesentence. They <strong>the</strong>n, to my great surprise, yielded <strong>the</strong> field, and <strong>the</strong> phraseappeared without English accompaniment. This was one of those small,unexpected victories that keep academic life so vibrant.I note, <strong>in</strong>cidentally, that Waxmann Verlag, <strong>in</strong> Münster, have been publish<strong>in</strong>ga journal called Tertium Comparationis: Journal for Comparative and MulticulturalEducation s<strong>in</strong>ce 1995. The words before <strong>the</strong> colon are of courseredundant but no doubt, it is hoped that <strong>the</strong>y are redolent too.5. Fur<strong>the</strong>r phenomenological excursions became even less focused. Thus, Roseand Kaplan <strong>in</strong>troduced us to <strong>the</strong> new field of ‘ethno-<strong>in</strong>quiry’. The world, <strong>the</strong>ypo<strong>in</strong>t out, consists of both people and th<strong>in</strong>gs, ‘and it is <strong>the</strong> task of <strong>the</strong> ethno<strong>in</strong>quirerto try to sort <strong>the</strong>m out’ (Kaplan, 1982: 15). For his part, Rose (1982: 19)reveals that ‘wordly th<strong>in</strong>gs are such critical matters that <strong>the</strong>y may be given aname. They can be called mundanities’. For a critical statement on thisnonsense, see Edwards (1983b). ‘Ethno-<strong>in</strong>quiry’ has apparently disappeared,I am glad to say, but it rema<strong>in</strong>s an example of <strong>the</strong> bizarreries that cont<strong>in</strong>ue toarise.6. Ano<strong>the</strong>r recent reviewer of Chilton’s book on political discourse is HailongTian (2006). Could anyone well, anyone who isn’t a discourse analyst bybirth read his review, with its pa<strong>in</strong>ful accounts of Enoch Powell’s famous‘rivers of blood’ speech and Bill Cl<strong>in</strong>ton’s 1999 announcement of air strikesaga<strong>in</strong>st <strong>the</strong> Serbs, without shudder<strong>in</strong>g at <strong>the</strong> lengthy but empty and jargonriddenrestatements of <strong>the</strong> obvious? And could anyone doubt that this is but areflection of wider noisome practice with<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> field?7. In his argument for a closer relationship between psychology and l<strong>in</strong>guistics more specifically, between social psychology and discourse studies Rob<strong>in</strong>son (1985: 136) makes <strong>the</strong> follow<strong>in</strong>g observation: ‘Unfortunately, <strong>the</strong>


Discourse Analysis and its Discontents 39implications for fur<strong>the</strong>r work are <strong>in</strong>f<strong>in</strong>ite <strong>in</strong> more than one respect. Spatiallyand temporally <strong>the</strong>re can be no end to studies that would be of practical useto <strong>in</strong>dividuals <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir daily lives’. This is certa<strong>in</strong>ly true. Indeed, it is quiteunremarkable, for who would argue that our <strong>in</strong>vestigations <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> humancondition are near<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>ir end? Still, Rob<strong>in</strong>son’s mention of <strong>in</strong>f<strong>in</strong>ity doesbr<strong>in</strong>g to m<strong>in</strong>d Borges’s famous map.At least Grimshaw’s (1989) study as mentioned <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> text here usedreal language excerpts. Some of <strong>the</strong> texts and o<strong>the</strong>r samples that are putunder <strong>the</strong> discoursal microscope are made up by <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>vestigator, thushead<strong>in</strong>g us even more dramatically towards maps much larger than reality.


Chapter 3Disadvantage: A Brief OverviewIntroductionIf one is <strong>in</strong>terested today <strong>in</strong> those educational difficulties that seem tofollow group l<strong>in</strong>es, one might turn to <strong>the</strong> literature on multicultural andmulti-ethnic education, on diversity <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> classroom, on m<strong>in</strong>ority-groupissues, on cultural heterogeneity, on educational ‘empowerment’, on<strong>in</strong>tergroup and <strong>in</strong>tercultural school<strong>in</strong>g, and so on. Representativetreatments can be found <strong>in</strong> Banks (1996), Mann<strong>in</strong>g and Baruth (2004)and Nieto (2004). Alternatively, if one is especially <strong>in</strong>terested <strong>in</strong> l<strong>in</strong>guisticmatters, <strong>the</strong> burgeon<strong>in</strong>g field of ‘variationist sociol<strong>in</strong>guistics’ couldrecommend itself: see Chambers et al. (2002); see also Chambers (1995),James Milroy (1992) and Lesley Milroy (1987). Part of its obvious remit is<strong>the</strong> study of dialect differentiation along class l<strong>in</strong>es, and this cont<strong>in</strong>ues atradition particularly associated with <strong>the</strong> work of Labov on <strong>the</strong> ‘socialstratification’ of language (see, for <strong>in</strong>stance, Labov’s [2006] study ofEnglish <strong>in</strong> New York City). Trudgill’s ‘triangle model’ shows how dialectdifferences become less pronounced as one moves up <strong>the</strong> social-classhierarchy; as Coulmas (2005: 29) <strong>the</strong>n observes, ‘<strong>the</strong> speech of <strong>the</strong>disadvantaged or underclass is more pronouncedly regional than that ofmiddle-class speakers’ (see also Trudgill, 2000, 2002).The more contemporary research directions rarely, however, get to <strong>the</strong>heart of difficulties faced by children at school, difficulties oftenexacerbated by l<strong>in</strong>guistic practices and perceptions. At <strong>the</strong> ‘macro’ level,for example, <strong>the</strong> commendable concern with diversity <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> classroomoften jumps more or less immediately to what I shall style below as <strong>the</strong>‘difference’ position. Given <strong>the</strong> validity of this position (as we shall see),this is entirely reasonable, but it does mean that some real-life problemsare ra<strong>the</strong>r skipped over. At more ‘micro’ levels, we often f<strong>in</strong>d variationistl<strong>in</strong>guists attend<strong>in</strong>g to f<strong>in</strong>e-gra<strong>in</strong>ed dist<strong>in</strong>ctions of syntax and pronunciation.It is perhaps tell<strong>in</strong>g that, <strong>in</strong> his chapter on class variation, Coulmas(2005) gives us only one paragraph on <strong>the</strong> ‘Bernste<strong>in</strong>ian’ era (see below).It is also tell<strong>in</strong>g that <strong>the</strong> title of this chapter is ‘Standard and Dialect: SocialStratification as a Factor of L<strong>in</strong>guistic Choice’, and that Coulmas goes on40


Disadvantage: A Brief Overview 41to discuss <strong>the</strong> fact that ‘dialects can be chosen’ (Coulmas, 2005: 18). This iscerta<strong>in</strong>ly correct, and <strong>the</strong>re is, <strong>in</strong> fact, a large literature on l<strong>in</strong>guistic‘accommodation’; <strong>the</strong> work of Giles and his colleagues is noteworthy here(see Giles & Coupland, 1991; Rob<strong>in</strong>son & Giles, 2001). Aga<strong>in</strong>, however,<strong>the</strong> idea of choos<strong>in</strong>g appropriately from one’s speech repertoire ra<strong>the</strong>rsidesteps <strong>the</strong> issues of importance for young, nonstandard-dialectspeak<strong>in</strong>gchildren.So, very few researchers write about ‘deprived’ or ‘disadvantaged’children any more. There are some good reasons for term<strong>in</strong>ologicalchanges, but also some that are ra<strong>the</strong>r less compell<strong>in</strong>g, and many newco<strong>in</strong>ages will soon fade away, just like those <strong>the</strong>y replaced. Here is acontemporary observation:From a cultural perspective, many of <strong>the</strong> problems that languagem<strong>in</strong>ority [sic] students experience <strong>in</strong> ma<strong>in</strong>stream programs can beattributed to <strong>the</strong> school’s devaluation of <strong>the</strong> <strong>home</strong> and culture of <strong>the</strong>students ra<strong>the</strong>r than to <strong>the</strong>ir cultural differences. In culturally andl<strong>in</strong>guistically sensitive programs, students are not labeled ‘at risk’ acultural-deficit approach. Culturally sensitive programs have movedbeyond <strong>home</strong>-school discont<strong>in</strong>uity, cultural relativity, or culturaldifference <strong>the</strong>ory and have made room for more equitable, culturallysensitive school<strong>in</strong>g def<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong> cooperation with <strong>the</strong> community.(Ovando & Gourd, 1996: 315)This is a representative quotation, <strong>in</strong>asmuch as <strong>the</strong> new ‘culturalsensitivity’ that it trumpets goes hand <strong>in</strong> hand with muddled th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g.It is certa<strong>in</strong>ly true that <strong>the</strong> <strong>home</strong> backgrounds of some m<strong>in</strong>ority-groupchildren are devalued <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> classroom, but <strong>the</strong> second half of <strong>the</strong> firstsentence is confused: <strong>the</strong> <strong>home</strong>-school differences are precisely what fuel‘devaluation’. In <strong>the</strong> second sentence, it is <strong>in</strong>correct to equate <strong>the</strong> ‘at-risk’description with a ‘deficit’ perspective, s<strong>in</strong>ce it is entirely possible toreject <strong>the</strong> latter while acknowledg<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> former. The third sentence is <strong>the</strong>oddest of <strong>the</strong> three. How can cultural sensitivity ‘move beyond’ <strong>home</strong>schooldiscont<strong>in</strong>uity, when that is <strong>the</strong> foundation-stone of <strong>the</strong> matter?How can it move beyond <strong>the</strong> cultural relativity that is <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>oreticalbasis for a different-but-not-deficient approach to disadvantage? Howcan it consider itself an approach separate from <strong>the</strong> ‘difference’perspective that is <strong>the</strong> socio-educational manifestation of culturalrelativity? And what do <strong>the</strong> f<strong>in</strong>e conclud<strong>in</strong>g words about equitabilityand community cooperation signify, o<strong>the</strong>r than earnest <strong>in</strong>tention? (Thereis also <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>felicitous repetition of <strong>the</strong> words ‘culturally sensitive’ <strong>in</strong> thisf<strong>in</strong>al sentence.)


42 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>As we shall see <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> follow<strong>in</strong>g chapters, three broad explanationshave been proposed for group-based educational difficulties. The firstholds that some populations suffer substantive deficiencies because ofgenetic <strong>in</strong>feriority; <strong>the</strong> second, that such deficits may be caused by faultyenvironments; <strong>the</strong> third, that what <strong>the</strong> first two positions view as deficitsare, <strong>in</strong> fact, differences attributable to variations <strong>in</strong> environment that are <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>mselves nei<strong>the</strong>r better nor worse than ‘ma<strong>in</strong>stream’ varieties.The first two explanations are essentially untenable, however, and <strong>the</strong>‘difference’ viewpo<strong>in</strong>t is <strong>the</strong> most reasonable on <strong>the</strong> basis of <strong>the</strong> availableevidence. The implication is that difficulties faced by certa<strong>in</strong> groups(lower-class ones, for <strong>in</strong>stance) are deficits only <strong>in</strong> a social sense, onlywhen assumptions of <strong>the</strong> correctness of o<strong>the</strong>r values (middle-class ones,for <strong>in</strong>stance) are taken <strong>in</strong>to account. While suffer<strong>in</strong>g from social ra<strong>the</strong>rthan cognitive deficits is not necessarily a lesser burden, of course,accuracy is important here, and desirable <strong>in</strong>terventions can have littlechance of mean<strong>in</strong>gful effect if <strong>the</strong>y are based upon faulty models.‘Disadvantage’ was a term first employed by those espous<strong>in</strong>g anenvironmental-deficit <strong>the</strong>sis (Deutsch, 1967). Thus, it became closelyassociated with so-called ‘compensatory education’, a thrust largely builtupon <strong>the</strong> environmentalist belief that <strong>in</strong>adequate patterns of earlysocialization could be remedied <strong>in</strong> school and pre-school programs(Bereiter & Engelmann, 1966). More enlightened adherence to ‘difference’models, <strong>in</strong> which environmental deficit and remedial education areobviously seen as flawed and <strong>in</strong>appropriate conceptions (<strong>in</strong>deed,‘compensation’ is hardly <strong>the</strong> mot juste if exist<strong>in</strong>g patterns are not<strong>in</strong>herently deficient), meant that ‘disadvantage’ became viewed <strong>in</strong> anegative light. Hill-Burnett (1979) argued, for <strong>in</strong>stance, that ‘disadvantage’was merely a euphemism for deficit; Adler (1979) discussed aportmanteau ‘deprived/disadvantaged’ concept; de Valdés (1979) used‘disadvantaged’ and ‘deficient’ <strong>in</strong>terchangeably; and Moss (1973: 19), <strong>in</strong> acontribution to an Open University block on language and learn<strong>in</strong>g,argued that ‘whe<strong>the</strong>r you prefer to use ‘‘disadvantaged’’, ‘‘deprived’’ orsome o<strong>the</strong>r term qualified by ‘‘socially’’, ‘‘economically’’ or ‘‘culturally’’is less important than <strong>the</strong> fact that <strong>the</strong>re is no child who can fit <strong>in</strong>to such acategory’. The anti-labell<strong>in</strong>g sentiment here may be admirable (althoughless than crystal clear), but <strong>the</strong> impatience with dist<strong>in</strong>ctions of term<strong>in</strong>ologyis not. Typically associated with a deficit model, ‘disadvantage’ hasbecome a word to be avoided. This is largely due, however, to a postmodernhypersensitivity that, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> f<strong>in</strong>al analysis, does no one any good.The term rema<strong>in</strong>s useful, and it need not be lumbered with unfairconnotations. 1


Disadvantage: A Brief Overview 43We are right to delete such <strong>in</strong>accuracies as ‘sociocultural deprivation’and ‘genetic deficiency’, but it would be a shame if ‘disadvantage’ wasjettisoned too. We can discuss certa<strong>in</strong> children as be<strong>in</strong>g at a disadvantage<strong>in</strong> society without cast<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> slightest aspersion upon <strong>the</strong>ir own culture,language, socialization and so on. Disadvantage signifies <strong>in</strong>equalitiesthat we know to exist, and to <strong>the</strong> extent to which one is excluded fromfull participation, one is disadvantaged. A related reason for <strong>the</strong>retention of <strong>the</strong> term ‘disadvantage’, as opposed to limp difference<strong>the</strong>oryphrases (‘culturally different’, for <strong>in</strong>stance), is that it can act as auseful counterbalance to <strong>the</strong> sometimes too sangu<strong>in</strong>e outlook ofdifference <strong>the</strong>orists. That is, just as term<strong>in</strong>g a child environmentallydeprived may <strong>in</strong>voke an unwarranted halo effect, so difference <strong>the</strong>oristshave sometimes been wont to see <strong>the</strong>ir subjects as nei<strong>the</strong>r need<strong>in</strong>g norask<strong>in</strong>g for outside help. Those who emphasize <strong>the</strong> strengths of ‘work<strong>in</strong>gclassculture’ (and it certa<strong>in</strong>ly has some: recall Orwell’s (1937) observationthat ‘<strong>the</strong>re is much <strong>in</strong> middle-class life that looks sickly anddebilitat<strong>in</strong>g when you see it from a work<strong>in</strong>g-class angle’), for example,ought to remember that <strong>the</strong>re is no virtue <strong>in</strong> poverty itself, and that poorchildren who achieve at school do so despite, and not because of,material and o<strong>the</strong>r <strong>in</strong>adequacies. As Rutter and Madge (1977: 2) oncenoted, ‘beh<strong>in</strong>d <strong>the</strong> words... <strong>the</strong> human predicament is real enough’.Retention of <strong>the</strong> forthright ‘disadvantage’ might be salutary here.While <strong>the</strong>re are a great many short- and long-term factors that mayprove disadvantageous to <strong>in</strong>dividuals <strong>in</strong> many areas of life, <strong>the</strong>psychological, educational and l<strong>in</strong>guistic disadvantage under discussionhere reflects relatively endur<strong>in</strong>g group conditions. The characteristics andlifestyles of some communities <strong>the</strong> work<strong>in</strong>g class, immigrant populationsand ethnic m<strong>in</strong>orities among <strong>the</strong>m may lead to poor schoolachievement and generally dampened chances of success <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> largersociety. The assumption is that <strong>the</strong> ‘cultures of poverty’, often marked byclass, or race or ethnicity, do little to prepare a child for <strong>the</strong> more middleclasscontexts and consequences of formal education. While <strong>in</strong>itial schoolentry implies, for all children, a break from <strong>the</strong> only life <strong>the</strong>y havehi<strong>the</strong>rto known, children from certa<strong>in</strong> groups may be at a relativedisadvantage because of a more sharply marked discont<strong>in</strong>uity between<strong>home</strong> and school.Disadvantage is a sociocultural phenomenon, <strong>the</strong>n, whose work<strong>in</strong>gsdo not rest upon genetic <strong>in</strong>tellectual disability; <strong>the</strong>y emerge, ra<strong>the</strong>r,because of variations <strong>in</strong> patterns of early socialization. It arises at po<strong>in</strong>tsof contact between groups that are at once dist<strong>in</strong>guishable and yet part of<strong>the</strong> same larger society, which is why it is generally most immediately


44 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>noticeable <strong>in</strong> educational contexts: <strong>the</strong> classroom is <strong>the</strong> earliest andarguably <strong>the</strong> s<strong>in</strong>gle most important po<strong>in</strong>t of contact between socialgroups and sub-groups. S<strong>in</strong>ce disadvantage always <strong>in</strong>volves a comparisonbetween socially unequal populations, an implication is that manyvalues and attitudes considered disadvantageous are only so whenjudged aga<strong>in</strong>st a standard imposed from outside <strong>the</strong> group itself.To repeat: <strong>the</strong> most accurate perspective on disadvantage def<strong>in</strong>es it <strong>in</strong>terms of environmental difference. It is true, of course, that some aspectsof some social environments, particularly those of early life, may giverise to problems that are very <strong>in</strong>tractable <strong>in</strong>deed (<strong>in</strong>adequate shelter andnutrition, for example, can clearly have devastat<strong>in</strong>g long-term effects).None<strong>the</strong>less, apart from clarify<strong>in</strong>g aetiological matters, and <strong>the</strong>rebyremov<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>accurate biological or environmental-deficit burdens from<strong>the</strong> backs of those whose social problems are quite sufficient unto <strong>the</strong>day, <strong>the</strong> thrust of <strong>the</strong> disadvantage-as-difference position is that it makesalteration (<strong>in</strong>deed, even ‘compensation’, if <strong>the</strong> nature of <strong>the</strong> problems tobe tackled is clearly understood) at least <strong>the</strong>oretically possible.‘Difference’ is essentially a matter of discont<strong>in</strong>uity. While some of <strong>the</strong>earlier discussions did not use <strong>the</strong> latter term (see Ogbu, 1982a, however),it is obvious that discont<strong>in</strong>uities, particularly those between <strong>the</strong> <strong>home</strong>and <strong>the</strong> school, are <strong>the</strong> heart of <strong>the</strong> matter. If people did not stray out of<strong>the</strong>ir immediate social sett<strong>in</strong>gs if <strong>in</strong>ner-city children, say, never left <strong>the</strong>irneighborhood, never went to school <strong>the</strong>n disadvantage as conceivedhere would not arise. It is contact, and <strong>the</strong> ramifications of contact, thatproduce social disadvantage, and it is social perceptions and norms thattranslate that disadvantage <strong>in</strong>to deficits. Now, some of <strong>the</strong> treatments <strong>in</strong><strong>the</strong> literature are more explicitly discuss<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> idea of disadvantage asdiscont<strong>in</strong>uity; Kellaghan (2001), for example, has brought it front andcenter <strong>in</strong> a new overview on def<strong>in</strong>itional matters. 2 An <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>gdevelopment here is <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>corporation of Bourdieu’s ideas of varietiesof ‘capital’. Economic capital is, of course, <strong>the</strong> most obvious type, s<strong>in</strong>ce<strong>the</strong> relationship between poverty and disadvantage, while not without itsnuances, is a strong one. As well, however, Kellaghan rem<strong>in</strong>ds us of <strong>the</strong>importance of cultural and social capital. Disadvantage may arise <strong>in</strong>situations <strong>in</strong> which <strong>the</strong> <strong>home</strong> does not adequately ‘foster cognitive andscholastic development’, or where aspects of ‘conduct... identity...social behaviour, attitudes and motivations’ (Kellaghan, 2001: 7) maylead to difficulties beyond <strong>the</strong> immediate environments that produce<strong>the</strong>m.Kellaghan’s illustrations of social and cultural capital make it clearthat we are still essentially talk<strong>in</strong>g about <strong>the</strong> ‘values and attitudes’ of <strong>the</strong>


Disadvantage: A Brief Overview 45<strong>home</strong>, and <strong>the</strong> implications <strong>the</strong>y have for current and future developments.And Bourdieu’s <strong>in</strong>sights are not particularly new <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>mselves.Kellaghan cites work (by Bourdieu and Passeron) on social reproductionthat dates to 1977 (and, <strong>in</strong> fact, to 1970 <strong>in</strong> its orig<strong>in</strong>al French version). 3None<strong>the</strong>less, doors may be opened here to new and <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g l<strong>in</strong>kages,because analyz<strong>in</strong>g family sett<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>in</strong> sub-divided ways may promptgreater subtlety of explanation: some may be f<strong>in</strong>ancially poor, for<strong>in</strong>stance, but rich <strong>in</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r ways; not all those who grow up <strong>in</strong> apparentlydisadvantaged circumstances are, <strong>in</strong> fact, disadvantaged <strong>the</strong>mselves; andso on. (The work of Garbar<strong>in</strong>o et al. [1997] has re<strong>in</strong>forced, for example,<strong>the</strong> ra<strong>the</strong>r obvious fact that most people who grow up <strong>in</strong> what wouldgenerally be perceived as unfavorable conditions become fully function<strong>in</strong>gadults.) In turn, <strong>in</strong>creased explanatory subtlety can prompt considerationof matters that were <strong>in</strong>sufficiently regarded before. Forexample, Kellaghan refers to <strong>the</strong> need for closer attention to those‘work<strong>in</strong>g-class’ values that were traditionally, and often cavalierly,downgraded. Such exam<strong>in</strong>ations are always useful, but (as I haveimplied above) one would not wish to see a romanticized view of suchvalues obscur<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> reality of a society largely run on, and responsive to,more middle-class ones. More <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g, perhaps, would be <strong>the</strong>exam<strong>in</strong>ation of <strong>the</strong> more general proposition that some aspects of somecultures may be <strong>in</strong>tr<strong>in</strong>sically less valuable than o<strong>the</strong>rs. Relatedly,<strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g cases might be made for <strong>the</strong> likelihood and/or <strong>the</strong> benefitsof disadvantaged children becom<strong>in</strong>g ‘bicultural’. That is, desired anddesirable competences along broadly socially approved l<strong>in</strong>es mightcoexist with orig<strong>in</strong>al ones: a psychological pattern of addition ra<strong>the</strong>rthan replacement. And f<strong>in</strong>ally here, more nuanced perspectives couldmake considerations of how schools might adapt to what children ‘br<strong>in</strong>gwith <strong>the</strong>m’ a partial reversal, that is to say, of <strong>the</strong> traditionalrequirements for pupils to conform <strong>the</strong>mselves to <strong>the</strong> school muchmore likely. I shall return to <strong>the</strong>se <strong>the</strong>mes later on, particularly to <strong>the</strong>l<strong>in</strong>guistic aspects of ‘bicultural’ arrangements and to educationaladaptations to nonstandard dialects <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> classroom.A recent overview by Pérez Carreón et al. (2005) has po<strong>in</strong>ted to someof <strong>the</strong> difficulties <strong>in</strong>volved <strong>in</strong> br<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> ‘cultural capital’ of <strong>the</strong> <strong>home</strong>to bear successfully upon school and classroom practice, particularlyamong poor, immigrant, <strong>in</strong>ner-city populations. As <strong>the</strong>y note, whilevirtually everyone accepts that parental <strong>in</strong>volvement can contribute tochildren’s success at school, <strong>the</strong>re is much less unanimity when onebeg<strong>in</strong>s to consider just how that <strong>in</strong>volvement can best be marshalled.And, although Pérez Carreón and his colleagues do not mention it, <strong>the</strong>re


46 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>is also a great deal of ra<strong>the</strong>r pious lip-service paid to br<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>g parents‘<strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> classroom’, when it is clear that, <strong>in</strong> many <strong>in</strong>stances, <strong>the</strong>irpresence is really not wanted. This is a subject for ano<strong>the</strong>r day, butanyone who has spent time with teachers will recognize that, overburdenedas <strong>the</strong>y often are, <strong>the</strong>y may resent ra<strong>the</strong>r than welcome directparental ‘engagement’. This is not true for all teachers or <strong>in</strong> allcircumstances, but once one gets beyond structured occasions, likedesignated parent-teacher meet<strong>in</strong>gs, one is <strong>in</strong> murkier territory.Disadvantage and PovertyAs I have already mentioned <strong>in</strong> pass<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>the</strong>re is an unsurpris<strong>in</strong>gcorrelation between socioeconomic status (SES) and school achievement.It is not a simple l<strong>in</strong>ear relationship, however, as <strong>the</strong> meta-analyses ofWhite (1982) and Sir<strong>in</strong> (2005) have shown; see also <strong>the</strong> multi-countrystudy of Marks (2006) on between- and with<strong>in</strong>-school differences <strong>in</strong>achievement. Studies typically base <strong>the</strong>ir <strong>in</strong>vestigations on parental<strong>in</strong>comes, occupations and levels of education, on <strong>the</strong> one hand, and onchildren’s measured atta<strong>in</strong>ments overall grade averages, standardizededucational assessments, s<strong>in</strong>gle-subject test scores (verbal skills, ma<strong>the</strong>maticsachievement, and so on) on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r.One f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g is that <strong>the</strong> relationship between SES and educationalachievement is greater at <strong>the</strong> level of <strong>the</strong> school than at <strong>the</strong> level of<strong>in</strong>dividual students; <strong>the</strong> wider generality of this American relationshiprema<strong>in</strong>s to be tested, s<strong>in</strong>ce it seems to apply <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> United States becauseof <strong>the</strong> association <strong>the</strong>re between school fund<strong>in</strong>g and district tax bases. Italso seems that collect<strong>in</strong>g family SES data from children is much less<strong>in</strong>formative than go<strong>in</strong>g directly to <strong>the</strong> parents, s<strong>in</strong>ce <strong>the</strong> former oftenover-estimate <strong>home</strong> resources; <strong>the</strong> disparities are greatest for youngchildren, for those from s<strong>in</strong>gle-parent families and for those at <strong>the</strong> bottomof <strong>the</strong> achievement tables. This is important, of course, s<strong>in</strong>ce suchchildren are typically <strong>the</strong> ones for whom we would like <strong>the</strong> most accurateSES data. A third f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g particularly important <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> context of thisbook is that SES (<strong>in</strong> Sir<strong>in</strong>’s American study, for <strong>in</strong>stance) is a strongerpredictor of achievement for white students than for o<strong>the</strong>rs. Form<strong>in</strong>ority-group pupils, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g African Americans, <strong>the</strong> general neighborhoodSES is more <strong>in</strong>dicative (see Dornbusch et al., 1991; Gonzaleset al., 1996). The <strong>in</strong>ference here is that lower-class m<strong>in</strong>ority groups oftenlive <strong>in</strong> neighborhoods with ‘higher educational risk factors’ (Sir<strong>in</strong>, 2005:441). Perhaps <strong>the</strong>se tend to swamp <strong>in</strong>dividual family variations. A relatedpo<strong>in</strong>t was made by Krieger and Fee (1994) who showed that simply


Disadvantage: A Brief Overview 47compar<strong>in</strong>g median family <strong>in</strong>comes across groups may give a mislead<strong>in</strong>gpicture of <strong>the</strong>ir relative SES. Their mid-1990s <strong>in</strong>vestigations <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> UnitedStates revealed that, although white family <strong>in</strong>comes were on average halfaga<strong>in</strong> as large as those of black families, <strong>the</strong> overall wealth of <strong>the</strong> former(<strong>the</strong>ir ‘capital assets’, most notably <strong>home</strong> ownership) was about ten timesgreater.None<strong>the</strong>less, while <strong>the</strong> two overlap to a considerable extent, disadvantageis not simply a synonym for poverty. With<strong>in</strong> areas of highunemployment, poor hous<strong>in</strong>g and low <strong>in</strong>come, one certa<strong>in</strong>ly expects tof<strong>in</strong>d a concentration of social or educational disadvantage. It is also truethat ethnic and racial m<strong>in</strong>orities are very often poor (although externaland visible markers of class or ethnicity may mask a great deal ofheterogeneity). On <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r hand, it would be logically <strong>in</strong>correct toequate comfortable physical surround<strong>in</strong>gs with absence of socio-educationaldisadvantage. It is clear that <strong>the</strong>re are many ‘good’ <strong>home</strong>s <strong>in</strong>work<strong>in</strong>g-class neighborhoods and many ‘poor’ ones <strong>in</strong> middle-classsuburbia; see Wiseman (1968) for an early expression of this, andGarbar<strong>in</strong>o et al. (1997).Recent statistics from Toronto a heavily multicultural city, with morethan a quarter of a million schoolchildren from virtually every countryon earth reveal someth<strong>in</strong>g of <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>teraction between ethnicity andmaterial poverty (Wente, 2006). While children from <strong>the</strong> poorestneighborhoods are three times more likely to drop out of school thanare those from <strong>the</strong> richest ones (33 versus 11%), achievement differencesamong ethnic groups are more strik<strong>in</strong>g. Romanian and Ch<strong>in</strong>ese children(with drop-out rates of about 11.5%) and Gujarati, Bengali and Tamilpupils (about 16%) are <strong>the</strong> most likely to f<strong>in</strong>ish school, while <strong>the</strong> leastlikely to stay <strong>the</strong> course are Somali, Caribbean, Portuguese and SouthAmerican children (whose drop-out rates are on <strong>the</strong> order of 40%). Thesefigures are, broadly speak<strong>in</strong>g, typical of o<strong>the</strong>r countries <strong>in</strong> which <strong>the</strong>seimmigrant groups are represented. Writ<strong>in</strong>g about <strong>the</strong> American experience,Ste<strong>in</strong>berg et al. (1996) consider that ethnicity is <strong>the</strong> most predictiveof children’s school success, more important than parental wealth, twoparentfamilies and stay-at-<strong>home</strong> mo<strong>the</strong>rs. The Asian students who do sowell <strong>in</strong> anglophone contexts benefit from <strong>home</strong>s <strong>in</strong> which educationalachievement is highly valued, and <strong>in</strong> which family habits and valuesreflect and support this. Their disproportionate presence <strong>in</strong> universityleveleducation is as marked as that of black and Hispanic children <strong>in</strong>opposite directions, of course.If so much importance rests upon family ‘culture’, obvious questionsarise about many contemporary educational <strong>in</strong>novations and practices


48 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong><strong>in</strong>tended to close <strong>the</strong> various achievement gaps. It is much too simplistic,however, to say that Asian parents value education more than do WestIndian or Hispanic ones. If we assume that virtually all parents <strong>in</strong> allethnic populations would prefer success to failure, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> questions ofimportance force us back a step or two: why do some parents support andre<strong>in</strong>force ‘school learn<strong>in</strong>g’ for <strong>the</strong>ir children more than some o<strong>the</strong>rs do?What accounts for <strong>the</strong> considerable variability <strong>in</strong> m<strong>in</strong>ority-group schoolperformance (see Ogbu, 1983, 1987)? It is not too difficult to drawdist<strong>in</strong>ctions here among (for example) degrees of prejudice and discrim<strong>in</strong>ationsuffered by different immigrant m<strong>in</strong>ority groups, nor is it difficultto predict <strong>the</strong> operation of various circular reactions, both positive andnegative. Because of historical factors, good luck and, above all, m<strong>in</strong>imalprejudice, Group A may be able to put its children on <strong>the</strong> beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>grungs of educational success. When success is achieved, greater penetrationof <strong>the</strong> middle-class ma<strong>in</strong>stream occurs, more material markers ofsuccess accrue, and <strong>the</strong> value of formal education becomes apparent.Group B, on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r hand, may be more significantly hamstrung from<strong>the</strong> beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g, and prejudice may have a more endur<strong>in</strong>gly corrosiveeffect. In socially unfavorable circumstances, where opportunities are fewand where <strong>the</strong> basic requirements of life consume virtually all <strong>the</strong> familyenergy and resources, it is easy to see that <strong>the</strong> rewards of formaleducation will be both less apparent and much less frequently achieved.If you cannot afford to buy educational lottery tickets, you are unlikely tow<strong>in</strong> any prizes.In a notable treatment of poverty, Ra<strong>in</strong>water (1970) outl<strong>in</strong>ed five majorperspectives, four of which result from <strong>the</strong> comb<strong>in</strong>ation of two polarizeddimensions, weakness-potency and virtue-badness. A classic historicalview holds that <strong>the</strong> poor are as potentially strong as anyone else, butsomehow lack virtue; from such a perspective, <strong>the</strong>y are immoral (ors<strong>in</strong>ful). If poor people are seen as bad but weak, on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r hand, whatwas s<strong>in</strong> can be considered illness: moral flaw and demonic possession areno longer favored explanations for aberrant behavior, and an importantimplication is that poverty-as-social-pathology might be remedied.Compensatory <strong>in</strong>terventions, for example, now become <strong>the</strong>oreticallypossible. A third comb<strong>in</strong>ation l<strong>in</strong>ks virtue and impotence: <strong>the</strong> poor arebasically like <strong>the</strong> rest of us, but <strong>the</strong>ir cop<strong>in</strong>g skills are underm<strong>in</strong>ed by alack of resources. An implication of this model is that people could behelped to help <strong>the</strong>mselves. Initial aid and guidance could set <strong>the</strong>m on<strong>the</strong>ir feet. At a societal level, this perspective undergirds efforts to assist<strong>the</strong> poor <strong>in</strong> ‘underdeveloped’ areas. Ra<strong>in</strong>water’s fourth logical possibilityis that <strong>the</strong> poor are both strong and good. They have defiantly turned <strong>the</strong>ir


Disadvantage: A Brief Overview 49backs on ma<strong>in</strong>stream society, where people are <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>gly alienatedand ‘depersonalized’, where psychological conditions may become sounpleasant that people may actually wish to ‘escape from freedom’ (asFromm [1941] famously put it). Individuals and groups have certa<strong>in</strong>lyacted on this desire, and some of <strong>the</strong> more egregious <strong>in</strong>stances haveshown what a high price can be exacted. See<strong>in</strong>g poor people as powerfuland virtuous has often arisen from a romanticized middle-class view.Ra<strong>in</strong>water labelled <strong>the</strong>se four models <strong>the</strong> moraliz<strong>in</strong>g, medicaliz<strong>in</strong>g,normaliz<strong>in</strong>g and apo<strong>the</strong>osiz<strong>in</strong>g approaches. They are all essentiallydescriptive: <strong>the</strong>y represent views of poverty, ra<strong>the</strong>r than explanationsof it. But <strong>the</strong>re is a fifth and more <strong>in</strong>structive approach, a naturaliz<strong>in</strong>gperspective, and it is one that clearly relates to <strong>the</strong> ‘difference-deficit’controversy touched on <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> previous section. On <strong>the</strong> one hand(Ra<strong>in</strong>water himself observed), a ‘biological determ<strong>in</strong>ism’ argues for<strong>in</strong>nate deficiencies of <strong>in</strong>telligence. The perceived utility of eugenicsand, more generally, a concern to look after people who cannotadequately judge for <strong>the</strong>mselves, are elements that have traditionally<strong>in</strong>formed <strong>the</strong> ‘benign totalitarianism’ associated with such a determ<strong>in</strong>isticposition. The o<strong>the</strong>r broad <strong>the</strong>me emerg<strong>in</strong>g from a ‘naturaliz<strong>in</strong>g’ perspectiveon poverty is one that stresses cultural difference: a group’s lifestyle,socialization patterns, habits, values and attitudes are seen as adequate <strong>in</strong><strong>the</strong> immediate environment, understood to have developed <strong>in</strong> ways mostappropriate for that environment. A strong adherence to such a po<strong>in</strong>t ofview might imply that no <strong>in</strong>tervention at all <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> lives of <strong>the</strong> poor is<strong>in</strong>dicated (recall those romanticized assessments of <strong>the</strong> strength andvigor of work<strong>in</strong>g-class life). However, <strong>the</strong> obvious facts of group contact,and <strong>the</strong> obvious advantages of mov<strong>in</strong>g beyond immediate environments,mean that <strong>the</strong> proponents of a ‘difference’ view can logically support<strong>in</strong>terventions aimed at extend<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> range of opportunities open to <strong>the</strong>poor, without condemn<strong>in</strong>g what <strong>the</strong>y already possess, or do.In <strong>the</strong> next two chapters, I will flesh out this <strong>in</strong>troductory overview,largely by present<strong>in</strong>g someth<strong>in</strong>g of <strong>the</strong> history and development ofscholarly conceptions of ‘disadvantage’ (see also Edwards, 1989). It isalways useful to come to grips with <strong>the</strong> bases of important arguments; aswell, an historical summary makes particular sense here because <strong>the</strong>broad <strong>the</strong>mes have rema<strong>in</strong>ed remarkably unaltered s<strong>in</strong>ce <strong>the</strong>y were firstformally presented <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> literature (Edwards, 1999a). The most importantand <strong>the</strong> most controversial research arguments about disadvantagewere made some time ago, and this is why some of <strong>the</strong> references <strong>in</strong>what follows may seem a little dated. Although <strong>the</strong> scholarly caravanmay have moved on, however, from discussions of biological or


50 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>environmental <strong>in</strong>feriority, it would be naïve to th<strong>in</strong>k that such perspectiveshave disappeared. Some variants rema<strong>in</strong> very powerful <strong>in</strong>deed.More reason, <strong>the</strong>n, to try and understand some of <strong>the</strong> underp<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>gs.Notes1. See my very short piece on <strong>the</strong> connotation of guilt-by-association that‘disadvantage’ came to have (Edwards, 1981).Corson (2001) uses <strong>the</strong> term ‘disadvantage’ at various po<strong>in</strong>ts <strong>in</strong> his usefultreatment of language diversity at school (i.e. Corson, 2001: 54, 80, 126) although you will search for it <strong>in</strong> va<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>dex. A very recent treatment of<strong>the</strong> plight of one group of black people <strong>in</strong> America (Edelman et al., 2006) isentitled Reconnect<strong>in</strong>g Disadvantaged Young Men (recent statistics concern<strong>in</strong>gblack unemployment, poverty and <strong>in</strong>carceration are given <strong>in</strong> Smi<strong>the</strong>rman,2006). In his new book on ‘urban language’, Rampton (2006) also uses <strong>the</strong>term <strong>in</strong> several places.Given <strong>the</strong> general demise of <strong>the</strong> term ‘disadvantage’, it is <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g thatCoulmas (2005: 27) notes that <strong>the</strong> evolv<strong>in</strong>g category of ‘social class’ is nolonger adequately captured by traditional labels (upper class, middle class,lower class, and <strong>the</strong>ir sub-divisions) and that some would jettison <strong>the</strong> term‘class’ and talk <strong>in</strong>stead of ‘social mobility’ and ‘social deprivation’. Plus çachange, and all that.2. The work of Kellaghan and his colleagues at <strong>the</strong> Educational Research Centre<strong>in</strong> Dubl<strong>in</strong> has for long been central (see also Archer & Edwards, 1982;Edwards, 1974; Kellaghan, 1977). A new report by Archer and Weir (2004)provides a valuable survey, focus<strong>in</strong>g particularly upon a number of factorscentral to any effective <strong>in</strong>tervention <strong>in</strong> disadvantage: beyond some familiarelements (pre-school provisions, parental <strong>in</strong>volvement, etc.), attention is paidto some of <strong>the</strong> newer <strong>in</strong>sights I touch upon <strong>in</strong> this section alterations toschool organization that will more accurately reflect what children first ‘br<strong>in</strong>gwith <strong>the</strong>m’, for example, or coord<strong>in</strong>ated l<strong>in</strong>kages among relevant communityagencies.3. The late philosopher was quite capable of unnecessary obscurity. Thus,Bourdieu (1989: 59) described his notion of ‘habitus’ (which simply means <strong>the</strong>whole environment physical, social, psychological of an <strong>in</strong>dividual, withall its comb<strong>in</strong>ations of various species of ‘capital’, with all its possibilities andlimitations) as ‘a system of dispositions common to all products of <strong>the</strong> samecondition<strong>in</strong>gs’. In <strong>the</strong> same book, Bourdieu (1989: 60) also po<strong>in</strong>ted to<strong>the</strong> s<strong>in</strong>gular habitus of <strong>the</strong> [group] members... united <strong>in</strong> a relation ofhomology, that is, of diversity with<strong>in</strong> homogeneity reflect<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> diversitywith<strong>in</strong> homogeneity characteristic of <strong>the</strong>ir social conditions of production.Each <strong>in</strong>dividual system of dispositions is a structural variant of <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs,express<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> s<strong>in</strong>gularity of its own position with<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> [group] and itstrajectory.Bourdieu is far from <strong>the</strong> worst offender with this sort of bafflegab. When notbe<strong>in</strong>g obscure, he veers to <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r extreme: ‘my work consists <strong>in</strong> say<strong>in</strong>g that


Disadvantage: A Brief Overview 51people are located <strong>in</strong> a social space, that <strong>the</strong>y aren’t just anywhere’ (p. 50).Who would have thought it? ‘Orwell! thou shouldst be liv<strong>in</strong>g at this hour’.Bourdieu’s work does, however, have <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>estimable advantage of be<strong>in</strong>gsufficiently elastic to prop up all sorts of arguments, <strong>in</strong> all sorts of arenas.I note, for example, that Corson (2001), cit<strong>in</strong>g Labov, Bernste<strong>in</strong> and Bourdieuas <strong>the</strong> three pivotal <strong>the</strong>orists <strong>in</strong> debates about nonstandard language, drawsparticular l<strong>in</strong>ks between <strong>the</strong> last two we can now understand <strong>the</strong> ‘codes’ asillustrations of variation <strong>in</strong> ‘cultural capital’.


Chapter 4Disadvantage: The Genetic CaseIntroductionDisadvantaged children’s characteristic ways of deal<strong>in</strong>g with <strong>the</strong>world often appear <strong>in</strong>appropriate or, at least, <strong>in</strong>effective, <strong>in</strong> social arenaswhere different values and behavior are found and encouraged. Coulddifferences here imply real deficits? Could we say that some varieties ofknowledge, skill and attitude are <strong>in</strong>herently better than o<strong>the</strong>rs? With itsassertion that <strong>the</strong> underp<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>gs of disadvantage are ones of difference,and not of ei<strong>the</strong>r environmental or genetic deficiency, <strong>the</strong> previousoverview has anticipated <strong>the</strong> answers to <strong>the</strong>se questions. But mean<strong>in</strong>gfulassertions require evidence, which is why <strong>in</strong> this chapter and <strong>the</strong> next I shall go <strong>in</strong>to some detail about deficit arguments and <strong>the</strong>ir flaws. (Thisdiscussion will also frame <strong>the</strong> subsequent and more specific treatment of<strong>the</strong> relationship between language and disadvantage.) I turn first togenetic matters.An appropriate <strong>in</strong>troduction here <strong>in</strong>volves <strong>the</strong> realization that anymean<strong>in</strong>gful argument about group variation between black and whitepopulations, for <strong>in</strong>stance must rest upon firm def<strong>in</strong>itional foot<strong>in</strong>gs.Over <strong>the</strong> last two or three generations, not only have politicalconsiderations made discussion of genetic differentiation disreputable,<strong>the</strong> scientific community has <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>gly rejected <strong>the</strong> very idea ofdifferent human ‘races’ (see Aldhous, 2002; Ossorio & Duster, 2005).Schwartz’s (2001) characterization of race as a ‘biologically mean<strong>in</strong>gless’concept may be taken as typical here. However, a recent special issueof Nature Genetics (2004) shows that <strong>the</strong> matter is hardly a settled one.Some contributors argue, like Schwartz, that human ‘racial’ categoriesare not discrete, and are essentially socially def<strong>in</strong>ed, but o<strong>the</strong>rs claim thatobvious markers (sk<strong>in</strong> color, hair formation and so on) suggest a smallnumber of basic classifications. Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, developments <strong>in</strong> ourknowledge of matters at <strong>the</strong> level of DNA that is, at <strong>the</strong> level of <strong>the</strong>human genome make <strong>the</strong> picture more <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g still; for some criticalcomments about what might be termed <strong>the</strong> sociology of this new geneticresearch, see Carter (2007) and Tutton (2007). On this most elementaldimension, human be<strong>in</strong>gs show very little genetic variation. Ossorio and52


Disadvantage: The Genetic Case 53Duster (2005: 117) note that ‘any two unrelated persons, chosen atrandom from across <strong>the</strong> globe, are 99.9% identical <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir nucleotidesequences [i.e. <strong>the</strong>ir DNA]’. An <strong>in</strong>trigu<strong>in</strong>g elucidation of what this mightmean has just become available: reports <strong>in</strong> Nature by <strong>the</strong> ‘Chimpanzee’research group (2005) show that <strong>the</strong> human and <strong>the</strong> chimpanzee genomemay overlap by as much as 99%. Now, s<strong>in</strong>ce we are very different fromchimps, <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r 1% (represent<strong>in</strong>g many million po<strong>in</strong>ts of differencebetween <strong>the</strong> two genome codes) obviously rema<strong>in</strong>s of <strong>in</strong>credibleimportance; this, <strong>in</strong> turn, suggests that, given <strong>the</strong> existence of threebillion DNA ‘build<strong>in</strong>g blocks’, an ‘<strong>in</strong>ter-human’ difference only a tenth aslarge could still mean considerable variability.While <strong>the</strong> scientific effort cont<strong>in</strong>ues, social <strong>in</strong>terpretations cont<strong>in</strong>ue todemonstrate confusion and uneas<strong>in</strong>ess with ‘racial’ classifications. For abureaucratic example here, consider that <strong>the</strong> forms for many Americanfederal grant<strong>in</strong>g agencies cont<strong>in</strong>ue to ask applicants to <strong>in</strong>dicate <strong>the</strong>ir race.The five current categories are American Indian or Alaskan Native, Blackor African American, Asian, Native Hawaiian or O<strong>the</strong>r Pacific Islander,and White (<strong>the</strong>re are, <strong>in</strong> addition, two ‘ethnic’ classifications: Hispanic orLat<strong>in</strong>o, and rationally enough, if not very elegantly Not Hispanicor Lat<strong>in</strong>o). But, as Wash<strong>in</strong>gton’s Office of Management and Budget(2005) makes clear (and <strong>the</strong>se words appear on many of <strong>the</strong> applicationforms <strong>the</strong>mselves):This classification provides a m<strong>in</strong>imum standard for ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g,collect<strong>in</strong>g, and present<strong>in</strong>g data on race and ethnicity for all Federalreport<strong>in</strong>g purposes. The categories <strong>in</strong> this classification are socialpoliticalconstructs and should not be <strong>in</strong>terpreted as be<strong>in</strong>g scientificor anthropological <strong>in</strong> nature.Laversuch (2005, 2007) provides a comprehensive historical account of<strong>the</strong> ‘racial term<strong>in</strong>ology’ used <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> American census to describe AfricanAmericans and o<strong>the</strong>rs. Applicants request<strong>in</strong>g official largesse <strong>in</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rcountries (Brita<strong>in</strong>, for example) may also be required to provide ancestral<strong>in</strong>formation nowadays, but <strong>the</strong> appropriate check-boxes are not accompaniedby any social-political qualifiers.An illustrative, if ra<strong>the</strong>r Pythonesque, situation recently occurred <strong>in</strong>ano<strong>the</strong>r part of America. One-fifth of <strong>the</strong> entry-level places at <strong>the</strong>Universidade de Brasília is reserved for black candidates and about 4000hopeful students identified <strong>the</strong>mselves as black <strong>in</strong> 2004. They wererequired to supply photographs, which a six-person commission (onestudent, two social scientists and three representatives of <strong>the</strong> country’sblack political organization <strong>the</strong> Movimento Negro Unificado) <strong>the</strong>n


54 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong><strong>in</strong>spected. Their job was to decide if <strong>the</strong> applicant was really black, andmore than 200 people were rejected. Some three dozen of <strong>the</strong>se lodgedcompla<strong>in</strong>ts and were <strong>in</strong>terviewed (by ano<strong>the</strong>r committee). Did <strong>the</strong>y havel<strong>in</strong>ks to ‘black culture’? Were <strong>the</strong>y members of <strong>the</strong> movimento? Did <strong>the</strong>yhave any mulatta girlfriends?This might all seem very odd, <strong>in</strong> a ‘mestizo republic where racialidentity was, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> formal sense, immaterial’, accord<strong>in</strong>g to Fry (2005: 26),who should, of course, have used <strong>the</strong> Portuguese word mestiço here.Indeed, precisely because <strong>the</strong>re is so much mix<strong>in</strong>g and, consequently,such wide variation <strong>in</strong> sk<strong>in</strong> color, Brazil is often thought of as a society <strong>in</strong>which <strong>the</strong> racism still prevalent elsewhere is much reduced. Many yearsago, however, a colleague of m<strong>in</strong>e from São Paulo told me that <strong>the</strong> f<strong>in</strong>egradations of color simply translated <strong>in</strong>to f<strong>in</strong>e gradations of prejudice.Recent visitors may be seduced by <strong>the</strong> immediacy of <strong>the</strong> favelas of Rio deJaneiro that contribute to its ‘reputation as a socially liberated Mecca’(Greenberg, 2005); and <strong>the</strong> ‘constant, thrill<strong>in</strong>g collision of <strong>the</strong> differentsocial classes’ on Rio’s streets may re<strong>in</strong>force <strong>the</strong> Brazilian ‘myth of racialdemocracy’, but <strong>the</strong> extreme disparity between haves and have-nots‘runs along racial l<strong>in</strong>es’. In his review of a Brazilian study by Telles(2004), Fry confirms <strong>the</strong> po<strong>in</strong>t: ‘Telles’s data’, he says, show that ‘<strong>the</strong>lighter you are <strong>the</strong> better’. Daniel’s (2006) comparison of race and colormatters <strong>in</strong> Brazil and <strong>the</strong> USA is also relevant here.These ra<strong>the</strong>r more accurate perceptions of Brazilian society wereconfirmed, <strong>in</strong> late 2005, when a dramatic discovery was made <strong>in</strong> Rio deJaneiro. A residential renovation project uncovered a long-lost burialground for African slaves: <strong>the</strong> Cemitério dos Pretos Novos (<strong>the</strong> Cemetery ofNew Blacks). Conta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g about 20,000 bodies <strong>in</strong>terred between 1770 and1830, this cemetery is much larger than <strong>the</strong> now well-known AfricanBurial Ground that was revealed dur<strong>in</strong>g construction <strong>in</strong> Manhattan <strong>in</strong>1991, a site conta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> rema<strong>in</strong>s of some 500 American slaves and freeBlacks. The Brazilian discovery was widely publicized, and severalimportant facts emerged. Brazil was <strong>the</strong> s<strong>in</strong>gle biggest new-world marketfor slaves, tak<strong>in</strong>g about half of <strong>the</strong> ten million people who suffered <strong>the</strong><strong>in</strong>famous ‘middle passage’. The cemitério grew on <strong>the</strong> site of <strong>the</strong> ma<strong>in</strong>slave market that had been moved from <strong>the</strong> town center to <strong>the</strong> unhealthycoastal marshlands of <strong>the</strong> Gamboa district. The shameful treatment ofslaves both <strong>the</strong> liv<strong>in</strong>g and <strong>the</strong> dead has been described as Brazil’sholocaust, and it would appear that <strong>the</strong> treatment of <strong>the</strong>ir descendantsstill leaves much to be desired. In Brazil today, where almost half of <strong>the</strong>190 million citizens are black or of mixed racial background, a recentUnited Nations Development Program report has provided yet fur<strong>the</strong>r


Disadvantage: The Genetic Case 55confirmation here: ‘<strong>the</strong> data merely corroborate what is already visible toany observer: <strong>the</strong> far<strong>the</strong>r one goes up... <strong>the</strong> power hierarchy, <strong>the</strong> whiterBrazilian society becomes’ (see Muello, 2005). A quirky but <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>gpaper by Edmonds (2007) discusses how perceptions of race and beautyreveal <strong>the</strong>mselves <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> flourish<strong>in</strong>g Brazilian plastic-surgery bus<strong>in</strong>ess.To undergo expensive cosmetic <strong>in</strong>tervention to alter a ‘negroid nose’,for <strong>in</strong>stance, or an ‘ugly’ Indian body is surely to give very tangibleproof of a socio-racial hierarchy.In his famous and much-repr<strong>in</strong>ted book on rich and poor, urbanand rural, separate and mixed, Gilberto Freyre (1936) argued thathybridity and cultural miscegenation were <strong>the</strong> touchstones of Braziliansociety and its greatest strength, a mix<strong>in</strong>g characterized by a ‘reciprocitybetween <strong>the</strong> cultures, and not a dom<strong>in</strong>ation of one by <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r’(Philippou, 2005: 252). This is surely an <strong>in</strong>accurate, if socially desirable,assessment; fur<strong>the</strong>r, it is possible that Freyre’s advocacy of racial equality<strong>in</strong> a society unwill<strong>in</strong>g to fully embrace it may have actually re<strong>in</strong>forcedwhat Skidmore (1974) later called ‘<strong>the</strong> whiten<strong>in</strong>g ideal’ <strong>in</strong> Brazil. In anyevent to return to <strong>the</strong> universidade <strong>the</strong>re is surely a poignancy <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>existence of an affirmative-action policy that would be out of place and,<strong>in</strong>deed, unnecessary <strong>in</strong> a truly mestiço society; see also Campos de Souzaand Nascimento (2008).F<strong>in</strong>ally, th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g about ‘racial’ mix<strong>in</strong>g rem<strong>in</strong>ds me of an anecdoterecounted by Ernst Mayr, <strong>the</strong> famous evolutionary biologist; it concerns ajournalist who travels to Haiti and <strong>in</strong>terviews <strong>the</strong> president:Most <strong>in</strong>discreetly <strong>the</strong> American newspaperman asked <strong>the</strong> Presidentwhat percentage of <strong>the</strong> people were white. And <strong>the</strong> President of Haitisaid, ‘‘Oh, about 95 per cent.’’ The American newspaperman looked alittle puzzled and said, ‘‘Well, how do you def<strong>in</strong>e white?’’ And <strong>the</strong>President of Haiti said, ‘‘How do you def<strong>in</strong>e colored?’’ And <strong>the</strong>American newspaperman said, ‘‘Well, of course, anybody with Negroblood is colored.’’ Said <strong>the</strong> President: ‘‘Well, that’s exactly ourdef<strong>in</strong>ition, too: anybody with white blood is white.’’ (Mayr, 1968: 104)The Genetic Case for DisadvantageEugenics and <strong>the</strong> roots of assessmentHistorically, biological determ<strong>in</strong>ism has been <strong>the</strong> most pervasive of‘scientific’ accounts for group disadvantage. It has always been a centralfeature of racist discourse that some groups are <strong>in</strong>ferior to o<strong>the</strong>rs, aperception that has led to a wide variety of actions, rang<strong>in</strong>g from general


56 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>paternalism, to Ra<strong>in</strong>water’s notion of ‘benign’ <strong>in</strong>terventionism, toconsiderably less <strong>in</strong>nocuous actions. Some have argued that it isanachronistic to consider Victorian eugenicists like Francis Galton,who co<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>the</strong> term ‘eugenics’ (see his Inquiries, 1883) as racist <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>modern sense of <strong>the</strong> term; <strong>the</strong>ir pr<strong>in</strong>ciples were based upon <strong>the</strong> science of<strong>the</strong> day, and <strong>the</strong>y ought not to be thought of as some scholarly lynchmob. Galton himself apparently began to th<strong>in</strong>k about eugenics <strong>in</strong> midcentury,focus<strong>in</strong>g on <strong>the</strong> concept <strong>in</strong> his 1869 book on ‘hereditary genius’.The word ‘eugenics’ suggests ‘well born’ (Galton’s own synonym was‘good <strong>in</strong> stock’) and he referred to <strong>the</strong> practice as <strong>the</strong> ‘science ofimprov<strong>in</strong>g stock’. In all this, he and his colleagues were follow<strong>in</strong>g avery ancient l<strong>in</strong>e: selective breed<strong>in</strong>g and <strong>in</strong>formed <strong>in</strong>terference withprocreation have been discussed (at least) <strong>in</strong> virtually all societies. 1The zeal with which Galton and o<strong>the</strong>rs pursued <strong>the</strong>se matters, anenthusiasm that also animated later assessors of <strong>in</strong>telligence those whosaw <strong>the</strong> measurement of IQ as a useful screen<strong>in</strong>g device to ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>racial ‘standards’, and so on has quite an evangelical aura. Indeed, <strong>in</strong>his 1869 book, Galton wrote about a ‘religious duty’ to practice eugenics,and Karl Pearson (his ‘statistical heir’) wrote about <strong>the</strong> new Galtonian‘religion’ <strong>in</strong> his adulatory biography. The religious connection has beenmost carefully explored by White (2005, 2006a, 2006b), and Higham(1955: 150) refers to Galton’s eugenics as a sort of ‘secular religion’. Thereis, as White has po<strong>in</strong>ted out, a strong streak of puritanism <strong>in</strong> Galton andhis epigones, a Calv<strong>in</strong>ism that consigns everyone to a predeterm<strong>in</strong>edfate. In fact, he bluntly states that ‘all <strong>the</strong> early psychologists of<strong>in</strong>telligence had puritan family roots’ (White, 2005: 428); while, at <strong>the</strong>end of his piece, he acknowledges that <strong>the</strong> correlation could beco<strong>in</strong>cidental, he clearly feels that it is not.White (2006b) also considers some of <strong>the</strong> later lum<strong>in</strong>aries of<strong>in</strong>telligence assessment. The test<strong>in</strong>g ethos often had religious or quasireligiousunderp<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>gs, <strong>in</strong> an age <strong>in</strong> which spiritual motivations weremore openly articulated than <strong>in</strong> our own, where it has never<strong>the</strong>lessdeveloped <strong>in</strong>to a highly technical branch of <strong>the</strong> larger social-scientificexercise. White’s glance at Philip Vernon and Hans Eysenck <strong>in</strong> Brita<strong>in</strong>,and at Arthur Jensen and Richard Herrnste<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong> America, supports <strong>the</strong>idea of a generational evolution away from <strong>the</strong> puritanism of <strong>the</strong> past.Perhaps, however, it is not too far-fetched to see <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> work of suchresearchers some new secularized form of devotion a zealousscientism, perhaps. In any event, if we take <strong>in</strong>to even m<strong>in</strong>imal account<strong>the</strong> tenor of <strong>the</strong> (Victorian) times and <strong>the</strong> early years of <strong>the</strong> 20th century,concerns for knowledge, for advancement and above all for human


Disadvantage: The Genetic Case 57‘betterment’, can be clearly seen as central factors <strong>in</strong> that muscularChristian zeal that ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>ed an empire and created <strong>the</strong> new transatlanticcolossus.Galton had strong Quaker roots, as did his biographer and acolyte,Pearson. In America, Henry Goddard (1912) <strong>the</strong> author of <strong>the</strong> famous<strong>in</strong>vestigation <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> feeble-m<strong>in</strong>ded Kallikak family was a Quaker, andLewis Terman had a puritan background. Cyril Burt, <strong>the</strong> educationalresearcher associated with <strong>the</strong> Butler Education Act of 1944, and <strong>the</strong>result<strong>in</strong>g ‘eleven-plus’ exam<strong>in</strong>ation, was of Congregationalist stock. Hewas also a great admirer of Galton, and White (2006b) rem<strong>in</strong>ds us thatBurt’s fa<strong>the</strong>r held him (Galton) to be, along with Milton and Darw<strong>in</strong>, <strong>the</strong>epitome of <strong>the</strong> ‘ideal man’. (Indeed, as Crook [2007] notes <strong>in</strong> his work onsocial Darw<strong>in</strong>ism, <strong>the</strong>re are many <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g connections between <strong>the</strong>Darw<strong>in</strong>ian <strong>in</strong>heritance and <strong>the</strong> eugenics movement.) It is quite clear that<strong>the</strong> younger Burt shared this view. He was, more directly, a member of<strong>the</strong> Eugenics Society that Galton had established <strong>in</strong> 1908. All of this has aparticular poignancy because of <strong>the</strong> revelations that Burt falsified someof his statistical data; see Edwards (1989). Like o<strong>the</strong>r puritan denom<strong>in</strong>ations,<strong>the</strong> Congregationalist offshoot of Calv<strong>in</strong>ism was strongly motivatedand ambitious, but somewhat restricted <strong>in</strong> its notions of charity:‘like <strong>the</strong> Quakers [<strong>the</strong>y tended] to look after <strong>the</strong>ir own poor, while be<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>different to poverty <strong>in</strong> general, see<strong>in</strong>g it as part of <strong>the</strong> providentialplan’ (White, 2005: 431432). This surely has obvious l<strong>in</strong>ks with a geneticdeterm<strong>in</strong>ism where <strong>in</strong>telligence is concerned. Ano<strong>the</strong>r lum<strong>in</strong>ary, WilliamMcDougall an early social psychologist and <strong>in</strong>terpreter of <strong>the</strong> ‘groupm<strong>in</strong>d’ that was so much a preoccupation at <strong>the</strong> turn of <strong>the</strong> (20th) century,and a eugenicist was from <strong>the</strong> Dissent<strong>in</strong>g background, which broadly<strong>in</strong>cludes Congregationalists and Quakers. A central and common tenetwas a devotion to knowledge and, more specifically, to <strong>the</strong> idea that <strong>the</strong>material success to which knowledge could lead was a mark of div<strong>in</strong>eapprobation.There were many o<strong>the</strong>rs of similar description. White notes thatl<strong>in</strong>kages between puritanism and <strong>in</strong>telligence test<strong>in</strong>g are not apparent <strong>in</strong>all cases, and he admits that <strong>the</strong>re is generally no ‘conclusive’ evidencethat dissent<strong>in</strong>g beliefs <strong>in</strong>fluenced educational research. Indeed, some of<strong>the</strong> observations made by Alfred B<strong>in</strong>et whose name became synonymouswith <strong>in</strong>telligence test<strong>in</strong>g suggest that he may be one of <strong>the</strong>exceptions. In 1909, he wrote that those who believed <strong>in</strong>telligence to bean <strong>in</strong>herited and unalterable quantity demonstrated both a ‘brutalpessimism’ and scientific <strong>in</strong>accuracy; see also Clarke and Clarke (2006).None<strong>the</strong>less, while <strong>the</strong>re will obviously be exceptions, and while White’s


58 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>scholarly caution is commendable, I th<strong>in</strong>k <strong>the</strong> case for religious zealunderp<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g eugenic and assessment <strong>in</strong>terests is compell<strong>in</strong>g. There is,after all, a logic here. A belief that most of human <strong>in</strong>tellectual capacity isa fixed matter, a concern for <strong>the</strong> efficient classification of human wheatand chaff that ‘objective’ test<strong>in</strong>g seems to offer, and a sense that <strong>the</strong> bestshould be encouraged and <strong>the</strong> worst restra<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>the</strong>se and relatedassumptions are ideological ra<strong>the</strong>r than scientific <strong>in</strong> nature, and <strong>the</strong>ideology <strong>in</strong> question is clearly religious <strong>in</strong> orig<strong>in</strong>.Some have argued that a marriage of Calv<strong>in</strong>istic conceits and‘scientific’ determ<strong>in</strong>ism necessarily implies considerably less <strong>in</strong>terventionthan Victorian scholars were <strong>in</strong> fact committed to. If all ispredest<strong>in</strong>ed, for <strong>in</strong>stance, why bo<strong>the</strong>r with education? Thus, <strong>in</strong> a seriesof papers <strong>in</strong> The New Republic, Walter Lippmann levelled many criticismsat <strong>the</strong> eugenics and test<strong>in</strong>g movement; <strong>the</strong> famous American columnistargued at one po<strong>in</strong>t that its <strong>in</strong>fluence meant that ‘<strong>the</strong> task of educationhad given way to <strong>the</strong> doctr<strong>in</strong>e of predest<strong>in</strong>ation and <strong>in</strong>fant damnation’(Lippmann, 1922: 298); see also below. Apart from <strong>the</strong> fact thatarguments about religious predest<strong>in</strong>ation are many and nuanced, all<strong>the</strong> early <strong>in</strong>telligence testers would have said that, whatever <strong>the</strong>irlimitations, people ought to exert <strong>the</strong>mselves as best <strong>the</strong>y could, ando<strong>the</strong>r more fortunate souls should feel obliged to assist. Besides, as White(2006b: 48) has noted, ‘none of <strong>the</strong>m held that high <strong>in</strong>nate ability isenough on its own. For Galton, one also needs ‘‘<strong>the</strong> habits of selfdiscipl<strong>in</strong>eand <strong>in</strong>dustry’’... Burt and Terman agreed with him’. So did<strong>the</strong>y all, <strong>in</strong> fact. Even those espous<strong>in</strong>g a strongly hereditarian position,<strong>the</strong>n, could allow for some environmental f<strong>in</strong>e-tun<strong>in</strong>g. And as well, ofcourse, <strong>the</strong>re were also those div<strong>in</strong>e <strong>in</strong>junctions relat<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>in</strong>dustryversus idleness, to mak<strong>in</strong>g sure that <strong>the</strong> devil found no work forunemployed hands.While <strong>the</strong> evaluators of <strong>in</strong>telligence naturally measured along a scale,<strong>the</strong>y were always (as White notes) particularly <strong>in</strong>terested <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> extremes.Galton argued, for <strong>in</strong>stance, that ‘an average man is morally and<strong>in</strong>tellectually an un<strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g be<strong>in</strong>g’ (Pearson, 1924: 384). The greatest<strong>in</strong>terest will clearly attach to <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>telligent élite (who now represent <strong>the</strong>religious few, <strong>the</strong> ‘elect’) and to those at <strong>the</strong> opposite end of <strong>the</strong> IQcont<strong>in</strong>uum (who can now stand <strong>in</strong> for <strong>the</strong> many, <strong>the</strong> damned). Naturally,<strong>the</strong> evaluators <strong>the</strong>mselves were always <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> first select group; as for <strong>the</strong>o<strong>the</strong>rs, <strong>the</strong>y were ‘democracy’s ballast, not always useless but always apotential liability’ (Terman, 1922: 658).I began here by not<strong>in</strong>g that <strong>the</strong> equation of ‘Galtonism’ with racismhas generally been seen as <strong>in</strong>accurate. A reassessment by Brookes (2004),


Disadvantage: The Genetic Case 59however, takes a ra<strong>the</strong>r harsh view of Galton, who reiterated his ‘racistviews’ with disturb<strong>in</strong>g frequency. As aga<strong>in</strong>st <strong>the</strong> idea that <strong>the</strong>se viewswere essentially popular ones at <strong>the</strong> time is <strong>the</strong> fact that eugenics wasnot at all a popularly-received notion when it first emerged. Ra<strong>the</strong>r, itsteadily ga<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong> acceptance as <strong>the</strong> f<strong>in</strong>-de-siècle approached, and <strong>the</strong>economic conditions, <strong>the</strong> unprecedented patterns of immigration ands<strong>in</strong>cere concerns for mass social welfare all comb<strong>in</strong>ed to br<strong>in</strong>g it to itszenith dur<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> first third of <strong>the</strong> 20th century. Mak<strong>in</strong>g use of primarysource material, Lowe’s (1979: 297) terse but careful analysis reveals <strong>the</strong>tw<strong>in</strong> thrusts of <strong>the</strong> eugenics movement at this time: <strong>the</strong> assessment of<strong>in</strong>telligence and ‘backwardness’ and <strong>the</strong> ‘obsessive concern with racialdegeneration’ (see also Lowe, 1980). The appeal of <strong>the</strong> ‘self-direction ofhuman evolution’ (<strong>the</strong> motto of a eugenics congress held <strong>in</strong> New York <strong>in</strong>1921) seemed undeniable. It was a very widespread appeal: Adams(1990), McLaren (1990) and Dowbigg<strong>in</strong> (1997) discuss <strong>the</strong> eugenicsmovement <strong>in</strong> Germany, Brazil, France, Russia, Canada and elsewhere.Societies were established around <strong>the</strong> world, and <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>ternationalconferences devoted to <strong>the</strong> topic were supported and attended bysome of <strong>the</strong> most em<strong>in</strong>ent scientific and political figures of <strong>the</strong> time.The New York meet<strong>in</strong>gs had been preceded by an <strong>in</strong>itial ga<strong>the</strong>r<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>London <strong>in</strong> 1912, and a third large assembly took place also at <strong>the</strong>Natural History Museum <strong>in</strong> New York <strong>in</strong> 1932. At this last one, <strong>the</strong>‘problem’ of African Americans was at <strong>the</strong> top of <strong>the</strong> agenda.Eugenics and selection <strong>in</strong> AmericaStrong connections were naturally forged between <strong>the</strong> popular andwidespread early 20th-century view that some groups were <strong>in</strong>herentlyless capable than o<strong>the</strong>rs, and <strong>the</strong> burgeon<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>telligence-test<strong>in</strong>g movementpioneered by Alfred B<strong>in</strong>et, Lewis Terman and o<strong>the</strong>rs. Evaluationsof ability <strong>in</strong> ways now seen as clearly ethnocentric and biased <strong>in</strong> favorof <strong>the</strong> social ‘ma<strong>in</strong>stream’ came to have unfortunate implications <strong>in</strong>eugenic practice and <strong>the</strong>ory, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> passage of sterilization laws, and<strong>in</strong> immigration control <strong>the</strong> last two be<strong>in</strong>g particularly important <strong>in</strong>America. It surely comes as no surprise to learn that scientific <strong>in</strong>vestigationsof <strong>the</strong> period discovered mental deficiency to be especiallyprevalent among <strong>the</strong> black population. (As White [2006b] remarks, <strong>the</strong>test<strong>in</strong>g movement <strong>in</strong> Brita<strong>in</strong> focused upon class; <strong>in</strong> America, on race.)Relatedly, many Italian, Polish and Jewish immigrants were classified asfeeble-m<strong>in</strong>ded compared with <strong>the</strong>ir British and nor<strong>the</strong>rn Europeancounterparts. Thus, <strong>the</strong> eugenicist Henry Goddard adm<strong>in</strong>istered versions


60 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>of <strong>the</strong> B<strong>in</strong>et IQ test to immigrants at Ellis Island. The tests were <strong>in</strong>English. None<strong>the</strong>less, <strong>the</strong> results suggested (to <strong>the</strong> testers) that Jews,Italians and Poles were of feeble <strong>in</strong>telligence (Slotk<strong>in</strong>, 2005). In one earlyadm<strong>in</strong>istration, Goddard found that 25 out of 30 new Jewish immigrantswere feeble-m<strong>in</strong>ded: ‘we are now gett<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> poorest of each race’, heargued (Portes & Rumbaut, 1996: 197). Goldste<strong>in</strong> (2006) has recentlywritten about <strong>the</strong> perceived ‘Jewish problem’ here, with particularly<strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g notes on relationships real and attributed between Jewsand blacks. More particularly still, he describes <strong>the</strong> classificationaldifficulties that <strong>the</strong> white ma<strong>in</strong>stream associated with <strong>the</strong> Jews <strong>the</strong>mselves:<strong>the</strong>y were obviously not black, but were <strong>the</strong>y ‘white’? It seems anodd question now, but Goldste<strong>in</strong> shows how caricatured representationsof Jews often gave <strong>the</strong>m ‘black’ lips and hair, and how <strong>the</strong> presence ofJewish merchants <strong>in</strong> black neighborhoods was seen to be at onceopportunistic and <strong>in</strong> opposition to white sensibilities. At <strong>the</strong> sametime, more middle-class Jews emulated ma<strong>in</strong>stream values even to <strong>the</strong>extent of mount<strong>in</strong>g black-face m<strong>in</strong>strel shows. Still, if Jews were somehownot fully ‘white’, <strong>the</strong>y were anti-semitic cartoons aside clearlynot black. How, <strong>the</strong>n, were <strong>the</strong>y to be understood?Grow<strong>in</strong>g recognition by white Americans that <strong>the</strong> Jews defied easyplacement <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> categories of black and white did not mean that<strong>the</strong> color l<strong>in</strong>e ceased to play a significant role <strong>in</strong> fram<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> ‘‘JewishProblem’’ dur<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> 1920s and 1930s. In fact antisemites <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>period between <strong>the</strong> two wars became preoccupied with understand<strong>in</strong>g<strong>the</strong> relationship between Jewishness and whiteness. If <strong>the</strong>ycould no longer defuse <strong>the</strong> danger <strong>the</strong>y saw <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Jews by liken<strong>in</strong>g<strong>the</strong>m to African Americans, <strong>the</strong>y aimed <strong>in</strong>stead to study, clarify, andexpose <strong>the</strong>ir role as an unstable element <strong>in</strong> white society. (Goldste<strong>in</strong>,2006: 125126)Handl<strong>in</strong>’s classic study of race and nationality <strong>in</strong> America (1957)rema<strong>in</strong>s a f<strong>in</strong>e source on <strong>the</strong> assessment and <strong>the</strong> subsequent restriction ofimmigrants <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> first decades of <strong>the</strong> 20th century. Particularly relevantfor my purposes here is his discussion of <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>fluential report of <strong>the</strong>Immigration Commission (1911) and <strong>the</strong> later analysis by Laughl<strong>in</strong>(1923); <strong>the</strong> latter was supervisor of <strong>the</strong> Eugenics Records Office (seebelow), and an associate of <strong>the</strong> Immigration Restriction League led byMadison Grant (1916) whose book, The Pass<strong>in</strong>g of <strong>the</strong> Great Race,extolled <strong>the</strong> unique virtues of <strong>the</strong> ‘Nordic pioneers’. In his submission,Laughl<strong>in</strong> po<strong>in</strong>ted out that ‘<strong>the</strong> foreign-born show an <strong>in</strong>cidence of<strong>in</strong>sanity <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> state and federal hospitals 2.85 times higher than that


Disadvantage: The Genetic Case 61shown by <strong>the</strong> whole population, which latter are descended largely fromolder American stock’ (see also Portes & Rumbaut, 1996: 162). It isunsurpris<strong>in</strong>g to learn, <strong>the</strong>n, that <strong>the</strong> National Orig<strong>in</strong>s Act of 1924 barredmuch immigration, particularly from Asia and south-eastern Europe.These <strong>in</strong>fluential documents fuelled and re<strong>in</strong>forced <strong>the</strong> dist<strong>in</strong>ctionbetween <strong>the</strong> desirable ‘old’ immigration (pre-1880) from nor<strong>the</strong>rn andwestern Europe, and <strong>the</strong> ‘new’ and <strong>in</strong>ferior variety orig<strong>in</strong>at<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>sou<strong>the</strong>rn and eastern Europe. Higham’s treatments (1975 and, particularly,1955) also provide <strong>in</strong>sightful overviews here. And a new and veryreadable book by Bru<strong>in</strong>ius (2006) discusses <strong>the</strong> eugenic movement, <strong>the</strong>sterilization campaigns and o<strong>the</strong>r aspects of America’s ‘quest for racialpurity’. His analysis of <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>fluence of Harry Laughl<strong>in</strong>, who was oftencalled as an expert witness <strong>in</strong> congressional hear<strong>in</strong>gs and important courtcases deal<strong>in</strong>g with eugenic matters, is particularly <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g; see alsoBlack (2003).It is important to realize, by <strong>the</strong> way, that <strong>the</strong> zeal for better ‘selection’was not directed at potential immigrants alone. Rafter’s (1988) collectionof documents relat<strong>in</strong>g to some notable cases of family ‘degeneracy’presents <strong>the</strong> famous Jukes and Kallikaks, as well as <strong>the</strong> ‘hereditarydefectives’ among <strong>the</strong> ‘Hill Folk’ of Massachusetts, <strong>the</strong> ‘Smoky Pilgrims’of Kansas, and o<strong>the</strong>rs. Deutsch (2009) recounts <strong>the</strong> story of <strong>the</strong> ‘worstfamily <strong>in</strong> America’ <strong>the</strong> Ishmaels, late 19th-century Indianapolis slumdwellerswho came to symbolize <strong>the</strong> need for urban eugenics programs;see also <strong>the</strong> orig<strong>in</strong>al report on <strong>the</strong> clan by McCulloch (1888). As part of anexcellent treatment of <strong>the</strong> eugenic ‘idea’ throughout history, Carlson(2001) also discusses <strong>the</strong> Ishmaels. A more general treatment of ‘<strong>the</strong> artsand sciences of human <strong>in</strong>equality’ is that of Ewen and Ewen (2006): <strong>the</strong>irsurvey takes <strong>the</strong> reader from physiognomy to craniometry, from eugenicsto modern sexism and racism. Murdoch (2007) provides yet ano<strong>the</strong>r‘popular’ account of <strong>the</strong> rise of <strong>the</strong> American test<strong>in</strong>g movement, from <strong>the</strong>ideas of Galton, through <strong>the</strong> test<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>sights of B<strong>in</strong>et, and on to <strong>the</strong>excesses that resulted. W<strong>in</strong>field (2007) focuses particularly on <strong>the</strong> way <strong>in</strong>which eugenic ideas became reflected <strong>in</strong> educational <strong>the</strong>ory and practice;she suggests that education, as an arm of <strong>the</strong> larger society, cont<strong>in</strong>ues tounfairly impose sort<strong>in</strong>g-out procedures on its charges. Perhaps, shenotes, ‘our ‘‘at-risk’’ students today were <strong>the</strong> ‘‘imbeciles’’ and ‘‘defectives’’of yesterday’ (W<strong>in</strong>field, 2007: 159).W<strong>in</strong>field began her account, <strong>in</strong>cidentally, by rem<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g readers that,<strong>in</strong> Me<strong>in</strong> Kampf, Hitler outl<strong>in</strong>es <strong>the</strong> modell<strong>in</strong>g of his racist plans on<strong>the</strong> provisions and thrust of American legislation of <strong>the</strong> 1920s (seealso <strong>the</strong> earlier essay by Crook, 2002). Indeed, Hitler was particularly


62 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>appreciative of Grant’s work, writ<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>the</strong> author and referr<strong>in</strong>g to hisbook as a ‘bible’. Many writers have po<strong>in</strong>ted to <strong>the</strong> lessons that <strong>the</strong> Nazislearned about <strong>the</strong> implementation of ‘eugenic’ ideas from <strong>the</strong> Americanexperience; Black (2003) and Bru<strong>in</strong>ius (2006) provide quite thoroughtreatments here. Roberts (2008) discusses eugenics and its Nazi implicationsas part of his new monograph on historical views of human be<strong>in</strong>gsas animals. Baum (2006) charts <strong>the</strong> rise of <strong>the</strong> idea of a Caucasian ‘race’;along <strong>the</strong> way, he presents useful <strong>in</strong>formation about <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>evitableconsequences: conceptions of racial superiority and <strong>in</strong>feriority, eugenicmovements, restrictions on immigration, and so on.While attention to <strong>the</strong> domestic population actually preceded thatgiven to newcomers, comparison soon began to be made. In 1855,Edward Jarvis had found that <strong>the</strong> proportion of immigrants <strong>in</strong> lunaticasylums <strong>in</strong> Massachusetts was greater than that of <strong>the</strong> native population,<strong>the</strong> ratio be<strong>in</strong>g about 5:4. Jarvis’s study is notable for two reasons: itwas <strong>the</strong> first American work to consider <strong>the</strong> relationship betweenimmigration and mental illness, and it demonstrated that poverty was<strong>the</strong> mediat<strong>in</strong>g variable. That is, s<strong>in</strong>ce <strong>the</strong>re were proportionally morepoor immigrants than poor natives, and s<strong>in</strong>ce asylum <strong>in</strong>mates tended tobe paupers, <strong>the</strong>n it was to be expected that one would f<strong>in</strong>d more<strong>in</strong>stitutionalized immigrants than <strong>the</strong>ir overall population numberswould suggest. This second feature of Jarvis’s work is of greatimportance, for it refuted any simplistic correlation between be<strong>in</strong>gforeign and be<strong>in</strong>g mentally ill. And yet, for many years afterwards,xenophobia and racism, coupled with eugenic enthusiasms, neglectedthis all-important clarification <strong>in</strong> favor of a more brutal and more directcorrelation between immigration and feeble-m<strong>in</strong>dedness. Thus, o<strong>the</strong>rstudies of ‘settled’ immigrants that found apparently higher rates ofmental illness often attributed <strong>the</strong>se to ‘psychopathic tendencies <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>constitution of those who emigrate’ (Portes & Rumbaut, 1996: 163). Rare<strong>in</strong>deed was <strong>the</strong> enquiry that gave any consideration to traumas ofupheaval and relocation, or to <strong>the</strong> fact that new-world experiences wereoften less than favorable.Several recent overviews have illum<strong>in</strong>ated <strong>the</strong> impact of eugenicth<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g on American programs meant to screen and, <strong>in</strong> some<strong>in</strong>stances, to compulsorily sterilize <strong>the</strong> ‘feeble-m<strong>in</strong>ded’. Kl<strong>in</strong>e (2001)demonstrates <strong>the</strong> broader social conceptions of sexuality and morality atwork here (conceptions that we have seen probed <strong>in</strong> recent debates overhuman clon<strong>in</strong>g). Stern (2005) focuses on <strong>the</strong> eugenics movement <strong>in</strong>California, where more than one-quarter of all <strong>in</strong>voluntary Americansterilizations occurred, and one of her chapters discusses ‘quarant<strong>in</strong>e and


Disadvantage: The Genetic Case 63eugenic gatekeep<strong>in</strong>g’ along <strong>the</strong> border with Mexico. Mol<strong>in</strong>a (2006)<strong>in</strong>vestigates <strong>the</strong> negative public-health attitudes towards immigrants <strong>in</strong>Los Angeles: <strong>the</strong> Ch<strong>in</strong>ese were ‘<strong>in</strong>terlopers <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> land of sunsh<strong>in</strong>e’(p. 15), <strong>the</strong> Mexicans were ‘a diseased, charity-seek<strong>in</strong>g group’ (p. 136),<strong>the</strong> Japanese were ‘ignorant, uncultured and half civilized’ (p. 57). Theywere all representative of <strong>the</strong> ‘vast masses of peasantry, degraded belowour utmost conceptions... [with] no history beh<strong>in</strong>d <strong>the</strong>m... beaten menfrom beaten races, represent<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> worst failures <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> struggle forexistence’ (Walker, 1896: 828; see also Black, 2003; Bru<strong>in</strong>ius, 2006).All of this work was expedited by <strong>the</strong> rapid development of a relianceupon test<strong>in</strong>g that has hardly abated s<strong>in</strong>ce. Giordano (2005) provides anadmirable overview of <strong>the</strong> growth of educational test<strong>in</strong>g, remark<strong>in</strong>gupon <strong>the</strong> racialized assumptions and underp<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>gs of many tests forimmigrant and black populations. The zeal for assessment, <strong>the</strong> prejudicedand ill-formed judgments that drove it and gave it its shape, and<strong>the</strong> unfortunate consequences for those many <strong>in</strong>dividuals whosepotentials and achievements were never given a fair opportunity toreveal <strong>the</strong>mselves <strong>the</strong>se co<strong>in</strong>cided with at least some scholarly concern.The famous Edw<strong>in</strong> Bor<strong>in</strong>g, for example, was able to po<strong>in</strong>t out as early as1923 that <strong>in</strong>telligence is what <strong>in</strong>telligence tests test. While Bor<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>tended to warn aga<strong>in</strong>st a sterile and static circularity, it is <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>gto consider that <strong>the</strong> statement could also be taken as an endorsement of<strong>the</strong> validity of exist<strong>in</strong>g measures of <strong>in</strong>telligence. The journalist and<strong>in</strong>ventor of <strong>the</strong> word ‘stereotype’ Walter Lippmann (1922) deservessome credit for tak<strong>in</strong>g on proponents of test<strong>in</strong>g and subject<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>irflawed and <strong>in</strong>complete th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g to criticisms that sound quite modern:‘<strong>in</strong>telligence’ tests are generally noth<strong>in</strong>g of <strong>the</strong> k<strong>in</strong>d, <strong>the</strong>y can be adaptedto suit many purposes, <strong>the</strong>y are not (what we would now call) ‘culturefair’,<strong>the</strong>y often build upon unproven assumptions about <strong>the</strong> relativeimportance of heredity and environment, and so on (see Block &Dwork<strong>in</strong>, 1976; Giordano, 2005); Pastore (1978) provides a commentaryon Lippmann’s writ<strong>in</strong>gs. For an excellent overview of <strong>the</strong> evolution of<strong>in</strong>telligence test<strong>in</strong>g, from Galton to Jensen, see Wickett (1990); for anhistorical consideration go<strong>in</strong>g back to <strong>the</strong> Greeks, Spearman’s (1937)dated but still very <strong>in</strong>formative work is recommended.Louis Marshall, one of <strong>the</strong> founders of <strong>the</strong> American JewishCommittee, also po<strong>in</strong>ted to <strong>the</strong> flaws <strong>in</strong> test methodology and adm<strong>in</strong>istration,as well as to <strong>the</strong> pseudo-science, hypocrisy and racism thatunderp<strong>in</strong>ned <strong>the</strong> whole enterprise. But <strong>the</strong> popular tide was runn<strong>in</strong>g fastaga<strong>in</strong>st <strong>the</strong> critics. This was, after all, an age <strong>in</strong> which one president(Hard<strong>in</strong>g) was popularly (but probably <strong>in</strong>accurately) thought to be a


64 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>member of <strong>the</strong> Ku Klux Klan, while ano<strong>the</strong>r (Wilson) had ‘rationalized<strong>the</strong> vigilantism of <strong>the</strong> KKK as a necessary counter to Black Reconstruction’(Slotk<strong>in</strong>, 2005: 220). In fact, as a testament to his friendship withD.W. Griffith, whose 1915 film, The Birth of a Nation, extolled <strong>the</strong> KKK,Wilson provided a quotation used <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> film: ‘The white men wereroused by a mere <strong>in</strong>st<strong>in</strong>ct of self-preservation... until at last <strong>the</strong>re hadsprung <strong>in</strong>to existence a great Ku Klux Klan, a veritable empire of <strong>the</strong>South, to protect <strong>the</strong> Sou<strong>the</strong>rn country’ (<strong>the</strong> l<strong>in</strong>e is apparently taken fromWilson, 1902).It is <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g to consider that <strong>the</strong> American zeal for <strong>in</strong>telligencetest<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>in</strong>itially built upon <strong>the</strong> B<strong>in</strong>et-Simon tests imported from France,was not matched <strong>in</strong> France itself. As Schneider (1992) has po<strong>in</strong>ted out,<strong>the</strong> anglophone practice obsession might be a better word of try<strong>in</strong>g toreduce <strong>in</strong>telligence to a s<strong>in</strong>gle (IQ) number was considered too much of ablunt <strong>in</strong>strument <strong>the</strong>re. But <strong>in</strong> Brita<strong>in</strong> and America (particularly <strong>the</strong>latter), <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>telligence-test<strong>in</strong>g movement of <strong>the</strong> early 20th century waspart and parcel of <strong>the</strong> growth of psychology itself (Samelson, 1977; andsociology, too see Carter, 2000). In his doctoral <strong>the</strong>sis, Terman (1906)had said that <strong>the</strong> discipl<strong>in</strong>e needed more <strong>in</strong>timate connections with ‘reallife’, and <strong>the</strong> heightened recognition it received (among psychologistsconduct<strong>in</strong>g and assess<strong>in</strong>g military <strong>in</strong>telligence-test<strong>in</strong>g, for example) wasa welcome development for <strong>the</strong> fledgl<strong>in</strong>g (social) science. A consequence,as Samelson (1978) po<strong>in</strong>ted out a little later, was that psychology verysoon found itself <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> ra<strong>the</strong>r embarrass<strong>in</strong>g position of hav<strong>in</strong>g to shakeoff this powerful early re<strong>in</strong>forcement of its scholarly status: ‘<strong>in</strong> 1920, mostpsychologists believed <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> existence of mental differences between[sic] races; by 1940, <strong>the</strong>y were search<strong>in</strong>g for <strong>the</strong> sources of ‘‘irrationalprejudice’’’ (Samelson, 1978: 265).The unrelent<strong>in</strong>g drive for evaluation and selection through standardizedtest<strong>in</strong>g procedures was greatly re<strong>in</strong>forced and stimulated bysimilar trends <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Army. As Chapman (1988) notes, <strong>the</strong> AmericanArmy versions of <strong>the</strong> French (B<strong>in</strong>et-Simon) <strong>in</strong>telligence test preparedby Lewis Terman and Arthur Otis (his student) were to be fur<strong>the</strong>rrevised after <strong>the</strong> war for use <strong>in</strong> schools. The famous military ‘Alpha’ and‘Beta’ <strong>in</strong>telligence tests were aimed at ‘men who read and write English’(<strong>the</strong> Alpha form) and for ‘foreigners and illiterates’ (Beta). They weremeant to serve a dual purpose: on <strong>the</strong> one hand, <strong>the</strong> Army wanted toknow someth<strong>in</strong>g of <strong>the</strong> competence of all those flood<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> service;on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r, <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>formation ga<strong>in</strong>ed was to be of use to those support<strong>in</strong>g<strong>the</strong> work of <strong>the</strong> Immigration Restriction League (founded <strong>in</strong> 1894 and, asalready noted, subsequently led by Madison Grant) <strong>in</strong> its advocacy of


Disadvantage: The Genetic Case 65literacy requirements for immigrants. But, of course, <strong>the</strong> not-so-hiddenagenda was to encourage <strong>the</strong> arrival of ‘Nordic’ immigrants, anddiscourage that of o<strong>the</strong>rs, particularly sou<strong>the</strong>rn Europeans. The Armytests were flawed <strong>in</strong> basic construction. For example, <strong>the</strong>y testedAmerican ‘cultural’ knowledge that would have been ‘familiar toEnglish-speak<strong>in</strong>g middle-class urban whites, but [not]... to non-Englishspeakers and to blacks and whites from rural districts’ (Slotk<strong>in</strong>, 2005:229). As well, <strong>the</strong>y were adm<strong>in</strong>istered to large groups, not <strong>in</strong>dividuals, <strong>in</strong>a bewilder<strong>in</strong>gly different variety of sett<strong>in</strong>gs, <strong>the</strong>y were scored byunqualified enlisted men, and so on. And yet, poor performance on<strong>the</strong>se deficient tests was still ascribed to <strong>in</strong>nate deficiency, and not to<strong>in</strong>adequacies <strong>in</strong> culturally specific areas. Thus, <strong>the</strong> Army tests, <strong>the</strong>mselvesbuilt upon earlier exercises aimed at pre-war immigrants, nowalso served post-war purposes of immigration restriction.The results of test<strong>in</strong>g 2 million soldiers, ‘many of whom were foreignborn and illiterate’ (Portes & Rumbaut, 1996: 197), firmly re<strong>in</strong>forced<strong>the</strong> nativist tendencies flourish<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> psychological, educational (andmany o<strong>the</strong>r) circles. Brigham (1923: 194) argued that ‘<strong>the</strong> representativesof <strong>the</strong> Alp<strong>in</strong>e and Mediterranean races <strong>in</strong> our immigration are <strong>in</strong>tellectually<strong>in</strong>ferior to <strong>the</strong> representatives of <strong>the</strong> Nordic race’, and Kirkpatrick(1926: 2) added that <strong>in</strong>nate deficiencies meant that no amount of‘Americanisation’ could turn immigrants <strong>in</strong>to ‘<strong>in</strong>telligent Americancitizens capable of appropriat<strong>in</strong>g and advanc<strong>in</strong>g a complex culture’(see also Gould, 1981).It seems bizarre that people could be tested <strong>in</strong> a language o<strong>the</strong>r than<strong>the</strong>ir own, about a culture with which <strong>the</strong>y were unfamiliar, and that<strong>the</strong>ir shortcom<strong>in</strong>gs would <strong>the</strong>n be attributed to genetic <strong>in</strong>feriorities. Butwe must remember that <strong>the</strong> tests were designed and adm<strong>in</strong>istered <strong>in</strong> acontext <strong>in</strong> which nativist m<strong>in</strong>ds were already made up. What waswanted was some ‘scientific’ justification for positions already taken.There were many psycho-educational traps await<strong>in</strong>g unwanted immigrants,and a tell<strong>in</strong>g example of how difficult <strong>the</strong>se were to avoid isfound <strong>in</strong> Sandiford and Kerr’s (1926) study of Ch<strong>in</strong>ese and Japanesechildren <strong>in</strong> Vancouver. The <strong>in</strong>vestigators found that <strong>the</strong>ir measured<strong>in</strong>telligence scores were well above those of <strong>the</strong>ir white schoolmates, andadmitted that <strong>the</strong> two groups were <strong>the</strong> most <strong>in</strong>telligent residents ofBritish Columbia. The prevalent arguments that it was <strong>the</strong> weakest wholeft <strong>home</strong> and became immigrants seemed unsusta<strong>in</strong>able <strong>in</strong> this case, andso <strong>the</strong> authors took <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r tack: it is <strong>the</strong> clever, resourceful andcourageous ones who emigrate. Now, if feeble-m<strong>in</strong>ded immigrants are aburden to <strong>the</strong>ir new communities, surely clever ones enhance <strong>the</strong>m?


66 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>Unfortunately, no: ‘<strong>the</strong> presence of so many clever, <strong>in</strong>dustrious andfrugal aliens, capable... of compet<strong>in</strong>g successfully with <strong>the</strong> nativewhites... constitutes a political and economic problem of <strong>the</strong> greatestimportance’ (Sandiford & Kerr, 1926: 365). Could <strong>the</strong>re be a clearerillustration of <strong>the</strong> heads-I-w<strong>in</strong>-tails-you-lose equation? 2As conflicts generally do, <strong>the</strong> 19141918 war highlighted manyexist<strong>in</strong>g tendencies. For example, <strong>the</strong> American black troops serv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>France often found an acceptance from <strong>the</strong>ir French counterparts <strong>the</strong>re,as well as from civilians, that <strong>the</strong>y were denied at <strong>home</strong>. This couldnot be allowed to cont<strong>in</strong>ue and so, <strong>in</strong> early August 1918, one ColonelL<strong>in</strong>ard a French liaison officer with <strong>the</strong> Americans issued a statemententitled ‘Secret Information Concern<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> Black American Troops’. Thiswas published <strong>the</strong> follow<strong>in</strong>g year <strong>in</strong> The Crisis, a black civil-rightsmagaz<strong>in</strong>e founded <strong>in</strong> 1910 by William Du Bois (see L<strong>in</strong>ard, 1919). Thestatement has sometimes been attributed to General John ‘Black Jack’Persh<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>the</strong> commander of <strong>the</strong> American Expeditionary Force. This ismistaken, but L<strong>in</strong>ard’s observations did have <strong>the</strong> bless<strong>in</strong>g of Persh<strong>in</strong>gand his staff. Directed towards French officers, <strong>the</strong> short statementpo<strong>in</strong>ted out that <strong>in</strong>timacy between <strong>the</strong> French and <strong>the</strong> black Americantroops must be prevented, <strong>the</strong> latter must not be commended too highly(‘particularly <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> presence of white Americans’), and <strong>the</strong> ‘nativepopulation’ must refra<strong>in</strong> from ‘spoil<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> Negroes’. Above all, L<strong>in</strong>ardtold his readers, ‘<strong>the</strong> black man is regarded by <strong>the</strong> white American as an<strong>in</strong>ferior be<strong>in</strong>g’. The racist attitudes animat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> whole exercise werenot so much k<strong>in</strong>dled by black-white fraternization <strong>in</strong> France as much asby <strong>the</strong> unwelcomed consequences of acceptance once <strong>the</strong> black soldiersreturned <strong>home</strong>. After all, ‘an experience of ‘‘undue social mix<strong>in</strong>g’’ <strong>in</strong>France would undo <strong>the</strong> lifelong lessons <strong>in</strong>culcated by Jim Crow’ (Slotk<strong>in</strong>,2005: 255).It is <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g but perhaps not very surpris<strong>in</strong>g to note that <strong>the</strong>Germans were vigorously ‘re<strong>in</strong>terpreted’ dur<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> war. Henry Osborn,a Columbia University professor, argued that ‘Prussian ferocity’ derivedfrom <strong>the</strong>ir Mongol ancestry (<strong>the</strong>y were Huns, after all). Previousassessments that had classified <strong>the</strong> Germans as true Teutons would, ofcourse, position <strong>the</strong>m too closely to those favored ‘Nordic’ immigrants.No, <strong>the</strong>y were essentially Asiatics, ‘wild Tartars... most ancient savagesof <strong>the</strong> steppes’ (Slotk<strong>in</strong>, 2005: 217). The next step is not difficult to predict:Germans were associated with ‘Negroes’. Slotk<strong>in</strong>’s book <strong>in</strong>cludes aposter show<strong>in</strong>g a slaver<strong>in</strong>g ape hold<strong>in</strong>g a club <strong>in</strong> one hand (labelled‘Kultur’) and a swoon<strong>in</strong>g white woman <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r. This ‘black Hun’ has


Disadvantage: The Genetic Case 67just stepped onto <strong>the</strong> shores of America, and <strong>the</strong> image is captioned,‘Destroy This Mad Brute: Enlist’.Professor Osborn was hardly <strong>the</strong> only Ivy League scholar to quicklysuccumb to war fever. Recall<strong>in</strong>g his student days at Harvard dur<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>First World War, John Dos Passos (1963: 77) recounts his astonishment athow <strong>the</strong> professors,most of <strong>the</strong>m rational New Englanders brought up <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> broadm<strong>in</strong>dedpragmatism of William James or <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> lyric idealism ofRalph Waldo Emerson, allowed <strong>the</strong>ir mental processes to be sotransformed by <strong>the</strong>ir conviction of <strong>the</strong> rightness of <strong>the</strong> Allied causeand <strong>the</strong> wickedness of <strong>the</strong> German enemy, that many of <strong>the</strong>mrema<strong>in</strong>ed narrow bigots for <strong>the</strong> rest of <strong>the</strong>ir lives.As I have noted, eugenic po<strong>in</strong>ts of view became more and morewidespread. They appealed to many perhaps most politicians andsocial commentators of various stripes. Among <strong>the</strong> latter can be countedH.G. Wells and George Bernard Shaw. And, writ<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>the</strong> Prime M<strong>in</strong>ister<strong>in</strong> 1910, W<strong>in</strong>ston Churchill (as <strong>home</strong> secretary) argued that sterilizationwould check <strong>the</strong> ‘unnatural and <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>gly rapid growth of <strong>the</strong> feeblem<strong>in</strong>dedand <strong>in</strong>sane classes’, someth<strong>in</strong>g that ‘constitutes a national andrace danger which it is impossible to exaggerate’ (Pont<strong>in</strong>g, 1994: 100). Ina letter to a prom<strong>in</strong>ent eugenicist, <strong>in</strong> 1913, Theodore Roosevelt made asimilar observation:I agree with you if you mean, as I suppose you do, that society has nobus<strong>in</strong>ess to permit degenerates to reproduce <strong>the</strong>ir k<strong>in</strong>d. It is reallyextraord<strong>in</strong>ary that our people refuse to apply to human be<strong>in</strong>gs suchelementary knowledge as every successful farmer is obliged to applyto his own stock breed<strong>in</strong>g... we have no bus<strong>in</strong>ess to permit <strong>the</strong>perpetuation of citizens of <strong>the</strong> wrong type. (Bru<strong>in</strong>ius, 2006: 190191)Grant (1916: 45), whose book I have mentioned above, proclaimed that‘<strong>the</strong> laws of nature require <strong>the</strong> obliteration of <strong>the</strong> unfit, and human life isvaluable only when it is of use to <strong>the</strong> community or race’. The fact that, aslate as 1916, Grant was able to write <strong>the</strong> follow<strong>in</strong>g paragraph is an<strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>dication not only of widespread prejudice, but also ofwhat it was considered acceptable to put <strong>in</strong> writ<strong>in</strong>g:The native American has always found, and f<strong>in</strong>ds now, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> blackmen, will<strong>in</strong>g followers who ask only to obey and to fur<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> idealsand wishes of <strong>the</strong> master race, without try<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>in</strong>ject <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> bodypolitic <strong>the</strong>ir own views, whe<strong>the</strong>r racial, religious, or social. Negroes


68 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>are never socialists or labor unionists, and as long as <strong>the</strong> dom<strong>in</strong>antimposes its will on <strong>the</strong> servient race, and as long as <strong>the</strong>y rema<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>same relation to <strong>the</strong> whites as <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> past, <strong>the</strong> negroes will be avaluable element <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> community, but once raised to social equality<strong>the</strong>ir <strong>in</strong>fluence will be destructive to <strong>the</strong>mselves and to <strong>the</strong> whites. If<strong>the</strong> purity of <strong>the</strong> two races is to be ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>ed, <strong>the</strong>y cannot cont<strong>in</strong>ueto live side by side, and this is a problem from which <strong>the</strong>re can be noescape. (Grant, 1916: 7879; see also Brace [2005] for useful notes onGrant and o<strong>the</strong>r prom<strong>in</strong>ent figures)Grant’s book sold <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> millions, and was widely translated mostnotably <strong>in</strong>to German. While scholars frequently attacked his ideas, Granthad many academic supporters, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> noted biologist, CharlesDavenport. The two collaborated to found <strong>the</strong> Galton Society <strong>in</strong> 1918;earlier, Davenport had established <strong>the</strong> Eugenics Record Office, underwrittenby <strong>the</strong> Carnegie Institution, and published his own very popularbook on heredity and eugenics (Davenport, 1911). In retrospect, <strong>the</strong>efforts of eugenicists like Davenport and Grant can be seen as <strong>the</strong> lastscientific (or, ra<strong>the</strong>r, quasi-scientific) gasp of a once-respectable (or quasirespectable)set of assumptions. Of course, <strong>the</strong>ir pass<strong>in</strong>g from <strong>the</strong>academic scene hardly signified anyth<strong>in</strong>g like a full and f<strong>in</strong>al disappearance.If more culturally sensitive sociologies and anthropologieswere ga<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g strength, if <strong>the</strong> scientific bases of most eugenic argumentswere <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>gly seen to be flawed or non-existent, and if <strong>the</strong> attentiongiven to lay commentators (like Grant) was <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>gly challenged bythat accorded to real scientific authorities well, we must not imag<strong>in</strong>ethat victories were ei<strong>the</strong>r swift or complete.In his decision <strong>in</strong> a famous Supreme Court case about <strong>in</strong>voluntarysterilization, Justice Oliver Wendell Holmes wrote, <strong>in</strong> 1927:We have seen more than once that <strong>the</strong> public welfare may call upon<strong>the</strong> best citizens for <strong>the</strong>ir lives. It would be strange if it could not callupon those who already sap <strong>the</strong> strength of <strong>the</strong> State for <strong>the</strong>se lessersacrifices, often not felt to be such by those concerned, <strong>in</strong> order toprevent our be<strong>in</strong>g swamped with <strong>in</strong>competence. It is better for all <strong>the</strong>world, if <strong>in</strong>stead of wait<strong>in</strong>g to execute degenerate offspr<strong>in</strong>g for crime,or to let <strong>the</strong>m starve for <strong>the</strong>ir imbecility, society can prevent thosewho are manifestly unfit from cont<strong>in</strong>u<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>ir k<strong>in</strong>d. The pr<strong>in</strong>ciplethat susta<strong>in</strong>s compulsory vacc<strong>in</strong>ation is broad enough to covercutt<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> Fallopian tubes... three generations of imbeciles areenough. (Laughl<strong>in</strong>, 1930: 52)


Disadvantage: The Genetic Case 69F<strong>in</strong>ally here, early 20th-century assessments of feeble-m<strong>in</strong>dedness andgeneral <strong>in</strong>competence also implicated language: a study by Goodenough(1926: 393), for example, concluded that ‘<strong>the</strong> use of a foreign language <strong>in</strong><strong>the</strong> <strong>home</strong> is one of <strong>the</strong> chief factors <strong>in</strong> produc<strong>in</strong>g mental retardation’.Similarly, Smith (1939) concluded, on <strong>the</strong> basis of her work with children<strong>in</strong> Hawaii, that attempts to use two languages h<strong>in</strong>dered development. Inhis classic <strong>Language</strong>s <strong>in</strong> Contact, We<strong>in</strong>reich (1953) summarized a history ofsuch mis<strong>in</strong>formation, present<strong>in</strong>g a long list of disorders associated withbil<strong>in</strong>gualism: moral depravity, stutter<strong>in</strong>g, left-handedness, idleness andexcessive materialism are among <strong>the</strong> more bizarre items on <strong>the</strong> list. AndFlores (2005) has recently summarized <strong>the</strong> matter for <strong>the</strong> Mexican-American population, a large and important constituency both <strong>the</strong>nand now.Contemporary manifestationsThe ultimate excesses of <strong>the</strong> biological view became evident dur<strong>in</strong>g<strong>the</strong> Second World War and <strong>the</strong>se, toge<strong>the</strong>r with o<strong>the</strong>r genocides of <strong>the</strong>20th century, have made assumptions of <strong>in</strong>nate <strong>in</strong>feriority ra<strong>the</strong>r lessacceptable. Or so it might seem. There cont<strong>in</strong>ue, for example, to besupporters of eugenic <strong>in</strong>terventions, some of <strong>the</strong>m quite notable. In 1970,William Shockley, a Nobel Prize w<strong>in</strong>ner <strong>in</strong> physics and <strong>the</strong> founder of‘Silicon Valley’, argued that such measures might be useful <strong>in</strong> counter<strong>in</strong>g<strong>the</strong> alleged decl<strong>in</strong>e <strong>in</strong> American <strong>in</strong>telligence. He was very much caughtup <strong>in</strong> Jensenist assertions that <strong>in</strong>telligence could be accurately ascerta<strong>in</strong>edand that certa<strong>in</strong> steps might follow; see below. At one po<strong>in</strong>t,Shockley suggested f<strong>in</strong>ancial compensation for black Americans will<strong>in</strong>gto undergo sterilization (see Shurk<strong>in</strong>, 2006).Much more commonly, however, we f<strong>in</strong>d that public disapproval hasdone little more than to drive racist assumptions underground, to make<strong>the</strong>ir expression less overt. In some important work, Jones and hiscolleagues (Jones & Sigall, 1971; Sigall & Page, 1971) led people to th<strong>in</strong>kthat <strong>the</strong>ir attitudes could be accurately measured by mach<strong>in</strong>e. When <strong>the</strong>ywere asked to verbally express <strong>the</strong> op<strong>in</strong>ions that <strong>the</strong>y now believed werealso be<strong>in</strong>g electronically monitored, some depress<strong>in</strong>gly familiar perceptionswere revealed. Indeed, <strong>the</strong>re was a partial re-emergence ofprejudices that had been expressed openly <strong>in</strong> attitude studies of <strong>the</strong>1920s and 1930s, prejudices that had become socially unacceptable s<strong>in</strong>ce<strong>the</strong>n. The general argument made by <strong>the</strong> researchers was that ‘sociallydesirable’ responses disappear or become attenuated <strong>in</strong> sett<strong>in</strong>gs where


70 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong><strong>the</strong>re seems to be no po<strong>in</strong>t <strong>in</strong> deception (a recent overview is provided byPlant et al., 2003).Racist actions rema<strong>in</strong> a grievous social problem <strong>in</strong> many contexts, and<strong>the</strong> studies just cited suggest that <strong>the</strong> attitudes from which <strong>the</strong>y stem mayl<strong>in</strong>ger beh<strong>in</strong>d politically correct masks; and Smedley and Smedley (2005)po<strong>in</strong>t out that while ‘race’ itself may be a ‘biological fiction’, racism isreal. With<strong>in</strong> post-war educated circles, however, respectable (or pseudorespectable)arguments for <strong>in</strong>nate genetic deficiency largely languisheduntil Arthur Jensen proposed that American blacks were <strong>in</strong>deed below<strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>telligence levels of normal whites. In his well-known paper <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>Harvard Educational Review, Jensen (1969) proposed that compensatoryeducation for black children had failed, largely because its proponentshad ignored genetic social-class and racial differences. Programs ofcompensatory education were (and sometimes still are) built upon <strong>the</strong>assumption that group differences <strong>in</strong> achievement and <strong>in</strong>telligence testperformance are traceable to environmental causes, and so a simple andimmediate response to Jensen’s paper was that it espoused a racist viewof society.Over <strong>the</strong> ensu<strong>in</strong>g 40 years, <strong>the</strong>re have been recurrent academicarguments about <strong>in</strong>nate <strong>in</strong>tellectual <strong>in</strong>feriority. The controversy ignitedby ‘Jensenism’ was repeated a quarter of a century later, when Herrnste<strong>in</strong>and Murray (1994) published The Bell Curve (see also Herrnste<strong>in</strong>, 1971,1973). Some of <strong>the</strong> heat and <strong>the</strong>re often is more heat than light <strong>in</strong> suchhighly charged arenas, even among supposedly dis<strong>in</strong>terested scholars can be gauged by look<strong>in</strong>g at Gould’s (1994) spirited rebuttal; see also hisearlier monograph on <strong>the</strong> measurement of <strong>in</strong>telligence (Gould, 1981), itspost-Bell Curve revision (1996), and <strong>the</strong> collections edited by Jacoby andGlauberman (1995) and Fraser (1995) both with fur<strong>the</strong>r contributionsby Gould. Beyond stimuli provided by fur<strong>the</strong>r scientific advance, as with<strong>the</strong> human genome projects (noted above), resurfac<strong>in</strong>gs of <strong>the</strong> genetic<strong>the</strong>sis at less enlightened levels are as predictable as <strong>the</strong> vehementresponses <strong>the</strong>y evoke. They can be expected, <strong>in</strong> fact, wheneverscapegoats are needed, whenever political conservatism is regnant,whenever liberal forces argue for renewed f<strong>in</strong>ancial and social attentionto poverty and oppression.None<strong>the</strong>less, <strong>the</strong> accusations of racism tout court rout<strong>in</strong>ely levelled atgenetic <strong>the</strong>orists are often over-simplifications. Besides be<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> firstcontemporary research-based argument for important group variation <strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>herited capabilities, Jensen’s <strong>the</strong>sis also provides <strong>the</strong> clearest evidencehere. In 1967, he argued that ‘low-average IQ’ could not be seen as‘evidence of poor genetic potential’ (Jensen, 1967: 10); <strong>in</strong> 1968, he


Disadvantage: The Genetic Case 71acknowledged that <strong>the</strong>re was ‘little <strong>in</strong>formation’ about <strong>the</strong> possibilities ofa genetic basis to disadvantage (Jensen, 1968: 22). It was only <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>notorious 1969 paper that Jensen came down on <strong>the</strong> side of a ‘genetichypo<strong>the</strong>sis’ (Jensen, 1969: 82; see also Jensen, 1973), although he stillconsidered environmental <strong>in</strong>teractions to be important. Regardless of itscorrectness, this demonstration of an evolv<strong>in</strong>g position is not consistentwith a racist perspective, where <strong>in</strong>tellectual stasis is <strong>the</strong> norm. Jensen cancerta<strong>in</strong>ly be accused, however, of mak<strong>in</strong>g ill-considered and <strong>in</strong>flammatorystatements:Is <strong>the</strong>re a danger that current welfare policies, unaided by eugenicforesight, could lead to <strong>the</strong> genetic enslavement of a substantialsegment of our population? (Jensen, 1969: 95)As we have already seen, assessments of <strong>in</strong>herent <strong>in</strong>tellectual <strong>in</strong>feriorityhave generally relied upon <strong>in</strong>telligence tests and <strong>the</strong> measurement ofIQ differences, and Jensen’s <strong>in</strong>vestigations were no exceptions. Of course,some tests are clearly biased <strong>in</strong> favor of certa<strong>in</strong> groups not all <strong>the</strong><strong>in</strong>iquities of <strong>the</strong> early 20th-century evaluations of immigrants have goneunremarked and so Jensen and o<strong>the</strong>rs have typically tried to avoidmeasures of highly specific abilities, rely<strong>in</strong>g ra<strong>the</strong>r upon tests tapp<strong>in</strong>gmore general mental capacity. Dist<strong>in</strong>ctions between specific and generalabilities all derive from Spearman’s early 20th-century categorizations of<strong>in</strong>telligence (see Spearman, 1927; Spearman & Wynn Jones, 1950). S<strong>in</strong>ce<strong>the</strong>n, many different types and classifications of <strong>in</strong>telligence have beenproposed; for comparisons of different social populations, however,<strong>the</strong> avoidance of group-specific measures rema<strong>in</strong>s <strong>the</strong> most essentialfeature.A basic and <strong>in</strong>surmountable difficulty rema<strong>in</strong>s, however. All tests nomatter how ‘culture-free’ or ‘culture-fair’ or ‘non-verbal’ are devised atsome time, by someone, to measure someth<strong>in</strong>g. Even if <strong>the</strong> object is to taphighly abstract, non-verbal <strong>in</strong>telligence (for example), socioculturaldeterm<strong>in</strong>ations of <strong>in</strong>telligence cannot be avoided. While tests canobviously be made less directly related to <strong>the</strong> knowledge and skillsavailable more to one group than to ano<strong>the</strong>r, even measures ofapparently general factors <strong>in</strong>volve assumptions about <strong>in</strong>telligence thatderive from a given set of values. To return to <strong>the</strong> central actors <strong>in</strong> thiscontemporary version of <strong>the</strong> drama, <strong>the</strong> argument that black and whitechildren share much that is culturally common, and hence should not bediscrim<strong>in</strong>ated aga<strong>in</strong>st by tests of so-called ‘general’ ability, simply doesnot come to terms with <strong>the</strong> degree and subtlety of group differences thatmay exist.


72 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>When it was found that some groups more materially disadvantagedthan American blacks outperformed <strong>the</strong>m on non-verbal <strong>in</strong>telligencetests, Jensen and o<strong>the</strong>rs claimed this to be a demonstration of <strong>the</strong>weakness of an environmentalist position. A specific <strong>in</strong>stance wasrecorded by Hans Eysenck: he observed that <strong>the</strong> test performance ofInuit children was superior to that of black youngsters, even though <strong>the</strong>former apparently live under much harsher environmental conditionsthan <strong>the</strong> latter; <strong>in</strong>deed, some Inuit test scores were at or above <strong>the</strong> normsestablished for white children. Eysenck (1975: 110) summarized <strong>the</strong>matter as follows:if social and sensory deprivation, or o<strong>the</strong>r environmental deprivationfactors, are postulated to account for IQ deficits <strong>in</strong> white work<strong>in</strong>gclassor coloured populations, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> logic of <strong>the</strong> explanationrequires absolutely that a severely deprived group, such as <strong>the</strong>Eskimos [sic], should show evidence of IQ deficit; <strong>the</strong> fact is that <strong>the</strong>ydo not.In fact, however, all that is demonstrated is <strong>the</strong> complexity of environmentalfactors, <strong>the</strong> difficulty <strong>in</strong> adequately assess<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>m, and <strong>the</strong>danger <strong>in</strong> simply equat<strong>in</strong>g material poverty with educational and socialdisadvantage; see Taylor and Skanes (1977) for a thoughtful response toEysenck’s assertions. To equate observable and ra<strong>the</strong>r gross <strong>in</strong>dices ofmaterial deprivation with <strong>in</strong>tellectual disadvantage, when such variablesmay not <strong>in</strong> fact be directly relevant, does not make for a strong case.There may exist all sorts of differences <strong>in</strong> all sorts of groups, such thatsome will score better than o<strong>the</strong>rs on any given test, and such differencesmay or may not be related to poverty of physical environment. It is atleast a reasonable assumption, however, that score differences may berelated to more specific, less visible variables that exist and operate <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>social environment. (In fairness to Jensen, Eysenck and <strong>the</strong>ir epigones, itshould be acknowledged that <strong>the</strong> environmentalist position that <strong>the</strong>yattacked did often base its arguments largely upon material deprivation;this emphasis, however, was a weakness of <strong>the</strong> environmentalist stanceon disadvantage, not of <strong>the</strong> explanatory value of <strong>the</strong> environment per se;see below.)Attempts have been made to control for environment by match<strong>in</strong>gsocioeconomic-status levels across <strong>the</strong> groups that are to be compared(black and white schoolchildren, for <strong>in</strong>stance), but <strong>the</strong>se cannot be veryuseful <strong>in</strong> contexts <strong>in</strong> which such match<strong>in</strong>g does not really implyenvironmental equality. In societies where racial prejudice exists, forexample, it is obvious that gross similarities <strong>in</strong> socioeconomic status may


Disadvantage: The Genetic Case 73only mask <strong>the</strong> effects of that prejudice; thus, it would be naïve to acceptthat match<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> educational and <strong>in</strong>come levels of blacks and whites <strong>in</strong>America implied <strong>the</strong> establishment of environmental equality between<strong>the</strong>m. A generation ago, Walter Bodmer succ<strong>in</strong>ctly observed that:<strong>the</strong> question of a possible genetic basis for <strong>the</strong> race-IQ difference willbe almost impossible to answer satisfactorily before <strong>the</strong> environmentaldifferences between US blacks and whites have beensubstantially reduced. (Bodmer, 1972: 111)Given <strong>the</strong> difficulties, <strong>the</strong>re has been some <strong>in</strong>terest <strong>in</strong> studies of identicaltw<strong>in</strong>s. On <strong>the</strong> surface, <strong>the</strong>y would seem to provide an ideal test-case:s<strong>in</strong>ce <strong>the</strong>y are genetically identical, any differences found must beattributable to environmental <strong>in</strong>fluences. And, s<strong>in</strong>ce <strong>the</strong> measured IQsof identical tw<strong>in</strong>s raised apart are typically found to be stronglycorrelated, it might appear that a strong case has been established for<strong>the</strong> relatively greater importance of nature over nurture. As Donald Hebb(1968) once put it, however, separated tw<strong>in</strong>s should be put <strong>in</strong> maximallydifferent environments to properly test nature-versus-nurture hypo<strong>the</strong>ses:send one of <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>fants to live <strong>in</strong> luxury, <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r to <strong>the</strong> slums. Thisis an ethically unconscionable practice, of course. In fact, <strong>in</strong> thoserelatively rare <strong>in</strong>stances <strong>in</strong> which identical tw<strong>in</strong>s have had to be broughtup <strong>in</strong> separate environments, <strong>the</strong> degree of separation is typicallym<strong>in</strong>imized as much as possible.These are <strong>the</strong> pivotal po<strong>in</strong>ts <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> genetics ‘case’, but <strong>the</strong>re are manyo<strong>the</strong>r <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g ones that I have had to omit <strong>in</strong> this brief survey. Test‘wiseness’ and test motivation, for <strong>in</strong>stance, are not equally distributedacross groups; relatedly, <strong>the</strong> social-psychological and situational factorssurround<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> actual adm<strong>in</strong>istration of tests (who are <strong>the</strong> testers; wheredoes <strong>the</strong> test<strong>in</strong>g take place?) have been shown to be very important.There are technical genetic questions about <strong>the</strong> measurement and<strong>in</strong>fluence of heritability with<strong>in</strong> and across groups. And even <strong>the</strong> highcorrelations reported between <strong>the</strong> measured <strong>in</strong>telligences of identicaltw<strong>in</strong>s reared apart have been questioned. Colman (1987: 77) provided anexcellent overview of <strong>the</strong> central issues here and, <strong>in</strong> summariz<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>m,noted how surprised he was ‘to discover how little support, even of <strong>the</strong>most <strong>in</strong>direct k<strong>in</strong>d, could be mustered for <strong>the</strong> hereditarian <strong>the</strong>sis’.Arguments have rema<strong>in</strong>ed controversial over <strong>the</strong> last several decades,even as <strong>the</strong>y have faded from important segments of <strong>the</strong> literature.I recall, for example, that when Jensen gave an <strong>in</strong>vited address at <strong>the</strong>University of Southampton <strong>in</strong> early 1999, various security measures werestill required. In a sense, all of this is quite ironic anyway: if we were to


74 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>follow <strong>the</strong> genetics case to its logical conclusion, skipp<strong>in</strong>g over some of<strong>the</strong> difficulties I have identified here, we would f<strong>in</strong>d that it has virtuallyno practical applicability at all! It was <strong>the</strong> alleged failure of compensatoryprograms, remember, that first motivated Jensen’s attention. On <strong>the</strong> basisof his <strong>in</strong>vestigations, he concluded that alterations <strong>in</strong> curricularapproaches were <strong>in</strong>dicated. Specifically, he recommended <strong>in</strong>structionaladjustments to help those children whose general abilities were of wha<strong>the</strong> termed <strong>the</strong> ‘level 1’ variety whose <strong>in</strong>nate skills, that is to say, weremore ‘associative’ than ‘conceptual’ (i.e. <strong>the</strong> more elaborative abilitiespossessed by ‘level 2’ <strong>in</strong>dividuals). Even on <strong>the</strong> basis of <strong>the</strong> summaryI have presented here, however, we can see that <strong>the</strong> isolation of suchability levels can be questioned on <strong>the</strong> grounds of <strong>in</strong>sufficient sensitivityto environmental nuance and, hence, <strong>in</strong> terms of gross over-simplification.As well, given that <strong>the</strong> levels clearly imply marked differences <strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>tellectual capability, variant teach<strong>in</strong>g methods could only serve to pullgroups fur<strong>the</strong>r apart. That is, even if cross-group genetic differences <strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>telligence were a significant factor to be reckoned with, could wereasonably teach some children <strong>in</strong> ways that might well downplay <strong>the</strong>elaborative and transformational skills required for full social participation?Such an approach could surely only be defended for <strong>the</strong> educationof severely sub-normal children whose genetic disabilities are pronouncedand obvious.These are not, of course, <strong>the</strong> children under discussion and, given thatfact, any applicability of <strong>the</strong> genetic argument evaporates. Measured<strong>in</strong>telligence differences between black and white children have typicallybeen on <strong>the</strong> order of 10 to 15 IQ po<strong>in</strong>ts. If we were to accept thatdemonstrable group differences do <strong>in</strong> fact exist, and that <strong>the</strong>se actuallyreflect someth<strong>in</strong>g of underly<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>telligence, <strong>the</strong> magnitude of <strong>the</strong>differences would still be <strong>in</strong>sufficient to cause great problems <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>normal classroom; and <strong>the</strong>y would certa<strong>in</strong>ly be too m<strong>in</strong>or to warrantdifferential curricular treatments for <strong>the</strong> children so clumsily ‘levelled’.In a response to Jensen’s 1969 paper, Jerome Kagan po<strong>in</strong>ted out that:genetic factors are likely to be most predictive of proficiency <strong>in</strong>mental talents that are extremely difficult to learn... learn<strong>in</strong>g to read,write or add are easy skills, well with<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> competence of all childrenwho do not have serious bra<strong>in</strong> damage... n<strong>in</strong>ety out of every 100children, black, yellow or white, are capable of adequate mastery of<strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>tellectual requirements of our schools. (Kagan, 1969: 277)Simply put, <strong>the</strong> po<strong>in</strong>t is this: even allow<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> scope of <strong>the</strong> claimsmade by <strong>the</strong> ‘nature’ proponents (which has obviously not been my


Disadvantage: The Genetic Case 75<strong>in</strong>tention here), <strong>the</strong>y have no practical relevance. Stephen Wisemansummarized it nicely a generation ago:<strong>the</strong> fierce controversies over <strong>the</strong> precise proportion of <strong>in</strong>fluenceexerted by nature as opposed to nurture are of importance to <strong>the</strong>geneticist and <strong>the</strong> psychologist, but for <strong>the</strong> teacher I suggest that <strong>the</strong>yare largely irrelevant. (Wiseman, 1973: 87)None<strong>the</strong>less, research on group differences <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>telligence is as perennialas <strong>the</strong> heated reaction it evokes. A very recent example is provided by <strong>the</strong><strong>in</strong>vestigations of Richard Lynn and Paul Irw<strong>in</strong>g, whose <strong>the</strong>sis is that menhave larger bra<strong>in</strong>s and higher IQs than women; this is <strong>the</strong> reason thatmen w<strong>in</strong> most of <strong>the</strong> Nobel prizes and o<strong>the</strong>r lofty academic dist<strong>in</strong>ctions.A brief report on <strong>the</strong> work, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Times Higher Education Supplement (2September 2005; see also Irw<strong>in</strong>g & Lynn, 2005), was accompanied by apiece by Irw<strong>in</strong>g (2005: 12), who argued that it was necessary to analyzeand <strong>in</strong>terpret controversial data: ‘<strong>the</strong> consequences of scientists suppress<strong>in</strong>gdata because <strong>the</strong>y do not fit <strong>in</strong> with <strong>the</strong>ir preferred ideological worldview are disastrous’. This is, of course, <strong>the</strong> most basic of scientificarguments: researchers must go where <strong>the</strong> data take <strong>the</strong>m. Jensen made<strong>the</strong> same argument and, <strong>in</strong> strictly scientific terms, it is irrefutable. Butwhere <strong>the</strong> objects of study are human be<strong>in</strong>gs, and where <strong>the</strong> context isone of both historical and contemporary controversy, one must be alive to<strong>the</strong> possibility that as Hudson (1973) bluntly observed <strong>in</strong>vestigationsmay fuel racism and may undercut or br<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>to question enlightenedsocial response (see also Cronbach, 1975). The potential problems hereare exacerbated, of course, when (as we have seen with Jensen) <strong>the</strong>studies are described or summarized <strong>in</strong> ill-considered ways, ways thatare bound to give offense.Also <strong>in</strong> September 2005, a popular Québec television show, Tout lemonde en parle, presented <strong>the</strong> views of a psychiatrist who claimed (as aRadio-Canada announcement summarized it) ‘que les Noirs et lesAutochtones avaient en moyenne un quotient <strong>in</strong>tellectuel <strong>in</strong>férieure àcelui des Blancs’. Radio-Canada (2005) argued that <strong>the</strong> show is meant tobe provocative, and that <strong>the</strong> management ‘estime avoir fait le bon choixen diffusant les propos controversés du Docteur Pierre Mailloux’. Theshow’s host and programm<strong>in</strong>g director argued that ‘offensive... andhateful discussions should be debated publicly... s<strong>in</strong>ce <strong>the</strong>y exist <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>underground of society, it took only one question [i.e. to Mailloux] to seeracism and xenophobia emerge candidly’ (Peritz, 2005). The broadcasterscerta<strong>in</strong>ly knew about Mailloux from previous <strong>in</strong>cidents: he has a ‘trackrecord of <strong>in</strong>cendiary remarks’. His comments drew immediate fire from


76 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong><strong>the</strong> Broadcast Standards Council, as well as from o<strong>the</strong>r <strong>in</strong>terested parties.But Mailloux rema<strong>in</strong>ed unrepentant: ‘de son côté, [il] ne regrette rien despropos qu’il a tenus en entrevue et a répété toute la journée qu’iln’accepte pas que la susceptibilité empéche de parler d’études scientifiques’.One th<strong>in</strong>g, at least, seems clear, <strong>in</strong> this alarm<strong>in</strong>g and apparentlyunend<strong>in</strong>g cycle: we must not allow hate speech to slip <strong>in</strong>to publicdiscourse under <strong>the</strong> banner of scientific <strong>in</strong>vestigation.Notes1. Buss (1976) makes <strong>the</strong> argument that, <strong>in</strong> addition to be<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> fa<strong>the</strong>r ofeugenics, Francis Galton also launched <strong>the</strong> study of ‘<strong>in</strong>dividual differences’,or ‘differential psychology’. His 1883 publication, for example, gave someconsiderable attention to gender differences. While ever <strong>the</strong> courteousVictorian gentleman, Galton was like many o<strong>the</strong>r men of <strong>the</strong> time ra<strong>the</strong>rtaken aback by fem<strong>in</strong>ist developments. He felt that women had weaker<strong>in</strong>tellects and powers of discrim<strong>in</strong>ation, go<strong>in</strong>g on to write that:coyness and caprice have <strong>in</strong> consequence become a heritage of <strong>the</strong> sex,toge<strong>the</strong>r with a cohort of allied weaknesses and petty deceits, that menhave come to th<strong>in</strong>k venial and even amiable <strong>in</strong> women, but which <strong>the</strong>ywould not tolerate among <strong>the</strong>mselves. (Galton, 1883: 39)Among many o<strong>the</strong>r th<strong>in</strong>gs, Galton was a committee member of an antisuffragesociety.2. An earlier example this time <strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>digenous Americans is found <strong>in</strong>Stetson’s (1897) study of <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>telligence of black and white schoolchildren <strong>in</strong>Wash<strong>in</strong>gton. His f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g that <strong>the</strong> former outperformed <strong>the</strong> latter, on <strong>the</strong> basisof <strong>the</strong>ir comprehension and recall of poetry, was unpalatable and unacceptableto him and to o<strong>the</strong>rs. Revisions of <strong>the</strong> procedure were immediatelysuggested. Wiggan (2007) comments on <strong>the</strong> matter (although his citation forStetson’s paper is <strong>in</strong>accurate).It is not my purpose here to fur<strong>the</strong>r discuss <strong>the</strong> art and science of test<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong> general, but I should alert <strong>the</strong> reader to <strong>the</strong> existence of an importantcontemporary literature on language test<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> particular. The recent books bySpolsky (1995), Shohamy (2001) and McNamara and Roever (2006) arerecommended here because <strong>the</strong>ir critical overviews are grounded <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>appropriate historical and social context.


Chapter 5Disadvantage: The EnvironmentalCaseIntroductionJensen is not <strong>the</strong> only contemporary researcher whose <strong>in</strong>vestigationsof ‘race’ and <strong>in</strong>telligence have proved controversial. In <strong>the</strong> UK, <strong>the</strong> viewsof <strong>the</strong> late Hans Eysenck were not dissimilar and, <strong>in</strong> Canada, <strong>the</strong> work ofPhilippe Rushton is relevant. In a 1995 book on ‘race’ and behavior(a book praised by Jensen and Eysenck), Rushton argued for <strong>the</strong>existence of three races (Orientals, Whites and Blacks) and claimed that<strong>the</strong> data show <strong>the</strong> first group to be better socially organized, to showgreater sexual restra<strong>in</strong>t and to be more <strong>in</strong>telligent than Europeans, who,<strong>in</strong> turn, score higher on such dimensions than Africans and <strong>the</strong>irdescendants. It is entirely possible that as he himself would no doubtclaim Rushton is simply go<strong>in</strong>g where he th<strong>in</strong>ks <strong>the</strong> data lead. He ra<strong>the</strong>rblotted his scientific copybook, however, by appear<strong>in</strong>g on GeraldoRivera’s ‘trash-television’ show <strong>in</strong> 1989, by speak<strong>in</strong>g at a conference of<strong>the</strong> American Renaissance organization (a white-separatist group) which led to a citation on <strong>the</strong> web-site of Stormfront, a white-supremacistbody and by accept<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> presidency of <strong>the</strong> Pioneer Fund, a researchagency whose position on matters of race and eugenics has occasionedmuch debate. Horowitz (1995) touches upon <strong>the</strong> important issues, bothpopular and scientific, that bear upon Rushton’s work and, <strong>in</strong>deed, uponall modern studies of ‘race’ and <strong>in</strong>telligence.The most recent statement by Rushton is that ‘black people have loweraverage IQ scores than white people... we have concluded that geneticfactors have a role to play <strong>in</strong> this difference, as evidenced by <strong>the</strong> fact thatblack <strong>in</strong>fants adopted and brought up by white middle-class parentsshow little improvement <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir IQ scores by late adolescence’ (Lynn &Rushton, 2006). It would seem that, despite <strong>the</strong> cautions expressed byBodmer and o<strong>the</strong>r geneticists (see Chapter 4), and despite a great deal ofsupport<strong>in</strong>g evidence from sociological and psychological <strong>in</strong>vestigations,Lynn and Rushton cont<strong>in</strong>ue to believe that <strong>the</strong> negative effects of liv<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong> societies <strong>in</strong> which racial prejudice cont<strong>in</strong>ues its baleful course are77


78 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>substantially countered when black children are raised <strong>in</strong> white <strong>home</strong>s.See Brace (2005) for some discussion of <strong>the</strong>se contemporary researchers<strong>in</strong>to ‘race’; see also Tucker (1994, 2002) for <strong>in</strong>vestigation of <strong>the</strong> politicaland f<strong>in</strong>ancial back<strong>in</strong>g that ‘racial research’ has had <strong>in</strong> North America. 1Environmental DeficiencyIf ‘genetic’, ‘hereditarian’ or ‘nature’ arguments have failed to rega<strong>in</strong>much lost ground <strong>in</strong> recent times despite <strong>the</strong> best efforts of a fewpsychologists <strong>the</strong> idea that some environments lead to substantive<strong>in</strong>tellectual deficiency rema<strong>in</strong>s powerful. As Harwood (1982) hasobserved, it has been <strong>the</strong> dom<strong>in</strong>ant <strong>the</strong>sis s<strong>in</strong>ce <strong>the</strong> mid-20th century,and it is still widely, if <strong>in</strong>articulately, believed that certa<strong>in</strong> lifestyles can beemotionally and cognitively crippl<strong>in</strong>g. (Remember here that we arediscuss<strong>in</strong>g an allegedly group-level phenomenon: no one would denythat, <strong>in</strong> many <strong>in</strong>dividual <strong>in</strong>stances, early deficiencies <strong>in</strong> nutrition, say, or<strong>in</strong> parent-child attachment can have tangible, unfavorable and sometimespermanent consequences.) A study by Edwards and McK<strong>in</strong>non(1987; see also follow<strong>in</strong>g chapters) clearly demonstrated <strong>the</strong> cont<strong>in</strong>u<strong>in</strong>gpower of <strong>the</strong> disadvantage-as-deficit perspective among teachers. Teachersconstitute a particularly important population here because <strong>the</strong>yare <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> front l<strong>in</strong>e, so to say, of educational disadvantage, and because<strong>the</strong>ir attitudes and actions can have a significant effect upon <strong>the</strong>irclassroom charges. More subtly and as I remark <strong>in</strong> Chapter 1 <strong>the</strong>re is<strong>the</strong> ever-present danger that, if teachers are not well <strong>in</strong>formed aboutdisadvantage before enter<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> classroom, <strong>the</strong>y may easily be assimilatedto <strong>the</strong> prevail<strong>in</strong>g ‘deficit’ ethos of <strong>the</strong> exist<strong>in</strong>g educationalestablishment. After all, <strong>in</strong> f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g one’s <strong>in</strong>structional feet, what couldbe more natural than to adopt <strong>the</strong> postures and practices of those already<strong>in</strong> place?In <strong>the</strong> environmental-deficit assessment of <strong>the</strong> major underp<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>gs ofdisadvantage, genetic determ<strong>in</strong>ants are rejected <strong>in</strong> favor of contextualfactors. Disadvantaged children are seen to arrive at school unpreparedfor its demands and challenges; <strong>the</strong>ir difficulties <strong>the</strong>re and, by extension,<strong>in</strong> later life, derive largely from <strong>the</strong> unsatisfactory nature of <strong>the</strong>ir earlyphysical, social and psychological background. It is <strong>the</strong> environmentaldeprivationapproach to disadvantage that has obviously provided <strong>the</strong>greatest impetus for compensatory education programs. There areseveral variants of <strong>the</strong> environmental position, but all of <strong>the</strong>m assumethat deprivations of one sort or ano<strong>the</strong>r lead to educational and socialdisadvantage: <strong>the</strong>y differ <strong>in</strong> expla<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g just how disadvantage arises.


Disadvantage: The Environmental Case 79In an early argument, sensory deprivation was thought to be <strong>the</strong> chiefculprit. It has long been known that animals reared <strong>in</strong> isolation fromo<strong>the</strong>rs, or <strong>in</strong> severely abnormal social conditions, develop <strong>in</strong> aberrant and<strong>in</strong>appropriate ways; if <strong>the</strong> early conditions are severe enough, recoverybecomes impossible. Among human be<strong>in</strong>gs too, we know that sensorydeprivation (or perceptual isolation) has dramatic consequences.Observations of prisoners <strong>in</strong> isolation cells and <strong>the</strong> victims of ‘bra<strong>in</strong>wash<strong>in</strong>g’or ‘thought reform’ are relevant here. The effects can be easilyreplicated <strong>in</strong> laboratory conditions. In studies at McGill Universitydur<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> 1950s, well-paid subjects were required to lie on a bed withno visual, somaes<strong>the</strong>tic or auditory stimulation: few could endure <strong>the</strong>monotony for more than a few days, and none for more than six. Hebb(1968: 252) described some of <strong>the</strong> effects: ‘<strong>the</strong> subjects <strong>in</strong> isolationcompla<strong>in</strong>ed of be<strong>in</strong>g unable to th<strong>in</strong>k coherently... <strong>the</strong>y began to havehalluc<strong>in</strong>ations... [<strong>the</strong>ir] very identity had begun to dis<strong>in</strong>tegrate’. O<strong>the</strong>revidence for <strong>the</strong> importance of early stimulation derives from studies of<strong>in</strong>stitutionalized children who while receiv<strong>in</strong>g adequate physical care lived <strong>in</strong> dull and unstimulat<strong>in</strong>g quarters, lack<strong>in</strong>g attention and personalcontact. In famous work by Skeels and Dye (1939), Spitz (1946) andDennis (1960), apathy, poor motor and mental performance, developmentalretardation and ‘anaclitic depression’ (whose symptoms <strong>in</strong>cludelistlessness, withdrawal, susceptibility to illness and anorexia) weredocumented consequences.Could, <strong>the</strong>n, <strong>the</strong> environmental conditions lead<strong>in</strong>g to social andeducational disadvantage have to do with <strong>in</strong>adequate stimulation and<strong>in</strong>terpersonal contact? The work of Hunt (1964: 242) was representativehere; he argued that <strong>the</strong> ‘effects of cultural deprivation [are]...analogous to <strong>the</strong> experimentally-found effects of experiential deprivation<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>fancy’ (see also Hunt, 1961, 1975). Any analogy, however, betweensensory deprivation <strong>in</strong> experimental animals and <strong>in</strong>stitutionalizedchildren, on <strong>the</strong> one hand, and <strong>the</strong> ‘cultural deprivation’ (i.e. disadvantage)of poor children, on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r, is very weak. Lower-class neighborhoods,for <strong>in</strong>stance, are not at all similar to <strong>the</strong> orphanages and hospitalsstudied by those students of anaclitic depression. Comparisons between<strong>the</strong> ‘sensory stimulation’ available <strong>in</strong> lower- and middle-class <strong>home</strong>smay reveal some <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g differences, but <strong>the</strong>re is little to suggest that<strong>the</strong> amount of stimulation is markedly different. (Indeed, we mightsuspect that, <strong>in</strong> many poor surround<strong>in</strong>gs, <strong>the</strong>re is too much stimulation,too little privacy and personal space, and so on.) Any attribution ofsensory deprivation to lower-class children, on <strong>the</strong> basis of work withanimals or orphans, has obviously not thought through <strong>the</strong> implications


80 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>of <strong>the</strong> term: ‘it has noth<strong>in</strong>g to do with <strong>the</strong> educational quality [howeverthat might be measured] of <strong>the</strong> stimuli available, but only with <strong>the</strong>irvariety, <strong>in</strong>tensity and pattern<strong>in</strong>g’ (Bereiter & Engelmann, 1966: 27).A more thoughtful approach to <strong>the</strong> environmental underp<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>gs ofdisadvantage has held that <strong>in</strong>adequacies <strong>in</strong> early socialization practiceslead to cognitive and emotional defects <strong>in</strong> children, defects that <strong>the</strong>ncreate difficulties at school. A representative op<strong>in</strong>ion was that of Deutsch(1967: 39): ‘<strong>the</strong> lower-class child enters <strong>the</strong> school situation so poorlyprepared to produce what <strong>the</strong> school demands that <strong>in</strong>itial failures arealmost <strong>in</strong>evitable’. The major thrust of <strong>the</strong> sociocultural-deprivationposition was <strong>the</strong>refore to try and isolate factors <strong>in</strong> early <strong>home</strong> environmentsthat might result <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>adequate development of cognitiveskills; as noted above, it is easy to see how this environmentalist view ofdisadvantage directly led to <strong>in</strong>tervention programs of ‘enrichment’ orcompensatory education. Some of <strong>the</strong> factors seen to suggest remediation<strong>in</strong>clude low socioeconomic status, poor material liv<strong>in</strong>g conditions, and<strong>in</strong>complete or dysfunctional families. More psychologically <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>gvariables <strong>in</strong>clude low value placed upon formal education, absence ofbooks at <strong>home</strong> and poor parent-child <strong>in</strong>teractions (most notably, deficientpatterns of mo<strong>the</strong>r-child communication). The <strong>home</strong> environment, <strong>in</strong>short, is viewed as one of noise, crowd<strong>in</strong>g and physical discomfort, one<strong>in</strong> which children have little opportunity to learn and develop, andwhere <strong>the</strong> usual (i.e. middle-class) parental role of tutor and guide isrestricted and <strong>in</strong>adequate. Perceptual, conceptual and verbal deficits areseen as <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>evitable consequences.In this cultural-deprivation stance, <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r major category ofdisadvantag<strong>in</strong>g factors <strong>in</strong>volves <strong>the</strong> children <strong>the</strong>mselves. They are seento be more ‘activity-orientated’, for example, than conceptually motivated.They are allegedly more concerned with <strong>the</strong> here-and-now, lesslikely to anticipate or th<strong>in</strong>k about <strong>the</strong> future, and <strong>the</strong>refore unwill<strong>in</strong>g todelay gratification; <strong>the</strong> emphasis is upon immediate reward. There is adim<strong>in</strong>ished regard for matters of ‘conscience’, <strong>in</strong>creased aggression,lowered self-esteem, poor academic motivation and restricted languageabilities.What is wrong with this picture? First, we f<strong>in</strong>d that, although manyresearchers have trumpeted <strong>the</strong> need to attend closely to details of <strong>the</strong>disadvantaged lifestyle, gross markers of socioeconomic status havealways rema<strong>in</strong>ed central <strong>in</strong> discussions of disadvantage; that is, despite<strong>the</strong> more detailed <strong>in</strong>formation available, <strong>the</strong> ma<strong>in</strong> pivot is still <strong>the</strong> equationof material deprivation with educational disadvantage (see Archer &Edwards, 1982). A second problem <strong>in</strong>volves <strong>the</strong> presumed characteristics


Disadvantage: The Environmental Case 81of disadvantage <strong>the</strong>mselves. We should be cautious, for example, <strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>terpret<strong>in</strong>g studies <strong>in</strong> which aspects of <strong>the</strong> <strong>home</strong> life of <strong>in</strong>dividuals arediscussed: how was such <strong>in</strong>formation obta<strong>in</strong>ed; does it derive from selfreport,or from <strong>in</strong>terviews with parents, children or teachers? Dataconcern<strong>in</strong>g personal background are clearly important, but it is difficultto obta<strong>in</strong> and measure <strong>the</strong>m with accuracy; <strong>in</strong> an early criticism, Gordon(1965) noted that much of <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>formation here was essentially speculation.As <strong>in</strong> many o<strong>the</strong>r areas of social enquiry, carefully designedlongitud<strong>in</strong>al studies would be much preferable to <strong>the</strong> snapshot <strong>in</strong>vestigationsthat have been vastly more common. Relatedly, <strong>in</strong> attempt<strong>in</strong>g todeterm<strong>in</strong>e characteristics of <strong>the</strong> disadvantaged child at school, relianceupon standardized tests and observations may be <strong>in</strong>adequate, for reasonsalready touched upon.Perhaps <strong>the</strong> most important po<strong>in</strong>t here, however one that relates, atleast <strong>in</strong> part, to <strong>the</strong> assessment difficulties noted above is that we do notfully understand <strong>the</strong> relationship between early environment and <strong>the</strong>characteristics of disadvantage, nor are we on firm ground whenconsider<strong>in</strong>g possible l<strong>in</strong>ks between <strong>the</strong>se characteristics and schoolsuccess (or lack of it). Mere classification and description are notsufficient. How can we account, for example, for <strong>the</strong> success of manychildren who live <strong>in</strong> disadvantaged areas and whose <strong>home</strong>s are<strong>in</strong>adequate <strong>in</strong> material and o<strong>the</strong>r ways? Wiseman, whom I have alreadycited on this matter, po<strong>in</strong>ts out that ‘bad <strong>home</strong>s and neighbourhoodsare more effective <strong>in</strong> prevent<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> emergence of brightness than <strong>the</strong>yare <strong>in</strong> produc<strong>in</strong>g backwardness’ (Wiseman, 1968: 268). And how dowe reconcile <strong>the</strong> poor academic performance of some immigrantand m<strong>in</strong>ority groups with <strong>the</strong> success of o<strong>the</strong>rs? Ogbu’s discussion of<strong>the</strong> ‘caste-like’ status that some but not all groups possess is germanehere. His central argument is that m<strong>in</strong>ority status need not bedisadvantag<strong>in</strong>g per se; if, however, a group is downgraded, ignored oroppressed, and if social mobility rema<strong>in</strong>s uncerta<strong>in</strong> regardless ofachievement, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> stage is set for disadvantaged status (see Ogbu,1978, 1982a, 1982b). But Ogbu’s more nuanced view rema<strong>in</strong>s, itself,<strong>in</strong>sufficiently sensitive to <strong>in</strong>tra-group variation, as d’Amato (1987) andErickson (1987) have demonstrated. The upshot is that f<strong>in</strong>ely detailedknowledge of <strong>the</strong> constituents of educational disadvantage rema<strong>in</strong>s<strong>in</strong>complete.In itself, this is not so much a criticism of <strong>the</strong> environmentalist position<strong>in</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>ciple as it is <strong>the</strong> lack of <strong>the</strong> necessary detail, which that positionreally requires. An additional po<strong>in</strong>t, however, does <strong>in</strong>volve a criticismof <strong>the</strong> environmental-deficit position per se. It is that beh<strong>in</strong>d <strong>the</strong>


82 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>environmentalist view, as it were, is a profound and overwhelm<strong>in</strong>gmiddle-class bias. Virtually all ‘deficits’ could be seen as strengths if <strong>the</strong>immediate context of <strong>the</strong> disadvantaged child were kept <strong>in</strong> m<strong>in</strong>d:<strong>in</strong>stead of discuss<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> supposed short-term gratification pattern of<strong>the</strong> disadvantaged youth... it would be possible to discuss <strong>the</strong> longtermgratification pattern typical of <strong>the</strong> middle class, with itsconsequences (e.g. <strong>in</strong>ability to enjoy <strong>the</strong> present moment, generationof guilt over immediate pleasures...). (Gordon, 1968: 70)Middle-class hedonism and <strong>the</strong> impulses of <strong>the</strong> ‘me’ generation areperhaps more apparent now than when Gordon wrote, but <strong>the</strong>y add to<strong>the</strong> thrust of his remarks ra<strong>the</strong>r than replac<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>m outright. It is entirelypossible for a prosperous middle class to <strong>in</strong>dulge itself <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> present andto simultaneously castigate itself for do<strong>in</strong>g so, but it rema<strong>in</strong>s <strong>the</strong> casethat, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> perceived absence of a favorable future, a here-and-nowhedonism makes good sense for those lower on <strong>the</strong> social hierarchy.Thus, a ‘poor’ conscience, aggressive behavior and o<strong>the</strong>r frequentlydiscussed traits can easily be seen as not only appropriate but em<strong>in</strong>entlysensible <strong>in</strong> certa<strong>in</strong> environments. The general po<strong>in</strong>t is not that certa<strong>in</strong>characteristics do not exist, but ra<strong>the</strong>r that it is <strong>in</strong>correct to view <strong>the</strong>m assubstantive deficits, which is <strong>the</strong> essence of <strong>the</strong> ‘difference’ position ondisadvantage, to which I now turn.Environmental DifferenceThe ‘difference’ view of disadvantage does not deny that childrenfrom <strong>the</strong> lower classes (for example) perform poorly <strong>in</strong> school, nor thatsuch children may arrive with different attitudes and values than <strong>the</strong>irmiddle-class schoolmates. For proponents of this view, however, suchdifferences are just that differences. Invok<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> charge of middleclassbias, difference <strong>the</strong>orists claim that a sociocultural-deprivationapproach unfairly translates difference <strong>in</strong>to deficit. (Some of <strong>the</strong> mostimportant support for <strong>the</strong> difference position comes from studies oflower-class language, an area to which I shall turn later.)As a first po<strong>in</strong>t, consider <strong>the</strong> oddness of <strong>the</strong> term ‘cultural deprivation’.S<strong>in</strong>ce it is clearly impossible to describe a group as be<strong>in</strong>g deprivedof its own culture, <strong>the</strong> real suggestion here must be that <strong>the</strong> culture <strong>in</strong>which certa<strong>in</strong> groups are seen to be deficient is that of <strong>the</strong> middle class.As already implied, <strong>in</strong>valid comparisons arise when <strong>the</strong> norms andstandards of one group are applied to <strong>the</strong> lifestyle of ano<strong>the</strong>r group, anda forceful rejection was expressed by Keddie (1973: 8):


Disadvantage: The Environmental Case 83[cultural deprivation] is a euphemism for say<strong>in</strong>g that work<strong>in</strong>g-classand ethnic groups have cultures which are at least dissonant with, ifnot <strong>in</strong>ferior to, <strong>the</strong> ‘‘ma<strong>in</strong>stream’’ culture of <strong>the</strong> society at large.In <strong>the</strong>ir studies of American Indian life, Wax and Wax (1971: 129130)reported that official evaluations rout<strong>in</strong>ely emphasized presumeddeficiencies: <strong>the</strong> <strong>home</strong> was described as hav<strong>in</strong>g ‘no books, no magaz<strong>in</strong>es,radio, television, newspapers it’s empty! ...<strong>the</strong> Indian child has such ameager experience’.The researchers aptly referred to this as a ‘vacuum ideology’, one <strong>in</strong>which <strong>the</strong> implied remedy is not so much upon replac<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>appropriateskills, attitudes and values as it is upon fill<strong>in</strong>g a void. Their conclud<strong>in</strong>gparagraph is worth cit<strong>in</strong>g here, s<strong>in</strong>ce it represents well <strong>the</strong> criticismsmade of cultural deprivation (note that, for ‘Indian child’, we could alsoread ‘black child’, ‘immigrant child’, ‘lower-class child’, etc.):If <strong>the</strong> Indian child appears as ‘‘culturally deprived’’, it is not becausehe is lack<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> experience or culture, but because <strong>the</strong> educationalagencies are unwill<strong>in</strong>g to recognize <strong>the</strong> alienness of his culture and<strong>the</strong> realities of his social world. It is not that <strong>the</strong> child is deprived ofculture, it is that <strong>the</strong> culture which is associated with his parents isderogated because <strong>the</strong>y are impoverished and powerless. (Wax &Wax, 1971: 138)If we comb<strong>in</strong>e <strong>the</strong> perspectives of educationalists like Keddie andanthropologists like Wax and Wax, it is easy to understand Persell’s(1981) view that cultural-deprivation <strong>the</strong>ories can be just as racist ashereditarian ones. As part of his argument that deficit philosophies areexercises <strong>in</strong> ‘blam<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> victim’, Ryan (1971) thus noted that it would bemore accurate to see schools as ‘culturally depriv<strong>in</strong>g’ <strong>in</strong>stitutions than tosee children as ‘culturally deprived’. Consequently, Ryan (1971: 61)argued that ‘<strong>the</strong> task to be accomplished is not to revise, amend andrepair deficient children, but to alter and transform <strong>the</strong> atmosphere andoperations of <strong>the</strong> schools to which we commit <strong>the</strong>se children’.The ‘difference’ view of disadvantage claims that, to <strong>the</strong> extent towhich lower-class society does not resemble that of <strong>the</strong> middle class, itsmembers will be on a less than equal foot<strong>in</strong>g. S<strong>in</strong>ce it is assumed that<strong>the</strong>re are no substantial or important <strong>in</strong>tergroup variations <strong>in</strong> basiccognitive ability, any differences simply reflect vary<strong>in</strong>g adaptations toenvironments, most particularly <strong>in</strong> terms of early socialization. Inherent<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> difference position is a respect for social diversity: cultural and


84 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>social pluralism is seen to represent an enrich<strong>in</strong>g aspect of <strong>the</strong> largersociety, not someth<strong>in</strong>g to be eradicated.Some researchers have questioned <strong>the</strong> frequent assertion one withwhich I concur that schools are middle-class <strong>in</strong>stitutions. If <strong>the</strong>y arenot, might it be <strong>the</strong> case that <strong>the</strong> <strong>home</strong>-school discont<strong>in</strong>uity fordisadvantaged children is not, after all, significantly more marked thanfor <strong>the</strong>ir non-disadvantaged counterparts? This <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g possibilitywas noted, for example, by several contributors to a discussion ofpoverty edited by Feagans and Farran (1982), and <strong>the</strong> particularemphasis was upon l<strong>in</strong>guistic variance. Tough (1982: 14) noted, forexample, that learn<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> many schools is a passive activity, and thatteachers’ talk dom<strong>in</strong>ates classroom dynamics; <strong>in</strong> that and o<strong>the</strong>r ways, shesuggested, ‘many schools operate <strong>in</strong> a way that is similar to <strong>the</strong>disadvantaged <strong>home</strong>’ (i.e. where, it is alleged, patterns of communicationare frequently more authoritarian than <strong>in</strong>teractive; see follow<strong>in</strong>g chapters).Snow (1982: 258) stated that it would be hard to make a strong case‘that classrooms are much more like middle-class than like lower-class<strong>home</strong>s’. And Farran (1982) remarked that schools are def<strong>in</strong>itely not likemiddle-class <strong>home</strong>s: <strong>the</strong>y are more rigidly didactic, <strong>the</strong>y are bureaucratic,<strong>the</strong>y emphasize rules and regulations, and so on.However, while <strong>the</strong> classroom is obviously not a clone of <strong>the</strong> familysitt<strong>in</strong>g room, <strong>the</strong> notion that <strong>the</strong> former is not, after all, a middle-classsett<strong>in</strong>g confuses <strong>the</strong> procedures of school<strong>in</strong>g with its <strong>in</strong>stitutional ethosand its <strong>in</strong>tentions. To claim, on <strong>the</strong> basis of procedures alone, that a<strong>home</strong>-school discont<strong>in</strong>uity does not apply particularly to lower-classchildren is to ignore possible discont<strong>in</strong>uities based upon <strong>the</strong> purposesbeh<strong>in</strong>d such procedures: <strong>the</strong>se soon become apparent, are more relevantthan <strong>the</strong> procedures, and may well lead to more difficulties for <strong>the</strong>disadvantaged child.Compensatory Intervention?From a ‘difference’ perspective, <strong>the</strong> notion of compensatory educationis clearly rejected, s<strong>in</strong>ce it implies that <strong>the</strong>re is someth<strong>in</strong>g deficient tobe improved or replaced. A difference position emphasizes above all,<strong>the</strong> need for schools to change, and to accommodate to <strong>the</strong> needs of<strong>the</strong> disadvantaged child: this need not mean a replacement of what <strong>the</strong>child br<strong>in</strong>gs to school, but ra<strong>the</strong>r an acceptance of <strong>the</strong> value of allbackgrounds. Still, reject<strong>in</strong>g a ‘replacement’ policy does not rule outattempts to enhance, broaden or add to children’s repertoires; suchattempts characterize more recent language programs, for example (see


Disadvantage: The Environmental Case 85below). Efforts directed towards <strong>the</strong> widen<strong>in</strong>g of exist<strong>in</strong>g abilities andattitudes are predicated, above all, upon <strong>the</strong> realpolitik awareness that however enlightened educational policies might be <strong>the</strong> world outside<strong>the</strong> school gates rema<strong>in</strong>s considerably less so. While wait<strong>in</strong>g for <strong>the</strong>millennium, <strong>the</strong>n, children should be equipped with tools to help <strong>the</strong>mmake <strong>the</strong>ir way <strong>in</strong> less-than-perfect societies.It is entirely reasonable, <strong>in</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r words, to reject <strong>the</strong> notions of culturaldeprivation and deficit while still admitt<strong>in</strong>g that differences mayconstitute social deficits. This can occur, for example, if teachers reactnegatively to disadvantaged children and expect less of <strong>the</strong>m than ofo<strong>the</strong>rs. A ‘self-fulfill<strong>in</strong>g prophecy’ can be created when a child, sensitiveto differential treatment from <strong>the</strong> teacher, comes to fulfill loweredexpectation (see Alvidrez & We<strong>in</strong>ste<strong>in</strong>, 1999; Archer & Edwards, 1982;Rist, 1970; Wigfield et al., 1999). Classic demonstrations of this are found<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> ‘Pygmalion-<strong>in</strong>-<strong>the</strong>-classroom’ studies of Rosenthal and Jacobson(1968); see also Fuchs (1973) and Rist (1970). These soon led to o<strong>the</strong>rs,<strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g Cooper (1979), Cooper and Good (1983), an expandedtreatment by Rosenthal and Jacobson (1992) and, most recently, a criticaloverview by Jussim and Harber (2005). Two recent papers haveemphasized someth<strong>in</strong>g I mentioned as particularly important, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>open<strong>in</strong>g chapter here: thus, Terrill and Mark (2000) and Ladd andL<strong>in</strong>derholm (2008) deal with <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>fluence of early labell<strong>in</strong>g andexpectations among beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g and ‘pre-service’ teachers. The formerstudy focuses upon black children and second-language learners, while<strong>the</strong> latter demonstrated (aga<strong>in</strong>) just how easy it is to affect teachers’judgments <strong>in</strong> this case, by show<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>m a video of children who wereallegedly pupils <strong>in</strong> good, average or bad schools. The authors built uponan earlier <strong>in</strong>vestigation by Pichert and Anderson (1977), and were able toshow that <strong>the</strong> perceptions of teachers who believed that <strong>the</strong> children <strong>the</strong>yhad seen were from poor schools ‘selected and recalled more negativebehaviors compared to those participants who believed <strong>the</strong>y wereview<strong>in</strong>g a ‘‘typical’’ school’ (p. 237).For <strong>the</strong> purposes of <strong>the</strong>ir study, it was important that <strong>the</strong> videoprepared by Ladd and L<strong>in</strong>derholm depicted actions that could bevariously or ambiguously <strong>in</strong>terpreted. ‘Was <strong>the</strong> image of a child patt<strong>in</strong>gano<strong>the</strong>r on <strong>the</strong> back a form of encouragement or support’, <strong>the</strong>y write(Ladd & L<strong>in</strong>derholm, 2008: 234), ‘or was it hitt<strong>in</strong>g or push<strong>in</strong>g?’ This isrem<strong>in</strong>iscent of <strong>the</strong> classic study by Condry and Condry (1976) <strong>in</strong> whichjudges were shown a film of an <strong>in</strong>fant confront<strong>in</strong>g various stimulusobjects; half were told that <strong>the</strong> baby was a boy, <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs that it was agirl. Allow<strong>in</strong>g for some variation attributable to judges’ experience with


86 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong><strong>in</strong>fants, <strong>the</strong> results showed that different emotions, and different levels ofemotion, were reported, and that <strong>the</strong>se differences rested upon <strong>the</strong> sexof <strong>the</strong> judge and, more importantly, on <strong>the</strong> sex attributed to <strong>the</strong> baby. Forexample, when <strong>the</strong> child was described to <strong>the</strong>m as be<strong>in</strong>g a boy, judgeswere more likely to see its reaction to a jack-<strong>in</strong>-<strong>the</strong>-box as be<strong>in</strong>g moreangry and less fearful. Condry and Condry termed this <strong>the</strong> ‘eye of <strong>the</strong>beholder’ effect; see also Condry et al. (1983), for a roughly analogous‘ear of <strong>the</strong> beholder’ one.Ladd and L<strong>in</strong>derholm provide two very tell<strong>in</strong>g illustrations. Samplecomments from judges who believed that <strong>the</strong> children <strong>the</strong>y werewatch<strong>in</strong>g were from a poor school <strong>in</strong>cluded <strong>the</strong> follow<strong>in</strong>g:This particular classroom was <strong>in</strong> complete chaos... <strong>the</strong> teacher hasno control over her classroom... <strong>the</strong> children seemed to be boredwith <strong>the</strong> teacher when <strong>the</strong>y were not do<strong>in</strong>g group activities... <strong>the</strong>teacher seemed to be at her desk or <strong>in</strong> one spot while lectur<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>the</strong>class.And here are some from observers watch<strong>in</strong>g exactly <strong>the</strong> samevideotape, remember who thought <strong>the</strong> children on <strong>the</strong> screen werepupils from a good school:They [<strong>the</strong> children] were help<strong>in</strong>g each o<strong>the</strong>r out... <strong>the</strong> teacher waswalk<strong>in</strong>g around <strong>the</strong> room aid<strong>in</strong>g [lend<strong>in</strong>g?] her assistance whenneeded... <strong>the</strong>re was not much of <strong>the</strong> teacher <strong>in</strong> front of <strong>the</strong> class...<strong>the</strong>y [<strong>the</strong> children] seemed to work well on <strong>the</strong>ir own. Lots of<strong>in</strong>dependent, thoughtful work.The net import of <strong>the</strong>se and o<strong>the</strong>r f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>gs is that teachers may treatchildren unfairly, on <strong>the</strong> basis of stereotyped and erroneous views of<strong>the</strong>ir likely capabilities. 2 To break this vicious circle, difference <strong>the</strong>orists(should) advocate <strong>the</strong> provision of appropriate psychological andl<strong>in</strong>guistic <strong>in</strong>formation to teachers. But even <strong>the</strong> most sangu<strong>in</strong>e difference<strong>the</strong>orist has to admit <strong>the</strong> cont<strong>in</strong>u<strong>in</strong>g strength of prevail<strong>in</strong>g norms. AsCole and Bruner (1972: 176) put it: ‘<strong>the</strong> great power of <strong>the</strong> middle classhas rendered differences <strong>in</strong>to deficits because middle-class behavior is<strong>the</strong> yardstick of success’. Indeed, if difference is commonly translated<strong>in</strong>to deficit, it may be little more than semantic quibbl<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>in</strong>sist on anydist<strong>in</strong>ction between <strong>the</strong> two. This does not mean that <strong>the</strong> game is notworth <strong>the</strong> candle far from it, s<strong>in</strong>ce <strong>the</strong> deep-seated unfairness thatpartial or <strong>in</strong>accurate perceptions lead to rema<strong>in</strong>s an important motivationfor change but it does suggest how difficult change can be.


Disadvantage: The Environmental Case 87Not surpris<strong>in</strong>gly, difference positions also underp<strong>in</strong> calls for largescalesocial change. To eradicate disadvantage is, <strong>in</strong> part, a matter ofchang<strong>in</strong>g traditional social views of <strong>the</strong> poor; it is also, however,necessary that society itself be changed so that poverty itself can bemore successfully attacked. Thus, unlike <strong>the</strong> environmentalists whofocus upon school as an agent for <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>tegration of <strong>the</strong> disadvantaged<strong>in</strong>to society at large, difference proponents see <strong>the</strong> school as but one part(albeit a very important one) of a much larger and more radical alterationof society.It has become clear enough, I hope, that <strong>the</strong> ‘difference’ perspective is<strong>the</strong> only one that has logic on its side. By way of conclusion, however,one or two cautionary po<strong>in</strong>ts suggest <strong>the</strong>mselves. The first, as noted, isthat difference <strong>the</strong>orists have sometimes tended to gloss over realproblems and to over-romanticize <strong>the</strong> poor (shades of Ra<strong>in</strong>water’s‘apo<strong>the</strong>osis’; see also Rob<strong>in</strong>son, 1976). While many of <strong>the</strong> characteristicsof disadvantaged children are best seen as differences and not deficits,<strong>the</strong>re is no doubt that such children frequently suffer from actualdeficiencies, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g poor hous<strong>in</strong>g, over-crowd<strong>in</strong>g, ill-health and<strong>in</strong>adequate nutrition. In do<strong>in</strong>g justice to <strong>the</strong>ir basic cognitive (andl<strong>in</strong>guistic) skills, we should not forget that <strong>the</strong>se arise despite, notbecause of, poor physical backgrounds. There is no <strong>in</strong>herent virtue <strong>in</strong>poverty and squalor. Or, as Aldous Huxley once remarked (1939: 79),‘poverty and suffer<strong>in</strong>g ennoble only when <strong>the</strong>y are voluntary. By<strong>in</strong>voluntary poverty and suffer<strong>in</strong>g men are made worse’. The o<strong>the</strong>rpo<strong>in</strong>t has to do with <strong>the</strong> attention focused upon <strong>the</strong> school as an agent ofsocial change. While deficit <strong>the</strong>orists, with <strong>the</strong>ir programs of compensatoryeducation, are clearly more emphatic here than are those support<strong>in</strong>gcultural difference, <strong>the</strong> latter have also <strong>in</strong>vested considerable energy <strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>form<strong>in</strong>g teachers and attempt<strong>in</strong>g to lessen misperceptions aboutdisadvantage generally. It is worth po<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g out that schools havehistorically followed <strong>the</strong> dom<strong>in</strong>ant social ma<strong>in</strong>stream ra<strong>the</strong>r than leadit. It is also worth remember<strong>in</strong>g that part of <strong>the</strong> ‘failure’ of compensatory<strong>in</strong>tervention that motivated Jensen and like-m<strong>in</strong>ded researchers can beplaced at <strong>the</strong> feet of political ra<strong>the</strong>r than educational agendas. The appealand <strong>the</strong> underp<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>gs of <strong>the</strong> well-known American Head Start program,for <strong>in</strong>stance, ‘lay more <strong>in</strong> political expedience than <strong>in</strong> practical efficacy’(Harwood, 1982: 51).To end on a positive note, however, <strong>the</strong> ‘failure’ of compensatoryprograms may have been overstated. Zigler and Valent<strong>in</strong>e’s lengthyanthology (1979) suggested that, while Head Start did not raise IQ scores,it did provide pleasant school experiences (and related services,


88 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>improved health care among <strong>the</strong>m) for very large numbers of children.Zigler and Seitz (1980) went on to note that success could should? beassessed <strong>in</strong> terms of improved social competence, physical health,educational motivation and achievement, and not only <strong>in</strong> terms offormal cognitive skills (see also Kellaghan, 1977). Perhaps we ask toomuch of educational programs <strong>in</strong> terms of future pay-offs; perhaps some<strong>in</strong>terventions that positively affect children’s lives can be accepted asgood <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>mselves, regardless of what <strong>the</strong>y may or may not lead to 10years on. After all, we do not provide sw<strong>in</strong>gs and roundabouts foryoungsters with <strong>the</strong> view that by so do<strong>in</strong>g we <strong>in</strong>crease social competence,now or <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> future; <strong>the</strong>y are seen as pleasant <strong>in</strong> and of<strong>the</strong>mselves.A Forensic Post-scriptIn this chapter, we have seen how important <strong>the</strong> assessment of<strong>in</strong>telligence has been historically: for immigrants, for <strong>the</strong> lower classessubject to eugenic ideologies, for disadvantaged children <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> classroom.The importance, <strong>the</strong> poignancy and <strong>the</strong> tragedy have arisen, <strong>in</strong>large part, because assessments have been mis-assessments. These, <strong>in</strong>turn, have generally rested upon faulty or <strong>in</strong>adequate test<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>struments.Now, <strong>in</strong> a new contemporary arena of <strong>the</strong> greatest moment oflife-and-death significance, <strong>in</strong> fact we are able to see that <strong>in</strong>adequaciesand mismeasurements persist. It is also relevant to our larger story thatthis arena has been, and cont<strong>in</strong>ues to be, one <strong>in</strong> which variousdisadvantaged populations are heavily over-represented. This lastsection is someth<strong>in</strong>g of a digression, to be sure, but it highlights adramatic chapter <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> long and often troubled story of <strong>in</strong>telligencetest<strong>in</strong>g and its consequences.Follow<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> mid-19th-century M’Naghten rules, a defence basedupon <strong>in</strong>sanity while often a very contentious matter has long beenaccepted pr<strong>in</strong>ciple <strong>in</strong> British and American crim<strong>in</strong>al justice systems.Similar, and sometimes more liberal, provisions exist <strong>in</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r countries.In what might appear to be a logical extension, <strong>the</strong> Supreme Court of <strong>the</strong>United States recently reversed a 1989 rul<strong>in</strong>g that mental retardationought not to exempt a murderer from <strong>the</strong> death penalty: thus, <strong>in</strong> 2002, <strong>the</strong>Court found execut<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> mentally retarded to be unconstitutional(McK<strong>in</strong>zey, 2005; Mossman, 2005). 3 While argu<strong>in</strong>g that dim<strong>in</strong>ished<strong>in</strong>tellectual capacities meant that <strong>the</strong> execution of <strong>the</strong> mentally retardedwould be ‘cruel and unusual punishment’, <strong>the</strong> Court op<strong>in</strong>ion left it tostate jurisdiction to develop ‘appropriate ways’ to apply <strong>the</strong> provisions.


Disadvantage: The Environmental Case 89If a diagnosis of mental retardation is made, McK<strong>in</strong>zey (2005: 3) observes,<strong>the</strong>n a death sentence ‘must be converted but to what? ...and whoqualifies for this life-sav<strong>in</strong>g diagnosis? ...how about those who developedMR [mental retardation] after <strong>the</strong> crime?’Sticky as <strong>the</strong>se sorts of matters are, <strong>the</strong>y are essentially legal issues.More complicated are those hav<strong>in</strong>g to do with assessment itself. Afterdiscuss<strong>in</strong>g ano<strong>the</strong>r capital case that of José Lopez <strong>in</strong> some detail,McK<strong>in</strong>zey (2005: 10) concludes by observ<strong>in</strong>g that:Atk<strong>in</strong>s hear<strong>in</strong>gs [see below] will take predictable courses. Thedefense experts will f<strong>in</strong>d ways of expla<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g away normal IQs andadaptive function<strong>in</strong>g, and produce scores <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> MR range. Theprosecution experts will deride <strong>the</strong> new test scores and argue <strong>the</strong>defendant is merely a mal<strong>in</strong>ger<strong>in</strong>g crook.The possibilities for judicial battles <strong>in</strong> which each side has its ownpsychiatrists are obviously much enlarged. But more central still is <strong>the</strong>question of <strong>the</strong> efficacy and <strong>the</strong> validity of <strong>the</strong> tests used to determ<strong>in</strong>e‘legal’ mental retardation. (The similarity to issues raised by <strong>the</strong> scopeand application of <strong>the</strong> M’Naghten rules issues of ‘legal’ <strong>in</strong>sanity asopposed to psychiatric conceptions of competence is strik<strong>in</strong>g here.)After all, an IQ-test score can now mean <strong>the</strong> difference between life anddeath; you can be legally ‘too dumb to die’ (Talbot, 2003). Raven (2005)po<strong>in</strong>ts out that <strong>the</strong> samples on which <strong>the</strong> test norms are based may bequestioned and, if some potential participants <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> norm<strong>in</strong>g exerciseschose not to take part, what effect might that have on <strong>the</strong> norms<strong>the</strong>mselves? As <strong>the</strong> author of one of <strong>the</strong> standard tests used here, Raven(2005: 68) refers to <strong>the</strong> ‘apparently extraord<strong>in</strong>ary application of psychologicaltests... tests of general cognitive ability are be<strong>in</strong>g used todeterm<strong>in</strong>e whe<strong>the</strong>r murderers will be executed or not’. He is appalledbecause of <strong>the</strong> enormous weight now placed upon measures whosevalidity and discrim<strong>in</strong>ative powers are not up to <strong>the</strong> task. Questionsabout <strong>the</strong> adequacy and appropriateness of <strong>the</strong> norm<strong>in</strong>g samples (andmany o<strong>the</strong>r technicalities of test construction) are hardly unique to thisforensic application, but deficiencies are ra<strong>the</strong>r more important forconvicted killers than for student-placement exercises. Relatedly, <strong>the</strong>reare more mundane, but still vitally important, issues here. Are <strong>the</strong> testtakerspay<strong>in</strong>g are <strong>the</strong>y, <strong>in</strong>deed, capable of pay<strong>in</strong>g sufficiently closeattention to evaluations be<strong>in</strong>g made of <strong>the</strong>m; are <strong>the</strong>y properly apply<strong>in</strong>g<strong>the</strong>mselves when presented with standardized psychological tests like<strong>the</strong> Wechsler <strong>in</strong>telligence scales and Raven’s progressive matrices?


90 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>It does <strong>in</strong>deed seem that f<strong>in</strong>e-gra<strong>in</strong>ed dist<strong>in</strong>ctions have been vital.When, <strong>in</strong> early August 2005, Daryl Atk<strong>in</strong>s was found after all to bementally competent, 3 it was reported that his several IQ-test results were59, 67, 74 and 76. The result<strong>in</strong>g average score (69) would have seemed toexempt him, if only by a hair, from <strong>the</strong> ultimate penalty, s<strong>in</strong>ce Virg<strong>in</strong>ialaw def<strong>in</strong>es mental retardation as <strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>g an IQ of 70 or below by <strong>the</strong>age of 18. Unfortunately, although Atk<strong>in</strong>s was 18 when he committedmurder, <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>telligence tests were adm<strong>in</strong>istered after that age (L<strong>in</strong>dsey,2005). One needs nei<strong>the</strong>r judicial nor psychiatric genius to see <strong>the</strong>Kafkaesque absurdity here.Although McK<strong>in</strong>zey’s (2005) concern that <strong>the</strong> Supreme Court rul<strong>in</strong>gmight lead to attempts on <strong>the</strong> part of competent murderers to appear<strong>in</strong>tellectually deficient seems not to have been borne out, <strong>the</strong> rul<strong>in</strong>g hascerta<strong>in</strong>ly reopened a number of old cases. Many prisoners now on deathrow may be mentally retarded, and <strong>the</strong>ir cases must be reconsidered.More <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>gly, contemporary and enlightened views suggest that <strong>the</strong>mentally retarded are still <strong>in</strong>dividuals, that reduced crim<strong>in</strong>al culpabilityarises from particular deficiencies that some may have and thatcategorical judgments are <strong>the</strong>refore unwarranted (Talbot, 2003). AsMossman (2005: 100) has put it, ‘mental retardation is an artificialcategory imposed on a spectrum of human capability’. At a very simplelevel, this is demonstrated by <strong>the</strong> fact that <strong>the</strong> professional criteria fordef<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g mental retardation have altered over <strong>the</strong> years: <strong>the</strong> AmericanAssociation on Mental Retardation (AAMR) has altered its def<strong>in</strong>ition 10times over <strong>the</strong> past century or so (Mossman, 2005). Relatedly, Talbot(2003) po<strong>in</strong>ts out that a lower<strong>in</strong>g of <strong>the</strong> IQ cut-off <strong>in</strong> 1973 meant that <strong>the</strong>proportion of <strong>the</strong> American population def<strong>in</strong>ed as mentally retardedimmediately dropped from 16 to 3%. Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, <strong>the</strong> characterizationof mental retardation by <strong>the</strong> AAMR and <strong>the</strong> American PsychiatricAssociation (APA) is not <strong>the</strong> same; <strong>the</strong> former now stresses classification<strong>in</strong> terms of levels of support needed, while <strong>the</strong> latter uses a moretraditional approach, grad<strong>in</strong>g degrees of general severity.The concerns and caveats become if possible even moreheightened when we discover that <strong>the</strong> Atk<strong>in</strong>s decision was praised by<strong>the</strong> mental health community (<strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> APA, <strong>the</strong> AAMR, <strong>the</strong>American Academy of Psychiatry and <strong>the</strong> Law, <strong>the</strong> American PsychologicalAssociation and o<strong>the</strong>rs). In fact, a representative of <strong>the</strong> APA’sjudicial committee particularly welcomed <strong>the</strong> decision, claim<strong>in</strong>g that itwould raise no problems because ‘mental retardation can be identifiedus<strong>in</strong>g time-tested <strong>in</strong>struments and protocols with proven validity andreliability’ (Mossmann, 2005: 99). Given what has already been discussed


Disadvantage: The Environmental Case 91here, this suggests a ra<strong>the</strong>r remarkable optimism, but it is even moreremarkable s<strong>in</strong>ce, <strong>in</strong> various amicus curiae <strong>in</strong>terventions, <strong>the</strong> APA has forsome time acknowledged that legal decisions ought not to slavishlyfollow psychiatric categorizations (Mossman, 2005). 4It is relevant to conclude here by not<strong>in</strong>g that Atk<strong>in</strong>s is black, Lopez isHispanic, and most of <strong>the</strong> death-row <strong>in</strong>mates <strong>in</strong>terviewed by Talbot(2003) were one or <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r. The use of <strong>in</strong>telligence-test results, howeverdubious <strong>the</strong>ir accuracy, might be seen generally as a good th<strong>in</strong>g. If onewere opposed to capital punishment per se, for <strong>in</strong>stance, one mightendorse any way of lessen<strong>in</strong>g its frequency, particularly given <strong>the</strong> hugeAmerican prison population, with its sizeable over-representation ofblack and o<strong>the</strong>r m<strong>in</strong>ority groups. But <strong>the</strong> fact rema<strong>in</strong>s that current legalapplications may mean life-and-death dist<strong>in</strong>ctions be<strong>in</strong>g drawn onflawed or <strong>in</strong>adequate data. It is unconscionable that Prisoner A, with ameasured IQ of 68, should escape <strong>the</strong> fate of Prisoner B, whose score is72. Beyond <strong>the</strong> difficulties already cited, anyone with <strong>the</strong> slightestfamiliarity with psychological test<strong>in</strong>g knows that such m<strong>in</strong>or differencesare often fleet<strong>in</strong>g and, if stable, often mean<strong>in</strong>gless. F<strong>in</strong>ally, s<strong>in</strong>ce differentstates are free to establish different ‘cut-off’ criteria, it is also possible thata test result that would spare a prisoner <strong>in</strong> one jurisdiction wouldcondemn him to death <strong>in</strong> ano<strong>the</strong>r. And tim<strong>in</strong>g may also be of <strong>the</strong> essence:‘judged aga<strong>in</strong>st yesterday’s norms one should die; yet, given today’snorms, one may live’ (Raven, 2005: 68).As Raven and Stephenson (2001) have argued, competence and<strong>in</strong>competence <strong>in</strong> modern society and <strong>the</strong> crim<strong>in</strong>al ramifications<strong>the</strong>reof are heavily dependent upon <strong>the</strong> rewards and punishments of<strong>the</strong> social environment. This suggests that, where environments are‘disadvantag<strong>in</strong>g’ <strong>in</strong> one way or ano<strong>the</strong>r, changes <strong>in</strong> early social contexts,coupled with more <strong>in</strong>formed perceptions of those contexts, are likely tobe more humane and more effective than later attempts to sort th<strong>in</strong>gs out,especially if such attempts are cobbled toge<strong>the</strong>r <strong>in</strong> ill-considered ways.Notes1. Tucker (2002: 197) notes that, <strong>in</strong> 1999, Rushton (1995) had ‘tens of thousands’of copies of an abridged version of his Race, Evolution and Behavior sent tosocial scientists <strong>in</strong> several discipl<strong>in</strong>es. This is not quite as bizarre as agree<strong>in</strong>gto appear on trash television, but it is still very odd behavior. It certa<strong>in</strong>ly didnoth<strong>in</strong>g to endear Rushton or his ideas to a wider academic audience; quite<strong>the</strong> contrary, <strong>in</strong> fact.2. There is a large literature outl<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> many variables that can evokestereotyped and often <strong>in</strong>accurate perceptions. Someth<strong>in</strong>g as simple as achild’s first name can produce predictable effects. Teachers (and o<strong>the</strong>rs, of


92 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>course) may form judgments on <strong>the</strong> basis of (say) <strong>the</strong> popularity orstrangeness of names, or of those that immediately suggest a particularethnic or social group. Recent work by Anderson-Clark et al. (2008) and Fryerand Levitt (2004b), for <strong>in</strong>stance, has demonstrated <strong>the</strong> negative perceptions ofwhite teachers that can be elicited when contemporary African Americannames are <strong>the</strong> ‘triggers’; see also Christenfeld and Larsen (2008).3. Prior to <strong>the</strong> Supreme Court decision of 2002, provisions existed at <strong>the</strong> statelevel for exempt<strong>in</strong>g mentally retarded people from execution. At <strong>the</strong> time of<strong>the</strong> earlier (1989) rul<strong>in</strong>g, only two states had such legislation, but <strong>the</strong> numberhad grown to 18 by 2002 (Mossman, 2005; Talbot, 2003). It is someth<strong>in</strong>g of anirony that, after lengthy judicial procedures, <strong>the</strong> defendant <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> landmarkcase discussed here (formally designated as Atk<strong>in</strong>s v Virg<strong>in</strong>ia, 2002) wasfound not to be mentally retarded, after all.4. In fact, a very recent publication (Cosgrove et al., 2006) suggests <strong>the</strong> need foreven fur<strong>the</strong>r caution. The authors exam<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>the</strong> f<strong>in</strong>ancial l<strong>in</strong>ks betweenpharmaceutical companies and members of <strong>the</strong> APA panels responsible for<strong>the</strong> fourth edition of <strong>the</strong> association’s <strong>in</strong>fluential Diagnostic and StatisticalManual of Mental Disorders (American Psychiatric Association, 2000). Theydiscovered that 95 of <strong>the</strong> 170 scientists had at least one such ‘f<strong>in</strong>ancialassociation’. The ties took <strong>the</strong> form of research fund<strong>in</strong>g and consultancy orspeak<strong>in</strong>g fees. Cosgrove and her colleagues note that <strong>the</strong> connections werestrongest <strong>in</strong> diagnostic doma<strong>in</strong>s <strong>in</strong> which drug treatment is primary; <strong>in</strong> two of<strong>the</strong> panels (those deal<strong>in</strong>g with mood disorders and schizophrenia), everymember was f<strong>in</strong>ancially l<strong>in</strong>ked with a drug company. The authors do notclaim to have proved <strong>the</strong> existence of <strong>in</strong>appropriate <strong>in</strong>fluence, but <strong>the</strong>y doargue for a full-disclosure policy, which seems a modest enough recommendation<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> circumstances.In newspaper <strong>in</strong>terviews, representatives of <strong>the</strong> APA have denied anypharmaceutical <strong>in</strong>dustry <strong>in</strong>fluence on DSM revisions, have regretted <strong>the</strong>‘<strong>in</strong>nuendo’ of <strong>the</strong> Cosgrove study, but have also agreed that transparencywould be <strong>the</strong> watchword <strong>in</strong> future editions of <strong>the</strong> manual (Carey, 2006).


Chapter 6The <strong>Language</strong> DebateIntroductionThe argument that discourse analysis should become <strong>the</strong> centralcomponent <strong>in</strong> a reworked social psychology represents one facet of arecent growth of <strong>in</strong>terest <strong>in</strong> more f<strong>in</strong>e-gra<strong>in</strong>ed studies of language <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>classroom. Despite my critical comments (ma<strong>in</strong>ly <strong>in</strong> Chapter 2) about <strong>the</strong>value of micro-level enquiry, <strong>the</strong>re is little doubt that <strong>the</strong> new emphaseshere have allied <strong>the</strong>mselves with a rejection of ‘deficit’ pr<strong>in</strong>ciples and <strong>the</strong>disembodied and artificial speech analyses associated with <strong>the</strong>m (seeAtk<strong>in</strong>son, 1985; Edwards & Mercer, 1986; Mercer & Edwards, 1981;Rob<strong>in</strong>son, 1985). In one <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g analysis, Mehan (1984) suggested thatclassroom language may be of sufficient specificity to constitute a‘cultural code’ <strong>in</strong> itself, one that must be mastered for school success.On <strong>the</strong> basis of what I have already discussed here, we could add acorollary: disadvantage may be understood as aris<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> part fromdifferential mastery of this subtle and unarticulated style that comb<strong>in</strong>esboth knowledge and its appropriate display.One important advantage of this perspective is that it <strong>in</strong>volvesteachers as well as pupils. Mehan describes a study <strong>in</strong> which differences<strong>in</strong> language styles between lower-status children and <strong>the</strong>ir teachers wereassessed and, follow<strong>in</strong>g this, <strong>the</strong> latter were assisted <strong>in</strong> mak<strong>in</strong>g someadaptations to <strong>the</strong> children’s language patterns. With teachers phras<strong>in</strong>g<strong>the</strong>ir questions <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> children’s maternal style, <strong>the</strong>ir passivity and ‘nonverbality’decreased; and, with <strong>the</strong> establishment of an enhancedparticipation, children could be gradually <strong>in</strong>troduced to more standardusage. This type of educational adaptability is a long way removed fromprogrammed <strong>in</strong>tervention based upon assumptions of l<strong>in</strong>guistic deprivation.While mak<strong>in</strong>g a general argument similar to Mehan’s, Young (1983)noted that such alterations <strong>in</strong> teacher practice do not always come easy.They typically have to combat longstand<strong>in</strong>g traditions based more upon<strong>the</strong> ma<strong>in</strong>tenance of classroom dom<strong>in</strong>ance and control than upon <strong>the</strong>optimization of learn<strong>in</strong>g.Sett<strong>in</strong>g aside conceptions and assessments of <strong>in</strong>telligence, debatesabout whe<strong>the</strong>r or not some language varieties are <strong>in</strong>ferior to o<strong>the</strong>rs have93


94 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>provided <strong>the</strong> most <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g sub-plot with<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> larger story ofdisadvantage. Evaluations of language were at once <strong>the</strong> ma<strong>in</strong> pillar of<strong>the</strong> deprivation position and, at <strong>the</strong> same time, <strong>the</strong> arena <strong>in</strong> which <strong>the</strong>‘difference’ attack on that position was (and is) <strong>the</strong> most thoroughgo<strong>in</strong>gand <strong>the</strong> most successful. So, even though <strong>the</strong> preced<strong>in</strong>g discussions meanthat <strong>the</strong> outcome here can be anticipated before we start, <strong>the</strong> illustrativevalue is very great.As <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> previous chapters, much of my purpose here is to presentsometh<strong>in</strong>g of <strong>the</strong> background to current positions. For that reason, I havecited many studies from <strong>the</strong> 1960s and 1970s, <strong>the</strong> times when matters stillextremely relevant <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> ‘real world’ <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> contemporary classroom,to name one important arena were be<strong>in</strong>g thrashed out <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> literature.Of particular importance <strong>in</strong> all this is <strong>the</strong> realization that, although <strong>the</strong>‘difference’ po<strong>in</strong>t of view may have won <strong>the</strong> day <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>tellectual terms,‘deficit’ views of one sort or ano<strong>the</strong>r rema<strong>in</strong> dom<strong>in</strong>ant beyond <strong>the</strong> grovesof academe. For two recent overviews, see Ng (2007) and Wright andBougie (2007).The educational stage has always been <strong>the</strong> most important here, andso we might beg<strong>in</strong> this chapter by <strong>in</strong>troduc<strong>in</strong>g two of <strong>the</strong> star players,characters whose cont<strong>in</strong>u<strong>in</strong>gly appeal<strong>in</strong>g roles have contributed to a playwith a run far longer than that of The Mousetrap. InSpeed <strong>the</strong> Plough, firstperformed at Covent Garden <strong>in</strong> 1800, Thomas Morton <strong>in</strong>troduced <strong>the</strong>famous Mrs Grundy. Like Mrs Harris, Sairey Gamp’s <strong>in</strong>visible friend <strong>in</strong>Mart<strong>in</strong> Chuzzlewit, Mrs Grundy never actually appears herself. She isrespectfully <strong>in</strong>voked by Farmer Ashfield’s wife, however, as <strong>the</strong> epitomeof polite acceptability, and her name has s<strong>in</strong>ce become synonymous withnarrow puritanism, ‘morality’ and l<strong>in</strong>guistic purism of <strong>the</strong> mostconventional sort. Dame Ashfield’s concerns <strong>in</strong> matters of propriety ‘What will Mrs Grundy say? What will Mrs Grundy th<strong>in</strong>k?’ haveevolved <strong>in</strong>to apprehensions with which those readers who rememberschool grammar classes will no doubt be familiar. They may be lessfamiliar with Miss Fidditch, one of those schoolteachers who wouldra<strong>the</strong>r ‘parse than eat’. In Mart<strong>in</strong> Joos’s (1967) famous little book on style,The Five Clocks, Miss Fidditch plays a central role, consider<strong>in</strong>g herself as<strong>the</strong> prophet of <strong>the</strong> great god, Webster. Mrs Grundy and Miss Fidditchhave had many relatives <strong>in</strong> school systems around <strong>the</strong> world, and <strong>the</strong>ir<strong>in</strong>fluence cont<strong>in</strong>ues. 1Trudgill (1979: 21) reproduced some press reaction to his book onlanguage variation at school (Trudgill, 1975). The general feel<strong>in</strong>g was thatany defence of nonstandard varieties was a blow aga<strong>in</strong>st ‘good’ grammarand a support for ‘<strong>in</strong>complete and lazy’ language. A writer <strong>in</strong> The


The <strong>Language</strong> Debate 95Guardian <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Education Section, no less claimed that childrenspeak<strong>in</strong>g what he called ‘an East London dialect offshoot’ (whatever thatanimal might be) are ‘lack<strong>in</strong>g entire sounds and words <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir vocalrepertoire’. A Sunday Telegraph columnist argued that fail<strong>in</strong>g to ‘correct’lower-class grammar was deny<strong>in</strong>g children <strong>the</strong> very ‘right to knowledge’.Lippi-Green (1997) provides many examples of widespread negativeattitudes towards Black English (and o<strong>the</strong>r nonstandard dialects) <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>United States; as we shall see, such attitudes can be just as common amongteachers as among ‘laypersons’, and just as strongly held by nonstandarddialectspeakers <strong>the</strong>mselves as <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> public at large.Deficient <strong>Language</strong>S<strong>in</strong>ce class and regional differences <strong>in</strong> accent and dialect have alwaysbeen <strong>the</strong> source of comment, imitation and derision, it is not difficult tounderstand <strong>the</strong> appeal of a formal deficit view of certa<strong>in</strong> speech styles.One of <strong>the</strong> first scholarly attempts (perhaps <strong>the</strong> first; see Dittmar, 1976) to<strong>in</strong>vestigate class differences <strong>in</strong> speech was that of Schatzman and Strauss(1955). Follow<strong>in</strong>g a tornado <strong>in</strong> Arkansas, lower- and middle-classrespondents were asked to describe <strong>the</strong> frighten<strong>in</strong>g event. The formergroup were found to transmit much less <strong>in</strong>formation about <strong>the</strong>occurrence than were <strong>the</strong> latter. There was little attempt to set <strong>the</strong> scene,as it were, for <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terviewer, and <strong>the</strong> respondents were apparently ableto do little more than reconstruct <strong>the</strong> event as it had appeared to <strong>the</strong>mdirectly and personally <strong>in</strong> ‘particularistic or concrete terms’ (Schatzman& Strauss, 1955: 333). There was much digression, which, though perhapsmean<strong>in</strong>gful for <strong>the</strong> speaker, was irrelevant and/or confus<strong>in</strong>g for <strong>the</strong>listener. The lower-class <strong>in</strong>terviewees seemed to assume that <strong>the</strong><strong>in</strong>terviewer shared much contextual <strong>in</strong>formation when, <strong>in</strong> fact, thiswas not so. Middle-class <strong>in</strong>formants, by contrast, were generally able toreconstruct <strong>the</strong> event <strong>in</strong> a logical and mean<strong>in</strong>gful way. Schatzman andStrauss acknowledged that <strong>the</strong> lower-class people were communicat<strong>in</strong>gacross class l<strong>in</strong>es (i.e. to a middle-class <strong>in</strong>terviewer) and were probablymore unfamiliar with <strong>the</strong> requirements of <strong>the</strong> task important po<strong>in</strong>ts, aswe shall see. Never<strong>the</strong>less, <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>vestigators felt able to conclude that thisgroup of respondents had a reduced capacity for perceiv<strong>in</strong>g andcommunicat<strong>in</strong>g abstract thoughts; some, <strong>the</strong>y argued, ‘literally cannottell a straight story or describe a simple <strong>in</strong>cident coherently’ (Schatzman& Strauss, 1955: 336; see also Strauss & Schatzman, 1960).In a related study, Templ<strong>in</strong> (1957) obta<strong>in</strong>ed speech samples fromlower- and middle-class white American children (aged between three


96 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>and seven). In terms of complexity of utterance, analysis revealed thatclass differences were m<strong>in</strong>imal: although <strong>the</strong>re was some tendency forlower-class children to use simpler sentences (i.e. fewer phrase andclausal constructions), it was not <strong>the</strong> case that <strong>the</strong>y never used morecomplex expressions. One could not deduce, <strong>the</strong>n, that lower-classchildren were unable to produce certa<strong>in</strong> forms, only that <strong>the</strong>y madeless use of <strong>the</strong>m than did <strong>the</strong>ir middle-class counterparts; similarconclusions can be drawn from a longitud<strong>in</strong>al study reported by Loban(1963). The general po<strong>in</strong>t here aga<strong>in</strong>, someth<strong>in</strong>g to which we shallreturn revolves around <strong>the</strong> difficulty of <strong>in</strong>ferr<strong>in</strong>g l<strong>in</strong>guistic competencefrom l<strong>in</strong>guistic performance. After all, even if a child used a subord<strong>in</strong>ateclause only once <strong>in</strong> a hundred utterances, some basic capability could be<strong>in</strong>ferred. (In fact, as Dittmar [1976: 49] po<strong>in</strong>ted out, even if no sententialcomplexity at all is produced, one cannot be certa<strong>in</strong> of underly<strong>in</strong>gcompetences: perhaps some can easily understand clausal complexitiesbut lack ‘a disposition towards produc<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>m’.) An important questionrema<strong>in</strong>s, of course why does habitual performance take <strong>the</strong> form itdoes? but this is somewhat different from talk<strong>in</strong>g about basic l<strong>in</strong>guisticabilities and disabilities.Basil Bernste<strong>in</strong> and his followersMost relevant here, however, is <strong>the</strong> work of <strong>the</strong> late Basil Bernste<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong><strong>the</strong> 1950s. Influential <strong>in</strong> sociological and educational circles, his reports ofwork<strong>in</strong>g-class and middle-class language appeared to support a deficitposition, even though he later claimed that this was not <strong>the</strong> case. In <strong>the</strong><strong>in</strong>troduction to his 1971 book, for <strong>in</strong>stance, Bernste<strong>in</strong> acknowledges earlyweaknesses and ambiguities (but see Tony Edwards, 1974). Considerhere what Rosen (1972: 34), one of Bernste<strong>in</strong>’s fiercest but most carefulcritics, had to say:Bernste<strong>in</strong> protests that his work has been misunderstood, misusedand vulgarized... And he is absolutely right. However, as he also tellsus his papers are ‘‘obscure, lack precision and probably abound <strong>in</strong>ambiguities’’ (Bernste<strong>in</strong>, 1971, p. 19), that is scarcely to be wondered at.A little earlier <strong>in</strong> his argument, Rosen cites an even more <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>gadmission, <strong>in</strong> which Bernste<strong>in</strong> (1971: 11) refers to his early papers as‘conceptually weak... horrify<strong>in</strong>gly coarse’. Ultimately, as Rosen (1972: 15)suggests,you cannot protest very conv<strong>in</strong>c<strong>in</strong>gly aga<strong>in</strong>st <strong>the</strong> harm done by <strong>the</strong>label ‘‘l<strong>in</strong>guistic deprivation’’ when your own <strong>the</strong>ory po<strong>in</strong>ts to a


The <strong>Language</strong> Debate 97deficit, <strong>in</strong>deed when you have actually stated... that ‘‘<strong>the</strong> normall<strong>in</strong>guistic environment of <strong>the</strong> work<strong>in</strong>g class is one of l<strong>in</strong>guisticdeprivation’’.There is a Jewish proverb, Rosen rem<strong>in</strong>ds us, about try<strong>in</strong>g to dance attwo wedd<strong>in</strong>gs at <strong>the</strong> same time.Bernste<strong>in</strong>’s l<strong>in</strong>guistic <strong>in</strong>sights centered upon ‘public’ and ‘formal’variants. The former, he said, is chiefly characterized by an emphasisupon ‘<strong>the</strong> emotive ra<strong>the</strong>r than <strong>the</strong> logical implications’ (Bernste<strong>in</strong>, 1958:164) of language; and subsequent elaborations (Bernste<strong>in</strong>, 1959) revealthat public language is grammatically simple, and generally limited <strong>in</strong>expressive possibilities. Its users, like those lower-class respondentsdescribed by Schatzman and Strauss (whose work Bernste<strong>in</strong> acknowledged),apparently have few syntactic and lexical alternatives, and arerestricted to concrete and non-symbolic modes of expression. Publiclanguage is essentially <strong>the</strong> only l<strong>in</strong>guistic variant available to <strong>the</strong> lowerclass. On <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r hand, middle-class speakers while will<strong>in</strong>g and ableto use <strong>the</strong> public variety also have access to ‘formal’ language.Bernste<strong>in</strong> described this as essentially <strong>the</strong> mirror image of its poorercounterpart. Where <strong>the</strong> latter is simple, semantically implicit andconceptually weak, formal language is grammatically complex, semanticallyexplicit and rich <strong>in</strong> symbolic possibilities.In his earlier papers, Bernste<strong>in</strong> (1958, 1959, 1960) referred tocharacteristics of lower-class children often cited by <strong>the</strong> environmentaldeficit<strong>the</strong>orists: difficulty <strong>in</strong> delay<strong>in</strong>g immediate gratification and ofplann<strong>in</strong>g for <strong>the</strong> future, ‘volatile’ expressive behavior and so on. Herelated <strong>the</strong> l<strong>in</strong>guistic variants to those of social milieu, not<strong>in</strong>g that:one mode [of speech], associated with <strong>the</strong> middle-class, po<strong>in</strong>ts to <strong>the</strong>possibilities with<strong>in</strong> a complex conceptual hierarchy for <strong>the</strong> organizationof experience, <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r, associated with <strong>the</strong> lower work<strong>in</strong>g-class,progressively limits <strong>the</strong> type of stimuli to which <strong>the</strong> child learns torespond. (Bernste<strong>in</strong>, 1960: 276)Before long, to complete what appears to be quite a well-rounded pictureof deficiency, ‘public’ and ‘formal’ language variants were translated <strong>in</strong>to<strong>the</strong> more well-known ‘restricted’ and ‘elaborated’ codes (see Bernste<strong>in</strong>,1962a). Bernste<strong>in</strong>’s early experimental data are found <strong>in</strong> four connectedpapers (1958, 1960, 1962a, 1962b), and <strong>the</strong> most salient f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>gs revealedclass differences <strong>in</strong> verbal performance between public-school boys, on<strong>the</strong> one hand, and work<strong>in</strong>g-class messenger boys, on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r. The<strong>in</strong>ferior verbal abilities of <strong>the</strong> messengers were to be expla<strong>in</strong>ed, Bernste<strong>in</strong>


98 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>(1960: 276) noted, by <strong>the</strong> fact that ‘<strong>the</strong> normal l<strong>in</strong>guistic environment of<strong>the</strong> work<strong>in</strong>g class is one of relative deprivation’.Such an <strong>in</strong>terpretation made it difficult, of course, to believe thatBernste<strong>in</strong> was not an adherent of <strong>the</strong> ‘deficit’ viewpo<strong>in</strong>t this despitelater disclaimers, and despite <strong>the</strong> occasional reference to <strong>the</strong> strengths ofpublic/restricted codes (‘emotionally virile, pithy and powerful... ametaphoric range of considerable force and appropriateness’: Bernste<strong>in</strong>,1959: 322323). Rosen (1972), Tony Edwards (1974) and Dittmar (1976)were among <strong>the</strong> earliest doubt<strong>in</strong>g apostles here. One of <strong>the</strong> most cutt<strong>in</strong>gassessments, however, was that of Jackson (1974: 65), who beg<strong>in</strong>s areview (one that runs to almost 20 pages) of <strong>the</strong> first two volumes ofBernste<strong>in</strong>’s work on ‘class, codes and control’ by not<strong>in</strong>g that ‘it is neverentirely pleasant to have to say that a major scientific reputation isfounded on a myth’ (<strong>the</strong> ‘entirely’ is a nice touch here). Jackson concludeswith <strong>the</strong> sw<strong>in</strong>ge<strong>in</strong>g assertion that Bernste<strong>in</strong>’s work is essentially an‘artistic <strong>in</strong>terpretation of <strong>the</strong> world’, and quite unscientific.That a work of art [Jackson goes on to say]... should have to bepresented to <strong>the</strong> world as pseudo-science, presumably <strong>in</strong> order toga<strong>in</strong> recognition, research grants and a chair, is a savage comment onwhat we are prepared to f<strong>in</strong>ance and respect, and on <strong>the</strong> scientificstandards of <strong>in</strong>stitutional sociology. (Jackson, 1974: 81)A generation on, Joseph (2004: 69) provides a powerful retrospectiveassessment: ‘Bernste<strong>in</strong> was clearly say<strong>in</strong>g despite his later vehementbut dis<strong>in</strong>genuous denials that only middle-class people have truepersonal identities and full cognition of <strong>the</strong>ir world. Work<strong>in</strong>g-classpeople have strong social identity, shared with o<strong>the</strong>rs who speak only<strong>the</strong> restricted code’. Strong words. Some may f<strong>in</strong>d <strong>the</strong>m a little toostrong, perhaps, but it is worth reproduc<strong>in</strong>g here Joseph’s fullercommentary:When <strong>the</strong>se statements [about codes] were <strong>in</strong>terpreted <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> onlyreasonable way <strong>the</strong>y could be as mean<strong>in</strong>g that <strong>the</strong> language of <strong>the</strong>work<strong>in</strong>g classes renders <strong>the</strong>ir speakers cognitively deficient and<strong>in</strong>dist<strong>in</strong>ct as <strong>in</strong>dividuals and when objections were raised to this,Bernste<strong>in</strong> reacted with shock, and over subsequent decades alteredhis statements to make <strong>the</strong>m sound less like negative judgements on<strong>the</strong> work<strong>in</strong>g classes. He responded robustly to anyone who criticised[such] statements... and while he deserves credit for shift<strong>in</strong>g hisstance... he never came to grips with <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>escapable implications of<strong>the</strong> early work that made his name. Efforts to rehabilitate him <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>


The <strong>Language</strong> Debate 991990s have not resulted <strong>in</strong> his reformulated views on socialdifference, language and identity hav<strong>in</strong>g wide <strong>in</strong>fluence. They arestill seen as be<strong>in</strong>g based on a form of l<strong>in</strong>guistic determ<strong>in</strong>ism that hasgone out of fashion. (Joseph, 2003: 6970)My only reservation with Joseph’s observation, which neatly summarizesl’affaire Bernste<strong>in</strong>, is that say<strong>in</strong>g that deficit models have becomeunfashionable is to downplay <strong>the</strong> social-scientific evidence that didmuch more than simply edge <strong>the</strong>m off <strong>the</strong> catwalk.A study by Hawk<strong>in</strong>s (1969) referred to by Coulthard (1969: 45) as‘<strong>the</strong> most <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g and challeng<strong>in</strong>g empirical paper... on restricted andelaborated codes’ prompted some reveal<strong>in</strong>g comments by Bernste<strong>in</strong>himself. Hawk<strong>in</strong>s had asked middle-class and work<strong>in</strong>g-class children tomake up stories on <strong>the</strong> basis of a series of pictures and, on <strong>the</strong> basis of <strong>the</strong>responses, Hawk<strong>in</strong>s created two versions; <strong>the</strong> middle-class narrative is asfollows:Three boys are play<strong>in</strong>g football and one boy kicks <strong>the</strong> ball and itgoes through <strong>the</strong> w<strong>in</strong>dow <strong>the</strong> ball breaks <strong>the</strong> w<strong>in</strong>dow and <strong>the</strong>boys are look<strong>in</strong>g at it and a man comes out and shouts at <strong>the</strong>m because <strong>the</strong>y’ve broken <strong>the</strong> w<strong>in</strong>dow so <strong>the</strong>y run away and <strong>the</strong>nthat lady looks out of her w<strong>in</strong>dow and she tells <strong>the</strong> boys off.And here is <strong>the</strong> work<strong>in</strong>g-class sample:They’re play<strong>in</strong>g football and he kicks it and it goes through <strong>the</strong>re it breaks <strong>the</strong> w<strong>in</strong>dow and <strong>the</strong>y’re look<strong>in</strong>g at it and he comes out and shouts at <strong>the</strong>m because <strong>the</strong>y’ve broken it so <strong>the</strong>y run away and <strong>the</strong>n she looks out and she tells <strong>the</strong>m off.The first version takes little for granted, Bernste<strong>in</strong> (1972a: 167) tells us, <strong>the</strong>reader does not have to see <strong>the</strong> pictures <strong>in</strong> order to understand <strong>the</strong> story,and <strong>the</strong> little narrative is thus ‘free of <strong>the</strong> context which generated it’.This is not so for <strong>the</strong> work<strong>in</strong>g-class version, where <strong>the</strong> mean<strong>in</strong>g isimplicit and where <strong>the</strong> reader must have access to <strong>the</strong> pictures beforebe<strong>in</strong>g able to understand <strong>the</strong> paragraph. Bernste<strong>in</strong> argued that <strong>the</strong>importance of Hawk<strong>in</strong>s’ work rested upon <strong>the</strong> demonstration of classdifferences <strong>in</strong> responses to <strong>the</strong> same stimuli. There are some difficulties,however.First, <strong>the</strong> stories are hypo<strong>the</strong>tical: Hawk<strong>in</strong>s himself made <strong>the</strong>m up,ra<strong>the</strong>r than present<strong>in</strong>g actual examples produced by <strong>the</strong> children<strong>the</strong>mselves. 2 Second, Bernste<strong>in</strong> and Hawk<strong>in</strong>s consider <strong>the</strong> work<strong>in</strong>g-classversion as less than ideal because it seems to assume that <strong>the</strong> reader


100 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>shares background <strong>in</strong>formation with <strong>the</strong> teller (i.e. has seen <strong>the</strong> samepictures); <strong>the</strong> reader will recall that this was a communicative obstacleremarked upon by Schatzman and Straus. In this case, however, asStubbs (1983), Trudgill (1975) and Coulthard (1969) all po<strong>in</strong>ted out, <strong>the</strong>experimenter was present when <strong>the</strong> children constructed <strong>the</strong>ir stories,and thus did see <strong>the</strong> pictures. One might quite reasonably argue,<strong>the</strong>refore, that <strong>the</strong> work<strong>in</strong>g-class version was more appropriate <strong>in</strong> acontext <strong>in</strong> which both speaker and listener had <strong>the</strong> same <strong>in</strong>formation <strong>in</strong>front of <strong>the</strong>m.An equation of work<strong>in</strong>g-class language with <strong>in</strong>ferior language isespecially unfortunate even with<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> conf<strong>in</strong>es of Bernste<strong>in</strong>’s own<strong>the</strong>oretical space when it is realized that (for example) work<strong>in</strong>g-classchildren can use elaborated code under some circumstances. This iseasily demonstrated. In British <strong>in</strong>vestigations undertaken at <strong>the</strong> height ofBernste<strong>in</strong>’s <strong>in</strong>fluence, Rob<strong>in</strong>son (1965) found that <strong>the</strong> grammatical usagesof work<strong>in</strong>g-class children writ<strong>in</strong>g formal letters were not markedlydifferent from those of <strong>the</strong>ir middle-class counterparts. Rushton andYoung (1975) reported that class differences were <strong>in</strong>fluenced by <strong>the</strong>context of <strong>the</strong> task (<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir study, different essay topics: imag<strong>in</strong>ative,op<strong>in</strong>ionative or technical). The most <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g studies here, however,are American ones.In a series of <strong>in</strong>vestigations with black children, Marwit and associates(Marwit, 1977; Marwit & Marwit, 1973, 1976; Marwit & Neumann, 1974;Marwit et al., 1972) demonstrated that <strong>the</strong> understand<strong>in</strong>g and <strong>the</strong> use of standard English develops over <strong>the</strong> course of <strong>the</strong> primary-schoolgrades. This does not imply any abandonment of maternal speechpatterns. It is, ra<strong>the</strong>r an illustration of early and grow<strong>in</strong>g awareness of <strong>the</strong>differences, both substantive and evaluative, between standard andnonstandard varieties, and of <strong>the</strong> differential appropriateness of <strong>the</strong>sevarieties <strong>in</strong> specific contexts (see also Day, 1982; Gay & Tweney, 1976).More recent research cont<strong>in</strong>ues to confirm <strong>the</strong> connection: Tannen et al.(1997) found that older nonstandard-speak<strong>in</strong>g children can easily shift to<strong>the</strong> standard when <strong>the</strong> context suggests it.In this connection, Piestrup (1973) reported that, when white teachersstigmatized <strong>the</strong> use of nonstandard language <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> classroom, <strong>the</strong>children’s use of Black English actually <strong>in</strong>creased, or became moreemphasized. The opposite was true <strong>in</strong> classrooms where teachers didnot ‘punish’ <strong>the</strong> use of nonstandard forms. Beyond <strong>the</strong> facilitation ofstandard-dialect use per se, it is easy to see that acceptance ofnonstandard dialects at school will likely <strong>in</strong>crease <strong>the</strong> general ‘comfort’level of <strong>the</strong> students, and this can be expected to produce educational


The <strong>Language</strong> Debate 101benefits of all k<strong>in</strong>ds (see Nero, 2006; Rickford & Rickford, 1995; Siegel,2006, 2007). All of this is surely a specific example of a very general rule:<strong>the</strong> best way to expedite <strong>the</strong> learn<strong>in</strong>g of someth<strong>in</strong>g new is to start withwhat children br<strong>in</strong>g with <strong>the</strong>m, to build upon exist<strong>in</strong>g competence andpractice. With particular regard to language, it is clear that s<strong>in</strong>ce allvarieties, standard or nonstandard, have symbolic as well as communicativefunctions, to denigrate or dismiss <strong>the</strong>m is to threaten or belittlean important marker of group solidarity; this is an important matter towhich I shall return.The early work show<strong>in</strong>g that lower-class children could, after all, useBernste<strong>in</strong>’s more ‘elaborated’ codes is, <strong>in</strong> fact, evidence for <strong>the</strong> commonphenomenon of ‘bidialectalism’, which, <strong>in</strong>deed, typically <strong>in</strong>volvesvarieties of higher and lower prestige. The more standard format canbe expected <strong>in</strong> formal or extra-group <strong>in</strong>teractions, <strong>the</strong> more nonstandardmedium <strong>in</strong> contexts of familiarity and <strong>in</strong>timacy. Both have <strong>the</strong>ir uses,which expla<strong>in</strong>s why one generally does not drive out <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r. Theremay be compell<strong>in</strong>g social reasons, for <strong>in</strong>stance, for <strong>the</strong> ma<strong>in</strong>tenance oflow-prestige varieties. Speicher and McMahon (1992) report on <strong>the</strong> peerpressure among <strong>the</strong>ir black <strong>in</strong>formants to use Black English, or risk be<strong>in</strong>glabeled an ‘oreo’ (a biscuit that is black on <strong>the</strong> outside, but white <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>middle); among native North Americans <strong>the</strong> cognate term is ‘apple’,among Asian Americans it is ‘banana’ and so on. This is a specificexample of a much broader phenomenon: <strong>the</strong> ostracism that can followattempts to leave one’s group and jo<strong>in</strong> ano<strong>the</strong>r.Thus, a generation ago, Carranza and Ryan (1975) noted that MexicanAmericans who abandon Spanish for <strong>the</strong> socioeconomic rewards ofEnglish may be seen by <strong>the</strong>ir friends as vendidos: ‘sell-outs’. The samelabel<strong>in</strong>g was applied to French speakers <strong>in</strong> Quebec who moved toEnglish; <strong>the</strong>y were vendus. Of course, if one could make a clean andcomplete break, if one could leave beh<strong>in</strong>d one life and move seamlessly<strong>in</strong>to ano<strong>the</strong>r, <strong>the</strong>se epi<strong>the</strong>ts would lose some of <strong>the</strong>ir force, and wouldperhaps reflect only some difficult, but temporary, period of transition.But, it is extremely difficult to make such moves, particularly, of course,when many o<strong>the</strong>r th<strong>in</strong>gs besides language have to be adjusted. Indeed,some th<strong>in</strong>gs, like sk<strong>in</strong> color, cannot be adjusted at all (Michael Jacksonnotwithstand<strong>in</strong>g). So, <strong>the</strong> danger is of end<strong>in</strong>g up <strong>in</strong> some psychosocialno-man’s land, of becom<strong>in</strong>g ‘marg<strong>in</strong>alized’. In that case, labels and <strong>the</strong>attitudes susta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>m would have real and ongo<strong>in</strong>g force. Suchconsiderations give many people pause.It would, however, be both wrong and <strong>in</strong>complete to th<strong>in</strong>k that onlynegative possibilities restra<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividuals from attempt<strong>in</strong>g cultural or


102 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>l<strong>in</strong>guistic shift. We should remember that <strong>the</strong>re are strong positive forcesb<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g us to our groups, even if those groups are low <strong>in</strong> status. Theymay lack social prestige but <strong>the</strong>y are ours. Their ways and traditions arefamiliar, <strong>the</strong>ir speech patterns are our maternal <strong>in</strong>heritances, and asmentioned every language and dialect has symbolic value for itsspeakers. The ‘identity function’ is carried as much by Cockney as it is byOxfordese, as much by Quebec joual as Parisian French. Ryan’s (1979)brief paper on <strong>the</strong> persistence of low-prestige dialects rema<strong>in</strong>s <strong>in</strong>structivehere, and a recent paper by Abd-el-Jawad (2006) discusses <strong>the</strong> persistenceof m<strong>in</strong>ority languages: where <strong>the</strong> ord<strong>in</strong>ary communicative functionshave been largely (or wholly) replaced by a ‘larger’ language, <strong>the</strong> smallermay yet persist because of <strong>the</strong> strong symbolic value it reta<strong>in</strong>s for groupmembers. Relatedly, a language no longer widely spoken may rema<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>repository of a group’s tradition, literature and so on.We should conclude this section with a general consideration of <strong>the</strong><strong>in</strong>fluence of Bernste<strong>in</strong> or should it be <strong>the</strong> early Bernste<strong>in</strong> or, perhaps,Bernste<strong>in</strong> mis<strong>in</strong>terpreted? He made a number of attempts to justify hisposition (<strong>in</strong> 1971 and 1972b, for example), and his f<strong>in</strong>al arguments <strong>in</strong>response to criticisms of <strong>the</strong> codes were made <strong>in</strong> 1987 (revised andenlarged <strong>in</strong> 1990). Here, Bernste<strong>in</strong> gave particular attention to <strong>the</strong> work ofLabov (1969), Stubbs (1983a) and Gibson (1984), and even refers to a briefcriticism of m<strong>in</strong>e (Edwards, 1987). The critics are seen to have ignoredsalient features of <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory, and to have been unfairly selective. As partof this defence, Bernste<strong>in</strong> (1990: 101) attempts aga<strong>in</strong> to say what his codesare and what <strong>the</strong>y are not: ‘a code is a regulative pr<strong>in</strong>ciple, tacitly acquired,which selects and <strong>in</strong>tegrates relevant mean<strong>in</strong>gs, forms of realizations,and evok<strong>in</strong>g contexts’. It seems to me that, apart from re<strong>in</strong>forc<strong>in</strong>g earliercriticisms about <strong>the</strong> opacity of his prose, this use of words like ‘tacitly’,‘relevant’ and ‘forms’ provides for almost <strong>in</strong>f<strong>in</strong>ite slippage.Bernste<strong>in</strong> (1997: 47) discusses <strong>the</strong> context with<strong>in</strong> which his code <strong>the</strong>orywas formulated and presented, and even tries to argue that <strong>the</strong>difference/deficit debate was ‘of little <strong>the</strong>oretical significance’ and‘obscured more than it revealed’. He also offers here a critical analysisof Labov’s sem<strong>in</strong>al 1969 paper, but pays no attention to <strong>the</strong> grammaticalaspects that (as we shall see) constitute <strong>the</strong> most important element <strong>in</strong>Labov’s conv<strong>in</strong>c<strong>in</strong>g argument aga<strong>in</strong>st deficit hypo<strong>the</strong>ses.Beyond its baleful <strong>in</strong>fluence <strong>in</strong> educational sett<strong>in</strong>gs, Bernste<strong>in</strong>’s workhas been taken up <strong>in</strong> some (fairly limited) scholarly quarters, particularlywhere Halliday’s ‘systemic’ l<strong>in</strong>guistics and questions about possiblevariations <strong>in</strong> language functions across social groups are under consideration.These are areas where Bernste<strong>in</strong> latterly claimed that <strong>the</strong>


The <strong>Language</strong> Debate 103import of his work was really to be found (see, e.g. Bernste<strong>in</strong>, 1996).Support here has typically built upon <strong>the</strong> notion that <strong>the</strong> codes reflectl<strong>in</strong>guistic performance and not basic competence. In po<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>the</strong> grow<strong>in</strong>gsense that educational failure was l<strong>in</strong>guistic failure (‘this notion is <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>air, so to speak’), Halliday (1973b) was obliged to acknowledge that <strong>the</strong>source of <strong>the</strong> equation could be found <strong>in</strong> Bernste<strong>in</strong>’s work. What a pity,Halliday implies, that <strong>the</strong> codes have become <strong>the</strong> culprit, given ‘<strong>the</strong> carewhich Bernste<strong>in</strong> has taken to emphasize that nei<strong>the</strong>r is more highlyvalued than <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r’ (Halliday, 1973b: x). This is surely verydis<strong>in</strong>genuous, s<strong>in</strong>ce we have ample evidence that by his own admission Bernste<strong>in</strong> took very little care <strong>in</strong> this regard. Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, if you willcall one of your variants ‘elaborated’ and <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r ‘restricted’...Apart from <strong>the</strong> sympa<strong>the</strong>tic writ<strong>in</strong>gs of Halliday (1973a, 1973b, 1975),relevant collections <strong>in</strong>clude those edited by Atk<strong>in</strong>son et al. (1995),Christie (1999) and Power et al. (2001). Foley (1991) also takes <strong>the</strong> l<strong>in</strong>ethat Bernste<strong>in</strong> has been mis<strong>in</strong>terpreted, this time <strong>in</strong> a context ofcomparison with <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ories of Vygotsky and Halliday. Of most <strong>in</strong>terest,however, is <strong>the</strong> very recent anthology of Ruqaiya Hasan’s papers, asedited by Webster (2005). This collection is an excellent resource if youare <strong>in</strong>terested <strong>in</strong> Bernste<strong>in</strong> and <strong>the</strong> ‘social-semiotic mediation of m<strong>in</strong>d’, orperhaps <strong>the</strong> ‘meta-dialogism’ of his ‘exotropic’ <strong>the</strong>ory.An <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g defense of Bernste<strong>in</strong> and his work has been mountedby Rob<strong>in</strong>son (1998), who suggests that many of <strong>the</strong> views for whichBernste<strong>in</strong> was most vilified were not, <strong>in</strong> fact, his views at all. Rob<strong>in</strong>sonalso ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>s that academic criticism of Bernste<strong>in</strong> was essentially nonconstructive,not ‘Popperian-based’ and often personalized. However,while such criticism certa<strong>in</strong>ly arose <strong>in</strong> some quarters, it would be a greatmistake to imag<strong>in</strong>e that more measured treatments were absent (seeEdwards, 1989; and <strong>the</strong> follow<strong>in</strong>g chapter). Rob<strong>in</strong>son (2001) adds that <strong>the</strong>activities of members of Bernste<strong>in</strong>’s research team (of whom he was one)came to a ra<strong>the</strong>r abrupt halt, largely because of mount<strong>in</strong>g academiccensure. Their publications, he argues, were simply ignored <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>political and educational corridors of power. Mention<strong>in</strong>g Labov’s workparticularly, Rob<strong>in</strong>son (2001: 238) laments that <strong>the</strong> criticisms cameunaccompanied with any ‘constructive alternative curriculum... [and]simply left <strong>the</strong> disadvantaged children to suffer <strong>the</strong> same fate as <strong>the</strong>irancestors’. Now, while it is very useful if a critical perspective is soaccompanied, <strong>the</strong>re is no logical requirement; <strong>in</strong>deed, it is quite commonto recognize <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>adequacy of exist<strong>in</strong>g approaches without be<strong>in</strong>g able tocome up with satisfactory solutions. But Rob<strong>in</strong>son is, <strong>in</strong> any event,mistaken <strong>in</strong> his assertion that <strong>the</strong> current state of affairs leaves children <strong>in</strong>


104 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>some retrograde state of suffer<strong>in</strong>g. Adopt<strong>in</strong>g a ‘difference’ perspective ondisadvantage, for example, hardly precludes <strong>in</strong>tervention, although itdoes rule out, quite rightly, attempts founded on flawed understand<strong>in</strong>gof children’s l<strong>in</strong>guistic and cognitive capacities.F<strong>in</strong>ally here, Blommaert (2005: 13) has noted that Bernste<strong>in</strong>’s sensethat <strong>the</strong> l<strong>in</strong>guistic resources to which children have access are differentiallydistributed across class l<strong>in</strong>es rema<strong>in</strong>s valid, corroborated as it is byBourdieu’s notions of social reproduction, language and symbolic power(see Bourdieu, 1991; Bourdieu & Passeron, 1977). This is hardly anendorsement of Bernste<strong>in</strong>ian <strong>in</strong>sights, however, s<strong>in</strong>ce no ‘difference’<strong>the</strong>orist would have any quarrel with such a common-sense idea. Thedifference-deficit argument has always h<strong>in</strong>ged upon <strong>the</strong> mean<strong>in</strong>g and <strong>the</strong>consequences of social-class variations <strong>in</strong> language.Bernste<strong>in</strong> and compensatory educationIn distanc<strong>in</strong>g himself from ‘deficit’ <strong>the</strong>ories, Bernste<strong>in</strong> also dissociatedhimself from programs of educational <strong>in</strong>tervention, of ‘compensatoryeducation’. Indeed, Bernste<strong>in</strong> (1972b: 137) po<strong>in</strong>ted out that <strong>the</strong> latter termwas particularly unfortunate, s<strong>in</strong>ce it implies that ‘someth<strong>in</strong>g is lack<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> family, and so <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> child... <strong>the</strong> children become little deficitsystems’. The simple fact rema<strong>in</strong>s, however, that Bernste<strong>in</strong>’s work fuelledsome specific scholarly extensions and, perhaps more importantly, subtlyre<strong>in</strong>forced powerful exist<strong>in</strong>g currents <strong>in</strong> and beyond <strong>the</strong> classroom. Thus,when Trudgill (1975) <strong>in</strong>vestigated both Bernste<strong>in</strong>’s work and <strong>the</strong>criticisms of it what did Bernste<strong>in</strong> really mean? would it make moresense to consider <strong>the</strong> ‘codes’ as sociol<strong>in</strong>guistic variants ra<strong>the</strong>r thanl<strong>in</strong>guistic phenomena? he emphasized its effects <strong>in</strong> educational and<strong>in</strong>structional sett<strong>in</strong>gs. One of <strong>the</strong> simplest and clearest statements here isthat of Cheshire et al. (1989: 6): despite Bernste<strong>in</strong>’s ‘strenuous’ denials,<strong>the</strong>y note, ‘his work was widely <strong>in</strong>terpreted <strong>in</strong> Brita<strong>in</strong>, <strong>in</strong> North Americaand <strong>in</strong> Europe as suggest<strong>in</strong>g that <strong>the</strong> standard language could be equatedwith <strong>the</strong> elaborated code and work<strong>in</strong>g-class non-standard dialects with<strong>the</strong> restricted code’.Apart from <strong>the</strong> summaries and expansions produced by Bernste<strong>in</strong>’scolleagues <strong>in</strong> Brita<strong>in</strong>, <strong>the</strong> most important and <strong>the</strong> most damag<strong>in</strong>gconsequences of his work occurred with<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> American educationalcommunity. Hess and Shipman’s (1965, 1968a, 1968b) work on mo<strong>the</strong>rchildcommunication and maternal ‘control’ is representative here. Thelower-class family was seen to have ‘imperative-normative’ communicativepatterns, with little of <strong>the</strong> personal and rational elements typical


The <strong>Language</strong> Debate 105of middle-class mo<strong>the</strong>r/child <strong>in</strong>teractions. The authors summarize <strong>the</strong>irf<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>gs as follows:The mean<strong>in</strong>g of deprivation would thus seem to be a deprivation ofmean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> early cognitive relationships between mo<strong>the</strong>r andchild. This environment produces a child who relates to authorityra<strong>the</strong>r than to rationale, who may often be compliant but is notreflective <strong>in</strong> his behavior, and for whom <strong>the</strong> consequences of an actare largely considered <strong>in</strong> terms of immediate punishment or rewardra<strong>the</strong>r than future effects and long-range goals. (Hess & Shipman,1968b: 103)The clever but vacuous phrase that beg<strong>in</strong>s <strong>the</strong> quotation soonrecommended itself to many ‘deficit’ researchers. Indeed, <strong>the</strong> generalimport of <strong>the</strong> statement as a whole l<strong>in</strong>ks perfectly with <strong>the</strong> broaderenvironmental-deficit perspective already discussed. Hess and Shipmango on to argue that, s<strong>in</strong>ce <strong>the</strong> early life of <strong>the</strong> lower-class child is mentallystunt<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>in</strong>tervention aimed at noth<strong>in</strong>g less than ‘resocialization’ is<strong>in</strong>dicated.The criticisms that can be made of this sort of work are by nowfamiliar. It is always difficult to generalize from psychological prob<strong>in</strong>gsof one sort or ano<strong>the</strong>r especially with social groups for whom <strong>the</strong>y arestrange and artificial occurrences to what actually takes place <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong><strong>home</strong>. Assumptions about l<strong>in</strong>ks between different types of maternalbehavior and children’s cognitive development are difficult to confirm.Powerful assumptions of <strong>the</strong> ‘normality’ and ‘correctness’ of middleclassattitudes and lifestyles may <strong>in</strong>fect even <strong>the</strong> most sensitiveassessments of lower-class environments. And so on.Somewhat more sophisticated work on class differences <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>‘language of maternal control’ was presented by Cook-Gumperz (1973).On <strong>the</strong> basis of tape-recorded <strong>in</strong>terviews, work<strong>in</strong>g-class mo<strong>the</strong>rs wereobserved to employ ‘imperative’ modes of control, while <strong>the</strong> middle classutilized a broader and more personal mode. Never<strong>the</strong>less, considerable<strong>in</strong>tra-class variation was also found. Related to <strong>the</strong> broad tendencies ofclass differences <strong>in</strong> control techniques was <strong>the</strong> use of elaborated code <strong>in</strong><strong>the</strong> middle-class mo<strong>the</strong>rs’ speech, and restricted code <strong>in</strong> that of <strong>the</strong>irwork<strong>in</strong>g-class counterparts. Similar work was reported by Rob<strong>in</strong>son andRackstraw (1972): <strong>in</strong> response to various questions, middle-class childrenwere found to give more <strong>in</strong>formation, and to expla<strong>in</strong> and amplify upon<strong>the</strong>ir answers more fully, than did work<strong>in</strong>g-class children; <strong>the</strong> answers of<strong>the</strong> latter often <strong>in</strong>volved simple appeals to authority or custom.


106 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>I have already referred to <strong>the</strong> environmental-deficit position as <strong>the</strong>chief stimulant to <strong>in</strong>terest <strong>in</strong> compensatory education (see Deutsch,1967). It is now possible to be more specific, and to see language as <strong>the</strong>central pillar of many <strong>in</strong>tervention programs, whose essential raison d’êtrewas to combat <strong>the</strong> chimera of ‘verbal deprivation’.In one of <strong>the</strong> earliest and best-known programs, Bereiter andEngelmann (1966: 39) began from <strong>the</strong> premise that disadvantagedchildren are retarded <strong>in</strong> reason<strong>in</strong>g ability and language skills: <strong>the</strong>irlanguage is ‘immature’, <strong>the</strong>y lack ‘<strong>the</strong> most rudimentary forms ofconstructive dialogue’. In fact, Bereiter and Engelmann claimed, morethan once, that <strong>the</strong> disadvantaged child attempts to get along withoutlanguage wherever possible. ‘<strong>Language</strong>’, <strong>the</strong>y said, ‘is apparentlydispensable enough <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> life of <strong>the</strong> lower-class child for an occasionalchild to get along without it altoge<strong>the</strong>r’ (p. 31); or, a little fur<strong>the</strong>r on,‘language for <strong>the</strong> disadvantaged child seems to be an aspect of socialbehavior which is not of vital importance’ (p. 42). On this bizarre andludicrous basis, Bereiter and Engelmann who clearly never bo<strong>the</strong>red toobserve lower-class children at play put toge<strong>the</strong>r a remedial program.(Labov’s [1969: 33] reaction reflects <strong>the</strong> astonishment felt by l<strong>in</strong>guistsconfronted with <strong>the</strong> bl<strong>in</strong>dness or deafness of <strong>the</strong> deficit <strong>the</strong>orists: ‘<strong>the</strong>view of <strong>the</strong> Negro speech community which we obta<strong>in</strong> from our work <strong>in</strong><strong>the</strong> ghetto is precisely <strong>the</strong> opposite... we see a child ba<strong>the</strong>d <strong>in</strong> verbalstimulation from morn<strong>in</strong>g to night’.)The most immediate problem for Bereiter and Engelmann was to breakdown what <strong>the</strong>y termed <strong>the</strong> ‘giant word’ syndrome. The ‘deprived child’cannot say ‘I a<strong>in</strong>’t got no juice’ but, <strong>in</strong>stead, ‘Uai-ga-na-ju’ (p. 34). Theauthors considered this phenomenon directly consistent with Bernste<strong>in</strong>’snotion of restricted code, and <strong>the</strong> remedy consisted largely of <strong>in</strong>tensiveand highly specific drills <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> use of ‘correct’ English. Detailed<strong>in</strong>structions are provided for teachers Bereiter and Engelmann’s bookis, <strong>in</strong> fact, essentially an educational manual one example of which willbe more than sufficient:(A)(B)(C)(D)Present an object and give <strong>the</strong> appropriate identity statement.‘‘This is a ball.’’Follow <strong>the</strong> statement with a yes-no question. ‘‘Is this a ball?’’Answer <strong>the</strong> question. ‘‘Yes, this is a ball.’’Repeat <strong>the</strong> question and encourage <strong>the</strong> children to answer it.(p. 140)


The <strong>Language</strong> Debate 107Throughout <strong>the</strong> program, it is apparent that <strong>the</strong> authors’ conception of<strong>the</strong> language of disadvantaged children is startl<strong>in</strong>gly <strong>in</strong>accurate. Toanticipate later arguments a bit: Labov (1969) observed that <strong>the</strong> authors’belief that usages like ‘<strong>the</strong>y m<strong>in</strong>e’ is <strong>in</strong>correct and illogical reveals a lackof awareness of Black English grammar, <strong>in</strong> which <strong>the</strong> deletion of <strong>the</strong>present-tense copula verb (‘are’, <strong>in</strong> this case) is a regularity. Labov alsopo<strong>in</strong>ted to <strong>the</strong>ir unfortunate dismissal of ‘In <strong>the</strong> tree’ as an illogicalanswer to <strong>the</strong> teacher’s question, ‘Where is <strong>the</strong> squirrel?’ Everyone usessuch economical elliptical statements and, <strong>in</strong> fact, <strong>the</strong>ir use clearly showsthat <strong>the</strong> listener has paid close attention to <strong>the</strong> grammatical context of <strong>the</strong>question.Ano<strong>the</strong>r well-known American project for disadvantaged blackchildren was that of Klaus and Gray (1968; see also Gray & Klaus,1970). Characteriz<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> children’s <strong>home</strong> life as noisy, disorganized and<strong>in</strong>adequate for <strong>the</strong> ‘proper’ development of cognitive skills, <strong>the</strong> authorsacknowledge <strong>the</strong>ir debt to Bernste<strong>in</strong>. They def<strong>in</strong>e <strong>the</strong> restricted code as:one <strong>in</strong> which most of <strong>the</strong> mean<strong>in</strong>g must be carried by o<strong>the</strong>r aspects of<strong>the</strong> total situation: facial expression, <strong>in</strong>tonation ra<strong>the</strong>r than wordsspoken, <strong>the</strong> circumstances. The child, thus, does not learn to uselanguage effectively. (Klaus & Gray, 1968: 8)(Indeed, <strong>the</strong> essence of this quotation is traceable to Bernste<strong>in</strong>’s earliestpaper on class and language.)Overall, early (pre-1970) programs of compensatory education weregenerally built upon l<strong>in</strong>guistic-deficit <strong>the</strong>ory, and often displayed someacqua<strong>in</strong>tance with Bernste<strong>in</strong>’s work <strong>in</strong> particular. This is true not only for<strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual programs just touched upon here, but also for <strong>the</strong> massiveAmerican Head Start project, an <strong>in</strong>tervention designed to give poorchildren pre-school experience that would allow <strong>the</strong>m to enter <strong>the</strong>regular school itself on a more equal foot<strong>in</strong>g. Spr<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>g from PresidentJohnson’s ‘War on Poverty’ <strong>in</strong> 1965, and fuelled by Coleman’s (1966)report on equality of educational opportunity (see also Jencks, 1972),Head Start was soon deal<strong>in</strong>g with hundreds of thousands of children.As <strong>the</strong> deficit perspective waned, however, later educational <strong>in</strong>terventionslooked somewhat more enlightened at least, <strong>the</strong> term‘compensatory education’ was <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>gly seen as <strong>in</strong>appropriate, undercutby <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>sights of <strong>the</strong> ‘difference’ position. In Brita<strong>in</strong>, for example, <strong>the</strong>Plowden Report (1967) focused attention upon <strong>the</strong> problems of children<strong>in</strong> urban areas and recommended <strong>the</strong> identification of ‘educationalpriority areas’ on <strong>the</strong> basis of a number of visible criteria <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g largefamily size, receipt of state benefits and poor hous<strong>in</strong>g. Virtually all


108 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong><strong>in</strong>tervention <strong>in</strong>itiatives early programs or later ones have <strong>in</strong>terested<strong>the</strong>mselves <strong>in</strong> language matters and, to that extent, have rema<strong>in</strong>ed‘remedial’ <strong>in</strong> nature. Indeed, as I have already h<strong>in</strong>ted (and as we shall see<strong>in</strong> more detail later on), an adherence to a ‘difference’ perspective doesnot rule out concern for children’s l<strong>in</strong>guistic repertoires or educational<strong>in</strong>tervention per se. It does rule out, however, <strong>in</strong>terventions built uponfalse foot<strong>in</strong>gs. Thus, Bridget Plowden herself cautioned aga<strong>in</strong>st programspredicated upon <strong>the</strong> idea that all should th<strong>in</strong>k ‘<strong>the</strong> same way as we doourselves’; she went on:education for <strong>the</strong> deprived child [should be] complementary to his<strong>home</strong>... ra<strong>the</strong>r than compensatory, which really means that <strong>the</strong> <strong>home</strong>has no merit. (Plowden, 1970: 12)This view may not be fully with<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> approved ‘difference’ camp ondisadvantage, but <strong>the</strong> words here suggest a considerable advance from<strong>the</strong> hard-l<strong>in</strong>e deficit approach that was still common when <strong>the</strong>y werewritten. 3Although I shall shortly turn to some detailed criticisms of <strong>the</strong> deficitview of language, we know already from <strong>the</strong> more general discussion ofdisadvantage that deficit perspectives are flawed. So, just as we haverejected labels like ‘cultural deprivation’, as <strong>in</strong>accurate and, <strong>in</strong>deed,nonsensical, we can also reject <strong>the</strong> more specific notion of ‘verbaldeprivation’. By extension, <strong>the</strong> philosophical underp<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>gs of ‘compensatory’education are equally shaky: if <strong>the</strong> language of disadvantagedchildren is not deficient, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong>re is noth<strong>in</strong>g to compensate for. We may,for practical purposes, wish to <strong>in</strong>crease or broaden children’s l<strong>in</strong>guisticrepertoires, but this is ano<strong>the</strong>r matter (see below), and any attempt to doso is not likely to succeed if it is founded on deep misunderstand<strong>in</strong>g ofexist<strong>in</strong>g l<strong>in</strong>guistic capabilities.The ignorance of <strong>the</strong> importance of cultural relativism, and <strong>the</strong> bl<strong>in</strong>dimposition of middle-class standards to which this ignorance leads, havealways been <strong>the</strong> major issues <strong>in</strong> critical discussions of compensatoryeducation and verbal deprivation. Investigations of lower-class beliefs,attitudes and values by middle-class <strong>in</strong>terviewers, us<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>strumentsstandardized (if at all) with middle-class populations, often tak<strong>in</strong>g place<strong>in</strong> middle-class sett<strong>in</strong>gs (<strong>the</strong> university cl<strong>in</strong>ic, <strong>the</strong> social-scientificlaboratory) are likely to produce dubious results. 4 Recall, for example,that Hess and Shipman’s studies <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> 1960s led <strong>the</strong>m to advocate <strong>the</strong>‘resocialization’ of <strong>the</strong> disadvantaged child this to <strong>in</strong>volve strong andprolonged <strong>in</strong>tervention <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> family and, <strong>in</strong> some cases, actual removal


The <strong>Language</strong> Debate 109of <strong>the</strong> child a proposal based upon a direct imputation of lower-classfamily <strong>in</strong>adequacy. Even at <strong>the</strong> time, <strong>the</strong>re were those who protested:Do we have <strong>the</strong> right to impose middle-class standards on lowerclassand black families?... Are we confident that <strong>the</strong> middle-classvalue system, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> current school system, is an appropriatestandard of health? If middle-class behavior patterns are to provide<strong>the</strong> outcome criteria, is it not necessary to seek and explore shortcom<strong>in</strong>gs<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>se patterns? (Sroufe, 1970: 143)Such cautionary observations, unfortunately, were typically only halfheard. The more extreme suggestions of deficit-<strong>the</strong>ory <strong>in</strong>terventionists(schemes for wholesale ‘resocialization’ of children, for <strong>in</strong>stance) were byand large resisted although, it has to be said, <strong>the</strong>ir plans were oftenrejected on economic and not philosophical grounds but calls forsusta<strong>in</strong>ed attention to middle-class lifestyles were rarely heeded. Assumptionsof <strong>the</strong> correctness or appropriateness of such lifestyles run verydeep <strong>in</strong>deed. (I don’t mean to suggest, of course, that bourgeois lifestyleshave not regularly commanded attention. History reveals little nuance,however where social analysis has not <strong>in</strong>ord<strong>in</strong>ately praised <strong>the</strong> middleclass, it has called for its obliteration.)As I have implied, <strong>the</strong> argument aga<strong>in</strong>st compensatory education andlanguage deficit is not quite complete. It is true that undercutt<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>deficit position necessarily means bolster<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> oppos<strong>in</strong>g po<strong>in</strong>t of view,but it is reasonable to supplement this sort of ‘negative’ support withmore direct and more positive evidence for <strong>the</strong> accuracy of <strong>the</strong>‘difference’ argument. Therefore, we should now consider some fur<strong>the</strong>rlanguage details.Different <strong>Language</strong>Introductory observationsWhile <strong>the</strong> ‘strong’ form of <strong>the</strong> famous Whorfian hypo<strong>the</strong>sis thatlanguage determ<strong>in</strong>es thought is generally rejected, no one denies <strong>the</strong><strong>in</strong>fluence of language upon our habitual ways of consider<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> world(nor, of course, that <strong>the</strong> environment has some formative <strong>in</strong>fluence uponlanguage development). Where languages come to be suited to <strong>the</strong>immediate needs of <strong>the</strong>ir speakers, one implication is that all validconsiderations of language usage must also be sensitive to culturalvariation; ano<strong>the</strong>r is that assessments of languages <strong>in</strong> terms of ‘better’ or‘worse’ are untenable. No <strong>in</strong>formed op<strong>in</strong>ion could hold that French is‘better’ than English, or that English is ‘worse’ than German, and <strong>the</strong>


110 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>pr<strong>in</strong>ciple holds regardless of <strong>the</strong> languages under comparison. AsLenneberg (1967) observed, <strong>the</strong>re are no ‘primitive’ languages, novarieties that are <strong>in</strong>herently more complete or more logical than o<strong>the</strong>rs;‘logic’ <strong>in</strong> languages is simply a synonym for ‘grammar’. Lenneberg’sobservation is only one example of a broadly held l<strong>in</strong>guistic conviction;<strong>the</strong> fact that it was made when <strong>the</strong> ‘deficit’ perspective on disadvantagewas at its peak is an <strong>in</strong>dication of how l<strong>in</strong>guistically ill-<strong>in</strong>formed were <strong>the</strong><strong>the</strong>orists of ‘verbal deprivation’. (When I equate logic with grammar,<strong>in</strong>cidentally, I obviously presc<strong>in</strong>d from arguments for an underly<strong>in</strong>gdeep ‘logic’ common to all languages.) Similar <strong>in</strong>sights apply to dialects ‘just as <strong>the</strong>re is no l<strong>in</strong>guistic reason for argu<strong>in</strong>g that Gaelic is superiorto Ch<strong>in</strong>ese, so no English dialect can be claimed to be l<strong>in</strong>guisticallysuperior or <strong>in</strong>ferior to any o<strong>the</strong>r’ (Trudgill, 1975: 26), and this chapter willprovide support<strong>in</strong>g evidence.(There is, of course, ample evidence that beyond <strong>the</strong> enlightened anddata-driven assessments of scholars languages and dialects are not allof equal, or potentially equal, value. Fishman has made <strong>the</strong> po<strong>in</strong>t,directly and <strong>in</strong>directly, throughout his work (e.g. Fishman, 1980, 1987;García, 1991). And Mackey (1978: 7) po<strong>in</strong>ted out, some time ago, that‘only before God and <strong>the</strong> l<strong>in</strong>guist are all languages equal. Everyoneknows that you can go fur<strong>the</strong>r with some languages than you can witho<strong>the</strong>rs’. We shall certa<strong>in</strong>ly see support<strong>in</strong>g evidence for this, here and <strong>in</strong>o<strong>the</strong>r chapters.)By an early age, and certa<strong>in</strong>ly by <strong>the</strong> time <strong>the</strong>y go to school, allchildren with<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> normal range of <strong>in</strong>telligence have acquired a fluentgrasp of <strong>the</strong>ir maternal variety. S<strong>in</strong>ce, as we shall see, all dialects are fullyfledged, rule-governed systems across which comparisons of ‘better’ or‘worse’ cannot legitimately be made, <strong>the</strong>n it follows that all childrenlearn ‘proper’ or ‘correct’ language. While ‘a fluent grasp’ is not <strong>the</strong> sameas a perfect one, some l<strong>in</strong>guists ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong> that children are on <strong>the</strong> road tothis perfection, that <strong>the</strong>y are learn<strong>in</strong>g a proper language properly. Inconsider<strong>in</strong>g this proposition, Trudgill (1975) notes that we all make slipsof <strong>the</strong> tongue, or say th<strong>in</strong>gs that we don’t mean to; fatigue is often a factorhere, of course. He also realizes that we sometimes use words withoutknow<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>ir proper or accepted mean<strong>in</strong>g. He adds that, if we <strong>in</strong>tend tospeak <strong>in</strong> a particular dialect but <strong>the</strong>n use a word or phrase from ano<strong>the</strong>r,this could be construed as a mistake; terms like ‘style’, ‘register’ and‘jargon’ could be substituted for ‘dialect’ here. And f<strong>in</strong>ally, Trudgillaccepts that we often make mistakes <strong>in</strong> speak<strong>in</strong>g a language that is notour first. But he is adamant that:


The <strong>Language</strong> Debate 111apart from <strong>the</strong>se cases, however, we have to say that all normal adultspeakers know and <strong>the</strong>refore use <strong>the</strong>ir own dialect... perfectly. Nogrammatical form which occurs <strong>in</strong> any... dialect is an error: with <strong>the</strong>exception of those <strong>in</strong>stances we have just listed, native speakers donot make mistakes. (Trudgill, 1975: 45)This has proved a difficult concept to accept <strong>in</strong> some quarters. MrsGrundy and <strong>the</strong> great host of lesser prescriptivists obviously reject it.And more broad-m<strong>in</strong>ded observers often concur with Amis’s (1990: 307)statement that ‘<strong>the</strong>re is a right way of us<strong>in</strong>g words and construct<strong>in</strong>gsentences, and plenty of wrong ways’. Teachers form an obvious grouphere; as Lippi-Green (1997: 131) and many o<strong>the</strong>rs have po<strong>in</strong>ted out, <strong>the</strong>yhave traditionally had strong views about what is correct and <strong>in</strong>correct,and have been ‘firm believers <strong>in</strong> a standard language ideology’ thatunderp<strong>in</strong>s those views.Many of Amis’s l<strong>in</strong>guistic observations are humorous, but some areill-<strong>in</strong>formed. It is not quite <strong>the</strong> case, for example, that ‘l<strong>in</strong>guists andlexicographers’ have given ‘<strong>the</strong>ir followers leave to spatter <strong>the</strong>ir talk andprose with any old illiteracy or howler that took <strong>the</strong>ir fancy’, whilerema<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g, <strong>the</strong>mselves, scrupulous adherents of ‘correct’ language ‘likea parson grimly preserv<strong>in</strong>g his own chastity while recommend<strong>in</strong>gadultery to his parishioners’ (Amis, 1990: 308). This br<strong>in</strong>gs to m<strong>in</strong>d <strong>the</strong>polished standard of those who defend nonstandard variants, <strong>the</strong> cutglassaccents of those who go to <strong>the</strong> barricades for o<strong>the</strong>rs. Hardlyhe<strong>in</strong>ous, of course, but <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g. It would be a mistake, <strong>in</strong>cidentally, toth<strong>in</strong>k that <strong>the</strong> late Sir K<strong>in</strong>gsley was simply a well-known specimen of <strong>the</strong>‘appalled of Tunbridge Wells’ species; he was always <strong>in</strong>terested <strong>in</strong>matters l<strong>in</strong>guistic and, apart from reviews like <strong>the</strong> one I cite here, hewrote an <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g book on modern English usage (Amis, 1997).The acknowledgement that <strong>the</strong>re are no ‘<strong>in</strong>adequate’ or ‘debased’dialects took longer to ripen with<strong>in</strong> l<strong>in</strong>guistics than did <strong>the</strong> parallelargument about language per se. Outside <strong>the</strong> academic prec<strong>in</strong>cts, itrema<strong>in</strong>s an idea whose force is ra<strong>the</strong>r weak. Few scholars are naïveenough to th<strong>in</strong>k that dissem<strong>in</strong>ation of enlightened l<strong>in</strong>guistic th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g willquickly change social perspectives on <strong>the</strong> Black English Vernacular(BEV), Cockney or Joual. But l<strong>in</strong>guists have <strong>in</strong>terested <strong>the</strong>mselves <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>language of disadvantage because <strong>the</strong> proponents of deficit-language<strong>the</strong>ory and <strong>the</strong> advocates of compensatory education were once wellensconced with<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> hallowed groves.Investigations of disadvantaged language are also of great <strong>in</strong>terestprecisely because <strong>the</strong>y are a gauge of prejudice, and studies of BEV are


112 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>particularly noteworthy here. Fasold (2006) po<strong>in</strong>ts out that, while <strong>the</strong>equation of BEV with ‘bad English’ is obviously false, <strong>the</strong> world beyond<strong>the</strong> academy still f<strong>in</strong>ds it to be ‘uncontroversially true’. The essence of <strong>the</strong>matter was stated by Spears:If black English vernacular has economically handicapped blacks,why haven’t varieties of nonstandard white English economicallyhandicapped <strong>the</strong> majority of white Americans who speak <strong>the</strong>m... Ibelieve this is simply ano<strong>the</strong>r way of side-stepp<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> fundamentalissue of <strong>in</strong>stitutional racism. (Spears, 1987: 55)This is not entirely fair, s<strong>in</strong>ce many white Americans have been held back<strong>in</strong> one way or ano<strong>the</strong>r because of <strong>the</strong> way <strong>the</strong>y speak. In terms of <strong>the</strong>degree and <strong>the</strong> scope of handicap, however, Spears is quite right. Evenblunter was Foster (1997: 11): ‘<strong>the</strong> reason that African American Englishhas drawn such fire is not because it is <strong>in</strong>ferior, but because it is spokenby Black people’. And James Baldw<strong>in</strong> wrote <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> New York Times (1979)that ‘it is not <strong>the</strong> black child’s language that is <strong>in</strong> question, it is not hislanguage that is despised. It is his experience’.We must acknowledge at <strong>the</strong> outset, of course, that an excellent andobvious case can be made for acquir<strong>in</strong>g greater facility with <strong>the</strong> standardforms endorsed at school and beyond. Draw<strong>in</strong>g upon <strong>the</strong> strongl<strong>in</strong>guistic evidence attest<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>the</strong> validity of all dialects (see below),Trudgill (1975) has argued for a very liberal attitude towards nonstandardvarieties at school; he feels that <strong>the</strong> best course of action <strong>in</strong>volveschang<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> negative attitudes that unfairly stigmatize those varieties.This position is both logical and desirable. Until <strong>the</strong> millennium arrives,however, we should understand that problems are go<strong>in</strong>g to cont<strong>in</strong>ue forcerta<strong>in</strong> groups of speakers; see Davies (1985). The German work ofAmmon (1977, 1983) is relevant here, and Corson (1993, 2001) cites SouthAmerican, Australian, Canadian, British and German research demonstrat<strong>in</strong>g<strong>the</strong> valued status of standard Spanish, English, Portuguese andGerman, and <strong>the</strong> low prestige of nonstandard forms.Ammon et al. (1989), Hagen (1987), Tuveng and Wold (2005) andWiggen (1978) make similar observations from European perspectives.Directly or <strong>in</strong>directly, <strong>the</strong>y all underscore <strong>the</strong> importance of bidialectalism;not, of course, a bidialectalism by fiat, but ra<strong>the</strong>r one that all <strong>the</strong> availabledata show will emerge naturally <strong>in</strong> tolerant conditions. In essence, this isan argument for a ra<strong>the</strong>r passive approach to <strong>the</strong> repertoire expansionthat bidialectalism implies. Ammon has suggested that such an approachmay not be <strong>the</strong> most expeditious <strong>in</strong> advanc<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> desired social mobilitythat standard-language usage can facilitate. However, his preferred


The <strong>Language</strong> Debate 113‘solution’ is a gradual disappearance of nonstandard varieties altoge<strong>the</strong>r,and he is thus more concerned with dialect transition than with dialectcoexistence. The great problem here is that more active programs couldeasily have <strong>the</strong> effect of stigmatiz<strong>in</strong>g nonstandard varieties <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> ears of<strong>the</strong>ir speakers: th<strong>in</strong>k of those ill-considered American ‘deficit’ <strong>in</strong>terventions.Children generally do not respond well to approaches, howeverbenevolently <strong>in</strong>spired, that essentially suggest to <strong>the</strong>m that <strong>the</strong>irmaternal dialect is <strong>in</strong> some way flawed.It is possible, of course, that even passively encourag<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> additionof more standard forms to less standard ones a typical scenario herewould be standard-speak<strong>in</strong>g teachers implicitly act<strong>in</strong>g as models for<strong>the</strong>ir pupils, whose own varieties would be accepted <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> classroom might contribute to <strong>the</strong> eventual eradication of <strong>the</strong> latter. Perhaps, that is,bidialectalism cannot be ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>ed permanently (see Moses et al., 1976,for an early discussion of this). This is an <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g question, and onethat crosses <strong>the</strong> boundaries between language and dialect. None<strong>the</strong>less,provid<strong>in</strong>g people with additional l<strong>in</strong>guistic flexibility would seem aneasy matter to justify always provid<strong>in</strong>g, of course, that addition doesnot become replacement for those who value <strong>the</strong> former but do not want<strong>the</strong> latter. In terms of group identity ma<strong>in</strong>tenance, <strong>the</strong>re are compell<strong>in</strong>greasons for <strong>the</strong> persistence of varieties lack<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> social prestige. Thesecan fuel a rejection of attempted language or dialect shift (at an<strong>in</strong>dividual level) or, more likely, a bil<strong>in</strong>gualism or bidialectalism <strong>in</strong>which some variety of broader utility is added to <strong>the</strong> maternal mediumof <strong>home</strong> and hearth.It is quite true that suggest<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> utility of dialect expansion can bevery easily taken as an implicit argument that <strong>the</strong> exist<strong>in</strong>g variety is, <strong>in</strong>fact, flawed. It is a delicate undertak<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>the</strong>n, to effectively promoteaddition ra<strong>the</strong>r than replacement: teachers (and o<strong>the</strong>rs) must obviouslytread very carefully here. But it is an entirely worthwhile objective, andone whose importance is obvious to anyone who understands socialstratification and its l<strong>in</strong>guistic markers. It is also easier, perhaps, than itmight first seem, for <strong>the</strong> sensitive teacher will <strong>in</strong> most cases be met bysensitive children, who are well on <strong>the</strong> way, <strong>the</strong>mselves, to an understand<strong>in</strong>gof <strong>the</strong> work<strong>in</strong>gs of that wider stratified society beyond <strong>the</strong>school gates.Demonstrat<strong>in</strong>g differenceI am about to discuss here <strong>the</strong> important work of William Labov andhis colleagues on BEV, but it is important to realize that, central as it is <strong>in</strong>


114 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong><strong>the</strong> literature, it was not <strong>the</strong> earliest formal demonstration of <strong>the</strong>l<strong>in</strong>guistic validity of that dialect. The work of Lorenzo Dow Turner(1949) has been unjustifiably neglected until relatively recently (see <strong>the</strong>‘biographical dedication’ to Turner <strong>in</strong> Holloway & Vass, 1997; see also hisentry <strong>in</strong> Stammerjohann, 1996), and it is not unfair to suggest that part of<strong>the</strong> reason for this neglect is that Turner was himself a black scholar. Heis now, however, receiv<strong>in</strong>g some greater measure of attention, and his<strong>in</strong>vestigations of <strong>the</strong> Gullah dialect of South Carol<strong>in</strong>a are <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>glyrecognized for <strong>the</strong> pioneer<strong>in</strong>g efforts, <strong>in</strong> both focus and scope, which <strong>the</strong>yso obviously were. Whatever <strong>the</strong> ultimate assessment of <strong>the</strong> ‘Africanness’of BEV may be, Turner’s work on creolization will rema<strong>in</strong> pivotal.Labov was certa<strong>in</strong>ly, however, among <strong>the</strong> earliest scholars to systematicallyrefute <strong>the</strong> ‘deficit’ viewpo<strong>in</strong>t, and his now-classic assault on‘verbal deprivation’ appeared <strong>in</strong> 1969. He illustrates how <strong>in</strong>teractionstypically <strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>g white middle-class <strong>in</strong>terviewers and apprehensiveblack youngsters made ‘defensive, monosyllabic’ responses very predictableand, conversely, how easy it was to dramatically <strong>in</strong>crease <strong>the</strong>amount of speech produced by creat<strong>in</strong>g a more relaxed sett<strong>in</strong>g. Thegeneral suggestion, simply, is that ‘verbal deprivation’ is an artifact of<strong>in</strong>appropriate techniques. Labov also notes <strong>the</strong> important dist<strong>in</strong>ctionbetween <strong>the</strong> comprehension of a statement and its reproduction. Bymeans of a simple experiment, <strong>in</strong> which a child hears a statement and isasked to repeat it, he shows that a black child who hears ‘I asked Alv<strong>in</strong> ifhe knows how to play basketball’ might well repeat it as ‘I ax Alv<strong>in</strong> do heknow how to play basketball’ or perhaps ‘I axt Alv<strong>in</strong> does he know howto play basketball’. While such ‘errors’ are fuel for deficit <strong>the</strong>orists, itbecomes clear that <strong>the</strong>y simply reflect <strong>the</strong> regularities (<strong>in</strong> grammar andpronunciation) of <strong>the</strong> child’s dialect, and are not substandard attempts toimitate <strong>the</strong> patterns of <strong>the</strong> more ‘standard’ variety. With regard to basiccognition and <strong>the</strong> grasp of mean<strong>in</strong>g, it is clear that <strong>the</strong>re is no deficiency:<strong>the</strong> child has understood <strong>the</strong> sentence and has <strong>the</strong>n reproduced it <strong>in</strong> afamiliar form (see also Marwit, 1977; Marwit et al., 1972). The <strong>in</strong>sight herewas streng<strong>the</strong>ned by Baratz (1969), whose study showed that whitechildren make similar alterations between what is heard and what isreplied: given <strong>the</strong> sentence ‘Do Deborah like to play wif <strong>the</strong> girl...?’, mostrepeated it as ‘Does Deborah like to play with <strong>the</strong> girl...?’Labov also questioned <strong>the</strong> basic idea that Bernste<strong>in</strong>’s elaborated codewas <strong>in</strong> fact <strong>the</strong> more desirable of <strong>the</strong> two, not<strong>in</strong>g that <strong>the</strong> most desirablelanguage is often <strong>the</strong> simplest, and that lower-class speech can be moredirect and powerful than <strong>the</strong> hesitant and qualified style of <strong>the</strong> middleclass: often ‘turgid, redundant and empty’ (Labov, 1969: 34). In general


The <strong>Language</strong> Debate 115terms, <strong>the</strong>n, Labov suggested that <strong>the</strong> ‘non-verbality’ of disadvantagedchildren is a myth (see also Keddie, 1973), that it is dangerous to <strong>in</strong>ferunderly<strong>in</strong>g ability from particularities of language usage, and thatarguments for <strong>the</strong> superiority of <strong>the</strong> middle-class elaborated code maybe facile.Labov also turned more directly to <strong>the</strong> central question here: <strong>the</strong><strong>in</strong>ternal adequacy (i.e. <strong>the</strong> ‘logic’) of disadvantaged and nonstandardlanguage. The arguments all revolve around <strong>the</strong> central po<strong>in</strong>t of rulegovernedusage. To show that a dialect is not some <strong>in</strong>accurate anddeficient approximation of ‘correct’ language, it is necessary to demonstratethat it follows rules of its own. Two or three of Labov’s exampleshere will make <strong>the</strong> po<strong>in</strong>t that such regularity is <strong>in</strong>deed a feature of BlackEnglish and, by extension, of all dialects (see also <strong>the</strong> similarlypioneer<strong>in</strong>g work of Shuy, 1970; Wolfram, 1969). References to ‘BlackEnglish’ and its rules should not, <strong>in</strong>cidentally, be taken to mean that <strong>the</strong>variety is some l<strong>in</strong>guistic monolith, spoken by all black people. The<strong>in</strong>vestigations of Labov and most o<strong>the</strong>r American l<strong>in</strong>guists focus upon<strong>in</strong>ner-city urban populations, and <strong>the</strong> l<strong>in</strong>guistic features <strong>the</strong>y report arenot necessarily found <strong>in</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r communities (<strong>in</strong> rural black sett<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>in</strong>Nova Scotia, to cite one context: see Edwards, 1999b). Similarly, <strong>in</strong> herstudy of Barbadians <strong>in</strong> New York, Callender (2005: 17) notes that <strong>the</strong>common use of BEV as a synonym for AAVE (African AmericanVernacular English) neglects o<strong>the</strong>r varieties: thus, ‘black dialects ofEnglish that are not American have been largely unrecognized’. H<strong>in</strong>tonand Pollock (2000) draw particular attention to <strong>the</strong> neglect of regionalvariation <strong>in</strong> BEV, call<strong>in</strong>g explicitly for more study of smaller and ruralcommunities. Of course, <strong>the</strong> essential po<strong>in</strong>ts made by l<strong>in</strong>guistic researchersabout dialect validity rema<strong>in</strong> unaffected.One frequently stigmatized feature of BEV is <strong>the</strong> deletion of <strong>the</strong> copulaverb, <strong>in</strong> sentences like ‘We go<strong>in</strong>’ to <strong>the</strong> store’. In o<strong>the</strong>r <strong>in</strong>stances, however,<strong>the</strong> verb appears: ‘She was go<strong>in</strong>’ with me’, for <strong>in</strong>stance. The regularityhere depends upon tense (present or past) and it maps perfectly onto amore standard template. Thus, where standard English allows verbalcontraction (‘They are go<strong>in</strong>g’ can legitimately become ‘They’re go<strong>in</strong>g’), soBEV allows deletion. And, where standard usage bars contraction (<strong>in</strong> pasttenseusages, for example), so BEV disallows deletion. Different rules, tobe sure, but equally ‘logical’. It is worth po<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g out here that presenttensecopula deletion is hardly unique to BEV. In virtually all varieties ofEnglish it is common to hear constructions like ‘This your car?’ (as apoliceman might ask a double-parked motorist). Such verbal ellipsis alsooccurs <strong>in</strong> ‘headl<strong>in</strong>e’ English (‘Richard Burton dead’) and on signs (‘Exit at


116 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>rear’). Beyond English, too, <strong>the</strong> practice is common. Even <strong>in</strong> Lat<strong>in</strong>, Mount(2006) po<strong>in</strong>ts out, it is quite normal to say ‘Paris Hilton bella’, with animplied but absent ‘est’ between <strong>the</strong> second and third words; his book is<strong>in</strong>structive and enterta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g, even though his description of Ms Hilton isnot universally shared.BEV also changes <strong>the</strong> positive ‘He know someth<strong>in</strong>g’ to <strong>the</strong> negative‘He don’t know noth<strong>in</strong>g’. That is, like many languages around <strong>the</strong> world,it customarily employs <strong>the</strong> double negative so frowned upon by MissFidditch, Mrs Grundy and <strong>the</strong>ir many relatives. Of course, speakers ofstandard English also use double-negative constructions; <strong>the</strong>y are notdeemed ungrammatical, because of <strong>the</strong> clue found <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> stress. Thus, itis perfectly acceptable to say ‘He does not know noth<strong>in</strong>g’ mean<strong>in</strong>g tha<strong>the</strong> does, <strong>in</strong> fact, know someth<strong>in</strong>g. And exactly <strong>the</strong> same sort of emphasis isemployed by <strong>the</strong> black speaker who says ‘He don’t know noth<strong>in</strong>g’.Emphasis is thus used by all speakers when a double negative is<strong>in</strong>tended, but black speakers may use <strong>the</strong> unstressed double negative <strong>in</strong>contexts <strong>in</strong> which o<strong>the</strong>rs may use <strong>the</strong> s<strong>in</strong>gle negative.Yet ano<strong>the</strong>r regular feature of BEV is <strong>the</strong> omission of <strong>the</strong> possessive ‘s’,giv<strong>in</strong>g rise to sentences like ‘This Jane house’. Here, <strong>the</strong> important po<strong>in</strong>tis that no ambiguity is <strong>in</strong>troduced; where it might be possible does ‘<strong>the</strong>man teacher’ mean <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>structor who has a male <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> class, or <strong>the</strong><strong>in</strong>structor himself? matters are resolved with emphasis and contextualcues (Torrey, 1973).There are also pronunciation differences, of course. Some of <strong>the</strong> morecommon variations found <strong>in</strong> BEV <strong>in</strong>clude ‘th’ becom<strong>in</strong>g ‘d’ (‘<strong>the</strong>y’becomes ‘dey’), or ‘f’ (‘with’ becomes ‘wif’) or ‘t’ (‘someth<strong>in</strong>g’ becomes‘somet<strong>in</strong>g’). It is <strong>in</strong>structive to recall that <strong>the</strong>se forms are not unique toBEV (‘th’ becom<strong>in</strong>g ‘d’ or ‘t’, for example, is common <strong>in</strong> work<strong>in</strong>g-classDubl<strong>in</strong> English; ‘wif’ is common <strong>in</strong> parts of Cardiff; and so on). As with<strong>the</strong> more important grammatical features, it is <strong>the</strong> regularity with which<strong>the</strong>se pronunciation variants occur that is germane here (see alsoWolfram, 1973).The implications of <strong>the</strong>se f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>gs are obvious. BEV is a valid variety.It is not substandard, although we may legitimately term it nonstandard,where that label is clearly understood to be a simple and non-pejorativedescription of social fact. Black children and o<strong>the</strong>r speakers of nonstandardvarieties are not verbally deficient. The aims and approaches ofmost programs of compensatory <strong>in</strong>tervention are misguided. BEV madea useful test-case, not only because it diverges from standard forms moremarkedly than do many o<strong>the</strong>r dialects, but also because it was for so longconsidered to be substandard and illogical English (see <strong>the</strong> very useful


The <strong>Language</strong> Debate 117overview by Smi<strong>the</strong>rman-Donaldson, 1988). And this consideration, asmy earlier reference to Foster (1997) makes clear, is <strong>in</strong>extricably<strong>in</strong>tertw<strong>in</strong>ed with longstand<strong>in</strong>g prejudice aga<strong>in</strong>st black people. It is worthmention<strong>in</strong>g at this po<strong>in</strong>t that many features of BEV dialects areencountered well beyond <strong>the</strong> black community. Roy Wilk<strong>in</strong>s, <strong>the</strong>executive director of <strong>the</strong> NAACP (and editor of The Crisis, <strong>the</strong> magaz<strong>in</strong>efounded <strong>in</strong> 1910 by William Du Bois), made <strong>the</strong> po<strong>in</strong>t <strong>in</strong> 1971: BEV,he said, is ‘more regional than racial... more sou<strong>the</strong>rn than Negro... [it] isbasically <strong>the</strong> same slovenly English spoken by <strong>the</strong> south’s undereducatedpoor white population’ (Wilk<strong>in</strong>s, 1971: 78). The po<strong>in</strong>t wasconfirmed by <strong>the</strong> black academics <strong>in</strong>terviewed later by Speicher andMcMahon (1992). Regrettably, it is also worth mention<strong>in</strong>g that, likeWilk<strong>in</strong>s, <strong>the</strong>y also tended see BEV as a restricted approximation to‘proper’ English; only a few considered it ‘a full l<strong>in</strong>guistic system’(Speicher & McMahon, 1992: 391; see also Pederson, cited <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Globe &Mail, 1997). We shall see fur<strong>the</strong>r evidence of this with<strong>in</strong>-communitydisda<strong>in</strong> for <strong>the</strong> vernacular when we turn to <strong>the</strong> discussion of ‘Ebonics’.The demonstration that Black English is a fully formed medium makesa very strong case aga<strong>in</strong>st l<strong>in</strong>guistic deficiency <strong>the</strong>ories <strong>in</strong> general. Thestudies undertaken by Labov and his American colleagues naturallyspawned many o<strong>the</strong>rs, and it is fair to say that, <strong>in</strong> all <strong>in</strong>stances where<strong>in</strong>vestigations have been l<strong>in</strong>guistically respectable, <strong>the</strong> falsity of <strong>the</strong>‘deficit’ view of nonstandard speech has been exposed. Where anonstandard variety differs widely from standard forms (as with somevarieties of West Indian English, for <strong>in</strong>stance), <strong>the</strong>n it approaches <strong>the</strong>status of a separate language, <strong>in</strong> which case <strong>the</strong>re is little difficulty <strong>in</strong>view<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> system as merely different. 5 If, on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r hand, a dialect isnot hugely variant from <strong>the</strong> standard, <strong>the</strong>n it follows that most of it isstandard. The ‘gears and axles of English grammatical mach<strong>in</strong>ery areavailable to speakers of all dialects’, as Labov (1976: 64) put it. His twovolumeoverview (Labov, 1994) provides an admirable summary of workon language variation and change, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g buttress<strong>in</strong>g replications ofsome of <strong>the</strong> early studies that I have reported here.The summary position, <strong>the</strong>n, is this: any deficit view of l<strong>in</strong>guisticbehavior is <strong>in</strong>correct: no language, or language variety, has been shownto be more accurate, logical or capable of expression than ano<strong>the</strong>r.Fur<strong>the</strong>r, it is wrong to claim that some variations constra<strong>in</strong> basic<strong>in</strong>tellectual or cognitive function<strong>in</strong>g. Ra<strong>the</strong>r, different language groupsand sub-groups develop speech patterns that differ <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir modes ofexpression, vocabulary and pronunciation. (There is also <strong>the</strong> matter ofdifferent groups assign<strong>in</strong>g different functions to language, someth<strong>in</strong>g that


118 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>Bernste<strong>in</strong> latterly claimed his work demonstrated; see above. There are<strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g questions to be asked here, but none deals with <strong>in</strong>herentl<strong>in</strong>guistic deficiency.) There is, <strong>the</strong>n, a certa<strong>in</strong> logic to Houston’s (1970)assertion that <strong>the</strong> language of disadvantaged children a representation,like all varieties, of particular cultures and environments should be leftalone and not changed <strong>in</strong> any way. There rema<strong>in</strong>s, however, <strong>the</strong> questionof social liability. In effect, <strong>the</strong> rejection of deficit <strong>in</strong>terpretations oflanguage is a sort of ground-clear<strong>in</strong>g: what, if anyth<strong>in</strong>g, ought to be doneabout disadvantaged speech rema<strong>in</strong>s an open matter.The Views of TeachersThe classroom represents <strong>the</strong> s<strong>in</strong>gle most important po<strong>in</strong>t of contactbetween social dialects; it is where nonstandard speakers first becomeconscious of <strong>the</strong>ir own speech patterns, and where <strong>the</strong> regulations andimpositions of <strong>the</strong> larger society first make <strong>the</strong>mselves felt. Consequently,it is appropriate here to touch briefly upon teachers’ attitudes. At ageneral level, it is clear that, like o<strong>the</strong>rs, many teachers have implicit‘deficit’ op<strong>in</strong>ions about disadvantage, believ<strong>in</strong>g that <strong>in</strong>adequate environmentsstunt cognitive capacity. Such op<strong>in</strong>ions <strong>the</strong>n contribute to whatRist (1970) famously referred to as a circular and self-fulfill<strong>in</strong>g prophecy:teachers expect certa<strong>in</strong> children to do poorly at school; <strong>the</strong>y treat <strong>the</strong>m <strong>in</strong>certa<strong>in</strong> ways; <strong>the</strong> children respond <strong>in</strong> certa<strong>in</strong> ways; and <strong>in</strong>itial expectationsare confirmed. Rosenthal and Jacobson (1968) had earlier demonstratedhow easy it is to experimentally manipulate expectations, andFuchs (1973) showed how such ‘manipulations’ occur naturally: newteachers are ‘socialized’ by <strong>the</strong> attitudes and assumptions of thosealready <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> classroom. In such a manner, disadvantage is perpetuated;see also my remarks <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>troduction, and <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> previous chapter.When we turn, more specifically, to consideration of nonstandardlanguage, two <strong>in</strong>terrelated features present <strong>the</strong>mselves: teachers’ attitudestowards nonstandard speech per se, and attitudes towardsdisadvantage that are evoked by nonstandard speech. General research<strong>in</strong> accent and dialect evaluation reveals that speech particularitiestypically act as triggers for wider social stereotypes, but it is clear that acircularity is established whereby <strong>the</strong> presence of such stereotypes colorssubsequent assessments of accent and dialect variation; and so on. In anyevent, it is easy to demonstrate that teachers’ views of disadvantagedspeech are just as likely as those of less enlightened observers to employsuch deficit adjectives as ‘wrong’, ‘bad’, ‘careless’, ‘sloppy’, ‘slovenly’ and‘vulgar’ (Trudgill, 1975: 63). Teachers have all too frequently assumed


The <strong>Language</strong> Debate 119that nonstandard dialects are equivalent to ‘restricted’ codes, and <strong>the</strong>research reported by Shafer and Shafer (1975) and Thomson (1977)reveals that <strong>the</strong>se assumptions are made <strong>in</strong> many geographic sett<strong>in</strong>gs: <strong>the</strong>phenomena under discussion here are not limited to Brita<strong>in</strong> and America,nor, <strong>in</strong>deed, to anglophone contexts. Trudgill (1975) has argued that <strong>the</strong><strong>in</strong>fluence of Bernste<strong>in</strong> was unfortunate s<strong>in</strong>ce, at a time when moreenlightened views about speech and language variants had begun tocirculate, <strong>the</strong> notoriety of ‘public’ and ‘restricted’ codes re<strong>in</strong>forcedlongstand<strong>in</strong>g prejudices, and seemed to grant <strong>the</strong>m some <strong>in</strong>tellectualrespectability. Bernste<strong>in</strong>’s views so easily assimilated by those hold<strong>in</strong>gtraditional attitudes towards ‘correctness’ rema<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong> circulation; <strong>the</strong>ysurfaced, for <strong>in</strong>stance, <strong>in</strong> John Honey’s notorious arguments, first made <strong>in</strong>a pamphlet published by <strong>the</strong> National Council for Educational Standards(1983a), about <strong>the</strong> ‘language trap’ allegedly created by <strong>the</strong> noxious and<strong>in</strong>accurate <strong>the</strong>ories of l<strong>in</strong>guists (see Chapter 7). 6There is quite a large literature reveal<strong>in</strong>g teachers’ negative perceptionsof disadvantaged speech varieties. The conclusions drawn <strong>in</strong> aQuébec study summarize th<strong>in</strong>gs nicely: ‘a lower-class youngster’s styleof speech may mark or caricature him and thus adversely affect hisopportunities <strong>in</strong> various situations, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> school environment’(Frender et al., 1970: 305). In similar work, Seligman et al. (1972: 141)found speech style to be ‘an important cue to <strong>the</strong> teachers <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>irevaluations of students. Even when comb<strong>in</strong>ed with o<strong>the</strong>r cues, its effectdid not dim<strong>in</strong>ish’. Choy and Dodd (1976) found that teachers <strong>in</strong> Hawaiiconsistently favored standard-dialect speakers <strong>in</strong> primary school; <strong>the</strong>ywere described as higher achievers, more confident and less ‘disruptive’<strong>in</strong> class. The authors were also able to show how absurdly wide-rang<strong>in</strong>gsuch evaluations can be: nonstandard speakers were thought less likely,for example, to have happy marriages. Granger et al. (1977: 795) found a‘dist<strong>in</strong>ct social class and racial bias’ <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir studies of teachers’ reactionsto BEV, suggest<strong>in</strong>g that ‘<strong>the</strong> teachers were attend<strong>in</strong>g less to what a childsaid than to how he said it’. The extensive program of researchsummarized <strong>in</strong> Williams (1976; see also Chapter 8) found that a recurr<strong>in</strong>gfactor <strong>in</strong> studies of teachers’ evaluations was what he labelled ‘ethnicity/nonstandardness’ a composite description of a number of discretesemantic-differential scales. Disadvantaged children were generally seenas be<strong>in</strong>g more ‘ethnic’ or more ‘nonstandard’ than o<strong>the</strong>rs, suggest<strong>in</strong>g astrong connection <strong>in</strong> teachers’ m<strong>in</strong>ds between cognitive ability and likelyacademic success, on <strong>the</strong> one hand, and membership <strong>in</strong> certa<strong>in</strong> groups,on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r. It is also significant that Williams and his associates foundthat such perceptions (of black, white and Mexican American children


120 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>liv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> Texas) were held by both black and white teachers. This suggeststhat simply employ<strong>in</strong>g more teachers from traditionally disadvantagedgroups may not lighten <strong>the</strong> evaluative load borne by children at school.In fact, it is very likely that, whatever <strong>the</strong>ir personal backgrounds,teachers become socialized <strong>in</strong>to middle-class ways. 7The overall implication here is clear. Like everyone else, teachersma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong> stereotyped and often prejudicial views of certa<strong>in</strong> languagevarieties and <strong>the</strong>ir speakers. In one sense, <strong>the</strong>n, <strong>the</strong> data document<strong>in</strong>g<strong>the</strong>ir attitudes merely reflect a specific aspect of a general phenomenon.But teachers’ views are, of course, ra<strong>the</strong>r special because of <strong>the</strong> position<strong>the</strong>y occupy <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> lives of disadvantaged children. Beyond <strong>the</strong>demonstration (<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> early studies mentioned above, and <strong>in</strong> manyo<strong>the</strong>rs) that speech patterns can <strong>in</strong>fluence teachers’ evaluations ofchildren, <strong>the</strong>re is also <strong>the</strong> suggestion that <strong>the</strong> attitudes beh<strong>in</strong>d suchassessments may affect children’s educational progress. This is whatlends a special poignancy to <strong>the</strong> discussion an extension of which willbe found <strong>in</strong> Chapter 8.Read<strong>in</strong>g MattersThe discussion so far has argued for <strong>the</strong> l<strong>in</strong>guistic validity of alldialects and, as a consequence, for <strong>the</strong>ir acceptance <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> classroom andelsewhere. This says noth<strong>in</strong>g, however, about <strong>the</strong> practical utility ofexpand<strong>in</strong>g repertoires, about add<strong>in</strong>g some facility <strong>in</strong> standard forms tononstandard maternal varieties. There are, after all, social conventionsthat are not likely to change <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> near future, and <strong>the</strong>se have <strong>the</strong> greatand very important power of translat<strong>in</strong>g difference <strong>in</strong>to deficit socialdeficit only, perhaps, and deficit based upon mis<strong>in</strong>formation andprejudice, but deficit none<strong>the</strong>less. A social convention that is easier todefend, hav<strong>in</strong>g its ground <strong>in</strong> practicality, <strong>in</strong>volves <strong>the</strong> language ofread<strong>in</strong>g and writ<strong>in</strong>g. Here, a good case can obviously be made for acommon standard. It is a fair objection that this may favor those whoseoral fluency is <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> standard dialect, but for all children evenstandard-speak<strong>in</strong>g children formal learn<strong>in</strong>g is required to move fromspoken language to pr<strong>in</strong>t. The evidence suggests that <strong>the</strong> effort <strong>in</strong>volvedhere is not, <strong>in</strong> fact, appreciably more for nonstandard-dialect speakers.In this connection and rem<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g us of po<strong>in</strong>ts made earlier <strong>in</strong> thischapter Torrey (1973: 68) noted that:<strong>the</strong> difference <strong>in</strong> phonology between Standard English and BlackEnglish is not directly relevant to read<strong>in</strong>g. All children who learn toread English have to break a fairly complex code of sound-spell<strong>in</strong>g


The <strong>Language</strong> Debate 121relationships. The fact that <strong>the</strong> correspondences are different forspeakers of Afro-American does not <strong>in</strong> itself prove that <strong>the</strong>y are moredifficult than for standard speakers.This seems plausible, but as Harber and Bryen (1976) soon added, <strong>the</strong>possibility of dialect <strong>in</strong>terference <strong>in</strong> read<strong>in</strong>g cannot be completely ruledout. (Trudgill [1979: 17] has noted that accent differences might bethought to be more troublesome <strong>in</strong> many cases than dialect variations,but also that teachers report that this is not generally so: ‘English spell<strong>in</strong>gis probably sufficiently distant from pronunciation not to favor oneaccent over any o<strong>the</strong>r: all speakers are at an equal disadvantage’.) Thisexpla<strong>in</strong>s why <strong>the</strong>re have been periodic attempts to provide read<strong>in</strong>gmaterials <strong>in</strong> nonstandard dialects.Baratz’s view (1970) is representative of early th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g here. Propos<strong>in</strong>gthat black children be given books written <strong>in</strong> BEV, she argued thatread<strong>in</strong>g competence <strong>in</strong> one’s own dialect is a necessary prerequisite forstandard-dialect read<strong>in</strong>g ability. To fur<strong>the</strong>r facilitate <strong>the</strong> atta<strong>in</strong>ment of thisend, Baratz also called for ‘transition texts’ as a halfway-stop betweenBEV and standard-English books (see also Baratz, 1972; Baratz & Shuy,1969; Stewart, 1972). This perspective has been broadened s<strong>in</strong>ce Baratz’sobservations. Thus, Rickford (2005) discusses <strong>the</strong> use of ‘bridg<strong>in</strong>g’materials for black children, cit<strong>in</strong>g a large-scale study by Simpk<strong>in</strong>s andSimpk<strong>in</strong>s (1981; see also Simpk<strong>in</strong>s et al., 1977). About 80% of some 500secondary-school students were given materials thatbegan with narratives and exercises written <strong>in</strong> Ebonics [see below].They <strong>the</strong>n went through a transitional series of readers written <strong>in</strong> avariety <strong>in</strong>termediate between Ebonics and English [sic], and endedwith a f<strong>in</strong>al series written entirely <strong>in</strong> Standard English. (Rickford,2005: 31)The o<strong>the</strong>r 20% constituted a control group that used traditional read<strong>in</strong>gbooks. After four months, <strong>the</strong> researchers report that this control groupshowed only 1.6 months of ‘read<strong>in</strong>g ga<strong>in</strong>’. By contrast, those exposed to<strong>the</strong> bridg<strong>in</strong>g readers showed 6.2 months of such advance. These are quitedramatic f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>gs. Yet Rickford po<strong>in</strong>ts out that <strong>the</strong> negative publicity thatwas to prove so important 15 years later <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Oakland Ebonics debatemade its mark here, too to such an extent that <strong>the</strong> publisher of <strong>the</strong>‘transitional’ readers halted <strong>the</strong>ir production. And, as <strong>in</strong> that latercontroversy, with<strong>in</strong>-group criticism was not far to seek. John McWhorter(1997a, 1997b), for example, a well-known black <strong>in</strong>tellectual, argued <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>wake of <strong>the</strong> Oakland brouhaha that schoolbooks <strong>in</strong> BEV had no effect


122 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>upon <strong>the</strong> development of read<strong>in</strong>g skills. (I shall pay closer attention to <strong>the</strong>Ebonics debate <strong>in</strong> a later chapter.) As Rickford notes, however, <strong>the</strong> studiesto which McWhorter referred were of <strong>the</strong> quick-and-dirty variety, lack<strong>in</strong>gany ‘time depth’ (see also <strong>the</strong> earlier observations on this po<strong>in</strong>t by Simons& Johnson, 1974). Rickford and Rickford (2005) thus call for renewedattention to bridg<strong>in</strong>g materials, and outl<strong>in</strong>e <strong>the</strong> requirements of futureresearch <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> area.Whatever <strong>the</strong> f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>gs of educational researchers are, or will be, <strong>the</strong>reis considerable evidence from a number of sett<strong>in</strong>gs show<strong>in</strong>g that manyparents do not want to see <strong>the</strong>ir nonstandard language variety <strong>in</strong>schoolbooks. Their attitudes may be regrettable (reflect<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>accurateassessments of l<strong>in</strong>guistic <strong>in</strong>feriority), or <strong>the</strong>y may be less than fully<strong>in</strong>formed (neglect<strong>in</strong>g, for <strong>in</strong>stance, <strong>the</strong> possibility of a bidialectalism thatextends to read<strong>in</strong>g), or <strong>the</strong>y may be ‘practical’, at least <strong>in</strong> some traditional‘time-on-task’ perspective (that is, parents may see <strong>the</strong> use of such booksas anti<strong>the</strong>tical to <strong>the</strong>ir views of <strong>the</strong> school as an agent of socialadvancement, and likely to delay or impair standard-language abilities).One th<strong>in</strong>g is certa<strong>in</strong>, however: parental attitudes cannot be ignored.Ano<strong>the</strong>r is that <strong>the</strong>ir views may be somewhat more subtle than I havejust implied. Cov<strong>in</strong>gton (1976) po<strong>in</strong>ted out, for <strong>in</strong>stance, that blackparents <strong>in</strong> Wash<strong>in</strong>gton who wanted tolerance of <strong>the</strong>ir children’s BEV <strong>in</strong><strong>the</strong> classroom were, at <strong>the</strong> same time, strongly opposed to textbookswritten <strong>in</strong> that variety; similar op<strong>in</strong>ions have been reported by Harberand Bryen (1976) and Venezky (1970).Beyond <strong>the</strong> social-political objections, criticisms of such educational<strong>in</strong>itiatives <strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>g nonstandard textbooks have built upon Torrey’spo<strong>in</strong>t of view (above), argu<strong>in</strong>g that it may simply be unnecessary because while we obviously do not know everyth<strong>in</strong>g about potential crossdialectalproblems it seems likely that any such <strong>in</strong>terference would bem<strong>in</strong>imal. Trudgill (1975) echoed Torrey <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> British context and, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>American one, Labov (1976: 241) fur<strong>the</strong>r re<strong>in</strong>forced <strong>the</strong> po<strong>in</strong>t:Some writers seem to believe that <strong>the</strong> major problem caus<strong>in</strong>g read<strong>in</strong>gfailure is structural <strong>in</strong>terference between <strong>the</strong>se two forms of English[BEV and standard]. Our research po<strong>in</strong>ts <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> opposite direction...The number of structures unique to BEV are [sic] small, and it seemsunlikely that <strong>the</strong>y could be responsible for <strong>the</strong> disastrous record ofread<strong>in</strong>g failure <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>ner city schools.Besides <strong>the</strong> work already cited, a few o<strong>the</strong>r experimental studies havealso suggested that read<strong>in</strong>g materials <strong>in</strong> BEV might be useful, although<strong>the</strong> f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>gs here are ra<strong>the</strong>r <strong>in</strong>consistent (see Somervill, 1974, 1975;


The <strong>Language</strong> Debate 123Somervill & Jacobs, 1972; Thurmond, 1977). Venezky (1970, 1981), a wellknownread<strong>in</strong>g specialist, summarized <strong>the</strong> matter by not<strong>in</strong>g that, if itcould reliably be shown that provision of nonstandard read<strong>in</strong>g materialswould assist <strong>in</strong> skill development, <strong>the</strong>re could be no reasonable objection.In <strong>the</strong> absence of such a demonstration, however, <strong>the</strong> time and expense<strong>in</strong>volved <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> production of <strong>the</strong>se materials seem <strong>in</strong>appropriate. This isquite apart from <strong>the</strong> social objections already touched upon, as well asfrom important questions that would <strong>in</strong>evitably arise about <strong>the</strong> numberof varieties to be represented <strong>in</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>t, <strong>the</strong> best methods of captur<strong>in</strong>gnonstandard pronunciation on <strong>the</strong> page, <strong>the</strong> tim<strong>in</strong>g of <strong>the</strong> transition tostandard-dialect texts, and so on.A variant approach here has argued for <strong>the</strong> elim<strong>in</strong>ation of po<strong>in</strong>ts ofdialect <strong>in</strong>terference from read<strong>in</strong>g texts; some sort of ‘neutral’ text wasapparently envisaged. This attracts <strong>the</strong> same general criticisms alreadynoted, but it does alert us to an attitude that has been steadily grow<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> too ‘politically correct’ a manner, however, some might say s<strong>in</strong>ceBaratz, Torrey and Labov first presented <strong>the</strong>ir research results. It issimply that <strong>the</strong> deletion of certa<strong>in</strong> features that are strongly andspecifically associated with given social groups might be useful: more‘culture-free’ or ‘culture-fair’ books, <strong>in</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r words. Such a practicecould lead to stories stripped of all color and style, could be pressed <strong>in</strong>to<strong>the</strong> service of retroactive ‘cleans<strong>in</strong>g’, could be bowdlerization but itcould also produce more broadly useful materials (see Vick, 1974). It hasalready been used extensively, particularly with regard to genderdescriptions and stereotypes. Of course, this is not <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> service ofnonstandard textbooks.The most reasonable approach, <strong>in</strong> fact, tends to be almost a nonapproach.Texts cont<strong>in</strong>ue to be written <strong>in</strong> more or less standard dialect,but children are allowed to recite and reproduce mean<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir owndialect (see Simons, 1974; Venezky, 1970), or accent (‘<strong>the</strong>re is no reasonwhy a person cannot learn to read Standard English texts quite well <strong>in</strong> anonstandard pronunciation’: Labov, 1972: 289). This po<strong>in</strong>t of view buildsupon <strong>the</strong> experimental evidence concern<strong>in</strong>g sentence repetition (as notedabove): that is, children are likely to repeat material, standard ornonstandard, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir maternal dialect. The assumption is that <strong>the</strong>nonstandard-dialect-speak<strong>in</strong>g child’s decod<strong>in</strong>g abilities (i.e. extract<strong>in</strong>g<strong>the</strong> mean<strong>in</strong>g from pr<strong>in</strong>t on <strong>the</strong> page) will lead to encod<strong>in</strong>g what hasbeen read (e.g. read<strong>in</strong>g aloud) <strong>in</strong> a nonstandard format.It is also consistent with a difference view of nonstandard speech andlanguage, of course. As we have <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>gly come to realize <strong>the</strong> validityand <strong>the</strong> completeness of nonstandard dialects, so it follows that <strong>the</strong>re is


124 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>less and less to ‘do’ for <strong>the</strong> disadvantaged child <strong>in</strong> terms of curriculumalteration. Ra<strong>the</strong>r, <strong>the</strong> required changes are more attitud<strong>in</strong>al <strong>in</strong> nature,rest<strong>in</strong>g upon more accurate psychological, social and l<strong>in</strong>guistic understand<strong>in</strong>g.Just as with oral language, much depends here upon <strong>the</strong>knowledge and <strong>the</strong> sensitivity of teachers; and, as with speech, it isassumed that all children can develop standard-dialect read<strong>in</strong>g skills.Given <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>g comprehension, <strong>the</strong>re is every <strong>in</strong>dication that childrenwill also have <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>g choice on <strong>the</strong> ‘reproduction’ side of <strong>the</strong>equation. There is an abundance of models (both pr<strong>in</strong>ted and spoken)here, rang<strong>in</strong>g from classroom teachers and <strong>the</strong> books <strong>the</strong>y use, to <strong>the</strong>wider world beyond <strong>the</strong> school gates. It is, of course, expected thatchildren will not be left entirely to <strong>the</strong>ir own devices: <strong>the</strong>y are <strong>in</strong> school,after all. Teachers who are, <strong>the</strong>mselves, well-<strong>in</strong>formed can graduallymake clear <strong>the</strong> contexts <strong>in</strong> which standard usage is most appropriate andwhere, <strong>the</strong>refore, its use is likely to be most beneficial. But, as with o<strong>the</strong>rimportant aspects of life, much can be left to <strong>the</strong> evolv<strong>in</strong>g discretion ofthose most directly <strong>in</strong>volved.Some may th<strong>in</strong>k that this ‘approach’ is much too laissez-faire, but weshould bear <strong>in</strong> m<strong>in</strong>d that any more formal or strict approach (even ifstemm<strong>in</strong>g from <strong>the</strong> best of motives) is not likely to work and may, <strong>in</strong> fact,widen <strong>the</strong> gap that already too frequently exists between <strong>the</strong> disadvantagedchild and <strong>the</strong> school. In this regard, Bullock (1975: 143) made asensible recommendation:The teacher’s aim should be to <strong>in</strong>dicate to his [sic] pupils <strong>the</strong> value ofawareness and flexibility, so that <strong>the</strong>y can make <strong>the</strong>ir own decisionsand modify <strong>the</strong>se as <strong>the</strong>ir views alter.A short postscript: beyond possible contributions to skills development,it may be that books written <strong>in</strong> nonstandard varieties have o<strong>the</strong>rvalues. For example, materials produced <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> local vernacular ofBallyfermot, a work<strong>in</strong>g-class suburb of Dubl<strong>in</strong>, were seen to ‘legitimize’that variety (Murphy, 1975) and books <strong>in</strong> BEV have, it is argued,re<strong>in</strong>forced <strong>the</strong> self-esteem of <strong>the</strong>ir readers (Edwards, 1989).Notes1. Miss Fidditch and Mrs Grundy may be candidates for <strong>the</strong> Freudian couch. Itis now ‘pretty generally recognized by psycho-analysts’, observed Flugel(1934: 205), ‘that anal factors often play a part <strong>in</strong> our attitude towardsl<strong>in</strong>guistic correctness’. Anal repression may lead to ‘disagreeable feel<strong>in</strong>gs’ <strong>in</strong>both speaker and listener: <strong>the</strong> former, guilty of a lapse of l<strong>in</strong>guisticcorrectness; <strong>the</strong> latter, forced to hear speech ‘murdered’ by clums<strong>in</strong>ess. ‘The


The <strong>Language</strong> Debate 125scholarly schoolmaster who is ‘‘disgusted’’ by <strong>the</strong> ‘‘howlers’’ of... his pupilsaffords one strik<strong>in</strong>g example of this k<strong>in</strong>d’ (p. 206).Flugel’s ma<strong>in</strong> authority here is Ernest Jones, <strong>the</strong> pioneer of psychoanalysis<strong>in</strong> Brita<strong>in</strong>, and Freud’s biographer (see Jones, 1918).2. Bernste<strong>in</strong> himself (1971, 1972a) analyzed constructed data (see also Rosen,1972, for a criticism), and <strong>the</strong> practice was more common than might beimag<strong>in</strong>ed, especially among ‘deficit’ <strong>the</strong>orists. Nowadays, <strong>the</strong> enormousbenefits aris<strong>in</strong>g from construct<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> data that are to be <strong>in</strong>terpreted haveproved most appeal<strong>in</strong>g to discourse analysts.3. Lady Plowden died <strong>in</strong> 2000, aged 90, and Corbett’s obituary <strong>in</strong> The Guardian(3 October) made a po<strong>in</strong>t of mention<strong>in</strong>g that her life of voluntary serviceconstituted one of <strong>the</strong> last examples of <strong>the</strong> ‘great and <strong>the</strong> good’ caste at work<strong>in</strong> British public life, <strong>in</strong> which leadership roles on national bodies andcommissions were traditionally filled by members of that caste. So, perhaps ah<strong>in</strong>t of Lady Bountiful ‘as we do ourselves’ was to be expected. ThePlowden Report, and ‘Plowdenism’, were heavily criticised from all sides, but itis <strong>in</strong>structive to remember <strong>the</strong> arguments made for parental <strong>in</strong>volvement, forsensitive pre-school provision, for greater and more comprehensive attentionto <strong>the</strong> very real problems of poor children at <strong>home</strong> and at school. For a usefulretrospective, see Halsey and Sylva (1987).4. Cross-cultural sensitivity rema<strong>in</strong>s key, however. See<strong>in</strong>g how well disadvantagedchildren do on essentially middle-class tasks can be very useful, forexample provided <strong>the</strong> aim is to get some measure of likely problems <strong>in</strong>classrooms where such tasks are commonly encountered, and not to assessbasic ‘deficiency’. Similarly, while it is not unreasonable to probe nonstandard-dialect-speak<strong>in</strong>gchildren for <strong>the</strong>ir knowledge and use of standardforms, it is absurd to use <strong>the</strong> f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>gs as <strong>in</strong>dications of maternal-varietydevelopment (see Baratz, 1969; Edwards, 1977a, 1977b).5. One doesn’t have to go to <strong>the</strong> Caribbean, however. In 1983, BBC televisionbroadcast a series called Auf Wiedersehen, Pet, about Geordie brickies who goto work <strong>in</strong> Germany. The English newspapers carried stories from viewerswho were appreciative, but who asked for subtitles. (The show made a briefreappearance at Christmas 2004.)6. The Council has been described as a ‘right-w<strong>in</strong>g pressure group’ (Crowley,1989).7. It would also be naïve to assume that those who have achieved positions ofsocial security will necessarily be sympa<strong>the</strong>tic to those <strong>the</strong>y have left beh<strong>in</strong>d.The person who has climbed <strong>the</strong> ladder of success may be more likely to stepon <strong>the</strong> f<strong>in</strong>gers of those follow<strong>in</strong>g than to help <strong>the</strong>m for to br<strong>in</strong>g o<strong>the</strong>rs ‘up’ isto dilute <strong>the</strong> s<strong>in</strong>gularity of one’s own atta<strong>in</strong>ments. A more elegant expressionof <strong>the</strong> same idea is found <strong>in</strong> Julius Caesar (II.i.2227), when Brutus observesThat lowl<strong>in</strong>ess is young ambition’s ladder,Whereto <strong>the</strong> climber-upward turns his face;But when he once atta<strong>in</strong>s <strong>the</strong> upmost round,He <strong>the</strong>n unto <strong>the</strong> ladder turns his back,Looks <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> clouds, scorn<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> base degreesBy which he did ascend.


Chapter 7The Persistence of L<strong>in</strong>guistic DeficitTheoretical ExtensionsMost socially stratified societies have had ra<strong>the</strong>r firm ideas about‘correct’ and ‘<strong>in</strong>correct’ language, and nowhere have <strong>the</strong>se ideas beenmore explicit than <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> classroom, traditionally a forceful supporter of‘proper’ language. The most important corollary was <strong>the</strong> school’s role strongly articulated with<strong>in</strong> its walls, and strongly if sometimes implicitlyre<strong>in</strong>forced from without <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> eradication of ‘substandard’ varieties. Inthis, <strong>the</strong> school has always had considerable power: it is a highly visible<strong>in</strong>stitution, whose forms and formalities typically adhere to prevail<strong>in</strong>gmiddle-class po<strong>in</strong>ts of view; it provides <strong>the</strong> first susta<strong>in</strong>ed break from <strong>the</strong><strong>home</strong> environment <strong>in</strong> which l<strong>in</strong>guistic contact across groups has beenm<strong>in</strong>imal; it receives children at a young age and extends its <strong>in</strong>fluenceover <strong>the</strong>m for a long time. For children speak<strong>in</strong>g a standard variety,<strong>the</strong> <strong>home</strong>-school l<strong>in</strong>k is close, and <strong>the</strong> classroom may essentially be aformalized version of <strong>the</strong> <strong>home</strong>. For disadvantaged children, however,<strong>the</strong>re often exists a marked <strong>home</strong>-school discont<strong>in</strong>uity, aris<strong>in</strong>g from thatcontact which is itself central to <strong>the</strong> very idea of disadvantage.As I noted earlier, <strong>the</strong>re has been some question as to whe<strong>the</strong>r or not<strong>the</strong> school really is a middle-class sett<strong>in</strong>g; some have claimed that it isactually more cont<strong>in</strong>uous with a work<strong>in</strong>g-class environment than o<strong>the</strong>rs(myself <strong>in</strong>cluded) have asserted. If this were so, it might imply lesssubstance to <strong>the</strong> charge that disadvantage as a product of socialcomparison is highlighted and susta<strong>in</strong>ed at school. In <strong>the</strong> collectionedited by Feagans and Farran (1982), for <strong>in</strong>stance, several authors took<strong>the</strong> l<strong>in</strong>e that schools do not re<strong>in</strong>force middle-class <strong>home</strong> practices; <strong>the</strong>yalso po<strong>in</strong>ted out that learn<strong>in</strong>g at school is passive, with teachers’ talkdom<strong>in</strong>at<strong>in</strong>g, that classrooms stress rigidity, bureaucracy and order, andthat schools are, <strong>in</strong> general, not unlike work<strong>in</strong>g-class <strong>home</strong>s (where,readers will recall, parents are allegedly more authoritarian, more<strong>in</strong>terested <strong>in</strong> order than <strong>in</strong> curiosity, more likely to direct than to consult,and so on). If it were true, however, that lower-class <strong>home</strong>s do stifle<strong>in</strong>tellectual quest<strong>in</strong>g under authoritarian rigidity a dubious andunnuanced contention it is also true that schools impose order126


The Persistence of L<strong>in</strong>guistic Deficit 127precisely so as to facilitate that same enterprise: an imposition of <strong>the</strong>m<strong>in</strong>imal order, that is to say, required for educational development tooccur. (I don’t deny, of course, <strong>the</strong> existence of some modern <strong>in</strong>carnationsof Do<strong>the</strong>boys Hall nor, more realistically, do I deny that many classroomsare not <strong>in</strong> practice what <strong>the</strong>y should be <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory.) In fact, where <strong>the</strong><strong>home</strong>-school discont<strong>in</strong>uity fuell<strong>in</strong>g disadvantage is not as serious as isoften imag<strong>in</strong>ed, this is probably due more to <strong>the</strong> fact that <strong>the</strong> work<strong>in</strong>gclassfamily is unlike its stereotyped representation <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> literature thanto <strong>the</strong> assumption that schools are closer to that stereotype and moreremoved from middle-class values.In accept<strong>in</strong>g that some speech styles are simply wrong, schools have ofcourse reflected extra-mural deficit views of disadvantage <strong>in</strong> general andof language <strong>in</strong> particular. These views, <strong>in</strong>cidentally, have been remarkablysimilar across social groups, for it is a commonplace and, after amoment’s thought, <strong>the</strong> psychology here is not difficult to comprehend that those with socially stigmatized speech styles often come to accept‘ma<strong>in</strong>stream’ perceptions of <strong>the</strong>ir low status and deficiency. The school’srole <strong>in</strong> l<strong>in</strong>guistic disadvantage has been a circularly re<strong>in</strong>forc<strong>in</strong>g one:children arrive speak<strong>in</strong>g a variety that is considered deficient; teachers,act<strong>in</strong>g from <strong>the</strong> best of (ill-founded) motives, aim to replace this with astandard variety; <strong>the</strong>y may also make attributions, based upon <strong>the</strong>irperceptions of speech, about <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>telligence, educability and likelyscholastic progress of <strong>the</strong>ir pupils. The vicious circle implicit <strong>in</strong> Rist’s(1970) famous ‘self-fulfill<strong>in</strong>g prophecy’ is completed when children,treated differently because of presumed deficiencies, do <strong>in</strong> fact come toperform less well than o<strong>the</strong>rs.There is little doubt that, <strong>in</strong> many jurisdictions, schools are more tolerantof language variation today than <strong>the</strong>y once were; aga<strong>in</strong>, this is related toattitudes beyond <strong>the</strong> school gates more liberal ones, <strong>in</strong> this case. 1 But‘tolerance’ rarely rests upon whole-hearted acceptance. Contemporaryassessments of ‘social <strong>in</strong>clusion’, of <strong>the</strong> evils of ‘marg<strong>in</strong>alization’ and‘stigmatization’, of <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>equities marked by race and class <strong>the</strong>se, ra<strong>the</strong>rthan more fundamental shifts <strong>in</strong> belief and understand<strong>in</strong>g, may be <strong>the</strong>operative pr<strong>in</strong>ciples at work <strong>in</strong> many <strong>in</strong>stances. I shall suggest below that<strong>the</strong>re has, <strong>in</strong> fact, been little real movement beyond deficit perspectives. 2Beyond <strong>the</strong> classroom, of course, it is clear to anyone with ears to hear (oreyes to read: <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> letters-to-<strong>the</strong>-editor sections of <strong>the</strong> newspaper, for<strong>in</strong>stance) that perceptions of ‘poor’ English have not disappeared.L<strong>in</strong>guistic evidence of <strong>the</strong> Labovian sort does not work very fast or verycompletely on popular stereotypes; and attitudes, by <strong>the</strong>ir psychologicalnature, can be doggedly resistant to unpalatable fact.


128 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>Indeed, even limited ga<strong>in</strong>s with<strong>in</strong> education ought not to be taken forgranted. A recent example of <strong>the</strong> volatility here is found <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> rejectionsof bil<strong>in</strong>gual education programs <strong>in</strong> some parts of America, <strong>the</strong> assertionbe<strong>in</strong>g that bil<strong>in</strong>gual education has gone too far <strong>in</strong> promot<strong>in</strong>g andsusta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g m<strong>in</strong>ority languages, that an undesirable balkanization mustbe resisted and so on. Flores (2005) discusses <strong>the</strong> l<strong>in</strong>ks between suchprograms and l<strong>in</strong>guistic disadvantage for <strong>the</strong> Hispanic children whoconstitute <strong>the</strong> great bulk of <strong>the</strong> bil<strong>in</strong>gual education constituency <strong>in</strong>America. Bedore and Peña (2008), Comm<strong>in</strong>s and Miramontes (1989),Delgado-Gaitan (1992), Gifford and Valdés (2006) and Jiménez (2000,2006) <strong>in</strong>vestigate fur<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> cont<strong>in</strong>u<strong>in</strong>g ‘deficit’ assumptions that aremade about Hispanic children and o<strong>the</strong>rs whose maternal language isnot English by teachers and some researchers. Related events beyond<strong>the</strong> schoolroom <strong>in</strong>clude <strong>the</strong> occasional but recurr<strong>in</strong>g efforts to formallydesignate English as <strong>the</strong> official language of <strong>the</strong> United States, and of <strong>the</strong>success of such efforts at <strong>the</strong> state level. More than half of <strong>the</strong> 50 statesnow have official-English legislation. Several of <strong>the</strong>se, it is true, havedesignated English as co-official with ano<strong>the</strong>r language, as have someAmerican territories; <strong>in</strong> one case <strong>the</strong> Nor<strong>the</strong>rn Marianas tril<strong>in</strong>gualismis official (Chamorro, Carol<strong>in</strong>ian and English).As well as acknowledg<strong>in</strong>g that reasoned academic argument may notalways penetrate as far or as quickly as we would wish, it is clear that <strong>the</strong>‘limited-ga<strong>in</strong>’ argument I have cited above also applies with<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>hallowed groves <strong>the</strong>mselves. The Feagans and Farran (1982) collection,already mentioned, brought toge<strong>the</strong>r some well-known writers, all ofwhom were well aware of <strong>the</strong> latest research bear<strong>in</strong>g upon l<strong>in</strong>guisticdifference-and-deficit matters; well aware, that is, that <strong>the</strong> best psychol<strong>in</strong>guisticop<strong>in</strong>ion of <strong>the</strong> time supported a ‘difference’ po<strong>in</strong>t of view. Yet,<strong>the</strong> editors noted <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> preface that <strong>the</strong> deficit model became untenablenot only because of ‘new perspectives’, but also because <strong>in</strong>terventionsbased upon it did not work very well. The possibility is held out, <strong>in</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rwords, that only strategies were misguided, not underly<strong>in</strong>g assumptions.One of <strong>the</strong> chapter authors (Blank, 1982) considers that both differenceand deficit approaches have difficulties, but fails to make clear that <strong>the</strong>difficulties are not of equal force: <strong>the</strong> l<strong>in</strong>guistic objections to <strong>the</strong>fundamentals of <strong>the</strong> deficit position are overwhelm<strong>in</strong>g, while <strong>the</strong> sortsof ‘difference’ problems she discusses have to do with <strong>the</strong> assessment ofappropriate ranges of skills for different social groups. 3Blank also suggests that deficit <strong>the</strong>orists have typically concerned<strong>the</strong>mselves with semantic issues, difference <strong>the</strong>orists with syntax. Aga<strong>in</strong>,this <strong>in</strong>accurately weakens <strong>the</strong> anti-deficit case, for it implies that <strong>the</strong> model


The Persistence of L<strong>in</strong>guistic Deficit 129might, after all, reta<strong>in</strong> some validity. Tough (1982) argues here for astereotypically ‘deficit’ view of speech patterns <strong>in</strong> work<strong>in</strong>g-class <strong>home</strong>s, anargument she had made earlier (Tough, 1977) and which she cont<strong>in</strong>ued tomake (Tough, 1985). Ano<strong>the</strong>r contributor also muddied <strong>the</strong> picture byclaim<strong>in</strong>g that disadvantaged children do have deficits, which are notl<strong>in</strong>guistic but are ra<strong>the</strong>r deficiencies of knowledge; <strong>the</strong>se lead, <strong>the</strong>n, tosmaller vocabularies (Snow, 1982). While at first blush it would seem thatmatters of vocabulary are matters of language, it is apparent on reflectionthat <strong>the</strong> size and shape of a group’s vocabulary are best understood asproducts of environmental exigency. And this br<strong>in</strong>gs us back to differencera<strong>the</strong>r than deficit. After all, <strong>the</strong>re are many human groups who lack <strong>the</strong>term<strong>in</strong>ology of higher ma<strong>the</strong>matics, who have no word for ‘laser’; andwhat does this prove about any <strong>in</strong>nate cognitive deficiency?Overall, <strong>the</strong> argument that I made <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> second edition of a bookabout language and disadvantage (Edwards, 1989, see also Edwards2006) and complementary suggestions made by Crowley (2003) <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>second edition of his book on standard language seem justified. Varioustypes of ‘deficit’ models cont<strong>in</strong>ue to have adherents, both with<strong>in</strong> andwithout <strong>the</strong> educational world. There are ‘important cont<strong>in</strong>uities with <strong>the</strong>th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g of <strong>the</strong> past, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> repetition of many of <strong>the</strong> same po<strong>in</strong>tsof confusion and difficulty’ (Crowley, 2003: 231). In similar fashion,Wolfram (1998a) recently acknowledged that ‘entrenched myths aboutlanguage <strong>in</strong>adequacy are like a jack-<strong>in</strong>-<strong>the</strong>-box that keeps spr<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>g backup’; he goes on to say that<strong>the</strong> exposure of one l<strong>in</strong>e of reason<strong>in</strong>g as objectively unjustified andillogical doesn’t mean that l<strong>in</strong>guistic equality will be atta<strong>in</strong>ed. If <strong>the</strong>bottom-l<strong>in</strong>e belief is that one cultural group and by extension itslanguage is <strong>in</strong>ferior to ano<strong>the</strong>r, <strong>the</strong>n ano<strong>the</strong>r l<strong>in</strong>e of reason<strong>in</strong>g willsimply replace <strong>the</strong> old one. (Wolfram, 1998a: 105)Perhaps <strong>the</strong>re is someth<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>herent <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> nature of socially stratifiedsocieties that will always f<strong>in</strong>d a way to translate cultural difference <strong>in</strong>todeficiency. But even if this ra<strong>the</strong>r gloomy assessment is correct even ifwe can only hope to scotch <strong>the</strong> snake, not kill it we should makewhatever assaults we can on <strong>in</strong>accurate and prejudiced <strong>in</strong>terpretations.The Honey affairIn Brita<strong>in</strong>, some of <strong>the</strong> cont<strong>in</strong>u<strong>in</strong>g controversy has been stimulated by<strong>the</strong> work of John Honey. It is worth consider<strong>in</strong>g here, not only because of<strong>the</strong> prom<strong>in</strong>ence it achieved, but also because it represents so well <strong>the</strong>


130 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>cont<strong>in</strong>u<strong>in</strong>g force of deficit perspectives. In an impressive collectiondevoted to <strong>the</strong> ‘debate’ over standard English, <strong>the</strong> editors note at <strong>the</strong> verybeg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g that <strong>the</strong> need for discussion ‘became even more press<strong>in</strong>g after<strong>the</strong> publication of Honey’s <strong>Language</strong> is Power (1997) with its peculiarmixture of half truths and ad hom<strong>in</strong>em arguments’ (Bex & Watts, 1999:1). In fact, as we shall see very shortly, <strong>the</strong> most contentious aspects ofHoney’s book are rework<strong>in</strong>gs and restatements of material he had<strong>in</strong>troduced years before. Honey’s writ<strong>in</strong>g would probably not haveattracted much academic attention, were it not for <strong>the</strong> considerablecoverage it received <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> popular media. This coverage was largelyfavorable, because Honey was often seen as a champion of ‘proper’English, dar<strong>in</strong>g to break academically imposed taboos, an unapologeticand provocative critic of <strong>the</strong> prevail<strong>in</strong>g ‘liberal orthodoxy’ <strong>in</strong> education.‘You can’t pull <strong>the</strong> wool over Professor Honey’s ears’, said <strong>the</strong> Mail onSunday. 4 Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, most of <strong>the</strong> journalistic accolades emerged frompolitically right-w<strong>in</strong>g stances, and so most of <strong>the</strong> academic constituency certa<strong>in</strong>ly that segment that had worked hard to eradicate narrow andessentially reactionary <strong>in</strong>terpretations of language that translated differences<strong>in</strong>to deficits were put on <strong>the</strong>ir guard. Cameron (1995: 86) notes<strong>the</strong> ‘respectful’ media attention given to what was seen as Honey’s‘dar<strong>in</strong>g’ and ‘iconoclastic’ assault upon <strong>the</strong> prevail<strong>in</strong>g orthodoxy; she<strong>the</strong>n clarifies <strong>the</strong> difficulty that faced <strong>the</strong> academic community, and thatprompted it to respond:To <strong>the</strong> extent that Marenbon or Honey can air <strong>the</strong>ir value judgementsopenly, whereas <strong>the</strong>ir opponents <strong>in</strong> l<strong>in</strong>guistic science are moreconstra<strong>in</strong>ed by <strong>the</strong> norm of objectivity, <strong>the</strong> polemical advantage lieswith <strong>the</strong> conservatives, and <strong>the</strong> l<strong>in</strong>guists are likely to lose <strong>the</strong>argument. (Cameron, 1995: 100)(The Marenbon to whom Cameron refers here produced a pamphlet[1987] <strong>in</strong> which he argued for <strong>the</strong> superiority of standard English, andthat grammar ‘prescribes by describ<strong>in</strong>g’ [Marenbon, 1987: 20]: descriptiveefforts create norms which should <strong>the</strong>n be prescribed.)Honey’s various assaults on current l<strong>in</strong>guistic ideas (1983a, 1989, 1997)make for <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g read<strong>in</strong>g. In <strong>the</strong> first of <strong>the</strong>se, a ra<strong>the</strong>r notoriouspamphlet, he claimed that work support<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> position that all languagevarieties are equally valid systems work, that is, support<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>‘difference’ position was without any firm basis. Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, heconsidered it pernicious s<strong>in</strong>ce, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> current climate of unease with<strong>the</strong> allegedly low standards of written and spoken English, such workacted to underm<strong>in</strong>e attempts to raise <strong>the</strong>se standards. 5 Disadvantaged


The Persistence of L<strong>in</strong>guistic Deficit 131speakers of nonstandard English thus fall <strong>in</strong>to a ‘language trap’; <strong>the</strong>y needhelp <strong>in</strong> standard language <strong>in</strong> order to advance socially and economically,but <strong>the</strong> modern l<strong>in</strong>guistic paradigm <strong>in</strong>sists that schools should encourage<strong>the</strong> use of varieties of nonstandard English. The pivotal po<strong>in</strong>t, however(accord<strong>in</strong>g to Honey) is that all dialects are not equally valid: <strong>the</strong>re issometh<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>the</strong> ‘deficit’ idea after all.He argues, for example, that some varieties are superior to o<strong>the</strong>rs <strong>in</strong>that <strong>the</strong>y can express more rarefied concepts (he mentions higherma<strong>the</strong>matics, biochemistry and <strong>the</strong> philosophy of Wittgenste<strong>in</strong>). He is,of course, confus<strong>in</strong>g words with concepts. Vocabulary is, <strong>in</strong> itself, only an<strong>in</strong>dicator of relevant social ideas, beliefs, <strong>the</strong>ories and so on: societiesignorant of higher ma<strong>the</strong>matics will obviously not need terms to describeit. It is important to realize here that, as societies develop and change, so<strong>the</strong>ir languages alter. All dialects and languages are capable of express<strong>in</strong>gwhatever <strong>the</strong> social environment demands; see also Crowley (1989),who enlarges his discussion of Honey by referr<strong>in</strong>g to o<strong>the</strong>r ‘ideologists of<strong>the</strong> new right’.Honey sees <strong>the</strong> scholarly acceptance of <strong>the</strong> different-but-not-deficientviewpo<strong>in</strong>t as a reflection of Chomskyan <strong>in</strong>fluence, and of <strong>the</strong> contemporaryfashion to avoid mak<strong>in</strong>g moral judgments of societies and <strong>the</strong>irlanguages. Chomsky is seen to bolster <strong>the</strong> difference argument byhold<strong>in</strong>g that all human be<strong>in</strong>gs share similar underly<strong>in</strong>g l<strong>in</strong>guisticcapacities, that all languages are essentially similar at some deep level.Consequently, qualitative judgments are <strong>in</strong>appropriate across languages.I suppose this is true, but even if Chomskyan (and o<strong>the</strong>r, more recent)‘<strong>in</strong>natist’ <strong>the</strong>ories were completely transcended, <strong>the</strong> argument that allvarieties are adequate for <strong>the</strong>ir users would still not necessarily beweakened because one would have to claim that different groups ofhuman be<strong>in</strong>gs differ markedly <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir <strong>in</strong>nate conceptual powers, a claimthat has never been substantiated. In general, questions of variations <strong>in</strong>social development possibly of <strong>in</strong>equalities <strong>in</strong> cognitive capacities, andcerta<strong>in</strong>ly of marked differences <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> operation of such capacities <strong>in</strong>particular environments are large and vexed. I would simply arguethat, whatever <strong>the</strong> verdict may be <strong>in</strong> terms of cognitive development<strong>in</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r areas, that of adequate language is a human universal (see alsoEdwards, 1985).On <strong>the</strong> second po<strong>in</strong>t, it is true that cultural relativism has been apowerful <strong>in</strong>fluence <strong>in</strong> contemporary literature, and it is <strong>the</strong> case, asHoney implies, that this can lead to difficulties: an extreme relativismmight seem to force us to embrace such repellent practices as Nazi warcrimes, cannibalism and female circumcision. My argument, however, is


132 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>simply that some aspects of relativism are more appropriate than o<strong>the</strong>rs,that relativism itself is relative, and that it is possible to construct an<strong>in</strong>tellectual position that allows us to legitimately criticize some featuresof societies while still permitt<strong>in</strong>g different-but-not-deficient analyses ofo<strong>the</strong>rs. I assume, for <strong>in</strong>stance, that a society that condones cannibalismand believes <strong>in</strong> witchcraft is <strong>in</strong>ferior, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>se respects, to one that doesnot. I do not see that this constra<strong>in</strong>s me to accept, as well, that languageX is superior to language Y, even if Y-speakers eat <strong>the</strong>ir neighbors whileX-speakers turn <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r cheek.Honey is particularly critical of Labov’s work, claim<strong>in</strong>g that it did not,after all, show <strong>the</strong> dialectal validity of Black English vernacular (BEV).But Honey pays only pass<strong>in</strong>g attention to <strong>the</strong> most important part of thatwork, <strong>the</strong> demonstration of <strong>the</strong> rule-governed nature of BEV; <strong>in</strong>deed, heattempts to undercut <strong>the</strong> very approach, not<strong>in</strong>g that not all l<strong>in</strong>guistsagree on what <strong>the</strong> rules are. The lack of perfect knowledge andagreement, however, is a l<strong>in</strong>guistic fact of life that is true for all varieties(<strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g standard English), and it misses <strong>the</strong> essential po<strong>in</strong>t thatl<strong>in</strong>guists do agree that rules exist and are abided by.When he turns to consider current educational practice, Honey errsaga<strong>in</strong> this time <strong>in</strong> his supposition that acceptance of <strong>the</strong> differenceposition necessarily entails active school promotion of nonstandardvarieties. Of course, it does not. The weight of <strong>the</strong> available evidencesuggests that schools should accept nonstandard varieties as valid systems;two corollaries are that teachers ought not to try and stamp <strong>the</strong>m out, andthat children should not be penalized for us<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>m. However, because ofsocial realities, schools should cont<strong>in</strong>ue to provide standard Englishmodels and to promote awareness of this dialect, with<strong>in</strong> an atmosphereof tolerance and respect for all o<strong>the</strong>r varieties (see also Pennycook, 2001). Itis important to remember here that a common standard can work to level<strong>the</strong> play<strong>in</strong>g field just as easily as privileg<strong>in</strong>g one group over ano<strong>the</strong>r: whichrole it fills, of course, depends upon how it is understood.Overall, <strong>the</strong> importance of Honey’s <strong>in</strong>tervention is not <strong>in</strong> its handl<strong>in</strong>gand <strong>in</strong>terpretation of l<strong>in</strong>guistic evidence; Crowley (1999) provides somechapter-and-verse documentation of Honey’s (1997) errors and ra<strong>the</strong>rcavalier presentation of evidence for his assertions. Ra<strong>the</strong>r, it lies <strong>in</strong> itsvery existence as an attempted defence of a l<strong>in</strong>guistic status quo seen tobe <strong>in</strong> danger. Honey is exercised over <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>g power ofcontemporary <strong>in</strong>fluences (<strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g television) compared to traditionalshapers of education and language (e.g. <strong>the</strong> Bible). He acknowledges thatchange is <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>evitable order of <strong>the</strong> day, but clearly regrets it. In fact, hisgeneral thrust can be seen as a desire to defend traditional values. This


The Persistence of L<strong>in</strong>guistic Deficit 133may or may not be a laudable objective per se a great deal depends, forexample, on <strong>the</strong> assessed value of <strong>the</strong> old and <strong>the</strong> new but one th<strong>in</strong>g issure: no reliable case of any sort can be built on <strong>in</strong>accurate foundations.Honey’s work is best seen as an effort to brea<strong>the</strong> renewed life <strong>in</strong>to a‘deficit’ philosophy and, as such, it has stimulated some provocative andpo<strong>in</strong>ted reaction. One of <strong>the</strong> chief l<strong>in</strong>guistic ‘oracles’ attacked <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> 1983pamphlet was David Crystal, whose response (Crystal, 1983) po<strong>in</strong>ted to <strong>the</strong>highly emotional language <strong>in</strong> which Honey couched his attacks on <strong>the</strong>modern l<strong>in</strong>guistic enterprise. ‘A great <strong>in</strong>dustry has grown up’, Honey hadsaid (on p. 2), ‘dedicated to disparag<strong>in</strong>g standard English... based onfantasies, fabrications and unproven hypo<strong>the</strong>ses’. This is a bit rich, asCrystal rightly notes, consider<strong>in</strong>g that Honey’s own assertions of <strong>the</strong>unscientific, uncritical and mislead<strong>in</strong>g views supposedly promulgated byl<strong>in</strong>guists verge on conspiracy-<strong>the</strong>ory rhetoric, and that his own ‘case’ restsra<strong>the</strong>r heavily upon secondary and often non-academic sources. The tw<strong>in</strong>strands of Honey’s argument are that <strong>the</strong>se nefarious l<strong>in</strong>guists hold allvarieties to be equally good, and that any emphasis upon standard Englishmust <strong>the</strong>refore be unjustifiable. Crystal neatly po<strong>in</strong>ts out that <strong>the</strong> ‘goodness’that contemporary l<strong>in</strong>guistics attributes to all languages and dialectsis a l<strong>in</strong>guistic and not a social matter and that <strong>the</strong>re is noth<strong>in</strong>gcontradictory <strong>in</strong> claim<strong>in</strong>g that purely l<strong>in</strong>guistic ‘goodness’ need not meanequivalence <strong>in</strong> a world where attitudes commonly translate difference <strong>in</strong>todeficit. The real implication here is not any sort of ‘language trap’ to whichdisadvantaged children are condemned, but ra<strong>the</strong>r as I have po<strong>in</strong>ted out(Edwards, 1983a) an enlightened and culturally sensitive policy ofbidialectalism. S<strong>in</strong>ce Honey himself ends up with a recommendation for‘bilectalism’, Crystal f<strong>in</strong>ds <strong>the</strong> whole argument to be a damp squib. O<strong>the</strong>rshave, too see Graddol and Swann (1988) on <strong>the</strong> synonymy of ‘bilectalism’and ‘bidialectalism’ and with o<strong>the</strong>r arguments, as well: for <strong>in</strong>stance,Honey (2000b) proposes that ‘<strong>in</strong> any society (or subculture) <strong>in</strong> whicheducatedness is an admired attribute, prestige will attach to those l<strong>in</strong>guisticforms which are perceived as characteristic of educatedness’. (Later, I shallhave more to say about <strong>the</strong> practical difficulties associated with bidialectalpolicies at school, but <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>oretical arguments for <strong>the</strong>m are firmly based.)Crystal’s (1983) lengthy review of Honey’s pamphlet appeared <strong>in</strong> anumber of <strong>the</strong> newsletter of <strong>the</strong> British Association for Applied L<strong>in</strong>guistics,accompany<strong>in</strong>g a second review (Hudson, 1983; see also Honey, 1983b,for a response to <strong>the</strong>se two). Later on, Honey (1997) acknowledged howunusual such double treatment was <strong>in</strong> those pages, particularly s<strong>in</strong>ce <strong>the</strong>work assessed was only 40 pages long. Such attention from <strong>the</strong> l<strong>in</strong>guistic‘establishment’ suggested to Honey a lash<strong>in</strong>g-out at an argument that


134 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>challenged widely-held but dubious views, a fierce reaction to a woundedprofessional amour propre. To o<strong>the</strong>rs, however, Honey’s pamphlet, whosestyle and argument (however unconv<strong>in</strong>c<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> an academic sense) led towide coverage <strong>in</strong> both <strong>the</strong> broadsheet and <strong>the</strong> tabloid press, required afirm response. Thus, Hudson described <strong>the</strong> work as a ‘prime exampleof demagoguery, tell<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> un<strong>in</strong>itiated what <strong>the</strong>y want to hear’. Trudgill(1998: 460), <strong>in</strong> a trenchant review of Honey (1997), said that ‘s<strong>in</strong>ce hecont<strong>in</strong>ues to masquerade as a l<strong>in</strong>guist... and s<strong>in</strong>ce <strong>the</strong> weight ofun<strong>in</strong>formed journalistic op<strong>in</strong>ion is on his side, we need to take everyopportunity we can to make it pla<strong>in</strong> that he is not speak<strong>in</strong>g on our behalf’.In an American review, Kochman (1985: 161) calls Honey’s pamphlet‘reactionary... elitist... <strong>in</strong>tellectually dishonest... mean-spirited’.Graddol and Swann (1988) present a very <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g analysis of <strong>the</strong>academic response to Honey’s pamphlet. They argue that <strong>the</strong> rejo<strong>in</strong>derswere not as dis<strong>in</strong>terested as <strong>the</strong>y might have been, and <strong>the</strong>y identifythree ma<strong>in</strong> ‘response strategies’. In <strong>the</strong> first of <strong>the</strong>se, Honey is seen as‘subversive’, an outsider <strong>in</strong>tent on smear<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> scholarly community;consequently even as <strong>the</strong>y were respond<strong>in</strong>g to his work someimplied that it was both <strong>in</strong>fra dig and useless to cross swords with suchan opponent. Relatedly, <strong>the</strong>re is a desire to deny Honey <strong>the</strong> ‘oxygen ofpublicity’. The second strategy rests upon a sense of outrage and <strong>in</strong>sult:much of <strong>the</strong> to-and-fro’<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> popular and academic press revealsthat many l<strong>in</strong>guists felt under personal attack (I make reference to someof this exchange here; a fuller account is provided by Graddol and Swann[1988] <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir appendix). A related feature here is that <strong>the</strong> self-defensivemoves were often accompanied by rem<strong>in</strong>ders of <strong>the</strong> writer’s own status<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> respectable academic world, and of how tedious it was, <strong>the</strong>n, tohave to take time to respond to someone like Honey.A third approach took Honey ra<strong>the</strong>r more seriously. Graddol andSwann po<strong>in</strong>t out that, whatever <strong>the</strong> underly<strong>in</strong>g strategy, any academicresponse to Honey represents an <strong>in</strong>tersection of ‘professional’ with ‘lay’discourse, and po<strong>in</strong>ts of contact here are traditionally fraught withdanger, particularly where and when specific matters are underp<strong>in</strong>nedby much broader ones. Thus, Graddol and Swann note that Honey’spamphlet was essentially a contribution to, and a reflection of, <strong>the</strong> ‘newright’ political order of <strong>the</strong> time. Consequently, when academics debatedHoney <strong>in</strong> newspaper columns and letters, <strong>the</strong>y were operat<strong>in</strong>g on <strong>the</strong>opposition’s terra<strong>in</strong> of choice:<strong>the</strong> l<strong>in</strong>guists wrote <strong>in</strong> order to protest at <strong>the</strong> misuse of misrepresentationof <strong>the</strong>ir academic work, but <strong>the</strong> very fact that <strong>the</strong>y appeared <strong>in</strong>


The Persistence of L<strong>in</strong>guistic Deficit 135opposition to <strong>the</strong> right-w<strong>in</strong>g correspondents would have confirmed<strong>the</strong> public impression that <strong>the</strong>y represent <strong>the</strong> radical left. They are, itseems, <strong>in</strong> someth<strong>in</strong>g of a trap. The more <strong>the</strong>y protest at be<strong>in</strong>gcharacterised as politically motivated, <strong>the</strong> more <strong>the</strong>y will appear tobe so. (Graddol & Swann, 1988: 104)I suggested above that <strong>the</strong> real motivation beh<strong>in</strong>d Honey’s pamphletcould well have been nostalgic regret for a l<strong>in</strong>guistic environment <strong>in</strong>which <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>fluence of <strong>the</strong> Bible and <strong>the</strong> Book of Common Prayer hasbeen eroded by vulgar modern villa<strong>in</strong>s <strong>the</strong> author mentions <strong>the</strong>pernicious idioms of Coronation Street, of <strong>the</strong> commercialized media, ofpop-celebrity culture. Crowley (1989: 271) also suggests that <strong>the</strong> ‘reactionarynostalgic thought’ of Honey and his ‘fellow travellers’ reveals adesire to return to ‘Victorian values’; this strikes me as reasonablyaccurate, although possibly a little unfair to <strong>the</strong> Victorians. 6 It is notsurpris<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>the</strong>n, to f<strong>in</strong>d that Honey concludes his pamphlet by argu<strong>in</strong>gthat ‘social justice’ demands that disadvantaged children be providedwith a ‘ready facility <strong>in</strong> standard English, even at <strong>the</strong> expense of <strong>the</strong>irdevelopment <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir orig<strong>in</strong>al non-standard variety [and] ... I amtempted to add, of <strong>the</strong>ir self-esteem’ (Honey, 1983a: 31). After all, sucha recommendation can rest perfectly well upon <strong>the</strong> assumption thatpernicious elements <strong>in</strong> modern life have led to, or encouraged, orre<strong>in</strong>forced deficiencies <strong>in</strong> l<strong>in</strong>guistic capability.It is yet ano<strong>the</strong>r of <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>ternal curiosities to be found throughoutHoney’s little monograph that as Crystal observes his argument forpromot<strong>in</strong>g standard English, even if it means some wound<strong>in</strong>g of <strong>the</strong> selfesteem,is made only a few paragraphs after Honey berates <strong>the</strong> bad olddays when nonstandard forms were ‘virtually outlawed’, when <strong>in</strong>sensitivityand ‘straightforward suppression’ were <strong>the</strong> order of <strong>the</strong> day. It alsodoes Honey’s case no good when he glibly asserts, à propos of self-esteem,that ‘I am not excessively impressed by <strong>the</strong> argument that <strong>the</strong> teach<strong>in</strong>g ofstandard English need cause all <strong>the</strong> consequences of shame, confusion,l<strong>in</strong>guistic <strong>in</strong>security, alienation, etc.’ (Honey, 1983a: 31). Honey presentsno evidence for this assertion which, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> absence of any support, has ara<strong>the</strong>r de haut en bas flavor.After produc<strong>in</strong>g an <strong>in</strong>terven<strong>in</strong>g book on accent (1989) <strong>in</strong> which, onceaga<strong>in</strong>, a great deal of <strong>the</strong> source material was m<strong>in</strong>ed from <strong>the</strong> popularpr<strong>in</strong>t and broadcast media (ironic, consider<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> laments made <strong>in</strong> hispamphlet) Honey returned to <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>me of language traps. This newproduction (1997) was subtitled The Story of Standard English and itsEnemies and no prizes will be awarded at this po<strong>in</strong>t for identify<strong>in</strong>g those


136 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>villa<strong>in</strong>s. The first two chapters, ‘The language myth’ and ‘The dialect trap’remake Honey’s pivotal po<strong>in</strong>ts: modern l<strong>in</strong>guistics holds, <strong>in</strong>correctly, thatall languages are ‘equal’; and <strong>the</strong> force of Bernste<strong>in</strong>’s valuable <strong>in</strong>sights <strong>in</strong>tomore and less complex ‘codes’ was blunted by <strong>the</strong> arguments of ‘<strong>the</strong> highpriest of modern sociol<strong>in</strong>guistics... William Labov’ (Honey, 1997: 23).Here and elsewhere, Honey laments <strong>the</strong> fact that his own work could not‘dent <strong>the</strong> authority’ (p. 29) of what soon came to be <strong>the</strong> received l<strong>in</strong>guisticwisdom. Taken toge<strong>the</strong>r with <strong>the</strong> ‘high priest’ remark, <strong>the</strong> suggestion hereis of an unscientific hierarchy, irrationally resistant to <strong>the</strong> truth. Thus, ‘<strong>the</strong>Bernste<strong>in</strong> ‘‘deficit’’ model was rejected, and dismissed as unacceptable,simply because enough established figures <strong>in</strong> l<strong>in</strong>guistics declared it to beso’ (p. 29). Such a stance, of course, is not uncommon among thosewho feel <strong>the</strong>ir po<strong>in</strong>ts of view have been neglected by <strong>the</strong> community <strong>the</strong>ywish to contribute to, and to be recognized by. Still, a judicious applicationof Occam’s razor might <strong>in</strong>dicate more straightforward reasons forrejection.Beyond <strong>the</strong> open<strong>in</strong>g chapters, <strong>the</strong> whole book is essentially devoted toa refutation of Honey’s critics: chapters treat those enemies of Englishwho have attempted to rewrite <strong>the</strong> story of standard English, who haverejected prescriptivist models and approaches rejected, that is to say,<strong>the</strong> widely-held belief ‘that <strong>the</strong>re is such a th<strong>in</strong>g as correct English’(Honey, 1997: 144) who have abdicated <strong>the</strong> noble duty of safeguard<strong>in</strong>g<strong>the</strong> language, and whose laissez-faire l<strong>in</strong>guistics have created an educationally‘lost generation’. At <strong>the</strong> end of <strong>the</strong> book, and particularly <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>penultimate chapter (‘The <strong>Language</strong> Trap debate’), Honey turns mostexplicitly on his various critics. He argues that, beyond <strong>the</strong>ir evidentrejection of <strong>the</strong> content per se, l<strong>in</strong>guistic scholars’ reactions to his workwere strongly motivated by <strong>the</strong>ir desire to stifle a ‘dangerous <strong>in</strong>surgent’(see also Graddol & Swann, 1988). This seems fairly reasonable to me,actually, s<strong>in</strong>ce Honey himself pulls no personal punches <strong>in</strong> his pamphlet,and elsewhere (Honey, 1983a, 1997, 1998). Among <strong>the</strong> heavyweights hehas taken on are Trudgill, Crystal, Labov, Haugen, Lyons, Wolfram,P<strong>in</strong>ker, Harris, Aitchison and <strong>the</strong> Milroys, and it is surely not surpris<strong>in</strong>gthat those placed <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> spotlight would feel both personally andprofessionally aggrieved. (The old French witticism comes to m<strong>in</strong>dhere: ‘cet animal est très méchant; quand on l’attaque, il se défend’.)Honey also po<strong>in</strong>ts to <strong>the</strong> grow<strong>in</strong>g accusations of <strong>the</strong> polemical(right-w<strong>in</strong>g) bias of his work, a damn<strong>in</strong>g th<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> what is a generallyleft-lean<strong>in</strong>g academy. There is probably some substance to this, at least <strong>in</strong>terms of more or less immediate reaction, but any such <strong>in</strong>itial position<strong>in</strong>gwould very soon become vitiated if substantive argument did not follow.


The Persistence of L<strong>in</strong>guistic Deficit 137It seems that Honey is at pa<strong>in</strong>s to br<strong>in</strong>g up his <strong>the</strong>sis, and its numerouscritics, wherever possible. For example, <strong>in</strong> an extremely lengthy reviewof Mugglestone’s (1995) <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g book on ‘talk<strong>in</strong>g proper’, Honey(2000b) f<strong>in</strong>ds <strong>the</strong> central argument about <strong>the</strong> relationship between speechand status undercut by <strong>the</strong> author’s uncritical acceptance of <strong>the</strong>‘l<strong>in</strong>guistic equality hypo<strong>the</strong>sis’. Honey’s po<strong>in</strong>t here seems to be anattempted dissociation of ‘educatedness’ and social éliteness. Hecriticizes Mugglestone’s ‘false correlation of accents with <strong>the</strong> social eliteas such, ra<strong>the</strong>r than with people who were perceived as educated’. Heacknowledges that ‘to be a gentleman was one of <strong>the</strong> frequentaccompaniments of educatedness’, but rejects <strong>the</strong> notion that it was a‘def<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g characteristic’. (Crowley, 1999, provides a good discussion ofHoney’s difficulties with ‘educatedness’.) Now, <strong>the</strong>re is <strong>in</strong>deed a greatdeal to say and to understand about <strong>the</strong> relationships between speechstyle and social evaluation, and this is particularly so <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> 19th-centurysett<strong>in</strong>g closely exam<strong>in</strong>ed by Mugglestone <strong>in</strong> her book (see also <strong>the</strong>earlier treatments of Brook [1963, 1970], Chapman [1994], McIntosh[1998], Mitchell [2001], Phillipps [1984] and Wright [2000] discussionsthat range, <strong>in</strong>deed, well beyond <strong>the</strong> 19th century). It is dis<strong>in</strong>genuous,however, to try and make a strong case for <strong>the</strong> dissociation just noted. Itis entirely understandable that Honey would wish to do so, of course, fordown that avenue lies <strong>the</strong> claim that <strong>the</strong>re is, after all, some <strong>in</strong>tr<strong>in</strong>sicsuperiority attach<strong>in</strong>g to standard dialects <strong>the</strong>y are <strong>the</strong> educated ones,reflect<strong>in</strong>g literacy and learn<strong>in</strong>g entirely foreign to ‘barrow-boys orwasherwomen’. But we have subtly stepped aside here from <strong>the</strong> basicmatters of l<strong>in</strong>guistic importance: l<strong>in</strong>guistic adequacy and <strong>the</strong> fullyfledged nature of all dialects.Trudgill’s (1998) review of Honey (1997) makes very clearly, I shouldsay what are now familiar po<strong>in</strong>ts. Two of <strong>the</strong> new ones are that <strong>the</strong>author is not a tra<strong>in</strong>ed l<strong>in</strong>guist, and thatHoney is not a modest man... he genu<strong>in</strong>ely believes he hassucceeded, s<strong>in</strong>gle handed, <strong>in</strong> demolish<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>gs of generationsof l<strong>in</strong>guistic scholarship... he certa<strong>in</strong>ly gets plenty of publicitywhich... he shows every sign of enjoy<strong>in</strong>g. (Trudgill, 1998: 457458)When Honey (2000a) <strong>the</strong>n made a rejo<strong>in</strong>der to Trudgill’s review don’tworry, we are near<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> end of this circular comedy he seemed toagree that his l<strong>in</strong>guistic credentials were <strong>in</strong>deed ra<strong>the</strong>r slight and that,yes, he did enjoy his media limelight. Sour grapes on Trudgill’s part,s<strong>in</strong>ce Honey says that his celebrity ‘may just possibly have been because


138 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>my views were judged to be more widely credible’ (p. 318). There areo<strong>the</strong>r possibilities, of course.There are a number of <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g conclusions to be drawn from thisepisode, and I have h<strong>in</strong>ted at most of <strong>the</strong>m. But let me conclude here byre-emphasiz<strong>in</strong>g one or two of <strong>the</strong> most salient. Whatever <strong>the</strong> scholarlyevidence may suggest, questions of <strong>the</strong> ‘goodness’ of language aretypically political ones, rest<strong>in</strong>g upon social bedrock that is both wide anddeep. The reported death of ‘deficit’ perspectives was an exaggeration.Second, <strong>the</strong> notion of <strong>the</strong> ‘equality’ of all language varieties shouldprobably be abandoned. ‘Equality’ is obviously not <strong>the</strong> mot juste whensome varieties have labyr<strong>in</strong>th<strong>in</strong>e complexities of tense-mark<strong>in</strong>g, wheno<strong>the</strong>rs describe k<strong>in</strong>ship relationships out to <strong>the</strong> fur<strong>the</strong>st reaches of <strong>the</strong>family tree, and so on. (I choose <strong>the</strong>se two examples, <strong>in</strong>cidentally, s<strong>in</strong>ce<strong>the</strong>y refer to languages spoken by what <strong>the</strong> popular m<strong>in</strong>d and presswould describe as ‘primitive groups’ those unfortunate societieshav<strong>in</strong>g, as John V<strong>in</strong>cent suggested <strong>in</strong> The Times [23 February 1983], ‘nosocial development’.) 7 Cont<strong>in</strong>ued reference to <strong>the</strong> ‘equality’ of allvarieties provides easy targets for deficit <strong>the</strong>orists. Although l<strong>in</strong>guistsand o<strong>the</strong>r scholars who make such reference are generally <strong>in</strong>dulg<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> abit of commonly shared shorthand, it would be more accurate to say thatall varieties are sufficient unto <strong>the</strong> day, that all can bend and stretch asrequired, that <strong>the</strong> totality of a group’s ideas and concepts can, at anypo<strong>in</strong>t, be adequately depicted and discussed. More accurate, althoughadmittedly less aphoristic, but less amenable to simple-m<strong>in</strong>ded sociopoliticalmanipulation.Graddol and Swann (1988: 9596) go a bit fur<strong>the</strong>r, suggest<strong>in</strong>g that, <strong>in</strong><strong>the</strong> privacy of <strong>the</strong>ir studies, l<strong>in</strong>guists reject <strong>the</strong> idea of ‘completel<strong>in</strong>guistic equality’, that <strong>the</strong>y consider <strong>the</strong> notion to be a sort of ‘work<strong>in</strong>ghypo<strong>the</strong>sis’ and admit that ‘<strong>the</strong>re are a number of naturally occurr<strong>in</strong>glanguage varieties which must be discreetly passed over to preserve <strong>the</strong><strong>in</strong>tegrity of <strong>the</strong> doctr<strong>in</strong>e’. And, with Hymes (1972), <strong>the</strong> authors alsosuggest a political imperative underp<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g ‘equality’, an ‘ideologicalconfidence’ <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> notion.I would say <strong>the</strong>y are bend<strong>in</strong>g fur<strong>the</strong>r backwards than necessary here.First, replac<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> terse but <strong>in</strong>accurate idea of ‘equality’ with what it isreally meant to express deflates some of <strong>the</strong> necessity. This, <strong>in</strong> turn,allows us to see that <strong>the</strong> troublesome ‘to-be-passed-over’ varieties Graddol and Swann mention children’s speech, contact varieties and<strong>in</strong>terlanguages are not <strong>in</strong> fact troublesome at all. They too conform tofuller senses of ‘equality’. There is also a very relevant po<strong>in</strong>t here; it is notoften made, but it clearly bears upon all discussions of ‘equality’, and it


The Persistence of L<strong>in</strong>guistic Deficit 139undercuts all attempts to pervert or manipulate <strong>the</strong> idea. It is simply this.All human communities are speak<strong>in</strong>g communities, and everyth<strong>in</strong>g weknow about cognitive capacity and social development makes it bo<strong>the</strong>asier and more logical to assume that <strong>the</strong>y all have languages that serve<strong>the</strong>ir purposes. A bizarre opposite assertion would be that <strong>the</strong> languagesof some groups are flawed, that (for example) a group might lack <strong>the</strong>l<strong>in</strong>guistic capacity to fully discuss, up to <strong>the</strong> level of its conceptualknowledge, <strong>the</strong> trees and bushes <strong>in</strong> its environment.To put it ano<strong>the</strong>r way: given what is known about human cognitivedevelopment, <strong>the</strong> ‘rule-governed’ hypo<strong>the</strong>sis that is (or ought to be) at<strong>the</strong> heart of all discussions of ‘equality’ makes much more <strong>in</strong>tr<strong>in</strong>sic sensethan some ‘haphazard’ one and this, regardless of any specificempirical observation at all. For what group, wherever and however itmay live, could ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong> itself adequately with an <strong>in</strong>complete or<strong>in</strong>consistent communication system? These adjectives reflect exactly <strong>the</strong>sort of illegitimate cross-group comparison that, as we have seen,animates <strong>the</strong> very idea of ‘disadvantage’.Empirical ExcursionsAccompany<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> popular and <strong>the</strong>oretical persistence of ‘deficit’perspectives are f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>gs of an empirical nature. Many of <strong>the</strong>se are, ei<strong>the</strong>rdirectly or implicitly, related to Bernste<strong>in</strong>’s <strong>in</strong>fluence which, <strong>in</strong> itsembrace of both researchers and teachers, has traveled far beyond <strong>the</strong>English-language sphere. Thus, for example, well after <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>itialassertions underp<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> ‘difference’ position, Gordon (1978) lookedat <strong>the</strong> impact of Bernste<strong>in</strong>’s writ<strong>in</strong>gs upon a sample of primary-schoolteachers <strong>in</strong> Suffolk. They reported that deficit <strong>the</strong>ory had been a part of<strong>the</strong>ir tra<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g courses, and that it expressed and re<strong>in</strong>forced ideas alreadywidely current among teachers. A few of <strong>the</strong> teachers made criticalremarks, but only those who had actually read papers by and aboutBernste<strong>in</strong> were skeptical or critical. Those whose awareness was more<strong>in</strong>formally derived were <strong>the</strong> most accept<strong>in</strong>g of it. This is a fasc<strong>in</strong>at<strong>in</strong>g andsuggestive detail. When we consider that close and direct exam<strong>in</strong>ationmay lead to an awareness of <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>oretical fragility of <strong>the</strong> ‘codes’, <strong>the</strong>fact that most teachers (like <strong>the</strong> rest of us) absorb new ideas ra<strong>the</strong>r lessstraightforwardly becomes a salient one <strong>in</strong>deed. One implication is,surely, that teachers ought to be given more opportunity for focusedstudy, for opportunities to see that some emperors have a limitedwardrobe.


140 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>Generally, Gordon’s <strong>in</strong>terviews revealed that Bernste<strong>in</strong>’s formulationswere attractive to teachers, confirm<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>ir exist<strong>in</strong>g views and assumptionsabout children’s speech. Among <strong>the</strong> more <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g comments:‘Bernste<strong>in</strong> ...is say<strong>in</strong>g someth<strong>in</strong>g which most teachers take <strong>in</strong> through<strong>the</strong>ir f<strong>in</strong>gers, as you might say it, every day of <strong>the</strong>ir lives’; and ‘everyoneknows that children from certa<strong>in</strong> backgrounds do have a restricted codeof speech... you can’t mistake it when you meet it, can you?’ (Gordon,1978: 104, 106; see also Gordon, 1981). Mason (1986: 279) makes <strong>the</strong>explicit po<strong>in</strong>t that <strong>the</strong> deficit hypo<strong>the</strong>sis is <strong>in</strong>tertw<strong>in</strong>ed with Bernste<strong>in</strong>’s<strong>the</strong>ory, and has ‘rema<strong>in</strong>ed alive <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> m<strong>in</strong>ds of many practic<strong>in</strong>g schoolteachers’;she goes on to underl<strong>in</strong>e <strong>the</strong> dist<strong>in</strong>ction between concrete andabstract language as Bernste<strong>in</strong>’s ‘fundamental <strong>in</strong>sight’. Such po<strong>in</strong>ts ofview take us back, <strong>in</strong>deed, to <strong>the</strong> pre-Bernste<strong>in</strong>ian assessments ofSchatzman and Strauss (1955; see also Carr<strong>in</strong>gton & Williamson, 1987,for a reply to Mason). In two fur<strong>the</strong>r examples, Jay et al. (1980) and Gullo(1981) treat social-class language differences from a Bernste<strong>in</strong>ian perspective;Gullo, <strong>in</strong> particular, apparently accept<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> view that poorchildren’s language is l<strong>in</strong>ked to <strong>the</strong> concrete present and is less used forabstract reason<strong>in</strong>g. Reports on <strong>the</strong> acceptance of Bernste<strong>in</strong> and ‘deficit’among teachers outside <strong>the</strong> UK and North America can be found <strong>in</strong>Shafer and Shafer (1975), Thomson (1977) and Cheshire et al. (1989).Loman’s (1974) <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g collection provides translations of work both‘for’ and ‘aga<strong>in</strong>st’ Bernste<strong>in</strong>; <strong>the</strong> editor’s own two contributions attemptto provide an objective overview of <strong>the</strong> important issues; it is noteworthythat Loman refers particularly to Bernste<strong>in</strong>’s often opaque prose. Theidea that Bernste<strong>in</strong> was not, <strong>in</strong> fact, a deficit <strong>the</strong>orist has also beenrevisited: Atk<strong>in</strong>son’s (1985) re<strong>in</strong>troduction to his work has thusprompted some re-exam<strong>in</strong>ation (e.g. Davies, 1987; Tony Edwards,1987a, 1987b).F<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>gs similar to Gordon’s emerge from a later study undertaken <strong>in</strong>Nova Scotia, <strong>in</strong> which 96 teachers from 10 schools (seven primary andthree secondary) were asked about educational disadvantage (Edwards& McK<strong>in</strong>non, 1987). The schools served a rural population that waspredom<strong>in</strong>antly white and English-speak<strong>in</strong>g, but <strong>the</strong>re were also sizeablegroups of French Acadian and black pupils. Teachers discusseddisadvantage <strong>in</strong> general, <strong>in</strong>dicated whe<strong>the</strong>r or not <strong>the</strong>y had receivedany <strong>in</strong>formation about it dur<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>ir tra<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g, and were <strong>the</strong>n asked tojudge <strong>the</strong> degree of importance of a number of <strong>home</strong> background andpersonal characteristics. They were also asked to consider languagematters specifically. It was very clear that most teachers held an implicit


The Persistence of L<strong>in</strong>guistic Deficit 141‘deficit’ po<strong>in</strong>t of view; here are two representative comments (Edwards &McK<strong>in</strong>non, 1987: 337):Disadvantage suggests an <strong>in</strong>formational and experiential <strong>in</strong>feriority...an <strong>in</strong>ability to make full use of novel <strong>in</strong>formation and,conversely, to call upon past experiences <strong>in</strong> novel situations;[Disadvantaged children have] lack of experiences, poor languagedevelopment... usually disorganized. They usually are not motivatedby long-term rewards. Goals must be short-term. Thesestudents generally come from lower economic levels, but not always.A fur<strong>the</strong>r characteristic of [disadvantaged] families I would say isdisorganization and a low priority placed on learn<strong>in</strong>g.Certa<strong>in</strong>ly, not all teachers phrased <strong>the</strong>ir feel<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> such terms which,<strong>in</strong>deed, show some familiarity with <strong>the</strong> literature or, at least, <strong>the</strong> jargon but <strong>the</strong> general tenor of op<strong>in</strong>ion is fairly reflected <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>se comments.There is some suggestion <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>se and o<strong>the</strong>r observations that teachersmay have adapted new <strong>in</strong>formation to old attitudes; this is particularlyevident <strong>in</strong> phrases like ‘<strong>in</strong>formational and experiential <strong>in</strong>feriority’, whichare redolent of <strong>the</strong> environmental-deficit literature. This, <strong>in</strong> turn, suggestsa difficulty I have already touched upon. It is common to hear calls forteacher-tra<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g courses and <strong>in</strong>-service workshops to deal with <strong>the</strong> latestpsychological and l<strong>in</strong>guistic developments of <strong>in</strong>terest. Teachers may not,however, get full or adequate presentations, and may simply assimilatewhat <strong>in</strong>formation <strong>the</strong>y do get to exist<strong>in</strong>g frameworks, frameworks likelyto reflect deficit perceptions.Turn<strong>in</strong>g to language matters specifically, teachers po<strong>in</strong>ted to poorgrammar, vocabulary, articulation and read<strong>in</strong>g as important aspects ofdisadvantage. Aga<strong>in</strong>, differences were generally seen as deficits. Somerepresentative comments will aga<strong>in</strong> illustrate this (Edwards & McK<strong>in</strong>non,1987: 339):[Children often cannot] articulate <strong>the</strong>ir thoughts and feel<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>in</strong> sucha way that <strong>the</strong>y satisfy both <strong>the</strong>mselves and <strong>the</strong>ir audience;The common element of experience among all disadvantagedchildren is <strong>in</strong>frequent <strong>in</strong>teraction with adults <strong>in</strong> discovery activitieswhere op<strong>in</strong>ions and experiences can be shared;Both receptive and expressive skills seem to have low levels of valueand priority when it comes to develop<strong>in</strong>g accuracy and fluency.Aga<strong>in</strong>, we see beliefs that correspond strik<strong>in</strong>gly with views expressed <strong>in</strong><strong>the</strong> deficit literature. Children are seen to be unable to communicateadequately, <strong>the</strong>y lack <strong>the</strong> experiences and <strong>in</strong>teractions that are necessary


142 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>for develop<strong>in</strong>g language skills and, <strong>in</strong>deed, it is suggested that <strong>the</strong>ir‘receptive and expressive’ talents are not greatly valued anyway. This lastpo<strong>in</strong>t is particularly rem<strong>in</strong>iscent of <strong>the</strong> l<strong>in</strong>guistically misguided sentimentsof deficit <strong>the</strong>orists of <strong>the</strong> 1960s.Teachers are not malicious, <strong>the</strong>y can hardly be said to be unsympa<strong>the</strong>ticto language ‘problems’, and it is probably fair to say that <strong>the</strong>re nowexists greater tolerance for language variation than was once <strong>the</strong> case.Still, while teachers view language differences as spr<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>g from varied<strong>home</strong> backgrounds (true), <strong>the</strong>y also often cont<strong>in</strong>ue to see <strong>the</strong>m asnecessitat<strong>in</strong>g some sort of compensatory action (dubious). Severalteachers <strong>in</strong> this study commented extensively on <strong>the</strong> ‘poor’ Englishlearned at <strong>home</strong>, and <strong>the</strong> consequent need to teach children ‘correct’English. This task, some felt, was analogous to teach<strong>in</strong>g a new languagealtoge<strong>the</strong>r. The various programs and activities suggested as useful herewere aga<strong>in</strong> echoes of <strong>the</strong> dreary recommendations of language-deficit<strong>the</strong>orists: language drills, speech <strong>the</strong>rapy, and so on.Where teachers were <strong>in</strong> contact with m<strong>in</strong>ority-group children, <strong>the</strong>speech patterns of <strong>the</strong>se were s<strong>in</strong>gled out for attention. Many put blackand Acadian children at <strong>the</strong> top of <strong>the</strong> lists of those hav<strong>in</strong>g languagedifficulties. A fairly general view was expressed by one teacher as follows:‘Blacks have a slang language all <strong>the</strong>ir own. They will not use properEnglish when opportunity arises’ (Edwards & McK<strong>in</strong>non, 1987: 339). In<strong>the</strong> secondary school hav<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> highest number of black pupils, 11 of <strong>the</strong>22 teachers commented explicitly on <strong>the</strong> children’s language problems.Such f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>gs are consistent with those reported elsewhere. In herdiscussion of <strong>the</strong> educational situation of Puerto Rican children <strong>in</strong>America, Walsh found teachers whose views seem to have ‘effectivelysummarized all of <strong>the</strong> conclusions drawn from Bernste<strong>in</strong>’s <strong>the</strong>ories ofrestricted and elaborated codes’ (Lippi-Green, 1997: 111):These poor kids come to school speak<strong>in</strong>g a hodge podge. They are allmixed up and don’t know any language well. As a result, <strong>the</strong>y can’teven th<strong>in</strong>k clearly. That’s why <strong>the</strong>y don’t learn. It’s our job to teach<strong>the</strong>m language to make up for <strong>the</strong>ir deficiency. And, s<strong>in</strong>ce <strong>the</strong>irparents don’t really know any language ei<strong>the</strong>r, why should we wastetime on Spanish? It is ‘‘good’’ English which has to be <strong>the</strong> focus.(Walsh, 1991: 107)Could we ask for a clearer or more succ<strong>in</strong>ct statement of <strong>the</strong> ‘deficit’position? The very persistence of such views, more than two decadesafter <strong>the</strong> demonstrations by Labov and his colleagues is noteworthy <strong>in</strong>itself, of course noteworthy and (as Lippi-Green, 1997: 111 observes)


The Persistence of L<strong>in</strong>guistic Deficit 143<strong>in</strong>dicative of ‘how seductive such rhetoric can be’. In any event, it isdeeply disturb<strong>in</strong>g to th<strong>in</strong>k that teachers still approach <strong>the</strong> children <strong>in</strong><strong>the</strong>ir classrooms with this set of warped and warp<strong>in</strong>g assumptions.The disadvantaged children reported on above were Spanish-Englishbil<strong>in</strong>guals, and this is important for at least two reasons. First, as withEdwards and McK<strong>in</strong>non’s (1987) French-speak<strong>in</strong>g youngsters, we arerem<strong>in</strong>ded that l<strong>in</strong>guistic ‘deficits’ are commonly alleged to exist bothwith<strong>in</strong> and across language boundaries. The <strong>in</strong>ner-city black childrenwhose speech was <strong>the</strong> primary focus of both deficit and difference<strong>the</strong>orists were monol<strong>in</strong>gual English speakers, so <strong>the</strong>ir ‘problem’ was at<strong>the</strong> level of dialect. In o<strong>the</strong>r contexts, however with <strong>in</strong>digenous orimmigrant ethnic-m<strong>in</strong>ority children <strong>the</strong> problem is at <strong>the</strong> level oflanguage itself: pupils arrive <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> classroom without a knowledge ofEnglish (for <strong>in</strong>stance). There are, of course, some <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g wheelswith<strong>in</strong>-wheelshere. For <strong>in</strong>stance, many non-English-speak<strong>in</strong>g m<strong>in</strong>oritygroupchildren will be disadvantaged <strong>in</strong> some of <strong>the</strong> ‘classic’ waysoutl<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong> earlier chapters. Because of this, it is very likely that <strong>the</strong>English <strong>the</strong>y soon beg<strong>in</strong> to acquire will not be some standard-like variety;on <strong>the</strong> contrary, it is generally a nonstandard dialect. The potential forjump<strong>in</strong>g from a language fry<strong>in</strong>g-pan <strong>in</strong>to a dialect fire is obvious.Second, we note <strong>the</strong> impression that bil<strong>in</strong>gual children can make on <strong>the</strong>l<strong>in</strong>guistically naïve teacher: <strong>the</strong>y (and <strong>the</strong>ir parents, too) are ‘mixed up’and do not know ei<strong>the</strong>r language very well. Such a misguided perceptionis perhaps more predictable when teachers who know only one language<strong>the</strong>mselves and who live <strong>in</strong> an essentially monol<strong>in</strong>gual environment areconsider<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> competences of children who are at once materiallydisadvantaged and bil<strong>in</strong>gual. But it is not limited to <strong>the</strong>m.The em<strong>in</strong>ent l<strong>in</strong>guist Leonard Bloomfield described a North AmericanIndian <strong>in</strong> this way (Bloomfield, 1927: 437):White Thunder, a man around 40, speaks less English thanMenom<strong>in</strong>i, and that is a strong <strong>in</strong>dictment, for his Menom<strong>in</strong>i isatrocious. His vocabulary is small, his <strong>in</strong>flections are often barbarous,he constructs sentences of a few threadbare models. He may be saidto speak no language tolerably.This is an early illustration of what Hansegård (1968) later described (<strong>in</strong>studies of F<strong>in</strong>nish-Swedish bil<strong>in</strong>guals) as halvspråkighet (‘half-language’).In contemporary usage, <strong>the</strong> term ‘semil<strong>in</strong>gualism’ soon became enlarged:from a solely l<strong>in</strong>guistic description, it went on to atta<strong>in</strong> some prom<strong>in</strong>enceas a catchword with political and ideological overtones. Some categories ofdisadvantaged children, for example <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g those <strong>in</strong> groups just


144 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>touched upon here were seen to be condemned to a life of l<strong>in</strong>guistichalf-light and shadow, because of deficient environments. At its base was<strong>the</strong> notion that l<strong>in</strong>guistic capacity was of some f<strong>in</strong>ite or ‘conta<strong>in</strong>erized’nature; and at its simplest, it implied that what you ga<strong>in</strong> on <strong>the</strong> sw<strong>in</strong>gs ofone language you lose on <strong>the</strong> roundabouts of <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r.Us<strong>in</strong>g a ‘fixed-conta<strong>in</strong>er’ metaphor for language acquisition and skills,however, is problematic. It is rem<strong>in</strong>iscent of <strong>the</strong> old, and now discredited,craniometry axioms that l<strong>in</strong>ked bra<strong>in</strong> size to <strong>in</strong>telligence and even if wewere to admit <strong>the</strong> likelihood of some f<strong>in</strong>ite-capacity model all that weknow of <strong>in</strong>tellectual structures and functions suggests that <strong>the</strong> capacity(for languages, among o<strong>the</strong>r th<strong>in</strong>gs) is large enough that few of us needworry about exceed<strong>in</strong>g our limits. Early <strong>in</strong> his partnership with Watson,Sherlock Holmes expla<strong>in</strong>ed his ignorance of many th<strong>in</strong>gs by say<strong>in</strong>g that<strong>the</strong> bra<strong>in</strong> was like an attic, that one should fill it wisely accord<strong>in</strong>g to one’sneeds. Near <strong>the</strong> beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g of A Study <strong>in</strong> Scarlet, he told his partner that ‘itis a mistake to th<strong>in</strong>k that that little room has elastic walls and can distendto any extent’. There are limits, of course, but Holmes grievouslyunderestimated <strong>the</strong>m. He could easily have remedied his ignorance ofliterature and astronomy without displac<strong>in</strong>g his knowledge of poisons or<strong>the</strong> many varieties of cigarette ash.If <strong>the</strong>re is any credibility at all to <strong>the</strong> idea of ‘semil<strong>in</strong>gualism’, it mustrest upon a ra<strong>the</strong>r rare complex of deprivations. It should certa<strong>in</strong>ly notbe seen as any sort of loom<strong>in</strong>g danger attach<strong>in</strong>g to l<strong>in</strong>guistic duality,for which it represents only ‘a half-baked <strong>the</strong>ory of communicativecompetence’ (Mart<strong>in</strong>-Jones & Roma<strong>in</strong>e, 1985; see also Baetens Beardsmore,1986; Edelsky et al., 1983). It is regrettable, to say <strong>the</strong> least, that <strong>the</strong>notion and <strong>the</strong> underly<strong>in</strong>g assumptions that it is built upon shouldconstitute yet ano<strong>the</strong>r burden for l<strong>in</strong>guistically disadvantaged children.Notes1. Schools are always better thought of as reflections of broader social currentsthan as leaders of enlightened op<strong>in</strong>ion. As we shall see, problems typicallyarise very quickly when teachers are asked to pull aga<strong>in</strong>st <strong>the</strong> tide flow<strong>in</strong>gbeyond <strong>the</strong> school gates.2. Cheshire et al. (1989: 6) note that ‘<strong>the</strong> legacy of Bernste<strong>in</strong> lives on’ and <strong>the</strong>ircollection demonstrates <strong>the</strong> persistence of deficit views among teachers <strong>in</strong>many European countries. Also, a recent number of <strong>Language</strong> and Education<strong>in</strong>cludes a piece by Myhill and Dunk<strong>in</strong> (2005) <strong>in</strong> which reference is made to<strong>the</strong> hypo<strong>the</strong>ses of Bernste<strong>in</strong> and Tough. The reference is only a pass<strong>in</strong>g one,but it appears <strong>in</strong> a list of citations (to Alexander, to Barnes, even to Vygotsky)concern<strong>in</strong>g classroom talk and <strong>the</strong>re is no <strong>in</strong>dication at all that some<strong>in</strong>sights may be more equal than o<strong>the</strong>rs.


The Persistence of L<strong>in</strong>guistic Deficit 145Wiggan (2007 see also note 3) also comments on Bernste<strong>in</strong>’s analyseswithout mak<strong>in</strong>g any critical observations; consequently, <strong>the</strong>y are simplypresented as part of a very long, but very shallow, overview of studies <strong>in</strong><strong>the</strong> area.3. In his very recent overview of educational disadvantage, Wiggan (2007; seealso note 2) also fails to come down strongly on <strong>the</strong> side of environmentaldifference. The author provides a reasonable coverage of both <strong>the</strong> genetic andenvironmental approaches to disadvantage, divid<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> latter <strong>in</strong>to matters of‘social class and cultural poverty, teacher expectancy, and student oppositionalidentity’ (p. 321). He adds to <strong>the</strong>se <strong>the</strong> unfair effects of standardizedtest<strong>in</strong>g. He does not, however, make <strong>the</strong> deficiencies of <strong>the</strong> ‘cultural poverty’assessment clear enough and, <strong>in</strong>deed, notes that ‘it is conceivable that someaspects of all four [orig<strong>in</strong>al] explanations affect student achievement’ (p. 322).Much stronger and less equivocal summaries are needed if we are to fullyembrace <strong>the</strong> different-but-not-deficient explanation for group disadvantagethat I advocate <strong>in</strong> this book.4. I have assembled <strong>the</strong>se comments from <strong>the</strong> back-cover blurbs on Honey (1997).5. Honey’s pamphlet was published by <strong>the</strong> National Council for EducationalStandards, described <strong>in</strong> a note <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Times Higher Education Supplement (2January 1987: 6) as an ‘<strong>in</strong>fluential group of right-w<strong>in</strong>g lobbyists’ (see alsoGraddol & Swann, 1988). Reactionary compla<strong>in</strong>ts about abysmal modernusage are, of course, as eternal as criticisms of <strong>the</strong> ‘younger generation’. Formy own review of Honey’s pamphlet, see Edwards (1983a).6. The second edition of Crowley’s (2003) book extends <strong>the</strong> relevant exchange,<strong>in</strong> a brief discussion of Honey (1997); see also Crowley (1999). Holborow(1999) also presents <strong>the</strong> familiar criticisms of Honey’s position; her espousalof a ra<strong>the</strong>r qua<strong>in</strong>t Marxist perspective, however, means that she has little timefor almost any contemporary l<strong>in</strong>guist.7. Bauer (1998: 8283) touches upon American Indian languages whose verbconstructions make dist<strong>in</strong>ctions between th<strong>in</strong>gs that happened recently andthose that occurred long ago, and between th<strong>in</strong>gs that speakers know<strong>the</strong>mselves and those that <strong>the</strong>y have been told about:In <strong>the</strong>se languages, I would require a different form of <strong>the</strong> verb lose to say<strong>in</strong> 1996 ‘‘England lost to Germany <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> semi-f<strong>in</strong>als’’ and to say <strong>in</strong> 1996‘‘The English lost <strong>the</strong> battle of Hast<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>in</strong> 1066’’. And both of <strong>the</strong>se(which I only know because I have been told so) would require a differentverb from ‘‘I lost my game of Scrabble this afternoon’’, which I know frommy own experience.Bauer goes on to mention that, <strong>in</strong> Maori, <strong>the</strong>re are different pronouns forwe when it refers (on <strong>the</strong> one hand) to ‘you <strong>the</strong> listener and me <strong>the</strong> speaker’and (on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r hand) to ‘me <strong>the</strong> speaker and someone else’ (see also Evans,1998, on Australian aborig<strong>in</strong>al languages).These are just a couple of very simple examples; <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terested reader caneasily f<strong>in</strong>d dictionaries and grammars full of illustrations of <strong>the</strong> complexitiesof ‘primitive’ varieties.


Chapter 8Evaluative Reactions to <strong>the</strong><strong>Language</strong> of Disadvantage<strong>Language</strong> Attitudes and <strong>the</strong> M<strong>in</strong>ority-group ReactionOne of <strong>the</strong> most poignant aspects of <strong>the</strong> social evaluation of language is<strong>the</strong> widely reported tendency for nonstandard speakers to accept andagree with unfavorable stereotypes of <strong>the</strong>ir speech styles. Labov (1976)found, for <strong>in</strong>stance, that those whose speech <strong>in</strong>cludes nonstandard orstigmatized forms are typically <strong>the</strong>ir own harshest critics. This is anexample of what Lambert et al. (1960) called <strong>the</strong> ‘m<strong>in</strong>ority-group reaction’,<strong>in</strong> which <strong>the</strong> perceptions and stereotypes of <strong>the</strong> ‘ma<strong>in</strong>stream’ are acceptedby those outside it. The reaction is, of course, a particular l<strong>in</strong>guisticmanifestation of <strong>the</strong> much broader <strong>in</strong>terplay between social dom<strong>in</strong>anceand subord<strong>in</strong>ation. It is important to note, however, that social relationshipsare dynamic, and that language matters often provide a usefulperspective on change. The black respondents to whom Labov spoke <strong>in</strong><strong>the</strong> 1970s are not <strong>the</strong> same as those <strong>in</strong>terviewed by Ogbu (1999) ageneration later (see below). As we shall see, <strong>the</strong>ir l<strong>in</strong>guistic attitudeshave become more complex: <strong>the</strong>y cont<strong>in</strong>ue to believe that ‘white talk’ is‘proper’, and that Black English Vernacular (BEV) is not, but <strong>the</strong>re is apride <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> use and <strong>the</strong> ‘solidarity functions’ of <strong>the</strong>ir vernacular that wasnot felt or, at least, not expressed, <strong>in</strong> earlier <strong>in</strong>vestigations. 1In 1960, Lambert et al. <strong>in</strong>troduced <strong>the</strong> ‘matched-guise’ technique, amethod of <strong>in</strong>vestigat<strong>in</strong>g reactions to speech variants. Judges evaluate arecorded speaker’s personality, along any dimension of <strong>in</strong>terest, afterhear<strong>in</strong>g him or her read <strong>the</strong> same passage <strong>in</strong> each of two or morelanguages, dialects or accents. The fact that <strong>the</strong> speaker is, for all ‘guises’,<strong>the</strong> same person is not revealed to <strong>the</strong> assessors (who typically do notguess this). S<strong>in</strong>ce any potentially confound<strong>in</strong>g variables (pitch, tone ofvoice and so on) are, of course, constant across <strong>the</strong> ‘guises’, <strong>the</strong> rat<strong>in</strong>gsgiven are considered to more accurately reflect stereotypic reactions to<strong>the</strong> language variety per se than would be <strong>the</strong> case if separate speakersof each l<strong>in</strong>guistic variant were used. (For a brief discussion of some of <strong>the</strong>146


Evaluative Reactions to <strong>the</strong> <strong>Language</strong> of Disadvantage 147criticisms that have been made of <strong>the</strong> ‘matched-guise’ technique, none ofwhich are fatal, see Edwards, 1989.)In this <strong>in</strong>itial study, Lambert and his colleagues were <strong>in</strong>terested <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>reactions of French- and English-speak<strong>in</strong>g Montreal students towardsFrench and English voices. On most of <strong>the</strong> dimensions evaluated(ambition, <strong>in</strong>telligence, sense of humor, etc.), English-speak<strong>in</strong>g judgesreacted more favorably to English guises. Of greater <strong>in</strong>terest, however,were <strong>the</strong> rat<strong>in</strong>gs given by <strong>the</strong> French-speak<strong>in</strong>g raters, for not only did <strong>the</strong>y,too, evaluate <strong>the</strong> English guises more positively than <strong>the</strong>y did <strong>the</strong> Frenchones, <strong>the</strong>y also gave less favorable responses to <strong>the</strong> French guises than didEnglish-speak<strong>in</strong>g judges. The researchers <strong>in</strong>terpreted <strong>the</strong>se f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>gs asevidence of what <strong>the</strong>y <strong>the</strong>n termed a ‘m<strong>in</strong>ority-group reaction’. That is, <strong>the</strong>French-speak<strong>in</strong>g student judges, perceiv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>mselves as subord<strong>in</strong>ate <strong>in</strong>some ways to <strong>the</strong> English-speak<strong>in</strong>g population, apparently adopted (andeven slightly magnified) <strong>the</strong> stereotyped values of this latter group. Britishmatched-guise work lent some support here: Cheyne (1970) found thatboth Scottish and English judges tended to rate Scottish speakers as lower<strong>in</strong> status than <strong>the</strong>ir English counterparts.d’Anglejan and Tucker (1973), <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir study of French dialects, providedfur<strong>the</strong>r confirmation of <strong>the</strong> ‘m<strong>in</strong>ority-group’ effect (not us<strong>in</strong>g matchedguises). When French-Canadian students, teachers and factory workers(more than 200 <strong>in</strong> total) were asked <strong>the</strong>ir op<strong>in</strong>ions of Quebec, Europeanand Parisian French, <strong>the</strong>y rejected <strong>the</strong> idea that Quebec French was <strong>in</strong>feriorto <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r two, or that Parisian French was <strong>the</strong> ‘best’ form of <strong>the</strong>language. Never<strong>the</strong>less, when presented with <strong>the</strong> taped voices of upperclassand lower-class French-Canadian speakers, and European Frenchspeakers, <strong>the</strong> respondents downgraded both Canadian styles <strong>in</strong> terms ofqualities like ambition and <strong>in</strong>telligence; even <strong>in</strong> terms of likeability, <strong>the</strong>European speech style evoked more favorable responses. In 1975,Carranza and Ryan asked Mexican-American and Anglo-Americanstudents (of Spanish) to judge speakers of English and Spanish. Sixteensuch speakers were presented, on tape, talk<strong>in</strong>g about simple domestic orschool events. The personality characteristics to be evaluated broadlyreflected ei<strong>the</strong>r prestige (status) or what <strong>the</strong> researchers termed ‘solidarity’(<strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>g traits like friendl<strong>in</strong>ess, k<strong>in</strong>dness, trustworth<strong>in</strong>ess and so on).Over all judges, English was viewed more favorably when <strong>the</strong> speaker’stopic was school-related, Spanish when it dealt with domestic matters.Fur<strong>the</strong>r, English was reacted to more favorably on both status-related and‘solidarity’ traits. One implication is that a low-prestige language varietymay have more positive connotations <strong>in</strong> terms of qualities like <strong>in</strong>tegrity,social attractiveness and friendl<strong>in</strong>ess than it does when matters of


148 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong><strong>in</strong>telligence, ambition, <strong>in</strong>dustriousness and competence are <strong>the</strong> issue;ano<strong>the</strong>r is that this relationship seems to obta<strong>in</strong> both for members of <strong>the</strong>low-prestige group and for more middle-class speakers. In related work,Ryan and Carranza (1975) found similar results when consider<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>evaluations of standard English and Mexican-accented English made byMexican-American, black and ‘anglo’ speakers: <strong>the</strong> former was assessed ashigher <strong>in</strong> status than <strong>the</strong> latter. In a fur<strong>the</strong>r ref<strong>in</strong>ement, Ryan et al. (1977)found that <strong>the</strong> degree of nonstandardness <strong>in</strong>fluenced judges’ evaluations.Rat<strong>in</strong>gs of Spanish-English bil<strong>in</strong>guals, read<strong>in</strong>g an English passage, showedthat favorability of impressions decreased as degree of Spanish accentedness<strong>in</strong>creased. Studies from <strong>the</strong> same period <strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>g black Americanspeakers are also suggestive. Tucker and Lambert (1969), for example,presented a number of different American English dialect varieties to threegroups of university students nor<strong>the</strong>rn white, sou<strong>the</strong>rn white andsou<strong>the</strong>rn black and found that all groups evaluated standard-Englishspeakers most favorably.The relevant literature here, largely from <strong>the</strong> 1960s and 1970s, whensuch work was at its apogee, is an extensive one and it confirms what hasbeen well understood at a popular level for a long time. The speechpatterns of regional speakers, of ethnic m<strong>in</strong>ority-group members, oflower- or work<strong>in</strong>g-class populations (categories that frequently overlap,of course) elicit negative evaluations, most importantly <strong>in</strong> terms ofperceived status, prestige or ‘educatedness’, and this stereotypic patternseems to hold whe<strong>the</strong>r or not <strong>the</strong> listeners are standard speakers<strong>the</strong>mselves. Some of <strong>the</strong>se early studies, undertaken before <strong>the</strong> morerecent emergence of black or Hispanic ‘pride’, do reveal h<strong>in</strong>ts ofl<strong>in</strong>guistic and psychological developments to come. Flores and Hopper(1975), for <strong>in</strong>stance, found slight preferences on <strong>the</strong> part of Mexican-American judges for <strong>the</strong> speech styles of compañeros who referred to<strong>the</strong>mselves as ‘Chicano’. But it would be naïve to assume that negativelanguage stereotypes are generally wan<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> a broad societal sense. Thefeel<strong>in</strong>g that one’s own speech is not ‘good’ has historically been a verycommon phenomenon <strong>in</strong>deed, for reasons that are as clear as <strong>the</strong>y areunfair. It is a particularly disturb<strong>in</strong>g one, however, when we considerhow easily <strong>the</strong> belief may be exacerbated by those who might beexpected to know better: teachers, for <strong>in</strong>stance. As Halliday (1968: 165)once observed:A speaker who is made ashamed of his own language habits suffers abasic <strong>in</strong>jury as a human be<strong>in</strong>g; to make anyone, especially a child,


Evaluative Reactions to <strong>the</strong> <strong>Language</strong> of Disadvantage 149feel so ashamed is as <strong>in</strong>defensible as to make him feel ashamed of <strong>the</strong>colour of his sk<strong>in</strong>.Some have debated <strong>the</strong> depth of <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>jury here; no enlightened op<strong>in</strong>ion,however, doubts <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>defensibility, <strong>the</strong> unfairness, of <strong>the</strong> process.The reliable <strong>the</strong>atrical tradition, <strong>in</strong> which a comic effect is producedthrough hav<strong>in</strong>g a duchess speak with a Cockney accent, has its moremundane counterparts as well. Indeed, <strong>the</strong> perceived <strong>in</strong>congruity thatproduces comedy on <strong>the</strong> stage and <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> c<strong>in</strong>ema would not be effectivewithout an audience fully alive to <strong>the</strong> powerful social connotations ofl<strong>in</strong>guistic variants. Given that people are aware of negative stereotypes of<strong>the</strong>ir own speech styles and, <strong>in</strong>deed, that <strong>the</strong>y <strong>the</strong>mselves have accepted<strong>the</strong>m <strong>in</strong> many cases, we might ask why low-status speech varietiescont<strong>in</strong>ue to exist. After all, it would seem that a realization of <strong>the</strong>potential limitations, <strong>in</strong> practical terms, of some varieties might lead to<strong>the</strong>ir eradication or, at least, to <strong>the</strong> expansion of <strong>the</strong> l<strong>in</strong>guisticrepertoire, to <strong>the</strong> development of bidialectal capability. We know thatthis is not, <strong>in</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>ciple, a difficult accomplishment. It is very commonamong actors, for example; and, at less <strong>the</strong>atrical levels, <strong>the</strong> process ofselect<strong>in</strong>g from a l<strong>in</strong>guistic pool of possibilities, accord<strong>in</strong>g to perceptionsof <strong>the</strong> sett<strong>in</strong>g, is even more common. It can hardly be alleged, ei<strong>the</strong>r, thatnonstandard speakers are without adequate models for repertoireexpansion. Schoolteachers comprised <strong>the</strong> traditional set of standardshere and, today, <strong>the</strong> pervasive <strong>in</strong>fluence of <strong>the</strong> public media means thatvirtually all nonstandard speakers have at least passive access tostandard forms. Never<strong>the</strong>less, <strong>the</strong> levell<strong>in</strong>g of local speech styles and,more po<strong>in</strong>tedly here, <strong>the</strong> gradual disappearance of low-status variantsthat some had predicted as an <strong>in</strong>evitable consequence of <strong>the</strong> spread of <strong>the</strong>broadcast media, seems not to have occurred.<strong>Language</strong> Attitudes and Group SolidarityAmong his o<strong>the</strong>r contributions, Fishman has always po<strong>in</strong>ted to <strong>the</strong>salience of language attitudes (see, e.g. <strong>the</strong> collection of his papers editedby Hornberger & Pütz, 2006; and his own recent paean to ‘positiveethnol<strong>in</strong>guistic consciousness’: Fishman, 1996). Naturally enough, pride<strong>in</strong> one’s culture often <strong>in</strong>volves affection for <strong>the</strong> language of that culture.L<strong>in</strong>guistic pride and self-confidence can be resurgent when groupspreviously oppressed, discrim<strong>in</strong>ated aga<strong>in</strong>st and thought to be <strong>in</strong>ferior,rediscover a broader social strength and assertion, and this can be as truefor cultural sub-groups and dialects as it is for larger populations andlanguages. Thus, Carranza and Ryan (1975) discussed <strong>the</strong> ‘solidarity’


150 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>function of language <strong>in</strong> contemporary American black and Chicanocontexts. A language or dialect, though it may be lack<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> general socialprestige, may never<strong>the</strong>less function as a powerful bond<strong>in</strong>g agent,provid<strong>in</strong>g a sense of identity. Indeed, it is a social and l<strong>in</strong>guistic factthat any variety can be <strong>the</strong> voice of group identity, a central element <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>revitalized ‘consciousness’ of nonstandard-dialect speakers.But <strong>the</strong> solidarity function of language <strong>the</strong> symbolic role oflanguage, that is to say, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> articulation of group identity is clearlynot restricted to situations <strong>in</strong> which earlier self-denigration has nowgiven way to admiration and allegiance. For we also observe adis<strong>in</strong>cl<strong>in</strong>ation to alter speech styles on <strong>the</strong> parts of groups that seemnot to have experienced any sudden upsurge <strong>in</strong> group pride, and whocont<strong>in</strong>ue to adhere to <strong>the</strong> larger society’s unfavorable stereotypes of <strong>the</strong>irspeech patterns: speakers of low-status dialects of urban British Englishare examples here. Can we put this down to a more generally liberalattitude towards speech variants per se? It is true that views are not asrigid as <strong>the</strong>y once were. The l<strong>in</strong>guistic variation to be found now <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ma<strong>in</strong>stream media is an <strong>in</strong>dication of this, and an even more <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>gdevelopment is <strong>the</strong> ap<strong>in</strong>g of non-ma<strong>in</strong>stream behavior, attitudes andspeech style by certa<strong>in</strong> middle-class constituencies (notably youngpeople: see also <strong>the</strong> discussion of ‘covert prestige’, below). But prejudicialviews obviously persist, even if <strong>the</strong>ir force has lessened <strong>in</strong> some quarters.The solidarity function associated with a common language style,even if it is nonstandard and non-prestigious, is powerful and general.Group identity is a known quantity, and <strong>in</strong> that sense, is safe. Attempts toalter one’s speech style, to jettison a low-status variant, or even to addano<strong>the</strong>r dialectal str<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>the</strong> bow, on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r hand, are riskyundertak<strong>in</strong>gs. Failure may lead to a sense of marg<strong>in</strong>ality, a sense of notbe<strong>in</strong>g a full (and fully accepted) member of any social group. As notedearlier, <strong>the</strong> Mexican American who abandoned Spanish for <strong>the</strong> socioeconomicrewards of English risked be<strong>in</strong>g labeled a vendido, a ‘sell-out’, al<strong>in</strong>guistic quisl<strong>in</strong>g. The <strong>in</strong>dividual who wishes to add, and not to replace,may also fall between stools. The ma<strong>in</strong>tenance of Spanish (language andculture) may exist uneasily alongside <strong>the</strong> acquisition of English,particularly <strong>in</strong> a world <strong>in</strong> which bil<strong>in</strong>gualism is often a way-station on<strong>the</strong> road to a new monol<strong>in</strong>gualism, a world <strong>in</strong> which English <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>glythreatens o<strong>the</strong>r variants (see Edwards, 1994a).This sort of situation is not unrelated to that <strong>in</strong> which talk<strong>in</strong>g ‘posh’ isseen as affectation. Indeed, Bragg and Ellis (1976) reported <strong>the</strong> Cockneyop<strong>in</strong>ion that if a child were to speak ‘posh’, friends would label him (orher, of course) as ‘a queer’. A generation earlier, Orwell (1941: 74)


Evaluative Reactions to <strong>the</strong> <strong>Language</strong> of Disadvantage 151famously observed that ‘nearly every Englishman of work<strong>in</strong>g-classorig<strong>in</strong> considers it effem<strong>in</strong>ate to pronounce foreign words correctly’.Kissau (2006: 415) reports that this attitude apparently persists: Canadiansecondary-school boys report that <strong>the</strong> French classroom is a ‘femaledoma<strong>in</strong>’, and not a place for males. One language teacher observed that‘<strong>the</strong>re’s still a lot of sexist th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g that a man doesn’t learn languages. Aman does math or eng<strong>in</strong>eer<strong>in</strong>g’ (see also Carr & Pauwels, 2006, below).Ogbu (1999) has described how black people <strong>in</strong> West Oakland(California) consider that ‘proper’ English is white English, and thatBEV is poor slang or, less pejoratively, ‘just pla<strong>in</strong> talk<strong>in</strong>’. On fur<strong>the</strong>r<strong>in</strong>vestigation, it is clear that BEV is seen as <strong>the</strong> ord<strong>in</strong>ary vernacular, <strong>the</strong>‘low’ variant <strong>in</strong> a diglossic situation. And Ogbu also f<strong>in</strong>ds that, althoughhis respondents did not articulate <strong>the</strong> notion, <strong>the</strong>y feel caught: <strong>the</strong> BEVthat represents <strong>home</strong>, familiarity and group identity is threatened by <strong>the</strong>mastery of ‘proper’ English, a mastery that is seen as necessary for schooland work success. They believe, <strong>in</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r words, <strong>in</strong> a sort of ‘subtractivebidialectalism’. The ‘dialect dilemma’, <strong>the</strong> belief that <strong>the</strong> necessaryacquisition of standard English will tend to erode <strong>the</strong> vernacular, issometimes re<strong>in</strong>forced by a feel<strong>in</strong>g (both with<strong>in</strong> and without academia)that this process is part of <strong>the</strong> assimilatory <strong>in</strong>tent of ‘ma<strong>in</strong>stream’ schooland society. Ogbu notes that, on <strong>the</strong> one hand, black professionals,advocates, educators and communities endorse <strong>the</strong> learn<strong>in</strong>g of standardEnglish, but <strong>the</strong>n turn around and condemn its acquisition on <strong>the</strong>grounds that it threatens ‘Black English identity and racial solidarity’(Ogbu, 1999: 180).But Ogbu argues that <strong>the</strong> belief may be just that and does not reflectactual practice. After all, a more or less stable bidialectalism is <strong>the</strong> norm <strong>in</strong>many contexts, and it is certa<strong>in</strong>ly part of <strong>the</strong> repertoire of large numbers ofblack Americans. Is <strong>the</strong>re, <strong>the</strong>n, any real dilemma here? Well, it is possible,just as ‘subtractive bil<strong>in</strong>gualism’ is possible where <strong>the</strong> acquisition of anew language gradually ousts an exist<strong>in</strong>g one but, <strong>in</strong> both cases, any‘subtraction’ that occurs is a symptom of larger social forces that makeresistance unlikely to succeed. In <strong>the</strong> case of black American culture andits current pervasiveness well beyond <strong>the</strong> boundaries of <strong>the</strong> blackcommunity itself I should th<strong>in</strong>k that a diglossic relationship betweenBEV and standard English is likely to endure for <strong>the</strong> foreseeable future. Butif a ‘dilemma’ is perceived, it has at least a psychological existence. Ogbu’s<strong>in</strong>formants clearly feel that, when a black person ‘is talk<strong>in</strong>g proper, he orshe is putt<strong>in</strong>’ on [italics added] or pretend<strong>in</strong>g to be white or to talk likewhite people’ (Ogbu, 1999: 171172). They told him that it is ‘<strong>in</strong>sane topretend to be white’, that speak<strong>in</strong>g standard English is a pretence, a fake.


152 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>They don’t actually speak of betrayal of <strong>the</strong> group here, but <strong>the</strong> implicationis pla<strong>in</strong> and quite similar to <strong>the</strong> vendido possibility noted above.Ogbu’s ‘dialect dilemma’ is <strong>the</strong> same phenomenon that Smi<strong>the</strong>rman(2006) discusses under <strong>the</strong> head<strong>in</strong>g of ‘l<strong>in</strong>guistic push-pull’, a l<strong>in</strong>guisticcontradiction whereby black speakers simultaneously embrace BEV anddislike it. ‘On <strong>the</strong> one hand’, she says, ‘Blacks have believed that <strong>the</strong> priceof <strong>the</strong> ticket for Black education and survival and success <strong>in</strong> WhiteAmerica is eradication of Black Talk. On <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r hand, Blacks alsorecognize that language is bound up with Black identity and culture’(Smi<strong>the</strong>rman, 2006: 129). This ‘push-pull’ situation obviously affectsmany nonstandard-language speakers <strong>in</strong> many sett<strong>in</strong>gs. The solution, a<strong>the</strong>oretically plausible bidialectalism by which you can eat yourl<strong>in</strong>guistic cake while still hav<strong>in</strong>g it, is not always easy to ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>.There is ano<strong>the</strong>r very obvious factor that deters some nonstandarddialectspeakers from attempt<strong>in</strong>g to ‘improve’ <strong>the</strong>ir speech styles. If weconsider, for <strong>in</strong>stance, that negative reactions to BEV typically reflectbroader social or racial attitudes, <strong>the</strong>n it follows that, for a black person or any o<strong>the</strong>r member of a ‘visible m<strong>in</strong>ority’ group learn<strong>in</strong>g and us<strong>in</strong>g astandard dialect may not necessarily alter th<strong>in</strong>gs very much. Indeed,<strong>the</strong>re is some suggestion <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> literature that black speakers who sound‘white’ may elicit more negative attitudes. Some early studies by Gilesand Bourhis (1975, 1976) demonstrated this among West Indians <strong>in</strong>Cardiff, and similar observations have been made <strong>in</strong> Canada and <strong>the</strong>USA (see Edwards, 1989).It is not <strong>in</strong>variably <strong>the</strong> case that lower-class speakers consider <strong>the</strong>irown language patterns to be <strong>in</strong>ferior variants. At <strong>the</strong> beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g here,I mentioned how altered social circumstances a reawaken<strong>in</strong>g of group‘pride’ or ‘consciousness’, for <strong>in</strong>stance can lead to altered selfperceptions,<strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g l<strong>in</strong>guistic ones. This process is underl<strong>in</strong>ed by<strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>gly common tendency to exaggerate or heighten, whe<strong>the</strong>rconsciously or not, speech styles that were previously disapproved of.What was once an ‘<strong>in</strong>ferior’ variety goes beyond mere equivalence wi<strong>the</strong>rstwhile ‘better’ forms, and comes to be seen as superior to <strong>the</strong>m: moredirect, more pithy, more animated. In this way, nonstandard speechcomes to possess a new status for its speakers. In a study of blacksecondary-school students, Fordham reports (1999: 272) that BEV is now<strong>the</strong> ‘norm aga<strong>in</strong>st which all o<strong>the</strong>r speech practices are evaluated’;standard English is no longer privileged; <strong>in</strong>deed, ‘it is ‘‘dissed’’(disrespected) and is only ‘‘leased’’ by <strong>the</strong> students on a daily basisfrom n<strong>in</strong>e to three’. There are attractions here, too, for some middle-classand more or less standard-dialect-speak<strong>in</strong>g adolescents, a sort of ‘street


Evaluative Reactions to <strong>the</strong> <strong>Language</strong> of Disadvantage 153prestige’ now associated with BEV <strong>in</strong> popular culture. The attractivenessof nonstandard dialect is not restricted to teenagers, however: <strong>the</strong>re isalso <strong>the</strong> socially broader phenomenon of covert prestige.‘Covert prestige’ rests upon <strong>the</strong> related facts that <strong>the</strong> perceiveddirectness and vibrancy of nonstandard speech are understood as‘macho’ qualities and that mascul<strong>in</strong>ity itself is a favored quantity. Thecont<strong>in</strong>ued existence of nonstandard forms and <strong>the</strong> dis<strong>in</strong>cl<strong>in</strong>ation toabandon <strong>the</strong>m will clearly be streng<strong>the</strong>ned if <strong>the</strong>ir allure crosses groupboundaries. Labov (1977, 2006) commented upon <strong>the</strong> covert-prestigephenomenon <strong>in</strong> New York, contrast<strong>in</strong>g its effects with <strong>the</strong> ‘hypercorrect’usage of nonstandard speakers who may (he suggested) feel l<strong>in</strong>guistically<strong>in</strong>secure about ‘stigmatized’ features of <strong>the</strong>ir dialect, and who mayattempt higher-status speech forms, particularly <strong>in</strong> formal contexts. Infact, <strong>in</strong> sett<strong>in</strong>gs of <strong>the</strong> greatest formality, Labov reported that his lowerclassrespondents’ use of prestige forms actually surpassed that of uppermiddle-classspeakers. Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, when asked about <strong>the</strong>ir customaryl<strong>in</strong>guistic practices, <strong>the</strong> former tended to exaggerate <strong>the</strong>ir use of higherstatusforms. The po<strong>in</strong>t of <strong>in</strong>terest here, of course, is not <strong>the</strong> lack ofaccuracy of such self-reports but, ra<strong>the</strong>r, <strong>the</strong> psychological underp<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>gsthat give rise to <strong>the</strong>m. 2 Of course, <strong>the</strong> downgrad<strong>in</strong>g of personalspeech styles that is revealed by hypercorrection rarely leads to wholesaleabandonment of maternal nonstandard dialects, and it is here that<strong>the</strong> more latent prestige of <strong>the</strong> dialects can be seen as a sort of counterbalance.Work <strong>in</strong> Brita<strong>in</strong> has supplemented and confirmed <strong>the</strong>se f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>gs. In asummary, Trudgill (2000) notes that <strong>the</strong> mascul<strong>in</strong>ity of work<strong>in</strong>g-classspeech may derive from <strong>the</strong> tough or rugged nature of work<strong>in</strong>g-class life;this rests upon evidence assembled much earlier. Trudgill (1972), for<strong>in</strong>stance, had asked respondents <strong>in</strong> Norwich to <strong>in</strong>dicate <strong>the</strong> pronunciations<strong>the</strong>y usually gave to words commonly hav<strong>in</strong>g more than onepronunciation (e.g. <strong>the</strong> word tune may be pronounced ei<strong>the</strong>r tyōōn ortōōn, with <strong>the</strong> former be<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> more ‘prestigious’ variant). While Labovhad found a general tendency for respondents <strong>in</strong> New York to overreport<strong>the</strong> use of higher-status pronunciations, Trudgill’s results <strong>in</strong>dicatedthat males, both work<strong>in</strong>g class and middle class, often claimedto use nonstandard forms even when <strong>the</strong>y did not customarily do. (Thetrans-Atlantic variation, it has been argued, might be <strong>the</strong> result of aweaker assimilation of middle-class norms among members of <strong>the</strong>English work<strong>in</strong>g class, or to Trudgill’s more subtle analyses of sexdifferences.) It seems clear that work<strong>in</strong>g-class, nonstandard forms havean attraction that cuts across class boundaries, and it is this attraction that


154 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>provides <strong>the</strong> covert prestige associated with such forms. S<strong>in</strong>ce it is basedupon associations between nonstandard speech and mascul<strong>in</strong>ity, covertprestige is essentially a male phenomenon. Thus, Labov (2006) notes that<strong>the</strong> positive mascul<strong>in</strong>e connotations of nonstandard speech, for men, donot seem to be balanced by similar positive values for women. Aga<strong>in</strong>, <strong>the</strong>work of Trudgill (1972) <strong>in</strong> Norwich bears this out. Unlike <strong>the</strong>ir malecounterparts, <strong>the</strong> women <strong>in</strong> his studies <strong>the</strong>re tended to claim morestandard usage than <strong>the</strong>y actually employed; see also <strong>the</strong> follow<strong>in</strong>gsection here.A reveal<strong>in</strong>g anecdote <strong>in</strong>dicates <strong>the</strong> cross-boundary attractiveness and,<strong>in</strong>deed, <strong>the</strong> utility of work<strong>in</strong>g-class usage. A few years ago, I was <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>office of a middle-aged, upper-middle-class male American universityprofessor. As <strong>the</strong> head of his department, he was be<strong>in</strong>g pressed by two orthree colleagues (also male) on a current academic matter. He was clearlyunable or unwill<strong>in</strong>g to go along with <strong>the</strong>ir request. After a few m<strong>in</strong>utes ofpolite and ‘educated’ give-and-take, my friend turned to <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs,smiled broadly and exclaimed, ‘Listen boys, you know <strong>the</strong>re a<strong>in</strong>’t no wayI can do it’. His departmental colleagues immediately ceded <strong>the</strong> po<strong>in</strong>t.Fall<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>to this nonstandard pattern was a signal of directness andfirmness, of an egalitarian <strong>in</strong>formality, of <strong>the</strong> truth. The essence here lies<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> perceived contrast between no-nonsense usage, on <strong>the</strong> one hand,and <strong>in</strong>flated and often evasive language, on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r: straight shoot<strong>in</strong>gversus humbug or, more frankly, bullshit. The latter has now become<strong>the</strong> object of <strong>in</strong>creased scholarly scrut<strong>in</strong>y (see Frankfurt, 2005; and, formore ‘popular’ treatments, Penny, 2005, and Webb, 2005).Gender MattersThe mascul<strong>in</strong>ity of nonstandard usage that Labov reported <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>American context is, <strong>in</strong> some sense, <strong>the</strong> mirror image of <strong>the</strong> unfavorableconnotations <strong>the</strong> ‘poshness’, <strong>the</strong> ‘effem<strong>in</strong>acy’ of higher-status speechstyles. Work<strong>in</strong>g-class perceptions here, as reported by Bragg, Ellis andOrwell (see above), are re<strong>in</strong>forced by <strong>the</strong> covert prestige that <strong>in</strong>fluencesmiddle-class speakers. Attitud<strong>in</strong>al dynamics underp<strong>in</strong>ned by conceptionsof <strong>the</strong> mascul<strong>in</strong>ity or fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>ity of speech styles are oftenparticularly notable at school. They extend beyond dialects, too. Thus,as Carr and Pauwels (2006: 1) note <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir open<strong>in</strong>g sentence, ‘from <strong>the</strong>moment when foreign language study becomes optional, classroomsacross <strong>the</strong> English-dom<strong>in</strong>ant communities of <strong>the</strong> world are <strong>in</strong>habitedprimarily by girls and staffed predom<strong>in</strong>antly by women: boys for <strong>the</strong>most part disappear’, and <strong>the</strong>y go on to discuss <strong>the</strong> ‘gendered shape’ of


Evaluative Reactions to <strong>the</strong> <strong>Language</strong> of Disadvantage 155language learn<strong>in</strong>g at school. They embed <strong>the</strong>ir f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> broadereducational context <strong>in</strong> which boys are gradually becom<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> gender ofconcern because <strong>the</strong>y are more un<strong>in</strong>terested, disaffected and disadvantaged.Sommers (2000) provides a more polemical treatment of thisbroader context; see also He<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g-Boynton and Haitema (2007) andL<strong>in</strong>dsay and Muijs (2006), as well as <strong>the</strong> discussions of boys’ attitudes <strong>in</strong><strong>the</strong> Ebonics section, below. Ew<strong>in</strong>g (2006) and Younger and Warr<strong>in</strong>gton(2006) provide some cautionary notes, based on analyses <strong>in</strong> Russian,British and o<strong>the</strong>r European sett<strong>in</strong>gs.It would seem obvious that <strong>the</strong> mascul<strong>in</strong>e directness that is <strong>the</strong> basis ofcovert prestige would be less attractive to girls and women. Indeed, <strong>the</strong>yare generally found to be more disposed towards standard, middle-classstyles; a ‘classic’ study here is that of Fischer (1958). Thus, <strong>the</strong>y have beenseen by some to produce ‘politer’ and more ‘correct’ speech than do <strong>the</strong>irmale counterparts. A greater l<strong>in</strong>guistic <strong>in</strong>security among women hasoften been considered central here, an <strong>in</strong>security that may rest upon amore pronounced status-consciousness, coupled with a traditional lackof social def<strong>in</strong>ition for women (as opposed to men, with occupationaldef<strong>in</strong>itions to susta<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>m; see Labov, 2006; Trudgill 1972, 2000). Lateranalyses have, unsurpris<strong>in</strong>gly, suggested that <strong>the</strong> picture is ra<strong>the</strong>r morecomplicated than that; beyond <strong>the</strong> well-known general work of Brownand Lev<strong>in</strong>son (1987) ano<strong>the</strong>r so-called ‘classic’ <strong>the</strong>re are valuable andmore recent summaries by Coates (1996, 2004), Crawford (1995) andHolmes (1995). Mills (2003) provides an <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g discussion that<strong>in</strong>terweaves considerations of ‘politeness’ and ‘nonstandardness’ with<strong>in</strong><strong>the</strong> context of social power and its negotiation. Lakoff’s (1975) importantwork on women’s language has now been supplemented by discussionsof men’s language (Coates, 2003; Johnson & Me<strong>in</strong>hof, 1997); and Watts(2003) and Hickey and Stewart (2005) place <strong>the</strong> topic <strong>in</strong> broadestperspective, go<strong>in</strong>g beyond gender contexts per se. Salkie (2004: 29) hasrecently noted that ‘politeness is what <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> language field we call aWhelk (What every l<strong>in</strong>guist knows)’, and it is certa<strong>in</strong>ly <strong>the</strong> case thatstudies <strong>in</strong> politeness and its ramifications have <strong>in</strong>creased dramatically <strong>in</strong><strong>the</strong> last two decades. What is more important, however, as revealed <strong>in</strong><strong>the</strong> approaches of several of <strong>the</strong> books just cited, is that studies of genderand-languagerelationships particularly those bear<strong>in</strong>g upon differentialusage of ‘correct’ or ‘standard’ speech are now <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>gly likely totreat both genders under <strong>the</strong> same roof. This is a welcome developmentfrom earlier work, <strong>in</strong> which <strong>the</strong> language of one gender was taken as abasel<strong>in</strong>e from which to assess that of <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r: need I specify which wasdeemed to set <strong>the</strong> general basel<strong>in</strong>e?


156 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>A study by Edwards (1979a) tested some of <strong>the</strong> implications oflanguage perceptions and prestige <strong>in</strong> a group of prepubertal children.Physiological sex differences relat<strong>in</strong>g to speech production are, of course,not very marked <strong>in</strong> such children, but earlier work had confirmed whatcommon-sense knows: on <strong>the</strong> basis of speech samples alone, listeners cantypically dist<strong>in</strong>guish boys from girls with a high degree of accuracy; seeMeditch (1975), Sachs (1975), Sachs et al. (1973) and We<strong>in</strong>berg and Bennett,(1971). It is children’s early adherence to social norms concern<strong>in</strong>g maleand female speech that allows such accuracy <strong>in</strong> sex-identification. In mystudy, voice samples of 20 work<strong>in</strong>g-class and 20 middle-class 10-year-oldswere presented to 14 adult judges (Irish tra<strong>in</strong>ee teachers) whose task was,simply, to identify <strong>the</strong> gender of each speaker. As well, five o<strong>the</strong>r judgeswere asked to rate all <strong>the</strong> voices on four dimensions related tomascul<strong>in</strong>ity/fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>ity.It was found, first of all, that for both boys and girls <strong>the</strong> voices ofwork<strong>in</strong>g-class children were perceived as rougher and more mascul<strong>in</strong>ethan those of <strong>the</strong>ir middle-class counterparts; that is, <strong>the</strong> associationbetween mascul<strong>in</strong>ity and work<strong>in</strong>g-class speech that I have alreadydiscussed was confirmed. As <strong>in</strong> previous work, <strong>the</strong>re was a high overalldegree of accuracy <strong>in</strong> sex-identification (about 84%, <strong>in</strong> fact), but <strong>the</strong> majorf<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g of <strong>the</strong> study, one that fur<strong>the</strong>r supports notions of covert prestige,was that <strong>the</strong> errors made were not randomly distributed. First of all,female judges were more accurate than <strong>the</strong>ir male counterparts <strong>in</strong>identify<strong>in</strong>g children’s gender. This accords with Meditch’s (1975) resultsand, more importantly, with both scholarly and <strong>in</strong>formal observations offemales’ greater sensitivity <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>terpersonal relationships <strong>in</strong> general, and<strong>in</strong> verbal <strong>in</strong>teractions <strong>in</strong> particular. Secondly, beyond <strong>the</strong> differentialaccuracy of male and female judge-listeners, a significant <strong>in</strong>teraction wasfound <strong>in</strong> terms of errors made between social class and gender. Thatis, among <strong>the</strong> work<strong>in</strong>g-class children, few boys were mistaken as girls,but errors made about girls were considerably greater. For <strong>the</strong> middleclasschildren, <strong>the</strong> pattern was reversed, and more errors were made with<strong>the</strong> boys than with <strong>the</strong> girls.The explanation provided for <strong>the</strong>se results can be briefly summarizedhere. It would appear as if <strong>the</strong> general mascul<strong>in</strong>ity of work<strong>in</strong>g-classspeech caused girls to be misidentified as boys by <strong>the</strong> middle-classjudges. Middle-class speech, relatively more fem<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>e, allowed <strong>the</strong>operation of what we might term <strong>the</strong> ‘boys sound like girls’ pr<strong>in</strong>ciple.This reflects <strong>the</strong> fact that, at puberty, it is boys’ speech that changes mostmarkedly <strong>in</strong> assum<strong>in</strong>g adult characteristics. Different social conventionsoperate for work<strong>in</strong>g-class and middle-class speech, young children are


Evaluative Reactions to <strong>the</strong> <strong>Language</strong> of Disadvantage 157aware of <strong>the</strong>se, and this awareness is exemplified, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir own speechpatterns, by adherence to <strong>the</strong> appropriate norms. Differential accuracy <strong>in</strong><strong>the</strong> identification of children’s gender can <strong>the</strong>n be seen as a consequenceof <strong>the</strong>se social processes.Teachers’ Views of ‘Disadvantaged’ <strong>Language</strong>In an early Irish study (Edwards, 1974), 24 teachers of disadvantagedDubl<strong>in</strong> children provided <strong>in</strong>formation about <strong>the</strong>ir pupils via questionnairesand <strong>in</strong>terviews. In addition, each teacher was given a list of 10traits commonly associated with disadvantaged children <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> literature,and was asked to rank <strong>the</strong>se <strong>in</strong> order of importance as useful andaccurate descriptions of disadvantage. On this rank<strong>in</strong>g task, ‘poorlanguage ability’ was ranked second <strong>in</strong> importance; only ‘poor liv<strong>in</strong>gconditions’ were perceived to be of greater salience when consider<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>problems of <strong>the</strong> disadvantaged child. Dur<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terviews, too, manyteachers mentioned language difficulties of various k<strong>in</strong>ds as an importantaspect of <strong>the</strong>ir view of disadvantage. And <strong>the</strong> questionnaire datarevealed that, overall, teachers reported 28% of <strong>the</strong> pupils (310 <strong>in</strong> total) ashav<strong>in</strong>g difficulties associated with language; of <strong>the</strong>se, about threequarterswere of <strong>the</strong> ‘poor vocabulary’ or ‘poor self-expression’ type.In a subsequent <strong>in</strong>vestigation (Edwards, 1977b), speech samples wererecorded from 20 work<strong>in</strong>g-class and 20 middle-class Dubl<strong>in</strong> boys (wi<strong>the</strong>qual numbers taken from primary and fifth-level classes). All <strong>the</strong>children were, on <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>formation of <strong>the</strong>ir teachers, average students.Adult middle-class judges were <strong>the</strong>n asked to evaluate <strong>the</strong> children’s<strong>in</strong>telligence, fluency, vocabulary, general voice quality (e.g. pronunciationand <strong>in</strong>tonation) and communicative ability. On all measures, <strong>the</strong>more disadvantaged children were viewed less favorably than <strong>the</strong>irmiddle-class counterparts. In <strong>in</strong>terpret<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> results, I reasoned that <strong>the</strong>lower rat<strong>in</strong>gs received on fluency and communication might well reflect‘poorer’ performance, if <strong>the</strong> norms of <strong>the</strong> middle-class judges were taken<strong>in</strong>to account; for <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r measures, however especially that of voicequality we are presumably see<strong>in</strong>g more subjective impressions. These,<strong>in</strong> turn, reflect what we can, by now, understand to be pervasive socialstereotypes that may have noth<strong>in</strong>g to do with <strong>in</strong>tr<strong>in</strong>sic voice elements.S<strong>in</strong>ce <strong>the</strong>se sorts of f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>gs have been widely replicated across a rangeof contexts, it is as well to consider what <strong>the</strong>y suggest. They <strong>in</strong>dicate thatteachers are, naturally enough, concerned about children’s speech andlanguage and s<strong>in</strong>ce <strong>the</strong>y are obviously not isolated from broader socialperspectives <strong>the</strong>y tend to see <strong>the</strong> speech of disadvantaged children as


158 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong><strong>in</strong>accurate, sloppy and likely to reflect lowered achievement potential. Itwould be wrong, of course, to assume that such views are set <strong>in</strong> stone, thatteachers’ expectations cannot be revised. 3 It is also important to rememberthat, while language is a central feature of personality (and perceptions ofpersonality), it is not <strong>the</strong> only one. Teachers are constantly <strong>in</strong>teract<strong>in</strong>g withchildren, come to have access to a variety of <strong>in</strong>formation about <strong>the</strong>m, andcan <strong>the</strong>refore <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>gly place speech <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> context of o<strong>the</strong>r variables. Alater <strong>in</strong>vestigation (Edwards, 1979b; see below) found, for <strong>in</strong>stance, thatteachers evaluat<strong>in</strong>g children (on <strong>the</strong> basis of speech samples alone) quiterightly had reservations about how well impressions would stand up once<strong>the</strong>y had fur<strong>the</strong>r <strong>in</strong>formation about <strong>the</strong> children. We should always bear <strong>in</strong>m<strong>in</strong>d, <strong>the</strong>n, that ‘language studies’ typically deal with only one aspect ofchildren’s behavior and, fur<strong>the</strong>r, that <strong>the</strong> speech samples to be assessed areoften presented <strong>in</strong> disembodied and somewhat artificial forms. Allow<strong>in</strong>g,however, for <strong>the</strong> possibility of l<strong>in</strong>guistic tunnel vision, <strong>the</strong> weight ofevidence from many sources suggests <strong>the</strong> great importance of speech andlanguage per se, as well as <strong>the</strong>ir <strong>in</strong>tertw<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>gs with o<strong>the</strong>r aspects ofchildren’s abilities, behavior and attitude. Whe<strong>the</strong>r alone or <strong>in</strong> comb<strong>in</strong>ation,language matters are often pivotal elements <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> perceptions andassessments made of children (and not only children, of course).A relevant demonstration is found <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> work of Seligman et al. (1972).In addition to consider<strong>in</strong>g reactions to voice alone, student teachers werealso provided with photographs of <strong>the</strong> children, <strong>the</strong>ir draw<strong>in</strong>gs andwritten compositions. The researchers had, <strong>in</strong> fact, selected and comb<strong>in</strong>edsuch <strong>in</strong>formation (collected from third-grade boys <strong>in</strong> Montreal, andsubjected to pre-test evaluation) so that <strong>the</strong> work of eight ‘hypo<strong>the</strong>tical’children could be presented to <strong>the</strong> teacher-judges. All possible comb<strong>in</strong>ationsof ‘good’ and ‘poor’ voices, photographs and draw<strong>in</strong>gs/compositionswere represented <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>se eight composites. Seligman and hiscolleagues found that all types of <strong>in</strong>formation <strong>in</strong>fluenced <strong>the</strong> rat<strong>in</strong>gs: boyswho had better voices, who looked <strong>in</strong>telligent and who had producedgood compositions and draw<strong>in</strong>gs were all judged to be more <strong>in</strong>telligent,better students and so on. S<strong>in</strong>ce speech style seemed always to be animportant factor <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> evaluations made, <strong>the</strong> study supports <strong>the</strong>contention that, even <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> presence of o<strong>the</strong>r <strong>in</strong>formation, languageacts as a central cue. The authors express <strong>the</strong> concern that animates allresearchers: teachers may make serious judgments based upon <strong>in</strong>formationthat may be irrelevant to considerations of children’s ability andscholastic potential. (See also ano<strong>the</strong>r early experiment this one byPiché et al. [1977] <strong>in</strong> which <strong>the</strong> contribution of speech factors to judges’assessments was ra<strong>the</strong>r more complicated. There were methodological


Evaluative Reactions to <strong>the</strong> <strong>Language</strong> of Disadvantage 159differences between <strong>the</strong> two <strong>in</strong>vestigations, however, and <strong>the</strong> Piché study<strong>in</strong>volved black children: an important variation.)Evidence of <strong>the</strong> possible scope of <strong>the</strong> relationship between teacherrat<strong>in</strong>gs and speech style was provided <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Hawaiian study by Choyand Dodd (1976) already noted (<strong>in</strong> Chapter 6). When asked to rateprimary-school children who spoke ei<strong>the</strong>r standard or nonstandardvarieties of English, teachers consistently favored <strong>the</strong> former. Thesechildren were seen to be more confident, better at school, less ‘disruptive’<strong>in</strong> class and likely to achieve greater academic and social success. But <strong>the</strong>assessors were also will<strong>in</strong>g to go well beyond school-related matters, tomake predictions about more general social capabilities: judgments ofhow happy <strong>the</strong> children’s marriages would likely be, for example. Auseful summary discussion of this expansive evaluation is that of Rossand Nisbett (1991). They note that <strong>the</strong> tendency to account for behaviorand its consequences <strong>in</strong> terms of <strong>in</strong>ternal traits of <strong>the</strong> ‘actor’ ra<strong>the</strong>r thanexternal or ‘situational’ factors (<strong>the</strong>y call it a ‘dispositional’ tendency) isso strong that ‘people will make confident trait-based predictions on asmall evidence base’ (Ross & Nisbett, 1991: 124).Williams and his colleagues conducted an important series of studies<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> 1970s; collectively, <strong>the</strong>se comprise one of <strong>the</strong> most comprehensiveand susta<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong>vestigations of disadvantaged speech <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Americancontext. The work builds from <strong>the</strong> familiar observation that manyevaluations rest upon stereotypes elicited by <strong>the</strong> speech samples presentedto judges. Whereas previous work had ei<strong>the</strong>r focused upon <strong>the</strong> operationof <strong>the</strong> evaluation process per se (e.g. <strong>the</strong> Montreal studies of Lambert andhis colleagues) or on <strong>the</strong> isolation of <strong>the</strong> features or characteristics ofspeech most important <strong>in</strong> that process (e.g. <strong>the</strong> work by Labov, Trudgilland o<strong>the</strong>rs on speech-status markers), Williams was concerned with both(see Williams, 1970a). In a study of black and white primary-schoolchildren, Williams (1970b) asked Chicago teachers (white or black<strong>the</strong>mselves) to rate <strong>the</strong> pupils on a number of semantic-differential scales:<strong>the</strong> dimensions <strong>in</strong>cluded fluency, complexity of sentences, reticence andpronunciation, but <strong>the</strong>re were also scales that asked for judgments aboutfamily socioeconomic status, degree of disadvantage and standardnessor nonstandardness of speech. Factor analysis of <strong>the</strong> rat<strong>in</strong>gs suggestedtwo important <strong>the</strong>mes. One of <strong>the</strong>se, labelled ‘confidence/eagerness’,reflected children’s perceived confidence and social status. The o<strong>the</strong>r wasalso associated with social-status judgments, relat<strong>in</strong>g ma<strong>in</strong>ly to perceptionsof ethnicity and <strong>the</strong> nonstandardness or standardness of speech:unsurpris<strong>in</strong>gly, it was labelled ‘ethnicity/nonstandardness’. The argument,<strong>the</strong>n, is that teachers evaluated <strong>the</strong> speech samples (and <strong>the</strong>


160 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>children) along two broad dimensions; one of <strong>the</strong>se appears to relate toethnicity and ethnic, nonstandard speech patterns, while <strong>the</strong> secondreflects relatively personal attributes of children <strong>the</strong>mselves. As to <strong>the</strong>specific speech cues elicit<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> teachers’ reactions, Williams identified anumber of types: frequency of paus<strong>in</strong>g, for example, was found to benegatively related to confidence rat<strong>in</strong>gs, and nonstandard grammaticalvariants (as found <strong>in</strong> BEV: see above) were associated with evaluationsalong <strong>the</strong> ethnicity/nonstandardness dimension.In an expanded study, Williams et al. (1972) probed <strong>the</strong> evaluationsmade of low- and middle-status black, white and Mexican-Americanchildren by teachers <strong>in</strong> Texas. They confirmed <strong>the</strong> previously establishedtwo-factor model of teachers’ judgments, and <strong>the</strong> f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>gs that childrenof low socioeconomic status are considered more ‘ethnic/nonstandard’and are viewed less favorably on variables underp<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> ‘confidence/eagerness’dimension. With<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> low-status category, whitechildren were seen more positively, and as less ‘ethnic/nonstandard’than were <strong>the</strong> black and Mexican-American pupils. Williams and hiscolleagues also found that <strong>the</strong> teachers’ evaluations of <strong>the</strong> actual childrenrepresent<strong>in</strong>g each of <strong>the</strong> ethnic groups <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> study correlated reasonablywell with <strong>the</strong>ir more general semantic-differential evaluations of <strong>the</strong>three groups (when <strong>the</strong>se were presented to <strong>the</strong>m via simple writtenlabels). This led <strong>the</strong> authors to suggest that, <strong>in</strong> rat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual child,teachers may be fulfill<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>ir own, more general expectations. Theyalso note that black and white teachers’ perceptions were remarkablysimilar. This important f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g suggests that speech evaluations easilygeneralize across ethnic and class boundaries, and may reflect whatmany have seen as <strong>the</strong> rapid <strong>in</strong>ternalization of ‘ma<strong>in</strong>stream’ social valuesby members of relatively non-prestigious groups who move <strong>in</strong>to thatma<strong>in</strong>stream wholly, partially or, <strong>in</strong>deed, <strong>in</strong> posse.Fur<strong>the</strong>r Ref<strong>in</strong>ements <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Study of ‘Disadvantaged’<strong>Language</strong>Social psychologists have generally <strong>in</strong>vestigated language perceptionsdirectly (by f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g, for <strong>in</strong>stance, appropriate representatives of each of<strong>the</strong> speech varieties to be <strong>in</strong>vestigated) or <strong>in</strong>directly (<strong>the</strong> classic <strong>in</strong>directapproach has been Lambert’s ‘matched-guise’ technique; see above). Inboth <strong>the</strong> direct and <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>direct approaches, speech samples are often‘pre-tested’ by an appropriate group of judges, so as to ensure that <strong>the</strong>ydo <strong>in</strong>deed reflect <strong>the</strong> proper group. These sorts of studies have produceda sizeable body of evidence bear<strong>in</strong>g on social perceptions, stereotypes


Evaluative Reactions to <strong>the</strong> <strong>Language</strong> of Disadvantage 161and language attitudes. We can now predict with some confidence whatsorts of reactions will be elicited when people hear varieties of BlackEnglish, Newfoundland English, Cockney, ‘Received Pronunciation’,Boston Brahm<strong>in</strong> English and many o<strong>the</strong>rs.Attitudes are dynamic and not static, of course. This suggests (amongo<strong>the</strong>r th<strong>in</strong>gs) that <strong>in</strong>vestigations must be repeated from time to time <strong>in</strong>order to pick up any changes. A recent example here is provided byFabricius (2006: 119120), who po<strong>in</strong>ts out that ‘Received Pronunciation’(RP: traditionally <strong>the</strong> highest-status variety <strong>in</strong> England) is sometimesstigmatized. Its speakers may be perceived as ‘posh’ or ‘snobbish’(a longstand<strong>in</strong>g view, as we have already seen) and <strong>the</strong>ir accents asreflective of an ‘elitist discoursal stance’. Young people <strong>in</strong> particular, it issuggested, are now likely to repudiate ‘attitudes that susta<strong>in</strong>ed accentprejudice’.Accents and dialects change, too. Even <strong>the</strong> Queen’s English has alteredover <strong>the</strong> last half-century; it now shows some <strong>in</strong>fluences of ‘EstuaryEnglish’, a comb<strong>in</strong>ation of London work<strong>in</strong>g-class speech and RP, firstdescribed by Rosewarne (1984, 1994). Analyz<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> Queen’s vowelsounds over four decades of her annual Christmas messages, Harr<strong>in</strong>gtonet al. (2000: 927) found significant changes, evidence of a ‘drift <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>Queen’s accent towards one that is characteristic of speakers who areyounger and/or lower <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> social hierarchy’. Her accent has movedcloser to what <strong>the</strong> authors style ‘standard sou<strong>the</strong>rn British’, although itrema<strong>in</strong>s ‘clearly set apart’ from it. Besides rais<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>trigu<strong>in</strong>g notionthat <strong>the</strong> Queen no longer speaks <strong>the</strong> Queen’s English <strong>the</strong> way she oncedid, <strong>the</strong> import of <strong>the</strong>se studies is a bit broader. It is one th<strong>in</strong>g to describe<strong>the</strong> rise and appeal of <strong>the</strong> new estuar<strong>in</strong>e accent among younger speakers,but it is ano<strong>the</strong>r to show its effects upon exist<strong>in</strong>g speakers, especially RPspeakers. The fact that <strong>the</strong> speech of <strong>the</strong> Queen herself is <strong>in</strong>fluenced bychange suggests that, for more ‘ord<strong>in</strong>ary’ <strong>in</strong>dividuals, <strong>the</strong> alterations arelikely to be greater. As Harr<strong>in</strong>gton et al. (2000: 927) conclude, ‘<strong>the</strong> extentof such... <strong>in</strong>fluences is probably more marked for most adult speakers,who are not <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> position of hav<strong>in</strong>g to defend a particular form ofEnglish’ to which we might add that <strong>the</strong>y also live <strong>in</strong> ra<strong>the</strong>r closerproximity to those <strong>in</strong>fluences than does Elizabeth R.As part of this little digression, it may be useful here to make a po<strong>in</strong>tabout term<strong>in</strong>ology. While common usage refers to language-attitudestudies, most are actually studies of belief. If, for example, you assessresponses to questions like ‘How <strong>in</strong>telligent do you th<strong>in</strong>k this speaker is?’or ‘How fluent is this speaker?’, you may f<strong>in</strong>d out what <strong>the</strong> respondentbelieves. It would take fur<strong>the</strong>r prob<strong>in</strong>g to add <strong>the</strong> affective or emotional


162 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>dimension to <strong>the</strong> cognitive one reflected <strong>in</strong> belief, and such an additionis needed for a fuller attitud<strong>in</strong>al evaluation. The po<strong>in</strong>t becomes clearer ifwe consider more broadly based <strong>in</strong>vestigations. In many languagestudies, for <strong>in</strong>stance, it is common to elicit responses to questions like‘How important is a knowledge of French for you (your children, thiscommunity, etc.)?’ Clearly, one might feel that such knowledge wasextremely important while, at <strong>the</strong> same time, heartily dislik<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>language, its speakers and <strong>the</strong> necessity to learn it (see also Goot, 1993,on <strong>the</strong> degree of ‘passion’ underp<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g respondents’ rat<strong>in</strong>gs).If we concerned ourselves more directly with fully fleshed attitudes,ra<strong>the</strong>r than <strong>the</strong> beliefs commonly <strong>in</strong>dicated by check-marks on scales,we might beg<strong>in</strong> to f<strong>in</strong>d out more about <strong>the</strong> reasons beh<strong>in</strong>d judges’evaluations. Recent developments <strong>in</strong> ‘perceptual dialectology’ arerelevant here. The term, particularly associated with <strong>the</strong> work of Prestonand his associates, reflects a sort of marriage between <strong>the</strong> study of dialectvariation and ‘folk l<strong>in</strong>guistics’ (i.e. popular language attitudes, beliefsand stereotypes), so as to tap <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> subjective ‘real-world’ perceptionsthat are often at variance with scholarly <strong>in</strong>sight, and usually much moreimportant. The data-collection methods used go well beyond structured<strong>in</strong>terviews, questionnaires and <strong>the</strong> like: <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>tention is to allowrespondents to more fully contextualize <strong>the</strong>ir po<strong>in</strong>ts of view (Preston,1989, 1999; see also Long & Preston, 2002; Niedzielski & Preston, 2000).For fur<strong>the</strong>r comments on <strong>the</strong> desirability of broader evaluation exercises,see Edwards (1982), Palozzi (2006), and below.Beyond predict<strong>in</strong>g differential reactions to dialect varieties, we canalso make predictions about those varieties produced by non-nativespeakers of English that show <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>fluence of <strong>the</strong> first language. Weunderstand, at a general level, how <strong>the</strong>se reactions come about, vial<strong>in</strong>guistic ‘trigger<strong>in</strong>g’, and how <strong>the</strong>y reflect a set of stereotypical attitudes(or beliefs, at any rate) that listeners have of speakers. Investigators havenot, however, gone very much beyond fairly gross explanations; that is,<strong>the</strong>y have typically not related speech evaluations to particular speechattributes. Thus, although hundreds of experiments have revealednegative reactions towards BEV (for example), we have very little<strong>in</strong>formation relat<strong>in</strong>g specific l<strong>in</strong>guistic attributes of that variety to suchreactions. These could plausibly <strong>in</strong>clude pronunciation patterns, particulargrammatical constructions, dialect-specific lexical items, or anycomb<strong>in</strong>ation of <strong>the</strong>se and o<strong>the</strong>r factors.In o<strong>the</strong>r words, <strong>the</strong> simultaneous consideration of both evaluation and<strong>the</strong> cues trigger<strong>in</strong>g it advocated, and to some extent acted upon, byWilliams and his colleagues has not attracted a great deal of research


Evaluative Reactions to <strong>the</strong> <strong>Language</strong> of Disadvantage 163<strong>in</strong>terest. Social psychology has <strong>in</strong>terested itself <strong>in</strong> non-l<strong>in</strong>guistic featuresthat may stimulate or <strong>in</strong>fluence evaluative reactions: matters of context,topic and salience, as well as degrees of emotionality, humor andabstraction, have figured <strong>in</strong> many studies. The closest approach, perhaps,to <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>vestigation of l<strong>in</strong>guistic elements is found <strong>in</strong> work on levels offormality/<strong>in</strong>formality. It is also true that Giles and Ryan (1982: 210) madean argument for ‘more detailed l<strong>in</strong>guistic and acoustic descriptions of <strong>the</strong>stimulus voices as well as exam<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> relative evaluative salience of<strong>the</strong>se particulars for different types of listeners’, and Rob<strong>in</strong>son (1985) alsoargued for improved collaboration between social psychology andl<strong>in</strong>guistics. A related, although not so po<strong>in</strong>ted, observation was madeby Edwards (1982), <strong>in</strong> call<strong>in</strong>g for fuller prob<strong>in</strong>g of <strong>the</strong> reasons beh<strong>in</strong>djudges’ evaluative decisions. In general, though, social psychologistshave done little <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> way of isolat<strong>in</strong>g ‘l<strong>in</strong>guistic and acoustic’ variablesand relat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>m to evaluative judgments. This is hardly surpris<strong>in</strong>g, forsuch work is simply not <strong>the</strong>ir métier.Recent l<strong>in</strong>guistic research has dealt with features that characterize anddifferentiate language varieties, and some has focused on those verysocial-class and ethnic varieties that are of particular <strong>in</strong>terest and concernhere. Laver and Trudgill’s (1979) chapter on ‘social markers’ rema<strong>in</strong>s auseful reference, alert<strong>in</strong>g us to such phenomena as:. <strong>the</strong> nasality habitually associated with some varieties of English(RP, for example);. <strong>the</strong> wide dialectal variations <strong>in</strong> consonant pronunciation: thus, RPspeakers pronounce lock and loch more or less identically, with af<strong>in</strong>al /k/, but (some) Scottish pronunciations <strong>in</strong>volve f<strong>in</strong>al /x/. Togive ano<strong>the</strong>r example, British English pronunciation of <strong>the</strong> postvocalic/r/ <strong>in</strong> words like cart and mar is <strong>in</strong>versely related to socialclassstatus, whereas <strong>in</strong> some varieties of American English (<strong>in</strong>New York, for <strong>in</strong>stance) a positive correlation exists between /r/-pronunciation and status;. grammatical variation (e.g. copula deletion <strong>in</strong> BEV: thus, standardEnglish <strong>the</strong>y are go<strong>in</strong>g becomes <strong>the</strong>y go<strong>in</strong>g);. lexical differences (e.g. some English speakers brew <strong>the</strong>ir tea, somemash it, some let it steep, some let it set, and so on).If, however, l<strong>in</strong>guists have been <strong>the</strong> ones to describe such variation, <strong>the</strong>yhave ei<strong>the</strong>r been relatively un<strong>in</strong>terested <strong>in</strong> its relation to differences <strong>in</strong>social rat<strong>in</strong>gs or have simply assumed that <strong>the</strong> more obvious and salientl<strong>in</strong>guistic markers are <strong>the</strong> relevant triggers. Like social psychologists,l<strong>in</strong>guists too have generally stuck to <strong>the</strong>ir lasts. (There are some notable


164 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>exceptions: see, aga<strong>in</strong>, Laver and Trudgill [1979], as well as Graff et al.[1983].)We would benefit, <strong>the</strong>refore, from efforts to revive <strong>the</strong> doubleemphasis of Williams and his colleagues, perhaps to bridge more <strong>the</strong>work of psychology and l<strong>in</strong>guistics. The effect would be to ref<strong>in</strong>e andparticularize our knowledge of how specific aspects of speech elicitspecific types of evaluative reactions. Recent useful forays <strong>in</strong> this directioncan be found <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> collection edited by Milroy and Preston (1999). Ofcourse, even if we could isolate <strong>the</strong> most important speech cues, it isunclear what immediate use this would have. Attempt<strong>in</strong>g to alterspecific speech characteristics, for example, would be difficult <strong>in</strong> itselfand among speech communities of so-called ‘visible m<strong>in</strong>orities’ probably of little ‘stand-alone’ benefit. On <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r hand, a generalpolicy of addition to or expansion of a child’s l<strong>in</strong>guistic repertoire couldrender such detailed <strong>in</strong>formation almost unnecessary. None<strong>the</strong>less,arguments have been made from with<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> American black communitythat <strong>the</strong> acquisition of more standard features of English would at leastremove one potential stimulus to negative perception. As a blackeducator said on an <strong>in</strong>structional video, ‘At least <strong>the</strong>y won’t be able tosay that you didn’t get that job ‘‘cause you speak poor English’’’ (seeAlvarez & Kolker, 1987).In ano<strong>the</strong>r useful development, Williams (1974, 1976) discussed wha<strong>the</strong> termed <strong>the</strong> ‘latitude of attitude acceptance’. Not an entirely newconcept <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> larger doma<strong>in</strong> of social psychology, this is an acknowledgementthat raters’ evaluations may not be entirely adequatelyexpressed by mak<strong>in</strong>g a s<strong>in</strong>gle mark on some semantic-differential scale.Hav<strong>in</strong>g particular regard to language-evaluation studies, Williamsargued that determ<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g judges’ range of acceptance might be a usefuladdition to that s<strong>in</strong>gle mark. Beyond mak<strong>in</strong>g a rat<strong>in</strong>g choice <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> usualway, judges could also <strong>in</strong>dicate o<strong>the</strong>r generally acceptable rat<strong>in</strong>gpossibilities; likewise, rat<strong>in</strong>gs that would def<strong>in</strong>itely be rejected couldalso be revealed. An example might be:This child sounds: passive +:+ :+::–:–:–activeThe three ‘plus’ signs towards <strong>the</strong> ‘passive’ end of <strong>the</strong> scale here could<strong>in</strong>dicate rat<strong>in</strong>gs generally acceptable to a judge: his or her ‘latitude ofacceptance’. If one of <strong>the</strong>se was circled or o<strong>the</strong>rwise highlighted (I haveput it <strong>in</strong> bold here), that could be taken as <strong>the</strong> judge’s s<strong>in</strong>gle bestestimate. A position left blank (as <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> mid-position, above) coulddenote lack of decision or neutrality, with <strong>the</strong> three ‘m<strong>in</strong>us’ signs


Evaluative Reactions to <strong>the</strong> <strong>Language</strong> of Disadvantage 165<strong>in</strong>dicat<strong>in</strong>g possibilities def<strong>in</strong>itely rejected; see also <strong>the</strong> reference madeabove to Goot (1993) on <strong>the</strong> assessment of evaluative ‘<strong>in</strong>tensity’.Ano<strong>the</strong>r Irish study (already briefly referred to above: Edwards, 1979b)did <strong>in</strong>volve somewhat more detailed <strong>in</strong>quiry. In addition to test<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>generality of <strong>the</strong> previous f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>gs with regard to speech evaluations, tworef<strong>in</strong>ements were <strong>in</strong>troduced. The first was <strong>the</strong> measurement of anysex-of-rater effects. Previous studies had dealt ma<strong>in</strong>ly with female teacherraters quite reasonably, s<strong>in</strong>ce <strong>in</strong> North America most primary-schoolteachers are female. In <strong>the</strong> Irish context, however, <strong>the</strong> large numbers ofmale primary teachers prompted consideration of judges’ gender as apossibly important variable. The second variant was to attempt to measure<strong>the</strong> judges’ confidence <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir rat<strong>in</strong>gs. The reason<strong>in</strong>g beh<strong>in</strong>d this wassimply that respondents almost always comply with requests to fill <strong>in</strong> all<strong>the</strong> scales provided <strong>in</strong> evaluation studies, even though <strong>the</strong>y may feel thatsome are less appropriate than o<strong>the</strong>rs (<strong>in</strong>deed, raters often express doubts<strong>in</strong> this regard typically at <strong>the</strong> conclusion of <strong>the</strong> experimental task).Judges’ confidence, or <strong>the</strong> lack of it, could well be of some importance <strong>in</strong><strong>the</strong> overall <strong>in</strong>terpretation of results. Early on, Williams (1974) observedthat respondents are will<strong>in</strong>g to make judgments after very brief exposureto a stimulus voice and, as we have seen (<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Choy and Dodd study,for example) <strong>the</strong>se judgments may be almost ludicrously wide rang<strong>in</strong>g.The ‘latitude of attitude’ that judges were prepared to accept was seen byWilliams to extend somewhat <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>vestigator’s understand<strong>in</strong>g of <strong>the</strong>rat<strong>in</strong>g procedure and, <strong>in</strong> like manner, <strong>the</strong> assessment of judges’ confidence<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir rat<strong>in</strong>gs was here considered as an expression of how wide <strong>the</strong>irimplicit latitude of acceptance might be if <strong>in</strong> fact it existed at all.Two groups of twenty 10-year-old Dubl<strong>in</strong> children (10 boys and 10girls <strong>in</strong> each group) provided <strong>the</strong> speech samples here: one groupcomprised disadvantaged, lower-class children; <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r was a middleclasssample. After a practice trial, <strong>the</strong> children were tape-recorded whileread<strong>in</strong>g a short passage, selected with <strong>the</strong> assistance of <strong>the</strong>ir teachers.Fourteen teachers-<strong>in</strong>-tra<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g (seven male, seven female) served asjudges <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> study, and <strong>the</strong>y responded to 17 semantic-differentialscales, which touched upon various aspects of <strong>the</strong> children’s personalityand background (e.g. fluency, <strong>in</strong>telligence, enthusiasm, likely schoolachievement, perceived degree of disadvantage). Accompany<strong>in</strong>g each of<strong>the</strong>se rat<strong>in</strong>g scales was a second seven-po<strong>in</strong>t scale on which <strong>the</strong> judgeswere asked to <strong>in</strong>dicate <strong>the</strong> degree of confidence <strong>the</strong>y had <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>‘substantive’ rat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>y had just made. F<strong>in</strong>ally, all raters were <strong>in</strong>terviewedat <strong>the</strong> conclusion of <strong>the</strong> study about <strong>the</strong>ir knowledge andop<strong>in</strong>ions of disadvantage, language and <strong>the</strong> experiment itself.


166 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>The major results were as follows. First, on every scale, <strong>the</strong>disadvantaged children received less favorable rat<strong>in</strong>gs than did <strong>the</strong>middle-class children; <strong>the</strong> support for earlier work was clear. Factoranalysis of <strong>the</strong> rat<strong>in</strong>gs showed all of <strong>the</strong>m to be highly <strong>in</strong>terrelated, andonly one important factor emerged. We could recall here Williams’sconsistent f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g of two important factors <strong>in</strong> teacher rat<strong>in</strong>gs: ‘confidence/eagerness’and ‘ethnicity/nonstandardness’. S<strong>in</strong>ce ethnicity wasnot a factor <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Irish context, it is <strong>the</strong>refore unsurpris<strong>in</strong>g that only onefactor (‘disadvantage-nondisadvantage’) emerged here. This result suggests<strong>the</strong> validity of <strong>the</strong> idea that teachers’ reactions derive from someoverall elicited stereotype of disadvantaged children. One would notwish to deny that o<strong>the</strong>r scales and o<strong>the</strong>r speech situations might evokeo<strong>the</strong>r factors; <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> school context, however, judgments of disadvantagedchildren at least on scales relat<strong>in</strong>g to language and school ability may well be ra<strong>the</strong>r unidimensional.Turn<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>the</strong> ‘confidence’ scales, we see an analogous f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g: nondisadvantagedchildren were judged with greater certa<strong>in</strong>ty than <strong>the</strong>disadvantaged. An <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g difference, however, occurred between <strong>the</strong>two sorts of rat<strong>in</strong>gs, with regard to <strong>the</strong> gender of <strong>the</strong> judges. Maleteachers were found to give higher rat<strong>in</strong>gs on <strong>the</strong> substantive scales thanwere female judges; on <strong>the</strong> ‘confidence’ scales, however, <strong>the</strong> reverse was<strong>the</strong> case. Thus, it appeared that, overall, males made more positiverat<strong>in</strong>gs, but were less sure of <strong>the</strong>m, while females were more confidentabout <strong>the</strong>ir somewhat less favorable substantive rat<strong>in</strong>gs. Apart from<strong>in</strong>dicat<strong>in</strong>g that one is not deal<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>in</strong> rat<strong>in</strong>g scales generally, with a simpleresponse tendency for one gender to make higher or lower marks on ascale, <strong>the</strong>re is an <strong>in</strong>trigu<strong>in</strong>g possibility here, and it is one that deservesfur<strong>the</strong>r study (if only because scales rema<strong>in</strong> so commonplace <strong>in</strong> socialpsychologicaland sociol<strong>in</strong>guistic research). Perhaps males tend to overcommit<strong>the</strong>mselves <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir rat<strong>in</strong>gs, to make somewhat more polarizedjudgments and <strong>the</strong>n take <strong>the</strong> opportunity provided by <strong>the</strong> confidencescales to ‘soften’ <strong>the</strong>ir judgments, as it were. Females, hav<strong>in</strong>g been morecircumspect from <strong>the</strong> start, may not f<strong>in</strong>d this necessary.Consider<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> confidence rat<strong>in</strong>gs as <strong>the</strong>y related to each <strong>in</strong>dividualsubstantive scale, it was found that some of <strong>the</strong> latter tended to be ratedwith greater certa<strong>in</strong>ty than o<strong>the</strong>rs. S<strong>in</strong>ce I have just po<strong>in</strong>ted out that all<strong>the</strong> substantive scales were highly <strong>in</strong>terrelated (<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> factor analysis), itmight seem that, if some smaller subset were required, it would not makemuch difference which scales were chosen. However, <strong>the</strong> results of <strong>the</strong>confidence judgments reveal that some scales have at least greater facevalidity than o<strong>the</strong>rs. The generality here is this: judges were more


Evaluative Reactions to <strong>the</strong> <strong>Language</strong> of Disadvantage 167confident when asked to rate aspects of personality that are more or lessdirectly relatable to <strong>the</strong> speech sample itself (e.g. fluency, read<strong>in</strong>g ability,pronunciation), and less comfortable when asked to assess such th<strong>in</strong>gs as<strong>the</strong> happ<strong>in</strong>ess of <strong>the</strong> child and family socioeconomic status. It may bethat a sort of halo effect is at work here: rat<strong>in</strong>gs about which judges aremore confident are allowed to sway decisions that are requested undermore dubious or far-fetched head<strong>in</strong>gs. Besides confirm<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>the</strong>n, <strong>the</strong>now-familiar differences <strong>in</strong> judges’ perceptions of disadvantaged children,<strong>the</strong> study also shows that although will<strong>in</strong>g to fill <strong>in</strong> all <strong>the</strong> scalesprovided raters are clearly more comfortable with assessments that itseems more reasonable to make, given <strong>the</strong> stimulus sample provided.This variation <strong>in</strong> comfort level, and <strong>the</strong> commendable caution that mustunderp<strong>in</strong> it, are matters that researchers would do well to take to heart.F<strong>in</strong>ally here, <strong>the</strong> differences attributable to judges’ gender also suggestpossibilities that may be important for those engaged <strong>in</strong> rat<strong>in</strong>g-scaleresearch.The most general implication of all <strong>the</strong>se evaluation studies is clear.Listener-evaluators (teachers be<strong>in</strong>g a most important group here) areprone to stereotyped and often negative views of certa<strong>in</strong> languagevarieties and <strong>the</strong>ir speakers. The importance of this derives from <strong>the</strong>evidence that different language varieties are not l<strong>in</strong>guistically deficient.While <strong>the</strong> data about teachers’ attitudes and evaluations simply reveal, <strong>in</strong>one context, a perceived relationship between certa<strong>in</strong> language varietiesand social deficit that occurs <strong>in</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r sett<strong>in</strong>gs, teachers’ views andbehavior are of ra<strong>the</strong>r special significance <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> lives of disadvantagedchildren. In a review of many sociol<strong>in</strong>guistic studies, Rob<strong>in</strong>son (1972:116) po<strong>in</strong>ted out that speech may not always be an irrelevant orerroneous clue to a child’s ability: ‘if <strong>the</strong> self-fulfill<strong>in</strong>g prophecy isfulfilled, <strong>the</strong>n paradoxically <strong>the</strong> argument that certa<strong>in</strong> language behavioursare associated with educational atta<strong>in</strong>ments has a reasonable(even if unnecessary) foundation’. This is a useful po<strong>in</strong>t, although it doesnot detract from <strong>the</strong> thrust of <strong>the</strong> studies reported here.There are really two related issues <strong>in</strong> contention: one is <strong>the</strong>demonstration that speech style can <strong>in</strong>fluence perceptions and evaluations;<strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r is <strong>the</strong> manner <strong>in</strong> which <strong>the</strong> attitudes and beliefs thatunderlie such assessments may affect children’s school progress. Thelatter is bound to be a more speculative aspect than <strong>the</strong> former, s<strong>in</strong>ce it isso difficult to tease out, <strong>in</strong> natural sett<strong>in</strong>gs, <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>fluence of one variableamong many. And, as Rob<strong>in</strong>son implies, <strong>the</strong>re is always <strong>the</strong> possibilitythat, because of pressure and prejudice, relationships found betweenspeech and school success may actually have social validity. We may


168 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>never<strong>the</strong>less consider, however, that attitudes towards <strong>the</strong> speech ofdisadvantaged children often contribute to an unfair and unnecessaryhandicap to <strong>the</strong>ir progress.Notes1. When consider<strong>in</strong>g phenomena like <strong>the</strong> ‘m<strong>in</strong>ority-group reaction’, we shouldremember that <strong>the</strong> l<strong>in</strong>es of comparison are not simply drawn betweenmajorities and m<strong>in</strong>orities, but also among m<strong>in</strong>ority groups <strong>the</strong>mselves.Preferences and prejudices here can reflect and re<strong>in</strong>force actual or perceivedposition<strong>in</strong>g along social spectra. Disda<strong>in</strong>ed when <strong>the</strong>y first arrived <strong>in</strong>America, <strong>the</strong> Irish were able to look down upon later arrivals once <strong>the</strong>irown social security had begun to take form. Or, as <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Brazilian casediscussed <strong>in</strong> Chapter 4, places on <strong>the</strong> social spectrum can reflect shades ofsk<strong>in</strong> color. Orwell wrote of some animals be<strong>in</strong>g more equal than o<strong>the</strong>rs, andAllardt (1984: 203) rephrased <strong>the</strong> aphorism when he said that some m<strong>in</strong>oritygroups are more m<strong>in</strong>or than o<strong>the</strong>rs.In America, <strong>the</strong> National Conference for Community and Justice (founded<strong>in</strong> 1927 as <strong>the</strong> National Conference of Christians and Jews, with a name change<strong>in</strong> 1998) has issued three reports <strong>in</strong> 1994, 2000 and 2006 on <strong>in</strong>tergrouprelations. The first of <strong>the</strong>se revealed that more than 40% of black and HispanicAmericans felt that <strong>the</strong>ir Asian neighbors tended to be crafty and unscrupulous<strong>in</strong> bus<strong>in</strong>ess matters. About half of <strong>the</strong> black respondents, and more thantwo-thirds of <strong>the</strong> Asian Americans agreed that Hispanics had families largerthan <strong>the</strong>y could reasonably support. And some 30% of Asian and HispanicAmericans thought that blacks were quite content to live on welfare payments(Holmes, 1994; National Conference of Christians and Jews, 1994).The second report found some improvement <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>tergroup attitudes, andgreater contact across groups. Still, only 30% were satisfied with <strong>the</strong> state ofthat contact, many reported <strong>in</strong>stances of discrim<strong>in</strong>ation, and about 80% of <strong>the</strong><strong>in</strong>formants agreed that racial, ethnic and religious tensions rema<strong>in</strong>ed seriousmatters (National Conference for Community and Justice, 2000).The latest report (National Conference for Community and Justice, 2006)reported some fur<strong>the</strong>r improvement: now, some 42% reported satisfactionwith <strong>the</strong> state of <strong>in</strong>tergroup contact, with relationships with HispanicAmericans show<strong>in</strong>g particular improvement. However, roughly <strong>the</strong> samepercentage of respondents as <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> 2000 report still thought that varioustensions were still very much alive. Much more anti-Muslim discrim<strong>in</strong>ationwas reported, and almost 40% of <strong>the</strong> respondents felt that it would beacceptable to have separation of <strong>the</strong> races, ‘as long as <strong>the</strong>y have equalopportunity’. And, <strong>in</strong> terms of <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terrelationships among Asian, Hispanicand black Americans, <strong>the</strong>se latest results not only showed importantvariations per se black <strong>in</strong>formants hold<strong>in</strong>g, for example, <strong>the</strong> most negativeviews of <strong>the</strong> state of <strong>in</strong>tergroup contact but <strong>the</strong>y also revealed <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>gbetween-group perceptual disparities. Thus, while black respondents reportedthat <strong>the</strong>ir closest relationships were with Hispanics, <strong>the</strong> latter weremost positive about <strong>the</strong>ir relationships with whites and whites, <strong>in</strong> turn, putHispanics below black and Asian Americans <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>se terms!


Evaluative Reactions to <strong>the</strong> <strong>Language</strong> of Disadvantage 169Taken toge<strong>the</strong>r, <strong>the</strong> f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>gs of <strong>the</strong>se three reports are <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g because<strong>the</strong>y demonstrate <strong>the</strong> dynamic nature of <strong>in</strong>tergroup contact, and <strong>the</strong> way <strong>in</strong>which it reflects broader social contexts. Thus, Hispanics are now much morenumerous <strong>in</strong> America, and much more widespread, and ubiquity can oftenlessen antipathy. On <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r hand, Muslim Americans are pay<strong>in</strong>g a socialprice for Islamic fundamentalism. Beyond this, two important po<strong>in</strong>ts standout. First, <strong>the</strong> general levels of ‘life satisfaction’ rema<strong>in</strong> much lower amongblacks than among ei<strong>the</strong>r whites or Asians, and <strong>the</strong>y cont<strong>in</strong>ue to report <strong>the</strong>greatest levels of prejudicial discrim<strong>in</strong>ation. Second, it would seem that despite <strong>the</strong> rul<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> landmark Brown v Board of Education case of 1954, thatto be separate is to be <strong>in</strong>herently unequal (see Chapter 9) a large m<strong>in</strong>ority ofrespondents still apparently fail to grasp <strong>the</strong> po<strong>in</strong>t.2. When an American speaker says kyōō’pon <strong>in</strong>stead of kōō’pon, we have ano<strong>the</strong>rvariety of hypercorrection; here it arises from <strong>the</strong> notion that, if higher-statusspeakers say styōōd’nt ra<strong>the</strong>r than stōōd’nt, <strong>the</strong>n an analogous pronunciationmust be ‘correct’ for coupon. The fur<strong>the</strong>r <strong>in</strong>terest here is that <strong>the</strong> moreprestigious American pronunciation of student is itself a conscious adoptionof British usage and recent work by Boberg (1999) reveals some pitfalls.The American ‘nativization’ of foreign words spelled with Ba thathave entered <strong>the</strong> lexicon (words like macho and pasta) has, Boberg suggests, astrong ‘aes<strong>the</strong>tic’ dimension. This favors a render<strong>in</strong>g of <strong>the</strong> sound as /a:/ (as<strong>in</strong> fa<strong>the</strong>r) ra<strong>the</strong>r than as /æ/ (as <strong>in</strong> fat). And this ‘aes<strong>the</strong>tic’ sense derives from<strong>the</strong> idea that British usage <strong>in</strong> which <strong>the</strong> /a:/ pronunciation is consideredmore typical is prestigious usage. Ironies arise, Boberg shows, when <strong>the</strong>American /a:/-based pronunciation of such foreign imports, based uponperceptions of British elegance and ‘correctness’, <strong>in</strong> fact diverges from <strong>the</strong> /ae/pronunciation given to such borrow<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>in</strong> standard British English; see alsoEdwards (1999a).Jones (2001) provides some background for this sort of work <strong>in</strong> a recentbook on American anglophilia (see particularly her Chapter 4, ‘Gee, I loveyour accent’).3. It rema<strong>in</strong>s <strong>the</strong> case, however, that teachers-<strong>in</strong>-tra<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g very rarely receivemuch <strong>in</strong>formation about <strong>the</strong> aetiology of disadvantage <strong>in</strong> general, or itsl<strong>in</strong>guistic aspects <strong>in</strong> particular despite <strong>the</strong> fact that, as I have shown to manystudents over two decades, a reasonable grasp of <strong>the</strong> ‘difference’ position canbe quickly acquired: this is not rocket science. See my <strong>in</strong>troductory chapter forfur<strong>the</strong>r details.


Chapter 9Black English as EbonicsIntroductionI have already discussed Black English and <strong>the</strong> very important rolethat <strong>the</strong> analysis of it has played <strong>in</strong> our understand<strong>in</strong>g of <strong>the</strong> l<strong>in</strong>guisticvalidity of all dialects. The importance here is of global significance,relevant wherever nonstandard dialects are derogated. S<strong>in</strong>ce BlackEnglish Vernacular (BEV) had for so long been a variety particularlylack<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> prestige, it became clear that any demonstration of itsl<strong>in</strong>guistic validity as one English dialect among many would logicallytransfer to o<strong>the</strong>r less stigmatized nonstandard forms. The evidencepresented by Labov and o<strong>the</strong>rs for this l<strong>in</strong>guistic validity and, <strong>the</strong>refore,for <strong>the</strong> communicative competence of <strong>the</strong> speakers of BEV, rema<strong>in</strong>sstrong, even if <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>sights often rema<strong>in</strong> regrettably unavailable to <strong>the</strong>public <strong>in</strong> general, and to teachers <strong>in</strong> particular.In a recent discussion, Niedzielski (2005: 259260) illustrates <strong>the</strong>cont<strong>in</strong>u<strong>in</strong>g problems affect<strong>in</strong>g black children. She cites work published<strong>in</strong> 1999 show<strong>in</strong>g that ‘while African-Americans make up approximately12% of <strong>the</strong> US population, <strong>the</strong>y make up an astound<strong>in</strong>g 41% of <strong>the</strong>students <strong>in</strong> American schools labeled ‘‘educably mentally retarded’’’.This attribution rests largely on language evaluations that cont<strong>in</strong>ue to seemore <strong>in</strong>correctness, more impurity and more speech pathology <strong>in</strong> BEV;see also Adger et al. (1992). Ano<strong>the</strong>r <strong>in</strong>dication of bias is found <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>hear<strong>in</strong>g-assessment referrals made by teachers. Although black childrenare not statistically more likely than <strong>the</strong>ir white counterparts to havehear<strong>in</strong>g problems <strong>in</strong> fact, <strong>the</strong>re is some evidence that, as a group, <strong>the</strong>reis less hear<strong>in</strong>g loss <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> black community <strong>the</strong>y are much more likely tobe referred to speech-and-hear<strong>in</strong>g personnel. Data from a professionalbody of specialists reveal that black children are referred <strong>in</strong> proportionsthat are double <strong>the</strong>ir actual numbers <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> population; see also AmericanSpeech-<strong>Language</strong> Hear<strong>in</strong>g Association (1997).Labov (1976) rem<strong>in</strong>ded us that speakers of nonstandard dialectstypically understand standard forms with little or no difficulty. Relatedly,he noted that <strong>the</strong> ‘gears and axles of English grammatical mach<strong>in</strong>ery areavailable to speakers of all dialects’ (Labov, 1976: 64). Of course,170


Black English as Ebonics 171nonstandard speakers may not regularly use <strong>the</strong> more standard variants:<strong>the</strong>re are well-understood differences, <strong>in</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r words, between competenceand performance. Indeed, <strong>the</strong> basic dist<strong>in</strong>ction here had been madeclear at <strong>the</strong> very time that <strong>the</strong> ‘deficit’ position was at its strongest. As Ihave already po<strong>in</strong>ted out, Trudgill (1975) observed that work<strong>in</strong>g-classchildren could use Bernste<strong>in</strong>’s ‘elaborated code’ under certa<strong>in</strong> circumstances;and, earlier still, Rob<strong>in</strong>son (1965) had found that <strong>the</strong> writtengrammar of work<strong>in</strong>g-class children was not markedly different from thatof middle-class pupils (see also Rushton & Young, 1975).It is abundantly clear that <strong>the</strong> context <strong>in</strong> which language is displayedand recorded is of <strong>the</strong> greatest significance someth<strong>in</strong>g that Labov (1969)famously illustrated <strong>in</strong> his demonstrations that <strong>the</strong> vaunted ‘nonverbality’of <strong>the</strong> black child could be made to disappear if <strong>in</strong>terviewand observation situations were made more appropriate. One implicationhere is that <strong>the</strong> use of BEV among black children varies (Edwards &Giles, 1984). Torrey (1983: 642) thus po<strong>in</strong>ted out that:a teacher <strong>in</strong> a class of black children who hears BE forms frequentlyshould not conclude that all or even most of <strong>the</strong> class membersconform to <strong>the</strong> general description of BE... some <strong>in</strong>dividuals useonly one or two BE forms, and o<strong>the</strong>rs completely standard forms.Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, some who use many BE forms <strong>in</strong> spontaneous speechare perfectly able to handle SE <strong>in</strong> read<strong>in</strong>g and o<strong>the</strong>r language tests.The black children so profoundly misunderstood by deficit <strong>the</strong>oristsare, of course, possessors of a vibrant l<strong>in</strong>guistic heritage and a rich oralculture. It is quite remarkable that such obvious markers of anhistorically longstand<strong>in</strong>g tradition were <strong>in</strong>visible or ignored by‘deficit’ proponents of remedial and compensatory education. WhereBereiter and Engelmann (1966) saw black children as lack<strong>in</strong>g rudimentaryforms of dialogue, unable to recognize s<strong>in</strong>gle words and view<strong>in</strong>glanguage as someth<strong>in</strong>g dispensable <strong>in</strong> social life (one wonders, still, howsuch bl<strong>in</strong>dness could have occurred), Labov (1969: 33) and his colleaguessaw <strong>the</strong>se same children liv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> a community ‘ba<strong>the</strong>d <strong>in</strong> verbalstimulation from morn<strong>in</strong>g to night’.A study by Edwards (1999b) illum<strong>in</strong>ates both <strong>the</strong> cont<strong>in</strong>u<strong>in</strong>g difficulties<strong>in</strong> teacher’s perceptions of nonstandard speech and someth<strong>in</strong>g of <strong>the</strong>oral fluency of black children. Among a rural primary-school population<strong>in</strong> Nova Scotia, black children, white Acadian-French children and whitechildren of English-speak<strong>in</strong>g background were studied. Each childprovided three speech samples: a set read<strong>in</strong>g passage, a retold story(i.e. <strong>the</strong> experimenter tells <strong>the</strong> child a story, who <strong>the</strong>n retells it a


172 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>technique used by Piaget, 1952, and somewhat more narrowly byHouston, 1973) and spontaneous speech on any topic of <strong>in</strong>terest to <strong>the</strong>child. Adult judges <strong>the</strong>n evaluated <strong>the</strong> children on standard personalitydimensions. The ma<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>tent here was to see if perceived speakerfavorability varied with type of speech sample evaluated.It was found, first, that black children were generally evaluated lessfavorably than <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r two groups; second, spontaneous speechtended, across <strong>the</strong> board, to elicit <strong>the</strong> highest rat<strong>in</strong>gs. Of greatest <strong>in</strong>teres<strong>the</strong>re, however, were <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>teractions found between group and speechtype, and here it was found that <strong>the</strong> black children profited most, so tospeak, from <strong>the</strong> spontaneous speech rat<strong>in</strong>gs. To put it ano<strong>the</strong>r way: <strong>the</strong>differences <strong>in</strong> evaluations evoked by black children’s read<strong>in</strong>g/storyretell<strong>in</strong>gand spontaneous speech productions were much more markedthan those perta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g to <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r two groups of children. The suggestionis that black children, whose culture is orally strong, will produce <strong>the</strong>best l<strong>in</strong>guistic results (‘best’, that is, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> perceptions of white listeners)when <strong>the</strong> context allows <strong>the</strong>m to show evidence of that cultural strengthand richness. There are ra<strong>the</strong>r obvious implications here, both for fur<strong>the</strong>rstudy and for <strong>in</strong>terpret<strong>in</strong>g and react<strong>in</strong>g to language behavior <strong>in</strong> morestructured contexts (like classrooms).EbonicsIn this section, I hope to show that <strong>the</strong> value both <strong>in</strong>tr<strong>in</strong>sic andgeneralizable of attend<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>the</strong> sociology of BEV has not dim<strong>in</strong>ished.The Brown v. Board of Education decision of 1954 is seen as a legalmilestone <strong>in</strong> black education <strong>in</strong> America, <strong>the</strong> Supreme Court rul<strong>in</strong>gunanimously that ‘separate is <strong>in</strong>herently unequal’. Schools were told todesegregate ‘with all deliberate speed’ (see <strong>the</strong> latest treatment byDaugherity & Bolton, 2008). This overturned more than half a centuryof educational segregation underp<strong>in</strong>ned by ‘separate but equal’ provisionsthat legitimated a most unequal state of affairs, and it held <strong>the</strong>promise of real educational equality. But this has generally not come topass. Why not? Because o<strong>the</strong>r social obstacles to black progress haverema<strong>in</strong>ed firmly <strong>in</strong> place, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> ‘tremendous l<strong>in</strong>guistic divisionsbetween those who trace <strong>the</strong>ir ancestry to African slaves and those whodo not’ (Baugh, 2006: 91). There are threads, <strong>the</strong>refore, that connect Brownto <strong>the</strong> important cases <strong>in</strong> Michigan and California that I shall touch uponbelow; see also Ball and Alim (2006), Bartee and Brown (2007), Brown(2007) and Jackson (2005).


Black English as Ebonics 173In <strong>the</strong> late 1970s, parents of more than a dozen black children at <strong>the</strong>Mart<strong>in</strong> Lu<strong>the</strong>r K<strong>in</strong>g primary school <strong>in</strong> Ann Arbor, Michigan, alleged that<strong>the</strong> school was not properly educat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>ir children. They were do<strong>in</strong>gpoorly at school and <strong>the</strong> parents’ view was that teachers were unaware of<strong>the</strong> important sociocultural differences between <strong>the</strong>se children and <strong>the</strong>irwhite counterparts (80% of <strong>the</strong> school population), and that languagebarriers prevented school success. Indeed, <strong>the</strong> children had been(<strong>in</strong>accurately, needless to say) labelled as educationally retarded andlearn<strong>in</strong>g disabled, were relegated to speech classes for languagedeficiency, and were suspended, discipl<strong>in</strong>ed and held back. In July1979, after a month-long trial <strong>in</strong> which several prom<strong>in</strong>ent l<strong>in</strong>guiststestified (none for <strong>the</strong> defendants), a federal court judge ruled that schoolauthorities had failed to act to overcome language barriers, and ordered<strong>the</strong>m to devise curricula to help <strong>the</strong> children (particularly with <strong>the</strong>irread<strong>in</strong>g development). That is, <strong>the</strong> schools were to adapt.Contrary to some reports, <strong>the</strong> school was not required to teach BEV,nor were teachers required to learn it so as to communicate with <strong>the</strong>irpupils <strong>the</strong>y already communicated well enough, and <strong>the</strong> essentialproblem was with <strong>the</strong> teach<strong>in</strong>g of read<strong>in</strong>g. (Work by McDermott andGospod<strong>in</strong>off [1981] and Lucas and Borders [1987] has s<strong>in</strong>ce confirmedthat dialect variation per se rarely leads to difficulties with classroomcommunication.) Of great <strong>in</strong>terest, <strong>the</strong>n and of great significance for <strong>the</strong>present discussion was <strong>the</strong> f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g that BEV itself was not a po<strong>in</strong>t of<strong>in</strong>terference. Ra<strong>the</strong>r, <strong>the</strong> barriers arose here because of <strong>the</strong> negativereactions to <strong>the</strong> dialect, coupled with <strong>in</strong>accurate teacher expectations and(to put it bluntly) racist perceptions. The l<strong>in</strong>guistic evidence <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> caseenabled <strong>the</strong> judge to f<strong>in</strong>d that BEV was a valid and dist<strong>in</strong>ct Englishdialect; at <strong>the</strong> same time, he supported <strong>the</strong> view that standard English(some form of standard American English, perhaps) was a necessarycomponent of success <strong>in</strong> school and beyond. Indeed, <strong>the</strong> judge went sofar as to say that BEV was not an acceptable method of communication <strong>in</strong>many contexts.Naturally, <strong>the</strong> case received very wide publicity, and much of <strong>the</strong> presscoverage was mis<strong>in</strong>formed and distorted (see Venezky, 1981). As well,general op<strong>in</strong>ion was divided on many aspects. Consequently, a symposiumwas planned to discuss <strong>the</strong> elements and implications of <strong>the</strong> K<strong>in</strong>gdecision; this took place <strong>in</strong> February 1980. The conference itself became amedia event with, among o<strong>the</strong>rs, a BBC film crew and a team from <strong>the</strong>American National Public Radio organization <strong>in</strong> attendance. A book ofproceed<strong>in</strong>gs soon appeared (Smi<strong>the</strong>rman, 1981a), and this presents <strong>the</strong>


174 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>fullest available account of <strong>the</strong> whole issue; see also Smi<strong>the</strong>rman (1981b)and Zorn (1982).As one of <strong>the</strong> l<strong>in</strong>guists testify<strong>in</strong>g at <strong>the</strong> trial, Labov (1982) also preparedsome lengthy notes on <strong>the</strong> case, with observations on <strong>the</strong> educationaltreatment that <strong>the</strong> black children had received (and which had led to <strong>the</strong>trial). He wrote that, <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>vok<strong>in</strong>g federal law direct<strong>in</strong>g educationalauthorities to act aga<strong>in</strong>st language barriers found to impede pupilprogress, <strong>the</strong> judge clearly did not believe that such law applied only <strong>in</strong>foreign-language situations. Although this may have been <strong>the</strong> orig<strong>in</strong>alth<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> exist<strong>in</strong>g legal provisions (see Zorn, 1982; but also Bailey, 1981),<strong>the</strong> judge did not class BEV as a separate language. Labov went on to cite<strong>the</strong> trial as an illustration of l<strong>in</strong>guists’ <strong>in</strong>volvement <strong>in</strong> contemporary,real-life issues; <strong>the</strong> abstract to his paper is worth quot<strong>in</strong>g here:Though many l<strong>in</strong>guists have shown a strong concern for socialissues, <strong>the</strong>re is an apparent contradiction between <strong>the</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>ciples ofobjectivity needed for scientific work and commitment to socialaction. The Black English trial <strong>in</strong> Ann Arbor showed one way <strong>in</strong>which this contradiction could be resolved. The first decade ofresearch on Black English was marked by violent differences betweencreolists and dialectologists on <strong>the</strong> structure and orig<strong>in</strong> of <strong>the</strong> dialect.The possibility of a jo<strong>in</strong>t po<strong>in</strong>t of view first appeared <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> generalreaction of l<strong>in</strong>guists aga<strong>in</strong>st <strong>the</strong> view that blacks were l<strong>in</strong>guisticallyand genetically <strong>in</strong>ferior. The entrance of black l<strong>in</strong>guists <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> fieldwas a critical factor <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> fur<strong>the</strong>r development of <strong>the</strong> creolehypo<strong>the</strong>sis and <strong>the</strong> recognition of <strong>the</strong> dist<strong>in</strong>ctive features of <strong>the</strong> tenseand aspect system. At <strong>the</strong> trial, l<strong>in</strong>guists were able to present effectivetestimony <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> form of a unified view on <strong>the</strong> orig<strong>in</strong>s and structuralcharacteristics of <strong>the</strong> Black English Vernacular and argue for itsvalidity as an alternate to standard English. (Labov, 1982: 165)Discussions and disagreements about <strong>the</strong> ‘orig<strong>in</strong>s and structuralcharacteristics’ of BEV have cont<strong>in</strong>ued. There are some very goodtreatments of its history and development; particularly recommendedhere are books by Lanehart (2001), Mufwene et al. (1998), Poplack (2000;see also Poplack & Tagliamonte, 2001) and Wolfram and Thomas (2002).Green’s (2002) treatment is also of <strong>in</strong>terest: although her book isessentially devoted to matters of lexicon, phonology and syntax, shedoes devote a f<strong>in</strong>al chapter to ‘social’ aspects of BEV. In fact, <strong>in</strong> about 30pages or so, she touches upon all <strong>the</strong> key sociological questions:perceptions of BEV by researchers and <strong>the</strong> general public, <strong>the</strong> issue ofbidialectalism <strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>g BEV and standard English, and appropriate


Black English as Ebonics 175responses to BEV <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> classroom. Of considerable <strong>in</strong>terest here aredebates about <strong>the</strong> ‘African-ness’ of BEV, on <strong>the</strong> one hand, and its status asone English dialect among many, on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r. These def<strong>in</strong>itional mattersare not only of narrow academic concern; <strong>the</strong>y have figured <strong>in</strong> morepublic discussions too, notably <strong>the</strong> Oakland ‘case’ (see below), <strong>in</strong> whichclaims that ‘Ebonics’ was basically an African variety could have beenimportant factors <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> type of educational provisions to be made forblack children at school (see Rickford, 2002; Smith, 2001).As it turned out, <strong>the</strong> Ann Arbor case was a precursor to a still morewidely discussed situation: <strong>the</strong> resolution of <strong>the</strong> Oakland, California,school board, <strong>in</strong> December 1996, declar<strong>in</strong>g Ebonics to be <strong>the</strong> nativelanguage of its black students. There are several reliable overviewsavailable <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> literature; among <strong>the</strong> important monographs are those byBaugh (2000), Kretzschmar (1998), Pandey (2000) and Ramirez et al.(2005). My citations from <strong>the</strong> actual Oakland decisions are taken from <strong>the</strong>last of <strong>the</strong>se sources. Among <strong>the</strong> best paper-length discussions are thoseof Barnes (2003), Baugh (2002), Deák (2007), Rickford (2002), Smi<strong>the</strong>rman(1998) and Wolfram (1998). Recently, De Bose (2005) provided alanguage-plann<strong>in</strong>g approach to BEV, pay<strong>in</strong>g particular attention to itsuse at school.And what is Ebonics? The term was co<strong>in</strong>ed by researchers tak<strong>in</strong>g part<strong>in</strong> a conference <strong>in</strong> St Louis devoted to <strong>the</strong> language of black children.Baugh (2004: 307) writes that <strong>the</strong> ‘scholars at <strong>the</strong> 1973 meet<strong>in</strong>g were allAfrican Americans’, but <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> preface to his edited collection, Williams(1975) states that ‘many’ white researchers were also <strong>the</strong>re. In any event,<strong>the</strong> term (constructed from ‘ebony’‘phonics’) arose from <strong>the</strong> desire todef<strong>in</strong>e and describe black language from a black po<strong>in</strong>t of view. ‘Ebonics’can be generally taken as synonymous with o<strong>the</strong>r terms <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>gBlack English (BE), BEV and African American Vernacular English(AAVE) although some have tried to draw dist<strong>in</strong>ctions (see Rickford,2002). Speicher and McMahon (1992) observed that s<strong>in</strong>ce BEV is not adialect spoken solely by black people (see above) and s<strong>in</strong>ce <strong>the</strong> termcont<strong>in</strong>ues to be seen negatively <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> media and elsewhere, <strong>the</strong> label‘Ebonics’ may be preferable. They go on to say that ‘it avoids directreference to <strong>the</strong> race while ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g an association with African-American culture and, <strong>the</strong>refore, a l<strong>in</strong>k to <strong>the</strong> African traditions thatsurvived <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> code’ (Speicher & McMahon, 1992: 401). All reasonableenough, except that it is ra<strong>the</strong>r difficult to see ‘Ebonics’ as not mak<strong>in</strong>gpretty obvious reference to black people!In 1996, Oakland was one of a handful of cities <strong>in</strong> which a majority of<strong>the</strong> citizens were African Americans, and many of <strong>the</strong>ir children were


176 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>do<strong>in</strong>g very poorly at school (Baugh, 2004). Among <strong>the</strong> most contentiousstatements with<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> school board’s famous resolution were <strong>the</strong> observationsthat ‘validated scholarly studies... have also demonstrated thatAfrican <strong>Language</strong> Systems are genetically-based and not a dialect [sic] ofEnglish’, and that black pupils were <strong>the</strong>refore entitled to f<strong>in</strong>ancial supportunder <strong>the</strong> provisions of federal bil<strong>in</strong>gual education programs for speakersof ‘limited English proficiency’. Immediate criticism ensued, with <strong>the</strong>result that <strong>the</strong> Oakland board soon issued a ‘clarification’. Because of‘misconceptions <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> result<strong>in</strong>g press stories’, <strong>the</strong> board now claimed thatits <strong>in</strong>tent had been misunderstood. Specifically, it denied that it meant to‘teach Ebonics <strong>in</strong> place of English’, or to ‘classify Ebonics (i.e. ‘‘BlackEnglish’’) speak<strong>in</strong>g pupils as bil<strong>in</strong>gual’, or to condone ‘<strong>the</strong> use of slang’.The first and last of <strong>the</strong>se po<strong>in</strong>ts are no doubt accurate, but <strong>the</strong> second is atleast debatable. The statement of clarification also made a dis<strong>in</strong>genuouseffort to erase <strong>the</strong> bizarre usage, ‘genetically-based’, not<strong>in</strong>g that<strong>the</strong> term ‘‘genetically based’’ is synonymous with genesis. In <strong>the</strong>clause, ‘‘African <strong>Language</strong> Systems are genetically based [no hyphen<strong>in</strong> this repetition] and not a dialect of English’’, <strong>the</strong> term ‘‘geneticallybased’’ is used accord<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>the</strong> standard dictionary def<strong>in</strong>ition of ‘‘hasorig<strong>in</strong>s <strong>in</strong>’’.By itself, of course, this climb-down does not make <strong>the</strong> orig<strong>in</strong>alphras<strong>in</strong>g any more clear, although <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>tent is obvious: Ebonics is an<strong>in</strong>dependent system, with a ‘genesis’ unrelated to English.It soon became obvious that fur<strong>the</strong>r changes would be necessary.Thus, <strong>in</strong> early 1997, an amended resolution was passed. The <strong>in</strong>itialphrase now read: ‘... demonstrated that African <strong>Language</strong> Systems haveorig<strong>in</strong>s <strong>in</strong> West and Niger-Congo languages and are not merely dialects ofEnglish’ (my italics). O<strong>the</strong>r sections were also altered, <strong>the</strong> board nowwish<strong>in</strong>g to make clear its <strong>in</strong>tent to build upon exist<strong>in</strong>g language skills <strong>in</strong>order to ‘move students from <strong>the</strong> language patterns <strong>the</strong>y br<strong>in</strong>g to schoolto English proficiency’. This is someth<strong>in</strong>g mandated <strong>in</strong> federal bil<strong>in</strong>gualeducation provisions, but, <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>gly enough, <strong>the</strong> idea of ‘mov<strong>in</strong>g’students implies a transitional thrust rejected by those proponents ofbil<strong>in</strong>gual education who feel that its essential remit should be to ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>orig<strong>in</strong>al varieties while facilitat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> growth of English skills. Theseproponents are concerned with separate languages, of course (particularlySpanish), and so, to <strong>the</strong> extent that <strong>the</strong> Oakland revisions allowEbonics to be seen as an English dialect after all if one withconsiderable African admixture <strong>the</strong> reworked thrust rema<strong>in</strong>s <strong>in</strong> l<strong>in</strong>ewith exist<strong>in</strong>g federal provisions of ‘transitional’ <strong>in</strong>tent. The revisions


Black English as Ebonics 177ra<strong>the</strong>r muddy <strong>the</strong>se waters, however. The <strong>in</strong>tent <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> orig<strong>in</strong>al documentwas to <strong>in</strong>struct students ‘<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir primary language’ (i.e. Ebonics), both toma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong> that variety and to facilitate <strong>the</strong> acquisition of English. In <strong>the</strong>amended resolution, however, <strong>the</strong> ma<strong>in</strong> emphasis is upon master<strong>in</strong>gEnglish while, at <strong>the</strong> same time, ‘respect<strong>in</strong>g and embrac<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>legitimacy and richness’ of Ebonics.Even <strong>in</strong> its revised form, <strong>the</strong>n, <strong>the</strong> Oakland school board’s declarationwas not without ambiguities and <strong>in</strong>felicities: it was clearly not adocument produced by professional l<strong>in</strong>guists. It was perhaps anacknowledgement of this, coupled with <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>tense reaction to itsactivities, which f<strong>in</strong>ally led <strong>the</strong> board to delete references to Ebonicsaltoge<strong>the</strong>r (Baugh, 2004). The whole matter, however, rema<strong>in</strong>s <strong>in</strong>structive<strong>in</strong> a number of ways. 1 If we put aside matters of dialect-languagedist<strong>in</strong>ction, and acknowledgements that both scholarly and officialdeterm<strong>in</strong>ations have made it clear that Ebonics is a form of nonstandardEnglish (and thus <strong>in</strong>eligible for support under <strong>the</strong> auspices of exist<strong>in</strong>gbil<strong>in</strong>gual education legislation), we are still left with an <strong>in</strong>tensely<strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g and <strong>in</strong>formative chapter <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> sociology of language. RichardRiley, <strong>the</strong> American Secretary of Education, lost no time <strong>in</strong> mak<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>official position clear. On Box<strong>in</strong>g Day, 1996, he stated that Ebonics was anonstandard form of English and not a foreign language. ‘Elevat<strong>in</strong>gBlack English to <strong>the</strong> status of a language’, he said, ‘is not <strong>the</strong> way to raisestandards of achievement <strong>in</strong> our schools’ (Globe & Mail, 1996). Baugh(2000) and Richardson (1998) discuss Riley’s reaction, and provide fullerdetails of o<strong>the</strong>r governmental and official responses.Some of <strong>the</strong> most salient aspects of <strong>the</strong> whole affair have been brieflybut usefully summarized by Wolfram (2005), who po<strong>in</strong>ted to <strong>the</strong> publicconceptions and misconceptions that it triggered. The school-boardresolutions were seen variously to suggest, first, that Ebonics was aseparate language tout court; second, that Ebonics was an Africanlanguage; third aris<strong>in</strong>g from <strong>the</strong> unfortunate term, ‘genetically-based’ that African Americans were ‘biologically predisposed’ to Ebonics;fourth, that speakers of Ebonics were as eligible as (say) HispanicAmericans for federal bil<strong>in</strong>gual education fund<strong>in</strong>g; fifth, that pupils wereto be taught <strong>in</strong> Ebonics by suitably prepared teachers. And Baugh (2004:316) provides a f<strong>in</strong>al important summary po<strong>in</strong>t: ‘<strong>the</strong> Ebonics debate thatbegan <strong>in</strong> Oakland was never fully resolved; <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> wake of a hostilepublic reception, it was simply abandoned’. Among <strong>the</strong> chorus of voices,many were hostile (as we shall see below), and even <strong>the</strong> moreenlightened ones were critical and cautious. An important issue wasleft hang<strong>in</strong>g, while ‘far too many African American students cont<strong>in</strong>ue to


178 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>attend underfunded and overcrowded schools’ (Baugh (2004: 316). This,<strong>in</strong> comb<strong>in</strong>ation with o<strong>the</strong>r social and political issues, ensures ongo<strong>in</strong>geducational underachievement.The language-dialect debate threw up some <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g discussions. Itis clear that while classify<strong>in</strong>g Ebonics as a separate language is notgenerally endorsed by l<strong>in</strong>guists (see Baugh, 2002, 2004), this hardlyimplies a dim<strong>in</strong>ished concern for <strong>the</strong> speakers of Ebonics-as-dialect.Baugh (2006: 97) rem<strong>in</strong>ds us that a good case can be made for‘educational policies targeted to <strong>the</strong> needs of nonstandard-dialectspeakers’. Relatedly, <strong>the</strong> term ‘dialect’ has no pejorative connotations <strong>in</strong><strong>the</strong> eyes of scholars. Some of those who argued for Ebonics-as-language,however, accepted <strong>the</strong> broadly held popular belief that ‘dialect’ doesmean a language form that is <strong>in</strong>ferior, <strong>in</strong>complete or <strong>in</strong>accurate, and <strong>the</strong>yhave typically been motivated by well-<strong>in</strong>tentioned concerns for <strong>the</strong> statusof Black English. Hence <strong>the</strong> impulse beh<strong>in</strong>d <strong>the</strong> label of ‘language’, butalso <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>ference that proponents of that label are not well-<strong>in</strong>formedlanguage scholars. Thus, as Steigerwald (2004: 12) po<strong>in</strong>ts out, <strong>the</strong> claimsof those who argue for Ebonics-as-language arise from ‘<strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>tersectionof nationalist [sic] politics and sketchy l<strong>in</strong>guistic science’. Of course, notbe<strong>in</strong>g a l<strong>in</strong>guist hardly means that one must forfeit one’s op<strong>in</strong>ion, but it isimportant to realize that argu<strong>in</strong>g from conviction is not <strong>the</strong> same asargu<strong>in</strong>g from evidence. The coexistence of <strong>the</strong> two perspectives caneasily lead as we know very well from many debates <strong>in</strong> many arenas oflife to misunderstand<strong>in</strong>g and conflict, difficulties that can arise fromlack of awareness or, more worry<strong>in</strong>gly, from willful neglect or ignorance.Wolfram’s (1998) report that he has often been asked if he ‘believed’ <strong>in</strong>Ebonics is tell<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> this connection.One l<strong>in</strong>guist, however, has proposed that Ebonics might be similar toScots, which some see as a dialect of English, o<strong>the</strong>rs as a language <strong>in</strong> itsown right. Both varieties, Fasold (2006) suggests, are more or lessequidistant from standard English. The question <strong>the</strong>n becomes, as it does<strong>in</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r debates over language-versus-dialect status, a political one (seeEdwards, 1985, 1994a), and actual degrees of difference, or <strong>in</strong>vocations ofmutual <strong>in</strong>telligibility, recede <strong>in</strong> def<strong>in</strong>itional importance. 2 L<strong>in</strong>guisticallyspeak<strong>in</strong>g, Fasold’s argument is not a strong one, but his <strong>in</strong>tention is clear,and derives from his concern that ‘dialect’ has negative connotations,and that ‘standard’ can have unfairly positive ones. To most people, al<strong>in</strong>guistically unexceptionable statement like, ‘Ebonics is a nonstandarddialect of English’ means that BEV is an <strong>in</strong>ferior variant. And, as Fasold(2006) goes on to clarify, while <strong>the</strong> term ‘standard’ <strong>in</strong>volves dist<strong>in</strong>ctionsthat are non-pejorative to l<strong>in</strong>guists, aris<strong>in</strong>g as <strong>the</strong>y do from historical and


Black English as Ebonics 179social dynamics and hav<strong>in</strong>g noth<strong>in</strong>g to say of any <strong>in</strong>tr<strong>in</strong>sic ‘correctness’,it generally conjures up exactly that sense of ‘correctness’ <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> publiceye. This is an entirely understandable reaction, of course, given that‘standards’ typically signify m<strong>in</strong>imum requirements, and ‘specificationsthat must be met for acceptability’ (Fasold, 2006: 194). 3Reactions to <strong>the</strong> Ebonics Debateand to BlackUnderachievementWhat about some specific examples of reactions to Ebonics? Wright(2005a) has assembled a bibliography of about 100 ‘scholarly references’and 55 newspaper articles (listed chronologically, from December 1996 toSeptember 2003; Todd, 1997, also provides a sample of press reaction).A number of prom<strong>in</strong>ent black scholars rejected <strong>the</strong> Oakland approach,while at <strong>the</strong> same time endors<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> underly<strong>in</strong>g motivation. HenryLouis Gates (cited by Rich, 1997), for <strong>in</strong>stance, said that <strong>the</strong> orig<strong>in</strong>aldeclaration was ‘obviously stupid and ridiculous’, but also that it was <strong>the</strong>‘sheer desperation of public schools <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>ner city’, <strong>the</strong> ‘grave nationalcrisis’, that pushed <strong>the</strong> ‘panicked Oakland board’ to move as it did. Gateswas also taken aback by <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>tensity of <strong>the</strong> reaction and <strong>the</strong> ‘nationalfixation’ on Ebonics. ‘As an African American’, he said, ‘I’m desperatefor solutions to illiteracy... I’d be open to any smart solution, but <strong>the</strong>Oakland school board didn’t come up with one’. Yet it was <strong>the</strong> board’s‘non-solution’ that attracted all <strong>the</strong> attention, ra<strong>the</strong>r than <strong>the</strong> underly<strong>in</strong>gproblems (Rich, 1997).With<strong>in</strong> a broader and ongo<strong>in</strong>g spectrum of criticism of BEV andnonstandard varieties generally (see Lippi-Green, 1997) both with<strong>in</strong>and without <strong>the</strong> black community it was clear that many blackAmericans were critical of <strong>the</strong> Oakland approach. Jesse Jackson <strong>in</strong>itiallydecried <strong>the</strong> school board’s declaration to say that black students didnot speak English was ‘foolish and <strong>in</strong>sult<strong>in</strong>g... this is an unacceptablesurrender, border<strong>in</strong>g on disgrace... it’s teach<strong>in</strong>g down to our children’;he later modified his views after meet<strong>in</strong>g with board members and someprom<strong>in</strong>ent l<strong>in</strong>guists (Todd, 1997: 15; see also McMillen, 1997). Thereaction of one black journalist Brent Staples of The New York Times was such that it prompted a prom<strong>in</strong>ent l<strong>in</strong>guist (Baugh, 2000) to accept acommission to write about <strong>the</strong> Ebonics controversy. Staples (1997) hadjo<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>the</strong> anti-Oakland brigade, claim<strong>in</strong>g that <strong>the</strong> school board deserved<strong>the</strong> scorn that greeted its assertion that ‘broken, <strong>in</strong>ner-city English [is] adist<strong>in</strong>ct ‘‘genetically based’’ language system’. He also made brief, butapparently approv<strong>in</strong>g, reference to a longer piece written four days


180 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>earlier by Heilbrunn (1997) <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> New Republic a dismissive paper thatBaugh (2000: 91) described as full of ‘sweep<strong>in</strong>g overgeneralizations’ thatdid great disservice to research across a range of scholarly discipl<strong>in</strong>es,demean<strong>in</strong>g it as ‘Ebonology’.The black critic with <strong>the</strong> highest profile was (and is) <strong>the</strong> popularenterta<strong>in</strong>er, Bill Cosby, who has been particularly outspoken about <strong>the</strong>language and behavior of <strong>the</strong> black community. As reported by Freeman(2006), Cosby said:Let me tell you someth<strong>in</strong>g... your dirty laundry gets out of school at2:30 every day: it’s curs<strong>in</strong>g and call<strong>in</strong>g each o<strong>the</strong>r ‘nigger’ as <strong>the</strong>y’rewalk<strong>in</strong>g up and down <strong>the</strong> street. They th<strong>in</strong>k <strong>the</strong>y’re hip. They can’tread. They can’t write. They’re laugh<strong>in</strong>g and giggl<strong>in</strong>g, and <strong>the</strong>y’rego<strong>in</strong>g nowhere.Smi<strong>the</strong>rman (2006) po<strong>in</strong>ts out that Cosby was a vociferous opponent ofEbonics at <strong>the</strong> time of <strong>the</strong> Oakland trial, and he obviously rema<strong>in</strong>s so. Ina speech delivered <strong>in</strong> 2004, Cosby refers aga<strong>in</strong> to black youngstersstand<strong>in</strong>g on <strong>the</strong> corner... Everybody knows it’s important to speakEnglish except <strong>the</strong>se knuckleheads. You can’t land a plane with ‘‘whyyou a<strong>in</strong>’t’’. You can’t be a doctor with that k<strong>in</strong>d of crap com<strong>in</strong>g out ofyour mouth. (Cosby, 2004: 3)Cosby’s remarks were pr<strong>in</strong>ted <strong>in</strong> The Black Scholar, <strong>in</strong> an issue almostentirely dedicated to Black English; it is well worth consult<strong>in</strong>g for acontemporary overview of black scholarly op<strong>in</strong>ion. Particularly <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>gare <strong>the</strong> papers by Cole, who feels that Cosby has come out with harshbut necessary truths, and by Kirkland et al., who argue that Cosby isl<strong>in</strong>guistically ill-<strong>in</strong>formed; see also <strong>the</strong> contributions by Black andWoodford.It is someth<strong>in</strong>g of an irony, Smi<strong>the</strong>rman (2006) reports, to f<strong>in</strong>d thatCosby himself beyond putt<strong>in</strong>g BEV <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> mouths of some of hiscartoon characters had <strong>in</strong> fact acknowledged <strong>the</strong> acceptability of codeswitch<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong> his 2004 speech. ‘You used to talk a certa<strong>in</strong> way on <strong>the</strong>corner’, he said, ‘and you got <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> house and switched <strong>in</strong>to English’(Smi<strong>the</strong>rman, 2006: 3). Odder still, she notes, is that <strong>in</strong> a much earlierspeech (to <strong>the</strong> Congressional Black Caucus <strong>in</strong> 1971), Cosby told hisaudience that ‘I th<strong>in</strong>k all you niggas need to... check yourselves out...So I say good even<strong>in</strong>g, niggas’ (Dyson, 2005: 240). For a vehement but<strong>in</strong>formed denunciation, from a markedly left-w<strong>in</strong>g position, of Cosby’sstance and <strong>the</strong> broader sociopolitical context of which it is a part, seeCane (2004). McWhorter (2000, 2003) also provides fur<strong>the</strong>r po<strong>in</strong>ted


Black English as Ebonics 181criticism from a l<strong>in</strong>guistic perspective; and see Coates (2008) for ajournalistic overview.Beyond his <strong>in</strong>temperate language, Cosby is clearly upset by <strong>the</strong> pooreducational achievements of black students, and ascribes much of this toattitude and language. This can be seen as a particular focus upon a muchbroader social issue; see M<strong>in</strong>cy (2006) for studies of <strong>the</strong> behavior andattitudes of urban <strong>in</strong>ner-city black men. Among many aspects of <strong>the</strong>matter, it is clear that a sense of social ‘marg<strong>in</strong>alization’, coupled with andfuelled by poverty and prejudice, can lead to an <strong>in</strong>ability or anunwill<strong>in</strong>gness to engage <strong>in</strong> important and potentially reward<strong>in</strong>g activities.Thus, for <strong>in</strong>stance, a recent assessment of <strong>the</strong> poor academic performanceof black children <strong>in</strong>vokes <strong>the</strong> idea of disidentification with <strong>the</strong> school. Theimplication is that, to <strong>the</strong> extent that students do not ‘identify’ with <strong>the</strong>academic culture, <strong>the</strong>y will perform poorly <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> classroom. This seemsan entirely reasonable supposition, and Osborne (1997), Steele (1992),Steele and Aronson (1995) and o<strong>the</strong>rs have demonstrated that a lack ofconnection here is most pronounced among African American maleteenagers.‘Disidentification’ with <strong>the</strong> school is heightened when we considerthat some students ra<strong>the</strong>r more po<strong>in</strong>tedly develop what has been termedan ‘oppositional identity’ (Wiggan, 2007). This is obviously not someth<strong>in</strong>gthat applies solely to black students an active and oppositionaldisda<strong>in</strong> for school is an historically and culturally widespread phenomenon(see also A<strong>in</strong>sworth-Darnell & Downey, 1998; Farkas et al., 2002;Goldsmith, 2004; Tyson, 2002). St<strong>in</strong>son’s (2006) overview is particularlyuseful here, as he considers various approaches to understand<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>achievement gap that so often separates black and white students, boysespecially. Of particular <strong>in</strong>terest is <strong>the</strong> ‘cool pose’ often adopted by blackmale adolescents as a visible rejection of <strong>the</strong> life of <strong>the</strong> school. As Majorsand Billson (1993) and Majors and Gordon (1994) have demonstrated,displays of ‘ritualized mascul<strong>in</strong>ity’ <strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>g dress, posture, stance andstride, hairstyles, speech styles and o<strong>the</strong>r such ‘statements’ can all beimportant here. They signify a blatant and forceful rejection, to be sure,but <strong>the</strong>y also act as markers of group solidarity. Whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>y represent<strong>the</strong> most effective avenue of social progress is, of course, ano<strong>the</strong>r matterentirely, and one that is much discussed both with<strong>in</strong> and without <strong>the</strong>black community itself.No one doubts that children un<strong>in</strong>terested <strong>in</strong> school are unlikely to dowell <strong>the</strong>re, or that a vicious circle can easily be generated. Almost twogenerations ago, Katz (1967) po<strong>in</strong>ted to motivation as <strong>the</strong> centralunderly<strong>in</strong>g factor: failure at school (particularly early failure) tends to


182 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>sap motivation, decrease expectations, re<strong>in</strong>force low self-esteem and soon. This is clearly true, but later research has added ano<strong>the</strong>r possibility:low academic motivation may also stem from a view of education thatsees it as unimportant and/or unattractive. (The two possibilities areobviously not mutually exclusive.) Graham et al. (1998) used a ‘peernom<strong>in</strong>ation’ procedure to <strong>in</strong>vestigate this; that is, <strong>the</strong>y asked students totell <strong>the</strong>m who among <strong>the</strong>ir classmates <strong>the</strong>y admired and respected.Among white pupils, both boys and girls valued o<strong>the</strong>rs who were do<strong>in</strong>gwell at school. The choices made by African American and Lat<strong>in</strong>o boys,on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r hand, suggested a devaluation of academic achievement; seealso Taylor and Graham (2007). Similarly, Fryer and Levitt (2004a) havenoted that studious black pupils had fewer friends than did poorerstudents, that work<strong>in</strong>g hard may attract accusations of ‘act<strong>in</strong>g white’ andthat as a summary <strong>in</strong> The Economist (2008: 34) put it it seems to be‘cool to be dumb... it would be hard to imag<strong>in</strong>e a more crippl<strong>in</strong>gcultural norm’.Graham et al. (1998: 606) go on to note that all participants <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>irstudy boys and girls, white, black and Hispanic associated ‘academicdisengagement and social deviance with be<strong>in</strong>g male, a low achiever, andan ethnic m<strong>in</strong>ority’. There seemed to be a general negative stereotype atwork, one that viewed low-achiev<strong>in</strong>g m<strong>in</strong>ority-group boys as not try<strong>in</strong>ghard at school, and not follow<strong>in</strong>g school norms and rules. Theresearchers cont<strong>in</strong>ue:We suspect that <strong>the</strong> African American and Lat<strong>in</strong>o boys <strong>in</strong> ourresearch are well aware of how <strong>the</strong>y are seen <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> eyes of o<strong>the</strong>rs andthat this awareness may have <strong>in</strong>fluenced what appeared to be <strong>the</strong>irrelative <strong>in</strong>difference to those who display achievement behaviors thatare valued by <strong>the</strong> larger society. Steele (1997) has written poignantlyabout how cop<strong>in</strong>g with negative stereotypes about <strong>the</strong>ir academiccompetence has led many African American students to academicallydisengage and discount <strong>the</strong> importance of school success.(Graham et al., 1998: 618)The more <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g questions are ‘underneath’, as it were: how andwhy does lack of <strong>in</strong>terest arise <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> first place, and how and why is itma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>ed when <strong>the</strong>re is so much evidence of its negative lifeconsequences? For <strong>the</strong> answers here, we have to look far beyond <strong>the</strong>school gates.In all of this, of course disidentification, oppositional identities,resistance to ‘talk<strong>in</strong>g white’ (see Chapter 8) or do<strong>in</strong>g well <strong>in</strong> school wemust remember that we are not deal<strong>in</strong>g with monolithic categories of


Black English as Ebonics 183students. A<strong>in</strong>sworth-Darnell and Downey (1998) and Goldsmith (2004)suggest that, under some circumstances, black, Hispanic and o<strong>the</strong>rm<strong>in</strong>ority-group youngsters may be more favorably disposed towardsschool than are <strong>the</strong>ir white counterparts. O<strong>the</strong>r researchers have shownthat high educational aspirations may sometimes be expected as areaction to social disadvantage, that success <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> classroom can be seenas a powerful response to historical oppression and <strong>in</strong>equality; see Akom(2003), O’Connor (1997) and Perry et al. (2003). Sometimes, <strong>in</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rwords, <strong>the</strong> disengagement that Ogbu and his associates have carefullydocumented over a number of years (see Fordham & Ogbu, 1986; Ogbu,2003; and Chapter 8) is not quite so evident. A moment’s reflection willreveal that both disengagement and its more positive opposite areentirely predictable responses to social disadvantage and prejudice, but itwill also suggest that <strong>the</strong> latter requires more self-discipl<strong>in</strong>e and is likely,<strong>the</strong>refore, to be <strong>in</strong> shorter supply than <strong>the</strong> former. In any event, recentAmerican social history shows quite clearly that m<strong>in</strong>ority-group difficultiesare real and, some would say, on <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>crease.While acknowledg<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> existence of broad social problems, it is stillreasonable to th<strong>in</strong>k about what might usefully be done <strong>in</strong> specific areas.One could agree or disagree with Bill Cosby (1997), for example, when hesays that ‘legitimiz<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> street <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> classroom is backwards. We shouldbe work<strong>in</strong>g hard to legitimize <strong>the</strong> classroom and English <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> street’.But <strong>the</strong> sentiments are not silly, and <strong>the</strong>y are clearly widely held. Indeed,<strong>the</strong>y can be understood <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> light of earlier discussions about <strong>the</strong> way <strong>in</strong>which l<strong>in</strong>guistic difference is translated <strong>in</strong>to l<strong>in</strong>guistic deficit through <strong>the</strong>power of social pressure. But <strong>the</strong>se earlier arguments also po<strong>in</strong>ted out that<strong>the</strong> difference-<strong>in</strong>to-deficit transformation was based upon an <strong>in</strong>validassessment of nonstandard dialect: it may be pervasive, but it is <strong>in</strong>accurateand should <strong>the</strong>refore be contested wherever possible. It is clear that <strong>the</strong>black critics of Ebonics do generally see it as a deficient variety, a po<strong>in</strong>t ofview that demonstrates <strong>the</strong>ir lack of l<strong>in</strong>guistic awareness, and for which<strong>the</strong>y may fairly be criticized. They cannot be criticized, however, for <strong>the</strong>irgenu<strong>in</strong>e concern for black children, nor, obviously, can <strong>the</strong>y be accused ofreject<strong>in</strong>g BEV on racially prejudiced pr<strong>in</strong>ciples.This accusation can, however, be levelled at many of <strong>the</strong> ‘popular’reactions to <strong>the</strong> Ebonics debate, reactions that are merely specificmanifestations of long-held stereotypes and prejudicial op<strong>in</strong>ions. Thesewere (and are) most easily seen <strong>in</strong> what passes for ‘humor’; <strong>the</strong> Lord’sPrayer rendered <strong>in</strong> Ebonics, or cartoons depict<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> English languagesla<strong>in</strong> by <strong>the</strong> ‘Ebonic plague’, or show<strong>in</strong>g a child at <strong>the</strong> blackboard hav<strong>in</strong>g written 7316 and <strong>the</strong>n tell<strong>in</strong>g his teacher ‘it’s mathabonics’


184 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>(Baugh, 2000; Scott, 1998). Nowadays, <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>ternet provides <strong>the</strong> quickestand most up-to-date po<strong>in</strong>t of entry <strong>in</strong>to this vast and largely unpleasantworld. I have just typed <strong>the</strong> words ‘Ebonics humor’ <strong>in</strong>to a Google search,and near <strong>the</strong> top of <strong>the</strong> list of some 101,000 ‘hits’ appears <strong>the</strong> follow<strong>in</strong>g:‘Ebonics language lesson. Ever wanted to talk like a nigger? Then listenup’. The power of <strong>the</strong> public media was illustrated <strong>in</strong> a recent study ofattitudes towards Ebonics (Barnes, 2003). Among a large sample ofuniversity students (roughly evenly divided between black and white,male and female), <strong>the</strong> author discovered that none was ‘overwhelm<strong>in</strong>gly<strong>in</strong> agreement about Ebonics as a communicative and teach<strong>in</strong>g tool’(Barnes, 2003: 252). More specifically, she wrote that:it is clear that knowledge about <strong>the</strong> Oakland School Board resolutiontended to negatively affect <strong>the</strong> viewpo<strong>in</strong>ts of many sample members.Awareness about <strong>the</strong> controversy reduced positive op<strong>in</strong>ions aboutEbonics and re<strong>in</strong>forced more negative views... This f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g confirms<strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>fluential role played by <strong>the</strong> media <strong>in</strong> shap<strong>in</strong>g public op<strong>in</strong>ion.(Barnes, 2003: 258)Barnes’s results are not quite as straightforward as she presents <strong>the</strong>m, but<strong>the</strong>y demonstrate, at <strong>the</strong> least, considerable ambivalence about <strong>the</strong> statusand possible role of Ebonics. It also seems likely that this ambivalencewas, <strong>in</strong> many <strong>in</strong>stances, pre-exist<strong>in</strong>g, but <strong>the</strong>n became fur<strong>the</strong>r re<strong>in</strong>forcedby <strong>the</strong> popular press <strong>in</strong> all its forms. And, s<strong>in</strong>ce that medium wasgenerally negative ei<strong>the</strong>r downright prejudiced or, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> case of someblack commentators and ‘celebrities’ of one sort or ano<strong>the</strong>r, cautiousand/or dismayed it is also reasonable to suppose that ambivalencetended to be ‘shaped’ towards <strong>the</strong> unfavorable end of <strong>the</strong> attitud<strong>in</strong>alscale.Notes1. If noth<strong>in</strong>g else, <strong>the</strong> Oakland affair has surely given <strong>the</strong> lie to Gertrude Ste<strong>in</strong>’sfamous observation. ‘What was <strong>the</strong> use’, she said, ‘of my hav<strong>in</strong>g come fromOakland... <strong>the</strong>re is no <strong>the</strong>re <strong>the</strong>re’ (Ste<strong>in</strong>, 1937: 289).2. As Max We<strong>in</strong>reich once observed: ‘a language is a dialect that has an armyand a navy’. And, as Fillmore (2005: 162) po<strong>in</strong>ts out, ‘decid<strong>in</strong>g whe<strong>the</strong>r BBCnewsreaders and Lynchburg, VA radio evangelists speak different dialects of<strong>the</strong> same language or different languages <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> same language family is on<strong>the</strong> level of decid<strong>in</strong>g whe<strong>the</strong>r Greenland is a small cont<strong>in</strong>ent or a large island’.3. I am rem<strong>in</strong>ded here of ano<strong>the</strong>r connection between Ebonics and Scots. In <strong>the</strong>former, <strong>the</strong>re exists a well-known game of verbal fenc<strong>in</strong>g called ‘<strong>the</strong> dozens’;this typically <strong>in</strong>volves an exchange of <strong>in</strong>sults that cont<strong>in</strong>ues until one of <strong>the</strong>players can make no comeback. (Some have argued that <strong>the</strong> term derivesfrom <strong>the</strong> practice of sell<strong>in</strong>g deformed or mutilated slaves by <strong>the</strong> dozen to be


Black English as Ebonics 185sold <strong>in</strong> such a lot be<strong>in</strong>g an egregious <strong>in</strong>sult to dignity and worth whileo<strong>the</strong>rs suggest that it implies that <strong>the</strong> game of <strong>in</strong>sults goes up to 12exchanges.) As Smi<strong>the</strong>rman (2006: 28) observes, <strong>the</strong> most important rule <strong>in</strong><strong>the</strong> game is that <strong>the</strong> slanderous comments ‘must not be literally true, becausetruth takes <strong>the</strong> game out of <strong>the</strong> realm of play <strong>in</strong>to reality’.In Scotland, <strong>the</strong> 15th-century practice of ‘flyt<strong>in</strong>g’ (i.e. quarrell<strong>in</strong>g ordisput<strong>in</strong>g) also <strong>in</strong>volved fierce and colorful <strong>in</strong>sult; ‘a stylized tour de force ofmutually exchanged abuse, each contestant striv<strong>in</strong>g to outdo <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r <strong>in</strong>brilliantly <strong>in</strong>ventive <strong>in</strong>vective... not to be taken as <strong>in</strong>dicat<strong>in</strong>g personalanimus’ (Ousby, 2000: 282). There are parallels <strong>in</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r Celtic countries, <strong>in</strong>nor<strong>the</strong>rn Europe generally, and <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Islamic world. In fact, such elaborateritualized exchanges, often scurrilous <strong>in</strong> nature, occur widely, and particularly<strong>in</strong> oral cultures or those <strong>in</strong> which verbal dexterity per se has rema<strong>in</strong>edprestigious.The classic Scottish example is The Flyt<strong>in</strong>g of Dunbar and Kennedie, whichScott found to be ‘<strong>the</strong> most repellent poem he knew <strong>in</strong> any language’ (Ousby,2000: 282; Dunbar, 1508).


Chapter 10‘Foreign’ <strong>Language</strong>s <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong><strong>Classroom</strong>IntroductionOnce a privilege, access to education is now a right; <strong>in</strong>deed, mostchildren are required to go to school until a determ<strong>in</strong>ed age. <strong>Classroom</strong>smust often cater, <strong>the</strong>n, for children from a variety of l<strong>in</strong>guistic and culturalbackgrounds, a circumstance that can give rise to educational pressures ofvarious k<strong>in</strong>ds. There are many different ways <strong>in</strong> which schools, andeducational bureaucracies <strong>in</strong> general, can respond to issues raised by <strong>the</strong>heterogeneity of populations, but perhaps it is not unfair to see <strong>the</strong>se asfall<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>to two (very) broad categories. The first <strong>in</strong>volves pupils adapt<strong>in</strong>gto <strong>the</strong> ideas and methods of <strong>the</strong> school; <strong>the</strong> second <strong>in</strong>volves <strong>the</strong> schooldemonstrat<strong>in</strong>g, to a greater or lesser degree, a will<strong>in</strong>gness to adapt itself to<strong>the</strong> pupils. The fur<strong>the</strong>r back <strong>in</strong> time one goes, <strong>the</strong> more likely it is that onewill encounter examples with<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> first of <strong>the</strong>se categories. Conversely,present-day education <strong>in</strong> many parts of <strong>the</strong> world is likely to exhibit someadaptive tendencies or, at least, it is now considered reasonable todiscuss possibilities <strong>in</strong> this connection. In terms of respond<strong>in</strong>g to whatis essentially a discont<strong>in</strong>uity between <strong>the</strong> milieus of <strong>home</strong> and school, both<strong>the</strong> ma<strong>in</strong>tenance of a relatively unaltered ‘core’ curriculum with<strong>in</strong> atraditional milieu, and a policy of accommodation, can be understood tohave positive and negative aspects.The focus of this book is largely upon responses to children’s variedlanguage abilities, but <strong>the</strong>se are often <strong>in</strong>tertw<strong>in</strong>ed with considerations ofmessage as well as medium. In terms of what is to be taught, for example,it is now common to read about <strong>the</strong> provision of group-specific<strong>in</strong>formation history, culture, l<strong>in</strong>guistic heritage, religion and so on particularly where <strong>the</strong>re are sufficient concentrations of <strong>in</strong>digenous orimmigrant m<strong>in</strong>ority-group children. Questions of <strong>the</strong> degree to whichcontent should be modified for specific student populations or, <strong>in</strong>deed, of<strong>the</strong> appropriateness of <strong>the</strong> exercise at all have become very heated <strong>in</strong>some sett<strong>in</strong>gs. The value of learn<strong>in</strong>g about one’s own group seemsreasonable, but it may also be valuable to require all pupils to learn <strong>the</strong>186


‘Foreign’ <strong>Language</strong>s <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong> 187same th<strong>in</strong>gs. An educational program that is more ‘adaptable’ to localcontexts may also be a program that prepares children badly forparticipation <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> wider social milieu. S<strong>in</strong>ce many non-‘ma<strong>in</strong>stream’families see (accurately or not) <strong>the</strong>ir children’s future directly related tosuccess <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> ma<strong>in</strong>stream, approaches that focus too closely uponsubcultural values may be at once well-mean<strong>in</strong>g and dangerous. We donot, after all, wish to see education limit<strong>in</strong>g children’s chances. I shallreturn to <strong>the</strong>se broader matters of multicultural education later on.The issues of immediate <strong>in</strong>terest <strong>in</strong> this chapter <strong>in</strong>volve ‘foreign’languages at school. I am not primarily concerned here with <strong>the</strong>‘traditional’ teach<strong>in</strong>g of languages (but see <strong>the</strong> follow<strong>in</strong>g section) French, German or Spanish as part of <strong>the</strong> regular secondary-schoolcurriculum, for example or with <strong>the</strong> large literature on <strong>the</strong> teach<strong>in</strong>g andlearn<strong>in</strong>g of modern languages. There have been many fads and fashions<strong>in</strong> teach<strong>in</strong>g techniques and methods, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> use of technologies of varioussorts, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> connections between language-as-subject and language-astool,and so on. The more relevant matters for my purposes have to dowith <strong>the</strong> adaptations that schools make (or do not make) when deal<strong>in</strong>gwith l<strong>in</strong>guistic heterogeneity: it is this that l<strong>in</strong>ks <strong>the</strong> current focus with<strong>the</strong> preced<strong>in</strong>g discussion of <strong>the</strong> educational treatment of nonstandarddialectspeakers.M<strong>in</strong>ority-group populations are commonly understood to be constituentsof a larger society who are outside some def<strong>in</strong>able majority-group‘ma<strong>in</strong>stream’ <strong>in</strong> important ways. Two obvious and common po<strong>in</strong>ts ofdifferentiation are <strong>the</strong> relative size of <strong>the</strong> groups and <strong>the</strong> sociopoliticalrelationships that l<strong>in</strong>k <strong>the</strong>m. (I realize of course that <strong>the</strong> idea of a‘ma<strong>in</strong>stream’ is itself dubious <strong>in</strong> some contexts, that a ‘ma<strong>in</strong>stream’ <strong>in</strong>many societies is a dynamic and not a static entity, that <strong>the</strong>re may bemore than one ‘ma<strong>in</strong>stream’ <strong>in</strong> a given sett<strong>in</strong>g, and so on.) There aredifferent types of m<strong>in</strong>orities, and <strong>the</strong> differences often reside <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>vary<strong>in</strong>g ways <strong>in</strong> which groups come <strong>in</strong>to contact: frontier populations(often exhibit<strong>in</strong>g very <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g language variations from <strong>the</strong>ir more‘heartland’ counterparts, for <strong>in</strong>stance), migrant-worker concentrations(<strong>the</strong> Gastarbeiter <strong>in</strong> western Europe whose immigrant status <strong>in</strong> severalcountries has now been exchanged for residential permanence), <strong>in</strong>digenousgroups now part of larger political units (<strong>the</strong> Welsh, <strong>the</strong> Bretons,<strong>the</strong> Catalans) and immigrant populations are all notable examples here.For present purposes, it is clear that <strong>in</strong>digenous m<strong>in</strong>orities andimmigrant groups are of <strong>the</strong> greatest <strong>in</strong>terest. An allegiance to nonma<strong>in</strong>streamculture, or a mixed allegiance, means that immigrantpopulations and <strong>in</strong>digenous groups are to some extent separate, both


188 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong><strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir own eyes and <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> perceptions of o<strong>the</strong>rs. In some cases, <strong>the</strong>separateness decreases over time, sometimes to such an extent that it islost, but this is not <strong>in</strong>evitable. Some groups, or some group members,resist assimilation; for o<strong>the</strong>rs, visible dist<strong>in</strong>ctiveness may mean a moreendur<strong>in</strong>g separateness, even if this is not desired. As with <strong>the</strong> earlierdiscussion of <strong>the</strong> discont<strong>in</strong>uities that may dist<strong>in</strong>guish nonstandard,work<strong>in</strong>g-class speakers from some ma<strong>in</strong>stream or middle-class population,<strong>the</strong> most germane matters here have to do with <strong>the</strong> po<strong>in</strong>ts of contactbetween those who dom<strong>in</strong>ate and those who do not. It is <strong>the</strong> dynamics of<strong>the</strong>se contact po<strong>in</strong>ts that ei<strong>the</strong>r produce or suppress l<strong>in</strong>guistic accommodation,and this is true whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> accommodation is simply to easem<strong>in</strong>ority-group speakers more efficiently <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> dom<strong>in</strong>ant l<strong>in</strong>guisticchannel, or to contribute to some relatively endur<strong>in</strong>g cultural pluralism.<strong>Language</strong>, <strong>in</strong> all its forms, has always been <strong>the</strong> central feature ofeducation. As we have already seen, concerns for language havegenerally coexisted with strong sentiments about what is correct andwhat is wrong, what is different and what is deficient. This prescriptivisttendency has both reflected and re<strong>in</strong>forced broader ‘ma<strong>in</strong>stream’op<strong>in</strong>ion. We have also seen how certa<strong>in</strong> groups of children whoselanguage is not of <strong>the</strong> standard variety typically taught and encouragedat school children of <strong>the</strong> work<strong>in</strong>g class, or of ethnic-m<strong>in</strong>ority orig<strong>in</strong> orof both have been seen as l<strong>in</strong>guistically disadvantaged and <strong>in</strong> need ofremedial or compensatory attention. The aim here has often been toreplace an allegedly flawed maternal variety with a ‘correct’ one, although<strong>the</strong>re is perhaps an <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>g tendency to opt for a policy of repertoireexpansion: to supplement <strong>the</strong> maternal variety, that is, with a morestandard form. From a l<strong>in</strong>guistic po<strong>in</strong>t of view, this is certa<strong>in</strong>ly a moreenlightened approach, but putt<strong>in</strong>g it <strong>in</strong>to effect is a delicate exercise thatis rarely handled well, even when teachers are <strong>in</strong>formed and sympa<strong>the</strong>tic.Replacement rema<strong>in</strong>s <strong>the</strong> policy <strong>in</strong> too many sett<strong>in</strong>gs, however,and even where more progressive views obta<strong>in</strong>, it regularly reappearswhenever ‘decl<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g standards’ are an issue, or whenever a previouslydisparaged dialect makes a bid for a place <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> classroom.When we move from dialect to language, we should first of all recallthat l<strong>in</strong>guistic prejudices and <strong>the</strong>ir important ramifications have oftenmade a seem<strong>in</strong>gly effortless leap from nonstandard to altoge<strong>the</strong>rseparate varieties. In a previous chapter, for <strong>in</strong>stance, I touched uponearly 20th-century assessments of <strong>in</strong>telligence that regularly demonstrated<strong>the</strong> feeble-m<strong>in</strong>dedness of non-English speakers, mentionedGoodenough’s (1926: 393) observation that ‘<strong>the</strong> use of a foreign language<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>home</strong> is one of <strong>the</strong> chief factors <strong>in</strong> produc<strong>in</strong>g mental retardation’,


‘Foreign’ <strong>Language</strong>s <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong> 189and alluded to We<strong>in</strong>reich’s (1953) compilation <strong>in</strong> which everyth<strong>in</strong>g fromidleness to moral depravity was seen to be a consequence of bil<strong>in</strong>gualism.Flores (2005), whose work I have also cited previously, has provideda closer focus on <strong>the</strong>se prejudices <strong>in</strong> her historical overview of Spanishspeak<strong>in</strong>gschoolchildren <strong>in</strong> 20th-century America; see also Gifford andValdés (2006) and Jiménez (2006). Early conceptions of an associationamong measured <strong>in</strong>telligence, <strong>the</strong> Spanish language and mental deficiencygave way to <strong>the</strong> idea that bil<strong>in</strong>gualism was somehow an‘unnatural’ state of affairs, and one that h<strong>in</strong>dered educational progress.Focus <strong>the</strong>n shifted, around mid-century, to <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>adequacies of a‘culturally deprived’ <strong>home</strong> and neighborhood, and <strong>the</strong>n to <strong>the</strong> newspectre of ‘semil<strong>in</strong>gualism’ a twist on <strong>the</strong> problems of bil<strong>in</strong>gualism,<strong>in</strong>asmuch as <strong>the</strong> price of bil<strong>in</strong>gualism was now seen to be <strong>in</strong>adequacy <strong>in</strong>each language. As <strong>the</strong> century drew to a close, Spanish-speak<strong>in</strong>gyoungsters <strong>in</strong> America were seen to be ‘at risk’, <strong>the</strong>ir uneducated parentsfail<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>in</strong>stil <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>m any concern for, or <strong>in</strong>terest <strong>in</strong>, formal school<strong>in</strong>g.Plus ça change...<strong>Language</strong> Learn<strong>in</strong>g and <strong>Language</strong> Attitudes<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>If we move beyond stigmatized dialects and languages, we realize that,while schools have always concerned <strong>the</strong>mselves with ‘correctness’, <strong>the</strong>yhave also recognized that competence <strong>in</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r languages is a mark ofeducation. I noted <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> previous section that my major focus here is noton <strong>the</strong> traditional concerns associated with language learn<strong>in</strong>g at school.Ra<strong>the</strong>r, <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>tent here as <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> earlier discussion of ‘disadvantaged’dialect speakers is to consider <strong>the</strong> l<strong>in</strong>guistic and cultural ramifications ofeducational contact between groups of unequal social clout. How are <strong>the</strong>speakers of <strong>in</strong>digenous- and immigrant-m<strong>in</strong>ority languages dealt with atschool, what value (if any) is placed upon <strong>the</strong>ir maternal varieties, to whatextent should <strong>the</strong> school be open to alterations with <strong>the</strong>se speakers <strong>in</strong>m<strong>in</strong>d? These and o<strong>the</strong>r similar questions are central. But it seems useful topreface fur<strong>the</strong>r comment with a brief discussion of broader aspects oflanguage-at-school. After all, besides <strong>the</strong> historical value placed uponlanguages per se, besides <strong>the</strong> central position of Greek and Lat<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>curriculum, besides <strong>the</strong> unremarked-upon addition of a modern Europeanlanguage to <strong>the</strong> repertoire of <strong>the</strong> well-rounded Victorian besides all<strong>the</strong>se, <strong>the</strong>re have always existed contexts that have made <strong>the</strong> expansion oflanguage repertoires simply necessary. The classroom is an obvious, if notalways a very efficient, sett<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> which such learn<strong>in</strong>g can take place.


190 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>In situations of necessity it is clear that <strong>the</strong> efforts of <strong>the</strong> school aredriven and re<strong>in</strong>forced by extra-educational forces. Conversely, wherenecessity is not a feature, schools must act more <strong>in</strong> isolation and, needlessto say, <strong>the</strong>ir task is much more difficult. These simple facts account formany of <strong>the</strong> disparities observed <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> success of language teach<strong>in</strong>g andlearn<strong>in</strong>g. One need not be a Solomon to see that <strong>the</strong>re are moredifficulties teach<strong>in</strong>g German <strong>in</strong> Iowa than <strong>in</strong> Nijmegen. In <strong>the</strong> Iowas of<strong>the</strong> world and <strong>the</strong>re are many of <strong>the</strong>m, especially <strong>in</strong> anglophonecommunities <strong>the</strong> difficulty of creat<strong>in</strong>g an <strong>in</strong>strumental need for foreignlanguages means that language attitudes may become more importantthan <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Nijmegens (see below). Here, of course, schools have oftendone a poor job. Traditional classes, with <strong>the</strong>ir emphasis upon grammarand writ<strong>in</strong>g skills, have often made <strong>the</strong> learn<strong>in</strong>g of languages a passive,receptive matter for students. This is hardly likely to <strong>in</strong>duce <strong>in</strong> pupils anysense that learn<strong>in</strong>g German is a different sort of exercise than learn<strong>in</strong>gtrigonometry or ancient history. It does noth<strong>in</strong>g to reduce <strong>the</strong> artificialityof a classroom <strong>in</strong> which teachers and pupils rout<strong>in</strong>ely but ra<strong>the</strong>runnaturally use a language that is nei<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>ir maternal variety norone that can be put to any immediate use. It is, additionally, nei<strong>the</strong>r anextension of <strong>the</strong> way first languages are acquired where communicationis stressed and where grammatical ref<strong>in</strong>ements come afterwards nor a representation of normal, <strong>in</strong>teractive conversation. Modernmethods have attempted to remedy this. The chief development is toencourage a more ‘natural’ conversational <strong>in</strong>terplay and <strong>the</strong>re have beenreal strides made here. But, without go<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> large literature onmethods that is peripheral to my present purpose, it can be appreciatedthat school language learn<strong>in</strong>g will always ei<strong>the</strong>r benefit from externallyimposed necessity or suffer for <strong>the</strong> lack of it.The perceived importance of attitude and motivation <strong>in</strong> languagelearn<strong>in</strong>gexercises, and <strong>the</strong> endur<strong>in</strong>g difficulties <strong>in</strong> encourag<strong>in</strong>g andma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>terest <strong>in</strong> classroom sett<strong>in</strong>gs, have led to a specialistliterature on language attitudes (or beliefs, of course: see above). I amnot closely concerned here with <strong>the</strong> technicalities of this literature; goodoverviews can be found <strong>in</strong> Dörnyei and Schmidt (2001), Dörnyei (2005)and, especially, Dörnyei and Ushioda (2009). The latter comprises anexcellent treatment, <strong>in</strong> 18 chapters, by all <strong>the</strong> important currentresearchers <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> field. Beyond <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>troductory and conclud<strong>in</strong>gchapters, <strong>the</strong> two editors also provide substantive chapters <strong>the</strong>mselves;additionally, <strong>the</strong>re are noteworthy contributions by MacIntyre, Clément,Kormos, Segalowitz, Noels and many o<strong>the</strong>rs. For recent treatments thatembed discussions of attitude and motivation <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> broader language


‘Foreign’ <strong>Language</strong>s <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong> 191literature, see Bhatia and Ritchie (2006) and Gass and Sel<strong>in</strong>ker (2008); <strong>the</strong>latter can be particularly recommended as a comprehensive <strong>in</strong>troductorytext. Throughout <strong>the</strong> literature, <strong>the</strong> generality is that favorable attitudescontribute to <strong>the</strong> ease and depth of second-language acquisition. This hasbecome a widely accepted po<strong>in</strong>t: ‘motivation appears to be <strong>the</strong> secondstrongest predictor of success, trail<strong>in</strong>g only aptitude’ (Gass & Sel<strong>in</strong>ker,2008: 426). While <strong>the</strong>re is much room for detailed consideration of <strong>the</strong>varied forms that motivation may take, <strong>the</strong> general po<strong>in</strong>t seems soobvious that it would hardly merit detailed attention. Some years ago,however, Macnamara (1973) appeared to take a contrary view, assert<strong>in</strong>gthat attitudes were of little importance <strong>in</strong> language learn<strong>in</strong>g. Hisargument rema<strong>in</strong>s a succ<strong>in</strong>ct and noteworthy one; it is <strong>in</strong>structiveeven where it errs.Macnamara first noted that necessity may overpower attitudes: a childwho moves from Birm<strong>in</strong>gham to Berl<strong>in</strong> will learn German. This po<strong>in</strong>t,which applies also to adults, is clearly correct and most people cancorroborate it from personal or <strong>in</strong>direct experience. At about <strong>the</strong> sametime as Macnamara was writ<strong>in</strong>g, an illustrative confirmation was found<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> report of a large-scale language-attitude survey <strong>in</strong> his own paysnatal <strong>the</strong> use of Irish was found to be more associated with ability thanwith attitudes (Committee on Irish <strong>Language</strong> Attitudes Research, 1975).This unsurpris<strong>in</strong>g relationship does not mean that attitudes are unimportant,but it does rem<strong>in</strong>d us that ‘<strong>in</strong> certa<strong>in</strong> contexts, attitudes are morelikely to assume importance only after some m<strong>in</strong>imal competence hasbeen established’ (Edwards, 1977c: 57). There is thus some reason toth<strong>in</strong>k that, <strong>in</strong> real-life contexts, attitudes may <strong>in</strong>deed be secondary <strong>in</strong>importance to ability. Macnamara’s second po<strong>in</strong>t also has to do withlanguage learn<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> real world. He refers to <strong>the</strong> adoption of Englishby <strong>the</strong> Irish population, a language shift not accompanied by favorableattitudes. Indeed, most historical changes <strong>in</strong> language use owe muchmore to socioeconomic and political exigencies than <strong>the</strong>y do to attitudes.However, Macnamara does acknowledge that attitudes of a sort <strong>in</strong>strumental attitudes may play a part <strong>in</strong> such broadly-based shifts.For example, while a mid-19th-century Irishman might have loa<strong>the</strong>dEnglish and what it represented, he may yet have come to grudg<strong>in</strong>glyrealize <strong>the</strong> usefulness of <strong>the</strong> language for himself and, more importantly,for his children. There would have been, <strong>the</strong>refore, no <strong>in</strong>tegrativemotivation, no desire to learn English <strong>in</strong> order to facilitate culturalmobility, but a possibly reluctant <strong>in</strong>strumental one; for a discussion of<strong>the</strong>se attitude variants that Macnamara draws upon, see Gardner andLambert (1972).


192 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>Interest<strong>in</strong>gly enough, Macnamara rejects <strong>the</strong> possibility of any reallysignificant <strong>in</strong>strumental motivation <strong>in</strong> such cases on a technicality, as itwere; he claims that Gardner, Lambert and o<strong>the</strong>rs had reserved this termto describe present learn<strong>in</strong>g for future purposes. However, whatever <strong>the</strong>views have been of what constitutes <strong>in</strong>strumental motivation, it is clearly<strong>in</strong>correct to deny <strong>the</strong> term’s aptness for <strong>the</strong> experience of <strong>the</strong> childtransported to Germany, or of <strong>the</strong> Irishman’s move to English. Justbecause <strong>the</strong> Irishman hated <strong>the</strong> English occupation did not mean that hecould not appreciate <strong>the</strong> value of <strong>the</strong> language of his ascendancy masters.Just because <strong>the</strong> child cannot appreciate <strong>the</strong> future usefulness of Germandoes not mean that he or she is unaware at some level of its presentutility and this is obviously an <strong>in</strong>strumental aspect. All of this led me tosuggest a dist<strong>in</strong>ction between positive and favorable attitude (Edwards,1983c). The two terms need not, after all, be synonymous: a positiveposition is one of certa<strong>in</strong>ty or assurance, but it need not be pleasant. ‘Ipositively loa<strong>the</strong> it’ is not an oxymoronic statement. To stay with <strong>the</strong> Irishexample, we could say that <strong>the</strong> attitude of <strong>the</strong> mass of <strong>the</strong> 19th-centurypopulation towards <strong>the</strong> English language was positive and <strong>in</strong>strumental,but not favorable (and certa<strong>in</strong>ly not <strong>in</strong>tegrative).The third strand to Macnamara’s argument br<strong>in</strong>gs us back to <strong>the</strong>classroom. He contends that traditional language learn<strong>in</strong>g at school hasbeen an unreal and artificial affair, an undertak<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> which communicationis subord<strong>in</strong>ate to an appreciation of language as an academic subject.It is this lack of communicative purpose, and not children’s attitudes, tha<strong>the</strong> feels underlies <strong>the</strong>ir poor language competence. Although I wouldagree that a great fail<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> language classrooms has been <strong>the</strong> absence ofany realistic usage, I do not th<strong>in</strong>k that this means that attitudes are of smallimportance. It is ra<strong>the</strong>r a matter of attitudes tak<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>ir proper position,which <strong>in</strong> many cases is secondary to language ability. In <strong>in</strong>stances ofsocietal language shift (from Irish to English, say) as well as <strong>in</strong> cases of<strong>in</strong>dividual necessity, <strong>the</strong> po<strong>in</strong>t is not that attitudes are unimportant, butthat <strong>the</strong>y are <strong>in</strong>strumental, if unfavorable. The argument that <strong>the</strong> classroomis an ‘artificial’ context may reflect a condemnation of traditionalapproaches, but it does not of itself <strong>in</strong>dicate that attitudes are trivial.In fact, as noted earlier, attitudes are clearly of considerable importance(<strong>in</strong> language learn<strong>in</strong>g, and <strong>in</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r subject areas) precisely because of‘artificiality’. If a context is not perceived as pert<strong>in</strong>ent to real life, or doesnot arise from necessity, <strong>the</strong>n attitudes may make a real difference.In fact, if we return aga<strong>in</strong> to <strong>the</strong> Irish situation, we can see that <strong>the</strong>notion of artificiality can extend beyond <strong>the</strong> classroom. With <strong>the</strong>establishment of <strong>the</strong> Irish state <strong>in</strong> 1922, and <strong>the</strong> subsequent revival


‘Foreign’ <strong>Language</strong>s <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong> 193emphasis upon schools as agents of Irish-language restoration, <strong>the</strong>rearose a disjunction between official aims regard<strong>in</strong>g Irish and actual,societal l<strong>in</strong>guistic behavior. An ever-decreas<strong>in</strong>g level of native competencehas been accompanied by an <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>g m<strong>in</strong>imal competence <strong>in</strong>basic skills, produced entirely through education. It can <strong>the</strong>refore beargued that schools, and <strong>the</strong> attitudes towards Irish that <strong>the</strong>y haveencouraged, have been of <strong>the</strong> greatest importance <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> ma<strong>in</strong>tenance ofIrish (such as it is: see Edwards, 1977c; <strong>in</strong> preparation). It is worthpo<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g out here, by <strong>the</strong> way, that this brief treatment of <strong>the</strong> fortunes ofIrish takes us back to <strong>the</strong> m<strong>in</strong>ority-group scenarios previously touchedupon. Irish people <strong>in</strong> Ireland are obviously nei<strong>the</strong>r an <strong>in</strong>digenous nor animmigrant m<strong>in</strong>ority group; <strong>the</strong>ir orig<strong>in</strong>al group language, however, hasbecome a m<strong>in</strong>ority variety <strong>in</strong> its own <strong>home</strong>, as it were. This po<strong>in</strong>ts to an<strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g sub-division with<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>digenous-m<strong>in</strong>ority category. If weconsider, say, <strong>the</strong> Indian ‘first nations’ of Canada, it is obvious that both<strong>the</strong> speakers and <strong>the</strong>ir languages are of m<strong>in</strong>ority status; but if we look atareas like Ireland and Wales, it is equally clear that, while <strong>the</strong>autochthonous <strong>in</strong>habitants are still <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> majority <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> land, <strong>the</strong>irorig<strong>in</strong>al varieties have become ‘m<strong>in</strong>oritized’. This is because <strong>the</strong>ir landand <strong>the</strong>ir languages have come <strong>in</strong>to contact with powerful neighbors andrivals. It follows that language-revival efforts <strong>in</strong> such sett<strong>in</strong>gs will have aspecial poignancy. 1With even a m<strong>in</strong>imal sense of <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>teractions among attitude,motivation and perceived necessity, it becomes easy to understand <strong>the</strong>problems associated with teach<strong>in</strong>g and learn<strong>in</strong>g foreign languages <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>contemporary anglophone context <strong>in</strong> Brita<strong>in</strong>, <strong>in</strong> Australia and NewZealand and, above all, <strong>in</strong> North America. The difficulties arise becauseof contextual conditions hav<strong>in</strong>g to do with power and dom<strong>in</strong>ance, andwith <strong>the</strong> fact that, <strong>in</strong> a world made <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>gly safe for anglophones,<strong>the</strong>re is less and less reason (or so it seems to many, students <strong>in</strong>cluded)for <strong>the</strong>m to learn any o<strong>the</strong>r language. Swaffar (1999: 1011) recentlymade some suggestions ‘to help foreign language departments assumecommand of <strong>the</strong>ir dest<strong>in</strong>ies’, and <strong>the</strong> usual suspects were pedanticallyrounded up: a redef<strong>in</strong>ition of <strong>the</strong> discipl<strong>in</strong>e (‘as a dist<strong>in</strong>ct and sequenced<strong>in</strong>quiry <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> constituents and applications of mean<strong>in</strong>gful communication’),more emphasis upon communication and less upon narrowgrammatical accuracy, <strong>the</strong> establishment of standards, models andcommon curricula (for ‘consistent pedagogical rhetoric’) and so on. Allvery laudable, no doubt but why do I th<strong>in</strong>k of Nero? It has always beendifficult to sell languages <strong>in</strong> Kansas: wherever you go, for manyhundreds of miles, English will take you to McDonalds, get you a burger


194 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>and br<strong>in</strong>g you safely <strong>home</strong> aga<strong>in</strong> and a thorough rework<strong>in</strong>g ofpedagogical rhetoric doesn’t amount to sale prices.Broadly speak<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>the</strong>re are two paths through <strong>the</strong> woods, althoughoccasionally <strong>the</strong>y share <strong>the</strong> same ground. The first is for foreign-languageteach<strong>in</strong>g to satisfy itself with that shr<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g pool of students <strong>in</strong>tr<strong>in</strong>sically<strong>in</strong>terested <strong>in</strong> languages and <strong>the</strong>ir cultures. These are, after all, <strong>the</strong> studentsnearest to one’s own <strong>in</strong>tellectual heart. The problem is that <strong>the</strong> ‘natural’constituency here might prove too small to support a discipl<strong>in</strong>e at desiredlevels, and it is hard to nurture <strong>in</strong> any direct way. The o<strong>the</strong>r is to hope andwork for a renewed <strong>in</strong>strumental <strong>in</strong>terest, with whatever longer-termfallout that might lead to. To some extent, this is dependent upon a contextthat extends well beyond national borders, upon alterations <strong>in</strong> globall<strong>in</strong>guistic circumstance that, while <strong>in</strong>evitable, are not always easy topredict. But one could argue, as well, that th<strong>in</strong>gs might be done at <strong>home</strong> <strong>in</strong> an <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>gly multil<strong>in</strong>gual Brita<strong>in</strong>, for <strong>in</strong>stance, or, <strong>in</strong> an Americawhere <strong>the</strong> number of Hispanics has recently overtaken that of blackAmericans. This latter situation is an <strong>in</strong>structive one.The study of Spanish <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> United States is self-evidently important:it is a language with a lengthy cultural and literary tradition, with many<strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g branches to <strong>the</strong> orig<strong>in</strong>al trunk. At <strong>the</strong> same time, it rema<strong>in</strong>s awidely used variety around <strong>the</strong> world; with someth<strong>in</strong>g like 300 millionspeakers, it runs fourth (beh<strong>in</strong>d H<strong>in</strong>di, Ch<strong>in</strong>ese and English) <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> usagesweepstakes. Academically, <strong>the</strong>n, it is <strong>the</strong> ideal American secondlanguage, and so, with both a global and a national presence, it is nowonder that Spanish is <strong>in</strong>deed <strong>the</strong> l<strong>in</strong>chp<strong>in</strong> of modern-language teach<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> United States.Thewholearea,however,rema<strong>in</strong>sweak weaker than one might firstexpect. Even though statistics assembled by <strong>the</strong> Modern <strong>Language</strong>Association (see Edwards, 2001) showed an overall <strong>in</strong>crease of about 5%<strong>in</strong> foreign-language enrolments s<strong>in</strong>ce 1995, only 1.2 million college studentswere represented here, fewer than 8% of <strong>the</strong> total. There were steepdecl<strong>in</strong>es <strong>in</strong> some quarters: enrolments <strong>in</strong> German were reportedly downby 7.5% (90,000 students altoge<strong>the</strong>r), and those <strong>in</strong> French decreased by 3%(to about 200,000). But for Spanish, <strong>the</strong> figures were better. With enrolmentsup by about 8%, which translates to some 660,000 students, one can seethat students of Spanish constituted 55% of all tertiary-level languagestudents. Is Spanish learn<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> a healthy situation, <strong>the</strong>n, or does it onlyseem so <strong>in</strong> comparison with weaker sisters? This may be an impossiblequestion to answer. After all, how many students ought to be study<strong>in</strong>gSpanish or archaeology, or quantum mechanics, or sculpture? Still, onemight expect that language study would be more immediately related to


‘Foreign’ <strong>Language</strong>s <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong> 195extra-educational factors jobs, mobility, opportunity and so on and, ifthat is so, <strong>the</strong>n one might wonder why <strong>the</strong> strength of <strong>the</strong> AmericanHispanic community does not bolster <strong>the</strong> educational effort more.In fact, despite America’s multi-ethnic status <strong>in</strong> general, and itspowerful Hispanic components more specifically, we come back to acontext of anglophone dom<strong>in</strong>ance that obta<strong>in</strong>s both with<strong>in</strong> and withoutnational borders. It is a context that makes some recent comments byCarlos Fuentes (1999) seem ra<strong>the</strong>r naïve even though <strong>the</strong>y are em<strong>in</strong>entlyunderstandable, reflective of <strong>the</strong> views of many and, <strong>in</strong>deed, attractive <strong>in</strong><strong>the</strong>ir impulse. He asks why most Americans know only English and sees<strong>the</strong>ir monol<strong>in</strong>gualism as a ‘great paradox’: <strong>the</strong> United States is at once <strong>the</strong>supreme and <strong>the</strong> most isolated world power. Why, Fuentes cont<strong>in</strong>ued,does America ‘want to be a monol<strong>in</strong>gual country?’ All 21st-centuryAmericans ought to know more than one language, to better understand<strong>the</strong> world, to deal with cross-cultural problems, y demás. Obviously,monol<strong>in</strong>gualism is not a paradox, and to say that Americans ‘want’ to bemonol<strong>in</strong>gual would seem to miss <strong>the</strong> po<strong>in</strong>t; it is simply that English servesacross virtually all <strong>the</strong> important doma<strong>in</strong>s of <strong>the</strong>ir lives.More subtly, though, it might be argued that Americans do <strong>in</strong>deed‘want’ to be monol<strong>in</strong>gual, or, to put it more aptly, <strong>the</strong>y see no compell<strong>in</strong>greason to expand <strong>the</strong>ir repertoires. In such a climate, it is easy to see what<strong>the</strong> consequences are likely to be for language teach<strong>in</strong>g and learn<strong>in</strong>g atschool. Given some of <strong>the</strong> less rational ramifications of <strong>the</strong> 2001 attackson New York City, it is also easy to see that not only do languages o<strong>the</strong>rthan English appear unnecessary, <strong>the</strong>ir use can be seen as downrightun-American, <strong>the</strong>ir speakers as unwill<strong>in</strong>g to throw <strong>the</strong>mselves wholeheartedly<strong>in</strong>to that wonderful melt<strong>in</strong>g-pot, <strong>the</strong> cont<strong>in</strong>u<strong>in</strong>g allegiance too<strong>the</strong>r cultures a suspect commodity. And, of course, such broaderperceptions feed back <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> educational arena, and so we return yetaga<strong>in</strong> to <strong>the</strong> importance of <strong>the</strong> wider society beyond <strong>the</strong> school gates forwhat ultimately transpires with<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>m; and, relatedly, to <strong>the</strong> importantfact occasionally overlooked or ignored that schools are most efficientas reflections of that wider society and not as <strong>in</strong>novative vanguards ofchang<strong>in</strong>g attitudes and behavior.<strong>Language</strong> and ‘Empowerment’Aga<strong>in</strong> here, we can note <strong>the</strong> longstand<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>terests and manycontributions of Fishman for a recent expression, see Fishman (2006);see also Pütz et al. (2006). It is quite clear that power relationships particularly, of course, those that are markedly unequal are beh<strong>in</strong>d all


196 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>substantive m<strong>in</strong>ority-majority <strong>in</strong>teractions. Just as <strong>the</strong>re are manyexamples of ‘m<strong>in</strong>ority-group’ populations that are numerically superiorbut socially and politically subord<strong>in</strong>ate (<strong>the</strong> black populations of apar<strong>the</strong>idSouth Africa, for <strong>in</strong>stance), so <strong>the</strong>re are many examples of groupswhose power far outstrips <strong>the</strong>ir demographic stand<strong>in</strong>g (th<strong>in</strong>k of <strong>the</strong>British Raj). Given a desire that <strong>the</strong> school should make someaccommodation to l<strong>in</strong>guistic heterogeneity, particularly where m<strong>in</strong>ority-grouplanguages are <strong>in</strong>volved and, more particularly still, wherem<strong>in</strong>ority-group status overlaps with socioeconomic disadvantage, it isperhaps natural that some researchers would beg<strong>in</strong> to focus upon <strong>the</strong>nexus of language and power. S<strong>in</strong>ce a disparagement of some varieties,whe<strong>the</strong>r nonstandard dialects or entirely separate languages, is clearly animportant manifestation of broader negative stereotypes, it is understandablethat some have thought to ‘empower’ <strong>the</strong> speakers of thosevarieties with a sort of l<strong>in</strong>guistic affirmative action. Thus, Cumm<strong>in</strong>s(1986) argues that m<strong>in</strong>ority-group children can be ‘empowered’ if <strong>the</strong>irmaternal varieties are accorded some place <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> classroom, and if <strong>the</strong>irparents and communities are folded <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> educational process. Suchpo<strong>in</strong>ts are unexceptionable as <strong>the</strong>y stand as is Corson’s (2001: 14) notethat extended language repertoires are ‘potentially empower<strong>in</strong>g’. Therhetoric of empowerment, however, is often ra<strong>the</strong>r more po<strong>in</strong>ted. Thus,Delgado-Gaitan and Trueba (1991: 138) def<strong>in</strong>e empowerment as <strong>the</strong>‘process of acquir<strong>in</strong>g power... of transition from lack of control to <strong>the</strong>acquisition of control over one’s life’. In a more cooperative tenor, Baker(2006: 417) refers to empowerment as ‘movement... from coercive... tocollaborative relationships, power shar<strong>in</strong>g and power creat<strong>in</strong>g, where <strong>the</strong>identities of m<strong>in</strong>orities are affirmed and voiced’. Cumm<strong>in</strong>s (1996: 15) alsostresses that empowerment is ‘<strong>the</strong> collaborative creation of power’.One or two po<strong>in</strong>ts should be added here. It is not clear, for example,that ‘empowerment’ is ei<strong>the</strong>r particularly collaborative or someth<strong>in</strong>g thatdisadvantaged groups and <strong>in</strong>dividuals can activate for <strong>the</strong>mselves. On<strong>the</strong> contrary, it would be more accurate to see it as a compensatorydevice. That is, action on behalf of ethnocultural or sociocultural groupswhose languages and cultures are seen to be disparaged, devalued oractually threatened, is seldom <strong>in</strong>itiated before some sufficient rationale isperceived; <strong>in</strong> many sett<strong>in</strong>gs, past and present, this perception has oftenseemed (to some, at least) a ra<strong>the</strong>r delayed reaction. Regardless, however,of whe<strong>the</strong>r or not <strong>in</strong>tervention is seen to be too little or too late,consider<strong>in</strong>g empowerment with<strong>in</strong> a compensatory framework surely hassome tell<strong>in</strong>g implications. The very word ‘empowerment’ suggests anexchange between unequal partners. In its orig<strong>in</strong>al senses, to empower


‘Foreign’ <strong>Language</strong>s <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong> 197meant to license or to authorize: it always bore an implication of<strong>in</strong>equality, s<strong>in</strong>ce <strong>the</strong> one authoriz<strong>in</strong>g is clearly <strong>the</strong> one <strong>in</strong> control. This,however, can be a strictly limited sort of <strong>in</strong>equality, not one thatnecessarily conjures up broad images of strength on <strong>the</strong> one hand andfrailty on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r. Authorizations and licenses can be for specific, andspecifically restricted, commissions. Today, however, <strong>the</strong> sense hasapparently expanded to <strong>in</strong>clude <strong>the</strong> relief of broad <strong>in</strong>sufficiency through<strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>tervention of general power.Contemporary understand<strong>in</strong>gs and treatments of cultural and l<strong>in</strong>guisticempowerment now typically assume that important psychosocialfactors provide <strong>the</strong> most central rationale for <strong>in</strong>tervention, and that such<strong>in</strong>tervention is justified on <strong>the</strong> basis of longstand<strong>in</strong>g oppression,prejudice, conquest, colonization and so on: historical or systemicunfairness, <strong>in</strong> a word. The sense is that what was stripped away ordevalued ought now to be restored, and that it is em<strong>in</strong>ently reasonablethat those who have benefited most <strong>in</strong> previous contact sett<strong>in</strong>gs shouldnow be <strong>the</strong> ones to make some sort of restitution. But this sense is surely<strong>in</strong>separable from ano<strong>the</strong>r: that <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividuals or groups currentlydisadvantaged are unable to resolve <strong>the</strong>ir l<strong>in</strong>guistic and culturaldilemmas by <strong>the</strong>mselves. All of which leads to <strong>the</strong> observation thatempowerment <strong>in</strong>evitably <strong>in</strong>volves <strong>the</strong> bestowal of someth<strong>in</strong>g by <strong>the</strong>strong; and this, I suggest, is very different from <strong>the</strong> tak<strong>in</strong>g of power, sohistorically characteristic of those who are currently strong. I go fur<strong>the</strong>r:<strong>the</strong> suggestion here is that empowerment, as it is commonly understood,logically implies, and actually re<strong>in</strong>forces, a cont<strong>in</strong>uation of group<strong>in</strong>equalities.The school is <strong>the</strong> most obvious arena for exercises <strong>in</strong> empowermentaimed at ethnic-m<strong>in</strong>ority-group children (as well, of course, as thosesocially disadvantaged nonstandard-dialect speakers already discussed).Indeed, <strong>the</strong> school is often seen as <strong>the</strong> place <strong>in</strong> which to act on behalf ofbeleaguered, neglected or disparaged languages, as well as <strong>the</strong> culturesfrom which <strong>the</strong>y derive (a broader matter that I shall turn to <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>follow<strong>in</strong>g chapter). It is an obvious place for some familiar reasons. First,school is a powerful <strong>in</strong>stitution that, while generally an arm of ma<strong>in</strong>streamsociety, is none<strong>the</strong>less <strong>the</strong>oretically committed to <strong>the</strong> developmentof all who attend. In that sense, it is one of <strong>the</strong> most ‘neutral’territories <strong>in</strong> which <strong>in</strong>dividuals are likely to f<strong>in</strong>d <strong>the</strong>mselves: certa<strong>in</strong>ly amore enlightened sett<strong>in</strong>g than most beyond <strong>the</strong> playground. Second,school benefits from hav<strong>in</strong>g a captive audience. Children <strong>in</strong> mostsocieties must attend from an early age, and it is significant that go<strong>in</strong>gto school represents <strong>the</strong> first susta<strong>in</strong>ed ‘break’ from <strong>the</strong> <strong>home</strong>; <strong>the</strong>y must


198 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong><strong>the</strong>n rema<strong>in</strong> at school for a considerable period of time. Third, <strong>the</strong>educational context is a natural one <strong>in</strong> which cultural contact and itsconsequences might be discussed, understood, treated and so on.A less familiar but hardly less important reason for school to be acommon site of attempted empowerment is that it encapsulates that ideaof empowerment-as-compensation noted above. School is at once acompensat<strong>in</strong>g mechanism and a cont<strong>in</strong>u<strong>in</strong>gly strong arm of that societywhose dom<strong>in</strong>ance creates <strong>the</strong> need for compensation <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> first place.The potential conflicts here are not, of course, lost upon <strong>the</strong> participants.Internal contradictions can arise even where one may assume a generalgoodwill towards <strong>the</strong> ‘o<strong>the</strong>rs’ with<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> school prec<strong>in</strong>cts. If, as issometimes <strong>the</strong> case (and was often <strong>the</strong> case), school is a ra<strong>the</strong>r lessgenerously m<strong>in</strong>ded <strong>in</strong>stitution, <strong>the</strong>n it is easy to see that any ‘compensation’on offer would be severely restricted, <strong>in</strong> l<strong>in</strong>e with <strong>the</strong> perceivedrequirements of <strong>the</strong> ma<strong>in</strong>stream. Historical accounts of work<strong>in</strong>g-classeducation where it existed at all illustrate that <strong>the</strong> general aim wasmore to facilitate <strong>the</strong> cont<strong>in</strong>ued production of workers than it was toassist <strong>in</strong> upward social mobility. Prior to <strong>the</strong> mid-19th century, at anyrate, ‘disadvantaged’ pupils who were helped to rise by education wereusually <strong>in</strong>advertent beneficiaries of <strong>the</strong> work<strong>in</strong>gs of some Smithian<strong>in</strong>visible hand.Even allow<strong>in</strong>g for excellent <strong>in</strong>tentions, dedicated teachers andadequate resources, <strong>the</strong>re are strong grounds for th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g that relianceupon school as an empower<strong>in</strong>g agent is naïve; and, as with naïveté <strong>in</strong>o<strong>the</strong>r sett<strong>in</strong>gs, <strong>in</strong>nocence coupled with ignorance can exacerbate matters.S<strong>in</strong>ce I shall return to broader matters of social pluralism, assimilationand <strong>the</strong> role of schools as agents of policy <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> next chapters, I willsimply leap to a summary po<strong>in</strong>t here: school cannot compensate forsociety. It is quite clear, <strong>in</strong>cidentally, that proponents of l<strong>in</strong>guistic andcultural empowerment are fully aware of this. Empowerment ‘can befur<strong>the</strong>red by education, but also needs to be realized <strong>in</strong> legal, social,cultural and particularly economic and political events’ (Baker, 2006:418). This is clearly true (see also Delgado-Gaitan & Trueba, 1991, forsimilar sentiments), but such statements have become almost ritual onesamong educational researchers. I th<strong>in</strong>k it is <strong>in</strong>appropriate to make suchglanc<strong>in</strong>g reference to those extra-academic contexts when <strong>the</strong>y are, <strong>in</strong>fact, <strong>the</strong> ones of <strong>the</strong> greatest importance, <strong>the</strong> ones whose determ<strong>in</strong>ationsand values filter down to <strong>the</strong> school not <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r way around. Ofcourse, I do not mean to say that schools are impotent <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>se matters,nor that <strong>the</strong>y should <strong>in</strong>evitably wait to take <strong>the</strong>ir lead from society atlarge. I do mean to say, however, that it is wrong to suggest an importance


‘Foreign’ <strong>Language</strong>s <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong> 199and a centrality that <strong>the</strong>y rarely have: wrong, and perhaps cruel, to implythat a measure of extra attention <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> classroom will translate <strong>in</strong>toanyth<strong>in</strong>g mean<strong>in</strong>gful outside it.In l<strong>in</strong>e with earlier remarks about <strong>the</strong> expansion of <strong>the</strong> very notion of‘empowerment’, it may be useful to consider a recent treatment that l<strong>in</strong>ksthat term with o<strong>the</strong>r educationally potent matters. In a short section of<strong>the</strong>ir well-known encyclopedia, Baker and Jones (1998) note thatl<strong>in</strong>guistic and cultural empowerment <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> classroom is a catalyst forsuccess and that, where parents can also be <strong>in</strong>volved, <strong>the</strong> benefits mayextend <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> local community. More specifically, <strong>the</strong>y suggest thatsuch success may occur via <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>termediate step of enhanced selfesteem;see also Wright and Bougie (2007). S<strong>in</strong>ce ‘self-esteem’ and itsconcomitants have become a sacred cow and, like <strong>the</strong> real animal, oftena barrier to movement it is some relief that arguments have recentlybeen made that too much emphasis on <strong>the</strong> alleged fragility of <strong>the</strong> youngpsyche, and too little on more traditional concerns for learn<strong>in</strong>g, is not agood th<strong>in</strong>g for children <strong>in</strong> general, and particularly harmful for <strong>the</strong>disadvantaged.Apart from <strong>the</strong> supposed l<strong>in</strong>kage between empowerment and selfesteem,Baker and Jones discuss o<strong>the</strong>r related matters. They note, forexample, that traditional test<strong>in</strong>g procedures ‘tend by <strong>the</strong>ir very nature tolocate problems <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual student... [and] may fail to locate <strong>the</strong>root of <strong>the</strong> problem <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> social, economic or educational system’;improved assessment procedures, based upon ‘advocacy’, will focusupon <strong>the</strong> ‘system’; and so on (Baker & Jones, 1998: 542). These matters,while not necessarily connected with considerations of ‘self-esteem’,none<strong>the</strong>less often accompany <strong>the</strong>m <strong>in</strong> discussions of this sort. Educational‘empowerment’ is thus seen to <strong>in</strong>volve criticism of ‘<strong>the</strong> system’.This is a reasonable corollary, it seems to me, but it is typically undercut(as it is <strong>in</strong> this case) by an immediate refocus<strong>in</strong>g upon too narrow acontext, a formulaic acknowledgement of <strong>the</strong> need to ‘change <strong>the</strong> system’ but <strong>the</strong>n a quick return to a decontextualized accent upon <strong>the</strong> schoolalone. The ritual nod usually takes <strong>the</strong> form of a statement that <strong>the</strong> schoolcannot go it alone; thus, Baker and Jones (1998: 542) make <strong>the</strong>observation, later repeated <strong>in</strong> Baker (2006: 418 cited above), about<strong>the</strong> need for accompany<strong>in</strong>g action <strong>in</strong> economic, social, political and o<strong>the</strong>rarenas. As I have implied, this round<strong>in</strong>g up of <strong>the</strong> usual suspects isperhaps worse than not mention<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>m, for <strong>the</strong> implication is that, afterall, <strong>the</strong>y collectively constitute only some sort of m<strong>in</strong>or extension to <strong>the</strong>real arena of action. Noth<strong>in</strong>g, of course, could be more <strong>in</strong>verted.


200 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>Ano<strong>the</strong>r difficulty and, aga<strong>in</strong>, it is a regrettably typical one revealed<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> forego<strong>in</strong>g citations also <strong>in</strong>volves ‘<strong>the</strong> system’. While it is quiteplausible to suggest that empowerment requires some exam<strong>in</strong>ation of ‘<strong>the</strong>system’, it is not so reasonable to proceed on <strong>the</strong> assumption that <strong>the</strong> socialcontext is to be blamed for problems illum<strong>in</strong>ated through test<strong>in</strong>g. This is,admittedly, a delicate matter, for it is a truism that a prejudiced oroppressive society extends a generally deaden<strong>in</strong>g hand over its disadvantagedand m<strong>in</strong>ority-group segments. But at <strong>the</strong> same time, it can be alltoo easy to <strong>in</strong>accurately lay all problems at <strong>the</strong> social ra<strong>the</strong>r than <strong>the</strong><strong>in</strong>dividual foot. The delicacy of <strong>the</strong> po<strong>in</strong>t here is sharpened when oneconsiders that <strong>the</strong> attempt to lessen <strong>the</strong> burden of <strong>the</strong> disadvantaged<strong>in</strong>dividual <strong>in</strong> this way often proceeds from good <strong>in</strong>tentions; once aga<strong>in</strong>,however, it is an example of empowerment-as-compensation. As such, itcan be seen as condescend<strong>in</strong>g and demean<strong>in</strong>g, as actually re<strong>in</strong>forc<strong>in</strong>g adebilitat<strong>in</strong>g scenario of victimization and passivity, as fail<strong>in</strong>g to accomplishany real play<strong>in</strong>g-field level<strong>in</strong>g, as (at best) a delay<strong>in</strong>g tactic ra<strong>the</strong>rthan a solution and, overall, as an example of attitudes and behavior<strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>gly rejected by those most directly affected.Beyond <strong>the</strong>se generalities, we should turn to some more specificeducational programs aimed at speakers of foreign languages: bil<strong>in</strong>gualeducation arrangements of various sorts, immersion education and socalled‘heritage-language’ programs. Baker (2006) provides a very goodsummary of <strong>the</strong> varieties that exist under <strong>the</strong>se head<strong>in</strong>gs, and I will dealwith some of <strong>the</strong> important issues <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> follow<strong>in</strong>g chapters; here I shallonly make a few remarks about ‘heritage’ languages at school.Heritage <strong>Language</strong>s <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>There are several <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g matters that even a cursory glance at‘foreign’ languages must touch upon. First, of course, are questions about<strong>the</strong> appropriate treatment of children’s maternal varieties <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> classroom:should educational accommodation be made and, if so, <strong>in</strong> whatway? Second, <strong>the</strong>re are political and ideological issues. Some of <strong>the</strong>sehave to do with <strong>the</strong> practicalities of <strong>in</strong>struction: how best to deal withdialect variations, for <strong>in</strong>stance, but also considerations of costs, beneficiariesand so on. O<strong>the</strong>rs <strong>in</strong>volve larger social concerns like culturalpluralism and assimilation. A common argument here, from those whofavor <strong>the</strong> one-language approach that so often accompanies an assimilationistideology, is that ‘<strong>the</strong> government’ ought not to use general taxrevenues to support <strong>the</strong> languages and cultures of m<strong>in</strong>ority groups.Third, <strong>the</strong>re are questions of provenance, def<strong>in</strong>ition and labell<strong>in</strong>g. In


‘Foreign’ <strong>Language</strong>s <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong> 201Canada, for example, language matters have arranged <strong>the</strong>mselves <strong>in</strong> fourcategories: French, English, aborig<strong>in</strong>al varieties and <strong>the</strong> languages of <strong>the</strong>‘allophones’ (essentially, <strong>the</strong> varieties brought by non-francophone andnon-anglophone immigrants).‘Allophone’ varieties <strong>in</strong> Canada are <strong>the</strong> ones specifically labelled as‘heritage’ languages and, latterly, as ‘<strong>in</strong>ternational’ languages. Obviously,nei<strong>the</strong>r adjective is specifically appropriate here; equally obviously,however, labels have significance, and name changes can reflect shift<strong>in</strong>gsociopolitical underp<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>gs. Cumm<strong>in</strong>s (2005) lists some of <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rlanguage labels that have been applied: ethnic, m<strong>in</strong>ority, ancestral, third,modern, non-official and (<strong>in</strong> Quebec) langues d’orig<strong>in</strong>e and languespatrimoniales. Some of <strong>the</strong>se terms have also been used <strong>in</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r contexts,too, and community language has proved particularly popular <strong>in</strong> Australia(Clyne, 2005), where it has <strong>the</strong> same connotations as heritage languagedoes <strong>in</strong> Canada (i.e. immigrant varieties, but not <strong>in</strong>digenous ones).The Canadian picture is broadly <strong>in</strong>structive here and, if we turn first to<strong>in</strong>digenous languages, it is a bleak one (as it so often is for autochthonousm<strong>in</strong>ority languages elsewhere). Prior to <strong>the</strong> com<strong>in</strong>g of <strong>the</strong> Europeans <strong>in</strong><strong>the</strong> 16th century, millions of North Americans spoke as many as 300languages. In Canada today, just over 1 million people are of declaredaborig<strong>in</strong>al orig<strong>in</strong>: Indian, Métis or Inuit. Only about 17% have anaborig<strong>in</strong>al language as <strong>the</strong>ir mo<strong>the</strong>r tongue, and fewer still (11%) useone at <strong>home</strong>. Statistics are somewhat different for those who moreformally identify <strong>the</strong>mselves as Canadian Aborig<strong>in</strong>als. Drapeau (1998)reports, for <strong>in</strong>stance, that about 33% of this group (which comprises some625,000 people) can speak an aborig<strong>in</strong>al variety, and ano<strong>the</strong>r 17% reportsome degree of understand<strong>in</strong>g.There are 53 aborig<strong>in</strong>al languages still extant <strong>in</strong> Canada, classified <strong>in</strong>to11 families and ‘isolates’ (languages for which scholars cannot f<strong>in</strong>dfamilial relationships). Accurate speaker estimates are rare (see Cook,1998), but a simple comparison of overall population size and number ofvarieties will lead to obvious conclusions. Only 3 of <strong>the</strong> 53 have morethan 5000 speakers (Inuktitut, Ojibwa and Cree: <strong>the</strong> last is <strong>the</strong> strongest,with some 60,000 speakers), and only <strong>the</strong>se three are considered to have agood chance of survival. The 50 o<strong>the</strong>rs range from ‘moderatelyendangered’ to ‘verg<strong>in</strong>g on ext<strong>in</strong>ction’. Eight varieties have fewer thanten speakers each. The problems afflict<strong>in</strong>g aborig<strong>in</strong>al-language ma<strong>in</strong>tenance,<strong>the</strong>n, are easily understood, and <strong>in</strong>digenous cultures cont<strong>in</strong>ue tobe at <strong>the</strong> gravest risk, follow<strong>in</strong>g conquest and much subsequent illtreatment.Education through and about aborig<strong>in</strong>al languages has grownrecently, but it is often restricted to <strong>the</strong> earliest school years. In any event,


202 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>educational programs are always uncerta<strong>in</strong> guarantees of ‘ord<strong>in</strong>ary’language cont<strong>in</strong>uity, particularly when o<strong>the</strong>r social pressures operate <strong>in</strong><strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r direction.A consideration of immigrant m<strong>in</strong>ority languages <strong>the</strong> ‘allophone’varieties to which, however <strong>in</strong>accurately, <strong>the</strong> ‘heritage’ label has beenattached gives rise to an issue that can be added to those listed <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>first paragraph of this section. It is one often heard <strong>in</strong> ‘new-world’societies where immigrants (<strong>in</strong>itially from Europe, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> ma<strong>in</strong>, but nowoften from Asia and Africa) constitute such a large presence. 2 Why notcapitalize on all this cultural wealth, <strong>in</strong>stead of rail<strong>in</strong>g aga<strong>in</strong>st ‘languageproblems’ and <strong>the</strong> like? Why not fur<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> scope of <strong>the</strong> Canadian social‘mosaic’ <strong>in</strong> place of <strong>the</strong> American ‘melt<strong>in</strong>g-pot’? All of this seems to makegood sense because, even <strong>in</strong> a world made <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>gly safe foranglophones, <strong>the</strong>re are real and immediate benefits to multil<strong>in</strong>gualcompetencies. Indeed, strong practical cases can often be made: be<strong>in</strong>gable to talk to customers <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir own languages is a recurr<strong>in</strong>gly obviousexample; and Americans and o<strong>the</strong>rs have been rem<strong>in</strong>ded <strong>in</strong> recent yearsof how useful it might be to have more speakers of Arabic, Pashto andFarsi. Blanco (1983: 282) po<strong>in</strong>ts to <strong>the</strong> strange mentality that ‘allows <strong>the</strong>squander<strong>in</strong>g of valuable l<strong>in</strong>guistic resources, only to try to recapture orcreate <strong>the</strong>m later’. Cumm<strong>in</strong>s (2005), too, advocates more <strong>in</strong>clusiverecognition of heritage languages; like Blanco, he deplores <strong>the</strong> ‘squander<strong>in</strong>g’of resources, and he makes some useful and specific proposalsfor change; see also <strong>the</strong> collections edited by Fishman (1999, 2001).Jaspaert and Kroon (1991) present some data on <strong>the</strong> educationaltreatment of both <strong>in</strong>digenous and immigrant languages <strong>in</strong> Europe, andExtra and Gorter (2001) provide a f<strong>in</strong>e overview of <strong>the</strong> ‘o<strong>the</strong>r’ languagesof Europe, one <strong>in</strong> which particular attention is paid to educationalimplications. In a related collection, Extra and Yağmur (2004) focus morespecifically upon immigrant varieties <strong>in</strong> European cities: immigration isgenerally an urban phenomenon, after all. The contributors discusssituations <strong>in</strong> Sweden, Germany, The Ne<strong>the</strong>rlands, Belgium, France andSpa<strong>in</strong>. As <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> earlier volume, <strong>the</strong> emphasis here is upon <strong>the</strong>educational sett<strong>in</strong>g.A very recent paper by Wallen and Kelly-Holmes (2006) discusses <strong>the</strong>‘new’ immigration <strong>in</strong> Ireland, and its implications for languages at school.As everyone knows, Ireland has historically been a country of emigrants;now, because of European Union policies on mobility, and <strong>the</strong> strength of<strong>the</strong> Irish economy, it has received many thousands of immigrants (largelyfrom eastern Europe) and refugees (from Congo, Somalia and o<strong>the</strong>r‘underdeveloped’ regions). The current Irish Education Act notes that <strong>the</strong>


‘Foreign’ <strong>Language</strong>s <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong> 203‘language and cultural needs of students... should be catered for’(Ireland, 1998: 118), a declaration that would seem to bode well for <strong>the</strong>new immigrants. Of course, as Wallen and Kelly-Holmes (2006: 144)observe, <strong>the</strong> statement precedes <strong>the</strong> most recent waves of immigration,and was meant to apply to <strong>the</strong> language needs and wishes of Irishspeakers <strong>in</strong> an educational system that has traditionally been bil<strong>in</strong>guallym<strong>in</strong>ded, with room for both English (<strong>the</strong> language of everyday life) andIrish (officially <strong>the</strong> ‘first language’). None<strong>the</strong>less, <strong>the</strong>re is a po<strong>in</strong>t of entryhere that could be exploited for those wish<strong>in</strong>g to argue for ‘educationrights <strong>in</strong> languages o<strong>the</strong>r than Irish and English’. Of course, even with <strong>the</strong><strong>in</strong>flux of Latvians and Lithuanians, of Brazilians and Congolese, <strong>the</strong> Irishscene is nowhere near as l<strong>in</strong>guistically diverse as o<strong>the</strong>rs. I mention <strong>the</strong>context here, however, because it reveals just how dynamic <strong>the</strong> politics ofdiversity can be: who would have guessed, even a dozen years ago, thatquestions of language-<strong>in</strong>-<strong>the</strong>-classroom would be important <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Irishcontext?A new collection edited by Hornberger (2005) deals with heritagelanguageteach<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> American and Australia. And a collection of papersassembled by Creese and Mart<strong>in</strong> (2006a), treats ‘complementary’ schools<strong>in</strong> England. Sometimes referred to as ‘community’ or ‘supplementary’schools, <strong>the</strong>se are voluntary efforts that stress mo<strong>the</strong>r-tongue education,and <strong>the</strong>y occur outside regular school hours. While no one would denythat particular religious or ethnol<strong>in</strong>guistic groups have a perfect right tomake such arrangements for <strong>the</strong>mselves, <strong>the</strong> most <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g questionhere apart, of course, from pedagogical and l<strong>in</strong>guistic effectiveness iswhe<strong>the</strong>r or not such groups should be obliged to do so. Creese andMart<strong>in</strong> (2006b: 1), for example, take <strong>the</strong> position that complementaryschool<strong>in</strong>g is a ‘response to an historically monol<strong>in</strong>gual ideology whichignores <strong>the</strong> complexity of multil<strong>in</strong>gual England’. The implication is that amore enlightened system would and should have made provision for <strong>the</strong>children with<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> ord<strong>in</strong>ary curriculum; see also Li Wei (2006) for somecogent discussion of <strong>the</strong> most important po<strong>in</strong>ts.The Canadian experience is aga<strong>in</strong> illustrative here, and it is <strong>the</strong> onethat has generated <strong>the</strong> greatest and <strong>the</strong> most susta<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong>terest. This isbecause <strong>the</strong> country has both <strong>in</strong>digenous and immigrant populations,because it also has uniquely among ‘receiv<strong>in</strong>g’ countries of <strong>the</strong> newworld two ethnocultural ‘ma<strong>in</strong>streams’, and because its largest citiesare probably <strong>the</strong> most multicultural <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> world. Official statistics (seeDepartment of Canadian Heritage, 2000: 5) reveal that, <strong>in</strong> 1996, 48% of<strong>the</strong> population <strong>in</strong> all Canadian metropolitan areas reported ‘at least oneethnic orig<strong>in</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r than British, French, Canadian or Aborig<strong>in</strong>al’. In <strong>the</strong>


204 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>Montreal/Ottawa region, <strong>the</strong> figure is about one-third, but <strong>in</strong> Vancouverit is 64% and <strong>in</strong> Toronto, 68%: thus, more than half of all Torontoschoolchildren come from <strong>home</strong>s <strong>in</strong> which nei<strong>the</strong>r French nor English is<strong>the</strong> mo<strong>the</strong>r tongue. (Burtonwood and Bruce [1999] report that ethnicm<strong>in</strong>oritypupils now constitute <strong>the</strong> majority <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>ner London, too, as wellas <strong>in</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r large English cities.) An added factor of <strong>in</strong>terest, certa<strong>in</strong>ly notunique to Canada, arises when one considers that immigrant or‘allophone’ populations are <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>gly full citizens of <strong>the</strong>ir newcountries; apart from <strong>the</strong> predictable crass opportunism that this createsamong politicians, <strong>the</strong> development has important implications for <strong>the</strong>very notion of a ‘ma<strong>in</strong>stream’.Canadian census figures present fur<strong>the</strong>r details of a picture whosebroad outl<strong>in</strong>e is already obvious: about 20% of <strong>the</strong> population (i.e. almost6 million people) can speak a language o<strong>the</strong>r than French or English,and 10% speak such a variety most often at <strong>home</strong>. Immigration dur<strong>in</strong>g<strong>the</strong> post-war years greatly <strong>in</strong>creased <strong>the</strong> overall numbers here, but more<strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g, perhaps, is <strong>the</strong> chang<strong>in</strong>g nature of <strong>the</strong> mixture of <strong>the</strong>se‘allophone’ languages. In 1971, German, Italian, Ukra<strong>in</strong>ian, Dutch andPolish were <strong>the</strong> most numerous varieties; <strong>in</strong> 1991, Ch<strong>in</strong>ese speakers haddramatically <strong>in</strong>creased (from 95,000 to over 500,000), and Punjabi alsoarrived <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> ‘top ten’; by 1996, Arabic and Tagalog had jo<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>the</strong>m. 3As Cumm<strong>in</strong>s (1998) po<strong>in</strong>ts out, federal support for <strong>the</strong> teach<strong>in</strong>g of‘heritage’ or ‘<strong>in</strong>ternational’ languages has not been very substantial.Wary of public op<strong>in</strong>ion that has never been particularly well-disposedtowards fund<strong>in</strong>g ‘foreign’ languages, it has usually taken <strong>the</strong> form ofsubventions to communities who as with <strong>the</strong> ‘complementary’-schoolarrangements <strong>in</strong> England organize <strong>the</strong> teach<strong>in</strong>g of <strong>the</strong>ir languagesoutside regular school hours. Saturday-morn<strong>in</strong>g schools are typical here.Direct educational <strong>in</strong>itiatives are prov<strong>in</strong>cial matters <strong>in</strong> Canada, and <strong>the</strong>most extensive programs are <strong>the</strong>refore found <strong>in</strong> regions with <strong>the</strong> greatestnumbers and concentrations of immigrant-language groups. In Ontario,for <strong>in</strong>stance, well over 100,000 students learn more than 60 languages.However, <strong>the</strong> program requires both community <strong>in</strong>volvement andm<strong>in</strong>imum numbers of potential students and, aga<strong>in</strong>, classes take placeoutside <strong>the</strong> regular school curriculum. Similar programs exist elsewhere<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> country (see also Edwards, 1993).Notes1. I am rem<strong>in</strong>ded here of a similar case, one that shows <strong>the</strong> dynamics at workat a more ‘micro’ level. About 15 miles from my university <strong>in</strong> Nova Scotiais a small Acadian village. Such have been <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>cursions of English upon


‘Foreign’ <strong>Language</strong>s <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong> 205French, however, that it proved necessary for <strong>the</strong> villagers to establish aFrench-immersion school this, for children whose surnames were Bouchardand Doiron, Landry and Pettipas.2. As McBrien (2005) po<strong>in</strong>ts out, refugees form an <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g sub-category here,one that is not always sufficiently dist<strong>in</strong>guished from that of voluntaryimmigration. Many countries now have large refugee populations (see Cutts,2000) and United Nations statistics reveal that children typically comprisemore than half of such groups. There are specific educational implications forchildren who have often had ra<strong>the</strong>r more traumatic experiences than o<strong>the</strong>rimmigrants. For a very recent <strong>in</strong>vestigation of refugee language issues, seeMaloof et al. (2006).3. The 10 most common languages <strong>in</strong> Canada now are Ch<strong>in</strong>ese (with about800,000 speakers), Italian (700,000), German (650,000), Spanish (500,000),Portuguese and Polish (about 260,000 each), Punjabi (250,000), Arabic andUkra<strong>in</strong>ian (about 220,000 each) and Tagalog (190,000). The shift from <strong>the</strong> olderEuropean immigration patterns is clear. Marmen and Corbeil (1999) provide asucc<strong>in</strong>ct guide to many fur<strong>the</strong>r details.


Chapter 11Multiculturalism and MulticulturalEducationIntroductionWhen we talk about any aspect of <strong>the</strong> ‘social life of language’, we aretalk<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>in</strong> good part, about markers of broad social attitudes and values.It is true, of course, that <strong>in</strong> studies of Black English and o<strong>the</strong>rnonstandard dialects, <strong>the</strong>re are l<strong>in</strong>guistic and sociol<strong>in</strong>guistic facts to beascerta<strong>in</strong>ed and discussed, facts that demonstrate (for example) <strong>the</strong> rulegovernedand valid nature of such variants. It is true that approachestaken to foreign languages <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> classroom can (or should) rest uponclear conceptions of <strong>the</strong> mechanics of language contact. And it is true thatprovisions made for bil<strong>in</strong>gual educational accommodations someth<strong>in</strong>gI shall turn to <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> next chapters may quite satisfactorily arise frompedagogical imperatives alone. But it is equally true that <strong>the</strong> veryphenomenon of ‘nonstandardness’ suggests someth<strong>in</strong>g of social stratification,of sociopolitical hierarchy, of prestige and stigma; that it is not somany years ago that speakers of foreign languages <strong>in</strong> anglophonecontexts were rout<strong>in</strong>ely treated as if <strong>the</strong>y were educationally retarded;and that bil<strong>in</strong>gual education is always accompanied by heavy socialbaggage. All of this reflects <strong>the</strong> fact that, as well as be<strong>in</strong>g a carrier ofcommunicative mean<strong>in</strong>gs, language is also <strong>the</strong> bearer of more symbolicand <strong>in</strong>tangible mean<strong>in</strong>gs mean<strong>in</strong>gs that, ultimately, have to do withquestions of identity, of self-def<strong>in</strong>ition and def<strong>in</strong>ition by o<strong>the</strong>rs, of‘groupness’ and its boundaries. Considerations of languages <strong>in</strong> contact,<strong>the</strong>n, are almost <strong>in</strong>evitably considerations of cultures <strong>in</strong> contact.Bil<strong>in</strong>gualism and multil<strong>in</strong>gualism implicate biculturalism and multiculturalism.Multiculturalism can be ei<strong>the</strong>r a de facto description of an ethnicallyheterogeneous society or a matter of policy, or both. One may f<strong>in</strong>dsocieties that are multicultural on <strong>the</strong> ground, as it were, but officiallymonocultural, but it is rare to f<strong>in</strong>d formal policies of multiculturalism atgovernmental, educational and o<strong>the</strong>r such levels <strong>in</strong> contexts that lack anysubstantial or concentrated ethnic variety. Where official policies do exist,206


Multiculturalism and Multicultural Education 207it is not always correct to read <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong>m any great respect for diversity.They are sometimes ra<strong>the</strong>r grudg<strong>in</strong>g accommodations aris<strong>in</strong>g from <strong>the</strong>force of circumstance, politically opportunistic reflexes <strong>in</strong> sett<strong>in</strong>gs where‘ethnics’ are vot<strong>in</strong>g citizens or, <strong>in</strong>deed, attempts to block <strong>the</strong> activities ofstronger m<strong>in</strong>ority groups by formulat<strong>in</strong>g m<strong>in</strong>ority-group policy <strong>in</strong> ablanket fashion. Apparently democratic responses that purport toconsider <strong>the</strong> needs of all groups large or small, strong or weak canactually be a clever way of obviat<strong>in</strong>g or dilut<strong>in</strong>g mean<strong>in</strong>gful actions forany of <strong>the</strong>m. French governments, for <strong>in</strong>stance, have used this sort ofdivide-and-conquer approach <strong>in</strong> deal<strong>in</strong>gs with m<strong>in</strong>ority groups <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>hexagone: a cont<strong>in</strong>uation of <strong>the</strong> historically traditional centralization. In arecent variant, <strong>the</strong> primary player <strong>in</strong> la francophonie has appealed to o<strong>the</strong>rlanguage communities to help it stand firm aga<strong>in</strong>st <strong>the</strong> homogeniz<strong>in</strong>gevils of global anglicization. It is quite clear, however, that ano<strong>the</strong>r aspectof French tradition is at work here. That is, while France cont<strong>in</strong>ues to carevery little for any language o<strong>the</strong>r than its own, it is desperate to enlistwhatever help it can get for someth<strong>in</strong>g that it does care a great dealabout: its own l<strong>in</strong>guistic loss of place <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> world.It is clear that any discussion of multiculturalism is one that may meanquite different th<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>in</strong> different quarters. There have always been, ofcourse, strong and dis<strong>in</strong>terested sentiments supportive of cultural andl<strong>in</strong>guistic pluralism. On <strong>the</strong> one hand, some groups may legitimately feelthat <strong>the</strong>ir cultures are under threat from powerful neighbors. If arevitalized ‘<strong>in</strong>ternal’ monoculturalism is no longer seen as practical, anaccommodation that allows some cultural duality can <strong>the</strong>n be seen as anattractive option. Such a posture is likely to become more prom<strong>in</strong>ent <strong>in</strong>times like our own, when a pervasive global ‘monoculture’ casts its longshadow over all o<strong>the</strong>rs. On <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r hand, however, one need not be amember of a group whose language and culture is at (real or perceived)risk, to endorse some sort of pluralistic perspective. Just as educatedpeople have always been <strong>in</strong>terested <strong>in</strong> learn<strong>in</strong>g o<strong>the</strong>r languages, so anunderstand<strong>in</strong>g of cultures o<strong>the</strong>r than one’s own has always been a markof enlightenment. Just as all well-rounded programs of educationtraditionally gave an honored place to languages modern and classical,so all such programs took learners beyond <strong>the</strong> conf<strong>in</strong>es of <strong>the</strong>ir owncultural immediacy. Although formal language learn<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> anglophonesocieties is obviously not what it once was, <strong>the</strong> cross-cultural componentsof education rema<strong>in</strong> as central as ever, and this is so, even when <strong>the</strong>y arenot specifically identified as such. All education, by its very nature,transcends <strong>the</strong> time and place <strong>in</strong> which it f<strong>in</strong>ds itself. All good educationis multicultural.


208 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>Unity and <strong>Diversity</strong>At a societal level, <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g tensions very often exist betweendiversity and unity. Liberal democracies are obliged by <strong>the</strong>ir own deepestpr<strong>in</strong>ciples to consider <strong>the</strong> well-be<strong>in</strong>g of <strong>the</strong>ir populations, and not simplyto ride rough-shod over all but ‘ma<strong>in</strong>stream’ or majority-group <strong>in</strong>terests.In many such societies, <strong>the</strong>se pr<strong>in</strong>ciples are streng<strong>the</strong>ned by <strong>the</strong>historically enlightened emphases I mentioned above. When translatedfrom <strong>the</strong> educational arena per se to <strong>the</strong> broader social one, <strong>the</strong>se maymean real concern, and not just pious lip-service, for <strong>the</strong> protection andma<strong>in</strong>tenance of subcultures, particularly those seen to be at risk ofassimilation. The concern takes greater force when <strong>the</strong> members of thosegroups are citizens (as I noted <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> previous chapter). But tensions arisebecause, coexistent with what we might roughly call <strong>the</strong> ‘liberalperspective’ here, are fears of social fragmentation, of <strong>the</strong> dilution of acommon civic polity. These can derive from nativist or racist sentiments,but it would be a great mistake to ascribe all such apprehensions to suchunpleasant and unworthy reactions. In <strong>the</strong> Canadian context, forexample, one frequently comes across <strong>the</strong> follow<strong>in</strong>g sort of argument:s<strong>in</strong>ce <strong>the</strong> Canadian identity itself rema<strong>in</strong>s a ra<strong>the</strong>r shaky commodity, duelargely to <strong>the</strong> overwhelm<strong>in</strong>g presence of its all-<strong>in</strong>trusive sou<strong>the</strong>rnneighbor, how can we ever expect a strong national ethos to take shapeif our policies of multiculturalism and tolerance make a cont<strong>in</strong>u<strong>in</strong>g virtueout of a balkaniz<strong>in</strong>g diversity? This is a rough paraphrase, but it is not anunfair characterization of <strong>the</strong> worry felt by some whose democraticcredentials rema<strong>in</strong> impeccable.It is important to note that <strong>the</strong> tension between social diversity andsocial unity at least, as this is reflected <strong>in</strong> official responses toethnol<strong>in</strong>guistic heterogeneity is both <strong>in</strong>evitable and dynamic. It is<strong>in</strong>evitable because <strong>the</strong> champion<strong>in</strong>g of <strong>in</strong>dividual rights that is <strong>the</strong>traditional liberal legacy has always had to at least consider rights thatmight <strong>in</strong>here <strong>in</strong> groups. Indeed, some recent political philosophy hasattempted to reconcile <strong>the</strong> two at some levels, as part of an effort to dealequitably with cultural and l<strong>in</strong>guistic variation. And it is dynamicbecause social policy is not a science. It does not proceed <strong>in</strong> cumulativeand self-correct<strong>in</strong>g fashion, each advance build<strong>in</strong>g upon and mak<strong>in</strong>gadjustments to previous <strong>in</strong>sights; ra<strong>the</strong>r, it is subject to variations <strong>in</strong>social conditions and attitudes. The recent actions <strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>g Islamistextremists and western targets provide <strong>the</strong> best contemporary examples.Thus, <strong>the</strong> strongly favorable Dutch stance on multiculturalism has beenshaken by <strong>the</strong> 2004 assass<strong>in</strong>ation of Theo van Gogh, a provocative critic


Multiculturalism and Multicultural Education 209of religious orthodoxies, although fissures had already developed. Forexample, longer-established m<strong>in</strong>ority groups (particularly those fromSur<strong>in</strong>am and <strong>the</strong> Dutch Antilles) have become <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>gly differentiatedfrom Muslim populations <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> eyes of <strong>the</strong> ‘ma<strong>in</strong>stream’. Coenders et al.(2008) and Sniderman and Hagendoorn (2007) have provided usefuloverviews of chang<strong>in</strong>g Dutch positions, each attempt<strong>in</strong>g to put Dutchreactions <strong>in</strong> broader social context. The French attitude to <strong>the</strong>ir largeimmigrant populations was sharply focussed by <strong>the</strong> week of riot<strong>in</strong>g andburn<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Muslim banlieux <strong>in</strong> 2005. The Madrid tra<strong>in</strong> bomb<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>2004 and <strong>the</strong> London underground attack of 2005 have also led to policyre-exam<strong>in</strong>ation, to say noth<strong>in</strong>g of galvaniz<strong>in</strong>g all shades of publicop<strong>in</strong>ion.An <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g recent development is <strong>the</strong> suggestion by <strong>the</strong> M<strong>in</strong>isterfor Higher Education that compulsory classes <strong>in</strong> ‘core British values’ beadded to exist<strong>in</strong>g ones on citizenship. Supporters immediately noted thatBill Rammell’s remarks (<strong>in</strong> May 2006) only built upon earlier suggestions<strong>in</strong> January by Gordon Brown, <strong>the</strong>n Chancellor that <strong>the</strong> governmentshould establish a ‘British Day’ and encourage citizens to put a unionflag ‘<strong>in</strong> every garden’ (Helm, 2006a, 2006b). Reactions to <strong>the</strong>se ideaswere, at best, ra<strong>the</strong>r mixed (BBC, 2006), but <strong>the</strong>re is no doubt that ‘statesponsoredflag wav<strong>in</strong>g’ strikes many as ei<strong>the</strong>r American or (as one DailyMail columnist put it) totalitarian <strong>in</strong> its impulse; see also Parekh (2006).Roger Scruton (2006) a reactionary commentator, <strong>in</strong> a right-w<strong>in</strong>gnewspaper did manage to put his f<strong>in</strong>ger on <strong>the</strong> essential fallacy <strong>in</strong> allthis. Whatever one’s views are of national ‘values’ (or of ProfessorScruton, for that matter), it is clearly wrong to th<strong>in</strong>k that values are ‘ak<strong>in</strong>d of knowledge, to be put up on <strong>the</strong> blackboard... values are mattersof practice, not of <strong>the</strong>ory. They are not so much taught as imparted’.In an apparent demonstration of Jungian synchronicity, I came acrosstwo analogous references with<strong>in</strong> a week of read<strong>in</strong>g Scruton’s piece. HugoWilliams, <strong>the</strong> ‘Freelance’ columnist <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Times Literary Supplement,reported glumly on <strong>the</strong> recent announcement that Well<strong>in</strong>gton College <strong>the</strong> Berkshire public school established <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> mid-19th century as amemorial to <strong>the</strong> Iron Duke himself was about to provide ‘happ<strong>in</strong>esslessons’ to its students. Rem<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g us that ‘show, don’t tell’ is <strong>the</strong> mottofor all successful creative writ<strong>in</strong>g, Williams’s (2006) implication is that an<strong>in</strong>direct approach to someth<strong>in</strong>g as important but as vague as ‘happ<strong>in</strong>ess’is surely preferable to attempts to bludgeon it <strong>in</strong>to children’s heads. AndRoger Schank, a cognitive scientist writ<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Times Higher EducationSupplement (2006), argues that while <strong>the</strong> most important acquisitions forstudents are reason<strong>in</strong>g ability, communication skills and human-relations


210 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>sensitivity, none should be taught as a subject. Indeed, we might want togo a bit fur<strong>the</strong>r, and say that none can be taught as subjects <strong>in</strong> anymean<strong>in</strong>gful way. (Schank’s impressive educational credentials are,perhaps, a little sullied by his current occupation. He is ‘Chief Learn<strong>in</strong>gOfficer’ at Trump University, an onl<strong>in</strong>e real-estate college founded by‘The Donald’ himself <strong>in</strong> 2005.)All of this tends to a broad and venerable conclusion: <strong>the</strong> mostimportant th<strong>in</strong>gs cannot be taught, although <strong>the</strong>y can obviously belearned. This does not lessen for a moment <strong>the</strong> importance of teachers, ofcourse <strong>the</strong>y will always be needed to provide educational fuel,<strong>in</strong>centive and, often, <strong>in</strong>spiration but it does rem<strong>in</strong>d us of <strong>the</strong> centralityof <strong>the</strong> recipients to <strong>the</strong> whole enterprise.Ano<strong>the</strong>r relevant development is <strong>the</strong> post-2001 American debate overborder security and immigration, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> question of <strong>the</strong> twelvemillion ‘illegal aliens’ that was brought to <strong>the</strong> fore <strong>in</strong> early 2006. Amongo<strong>the</strong>r th<strong>in</strong>gs, this has reawakened <strong>in</strong>terest <strong>in</strong> mak<strong>in</strong>g English <strong>the</strong> officiallanguage of <strong>the</strong> country (Agence France-Press, 2006; see also Edwards,1990). Proponents of ‘Official English’ <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> USA have been directly or<strong>in</strong>directly <strong>in</strong>volved <strong>in</strong> legislative efforts at <strong>the</strong> state level: thirty statesnow proclaim English as official, with Ohio set to become <strong>the</strong> thirty-first.Success has eluded <strong>the</strong>m at <strong>the</strong> federal level, however. The most recentattempt <strong>the</strong>re occurred <strong>in</strong> February 2007; more than one third of <strong>the</strong>members of <strong>the</strong> House of Representatives agreed to ‘declare English as<strong>the</strong> official language of <strong>the</strong> United States’ (H.R. 997). Academic reactionhas always been quick <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>se matters. For <strong>in</strong>stance, <strong>in</strong> connection withan earlier (2006) legislative <strong>in</strong>itiative almost every sitt<strong>in</strong>g of Congresssees a proposal to make English official members of <strong>the</strong> AmericanAssociation for Applied L<strong>in</strong>guistics received an email message not<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>organization’s deep concern about moves to legally enshr<strong>in</strong>e <strong>the</strong> status ofEnglish and to restrict <strong>the</strong> provision of services <strong>in</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r languages. Theywere urged to get <strong>in</strong> touch with <strong>the</strong>ir state representatives, and atemplate letter for this purpose was attached to <strong>the</strong> ma<strong>in</strong> message.Beyond <strong>the</strong> assertion that language matters are not an <strong>in</strong>tegral part ofborder security, four specific po<strong>in</strong>ts were made: (1) <strong>the</strong> status of Englishdoes not need legislated protection; (2) respect for o<strong>the</strong>r languages <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>United States is important for ‘foster<strong>in</strong>g national loyalty’; (3) for <strong>the</strong>‘unity of national purpose’, it is preferable that citizens and residentshave documents and services <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir own languages; (4) attempts toheighten <strong>the</strong> importance of foreign-language learn<strong>in</strong>g ‘for nationalsecurity purposes’ will be weakened if foreign languages are undercut


Multiculturalism and Multicultural Education 211at <strong>the</strong> federal level. Fur<strong>the</strong>r details about ‘Official English’ and itsramifications can be found <strong>in</strong> Chapter 13 (see especially note 5 <strong>the</strong>re).Historical perspectivesMulticultural matters are important <strong>in</strong> many contexts, but <strong>the</strong>y areobviously magnified <strong>in</strong> sett<strong>in</strong>gs of greater ethnic diversity. They areparticularly salient, <strong>the</strong>n, among <strong>the</strong> immigrant and ‘guest-worker’populations of western Europe, and are of even more longstand<strong>in</strong>gprom<strong>in</strong>ence <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> new-world ‘receiv<strong>in</strong>g’ countries, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g Canada,<strong>the</strong> United States and Australia. All of <strong>the</strong>se owe <strong>the</strong>ir contemporaryexistence to successive waves of immigrants and, although each beganwith dom<strong>in</strong>ant immigrant populations, <strong>the</strong>ir recent histories have beenmarked by great variation among <strong>in</strong>com<strong>in</strong>g groups. As I noted <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> lastchapter, more than half of all <strong>the</strong> schoolchildren <strong>in</strong> Toronto (where <strong>the</strong>population of <strong>the</strong> greater metropolitan area is now almost five million)come from <strong>home</strong>s where nei<strong>the</strong>r French nor English is <strong>the</strong> mo<strong>the</strong>r tongue.We have already seen that policies <strong>in</strong> late 19th- and early 20th-centuryAmerica were strongly assimilationist, both l<strong>in</strong>guistically and o<strong>the</strong>rwise.The process began at Ellis Island, <strong>in</strong> New York harbor, where <strong>the</strong> names ofimmigrants were often changed. While it is a myth that brutal abbreviationsand alterations were imposed by unfeel<strong>in</strong>g and monol<strong>in</strong>gualimmigration officers, and while many changes resulted from <strong>the</strong> immigrants’own attempts to make <strong>the</strong>ir names more ‘American’ <strong>in</strong> one wayor ano<strong>the</strong>r, <strong>the</strong>re is little doubt that <strong>the</strong> process was seen on all sides asboth desirable and practical. After all, <strong>the</strong> languages of <strong>the</strong> new arrivalswere often seen as exotic, unpronounceable and <strong>in</strong>ferior to English. Thefamous melt<strong>in</strong>g-pot popularized by Israel Zangwill (1909) was at full boil.But Zangwill’s democratic notion that all <strong>the</strong> immigrants would be giventhis fiery baptism, and that all would emerge as newly m<strong>in</strong>ted Americans was never <strong>the</strong> reality. Beyond <strong>the</strong> fact that some immigrant groups, aswell as <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>digenous peoples of <strong>the</strong> cont<strong>in</strong>ent, were unwill<strong>in</strong>g toundergo immersion, racial prejudice meant that many would be refusedsuch immersion anyway. Slightly less obvious was <strong>the</strong> fact that some totalamalgamation à la Zangwill was never on <strong>the</strong> cards: only some identitieswere to be melted down and re-cast. Assimilative forces were to bebrought to bear upon certa<strong>in</strong> categories of newcomers, whose task it wasto accommodate <strong>the</strong>mselves to an exist<strong>in</strong>g ma<strong>in</strong>stream. That is why <strong>the</strong>term anglo-conformity is more apt not only <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> United States, but<strong>in</strong> Australia and <strong>in</strong> most parts of Canada than some metaphor of acrucible <strong>in</strong> which all would be mixed, and from which would emerge,


212 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>phoenix-like, a new culture <strong>in</strong> which <strong>the</strong> threads of all <strong>the</strong> earlier oneswould be seamlessly and <strong>in</strong>visibly <strong>in</strong>terwoven.From <strong>the</strong> beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g, however, it was <strong>the</strong> tension surround<strong>in</strong>g diversityand unity that animated those th<strong>in</strong>kers who were nei<strong>the</strong>r so naïve as toth<strong>in</strong>k that <strong>the</strong> melt<strong>in</strong>g pot was a democratic cauldron with room foreveryone, nor motivated by a crude nativism. An early proponent of anendur<strong>in</strong>g multiculturalism was Horace Kallen (1915, 1924), who arguedthat <strong>the</strong>re was no overarch<strong>in</strong>g American nationality but, ra<strong>the</strong>r, acollection of dist<strong>in</strong>ct groups who could perpetuate <strong>the</strong>mselves <strong>in</strong>def<strong>in</strong>itely.Kallen’s ideal was a harmonious diversity, a stable culturalpluralism. He made provision <strong>in</strong> his model for some assimilationthrough consensus, allow<strong>in</strong>g for <strong>the</strong> unum <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> national motto whileemphasis<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> pluribus. (Part of <strong>the</strong> unum, <strong>in</strong>cidentally, would beEnglish as <strong>the</strong> common language.)Most scholars, however, believed and hoped that <strong>the</strong> assimilation ofimmigrants would proceed <strong>in</strong> what was called ‘straight-l<strong>in</strong>e’ fashion,although a roar<strong>in</strong>g and <strong>in</strong>sensitive melt<strong>in</strong>g-pot was rarely what <strong>the</strong>yhad <strong>in</strong> m<strong>in</strong>d. Thus, <strong>the</strong> prom<strong>in</strong>ent sociologist, Robert Park, consideredthat assimilation was not someth<strong>in</strong>g to be forced upon immigrants;<strong>the</strong>y should, ra<strong>the</strong>r, be helped towards full participation <strong>in</strong> nationallife. A natural progression was perceived, from competition and conflictto accommodation and <strong>in</strong>corporation (assimilation): <strong>the</strong> famous‘race-relations cycle’. Recent <strong>in</strong>terpretations strongly suggest that Parkand his fellow scholars were liberals (some were romantics) caught <strong>in</strong> adilemma. Park himself felt that civilization subverts attractive andegalitarian ‘small’ cultures with <strong>the</strong>ir ‘redemptive’ solidarity and hewas, <strong>in</strong> many ways, a champion of what he termed ‘parochial culture’ (seeLal, 1990). At <strong>the</strong> same time, he did not wish to repudiate larger society,whose attractions and advantages were clear. He and his colleagues wereboth progressive and pragmatic, but <strong>the</strong>y also wished to <strong>in</strong>corporateearlier and ‘smaller’ group values <strong>in</strong> a broader society that was, itself, stilldevelop<strong>in</strong>g. They struggled, as liberals often do, with <strong>the</strong> compet<strong>in</strong>gattractions of past and present, rural and urban, diversity and unity.In most contexts, however, some sort of assimilationist model prevailed,ei<strong>the</strong>r officially or more powerfully, <strong>in</strong> democratic societies unofficially;<strong>in</strong>deed it was really only <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> 1960s that academic <strong>in</strong>terest <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>assimilation-pluralism equation revived. This was <strong>in</strong>tertw<strong>in</strong>ed with whatlooked to some to be an ethnic-m<strong>in</strong>ority ‘revival’ or ‘resurgence’. Manycommentators suggested that this was surpris<strong>in</strong>g, that <strong>the</strong> recrudescenceof ethnic consciousness was a reaction to ‘straight-l<strong>in</strong>e’ assimilation thathad somehow crept up unseen. Speak<strong>in</strong>g for many, an apologist for


Multiculturalism and Multicultural Education 213diversity noted that ‘one of <strong>the</strong> most extraord<strong>in</strong>ary events of our time hasbeen <strong>the</strong> resurgence of tribalism <strong>in</strong> a supposedly secularized andtechnocratic world... ties of race, nationality and religion seem to havetaken on new importance’ (cited by Mann, 1979: 1718).In fact, however, it is debatable whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>re was any ethnic‘resurgence’; it might be more apt to describe an ethnic persistence whichbecamemorevisible<strong>in</strong>timeswhichwereatoncetend<strong>in</strong>gmoreandmoretosome global ‘monoculture’ and, at <strong>the</strong> same time, more sympa<strong>the</strong>tic to <strong>the</strong>plight of small-group identities. 1 In any event, <strong>the</strong> renewed visibility of whatsome called <strong>the</strong> ‘new ethnicity’ was celebrated <strong>in</strong> many quarters, not leastby scholars professionally and personally committed to an endur<strong>in</strong>g socialdiversity. More poetic than most, but not unrepresentative, Michael Novakobserved that this phenomenon represented a ‘true, real, multiculturalcosmopolitanism... struggl<strong>in</strong>g to be born is a creature of multiculturalbeauty, dazzl<strong>in</strong>g, free, a higher and richer form of life. It was fashioned <strong>in</strong><strong>the</strong> pa<strong>in</strong>ful darkness of <strong>the</strong> melt<strong>in</strong>g pot and now, at <strong>the</strong> appo<strong>in</strong>ted time, itawakens’ (cited <strong>in</strong> Gleason, 1979: 17; see also Novak, 1971).Contemporary directionsA renewed grappl<strong>in</strong>g with <strong>the</strong> difficulties and attractions of culturalpluralism led many researchers to develop <strong>the</strong>ories and models thatdepicted and supported a workable accommodation between unity anddiversity. Sociological terms like pluralistic <strong>in</strong>tegration, participationistpluralism, modified pluralism, liberal pluralism, multivariate assimilationand social accommodation (among o<strong>the</strong>rs) are <strong>in</strong>dicative here. Some of<strong>the</strong> ‘committed’ were (and rema<strong>in</strong>) critical of any sort of modified orattenuated multiculturalism, on <strong>the</strong> grounds that it can only be a detouron <strong>the</strong> road to <strong>the</strong> old and bad assimilation. Sociological models thatattempt to capture some <strong>in</strong>termediate position between total assimilationand group segregation, however, are at least rough reflections of whatmost <strong>in</strong>digenous and immigrant populations aim for. Besides, even ifsome seamless assimilation is <strong>the</strong> ultimate social dest<strong>in</strong>y, it is difficult tosee how it might be avoided for significant segments of <strong>the</strong> population,short of draconian measures unlikely to be acceptable <strong>in</strong> democraticsocieties. (There are groups, usually hav<strong>in</strong>g a strong religious core to<strong>the</strong>ir identity, whose voluntary segregation from ‘ma<strong>in</strong>stream’ societycan be quite endur<strong>in</strong>g. I note, however, that recent reports suggest that,even among such stalwart populations as <strong>the</strong> Amish, <strong>the</strong> Mennonites and<strong>the</strong> Pennsylvania ‘Dutch’, <strong>the</strong> ma<strong>in</strong>stream tends to erode groupboundaries.)


214 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>The <strong>in</strong>terest <strong>in</strong> exam<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g or re-exam<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g multiculturalism hascont<strong>in</strong>ued more or less unabated, and a very important recent developmenthas been <strong>the</strong> attention given to it by political philosophers. Theimportance here arises from <strong>the</strong> fact that, for <strong>the</strong> first time, efforts havebeen made to consider <strong>the</strong> matter from a general and dis<strong>in</strong>terested po<strong>in</strong>tof view ra<strong>the</strong>r than from a parti pris stance. In 1992, for example, CharlesTaylor wrote about <strong>the</strong> tensions underp<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g multiculturalism asstruggles for <strong>the</strong> ‘recognition’ of group identities. He argued that, <strong>in</strong> aworld <strong>in</strong> which <strong>the</strong> old social hierarchies have collapsed with <strong>the</strong>irselective and <strong>in</strong>egalitarian bases for honor and <strong>in</strong> which a democraticsense of <strong>in</strong>dividual dignity has arisen, <strong>the</strong> politics of equal recognitionhave assumed great importance. But demands for equality must coexistwith demands for uniqueness; as Taylor puts it, <strong>the</strong> new ‘politics ofrecognition’ is closely tied to a ‘politics of difference’. The demands ofuniversal respect, on <strong>the</strong> one hand, and of particularity, on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r,suggest difficulties:The reproach <strong>the</strong> first makes to <strong>the</strong> second is just that it violates <strong>the</strong>pr<strong>in</strong>ciple of nondiscrim<strong>in</strong>ation. The reproach <strong>the</strong> second makes to <strong>the</strong>first is that it negates identity by forc<strong>in</strong>g people <strong>in</strong>to a homogeneousmold that is untrue to <strong>the</strong>m. (Taylor, 1992: 43)This is a ra<strong>the</strong>r neat exposition of one face of that unity-diversity tensionthat I have touched upon here.Hav<strong>in</strong>g due regard to <strong>the</strong> collectivist impulses that underp<strong>in</strong> multiculturalism(on <strong>the</strong> one hand), and to <strong>the</strong> traditional liberal-democraticview that argues for <strong>in</strong>dividual equality but rema<strong>in</strong>s as neutral aspossible on <strong>the</strong> cultural ‘content’ of life (on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r), Taylor attempts tochart a middle course. He suggests an ‘hospitable’ variant of liberalismthat should not claim complete neutrality. He also touches upon <strong>the</strong>extended demand that not only should all cultures be given some degreeof support, but also that we ought to recognize <strong>the</strong>ir equal worth. But areall cultures really equally worthy? Taylor sensibly observes that whilejudgments of equal worth require <strong>in</strong>vestigation, we might reasonablystart from a presumption of equality. His essay sets <strong>the</strong> stage for fur<strong>the</strong>rand more detailed work that has only ga<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong> importance (see, e.g.Kymlicka, 1995a, 1995b).Appear<strong>in</strong>g at <strong>the</strong> same time as Taylor’s book were two o<strong>the</strong>r treatmentsof multiculturalism, <strong>the</strong> more polemical of <strong>the</strong>m by a very em<strong>in</strong>entAmerican historian. The title of Arthur Schles<strong>in</strong>ger’s (1992) book TheDisunit<strong>in</strong>g of America provides a ra<strong>the</strong>r strong h<strong>in</strong>t about his viewsof multiculturalism, and <strong>the</strong> work is essentially a panegyric to <strong>the</strong>


Multiculturalism and Multicultural Education 215assimilative power of America and a lament that that power seems to beon <strong>the</strong> wane. The <strong>the</strong>me appears early on: ‘unless a common purposeb<strong>in</strong>ds [people of different ethnic orig<strong>in</strong>s] toge<strong>the</strong>r, tribal hostilities willdrive <strong>the</strong>m apart’ (Schles<strong>in</strong>ger, 1992: 10). While <strong>the</strong> author acknowledges<strong>the</strong> contributions of ethnicity, <strong>the</strong> fact that he refers to recent manifestationsof it as an ‘eruption’ is suggestive; <strong>in</strong> fact, he argues throughout thatits potency has preserved an unhealthy diversity. He po<strong>in</strong>ts, ra<strong>the</strong>rcuriously, to a ‘separatist impulse’ <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> black community, to <strong>the</strong> challengeto social unity represented by <strong>the</strong> ‘bil<strong>in</strong>gualism movement’ and to <strong>the</strong>growth of Hispanic <strong>in</strong>fluence. Ultimately, however, Schles<strong>in</strong>ger rema<strong>in</strong>soptimistic that assimilative forces will successfully deal with <strong>the</strong> newchallenge of pluralism. In a tone that is all too evident <strong>in</strong> Americantreatments of subjects of global concern, he claims that now, more thanever, <strong>the</strong> United States should set an example of social cohesion. Not onlydo many f<strong>in</strong>d this stak<strong>in</strong>g out of <strong>the</strong> moral high ground dist<strong>in</strong>ctlyunattractive, recent events and cont<strong>in</strong>u<strong>in</strong>gly baleful social statistics make itan empty proposition. But Schles<strong>in</strong>ger, like many o<strong>the</strong>rs, seems to believethat <strong>the</strong> American beacon sh<strong>in</strong>es on, undimmed, for all of us unfortunateenough not to already live comfortably with<strong>in</strong> its light.This American attitude, and reactions to it, has of course come verymuch to <strong>the</strong> fore with <strong>the</strong> events of 11 September 2001 and <strong>the</strong>iraftermath. Thomas Friedman, <strong>the</strong> Pulitzer Prize-w<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g columnist forThe New York Times, found many American <strong>in</strong>tellectual stances distasteful(see Edwards, 2004b, for fuller details) and so he told his daughters oneeven<strong>in</strong>g that, while <strong>the</strong>y could br<strong>in</strong>g <strong>home</strong> someone who was ‘black,white or purple... you will never come <strong>in</strong> this house and not love yourcountry and not thank God every day that you were born an American’(Friedman, 2002: 313). Some may be surprised to f<strong>in</strong>d such j<strong>in</strong>goism <strong>in</strong><strong>the</strong> remarks of an educated person but, on <strong>the</strong> subject of patriotic pride,even o<strong>the</strong>rwise sensitive Americans have long demonstrated <strong>the</strong> samesort of bl<strong>in</strong>dness. Recently, read<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> essays of John Dos Passos, I found<strong>the</strong> author observ<strong>in</strong>g that ‘we can’t get away from <strong>the</strong> fact that mosteverybody <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> world believes <strong>in</strong> his heart that life is more worth liv<strong>in</strong>gfor <strong>the</strong> average man <strong>in</strong> North America than anywhere else’ (Dos Passos,1964: 37 but Dos Passos first published his observation <strong>in</strong> 1941).Allow<strong>in</strong>g for variations <strong>in</strong> style, perhaps <strong>the</strong>se sentiments have more todo with perceived dom<strong>in</strong>ance than with any particular state allegiance;a century ago, Cecil Rhodes reportedly said that to be an Englishman wasto have won first prize <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> lottery of life.While Schles<strong>in</strong>ger’s treatment is a ra<strong>the</strong>r crude and narrow one, he has,of course, touched upon many real problems that exist <strong>in</strong> democratic and


216 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>multicultural societies. A strength of his book is <strong>the</strong> demonstration thatissues of multiculturalism, racism, prejudice, language, <strong>the</strong> eurocentriccanon, political correctness and perceived assaults on an anglocentricma<strong>in</strong>stream are all <strong>in</strong>termeshed. What underp<strong>in</strong>s this <strong>in</strong>terpenetration arestill deeper matters of group voice, of social <strong>in</strong>clusion and exclusion, ofunity and diversity. A weakness of <strong>the</strong> book, however, is Schles<strong>in</strong>ger’soverly blunt defence of an American conservative status quo; whileconcessions are made to <strong>the</strong> civiliz<strong>in</strong>g value of cross-cultural sensitivity,<strong>the</strong> exist<strong>in</strong>g pattern is seen as essentially sound. It is entirely reasonable,of course, for Schles<strong>in</strong>ger to argue for quite specific positions. As well,I would not argue with <strong>the</strong> need for a defence aga<strong>in</strong>st some sociopoliticalassaults nor, <strong>in</strong>deed, would I want to hold on some a priori basis thatexist<strong>in</strong>g patterns are unsound or untenable. My criticism is that somepo<strong>in</strong>ts are <strong>in</strong>accurately or <strong>in</strong>completely stated, and a work by an importantscholar <strong>in</strong> a highly sensitive area is <strong>in</strong>sufficiently nuanced.One might th<strong>in</strong>k <strong>the</strong> same of <strong>the</strong> book by Robert Hughes s<strong>in</strong>ce, <strong>in</strong> his<strong>in</strong>troductory remarks, he acknowledges a debt to Schles<strong>in</strong>ger, ‘whoseown recent book... says much of what I say but said it earlier and better’(Hughes, 1993: xiii). None<strong>the</strong>less, unlike <strong>the</strong> historian, <strong>the</strong> journalistHughes excoriates both left and right <strong>in</strong> an attempt to defend a middleground. This is his way of deal<strong>in</strong>g with contemporary tensions and, on<strong>the</strong> surface at least, <strong>the</strong>re is much to recommend it. In this sense,Hughes’s argument is broadly rem<strong>in</strong>iscent of Taylor’s plea for a similarsort of position and, <strong>in</strong> fact, his book could be seen as a popularizedversion of Taylor’s more scholarly discussion. We f<strong>in</strong>d Hughes to besupportive of a ‘generous and tolerant’ multiculturalism, but stronglyopposed to what multiculturalism has become <strong>in</strong> a fragmented culture:a marker of pernicious separatist sentiments. S<strong>in</strong>ce <strong>the</strong> polyphonicmessage of multiculturalism is someth<strong>in</strong>g that Americans, of all people,might most benefit from, Hughes f<strong>in</strong>ds it ironic (but sadly predictable)that multiculturalism <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> United States is not so much about aproliferation of voices as it is a shout<strong>in</strong>g contest. What he refers to as‘radical multiculturalism’ is a guise for Europe-bash<strong>in</strong>g; one might saythat while lip-service is given to diversity, a genu<strong>in</strong>e pluralism is far from<strong>the</strong> m<strong>in</strong>ds of most multiculturalists. Radical multiculturalism is alsocritical of much historical <strong>in</strong>terpretation: Columbus <strong>the</strong> hero is now <strong>the</strong>blackest of villa<strong>in</strong>s (if one can still use that form of expression). LikeSchles<strong>in</strong>ger before him, Hughes decries <strong>the</strong> corruption of knowledge <strong>in</strong><strong>the</strong> service of some group’s ‘self-esteem’ (nei<strong>the</strong>r author, however, isunaware of <strong>the</strong> social construction of knowledge).


Multiculturalism and Multicultural Education 217Taken toge<strong>the</strong>r, <strong>the</strong>se three books touch upon virtually all of <strong>the</strong>cont<strong>in</strong>u<strong>in</strong>gly important aspects of <strong>the</strong> multiculturalism debate. As I havealready implied, it is clear that <strong>the</strong> varied aspects of this issue assumeimportance because, ultimately, <strong>the</strong>y all have to do with clamors for equal‘voice’, <strong>the</strong>y all deal with <strong>the</strong> politics, <strong>the</strong> sociology and <strong>the</strong> l<strong>in</strong>guistics ofidentity. And it is notable that (even <strong>in</strong> Schles<strong>in</strong>ger’s monograph), concernis expressed <strong>in</strong> compromise, <strong>in</strong> mediation, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> ‘middle ground’. Theauthors suggest that this territory has been quite <strong>in</strong>adequately mapped and, more than a decade on, this rema<strong>in</strong>s <strong>the</strong> case.Multiculturalism <strong>in</strong> CanadaAny <strong>in</strong>troductory discussion of multiculturalism would be <strong>in</strong>completewithout some consideration of <strong>the</strong> Canadian case for several reasons.First, Canada is unique among new-world ‘receiv<strong>in</strong>g’ societies <strong>in</strong> that ithas had, from <strong>the</strong> beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g, two powerful cultural and l<strong>in</strong>guisticma<strong>in</strong>streams (if <strong>the</strong> noun can reasonably be pluralized). While Australia,<strong>the</strong> United States, Brazil and Argent<strong>in</strong>a all have one clearly def<strong>in</strong>edethnol<strong>in</strong>guistic fons et origo, Canada is marked by a French-Englishduality. I am presc<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g from some important matters, of course: <strong>the</strong>two components of Canada’s ethnol<strong>in</strong>guistic duality are by and largegeographically dist<strong>in</strong>ct; all features are <strong>in</strong> dynamic flux consider <strong>the</strong>rapid and cont<strong>in</strong>u<strong>in</strong>g rise of <strong>the</strong> Hispanic component <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> UnitedStates; and my reference to dom<strong>in</strong>ant ma<strong>in</strong>streams does not apply topre-European America. Second, Canada had <strong>the</strong> first official multiculturalismpolicy. The government position here formed <strong>the</strong> basis fornational responses elsewhere, notably <strong>in</strong> Australia and Brita<strong>in</strong> but not<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> United States, where <strong>the</strong>re is no official federal multiculturalpolicy. Many accommodations have been made <strong>in</strong> recent years, however,to <strong>the</strong> grow<strong>in</strong>g Hispanic presence; many services, both official andprivate, are available <strong>in</strong> Spanish. As well, a federally supported bil<strong>in</strong>gualeducation program was <strong>in</strong>stituted <strong>in</strong> 1968, and many have <strong>in</strong>terpretedthis (<strong>in</strong>correctly, <strong>in</strong> my view) as a de facto endorsement of multiculturalismand multil<strong>in</strong>gualism; see <strong>the</strong> more focused discussion <strong>in</strong><strong>the</strong> next two chapters. Third, <strong>the</strong> Canadian multicultural policy has hadto coexist from its beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g (<strong>in</strong> 1971) with ano<strong>the</strong>r social-eng<strong>in</strong>eer<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>itiative: official bil<strong>in</strong>gualism.Burnet was an early and <strong>in</strong>cisive commentator on <strong>the</strong> Canadianmulticulturalism policy, see<strong>in</strong>g it:as encourag<strong>in</strong>g those members of ethnic groups who want to do so toma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong> a proud sense of <strong>the</strong> contribution of <strong>the</strong>ir groups to


218 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>Canadian society. Interpreted <strong>in</strong> this way, it becomes someth<strong>in</strong>g veryNorth American: voluntary marg<strong>in</strong>al differentiation among peopleswho are equal participants <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> society. (Burnet, 1975: 211)She went on to note, however, that if <strong>the</strong> policy was construed as somewholesale ma<strong>in</strong>tenance of ‘foreign’ cultures <strong>in</strong> Canada, <strong>the</strong>n it would not(and perhaps should not) endure.The policy certa<strong>in</strong>ly attracted criticism from <strong>the</strong> beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g. At a<strong>the</strong>oretical level, <strong>the</strong> late John Porter (1972) observed that officialmulticulturalism might prove a regressive force by help<strong>in</strong>g to ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>an ethnic stratification that places group <strong>in</strong>terests above those of <strong>the</strong><strong>in</strong>dividual. Ano<strong>the</strong>r frequently voiced criticism has been that <strong>the</strong> entiremulticultural thrust has been politically opportunistic, both <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> largersense of attempt<strong>in</strong>g some national reconciliation between <strong>the</strong> two‘charter’ groups (i.e. <strong>the</strong> French and <strong>the</strong> English) and <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs (<strong>the</strong>‘allophones’), and <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> more specific desire to attract ‘ethnic’ voters.The difficulty (some said <strong>the</strong> absurdity) of attempt<strong>in</strong>g to supportmulticulturalism with<strong>in</strong> a French-English bil<strong>in</strong>gualism was also quicklybrought to <strong>the</strong> fore. A well-known Ukra<strong>in</strong>ian-Canadian scholar (Lupul,1982: 100) thus described a situation of ‘political pragmatism’ whichpleased no one... The failure to provide multiculturalism with al<strong>in</strong>guistic base especially displeased <strong>the</strong> Ukra<strong>in</strong>ians; <strong>the</strong> loosen<strong>in</strong>g of<strong>the</strong> ties between language and culture angered <strong>the</strong> francophones whodisliked any suggestion that <strong>the</strong> status of <strong>the</strong>ir culture was on a parwith that of o<strong>the</strong>r ethnic groups. 2Much criticism of multiculturalism has <strong>in</strong>deed come from <strong>the</strong>francophone community. Rocher (1973), for example, po<strong>in</strong>ted out thatmulticulturalism might underm<strong>in</strong>e official bil<strong>in</strong>gualism, might be<strong>in</strong>compatible with national unity, and could generally prove a regressivestep for <strong>the</strong> French who have <strong>the</strong>ir own longstand<strong>in</strong>g concerns withdom<strong>in</strong>ance and equality. The fear, above all, is that <strong>the</strong> francophonesmight be reduced to <strong>the</strong> status of <strong>the</strong> ethnic ‘o<strong>the</strong>rs’, <strong>the</strong> ‘allophones’. Itcould, of course, be argued that a multiculturalism policy must have asimilar effect on <strong>the</strong> anglophone community, but this latter group is not<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> same precarious position as <strong>the</strong> French. Indeed, a cynical view isthat <strong>the</strong> (relatively) greater support for multiculturalism from <strong>the</strong> Englishsector existed because it was seen as a defus<strong>in</strong>g of <strong>the</strong> French ‘problem’<strong>in</strong> Canada. There is a dilemma here for francophones: a rejection ofmulticulturalism on <strong>the</strong> grounds just noted may have some substancebut, equally, a non-<strong>in</strong>terventionist policy on <strong>the</strong> part of <strong>the</strong> government


Multiculturalism and Multicultural Education 219could be seen as a tacit acknowledgement of ethnic ‘melt<strong>in</strong>g’, whichwould ultimately enlarge <strong>the</strong> anglophone proportions of <strong>the</strong> country.A summary statement <strong>in</strong> a Globe & Mail [Toronto] leader <strong>in</strong> May 1985rema<strong>in</strong>s <strong>in</strong>sightful:Multiculturalism is a highly ambiguous concept. At one level, itaffirms <strong>the</strong> legitimacy of all <strong>the</strong> world’s cultures... At ano<strong>the</strong>r, itencourages immigrants and <strong>the</strong>ir descendants to perpetuate orig<strong>in</strong>alvalues and customs [<strong>the</strong> implication here is that not all of <strong>the</strong>se arepositive]. It is often said that only by nourish<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>ir differences canimmigrants hope for equality with<strong>in</strong> Canada, a <strong>the</strong>sis hardlyconfirmed by experience.We have returned, <strong>the</strong>n, to <strong>the</strong> essential tension that applies <strong>in</strong> allmulticultural contexts, well beyond <strong>the</strong> specifically Canadian sett<strong>in</strong>g.F<strong>in</strong>ally here, it is reasonable to ask what ‘ord<strong>in</strong>ary’ people th<strong>in</strong>k aboutmulticultural policies and applications. As part of a well-known overviewof <strong>the</strong> contemporary scene, Raymond Breton (1986: 4748)summarized a number of experimental f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>gs and op<strong>in</strong>ion polls asfollows:<strong>the</strong> research results on popular attitudes do not <strong>in</strong>dicate a strong andwidespread demand for state <strong>in</strong>tervention <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> ethnocultural field,except for <strong>the</strong> symbolic affirmation of Canada as a multiculturalra<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>n bicultural society. The demand for a federal policy ofmulticulturalism seems to have come primarily from ethnic organizationalelites and <strong>the</strong>ir supporters, from government agencies and<strong>the</strong>ir officers, and from political authorities.Recent developments have only re<strong>in</strong>forced Breton’s comments. TheCanadian population has a certa<strong>in</strong> (unspecified, perhaps unspecifiable)level of tolerance for diversity, a certa<strong>in</strong> fund of passive goodwill, acerta<strong>in</strong> will<strong>in</strong>gness to see <strong>the</strong> ‘o<strong>the</strong>rs’ shape <strong>the</strong>ir lives as desired. It doesnot have any great sympathy for real changes <strong>in</strong> social <strong>in</strong>stitutions, fordirect (especially f<strong>in</strong>ancial) official <strong>in</strong>volvement <strong>in</strong> ethnocultural affairs,for any substantial alteration to an anglo-conformity pattern. One could,of course, dismiss public op<strong>in</strong>ion here as un<strong>in</strong>formed and narrowly selfconcerned.The question of whe<strong>the</strong>r it would be wise or expedient to doso, and <strong>the</strong> even more <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g question of <strong>the</strong> degree of acuityrevealed <strong>in</strong> public surveys might suggest, however, that such a blanketdismissal would be <strong>in</strong>appropriate. In any event, cross-national comparisonsreveal that Canadian dynamics are similar to those <strong>in</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rcountries with substantial immigrant communities.


220 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>Multiculturalism <strong>in</strong> EducationThe impulse beh<strong>in</strong>d multicultural education is very largely a positiveone. In a post-modern and politically correct environment it has, <strong>in</strong> manyeyes, a mo<strong>the</strong>rhood quality, but one need not be an ideologue of anyparticular stripe to see <strong>in</strong> such education a progressive and liberaliz<strong>in</strong>gforce. Indeed, we would be hard pressed to deny (<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory, at least) <strong>the</strong>utility and justice of an educational thrust that aims to alert children to<strong>the</strong> varied world around <strong>the</strong>m, whe<strong>the</strong>r or not it exists <strong>in</strong> microcosm <strong>in</strong><strong>the</strong>ir own classroom, to <strong>in</strong>culcate cross-cultural respect, and to form abulwark aga<strong>in</strong>st racism and <strong>in</strong>tolerance. The problems arise fromdef<strong>in</strong>ition and <strong>in</strong>terpretation, on <strong>the</strong> one hand, and from implementation,on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r.What should a multicultural program look like at school? There aremany possibilities, and probably no two programs could be identical, ifonly for <strong>the</strong> reason that local ethnic realities (which presumably shouldbe reflected <strong>in</strong> such programs, at least to some extent) alter with context.However, <strong>the</strong>re are two broad approaches. One, now almost entirelyrejected at an <strong>in</strong>tellectual level but still much <strong>in</strong> evidence, is a sort ofethnic show-and-tell <strong>in</strong> which cultural manifestations are paraded <strong>in</strong> aself-conscious and often trivial fashion. While <strong>the</strong> specifics of culturalvariation do, of course, have a place <strong>in</strong> a more thoughtful program, littlecan be expected if <strong>the</strong>y are presented essentially as varieties of <strong>the</strong> exotic.Children (and teachers) may look forward to <strong>the</strong>se experiences, butlargely as light relief from <strong>the</strong> real work of <strong>the</strong> school, tak<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>ir placewith unexpected but welcome school assemblies and old-style lessons <strong>in</strong>religion and citizenship.The second approach <strong>in</strong>volves a broader and less superficial stance onmulticulturalism. Programs here are often heavy with objectives andcurricula and, while well-mean<strong>in</strong>g, may be ei<strong>the</strong>r leaden and <strong>in</strong>sensitiveor woolly and arbitrary. One representative writer discussed a multiculturalcurriculum focuss<strong>in</strong>g upon <strong>the</strong> ‘subjective content of <strong>the</strong>teachers’ and students’ own consciousness’. He went on to write:As an action system, <strong>the</strong> classroom of teacher and students wouldexam<strong>in</strong>e <strong>the</strong> historical process which creates each <strong>in</strong>dividual. Theshared solidarity, when related to common experience, would plant<strong>the</strong> seeds of collective change. (Connors, 1984: 110)These are <strong>the</strong> sorts of vapor<strong>in</strong>gs that give academics a bad name.Go<strong>in</strong>g beyond <strong>the</strong> style, such as it is, <strong>the</strong>re is an assumption here thatschools possess a power for social change that history shows to be rare.


Multiculturalism and Multicultural Education 221Schools act<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> relative isolation from o<strong>the</strong>r social currents andemphases upon multicultural awareness and its ramifications are,unfortunately, often seen as matters that can be neatly assigned toclassrooms have very limited potency. The realization of this isimportant for all those who wish schools to act as agents of change;thus, calls for schools to ‘empower’ m<strong>in</strong>ority students may be wellmean<strong>in</strong>g,but <strong>the</strong>y are usually naïve. Through example and practice,schools can legitimize cultural varieties and markers (<strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g language),but educational legitimation is not empowerment. It may lead toit, or contribute to it, but (aga<strong>in</strong>) not when schools are asked to shoulder<strong>the</strong> load almost unassisted.The vagueness of Connors’s remarks reflects <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>substantial and<strong>in</strong>tellectually empty nature of much of <strong>the</strong> writ<strong>in</strong>g on multiculturaleducation. As I have mentioned already, few would deny <strong>the</strong> psychologicaland social benefits potentially associated with a heightenedcultural awareness. In order for this to be realized, however, a m<strong>in</strong>imumrequirement is that any multicultural <strong>in</strong>itiative be firmly embeddedwith<strong>in</strong> an appropriate, valued and systematic context. This contextalready exists, <strong>in</strong> fact, <strong>in</strong> exist<strong>in</strong>g curricula, although <strong>the</strong>re are immediatelyobvious difficulties that can quickly vitiate programs. The thoughtfulremoval of boundaries of convenience, for example, would seemparamount. Cross-cultural sensitivity might be said to rest upon cross- ormultidiscipl<strong>in</strong>ary underp<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>gs: mean<strong>in</strong>gful <strong>in</strong>terconnections amongsocial studies, history and geography, for example, would facilitate <strong>the</strong>emergence of multicultural <strong>the</strong>mes. This is hardly a radical notion: canwe conceive, <strong>in</strong> fact, of a mean<strong>in</strong>gful history that is not multicultural? Infact, as I mentioned <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>troduction, all education worthy of <strong>the</strong> nameis multicultural.Properly <strong>in</strong>tegrated programs, <strong>in</strong>cidentally, would go some waytowards alleviat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> concerns of m<strong>in</strong>ority-group members <strong>the</strong>mselves,many of whom have quite rightly been suspicious from <strong>the</strong> start. InBrita<strong>in</strong>, <strong>the</strong> West Indian writer, Maureen Stone (1981: 77) argued ageneration ago that schools should cont<strong>in</strong>ue to stress ‘core’ knowledge.She rejected <strong>the</strong> vague ‘affective’ goals of much modern multiculturaleducation:I want to suggest that MRE [multiracial education] is conceptuallyunsound... while at <strong>the</strong> same time creat<strong>in</strong>g for teachers, both radicaland liberal, <strong>the</strong> illusion that <strong>the</strong>y are do<strong>in</strong>g someth<strong>in</strong>g special for aparticularly disadvantaged group.


222 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>Ano<strong>the</strong>r black parent and educator made <strong>the</strong> related comment that‘Black parents don’t want black studies or multicultural education for<strong>the</strong>ir children that is for white children; black pupils need to be good atscience, history, geography at what society th<strong>in</strong>ks of as th<strong>in</strong>gs of worth’(Woodford, 1982). Even earlier, Coard (1971) had written about <strong>the</strong><strong>in</strong>sensitive and <strong>in</strong>appropriate educational practices that caused WestIndian children <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> UK to become ‘educationally subnormal’; now, are-publication of his work, toge<strong>the</strong>r with a number of commentaries(Richardson, 2005), argues that schools cont<strong>in</strong>ue to fail black children. 3The apprehensions here rema<strong>in</strong> both potent and plausible, and wehave seen specifically l<strong>in</strong>guistic manifestations of <strong>the</strong>m <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> debatessurround<strong>in</strong>g Ebonics. But, just as children can be bidialectal, hav<strong>in</strong>gaccess to both nonstandard and more standard forms, so black children all children can and should be assisted to develop multiculturalsensitivities that supplement more traditional educational offer<strong>in</strong>gs. But,to repeat, any promotion of such sensitivities must be an <strong>in</strong>extricable partof <strong>the</strong> whole educational enterprise. If it does not, it will be viewed as apossibly divert<strong>in</strong>g but largely <strong>in</strong>substantial adjunct to more obviousclassroom concerns. Not only will this mean a failure to engage those‘ma<strong>in</strong>stream’ pupils who arguably stand <strong>in</strong> greatest need of enhancedcross-cultural awareness, it could also be <strong>in</strong>terpreted as a lack ofmean<strong>in</strong>gful concern by those ‘o<strong>the</strong>rs’ whose very presence rem<strong>in</strong>ds usof what a fully formed education ought to <strong>in</strong>volve.Although <strong>the</strong>re is quite a large literature on multicultural education,most of it is quite unsatisfy<strong>in</strong>g, for a number of reasons (Banks & Banks,1995, and Gay, 1994, can be recommended, however). First, some of <strong>the</strong>literature makes only brief remarks about <strong>the</strong> value of tolerance anddiversity <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> classroom, and <strong>the</strong>n immediately focuses upon purelylanguage issues (see Edwards, 1985). This is both distress<strong>in</strong>g andunderstandable. It is distress<strong>in</strong>g, because if multicultural educationlargely concerns itself with responses to language diversity, <strong>the</strong>n it atonce becomes a narrower (although certa<strong>in</strong>ly not worthless) undertak<strong>in</strong>g,one that significantly overlaps with <strong>the</strong>mes and approaches we havealready touched upon here: <strong>in</strong> short, it loses any claim to <strong>in</strong>dependentexistence. It is understandable because, compared with <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>tangibleand unrealistic nature of much of <strong>the</strong> relevant literature, an emphasisupon language at least provides someth<strong>in</strong>g solid to focus upon. Second,and particularly marked <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> American context, much of <strong>the</strong> literaturedevotes itself to specific constituencies and issues: afrocentric educationfor black children, for <strong>in</strong>stance, or programs designed for children ofHispanic background. This second tendency actually turns <strong>the</strong> idea of


Multiculturalism and Multicultural Education 223multicultural education on its head. A reasonable desire to pay closerattention to ‘disadvantaged’ ethnic populations can produce a curriculumthat essentially replaces one exist<strong>in</strong>g unidimensional thrust withano<strong>the</strong>r. An ostensible concern for cultural pluralism writ large oftenturns out to be special plead<strong>in</strong>g for some particular group. We see thismost notably <strong>in</strong> programs that are actively committed to equity andsocial justice (see also below). Third, a great deal of <strong>the</strong> literature iscouched <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>flated but vacuous language. We have already had a briefexposure to this, but <strong>the</strong>re are many examples. If you go, for <strong>in</strong>stance, to<strong>the</strong> website of <strong>the</strong> National Association for Multicultural Education (anAmerican organization based <strong>in</strong> Maryland), you will f<strong>in</strong>d a lengthydef<strong>in</strong>ition, parts of which read as follows:Multicultural education is a philosophical concept built on <strong>the</strong> idealsof freedom, justice, equality, equity, and human dignity... it challengesall forms of discrim<strong>in</strong>ation... it helps students develop apositive self-concept... it prepares all students to work activelytoward structural equality <strong>in</strong> organizations and <strong>in</strong>stitutions byprovid<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> knowledge, dispositions, and skills for <strong>the</strong> redistributionof power and <strong>in</strong>come among diverse groups. Thus, school curriculum[sic] must directly address issues of racism, classism, l<strong>in</strong>guicism,ablism [sic], ageism, heterosexism, religious <strong>in</strong>tolerance, andxenophobia... students and <strong>the</strong>ir life histories and experiences shouldbe placed at <strong>the</strong> center of <strong>the</strong> teach<strong>in</strong>g and learn<strong>in</strong>g process...multicultural education demands a school staff that is culturallycompetent, and to <strong>the</strong> greatest extent possible racially, culturally, andl<strong>in</strong>guistically diverse... multicultural education attempts to offer allstudents an equitable educational opportunity, while at <strong>the</strong> same timeencourag<strong>in</strong>g students to critique [sic] society <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest of socialjustice. (National Association for Multicultural Education, 2003)I apologize for such a lengthy extract, but it surely conta<strong>in</strong>s some<strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g material. The most salient feature is <strong>the</strong> alternation betweenassertions that no educationalist could quarrel with and o<strong>the</strong>rs that arera<strong>the</strong>r more po<strong>in</strong>ted. Freedom, justice, dignity, tolerance and even <strong>the</strong>slightly more dubious ritual nod <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> direction of self-esteem whatteacher would ga<strong>in</strong>say <strong>the</strong>se? Some of <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r statements, however,make multicultural education sound more like a tra<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g ground for <strong>the</strong>politically correct shock troops of anti-discrim<strong>in</strong>ation and ethno-racialequality. Ano<strong>the</strong>r po<strong>in</strong>t of <strong>in</strong>terest here is <strong>the</strong> placement of children’s ‘lifehistories’ and teachers’ ‘cultural competence’ at <strong>the</strong> center of <strong>the</strong>educational exercise. What exactly is this meant to imply that is, if it


224 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>reflects anyth<strong>in</strong>g more than some vague feel-good factor? Are we tounderstand, for <strong>in</strong>stance, that <strong>in</strong> non-multicultural classrooms, children’sexperiences are not drawn upon by sensitive teachers, and that cultural<strong>in</strong>competence is rag<strong>in</strong>g, even perhaps among those who teach history andsocial studies? Pass<strong>in</strong>g over <strong>the</strong> (presumably related) implication that <strong>the</strong>selection of teachers on racial, cultural and l<strong>in</strong>guistic grounds is of apriority higher than <strong>the</strong> traditional search for skills <strong>in</strong> knowledge andpedagogy, I note that any (<strong>in</strong>direct) mention of knowledge for pupilsnow, ra<strong>the</strong>r than for <strong>the</strong>ir teachers occurs only at <strong>the</strong> very end of <strong>the</strong>Association’s statement. It refers to ‘educational opportunity’, which wemight charitably assume does <strong>in</strong> fact mean someth<strong>in</strong>g to do with actualcontent learn<strong>in</strong>g, but <strong>the</strong> piece quickly returns to, and concludes with,<strong>the</strong> formation of junior social critics.I do not want to be misunderstood here. I am, of course, <strong>in</strong>terested <strong>in</strong>schools <strong>in</strong>culcat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir charges cross-cultural sensitivities, defencesaga<strong>in</strong>st <strong>in</strong>tolerance and prejudice, critical capabilities that will alert <strong>the</strong>mto social <strong>in</strong>equities outside <strong>the</strong> school gates, and so on. But I am deeplysuspicious of attempts to formalize this, particularly when thoseattempts are phrased <strong>in</strong> language that reveals little real sensitivity itself,and when <strong>the</strong> classroom is apparently seen more as an <strong>in</strong>doctr<strong>in</strong>ationcenter than a place of learn<strong>in</strong>g. 4 Here, Olneck (2000: 318) describesmulticultural education (a force, he says, that ‘aims to resist and todisplace Euro-American cultural dom<strong>in</strong>ation’):Multicultural education <strong>in</strong>tegrates content and perspectives orig<strong>in</strong>at<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> experiences of nondom<strong>in</strong>ant racial, ethnic and l<strong>in</strong>guisticgroups <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> curriculum; it enables students to recognize <strong>the</strong> roleof power <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> construction of knowledge; it aims to cultivatedemocratic attitudes, values and behaviors among students; itutilizes culturally congruent pedagogy; and it reorders <strong>the</strong> schools’status and cultural systems to make <strong>the</strong>m fair to those previouslydisempowered by Euro-American dom<strong>in</strong>ance.It would seem that <strong>the</strong> production of junior cultural commissars leaveslittle time for arithmetic, literature and geography.Sett<strong>in</strong>g aside <strong>the</strong> more bizarre expressions of multiculturalism-<strong>in</strong>education,I believe that <strong>the</strong> many virtues of that enterprise have alwaysbeen educational virtues, and that beneath <strong>the</strong>m is a critical capacity for<strong>in</strong>dependent and dis<strong>in</strong>terested analysis a quality, aga<strong>in</strong>, that has alwaysbeen <strong>the</strong> cornerstone of education. Here is a representative list of <strong>the</strong>essential components of effective multicultural education: ‘<strong>the</strong> promotionof good reason<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>the</strong> development of concept of person [sic], <strong>the</strong>


Multiculturalism and Multicultural Education 225development of a concept and sense of self-worth, <strong>the</strong> development of aconcept of society [?], and <strong>the</strong> understand<strong>in</strong>g of such concepts as prejudiceand stereotyp<strong>in</strong>g’ (Wright & LaBar, 1984: 118). Putt<strong>in</strong>g aside <strong>the</strong> clumsyand unfocused expression here, <strong>in</strong> what possible way could <strong>the</strong>seeducational thrusts not relate to all good classroom practice? If <strong>the</strong>dis<strong>in</strong>terested underp<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g rema<strong>in</strong>s undeveloped, <strong>the</strong>n it seems to methat educationalists and <strong>the</strong>orists can carry on as much as <strong>the</strong>y like aboutequity, xenophobia, l<strong>in</strong>guicism and all <strong>the</strong> rest: noth<strong>in</strong>g substantial willhappen, noth<strong>in</strong>g will really transfer beyond <strong>the</strong> immediate conf<strong>in</strong>es of <strong>the</strong>classroom, because <strong>the</strong> necessary scaffold<strong>in</strong>g will be absent. 5 If, on <strong>the</strong>contrary, teachers succeed <strong>in</strong> present<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>formation to students that bothdevelops <strong>in</strong>to knowledge and gradually hones <strong>the</strong> general critical faculties,<strong>the</strong>n those matters of particular <strong>in</strong>terest to ‘multiculturalists’ can beassumed to develop, too. A ris<strong>in</strong>g tide floats all boats.An early critical <strong>in</strong>vestigation, one <strong>in</strong>appropriately neglected <strong>in</strong> a fieldalways <strong>in</strong> need of careful scrut<strong>in</strong>y, is Bullivant’s (1981) treatment ofpluralism <strong>in</strong> education. While some of <strong>the</strong> particulars of his half-dozencontexts (Australia, Hawaii, Fiji, <strong>the</strong> UK, Canada and <strong>the</strong> USA) have nowaltered, his general observations rema<strong>in</strong> important. This is simply because<strong>the</strong> animat<strong>in</strong>g tensions of multiculturalism-<strong>in</strong>-education are very much as<strong>the</strong>y have always been. Bullivant’s strongest contention is that multiculturaleducation, a confused and confus<strong>in</strong>g amalgam of methods andobjectives, is just ano<strong>the</strong>r form of dom<strong>in</strong>ant-group ‘hegemony’. ‘Multiculturalism’,he suggests, ‘may be a subtle way of appear<strong>in</strong>g to givemembers of ethnocultural groups what <strong>the</strong>y want <strong>in</strong> education while <strong>in</strong>reality giv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>m little that will enhance <strong>the</strong>ir life chances’ (Bullivant,1981: ix). We have already seen that <strong>the</strong>re have been m<strong>in</strong>ority-groupsuspicions about multicultural education, as well as <strong>the</strong> argument thatmulticulturalism-as-policy represents a politically opportunistic responseto ‘ethnic’ populations, particularly if <strong>the</strong>y have vot<strong>in</strong>g power. Bullivant’ssecond pivotal argument has to do with what he calls <strong>the</strong> ‘pluralistdilemma’: while a democratic concern for all citizens can <strong>the</strong>oretically bereflected <strong>in</strong> particularized educational approaches, <strong>the</strong>se may contribute to‘weaken<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> cohesion of <strong>the</strong> nation-state [sic] by <strong>in</strong>terfer<strong>in</strong>g with <strong>the</strong>enculturation imperative <strong>the</strong> need to have enough of a common culturepassed on to each generation of children’ (Bullivant, 1981: 14). The tensionhere is between what Bullivant (cit<strong>in</strong>g an earlier author: see Butts et al.,1977) calls ‘civism’ and ‘pluralism’, which is yet ano<strong>the</strong>r restatement of <strong>the</strong>unity-diversity dynamic (see also Higham, 1974, 1975).Bullivant’s third major argument is that very roughly speak<strong>in</strong>g schools should concern <strong>the</strong>mselves with <strong>the</strong> ‘civism’ side of <strong>the</strong> co<strong>in</strong>, and


226 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>leave <strong>the</strong> ma<strong>in</strong>tenance and/or development of ‘pluralism’ <strong>in</strong> private andvoluntary hands. Activities under <strong>the</strong> latter head<strong>in</strong>g can <strong>in</strong>clude ethniclanguageretention, religious observances, and so on. This is a familiarposition, and one of cont<strong>in</strong>u<strong>in</strong>g concern <strong>in</strong>asmuch as it has animatedscholarly philosophical <strong>in</strong>terest. Kymlicka (1995a), for example, hasargued that liberal democracies have to pay attention to those culturalfeatures that Bullivant would leave to <strong>the</strong> groups <strong>the</strong>mselves. This is notan abdication of <strong>the</strong> traditional liberal focus upon <strong>in</strong>dividual rights, hesuggests, because such rights may be virtually mean<strong>in</strong>gless without ama<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>ed cultural context (see also Edwards, 2003b). Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore,Kymlicka and o<strong>the</strong>rs have claimed that s<strong>in</strong>ce traditional liberal ‘neutrality’<strong>in</strong> respect of <strong>the</strong> contents of daily life is a fiction if only bydefault, all societies privilege particular languages, endorse certa<strong>in</strong>educational endeavors, and so on a refusal to countenance ‘official’support at <strong>the</strong> group level for non-ma<strong>in</strong>stream populations mustlogically be unfair. In his fourth argument, Bullivant cautions that it isnaïve to th<strong>in</strong>k that, whe<strong>the</strong>r left <strong>in</strong> private hands or not, multicultural<strong>in</strong>tervention can of itself help m<strong>in</strong>ority groups to cope with <strong>the</strong> ‘politicalrealities’ of life. He notes, specifically, that many programs proceed on<strong>the</strong> flawed assumption that real ‘empowerment’ (Bullivant does not use<strong>the</strong> word itself) can orig<strong>in</strong>ate or be substantially enhanced by classroomactivities; see my earlier comments on this topic. He suggests go<strong>in</strong>g all<strong>the</strong> way back to Kallen’s (1924) <strong>in</strong>sightful view that any mean<strong>in</strong>gfulcultural pluralism grows out of political democracy and equity; it doesnot create it.Strong and Weak MulticulturalismIt comes as no surprise that Bullivant concludes by agree<strong>in</strong>g withGlazer (1977: 24) that <strong>the</strong> work of education is ‘centered on <strong>the</strong> commonculture. Cultural pluralism describes a supplement... it does not, andshould not, describe <strong>the</strong> whole’. 6 Clearly, Glazer believes that this‘supplemental’ approach is someth<strong>in</strong>g best left to unofficial agencies orcommunities. But, equally clearly, we can see that considerable change to‘<strong>the</strong> common culture’ has occurred <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> 30 years s<strong>in</strong>ce Glazer wrote<strong>the</strong>se words. If it has changed largely because of <strong>the</strong> grow<strong>in</strong>g andpermanent presence of those who were not part of older ma<strong>in</strong>streams,<strong>the</strong>n it is easy to see that <strong>the</strong> very notion of what constitutes multiculturalismand multicultural education will alter. Glazer has returned to<strong>the</strong> topic several times most notably <strong>in</strong> a 1997 book that proclaims WeAre All Multiculturalists Now. 7 Glazer’s new, if grudg<strong>in</strong>g, acceptance of


Multiculturalism and Multicultural Education 227<strong>the</strong> reality of multicultural education emerges from <strong>the</strong> particularities of<strong>the</strong> American context. As Kymlicka (1998) po<strong>in</strong>ts out <strong>in</strong> an <strong>in</strong>sightfulreview, <strong>the</strong> argument is that black students are <strong>the</strong> ‘storm troops’ ofmulticulturalism and that, had black people become more fully <strong>in</strong>tegrated<strong>in</strong>to society, contemporary multicultural accommodations wouldnot have occurred. This, Kymlicka th<strong>in</strong>ks, is a correct but restricted view:it ignores <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>gly powerful presence of Hispanic Americans, for<strong>in</strong>stance. As well, multicultural policies have been adopted <strong>in</strong> countries(most notably, Canada and Australia) without <strong>the</strong> American history ofracial conflict. Glazer’s sense is that multiculturalism is irrevocably partof <strong>the</strong> American educational system, and that <strong>the</strong> questions now have todo with what forms its presence will take.Glazer’s po<strong>in</strong>t of view is not <strong>the</strong> only one possible. In his short pieceon ‘boutique’ multiculturalism, Stanley Fish (1998) argues that multiculturalismis impossible. On <strong>the</strong> one hand, <strong>the</strong> superficialities of weak(‘boutique’) multiculturalism hardly justify <strong>the</strong> noun at all. It is a sort of‘flirtation’ or ‘cosmetic relationship’, one that stops well short of athoroughgo<strong>in</strong>g acceptance of difference. Fish refers to <strong>the</strong> scath<strong>in</strong>g essayby Tom Wolfe (1970) on ‘radical chic’: Wolfe’s description of <strong>the</strong> party for<strong>the</strong> Black Pan<strong>the</strong>rs held by Leonard Bernste<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong> his opulent Park Avenueapartment <strong>in</strong> 1970 rema<strong>in</strong>s, after almost 40 years, a delicious read. Thisweak stance may <strong>in</strong>volve admiration, enjoyment or sympathy with <strong>the</strong>‘o<strong>the</strong>r’, but it will not extend its appreciation to offences aga<strong>in</strong>st ‘<strong>the</strong>canons of civilized decency’ (Fish, 1998: 69). There are many illustrationsof what Fish means here, and he cites some obvious ones himself; thus,while ‘boutique’ multiculturalists may respect religious beliefs o<strong>the</strong>r<strong>the</strong>ir own, <strong>the</strong>y will draw <strong>the</strong> l<strong>in</strong>e at (say) polygamy. Fish is essentiallyrestat<strong>in</strong>g here <strong>the</strong> idea that toleration can mean very little if it covers onlythose th<strong>in</strong>gs that are different but still generally ‘acceptable’. This, ofcourse, is a very <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g and murky area. Perhaps <strong>the</strong>re may be broadacceptance at <strong>the</strong> extremes <strong>the</strong>re are probably very few among us, for<strong>in</strong>stance, whose tolerance for <strong>the</strong> plurality of beliefs would embraceritual cannibalism but extreme behavior is rarely <strong>the</strong> issue.(I mention cannibalism on purpose here. I am not th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g ofHannibal Lecter, but of a recent gruesome case <strong>in</strong> Germany. In December2003, Arm<strong>in</strong> Meiwes was put on trial for eat<strong>in</strong>g an apparently will<strong>in</strong>gvictim, one Bernd Brandes. The two had <strong>in</strong>itially ‘met’ through <strong>the</strong><strong>in</strong>ternet. Cannibalism is not a crime <strong>in</strong> Germany, and Meiwes wasorig<strong>in</strong>ally sentenced to about eight years for manslaughter; later, at anew trial <strong>in</strong> 2006, he was sentenced to life imprisonment for murder.How many, I wonder, would be will<strong>in</strong>g to apply to cases like this some


228 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>version of John Stuart Mill’s ‘harm pr<strong>in</strong>ciple’ <strong>the</strong> familiar notion, thatis, that freedom should extend up to <strong>the</strong> po<strong>in</strong>t at which its exerciseimp<strong>in</strong>ges upon <strong>the</strong> freedom of someone else. Does <strong>the</strong> fact that <strong>the</strong> victim<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Miewes case was a consent<strong>in</strong>g partner <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> bizarre act mean thatthis pr<strong>in</strong>ciple rema<strong>in</strong>ed unviolated? Some might say that <strong>the</strong> barbarity of<strong>the</strong> deed implies mental illness, which, <strong>in</strong> turn, would <strong>in</strong>validate any realfreedom here. But, when we consider that Miewes was [and is] anapparently sane and rational man, <strong>the</strong> argument that he is mentallydisturbed because he did someth<strong>in</strong>g that must be evidence of psychological<strong>in</strong>stability is begg<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> question. He was described by aneighbor, at his first trial, as ‘friendly and sensitive’ and more to <strong>the</strong>po<strong>in</strong>t [perhaps] a psychiatrist testified that Miewes was not mentallyill, although he did lack ‘warm and tender feel<strong>in</strong>gs’ for o<strong>the</strong>rs, andseemed ‘smug and self-assured’. That would describe a great manypeople, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g virtually all rich and successful bus<strong>in</strong>essmen [forexample]: <strong>the</strong>y may be figurative cannibals, but few are literal ones. Foodfor thought...?)On <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r hand, Fish argues, <strong>the</strong>re is a ‘strong’ multiculturalism, <strong>in</strong>which tolerance and ‘deep respect’ for different cultures trump bothrationality and universalism. As many o<strong>the</strong>rs have found out, however,a thoroughgo<strong>in</strong>g tolerance meets its match when its object is <strong>in</strong>tolerant.(At <strong>the</strong> political level, <strong>the</strong> corollary is this: should democratic regimestolerate movements and attitudes whose raison d’être is <strong>the</strong> overthrow ofdemocratic pr<strong>in</strong>ciple?) If one’s tolerance did extend so far as to embracean <strong>in</strong>tolerant ‘o<strong>the</strong>r’, <strong>the</strong>n, as Fish po<strong>in</strong>ts out, it would no longer betolerance. On <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r hand, if <strong>the</strong> tolerant and liberal-m<strong>in</strong>ded f<strong>in</strong>d that<strong>the</strong>re is, <strong>in</strong>deed, a sand-l<strong>in</strong>e beyond which <strong>the</strong>y will not go (Fishmentions <strong>the</strong> Islamic fatwa on Salman Rushdie, but <strong>the</strong>re are many o<strong>the</strong>rcultural practices female circumcision, child slavery and so on thatare often cited), <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong>y have given up respect<strong>in</strong>g that o<strong>the</strong>r culture ‘at<strong>the</strong> po<strong>in</strong>t where its dist<strong>in</strong>ctiveness is most obviously at stake’ (Fish, 1998:73). Fish cont<strong>in</strong>ues:Typically, <strong>the</strong> strong multiculturalist will grab <strong>the</strong> second handle ofthis dilemma (usually <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> name of some supracultural universalnow seen to have been hid<strong>in</strong>g up his sleeve from <strong>the</strong> beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g) and<strong>the</strong>reby reveal himself not to be a strong multiculturalist at all.Indeed, it turns out that strong multiculturalism is not a dist<strong>in</strong>ctposition, but a somewhat deeper <strong>in</strong>stance of <strong>the</strong> shallow category ofboutique multiculturalism. (Fish, 1998: 7374)


Multiculturalism and Multicultural Education 229Suppose, however, that ‘strong’ multiculturalists really stuck to <strong>the</strong>irguns and ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>ed a respect for some o<strong>the</strong>r culture no matter what itdid or thought. Then <strong>the</strong>y would have become ‘really strong’ multiculturalists.Such <strong>in</strong>dividuals, Fish suggests, those who would cont<strong>in</strong>ueto respect a culture that was <strong>in</strong>tolerant of ano<strong>the</strong>r culture’s dist<strong>in</strong>ctiveness,become <strong>in</strong> fact ‘uniculturalists’. So, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> end, it doesn’t matter.‘Boutique’ multiculturalism is superficial and not really worthy of <strong>the</strong>name; ‘strong’ multiculturalism typically falters when <strong>the</strong> go<strong>in</strong>g getsrough; and ‘really strong’ multiculturalism, with its death-and-glorydeterm<strong>in</strong>ation, turns <strong>in</strong>to a monocultural stance. Hence <strong>the</strong> conclusionthat Fish (1998: 75) arrives at: ‘no one could possibly be multiculturalist <strong>in</strong>any <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g and coherent sense’.I began this chapter by say<strong>in</strong>g that multiculturalism was ei<strong>the</strong>r a defacto state of social affairs or a matter of policy, and this most basicdist<strong>in</strong>ction extends <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> classroom, too. There is a difference betweenteachers attempt<strong>in</strong>g to deal equitably and sensitively with cultural andl<strong>in</strong>guistic heterogeneity, and explicit policies of multicultural education.The latter, I have suggested here, are generally problematic, <strong>the</strong>irconstituents prone to extremes. Ei<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>y are stated <strong>in</strong> vague generalities,often tricked out <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> latest educational jargon, or <strong>the</strong>y restate <strong>the</strong>obvious and thus re<strong>in</strong>force my contention that all good education ismulticultural <strong>in</strong> nature anyway. I want to conclude here by mention<strong>in</strong>gsometh<strong>in</strong>g that is ei<strong>the</strong>r a contribution to <strong>the</strong> ma<strong>in</strong>tenance of <strong>the</strong>dist<strong>in</strong>ction to <strong>the</strong> potential po<strong>in</strong>t at which a de facto multiculturalreality produces social, political and educational policy or, <strong>in</strong> fact, arestatement of that dist<strong>in</strong>ction. It is a dichotomy that I suggested to aDanish audience more than a decade ago: hard (or strong) versus soft (orweak) multiculturalism (Edwards, 1994b).I modelled my argument on <strong>the</strong> debate surround<strong>in</strong>g Whorf’s classicl<strong>in</strong>guistic relativity hypo<strong>the</strong>sis (Carroll, 1972; Edwards, 1989). Whorfhimself had essentially argued that language determ<strong>in</strong>es thought: ourown particular language <strong>in</strong>fluences <strong>the</strong> ways <strong>in</strong> which we see <strong>the</strong> worldand, hence, our cognitive function<strong>in</strong>g. But this ‘strong’ hypo<strong>the</strong>sis isrejected by l<strong>in</strong>guists and psychologists, who cite such evidence as <strong>the</strong>possibility of translat<strong>in</strong>g from one language to ano<strong>the</strong>r, and <strong>the</strong> fact thatwe are all capable of expand<strong>in</strong>g and adjust<strong>in</strong>g our language (ourvocabulary, to give one specific example) if circumstances require. Thereis no good evidence, <strong>in</strong> short, to suggest a ‘tight’ connection between <strong>the</strong>particular language one speaks and one’s basic thought processes. Thereis evidence, however, for <strong>the</strong> shap<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>fluence of environment uponlanguage. If, for <strong>in</strong>stance, your community lives <strong>in</strong> a desert, and has done


230 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>so for a long time, it is quite possible that your color vocabulary will notrange over <strong>the</strong> nuances of green and red reflected <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> language ofspeakers <strong>in</strong> more temperate climatic zones. If, however, your groupsuddenly f<strong>in</strong>ds oil under <strong>the</strong> sands, becomes very rich, and moves enmasse to <strong>the</strong> Riviera, <strong>the</strong>n you can be sure that lexical expansion will soonfollow. So, while a ‘strong’ or ‘tight’ Whorfianism is unlikely, a ‘weaker’variety makes perfect sense, for <strong>the</strong> reason just mentioned. It is plausibleto accept that <strong>the</strong>re is a circular and mutually re<strong>in</strong>forc<strong>in</strong>g relationshipbetween language and <strong>the</strong> environment (both physical and sociocultural) and <strong>the</strong> upshot will be that language <strong>in</strong>fluences our customary orhabitual ways of th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g. That is, <strong>the</strong>re is a connection here, but it is a‘loose’ one reflect<strong>in</strong>g habitual ways of look<strong>in</strong>g at <strong>the</strong> world, notcognitively <strong>in</strong>evitable ones. 8In like manner, I suggested that <strong>the</strong>re is a ‘soft’ multiculturalism thatacknowledges diversity, and may even make some formal accommodationto it at educational or social-policy levels, and a ‘hard’ version thatunderp<strong>in</strong>s deeper and more permanent structural alterations. In practice,<strong>the</strong> first reflects an older social vision that whe<strong>the</strong>r unarticulated orofficially upheld believes <strong>in</strong> some ultimate assimilation. It is anassimilation of choice, one might say, and not a forced or legislatedone; none<strong>the</strong>less, assimilation is seen as a desirable end-po<strong>in</strong>t. Particulargroups, or <strong>in</strong>dividuals with<strong>in</strong> groups, may wish to ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong> markers ofethnic dist<strong>in</strong>ctiveness, but most will acquiesce at some po<strong>in</strong>t to <strong>the</strong> socialpressures and benefits associated with ‘ma<strong>in</strong>stream’ life. This is <strong>the</strong>general pattern that has described <strong>the</strong> social trajectories of most newworldimmigrants: <strong>the</strong> ethnic connection between a fourth-generation‘Polish-American’ and her first-generation forebear is now largely asymbolic one. (Precisely because of its <strong>in</strong>tangibility, symbolic ethnicitycan be a very endur<strong>in</strong>g matter, and it is not an <strong>in</strong>considerable orpsychologically negligible quantity; for details, see Edwards, 1994a.) It is,<strong>in</strong> fact, essentially what Horace Kallen (1924) wrote about under <strong>the</strong>head<strong>in</strong>g of ‘cultural pluralism’. A typical l<strong>in</strong>guistic manifestation hereis this: first-generation monol<strong>in</strong>gualism <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> language spoken uponarrival at (say) Ellis Island; second-generation bil<strong>in</strong>gualism <strong>in</strong> thatlanguage and English; third-generation monol<strong>in</strong>gualism <strong>in</strong> English.‘Hard’ multiculturalism, on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r hand, is a more clearly articulatedpolicy that aims at an endur<strong>in</strong>g diversity, an ongo<strong>in</strong>g ethnoculturalpluralism, a society with room for a broad array of languages andcultures. Harmonious <strong>in</strong>tergroup relations are, of course, hoped for here;<strong>in</strong>deed, <strong>the</strong> argument is often made that it is precisely <strong>the</strong> recognition andcultivation of diversity that will lead to such relations. The belief is, as


Multiculturalism and Multicultural Education 231Gerstle (2001: 349) put it, that ‘cultural diversity and national pride [are]compatible... that ethnic diversity and a respect for ethnic and racialdifferences streng<strong>the</strong>ned America’. Outright ‘anti-multiculturalists’, aswell as proponents of ‘softer’ versions, make a counter-argument.Permanent ethnocultural heterogeneity is a recipe for social discord and(as <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Canadian case, for example), it will work aga<strong>in</strong>st <strong>the</strong> gradual anddesirable emergence of some overall national ethos.There have been o<strong>the</strong>r similar dist<strong>in</strong>ctions. Higham (1982) wrote of‘hard’ and ‘soft’ pluralism, Dev<strong>in</strong>e (1996) makes a ‘strong’ and ‘weak’dist<strong>in</strong>ction, and Wood (1994: 4849) at about <strong>the</strong> same time I wasdiscuss<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> matter <strong>in</strong> Odense referred to ‘hard’ and ‘soft’ multiculturalism<strong>in</strong> America. Like Schles<strong>in</strong>ger, Wood is an historian, and <strong>the</strong>type of dist<strong>in</strong>ction he draws is a very po<strong>in</strong>ted one, rem<strong>in</strong>iscent ofSchles<strong>in</strong>ger’s (1992) earlier arguments:There is no doubt that our understand<strong>in</strong>g of American history hasbeen profoundly enriched by what might be called a soft multiculturalapproach... we used to call it pluralism, which assumed aprocess of assimilation. Celebrat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> dist<strong>in</strong>ctiveness of one’s groupor ethnicity always has been part of <strong>the</strong> process of becom<strong>in</strong>gAmerican... what is new and alarm<strong>in</strong>g is <strong>the</strong> use of ‘‘identitypolitics’’ and what might be called hard multiculturalism to break up<strong>the</strong> nation <strong>in</strong>to antagonistic and irreconcilable fragments.The dist<strong>in</strong>ction here is overdrawn and unnecessarily conspiratorial.The real efforts of <strong>the</strong> ‘hard’ multiculturalists are not to break up <strong>the</strong>nation but, as I have implied above, to fundamentally alter its character.‘Hard’ multiculturalists could po<strong>in</strong>t nowadays, for <strong>in</strong>stance, to <strong>the</strong>powerful Hispanic population <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> United States, and to <strong>the</strong> changesthat this <strong>in</strong>fluential presence has brought to everyday life, as an exampleof a real sea-change <strong>in</strong> American society. ‘Soft’ multiculturalists look at<strong>the</strong> same picture, and bewail <strong>the</strong> pass<strong>in</strong>g of <strong>the</strong> status quo.Notes1. A po<strong>in</strong>t of comparison here: <strong>in</strong> formerly Communist societies, <strong>the</strong> emergencefrom under <strong>the</strong> dead hand of totalitarianism often signalled, unfortunately, areturn to older ethnic rivalries. But this does not mean that democracy awoke<strong>the</strong> sleep<strong>in</strong>g pr<strong>in</strong>cess she had always been <strong>the</strong>re, wait<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> w<strong>in</strong>gs for anew chance to occupy <strong>the</strong> spotlight.2. A much fuller story of Canadian multiculturalism from <strong>the</strong> importantUkra<strong>in</strong>ian po<strong>in</strong>t of view, is found <strong>in</strong> Lupul’s lengthy memoir (2005). Scholarsfrom <strong>the</strong> Canadian Ukra<strong>in</strong>ian community have, from <strong>the</strong> first, been keenobservers of, and commentators on, <strong>the</strong> federal policy of multiculturalism.


232 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>3. Bernard Coard is far from an ord<strong>in</strong>ary educational scholar. After his doctoralstudies <strong>in</strong> England, he returned to his <strong>home</strong> <strong>in</strong> Grenada and jo<strong>in</strong>ed a left-w<strong>in</strong>gpolitical party, which, under <strong>the</strong> leadership of Maurice Bishop, seized power<strong>in</strong> 1979. As <strong>the</strong> deputy Prime M<strong>in</strong>ister, Coard <strong>the</strong>n overthrew Bishop’sgovernment <strong>in</strong> 1983 Bishop and some of his cab<strong>in</strong>et colleagues wereunceremoniously shot to death. Shortly <strong>the</strong>reafter came <strong>the</strong> American<strong>in</strong>vasion of <strong>the</strong> island. With some o<strong>the</strong>rs (<strong>the</strong> ‘Grenada Seventeen’), Coardwas arrested, sentenced to death <strong>in</strong> 1986, and is currently serv<strong>in</strong>g a lifesentence. He ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>s his <strong>in</strong>nocence, claim<strong>in</strong>g that his conviction was at <strong>the</strong>hands of a kangaroo court (see Noel, 2005).4. I am well aware that all education reflects some values and not o<strong>the</strong>rs, that noclassroom sett<strong>in</strong>g is free of <strong>the</strong> constra<strong>in</strong>ts and attitudes that characterize <strong>the</strong>society <strong>in</strong> which it takes its place. But two po<strong>in</strong>ts suggest <strong>the</strong>mselves here. First,is it any sort of advance to replace one set of constra<strong>in</strong>ts with ano<strong>the</strong>r as someof <strong>the</strong> more radical multicultural curricula, <strong>in</strong> an ironic rejection of <strong>the</strong> verypr<strong>in</strong>ciples of diversity that are supposed to animate <strong>the</strong>m, would apparentlylike to see? Second, considerations of degree are relevant here. While it is logicalto admit that no contexts are value-free, it is not illogical to suggest thatsome are more value-laden than o<strong>the</strong>rs. Consider <strong>the</strong> follow<strong>in</strong>g quotation from<strong>the</strong> em<strong>in</strong>ent scholar of nationalism, Elie Kedourie (1961: 8384), and replace <strong>the</strong>word ‘nationalist’ with ‘multiculturalist’:On nationalist <strong>the</strong>ory... <strong>the</strong> purpose of education is not to transmitknowledge, traditional wisdom, and <strong>the</strong> ways devised by a society forattend<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>the</strong> common concerns; its purpose ra<strong>the</strong>r is wholly political.This may seem a little too po<strong>in</strong>ted to those with no experience of regimesthat are o<strong>the</strong>r than liberal-democratic, and I would not want to suggest thatmodern <strong>the</strong>orists of multicultural education despise knowledge and wisdom.But I would argue that <strong>in</strong>appropriate pendulum positions become more likelywith <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>g adherence to particular ideologies and, fur<strong>the</strong>r, that harmfulconsequences are likely to be exacerbated when those ideologies are,<strong>the</strong>mselves, subject to <strong>the</strong> vagaries of often ephemeral cultural <strong>in</strong>terpretation.5. It is worth po<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g out here that, like o<strong>the</strong>r important areas ly<strong>in</strong>g at <strong>the</strong><strong>in</strong>tersection of research and application, <strong>the</strong> entire ‘multicultural enterprise’ ismost often associated with those who have pre-exist<strong>in</strong>g commitments toparticular aspects of that application. Noth<strong>in</strong>g wrong with that, of course and, aga<strong>in</strong>, one can hardly argue for value-free <strong>in</strong>vestigation <strong>in</strong> any socialscientifictopic but on <strong>the</strong> ground, as it were, this does sometimes mean thatdis<strong>in</strong>terested scholarship is not always as front-and-center as one might like.There are curious wheels-with<strong>in</strong>-wheels here, too. I have on my desk abrochure advertis<strong>in</strong>g a journal of <strong>the</strong> World Communication Association. TheJournal of Intercultural Communication Research is edited <strong>in</strong> Wiscons<strong>in</strong> and,among its 47 editorial-board members, only three (two from Japan, one fromCanada) are at non-American universities. This is surely a little odd, given <strong>the</strong>journal’s subject area.6. This is a mistaken citation. Glazer’s chapter occupies pages 85 to 109 <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>anthology by Coleman et al. (1977), someth<strong>in</strong>g noted correctly <strong>in</strong> Bullivant’sreference list. Not only is page 24 not a part of Glazer’s piece, <strong>the</strong> latter does


Multiculturalism and Multicultural Education 233not <strong>in</strong>clude <strong>the</strong> comments cited by Bullivant! None<strong>the</strong>less, <strong>the</strong> spirit ofGlazer’s op<strong>in</strong>ion is accurately reflected <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>m.7. Glazer was slightly anticipated here by <strong>the</strong> journalist and scholar, LouisMenand (1994); he po<strong>in</strong>ted out that ‘almost everyone today... is some k<strong>in</strong>d ofa multiculturalist’.8. Even with ‘strong’ Whorfianism, it is, of course, legitimate to ask why thosethought-determ<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g languages developed differently at all. This would seemto br<strong>in</strong>g us back to <strong>the</strong> environment aga<strong>in</strong> and, <strong>in</strong>deed, Whorf himself noted<strong>the</strong> constant <strong>in</strong>terplay of language patterns and cultural norms.


Chapter 12Bil<strong>in</strong>gualism: A Very Brief OverviewIntroductionThere is a huge literature on what one might term <strong>the</strong> ‘technicalities’of bil<strong>in</strong>gualism and bil<strong>in</strong>gual education: def<strong>in</strong>itions (of course), <strong>the</strong>assessment and measurement of various degrees and dimensions ofbil<strong>in</strong>gualism, <strong>the</strong> relationship between language acquisition and o<strong>the</strong>rvariables (age, gender, <strong>in</strong>telligence, motivation and attitude, socioeconomicstatus, m<strong>in</strong>ority-group membership, <strong>the</strong> sociocultural and sociopoliticalcontext), <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>tricacies of borrow<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>in</strong>terference and switch<strong>in</strong>gacross two or more languages, bil<strong>in</strong>gual and multil<strong>in</strong>gual literacy, <strong>the</strong>relationship between personal and societal bil<strong>in</strong>gualism, types ofbil<strong>in</strong>gual education provisions, <strong>the</strong> effectiveness of programs of bil<strong>in</strong>gualeducation. Obviously, it would be impossible for me to do more thanprovide <strong>the</strong> briefest of <strong>in</strong>troductions here, but, <strong>in</strong> any event, a deeptreatment of <strong>the</strong> nuts and bolts of bil<strong>in</strong>gualism is not to my purpose. Aswill be seen, I am more concerned with <strong>the</strong> symbolic and group-identityaspects of bil<strong>in</strong>gualism, particularly where ‘smaller’ languages come <strong>in</strong>tocontact with ‘larger’ ones.Ano<strong>the</strong>r reason for not provid<strong>in</strong>g much detail here is simply that thishas been thoroughly done elsewhere, <strong>in</strong> topical surveys that are clear,up-to-date and easily accessible. Chief among <strong>the</strong>se are <strong>the</strong> encyclopediaof Baker and Jones (1998) and Baker’s smaller but still very comprehensivetextbook (2006). The recent handbook by Bhatia and Ritchie (2004) isvery useful, and several publishers (Pergamon, De Gruyter, Spr<strong>in</strong>ger,Blackwell and Oxford University Press among <strong>the</strong>m) have recentlyissued large reference volumes and encyclopedias on various aspects of<strong>the</strong> ‘social life’ of language; see also and Hamers and Blanc (2000), Li Wei(2000) and Roma<strong>in</strong>e (1995).Def<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g Bil<strong>in</strong>gualismEveryone is bil<strong>in</strong>gual. That is, <strong>the</strong>re is no one <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> world (no adult,anyway) who does not know at least a few words <strong>in</strong> languages o<strong>the</strong>r than<strong>the</strong> maternal variety. If, as an English speaker, you can say c’est la vie or234


Bil<strong>in</strong>gualism: A Very Brief Overview 235gracias or guten Tag or tovarisch or even if you only understand <strong>the</strong>m you clearly have some ‘command’ of a foreign tongue. Of course, thissort of competence does not lead many to th<strong>in</strong>k of bil<strong>in</strong>gualism. If, on <strong>the</strong>o<strong>the</strong>r hand, you are conversationally fluent <strong>in</strong> more than one language,<strong>the</strong>n bil<strong>in</strong>gualism may be an apt designation. And if, on <strong>the</strong> third hand,you are like <strong>the</strong> literary critic and essayist, George Ste<strong>in</strong>er, who claimsequal fluency <strong>in</strong> English, French and German, <strong>the</strong>n bil<strong>in</strong>gualism (actuallytril<strong>in</strong>gualism <strong>in</strong> this case) seems apter still.Giuseppe Mezzofanti, chief curator <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Vatican Library <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> early19th century, was reportedly fluent <strong>in</strong> 60 languages and had translat<strong>in</strong>gability <strong>in</strong> twice that number. Georges Schmidt, head of <strong>the</strong> term<strong>in</strong>ologysection at <strong>the</strong> United Nations <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> 1960s, knew 20 languages. GeorgeSte<strong>in</strong>er and all <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r well-known polyglots <strong>the</strong> Stoppards,Kunderas and Nabokovs of <strong>the</strong> world typically have three or fourlanguages (and so, of course, do many hundreds of millions ofunremarked and unremarkable people). Even more common arebil<strong>in</strong>guals, with a paltry dual fluency. And <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong>re is your cous<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>Birm<strong>in</strong>gham, who can just about understand what c’est la vie means.How are <strong>the</strong>se fluencies related? Mezzofanti would seem to be moremultil<strong>in</strong>gual than Ste<strong>in</strong>er, but <strong>the</strong> latter claims that his varieties are soequally deeply held that, even after rigorous self-exam<strong>in</strong>ation of whichlanguage emerges spontaneously <strong>in</strong> times of emergency or elevatedemotion, which variety is dreamt <strong>in</strong>, which is associated with <strong>the</strong> earliestmemories no one of <strong>the</strong> three seems dom<strong>in</strong>ant. (Ste<strong>in</strong>er and o<strong>the</strong>rs haveargued, <strong>in</strong> fact, that <strong>the</strong>re may be important l<strong>in</strong>guistic and cognitivedifferences between a person who has a clear and obvious first language,to which o<strong>the</strong>rs have been added, and someone like himself, who isapparently maternally multil<strong>in</strong>gual. Wierzbicka’s [2005] perceptivepaper on <strong>the</strong> different perspectives of mono- and multil<strong>in</strong>gual peopleis relevant here.) And if <strong>the</strong>re is some difficulty <strong>in</strong> compar<strong>in</strong>g capabilities,given that both number and depth seem to be important, where mightwe place <strong>the</strong> Schmidts of <strong>the</strong> world? And your Birm<strong>in</strong>gham cous<strong>in</strong>:ought she to count as bil<strong>in</strong>gual at all? Beyond <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>formal <strong>in</strong>terest thathas always attached to polymathic capabilities, beyond <strong>the</strong> Gu<strong>in</strong>ness Bookof Records, <strong>the</strong> assessment of l<strong>in</strong>guistic competence has considerablescholarly importance.As may be imag<strong>in</strong>ed, it is easy to f<strong>in</strong>d def<strong>in</strong>itions of bil<strong>in</strong>gualism thatreflect widely divergent responses to <strong>the</strong> question of degree. In 1933, forexample, Bloomfield observed that bil<strong>in</strong>gualism resulted from <strong>the</strong>addition of a perfectly learned foreign language to one’s own, undim<strong>in</strong>ishednative tongue. He did ra<strong>the</strong>r confuse <strong>the</strong> issue, however, by


236 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>admitt<strong>in</strong>g that <strong>the</strong> def<strong>in</strong>ition of ‘perfection’ was a relative one. We<strong>in</strong>reich(1953) simply def<strong>in</strong>ed bil<strong>in</strong>gualism as <strong>the</strong> alternate use of two languages.In <strong>the</strong> same year, Haugen suggested that bil<strong>in</strong>gualism began with <strong>the</strong>ability to produce complete and mean<strong>in</strong>gful utterances <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> secondlanguage; this suggests that your Birm<strong>in</strong>gham cous<strong>in</strong> is bil<strong>in</strong>gual.Generally speak<strong>in</strong>g, earlier def<strong>in</strong>itions tended to restrict bil<strong>in</strong>gualism toequal mastery of two languages, while later ones have allowed muchgreater variation <strong>in</strong> competence. But s<strong>in</strong>ce this relaxation proves <strong>in</strong>practice to be as unsatisfactory as an argument from perfection, mostmodern treatments acknowledge that any mean<strong>in</strong>gful discussion mustbe attempted with<strong>in</strong> a specific context, and for specific purposes.Fur<strong>the</strong>r complicat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> matter of degree, this question of wherebil<strong>in</strong>gualism starts, is <strong>the</strong> fact that any l<strong>in</strong>e drawn must cross not just onegeneral language dimension, but many more specific threads of ability.Consider, first, that <strong>the</strong>re are four basic language skills: listen<strong>in</strong>g,speak<strong>in</strong>g, read<strong>in</strong>g and writ<strong>in</strong>g. 1 Consider fur<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> possible subdivisions:speak<strong>in</strong>g skill, for example, <strong>in</strong>cludes what may be quite divergentlevels of expression <strong>in</strong> vocabulary, grammar and accent. Thus, <strong>the</strong>re is asubstantial number of elements here, all of which figure <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>assessment of bil<strong>in</strong>gualism. It does not follow that strength <strong>in</strong> one meansstrength <strong>in</strong> ano<strong>the</strong>r; thus, Baker (1988: 2) noted thata pupil may be able to understand spoken English and Welsh, speakEnglish fluently but Welsh only halt<strong>in</strong>gly, read <strong>in</strong> Welsh with aread<strong>in</strong>g age of six and <strong>in</strong> English with a read<strong>in</strong>g age of eight, writepoorly <strong>in</strong> English and not at all <strong>in</strong> Welsh. Is that pupil bil<strong>in</strong>gual?In general, given both <strong>the</strong> basic skills, and <strong>the</strong>ir subdivisions, <strong>the</strong>re are atleast 20 dimensions of language that might be assessed <strong>in</strong> order todeterm<strong>in</strong>e bil<strong>in</strong>gual proficiency. While <strong>in</strong> many cases it is quite clearwhich language is dom<strong>in</strong>ant (at least with<strong>in</strong> some given doma<strong>in</strong>), arough reckon<strong>in</strong>g may be quite <strong>in</strong>adequate if we wish, say, to comparegroups of bil<strong>in</strong>gual <strong>in</strong>dividuals, or if we wish to study <strong>the</strong> relationshipbetween bil<strong>in</strong>gualism and o<strong>the</strong>r personality traits.Many tests have been used to measure bil<strong>in</strong>gualism; <strong>the</strong>se <strong>in</strong>cluderat<strong>in</strong>g scales and tests of fluency, flexibility and dom<strong>in</strong>ance. The firstof <strong>the</strong>se can <strong>in</strong>volve <strong>in</strong>terviews, language-usage measures and selfassessmentprocedures. In some ways, rely<strong>in</strong>g upon self-rat<strong>in</strong>gs has a lotto recommend it, but <strong>the</strong> strengths here rest upon <strong>the</strong> capacity of an<strong>in</strong>dividual to be able to self-report accurately, a roughly equivalent senseacross <strong>in</strong>dividuals of what competence means, and a will<strong>in</strong>gness to betruthful <strong>in</strong> response. None of <strong>the</strong>se can be taken for granted. Indeed,


Bil<strong>in</strong>gualism: A Very Brief Overview 237some of <strong>the</strong> problems here can also affect <strong>the</strong> apparently more objectivetests of fluency and flexibility. We might, for example, ask people torespond to <strong>in</strong>structions <strong>in</strong> two languages, measure <strong>the</strong>ir response timesand, on this basis, try to ascerta<strong>in</strong> dom<strong>in</strong>ance. Or we could presentpicture-nam<strong>in</strong>g or word-completion tasks, we could ask subjects to readaloud or we might present a word that occurs <strong>in</strong> both languages (pipe, forexample, occurs <strong>in</strong> both French and English) and see how it ispronounced. We could simply test for extent of vocabulary, or see howmany synonyms for a given word a person can come up with. Und soweiter.As well, it can easily be appreciated that factors such as attitude, age,sex, <strong>in</strong>telligence, memory, l<strong>in</strong>guistic distance between languages and <strong>the</strong>context of test<strong>in</strong>g all have <strong>the</strong> potential to confuse and confound <strong>the</strong>picture. Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, even if we were able to gauge with some accuracy,<strong>the</strong>re would rema<strong>in</strong> problems of adequate labell<strong>in</strong>g. That is, measured<strong>in</strong>dividuals would hardly fall <strong>in</strong>to one, or two, or four neat categories ofability, or degrees of bil<strong>in</strong>gualism. I should also mention here <strong>the</strong>commonly held view that limits exist on l<strong>in</strong>guistic capacities, that <strong>the</strong>reis some f<strong>in</strong>ite available cranial space; <strong>in</strong>deed, this ‘conta<strong>in</strong>er’ philosophybedevilled <strong>the</strong> academic literature for quite some time. As I have alreadynoted, <strong>the</strong> suggestion is at its simplest that what you ga<strong>in</strong> on <strong>the</strong>sw<strong>in</strong>gs of one language you lose on <strong>the</strong> roundabouts of <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r. But allsuch metaphors are flawed <strong>in</strong> at least two ways: first, <strong>the</strong>re is no evidencethat a simplistic conta<strong>in</strong>er model is appropriate at all; second, even if wewere to acknowledge some f<strong>in</strong>ite absorption and retention potentials, allthat we know of <strong>in</strong>tellectual structure and function would suggest that<strong>the</strong>y are quite large enough that we need not worry about exhaust<strong>in</strong>g ourmental credit (th<strong>in</strong>k of Card<strong>in</strong>al Mezzofanti). (Obviously, <strong>the</strong> l<strong>in</strong>guisticaspects are but one part of a more general cognitive picture; <strong>the</strong> mostrecent neuropsychological research suggests <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>adequacy of simple‘conta<strong>in</strong>er’ metaphors; see Fernyhough, 2006, for a cursory considerationof ‘metaphors of m<strong>in</strong>d’.)There are some important dichotomies to attend to, as well. First, <strong>the</strong>reis <strong>the</strong> dist<strong>in</strong>ction between receptive (or passive) bil<strong>in</strong>gualism andproductive (or active) competence. The difference here is between thosewho understand a language, ei<strong>the</strong>r spoken or written, but cannotproduce it <strong>the</strong>mselves, and those who can do both. Second, <strong>the</strong>re is adist<strong>in</strong>ction between additive and subtractive bil<strong>in</strong>gualism: with <strong>the</strong> former,<strong>the</strong> learn<strong>in</strong>g of ano<strong>the</strong>r language means an expansion of <strong>the</strong> l<strong>in</strong>guisticrepertoire; with <strong>the</strong> latter, <strong>the</strong> new language may displace <strong>the</strong> exist<strong>in</strong>gone. Additive bil<strong>in</strong>gualism generally occurs where both languages


238 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>cont<strong>in</strong>ue to be useful and valued; subtractive bil<strong>in</strong>gualism, on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rhand, usually occurs <strong>in</strong> sett<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>in</strong> which one language is valued morethan <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r, where one dom<strong>in</strong>ates <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r, where one is on <strong>the</strong>ascendant and <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r is wan<strong>in</strong>g. 2 A third important contrast is thatbetween primary and secondary bil<strong>in</strong>gualism, between a dual-languagecompetence acquired naturally, through contextual demands, and onewhere systematic and formal <strong>in</strong>struction has occurred. F<strong>in</strong>ally here, somewriters have drawn yet ano<strong>the</strong>r dist<strong>in</strong>ction: language acquisition is torefer to gradual or ‘natural’ l<strong>in</strong>guistic development (<strong>in</strong> ei<strong>the</strong>r first orsubsequent varieties), while language learn<strong>in</strong>g is to be reserved for morestudied and formal atta<strong>in</strong>ments (most typically, at school).These are not watertight compartments, of course. For <strong>in</strong>stance, onemight pick up a fluently conversational grasp of a language <strong>in</strong> arelatively <strong>in</strong>formal way, and later feel <strong>the</strong> need to add some read<strong>in</strong>gand writ<strong>in</strong>g skills. None<strong>the</strong>less, bil<strong>in</strong>gual people <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Gaeltacht ofIreland or Scotland are obviously different from residents of Dubl<strong>in</strong>,Glasgow or Ed<strong>in</strong>burgh, who have more self-consciously set <strong>the</strong>mselvesto become bil<strong>in</strong>gual, and lump<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>se two groups toge<strong>the</strong>r under as<strong>in</strong>gle bil<strong>in</strong>gual rubric might not lead to <strong>the</strong> most accurate descriptions.Becom<strong>in</strong>g Bil<strong>in</strong>gualThe fact that a majority of <strong>the</strong> global population has at least some levelof multil<strong>in</strong>gual competence surely <strong>in</strong>dicates that add<strong>in</strong>g a secondlanguage is not a particularly remarkable feat. English and Americanmonol<strong>in</strong>guals often compla<strong>in</strong> that <strong>the</strong>y have no aptitude for foreignlanguagelearn<strong>in</strong>g. This is usually accompanied by expressions of envyfor those multil<strong>in</strong>gual Europeans, Asians and Africans, and sometimes(more subtly) by a l<strong>in</strong>guistic smugness reflect<strong>in</strong>g a deeply held convictionthat, after all, those clever ‘o<strong>the</strong>rs’ who don’t already know Englishwill have to accommodate <strong>the</strong>mselves <strong>in</strong> a world made <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>gly safefor anglophones. All such attitudes, of course, reveal more about socialdom<strong>in</strong>ance and convention than <strong>the</strong>y do about aptitude.Second-language acquisition has been dichotomized as simultaneousor successive. The first describes exposure to more than one variety from<strong>the</strong> onset of speech or, at least, from a very young age (somecommentators have suggested age three or four as a ra<strong>the</strong>r arbitrarycut-off), while <strong>the</strong> second refers to <strong>the</strong> addition of a new variety to anexist<strong>in</strong>g one at a later age. Simultaneous acquisition most commonlyoccurs under <strong>the</strong> ‘one parent, one language’ head<strong>in</strong>g pr<strong>in</strong>ciple: mo<strong>the</strong>rspeaks German to <strong>the</strong> child, fa<strong>the</strong>r speaks English. There are some classic


Bil<strong>in</strong>gualism: A Very Brief Overview 239accounts of this <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> literature (e.g. Leopold, 19391949; Ronjat, 1913).Given <strong>the</strong> cont<strong>in</strong>u<strong>in</strong>g reservations about bil<strong>in</strong>gualism <strong>in</strong> some parts of<strong>the</strong> popular (anglophone) m<strong>in</strong>d, it should be noted that <strong>the</strong> literaturestrongly suggests that general l<strong>in</strong>guistic and mental development is notadversely affected. Br<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>g up children bil<strong>in</strong>gually is not a riskybus<strong>in</strong>ess. Where negative consequences have been observed, <strong>the</strong>se arealmost always due to social, personal, cultural or o<strong>the</strong>r factors, and not tobil<strong>in</strong>gualism per se. With appropriate social conditions, <strong>the</strong>n, bil<strong>in</strong>gualismis just as ‘natural’ as monol<strong>in</strong>gualism; statistically speak<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>in</strong>deed,it is much more natural. With sufficient motivation and opportunity, allnormally <strong>in</strong>telligent people can learn ano<strong>the</strong>r variety, and those whoclaim <strong>the</strong>y are ‘no good’ at foreign languages are usually lack<strong>in</strong>g one orboth of <strong>the</strong>se. This is not to deny that <strong>the</strong>re may exist <strong>in</strong>dividuals whohave a greater <strong>in</strong>nate or acquired aptitude: a ‘good ear’ may be helpful,as well as a good memory and a capacity for self-<strong>in</strong>itiated application;beyond <strong>the</strong>se, adaptability and genu<strong>in</strong>e <strong>in</strong>terest <strong>in</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r cultures are nodoubt important. But <strong>the</strong>se factors are all of general value and do notform a package specifically implicated <strong>in</strong> language learn<strong>in</strong>g and <strong>in</strong> anyevent <strong>the</strong>y are dwarfed by contextual pressures and demands.There are many formal methods for teach<strong>in</strong>g languages. Generallyspeak<strong>in</strong>g, older approaches tended to stress <strong>the</strong> memorization ofgrammatical rules and lexicon <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> service of literary study, and littleattention was given to oral language. In more contemporary schoolsett<strong>in</strong>gs this has changed, although even high-tech language laboratoriessometimes merely <strong>in</strong>dividualize older approaches, ra<strong>the</strong>r than signall<strong>in</strong>ga change of course towards more conversational competence. Still, whileit rema<strong>in</strong>s difficult for <strong>the</strong> classroom to become a representation of <strong>the</strong>street, <strong>the</strong> tendency is for more and more conversation. Students areencouraged to speak before learn<strong>in</strong>g formal grammar, and <strong>the</strong> use of<strong>the</strong> maternal variety is often kept to a m<strong>in</strong>imum; <strong>in</strong> short, secondlanguageacquisition is meant to resemble first-language learn<strong>in</strong>g asmuch as possible.A number of <strong>the</strong>oretical perspectives <strong>in</strong>form language-acquisitionpractices, and I shall merely touch upon <strong>the</strong>m here. Social-psychological<strong>the</strong>ories have paid particular attention to motivational features, and thismakes a good deal of sense. If we agree that language is a social activity,and if we accept that almost everyone is cognitively capable of learn<strong>in</strong>gsecond (and subsequent) varieties, <strong>the</strong>n it follows that <strong>the</strong> force of <strong>the</strong>situation and <strong>the</strong> attitud<strong>in</strong>al atmosphere are central. The dist<strong>in</strong>ction thatI have already mentioned between <strong>in</strong>strumental and <strong>in</strong>tegrative motivationsfor second-language learn<strong>in</strong>g was first drawn <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> 1960s. The


240 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>former refers to a desire to learn for utilitarian purposes, <strong>the</strong> latter tolanguage learn<strong>in</strong>g as part of a wish to know more about, to <strong>in</strong>teract with,and perhaps ultimately to immerse oneself <strong>in</strong> ano<strong>the</strong>r culture. Perhaps,however, a well-fleshed <strong>in</strong>strumental attitude must <strong>in</strong>clude at least some<strong>in</strong>tegrative motivation, and one can also imag<strong>in</strong>e a development of <strong>the</strong>former <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> latter. In any event, Gardner and Lambert (1972)presented a well-known framework for second-language learn<strong>in</strong>g that<strong>in</strong>corporates <strong>the</strong> dist<strong>in</strong>ction. A later model, described by Noels andClément (1998), has aimed to embed <strong>in</strong>dividual motivations still moredeeply <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> social sett<strong>in</strong>g. Of special <strong>in</strong>terest here is <strong>the</strong> tension seen toexist between an <strong>in</strong>tegrative motivation and fear of assimilation; <strong>the</strong>model thus has particular relevance for those language learners who arealso m<strong>in</strong>ority-group members, and whose first language is threatened by<strong>the</strong> forces of those speak<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> second. A fur<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>oretical developmentis <strong>the</strong> formulation of Giles and his colleagues (see Giles &Coupland, 1991) <strong>in</strong> which language learn<strong>in</strong>g is seen as essentially an<strong>in</strong>tergroup process. Much more consideration is <strong>the</strong>refore given toassimilative tendencies and apprehensions, to <strong>the</strong> preservation ofethnic-group boundaries and identities.A recent ‘general <strong>the</strong>ory’ of second-language learn<strong>in</strong>g has beenproposed by Spolsky (1989a). It syn<strong>the</strong>sizes earlier and more particularizedefforts and it also touches upon first-language acquisition. Spolsky’sapproach has five pivotal features:(a)(b)(c)(d)(e)it attempts to br<strong>in</strong>g all aspects of language learn<strong>in</strong>g under oneroof;it aims for precision and clarity, so that <strong>the</strong> broad coverage doesnot blur details of vary<strong>in</strong>g contexts, goals and outcomes;it assumes that all aspects of learn<strong>in</strong>g are <strong>in</strong>teractive; although<strong>the</strong>y need not be operative <strong>in</strong> all contexts, <strong>the</strong>y all <strong>in</strong>terpenetrate.On <strong>the</strong> subject of motivation, for example, Spolsky wishes todetail types and strengths;it argues that all language learn<strong>in</strong>g must be seen with<strong>in</strong> a socialsett<strong>in</strong>g;it holds that some conditions for learn<strong>in</strong>g are ‘‘graded’’: <strong>the</strong> more<strong>in</strong>tense or favourable <strong>the</strong>y are, <strong>the</strong> more likely a l<strong>in</strong>guisticconsequence becomes. O<strong>the</strong>rs are ‘‘typicality’’ states: <strong>the</strong>y occurusually but not <strong>in</strong>evitably.Application and prediction form <strong>the</strong> acid test <strong>in</strong> all such <strong>the</strong>oreticalmodels (for a recent overview, see Mitchell & Myles, 1998), and somemight suggest that <strong>the</strong>y have done little more than codify and formalize


Bil<strong>in</strong>gualism: A Very Brief Overview 241what has been known for a long time. None<strong>the</strong>less, <strong>the</strong>y all usefullyemphasize <strong>the</strong> importance of <strong>the</strong> sett<strong>in</strong>g and, with<strong>in</strong> it, <strong>the</strong> desires, needs,attitudes and motivations of ord<strong>in</strong>ary people. And <strong>the</strong>y all scotch <strong>the</strong>myth that some people, or some groups, have no ‘head’ for languages,and that second-language aptitude is a rare commodity usually best seen<strong>in</strong> non-anglophones.This br<strong>in</strong>gs us to ano<strong>the</strong>r important topic: <strong>the</strong> relationship betweenbil<strong>in</strong>gualism and <strong>in</strong>telligence. It is one th<strong>in</strong>g to say that all normal peoplehave <strong>the</strong> basic capacity to expand <strong>the</strong>ir l<strong>in</strong>guistic repertoires, and thatdo<strong>in</strong>g so exacts no cognitive price. But what of <strong>the</strong> notion thatbil<strong>in</strong>gualism can <strong>in</strong>crease <strong>in</strong>tellectual scope? It is an historically commonview that one’s personality expands with extra languages, particularlyamong those already bil<strong>in</strong>gual and, more particularly still, among <strong>the</strong>social élite for whom an additional language or two was always an<strong>in</strong>tegral part of civilized life. 3Generally speak<strong>in</strong>g, early studies tended to associate bil<strong>in</strong>gualismwith lowered <strong>in</strong>telligence, and it is unsurpris<strong>in</strong>g that many of <strong>the</strong>m wereconducted <strong>in</strong> America at a time of great concern with <strong>the</strong> flood ofimmigrants from Europe (roughly, 19001920). As we have seen <strong>in</strong> earlierchapters, <strong>the</strong> history of <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>telligence-test<strong>in</strong>g movement itself is afasc<strong>in</strong>at<strong>in</strong>g and detailed one, as well as an example of <strong>the</strong> misuse of‘science’ when allied with ignorance and prejudice. In addition, however,to <strong>the</strong> negative associations between bil<strong>in</strong>gualism and <strong>in</strong>telligence thatstemmed from social fears and prejudices, <strong>the</strong>re have also been moredis<strong>in</strong>terested studies that po<strong>in</strong>ted to problems here. Virtually all wereflawed, however, by <strong>in</strong>adequate controls <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir experimental procedures.The problem of statistical <strong>in</strong>ference has been even more important:if one observes a correlation between measured <strong>in</strong>telligence andbil<strong>in</strong>gualism, <strong>the</strong>n has <strong>the</strong> first caused <strong>the</strong> second, or vice versa, or is<strong>the</strong>re a third factor (perhaps unknown or unmeasured) that <strong>in</strong>fluencesboth and thus accounts for <strong>the</strong>ir relationship? Correlation need not implycausation.Later research tended to show essentially no relationship between<strong>in</strong>telligence and bil<strong>in</strong>gualism, and this work was generally more carefullydone than <strong>the</strong> earlier studies. Controll<strong>in</strong>g for gender, age and socialclassdifferences became common procedure, and <strong>the</strong> lack of such controlwas <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>gly seen to have produced <strong>the</strong> negative associations foundpreviously. What some have seen as a turn<strong>in</strong>g-po<strong>in</strong>t came <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> early1960s, when f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>gs show<strong>in</strong>g a positive relationship between <strong>in</strong>telligenceand bil<strong>in</strong>gualism began to appear. In Montreal, for <strong>in</strong>stance, Peal andLambert (1962) found that 10-year-old bil<strong>in</strong>gual children outperformed


242 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong><strong>the</strong>ir monol<strong>in</strong>gual counterparts on both verbal and non-verbal <strong>in</strong>telligencetests. The authors concluded that <strong>the</strong> bil<strong>in</strong>gual child had greatermental flexibility and superior concept-formation skills, although <strong>the</strong>yalso admitted that <strong>the</strong> directionality of <strong>the</strong> correlation between bil<strong>in</strong>gualability and measured <strong>in</strong>telligence could not be ascerta<strong>in</strong>ed. Follow<strong>in</strong>gPeal and Lambert’s <strong>in</strong>vestigation, many o<strong>the</strong>rs have supported a positiverelationship between bil<strong>in</strong>gualism and <strong>in</strong>telligence. Equally, <strong>the</strong>re havebeen dissent<strong>in</strong>g views, as well as cogent criticism of <strong>the</strong> 1962 study itself.The latter center upon <strong>the</strong> ‘directionality’ limitation just mentioned, butalso upon <strong>the</strong> generalizability of <strong>the</strong> results: important here are Peal andLambert’s use of only ‘balanced’ bil<strong>in</strong>guals, as well as questions about<strong>the</strong> representativeness of <strong>the</strong> sample of children and <strong>the</strong> difficulty ofequat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>home</strong> backgrounds simply by hold<strong>in</strong>g socioeconomic statusconstant.Beyond <strong>the</strong> problems <strong>in</strong> def<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g bil<strong>in</strong>gual ability per se, o<strong>the</strong>rformidable difficulties arise. Do perfectly balanced bil<strong>in</strong>guals persons<strong>in</strong> whom <strong>the</strong> two languages exist at equal levels of fluency constitute<strong>the</strong> ‘best’ contrast with monol<strong>in</strong>guals? And, even assum<strong>in</strong>g that we couldadequately assess degrees of language competence, <strong>the</strong> measurement of<strong>in</strong>telligence rema<strong>in</strong>s problematic. How do we ensure comparabilitybetween groups of bil<strong>in</strong>guals and monol<strong>in</strong>guals: controll<strong>in</strong>g for age,gender and some o<strong>the</strong>r variables may not be difficult, but what aboutsocioeconomic status? Most measures of this may not come to grips wellenough with <strong>home</strong> differences of vital importance; see <strong>the</strong> earlierdiscussion of disadvantage. And, aga<strong>in</strong>, <strong>the</strong> correlational problem: ifwe discover a relationship between bil<strong>in</strong>gualism and <strong>in</strong>telligence, can webe sure it is a causal one and, if so, <strong>in</strong> which direction does <strong>the</strong> causalityflow? Does bil<strong>in</strong>gualism heighten <strong>in</strong>telligence, or does brightness<strong>in</strong>crease <strong>the</strong> likelihood of functional bil<strong>in</strong>gualism?These and o<strong>the</strong>r difficulties mean that strong conclusions aboutbil<strong>in</strong>gualism and cognition are not warranted. Some feel that <strong>the</strong>re isa l<strong>in</strong>k between <strong>the</strong> two, but that any cognitive advantages attach<strong>in</strong>gto bil<strong>in</strong>gualism are ra<strong>the</strong>r slight; o<strong>the</strong>rs have been ma<strong>in</strong>ly concernedto show that <strong>the</strong>re is not a cognitive price to be paid for bil<strong>in</strong>gualism.As McLaughl<strong>in</strong> (1978: 206) noted: ‘almost no general statementsare warranted by research on <strong>the</strong> effects of bil<strong>in</strong>gualism... <strong>in</strong> almostevery case, <strong>the</strong> f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>gs of research are ei<strong>the</strong>r contradicted by o<strong>the</strong>rresearch or can be questioned on methodological grounds’. And Paulston(cited by Rotberg, 1984: 137) added that bil<strong>in</strong>gual education research ischaracterized by ‘disparate f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>gs and <strong>in</strong>conclusive results... a studycan be found to support virtually every possible op<strong>in</strong>ion’. Research


Bil<strong>in</strong>gualism: A Very Brief Overview 243(and experience) has shown that bil<strong>in</strong>gualism does not lead to decreasedor weakened capacities. Most people <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> world are bil<strong>in</strong>gual or better,and while some are well-educated and socioeconomically secure <strong>the</strong>social circumstances of <strong>the</strong> majority are modest. It would seem illogicalto believe, <strong>the</strong>n, that bil<strong>in</strong>gualism per se is likely to <strong>in</strong>volve anysignificant <strong>in</strong>crease <strong>in</strong> basic cognitive and <strong>in</strong>tellectual skills. It wouldsurely be perverse, however, to deny that bil<strong>in</strong>gualism can representano<strong>the</strong>r dimension of ability and, <strong>in</strong> that sense, represent a repertoireexpansion. I see noth<strong>in</strong>g controversial about this, just as I would seenoth<strong>in</strong>g controversial <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> statement that a number of years’ devotionto <strong>the</strong> study of great literature can lead to a heightened or, at least, alteredsensitivity to <strong>the</strong> human condition.Bil<strong>in</strong>gualism and IdentityBe<strong>in</strong>g ‘maternally’ or ‘simultaneously’ bil<strong>in</strong>gual from <strong>the</strong> earliest age,learn<strong>in</strong>g ano<strong>the</strong>r language (whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>in</strong> an ‘additive’ or a ‘subtractive’context) through force of circumstance, expand<strong>in</strong>g a l<strong>in</strong>guistic repertoireas part of one’s scholarly or <strong>in</strong>tellectual life <strong>the</strong>se are all importantmatters, and <strong>the</strong>re is a large and often f<strong>in</strong>ely-detailed literature devotedto <strong>the</strong>m and <strong>the</strong>ir many ramifications. But <strong>the</strong>re is ano<strong>the</strong>r approach tobil<strong>in</strong>gualism, one that considers it from a less communicative but moresymbolic perspective, and one that l<strong>in</strong>ks <strong>the</strong> personal aspects of languageand languages with features that operate at more collective levels.If it is <strong>the</strong> l<strong>in</strong>guistic condition of most adult human be<strong>in</strong>gs and if aswe are now regularly <strong>in</strong>formed by some of <strong>the</strong> stranger practitioners of<strong>the</strong> l<strong>in</strong>guistic arts monol<strong>in</strong>gualism is an aberration, an affliction of <strong>the</strong>powerful and a disease to be cured, <strong>the</strong>n one might reasonably ask whybil<strong>in</strong>gualism should elicit any specific attention. 4 As someth<strong>in</strong>g easilyavailable to <strong>the</strong> poor and <strong>the</strong> illiterate, someth<strong>in</strong>g that can be almosteffortlessly acquired by <strong>the</strong> youngest and most <strong>in</strong>experienced membersof society, it might seem to have attracted ra<strong>the</strong>r more than its share ofacademic attention. Naturally, I don’t mean to suggest that language perse is now a completely open book to us. The work<strong>in</strong>gs of this marvellousfacility, which sets us apart <strong>in</strong> tremendous degree if not <strong>in</strong> basic pr<strong>in</strong>ciplefrom even those clever apes and dolph<strong>in</strong>s, are not fully transparent <strong>in</strong>ei<strong>the</strong>r development or use. Still, with<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> broader study of language,what happens once could perhaps easily be seen as (mutatis mutandis)happen<strong>in</strong>g aga<strong>in</strong>. Why should a second or subsequent language warrantmore than an extend<strong>in</strong>g footnote to <strong>the</strong> broader l<strong>in</strong>guistic enquiry? Why


244 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>should bil<strong>in</strong>gualism occupy its own niche <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> larger l<strong>in</strong>guistic,psychol<strong>in</strong>guistic and sociol<strong>in</strong>guistic enterprise?It is true, of course, that second-language acquisition cannot, <strong>in</strong>pr<strong>in</strong>ciple, be a precise replica of first-language learn<strong>in</strong>g, for <strong>the</strong> simplereason of be<strong>in</strong>g second. Heraclitus told us a long time ago that you can’tstep <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> same river twice. The po<strong>in</strong>t I wish to make here, however, isthat <strong>the</strong> technicalities of <strong>the</strong> broad l<strong>in</strong>guistic enterprise vital and<strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g as <strong>the</strong>y are cannot, <strong>the</strong>mselves, fully expla<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> depth of<strong>in</strong>terest <strong>in</strong> multil<strong>in</strong>gual accommodations. To understand <strong>the</strong>m more fully,we have to move beyond language itself, beyond psychol<strong>in</strong>guistics,beyond experimental studies and educational programs that illum<strong>in</strong>ateand facilitate repertoire expansion. We have to go beyond <strong>in</strong>strumentalmatters altoge<strong>the</strong>r, and consider issues of psychology and sociology, ofsymbol and subjectivity. In a word, we must th<strong>in</strong>k about <strong>the</strong> relationshipbetween language and identity, and how it may alter when more thanone variety is <strong>in</strong>volved.Speak<strong>in</strong>g a particular language means belong<strong>in</strong>g to a particular speechcommunity and this implies that part of <strong>the</strong> social context <strong>in</strong> which one’s<strong>in</strong>dividual personality is embedded, and which supplies some of <strong>the</strong> rawmaterials for that personality, will be l<strong>in</strong>guistic. S<strong>in</strong>ce disentangl<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>l<strong>in</strong>guistic features from all o<strong>the</strong>rs is hardly an easy task, it has alwaysbeen difficult to make a compell<strong>in</strong>g case that membership <strong>in</strong> a givenspeech community has <strong>in</strong> isolation, as it were, from o<strong>the</strong>r socializ<strong>in</strong>gthreads concretely specifiable consequences for personality. But some<strong>in</strong>trigu<strong>in</strong>g questions present <strong>the</strong>mselves none<strong>the</strong>less.Much of <strong>in</strong>terest rests upon <strong>the</strong> degree to which bil<strong>in</strong>guals possessei<strong>the</strong>r two (<strong>the</strong>oretically) separately identifiable systems of language from each of which <strong>the</strong>y can draw, as circumstances warrant or somemore <strong>in</strong>tertw<strong>in</strong>ed l<strong>in</strong>guistic and, perhaps, cognitive duality. There is a‘popular’ (and sometimes scholarly) notion that bil<strong>in</strong>gual <strong>in</strong>dividualsmust have a sort of split mentality: two persons <strong>in</strong> one, as it were.Grosjean (1982) and o<strong>the</strong>rs have certa<strong>in</strong>ly reported that bil<strong>in</strong>guals<strong>the</strong>mselves sometimes feel that language choice draws out, and drawsupon, different personalities. But, as Baker and Jones (1998) and Hamersand Blanc (2000) tell us, <strong>the</strong> evidence here is anecdotal at best. Indeed, wecould go a bit fur<strong>the</strong>r and po<strong>in</strong>t to <strong>the</strong> large logical and rationaldifficulties that some two-<strong>in</strong>-one arrangement would create. But, <strong>in</strong> a‘weaker’ sense, as it were, <strong>the</strong>re are certa<strong>in</strong>ly <strong>in</strong>dications that languagechoice may implicate different aspects of <strong>the</strong> personality. Bil<strong>in</strong>gualsrespond<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>in</strong>terviews and questionnaires are liable to give slightlydifferent pictures of <strong>the</strong>mselves, depend<strong>in</strong>g upon <strong>the</strong> language used.


Bil<strong>in</strong>gualism: A Very Brief Overview 245They may make different responses to objective or projective probes.Responses may be more emotional through one variety (typically, but not<strong>in</strong>evitably, <strong>the</strong>ir maternal language). They may more strongly affirm <strong>the</strong>irsense of ethnic identity <strong>in</strong> one language than <strong>in</strong> ano<strong>the</strong>r. And so on: see<strong>the</strong> various studies usefully summarized by Hamers and Blanc (2000).The fact that different social sett<strong>in</strong>gs and variations <strong>in</strong> language-emotionl<strong>in</strong>kages lead to different patterns of self-presentation does not logicallyimply separate personalities, but it does suggest an enhanced repertoireof possibility.People belong to many groups at once, and all groups all, at least,that have boundaries possess<strong>in</strong>g some degree of permanence havecharacteristics that mark <strong>the</strong>ir identity. Where language issues arecentral, <strong>the</strong> most salient group is often <strong>the</strong> ethnocultural community:overlaps of importance may occur because of simultaneous membership<strong>in</strong> gender, socioeconomic, educational, occupational and many o<strong>the</strong>rcategories, but <strong>the</strong> base here is an ethnic one. The <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g po<strong>in</strong>t, <strong>the</strong>n,is <strong>the</strong> significance of a bil<strong>in</strong>gualism that l<strong>in</strong>ks an <strong>in</strong>dividual to more thanone ethnocultural community. How does it feel, we might ask, to have afoot <strong>in</strong> more than one camp? Is it this that could lead to thatpsychological splitt<strong>in</strong>g that we have rejected on more purely cognitivegrounds? Or is such duality <strong>the</strong> orig<strong>in</strong> of <strong>the</strong> expanded acuity andawareness that some have claimed for bil<strong>in</strong>guals? The short answers to<strong>the</strong>se sorts of questions are all positive, or potentially positive, <strong>in</strong> a world<strong>in</strong> which complicated patterns of social relations are made still more<strong>in</strong>tricate by a very wide (<strong>the</strong>oretically <strong>in</strong>f<strong>in</strong>ite, <strong>in</strong> fact) range of l<strong>in</strong>guisticcapabilities.Of course, a great deal of bil<strong>in</strong>gualism has very little emotionalsignificance, imp<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>g only slightly upon feel<strong>in</strong>gs of identity or‘belong<strong>in</strong>g’. The purely <strong>in</strong>strumental fluencies needed to conduct simplebus<strong>in</strong>ess transactions, for <strong>in</strong>stance, do not represent a psychologicallyimportant excursion from one’s ethnic base camp. This is probably ara<strong>the</strong>r larger category than is often thought. For example, <strong>the</strong> breadth offluencies among that broad swa<strong>the</strong> of humanity that we have alreadylabelled as multil<strong>in</strong>gual does not <strong>in</strong> itself imply emotional or psychologicaldepth. It may, more simply, reflect <strong>the</strong> exigencies of a complicatedpublic life, with language capabilities developed only to <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>strumentalextent needed.In a typical example of multiple <strong>in</strong>strumental l<strong>in</strong>guistic abilities, wef<strong>in</strong>d a Mumbai spice merchant whose maternal variety is a Kathiawaridialect of Gujerati. At work, he usually speaks Kacchi; <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> marketplace he f<strong>in</strong>ds Marathi useful; at <strong>the</strong> railway station, H<strong>in</strong>di is usual.


246 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>English is <strong>the</strong> medium when he flies with Air India to New Delhi, and hesometimes watches English-language films at <strong>the</strong> c<strong>in</strong>ema. He reads aGujerati newspaper written <strong>in</strong> a dialect somewhat more ‘standard’ thanhis own. Our merchant sometimes has deal<strong>in</strong>gs with a Bengali colleaguewho rout<strong>in</strong>ely speaks both ‘high’ and ‘low’ Bengali a man whose‘primary’ wife speaks a dialect strongly marked as a female variant, andwhose ‘secondary’ wife normally speaks Urdu. His office managerspeaks Dhaki and his servants variously use Bhojpuri, Awadhi, Maithili,Ahiri and Chatgaya. This Bengali bus<strong>in</strong>essman has a cous<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong> Orissa, anOriya speaker married to a Tamil: <strong>the</strong>y use English at <strong>home</strong>, but <strong>the</strong>irchildren are more likely to speak Bengali; <strong>the</strong>y employ a H<strong>in</strong>dustan<strong>in</strong>urse and a Nepali watchman. I have drawn upon Pandit (1979) andPattanayak (1986) for <strong>the</strong>se examples; see some fur<strong>the</strong>r illustrations <strong>in</strong>D’Souza (2006).There are many bil<strong>in</strong>guals, however, whose competence is more deepseatedand whose abilities go beyond <strong>in</strong>strumentality, and <strong>the</strong>se aretypically <strong>the</strong> people one has <strong>in</strong> m<strong>in</strong>d when consider<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> relationshipbetween bil<strong>in</strong>gualism and identity. There are two broad divisions ofrelevance here: <strong>the</strong> first comprises those bil<strong>in</strong>guals with a k<strong>in</strong>shipattachment to each group (we will detour here around a large literature,and accept ei<strong>the</strong>r real or perceived attachments); <strong>the</strong> second is made upof people who have, <strong>in</strong> a more formal way, acquired ano<strong>the</strong>r l<strong>in</strong>guisticcitizenship, as it were. The latter division <strong>in</strong>volves a so-called ‘élitebil<strong>in</strong>gualism’, best exemplified by socially well-placed persons whoseformal <strong>in</strong>struction would traditionally have been seen as <strong>in</strong>completewithout <strong>the</strong> acquisition of ano<strong>the</strong>r language or two. Typically, <strong>the</strong>n, élitebil<strong>in</strong>gualism <strong>in</strong>volves prestigious languages, although <strong>the</strong> term couldreasonably be extended to cover <strong>the</strong> competence of those whose maternalvariety is of lesser-used status, as well as of those lucky, <strong>in</strong>telligentor <strong>in</strong>dustrious enough to have achieved upward mobility througheducation. 5 Élite bil<strong>in</strong>gualism is often discussed <strong>in</strong> comparison with‘folk bil<strong>in</strong>gualism’, where <strong>the</strong> latter signifies a necessity-<strong>in</strong>duced repertoireexpansion; <strong>in</strong>deed, <strong>the</strong> dist<strong>in</strong>ction seems apt, particularly when oneconsiders that, historically, <strong>the</strong> élite variety often had as much to do withsocial-status mark<strong>in</strong>g as it did with a thirst for knowledge and culturalboundary cross<strong>in</strong>g. In earlier times, not to have known Lat<strong>in</strong> or Greek orFrench <strong>in</strong> addition to one’s vernacular would have been unth<strong>in</strong>kable foreducated people, but unth<strong>in</strong>kable, perhaps, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> same way that itwould have been unth<strong>in</strong>kable not to have had servants. Among <strong>the</strong>members of this group, <strong>the</strong>re were (and are) many driven by purerscholastic motives, of course. But acknowledg<strong>in</strong>g this also means


Bil<strong>in</strong>gualism: A Very Brief Overview 247acknowledg<strong>in</strong>g that élite bil<strong>in</strong>gualism need not rule out <strong>the</strong> motives ofnecessity more usually associated with <strong>the</strong> folk variety. It is just thatnecessity itself becomes a little more rarefied, a little more <strong>in</strong>tellectual<strong>in</strong> nature.In any event, it is not difficult to see that <strong>the</strong> life’s work of a sensitivescholar could arise from, or give rise to, an extended group allegiance orsense of belong<strong>in</strong>g. Indeed, this scenario also <strong>the</strong>oretically applies tothose whose excursions across boundaries are motivated by noth<strong>in</strong>gmore than <strong>in</strong>terest. After all, given a threshold of <strong>in</strong>telligence andsensitivity, <strong>the</strong> difference between <strong>the</strong> scholar and <strong>the</strong> amateur lies <strong>in</strong>formality of focus. The general po<strong>in</strong>t here is that we can ally ourselves, bymore or less conscious effort, with ano<strong>the</strong>r group, and that a formallycultivated bil<strong>in</strong>gualism can act as <strong>the</strong> bridge here.What of <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r broad category, those bil<strong>in</strong>guals who have some realor understood blood attachment to more than one language community?Sett<strong>in</strong>g aside <strong>the</strong> technicalities associated with <strong>the</strong> onset and tim<strong>in</strong>g ofbil<strong>in</strong>gual acquisition, it is surely <strong>the</strong> case that <strong>the</strong> deeper <strong>the</strong> l<strong>in</strong>guisticand cultural burrow<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>to ano<strong>the</strong>r community, <strong>the</strong> greater <strong>the</strong> impactupon identity. This, <strong>in</strong> turn, suggests that those whose bil<strong>in</strong>gualcompetence is nurtured early will, o<strong>the</strong>r th<strong>in</strong>gs be<strong>in</strong>g equal, have afirmer foot <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> two (or more) camps. It will usually be <strong>the</strong> case, ofcourse, that one camp will have psychological and emotional primacy.But <strong>the</strong>re are some cases where <strong>home</strong> itself is difficult to establish, at least<strong>in</strong> any simple unidimensional sense some cases, that is, where bil<strong>in</strong>gualor multil<strong>in</strong>gual capacities, l<strong>in</strong>ked to <strong>the</strong>ir several cultural bases, developso early and so deeply that a primary allegiance is hard to discover.(Th<strong>in</strong>k of George Ste<strong>in</strong>er aga<strong>in</strong>, argu<strong>in</strong>g [1992: 128] that his sort of‘primary multil<strong>in</strong>gualism’ may be ‘an <strong>in</strong>tegral state of affairs, a caseradically on its own’.) There are generally two ways to consider <strong>the</strong>situations of those whose bil<strong>in</strong>gualism beg<strong>in</strong>s at <strong>the</strong> parental knees. Thefirst is simply that two or more base camps are <strong>home</strong> simultaneously;<strong>the</strong> second is that one primary <strong>home</strong> <strong>in</strong>deed exists, but it is constructed,<strong>in</strong> a manner unique to <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual, from materials taken from severalsources.As we move towards <strong>the</strong> bil<strong>in</strong>gualism of more ‘ord<strong>in</strong>ary’ <strong>in</strong>dividuals,we move more obviously towards <strong>the</strong> idea of a unitary identity wovenfrom several strands, to be sure, but <strong>in</strong>evitably <strong>in</strong>fluenced by onelanguage and culture more than by o<strong>the</strong>rs. But, if we move from <strong>the</strong>Ste<strong>in</strong>ers of <strong>the</strong> world, whose literary and l<strong>in</strong>guistic power, and <strong>the</strong> abilityto reflect <strong>in</strong> mean<strong>in</strong>gful ways upon its multifaceted orig<strong>in</strong>, is simplyunavailable to most people, we must not imag<strong>in</strong>e that we have moved


248 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>away from enlarged identities per se. It is both <strong>the</strong> obligation and <strong>the</strong>fulfillment of <strong>in</strong>tellectual life, after all, to express what those who are lessarticulate also feel. There is, of course, a great deal of circumstantialevidence support<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> contention that it is <strong>the</strong> identity components, <strong>the</strong>symbols of <strong>the</strong> tribe, that energize languages beyond <strong>the</strong>ir <strong>in</strong>strumentalexistences: obvious examples are <strong>the</strong> relationships between language andethnicity, and language and nationalism.At <strong>the</strong>se most potent levels of ‘groupness’, <strong>the</strong>re are clear dist<strong>in</strong>ctionsbetween monol<strong>in</strong>gual majority-group speakers <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir own ‘ma<strong>in</strong>stream’sett<strong>in</strong>gs, and m<strong>in</strong>ority-group members who are very oftenbil<strong>in</strong>gual by necessity (to take two extreme cases). For <strong>the</strong> former, <strong>the</strong><strong>in</strong>strumentality of language co<strong>in</strong>cides with its symbolic force, itsidentity-bear<strong>in</strong>g capacity: <strong>the</strong> language of shopp<strong>in</strong>g is also <strong>the</strong> languageof culture and tradition. For most people <strong>in</strong> this situation, <strong>the</strong> languageidentityl<strong>in</strong>kage is not problematic; <strong>in</strong>deed, it is seldom considered atall. M<strong>in</strong>ority-group speakers, however, rarely have <strong>the</strong> luxury of<strong>in</strong>attention. For <strong>the</strong>m, aspects of language and culture are often moreimmediate, and <strong>the</strong> crux of <strong>the</strong> matter is often a split between <strong>the</strong>language or languages that circumstances force <strong>the</strong>m to use, and <strong>the</strong>irmaternal, traditional or cultural variety. The upshot, <strong>the</strong>n, is thatbil<strong>in</strong>gualism and multil<strong>in</strong>gualism can throw matters of identity <strong>in</strong>tosharper relief, because of perceived threats to one (or more) languages.The result is that beyond <strong>the</strong> l<strong>in</strong>guistic technicalities, beyond variations<strong>in</strong> patterns of acquisition and development <strong>the</strong> most compell<strong>in</strong>g issuessurround<strong>in</strong>g bil<strong>in</strong>gualism are social and psychological. Beyond utilitarianand unemotional <strong>in</strong>strumentality, <strong>the</strong> heart of bil<strong>in</strong>gualism has to dowith identity and belong<strong>in</strong>g.Notes1. It is not <strong>in</strong>appropriate to add a fifth item to this list: sign<strong>in</strong>g. While manyrecent treatments of language and communication take <strong>the</strong> deaf community<strong>in</strong>to account, its status as a m<strong>in</strong>ority group is still often ignored. There nowexists, however, a significant ‘deaf culture’ described as a ‘healthysociological community’ by <strong>the</strong> Canadian Association of <strong>the</strong> Deaf, andits sister organizations around <strong>the</strong> world one that rejects <strong>the</strong> earlier andstill socially prevalent ‘medicalization of deafness’. Members of this culturereject such labels as ‘deficient’ or ‘disabled’ and, follow<strong>in</strong>g this logic, somealso reject medical <strong>in</strong>terventions aimed at reduc<strong>in</strong>g or elim<strong>in</strong>at<strong>in</strong>g deafness:attitudes towards cochlear implants are particularly polarized here.2. A notorious example here draws upon <strong>the</strong> dist<strong>in</strong>ction between <strong>the</strong> experiencesof anglophone Canadian pupils <strong>in</strong> all-French classrooms, and those ofSpanish-speak<strong>in</strong>g youngsters <strong>in</strong> English-medium classrooms <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> UnitedStates. See fur<strong>the</strong>r details <strong>in</strong> my discussion of ‘immersion’ and ‘submersion’.


Bil<strong>in</strong>gualism: A Very Brief Overview 2493. There have been those who demurred. In <strong>the</strong> 17th century, for <strong>in</strong>stance, JohnMilton (1644/1958) and Samuel Butler argued that expanded repertoires donot, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>mselves, imply <strong>in</strong>tellectual breadth. In 1662, <strong>in</strong> his unf<strong>in</strong>ished SatireUpon <strong>the</strong> Imperfection and Abuse of Human Learn<strong>in</strong>g, Butler po<strong>in</strong>ted out that ‘<strong>the</strong>more languages a man can speak/his talent has but sprung <strong>the</strong> greater leak’;see Butler (1850) and, for an early 19th-century rework<strong>in</strong>g of <strong>the</strong> idea,prefaced by some l<strong>in</strong>es from Butler’s poem, Hazlitt (1901).4. Wierzbicka (2005) is certa<strong>in</strong>ly not among <strong>the</strong> ‘strange’ crowd here, but shedoes illum<strong>in</strong>ate <strong>in</strong> very <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g ways <strong>the</strong> restrictions associated withmonol<strong>in</strong>gualism. She is particularly critical of <strong>the</strong>orists who write aboutlanguage, particularly about basic matters like language development and <strong>the</strong>relationship between language and thought. She takes P<strong>in</strong>ker (1994: 21) totask, for example, not<strong>in</strong>g that ‘his lack of cross-cultural and cross-l<strong>in</strong>guisticawareness underm<strong>in</strong>es <strong>the</strong> validity of [his] <strong>the</strong>oriz<strong>in</strong>g’.Elsewhere, Wierzbicka (2005: 9) says that P<strong>in</strong>ker ‘never looks at anylanguages o<strong>the</strong>r than English... all 517 works cited <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> references [to The<strong>Language</strong> Inst<strong>in</strong>ct] are <strong>in</strong> English’. Ste<strong>in</strong>er (1992: 127) had earlier argued for <strong>the</strong>study of languages ra<strong>the</strong>r than language, not<strong>in</strong>g that many contemporaryl<strong>in</strong>guists are hampered here because few of <strong>the</strong>m have ‘<strong>in</strong>habited <strong>the</strong> husk ofmore than one speech’. He cited <strong>the</strong> great Russian l<strong>in</strong>guist, Roman OsipovičJackobson: ‘Chomsky’s epigones often know only one language English and <strong>the</strong>y draw all <strong>the</strong>ir examples from it’ (Mehta, 1971: 79).5. It is important to realize that any dist<strong>in</strong>ction between ‘élite’ and ‘folk’bil<strong>in</strong>gualism cannot be mapped seamlessly onto some ‘school versus street’division. Immigrants very often learn <strong>the</strong>ir new language at school, but this isgenerally a matter of mundane necessity with noth<strong>in</strong>g élitist about it. It is not<strong>the</strong> classroom per se that accords élite status; see some fur<strong>the</strong>r comments <strong>in</strong>Edwards (<strong>in</strong> press-a).


Chapter 13Bil<strong>in</strong>gual EducationIntroductionIn bil<strong>in</strong>gual education, teach<strong>in</strong>g through two languages is a permanentor semi-permanent feature <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> classroom. Although such duality canarise for non-<strong>in</strong>strumental reasons, as part of a general educationalphilosophy one designed, for <strong>in</strong>stance, for those dest<strong>in</strong>ed to become‘élite’ bil<strong>in</strong>guals a more common scenario <strong>in</strong>volves need-drivenprograms of bil<strong>in</strong>gual education. It may be considered pedagogicallyimportant, for example, to provide at least early school<strong>in</strong>g through <strong>the</strong>medium of children’s first language (see also below). As well, if pupils’maternal languages are of m<strong>in</strong>ority status, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> desire to susta<strong>in</strong> andencourage those varieties, while also provid<strong>in</strong>g access to a ‘larger’medium, may also suggest bil<strong>in</strong>gual education. The idea here is usuallythat <strong>the</strong> basic educational foundations can be most firmly laid when <strong>the</strong>children’s ethnocultural identity is not jeopardized.Bil<strong>in</strong>gual education has a very long history <strong>in</strong>deed, but it is <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>relatively well-understood circumstances of Greek-Lat<strong>in</strong> bil<strong>in</strong>gualism(or diglossia) that we see <strong>the</strong> clearest foreshadow<strong>in</strong>g of circumstancesthat have rema<strong>in</strong>ed pert<strong>in</strong>ent ever s<strong>in</strong>ce. Lewis (1977) provided a briefsurvey, up to <strong>the</strong> time of <strong>the</strong> Renaissance, which rema<strong>in</strong>s useful. A morerecent treatment is that of Adams et al. (2002). Focus<strong>in</strong>g on <strong>the</strong> Romanage, Adams (2003) has produced a magisterial, if technically ra<strong>the</strong>rspecialized, account. (The term diglossia, <strong>in</strong>cidentally, is used to describea relatively endur<strong>in</strong>g relationship between two languages or dialects traditionally, ‘high’ and ‘low’ variants. Etymologically, of course, it issimply <strong>the</strong> Greek for ‘bil<strong>in</strong>gualism’.) Cicero, Qu<strong>in</strong>tilian and o<strong>the</strong>r Romanlum<strong>in</strong>aries preferred Greek to Lat<strong>in</strong> as <strong>the</strong> medium of school<strong>in</strong>g,pedagogy was generally modeled on Greek curricula, and formal<strong>in</strong>struction <strong>in</strong> Greek often preceded that <strong>in</strong> Lat<strong>in</strong>. S<strong>in</strong>ce children frompatrician <strong>home</strong>s were often cared for by Greek servants and tutors, <strong>the</strong>ywere frequently bil<strong>in</strong>gual before first go<strong>in</strong>g to school, anyway. Still,concerns were sometimes expressed about children speak<strong>in</strong>g Lat<strong>in</strong> withGreek <strong>in</strong>tonation and a precedent for more contemporary worries about <strong>the</strong> possibility of somehow over-burden<strong>in</strong>g a child’s time and250


Bil<strong>in</strong>gual Education 251‘limited’ cognitive capacity. Haarhoff (1920: 226) cites a scholar’scompla<strong>in</strong>t that bil<strong>in</strong>gual education may be all right for clever students,but schoolboys of average ability f<strong>in</strong>d it frustrat<strong>in</strong>g and exhaust<strong>in</strong>g.Many came to feel that <strong>the</strong> imposition of Greek condemned <strong>the</strong> young toboredom and drudgery.Act<strong>in</strong>g upon this po<strong>in</strong>t of view, however, took some considerable timeto develop. While <strong>the</strong> spread and <strong>in</strong>fluence of Lat<strong>in</strong> was a naturalconsequence of Roman imperial progress, Greek reta<strong>in</strong>ed a hardycultural prestige. The Greeks <strong>the</strong>mselves generally had a low op<strong>in</strong>ionof Lat<strong>in</strong>, only learn<strong>in</strong>g it for <strong>in</strong>strumental reasons an attitude that wasre<strong>in</strong>forced by <strong>the</strong> obvious <strong>in</strong>tellectual attractions <strong>the</strong>ir own languagecont<strong>in</strong>ued to hold for o<strong>the</strong>rs. In fact, <strong>the</strong> Romans <strong>the</strong>mselves accepted <strong>the</strong>social superiority of Greek for a long time after <strong>the</strong>y had dom<strong>in</strong>ated<strong>the</strong> hellenistic world. Of course, Lat<strong>in</strong> spread and ultimately producedmany lively offspr<strong>in</strong>g through which it cont<strong>in</strong>ues to live, but it isgenerally agreed that this happened without much formal plann<strong>in</strong>g.Lewis (1977: 179) notes that <strong>the</strong> Romans ‘made no effort to set up Lat<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>rivalry to [Greek] or to Lat<strong>in</strong>ize <strong>the</strong>ir political and military ga<strong>in</strong>s’. Theywere content, as some (but not all) subsequent empires have been, to let<strong>the</strong>ir military, mercantile and adm<strong>in</strong>istrative conquests carry Lat<strong>in</strong>throughout <strong>the</strong> empire.The Romans knew that, just as all roads led to <strong>the</strong> eternal city, so allcommerce led to Lat<strong>in</strong>. Indeed, <strong>in</strong> a clever piece of reverse psychology,<strong>the</strong>y sometimes erected barriers to <strong>the</strong>ir language, so that its acquisitionbecame ‘a privilege to be sought, like citizenship. The <strong>in</strong>habitants ofCumae [<strong>the</strong> <strong>home</strong> of <strong>the</strong> famous sibyl, near present-day Naples], for<strong>in</strong>stance, had to request permission to use Lat<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong> public affairs and <strong>in</strong><strong>the</strong> pursuit of trade’ (Lewis, 1977: 180). This laissez-faire approach to <strong>the</strong>irown language, coupled with a cont<strong>in</strong>u<strong>in</strong>g reverence for that of <strong>the</strong>Greeks whom <strong>the</strong>y had more or less completely subjugated by about 150BC, meant a bil<strong>in</strong>gualism that endured for a longer time than some mighthave predicted. As Lat<strong>in</strong> expanded its own literary and <strong>in</strong>tellectualscope, however, as it began to attract learners for o<strong>the</strong>r than purely<strong>in</strong>strumental purposes and as competent Greek teachers becameharder to f<strong>in</strong>d Lat<strong>in</strong>-Greek bil<strong>in</strong>gual education decl<strong>in</strong>ed. By <strong>the</strong> endof <strong>the</strong> 5th century it was virtually gone.In all contemporary examples of bil<strong>in</strong>gual education, <strong>the</strong>re arerecurr<strong>in</strong>g questions, many of <strong>the</strong>m discussed among Roman educators.When should bil<strong>in</strong>gual education be <strong>in</strong>troduced, and for how longshould it cont<strong>in</strong>ue? What <strong>in</strong>structional weight should be given to eachlanguage, and how best can formal dual-language education be


252 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong><strong>in</strong>tegrated with pre-exist<strong>in</strong>g and ‘non-bil<strong>in</strong>gual’ curricula? Shouldbil<strong>in</strong>gual education be available to (or, <strong>in</strong>deed, required of) all students or just <strong>the</strong> brighter ones? Should it be extended across a broad rangeof pupils, or designed pr<strong>in</strong>cipally for those whose mo<strong>the</strong>r tongue isa ‘m<strong>in</strong>ority’ one, or a variety that will not adequately serve <strong>in</strong> all areasof life?Varieties of Bil<strong>in</strong>gual EducationWhen a large number of possible student populations, <strong>in</strong> a largenumber of different sociocultural contexts, is comb<strong>in</strong>ed with variouseducational policies and desired educational outcomes, it is not difficultto understand <strong>the</strong> emergence of many types of bil<strong>in</strong>gual education. Infact, Mackey (1970) listed almost 100 categories and sub-categories; seealso Fishman’s approaches here, as summarized by García and Schiffman(2006). It is Baker’s (2006) typology that I shall draw upon here, however:it is easy to understand and quite comprehensive. 1 He lists 10 broadpossibilities, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g, for <strong>the</strong> sake of completeness, three non-bil<strong>in</strong>gualeducational sett<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>in</strong> which m<strong>in</strong>ority-group children have often found<strong>the</strong>mselves. Before we turn to <strong>the</strong>se, however, we should note that <strong>the</strong>most basic of ‘programs’ is no program at all: children are simply put<strong>in</strong>to exist<strong>in</strong>g ma<strong>in</strong>stream classrooms, and left to s<strong>in</strong>k or swim.Not swimm<strong>in</strong>g, but drown<strong>in</strong>gThe American sett<strong>in</strong>g is broadly <strong>in</strong>structive here. We f<strong>in</strong>d, first of all,that many leaders railed aga<strong>in</strong>st any departure from <strong>the</strong> traditionalma<strong>in</strong>stream classroom, a situation <strong>in</strong> which children must adapt to <strong>the</strong>school, while <strong>the</strong> latter rema<strong>in</strong>s essentially unchanged. Presidents fromTeddy Roosevelt to Ronald Reagan have argued for an Americanl<strong>in</strong>guistic and cultural crucible <strong>in</strong> which ‘dwellers <strong>in</strong> a polyglot board<strong>in</strong>ghouse’ emerge as unhyphenated, English-speak<strong>in</strong>g Americans, andaga<strong>in</strong>st any educational provisions ‘dedicated to preserv<strong>in</strong>g [immigrants’]native language and never gett<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>m adequate <strong>in</strong> English’. 2It may seem odd at first blush, but it is also easy to f<strong>in</strong>d similarsentiments among American immigrants <strong>the</strong>mselves: many members ofU.S. English, an organization dedicated to mak<strong>in</strong>g English <strong>the</strong> officiallanguage of <strong>the</strong> United States, are <strong>the</strong>mselves immigrants. This is oftennoted as evidence that <strong>the</strong> organization ought not to be seen as a narrow,chauv<strong>in</strong>istic and l<strong>in</strong>guistically <strong>in</strong>tolerant body but <strong>the</strong> psychology issurely <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g. I cannot delve deeper here, o<strong>the</strong>r than to po<strong>in</strong>t to oneor two possibilities. 3 It may be, for <strong>in</strong>stance, that immigrants who have


Bil<strong>in</strong>gual Education 253successfully re-established <strong>the</strong>mselves <strong>in</strong> a new society become morepatriotic than <strong>the</strong> natives; after all, <strong>the</strong>re is no true believer quite aszealous as <strong>the</strong> convert. They may, <strong>the</strong>n, evolve <strong>in</strong>to ardent proponents of<strong>the</strong> traditional American monol<strong>in</strong>gualism. An observation by <strong>the</strong> rightw<strong>in</strong>gcommentator Norman Podhoretz (1985) is <strong>in</strong>structive here, too: henotes that his ‘humiliat<strong>in</strong>g’ lack of English, <strong>in</strong> old-style submersionclassrooms, was a spur towards social mobility and success. His po<strong>in</strong>tmay be entirely accurate, of course, but it is also <strong>the</strong> case that success <strong>in</strong>adverse conditions sometimes tends to <strong>the</strong> ma<strong>in</strong>tenance of thoseconditions, not to <strong>the</strong>ir eradication. On <strong>the</strong> one hand, <strong>the</strong>re is often <strong>the</strong>feel<strong>in</strong>g that, if I had to struggle, why should th<strong>in</strong>gs be made easier foryou? On <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r, if I manage to progress per ardua ad astra, it may bevery much to my benefit to have my achievements rema<strong>in</strong> as s<strong>in</strong>gular aspossible. There is a glory <strong>in</strong> hav<strong>in</strong>g reached <strong>the</strong> peak by oneself, a glorythat will be diluted once <strong>the</strong> top of <strong>the</strong> mounta<strong>in</strong> is crowded. Consider, asanalogy, <strong>the</strong> woman who, by d<strong>in</strong>t of <strong>in</strong>credibly hard work and sacrifice,f<strong>in</strong>ally makes a place for herself <strong>in</strong> a prestigious law firm, previously anall-male bastion: is it <strong>in</strong>evitable that she will turn around and help someof her sisters up <strong>the</strong> ladder, or is it possible that she will pull <strong>the</strong> ladderup after her? (See also Chapter 6 particularly note 7.)In <strong>the</strong> contemporary American context, <strong>the</strong> s<strong>in</strong>gle most <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>gcase of an immigrant reject<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> bil<strong>in</strong>gual education enterprise is that ofRichard Rodriguez. In an <strong>in</strong>itial paper about his boyhood, he argues thatsupporters of bil<strong>in</strong>gual education imply today that students like memiss a great deal by not be<strong>in</strong>g taught <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir family’s language. What<strong>the</strong>y seem not to recognize is that, as a socially disadvantaged child,I regarded Spanish as a private language... what I needed to learn <strong>in</strong>school was that I had <strong>the</strong> right, and <strong>the</strong> obligation, to speak <strong>the</strong> publiclanguage. (Rodriguez, 1980a: 29; see also 1980b)Rodriguez admits that he would have felt less apprehensive if teachershad spoken to him <strong>in</strong> Spanish when he first entered <strong>the</strong> classroom but, <strong>in</strong>retrospect, feels that this would simply have delayed learn<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> ‘greatlesson of school: that I had a public identity’ (Rodriguez, 1980a: 30).In a biographical memoir, Rodriguez (1982) described a life <strong>in</strong>transition from <strong>the</strong> son of poor Mexican immigrants, to post-graduatestudy, to a successful career as a writer of elegant and thoughtful English.Learn<strong>in</strong>g English at school loosened his ties with parents and relativeswho rema<strong>in</strong>ed Spanish speak<strong>in</strong>g; or, as Rodriguez puts it, a growth <strong>in</strong>‘public <strong>in</strong>dividuality’ (via English) was associated with a dim<strong>in</strong>ished‘private <strong>in</strong>dividuality’ (through Spanish). But he also sensed <strong>the</strong> ‘deepest


254 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>truth’, that ‘<strong>in</strong>timacy is not created by a particular language; it is createdby <strong>in</strong>timates’ (p.32). This <strong>in</strong>sight, Rodriguez claimed, was lost on <strong>the</strong>‘bil<strong>in</strong>gualists’ (he refers to bil<strong>in</strong>gual educators). They ‘simplistically scorn<strong>the</strong> value and necessity of assimilation’ (p.26), <strong>the</strong>y are ‘filled withdecadent self-pity’, <strong>the</strong>y ‘romanticize public separateness’ (p.27). Well, itis easy to see why Rodriguez’s account ruffled fea<strong>the</strong>rs. It is also possibleto fault him for over-generaliz<strong>in</strong>g from a sample size of one. But hisaccount rema<strong>in</strong>s a provocative one.In a later book, Rodriguez (1993) cont<strong>in</strong>ues his personal exam<strong>in</strong>ationof life and culture <strong>in</strong> America. As <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> earlier work, his ‘f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>gs’ arenot to everyone’s taste. Sometimes, <strong>in</strong>deed, <strong>the</strong> expression is all, and <strong>the</strong>content is dubious: ‘European vocabularies do not have a silence richenough to describe <strong>the</strong> force with<strong>in</strong> Indian contemplation’ (Rodriguez,1993: 23). But consider <strong>the</strong> follow<strong>in</strong>g:There are <strong>in</strong>fluential educators today... who believe <strong>the</strong> purpose ofAmerican education is to <strong>in</strong>still <strong>in</strong> children a pride <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir ancestralpasts. Such a curtail<strong>in</strong>g of education seems to me condescend<strong>in</strong>g;seems to me <strong>the</strong> worst sort of missionary spirit... To argue for acommon culture is not to propose an exclusionary culture or a staticculture... Now <strong>the</strong> American university is dismantl<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> Americancanon <strong>in</strong> my name... Hispanics and Asians have become <strong>the</strong>convenient national excuse for <strong>the</strong> accomplishment of what Americahas always wanted done <strong>the</strong> sever<strong>in</strong>g of memory, <strong>the</strong> dismantlementof national culture. The end of history. (pp.169171)Among those critical of Rodriguez’s posture, Ortego y Gasca (1981)rem<strong>in</strong>ded him that, for many years, Mexican-American children were leftto ‘drift like flotsam’ <strong>in</strong> schools that made no accommodation for <strong>the</strong>irlack of English, with <strong>the</strong> well-documented result that Hispanic drop-outrates were gett<strong>in</strong>g on for three times <strong>the</strong> overall American average.Blanco (1983: 282) notes <strong>the</strong> irony that Rodriguez’s early loss of Spanishfluency was only remedied later: ‘<strong>in</strong> high school, he learned to read andwrite Spanish as an English speaker would. Rodriguez is a perfectexample of <strong>the</strong> American mentality that allows <strong>the</strong> squander<strong>in</strong>g ofvaluable l<strong>in</strong>guistic resources, only to try to recapture or create <strong>the</strong>mlater’. Kaplan (1983) makes ano<strong>the</strong>r useful po<strong>in</strong>t when he says that, whileRodriguez correctly draws attention to <strong>the</strong> political abuses and <strong>in</strong>adequaciesof bil<strong>in</strong>gual education, he misses its essential value. Of course,Kaplan (1983: 126) notes, <strong>the</strong> bil<strong>in</strong>gual education story is degraded bymany non-altruistic words and deeds, but <strong>the</strong>re is such a th<strong>in</strong>g as‘genu<strong>in</strong>e bil<strong>in</strong>gual education <strong>the</strong> dream that every child may have <strong>the</strong>


Bil<strong>in</strong>gual Education 255opportunity to ‘‘have’’ two languages or more’. So, <strong>in</strong> an area where <strong>the</strong>rehas been progress, where <strong>the</strong> demagogues have not had it all <strong>the</strong>ir ownway, Rodriguez’s writ<strong>in</strong>gs are a cruel cut <strong>in</strong>deed. With his personalexperience and his ‘power with words’, he might have helped <strong>the</strong> cause;<strong>in</strong>stead, <strong>in</strong> books that have attracted popular-press accolades, he hasdone just <strong>the</strong> opposite.Millions of immigrant cases demonstrate that old-style ‘submersion’works if, by ‘works’, we mean that it produces at least a m<strong>in</strong>imaldegree of fluency <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> ma<strong>in</strong>stream variety. It was not part of its<strong>in</strong>tention, of course, to bolster <strong>the</strong> languages that those to be submersedfirst br<strong>in</strong>g with <strong>the</strong>m to school. Despite <strong>the</strong> ra<strong>the</strong>r blustery manner ofsuccess stories like Podhoretz (who was not an immigrant himself, by <strong>the</strong>way, although his first language was Brooklyn Yiddish), we stronglysuspect that <strong>the</strong> psychological costs may have been high and, more to <strong>the</strong>po<strong>in</strong>t, unnecessary. Nunberg (1986) rightly po<strong>in</strong>ts out that l<strong>in</strong>guisticsubmersion was far from an ‘ennobl<strong>in</strong>g’ experience, and not anespecially efficient one, ei<strong>the</strong>r. Perhaps some sort of bil<strong>in</strong>gual provisionat school would have helped all those early immigrants to America, both<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir l<strong>in</strong>guistic progress and <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir psychological identity. But this, ofcourse, is to miss an important po<strong>in</strong>t, and one to which I shall return: formost of those who comment upon any form of language accommodation<strong>in</strong> official or semi-official sett<strong>in</strong>gs whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>y approve of it or not such accommodation is more political than pedagogical. Roosevelt,Reagan, Podhoretz and company have a vision (of America, <strong>in</strong> thiscase) of a l<strong>in</strong>guistically efficient and socially united country, a ‘nation’ <strong>in</strong>which one language is seen to <strong>in</strong>tegrate, and where more than one isconsidered both unnecessary and potentially balkaniz<strong>in</strong>g.To return to Baker and his typology: two of <strong>the</strong> three monol<strong>in</strong>gualcontexts that he lists are also ‘submersion’ <strong>in</strong> nature, but programs herediffer from <strong>the</strong> laissez-faire version (or non-version) that I have justdiscussed. Programs of so-called ‘structured immersion’ (still, <strong>in</strong> fact,submersion, as Baker po<strong>in</strong>ts out) enroll only m<strong>in</strong>ority-group children,sometimes mak<strong>in</strong>g ‘withdrawal’ or ‘pull-out’ provisions, by which <strong>the</strong>pupils are given extra, or compensatory, or specially designed ma<strong>in</strong>stream-languagelessons. The aim is clearly one of cultural assimilationand monol<strong>in</strong>gualism <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> ma<strong>in</strong>stream variety. The third monol<strong>in</strong>gualsett<strong>in</strong>g is a ‘segregationist’ one, <strong>in</strong> which m<strong>in</strong>ority-group students areforced to learn <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir maternal language. Baker’s discussion here treatsthis as a manifestation of apar<strong>the</strong>id policies through which <strong>the</strong> powerlessand <strong>the</strong> subord<strong>in</strong>ate are kept <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir subaltern positions.


256 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>Not drown<strong>in</strong>g, but swimm<strong>in</strong>g?Among <strong>the</strong> rema<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g (seven) educational contexts that Bakerdiscusses, three are listed as ‘weak’ forms of bil<strong>in</strong>gual education. Thereare, for <strong>in</strong>stance, ‘transitional’ programs, <strong>in</strong> which m<strong>in</strong>ority-groupspeakers are allowed <strong>in</strong>struction <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir maternal variety until <strong>the</strong>yare proficient enough <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> ma<strong>in</strong>stream language to move <strong>in</strong>to‘regular’ classrooms. This is a gentler alternative to s<strong>in</strong>k-or-swimsubmersion, but critics will po<strong>in</strong>t out that its aims are still essentiallyassimilative, and it is relatively unconcerned with <strong>the</strong> languages that<strong>the</strong> children first br<strong>in</strong>g with <strong>the</strong>m to school. In fact, it can be understoodas a sort of compensatory provision, to be phased out as early aspossible. Transitional programs have been <strong>the</strong> ma<strong>in</strong>stay of bil<strong>in</strong>gualeducation <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> United States, s<strong>in</strong>ce it was first federally mandated <strong>in</strong>1968, but <strong>the</strong>y are frequently found <strong>in</strong> some form or o<strong>the</strong>r <strong>in</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rsett<strong>in</strong>gs wherever, <strong>in</strong> fact, immigrant children come to school <strong>in</strong>liberal-democratic societies.A second form is ‘separatist’ education, a less violent manifestation ofapar<strong>the</strong>id. Although Baker states that <strong>the</strong> goal here is ‘limited bil<strong>in</strong>gualism’ which justifies his characterization of ‘separatist’ programs asweak bil<strong>in</strong>gual ones his brief discussion emphasizes first-languagemonol<strong>in</strong>gualism, and it would be more appropriate, <strong>the</strong>refore, to placesuch programs <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> monol<strong>in</strong>gual basket. Th<strong>in</strong>k of voluntarily selfsegregat<strong>in</strong>greligious groups (<strong>the</strong> Mennonites, <strong>the</strong> Old Order Amish, andso on) <strong>in</strong> which <strong>the</strong> ‘apartness’ is desired, and <strong>in</strong> which an endorsementof German (say) over English is a buttress to sociocultural isolation.A good argument could be made here that language practices dependupon <strong>the</strong> strength and degree <strong>the</strong> orthodoxy, perhaps of religious selfisolation;that is, <strong>in</strong> those societies whose borders are more permeablethan o<strong>the</strong>rs, we might expect to see educational provisions that do allowfor some ‘limited bil<strong>in</strong>gualism’. There is, of course, a very wide range ofpossibility here. I have just been read<strong>in</strong>g about some sub-groups with<strong>in</strong><strong>the</strong> larger Anabaptist tradition: some reject virtually all modern technology,some use trucks and vans but not cars (although <strong>the</strong>y may gladlyaccept lifts), some drive cars if <strong>the</strong>y are black, some allow electricity (butonly <strong>in</strong> emergencies), some use mach<strong>in</strong>es if <strong>the</strong>y run off batteries ra<strong>the</strong>rthan <strong>the</strong> ma<strong>in</strong>s, some will describe <strong>the</strong>mselves on websites so long aso<strong>the</strong>rs construct and ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>m, and so on. A bewilder<strong>in</strong>g variety,many of whose <strong>in</strong>tricacies are baffl<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>the</strong> outsider, and one that maybe reflected <strong>in</strong> many different educational thrusts.


Bil<strong>in</strong>gual Education 257The third format here is one with which many readers will be familiar:ma<strong>in</strong>stream classrooms with<strong>in</strong> which <strong>the</strong>re is some foreign-languageteach<strong>in</strong>g: <strong>the</strong> three-times-a-week language lesson from Mme Chiasson orHerr Schmidt or, if <strong>the</strong> school can’t quite run to native-speak<strong>in</strong>gteachers, perhaps Mrs Foyle and Mr Tanner do <strong>the</strong> honors, mak<strong>in</strong>g surealways to stay a lesson or two ahead of <strong>the</strong> pupils. These are <strong>the</strong> familiarprovisions made <strong>in</strong> many educational regimes for majority-group youngsters.Baker places this format <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> ‘weak’ division of bil<strong>in</strong>gualeducation, argu<strong>in</strong>g that <strong>the</strong> aim is, aga<strong>in</strong>, a ‘limited bil<strong>in</strong>gualism’.Many readers will no doubt agree that someth<strong>in</strong>g like ‘severely limited’or perhaps ‘crippled’ bil<strong>in</strong>gualism would be nearer <strong>the</strong> mark, consider<strong>in</strong>gthat 8 or 10 years of school French may enable you to rhyme off <strong>the</strong>pluperfect subjunctive of some irregular verb, but won’t allow you toorder a croque-monsieur and a Kronenbourg at <strong>the</strong> Brasserie Lipp.The four ‘strong’ varieties of bil<strong>in</strong>gual education listed by Baker areunited <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir aim of encourag<strong>in</strong>g bil<strong>in</strong>gualism. In ‘dual-language’programs (obviously not a uniquely dist<strong>in</strong>ctive description), bothm<strong>in</strong>ority- and majority-group children are <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> same classroom, andboth languages are used. Well-known examples <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> United States are<strong>the</strong> Spanish-English arrangements first <strong>in</strong>troduced <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> early 1960s <strong>in</strong>sou<strong>the</strong>rn Florida. There are a great many variants under <strong>the</strong> duallanguagerubric: <strong>the</strong> most important variables are <strong>the</strong> amount of timegiven to each language, and <strong>the</strong> tim<strong>in</strong>g of each (by subject, on alternatedays, etc.). A second strong form is ‘heritage-language ma<strong>in</strong>tenance’education, designed for m<strong>in</strong>ority-group speakers. Here, <strong>the</strong> nativelanguage is used <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> classroom, while <strong>the</strong> ma<strong>in</strong>stream variety isgradually developed. A third is <strong>the</strong> ‘ma<strong>in</strong>stream bil<strong>in</strong>gual’ provision, <strong>in</strong>which majority-group children learn <strong>in</strong> two (sometimes more) ‘big’languages. As Baker notes, classic examples here are found <strong>in</strong> socialcontexts (like S<strong>in</strong>gapore and Luxembourg) <strong>in</strong> which <strong>the</strong> general populationis bi- or multil<strong>in</strong>gual, and <strong>in</strong> various types of ‘European’ or‘International’ schools cater<strong>in</strong>g for socially or educationally élite parentswho want <strong>the</strong>ir children to become bil<strong>in</strong>gual.The f<strong>in</strong>al ‘strong’ form is ‘immersion’ education, <strong>in</strong> which majoritygroupchildren learn through a foreign language. The term was firstapplied to anglophone children <strong>in</strong> Montreal learn<strong>in</strong>g through French,but what was an educational experiment <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> 1960s has spreadthroughout Canada, and beyond. Putt<strong>in</strong>g English-speak<strong>in</strong>g children <strong>in</strong>French-only classrooms <strong>in</strong> Canada is not <strong>the</strong> same th<strong>in</strong>g as plac<strong>in</strong>gSpanish-speak<strong>in</strong>g children <strong>in</strong> English-only schools <strong>in</strong> America. Why?Most importantly, while Spanish is of m<strong>in</strong>ority status and, consequently,


258 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>under ongo<strong>in</strong>g threat <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> American ma<strong>in</strong>stream, <strong>the</strong> English of <strong>the</strong>Canadian students is not at any such risk. ‘Immersion’, <strong>the</strong>n, suggeststhat one is dipped <strong>in</strong>to a new l<strong>in</strong>guistic pool, but comes to <strong>the</strong> surfaceaga<strong>in</strong> with orig<strong>in</strong>al capacities still <strong>in</strong>tact. (‘Submersion’, as alreadyimplied, means that someth<strong>in</strong>g orig<strong>in</strong>al is be<strong>in</strong>g drowned and lost.)Beyond a desirable emphasis upon <strong>the</strong> production and subsequentencouragement of an ongo<strong>in</strong>g bil<strong>in</strong>gualism (and, <strong>in</strong>deed, biculturalism),Canadian-style immersion programs profit from be<strong>in</strong>g voluntary, andfrom hav<strong>in</strong>g committed and well-tra<strong>in</strong>ed teachers who are <strong>the</strong>mselvesbil<strong>in</strong>gual. These are not features of submersion education.The Effectiveness of Bil<strong>in</strong>gual EducationThere was, and is, great <strong>in</strong>terest <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> effectiveness of programs ofbil<strong>in</strong>gual education. Is <strong>the</strong>re a best model? Are some programs clearlymore effective than o<strong>the</strong>rs? The assessments by Crawford (1989, 1992a,2000) and Dicker (2003) provide many useful details on (American)bil<strong>in</strong>gual education. The authors are clearly <strong>in</strong> favor of ‘strong’ programs,and concerned to protect <strong>the</strong>m aga<strong>in</strong>st unfriendly legislation and <strong>the</strong>assaults by <strong>the</strong> U.S. English organization. The many statements andpapers reproduced <strong>in</strong> Crawford’s (1992b) collection will also be foundvery useful. The recent surveys by Petrovic (2005), San Miguel (2004)and Wiese and Garcia (2001) emphasize historical developments <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>American context, and Ferguson (2006) provides an overview from aEuropean perspective. For more global overviews, Baker (2006) andBaker and Jones (1998) are central sources, of course.It is worth say<strong>in</strong>g straight away that many questions about bil<strong>in</strong>gualeducation aims and outcomes are understandable but naïve: <strong>the</strong>re areso many categories, so many variations <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> populations catered for, somany different social contexts, so many ways of attempt<strong>in</strong>g to measureeffectiveness. Even committed commentators have sometimes wonderedif ‘prolonged reliance on <strong>the</strong> native tongue reduces students’ <strong>in</strong>centivesto learn English’ (any o<strong>the</strong>r ‘ma<strong>in</strong>stream’ language could, of course, besubstituted here), or if bil<strong>in</strong>gual learn<strong>in</strong>g ‘confuses <strong>the</strong> m<strong>in</strong>d and retardsschool achievement’ (Crawford, 1989: 86). There is, too, an apparentlycounter-<strong>in</strong>tuitive aspect here, at least for those who subscribe to <strong>the</strong>efficacy of <strong>the</strong> ‘time-on-task’ pr<strong>in</strong>ciple that is, <strong>the</strong> idea that <strong>the</strong> bestpredictor of success <strong>in</strong> learn<strong>in</strong>g is <strong>the</strong> amount of time devoted to <strong>the</strong>subject. Most of <strong>the</strong> em<strong>in</strong>ent opponents of bil<strong>in</strong>gual education represented<strong>in</strong> Imhoff’s (1990) anthology, for example, could not be broughtto understand that circumstances can easily undercut this pr<strong>in</strong>ciple.


Bil<strong>in</strong>gual Education 259O<strong>the</strong>rs may f<strong>in</strong>d it confus<strong>in</strong>g, too: I note that, <strong>in</strong> his recent account ofrais<strong>in</strong>g his own three children bil<strong>in</strong>gually, Caldas’s (2006) commentsabout time-on-task suggest a confound<strong>in</strong>g of immersion and submersionlearn<strong>in</strong>g contexts. (In fact, research suggests that, contrary to simplistictime-on-task conceptions, positive transfer can occur; as Yeung et al.[2000: 1005] po<strong>in</strong>t out <strong>in</strong> a defence of early education <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> mo<strong>the</strong>rtongue, ‘skills <strong>in</strong> a second language may be developed on <strong>the</strong> basis ofskills already acquired <strong>in</strong> [<strong>the</strong>] first’.)The ambiguities surround<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> effects of bil<strong>in</strong>gualism itself (as notedby McLaughl<strong>in</strong>, 1978; see also above) are, if anyth<strong>in</strong>g, multiplied <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>educational context. Thus, Wiley and Wright (2004) have recently po<strong>in</strong>tedout that, among a multitude of evaluation studies, one can easily f<strong>in</strong>dsome research support for almost any critical position on educationaleffectiveness; see also Paulston’s observation, <strong>in</strong> Chapter 12. Baker (2006:267) notes thatall programs could be effective... depend<strong>in</strong>g on <strong>the</strong> subtle chemistryof <strong>in</strong>teract<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>gredients, environments and processes. Attempts toprove <strong>the</strong> superiority of a particular model are po<strong>in</strong>tless andunproductive.As I shall illustrate fur<strong>the</strong>r, <strong>the</strong> whole area is highly politicized, andmany agendas are driven by sociopolitical considerations and sympathies,not solely by pedagogical ones. Hakuta (1991: 210) has writtenabout ‘be<strong>in</strong>g very doubtful that evaluation research <strong>in</strong> bil<strong>in</strong>gual educationwill ever emerge out of <strong>the</strong> stranglehold of political forces’, andTannen (1998) has suggested that discussions of many controversialmatters have become so politically and socially polarized that resolutionsometimes seems impossible.In a related po<strong>in</strong>t, those engaged <strong>in</strong> research exercises are rarelyneutral, even by <strong>the</strong> general standards of social science. Indeed, Baker(2006: 287) notes that experimenters’ hypo<strong>the</strong>ses often ‘hide <strong>the</strong>irexpectations’ a ra<strong>the</strong>r more po<strong>in</strong>ted criticism (see also Hakuta, 2002).For such reasons, those <strong>in</strong>terested <strong>in</strong> assessments of bil<strong>in</strong>gual educationhave <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>gly turned to so-called ‘meta-analyses’, <strong>in</strong>vestigations thatsimultaneously consider <strong>the</strong> methods and f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>gs of numerous <strong>in</strong>dividualstudies, look<strong>in</strong>g for strengths and weaknesses, plausible generalitiesand unlikely assertions. It is both <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g (at least) and worry<strong>in</strong>g that<strong>the</strong> orig<strong>in</strong>al studies, adequately conducted to be suitable <strong>in</strong>put for <strong>the</strong>segrander meta-analyses, form a laughably small percentage of <strong>the</strong> total. Inone large-scale re-exam<strong>in</strong>ation, only 8 out of 175 evaluation exerciseswere judged relatively unflawed; <strong>in</strong> ano<strong>the</strong>r, 18 out of 600 reports were


260 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>considered ‘methodologically sound and deserv<strong>in</strong>g of fur<strong>the</strong>r exam<strong>in</strong>ation’;<strong>in</strong> a third, 7 out of about 150 reports ‘met m<strong>in</strong>imal criteria’; and soon (Lam, 1992: 184). And meta-analyses <strong>the</strong>mselves are hardly immunefrom attack. Baker’s discussion of this very contentious territory revealshow biblical (or byzant<strong>in</strong>e) <strong>the</strong> possibilities for analysis and <strong>in</strong>terpretationhave become. Referr<strong>in</strong>g, for <strong>in</strong>stance, to a 500-page report producedby a panel of experts on bil<strong>in</strong>gual education, he notes that its f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>gswere immediately seized upon ‘by opponents and proponents ofbil<strong>in</strong>gual education as justification of <strong>the</strong>ir quite different positions’(Baker, 2006: 268). Bil<strong>in</strong>gual education has, <strong>in</strong> truth, become a largegrowth <strong>in</strong>dustry, and <strong>in</strong> its mach<strong>in</strong>ations its ‘customers’ often seem quiteforgotten.Can any generalities be extracted from research f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>gs, not just thosearis<strong>in</strong>g from highly politicized American programs of bil<strong>in</strong>gual education,but also from <strong>the</strong> many variants elsewhere? For ‘ma<strong>in</strong>stream’children learn<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> immersion classrooms anglophone youngsterslearn<strong>in</strong>g through French <strong>in</strong> Montreal, for example <strong>the</strong> evidencesuggests that <strong>the</strong>ir bil<strong>in</strong>gualism will be much deeper and broader thanthat acquired by <strong>the</strong>ir counterparts <strong>in</strong> more traditional sett<strong>in</strong>gs. At <strong>the</strong>same time, <strong>the</strong>re is no reason to suspect that <strong>the</strong>re is any retard<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>fluence upon <strong>the</strong>ir English skills, or upon <strong>the</strong>ir grasp of subject matterpresented <strong>in</strong> a language that is not <strong>the</strong>ir first. Understandably enough,<strong>the</strong>re may be some temporary ‘delays’ <strong>in</strong> some areas, but <strong>the</strong>se typicallydisappear (<strong>in</strong> comparisons with non-immersion children) quite quickly.There seems little question, <strong>in</strong> fact, that immersion programs are <strong>the</strong> bestoption for ma<strong>in</strong>stream children wish<strong>in</strong>g to become bil<strong>in</strong>gual throughschool<strong>in</strong>g. Canadian parents have <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>gly understood that, which iswhy even at a time when bil<strong>in</strong>gualism-as-federal-policy has comeunder <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>g stra<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest <strong>in</strong> immersion has <strong>in</strong>creased.The picture is not perfect, however. It is not true, for example, thatimmersion graduates have a native-like comprehension of <strong>the</strong>ir secondlanguage. Indeed, <strong>the</strong> French produced by Canadian immersion studentshas been variously described as ‘somewhat artificial’ or ‘Frenglish’ or‘fossilized <strong>in</strong>terlanguage’ (see Edwards, 1994a). And, at a broader sociallevel, immersion education has not proved to be <strong>the</strong> hoped-for catalyst tobr<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> two Canadian l<strong>in</strong>guistic communities closer toge<strong>the</strong>r. Morespecifically, Genesee (1981) notes that some of <strong>the</strong> expected behavioraldifferences between immersion students and those <strong>in</strong>volved <strong>in</strong> moretraditional second-language learn<strong>in</strong>g at school have proved ra<strong>the</strong>r slight.Despite <strong>the</strong>ir technical superiority, <strong>the</strong> former do little read<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>irsecond variety and, like <strong>the</strong> latter, report <strong>in</strong>strumental ra<strong>the</strong>r than


Bil<strong>in</strong>gual Education 261<strong>in</strong>tegrative reasons for learn<strong>in</strong>g it. Although more likely to use moreFrench <strong>in</strong> personal encounters, immersion pupils tend to do no morethan <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs to seek out or <strong>in</strong>itiate such encounters. (It is true, ofcourse, that immersion students <strong>in</strong> many contexts will not have a greatdeal of opportunity to use <strong>the</strong>ir acquired fluency; this hardly applies <strong>in</strong>Montreal, however, <strong>the</strong> sett<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> which Genesee reports.) This onlyre<strong>in</strong>forces <strong>the</strong> observation that schools even immersion schools areunlikely <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>mselves to promote societal bil<strong>in</strong>gualism; see Mackey(1981) and our earlier discussions.If we turn now to m<strong>in</strong>ority-group children, more <strong>the</strong> focus <strong>in</strong> this bookthan are ‘ma<strong>in</strong>stream’ pupils, it seems safe to say that early education <strong>in</strong><strong>the</strong> mo<strong>the</strong>r tongue is beneficial; see also Hakuta (1991) for a usefultabular presentation of ‘research conclusions’, a list that he uses whenspeak<strong>in</strong>g to groups about bil<strong>in</strong>gual education. This is a bald statement,to be sure, and will require all sorts of qualification accord<strong>in</strong>g tocircumstance and context. But a moment’s reflection will suggest thatan own-language alternative to a brutal s<strong>in</strong>k-or-swim scenario must havea lot to recommend it, if only <strong>in</strong> terms of an <strong>in</strong>crease <strong>in</strong> psychologicalcomfort and a decrease <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> distress related to lack of understand<strong>in</strong>g.These less tangible, less measurable elements are often left out of allthose research studies and ‘meta-analyses’: <strong>the</strong>y are naturally concernedwith what can be ma<strong>the</strong>matically assessed, but a tunnel vision can easilydevelop <strong>in</strong> which more qualitative aspects are <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>gly ignoredaltoge<strong>the</strong>r. I don’t mean to imply, of course, that ‘quantitative’ researchersare <strong>the</strong>mselves unaware that important matters rema<strong>in</strong> out of <strong>the</strong>reach of <strong>the</strong>ir statistical nets, only that neglect can produce <strong>the</strong> sameeffects as ignorance. An <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g social-science development here hasbeen to try and ref<strong>in</strong>e those nets, and make <strong>the</strong>m capable of catch<strong>in</strong>gth<strong>in</strong>gs like self-esteem, happ<strong>in</strong>ess, security and so on. We are <strong>the</strong>nconfronted with <strong>the</strong> ludicrous spectacle of <strong>the</strong> ‘operationalization’ ofsuch <strong>in</strong>tangibles with <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>evitable result that whatever is measured <strong>in</strong><strong>the</strong>ir name is but a simulacrum (<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> true sense of <strong>the</strong> word: a copywithout an orig<strong>in</strong>al).An emphasis upon results is necessarily an emphasis upon <strong>the</strong>future if we do such-and-such now, what will <strong>the</strong> effect be later?While this is em<strong>in</strong>ently reasonable, it does ra<strong>the</strong>r neglect th<strong>in</strong>gs thatmay be desirable <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>mselves. I have already asked if we wouldremove sw<strong>in</strong>gs and roundabouts from <strong>the</strong> playground if def<strong>in</strong>itivestudies revealed that <strong>the</strong>y had no measurable effect on post-primaryacademic achievement.


262 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>Transition and ma<strong>in</strong>tenanceMany of <strong>the</strong> questions surround<strong>in</strong>g bil<strong>in</strong>gual provisions for m<strong>in</strong>oritygroupchildren deal essentially with programs that are ei<strong>the</strong>r transitionalor ma<strong>in</strong>tenance <strong>in</strong> nature. As we have already seen, supporters of bothvarieties hope to ease <strong>the</strong> earliest passage of children from <strong>home</strong> toschool, and <strong>the</strong>reby defuse some educational difficulties. They allsubscribe to <strong>the</strong> famous UNESCO (1953: 11) dictum that holds that ‘itis axiomatic that <strong>the</strong> best medium for teach<strong>in</strong>g a child is his mo<strong>the</strong>rtongue’.We should note that <strong>the</strong>re have been dissent<strong>in</strong>g views. Gupta (1997)po<strong>in</strong>ts out that, <strong>in</strong> some multil<strong>in</strong>gual sett<strong>in</strong>gs, it can be difficult todeterm<strong>in</strong>e <strong>the</strong> mo<strong>the</strong>r tongue (recall <strong>the</strong> simultaneously tril<strong>in</strong>gual GeorgeSte<strong>in</strong>er here). In contexts of dialect variation, it may be that <strong>the</strong> ‘mo<strong>the</strong>rtongue’ to be used <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> classroom will be perhaps has to be astandard form quite unlike <strong>the</strong> nonstandard variants of <strong>the</strong> pupils and, <strong>in</strong>heterogeneous sett<strong>in</strong>gs, mo<strong>the</strong>r tongue education may mean separateprograms for different ethnic groups, a potentially divisive and undesirablesituation. D’Souza’s (2006) discussion of <strong>the</strong> very complex Indiansituation is also <strong>in</strong>structive here. Apart from echo<strong>in</strong>g Gupta’s po<strong>in</strong>t about<strong>the</strong> very determ<strong>in</strong>ation of a mo<strong>the</strong>r tongue what is <strong>the</strong> mo<strong>the</strong>r tongue,she asks, for children who have no <strong>home</strong>, and who are forced to learn <strong>the</strong>language(s) of <strong>the</strong> streets? D’Souza notes that <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>structional mediummust often be <strong>the</strong> dom<strong>in</strong>ant language <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> state. Wee (2002: 285286)has discussed <strong>the</strong> issue as it affects people <strong>in</strong> S<strong>in</strong>gapore; he writes, forexample, that ‘it is entirely possible for some Ch<strong>in</strong>ese S<strong>in</strong>gaporeans toagree that Mandar<strong>in</strong>... is <strong>the</strong>ir mo<strong>the</strong>r tongue, but at <strong>the</strong> same time to beunwill<strong>in</strong>g to consider <strong>the</strong>mselves native speakers of Mandar<strong>in</strong>’.Even Phillipson (1992), whose career has been devoted to uncover<strong>in</strong>ga l<strong>in</strong>guistic ‘imperialism’ and ‘l<strong>in</strong>guicism’ that serves <strong>the</strong> ‘large’languages of <strong>the</strong> world at <strong>the</strong> expense of <strong>the</strong> ‘small’ ones, has feltobliged to record that not provid<strong>in</strong>g English-medium education toAfrican-language-speak<strong>in</strong>g children was <strong>in</strong>terpreted locally as a colonialistdesire to ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong> groups <strong>in</strong> subord<strong>in</strong>ate positions. (To ignore<strong>in</strong>digenous languages altoge<strong>the</strong>r can be equally <strong>in</strong>sensitive, of course.)We have already seen here how parents <strong>the</strong>mselves may reject maternallanguageeducation for <strong>the</strong>ir children. Sometimes this is based on a moreor less accurate assessment of <strong>the</strong> relative worth of compet<strong>in</strong>g varieties,and sometimes it reflects a regrettable ignorance of <strong>the</strong> possibilities<strong>in</strong>herent <strong>in</strong> some sort of bil<strong>in</strong>gual program; <strong>in</strong> all decisions, however,we must acknowledge that <strong>the</strong> children’s best <strong>in</strong>terests are uppermost


Bil<strong>in</strong>gual Education 263<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> m<strong>in</strong>ds of <strong>the</strong>ir parents. Baker (2006) touches upon <strong>the</strong> matter, too,referr<strong>in</strong>g to research with <strong>in</strong>digenous populations <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Americansouthwest. And an observation by Spolsky (1989b: 451) also <strong>in</strong> asouthwestern context rem<strong>in</strong>ds us that many ‘ord<strong>in</strong>ary’ people haveissues to deal with that are ra<strong>the</strong>r more immediate than language choice:A Navajo student of m<strong>in</strong>e once put <strong>the</strong> problem quite starkly: ifI have to choose, she said, between liv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> a hogan a mile from <strong>the</strong>nearest water where my son will grow up speak<strong>in</strong>g Navajo, ormov<strong>in</strong>g to a house <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> city with <strong>in</strong>door plumb<strong>in</strong>g where he willspeak English with <strong>the</strong> neighbors, I’ll pick English and a bathroom!These sorts of issues complicate <strong>the</strong> l<strong>in</strong>guistic picture <strong>in</strong> very realways. Interest<strong>in</strong>gly enough, <strong>the</strong>y all have consequences for children and<strong>the</strong>ir communities at a group level, ones that <strong>in</strong>volve, but also go beyond,purely pedagogical matters affect<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>dividual youngsters.To return to <strong>the</strong> dist<strong>in</strong>ction: <strong>the</strong>re are, of course, ideological differencesbetween those who support transitional bil<strong>in</strong>gual education and thosewho argue for ma<strong>in</strong>tenance programs. The first group believes that <strong>the</strong>real aim to be achieved as soon as is reasonable is a transition from<strong>the</strong> bil<strong>in</strong>gual classroom to <strong>the</strong> ma<strong>in</strong>stream one. The second envisagesprograms that contribute to a more endur<strong>in</strong>g bil<strong>in</strong>gualism, ones whoseobjective is <strong>the</strong> expansion of <strong>the</strong> l<strong>in</strong>guistic repertoire, not <strong>the</strong> replacementof one monol<strong>in</strong>gualism by ano<strong>the</strong>r. The transitional-ma<strong>in</strong>tenance dichotomyis not always clear, however, <strong>the</strong> result be<strong>in</strong>g a fur<strong>the</strong>r sub-literaturedevoted to <strong>the</strong> tim<strong>in</strong>g of bil<strong>in</strong>gual education provisions. With<strong>in</strong> transitionalprograms, Baker (2006) po<strong>in</strong>ts out, <strong>the</strong>re are ‘early-exit’ and ‘lateexit’options: <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> former, two years is <strong>the</strong> allotted time for bil<strong>in</strong>gualeducation; <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> latter, passage to <strong>the</strong> ‘ord<strong>in</strong>ary’ classroom can bedelayed for ano<strong>the</strong>r three or four years. In some circumstances, however,a bil<strong>in</strong>gual program that lasted until children were near<strong>in</strong>g or at <strong>the</strong> endof primary school might be styled ‘ma<strong>in</strong>tenance’. Under <strong>the</strong> essentiallycompensatory provisions of federally funded bil<strong>in</strong>gual education <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>USA, <strong>the</strong> tendency has clearly been to effect a transition as soon aspossible, but it is often found elsewhere, too: ‘where <strong>the</strong>re is a majoritylanguage and much immigration, <strong>the</strong>n education is often expected toprovide a l<strong>in</strong>guistic and cultural transition’ (Baker, 2006: 222).Jim Cumm<strong>in</strong>s is one of <strong>the</strong> best-known specialists <strong>in</strong> bil<strong>in</strong>gualism andbil<strong>in</strong>gual education (and someone I have known for a very long time),and I well remember a conversation I had with him many years ago, aconversation that revealed some misapprehensions (on my part) fuelledby <strong>the</strong> transitional-ma<strong>in</strong>tenance dist<strong>in</strong>ction. S<strong>in</strong>ce <strong>the</strong> 1980s, my own


264 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>writ<strong>in</strong>gs had supported bil<strong>in</strong>gual education provisions, but I argued fora transitional approach, on two related grounds. The available evidenceseemed to suggest that transition to <strong>the</strong> ma<strong>in</strong>stream was not alwaysnecessary for <strong>the</strong> gradual development of literacy <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> ma<strong>in</strong>streamlanguage, not that transition itself need be harmful. So, given <strong>the</strong>exigencies of limited resources and funds and, more importantly, <strong>the</strong>possibilities for that ethnic ‘separateness’ that Gupta (1997) has po<strong>in</strong>tedto I felt that an argument might be made, perhaps on <strong>the</strong> basis of adesirable social cohesion, for br<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>g all children under <strong>the</strong> onescholastic roof at some po<strong>in</strong>t. This went down ra<strong>the</strong>r badly with someof my academic colleagues, most of whom supported a cont<strong>in</strong>u<strong>in</strong>gpluralism, <strong>in</strong> which bil<strong>in</strong>gual education ma<strong>in</strong>tenance bil<strong>in</strong>gual education,that is was seen to have an important l<strong>in</strong>guistic and cultural partto play. Transitional programs were considered as cultural fifth columns.Then I discovered, through my discussions with Cumm<strong>in</strong>s, that whatI was advocat<strong>in</strong>g as transition was, <strong>in</strong> fact, what most of my colleaguesconsidered ma<strong>in</strong>tenance. That is, I had always rejected any facile ‘earlyexit’arrangements, always argued that m<strong>in</strong>ority-language-speak<strong>in</strong>gchildren should be given all <strong>the</strong> appropriate help possible (see, e.g.Edwards, 1984, 1990). On <strong>the</strong> basis of practical matters hav<strong>in</strong>g to do withresources, fairness across groups and so on, I didn’t th<strong>in</strong>k that bil<strong>in</strong>gualeducation could be justified for a more or less <strong>in</strong>def<strong>in</strong>ite term. But nei<strong>the</strong>rdid <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs!I felt a bit like M. Jourda<strong>in</strong>, Molière’s bourgeois gentilhomme, whoexcitedly discovers that he has speak<strong>in</strong>g prose all his life.Bil<strong>in</strong>gual Education <strong>in</strong> America: In Transit to TroubleThe American Bil<strong>in</strong>gual Education Act (1968) was largely compensatoryand transitional <strong>in</strong> tone and <strong>in</strong>tent. As Venezky (1981: 201) noted, <strong>the</strong> goalwas not ‘cultural retention, encouragement of a pluralistic society, orimprovement of native languages’. Now, if a transitional <strong>in</strong>tent is <strong>the</strong>official mandate, but a ma<strong>in</strong>tenance-program preference animates manyof those <strong>in</strong>volved, most of <strong>the</strong> academic commentators, and some of <strong>the</strong>assessors, <strong>the</strong>n we can see that, quite apart from <strong>the</strong> technical problemsof evaluation, profound philosophical differences will also bedevilaccurate assessments of program effectiveness. Although <strong>the</strong> emphasis<strong>in</strong> this section is upon <strong>the</strong> richly documented and very illustrativeAmerican sett<strong>in</strong>g, it is clear with ano<strong>the</strong>r reference to Baker’sobservation, above that such ideological variation can be expected toconfound dispassionate <strong>in</strong>vestigation well beyond American shores.


Bil<strong>in</strong>gual Education 265Amendments to, and reauthorizations of, <strong>the</strong> American bil<strong>in</strong>gualthrust (<strong>in</strong> 1974, 1978, 1984, 1988 and 1994) have all occasioned fur<strong>the</strong>rdebate about what <strong>the</strong> overall purposes were, what <strong>the</strong>y are and what<strong>the</strong>y should be. The most po<strong>in</strong>ted debates have been about how muchtime and energy should be devoted to <strong>the</strong> language that children firstbr<strong>in</strong>g with <strong>the</strong>m to school. The tendency over <strong>the</strong> last 40 years has beento <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>gly restrict any ‘ma<strong>in</strong>tenance’ tendencies, and to support <strong>the</strong>maternal language ‘only to <strong>the</strong> extent necessary for a child to achievecompetence <strong>in</strong> English’ (Baker, 2006: 193; see also Venezky, 1981, on <strong>the</strong>ever-narrow<strong>in</strong>g focus). In fact, <strong>in</strong> later years, federal fund<strong>in</strong>g was<strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>gly given to programs <strong>in</strong> which maternal varieties were usedvery m<strong>in</strong>imally, sometimes not at all (Wiese & Garcia, 2001). Reyes (2006)provides an example. Dur<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> 20002001 school year, about half of <strong>the</strong>eligible Hispanic children <strong>in</strong> New York City were <strong>in</strong> (transitional)bil<strong>in</strong>gual education programs; <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r half received English as aSecond <strong>Language</strong> (ESL) <strong>in</strong>struction with<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> monol<strong>in</strong>gual ma<strong>in</strong>stream.By 20042005, participation <strong>in</strong> bil<strong>in</strong>gual education had decl<strong>in</strong>ed to about30% and ESL-format enrolment had <strong>in</strong>creased to about 66%.We have already noted President Reagan’s antipathy towards bil<strong>in</strong>gualeducation, a stance that both reflected and re<strong>in</strong>forced broad governmentalattitudes towards provisions for m<strong>in</strong>ority-language children. Themost recent development President Bush’s ‘No Child Left Beh<strong>in</strong>d’(NCLB) <strong>in</strong>itiative of 2001 replaces exist<strong>in</strong>g bil<strong>in</strong>gual education legislationand buttresses still fur<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> tendency towards English-mediumschool<strong>in</strong>g (see Evans & Hornberger, 2005; Throop, 2007; Wright, 2005b). 4What was once called <strong>the</strong> Office of Bil<strong>in</strong>gual Education and M<strong>in</strong>ority<strong>Language</strong> Affairs changed its name, <strong>in</strong> 2002, to <strong>the</strong> Office of English<strong>Language</strong> Acquisition. Along with many o<strong>the</strong>rs, Katz (2004) lamentsthis monol<strong>in</strong>gual orientation: not only does <strong>the</strong> new legislation rollback bil<strong>in</strong>gual education <strong>in</strong>itiatives, it also undercuts second-languageacquisition for native English speakers, most of whose foreign-language<strong>in</strong>struction (such as it is) will not beg<strong>in</strong> until secondary school. In a world<strong>in</strong> which for all <strong>the</strong> power of English multil<strong>in</strong>gualism rema<strong>in</strong>s apowerful asset, this most recent emphasis has an isolat<strong>in</strong>g tendency forAmerica and Americans. And, as part of this NCLB <strong>in</strong>itiative, and asano<strong>the</strong>r reflection of <strong>the</strong> times, <strong>the</strong>re is a very strong reliance uponstandardized assessment devices: Crawford (2004) notes that <strong>the</strong> phraseshould read ‘No Child Left Untested’.In fact, quite apart from <strong>the</strong> monol<strong>in</strong>gual emphasis that has upsetsome observers of this new program, its general pedagogical implicationsare extremely disturb<strong>in</strong>g. Schools are now required to annually test <strong>the</strong>ir


266 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>pupils on read<strong>in</strong>g and arithmetic ability; <strong>the</strong> results must <strong>the</strong>n be madepublic and, more specifically, made public by group (black children,Hispanic children, ESL pupils, and so on). This is an important bus<strong>in</strong>ess:school fund<strong>in</strong>g can be dependent upon <strong>the</strong> scores achieved, schools canbe subject to massive rearrangements, with teachers fired and new oneshired, private educational companies can be brought <strong>in</strong> to take overoperations, and so on (see McNamara & Roever, 2006). There is no doubtthat some successes have been achieved, <strong>in</strong> terms of improv<strong>in</strong>g children’sassessed abilities, but it seems that those successes are largely withchildren who are ‘border-l<strong>in</strong>e’ cases. Those who are most seriouslyunderskilled are not benefit<strong>in</strong>g. There are, as well, some entirely expectedoutcomes.The program rewards narrow ‘teach<strong>in</strong>g for <strong>the</strong> tests’, and it ‘privileges’<strong>the</strong> two areas s<strong>in</strong>gled out for assessment, read<strong>in</strong>g and arithmetic.These are, of course, very important (arguably <strong>the</strong> most important)subjects, but less time is now given to o<strong>the</strong>r school subjects. In somecases, social studies and science have almost been elim<strong>in</strong>ated, withvirtually <strong>the</strong> entire school day given over to read<strong>in</strong>g and maths. Schoolshave also been found to cheat <strong>in</strong> test adm<strong>in</strong>istration and report<strong>in</strong>g. Given<strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>itial motivation of <strong>the</strong> enabl<strong>in</strong>g legislation, however, <strong>the</strong> mostobvious problem is that, while states must test, <strong>the</strong>y are free to construct<strong>the</strong> tests <strong>the</strong>mselves. In 2005, Mississippi children given Mississippiread<strong>in</strong>g tests made <strong>the</strong> highest proficiency scores <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> country; when,however, <strong>the</strong>y were tested with <strong>the</strong> more rigorous National Assessmentof Educational Progress <strong>in</strong>strument, <strong>the</strong>y fell to <strong>the</strong> very bottom of <strong>the</strong>50-state ledger! International observers have found it bizarre, to say<strong>the</strong> least, that laws requir<strong>in</strong>g regular test<strong>in</strong>g across America with <strong>the</strong>results of that test<strong>in</strong>g hav<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> potential to effect massive alterations <strong>in</strong>schools <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> very short term are not accompanied by requirements for<strong>the</strong> use of uniform assessment <strong>in</strong>struments; that one of <strong>the</strong> consequencesof <strong>the</strong> program has been to encourage a retrogressive drill-like emphasisupon what is to be tested; and that read<strong>in</strong>g and arithmetic, importantthough <strong>the</strong>y are, have been allowed <strong>in</strong> some <strong>in</strong>stances to shoulder asideo<strong>the</strong>r classroom topics and practices. For an excellent and up-to-datejournalistic account of NCLB matters <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g some mentioned <strong>in</strong> thisparagraph see Wallis and Steptoe (2007).Kozol (2007) provides a brief but succ<strong>in</strong>ct <strong>in</strong>dictment of <strong>the</strong> way <strong>in</strong>which <strong>the</strong> NCLB provisions greatly re<strong>in</strong>force <strong>the</strong> distress<strong>in</strong>g trendtowards <strong>the</strong> privatization of education <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> USA, and <strong>the</strong> expectationsof those <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> ‘education <strong>in</strong>dustry’. He cites <strong>the</strong> glee with which marketanalysts see ‘<strong>the</strong> K-12 market [as] <strong>the</strong> Big Enchilada’ (Kozol, 2007: 8).


Bil<strong>in</strong>gual Education 267Similarly, Larson’s (2007) collection demonstrates <strong>the</strong> attractiveness ofthis ‘<strong>in</strong>dustry’ for <strong>the</strong> corporate vultures now hover<strong>in</strong>g over <strong>the</strong>ramifications of <strong>the</strong> NCLB legislation. The broader issue of educationalprivatization is <strong>the</strong> subject of Wea<strong>the</strong>rs’s (2007) work<strong>in</strong>g-paper. He writesfrom a ‘critical discourse’ perspective, which leads him to makestatements about ‘<strong>the</strong> colonization of democratic discourse’ and ‘<strong>the</strong>larger struggle over control of <strong>the</strong> symbolic space’ (Wea<strong>the</strong>rs, 2007: 67,89). I would argue that, while textual analysis of highly charged issues <strong>in</strong><strong>the</strong> public arena is likely to confirm <strong>the</strong> debat<strong>in</strong>g and discourse strategiestypically used when large amounts of money are at stake, microscopicexam<strong>in</strong>ation of <strong>the</strong> ‘symbolic space’ is less important than forthrightaction <strong>in</strong> ‘real space’.A collection by Valenzuela et al. (2007) focuses on NCLB as it affectsm<strong>in</strong>ority-group children. Particular attention is given not to test scoresand o<strong>the</strong>r educational statistics, but ra<strong>the</strong>r to qualitative and ethnographic<strong>in</strong>sights. Among <strong>the</strong> most cutt<strong>in</strong>g commentaries is that ofMcDermott and Hall (2007: 11), who, after <strong>in</strong>vok<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> horrors ofHard Times and Gradgr<strong>in</strong>d’s <strong>in</strong>sistence on fact, go on to note:What a good idea, to leave no child left beh<strong>in</strong>d, and what a revolt<strong>in</strong>gdevelopment that its ma<strong>in</strong> effect has been to record just who is be<strong>in</strong>gleft beh<strong>in</strong>d accord<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>gly constra<strong>in</strong>ed versions of knowledgemeasured on high-stakes tests... NCLB eviscerates curriculumand teach<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> classrooms.The <strong>in</strong>creased emphasis upon English proficiency, coupled with <strong>the</strong><strong>in</strong>tensive test<strong>in</strong>g ethos of <strong>the</strong> new arrangements, certa<strong>in</strong>ly does meanmore difficulties for children who are not native speakers of English (seeF<strong>in</strong>e et al., 2007). Not only are <strong>the</strong>ir particular situations given lessattention, <strong>the</strong>ir <strong>in</strong>clusion <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> school populations to be tested can result<strong>in</strong> lower overall ‘scores’ <strong>in</strong> what is termed <strong>the</strong> ‘Adequate Yearly Progress’assessment. In terms of ‘break<strong>in</strong>g out’ ESL pupils, as <strong>the</strong>y comprise oneof <strong>the</strong> groups to be ‘disaggregated’ <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> assessment reports, ano<strong>the</strong>rproblem is that <strong>the</strong> classification of <strong>the</strong>se pupils, and <strong>the</strong> measurement of<strong>the</strong>ir language abilities, is not at all clear under <strong>the</strong> enabl<strong>in</strong>g legislation.Indeed, ESL children, unlike Hispanic or black youngsters, constitute agroup that is by its nature <strong>in</strong> flux; see McNamara and Roever (2006). AsEvans and Hornberger (2005) have written, <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>centive for schools todo well on <strong>the</strong> annual test<strong>in</strong>g exercises could and should <strong>the</strong>oreticallymean that more attention will be paid to ESL children. It is <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>collective <strong>in</strong>terest, after all. But such a <strong>the</strong>oretical consequence is oftenswamped <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> practical demands for more and more time to be given to


268 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong><strong>the</strong> two key <strong>the</strong>mes: literacy and ma<strong>the</strong>matics. There is a number of goodanalyses of <strong>the</strong> issue, <strong>the</strong> rapid growth of which <strong>in</strong>dicates <strong>the</strong> contentiousnature of <strong>the</strong> NCLB legislation and its implementation. Particularlyrecommended are Abernathy (2007), Chrismer et al. (2006), Hess andPetrilli (2006), Poetter et al. (2006), Valenzuela et al. (2007) and Yell andDrasgow (2005). Grenoble and Whaley (2006) provide a brief but usefuldiscussion of <strong>the</strong> new legislation <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> context of native non-Englishspeak<strong>in</strong>gyoungsters and attempts to ‘revitalise <strong>the</strong>ir flagg<strong>in</strong>g mo<strong>the</strong>rtongues’; see also Abedi (2004).The transitional emphasis <strong>in</strong> America (and, <strong>in</strong>deed, <strong>in</strong> most o<strong>the</strong>rcontexts) and <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>gly restricted scope of bil<strong>in</strong>gual program<strong>in</strong>itiatives have culm<strong>in</strong>ated <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> legislated rejection of those <strong>in</strong>itiatives<strong>in</strong> some quarters. In California, for example, a wealthy entrepreneur, RonUnz, spearheaded a campaign that led to <strong>the</strong> passage of Proposition 227 <strong>in</strong>1998. The act stressed <strong>the</strong> need to teach children English ‘as rapidly andas effectively as possible... children shall be taught English by be<strong>in</strong>gtaught <strong>in</strong> English’ (Baker, 2006: 196), and made bil<strong>in</strong>gual educationvirtually illegal; for useful discussions of this important event <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> lifeof bil<strong>in</strong>gual programs <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> USA, see Crawford (2004), García (2000) andOrellana et al. (1999). S<strong>in</strong>ce <strong>the</strong>n, bil<strong>in</strong>gual education <strong>in</strong> Arizona andMassachusetts has also been restricted. These were not particularly closecontests: <strong>the</strong> w<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g majorities <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> three states were 61, 63 and 68%,respectively. Dade County, Florida is famous as <strong>the</strong> <strong>home</strong> of <strong>the</strong> firstAmerican bil<strong>in</strong>gual education program <strong>in</strong> contemporary times: <strong>the</strong> CoralWay school experiment started <strong>in</strong> 1963, well before federally fundedprograms were established. But even <strong>the</strong>re, anti-bil<strong>in</strong>gual legislation wasenacted <strong>in</strong> 1980. While not specifically directed at schools, <strong>the</strong> law(passed with a 60% majority) compels official use of English only, andprohibits <strong>the</strong> f<strong>in</strong>ancial encouragement of any o<strong>the</strong>r language or of‘any culture o<strong>the</strong>r than that of <strong>the</strong> United States’ (Crawford, 1992a: 91;<strong>the</strong> text of <strong>the</strong> ord<strong>in</strong>ance can be found <strong>in</strong> Crawford, 1992b: 131). A fewyears later, Floridians endorsed English as <strong>the</strong> official state language, byan overwhelm<strong>in</strong>g marg<strong>in</strong> (8416%). 5The most <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g examples here are <strong>the</strong> first and <strong>the</strong> lastmentioned <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> preced<strong>in</strong>g paragraph. California and Florida are stateswith very large Hispanic populations, sett<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>in</strong> which unofficial uses ofSpanish have steadily expanded, but also sett<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>in</strong> which anglophonereactions to it have predictably been <strong>the</strong> strongest. It is of some <strong>in</strong>terest,too, that considerable numbers of Spanish-speak<strong>in</strong>g voters <strong>in</strong> Californiahave rejected bil<strong>in</strong>gual education naturally wish<strong>in</strong>g to heighten <strong>the</strong>irchildren’s chances of success <strong>in</strong> English milieus, and apparently swayed


Bil<strong>in</strong>gual Education 269by ‘time-on-task’ arguments <strong>in</strong> this regard. These have <strong>in</strong>cluded Unz andTuchman’s (1998) assertion that all-English <strong>in</strong>struction was necessary forfull participation <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> ‘American Dream’. 6The actual breakdown of <strong>the</strong> California results shows that abouttwo-thirds of <strong>the</strong> white voters were <strong>in</strong> favor of <strong>the</strong> Unz proposal. Thefigure was 40% among Hispanic voters, and <strong>the</strong> levels of support <strong>in</strong><strong>the</strong> Asian and African American communities were 57 and 48%,respectively. These are all <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g numbers, to be sure. A largem<strong>in</strong>ority of Spanish-speak<strong>in</strong>g voters <strong>the</strong> major beneficiaries of bil<strong>in</strong>gualeducation rejected it. African Americans, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> more or less immediateaftermath of <strong>the</strong> Oakland School Board controversies (see above)rema<strong>in</strong>ed divided over <strong>the</strong> issue. ‘Asians’, who represent a numberof language communities, and who could also <strong>the</strong>oretically benefit frombil<strong>in</strong>gual education provisions, showed a little more sympathy for <strong>the</strong>mthan did <strong>the</strong>ir white counterparts, but <strong>the</strong>ir vot<strong>in</strong>g patterns also reflect<strong>the</strong>ir well-known educational and socioeconomic success, a success thatis clearly not dependent upon any special educational programs.Even allow<strong>in</strong>g for some sort of ‘backlash’ on <strong>the</strong> part of Englishspeakers, some commentators have found it strange that legislation thatmany have seen as spr<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>g from unpleasant nativist sentiment shouldhave arisen <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> two most powerful Hispanic enclaves. This is acomplicated matter that I cannot delve fur<strong>the</strong>r <strong>in</strong>to here, but it should beremembered that strength of numbers allied, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Mexican-Americancase, with proximity to <strong>the</strong> <strong>home</strong>land does not seem to alter <strong>the</strong> basicdynamics of language shift <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> United States (a po<strong>in</strong>t that appliesequally well to <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r large m<strong>in</strong>ority group that rema<strong>in</strong>s near itsorig<strong>in</strong>s: <strong>the</strong> French-Canadians of New England). The rapidity of suchshift may be affected by <strong>the</strong>se factors, but its essential character, one thatis shared by all <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r immigrant groups <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> country, is unaltered.Thus, Porcel (2006: 107) rem<strong>in</strong>ds us that, while Miami Cubans ‘mighthave greater <strong>in</strong>centives and <strong>the</strong> best conditions for language ma<strong>in</strong>tenanceamong all U.S. Hispanics’, <strong>the</strong>y still show ‘a clear pattern of transitionalbil<strong>in</strong>gualism’. (It is possible, of course, that <strong>the</strong> phenomenal growth of<strong>the</strong> Hispanic population <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> United States, and its ever-widen<strong>in</strong>ggeographical distribution, may yet create an entirely new situation <strong>in</strong> thatcountry. This is <strong>the</strong> fear that motivates those agitat<strong>in</strong>g for English-onlylegislation at state and federal level.)There are two o<strong>the</strong>r very salient facts about <strong>the</strong> Miami ‘case’. First,while many o<strong>the</strong>r American cities have large immigrant populations, itsanti-bil<strong>in</strong>gual legislation of 1980 occurred when <strong>the</strong> Florida metropolishad <strong>the</strong> largest proportion of immigrants of any of <strong>the</strong>m more than


270 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>one-third (Castro, 1992). And second, while Spanish was often heard <strong>in</strong>Los Angeles, Houston and elsewhere, it fell differently on Floridian ears:elsewhere it was<strong>the</strong> language spoken by <strong>the</strong> people who worked <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> car wash andcame to trim <strong>the</strong> trees and cleared <strong>the</strong> tables <strong>in</strong> restaurants. In Miami,Spanish was spoken by <strong>the</strong> people who ate <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> restaurants, <strong>the</strong>people who owned <strong>the</strong> cars and <strong>the</strong> trees, which made, on <strong>the</strong> socioauditoryscale, a considerable difference... what was so unusualabout Spanish <strong>in</strong> Miami was not that it was so often spoken, but thatit was so often heard. (Didion, 1987: 63)This is an important and perspicacious comment by <strong>the</strong> famousAmerican writer, one that sounds an om<strong>in</strong>ous note for all immigrantsas <strong>the</strong>y beg<strong>in</strong> to ascend <strong>the</strong> socioeconomic ladder. They are not supposedto violate ‘<strong>the</strong> norm of immigrant subord<strong>in</strong>ation’ and, when <strong>the</strong>y do,reactionary consequences can be expected to follow (Castro, 1992: 181). Infact, <strong>the</strong> pattern is a remarkably robust one and <strong>in</strong>volves more than alittle conflict between <strong>the</strong> old-guard ma<strong>in</strong>stream and <strong>the</strong> socially mobilenewcomers. Those immigrants who were once on <strong>the</strong> receiv<strong>in</strong>g end ofsocial prejudice <strong>the</strong>mselves are just as likely to pass it on to newer wavesof arrivals. Those escap<strong>in</strong>g from <strong>the</strong> mid-19th-century fam<strong>in</strong>e were likelyto read ‘No Irish Need Apply’ signs <strong>in</strong> Boston w<strong>in</strong>dows; but, ageneration or two later, <strong>the</strong> politically savvy Irish were just as unpleasantto Slavs and Jews. It goes without say<strong>in</strong>g that <strong>the</strong> Irish are not to bes<strong>in</strong>gled out here; almost all groups reveal similar unpleasant dynamics,and no one’s hands are particularly clean when it comes to discrim<strong>in</strong>ationof this sort; see Morrison and Zabusky (1980) for a few <strong>in</strong>directadmissions of prejudicial attitudes and actions <strong>in</strong> this regard.One of <strong>the</strong> most popular arguments of those opposed to bil<strong>in</strong>gualeducation is that its implementation has created a substantial number ofeducators, adm<strong>in</strong>istrators, researchers, consultants, evaluators ando<strong>the</strong>rs. Their activities have re<strong>in</strong>forced those of teachers of foreignlanguages <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> United States, a constituency that has generally been <strong>in</strong>a bad way for a long time. There is, <strong>the</strong>n, a large group of educatedpeople with strong vested <strong>in</strong>terests <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> cont<strong>in</strong>uation of well-fundedbil<strong>in</strong>gual education (and o<strong>the</strong>r language) programs, and <strong>the</strong> voices ofsuch articulate defenders, it is claimed, are often ‘privileged’ over thoseof more ord<strong>in</strong>ary citizens. Thus, Unz noted correctly, so far as it goes that his Proposition-227 <strong>in</strong>itiative was one of <strong>the</strong> most popular <strong>in</strong>California history; he also wrote that:


Bil<strong>in</strong>gual Education 271<strong>the</strong> number of academics, professors of education, who supportbil<strong>in</strong>gual education outnumbers those who oppose bil<strong>in</strong>gual educationby probably about a thousand to one... When I attended publicforums... usually <strong>the</strong> audience was 95% aga<strong>in</strong>st [<strong>the</strong> Unz proposition],sometimes it was 98%, sometimes 100%. And that’s simplybecause <strong>the</strong> people who are most motivated to attend public forumsdeal<strong>in</strong>g with bil<strong>in</strong>gual education tend to be advocates of bil<strong>in</strong>gualeducation, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g a lot of bil<strong>in</strong>gual teachers and bil<strong>in</strong>gualadm<strong>in</strong>istrators and bil<strong>in</strong>gual academics. (Unz & Snow, 2002)There are many <strong>in</strong>trigu<strong>in</strong>g threads that could be followed up here, notleast of which are <strong>the</strong> likely correlations between typical academicpolitical postures left of center, broadly speak<strong>in</strong>g and support forsuch th<strong>in</strong>gs as bil<strong>in</strong>gualism, pluralism, <strong>the</strong> plight of <strong>the</strong> educationallydisadvantaged and so on. It is worth not<strong>in</strong>g, however, that Unz’sobservations are not his alone and that, <strong>in</strong>deed, <strong>the</strong>y are corroboratedby those views that are quite anti<strong>the</strong>tical to his. Gr<strong>in</strong>berg and Saavedra(2000) po<strong>in</strong>t out, for <strong>in</strong>stance, that <strong>the</strong> empower<strong>in</strong>g possibilities ofbil<strong>in</strong>gual education have been lost <strong>in</strong> a welter of bureaucracies andcompet<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>terests, all <strong>in</strong>tertw<strong>in</strong>ed with <strong>the</strong> allocation of substantialamounts of money. Indeed, new ‘fields of expertise’ have emerged thathave little to do with <strong>the</strong> legitimate beneficiaries of bil<strong>in</strong>gual <strong>in</strong>itiatives.Theoretical exercises and disembodied analyses of program effectivenesshave become <strong>in</strong>cestuous academic exercises. All of this means that, whileeducators and researchers may congratulate <strong>the</strong>mselves on <strong>the</strong>ir activities,<strong>the</strong>re now exists only ‘<strong>the</strong> illusion that <strong>the</strong> needs of displaced andsubjugated ‘‘o<strong>the</strong>rs’’ have been addressed’ (Gr<strong>in</strong>berg & Saavedra, 2000:433). Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, if we put aside <strong>the</strong> contemporary polemics of Unz,and <strong>the</strong> jargon-ridden discussion of Gr<strong>in</strong>berg and Saavedra, we f<strong>in</strong>d thatclearer and more dispassionate expressions have existed for a long time.Only three years after <strong>the</strong> passage of <strong>the</strong> orig<strong>in</strong>al enabl<strong>in</strong>g legislation forAmerican bil<strong>in</strong>gual education, Robert Roem<strong>in</strong>g (1971: 7879), a l<strong>in</strong>guist,language teacher and editor of The Modern <strong>Language</strong> Journal, po<strong>in</strong>ted to:<strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest of a professional group of second language teachers whomay f<strong>in</strong>d it advantageous to perpetuate support for language study.This is not an unwarranted suspicion. It is supported by colleaguesand laymen who f<strong>in</strong>d <strong>the</strong> fund<strong>in</strong>g of <strong>the</strong> Bil<strong>in</strong>gual Education Act veryprovidential at <strong>the</strong> po<strong>in</strong>t where <strong>the</strong> support of <strong>the</strong> National DefenseEducation Act was dim<strong>in</strong>ish<strong>in</strong>g.


272 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>Varghese (2004, 2006) discusses <strong>the</strong> current situation of bil<strong>in</strong>gualeducation teachers <strong>in</strong> America, not<strong>in</strong>g that, whatever <strong>the</strong>ir motivationsmay be, <strong>the</strong> grow<strong>in</strong>g politicization and controversy have provedconsiderable h<strong>in</strong>drances to <strong>the</strong> recruitment and tra<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g of new membersof <strong>the</strong> profession. M<strong>in</strong>aya-Rowe (2002) and before <strong>the</strong> 1998 Californialegislation Macías (1989) have also touched upon <strong>the</strong> matter. It is notdifficult to see <strong>the</strong> creation of a vicious circle here. The <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>gcriticisms of bil<strong>in</strong>gual education, its proponents and those who work <strong>in</strong>and around it lead to political outcomes like those <strong>in</strong> California andFlorida. An educational arena becomes stigmatized, and its scope shr<strong>in</strong>ksalong both f<strong>in</strong>ancial and social dimensions. There is room for fewerteachers, and fewer novices are attracted to what have becomecontentious classrooms, often <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> public spotlight. The field thusshr<strong>in</strong>ks fur<strong>the</strong>r.Education and PoliticsI mention all this by way of <strong>in</strong>troduction to a very abbreviateddiscussion of <strong>the</strong> politics of bil<strong>in</strong>gual education. In my view, this issometh<strong>in</strong>g that greatly overshadows <strong>the</strong> pedagogical aspects of <strong>the</strong>exercise; see Casanova (1991) and Petrovic (2005), who comments on <strong>the</strong>naïveté of those proponents of bil<strong>in</strong>gual education who neglect issues ofpolitical power. As Baker (2006: 197) succ<strong>in</strong>ctly puts it: ‘bil<strong>in</strong>gualeducation is not simply about provision, practice and pedagogy but isunavoidably about politics’. This is because <strong>the</strong> treatment of people whoare ‘non-ma<strong>in</strong>stream’ <strong>in</strong> one way or ano<strong>the</strong>r tells us more about views of<strong>the</strong>ir place <strong>in</strong> society, of desired (or unwanted) alterations <strong>in</strong> society itself,and of social hopes, fears and expectations, than it does about morepragmatic concerns with <strong>the</strong> maximization of classroom resources, <strong>the</strong>optimization of programs and assessments of educational best practice.The important matters, <strong>the</strong>n, have to do with sociocultural def<strong>in</strong>ition,group boundaries and identity. Under <strong>the</strong>se rubrics, programs ofbil<strong>in</strong>gual education are seen (by <strong>the</strong>ir supporters) as potential agents ofsocial change, as bulwarks of ethnol<strong>in</strong>guistic pluralism, as forces forgroup identities thought to be at risk.Those who endorse <strong>the</strong>se possibilities believe that cultural andl<strong>in</strong>guistic diversity is a social good, that it reflects <strong>the</strong> appropriateliberal-democratic acknowledgement of <strong>the</strong> heterogeneity of populations<strong>in</strong> many societies, and is <strong>the</strong>refore to be encouraged wherever possible,that it represents a more f<strong>in</strong>ely-tuned attention to <strong>in</strong>dividual andcollective human rights, and so on. As both legislative and public


Bil<strong>in</strong>gual Education 273reaction has demonstrated, however, arguments for alterations to a moretraditional ma<strong>in</strong>stream status quo typically come up aga<strong>in</strong>st strongopposition. From surveys and o<strong>the</strong>r forms of public-op<strong>in</strong>ion assessment,it is clear that such alterations are viewed as both unnecessary andundesirable, especially where <strong>the</strong> prevail<strong>in</strong>g monoculture is a powerfulone. Such perceptions are often connected with more specific fears ofsocial fragmentation and divisiveness. Sometimes <strong>the</strong>se derive from <strong>the</strong>desire to protect <strong>the</strong> ma<strong>in</strong>stream group (reasonable <strong>in</strong> some circumstances rang<strong>in</strong>g on racism <strong>in</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs); sometimes <strong>the</strong>y are expressed outof sympathy for a m<strong>in</strong>ority population which, it is thought, might bebetter served by be<strong>in</strong>g brought <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> ma<strong>in</strong>stream as soon as possible.I need hardly add, I suppose, that expressions of sympathy for m<strong>in</strong>oritiesare often simply more politically correct cloaks for nativist sentiments; orthat a narrow concern with a particular m<strong>in</strong>ority group and a lack ofconcern for o<strong>the</strong>rs is often presented under <strong>the</strong> guise of an endorsementof cultural pluralism per se.The greatest concerns and <strong>the</strong> bitterest wrangl<strong>in</strong>g about bil<strong>in</strong>gualeducation provisions are social <strong>in</strong> nature. The existence of thosecomplexities already touched upon means that, even if purely pedagogicalmatters were <strong>the</strong> ma<strong>in</strong> focus, <strong>the</strong>re would still be ample scope fordebates over measurements and outcomes. But <strong>the</strong>y would not be sovitriolic <strong>in</strong> nature if larger questions about social mobility, pluralism,ethnol<strong>in</strong>guistic diversity and assimilation <strong>in</strong> short, about <strong>the</strong> face ofsociety itself were not <strong>in</strong>timately <strong>in</strong>tertw<strong>in</strong>ed with cognitive and<strong>in</strong>structional ones. People can have fierce arguments about methods, but<strong>the</strong>y only go to war over substance. L<strong>in</strong>guists and educators <strong>the</strong>mselveshave always acknowledged that bil<strong>in</strong>gual education is not primarily al<strong>in</strong>guistic matter. Comment<strong>in</strong>g on <strong>the</strong> early American bil<strong>in</strong>gual educationscene, for <strong>in</strong>stance, Ferguson (1977: 43) stated thatsocial, political, psychological, economic and o<strong>the</strong>r factors mustsurely outweigh <strong>the</strong> purely l<strong>in</strong>guistic factors <strong>in</strong> any analysis ofbil<strong>in</strong>gual education efforts and <strong>in</strong> any actual policy plann<strong>in</strong>g forbil<strong>in</strong>gual education.The bluntest po<strong>in</strong>t of sociopolitical debate is, I suppose, between anyeducational provision for m<strong>in</strong>ority groups and none at all. Podhoretz ando<strong>the</strong>rs may approve of <strong>the</strong> s<strong>in</strong>k-or-swim approach that galvanizedsuccessful immigrants, but some will have o<strong>the</strong>r memories of submersion<strong>in</strong> foreign-language classrooms, and of punishments meted out for<strong>the</strong> use of <strong>the</strong>ir maternal variety. Indeed, among both <strong>in</strong>digenous andimmigrant m<strong>in</strong>ority groups, egregious measures were often taken. In


274 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>Wales, for example, <strong>the</strong> ‘Welsh Not’ was a stick or sign hung aroundan offend<strong>in</strong>g child’s neck. It would rema<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>re until transferred to<strong>the</strong> next victim who lapsed <strong>in</strong>to Welsh and, at <strong>the</strong> end of <strong>the</strong> day, <strong>the</strong>last stigmatized youngster might be beaten. In Scotland, a similar device(<strong>the</strong> maide-crochaidhe) was used and, <strong>in</strong> Ireland under <strong>the</strong> British, a ‘tallystick’ notched to <strong>in</strong>dicate every time a child spoke Irish acted asa record of misdemeanors (Edwards, 1989). Ngũgĩ wa Thiong’o (2004)has confirmed that Gĩkũyũ speakers <strong>in</strong> Kenya suffered <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> same way,and Stoller (1977) wrote of such punishments for Spanish-speak<strong>in</strong>gchildren <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> USA. The practice may have been widespread, <strong>in</strong>deed,although some caution is needed <strong>in</strong> accept<strong>in</strong>g all <strong>the</strong> accounts; seeEdwards (<strong>in</strong> preparation).Ngũgĩ wa Thiong’o is well known as a writer who abandoned writ<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong> English as a sociopolitical statement. Many o<strong>the</strong>r ‘colonial’ writershave struggled with hard language choices, too. In <strong>the</strong> foreword to hisfamous novel, Kanthapura, Raja Rao discussed <strong>the</strong> problems of convey<strong>in</strong>gone’s ‘spirit’ <strong>in</strong> a foreign language. He admitted that English was nota completely alien language <strong>in</strong>tellectually it was <strong>in</strong> many ways<strong>the</strong> primary language for educated Indians (as Sanskrit and Persianwere before) but he argues that it was not <strong>the</strong> language of ‘emotion’.He cont<strong>in</strong>ues:We are all <strong>in</strong>st<strong>in</strong>ctively bil<strong>in</strong>gual, many of us writ<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> our ownlanguage and <strong>in</strong> English. We cannot write like <strong>the</strong> English. We shouldnot. We cannot write only as Indians. We have grown to look at <strong>the</strong>large world as part of us. Our method of expression <strong>the</strong>refore has tobe a dialect which will some day prove to be as dist<strong>in</strong>ctive andcolourful as <strong>the</strong> Irish or <strong>the</strong> American. (Rao, 1938: vii)English has moved much fur<strong>the</strong>r and deeper <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> Indian consciousnesss<strong>in</strong>ce Rao expressed those sentiments (see Ashcroft et al., 2006). Theimplicit question he raises, <strong>the</strong>n, has even greater importance: to whatextent can a population ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong> a strong and <strong>in</strong>dependent psychosocialidentity if its orig<strong>in</strong>al language has been largely displaced or, at least,displaced <strong>in</strong> important doma<strong>in</strong>s by ano<strong>the</strong>r? Many would argue that a‘full’ or ‘au<strong>the</strong>ntic’ identity requires <strong>the</strong> ma<strong>in</strong>tenance of that first variety,but where does that leave <strong>the</strong> Indians, <strong>the</strong> Irish and o<strong>the</strong>rs? And what ofo<strong>the</strong>r groups who share languages, <strong>the</strong> Brazilians and <strong>the</strong> Portuguese,<strong>the</strong> Austrians and <strong>the</strong> Germans, even <strong>the</strong> Australians and <strong>the</strong> Canadians?Is it not possible for a population to take a ‘foreign language’ and make it<strong>the</strong>ir own <strong>in</strong> style, <strong>in</strong> pronunciation, <strong>in</strong> idiom (see Edwards, 1985)?


Bil<strong>in</strong>gual Education 275Overall, <strong>the</strong> best evidence shows that bil<strong>in</strong>gual education can bepedagogically useful and, <strong>in</strong> its (‘late-exit’) transitional format, can beeasily justified. It can quite reasonably, <strong>the</strong>n, be presented to <strong>the</strong> generalpublic as a sensible and fair reaction to l<strong>in</strong>guistic heterogeneity at school.Given appropriate resources and contexts, any return to ‘submersion’approaches is unconscionable and this conclusion logically permitsanswers to many of <strong>the</strong> questions posed <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> last two paragraphs. Themore active proponents of societal diversity and pluralism have objected,however, that transitional bil<strong>in</strong>gual education formats, even <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir moreenlightened forms, actually expedite assimilation and should <strong>the</strong>reforebe replaced with ma<strong>in</strong>tenance programs. They make a pedagogicalargument, as well. It is claimed that ma<strong>in</strong>tenance bil<strong>in</strong>gual education isnecessary for <strong>the</strong> maximization of English proficiency a po<strong>in</strong>t of viewthat still seems counter-<strong>in</strong>tuitive to some, but one predicated on <strong>the</strong>assumption that a firm and cont<strong>in</strong>u<strong>in</strong>g support of children’s maternalcompetences is <strong>the</strong> best foundation for mastery of ma<strong>in</strong>stream varieties.Here, I have already suggested that <strong>the</strong> matter is a bit more subtle: <strong>the</strong>reis no compell<strong>in</strong>g evidence for <strong>the</strong> necessity (on ma<strong>in</strong>stream-languageproficiencygrounds) of ma<strong>in</strong>tenance education; on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r hand,‘ma<strong>in</strong>stream<strong>in</strong>g’ may not be necessary for such proficiency. This allowsus, <strong>the</strong>n, to move on to considerations of ma<strong>in</strong>tenance education on o<strong>the</strong>rgrounds: as a support for ethnol<strong>in</strong>guistic pluralism and a force aga<strong>in</strong>stassimilation. We return, <strong>in</strong> a word, to broader sociopolitical <strong>the</strong>mes, andthis means that debates emerge more from ideological assumptions thanfrom dispassionate considerations of ‘data’. It would be <strong>in</strong>correct,however, to conclude that <strong>the</strong>re are <strong>in</strong> fact no ‘data’ of <strong>in</strong>terest here.First, <strong>the</strong>re is no evidence to suggest that, <strong>in</strong> liberal-democraticsocieties, many markers of ethnic-group identity (<strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g language)can be significantly ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>ed through formal <strong>in</strong>tervention unless <strong>the</strong>group concerned is a voluntarily self-segregat<strong>in</strong>g one. (If a group hassegregation forced upon it a morally <strong>in</strong>defensible situation <strong>the</strong>n<strong>in</strong>tervention is obviously <strong>in</strong> operation.) Some aspects of ethnicity,particularly symbolic and private ones, may rema<strong>in</strong> for a long time,but <strong>the</strong>y are not markers susceptible to formal efforts at sustenance (seeEdwards, 1985). Macro-level language shift, on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r hand, is<strong>in</strong>evitable for most m<strong>in</strong>ority groups. Second, <strong>the</strong> idea that programs ofbil<strong>in</strong>gual education can significantly affect <strong>the</strong> larger social landscapepresumes an altoge<strong>the</strong>r too powerful role for <strong>the</strong> school. When socialpressures and historical developments have created a situation <strong>in</strong> whicha community is seen to be at risk of language shift, we cannot expect


276 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>schools to halt this. We can, of course, expect schools to reflect andre<strong>in</strong>force larger trends exist<strong>in</strong>g outside <strong>the</strong>ir gates.A third po<strong>in</strong>t here is that <strong>the</strong> use of bil<strong>in</strong>gual-education <strong>in</strong>itiatives as aform of social eng<strong>in</strong>eer<strong>in</strong>g can be seen as an <strong>in</strong>appropriate use of officialpower, one that reflects <strong>the</strong> assumption that diversity is not only to beapproved of <strong>in</strong> a tolerant fashion, but also to be actively promoted to <strong>the</strong>level of official policy. This is hardly <strong>the</strong> place to go <strong>in</strong>to fur<strong>the</strong>r detail onthis very <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g matter, but I should po<strong>in</strong>t out that a rich literature isnow develop<strong>in</strong>g around <strong>the</strong> most appropriate responses that liberaldemocracies should make are obliged to make when faced wi<strong>the</strong>thnocultural heterogeneity (see Edwards, 2003b, 2004a). Relatedly, it isobvious that <strong>the</strong> implementation of ma<strong>in</strong>tenance programs would benefitfrom a general public sentiment <strong>in</strong> favor of diversity and pluralism and which would be sure to follow from whole-hearted governmentsupport for ethnic-group <strong>in</strong>terests. Once aga<strong>in</strong>, I can only touch (below)upon a large literature, this one deal<strong>in</strong>g with <strong>the</strong> measurement ofattitudes and beliefs about all aspects of ‘non-ma<strong>in</strong>stream’ language andculture. Allow<strong>in</strong>g for <strong>the</strong> fact that political correctness has cloakednegative attitudes that once were expressed more openly (see Edwards,1990) <strong>the</strong> implication be<strong>in</strong>g that <strong>the</strong>re is as much <strong>in</strong>tolerance <strong>in</strong> this areaas <strong>the</strong>re ever was <strong>the</strong>re are at <strong>the</strong> same time <strong>in</strong>dications of somemovement here. It seems, however, to be more towards a passivegoodwill than anyth<strong>in</strong>g else.Canadian surveys, for example, have revealed some public sense that‘unofficial’ languages and cultures can be strengths, but Berry et al. (1977:43) famously reported that ‘when money and effort are at stake...respondents switch to neutrality and even rejection of multiculturalism’(see also <strong>the</strong> similar f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>gs reported by Breton et al., 1980; Edwards &Chisholm, 1987; Edwards & Doucette, 1987). Palozzi’s (2006) study ofAmerican attitudes towards English and o<strong>the</strong>r languages <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> UnitedStates reveals <strong>the</strong> apparent ambiguities that so often occur <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>sesurveys. Many of his respondents, for <strong>in</strong>stance, endorsed <strong>the</strong> idea that itwas ‘un-American’ for citizens not to speak English, while also agree<strong>in</strong>gthat it was a good th<strong>in</strong>g for immigrant children to know <strong>the</strong>ir parents’maternal languages. It would be easy enough to focus upon <strong>the</strong> first sortof response, and argue that Americans are ma<strong>in</strong>ly <strong>in</strong> favor of some‘English-only’ arrangement, but a more complete assessment wouldsuggest that a ‘strict assimilationism’ is <strong>in</strong> fact rejected, and a somewhatmore liberal view of ‘foreign’ languages emerges. A useful analysis of <strong>the</strong>Australian scene (Goot, 1993: 226) po<strong>in</strong>ts, as well, to <strong>the</strong> differentunderstand<strong>in</strong>gs that are so often possible:


Bil<strong>in</strong>gual Education 277<strong>the</strong> most comprehensive survey of Australian attitudes to multiculturalismhas been variously <strong>in</strong>terpreted as show<strong>in</strong>g thatmulticulturalism enjoys a high level of support or very littlesupport at all.This sort of situation occurs because <strong>the</strong> sociopolitical stakes <strong>in</strong> surveyoutcomes are often quite large, because conceptions of multiculturalismand multil<strong>in</strong>gualism are often vague and imprecise, because questionsare not framed specifically enough (often on purpose) and, quitesimply, because ‘many, even most, see multiculturalism as someth<strong>in</strong>g of amixed bag’ (Goot, 1993: 251). Relatively frequent poll<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> Canada,Australia and o<strong>the</strong>r ‘receiv<strong>in</strong>g’ societies does not suggest any sea change<strong>in</strong> ma<strong>in</strong>stream public op<strong>in</strong>ion. Movement typically occurs only whenattitudes become less favorable, which, of course, <strong>the</strong>y predictably dowhenever events cast <strong>the</strong> cultures and languages of m<strong>in</strong>ority groups <strong>in</strong>negative or threaten<strong>in</strong>g lights. A contemporary example is found <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>current European and American antipathies occasioned by Islamistterrorism. One of <strong>the</strong> predictable, if unpleasant, consequences is a rise<strong>in</strong> narrow nativist sentiment or worse (see Koopmans et al., 2005, for arecent survey of <strong>the</strong> European scene). An example from recent history is<strong>the</strong> forced evacuation and <strong>in</strong>ternment of Japanese-Canadians andJapanese-Americans from <strong>the</strong>ir <strong>home</strong>s on <strong>the</strong> Pacific coast dur<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>Second World War. And, of course, <strong>the</strong>re are many well-known examplesfrom <strong>the</strong> more remote past.Notes1. My Baker-based discussion here is a much simplified condensation of hisown, and it omits many details, sub-categories, and <strong>the</strong> like; see alsoHornberger (1991) for a bil<strong>in</strong>gual program typology.A very recent book on bil<strong>in</strong>gual education (García, 2009) provides acomprehensive overview of <strong>the</strong> issues. If <strong>the</strong> ra<strong>the</strong>r breathless blurbs on <strong>the</strong>back cover are to be believed, it has been written with an unusual comb<strong>in</strong>ationof wisdom and heart, it will soon achieve classic status and, <strong>in</strong>deed, <strong>the</strong>author has ‘unemployed a lot of researchers’, s<strong>in</strong>ce <strong>the</strong>re will be no need forano<strong>the</strong>r book on <strong>the</strong> topic for a decade. But while García’s book certa<strong>in</strong>lypresents a great deal of useful <strong>in</strong>formation, readers should be well aware thata strongly favorable stance is evident throughout. At <strong>the</strong> beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>the</strong>author outl<strong>in</strong>es her ma<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>sis ‘that bil<strong>in</strong>gual education is <strong>the</strong> only way toeducate children <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> twenty-first century’ (García, 2009: 5; orig<strong>in</strong>al italics) and her conclusion discusses its ‘transformative potential’ (p. 387).Some may also f<strong>in</strong>d <strong>the</strong> fluency of <strong>the</strong> argument to be less than what mighthave been hoped for from a language specialist. It is one th<strong>in</strong>g (perhaps...)for a blurb writer to use a non-existent verb (‘unemploy’). But what is one tomake of <strong>the</strong> author’s use of ‘languag<strong>in</strong>g’ and ‘translanguag<strong>in</strong>g’ terms that


278 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>are at once ugly and wholly unnecessary? Should we be wary about tak<strong>in</strong>gadvice from someone who writes that ‘people language for many purposes’(García, 2009: 31) or that ‘<strong>in</strong>dividuals and communities... usually languagebil<strong>in</strong>gually, that is, <strong>the</strong>y translanguage when <strong>the</strong>y communicate’ (pp. 4344)?2. The first citation here is from a speech made by Roosevelt <strong>in</strong> early January,1919 just n<strong>in</strong>e days before his death, <strong>in</strong> fact but he had made many o<strong>the</strong>rsimilar remarks as early as 1907 (see also Davis, 1920). Ronald Reagan’sobservations can be found <strong>in</strong> his official papers (Reagan, 1982).3. See, however, <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g collection by Morrison and Zabusky (1980) <strong>in</strong>which about 140 immigrants tell <strong>the</strong>ir own stories. A few of <strong>the</strong>m are famous(Alistair Cooke, Edward Teller, Lynn Redgrave), but <strong>the</strong> vast majority areord<strong>in</strong>ary work<strong>in</strong>g people. Their attitudes towards language vary considerably,of course, but most are strongly pragmatic.4. In 2007, <strong>the</strong> American Educational Research Journal devoted a 175-page section(<strong>in</strong> volume 44, [3]) to <strong>the</strong> ‘No Child Left Beh<strong>in</strong>d’ program. Of particular<strong>in</strong>terest for my purposes here are <strong>the</strong> papers by Hursh and Balfanz et al. Thefirst places this new educational <strong>in</strong>itiative with<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> context of those neoliberalprivatization and free-market emphases that seem so odd whenapplied to children <strong>in</strong> classrooms; <strong>the</strong> second focuses on <strong>the</strong> impact of NCLBupon <strong>the</strong> poorest of schools and <strong>the</strong> weakest of pupils.5. The rise and <strong>the</strong> ambitions of <strong>the</strong> U.S. English movement constitute a naturalopposition to bil<strong>in</strong>gual education programs <strong>in</strong> America, although members ofthat organization have sometimes argued that <strong>the</strong>y are not aga<strong>in</strong>st ‘foreign’languages per se. Fuller details of U.S. English, its successes and failures, andreactions to it from various quarters, constitute an <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g story <strong>in</strong><strong>the</strong>mselves. See Chapter 11 for some discussion of <strong>the</strong> mach<strong>in</strong>ations of U.S.English at <strong>the</strong> state level; see also Edwards (1990, <strong>in</strong> press-b).6. Gloria Tuchman, a Mexican-American teacher, jo<strong>in</strong>ed forces with Unz’s‘English for <strong>the</strong> Children’ movement.


Chapter 14A Conclud<strong>in</strong>g StatementS<strong>in</strong>ce I have provided short chapter overviews at <strong>the</strong> beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g of thisbook and s<strong>in</strong>ce, more particularly, readers will f<strong>in</strong>d <strong>the</strong>re ra<strong>the</strong>r obvious<strong>in</strong>dications of my own assessments of many of <strong>the</strong> important <strong>the</strong>mes, thislast chapter can be a brief one.The general underp<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g for <strong>the</strong> work, and my motivation forundertak<strong>in</strong>g it, rest upon my belief that teachers, students andresearchers could profit from a broad-brush treatment of <strong>the</strong> importantlanguage issues hav<strong>in</strong>g educational components or ramifications. To thisend, I have provided what I hope is a useful comb<strong>in</strong>ation of a fairlycomprehensive and jargon-free survey with a rich and extensive set ofcitations for those who need or want <strong>the</strong>m. Of course, I make referencesto recent research throughout <strong>the</strong> book, but perhaps it is also necessary torepeat that my reliance on many publications that some may see asvenerable or, <strong>in</strong>deed, antique, is <strong>in</strong>tentional. Many early <strong>in</strong>sights have yetto be bettered, and have <strong>in</strong>appropriately fallen from general view. Manymore modern ones have, I believe, strayed from <strong>the</strong> paths of <strong>the</strong> greatestimmediacy and relevance for researchers and practitioners unless, ofcourse, <strong>the</strong> latter are <strong>the</strong>mselves engaged <strong>in</strong> what is sometimes narrowwork of very limited generalizability, sometimes work that smellsstrongly of <strong>the</strong> lamp. But it is not for such readers that this book hasbeen written.Many great writers, dramatists and o<strong>the</strong>r social commentators haveobserved, <strong>in</strong> one form or ano<strong>the</strong>r, that <strong>the</strong> measure of a society is bestdiscovered <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> ways it treats its less fortunate members. This iscerta<strong>in</strong>ly true when we consider those whose language br<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>the</strong>m to<strong>the</strong> particular attention of <strong>the</strong> educational system. The attitudes andreactions toward language and dialect varieties derive, of course, frombroader underly<strong>in</strong>g ones, and this is why I devote <strong>the</strong> open<strong>in</strong>g chaptersto <strong>the</strong> manner <strong>in</strong> which we have understood social disadvantage and,<strong>in</strong>deed, created it. The word itself is now <strong>in</strong> bad odor <strong>in</strong> some quarters,but I argue that, if used appropriately, ‘disadvantage’ rema<strong>in</strong>s anaccurate and useful description. It would seem perverse to deny <strong>the</strong>reality of social <strong>in</strong>equalities, or to ignore <strong>the</strong> stratifications that279


280 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>unfavorably position some groups of people. We do such groups noservice by romanticiz<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>ir plight, or by suggest<strong>in</strong>g that <strong>the</strong>irdisabilities are merely ‘different abilities’. To make such a case is toreveal a posture that cannot be susta<strong>in</strong>ed outside <strong>the</strong> academic cloisters,and it usually accompanies ideological perspectives hav<strong>in</strong>g little realconnection to <strong>the</strong> lives of those who are apparently meant to be <strong>the</strong>beneficiaries of attention. In fact, <strong>the</strong>re are many disadvantag<strong>in</strong>g featuresand characteristics that are non-randomly distributed across society, andsome have l<strong>in</strong>guistic aspects.Mealy-mou<strong>the</strong>d neologisms and periodic relabell<strong>in</strong>gs do little service,ei<strong>the</strong>r to scholarship or to those be<strong>in</strong>g described. But it would be an evengreater error to allow broad criticism here to undercut necessaryref<strong>in</strong>ements <strong>in</strong> our understand<strong>in</strong>g of social disadvantage, l<strong>in</strong>guisticand o<strong>the</strong>rwise. In my open<strong>in</strong>g chapters, <strong>the</strong>n, I try to make it as clearas I can that disadvantage is real, but that it is nei<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> product of<strong>in</strong>herent genetic deficiency nor <strong>the</strong> result of crippl<strong>in</strong>g environmentaldeficits. (Of course, <strong>the</strong>se can obviously accompany and re<strong>in</strong>force it.) Itis, ra<strong>the</strong>r, a phenomenon that can only occur <strong>in</strong> stratified societies, canonly emerge when social comparisons become possible. It reflects <strong>the</strong>judgments of those <strong>in</strong> power upon those who are relatively powerless.As considered here, <strong>the</strong>n, disadvantage is a social-psychological entity. Itcan thus be considered separately from <strong>the</strong> tangible or physicalconsequences of substantive genetic or environmental deficiencies.But this means, <strong>in</strong> effect, that social disadvantage can be even morereal, even more debilitat<strong>in</strong>g. This is because causes that are at once<strong>in</strong>tangible and pervasive can long outlast those that we can more clearlyidentify and, if necessary, combat. We have learned a great deal over <strong>the</strong>years about <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>accuracy and <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>iquity of most ‘genetic’ arguments,and <strong>in</strong>tervention is always at least <strong>the</strong>oretically possible where environmentalproblems retard physical or mental growth. No, with socialdisadvantage, we are <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> murky but potent realms of socialperception, and <strong>the</strong> great lesson here is that perception is reality. Whenwe th<strong>in</strong>k of social disadvantage, <strong>the</strong>n, we can elim<strong>in</strong>ate as I try to do <strong>in</strong><strong>the</strong> first few chapters actual, substantive deficiencies as <strong>the</strong> ma<strong>in</strong> fuel ofdisadvantage, logically arriv<strong>in</strong>g at <strong>the</strong> position that such disadvantagerepresents social difference. <strong>Language</strong>s and dialects of low prestigeoccupy that status because <strong>the</strong>y are not spoken by those who have <strong>the</strong>ability to assign terms like ‘standard’ and ‘nonstandard’. There is noth<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>herently wrong with any of <strong>the</strong>m, however one of <strong>the</strong> great truths ofmodern l<strong>in</strong>guistics that should be much more widely dissem<strong>in</strong>ated andwe are right to utterly reject <strong>the</strong> term ‘substandard’.


A Conclud<strong>in</strong>g Statement 281But it is much harder, and perhaps impossible, to root out thosedeeply felt beliefs, attitudes and prejudices that can undercut scholarly<strong>in</strong>sight. Any survey taken along any High Street will quickly reveal thatmost people cont<strong>in</strong>ue to have strong views about ‘correct’ and ‘<strong>in</strong>correct’speech and language. Stereotyped, <strong>in</strong>accurate (as we believe) and oftenunarticulated views can make m<strong>in</strong>cemeat of academic <strong>in</strong>sight, and <strong>the</strong>upshot for <strong>the</strong> disadvantaged is that many features of <strong>the</strong>ir social lives <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g language, <strong>the</strong> ‘marker’ that Bernard Shaw so famouslyremarked upon become stigmatized. In this way, via stereotype andignorance, difference is effortlessly translated <strong>in</strong>to deficiency. But thisdoes not mean does not mean at all that attempts to <strong>in</strong>form andeducate about disadvantage <strong>in</strong> general, and about <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>tr<strong>in</strong>sic validity oflanguages and dialects <strong>in</strong> particular, are fruitless. We may hope thatcumulative and unremitt<strong>in</strong>g efforts here will eventually have desirableresults; and, even if we believed that favorable outcomes were unlikely,that <strong>in</strong> itself would be no reason not to persevere. Rabbi Tarfon put <strong>the</strong>case more generally, almost two thousand years ago: <strong>the</strong> fact that one isnot always duty-bound, or able, to complete a task does not mean thatone is <strong>the</strong>refore morally free to ignore it altoge<strong>the</strong>r.Up to <strong>the</strong> end of Chapter 5, I have largely dealt with disadvantage <strong>in</strong> ageneral sense, but <strong>the</strong> next group of four chapters turns specifically tolanguage issues. Much of <strong>the</strong> central <strong>the</strong>me can, of course, be anticipated.Disadvantage per se is properly understood as reflect<strong>in</strong>g nei<strong>the</strong>r geneticnor environmental deficiency. Ra<strong>the</strong>r, its variant features, seen through<strong>the</strong> judgmental lenses focused upon it by <strong>the</strong> powerful middle class, arequickly altered from simple difference <strong>in</strong>to socially debilitat<strong>in</strong>g deficiency.This is nowhere reflected more clearly than <strong>in</strong> language patternsand language attitudes. The elements of <strong>the</strong> basic controversy are verysimple <strong>in</strong>deed, revolv<strong>in</strong>g around this question: can some languages ordialects be reasonably seen as better or worse than o<strong>the</strong>rs; is <strong>the</strong>re somelogic, <strong>in</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r words, to a sort of l<strong>in</strong>guistic hierarchy?Roughly analogous to <strong>the</strong> genetic, environmental and ‘difference’perspectives on disadvantage are <strong>the</strong> grammatical, aes<strong>the</strong>tic and ‘difference’approaches to language and dialect variation. Thanks to <strong>the</strong>concerted effort of l<strong>in</strong>guists <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> 1960s and 1970s, <strong>the</strong> idea that somevarieties might be less ‘logical’ than o<strong>the</strong>rs that <strong>the</strong>ir grammaticalmach<strong>in</strong>ery, <strong>the</strong>ir <strong>in</strong>ternal logic, so to say, was flawed has been soundlyrejected. All varieties are valid rule-bound systems of expressions and,<strong>in</strong>deed, a moment’s reflection ought to make us realize how very oddand unlikely th<strong>in</strong>gs would be were this not <strong>the</strong> case for all human groups.All varieties are, quite obviously, not equal at all po<strong>in</strong>ts along <strong>the</strong>


282 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>expressive cont<strong>in</strong>uum, but none has been found that is ei<strong>the</strong>r <strong>in</strong>adequatefor <strong>the</strong> current needs of its speakers or unable to make all necessaryadaptations as those needs alter. There are no ‘primitive’ languages ordialects. As to grammar or ‘logic’, <strong>the</strong>n, <strong>the</strong> case is clear. As to <strong>the</strong> secondapproach: it has been argued for a very long time, and often by very<strong>in</strong>fluential people, that some forms of language are better than o<strong>the</strong>rsbecause of <strong>the</strong>ir greater <strong>in</strong>tr<strong>in</strong>sic aes<strong>the</strong>tic appeal. Your language is uglyand guttural, full of stops and grunts, dom<strong>in</strong>ated by harsh consonantalsounds; my language is smooth and fluent, musical and mellifluous, withsoft vowel glides and end<strong>in</strong>gs. But here aga<strong>in</strong>, despite very markedbeliefs and preferences, experimental evidence shows quite clearly thataes<strong>the</strong>tic appreciation is <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> ears of listeners. Dialect varieties that,with<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> larger speech community, are seen as harsh and unpleasantare not so perceived by outsiders.The reason for this difference br<strong>in</strong>gs us exactly to <strong>the</strong> ‘difference’position itself. For we now understand that aes<strong>the</strong>tic reactions todifferent varieties of language are <strong>in</strong>tertw<strong>in</strong>ed with stereotypes of thosewho speak <strong>the</strong>m. If outport Newfoundland English is understood, <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>rest of Canada, as rustic, unsophisticated and hard on <strong>the</strong> ear, <strong>the</strong>n it isbecause its users are seen as unsophisticated people liv<strong>in</strong>g a hardscrabblelife far from <strong>the</strong> centers of power and elegance. If those liv<strong>in</strong>g on <strong>the</strong>island of Crete are <strong>the</strong> Newfoundlanders of Greece, <strong>the</strong>n we may expectthat Cretan Greek will be downgraded aes<strong>the</strong>tically by those speak<strong>in</strong>g<strong>the</strong> A<strong>the</strong>nian variety. And, <strong>in</strong> fact, <strong>the</strong>re is a generality here: <strong>the</strong> languageof those liv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> and around <strong>the</strong> social and political centers of power istypically viewed as ‘better’ <strong>in</strong> all ways <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> aes<strong>the</strong>tic quality than that of h<strong>in</strong>terland <strong>in</strong>habitants. There is usually a broad consensushere, one accepted just as much by members of <strong>the</strong> latter group as bythose liv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> capital city.If we move beyond aes<strong>the</strong>tics per se, and consider <strong>the</strong> many o<strong>the</strong>revaluative dimensions along which languages and dialects have beenjudged, we f<strong>in</strong>d that <strong>the</strong> picture becomes somewhat more complicated.Those unsophisticated regional-dialect speakers whose forms are consideredless grammatically correct and less easy on <strong>the</strong> ear will often farebetter on o<strong>the</strong>r scales: friendl<strong>in</strong>ess, for <strong>in</strong>stance, or <strong>in</strong>tegrity. That is to say,<strong>the</strong> speakers are seen to be friendlier, or more trustworthy, even though<strong>the</strong>ir voice qualities strike <strong>the</strong> listener as <strong>in</strong>elegant, and even though <strong>the</strong>irgrammar is taken to be but a crude approximation to what is ‘proper’. Torepeat: <strong>the</strong> assumption <strong>in</strong> all <strong>the</strong> work done <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>se matters is thatspeech just like many o<strong>the</strong>r markers of personal or social status actsas a trigger for social stereotypes. It can only operate, of course, among


A Conclud<strong>in</strong>g Statement 283those who have some knowledge of those stereotypes. That is whyjudges who know no Greek are unable to make <strong>the</strong> aes<strong>the</strong>tic dist<strong>in</strong>ctionsbetween Cretan and A<strong>the</strong>nian that are so bl<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>gly obvious to those <strong>in</strong><strong>the</strong> wider Greek speech community. That is why foreign visitors, sitt<strong>in</strong>gamong an audience of native English speakers will not appreciate <strong>the</strong>humor when <strong>the</strong> stage duchess opens her mouth and talks with aCockney accent.So, as with disadvantage itself, our explorations <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> social life oflanguage reveal that differences among varieties are just that differences. But, just as <strong>the</strong> alchemy of community ignorance andprejudice easily transmutes difference <strong>in</strong>to deficiency, so stereotyp<strong>in</strong>gand o<strong>the</strong>r <strong>in</strong>accuracies of social categorization have <strong>the</strong> power to turnl<strong>in</strong>guistic variation <strong>in</strong>to l<strong>in</strong>guistic deficit. That be<strong>in</strong>g so, I felt it necessary<strong>in</strong> this context to devote some specific attention to teachers, on <strong>the</strong> onehand, and to speakers of Black English, on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r. The first is easy tojustify. This entire book, after all, is about <strong>the</strong> play of language <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>classroom, and teachers have at least a co-starr<strong>in</strong>g role <strong>in</strong> that drama.And speakers of Black English? The study of <strong>the</strong>ir particular dialects isespecially reward<strong>in</strong>g precisely because those forms have so long beenlooked down upon along virtually all dimensions, and that, <strong>in</strong> turn, hasoccurred because <strong>the</strong>ir speakers have occupied <strong>the</strong> lower rungs of <strong>the</strong>social ladder. A corollary is that, if it were possible to show that <strong>the</strong>dialects of Black English were just as valid as any o<strong>the</strong>rs, that wouldsurely be a powerful support for <strong>the</strong> broader argument that all varietiesare fully-fledged systems of communication. And that demonstrationhas, <strong>in</strong> fact, taken place, to <strong>the</strong> complete satisfaction of those who aredis<strong>in</strong>terested and at least reasonably <strong>in</strong>telligent. The relatively recentcontroversies swirl<strong>in</strong>g around ‘Ebonics’ show only that not everyone yetpossesses those qualities. They have also brought to light some of <strong>the</strong>fur<strong>the</strong>r <strong>in</strong>tricacies attach<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>the</strong> ‘difference’ position. That is, if societyat large has not yet fully grasped <strong>the</strong> scholarly demonstrations bear<strong>in</strong>gupon <strong>the</strong> validity of different dialects or, <strong>in</strong> many cases, cont<strong>in</strong>ues toexhibit a wilful ignorance what practices suggest <strong>the</strong>mselves vis-à-visnonstandard dialects at school?In my last group of chapters, I move from nonstandard varieties toentirely separate languages. I attempt to outl<strong>in</strong>e someth<strong>in</strong>g of <strong>the</strong>historical and contemporary ways <strong>in</strong> which schools have responded toforeign languages <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir classrooms, and have tried to tease out some of<strong>the</strong> important features that are particularly to be looked for <strong>in</strong> multiculturaland multil<strong>in</strong>gual societies <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>gly common <strong>in</strong> many partsof <strong>the</strong> world. One of <strong>the</strong> most <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g aspects of this discussion


284 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong><strong>in</strong>volves, if not a paradox, <strong>the</strong>n someth<strong>in</strong>g of an irony. On <strong>the</strong> one hand,we see <strong>the</strong> traditional, and cont<strong>in</strong>u<strong>in</strong>g, respect that education has alwayshad for languages, <strong>the</strong> traditional emphasis upon help<strong>in</strong>g students learnforeign varieties <strong>in</strong> short, <strong>the</strong> age-old assertion that add<strong>in</strong>g a second orthird language to one’s mo<strong>the</strong>r tongue is an essential feature of aproperly rounded education. On <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r hand, we see particularly <strong>in</strong><strong>the</strong> immigrant-receiv<strong>in</strong>g societies of <strong>the</strong> new world, particularly <strong>in</strong> urbancontexts rich <strong>in</strong> l<strong>in</strong>guistic heterogeneity that not all foreign languagesare accorded equal status. Sometimes this seems to be relatively easy tojustify: <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> United States, for <strong>in</strong>stance, it is perhaps not unreasonable togive more attention to <strong>the</strong> teach<strong>in</strong>g and learn<strong>in</strong>g of Spanish than to <strong>the</strong>acquisition of Malay. But, <strong>in</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r <strong>in</strong>stances, it is clear that someassortment of those prejudices and stereotypes that I have just discussedis at work. If, for example, a school were to be confronted with a numberof pupils of Malay background, perhaps a case could be made for somel<strong>in</strong>guistic accommodation. This, at least, is <strong>the</strong> contention of those whoclaim that educational rigidity coupled with social, racial and o<strong>the</strong>rprejudices has neglected and failed to nourish many important l<strong>in</strong>guisticresources. There is a ‘human’ side to this sort of argument, <strong>in</strong> thatsometh<strong>in</strong>g of value to children and <strong>the</strong>ir parents is not given appropriateconsideration; and <strong>the</strong>re is a larger, societal side, too, <strong>in</strong>asmuch as all thatneglect may come to have strik<strong>in</strong>gly tangible consequences. WhenAmerica <strong>in</strong>tervenes <strong>in</strong> Iraq and Afghanistan, how many speakers ofArabic and Kurdish, of Pashto and Farsi, can it call upon?But <strong>the</strong>re are o<strong>the</strong>r po<strong>in</strong>ts to be considered, too. How many languagescan even <strong>the</strong> most sensitive school policy cater for? How are parental andcommunity views to be properly taken <strong>in</strong>to account? Before <strong>the</strong> passageof restrictive legislation <strong>in</strong> favor of French <strong>in</strong> Quebec, immigrants oftenhad quite fixed ideas. The Italian community <strong>in</strong> Montreal, for example,wanted its children to attend English-language schools, argu<strong>in</strong>g that <strong>the</strong>areas <strong>in</strong> which <strong>the</strong>y lived would ensure that French would be acquiredmore <strong>in</strong>formally <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> streets, playgrounds and through social activitiesgenerally, and that Italian would be transmitted at <strong>the</strong> family hearth.There are also questions of social <strong>in</strong>tegration and solidarity to be borne <strong>in</strong>m<strong>in</strong>d, and <strong>the</strong>se are often particularly marked exactly <strong>in</strong> those jurisdictionshav<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> greatest social and l<strong>in</strong>guistic diversity. Although notalways a popular message among many scholars who write aboutl<strong>in</strong>guistic heterogeneity, <strong>the</strong> protection and ma<strong>in</strong>tenance of ‘small’languages, and so on, a case can be and is regularly made that acommon language unites and helps to reduce <strong>the</strong> likelihood of socialbalkanization, or worse.


A Conclud<strong>in</strong>g Statement 285I take no strong stand here, myself, but I would recommend that someof those committed scholar-activists at least pay more attention to sucharguments. At a fairly benign level, we could cite <strong>the</strong> example of Canada.Here is a country whose history, formidable geography and patterns ofsettlement have comb<strong>in</strong>ed to bedevil <strong>the</strong> emergence of a broad nationalsensibility. Matters are exacerbated, of course, because of <strong>the</strong> proximity to<strong>the</strong> American leviathan. Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, <strong>the</strong> orig<strong>in</strong>al British-French dualitythat once def<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>the</strong> country is <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>gly overshadowed by <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>fluxof immigrants from all parts of <strong>the</strong> world: Vancouver, Toronto andMontreal are now among <strong>the</strong> most multicultural of all cities. To consider<strong>the</strong>se variables, and to consider also <strong>the</strong> reasonable desire to movetowards a shared sense of ‘Canadian-ness’, must surely add some layersof nuance to all discussions of <strong>the</strong> value of an endur<strong>in</strong>g multiculturalismand multil<strong>in</strong>gualism. And, at an entirely less benign level, we see howrecent violent events <strong>in</strong> Europe have brought about renewed concerns forsocial ‘unity’, for <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>tegration of immigrants and for <strong>the</strong> cont<strong>in</strong>uity ofimportant social values now seen to be under religious and o<strong>the</strong>rpressures. Sometimes, of course, <strong>the</strong>se concerns take very unpleasantand xenophobic shapes but when a tolerant community like TheNe<strong>the</strong>rlands, for long a beacon of multicultural flexibility, beg<strong>in</strong>s toreassess matters, it is surely reasonable to suggest some renewedattention to general questions hav<strong>in</strong>g to do with <strong>the</strong> accommodation ofl<strong>in</strong>guistic and cultural diversity <strong>in</strong> liberal-democratic societies.The f<strong>in</strong>al two substantive chapters <strong>in</strong> this book consider bil<strong>in</strong>gualismand bil<strong>in</strong>gual education, both of which now have a very large and variedliterature. Some have found it <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g and perhaps a little perplex<strong>in</strong>gthat, as a capability available to everyone of normal <strong>in</strong>telligence,bil<strong>in</strong>gualism rema<strong>in</strong>s less prevalent than its usefulness might suggest.As with o<strong>the</strong>r features of <strong>the</strong> social life of language, however, <strong>the</strong> picturebecomes clearer when we take broader matters <strong>in</strong>to account. I will returnto only three of <strong>the</strong>m at this po<strong>in</strong>t. First, given patterns of cultural andl<strong>in</strong>guistic dom<strong>in</strong>ance and subord<strong>in</strong>ation, one should expect that bil<strong>in</strong>gualismwill be an unevenly distributed quantity. Except <strong>in</strong> circumstanceswhere <strong>the</strong> languages <strong>in</strong> contact are of roughly equal socioeconomic clout,it is those whose varieties are less broadly useful, or less prestigious <strong>in</strong>important ways, who are most likely to expand <strong>the</strong>ir repertoires and tobecome bil<strong>in</strong>gual (or better, of course). The speakers of <strong>the</strong> ‘bigger’languages generally need to make fewer accommodations. There are, ofcourse, exceptions throughout history, <strong>the</strong> educated classes, scholars,and o<strong>the</strong>rs liv<strong>in</strong>g relatively privileged lives have always learned foreignlanguages; <strong>the</strong>se have often, of course, been ‘classical’ varieties, and only


286 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>rarely those spoken by <strong>the</strong> common people <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir midst. Generally,however, just as all roads of commerce, education and culture lead to <strong>the</strong>Rome of <strong>the</strong> day, so <strong>the</strong>re are accompany<strong>in</strong>g l<strong>in</strong>guistic pathways.A second po<strong>in</strong>t to bear <strong>in</strong> m<strong>in</strong>d when consider<strong>in</strong>g patterns ofbil<strong>in</strong>gualism has to do with identity. There are many motivations forlearn<strong>in</strong>g new languages, and for most ord<strong>in</strong>ary people <strong>the</strong>se have to dowith necessity, with mundane requirements for daily life, or with hopesfor social advance and improvement. But, if language were solely an<strong>in</strong>strumental medium, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> acquisition of some new and more usefulvariety would very soon lead to <strong>the</strong> discard<strong>in</strong>g of <strong>the</strong> orig<strong>in</strong>al one. Thatthis does not happen as quickly as mere practicality would suggest is an<strong>in</strong>dication of cont<strong>in</strong>u<strong>in</strong>g affections and, <strong>in</strong>deed, uses. The language of<strong>home</strong> and hearth can be reta<strong>in</strong>ed even as ano<strong>the</strong>r language takes overbeyond <strong>the</strong> front gate. Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, l<strong>in</strong>ger<strong>in</strong>g l<strong>in</strong>guistic threads can bedetected even later <strong>in</strong> language-contact scenarios. When, for example, <strong>the</strong>orig<strong>in</strong>al variety is no longer spoken even <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>timacy of <strong>the</strong> <strong>home</strong>, itssymbolic value as a marker of group history and tradition can bema<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>ed for a long time just as long, <strong>in</strong> fact, as is desired. It mayperhaps be said that, when a language has given up even this symbolicrole, <strong>the</strong> group <strong>in</strong> question has <strong>in</strong>deed become seamlessly assimilated<strong>in</strong>to ano<strong>the</strong>r, although even at that po<strong>in</strong>t o<strong>the</strong>r markers of ‘groupness’may yet be reta<strong>in</strong>ed.‘Bil<strong>in</strong>gualism’ <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>se last circumstances has become ra<strong>the</strong>r attenuated,of course, and <strong>the</strong> developmental course that I have outl<strong>in</strong>ed abovereveals a <strong>home</strong> truth: however long symbolic aspects of a language mayrema<strong>in</strong>, however endur<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>ir <strong>in</strong>fluence <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>gly latent though itmay be over generations, <strong>the</strong>se aspects rest upon <strong>the</strong> more ord<strong>in</strong>ary,communicative ones. Symbolism can outlive <strong>in</strong>strumentality, but it growsout of it. The unavoidable corollary is that, when l<strong>in</strong>guistic <strong>in</strong>strumentalityfades, <strong>the</strong> important symbolic pillars of support of social andpsychological support that even an unspoken language can cont<strong>in</strong>ue toprovide for <strong>the</strong> group cannot be expected to stand forever. They can, asI have just said, last for a very long time. Their power of enduranceresides <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir <strong>in</strong>timate and retir<strong>in</strong>g disposition; <strong>the</strong>ir very <strong>in</strong>tangibilitymeans that <strong>the</strong>y present no impediment to social mobility. Between <strong>the</strong>sixth-generation Polish American and her equally long-establishedItalian American neighbor, <strong>the</strong>re may yet rema<strong>in</strong> symbolic-languagedifferences that can be highlighted accord<strong>in</strong>g to need or desire eventhough, for all obvious and visible <strong>in</strong>tents and purposes, <strong>the</strong> neighborsare socially and culturally <strong>in</strong>dist<strong>in</strong>guishable. But <strong>the</strong> symbolic attachmentsthat my own family has to our Welsh past are now gone. Only <strong>the</strong>


A Conclud<strong>in</strong>g Statement 287name rema<strong>in</strong>s as a rem<strong>in</strong>der of distant orig<strong>in</strong>s, of ano<strong>the</strong>r language, ofvalues and customs long forgotten. Is this bad or sad? Well, it is certa<strong>in</strong>ly<strong>in</strong>evitable has proved <strong>in</strong>evitable, <strong>in</strong> fact, for virtually every person onearth, if one takes a long enough view of th<strong>in</strong>gs. Th<strong>in</strong>gs change.Instability over time is <strong>the</strong> only constant <strong>in</strong> human life. And this, <strong>in</strong>fact, is <strong>the</strong> essence of <strong>the</strong> third po<strong>in</strong>t about bil<strong>in</strong>gualism, howeverdef<strong>in</strong>ed. The difficulties of ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g a diglossic relationship amonglanguages that cont<strong>in</strong>ue to be spoken are replicated, if over a longer spanof time, when one or more of <strong>the</strong>m has retreated from <strong>the</strong> vernacularfield.Little rema<strong>in</strong>s to be said about bil<strong>in</strong>gualism brought <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> classroom,about formal programs of bil<strong>in</strong>gual education. They can beexpected to reflect, and sometimes contribute to, all <strong>the</strong> social <strong>in</strong>fluencesand pressures that I have just described. The accommodations nowmade for children who come to school with a ‘non-ma<strong>in</strong>stream’language ei<strong>the</strong>r an immigrant variety or a ‘small’ <strong>in</strong>digenous one are generally seen as a highly appropriate improvement over earliers<strong>in</strong>k-or-swim approaches. The philosophy of work<strong>in</strong>g with whatchildren first br<strong>in</strong>g with <strong>the</strong>m, with <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>tent of improv<strong>in</strong>g educationaloutcomes and, at <strong>the</strong> same time, of reduc<strong>in</strong>g social and psychologicalpressures, seems unexceptionable. But <strong>the</strong>se accommodations, thisphilosophy, are not above criticism and controversy. How manylanguages should a society cater for? How should choices be madeamong <strong>the</strong>m? What impact will educational accommodations have upon<strong>the</strong> forg<strong>in</strong>g of a common citizenry? Won’t multicultural and multil<strong>in</strong>gualpolicies keep groups isolated, and encourage cont<strong>in</strong>u<strong>in</strong>g social divisions?What about e pluribus unum? And, by <strong>the</strong> way, my ancestors hadto struggle to f<strong>in</strong>d <strong>the</strong>ir place <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> new world no accommodationswere made for <strong>the</strong>m, and look what good citizens <strong>the</strong>y became whyshould newcomers have it any easier?I am certa<strong>in</strong>ly not endors<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> impulses beh<strong>in</strong>d all of <strong>the</strong>se questions(and many o<strong>the</strong>r similar ones); <strong>in</strong>deed, some reflect quite unpleasantsocial attitudes. But I am suggest<strong>in</strong>g that <strong>the</strong>y are part of <strong>the</strong> social fabricwith<strong>in</strong> which all language-and-education <strong>in</strong>itiatives and programs mustexist. Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, I suggest that <strong>the</strong> pressures <strong>in</strong>herent <strong>in</strong> that largerfabric commonly have <strong>the</strong> effect of dwarf<strong>in</strong>g purely pedagogicaltendencies or desires. There are certa<strong>in</strong>ly <strong>in</strong>stances, <strong>the</strong>n, <strong>in</strong> whicheducational <strong>in</strong>novations of undeniable value have been shouted down, asit were, by unimag<strong>in</strong>ative or bigoted forces. On <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r hand, <strong>the</strong>re arealso examples of scholarly narrow-m<strong>in</strong>dedness, of a tunnel vision thatfoolishly neglects wider issues and concerns, of enquiries that are too


288 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>f<strong>in</strong>ely-tuned to only one context, of research enterprises that assume that<strong>the</strong> objects of study and <strong>the</strong> results of <strong>in</strong>vestigation can be treated <strong>in</strong>isolation.<strong>Language</strong> diversity <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> classroom is an important matter, and onethat as I hope to have shown here deserves more attention. Thatattention should, however, be as comprehensive and as ‘<strong>in</strong>clusive’ aspossible. For, broad as <strong>the</strong> topic is, and important as it is, it rema<strong>in</strong>san element <strong>in</strong> a yet wider picture. It is impossible to understand, measureor implement language responses and language programs withoutknow<strong>in</strong>g someth<strong>in</strong>g of <strong>the</strong> lives of languages across <strong>the</strong> whole societalspectrum. It is impossible to understand <strong>the</strong> school by rema<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g with<strong>in</strong>its gates. What should <strong>the</strong>y know of school<strong>in</strong>g who only school<strong>in</strong>g know?


ReferencesAbd-el-Jawad, Hassan (2006) Why do m<strong>in</strong>ority languages persist? The case ofCircassian <strong>in</strong> Jordan. International Journal of Bil<strong>in</strong>gual Education and Bil<strong>in</strong>gualism9, 5174.Abedi, Jamal (2004) The No Child Left Beh<strong>in</strong>d Act and English language learners:Assessment and accountability issues. Educational Researcher 33, 414.Abernathy, Scott (2007) No Child Left Beh<strong>in</strong>d and <strong>the</strong> Public Schools. Ann Arbor,MI: University of Michigan Press.Adams, J.N. (James Noel) (2003) Bil<strong>in</strong>gualism and <strong>the</strong> Lat<strong>in</strong> <strong>Language</strong>. Cambridge:Cambridge University Press.Adams, J.N. (James Noel), Mark Janse and Simon Swa<strong>in</strong> (eds) (2002) Bil<strong>in</strong>gualism<strong>in</strong> Ancient Society. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Adams, Mark (1990) The Wellborn Science: Eugenics <strong>in</strong> Germany, France, Brazil andRussia. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Adger, Carolyn, Walt Wolfram, Jennifer Detwyler and Beth Harry (1992)Confront<strong>in</strong>g dialect m<strong>in</strong>ority issues <strong>in</strong> special education. Paper to <strong>the</strong> ThirdNational Research Symposium on Limited English Proficient Student Issues,Wash<strong>in</strong>gton, August.Adler, Sol (1979) Poverty Children and <strong>the</strong>ir <strong>Language</strong>. New York: Grune & Stratton.Agence France-Presse (2006) Bush warm to ‘national language legislation’. Globe &Mail [Toronto], 20 May.A<strong>in</strong>sworth-Darnell, James and Douglas Downey (1998) Assess<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> oppositionalculture explanation for racial/ethnic differences <strong>in</strong> school performance.American Sociological Review 63, 536553.Akom, Antwi (2003) Re-exam<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g resistance as oppositional behavior: TheNation of Islam and <strong>the</strong> creation of a Black achievement ideology. Sociology ofEducation 76, 305325.Aldhous, Peter (2002) Geneticist fears ‘race-neutral’ studies will fail ethnicgroups. Nature 418 (6896), 355356.Allardt, Erik (1984) What constitutes a language m<strong>in</strong>ority? Journal of Multil<strong>in</strong>gualand Multicultural Development 5, 195205.Alvarez, Louis and Andrew Kolker (1987) American Tongues [video]. New York:Center for New American Media.Alvidrez, Jennifer and Rhona We<strong>in</strong>ste<strong>in</strong> (1999) Early teacher perceptions andlater student academic achievement. Journal of Educational Psychology 91,731746.American Dialect Society (1943) Needed Research <strong>in</strong> American English. Chicago,IL: ADS.American Dialect Society (1964) Needed Research <strong>in</strong> American English (1963).Tuscaloosa, AL: University of Alabama Press.289


290 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>American Dialect Society (1984) Needed Research <strong>in</strong> American English (1983).Tuscaloosa, AL: University of Alabama Press.American Psychiatric Association (2000) Diagnostic and Statistical Manual ofMental Disorders. Wash<strong>in</strong>gton, DC: A.P.A. (this is a revised and enlargedversion of <strong>the</strong> fourth edition of <strong>the</strong> DSM, published <strong>in</strong> 1994).American Speech-<strong>Language</strong>-Hear<strong>in</strong>g Association (1997) Omnibus Survey. Rockville,MD: ASHA.Amis, K<strong>in</strong>gsley (1990) Review of The Oxford Guide to English Usage (EdmundWe<strong>in</strong>er). In K<strong>in</strong>gsley Amis, The Amis Collection. London: Hutch<strong>in</strong>son (<strong>the</strong>review orig<strong>in</strong>ally appeared <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Observer, 19 February 1984).Amis, K<strong>in</strong>gsley (1997) The K<strong>in</strong>g’s English. London: Harper Coll<strong>in</strong>s.Ammon, Ulrich (1977) School problems of regional dialect speakers: Ideology andreality: Results and methods of empirical <strong>in</strong>vestigations <strong>in</strong> sou<strong>the</strong>rn Germany.Journal of Pragmatics 1, 4768.Ammon, Ulrich (1983) Soziale Bewertung des Dialektsprechers. In W. Besch et al.(eds) Handbuch der Dialektologie II. Berl<strong>in</strong>: Walter de Gruyter.Ammon, Ulrich, Klaus Mat<strong>the</strong>ier and Peter Nelde (eds) (1989) Dialekt und Schule<strong>in</strong> den europäischen Ländern (Sociol<strong>in</strong>guistica 3). Tüb<strong>in</strong>gen: Max Niemeyer.Anderson-Clark, Tracy, Raymond Green and Tracy Henley (2008) The relationshipbetween first names and teacher expectations for achievement motivation.Journal of <strong>Language</strong> and Social Psychology 27, 9499.Andersson, Lars and Peter Trudgill (1990) Bad <strong>Language</strong>. Oxford: Blackwell.Antaki, Charles (1988) Sound<strong>in</strong>g board. Times Higher Education Supplement,8 January.Archer, Peter and John Edwards (1982) Predict<strong>in</strong>g school achievement from dataon pupils obta<strong>in</strong>ed from teachers: Toward a screen<strong>in</strong>g device for disadvantage.Journal of Educational Psychology 74, 761770.Archer, Peter and Susan Weir (2004) Address<strong>in</strong>g Disadvantage: A Review of <strong>the</strong>International Literature and of Strategy <strong>in</strong> Ireland (Report to <strong>the</strong> EducationalDisadvantage Committee). Dubl<strong>in</strong>: Educational Research Centre. The EDCis found with<strong>in</strong> An Ro<strong>in</strong>n Oideachais agus Eolaíochta. On WWW at http://www.education.ie.Ashcroft, Bill, Gareth Griffiths and Helen Tiff<strong>in</strong> (eds) (2006) The Post-ColonialStudies Reader. London: Routledge.Atk<strong>in</strong>son, Paul (1985) <strong>Language</strong>, Structure and Reproduction: An Introduction to <strong>the</strong>Sociology of Basil Bernste<strong>in</strong>. London: Methuen.Atk<strong>in</strong>son, Paul, Brian Davies and Sara Delamont (eds) (1995) Discourse andReproduction: Essays <strong>in</strong> Honor of Basil Bernste<strong>in</strong>. Cresskill, NJ: Hampton.Baetens Beardsmore, Hugo (1986) Bil<strong>in</strong>gualism: Basic Pr<strong>in</strong>ciples. Clevedon: Multil<strong>in</strong>gualMatters.Bailey, Richard (1981) Education and <strong>the</strong> law: The K<strong>in</strong>g case <strong>in</strong> Ann Arbor. InG. Smi<strong>the</strong>rman (ed.) Black English and <strong>the</strong> Education of Black Children and Youth:Proceed<strong>in</strong>gs of <strong>the</strong> National Invitational Symposium on <strong>the</strong> K<strong>in</strong>g Decision. Detroit,MI: Center for Black Studies, Wayne State University.Baker, Col<strong>in</strong> (1988) Key Issues <strong>in</strong> Bil<strong>in</strong>gualism and Bil<strong>in</strong>gual Education. Clevedon:Multil<strong>in</strong>gual Matters.Baker, Col<strong>in</strong> (2006) Foundations of Bil<strong>in</strong>gual Education and Bil<strong>in</strong>gualism (4th edn).Clevedon: Multil<strong>in</strong>gual Matters.


References 291Baker, Col<strong>in</strong> and Sylvia Jones (1998) Encyclopedia of Bil<strong>in</strong>gualism and Bil<strong>in</strong>gualEducation. Clevedon: Multil<strong>in</strong>gual Matters.Baldw<strong>in</strong>, James (1979) If Black English isn’t a language, <strong>the</strong>n tell me, what is?The New York Times, 29 July.Balfanz, Robert, Nettie Legters, Thomas West and Lisa Weber (2007) Are NCLB’smeasures, <strong>in</strong>centives, and improvement strategies <strong>the</strong> right ones for <strong>the</strong>nation’s low-perform<strong>in</strong>g high schools? American Educational Research Journal44, 559593.Ball, Arnetha and H. Samy Alim (2006) Preparation, pedagogy, policy andpower: Brown, <strong>the</strong> K<strong>in</strong>g case, and <strong>the</strong> struggle for equal language rights. InA. Ball (ed.) With More Deliberate Speed: Achiev<strong>in</strong>g Equity and Excellence<strong>in</strong> Education. Oxford: Blackwell (Yearbook of <strong>the</strong> National Society for <strong>the</strong> Studyof Education 105 (2)).Banks, James (ed.) (1996) Multicultural Education, Transformative Knowledge andAction: Historical and Contemporary Perspectives. New York: Teachers CollegePress.Banks, James and Cherry Banks (eds) (1995) Handbook of Research on MulticulturalEducation. New York: Macmillan.Baratz, Joan (1969) A bi-dialectal task for determ<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g language proficiency <strong>in</strong>economically disadvantaged Negro children. Child Development 40, 889901.Baratz, Joan (1970) Teach<strong>in</strong>g read<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> an urban Negro school system. InF. Williams (ed.) <strong>Language</strong> and Poverty. Chicago, IL: Markham.Baratz, Joan (1972) Educational considerations for teach<strong>in</strong>g Standard Englishto Negro children. In B. Spolsky (ed.) The <strong>Language</strong> Education of M<strong>in</strong>orityChildren. Rowley, MA: Newbury.Baratz, Joan and Roger Shuy (eds) (1969) Teach<strong>in</strong>g Black Children to Read.Wash<strong>in</strong>gton, DC: Center for Applied L<strong>in</strong>guistics.Barnes, Sandra (2003) The Ebonics enigma: An analysis of attitudes on an urbancollege campus. Race, Ethnicity and Education 6, 247263.Bartee, Susan and Christopher Brown (2007) School Matters. New York: Lang.Basso, Keith (1970) To give up on words: Silence <strong>in</strong> Western Apache culture.Southwestern Journal of Anthropology 26, 213230.Bauer, Laurie and Peter Trudgill (eds) (1998) <strong>Language</strong> Myths. London: Pengu<strong>in</strong>.Bauer, W<strong>in</strong>ifred (1998) Some languages have no grammar. In L. Bauer andP. Trudgill (eds) <strong>Language</strong> Myths. London: Pengu<strong>in</strong>.Baugh, John (2000) Beyond Ebonics: L<strong>in</strong>guistic Pride and Racial Prejudice. New York:Oxford University Press.Baugh, John (2002) L<strong>in</strong>guistics, education, and <strong>the</strong> Ebonics firestorm. In J. Alatis,H. Hamilton and A-H. Tan (eds) L<strong>in</strong>guistics, <strong>Language</strong>, and <strong>the</strong> Professions.Wash<strong>in</strong>gton: Georgetown University Press.Baugh, John (2004) Ebonics and its controversy. In E. F<strong>in</strong>egan and J. Rickford(eds) <strong>Language</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> USA: Themes for <strong>the</strong> Twenty-first Century. Cambridge:Cambridge University Press.Baugh, John (2006) L<strong>in</strong>guistic considerations perta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g to Brown v. Board:Expos<strong>in</strong>g racial fallacies <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> new millennium. In A. Ball (ed.) With MoreDeliberate Speed: Achiev<strong>in</strong>g Equity and Excellence <strong>in</strong> Education. Oxford: Blackwell(Yearbook of <strong>the</strong> National Society for <strong>the</strong> Study of Education 105 (2)).Baum, Bruce (2006) The Rise and Fall of <strong>the</strong> Caucasian Race: A Political History ofRacial Identity. New York: New York University Press.


292 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>Bedore, Lisa and Elizabeth Peña (2008) Assessment of bil<strong>in</strong>gual children foridentification of language impairment: Current f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>gs and implicationsfor practice. International Journal of Bil<strong>in</strong>gual Education and Bil<strong>in</strong>gualism 11, 129.Bereiter, Carl and Siegfried Engelmann (1966) Teach<strong>in</strong>g Disadvantaged Children <strong>in</strong><strong>the</strong> Pre-school. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.Bernste<strong>in</strong>, Basil (1958) Some sociological determ<strong>in</strong>ants of perception: An enquiry<strong>in</strong>to subcultural differences. British Journal of Sociology 9, 159174.Bernste<strong>in</strong>, Basil (1959) A public language: Some sociological implications of al<strong>in</strong>guistic form. British Journal of Sociology 10, 311326.Bernste<strong>in</strong>, Basil (1960) <strong>Language</strong> and social class. British Journal of Sociology 11,271276.Bernste<strong>in</strong>, Basil (1962a) L<strong>in</strong>guistic codes, hesitation phenomena and <strong>in</strong>telligence.<strong>Language</strong> and Speech 5, 3146.Bernste<strong>in</strong>, Basil (1962b) Social class, l<strong>in</strong>guistic codes and grammatical elements.<strong>Language</strong> and Speech 5, 221240.Bernste<strong>in</strong>, Basil (1971) Class, Codes and Control, Volume 1: Theoretical StudiesTowards a Sociology of <strong>Language</strong>. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.Bernste<strong>in</strong>, Basil (1972a) Social class, language and socialization. In P.P. Giglioli(ed.) <strong>Language</strong> and Social Context. Harmondsworth: Pengu<strong>in</strong>.Bernste<strong>in</strong>, Basil (1972b) A critique of <strong>the</strong> concept of compensatory education. InC. Cazden, V. John and D. Hymes (eds) Functions of <strong>Language</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>.New York: Teachers College Press.Bernste<strong>in</strong>, Basil (1987) Social class, codes and communication. In U. Ammon, N.Dittmar and K. Mat<strong>the</strong>ier (eds) Soziol<strong>in</strong>guistik: E<strong>in</strong> Internationales Handbuch zurWissenschaft von Sprache und Gesellschaft. Berl<strong>in</strong>: Walter de Gruyter.Bernste<strong>in</strong>, Basil (1990) Class, Codes and Control, Volume 4: The Structur<strong>in</strong>g ofPedagogic Discourse. London: Routledge.Bernste<strong>in</strong>, Basil (1996) Class, Codes and Control, Volume 5: Pedagogy, SymbolicControl and Identity: Theory, Research, Critique. London: Routledge.Bernste<strong>in</strong>, Basil (1997) Sociol<strong>in</strong>guistics: A personal view. In C. Paulston andG.R. Tucker (eds) The Early Days of Sociol<strong>in</strong>guistics: Memories and Reflections.Dallas, TX: Summer Institute of L<strong>in</strong>guistics.Berry, John, Rudy Kal<strong>in</strong> and Donald Taylor (1977) Multiculturalism and EthnicAttitudes <strong>in</strong> Canada. Ottawa: Supply and Services Canada.Bex, Tony and Richard Watts (1999) Introduction. In T. Bex and R. Watts (eds)Standard English: Widen<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> Debate. London: Routledge.Beykont, Z. (ed.) (2002) The Power of Culture: Teach<strong>in</strong>g Across <strong>Language</strong> Difference.Cambridge, MA: Harvard Educational Publish<strong>in</strong>g.Bhatia, Tej and William Ritchie (2004) The Handbook of Bil<strong>in</strong>gualism. Oxford:Blackwell (paperback edition, 2006).Billig, Michael (1988) Review of Discourse and Social Psychology (Jonathan Potterand Margaret We<strong>the</strong>rell). The Psychologist 1, 23.B<strong>in</strong>et, Alfred (1909) Les idées modernes sur les enfants. Paris: Flammarion.Black, Edw<strong>in</strong> (2003) War Aga<strong>in</strong>st <strong>the</strong> Weak: Eugenics and America’s Campaign toCreate a Master Race. New York: Four Walls Eight W<strong>in</strong>dows.Black, Ray (2004) Where did we go wrong? Bill Cosby and <strong>the</strong> anxiety ofcommunal responsibility. The Black Scholar 34 (4), 1619.Blanco, George (1983) Review of Hunger of Memory (Richard Rodriguez). Modern<strong>Language</strong> Journal 67, 282283.


References 293Blank, Marion (1982) Mov<strong>in</strong>g beyond <strong>the</strong> difference-deficit debate. In L. Feagansand D. Farran (eds) The <strong>Language</strong> of Children Reared <strong>in</strong> Poverty. New York:Academic Press.Block, Ned and Gerald Dwork<strong>in</strong> (eds) (1976) The IQ Controversy: Critical Read<strong>in</strong>gs.New York: Pan<strong>the</strong>on.Blommaert, Jan (2005) Discourse: A Critical Introduction. Cambridge: CambridgeUniversity Press.Bloom, Benjam<strong>in</strong> (1969) The Jensen article. Harvard Educational Review 39,419421.Bloom, Benjam<strong>in</strong>, Allison Davis and Robert Hess (1965) Compensatory Educationfor Cultural Deprivation. New York: Holt, R<strong>in</strong>ehart & W<strong>in</strong>ston.Bloomfield, Leonard (1927) Literate and illiterate speech. American Speech 2,432439.Bloomfield, Leonard (1933) <strong>Language</strong>. New York: Holt.Boberg, Charles (1999) The attitud<strong>in</strong>al component of variation <strong>in</strong> AmericanEnglish foreign Ba nativization. Journal of <strong>Language</strong> and Social Psychology18, 4961.Bodmer, Walter (1972) Race and IQ: The genetic background. In K. Richardson,D. Spears and M. Richards (eds) Race, Culture and Intelligence. Harmondsworth:Pengu<strong>in</strong>.Borges, Jorge Luis (1999) Collected Fictions (A. Hurley, trans.). London: Pengu<strong>in</strong>.Bor<strong>in</strong>g, Edw<strong>in</strong> (1923) Intelligence as <strong>the</strong> tests test it. The New Republic, June(no. 35), 3537.De Bose, Charles (2005) The Sociology of African American <strong>Language</strong>: A <strong>Language</strong>Plann<strong>in</strong>g Perspective. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.Bourdieu, Pierre (1989) The Logic of Practice. Cambridge: Polity (orig<strong>in</strong>al: Le senspratique. Paris: M<strong>in</strong>uit, 1980).Bourdieu, Pierre and Jean-Claude Passeron (1977) Reproduction <strong>in</strong> Education,Society and Culture. London: Sage (orig<strong>in</strong>al: La reproduction: éléments pour unethéorie du système d’enseignement. Paris: M<strong>in</strong>uit, 1970).Brace, Charles Lor<strong>in</strong>g (2005) ‘Race’ is a Four-Letter Word: The Genesis of <strong>the</strong> Concept.Oxford: Oxford University Press.Breton, Raymond (1986) Multiculturalism and Canadian nation-build<strong>in</strong>g. InA. Cairns and C. Williams (eds) The Politics of Gender, Ethnicity and <strong>Language</strong><strong>in</strong> Canada. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.Breton, Raymond, Jeffrey Reitz and Victor Valent<strong>in</strong>e (1980) Cultural Boundaries and<strong>the</strong> Cohesion of Canada. Montreal: Institute for Research on Public Policy.Brigham, Carl (1923) A Study of American Intelligence. Pr<strong>in</strong>ceton, NJ: Pr<strong>in</strong>cetonUniversity Press.British Broadcast<strong>in</strong>g Corporation (BBC) (2006) Reaction to UK ‘core values’ idea.15 May. On WWW at www.newsvote.bbc.co.uk.Brook, G.L. (George Leslie) (1963) English Dialects. London: André Deutsch.Brook, G.L. (George Leslie) (1970) The <strong>Language</strong> of Dickens. London: AndréDeutsch.Brookes, Mart<strong>in</strong> (2004) Extreme Measures: The Dark Visions and Bright Ideas ofFrancis Galton. London: Bloomsbury.Brouwer, Niels and Fred Korthagen (2005) Can teacher education make adifference? American Educational Research Journal 42, 153224.


294 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>Brown, Christopher (ed.) (2007) Still not Equal: Expand<strong>in</strong>g Educational Opportunity<strong>in</strong> Society. New York: Lang.Brown, Penelope and Stephen Lev<strong>in</strong>son (1987) Politeness: Some Universals <strong>in</strong><strong>Language</strong> Use. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Bru<strong>in</strong>ius, Harry (2006) Better for All <strong>the</strong> World: The Secret History of ForcedSterilization and America’s Quest for Racial Purity. New York: Knopf.Brumfit, Christopher (2001) Individual Freedom <strong>in</strong> <strong>Language</strong> Teach<strong>in</strong>g. Oxford:Oxford University Press.Bullock, Alan (1975) A <strong>Language</strong> for Life (Bullock Report). Department ofEducation and Science (London): HMSO.Bullivant, Brian (1981) The Pluralist Dilemma <strong>in</strong> Education. Sydney: Allen &Unw<strong>in</strong>.Burnet, Jean (1975) The policy of multiculturalism with<strong>in</strong> a bil<strong>in</strong>gual framework.In A. Wolfgang (ed.) Education of Immigrant Students. Toronto: Ontario Institutefor Studies <strong>in</strong> Education.Burtonwood, Neil and Robert Bruce (1999) Cultural sensitivity: American andBritish teacher tra<strong>in</strong>ees compared a response to Thomas Deer<strong>in</strong>g. EducationalResearch 41, 9499.Buss, Allan (1976) Galton and sex differences: An historical note. Journal of <strong>the</strong>History of <strong>the</strong> Behavioral Sciences 12, 283285.Butler, Samuel (1850) The Poetical Works of Samuel Butler: Volume 2. London: Bell &Daldy.Butts, R. Freeman, Donald Peckenpaugh and Howard Kirschenbaum (1977) TheSchool’s Role as Moral Authority. Wash<strong>in</strong>gton, DC: Association for Supervisionand Curriculum Development.Caldas, Stephen (2006) Rais<strong>in</strong>g Bil<strong>in</strong>gual-Biliterate Children <strong>in</strong> Monoliterate Cultures.Clevedon: Multil<strong>in</strong>gual Matters.Callender, Tricia (2005) A deeper level of diversity: L<strong>in</strong>guistic and culturalrecognition for <strong>the</strong> ‘new’ black student <strong>in</strong> NYC: The Barbadian example. InZ. Zakharia and T. Arnste<strong>in</strong> (eds) <strong>Language</strong>s, Communities and Education.New York: Teachers College, Columbia University.Cameron, Deborah (1995) Verbal Hygiene. London: Routledge.Campos de Souza, Leone and Paulo Nascimento (2008) Brazilian national identityat a crossroads: The myth of racial democracy and <strong>the</strong> development of blackidentity. International Journal of Politics, Culture and Society 19, 129143.Cane, Don (2004) Bill Cosby rants aga<strong>in</strong>st ghetto poor: The crisis of blackleadership. Workers Vanguard, 17 September (no. 832). International CommunistLeague. On WWW at www.icl-fi.org.Carey, Benedict (2006) Study f<strong>in</strong>ds a l<strong>in</strong>k of drug makers to psychiatrists. TheNew York Times, 20 April.Carlson, Elof Axel (2001) The Unfit: A History of a Bad Idea. Cold Spr<strong>in</strong>g Harbor,NY: Cold Spr<strong>in</strong>g Harbor Laboratory Press.Carr, Jo and Anne Pauwels (2006) Boys and Foreign <strong>Language</strong> Learn<strong>in</strong>g: Real BoysDon’t Do <strong>Language</strong>s. Bas<strong>in</strong>gstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.Carranza, Miguel and Ellen Bouchard Ryan (1975) Evaluative reactions ofbil<strong>in</strong>gual Anglo and Mexican American adolescents toward speakers ofEnglish and Spanish. International Journal of <strong>the</strong> Sociology of <strong>Language</strong> 6,83104.


References 295Carr<strong>in</strong>gton, Bruce and John Williamson (1987) The deficit hypo<strong>the</strong>sis revisited.Educational Studies 13, 239245.Carroll, John (1972) <strong>Language</strong>, Thought and Reality: Selected Writ<strong>in</strong>gs of Benjam<strong>in</strong> LeeWhorf. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Carter, Robert (2000) Realism and Racism: Concepts of Race <strong>in</strong> Sociological Research.London: Routledge.Carter, Robert (2007) Genes, genomes and genealogies: The return of scientificracism? Ethnic and Racial Studies 30, 546556.Casanova, Ursula (1991) Bil<strong>in</strong>gual education: Politics or pedagogy? In OfeliaGarcía (ed.) Bil<strong>in</strong>gual Education: Focusschrift <strong>in</strong> Honor of Joshua A. Fishman.Amsterdam: John Benjam<strong>in</strong>s.Castro, Max (1992) On <strong>the</strong> curious question of language <strong>in</strong> Miami. In J. Crawford(ed.) <strong>Language</strong> Loyalties: A Source Book on <strong>the</strong> Official English Controversy.Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.Cazden, Courtney (1988) <strong>Classroom</strong> Discourse. Portsmouth, NH: He<strong>in</strong>emann.Chambers, Jack (1995) Sociol<strong>in</strong>guistic Theory. Oxford: Blackwell.Chambers, Jack, Peter Trudgill and Natalie Schill<strong>in</strong>g-Estes (eds) (2002) TheHandbook of <strong>Language</strong> Variation and Change. Oxford: Blackwell.Chapman, Paul (1988) Schools as Sorters: Lewis M. Terman, Applied Psychology,and <strong>the</strong> Intelligence Test<strong>in</strong>g Movement, 18901930. New York: New YorkUniversity Press.Chapman, Raymond (1994) Forms of Speech <strong>in</strong> Victorian Fiction. London: Longman.Cheshire, Jenny, Viv Edwards, Henk Münstermann and Bert Weltens (1989)Dialect and education <strong>in</strong> Europe: A general perspective. In J. Cheshire,V. Edwards, H. Münstermann and B. Weltens (eds) Dialect and Education: SomeEuropean Perspectives. Clevedon: Multil<strong>in</strong>gual Matters.Cheyne, William (1970) Stereotyped reactions to speakers with Scottish andEnglish regional accents. British Journal of Social and Cl<strong>in</strong>ical Psychology 9,7779.Chilton, Paul (2003) Analys<strong>in</strong>g Political Discourse: Theory and Practice. London:Routledge.Chimpanzee Sequenc<strong>in</strong>g and Analysis Consortium (2005) Initial sequence of <strong>the</strong>chimpanzee genome and comparison with <strong>the</strong> human genome. Nature 437(7055), 6987.Chomsky, Noam (1977) Dialogues ave Mitsou Ronat. Paris: Flammarion.Choy, Stephen and David Dodd (1976) Standard-English-speak<strong>in</strong>g and nonstandardHawaiian English-speak<strong>in</strong>g children: Comprehension of bothdialects and teachers’ evaluations. Journal of Educational Psychology 68,184193.Chrismer, Sara, Shannon Hodge and Debby Sa<strong>in</strong>til (eds) (2006) Assess<strong>in</strong>g NCLB:Perspectives and Prescriptions. Cambridge, MA: Harvard Education Press(Harvard Educational Review 76 (4)).Christenfeld, Nicholas and Britta Larsen (2008) The name game. The Psychologist21, 211213.Christie, Frances (ed.) (1999) Pedagogy and <strong>the</strong> Shap<strong>in</strong>g of Consciousness: L<strong>in</strong>guisticand Social Processes. London: Cassell.Clarke, Alan and Ann Clarke (2006) Born to be bright? The Psychologist 19, 409.Clyne, Michael (2005) Australia’s <strong>Language</strong> Potential. Sydney: University of NewSouth Wales Press.


296 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>Čmejrková, Svetla and Carlo Prevignano (2003) On conversation analysis:An <strong>in</strong>terview with Emanuel A. Schegloff. In C. Prevignano and P. Thibault(eds) Discuss<strong>in</strong>g Conversation Analysis: The Work of Emanuel A. Schegloff.Amsterdam: John Benjam<strong>in</strong>s.Coard, Bernard (1971) How <strong>the</strong> West Indian Child is Made Educationally Subnormal<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> British School System. London: New Beacon Books.Coates, Jennifer (1996) Women Talk. Oxford: Blackwell.Coates, Jennifer (2003) Men Talk. Oxford: Blackwell.Coates, Jennifer (2004) Women, Men and <strong>Language</strong>. London: Longman.Coates, Ta-Nehisi (2008) ‘This is how we lost to <strong>the</strong> white man’. Atlantic, May(301: 4), 5262.Cochran-Smith, Marilyn (1995) Color bl<strong>in</strong>dness and basket mak<strong>in</strong>g are not <strong>the</strong>answers: Confront<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> dilemmas of race, culture, and language diversity<strong>in</strong> teacher education. American Educational Research Journal 32, 493522.Coenders, Marcel, Marcel Lubbers, Peer Scheepers and Maykel Verkuyten (2008)More than two decades of chang<strong>in</strong>g ethnic attitudes <strong>in</strong> The Ne<strong>the</strong>rlands.Journal of Social Issues 64, 269285.Cole, Johnnetta (2004) On speak<strong>in</strong>g truth to ourselves and do<strong>in</strong>g right by ourchildren. The Black Scholar 34 (4), 69.Cole, Michael and Jerome Bruner (1972) Prelim<strong>in</strong>aries to a <strong>the</strong>ory of culturaldifferences. In I. Gordon (ed.) Early Childhood Education. Chicago, IL:University of Chicago Press.Coleman, James (1966) Equality of Educational Opportunity. Wash<strong>in</strong>gton, DC:United States Government Pr<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g Office.Coleman, James (1968) Review of Studies <strong>in</strong> Ethnomethodology (Harold Garf<strong>in</strong>kel).American Sociological Review 33, 126130.Colman, Andrew (1987) Facts, Fallacies and Frauds <strong>in</strong> Psychology. London:Hutch<strong>in</strong>son.Comm<strong>in</strong>s, Nancy and Ofelia Miramontes (1989) Perceived and actual l<strong>in</strong>guisticcompetence: A descriptive study of four low-achiev<strong>in</strong>g Hispanic bil<strong>in</strong>gualstudents. American Educational Research Journal 26, 443472.Committee on Irish <strong>Language</strong> Attitudes Research (1975) Report. Dubl<strong>in</strong>: GovernmentStationery Office.Condry, John and Sandra Condry (1976) Sex differences: A study of <strong>the</strong> eye of <strong>the</strong>beholder. Child Development 47, 812819.Condry, Sandra, John Condry and Lee Pogatshnik (1983) Sex differences: A studyof <strong>the</strong> ear of <strong>the</strong> beholder. Sex Roles 9, 697704.Connor, Ulla and Ana Moreno (2005) Tertium Comparationis: A vital component<strong>in</strong> contrastive rhetoric research. In P. Bruthiaux, D. Atk<strong>in</strong>son, W. Egg<strong>in</strong>gton,W. Grabe and V. Ramanathan (eds) Directions <strong>in</strong> Applied L<strong>in</strong>guistics: Essays<strong>in</strong> Honor of Robert B. Kaplan. Clevedon: Multil<strong>in</strong>gual Matters.Connors, Brian (1984) A multicultural curriculum as action for social justice. InS. Shapson and V. d’Oyley (eds) Bil<strong>in</strong>gual and Multicultural Education.Clevedon: Multil<strong>in</strong>gual Matters.Cook, Eung-Do (1998) Aborig<strong>in</strong>al languages: History. In J. Edwards (ed.)<strong>Language</strong> <strong>in</strong> Canada. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Cook-Gumperz, Jenny (1973) Social Control and Socialization: A Study of ClassDifferences <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Language</strong> of Maternal Control. London: Routledge & KeganPaul.


References 297Cooper, Harris (1979) Pygmalion grows up: A model for teacher expectationcommunication and performance <strong>in</strong>fluence. Review of Educational Research 49,389410.Cooper, Harris and Thomas Good (1983) Pygmalion Grows Up: Studies <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>Expectation Communication Process. New York: Longman.Corbett, Anne (2000) Lady Plowden (obituary). The Guardian, 3 October.Corson, David (1993) <strong>Language</strong>, M<strong>in</strong>ority Education and Gender. Clevedon: Multil<strong>in</strong>gualMatters.Corson, David (2001) <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> and Education. Mahwah, NJ: LawrenceErlbaum.Cosby, William (1997) Elements of igno-ebonics style. The Wall Street Journal, 10January.Cosby, William (2004) Dr Bill Cosby speaks at <strong>the</strong> 50th anniversary commemorationof <strong>the</strong> Brown v. Topeka Board of Education Supreme Court decision. The BlackScholar 34 (4), 25.Coser, Lewis (1975) Presidential address: Two methods <strong>in</strong> search of a substance.American Sociological Review 40, 691700.Cosgrove, Lisa, Sheldon Krimsky, Manisha Vijayaraghavan and Lisa Schneider(2006) F<strong>in</strong>ancial ties between DSM-IV panel members and <strong>the</strong> pharmaceutical<strong>in</strong>dustry. Psycho<strong>the</strong>rapy and Psychosomatics 75, 154160.Coulmas, Florian (2005) Sociol<strong>in</strong>guistics: The Study of Speakers’ Choices. Cambridge:Cambridge University Press.Coulthard, Michael (1969) A discussion of restricted and elaborated codes.Educational Review 22, 3850.Cov<strong>in</strong>gton, Ann (1976) Black people and Black English: Attitudes and deeducation<strong>in</strong> a biased macroculture. In D. Harrison and T. Trabasso (eds) BlackEnglish: A Sem<strong>in</strong>ar. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.Crawford, James (1989) Bil<strong>in</strong>gual Education: History, Politics, Theory and Practice.Trenton, NJ: Crane.Crawford, James (1992a) Hold Your Tongue: Bil<strong>in</strong>gualism and <strong>the</strong> Politics of ‘EnglishOnly’. Read<strong>in</strong>g, MA: Addison-Wesley.Crawford, James (ed.) (1992b) <strong>Language</strong> Loyalties: A Source Book on <strong>the</strong> OfficialEnglish Controversy. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.Crawford, James (2000) At War With <strong>Diversity</strong>: U.S. <strong>Language</strong> Policy <strong>in</strong> an Age ofAnxiety. Clevedon: Multil<strong>in</strong>gual Matters.Crawford, James (2004) Educat<strong>in</strong>g English Learners: <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong><strong>Classroom</strong>. Los Angeles, CA: Bil<strong>in</strong>gual Education Services (<strong>the</strong> 5th edition ofBil<strong>in</strong>gual Education: History, Politics, Theory and Practice).Crawford, Mary (1995) Talk<strong>in</strong>g Difference: On Gender and <strong>Language</strong>. London: Sage.Creese, Angela and Peter Mart<strong>in</strong> (eds) (2006a) Interaction <strong>in</strong> Complementary SchoolContexts. Clevedon: Multil<strong>in</strong>gual Matters (<strong>Language</strong> and Education 20 (1)).Creese, Angela and Peter Mart<strong>in</strong> (2006b) Interaction <strong>in</strong> complementary schoolcontexts: Develop<strong>in</strong>g identities of choice an <strong>in</strong>troduction. <strong>Language</strong> andEducation 20, 14.Cronbach, Lee (1975) Five decades of public controversy over mental test<strong>in</strong>g.American Psychologist 30, 114.Crook, Paul (2002) American eugenics and <strong>the</strong> Nazis. The European Legacy 7, 363381.


298 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>Crook, Paul (2007) Darw<strong>in</strong>’s Coat-Tails: Essays on Social Darw<strong>in</strong>ism. New York:Peter Lang.Crowley, Tony (1989) The Politics of Discourse: The Standard <strong>Language</strong> Question <strong>in</strong>British Cultural Debates. London: Macmillan.Crowley, Tony (1999) Curiouser and curiouser: Fall<strong>in</strong>g standards <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> StandardEnglish debate. In T. Bex and R. Watts (eds) Standard English: Widen<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>Debate. London: Routledge.Crowley, Tony (2003) Standard English and <strong>the</strong> Politics of <strong>Language</strong>. London:Palgrave Macmillan (2nd edn of Crowley, 1989).Crystal, David (1983) Review of The <strong>Language</strong> Trap (John Honey). BritishAssociation for Applied L<strong>in</strong>guistics Newsletter 18, 4250 (repr<strong>in</strong>ted <strong>in</strong> English <strong>in</strong>Education (NATE), 1984 (18: 1), 5465).Cumm<strong>in</strong>s, Jim (1986) Empower<strong>in</strong>g m<strong>in</strong>ority students: A framework for <strong>in</strong>tervention.Harvard Educational Review 56, 1836.Cumm<strong>in</strong>s, Jim (1996) Negotiat<strong>in</strong>g Identities: Education for Empowerment <strong>in</strong> a DiverseSociety. Sacramento, CA: California Association for Bil<strong>in</strong>gual Education.Cumm<strong>in</strong>s, Jim (1998) The teach<strong>in</strong>g of <strong>in</strong>ternational languages. In J. Edwards (ed.)<strong>Language</strong> <strong>in</strong> Canada. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Cumm<strong>in</strong>s, Jim (2005) A proposal for action: Strategies for recogniz<strong>in</strong>g heritagelanguage competence as a learn<strong>in</strong>g resource with<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> ma<strong>in</strong>stream classroom.Modern <strong>Language</strong> Journal 89, 585592 (this article is followed (pp. 592616) bycommentaries from Scott McG<strong>in</strong>nis, Terrence Wiley, Ofelia García, NancyHornberger, Jan<strong>in</strong>e Brutt-Griffler and S<strong>in</strong>free Makoni, and Kees de Bot andDurk Gorter).Cutts, Mark (ed.) (2000) The State of <strong>the</strong> World’s Refugees, 2000: Fifty Years ofHumanitarian Action. New York: Oxford University Press and Geneva: Office of<strong>the</strong> United Nations High Commissioner for Refugees.D’Amato, John (1987) The belly of <strong>the</strong> beast: On cultural differences, castelikestatus, and <strong>the</strong> politics of school. Anthropology and Education Quarterly 18,357360.d’Anglejan, Alison and G. Richard Tucker (1973) Sociol<strong>in</strong>guistic correlates ofspeech style <strong>in</strong> Quebec. In R. Shuy and R. Fasold (eds) <strong>Language</strong> Attitudes:Current Trends and Prospects. Wash<strong>in</strong>gton, DC: Georgetown University Press.Daniel, G. Reg<strong>in</strong>ald (2006) Race and Multiraciality <strong>in</strong> Brazil and <strong>the</strong> United States:Converg<strong>in</strong>g Paths? University Park, PA: Pennsylvania State University Press.Daugherity, Brian and Charles Bolton (eds) (2008) With All Deliberate Speed:Implement<strong>in</strong>g Brown v. Board of Education. Fayetteville, AR: University ofArkansas Press.Davenport, Charles (1911) Heredity <strong>in</strong> Relation to Eugenics. New York: Holt.Davies, Alan (1985) Standard and dialect English: The unacknowledgedidealisation of sociol<strong>in</strong>guistics. Journal of Multil<strong>in</strong>gual and MulticulturalDevelopment 6, 183192.Davies, Alan (1987) Review of <strong>Language</strong>, Structure and Reproduction (PaulAtk<strong>in</strong>son). <strong>Language</strong> Problems and <strong>Language</strong> Plann<strong>in</strong>g 11, 370372.Davis, Philip (ed.) (1920) Immigration and Americanization: Selected Read<strong>in</strong>gs.Boston, MA: G<strong>in</strong>n.Day, Richard (1982) Children’s attitudes towards language. In E. Bouchard Ryanand H. Giles (eds) Attitudes Towards <strong>Language</strong> Variation: Social and AppliedContexts. London: Edward Arnold.


References 299Deák, Julia (2007) African-American language and American l<strong>in</strong>guistic cultures:An analysis of language policies <strong>in</strong> education. Work<strong>in</strong>g Papers <strong>in</strong> EducationalL<strong>in</strong>guistics (Graduate School of Education, University of Pennsylvania) 22 (1),105134.Deer<strong>in</strong>g, Thomas (1997) Prepar<strong>in</strong>g to teach diverse student populations: A Britishand American perspective. Educational Research 39, 342350.Delgado-Gaitan, Concha (1992) School matters <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Mexican-American <strong>home</strong>:Socializ<strong>in</strong>g children to education. American Educational Research Journal 29,495513.Delgado-Gaitan, Concha and Henry Trueba (1991) Cross<strong>in</strong>g Cultural Borders:Education for Immigrant Families <strong>in</strong> America. London: Falmer.Dennis, Wayne (1960) Causes of retardation among <strong>in</strong>stitutional children: Iran.Journal of Genetic Psychology 96, 4759.Department of Canadian Heritage (2000) Annual Report on <strong>the</strong> Operation of <strong>the</strong>Canadian Multiculturalism Act. Ottawa: Supply & Services Canada.Derw<strong>in</strong>g, Tracey (2003) What do ESL students say about <strong>the</strong>ir accents? CanadianModern <strong>Language</strong> Review 59, 547566.Deutsch, Mart<strong>in</strong> (1967) The Disadvantaged Child. New York: Basic Books.Deutsch, Nathaniel (2009) Invent<strong>in</strong>g America’s ‘Worst’ Family: Eugenics, Islam, and<strong>the</strong> Fall and Rise of <strong>the</strong> Tribe of Ishmael. Berkeley, CA: University of CaliforniaPress.De Valdes, María (1979) Bil<strong>in</strong>gual education program for Spanish-speak<strong>in</strong>gchildren <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> United States. Canadian Modern <strong>Language</strong> Review 35, 407414.Dev<strong>in</strong>e, Philip (1996) Human <strong>Diversity</strong> and <strong>the</strong> Culture Wars. Westport, CT: Praeger.Dicker, Susan (2003) <strong>Language</strong>s <strong>in</strong> America: A Pluralist View (2nd edn). Clevedon:Multil<strong>in</strong>gual Matters.Didion, Joan (1987) Miami. New York: Simon & Schuster.Dittmar, Norbert (1976) Sociol<strong>in</strong>guistics: A Critical Survey of Theory and Application.London: Edward Arnold.Dornbusch, Sanford, Philip Ritter and Laurence Ste<strong>in</strong>berg (1991) Community<strong>in</strong>fluences on <strong>the</strong> relation of family statuses to adolescent school performance:Differences between African American and non-Hispanic whites. AmericanJournal of Education 38, 543567.Dörnyei, Zoltán (2005) The Psychology of <strong>the</strong> <strong>Language</strong> Learner. Mahwah, NJ:Lawrence Erlbaum.Dörnyei, Zoltán and Richard Schmidt (eds) (2001) Motivation and Second <strong>Language</strong>Acquisition. Honolulu, HI: University of Hawaii Press.Dörnyei, Zoltán and Ema Ushioda (eds) (2009) Motivation, <strong>Language</strong> Identity and<strong>the</strong> L2 Self. Bristol: Multil<strong>in</strong>gual Matters.Dos Passos, John (1963) Cogitations <strong>in</strong> a Roman <strong>the</strong>atre. Modern Age 8 (1), 7783.Dos Passos, John (1964) The use of <strong>the</strong> past. In Occasions and Protests. New York:Regnery (this essay was first published <strong>in</strong> The Ground We Stand On. New York:Harcourt, Brace & World, 1941).Dowbigg<strong>in</strong>, Ian (1997) Keep<strong>in</strong>g America Sane: Psychiatry and Eugenics <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> UnitedStates and Canada, 18801940. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Drapeau, Lynne (1998) Aborig<strong>in</strong>al languages: Current status. In J. Edwards (ed.)<strong>Language</strong> <strong>in</strong> Canada. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.D’Souza, Jean (2006) <strong>Language</strong>, education and <strong>the</strong> rights of <strong>the</strong> child. WorldEnglishes 25, 155166.


300 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>Dunbar, William (1508) The Flyt<strong>in</strong>g of Dunbar and Kennedy [sic]. Ed<strong>in</strong>burgh:Chepman & Myllar.Dyson, Michael (2005) Is Bill Cosby Right: Or Has <strong>the</strong> Black Middle Class Lost ItsM<strong>in</strong>d? New York: Basic Civitas.The Economist (2008) Nearer to overcom<strong>in</strong>g. 10 May (387: 8579), 3335.Edelman, Peter, Harry Holzer and Paul Offner (2006) Reconnect<strong>in</strong>g DisadvantagedYoung Men. Wash<strong>in</strong>gton, DC: Urban Institute.Edelsky, Carole, Sarah Hudelson, Barbara Flores, Florence Bark<strong>in</strong>, Bess Altwergerand Krist<strong>in</strong>a Jilbert (1983) Semil<strong>in</strong>gualism and language deficit. AppliedL<strong>in</strong>guistics 4, 122.Edmonds, Alexander (2007) ‘Triumphant miscegenation’: Reflections on beautyand race <strong>in</strong> Brazil. Journal of Intercultural Studies 28, 8397.Edwards, Anthony (1974) Social class and l<strong>in</strong>guistic <strong>in</strong>ference. Research <strong>in</strong>Education 12, 7180.Edwards, Anthony (1976) <strong>Language</strong> <strong>in</strong> Culture and Class. London: He<strong>in</strong>emann.Edwards, Anthony (1987a) Review of <strong>Language</strong>, Structure and Reproduction (PaulAtk<strong>in</strong>son). Journal of <strong>Language</strong> and Social Psychology 6, 6770.Edwards, Anthony (1987b) <strong>Language</strong> codes and classroom practice. OxfordReview of Education 13, 237247.Edwards, Derek and Neil Mercer (1986) Context and cont<strong>in</strong>uity: <strong>Classroom</strong>discourse and <strong>the</strong> development of shared knowledge. In K. Durk<strong>in</strong> (ed.)<strong>Language</strong> Development <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> School Years. London: Croom Helm.Edwards, John (1974) Characteristics of disadvantaged children. Irish Journal ofEducation 8, 4961.Edwards, John (1977a) Read<strong>in</strong>g, language and disadvantage. In V. Greaney (ed.)Studies <strong>in</strong> Read<strong>in</strong>g. Dubl<strong>in</strong>: Educational Company.Edwards, John (1977b) The speech of disadvantaged Dubl<strong>in</strong> children. <strong>Language</strong>Problems and <strong>Language</strong> Plann<strong>in</strong>g 1, 6572.Edwards, John (1977c) Review of Report (Committee on Irish <strong>Language</strong> AttitudesResearch). <strong>Language</strong> Problems and <strong>Language</strong> Plann<strong>in</strong>g 1, 5459.Edwards, John (1979a) Social class differences and <strong>the</strong> identification of sex <strong>in</strong>children’s speech. Journal of Child <strong>Language</strong> 6, 121127.Edwards, John (1979b) Judgements and confidence <strong>in</strong> reactions to disadvantagedspeech. In H. Giles and R. St. Clair (eds) <strong>Language</strong> and Social Psychology.Oxford: Blackwell.Edwards, John (1981) Disadvantage: Guilt by association. Educational Psychology1, 101103.Edwards, John (1982) <strong>Language</strong> attitudes and <strong>the</strong>ir implications among Englishspeakers. In E. Bouchard Ryan and H. Giles (eds) Attitudes Toward <strong>Language</strong>Variation: Social and Applied Contexts. London: Edward Arnold.Edwards, John (1983a) Review article on The <strong>Language</strong> Trap (John Honey). Journalof <strong>Language</strong> and Social Psychology 2, 6776.Edwards, John (1983b) Ethno-<strong>in</strong>quiry: Renaissance or illusion? Unpublishedpaper, St Francis Xavier University (available upon request).Edwards, John (1983c) <strong>Language</strong> attitudes <strong>in</strong> multil<strong>in</strong>gual sett<strong>in</strong>gs: A generalassessment. Journal of Multil<strong>in</strong>gual and Multicultural Development 4, 225236.Edwards, John (1984) <strong>Language</strong>, diversity and identity. In J. Edwards (ed.)L<strong>in</strong>guistic M<strong>in</strong>orities, Policies and Pluralism. London: Academic Press.


References 301Edwards, John (1985) <strong>Language</strong>, Society and Identity. Oxford: Blackwell (<strong>in</strong>association with André Deutsch).Edwards, John (1987) Elaborated and restricted codes. In U. Ammon, N. Dittmarand K. Mat<strong>the</strong>ier (eds) Soziol<strong>in</strong>guistik: E<strong>in</strong> Internationales Handbuch zurWissenschaft von Sprache und Gesellschaft. Berl<strong>in</strong>: Walter de Gruyter.Edwards, John (1989) <strong>Language</strong> and Disadvantage (2nd rev edn). London: Cole &Whurr (orig<strong>in</strong>al, London: Edward Arnold, 1979).Edwards, John (1990) Social purposes of bil<strong>in</strong>gual education: U.S. English, <strong>the</strong>ELA, and o<strong>the</strong>r matters. In G. Imhoff (ed.) Learn<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> Two <strong>Language</strong>s: FromConflict to Consensus <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Reorganization of Schools. New Brunswick, NJ:Transaction.Edwards, John (1993) Identity and language <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Canadian educational context.In M. Danesi, K. McLeod and S. Morris (eds) Heritage <strong>Language</strong>s and Education:The Canadian Experience. Toronto: Mosaic.Edwards, John (1994a) Multil<strong>in</strong>gualism. London: Routledge.Edwards, John (1994b) Identity, soft multiculturalism, language and <strong>the</strong> mapp<strong>in</strong>gof <strong>the</strong> middle ground. Paper presented at Multikulturelt Samfund og EtniskIdentitet conference, Odense University, December.Edwards, John (1999a) Ref<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g our understand<strong>in</strong>g of language attitudes. Journalof <strong>Language</strong> and Social Psychology 18, 101110.Edwards, John (1999b) Reactions to three types of speech sample from rural blackand white children. In L. Falk and M. Harry (eds) The English <strong>Language</strong> <strong>in</strong> NovaScotia. Lockeport, Nova Scotia: Roseway.Edwards, John (2001) <strong>Language</strong>s and language learn<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> face of worldEnglish. Profession, 109120 (Profession is <strong>the</strong> Annual of <strong>the</strong> Modern <strong>Language</strong>Association).Edwards, John (2003a) <strong>Language</strong> and <strong>the</strong> future. In H. Tonk<strong>in</strong> and T. Reagan (eds)<strong>Language</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Twenty-First Century. Amsterdam: John Benjam<strong>in</strong>s.Edwards, John (2003b) Contextualiz<strong>in</strong>g language rights. Journal of Human Rights2, 551571.Edwards, John (2004a) Ecol<strong>in</strong>guistic ideologies: A critical perspective. In M. Pütz,J. Neff-van Aertselaer and T. van Dijk (eds) Communicat<strong>in</strong>g Ideologies: Multidiscipl<strong>in</strong>aryPerspectives on <strong>Language</strong>, Discourse and Social Practice. Frankfurt:Peter Lang.Edwards, John (2004b) After <strong>the</strong> fall. Discourse and Society 15, 155184.Edwards, John (2006) Educational failure. In K. Brown (ed.) Encyclopedia of<strong>Language</strong> and L<strong>in</strong>guistics. Oxford: Elsevier.Edwards, John (2008) English <strong>in</strong> Canada. In M. Matto and H. Momma (eds)Blackwell Companion to <strong>the</strong> History of <strong>the</strong> English <strong>Language</strong>. Oxford: Blackwell.Edwards, John (<strong>in</strong> press-a) The treason of translation? Bil<strong>in</strong>gualism, l<strong>in</strong>guisticborders and identity. In H. Tonk<strong>in</strong>, M.E. Frank and M. Moen (eds) TheTranslator as Mediator of Cultures. Amsterdam: John Benjam<strong>in</strong>s.Edwards, John (<strong>in</strong> press-b) <strong>Language</strong> and Identity. Cambridge: CambridgeUniversity Press.Edwards, John (<strong>in</strong> preparation) Irish: The Triumph of Failure?Edwards, John and Joan Chisholm (1987) <strong>Language</strong>, multiculturalism andidentity: A Canadian study. Journal of Multil<strong>in</strong>gual and Multicultural Development8, 391408.


302 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>Edwards, John and Lori Doucette (1987) Ethnic salience, identity and symbolicethnicity. Canadian Ethnic Studies 19, 5262.Edwards, John and Howard Giles (1984) Applications of <strong>the</strong> social psychologyof language: Sociol<strong>in</strong>guistics and education. In P. Trudgill (ed.) AppliedSociol<strong>in</strong>guistics. London: Academic Press.Edwards, John and Margaret McK<strong>in</strong>non (1987) The cont<strong>in</strong>u<strong>in</strong>g appeal ofdisadvantage as deficit: A Canadian study <strong>in</strong> a rural context. Canadian Journalof Education 12, 330349.Edwards, Viv (1986) <strong>Language</strong> <strong>in</strong> a Black Community. Clevedon: Multil<strong>in</strong>gualMatters.Edwards, Viv (1987) Review of Educational L<strong>in</strong>guistic (Michael Stubbs). Journal of<strong>Language</strong> and Social Psychology 6, 141144.Elbow, Peter (2006) When <strong>the</strong> marg<strong>in</strong>s are at <strong>the</strong> center. In S. Nero (ed.) Dialects,Englishes, Creoles and Education. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.Erickson, Frederick (1987) Transformation and school success: The politics andculture of educational achievement. Anthropology and Education Quarterly 18,335356.Evans, Bruce and Nancy Hornberger (2005) No Child Left Beh<strong>in</strong>d: Repeal<strong>in</strong>g andunpeel<strong>in</strong>g federal language education policy <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> United States. <strong>Language</strong>Policy 4, 87106.Evans, Nicholas (1998) Aborig<strong>in</strong>es speak a primitive language. In L. Bauer andP. Trudgill (eds) <strong>Language</strong> Myths. London: Pengu<strong>in</strong>.Ewen, Elizabeth and Stuart Ewen (2006) Typecast<strong>in</strong>g: On <strong>the</strong> Arts and Sciences ofHuman Inequality. New York: Seven Stories.Ew<strong>in</strong>g, E. Thomas (2006) The repudiation of s<strong>in</strong>gle-sex education: Boys’ schools<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Soviet Union, 19431954. American Educational Research Journal 43,621650.Extra, Guus and Durk Gorter (2001) The O<strong>the</strong>r <strong>Language</strong>s of Europe: Demographic,Sociol<strong>in</strong>guistic and Educational Perspectives. Clevedon: Multil<strong>in</strong>gual Matters.Extra, Guus and Kutlay Yağmur (2004) Urban Multil<strong>in</strong>gualism <strong>in</strong> Europe: ImmigrantM<strong>in</strong>ority <strong>Language</strong>s at Home and School. Clevedon: Multil<strong>in</strong>gual Matters.Eysenck, Hans (1975) The Inequality of Man. London: Fontana.Fabricius, Anne (2006) The ‘vivid sociol<strong>in</strong>guistic profil<strong>in</strong>g’ of Received Pronunciation:Responses to gendered dialect-<strong>in</strong>-discourse. Journal of Sociol<strong>in</strong>guistics10, 111122.Fairclough, Norman (1988) <strong>Language</strong> and Power. London: Longman.Fairclough, Norman (1995) Critical Discourse Analysis. London: Longman.Farkas, George, Christy Lleras and Steve Maczuga (2002) Does oppositionalculture exist <strong>in</strong> m<strong>in</strong>ority and poverty peer groups? American Sociological Review67, 148155.Farran, Dale (1982) Intervention for poverty children alternative approaches.In L. Feagans and D. Farran (eds) The <strong>Language</strong> of Children Reared <strong>in</strong> Poverty.New York: Academic Press.Fasold, Ralph (1984) The Sociol<strong>in</strong>guistics of Society. Oxford: Blackwell.Fasold, Ralph (2006) Ebonic [sic] need not be English. In H. Luria, D. Seymourand T. Smoke (eds) <strong>Language</strong> and L<strong>in</strong>guistics <strong>in</strong> Context. Mahwah, NJ: LawrenceErlbaum.Feagans, Lynne and Dale Farran (eds) (1982) The <strong>Language</strong> of Children Reared <strong>in</strong>Poverty. New York: Academic Press.


References 303Ferguson, Charles (1977) L<strong>in</strong>guistic <strong>the</strong>ory. In Center for Applied L<strong>in</strong>guistics (ed.)Bil<strong>in</strong>gual Education: Current Perspectives. Arl<strong>in</strong>gton, VI: CAL.Ferguson, Gibson (2006) <strong>Language</strong> Plann<strong>in</strong>g and Education. Ed<strong>in</strong>burgh: Ed<strong>in</strong>burghUniversity Press.Ferneyhough, Charles (2006) Metaphors of m<strong>in</strong>d. The Psychologist 19, 356358.Ferris, Dana (2005) Reflections of a ‘blue collar l<strong>in</strong>guist’: Analysis of writtendiscourse, classroom research, and EAP pedagogy. In P. Bruthiaux,D. Atk<strong>in</strong>son, W. Egg<strong>in</strong>gton, W. Grabe and V. Ramanathan (eds) Directions <strong>in</strong>Applied L<strong>in</strong>guistics: Essays <strong>in</strong> Honor of Robert B. Kaplan. Clevedon: Multil<strong>in</strong>gualMatters.Fillmore, Charles (2005) A l<strong>in</strong>guist looks at <strong>the</strong> Ebonics debate. In J.D. Ramirez,T. Wiley, G. de Klerk, E. Lee and W. Wright (eds) Ebonics: The Urban EducationDebate (2nd edn). Clevedon: Multil<strong>in</strong>gual Matters.F<strong>in</strong>e, Michelle, Reva Jaffe-Walter, Pedro Pedraza, Valerie Futch and Brett Stoudt(2007) Swimm<strong>in</strong>g: On oxygen, resistance, and possibility for immigrant youthunder siege. Anthropology and Education Quarterly 38, 7696.Firth, Alan (1996) Review of Collegial Discourse and What’s Go<strong>in</strong>g On Here? (AllenGrimshaw). American Journal of Sociology 101, 14871492.Fischer, John (1958) Social <strong>in</strong>fluences on <strong>the</strong> choice of a l<strong>in</strong>guistic variant. Word 14,4756.Fish, Stanley (1998) Boutique multiculturalism. In A. Melzer, J. We<strong>in</strong>bergerand M.R. Z<strong>in</strong>man (eds) Multiculturalism and American Democracy. Lawrence,KS: University Press of Kansas.Fishman, Joshua (1980) Ethnic community mo<strong>the</strong>r tongue schools <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> USA.International Migration Review 14, 235247.Fishman, Joshua (1987) <strong>Language</strong> spread and language policy for endangeredlanguages. In J. Alatis (ed.) Georgetown University Round Table on <strong>Language</strong>s andL<strong>in</strong>guistics. Wash<strong>in</strong>gton, DC: Georgetown University Press.Fishman, Joshua (1996) In Praise of <strong>the</strong> Beloved <strong>Language</strong>. Berl<strong>in</strong>: Mouton deGruyter.Fishman, Joshua (ed.) (1999) Handbook of <strong>Language</strong> and Ethnic Identity. Oxford:Oxford University Press.Fishman, Joshua (ed.) (2001) Can Threatened <strong>Language</strong>s be Saved? Clevedon:Multil<strong>in</strong>gual Matters.Fishman, Joshua (2006) Sociol<strong>in</strong>guistics: More power(s) to you (On <strong>the</strong> explicitstudy of power <strong>in</strong> sociol<strong>in</strong>guistic research). In M. Pütz, J. Fishman and J. NeffvanAertselaer (eds) Along <strong>the</strong> Routes to Power. Berl<strong>in</strong>: Mouton de Gruyter.Flores, Barbara (2005) The <strong>in</strong>tellectual presence of <strong>the</strong> deficit view of Spanishspeak<strong>in</strong>gchildren <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> educational literature dur<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> 20th century. InP. Pedraza and M. Rivera (eds) Lat<strong>in</strong>o Education: An Agenda for CommunityAction Research. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.Flores, N. and Robert Hopper (1975) Mexican Americans’ evaluations of spokenSpanish and English. Speech Monographs 42, 9198.Flugel, J.C. (John Carl) (1934) Men and <strong>the</strong>ir Motives: Psycho-Analytical Studies.London: Kegan Paul, Trench, Trubner & Co.Foley, Joseph (1991) Vygotsky, Bernste<strong>in</strong> and Halliday: Towards a unified <strong>the</strong>oryof L1 and L2 learn<strong>in</strong>g. <strong>Language</strong>, Culture and Curriculum 4, 1742.Fordham, Signithia (1999) Diss<strong>in</strong>’ ‘<strong>the</strong> standard’: Ebonics as guerrilla warfare atCapital High. Anthropology & Education Quarterly 30, 272293.


304 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>Fordham, Signithia and John Ogbu (1986) Black students’ school success: Cop<strong>in</strong>gwith <strong>the</strong> ‘burden of act<strong>in</strong>g white’. Urban Review 18, 176206.Foster, Michele (1997) Ebonics: The children speak up. Quarterly of <strong>the</strong> NationalWrit<strong>in</strong>g Project 19 (1), 712.Foucault, Michel (1969) L’archéologie du savoir. Paris: Gallimard.Foucault, Michel (1971) L’ordre du discours. Paris: Gallimard.Frankfurt, Harry (2005) On Bullshit. Pr<strong>in</strong>ceton, NJ: Pr<strong>in</strong>ceton University Press.Fraser, Steven (ed.) (1995) The Bell Curve Wars: Race, Intelligence, and <strong>the</strong> Future ofAmerica. New York: Basic Books.Freeman, Alan (2006) Young, drift<strong>in</strong>g and black. Globe & Mail [Toronto], 1 April.Frender, Robert, Bruce Brown and Wallace Lambert (1970) The role of speechcharacteristics <strong>in</strong> scholastic success. Canadian Journal of Behavioural Science 2,299306.Freyre, Gilberto (1936) Sobrados e mucambos: decadencia do patriarcado no Brasil. SãoPaulo: Companhia Editora Nacional.Friedman, Thomas (2002) Longitudes and Attitudes: Explor<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> World afterSeptember 11. New York: Farrar, Straus & Giroux.Fromm, Erich (1941) Escape from Freedom. New York: Holt, R<strong>in</strong>ehart & W<strong>in</strong>ston.Fry, Peter (2005) Over <strong>the</strong> ra<strong>in</strong>bow. Times Literary Supplement, 28 January, 26.Fryer, Roland and Steven Levitt (2004a) Understand<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> black-white testscore gap <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> first two years of school. Review of Economics and Statistics 86,447464.Fryer, Roland and Steven Levitt (2004b) The causes and consequences ofdist<strong>in</strong>ctively black names. Quarterly Journal of Economics 119, 767805.Fuchs, Estelle (1973) How teachers learn to help children fail. In N. Keddie (ed.)T<strong>in</strong>ker, Tailor... The Myth of Cultural Deprivation. Harmondsworth: Pengu<strong>in</strong>.Fuentes, Carlos (1999) A cure for monol<strong>in</strong>gualism. Times Higher EducationSupplement, 17 December.Ga<strong>in</strong>e, Chris (2005) We’re All White, Thanks: The Persist<strong>in</strong>g Myth about ‘White’Schools. Stoke-on-Trent: Trentham.Galton, Francis (1869) Hereditary Genius: An Inquiry <strong>in</strong>to its Laws and Consequences.London: Macmillan.Galton, Francis (1883) Inquiries <strong>in</strong>to Human Faculty and its Development. London:Macmillan.Garbar<strong>in</strong>o, James, Kathleen Kostelny and Frank Barry (1997) Value transmission<strong>in</strong> an ecological context: The high-risk neighborhood. In J. Grusec andL. Kuczynski (eds) Parent<strong>in</strong>g and Children’s Internalization of Values. NewYork: Wiley.García, Eugene (ed.) (2000) California’s Proposition 227 (Special Issue of Bil<strong>in</strong>gualResearch Journal 24).García, Ofelia (ed.) (1991) Bil<strong>in</strong>gual Education: Focusschrift <strong>in</strong> Honor of JoshuaA. Fishman. Amsterdam: John Benjam<strong>in</strong>s.García, Ofelia (2009) Bil<strong>in</strong>gual Education <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> 21st Century. Chichester: Wiley-Blackwell.García, Ofelia and Harold Schiffman (2006) Fishmanian sociol<strong>in</strong>guistics (1949 to<strong>the</strong> present). In O. García, R. Peltz and H. Schiffman (eds) <strong>Language</strong> Loyalty,Cont<strong>in</strong>uity and Change: Joshua A. Fishman’s Contributions to International Sociol<strong>in</strong>guistics.Clevedon: Multil<strong>in</strong>gual Matters.


References 305Gardner, Robert and Wallace Lambert (1972) Attitudes and Motivation <strong>in</strong> Second-<strong>Language</strong> Learn<strong>in</strong>g. Rowley, MA: Newbury House.Garf<strong>in</strong>kel, Harold (1967) Studies <strong>in</strong> Ethnomethodology. New York: Prentice-Hall.Garrett, Peter, Nikolas Coupland and Angie Williams (eds) (2003) Investigat<strong>in</strong>g<strong>Language</strong> Attitudes. Cardiff: University of Wales Press.Gass, Susan and Larry Sel<strong>in</strong>ker (2008) Second <strong>Language</strong> Acquisition. London:Routledge.Gay, Geneva (1994) A Syn<strong>the</strong>sis of Scholarship <strong>in</strong> Multicultural Education. Napierville,IL: North Central Regional Educational Laboratory. On WWW atwww.ncrel.org/sdrs/areas/issues/educatrs/leadrshp/le0gay.htm.Gay, Judy and Ryan Tweney (1976) Comprehension and production of standardand black English by lower-class black children. Developmental Psychology 12,262268.Genesee, Fred (1981) Bil<strong>in</strong>gualism and biliteracy: A study of cross-culturalcontact <strong>in</strong> a bil<strong>in</strong>gual community. In J. Edwards (ed.) The Social Psychology ofRead<strong>in</strong>g. Silver Spr<strong>in</strong>g, MD: Institute of Modern <strong>Language</strong>s.Gerstle, Gary (2001) American Crucible: Race and Nation <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Twentieth Century.Pr<strong>in</strong>ceton, NJ: Pr<strong>in</strong>ceton University Press.Gibson, Rex (1984) Structuralism and Education. London: Methuen.Gifford, Bernard and Guadalupe Valdés (2006) The l<strong>in</strong>guistic isolation ofHispanic students <strong>in</strong> California’s public schools. In A. Ball (ed.) With MoreDeliberate Speed: Achiev<strong>in</strong>g Equity and Excellence <strong>in</strong> Education. Oxford: Blackwell(Yearbook of <strong>the</strong> National Society for <strong>the</strong> Study of Education 105 (2)).Giles, Howard and Richard Bourhis (1975) L<strong>in</strong>guistic assimilation: West Indians<strong>in</strong> Cardiff. <strong>Language</strong> Sciences 38, 912.Giles, Howard and Richard Bourhis (1976) Black speakers with white speech: Areal problem? In G. Nickel (ed.) Proceed<strong>in</strong>gs of <strong>the</strong> Fourth International Congresson Applied L<strong>in</strong>guistics: Volume 1. Stuttgart: Hochschul Verlag.Giles, Howard and Ellen Bouchard Ryan (1982) Prolegomena for develop<strong>in</strong>ga social psychological <strong>the</strong>ory of language attitudes. In E. Bouchard Ryan andH. Giles (eds) Attitudes Towards <strong>Language</strong> Variation: Social and Applied Contexts.London: Edward Arnold.Giles, Howard and Nikolas Coupland (1989) Discourse: Realignment or revolution?Journal of <strong>Language</strong> and Social Psychology 8, 6368.Giles, Howard and Nikolas Coupland (1991) <strong>Language</strong>: Contexts and Consequences.Milton Keynes: Open University Press.Giordano, Gerard (2005) How Test<strong>in</strong>g Came to Dom<strong>in</strong>ate American Schools: TheHistory of Educational Assessment. New York: Peter Lang.Glazer, Nathan (1977) Public education and American pluralism. In J. Colemanet al. (eds) Parents, Teachers and Children: Prospects for Choice <strong>in</strong> AmericanEducation. San Francisco, CA: Institute for Contemporary Studies.Glazer, Nathan (1997) We Are All Multiculturalists Now. Cambridge, MA: HarvardUniversity Press.Gleason, Philip (1979) Confusion compounded: The melt<strong>in</strong>g pot <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> 1960s and1970s. Ethnicity 6, 1020.Globe & Mail [Toronto] (1985) Mr Murta’s mosaic. 15 May.Globe & Mail [Toronto] (1996) United States. 26 December.Globe & Mail [Toronto] (1997) Black English. 6 February.


306 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>Goddard, Henry (1912) The Kallikak Family: A Study <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Heredity of Feeble-M<strong>in</strong>dedness. New York: Macmillan.Godley, Amanda, Brian Carpenter and Cynthia Werner (2007) ‘I’ll speak <strong>in</strong> properslang’: <strong>Language</strong> ideologies <strong>in</strong> a daily edit<strong>in</strong>g activity. Read<strong>in</strong>g ResearchQuarterly 42, 100131.Goldsmith, Pat (2004) Schools’ racial mix, students’ optimism, and <strong>the</strong> Black-White and Lat<strong>in</strong>o-White achievement gaps. Sociology of Education 77, 121147.Goldste<strong>in</strong>, Eric (2006) The Price of Whiteness: Jews, Race and American Identity.Pr<strong>in</strong>ceton, NJ: Pr<strong>in</strong>ceton University Press.Gonzales, Nancy, Ana Cauce, Ruth Freedman and Craig Mason (1996) Family,peer and neighborhood <strong>in</strong>fluences on academic achievement among AfricanAmerican adolescents. American Journal of Community Psychology 24, 365387.Goodenough, Florence (1926) Racial differences <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>telligence of schoolchildren. Journal of Experimental Psychology 9, 388397.Goot, Murray (1993) Multiculturalists, monoculturalists and <strong>the</strong> many <strong>in</strong>between: Attitudes to cultural diversity and <strong>the</strong>ir correlates. Australian andNew Zealand Journal of Sociology 29, 226253.Gordon, Edmund (1965) Characteristics of socially disadvantaged children.Review of Educational Research 35, 377388.Gordon, John (1968) The disadvantaged pupil. Irish Journal of Education 2, 69105.Gordon, John (1978) The reception of Bernste<strong>in</strong>’s sociol<strong>in</strong>guistic <strong>the</strong>ory amongprimary school teachers. University of East Anglia Papers <strong>in</strong> L<strong>in</strong>guistics 1.Gordon, John (1981) Verbal Deficit: A Critique. London: Croom Helm.Gould, Stephen Jay (1981) The Mismeasure of Man. New York: Norton (revised andexpanded edition, 1996).Gould, Stephen Jay (1994) Curveball. The New Yorker, 28 November, 139149(repr<strong>in</strong>ted <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> 1996 edition of The Mismeasure of Man, and <strong>in</strong> Fraser’s BellCurve Wars).Graddol, David and Joan Swann (1988) Trapp<strong>in</strong>g l<strong>in</strong>guists: An analysis ofl<strong>in</strong>guists’ responses to John Honey’s pamphlet ‘The <strong>Language</strong> Trap’. <strong>Language</strong>and Education 2, 95111.Graff, David, William Labov and Wendell Harris (1983) Test<strong>in</strong>g listeners’reactions to phonological markers of ethnic identity. In D. Sankoff (ed.)<strong>Diversity</strong> and Diachrony. Amsterdam: Benjam<strong>in</strong>s.Grafton, Anthony (1997) The Footnote. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Graham, Sandra, April Taylor and Cynthia Hudley (1998) Explor<strong>in</strong>g achievementvalues among ethnic m<strong>in</strong>ority early adolescents. Journal of EducationalPsychology 90, 606620.Granger, Robert, Marilyn Ma<strong>the</strong>ws, Lorene Quay and R. Verner (1977) Teacherjudgements of <strong>the</strong> communication effectiveness of children us<strong>in</strong>g differentspeech patterns. Journal of Educational Psychology 69, 793796.Grant, Madison (1916) The Pass<strong>in</strong>g of <strong>the</strong> Great Race. New York: Scribner.Gray, Susan and Rupert Klaus (1970) The early tra<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g project: A seventh-yearreport. Child Development 41, 909924.Green, Lisa (2002) African American English: A L<strong>in</strong>guistic Introduction. Cambridge:Cambridge University Press.Greenberg, Michael (2005) Freelance. The Times Literary Supplement, 9 September.Grenoble, Lenore and L<strong>in</strong>dsay Whaley (2006) Sav<strong>in</strong>g <strong>Language</strong>s: An Introduction to<strong>Language</strong> Revitalization. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.


References 307Grimshaw, Allen (1989) Collegial Discourse: Professional Conversation Among Peers.Norwood, NJ: Ablex.Grimshaw, Allen (ed.) (1994) What’s Go<strong>in</strong>g On Here? Complementary Studies ofProfessional Talk. Norwood, NJ: Ablex.Gr<strong>in</strong>berg, Jaime and Elizabeth Saavedra (2000) The constitution of bil<strong>in</strong>gual/ESLeducation as a discipl<strong>in</strong>ary practice: Genealogical explorations. Review ofEducational Research 70, 419441.Grosjean, François (1982) Life With Two <strong>Language</strong>s. Cambridge, MA: HarvardUniversity Press.Gullo, Dom<strong>in</strong>ic (1981) Social class differences <strong>in</strong> preschool children’s comprehensionof wh-questions. Child Development 52, 736740.Gumperz, John and Dell Hymes (eds) (1964) The Ethnography of Communication(American Anthropologist 66 (6), Part 2).Gupta, An<strong>the</strong>a Fraser (1997) When mo<strong>the</strong>r-tongue education is not preferred.Journal of Multil<strong>in</strong>gual and Multicultural Development 18, 496506.Guskey, Thomas (ed.) (2006a) Benjam<strong>in</strong> S. Bloom: Portraits of an Educator. Lanham,MD: Rowman & Littlefield.Guskey, Thomas (2006b) Compensatory education for cultural deprivation. InT. Guskey (ed.) Benjam<strong>in</strong> S. Bloom: Portraits of an Educator. Lanham, MD:Rowman & Littlefield.Haarhoff, Theodore (1920) Schools of Gaul. Oxford: Clarendon.Hagen, Anton (1987) Dialect speak<strong>in</strong>g and school education <strong>in</strong> western Europe.Sociol<strong>in</strong>guistica 1, 6179.Hailong Tian (2006) Review of Analys<strong>in</strong>g Political Discourse (Paul Chilton).<strong>Language</strong> <strong>in</strong> Society 35, 303306.Hakuta, Kenji (1991) What bil<strong>in</strong>gual education has taught <strong>the</strong> experimentalpsychologist. In O. García (ed.) Bil<strong>in</strong>gual Education: Focusschrift <strong>in</strong> Honor ofJoshua A. Fishman. Amsterdam: John Benjam<strong>in</strong>s.Hakuta, Kenji (2002) Comment. International Journal of <strong>the</strong> Sociology of <strong>Language</strong>155/156, 131136.Halliday, Michael (1968) The users and uses of language. In J. Fishman (ed.)Read<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Sociology of <strong>Language</strong>. The Hague: Mouton.Halliday, Michael (1973a) Explorations <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Functions of <strong>Language</strong>. London:Edward Arnold.Halliday, Michael (1973b) Foreword. In B. Bernste<strong>in</strong> (ed.) Class, Codes and Control,Volume 2: Applied Studies Towards a Sociology of <strong>Language</strong>. London: Routledge &Kegan Paul.Halliday, Michael (1975) Learn<strong>in</strong>g How to Mean: Explorations <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Development of<strong>Language</strong>. London: Edward Arnold.Halliday, Michael (1978) <strong>Language</strong> as Social Semiotic: The Social Interpretation of<strong>Language</strong> and Mean<strong>in</strong>g. London: Edward Arnold.Halliday, Michael (1989) Spoken and Written <strong>Language</strong>. Oxford: Oxford UniversityPress.Halsey, A.H. (Albert Henry) and Kathy Sylva (1987) Plowden Twenty Years On(Special Issue of Oxford Review of Education 13: 1).Hamers, Josiane and Michel Blanc (2000) Bil<strong>in</strong>guality and Bil<strong>in</strong>gualism (2nd edn).Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Handl<strong>in</strong>, Oscar (1957) Race and Nationality <strong>in</strong> American Life. Boston, MA: Little,Brown.


308 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>Hansegård, Nils (1968) Tvåspråkighet eller halvspråkighet? Stockholm: Aldus &Bonnier.Harber, Jean and Diane Bryen (1976) Black English and <strong>the</strong> task of read<strong>in</strong>g. Reviewof Educational Research 46, 387405.Harré, Rom and Grant Gillett (1994) The Discursive M<strong>in</strong>d. London: Sage.Harré, Rom and Peter Stearns (1995) Discursive Psychology <strong>in</strong> Practice. London:Sage.Harr<strong>in</strong>gton, Jonathan, Sallyanne Palethorpe and Ca<strong>the</strong>r<strong>in</strong>e Watson (2000) Does<strong>the</strong> Queen speak <strong>the</strong> Queen’s English? Nature 408 (6815), 2728.Harwood, Jonathan (1982) American academic op<strong>in</strong>ion and social change: Recentdevelopments <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> nature-nurture controversy. Oxford Review of Education 8,4167.Haugen, E<strong>in</strong>ar (1953) The Norwegian <strong>Language</strong> <strong>in</strong> America. Philadelphia, PA:University of Pennsylvania Press.Hawk<strong>in</strong>s, Peter (1969) Social class, <strong>the</strong> nom<strong>in</strong>al group and reference. <strong>Language</strong> andSpeech 12, 125135.Hazlitt, William (1901) Table-Talk: Essays on Men and Manners. London: GrantRichards.Heath, Shirley Brice (1983) Ways With Words. Cambridge: Cambridge UniversityPress.Hebb, Donald (1968) A Textbook of Psychology. Philadelphia, PA: Saunders.Heilbrunn, Jacob (1997) Speech <strong>the</strong>rapy. The New Republic 20 January (216: 3),1719.He<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g-Boynton, Audrey and Thomas Haitema (2007) A ten-year chronicle ofstudent attitudes toward foreign language <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> elementary school. Modern<strong>Language</strong> Journal 91, 149168.Helm, Toby (2006a) Fly <strong>the</strong> flag <strong>in</strong> every garden. Daily Telegraph, 14 January.Helm, Toby (2006b) School lessons <strong>in</strong> British values. Daily Telegraph, 16 May.Hélot, Christ<strong>in</strong>e and Andrea Young (2005) The notion of diversity <strong>in</strong> languageeducation: Policy and practice at primary level <strong>in</strong> France. <strong>Language</strong>, Culture andCurriculum 18, 242257.Herman, Simon (1961) Explorations <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> social psychology of language choice.Human Relations 14, 149164.Herrnste<strong>in</strong>, Richard (1971) I.Q. Atlantic Monthly, September (228: 7), 4364.Herrnste<strong>in</strong>, Richard (1973) I.Q. <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Meritocracy. Boston, MA: Little, Brown.Herrnste<strong>in</strong>, Richard and Charles Murray (1994) The Bell Curve: Intelligence andClass Structure <strong>in</strong> American Life. New York: Free Press.Hess, Frederick and Michael Petrilli (2006) ‘No Child Left Beh<strong>in</strong>d’ Primer. Frankfurt:Lang.Hess, Robert and Virg<strong>in</strong>ia Shipman (1965) Early experience and <strong>the</strong> socializationof cognitive modes <strong>in</strong> children. Child Development 36, 869886.Hess, Robert and Virg<strong>in</strong>ia Shipman (1968a) Maternal attitudes towards <strong>the</strong> schooland <strong>the</strong> role of <strong>the</strong> pupil: Some social class comparisons. In A.H. Passow (ed.)Develop<strong>in</strong>g Programs for <strong>the</strong> Educationally Disadvantaged. New York: TeachersCollege Press.Hess, Robert and Virg<strong>in</strong>ia Shipman (1968b) Maternal <strong>in</strong>fluences upon earlylearn<strong>in</strong>g: The cognitive environments of urban pre-school children. In R. Hessand R. Bear (eds) Early Education. Chicago, IL: Ald<strong>in</strong>e.


References 309Hickey, Leo and Miranda Stewart (eds) (2005) Politeness <strong>in</strong> Europe. Clevedon:Multil<strong>in</strong>gual Matters.Higham, John (1955) Strangers <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Land. New Brunswick, NJ: RutgersUniversity Press.Higham, John (1974) Integration versus pluralism: Ano<strong>the</strong>r American dilemma.The Center Magaz<strong>in</strong>e 7, 6773.Higham, John (1975) Send These to Me. New York: A<strong>the</strong>neum.Higham, John (1982) Current trends <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> study of ethnicity <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> United States.Journal of American Ethnic History 2, 515.Hill-Burnett, Jacquetta (1979) Anthropology <strong>in</strong> relation to education. AmericanBehavioral Scientist 23, 237274.H<strong>in</strong>ton, L<strong>in</strong>ette and Karen Pollock (2000) Regional variation <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> phonologicalcharacteristics of African American Vernacular English. World Englishes 19,5971.Hodges, Adam (2005) Review of Analys<strong>in</strong>g Political Discourse (Paul Chilton).Critical Inquiry <strong>in</strong> <strong>Language</strong> Studies 2, 244247.Holborow, Marnie (1999) The Politics of English: A Marxist View of <strong>Language</strong>.London: Sage.Holloway, Joseph and W<strong>in</strong>ifred Vass (1997) The African Heritage of AmericanEnglish. Bloom<strong>in</strong>gton, IN: Indiana University Press.Holmes, Janet (1995) Women, Men and Politeness. London: Longman.Holmes, Steven (1994) Survey f<strong>in</strong>ds m<strong>in</strong>orities resent one ano<strong>the</strong>r almost as muchas <strong>the</strong>y do whites. New York Times, 3 March.Honey, John (1983a) The <strong>Language</strong> Trap. Kenton, Middlesex: National Council forEducational Standards.Honey, John (1983b) The way l<strong>in</strong>guists argue: A reply to Crystal and Hudson.British Association for Applied L<strong>in</strong>guistics Newsletter 19, 3746.Honey, John (1989) Does Accent Matter? The Pygmalion Factor. London: Faber & Faber.Honey, John (1997) <strong>Language</strong> is Power: The Story of Standard English and its Enemies.London: Faber & Faber.Honey, John (1998) The straw hippopotamus. English Today 14 (3), 4144.Honey, John (2000a) A response to Peter Trudgill’s review of <strong>Language</strong> is Power.Journal of Sociol<strong>in</strong>guistics 4, 316319.Honey, John (2000b) The establishment of <strong>the</strong> English RP accent: A flawed<strong>in</strong>terpretation? (a review of Lynda Mugglestone’s Talk<strong>in</strong>g Proper). Bullet<strong>in</strong> TheInternational Association of University Professors of English. On WWW atwww.phon.ucl.ac.uk/<strong>home</strong>/estuary/honey-muggles.htm.Hornberger, Nancy (1991) Extend<strong>in</strong>g enrichment bil<strong>in</strong>gual education: Revisit<strong>in</strong>gtypologies and redirect<strong>in</strong>g policy. In O. García (ed.) Bil<strong>in</strong>gual Education:Focusschrift <strong>in</strong> Honor of Joshua A. Fishman. Amsterdam: John Benjam<strong>in</strong>s.Hornberger, Nancy (ed.) (2005) Heritage/Community <strong>Language</strong> Education (SpecialIssue of International Journal of Bil<strong>in</strong>gual Education and Bil<strong>in</strong>gualism 8, 2/3).Hornberger, Nancy and Mart<strong>in</strong> Pütz (eds) (2006) <strong>Language</strong> Loyalty, <strong>Language</strong>Plann<strong>in</strong>g and <strong>Language</strong> Revitalization: Recent Writ<strong>in</strong>gs and Reflections from JoshuaA. Fishman. Clevedon: Multil<strong>in</strong>gual Matters.Horowitz, Irv<strong>in</strong>g (1995) The Rushton file: Racial comparisons and mediapassions. Society 32 (2), 717.Houston, Susan (1970) A reexam<strong>in</strong>ation of some assumptions about <strong>the</strong> languageof <strong>the</strong> disadvantaged child. Child Development 41, 947963.


310 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>Houston, Susan (1973) Syntactic complexity and <strong>in</strong>formational transmission<strong>in</strong> first-graders: A cross-cultural study. Journal of Psychol<strong>in</strong>guistic Research 2,99114.Hudson, Liam (1973) The Cult of <strong>the</strong> Fact. New York: Harper & Row.Hudson, Richard (1983) Review of The <strong>Language</strong> Trap (John Honey). BritishAssociation for Applied L<strong>in</strong>guistics Newsletter 18, 5054.Hughes, Robert (1993) Culture of Compla<strong>in</strong>t: The Fray<strong>in</strong>g of America. Oxford:Oxford University Press.Hunt, James (1961) Intelligence and Experience. New York: Ronald Press.Hunt, James (1964) The psychological basis for us<strong>in</strong>g preschool enrichment as anantidote for cultural deprivation. Merrill-Palmer Quarterly 10, 209248.Hunt, James (1975) Reflections on a decade of early education. Journal of AbnormalChild Psychology 3, 275330.Hursh, David (2007) Assess<strong>in</strong>g No Child Left Beh<strong>in</strong>d and <strong>the</strong> rise of neoliberaleducation policies. American Educational Research Journal 44, 493518.Huxley, Aldous (1939) After Many a Summer. London: Chatto & W<strong>in</strong>dus (<strong>the</strong>quotation is from <strong>the</strong> 1972 Pengu<strong>in</strong> paperback edition).Hymes, Dell (1972) Review of Noam Chomsky (John Lyons). <strong>Language</strong> 48,416427.Hymes, Dell (1974) Foundations <strong>in</strong> Sociol<strong>in</strong>guistics: An Ethnographic Approach.Philadelphia, PA: University of Pennsylvania Press.Hymes, Dell (1986) Discourse: Scope without depth. International Journal of <strong>the</strong>Sociology of <strong>Language</strong> 57, 4989.[US] Immigration Commission (1911) Reports of <strong>the</strong> Immigration Commission.Wash<strong>in</strong>gton: Government Pr<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g Office (<strong>in</strong> 41 volumes).Imhoff, Gary (ed.) (1990) Learn<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> Two <strong>Language</strong>s: From Conflict to Consensus <strong>in</strong><strong>the</strong> Reorganization of Schools. New Brunswick, NJ: Transaction.Ireland (1998) The Education Act. Dubl<strong>in</strong>: Government Stationery Office.Irw<strong>in</strong>g, Paul (2005) We must study <strong>the</strong> real world, not our world view. TimesHigher Education Supplement, 2 September.Irw<strong>in</strong>g, Paul and Richard Lynn (2005) Sex differences <strong>in</strong> means and variability on<strong>the</strong> progressive matrices <strong>in</strong> university students: A meta-analysis. BritishJournal of Psychology 96, 505524.Jackson, John (2005) Science for Segregation: Race, Law and <strong>the</strong> Case aga<strong>in</strong>st Brown v.Board of Education. New York: New York University Press.Jackson, L. (1974) The myth of elaborated and restricted code. Higher EducationReview 6: 2, 6581.Jacoby, Russell and Naomi Glauberman (eds) (1995) The Bell Curve Debate: History,Documents, Op<strong>in</strong>ions. New York: Times Books.Jarvis, Edward (1855) Insanity and Idiocy <strong>in</strong> Massachusetts: Report of <strong>the</strong> Commissionon Lunacy. Boston, MA: White.Jaspaert, Koen and Sjaak Kroon (eds) (1991) Ethnic M<strong>in</strong>ority <strong>Language</strong>s andEducation. Amsterdam: Swets & Zeitl<strong>in</strong>ger.Jay, Susan, Donald Routh and John Brantley (1980) Social class differences <strong>in</strong>children’s comprehension of adult language. Journal of Psychol<strong>in</strong>guistic Research9, 205217.Jencks, Christopher (1972) Inequality: A Reassessment of <strong>the</strong> Effect of Family andSchool<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> America. New York: Basic Books (Jencks is <strong>the</strong> ma<strong>in</strong> author here,although seven collaborators are listed on cover and title page).


References 311Jensen, Arthur (1967) The culturally disadvantaged: Psychological and educationalaspects. Educational Research 10, 420.Jensen, Arthur (1968) Social class, race, and genetics: Implications for education.American Educational Research Journal 5, 142.Jensen, Arthur (1969) How much can we boost IQ and scholastic achievement?Harvard Educational Review 39, 1123.Jensen, Arthur (1973) Educability and Group Differences. New York: Harper & Row.Jiménez, Robert (2000) Literacy and <strong>the</strong> identity development of Lat<strong>in</strong>a/ostudents. American Educational Research Journal 37, 9711000.Jiménez, R. (2006) A response to ‘The l<strong>in</strong>guistic isolation of Hispanic students <strong>in</strong>California’s public schools’. In A. Ball (ed.) With More Deliberate Speed:Achiev<strong>in</strong>g Equity and Excellence <strong>in</strong> Education. Oxford: Blackwell (Yearbook of<strong>the</strong> National Society for <strong>the</strong> Study of Education 105 (2)).Johns, Ann (2005) English for academic purposes: Issues <strong>in</strong> undergraduatewrit<strong>in</strong>g and read<strong>in</strong>g. In P. Bruthiaux, D. Atk<strong>in</strong>son, W. Egg<strong>in</strong>gton, W. Grabeand V. Ramanathan (eds) Directions <strong>in</strong> Applied L<strong>in</strong>guistics: Essays <strong>in</strong> Honor ofRobert B. Kaplan. Clevedon: Multil<strong>in</strong>gual Matters.Johnson, Sally and Ulrike Me<strong>in</strong>hof (eds) (1997) <strong>Language</strong> and Mascul<strong>in</strong>ity. Oxford:Blackwell.Jones, Ernest (1918) Papers on Psycho-Analysis. London: Baillière, T<strong>in</strong>dall & Cox(revised and enlarged edition).Jones, Edward and Harold Sigall (1971) The bogus pipel<strong>in</strong>e: A new paradigm formeasur<strong>in</strong>g affect and attitude. Psychological Bullet<strong>in</strong> 76, 349364.Jones, Kathar<strong>in</strong>e (2001) Accent on Privilege: English Identities and Anglophilia <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>U.S. Philadelphia, PA: Temple University Press.Joos, Mart<strong>in</strong> (1967) The Five Clocks. New York: Harcourt, Brace & World.Joseph, John (2004) <strong>Language</strong> and Identity: National, Ethnic, Religious. London:Palgrave Macmillan.Julé, Allyson (2004) Gender, Participation and Silence <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>. New York:Palgrave Macmillan.Jussim, Lee and Kent Harber (2005) Teacher expectations and self-fulfill<strong>in</strong>gprophecies. Personality and Social Psychology Review 9, 131155.Kagan, Jerome (1969) Inadequate evidence and illogical conclusions. HarvardEducational Review 39, 274277.Kallen, Horace (1915) Democracy versus <strong>the</strong> melt<strong>in</strong>g pot: A study of Americannationality. The Nation (18 and 25 February), 190194 and 217220.Kallen, Horace (1924) Culture and Democracy <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> United States. New York: Boni& Liveright.Kaplan, Charles (1982) Report on <strong>the</strong> Kassel University conference. Sociol<strong>in</strong>guisticsNewsletter 13 (1), 1518.Kaplan, Robert (1983) Review of Hunger of Memory (Richard Rodriguez). <strong>Language</strong>Learn<strong>in</strong>g 33, 123126.Katz, Irw<strong>in</strong> (1967) Some motivational determ<strong>in</strong>ants of racial differences <strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>tellectual achievement. International Journal of Psychology 2, 112.Katz, Susan (2004) Does NCLB leave <strong>the</strong> U.S. beh<strong>in</strong>d <strong>in</strong> bil<strong>in</strong>gual teachereducation? English Education 36, 141152 (this issue (36: 2) is devoted to <strong>the</strong>No Child Left Beh<strong>in</strong>d provisions).Kautzsch, Alexander (2006) Review of African American English (Lisa Green).<strong>Language</strong> <strong>in</strong> Society 35, 149152.


312 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>Keddie, Nell (ed.) (1973) T<strong>in</strong>ker, Tailor... The Myth of Cultural Deprivation.Harmondsworth: Pengu<strong>in</strong>.Kedourie, Elie (1961) Nationalism. London: Hutch<strong>in</strong>son.Kellaghan, Thomas (1977) The Evaluation of an Intervention Programme forDisadvantaged Children. W<strong>in</strong>dsor: NFER (National Foundation for EducationalResearch).Kellaghan, Thomas (2001) Towards a def<strong>in</strong>ition of educational disadvantage. IrishJournal of Education 32, 322 (this issue appeared ra<strong>the</strong>r later than <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>dicateddate; see also <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r three papers <strong>in</strong> this number, papers that deal withdisadvantaged children’s read<strong>in</strong>g achievements, <strong>the</strong>ir attitudes towardsschool, and some of <strong>the</strong> services made available to ‘at risk’ families).Kirkland, David, Jeffrey Rob<strong>in</strong>son, Aust<strong>in</strong> Jackson and Geneva Smi<strong>the</strong>rman(2004) From ‘The lower economic’: Three young brothas and an old schoolwomanist respond to Dr Bill Cosby. The Black Scholar 34 (4), 1015.Kirkpatrick, Clifford (1926) Intelligence and Immigration. Baltimore, MD: Williams& Wilk<strong>in</strong>s.Kissau, Scott (2006) Gender differences <strong>in</strong> motivation to learn French. CanadianModern <strong>Language</strong> Review 62, 401422.Klaus, Rupert and Susan Gray (1968) The early tra<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g project for disadvantagedchildren: A report after five years. Monographs of <strong>the</strong> Society for Research <strong>in</strong> ChildDevelopment 33: 4.Kl<strong>in</strong>e, Wendy (2001) Build<strong>in</strong>g a Better Race: Gender, Sexuality and Eugenics from <strong>the</strong>Turn of <strong>the</strong> Century to <strong>the</strong> Baby Boom. Berkeley, CA: University of CaliforniaPress.Kochman, Thomas (1985) Review of The <strong>Language</strong> Trap (John Honey). <strong>Language</strong>Problems and <strong>Language</strong> Plann<strong>in</strong>g 9, 152162.Koopmans, Ruud, Paul Statham, Marco Giugni and Florence Passy (2005)Contested Citizenship: Immigration and Cultural <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> Europe. M<strong>in</strong>neapolis,MN: University of M<strong>in</strong>nesota Press.Kozol, Jonathan (2007) The big enchilada. Harper’s, August (315: 1887), 79.Kretzschmar, William (1998) Ebonics (Special Issue of <strong>the</strong> Journal of EnglishL<strong>in</strong>guistics 26: 2).Krieger, Nancy and Elizabeth Fee (1994) Social class: The miss<strong>in</strong>g l<strong>in</strong>k <strong>in</strong> U.S.health data. International Journal of Health Services 24, 2544.Kristiansen, Tore, Peter Garrett and Nikolas Coupland (eds) (2005) SubjectiveProcesses <strong>in</strong> <strong>Language</strong> Variation and Change (Acta L<strong>in</strong>guistica Hafniensia 37).Kymlicka, Will (1995a) Multicultural Citizenship. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Kymlicka, Will (ed.) (1995b) The Rights of M<strong>in</strong>ority Cultures. Oxford: OxfordUniversity Press.Kymlicka, Will (1998) Review of We Are All Multiculturalists Now (Nathan Glazer).Journal of Multil<strong>in</strong>gual and Multicultural Development 19, 165167.Labov, William (1969) The logic of nonstandard English. Georgetown Monographson <strong>Language</strong> and L<strong>in</strong>guistics 22, 131 (repr<strong>in</strong>ted <strong>in</strong> Keddie (q.v), from where <strong>the</strong>citations here are taken).Labov, William (1972) Some sources of read<strong>in</strong>g problems for Negro speakersof nonstandard English. In R. Abrahams and R. Troike (eds) <strong>Language</strong>and Cultural <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> American Education. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.


References 313Labov, William (1976) <strong>Language</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Inner City. Philadelphia, PA: University ofPennsylvania Press.Labov, William (1977) Sociol<strong>in</strong>guistic Patterns. Philadelphia, PA: University ofPennsylvania Press.Labov, William (1982) Objectivity and commitment <strong>in</strong> l<strong>in</strong>guistic science: The caseof <strong>the</strong> Black English trial <strong>in</strong> Ann Arbor. <strong>Language</strong> <strong>in</strong> Society 11, 165201.Labov, William (1994) Pr<strong>in</strong>ciples of L<strong>in</strong>guistic Change. Oxford: Blackwell (Volume 1:Internal Factors; Volume 2: Social Factors).Labov, William (2006) The Social Stratification of English <strong>in</strong> New York City (2nd edn).Cambridge: Cambridge University Press (orig<strong>in</strong>ally published <strong>in</strong> Wash<strong>in</strong>gton:Center for Applied L<strong>in</strong>guistics, 1966).Ladd, Judith and Tracy L<strong>in</strong>derholm (2008) A consequence of school grade labels:Pre-service teachers’ <strong>in</strong>terpretations and recall of children’s classroombehavior. Social Psychology of Education 11, 229242.Ladegaard, Hans (1998a) National stereotypes and language attitudes. <strong>Language</strong>and Communication 18, 251274.Ladegaard, Hans (1998b) Assess<strong>in</strong>g national stereotypes <strong>in</strong> language attitudestudies. Journal of Multil<strong>in</strong>gual and Multicultural Development 19, 182198.Ladegaard, Hans (1998c) Boys, girls, language and identity: <strong>Language</strong> attitudesand l<strong>in</strong>guistic behaviour <strong>in</strong> a rural community <strong>in</strong> Denmark. InternationalJournal of Applied L<strong>in</strong>guistics 8, 325.Ladegaard, Hans (2000) <strong>Language</strong> attitudes and sociol<strong>in</strong>guistic behaviour. Journalof Sociol<strong>in</strong>guistics 4, 214233.Ladegaard, Hans and Itesh Sachdev (2006) ‘I like <strong>the</strong> Americans... but I certa<strong>in</strong>lydon’t aim for an American accent’: <strong>Language</strong> attitudes, vitality and foreignlanguage learn<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> Denmark. Journal of Multil<strong>in</strong>gual and MulticulturalDevelopment 27, 91108.Lakoff, Rob<strong>in</strong> (1975) <strong>Language</strong> and Woman’s Place. New York: Harper & Row(a revised and expanded edition, edited by Mary Bucholtz, was publishedby Oxford University Press <strong>in</strong> 2004; toge<strong>the</strong>r with new <strong>in</strong>troductorymaterial, Bucholtz assembled two dozen scholarly commentaries on Lakoff’swork).Lal, Barbara (1990) The Romance of Culture <strong>in</strong> an Urban Civilization. London:Routledge.Lam, Tony (1992) Review of practices and problems <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> evaluation of bil<strong>in</strong>gualeducation. Review of Educational Research 62, 181203.Lambert, Wallace, Robert Hodgson, Robert Gardner and Steven Fillenbaum(1960) Evaluational reactions to spoken languages. Journal of Abnormal andSocial Psychology 60, 4451.Lanehart, Sonja (1998) African American Vernacular English and education.Journal of English L<strong>in</strong>guistics 26, 122136.Lanehart, Sonja (ed.) (2001) Sociocultural and Historical Contexts of African AmericanEnglish. Amsterdam: Benjam<strong>in</strong>s.Larson, Joanne (ed.) (2007) Literacy as Snake Oil. New York: Lang.Laughl<strong>in</strong>, Harry (1923) Analysis of America’s Modern Melt<strong>in</strong>g Pot. Wash<strong>in</strong>gton, DC:Government Pr<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g Office.Laughl<strong>in</strong>, Harry (1930) The Legal Status of Eugenical Sterilization. Chicago, IL:R<strong>in</strong>gley.


314 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>Laver, John and Peter Trudgill (1979) Phonetic and l<strong>in</strong>guistic markers <strong>in</strong> speech.In K. Scherer and H. Giles (eds) Social Markers <strong>in</strong> Speech. Cambridge:Cambridge University Press.Laversuch, Iman (2005) Census and Consensus? A Historical Exam<strong>in</strong>ation of <strong>the</strong> USCensus Racial Term<strong>in</strong>ology Used for American Residents of African Ancestry.Frankfurt: Peter Lang.Laversuch, Iman (2007) The politics of nam<strong>in</strong>g race and ethnicity: <strong>Language</strong>plann<strong>in</strong>g and policies regulat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> selection of racial ethnonyms used by <strong>the</strong>US Census 19902010. Current Issues <strong>in</strong> <strong>Language</strong> Plann<strong>in</strong>g 8, 365382.Lenneberg, Eric (1967) Biological Foundations of <strong>Language</strong>. New York: Wiley.Leopold, Werner (19391949) Speech Development of a Bil<strong>in</strong>gual Child. Evanston, IL:Northwestern University Press (4 volumes).Lesser, Ruth (2003) When conversation is not normal: The role of conversationanalysis <strong>in</strong> language pathology. In C. Prevignano and P. Thibault (eds)Discuss<strong>in</strong>g Conversation Analysis: The Work of Emanuel A. Schegloff. Amsterdam:John Benjam<strong>in</strong>s.Lewis, E. Glyn (1977) Bil<strong>in</strong>gualism and bil<strong>in</strong>gual education: The ancient world to<strong>the</strong> Renaissance. In J. Fishman (ed.) Bil<strong>in</strong>gual Education. Rowley, MA: Newbury(Lewis’s article forms an appendix to Fishman’s book).Li Wei (ed.) (2000) The Bil<strong>in</strong>gualism Reader. London: Routledge.Li Wei (2006) Complementary schools: Past, present and future. <strong>Language</strong> andEducation 20, 7683.L<strong>in</strong>ard, Jacques (1919) A French directive. The Crisis 18, 1618.L<strong>in</strong>dsay, Geoff and Daniel Muijs (2006) Challeng<strong>in</strong>g underachievement <strong>in</strong> boys.Educational Research 48, 313332.L<strong>in</strong>dsey, Sue (2005) Yorktown jurors conclude death row <strong>in</strong>mate is not mentallyretarded. Associated Press, 5 August. On WWW at http://www.wavy.com/global/story.Lippi-Green, Ros<strong>in</strong>a (1997) English with an Accent: <strong>Language</strong>, Ideology andDiscrim<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> United States. London: Routledge.Lippman, Walter (1922) Intelligence tests (a six-part series). The New Republic,25 October to 22 November (32: 412416), 213215, 246248, 275277, 297298and 328330; and 29 November (33: 417), 911 (<strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>-text citation here is fromno. 415 (15 November): ‘IV: The abuse of <strong>the</strong> tests’).Loban, Walter (1963) The <strong>Language</strong> of Elementary School Children. Champaign, IL:National Council of Teachers of English.Loman, Bengt (ed.) (1974) Barnspråk i klassamhälle. Lund: Läromedel/Gleerup (seeespecially Loman’s own two chapters: ‘Basil Bernste<strong>in</strong>s språkteori i tvärvetenskapligbelysn<strong>in</strong>g’ [‘Basil Bernste<strong>in</strong>’s language <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>terdiscipl<strong>in</strong>aryperspective’] and ‘Språket som socialt problem i USA’ [‘Speech as a socialproblem <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> USA’]).Long, Daniel and Dennis Preston (eds) (2002) Handbook of Perceptual Dialectology:Volume 2. Amsterdam: John Benjam<strong>in</strong>s.Lowe, Roy (1979) Eugenicists, doctors and <strong>the</strong> quest for national efficiency: Aneducational crusade, 19001939. History of Education 8, 293306.Lowe, Roy (1980) Eugenics and education: A note on <strong>the</strong> orig<strong>in</strong>s of <strong>the</strong><strong>in</strong>telligence test<strong>in</strong>g movement <strong>in</strong> England. Educational Studies 6, 18.Lucas, Ceil and Denise Borders (1987) <strong>Language</strong> diversity and classroomdiscourse. American Educational Research Journal 24, 119141.


References 315Luke, Allan (1995) Text and discourse <strong>in</strong> education: An <strong>in</strong>troduction to criticaldiscourse analysis. Review of Research <strong>in</strong> Education 21, 348.Luke, Allan (2004) Notes on <strong>the</strong> future of critical discourse studies. CriticalDiscourse Studies 1, 149152.Lupul, Manoly (1982) The political implementation of multiculturalism. Journal ofCanadian Studies 17, 93102.Lupul, Manoly (2005) The Politics of Multiculturalism. Edmonton: CanadianInstitute of Ukra<strong>in</strong>ian Studies Press.Lynn, Richard and J. Philippe Rushton (2006) Letter. Times Higher EducationSupplement, 7 April.Macías, Reynaldo (1989) Bil<strong>in</strong>gual Teacher Supply and Demand <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> United States.Los Angeles, CA: University of Sou<strong>the</strong>rn California Center for Multil<strong>in</strong>gualand Multicultural Research.Mackey, William (1970) A typology of bil<strong>in</strong>gual education. Foreign <strong>Language</strong>Annals 3, 596608.Mackey, William (1978) The importation of bil<strong>in</strong>gual education models. InJ. Alatis (ed.) Georgetown University Round Table on <strong>Language</strong>s and L<strong>in</strong>guistics.Wash<strong>in</strong>gton, DC: Georgetown University Press.Mackey, William (1981) Safeguard<strong>in</strong>g language <strong>in</strong> schools. <strong>Language</strong> and Society[Ottawa] 4: 1014.Macnamara, John (1973) Attitudes and learn<strong>in</strong>g a second language. In R. Shuyand R. Fasold (eds) <strong>Language</strong> Attitudes: Current Trends and Prospects. Wash<strong>in</strong>gton,DC: Georgetown University Press.Majors, Richard and Janet Billson (1993) Cool Pose: The Dilemmas of Black Manhood<strong>in</strong> America. New York: Simon & Schuster.Majors, Richard and Jacob Gordon (eds) (1994) The American Black Male. Chicago,IL: Nelson-Hall.Maloof, Valerie, Donald Rub<strong>in</strong> and Ann Miller (2006) Cultural competence andidentity <strong>in</strong> cross-cultural adaptation: The role of a Vietnamese heritagelanguage school. International Journal of Bil<strong>in</strong>gual Education and Bil<strong>in</strong>gualism9, 255273.Mann, Arthur (1979) The One and <strong>the</strong> Many. Chicago, IL: University of ChicagoPress.Mann<strong>in</strong>g, M. Lee and Leroy Baruth (2004) Multicultural Education of Children andAdolescents.Boston, MA: Allyn & Bacon.Marenbon, John (1987) English Our English: The New Orthodoxy Exam<strong>in</strong>ed. London:Centre for Policy Studies.Marks, Gary (2006) Are between- and with<strong>in</strong>-school differences <strong>in</strong> studentperformance largely due to socioeconomic background? Evidence from 30countries. Educational Research 48, 2140.Marmen, Louise and Jean-Pierre Corbeil (1999) <strong>Language</strong>s <strong>in</strong> Canada: 1996 Census.Ottawa: Supply & Services Canada.Mart<strong>in</strong>, Renée (ed.) (1995) Practic<strong>in</strong>g What We Preach: Confront<strong>in</strong>g <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong>Teacher Education. Albany, NY: State University of New York Press.Mart<strong>in</strong>-Jones, Marilyn and Suzanne Roma<strong>in</strong>e (1985) Semil<strong>in</strong>gualism: A halfbaked<strong>the</strong>ory of communicative competence. Applied L<strong>in</strong>guistics 6, 105117.Marwit, Samuel (1977) Black and white children’s use of standard English at 7, 9,and 12 years of age. Developmental Psychology 13, 8182.


316 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>Marwit, Samuel and Gail Neumann (1974) Black and white children’s comprehensionof standard and nonstandard English passages. Journal of EducationalPsychology 66, 329332.Marwit, Samuel and Karen Marwit (1973) Grammatical responses of Negro andCaucasian second graders as a function of standard and non-standard Englishpresentation. Journal of Educational Psychology 65, 187191.Marwit, Samuel and Karen Marwit (1976) Black children’s use of nonstandardgrammar: Two years later. Developmental Psychology 12, 3338.Marwit, Samuel, Karen Marwit and John Boswell (1972) Negro children’s use ofnonstandard grammar. Journal of Educational Psychology 63, 218224.Mason, Mary (1986) The deficit hypo<strong>the</strong>sis revisited. Educational Studies 12,279289.Mayr, Ernst (1968) Discussion. In M. Mead, T. Dobzhansky, E. Tobach andR. Light (eds) Science and <strong>the</strong> Concept of Race. New York: Columbia UniversityPress.McAllister, Gretchen and Jacquel<strong>in</strong>e Irv<strong>in</strong>e (2000) Cross-cultural competency andmulticultural teacher education. Review of Educational Research 70, 324.McBrien, J. Lynn (2005) Educational needs and barriers for refugee students <strong>in</strong><strong>the</strong> United States: A review of <strong>the</strong> literature. Review of Educational Research 75,329364.McCulloch, Oscar (1888) The Tribe of Ishmael: A Study <strong>in</strong> Social Degradation.Indianapolis, IN: Charity Organization Society.McDermott, Ray and Kenneth Gospod<strong>in</strong>off (1981) Social contexts for ethnicborders and school failure. In H. Trueba, G. Guthrie and K. Au (eds) Cultureand <strong>the</strong> Bil<strong>in</strong>gual <strong>Classroom</strong>. Rowley, MA: Newbury.McDermott, Ray and Kathleen Hall (2007) Scientifically debased research onlearn<strong>in</strong>g, 18542006. Anthropology and Education Quarterly 38, 915.McDiarmid, G. Williamson (1992) What to do about difference? A study ofmulticultural education for teacher tra<strong>in</strong>ees <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Los Angeles Unified SchoolDistrict. Journal of Teacher Education 43, 8393.McDiarmid, G. Williamson and Jeremy Price (1990) Prospective Teachers’ Views ofDiverse Learners: A Study of <strong>the</strong> Participants <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> ABCD Project. East Lans<strong>in</strong>g,MI: National Center for Research on Teacher Education.McIntosh, Carey (1998) The Evolution of English Prose, 1700-1800: Style, Politenessand Pr<strong>in</strong>t Culture. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.McK<strong>in</strong>zey, R. Kim (2005) Too dumb to die: Mental retardation meets <strong>the</strong>death penalty. Web Psych Empiricist. On WWW at http://www.wpe.<strong>in</strong>fo/papers_table.html. [The orig<strong>in</strong>al post<strong>in</strong>g was <strong>in</strong> September 2003; <strong>the</strong> mostrecent post<strong>in</strong>g, August 2005, <strong>in</strong>cludes three updates by McK<strong>in</strong>zey].McLaren, Angus (1990) Our Own Master Race: Eugenics <strong>in</strong> Canada, 18851945.Toronto: McClelland & Stewart.McLaughl<strong>in</strong>, Barry (1978) Second-<strong>Language</strong> Acquisition <strong>in</strong> Childhood. Hillsdale, NJ:Lawrence Erlbaum.McMillen, Liz (1997) L<strong>in</strong>guists f<strong>in</strong>d <strong>the</strong> debate over ‘Ebonics’ un<strong>in</strong>formed. TheChronicle of Higher Education, 17 January, 1617.McNamara, Tim and Carsten Roever (2006) <strong>Language</strong> Test<strong>in</strong>g: The Social Dimension.Oxford: Blackwell.McWhorter, John (1997a) Wast<strong>in</strong>g energy on an illusion. Black Scholar 27 (1), 914.


References 317McWhorter, John (1997b) Wast<strong>in</strong>g energy on an illusion: Six months later. BlackScholar 27 (2), 25.McWhorter, John (2000) Los<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> Race: Self-Sabotage <strong>in</strong> Black America. New York:Free Press.McWhorter, John (2003) Do<strong>in</strong>g Our Own Th<strong>in</strong>g: The Degradation of <strong>Language</strong> andMusic and Why We Should, Like, Care. New York: Gotham Books.Meditch, Andrea (1975) The development of sex-specific speech patterns <strong>in</strong>young children. Anthropological L<strong>in</strong>guistics 17, 421433.Mehan, Hugh (1984) <strong>Language</strong> and school<strong>in</strong>g. Sociology of Education 57, 174183.Mehta, Ved (1971) John is easy to please. The New Yorker, 8May,4487 (this essayis repr<strong>in</strong>ted with five o<strong>the</strong>rs <strong>in</strong> Mehta’s John Is Easy To Please: EncountersWith <strong>the</strong> Written and <strong>the</strong> Spoken Word. New York: Farrar, Straus & Giroux, 1971).Menand, Louis (1994) The culture wars. New York Review of Books, 6 October(no. 41), 16.Mercer, Neil and Derek Edwards (1981) Ground-rules for mutual understand<strong>in</strong>g:A social psychological approach to classroom knowledge. In N. Mercer (ed.)<strong>Language</strong> <strong>in</strong> School and Community. London: Edward Arnold.Mills, Sara (2003) Gender and Politeness. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Milroy, James (1984) Sociol<strong>in</strong>guistic methodology and <strong>the</strong> identification ofspeakers’ voices <strong>in</strong> legal proceed<strong>in</strong>gs. In P. Trudgill (ed.) Applied Sociol<strong>in</strong>guistics.London: Academic Press.Milroy, James (1992) L<strong>in</strong>guistic Variation and Change. Oxford: Blackwell.Milroy, James and Lesley Milroy (1985) Authority <strong>in</strong> <strong>Language</strong>: Investigat<strong>in</strong>gPrescription and Standardisation. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul (a secondedition, 1999, has a new subtitle: Investigat<strong>in</strong>g Standard English).Milroy, Lesley (1987) <strong>Language</strong> and Social Networks (2nd edn). Oxford: Blackwell.Milroy, Lesley and Dennis Preston (1999) Attitudes, Perceptions, and L<strong>in</strong>guisticFeatures (Special Issue of <strong>the</strong> Journal of <strong>Language</strong> and Social Psychology 18:1).Milton, John (1644/1958) Prose Writ<strong>in</strong>gs. London: Dent.M<strong>in</strong>aya-Rowe, Liliana (2002) Teacher Tra<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g and Effective Pedagogy <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Contextof Student <strong>Diversity</strong>. Greenwich, CT: Information Age.M<strong>in</strong>cy, Ronald (2006) Black Males Left Beh<strong>in</strong>d. Wash<strong>in</strong>gton, DC: Urban Institute.Mitchell, L<strong>in</strong>da (2001) Grammar Wars: <strong>Language</strong> as Cultural Battlefield <strong>in</strong> 17th- and18th-Century England. Aldershot: Ashgate.Mitchell, Rosamond and Florence Myles (1998) Second-<strong>Language</strong> Learn<strong>in</strong>g Theories.London: Arnold.Mol<strong>in</strong>a, Natalia (2006) Fit To Be Citizens? Public Health and Race <strong>in</strong> Los Angeles,18791939. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.Morrison, Joan and Charlotte Zabusky (1980) American Mosaic: The ImmigrantExperience <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Words of Those Who Lived It. New York: Dutton.Morton, Thomas (1800) Speed <strong>the</strong> Plough. London: Longman & Rees.Moses, Rae, Harvey Daniels and Robert Gundlach (1976) Teachers’ languageattitudes and bidialectalism. International Journal of <strong>the</strong> Sociology of <strong>Language</strong> 8,7791.Moss, Margaret (1973) Deprivation and Disadvantage. Bletchley: Open UniversityPress.Mossman, Douglas (2005) Capital punishment of <strong>the</strong> mentally disabled requiresspecial consideration. In N. Fisanick (ed.) The Ethics of Capital Punishment.


318 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>Detroit, MI: Greenhaven, 2005 (orig<strong>in</strong>ally published as ‘Psychiatry <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>courtroom’ <strong>in</strong> Public Affairs 150, 2237).Mount, Harry (2006) Amo, Amas, Amat... and All That. London: Short Books.Muello, Peter (2005) Rio’s boneyard of bondage. Globe & Mail [Toronto], 29November (<strong>the</strong> story was widely reported <strong>in</strong> newspapers around <strong>the</strong> world;<strong>the</strong> common wire-service story that most of <strong>the</strong>m reproduced mistakenlyrendered cemitério as cemeterio).Mufwene, Salikoko, John Rickford, Guy Bailey and John Baugh (eds) (1998)African American English: Structure, History and Use. New York: Routledge.Mugglestone, Lynda (1995) ‘Talk<strong>in</strong>g Proper’: The Rise of Accent as Social Symbol.Oxford: Clarendon Press.Murdoch, Stephen (2007) IQ: A Smart History of a Failed Idea. New York: Wiley.Murphy, Christ<strong>in</strong>a (1975) <strong>Language</strong>, idiom, accent and literacy: An <strong>in</strong>terviewwith John Edwards. Irish Times, 3 November.Myhill, Debra and Frances Dunk<strong>in</strong> (2005) Question<strong>in</strong>g learn<strong>in</strong>g. <strong>Language</strong> andEducation 19, 415427.National Association for Multicultural Education (2003) Multicultural Education.A def<strong>in</strong>itional statement adopted by <strong>the</strong> Board of Directors <strong>in</strong> February. OnWWW at www.nameorg.org.National Conference of Christians and Jews (1994) Tak<strong>in</strong>g America’s Pulse. NewYork: NCCJ.National Conference for Community and Justice (2000) Tak<strong>in</strong>g America’s Pulse, II.New York: NCCJ.National Conference for Community and Justice (2006) Tak<strong>in</strong>g America’s Pulse, III.New York: NCCJ.Nature Genetics (2004) Genetics of <strong>the</strong> human race (Special Issue: a supplement toVolume 36: 11).Nero, Shondell (ed.) (2006) Dialects, Englishes, Creoles and Education. Mahwah, NJ:Lawrence Erlbaum.Ng, Sik Hung (2007) <strong>Language</strong>-based discrim<strong>in</strong>ation. Journal of <strong>Language</strong> andSocial Psychology 26, 106122.Ngũgĩwa Thiong’o (2004) Gikuyu: Recover<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> orig<strong>in</strong>al. In W. Lesser (ed.) TheGenius of <strong>Language</strong>. New York: Pan<strong>the</strong>on.Niedzielski, Nancy (2005) L<strong>in</strong>guistic purism from several perspectives: Viewsfrom <strong>the</strong> ‘secure’ and ‘<strong>in</strong>secure’. In N. Langer and W. Davies (eds) L<strong>in</strong>guisticPurism <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Germanic <strong>Language</strong>s. Berl<strong>in</strong>: Walter de Gruyter.Niedzielski, Nancy and Dennis Preston (2000) Folk L<strong>in</strong>guistics. Berl<strong>in</strong>: Mouton deGruyter.Nieto, Sonia (2004) Affirm<strong>in</strong>g <strong>Diversity</strong>: The Sociopolitical Context of MulticulturalEducation. Boston, MA: Allyn & Bacon.Noel, Leroy (2005) Bernard Coard tells a mouthful. Tr<strong>in</strong>idad & Tobago NewsBullet<strong>in</strong> Board, 15 January. On WWW at www.tr<strong>in</strong>idadandtobagonews.com/forum/webbbs_config.pl/noframes/read/2750.Noels, Kim and Richard Clément (1998) <strong>Language</strong> <strong>in</strong> education. In J. Edwards(ed.) <strong>Language</strong> <strong>in</strong> Canada. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Noguera, Pedro (1996) Confront<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> urban <strong>in</strong> urban school reform. UrbanReview 28, 119.


References 319Novak, Michael (1971) The Rise of <strong>the</strong> Unmeltable Ethnics. New York: Macmillan(a revised edition, under <strong>the</strong> title Unmeltable Ethnics: Politics and Culture <strong>in</strong>American Life, appeared <strong>in</strong> 1996. New Brunswick, NJ: Transaction).Nunberg, Geoffrey (1986) An official language for California? New York Times, 2October.[U.S.] Office of Management and Budget (2005) Revisions to <strong>the</strong> standards for<strong>the</strong> classification of federal data on race and ethnicity. On WWW at http://www.whitehouse.gov/omb/fedreg/ombdir15.html.O’Connor, Carla (1997) Dispositions toward (collective) struggle and educationalresilience <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>ner city: A case analysis of six African-American high schoolstudents. American Educational Research Journal 34, 593629.Ogbu, John (1978) M<strong>in</strong>ority Education and Caste. New York: Academic Press.Ogbu, John (1982a) Cultural discont<strong>in</strong>uities and school<strong>in</strong>g. Anthropology andEducation Quarterly 13, 290307.Ogbu, John (1982b) Societal forces as a context of ghetto children’s school failure.In L. Feagans and D. Farran (eds) The <strong>Language</strong> of Children Reared <strong>in</strong> Poverty.New York: Academic Press.Ogbu, John (1983) M<strong>in</strong>ority status and school<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> plural societies. ComparativeEducation Review 27, 168190.Ogbu, John (1987) Variability <strong>in</strong> m<strong>in</strong>ority school performance: A problem <strong>in</strong>search of an explanation. Anthropology and Education Quarterly 18, 312334.Ogbu, John (1999) Beyond language: Ebonics, proper English and identity <strong>in</strong> aBlack-American speech community. American Educational Research Journal 36,147184.Ogbu, John (2003) Black American Students <strong>in</strong> an Affluent Suburb: A Study ofAcademic Disengagement. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.Olneck, Michael (2000) Can multicultural education change what counts ascultural capital? American Educational Research Journal 37, 317348.Orellana, Marjorie, Lucila Ek and Arcelia Hernández (1999) Bil<strong>in</strong>gual education<strong>in</strong> an immigrant community: Proposition 227 <strong>in</strong> California. International Journalof Bil<strong>in</strong>gual Education and Bil<strong>in</strong>gualism 2, 114130.Ortego y Gasca, Felipe (1981) A bil<strong>in</strong>gual childhood. American Scholar 50, 430431.Orwell, George (1937) The Road to Wigan Pier. London: Gollancz (<strong>the</strong> quotation istaken from <strong>the</strong> 1966 Pengu<strong>in</strong> paperback edition).Orwell, George (1940) England your England. In Inside <strong>the</strong> Whale and O<strong>the</strong>r Essays.London: Gollancz (<strong>the</strong> quotation is taken from <strong>the</strong> 1964 Pengu<strong>in</strong> paperbackedition).Osborn, Terry (2000) Critical Reflection and <strong>the</strong> Foreign <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>.Westport, CT: Berg<strong>in</strong> & Garvey.Osborne, Jason (1997) Race and academic disidentification. Journal of EducationalPsychology 89, 728735.Ossorio, Pilar and Troy Duster (2005) Race and genetics: Controversies <strong>in</strong>biomedical, behavioral and forensic sciences. American Psychologist 60, 115128 (this issue is devoted to ‘Genes, race and psychology <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> genome era’and, beyond <strong>the</strong> Ossorio and Duster paper, <strong>the</strong>re are useful contributions fromAudrey and Brian Smedley (q.v.) on race and racism, and from RobertSternberg, Elena Grigorenko and Kenneth Kidd, and Richard Cooper, on raceand <strong>in</strong>telligence).


320 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>Ousby, Ian (2000) The Cambridge Guide to Literature <strong>in</strong> English. Cambridge:Cambridge University Press.Ovando, Carlos and Karen Gourd (1996) Knowledge construction, languagema<strong>in</strong>tenance, revitalization and empowerment. In J. Banks (ed.) MulticulturalEducation, Transformative Knowledge and Action: Historical and ContemporaryPerspectives. New York: Teachers College Press.Palozzi, V<strong>in</strong>cent (2006) Assess<strong>in</strong>g voter attitude toward language policy issues <strong>in</strong><strong>the</strong> United States. <strong>Language</strong> Policy 5, 1539.Pandey, Anjali (2000) Symposium on <strong>the</strong> Ebonics Debate and African American<strong>Language</strong> (Special Section of World Englishes 19, 1).Pandit, Prabodh (1979) Perspectives on sociol<strong>in</strong>guistics <strong>in</strong> India. In W.McCormack and S. Wurm (eds) <strong>Language</strong> and Society. TheHague:Mouton.Parekh, Bhikhu (2006) Fight<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> war on dogma. CAUT Bullet<strong>in</strong> (CanadianAssociation of University Teachers), November.Pastore, Nicholas (1978) The Army <strong>in</strong>telligence tests and Walter Lippmann.Journal of <strong>the</strong> History of <strong>the</strong> Behavioral Sciences 14, 316327.Pattanayak, Debi (1986) On be<strong>in</strong>g and becom<strong>in</strong>g bil<strong>in</strong>gual <strong>in</strong> India. In J. Fishman,A. Tabouret-Keller, M. Clyne, B. Krishnamurti and M. Abdulaziz (eds) TheFergusonian Impact. Berl<strong>in</strong>: de Gruyter.Peal, Elizabeth and Wallace Lambert (1962) The relation of bil<strong>in</strong>gualism to<strong>in</strong>telligence. Psychological Monographs 76, 123.Pearce, Sarah (2005) You Wouldn’t Understand: White Teachers <strong>in</strong> Multiethnic<strong>Classroom</strong>s. Stoke-on-Trent: Trentham.Pearson, Karl (19141930) The Life, Letters and Labours of Francis Galton. Cambridge:Cambridge University Press (3 volumes <strong>in</strong> 4: Volume 1 (1914); Volume2 (1924); Volumes 3a and 3b (1930)).Penny, Laura (2005) Your Call is Important to Us: The Truth about Bullshit. Toronto:McClelland & Stewart.Pennycook, Alastair (2001) Critical Applied L<strong>in</strong>guistics: A Critical Introduction.Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.Pérez Carreón, Gustavo, Corey Drake and Angela Barton (2005) The importanceof presence: Immigrant parents’ school engagement experiences. AmericanEducational Research Journal 42, 465498.Peritz, Ingrid (2005) CBC <strong>in</strong> hot water after show guest says blacks have low IQs.Globe & Mail [Toronto], 30 September.Perry, Theresa, Claude Steele and Asa Hilliard (2003) Young, Gifted and Black:Promot<strong>in</strong>g High Achievement among African American Students. Boston, MA:Beacon.Persell, Carol<strong>in</strong>e (1981) Genetic and cultural deficit <strong>the</strong>ories: Two sides of <strong>the</strong>same racist co<strong>in</strong>. Journal of Black Studies 12, 1937.Petrovic, John (2005) The conservative restoration and neoliberal defenses ofbil<strong>in</strong>gual education. <strong>Language</strong> Policy 4, 395416.Philippou, Styliane (2005) Modernism and national identity <strong>in</strong> Brazil, or how tobrew a Brazilian stew. National Identities 7, 245264.Philips, Susan (1970) Acquisition of rules for appropriate speech usage. GeorgetownUniversity Round Table on L<strong>in</strong>guistics and <strong>Language</strong> Studies 23, 77101.Philips, Susan (1983) The Invisible Culture. New York: Longman.Phillipps, K.C. (Kenneth Charles) (1984) <strong>Language</strong> and Class <strong>in</strong> Victorian England.Oxford: Blackwell (<strong>in</strong> association with André Deutsch).


References 321Phillipson, Robert (1992) L<strong>in</strong>guistic Imperialism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Piaget, Jean (1952) The <strong>Language</strong> and Thought of <strong>the</strong> Child. London: Routledge &Kegan Paul.Pichart, James and Richard Anderson (1977) Tak<strong>in</strong>g different perspectives on astory. Journal of Educational Psychology 69, 309315.Piché, Gene, Michael Michl<strong>in</strong>, Donald Rub<strong>in</strong> and A. Sullivan (1977) Effectsof dialect-ethnicity, social class and quality of written compositions onteachers’ subjective evaluations of children. Communication Monographs 44,6072.Piestrup, Ann (1973) Black Dialect Interference and Accommodation of Read<strong>in</strong>gInstruction <strong>in</strong> First Grade. Berkeley, CA: University of California, <strong>Language</strong>-Behavior Research Laboratory.P<strong>in</strong>ker, Steven (1994) The <strong>Language</strong> Inst<strong>in</strong>ct. New York: Morrow.Plant, E. Ashby, Patricia Dev<strong>in</strong>e and Paige Brazey (2003) The bogus pipel<strong>in</strong>e andmotivations to respond without prejudice: Revisit<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> fad<strong>in</strong>g and fak<strong>in</strong>g ofracial prejudice. Group Processes and Intergroup Relations 6, 187200.Plowden, Bridget (1967) Children and Their Primary Schools (Plowden Report).Department of Education and Science (London): HMSO.Plowden, Bridget (1970) Compensatory education and <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>fant school. In T. Coxand C. Waite (eds) Teach<strong>in</strong>g Disadvantaged Children <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Infant School. Swansea:University College.Podhoretz, Norman (1985) Aga<strong>in</strong>st bil<strong>in</strong>gual education. New York Post, 8 October.Poetter, Thomas, Joseph Wegwert and Ca<strong>the</strong>r<strong>in</strong>e Haerr (2006) No Child Left Beh<strong>in</strong>dand <strong>the</strong> Illusion of Reform. Lanham, MD: University Press of America.Pont<strong>in</strong>g, Clive (1994) Churchill. London: Stevenson.Poplack, Shana (ed.) (2000) The English History of African American English. Oxford:Blackwell.Poplack, Shana and Sali Tagliamonte (2001) African American English <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>Diaspora. Oxford: Blackwell.Porcel, Jorge (2006) The paradox of Spanish among Miami Cubans. Journal ofSociol<strong>in</strong>guistics 10, 93110.Porter, John (1972) Dilemmas and contradictions of a multi-ethnic society.Transactions of <strong>the</strong> Royal Society of Canada 10, 193205.Portes, Alejandro and Rubén Rumbaut (1996) Immigrant America (2nd edn).Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.Potter, Jonathan and Margaret We<strong>the</strong>rell (1987) Discourse and Social Psychology.London: Sage.Power, Sally, Peter Aggleton, Julia Brannen, Andrew Brown, Lynn Chisholm andJohn Mace (eds) (2001) A Tribute to Basil Bernste<strong>in</strong>, 19242000. London: Instituteof Education.Preston, Dennis (1989) Perceptual Dialectology: Non-L<strong>in</strong>guists’ Views of ArealL<strong>in</strong>guistics. Dordrecht: Foris.Preston, Dennis (ed.) (1999) Handbook of Perceptual Dialectology: Volume 1.Amsterdam: John Benjam<strong>in</strong>s.Preston, Dennis (ed.) (2003) Needed Research <strong>in</strong> American Dialects. Durham, NC:Duke University Press.Pütz, Mart<strong>in</strong>, Joshua Fishman and Jo-Anne Neff-van Aertselaer (eds) (2006) Along<strong>the</strong> Routes to Power. Berl<strong>in</strong>: Mouton de Gruyter.


322 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>Quiocho, Alice and Francisco Rios (2000) The power of <strong>the</strong>ir presence: M<strong>in</strong>oritygroup teachers and school<strong>in</strong>g. Review of Educational Research 70, 485528.Radio-Canada (2005) Pla<strong>in</strong>tes contre le Docteur Mailloux devant le CRTC et leCollège des Médec<strong>in</strong>s. On WWW at www.radio-canada.ca/culture/.Rafter, Nicole (1988) White Trash: The Eugenic Family Studies, 18771919. Boston,MA: Nor<strong>the</strong>astern University Press.Ra<strong>in</strong>water, Lee (1970) Neutraliz<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> dis<strong>in</strong>herited: Some psychological aspectsof understand<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> poor. In V. Allen (ed.) Psychological Factors <strong>in</strong> Poverty.Chicago, IL: Markham.Ramirez, J. David, Terrence Wiley, Gerde de Klerk, Enid Lee and Wayne Wright(eds) (2005) Ebonics: The Urban Education Debate (2nd edn). Clevedon: Multil<strong>in</strong>gualMatters.Rampton, Ben (2006) <strong>Language</strong> <strong>in</strong> Late Modernity: Interaction <strong>in</strong> an Urban School.Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Rampton, Ben (2007) Neo-Hymesian l<strong>in</strong>guistic ethnography <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> UnitedK<strong>in</strong>gdom. Journal of Sociol<strong>in</strong>guistics 11, 584607.Rampton, Ben, Kar<strong>in</strong> Tust<strong>in</strong>g, Janet Mayb<strong>in</strong>, Richard Barwell, Angela Creese andVally Lytra (2004) U.K. l<strong>in</strong>guistic ethnography: A discussion paper. On WWWat www.l<strong>in</strong>g-ethnog.org.uk.Rampton, Ben, Janet Mayb<strong>in</strong> and Kar<strong>in</strong> Tust<strong>in</strong>g (eds) (2007) L<strong>in</strong>guisticEthnography: L<strong>in</strong>ks, Problems and Possibilities. Oxford: Blackwell (Journal ofSociol<strong>in</strong>guistics 11 (5)).Rao, Raja (1938) Kanthapura. London: Allen & Unw<strong>in</strong>.Raven, John (2005) Lethal <strong>in</strong>telligence. The Psychologist 18 (2), 68.Raven, John and John Stephenson (eds) (2001) Competence <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Learn<strong>in</strong>g Society.New York: Lang.Reagan, Ronald (1982) Public Papers of <strong>the</strong> Presidents of <strong>the</strong> United States: RonaldReagan, 1981. Book 1: January 20 to December 31, 1981. Wash<strong>in</strong>gton, DC: UnitedStates Government Pr<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g Office (Reagan’s speech was <strong>in</strong>itially reported <strong>in</strong><strong>the</strong> Democrat and Chronicle (Rochester, New York), 3 March 1981).Reagan, Timothy (2006) Review of Second <strong>Language</strong> Teacher Education: InternationalPerspectives (Diane Tedick). Studies <strong>in</strong> Second <strong>Language</strong> Acquisition 28, 133134.Reagan, Timothy and Terry Osborn (2002) The Foreign <strong>Language</strong> Educator <strong>in</strong>Society. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.Reyes, Luis (2006) The Aspira Consent Decree: A thirtieth-anniversary retrospectiveof bil<strong>in</strong>gual education <strong>in</strong> New York City. Harvard Educational Review 76,369400.Rich, F. (1997) The Ebonic plague. Globe & Mail [Toronto], 9 January.Richardson, Brian (2005) Tell It Like It Is: How Our Schools Fail Black Children.London: Trentham.Richardson, Ela<strong>in</strong>e (1998) The anti-Ebonics movement: ‘Standard’ English only.Journal of English L<strong>in</strong>guistics 26, 156169.Rickford, John (2002) L<strong>in</strong>guistics, education and <strong>the</strong> Ebonics firestorm. InJ. Alatis, H. Hamilton and A.-H. Tan (eds) Georgetown University Round Tableon <strong>Language</strong>s and L<strong>in</strong>guistics 2000: L<strong>in</strong>guistics, <strong>Language</strong> and <strong>the</strong> Professions:Education, Journalism, Law, Medic<strong>in</strong>e and Technology.Rickford, John (2005) Us<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> vernacular to teach <strong>the</strong> standard. In J.D. Ramirez,T. Wiley, G. de Klerk, E. Lee and W. Wright (eds) Ebonics: The Urban EducationDebate (2nd edn). Clevedon: Multil<strong>in</strong>gual Matters.


References 323Rickford, John and A. Rickford (1995/2005) Dialect readers revisited. L<strong>in</strong>guisticsand Education 7, 107128 (a two-page summary appears <strong>in</strong> J.D. Ramirez,T. Wiley, G. de Klerk, E. Lee and W. Wright (eds) Ebonics: The Urban EducationDebate (2nd edn). Clevedon: Multil<strong>in</strong>gual Matters, 2005).Rist, Ray (1970) Student social class and teacher expectations: The self-fulfill<strong>in</strong>gprophecy <strong>in</strong> ghetto education. Harvard Educational Review 40, 411451.Roberts, Mark (2008) The Mark of <strong>the</strong> Beast: Animality and Human Oppression. WestLafayette, IN: Purdue University Press.Rob<strong>in</strong>son, Philip (1976) Education and Poverty. London: Methuen.Rob<strong>in</strong>son, W. Peter (1965) The elaborated code <strong>in</strong> work<strong>in</strong>g class language.<strong>Language</strong> and Speech 8, 243252.Rob<strong>in</strong>son, W. Peter (1972) <strong>Language</strong> and Social Behaviour. Harmondsworth:Pengu<strong>in</strong>.Rob<strong>in</strong>son, W. Peter (1985) Social psychology and discourse. In T. van Dijk (ed.)Handbook of Discourse Analysis, Volume 1: Discipl<strong>in</strong>es of Discourse. London:Academic Press.Rob<strong>in</strong>son, W. Peter (1998) <strong>Language</strong> and social psychology: An <strong>in</strong>tersection ofopportunities and significance. Journal of <strong>Language</strong> and Social Psychology 17,276301.Rob<strong>in</strong>son, W. Peter (2001) A tale of two histories: <strong>Language</strong> use and education <strong>in</strong>relation to social class and gender. Journal of <strong>Language</strong> and Social Psychology 20,231247.Rob<strong>in</strong>son, W. Peter and Howard Giles (eds) (2001) The New Handbook of <strong>Language</strong>and Social Psychology. New York: John Wiley.Rob<strong>in</strong>son, W. Peter and Susan Rackstraw (1972) A Question of Answers. London:Routledge & Kegan Paul.Rocher, Guy (1973) Le Québec en mutation. Montreal: Éditions Hurtubise.Rodriguez, Richard (1980a) Aria: A memoir of a bil<strong>in</strong>gual childhood. AmericanScholar 50, 2542.Rodriguez, Richard (1980b) An education <strong>in</strong> language. In L. Michaels andC. Ricks (eds) The State of <strong>the</strong> <strong>Language</strong>. Berkeley, CA: University of CaliforniaPress.Rodriguez, Richard (1982) Hunger of Memory: The Education of Richard Rodríguez.Boston, MA: God<strong>in</strong>e.Rodriguez, Richard (1993) Days of Obligation: An Argument With My MexicanFa<strong>the</strong>r. London: Pengu<strong>in</strong>.Roem<strong>in</strong>g, Richard (1971) Bil<strong>in</strong>gualism and <strong>the</strong> national <strong>in</strong>terest. Modern <strong>Language</strong>Journal 55, 7381.Rogers, Rebecca, Elizabeth Malancharuvil-Berkes, Melissa Mosley, Diane Hui andGlynis Joseph (2005) Critical discourse analysis <strong>in</strong> education: A review of <strong>the</strong>literature. Review of Educational Research 75, 365416.Roma<strong>in</strong>e, Suzanne (1995) Bil<strong>in</strong>gualism (2nd edn). Oxford: Blackwell, 1995.Ronjat, Jules (1913) Le développement du langage observé chez un enfant bil<strong>in</strong>gue.Paris: Champion.Roosevelt, Theodore (1919) Abolish hyphen Roosevelt’s last words to public.Chicago Daily Tribune, 7 January.Rosen, E. (1982) Epistle to Kaplan: Remarks on <strong>the</strong> ethno-<strong>in</strong>quiries. Sociol<strong>in</strong>guisticsNewsletter 13 (1), 1823.


324 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>Rosen, Harold (1972) <strong>Language</strong> and Class: A Critical Look at <strong>the</strong> Theories of BasilBernste<strong>in</strong>. Bristol: Fall<strong>in</strong>g Wall Press.Rosen, Harold (1978) Sign<strong>in</strong>g on. The New Review 5: 1.Rosenthal, Robert and Lenore Jacobson (1968) Pygmalion <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>.New York: Holt, R<strong>in</strong>ehart & W<strong>in</strong>ston (see also <strong>the</strong> slightly enlarged edition New York: Irv<strong>in</strong>gton, 1992).Rosewarne, David (1984) Estuary English. Times Educational Supplement, 19 October.Rosewarne, David (1994) Estuary English: Tomorrow’s RP? English Today 37, 38.Ross, Lee and Richard Nisbett (1991) The Person and <strong>the</strong> Situation. Philadelphia,PA: Temple University Press.Rotberg, Iris (1984) Bil<strong>in</strong>gual education policy <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> United States. Prospects 14,133147.Rushton, J. Philippe (1995) Race, Evolution and Behavior. New Brunswick,NJ: Transaction.Rushton, J. Philippe and G. Young (1975) Context and complexity <strong>in</strong> work<strong>in</strong>gclass language. <strong>Language</strong> and Speech 18, 366387.Rutter, Michael and Nicola Madge (1977) Cycles of Disadvantage. London:He<strong>in</strong>emann.Ryan, Ellen Bouchard (1979) Why do low-prestige varieties persist? In H. Gilesand R. St Clair (eds) <strong>Language</strong> and Social Psychology. Oxford: Blackwell.Ryan, Ellen Bouchard and Miguel Carranza (1975) Evaluative reactions ofadolescents toward speakers of standard English and Mexican Americanaccented English. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 31, 855863.Ryan, Ellen Bouchard, Miguel Carranza and Robert Moffie (1977) Reactionstoward vary<strong>in</strong>g degrees of accentedness <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> speech of Spanish-Englishbil<strong>in</strong>guals. <strong>Language</strong> and Speech 20, 267273.Ryan, William (1971) Blam<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> Victim. New York: Pan<strong>the</strong>on.Sachs, Jacquel<strong>in</strong>e (1975) Cues to <strong>the</strong> identification of sex <strong>in</strong> children’s speech. InB. Thorne and N. Henley (eds) <strong>Language</strong> and Sex: Difference and Dom<strong>in</strong>ance.Rowley, MA: Newbury.Sachs, Jacquel<strong>in</strong>e, Philip Lieberman and Donna Erickson (1973) Anatomical andcultural determ<strong>in</strong>ants of male and female speech. In R. Shuy and R. Fasold(eds) <strong>Language</strong> Attitudes: Current Trends and Prospects. Wash<strong>in</strong>gton, DC:Georgetown University Press.Sacks, Harvey, Emanuel Schegloff and Gail Jefferson (1974) A simplest systematicsfor <strong>the</strong> organization of turn-tak<strong>in</strong>g for conversation. <strong>Language</strong> 50, 696735.Salkie, Raphael (2004) Blair’s lessons <strong>in</strong> ethics of respect. Times Higher EducationSupplement, 8 October.Samelson, Franz (1977) World War I <strong>in</strong>telligence test<strong>in</strong>g and <strong>the</strong> development ofpsychology. Journal of <strong>the</strong> History of <strong>the</strong> Behavioral Sciences 13, 274282.Samelson, Franz (1978) From ‘race psychology’ to ‘studies <strong>in</strong> prejudice’: Someobservations on <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>matic reversal <strong>in</strong> social psychology. Journal of <strong>the</strong>History of <strong>the</strong> Behavioral Sciences 13, 265278.Sampson, Geoffrey (1980) Schools of L<strong>in</strong>guistics: Competition and Evolution. London:Hutch<strong>in</strong>son.San Miguel, Guadalupe (2004) Contested Policy: The Rise and Fall of Federal Bil<strong>in</strong>gualEducation <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> United States, 19602001. Denton, TX: University of NorthTexas Press.


References 325Sandiford, Peter and Ruby Kerr (1926) Intelligence of Ch<strong>in</strong>ese and Japanesechildren. Journal of Educational Psychology 17, 361367.Schank, Roger (2006) Th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g is no help <strong>in</strong> mak<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> grade. Times HigherEducation Supplement, 28 April.Schatzman, Leonard and Anselm Strauss (1955) Social class and modes ofcommunication. American Journal of Sociology 60, 329338.Schegloff, Emanuel (1997) Whose text? Whose context? Discourse and Society 8,165187.Schles<strong>in</strong>ger, Arthur (1992) The Disunit<strong>in</strong>g of America: Reflections on a MulticulturalSociety. New York: Norton.Schneider, William (1992) After B<strong>in</strong>et: French <strong>in</strong>telligence test<strong>in</strong>g, 19001950.Journal of <strong>the</strong> History of <strong>the</strong> Behavioral Sciences 28, 111132.Schwartz, Robert (2001) Racial profil<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> medical research. New England Journalof Medic<strong>in</strong>e 344 (18), 13921393.Scott, Jerrie (1998) The serious side of Ebonics humor. Journal of English L<strong>in</strong>guistics26, 137155.Scruton, Roger (2006) Values are not learnt through teach<strong>in</strong>g. Daily Telegraph,16 May.Seligman, Clive, G. Richard Tucker and Wallace Lambert (1972) The effects ofspeech style and o<strong>the</strong>r attributes on teachers’ attitudes toward pupils.<strong>Language</strong> <strong>in</strong> Society 1, 131142.Shafer, Robert and Susanne Shafer (1975) Teacher attitudes towards children’slanguage <strong>in</strong> West Germany and England. Comparative Education 11, 4361.Shockley, William (1970) A ‘try simplest cases’ approach to <strong>the</strong> heredity-povertycrimeproblem. In V. Allen (ed.) Psychological Factors <strong>in</strong> Poverty. Chicago,IL: Markham.Shohamy, Elana (2001) The Power of Tests. Harlow: Longman.Shurk<strong>in</strong>, Joel (2006) Broken Genius: The Rise and Fall of William Shockley, Creator of<strong>the</strong> Electronic Age. London: Palgrave Macmillan.Shuy, Roger (1970) The sociol<strong>in</strong>guists and urban language problems. InF. Williams (ed.) <strong>Language</strong> and Poverty. Chicago, IL: Markham.Siegel, Jeff (2006) Keep<strong>in</strong>g creoles and dialects out of <strong>the</strong> classroom: Is it justified?In S. Nero (ed.) Dialects, Englishes, Creoles and Education. Mahwah, NJ:Lawrence Erlbaum.Siegel, Jeff (2007) Creoles and m<strong>in</strong>ority dialects <strong>in</strong> education: An update. <strong>Language</strong>and Education 21, 6686.Sigall, Harold and Richard Page (1971) Current stereotypes: A little fad<strong>in</strong>g, a littlefak<strong>in</strong>g. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 18, 247255.Simons, Herbert (1974) Black dialects and learn<strong>in</strong>g to read. In Jerry Johns (ed.)Literacy for Diverse Learners. Newark, DE: International Read<strong>in</strong>g Association.Simons, Herbert and Kenneth Johnson (1974) Black English syntax and read<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>terference. Research <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Teach<strong>in</strong>g of English 8, 339358.Simpk<strong>in</strong>s, Gary, Grace Holt and Charlesetta Simpk<strong>in</strong>s (1977) Bridge: A Cross-Cultural Read<strong>in</strong>g Program. Boston, MA: Houghton Miffl<strong>in</strong>.Simpk<strong>in</strong>s, Gary and Charlesetta Simpk<strong>in</strong>s (1981) Cross-cultural approach tocurriculum development. In G. Smi<strong>the</strong>rman (ed.) Black English and <strong>the</strong>Education of Black Children and Youth: Proceed<strong>in</strong>gs of <strong>the</strong> National InvitationalSymposium on <strong>the</strong> K<strong>in</strong>g Decision. Detroit, MI: Center for Black Studies, WayneState University.


326 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>Sir<strong>in</strong>, Selcuk (2005) Socioeconomic status and academic achievement: A metaanalyticreview of research. Review of Educational Research 75, 417453.Skeels, Harold and Harold Dye (1939) A study of <strong>the</strong> effects of differentialstimulation on mentally retarded children. Proceed<strong>in</strong>gs of <strong>the</strong> AmericanAssociation of Mental Deficiency 44, 114136.Skidmore, Thomas (1974) Black <strong>in</strong>to White: Race and Nationality <strong>in</strong> BrazilianThought. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Sleeter, Christ<strong>in</strong>e and Carl Grant (1987) An analysis of multicultural education <strong>in</strong><strong>the</strong> United States. Harvard Educational Review 57, 421444.Slembrouck, Stef (2001) Explanation, <strong>in</strong>terpretation and critique <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> analysis ofdiscourse. Critique of Anthropology 21, 3357.Slotk<strong>in</strong>, Richard (2005) Lost Battalions: The Great War and <strong>the</strong> Crisis of AmericanNationality. New York: Henry Holt.Smedley, Audrey and Brian Smedley (2005) Race as biology is fiction, racism as asocial problem is real. American Psychologist 60, 1626.Smith, Ernest (2001) Ebonics and bil<strong>in</strong>gual education of <strong>the</strong> African Americanchild. In C. Crawford (ed.) Ebonics and <strong>Language</strong> Education. New York:Sankofa.Smith, J. (1988) Review of Discourse and Social Psychology (Jonathan Potter andMargaret We<strong>the</strong>rell). The Psychologist 1, 109.Smith, Madorah (1939) Some light on <strong>the</strong> problem of bil<strong>in</strong>gualism as foundfrom a study of <strong>the</strong> progress <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> mastery of English among preschoolchildren of non-American ancestry <strong>in</strong> Hawaii. Genetic Psychology Monographs21, 119284.Smi<strong>the</strong>rman, Geneva (ed.) (1981a) Black English and <strong>the</strong> Education of Black Childrenand Youth: Proceed<strong>in</strong>gs of <strong>the</strong> National Invitational Symposium on <strong>the</strong> K<strong>in</strong>gDecision. Detroit, MI: Center for Black Studies, Wayne State University.Smi<strong>the</strong>rman, Geneva (1981b) What go round come round: K<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> perspective.Harvard Educational Review 51, 4056.Smi<strong>the</strong>rman, Geneva (1998) Ebonics, K<strong>in</strong>g and Oakland: Some folks don’t believefat meat is greasy. Journal of English L<strong>in</strong>guistics 26, 97107.Smi<strong>the</strong>rman, Geneva (2006) Word From <strong>the</strong> Mo<strong>the</strong>r: <strong>Language</strong> and AfricanAmericans. London: Routledge.Smi<strong>the</strong>rman-Donaldson, Geneva (1988) Discrim<strong>in</strong>atory discourse on Afro-American speech. In G. Smi<strong>the</strong>rman-Donaldson and T. van Dijk (eds.)Discourse and Discrim<strong>in</strong>ation. Detroit, MI: Wayne State University Press.Sniderman, Paul and Louk Hagendoorn (2007) When Ways of Life Collide:Multiculturalism and its Discontents <strong>in</strong> The Ne<strong>the</strong>rlands. Pr<strong>in</strong>ceton, NJ: Pr<strong>in</strong>cetonUniversity Press.Snow, Ca<strong>the</strong>r<strong>in</strong>e (1982) Knowledge and <strong>the</strong> use of language. In L. Feagans andD. Farran (eds) The <strong>Language</strong> of Children Reared <strong>in</strong> Poverty. New York:Academic.Sommers, Christ<strong>in</strong>a (2000) The War Aga<strong>in</strong>st Boys: How Misguided Fem<strong>in</strong>ism isHarm<strong>in</strong>g Our Young Men. New York: Simon & Schuster.Somervill, Mary (1974) <strong>Language</strong> of <strong>the</strong> disadvantaged: Toward resolution ofconflict. Journal of Negro Education 43, 284301.Somervill, Mary (1975) Dialect and read<strong>in</strong>g: A review of alternative solutions.Review of Educational Research 45, 247262.


References 327Somervill, Mary and John Jacobs (1972) The use of dialect <strong>in</strong> read<strong>in</strong>g materials forblack <strong>in</strong>ner-city children. Negro Educational Review 23, 1323.Spearman, Charles (1927) The Abilities of Man. London: Macmillan.Spearman, Charles (1937) Psychology Down <strong>the</strong> Ages. London: Macmillan(2 volumes).Spearman, Charles and Llewelyn Wynn Jones (1950) Human Ability. London:Macmillan.Spears, Arthur (1987) Are black and white vernaculars diverg<strong>in</strong>g? In R. Fasold,W. Labov, F. Vaughn-Cooke, G. Bailey, W. Wolfram, A. Spears and J. Rickford,Are Black and White Vernaculars Diverg<strong>in</strong>g? Papers from <strong>the</strong> NWAVE-XIV PanelDiscussion (American Speech 62 (1), 380).Speicher, Barbara and Seane McMahon (1992) Some African-American perspectiveson Black English Vernacular. <strong>Language</strong> <strong>in</strong> Society 21, 383407.Spender, Dale (1980) Talk<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> class. In D. Spender and E. Sarah (eds)Learn<strong>in</strong>g to Lose: Sexism and Education. London: Women’s Press.Spitz, René (1946) Anaclitic depression. Psychoanalytic Study of <strong>the</strong> Child 2,313342.Spolsky, Bernard (1989a) Conditions for Second-<strong>Language</strong> Learn<strong>in</strong>g. Oxford: OxfordUniversity Press.Spolsky, Bernard (1989b) Review of Key Issues <strong>in</strong> Bil<strong>in</strong>gualism and Bil<strong>in</strong>gualEducation (Col<strong>in</strong> Baker). Applied L<strong>in</strong>guistics 10, 449451.Spolsky, Bernard (1995) Measured Words: The Development of Objective <strong>Language</strong>Test<strong>in</strong>g. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Sroufe, L. Alan (1970) A methodological and philosophical critique of <strong>in</strong>terventionorientedresearch. Developmental Psychology 2, 140145.Stammerjohann, Harro (ed.) (1996) Lexicon Grammaticorum: Who’s Who <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>History of World L<strong>in</strong>guistics. Tüb<strong>in</strong>gen: Max Niemeyer.Stanworth, Michelle (1981) Gender and School<strong>in</strong>g: A Study of Sexual Divisions <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong><strong>Classroom</strong>. London: Women’s Research Centre.Staples, Brent (1997) The last tra<strong>in</strong> from Oakland. The New York Times, 24 January.Steele, Claude (1992) Race and <strong>the</strong> school<strong>in</strong>g of African-American Americans[sic]. Atlantic Monthly, May (269: 4), 6878.Steele, Claude (1997) A threat <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> air: How stereotypes shape <strong>in</strong>tellectualidentity and performance. American Psychologist 52, 613629.Steele, Claude and Joshua Aronson (1995) Stereotype threat and <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>tellectualtest performance of African-Americans. Journal of Personality and SocialPsychology 69, 797811.Steigerwald, David (2004) Culture’s Vanities: The Paradox of Cultural <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> aGlobalized World. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.Ste<strong>in</strong>, Gertrude (1937) Everybody’s Autobiography. New York: Random House.Ste<strong>in</strong>berg, Laurence, B. Bradford Brown and Sanford Dornbusch (1996) Beyond <strong>the</strong><strong>Classroom</strong>. New York: Simon & Schuster.Ste<strong>in</strong>er, George (1992) After Babel (2nd edn). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Ste<strong>in</strong>er, George and Cécile Ladjali (2003) Éloge de la transmission: le maître et l’élève.Paris: Alb<strong>in</strong> Michel.Stern, Alexandra (2005) Eugenic Nation: Faults and Frontiers of Better Breed<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>Modern America. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.Stetson, George (1897) Some memory tests of Whites and Blacks. PsychologicalReview 4, 285289.


328 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>Stewart, William (1972) On <strong>the</strong> use of Negro dialect <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> teach<strong>in</strong>g of read<strong>in</strong>g. InR. Abrahams and R. Troike (eds) <strong>Language</strong> and Cultural <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> AmericanEducation. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.St<strong>in</strong>son, David (2006) African American male adolescents, school<strong>in</strong>g (andma<strong>the</strong>matics): Deficiency, rejection, and achievement. Review of EducationalResearch 76, 477506.Stoller, Paul (1977) The language plann<strong>in</strong>g activities of <strong>the</strong> U.S. Office of Bil<strong>in</strong>gualEducation. L<strong>in</strong>guistics 189, 4560.Stone, Maureen (1981) The Education of <strong>the</strong> Black Child <strong>in</strong> Brita<strong>in</strong>: The Myth ofMultiracial Education. London: Fontana.Strauss, Anselm and Leonard Schatzman (1960) Cross-class <strong>in</strong>terview<strong>in</strong>g: Ananalysis of <strong>in</strong>teraction and communicative styles. In R. Adams and J. Preiss(eds) Human Organization Research. Homewood, IL: Dorsey.Stubbs, Michael (1983a) <strong>Language</strong>, Schools and <strong>Classroom</strong>s. London: Methuen.Stubbs, Michael (1983b) Discourse Analysis. Oxford: Blackwell.Stubbs, Michael (1984) Applied discourse analysis and educational l<strong>in</strong>guistics.In P. Trudgill (ed.) Applied Sociol<strong>in</strong>guistics. London: Academic Press.Stubbs, Michael (1986) Educational L<strong>in</strong>guistics. Oxford: Blackwell.Sudnow, David (1972) Temporal parameters of <strong>in</strong>terpersonal observation. InD. Sudnow (ed.) Studies <strong>in</strong> Social Interaction. New York: Free Press.Swaffar, Janet (1999) The case for foreign languages as a discipl<strong>in</strong>e. ADFL Bullet<strong>in</strong>30(3), 612.Swann, Michael (1985) Education for All: The Report of <strong>the</strong> Committee of Inquiry <strong>in</strong>to<strong>the</strong> Education of Children from Ethnic M<strong>in</strong>ority Groups (Report). Department ofEducation and Science (London): HMSO.Talbot, Margaret (2003) The executioner’s IQ test. New York Times Magaz<strong>in</strong>e,29 June.Tannen, Deborah (1998) The Argument Culture. New York: Random House.Tannen, Deborah, Shari Kendall and Carolyn Adger (1997) Conversationalpatterns across gender, class and ethnicity: Implications for classroomdiscourse. In B. Davies and D. Corson (eds) Oral Discourse and Education.Dordrecht: Kluwer.Taylor, April and Sandra Graham (2007) An exam<strong>in</strong>ation of <strong>the</strong> relationshipbetween achievement values and perceptions of barriers among low-SESAfrican American and Lat<strong>in</strong>o students. Journal of Educational Psychology 99,5264.Taylor, Charles (1992) Multiculturalism and ‘The Politics of Recognition’. Pr<strong>in</strong>ceton,NJ: Pr<strong>in</strong>ceton University Press.Taylor, L. and Graham Skanes (1977) A cross-cultural exam<strong>in</strong>ation of some ofJensen’s hypo<strong>the</strong>ses. Canadian Journal of Behavioural Science 9, 315322.Telles, Edward (2004) Race <strong>in</strong> Ano<strong>the</strong>r America: The Significance of Sk<strong>in</strong> Color <strong>in</strong>Brazil. Pr<strong>in</strong>ceton, NJ: Pr<strong>in</strong>ceton University Press.Templ<strong>in</strong>, Mildred (1957) Certa<strong>in</strong> <strong>Language</strong> Skills <strong>in</strong> Children. M<strong>in</strong>neapolis, MN:University of M<strong>in</strong>nesota Press.Tenenbaum, Harriet and Mart<strong>in</strong> Ruck (2007) Are teachers’ expectations differentfor racial m<strong>in</strong>ority than for European American students? A meta-analysis.Journal of Educational Psychology 99, 253273.Terman, Lewis (1906) Genius and stupidity: A study of some of <strong>the</strong><strong>in</strong>tellectual processes of seven ‘bright’ and seven ‘stupid’ boys. Pedagogical


References 329Sem<strong>in</strong>ary 13, 307373 (this, Terman’s PhD <strong>the</strong>sis, was repr<strong>in</strong>ted <strong>in</strong> 1975:New York: Arno).Terman, Lewis (1918) The use of <strong>in</strong>telligence tests <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Army. PsychologicalBullet<strong>in</strong> 15, 177187.Terman, Lewis (1922) Were we born that way? The World’s Work 44, 655660.Terrill, Marguerite and Dianne Mark (2000) Pre-service teachers’ expectations forschools with children of color and second-language learners. Journal of TeacherEducation 51, 149157.Thomson, J. (1977) Social class labell<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> application of Bernste<strong>in</strong>’s <strong>the</strong>ory of<strong>the</strong> codes to <strong>the</strong> identification of l<strong>in</strong>guistic advantage and disadvantage <strong>in</strong>five-year-old children. Educational Review 29, 273283.Throop, Rachel (2007) Teachers as language policy planners. Work<strong>in</strong>g Papers <strong>in</strong>Educational L<strong>in</strong>guistics (Graduate School of Education, University of Pennsylvania)22 (2), 4565.Thurmond, Vera (1977) The effect of Black English on <strong>the</strong> read<strong>in</strong>g testperformance of high school students. Journal of Educational Research 70,160163.Todd, Loreto (1997) Ebonics: An evaluation. English Today 13 (3), 1317.Toml<strong>in</strong>son, Sally (1984) Home, school and community. In M. Craft (ed.) Educationand Cultural Pluralism. London: Falmer.Torrey, Jane (1973) Illiteracy <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> ghetto. In N. Keddie (ed.) T<strong>in</strong>ker, Tailor...TheMyth of Cultural Deprivation. Harmondsworth: Pengu<strong>in</strong>.Torrey, Jane (1983) Black children’s knowledge of standard English. AmericanEducational Research Journal 20, 627643.Tough, Joan (1977) The Development of Mean<strong>in</strong>g: A Study of Children’s Use of<strong>Language</strong>. London: Allen & Unw<strong>in</strong>.Tough, Joan (1982) <strong>Language</strong>, poverty and disadvantage <strong>in</strong> school. In L. Feagansand D. Farran (eds) The <strong>Language</strong> of Children Reared <strong>in</strong> Poverty. New York:Academic Press.Tough, Joan (1985) Talk Two: Children Us<strong>in</strong>g English as a Second <strong>Language</strong>. London:Onyx.Trudgill, Peter (1972) Sex, covert prestige and l<strong>in</strong>guistic change <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> urbanBritish English of Norwich. <strong>Language</strong> <strong>in</strong> Society 1, 179195.Trudgill, Peter (1975) Accent, Dialect and <strong>the</strong> School. London: Edward Arnold.Trudgill, Peter (1979) Standard and non-standard dialects of English <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> UnitedK<strong>in</strong>gdom: Problems and policies. International Journal of <strong>the</strong> Sociology of<strong>Language</strong> 21, 924.Trudgill, Peter (1984) Preface. In P. Trudgill (ed.) Applied Sociol<strong>in</strong>guistics. London:Academic Press.Trudgill, Peter (1998) Review of <strong>Language</strong> is Power (John Honey). Journal ofSociol<strong>in</strong>guistics 2, 457461.Trudgill, Peter (2000) Sociol<strong>in</strong>guistics: An Introduction to <strong>Language</strong> and Society(4th edn). London: Pengu<strong>in</strong>.Trudgill, Peter (2002) Sociol<strong>in</strong>guistic Variation and Change. Wash<strong>in</strong>gton, DC:Georgetown University Press.Tucker, G. Richard and Wallace Lambert (1969) White and Negro listeners’reactions to various American-English dialects. Social Forces 47, 463468.Tucker, William (1994) The Science and Politics of Racial Research. Urbana, IL:University of Ill<strong>in</strong>ois Press.


330 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>Tucker, William (2002) The Fund<strong>in</strong>g of Scientific Racism: Wickliffe Draper and <strong>the</strong>Pioneer Fund. Urbana, IL: University of Ill<strong>in</strong>ois Press.Turner, L.D. (Lorenzo Dow) (1949) Africanisms <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Gullah Dialect. Chicago,IL: University of Chicago Press.Tust<strong>in</strong>g, Kar<strong>in</strong> and Janey Mayb<strong>in</strong> (2007) L<strong>in</strong>guistic ethnography and <strong>in</strong>terdiscipl<strong>in</strong>arity.Journal of Sociol<strong>in</strong>guistics 11, 575583.Tutton, Richard (2007) Open<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> white box: Explor<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> study of whiteness<strong>in</strong> contemporary genetics research. Ethnic and Racial Studies 30, 557569.Tuveng, Elena and Astri Wold (2005) The collaboration of teacher and languagem<strong>in</strong>oritychildren <strong>in</strong> mask<strong>in</strong>g comprehension problems <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> language of<strong>in</strong>struction: A case study <strong>in</strong> an urban Norwegian school. <strong>Language</strong> andEducation 19, 513536.Tyson, Karolyn (2002) Weigh<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>: Elementary-age students and <strong>the</strong> debate onattitudes toward school among Black students. Social Forces 80, 11571189.UNESCO (1953) The Use of Vernacular <strong>Language</strong>s <strong>in</strong> Education. Paris: UNESCO.Unz, Ron and Ca<strong>the</strong>r<strong>in</strong>e Snow (2002) Bil<strong>in</strong>gual education: A necessary help ora failed h<strong>in</strong>drance? Harvard Education Letter, January/February. On WWWat www.edletter.org/past/issues/2002-jf/forum.shtml/.Unz, Ron and Gloria Tuchman (1998) One homogeneous nation: The Unz<strong>in</strong>itiative. On WWW at http://www.smartnation.org/unz.htm.Valenzuela, Angela, L<strong>in</strong>da Prieto and Madlene Hamilton (2007) No Child LeftBeh<strong>in</strong>d and M<strong>in</strong>ority Youth: What <strong>the</strong> Qualitative Evidence Suggests. Berkeley, CA:University of California Press (Anthropology and Education Quarterly 38 (1)).Van Dijk, Teun (1993) Pr<strong>in</strong>ciples of critical discourse analysis. Discourse and Society4, 249283.Van Dijk, Teun (2001) Multidiscipl<strong>in</strong>ary CDA: A plea for diversity. In R. Wodakand M. Meyer (eds) Methods of Critical Discourse Analysis. London: Sage.Varghese, Manka (2004) Professional development for bil<strong>in</strong>gual teachers <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>United States. In J. Brutt-Griffler and M. Varghese (eds) Bil<strong>in</strong>gualism and<strong>Language</strong> Pedagogy. Clevedon: Multil<strong>in</strong>gual Matters.Varghese, Manka (2006) Bil<strong>in</strong>gual teachers-<strong>in</strong>-<strong>the</strong>-mak<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> Urbantown. Journalof Multil<strong>in</strong>gual and Multicultural Development 27, 211224.Venezky, Richard (1970) Nonstandard language and read<strong>in</strong>g. Elementary English47, 334345.Venezky, Richard (1981) Non-standard language and read<strong>in</strong>g: Ten years later. InJ. Edwards (ed.) The Social Psychology of Read<strong>in</strong>g. Silver Spr<strong>in</strong>g, MD: Institute ofModern <strong>Language</strong>s.Verschueren, Jeff (2001) Predicaments of criticism. Critique of Anthropology 21,5981.Vick, M. (1974) Relevant content for <strong>the</strong> black elementary school pupil. In J. Johns(ed.) Literacy for Diverse Learners. Newark, DE: International Read<strong>in</strong>g Association.Walker, Francis (1896) Restriction of immigration. Atlantic Monthly, June (77: 484),822829.Wallen, Mat<strong>the</strong>w and Helen Kelly-Holmes (2006) ‘I th<strong>in</strong>k <strong>the</strong>y just th<strong>in</strong>k it’sgo<strong>in</strong>g to go away at some stage’: Policy and practice <strong>in</strong> teach<strong>in</strong>g English asan additional language <strong>in</strong> Irish primary schools. <strong>Language</strong> and Education 20,141161.


References 331Wallis, Claudia and Sonja Steptoe (2007) How to fix ‘No Child Left Beh<strong>in</strong>d’. Time,4 June (169: 23), 2633.Walsh, Ca<strong>the</strong>r<strong>in</strong>e (1991) Pedagogy and <strong>the</strong> Struggle for Voice. New York: Berg<strong>in</strong> &Garvey.Wardhaugh, Ronald (2006) An Introduction to Sociol<strong>in</strong>guistics (5th edn). Oxford:Blackwell.Watts, Ronald (2003) Politeness. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Wax, Murray and Rosalie Wax (1971) Cultural deprivation as an educationalideology. In E. Leacock (ed.) The Culture of Poverty: A Critique. New York:Simon & Schuster.Wea<strong>the</strong>rs, John (2007) Privatiz<strong>in</strong>g schools. Work<strong>in</strong>g Papers <strong>in</strong> Educational L<strong>in</strong>guistics(Graduate School of Education, University of Pennsylvania) 22 (2), 6793.Webb, Nick (2005) The Dictionary of Bullshit. London: Robson.Webster, Jonathan (ed.) (2005) <strong>Language</strong>, Society and Consciousness: The CollectedWorks of Ruqaiya Hasan: Volume 1. London: Equ<strong>in</strong>ox (two fur<strong>the</strong>r volumes Semantic Variation: Mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> Society and <strong>Language</strong> <strong>in</strong> Education: Social Aspectsare <strong>in</strong> preparation).Wee, Lionel (2002) When English is not a mo<strong>the</strong>r tongue: L<strong>in</strong>guistic ownershipand <strong>the</strong> Eurasian community <strong>in</strong> S<strong>in</strong>gapore. Journal of Multil<strong>in</strong>gual and MulticulturalDevelopment 23, 282295.We<strong>in</strong>berg, Bernd and Suzanne Bennett (1971) Speaker sex recognition of 5- and6-year-old children’s voices. Journal of <strong>the</strong> Acoustical Society of America 50,12101213.We<strong>in</strong>reich, Uriel (1953) <strong>Language</strong>s <strong>in</strong> Contact. The Hague: Mouton.Wente, Margaret (2006) A for cultural capital. Globe & Mail [Toronto], 27 June.We<strong>the</strong>rell, Margaret (2007) A step too far: Discursive psychology, l<strong>in</strong>guisticethnography and questions of identity. Journal of Sociol<strong>in</strong>guistics 11, 661681.White, John (2005) Puritan <strong>in</strong>telligence. Oxford Review of Education 31, 423442.White, John (2006a) The religious orig<strong>in</strong>s of <strong>in</strong>telligence test<strong>in</strong>g. The Psychologist19, 360361.White, John (2006b) Intelligence, Dest<strong>in</strong>y and Education: The Ideological Roots ofIntelligence Test<strong>in</strong>g. London: Routledge.White, Karl (1982) The relationship between socioeconomic status and academicachievement. Psychological Bullet<strong>in</strong> 91, 461481.Wickett, John (1990) The Evolution and Development of <strong>the</strong> Intelligence Test<strong>in</strong>gMovement. Antigonish, Nova Scotia: St Francis Xavier University.Widdowson, Henry (2004) Text, Context, Pretext: Critical Issues <strong>in</strong> DiscourseAnalysis. Oxford: Blackwell.Wierzbicka, Anna (2005) Universal human concepts as a tool for explor<strong>in</strong>gbil<strong>in</strong>gual lives. International Journal of Bil<strong>in</strong>gualism 9, 726.Wiese, Ann-Marie and Eugene Garcia (2001) The Bil<strong>in</strong>gual Education Act:<strong>Language</strong> m<strong>in</strong>ority students and U.S. federal educational policy. InternationalJournal of Bil<strong>in</strong>gual Education and Bil<strong>in</strong>gualism 4, 229248.Wigfield, Allan, Alice Galper, Krist<strong>in</strong> Denton and Carol Seefeldt (1999) Teachers’beliefs about former Head Start and non-Head Start first-grade children’smotivation, performance, and future educational prospects. Journal of EducationalPsychology 91, 98104.


332 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>Wiggan, Greg (2007) Race, school achievement and educational <strong>in</strong>equality:Toward a student-based <strong>in</strong>quiry perspective. Review of Educational Research77, 310333.Wiggen, Geir (1978) The use of dialects <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>itial teach<strong>in</strong>g of <strong>the</strong> writtenlanguage: The Norwegian case. Paper presented at <strong>the</strong> AILA conference,Montreal.Wiley, Terrence and Wayne Wright (2004) Aga<strong>in</strong>st <strong>the</strong> undertow: <strong>Language</strong>m<strong>in</strong>orityeducation policy and politics <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> ‘age of accountability’. EducationalPolicy 18, 142168.Wilk<strong>in</strong>s, Roy (1971) Black nonsense. The Crisis 78 (3), 78.Williams, Frederick (1970a) <strong>Language</strong>, attitude and social change. In F. Williams(ed.) <strong>Language</strong> and Poverty. Chicago, IL: Markham.Williams, Frederick (1970b) Psychological correlates of speech characteristics:On sound<strong>in</strong>g disadvantaged. Journal of Speech and Hear<strong>in</strong>g Research 13,472488.Williams, Frederick (1974) The identification of l<strong>in</strong>guistic attitudes. L<strong>in</strong>guistics136, 2132.Williams, Frederick (1976) Explorations of <strong>the</strong> L<strong>in</strong>guistic Attitudes of teachers.Rowley, MA: Newbury.Williams, Frederick, Jack Whitehead and Leslie Miller (1972) Relations betweenlanguage attitudes and teacher expectancy. American Educational ResearchJournal 9, 263277.Williams, Hugo (2006) Freelance. Times Literary Supplement, 28 April.Williams, Robert (ed.) (1975) Ebonics: The True <strong>Language</strong> of Black Folks. St Louis,MO: Institute of Black Studies.Wilson, Woodrow (1902) A History of <strong>the</strong> American People. New York: HarperBro<strong>the</strong>rs.W<strong>in</strong>field, Ann (2007) Eugenics and Education <strong>in</strong> America. New York: Peter Lang.Wiseman, Stephen (1968) Educational deprivation and disadvantage. InH. Butcher (ed.) Educational Research <strong>in</strong> Brita<strong>in</strong>. London: University of LondonPress.Wiseman, Stephen (1973) The educational obstacle race: Factors that h<strong>in</strong>der pupilprogress. Educational Research 15, 8793.Wodak, Ruth (2006) Dilemmas of discourse (analysis). <strong>Language</strong> <strong>in</strong> Society 35,595611.Wolfe, Tom (1970) Radical Chic, and Mau-Mau<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> Flak Catchers. New York:Farrar, Straus & Giroux.Wolfram, Walt (1969) A Sociol<strong>in</strong>guistic Description of Detroit Negro Speech.Wash<strong>in</strong>gton, DC: Center for Applied L<strong>in</strong>guistics.Wolfram, Walt (1973) Objective and subjective parameters of language assimilationamong second generation Puerto Ricans <strong>in</strong> East Harlem. In R. Shuy andR. Fasold (eds) <strong>Language</strong> Attitudes: Current Trends and Prospects. Wash<strong>in</strong>gton:Georgetown University Press.Wolfram, Walt (1998a) Black children are verbally deprived. In L. Bauer andP. Trudgill (eds) <strong>Language</strong> Myths. London: Pengu<strong>in</strong>.Wolfram, Walt (1998b) <strong>Language</strong> ideology and dialect: Understand<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>Oakland Ebonics controversy. Journal of English L<strong>in</strong>guistics 26, 108121.


References 333Wolfram, Walt (2005) Ebonics and l<strong>in</strong>guistic science: Clarify<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> issues. InJ.D. Ramirez, T. Wiley, G. de Klerk, E. Lee and W. Wright (eds) Ebonics: TheUrban Education Debate (2nd edn). Clevedon: Multil<strong>in</strong>gual Matters.Wolfram, Walt and Donna Christian (1989) Dialects and Education: Issues andAnswers. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.Wolfram, Walt and Erik Thomas (2002) The Development of African AmericanEnglish. Oxford: Blackwell.Wood, Gordon (1994) The losable past. The New Republic, 7 November (211: 19),4649.Woodford, J. (2004) Bill Cosby, education, and <strong>the</strong> lumpeniz<strong>in</strong>g of <strong>the</strong> contemporaryBlack world. The Black Scholar 34 (4), 2126.Woodford, O. (1982) Interview on Ebony (BBC-TV), 17 November.Woodhead, Mart<strong>in</strong> (1988) When psychology <strong>in</strong>forms public policy: The case ofearly childhood <strong>in</strong>tervention. American Psychologist 43, 443454.Wright, Ian and Carol LaBar (1984) Multiculturalism and morality. In S. Shapsonand V. d’Oyley (eds) Bil<strong>in</strong>gual and Multicultural Education. Clevedon: Multil<strong>in</strong>gualMatters.Wright, Laura (ed.) (2000) The Development of Standard English, 13001800: Theories,Descriptions, Conflicts. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Wright, Stephen and Évelyne Bougie (2007) Intergroup contact and m<strong>in</strong>oritylanguageeducation. Journal of <strong>Language</strong> and Social Psychology 26, 157181.Wright, Wayne (2005a) Scholarly references and news titles. In J.D. Ramirez,T. Wiley, G. de Klerk, E. Lee and W. Wright (eds) Ebonics: The Urban EducationDebate (2nd edn). Clevedon: Multil<strong>in</strong>gual Matters.Wright, Wayne (2005b) Evolution of Federal Policy and Implications of No Child LeftBeh<strong>in</strong>d for <strong>Language</strong> M<strong>in</strong>ority Students. Tempe, AZ: Arizona State UniversityCollege of Education.Yancy, George (ed.) (1998) African American Philosophers. London: Routledge.Yeung, Alexander, Herbert Marsh and Rosemary Suliman (2000) Can twotongues live <strong>in</strong> harmony: Analysis of <strong>the</strong> National Education Longitud<strong>in</strong>al Studyof 1988 (NELS88) longitud<strong>in</strong>al data on <strong>the</strong> ma<strong>in</strong>tenance of <strong>home</strong> language.American Educational Research Journal 37, 10011026.Yell, Mitchell and Erik Drasgow (2005) No Child Left Beh<strong>in</strong>d: A Guide forProfessionals. Upper Saddle River, NJ: Pearson.Young, R. (1983) A school communication-deficit hypo<strong>the</strong>sis of educationaldisadvantage. Australian Journal of Education 27, 315.Younger, Michael and Molly Warr<strong>in</strong>gton (2006) Would Harry and Hermione havedone better <strong>in</strong> s<strong>in</strong>gle-sex classes? A review of s<strong>in</strong>gle-sex teach<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>coeducational secondary schools <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> United K<strong>in</strong>gdom. American EducationalResearch Journal 43, 579620.Zangwill, Israel (1909) The Melt<strong>in</strong>g Pot: Drama <strong>in</strong> Four Acts. London: He<strong>in</strong>emann.Zeichner, Kenneth (1994) Teacher socialization for cultural diversity. In J. Sikula,T. Buttery and E. Guyton (eds) Handbook of Research on Teacher Education. NewYork: Macmillan.Zéphir, Flore (1997) Haitian Creole language and bil<strong>in</strong>gual education <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>United States: Problem, right or resource? Journal of Multil<strong>in</strong>gual and MulticulturalDevelopment 18, 223237.


334 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>Zéphir, Flore (1999) Challenges for multicultural education: Sociol<strong>in</strong>guisticparallels between African American English and Haitian Creole. Journal ofMultil<strong>in</strong>gual and Multicultural Development 20, 134154.Zientek, L<strong>in</strong>da (2007) Prepar<strong>in</strong>g high-quality teachers: Views from <strong>the</strong> classroom.American Educational Research Journal 44, 9591001.Zigler, Edward and W<strong>in</strong>ne Berman (1983) Discern<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> future of earlychildhood <strong>in</strong>tervention. American Psychologist 38, 894906.Zigler, Edward and Victoria Seitz (1980) Head Start as a National Laboratory.Unpublished manuscript.Zigler, Edward and Jeanette Valent<strong>in</strong>e (1979) Project Head Start: A Legacy of <strong>the</strong> Waron Poverty. New York: Free Press.Zorn, Jeffrey (1982) Black English and <strong>the</strong> K<strong>in</strong>g decision. College English 44, 314320.


IndexAlthough <strong>the</strong>re is some overlap, this <strong>in</strong>dex generally omits entries for material that is clearly tobe found under a head<strong>in</strong>g shown <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> table of contents. Thus, for example, <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>formationcovered <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> ‘Compensatory Intervention?’ section of Chapter 5 is not referred to here <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>‘compensatory programs’ entry. Space constra<strong>in</strong>ts have meant that not all personal nameshave been listed here.Adorno, Theodor 34African Burial Ground (Manhattan) 54American Academy of Psychiatry and <strong>the</strong>Law 90American Army ‘Alpha’ and ‘Beta’ tests64-65American Association on MentalRetardation 90American Dialect Society 5American Jewish Committee 63American Psychiatric Association 90-92American Psychological Association 90American Renaissance 77Amis, K<strong>in</strong>gsley 111Ammon, Ulrich 112-113assimilation and pluralism 208-219, 225attitude– and belief 161-162– <strong>in</strong>strumental and <strong>in</strong>tegrative 190-195,239-240Baker, Col<strong>in</strong> 21, 196, 198-200, 234, 236, 244,252, 255-260, 263-265, 268, 272, 277Baldw<strong>in</strong>, James 112Baratz, Joan 121, 123, 125Baugh, John 172, 175-180, 184Benjam<strong>in</strong>, Walter 34Bereiter, Carl 42, 80, 106-107, 171Bernste<strong>in</strong>, Basil 16, 40, 51, 96-107, 118, 125,136, 139-145, 171– elaborated and restricted codes 96-106,114, 119, 139-144Bernste<strong>in</strong>, Leonard 227bidialectalism 101-102, 112, 122, 133,151-152, 174bil<strong>in</strong>gual education 20-22, 176-179– transition and ma<strong>in</strong>tenance 262-264Bil<strong>in</strong>gual Education Act (USA) 264-265, 271bil<strong>in</strong>gualism 20-22– acquisition models 238-241– assessment 236-238– and <strong>in</strong>telligence 241-243– types 236-248B<strong>in</strong>et, Alfred 57, 59, 60, 61, 64Black English 5-6, 18-19, 111-124, 146,151-154, 159-160– Ann Arbor trial 10, 173-175– Oakland case 121, 175-180, 184, 269Blanc, Michel 234, 244-245Blommaert, Jan 33-35, 104Bloomfield, Leonard 143, 235-236‘bogus pipel<strong>in</strong>e’ experiment 69Borges, Jorge Luis 36, 39Bor<strong>in</strong>g, Edw<strong>in</strong> 63Bourdieu, Pierre 44-45, 50-51, 104Breton, Raymond 219, 276Brown v Board of Education 169, 172Bru<strong>in</strong>ius, Harry 61-63, 67Bullivant, Brian 225-226, 232-233Burt, Cyril 57Bush, George W. 265Butler Education Act 57Butler, Samuel 249Calv<strong>in</strong>ism 56-58Cameron, Deborah 130Canada 200-204, 217-219cannibalism 227-228Carnegie Institution 68Cemitério dos Pretos Novos 54Center for Applied L<strong>in</strong>guistics 5Chomsky, Noam 26, 249Churchill, W<strong>in</strong>ston 67civism: see assimilation and pluralismCl<strong>in</strong>ton, Bill 38Coard, Bernard 222, 232335<strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>


336 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>compensatory programs 42, 70, 74-75, 78-80,104-109– and empowerment 195-200Corson, David 6-8, 26, 27, 37, 50-51, 112, 196Cosby, Bill 180-181, 183Coulmas, Florian 40-41, 50Coupland, Nik 31, 35covert prestige 18, 150, 152-155Crawford, James 258, 265, 268Crowley, Toney 125, 129, 131-132, 135, 137,145Crystal, David 133, 135, 136‘cultural deprivation’ 79-84, 108cultural relativism 131-132Cumm<strong>in</strong>s, Jim 196, 201-202, 204, 263-264deafness 248Deutsch, Mart<strong>in</strong> 42, 106Didion, Joan 270discourse analysis 10, 11, 14, 93, 125, 26disadvantage 14-18‘disidentification’ 181-183Dos Passos, John 67, 215‘<strong>the</strong> dozens’ 184Ebonics: see Black Englishempowerment 19, 221, 226Engelmann, Siegfried 42, 80, 106-107, 171Estuary English 161ethnography 28-31, 37eugenics 55-71Eugenics Records Office 60, 68Eugenics Society 57Eysenck, Hans 56, 72, 77Fasold, Ralph 7, 112, 178Ferguson, Charles 273Fidditch, Miss 94, 116, 124Fish, Stanley 227-229Fishman, Joshua 110, 149, 195, 202, 252flyt<strong>in</strong>g 185France 207, 209Frankfurt School 34Freud, Sigmund 124-125Freyre, Gilberto 55Friedman, Thomas 215Fromm, Erich 49Fuentes, Carlos 195Galton, Francis 56-59, 61, 63, 76Galton Society 68Gamp, Sairey 94Gates, Henry Louis 179gender 18, 27, 37Genesee, Fred 260-261genome 52-53, 70Giles, Howard 31, 34, 35, 41, 163, 171, 240Glazer, Nathan 226-227, 232-233Goddard, Henry 57, 59, 60Gould, Stephen Jay 70Graddol, David 133-136, 138, 145Gradgr<strong>in</strong>d, Thomas (Hard Times) 267Grant, Madison 60, 62, 64, 67, 68Greek 250-251Grimshaw, Allen 36, 39Gr<strong>in</strong>berg, Jaime 4Grundy, Mrs 94, 111, 116, 124Gupta, An<strong>the</strong>a Fraser 262, 264Halliday, Michael 34, 102-103, 148Hamers, Josiane 234, 244-245Harris, Mrs 94Haugen, E<strong>in</strong>ar 136, 236Hazlitt, William 249Head Start program 87, 107Heraclitus 244Hess, Robert 104-105, 108Higham, John 61, 225, 231Hilton, Paris 116Hitler, Adolf 61-62Holmes, Oliver Wendell 68Honey, John 17, 119, 129-137, 145Hughes, Robert 216Huxley, Aldous 87Hymes, Dell 28, 36, 138hypercorrection 18, 169identity 102, 113, 206-207, 217, 272-277immersion programs 21, 257-261Immigration Commission (USA) 60immigration control 59-64Immigration Restriction League (USA) 60,64India 245-246<strong>in</strong>telligence test<strong>in</strong>g 63-66, 71-73, 76, 88-91– tw<strong>in</strong> studies 73Irish 191-193, 203Ishmaels 61Jackson, Jesse 179Jakobson, Roman 249Jensen, Arthur 56, 63, 69-75, 77, 87Johnson, Lyndon 107Joseph, John 98-99Jukes 61Kallen, Horace 212, 226, 230Kallikaks 57, 61


Index 337Kedourie, Elie 232Kellaghan, Thomas 44-45, 50, 88Ku Klux Klan 64Kymlicka, Will 214, 226-227Labov, William 6, 10, 40, 51, 102, 103, 106,107, 113-117, 122-123, 127, 132, 136, 142,146, 153-155, 159, 170-171, 174Lambert, Wallace 146-148, 159-160, 191-192,240-242language– apar<strong>the</strong>id 255-256– competence and performance 96, 103,171– ‘effem<strong>in</strong>acy’ 150-151, 154– equality 138-139– <strong>in</strong>strumental and <strong>in</strong>tegrative motivation190-195, 239-240– politeness 155– test<strong>in</strong>g 76Lat<strong>in</strong> 250-251‘latitude of attitude acceptance’ 164-167Laughl<strong>in</strong>, Harry 60-61, 68Lewis, E. Glyn 250-251L<strong>in</strong>ard (Colonel) 66Lippmann, Walter 58, 63Lyons, John 136Mackey, William 110, 252, 261Macnamara, John 191-192maide-crochaidhe 274Mailloux, Pierre 75-76Marenbon, John 130matched-guise technique 146-148, 160Mayr, Ernst 55McWhorter, John 121-122, 180Menand, Louis 233Mezzofanti, Card<strong>in</strong>al 235, 237Mill, John Stuart 228Milroy, James 24, 40, 136Milroy, Lesley 10, 40, 136, 164Milton, John 249m<strong>in</strong>ority-group reaction 19, 168M’Naghten rules 88-89Molière (Jean-Baptiste Poquel<strong>in</strong>) 264Movimento Negro Unificado 53-54Mufwene, Salikoko 174Mugglestone, Lynda 137multiculturalism 20-21National Assessment of of Educational ProgressAct (USA) 266National Association for MulticulturalEducation (USA) 223National Conference for Community andJustice (USA) 168National Conference of Christians and Jews(USA) 168National Council for Educational Standards(UK) 119, 125, 145National Orig<strong>in</strong>s Act (USA) 61The Ne<strong>the</strong>rlands 208-209Ngg wa Thiong’o 274‘No Child Left Beh<strong>in</strong>d’ Act 265-268, 278Nova Scotia 115, 171-172, 204-205Novak, Michael 213Office of Bil<strong>in</strong>gual Education and M<strong>in</strong>ority<strong>Language</strong> Affairs (Wash<strong>in</strong>gton) 265Office of English <strong>Language</strong> Acquisition(Wash<strong>in</strong>gton) 265Office of Management and Budget(Wash<strong>in</strong>gton) 53Ogbu, John 44, 48, 81, 146, 151-152, 183Orwell, George 43, 51, 150-151, 154Park, Robert 212Pearson, Karl 56-58Persh<strong>in</strong>g, John (Black Jack) 66Phillipson, Robert 262P<strong>in</strong>ker, Steven 136, 249Pioneer Fund 77Plowden, Bridget 108, 125Plowden Report 107-108pluralism: see assimilation and pluralismPodhoretz, Norman 253, 255, 273Porter, John 218Portes, Alejandro 60-62, 65Powell, Enoch 38Preston, Dennis 10, 11, 162, 164Proposition 227 (California) 268, 270puritanism 56-58Pygmalion-<strong>in</strong>-<strong>the</strong>-classroom 85Queen’s English 161Rabbi Tarfon 281Ra<strong>in</strong>water, Lee 48-50, 56, 87Raja Rao 274Rampton, Ben 11, 29, 37, 50Raven, John 89-91Reagan, Ronald 252, 255, 265, 278Received Pronunciation (RP) 161, 163Rhodes, Cecil 215Rickford, John 121-122, 175Rob<strong>in</strong>son, W. Peter 38-39, 41, 103-105, 163,167, 171Rodriguez, Richard 253-255


338 <strong>Language</strong> <strong>Diversity</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Classroom</strong>Rogers, Rebecca 35-36Roosevelt, Theodore 67, 252, 255, 278Rumbaut, Rubén 60-62, 65Rushdie, Salman 228Rushton, Philippe 77, 91, 100, 171Saavedra, Elizabeth 4Schatzman, Leonard 95, 97, 100, 140Schles<strong>in</strong>ger, Arthur 214-217, 231Schmidt, Georges 235Scruton, Roger 209self-esteem 124, 199, 223, 261‘self-fulfill<strong>in</strong>g prophecy’ 85, 118, 127, 167‘semil<strong>in</strong>gualism’ 143-144Shaw, George Bernard 67, 281Shipman, Virg<strong>in</strong>ia 104-105, 108Shockley, William 69Shuy, Roger 115, 121silence 26-27, 37-38Slotk<strong>in</strong>, Richard 60, 64-66Smi<strong>the</strong>rman, Geneva 6, 50, 117, 173, 175,180, 185socioeconomic status 46-47, 72-73, 80-82Spearman, Charles 63, 71Spolsky, Bernard 76, 240Staples, Brent 179Ste<strong>in</strong>, Gertrude 184Ste<strong>in</strong>er, George 235, 247, 249, 262sterilization 59-63Strauss, Anselm 95, 97, 100, 140Stubbs, Michael 11, 24-26, 31, 37, 100, 102Swann, Joan 133-136, 138, 145Swann Report 4‘tally-stick’ 274Taylor, Charles 214teachers 139-145Terman, Lewis 57-59, 64Torrey, Jane 120, 122-123, 171Trudgill, Peter 9, 13, 37, 40, 94, 100, 104, 110,111, 112, 118-120, 122, 134, 136-137,153-155, 159, 163-164, 171Turner, Lorenzo Dow 114Unz, Ron 268-271, 278U.S. English 210, 252, 258, 278Venezky, Richard 122-123, 173, 264-265War on Poverty 107We<strong>in</strong>reich, Max 184We<strong>in</strong>reich, Uriel 69, 189Wells, H. G. 67‘Welsh Not’ 274White, John 56-59Whorfian hypo<strong>the</strong>sis 109-110, 229-230, 233Williams, Frederick 159-160, 162, 164-166Wolfe, Tom 227Wolfram, Walt 115-116, 129, 136, 174-175,177-178Zangwill, Israel 211

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!