12.07.2015 Views

Konrad Lorenz 1950 The comparative method in studying innate ...

Konrad Lorenz 1950 The comparative method in studying innate ...

Konrad Lorenz 1950 The comparative method in studying innate ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

<strong>Konrad</strong> <strong>Lorenz</strong> <strong>1950</strong><strong>The</strong> <strong>comparative</strong> <strong>method</strong> <strong>in</strong> study<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>nate behavior patternsSymposia of the Society for Experimental Biology 4 (Physiological Mechanisms <strong>in</strong>Animal Behavior): 221-254.[OCR by <strong>Konrad</strong> <strong>Lorenz</strong> Haus Altenberg – http://klha.at]Seitenumbrüche und -zahlen wie im Orig<strong>in</strong>al.


K. <strong>Lorenz</strong> <strong>1950</strong> <strong>The</strong> <strong>comparative</strong> <strong>method</strong> <strong>in</strong> study<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>nate behavior patterns 221 <strong>The</strong> <strong>comparative</strong> <strong>method</strong> <strong>in</strong> study<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>nate behavior patternsI. INTRODUCTIONLike many other branches of biological research, <strong>comparative</strong> ethology owes its existence to adiscovery. <strong>The</strong> discovery of a new particulate process, the function of which is <strong>comparative</strong>ly<strong>in</strong>dependent from the function of the organism as a 'whole', always opens a new l<strong>in</strong>e ofanalytical approach. <strong>The</strong> nature of the process then determ<strong>in</strong>es the <strong>method</strong> most favourablefor its experimental <strong>in</strong>vestigation, and this <strong>method</strong>, <strong>in</strong> its turn, determ<strong>in</strong>es the direction <strong>in</strong>which analytical research cont<strong>in</strong>ues to proceed. <strong>The</strong>re are many cases <strong>in</strong> which thedevelopment of a new and <strong>in</strong>dependent branch of biological science has thus been determ<strong>in</strong>edby the character of one particularly favourable object, modern genetics be<strong>in</strong>g the mostobvious example.<strong>The</strong> dist<strong>in</strong>ct and particulate physiological process whose discovery may be identifiedwith the orig<strong>in</strong> of <strong>comparative</strong> ethology as an <strong>in</strong>dependent branch of science is represented bya certa<strong>in</strong> type of <strong>in</strong>nate, genetically determ<strong>in</strong>ed behaviour patterns. Charles Otis Whitman,who was the first to discover them, called them simply 'Inst<strong>in</strong>cts'; Oskar He<strong>in</strong>roth, who, tenyears later, <strong>in</strong>dependently rediscovered them, spoke of 'arteigene Triebhandlungen'; I myselfhave called them 'Inst<strong>in</strong>kthandlungen', 'Erbkoord<strong>in</strong>ationen' and 'Inst<strong>in</strong>ktbewegungen'successively, thus further mix<strong>in</strong>g up term<strong>in</strong>ology. I shall, <strong>in</strong> the conference on term<strong>in</strong>ology,<strong>in</strong>cluded <strong>in</strong> the programme of this Symposium, propose the term endogenous movements forthis type of <strong>in</strong>nate behaviour pattern. Endogenous movements were not only discovered andrecognized as a very dist<strong>in</strong>ct phenomenon by C. O. Whitman as early as 1898, but alsosystematically studied and evaluated as taxonomic characters. Nevertheless, their extremeimportance as <strong>in</strong>dependent elements of behaviour was not generally realized until much later.It was only about 1930 that the discovery of endogenous activities began to act as a centre ofcrystallization, about which concerted efforts to analyse <strong>in</strong>nate behaviour patterns began tobecome organized. From then on, however, a quickly grow<strong>in</strong>g number of <strong>in</strong>vestigators beganto apply the <strong>method</strong>s dictated by the nature of the favourable object which had beendiscovered so much earlier by Whitman and He<strong>in</strong>roth. Thus <strong>comparative</strong> ethology developed,and therefore it is dist<strong>in</strong>guished by a particular set of


K. <strong>Lorenz</strong> <strong>1950</strong> <strong>The</strong> <strong>comparative</strong> <strong>method</strong> <strong>in</strong> study<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>nate behavior patterns 222 <strong>method</strong>s from all other schools also occupy<strong>in</strong>g themselves with the <strong>in</strong>nate behaviour ofanimals and men. To convey some idea of this particular set of <strong>method</strong>s is the task I have setmyself <strong>in</strong> this paper.I shall set about this task from two sides. Before try<strong>in</strong>g to expla<strong>in</strong> what <strong>comparative</strong>ethology is try<strong>in</strong>g to do, I propose to state, at least as clearly, what it is try<strong>in</strong>g not to do. Ideem it most necessary to show what particular errors of <strong>method</strong>, committed by the vitalisticand by the mechanistic schools of behaviour study, we are meticulously try<strong>in</strong>g to avoid, alsoto make it quite clear why these errors have prevented some fundamental facts about <strong>in</strong>natebehaviour from be<strong>in</strong>g discovered half a century sooner than they actually were. After thusdef<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g our own <strong>method</strong>s per exclusionem, I shall proceed to describe them <strong>in</strong> some detail.This plan <strong>in</strong>volves some serious criticism of both vitalistic and mechanistic schools,on 'purposive psychology' and some branches of 'Gestalt' psychology, as well as onbehaviourism and Pavlov's school of reflexology. I confidently assert that this criticism isirrefutable from the <strong>method</strong>ological po<strong>in</strong>t of view. But I want to make it absolutely clear atonce that <strong>comparative</strong> ethology has no right whatsoever to claim credit for not hav<strong>in</strong>grepeated the <strong>method</strong>ical errors of which we accuse vitalists and mechanists. A preconceivedidea is a very terrible danger <strong>in</strong>deed to all <strong>in</strong>ductive research, the very essence of which isunprejudiced observation. <strong>The</strong> narrow path of <strong>in</strong>ductive natural science is hemmed <strong>in</strong> on bothsides by <strong>method</strong>ological pitfalls, and is, therefore, by far easiest to walk along bl<strong>in</strong>dfolded.And this is exactly what Whitman and He<strong>in</strong>roth did. Happily ignorant of the great battlewaged by vitalists and mechanists on the field of animal behaviour, happily free from even awork<strong>in</strong>g hypotheses, two 'simple zoologists' were just observ<strong>in</strong>g the pigeons and ducks theyloved, and thus kept to the only way which leads to the accumulation of a sound, unbiasedbasis of <strong>in</strong>duction, without which no natural science can arise. Small tribute is due to them fornot tumbl<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>to the <strong>method</strong>ological traps, <strong>in</strong>to which vitalists and mechanists succeeded <strong>in</strong>shoulder<strong>in</strong>g each other, as I shall at once proceed to expla<strong>in</strong>. No very great tribute either isdue to them for apply<strong>in</strong>g the phyletic <strong>method</strong> to the study of <strong>in</strong>nate behaviour. Be<strong>in</strong>g<strong>comparative</strong> morphologists, it was only natural for them to do so. But by do<strong>in</strong>g it, theydiscovered a fact which could not be discovered from any but the phyletic po<strong>in</strong>t of view; theydiscovered an <strong>in</strong>dependent, particulate function of the central nervous system which, as anelement of animal and human behaviour, is, at the very least, equally important as the reflexor the conditioned reaction.


K. <strong>Lorenz</strong> <strong>1950</strong> <strong>The</strong> <strong>comparative</strong> <strong>method</strong> <strong>in</strong> study<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>nate behavior patterns 223 II. CONSEQUENCES OF THE DISPUTE BETWEEN VITALISTIC AND MECHANISTICSCHOOLS OF BEHAVIOUR STUDY(1) Antagonistic exaggerationsWithout any doubt the dispute between vitalism and mechanism has created and exaggerateda number of erroneous preconceptions which subsequently developed <strong>in</strong>to a serious obstacleto analytical research. It would be a difficult task for the historian to decide which sideorig<strong>in</strong>ally sent the pendulum sw<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>g and was responsible for the whole dispute. One mustnot forget, however, that vitalism is much older than mechanism, that the concept of entelechycomes from Aristotle, and that Johannes Müller and Claude Bernard were quite decidedlyvitalists, though they also undoubtedly were the pioneers of analytical physiology.Furthermore, the quarrel has had particularly disastrous results for the analytical <strong>in</strong>vestigationof such life processes as embryonic development, regeneration and <strong>in</strong>st<strong>in</strong>ctive behaviour,which, because of their 'wholeness', their 'directedness' and their apparent spontaneity, have,s<strong>in</strong>ce the very beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g of the dispute, constituted the stronghold of vitalism. Last, but notleast, the theoretical and philosophical position of vitalism is much more fundamentallywrong than the few much less portentous <strong>method</strong>ical errors, of which we accuse themechanistic schools. For all these reasons I th<strong>in</strong>k that we are justified <strong>in</strong> regard<strong>in</strong>g thevitalistic errors as primary and the reciprocal errors of the mechanists' reactions justified <strong>in</strong>themselves and only err<strong>in</strong>g through exaggeration.Vitalists base all their arguments on the purely dogmatic assertion that all lifeprocesses are governed by an essentially non-expla<strong>in</strong>able, preternatural 'factor', termed vitalforce, entelechy, whole-produc<strong>in</strong>g factor, and so on. <strong>The</strong> legitimate answer to this is obviouslythat no man can know to what extent causal analysis is go<strong>in</strong>g to succeed <strong>in</strong> expla<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g theprocesses of life, and that, if a man prefers to meditate upon the supernatural <strong>in</strong>stead of try<strong>in</strong>gto expla<strong>in</strong> th<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>in</strong> a natural way, a lamasery is a much more suitable place to do so than aresearch <strong>in</strong>stitute. Instead of which, mechanists replied that all life processes could beexpla<strong>in</strong>ed on the foundation of the laws of classical mechanics. If they rel<strong>in</strong>quished thisposition later, they only did so because modern physics did.If vitalists asserted that the existence of organic systems was due to a whole-produc<strong>in</strong>gfactor (Müller's ganzmachende Kraft), and therefore not expla<strong>in</strong>able by way of synthesis,mechanists answered that organic systems could be expla<strong>in</strong>ed very simply as a sum of veryfew sorts of elements. <strong>The</strong>y even grew quite dogmatic, <strong>in</strong> some cases, as to what theseelements were.


K. <strong>Lorenz</strong> <strong>1950</strong> <strong>The</strong> <strong>comparative</strong> <strong>method</strong> <strong>in</strong> study<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>nate behavior patterns 224 If vitalists asserted that life was the result of a direct<strong>in</strong>g force, mechanists altogetherneglected the fact that life processes do, <strong>in</strong> some cases, cont<strong>in</strong>ue to run <strong>in</strong> a certa<strong>in</strong> direction.If vitalists regarded the spontaneity of some life processes as a wonder and as the direct effectof their preternatural factor, mechanists replied by deny<strong>in</strong>g the very existence of spontaneousprocesses. If all the vitalistic factors, vital forces, direct<strong>in</strong>g forces, entelechy, <strong>in</strong>st<strong>in</strong>ct andhowever they were called, were, if we come down to fundamentals, noth<strong>in</strong>g else than the old,preternatural, immortal soul <strong>in</strong> a new guise, mechanists tried to build up a psychology withouta soul, and went so far as to neglect the existence of subjective phenomena altogether, evenwhere <strong>in</strong>trospection can tell us some most important facts about our own ways of act<strong>in</strong>g andreact<strong>in</strong>g.<strong>The</strong> very nature of these antagonistic exaggerations, <strong>in</strong>to which vitalism andmechanism were forc<strong>in</strong>g each other, makes it <strong>in</strong>telligible that of all fields of analyticalresearch the <strong>in</strong>vestigation of behaviour suffered most. Its well-def<strong>in</strong>ed character as a 'whole'or system, its directedness and purpose and, <strong>in</strong> some cases, its evident spontaneity, broughtanimal behaviour <strong>in</strong>to the very focus of the great dispute. Especially <strong>in</strong>nate behaviour sufferedfrom this, ma<strong>in</strong>ly because '<strong>in</strong>st<strong>in</strong>ct' was one of the card<strong>in</strong>al po<strong>in</strong>ts of dissension. To make clearthe <strong>method</strong>ical po<strong>in</strong>t of view held by <strong>comparative</strong> ethology, I th<strong>in</strong>k it necessary to expla<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>some detail the reciprocal errors which both the vitalistic and the mechanistic schools ofbehaviour study committed regard<strong>in</strong>g the items mentioned above.(2) Reciprocal errors <strong>in</strong> the treatment of systems<strong>The</strong> conception of the 'whole' was to vitalists the very essence of what never could beexpla<strong>in</strong>ed, be<strong>in</strong>g the direct consequence of a preternatural factor. Particular stress was laid onthe thesis that a whole could never be expla<strong>in</strong>ed by synthesis of particulate elements. To thisfatal resignation of analysis on the vitalistic side mechanists replied by try<strong>in</strong>g to synthetize allthe systems of behaviour on the basis of too few elements. This 'atomism' is an error verycharacteristic of mechanistic schools. This optimistic attempt was, of course, doomed tofailure, but not before it had brought valuable results. Even very crude simplisms have doneless damage to the progress of science than resignation.One of the most deplorable consequences which resulted from the 'atomistic' attemptsat expla<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g behaviour was the counter-recoil of 'Gestalt' psychology. It is an everlast<strong>in</strong>gmerit of Gestalt psychologists to have been the first consciously to <strong>in</strong>troduce the <strong>method</strong> of atruly correlative analysis of organic systems. <strong>The</strong>y were the first to prove the <strong>in</strong>herent fallacyof the atomistic <strong>method</strong> of artificially isolat<strong>in</strong>g a s<strong>in</strong>gle cha<strong>in</strong> of causation


K. <strong>Lorenz</strong> <strong>1950</strong> <strong>The</strong> <strong>comparative</strong> <strong>method</strong> <strong>in</strong> study<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>nate behavior patterns 228 the non-expla<strong>in</strong>able directive factor of life. Thus two problems were hushed up by onepseudo-explanation and therefore appeared as one. Whether an animal is strenuously striv<strong>in</strong>gto atta<strong>in</strong> some end or goal, chang<strong>in</strong>g its behaviour time and aga<strong>in</strong> adaptively to reach it, orwhether a stereotyped behaviour pattern automatically develops some survival value, the'directive factor' is, <strong>in</strong> the op<strong>in</strong>ion of purposive psychologists, one and the same: the '<strong>in</strong>fallible'<strong>in</strong>st<strong>in</strong>ct is tell<strong>in</strong>g the organism what it has to do. <strong>The</strong>refore it is only consistent to identify thesurvival value of any k<strong>in</strong>d of <strong>in</strong>nate behaviour patterns with the end or goal, at which theorganism as a subject is aim<strong>in</strong>g.It was Wallace Craig who cleared up this confusion and who, once for all, explodedthe myth of the '<strong>in</strong>fallibility' of <strong>in</strong>st<strong>in</strong>ct. He did so by show<strong>in</strong>g, with a wealth of observationalevidence, that the animal as a subject is certa<strong>in</strong>ly not aim<strong>in</strong>g at the survival value of itsactivities, but merely at the discharge of certa<strong>in</strong> actions, termed consummatory action byCraig. <strong>The</strong> recognition of this <strong>in</strong>dubitable fact is one of the utter commonplaces which are soamaz<strong>in</strong>gly hard to discover. Introspective self-observation makes it superlatively obvious thatthe purpose of what Craig termed appetitive behaviour is the discharge of <strong>in</strong>st<strong>in</strong>ctive actionand not its survival value. I cannot stop myself eat<strong>in</strong>g, though it is my purpose to lose weight.However obvious and even commonplace Craig's discovery may seem on close <strong>in</strong>spection, itnevertheless undoubtedly was one of the most decisive steps forward towards a realunderstand<strong>in</strong>g of behaviour. As Goethe says: 'Das ist das Schwerste von Allem, was dich amleichtesten dünket, mit den Augen zu sehn, was vor den Augen dir liegt.<strong>The</strong> greatest damage done to the analytical <strong>in</strong>vestigation of behaviour by the teach<strong>in</strong>gsof vitalists was, however, not caused by the confusion of purpose and survival value ofbehaviour, but by confound<strong>in</strong>g f<strong>in</strong>ality with causality. It is a fateful mistake to believe that theteleological 'understand<strong>in</strong>g' of behaviour (or, for that matter, of any process of life) makes itsuperfluous to ga<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>sight <strong>in</strong>to its causation. If Bierens de Haan says 'Wir betrachten denInst<strong>in</strong>kt, aber wir erklären ihn nicht' ('We contemplate <strong>in</strong>st<strong>in</strong>ct, but we do not try to expla<strong>in</strong>it'), our answer to this thesis is very clear. It is, of course, perfectly legitimate to meditateupon the obvious f<strong>in</strong>ality of any organic structure or function. It is even possible to reach, bythis contemplation, a very valuable 'understand<strong>in</strong>g' of it — <strong>in</strong> the teleological sense of theword. But this sort of understand<strong>in</strong>g does not <strong>in</strong>vest us with the power to change the naturalsequence of events. Mank<strong>in</strong>d owes its power over nature to its <strong>in</strong>sight <strong>in</strong>to causality. Asregards wholes or systems, they have a disconcert<strong>in</strong>g way of gett<strong>in</strong>g out of order and therebysupply us with a strong motive for want<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>sight <strong>in</strong>to their causal texture.


K. <strong>Lorenz</strong> <strong>1950</strong> <strong>The</strong> <strong>comparative</strong> <strong>method</strong> <strong>in</strong> study<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>nate behavior patterns 229 My teleological understand<strong>in</strong>g of my car is not worth a brass farth<strong>in</strong>g if a drop of water hasgot <strong>in</strong>to the jet of the carburettor, and Medic<strong>in</strong>e, the queen of all applied natural sciences, isforever <strong>in</strong> exactly the same position. No whole-produc<strong>in</strong>g factor helps the man <strong>in</strong> whoseappendix a cherry stone has got stuck. What I strongly resent is the ever-recurr<strong>in</strong>g vitalisticaspersion that our emphatic quest for causal understand<strong>in</strong>g implies materialistic bl<strong>in</strong>dness tothe existence of the great goals of humanity. Without full recognition — teleologicalrecognition! — of these goals, our quest for causality would lack its purpose. Without <strong>in</strong>sight<strong>in</strong>to causality the active pursuance of these goals would be impossible. We have particularlyurgent reasons to want <strong>in</strong>sight <strong>in</strong>to the causal context of '<strong>in</strong>st<strong>in</strong>ct'. With atomic bombs <strong>in</strong> itshands and with the endogenous aggressive drives of an irascible ape <strong>in</strong> its central nervoussystem, modern humanity is a whole or system which has got very thoroughly out of balance.No teleological meditation will help us, we shall have to do someth<strong>in</strong>g about it, and thisimplies the necessity of causal <strong>in</strong>sight.If vitalists persistently ignored the question why behaviour develops survival value, orwhy it is purposive, one should expect mechanists to stress the urgent necessity of putt<strong>in</strong>g justthese questions. Instead of do<strong>in</strong>g this, the mechanistic schools treated the very fact of survivalvalue and purpose exactly as if it were just another vitalistic superstition like entelechy,<strong>in</strong>st<strong>in</strong>ct and the like, that is to say, they flatly ignored it. It is perhaps too much to say that thequestion 'What for?' was strictly barred from the contemplations of behaviourists andreflexologists, but certa<strong>in</strong>ly no sufficient consideration was given to it. This effectivelyobstructed the mechanists' way of approach<strong>in</strong>g the problems of <strong>in</strong>nate behaviour from aselectionistic po<strong>in</strong>t of view, which, though certa<strong>in</strong>ly not 'vitalistic', is only possible if thesurvival value of a behaviour pattern is drawn <strong>in</strong>to consideration.In say<strong>in</strong>g above that no mechanist has ever raised the question after a causalexplanation of directedness and purposivity of behaviour, I have neglected one memorable<strong>in</strong>stance. No less a man than I. P. Pavlov has not only raised this question, but actually tried togive an answer to it. In a paper published <strong>in</strong> 1916 he writes: 'Analysis of the activities ofanimals and men has led me to the conclusion that, amongst other reflexes one particularreflex, the reflex of the goal (рефлекс целм) must be conceived, a striv<strong>in</strong>g for the atta<strong>in</strong>mentof one def<strong>in</strong>ite object send<strong>in</strong>g out stimuli' (translated from the Russian). Later on, he adds thatthis reflex is stand<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> a close relation to the unconditioned reflexes of tak<strong>in</strong>g food and ofcopulation. It is quite obvious that here purposive behaviour, <strong>in</strong> the special form of appetitivebehaviour, has obtruded itself to Pavlov's notice, also that, observ<strong>in</strong>g it chiefly <strong>in</strong> dogs andhumans, he believed that


K. <strong>Lorenz</strong> <strong>1950</strong> <strong>The</strong> <strong>comparative</strong> <strong>method</strong> <strong>in</strong> study<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>nate behavior patterns 231 describ<strong>in</strong>g his experiences with a certa<strong>in</strong> small and very lively dog who would on no accountkeep still when tied to the framework, to which reflexologists attach their dogs, Pavlovactually has <strong>in</strong>troduced a new reflex to meet the case, the 'reflex of freedom'. <strong>The</strong> mostconfirmed vitalist could not have done better by <strong>in</strong>troduc<strong>in</strong>g an <strong>in</strong>st<strong>in</strong>ct of freedom, and,curiously enough, he would have been far nearer the truth than the great mechanist. It is veryfar from my m<strong>in</strong>d to make fun of Pavlov. On the contrary, I regard this jarr<strong>in</strong>g contradictio <strong>in</strong>adjecto the 'reflex of freedom', as a rem<strong>in</strong>der of the limitations of the human m<strong>in</strong>d!(5) Reciprocal errors <strong>in</strong> the treatment of <strong>in</strong>nate behaviour<strong>The</strong> conception of '<strong>in</strong>st<strong>in</strong>ct' is one of the doubtful legacies left to us by the scholasticphilosophy of the middle ages. From the first, this conception was <strong>in</strong>troduced to offer whatappeared to be an explanation for such types of animal behaviour as were not explicable onthe familiar terms of <strong>in</strong>sight and <strong>in</strong>tellect and yet had a def<strong>in</strong>ite survival value to the animal.Medieval science was very prodigal with just this k<strong>in</strong>d of 'explanation'. <strong>The</strong> horror vacui, the'phlogiston' and many other conceptions are further examples. John Dewey, <strong>in</strong> his bookHuman Nature and Conduct, has given so irrefutable a critique of this type of explanation thatit is really superfluous to add even one word. If we accept a 'hom<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>st<strong>in</strong>ct' as anexplanation for the fact that a pigeon flies back to its loft, then, next time a child asks me whatmakes the tra<strong>in</strong> go, I shall answer that this is caused by a special factor, called the locomotiveforce. <strong>The</strong> justification <strong>in</strong> both cases is absolutely the same. If we concede it as a scientificallylegitimate sort of proceed<strong>in</strong>g, to bridge any arbitrarily chosen gap <strong>in</strong> our presentunderstand<strong>in</strong>g of nature by assum<strong>in</strong>g an oblig<strong>in</strong>g little wonder, then all scientific researchbecomes a pure farce.<strong>The</strong> obvious answer to the vitalistic assumption of the 'wonders of <strong>in</strong>st<strong>in</strong>ct' wouldhave been to explode these wonders one by one, by giv<strong>in</strong>g a sensible physiologicalexplanation for each of them, just as hosts of similar vitalistic 'wonders' have, s<strong>in</strong>ce the daysof Johannes Müller and Claude Bernard, been shattered by the progress of analytical research.It is a real wonder that no mechanist ever seriously tried to do this! Maybe <strong>in</strong>nate behaviour,with its evident character of a system, its obvious survival value and its undeniablespontaneity, did not seem attractive to the mechanistic <strong>method</strong>s of research; maybe it wasonly the great stress vitalists laid on '<strong>in</strong>st<strong>in</strong>ct' that made it distasteful to behaviourists andreflexologists. Anyhow, none of the mechanists ever systematically <strong>in</strong>vestigated <strong>in</strong>natebehaviour. <strong>The</strong> few reflexologists who deign to mention <strong>in</strong>nate behaviour patterns at all,conf<strong>in</strong>e themselves to the rather obvious statement that they


K. <strong>Lorenz</strong> <strong>1950</strong> <strong>The</strong> <strong>comparative</strong> <strong>method</strong> <strong>in</strong> study<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>nate behavior patterns 232 consist of cha<strong>in</strong>s of unconditioned reflexes, while some behaviourists, chief among them J. B.Watson, go so far as to deny the existence of any more highly differentiated forms of <strong>in</strong>natebehaviour, conced<strong>in</strong>g only that of simple 'motor mechanisms'.It is hardly an exaggeration to say that the large and immeasurably fertile field which<strong>in</strong>nate behaviour offers to analytical research was left unploughed because it lay, as no man'sland, between the two fronts of the antagonistic op<strong>in</strong>ions of vitalists and mechanists. Smallwonder, <strong>in</strong>deed, if it became 'the sport<strong>in</strong>g ground of fruitless philosophical speculation', asMax Hartmann said on a memorable occasion.(6) Lack of observational basisA short account of a philosophical quarrel, such as the one just given, of necessity, does an<strong>in</strong>justice to both sides. In fact, every abridged render<strong>in</strong>g of a philosophical system is animpudent caricature, tend<strong>in</strong>g to make the philosopher look a fool. It is, on pr<strong>in</strong>ciple,impossible to summarize philosophical op<strong>in</strong>ion <strong>in</strong> the same way as we are wont to do with theresults of our research. This must be borne <strong>in</strong> m<strong>in</strong>d, lest my representation of the reciprocalerrors of vitalism and mechanism seem an <strong>in</strong>solent libel of men whose immense merit I wouldbe the last to depreciate. I am quite aware of the immense over-simplification of all that hasbeen said above and of the many exceptions that have been left unmentioned. I only wanted tomake quite clear the general <strong>in</strong>fluence which the great vitalistic-mechanistic dispute has hadupon the <strong>in</strong>vestigation of <strong>in</strong>nate behaviour. I may have over-estimated and exaggerated this<strong>in</strong>fluence, and on this po<strong>in</strong>t I am open to discussion and very ready to make amends where Ihave erred.<strong>The</strong>re is one po<strong>in</strong>t, however, <strong>in</strong> our <strong>method</strong>ological criticism on the vitalistic andmechanistic schools of behaviour study on which I do not th<strong>in</strong>k that serious discussion ispossible. It means strik<strong>in</strong>g at the very roots of the teach<strong>in</strong>gs of a scientific school if oneaccuses it of <strong>in</strong>sufficient knowledge of facts, of <strong>in</strong>sufficiency of basis of <strong>in</strong>duction. Yet I donot see how this reproach can be spared to either of the great schools of behaviour study. It isan <strong>in</strong>violable law of <strong>in</strong>ductive natural science that it has to beg<strong>in</strong> with pure observation,totally devoid of any preconceived theory and even work<strong>in</strong>g hypothesis. This law has beenbroken by one and all of the great schools of behaviour study, and this one fundamental,<strong>method</strong>ical fault, is at the bottom of all the errors of which we accuse vitalists and mechanists.To put it crudely <strong>in</strong> two examples. If William McDougall had known all H. Elliot Howardknew about 'reactions <strong>in</strong>complete through lack of <strong>in</strong>tensity', he would never have confoundedsurvival value and purpose.


K. <strong>Lorenz</strong> <strong>1950</strong> <strong>The</strong> <strong>comparative</strong> <strong>method</strong> <strong>in</strong> study<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>nate behavior patterns 233 If J. B. Watson had only once reared a young bird <strong>in</strong> isolation, he would never have assertedthat all complicated behaviour patterns were conditioned. It was a really crush<strong>in</strong>g blow tocherished ideals when, as a young student, I first realized that the great authorities on'<strong>in</strong>st<strong>in</strong>ct', such as Lloyd Morgan and W. McDougall, did not know the relevant facts about<strong>in</strong>nate behaviour with which I, ignorant boy though I was, was mentally struggl<strong>in</strong>g even then;reactions not atta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g their goal because of lack of <strong>in</strong>tensity, vacuum activities and the<strong>in</strong>numerable ways <strong>in</strong> which <strong>in</strong>nate behaviour patterns were miscarry<strong>in</strong>g, were evidentlyunknown to the great theorists.I know of only two students of animal behaviour who really knew the animals aboutwhich they wrote and who were, at the time of their writ<strong>in</strong>gs, considered 'scientists' and notjust 'bird lovers'. One of them is H. S. Jenn<strong>in</strong>gs, who may, <strong>in</strong> a loose sense, be considered as abehaviourist; the other is Jakob von Uexküll, who certa<strong>in</strong>ly was a vitalist. In spite of theworld-wide discrepancy of their philosophical positions they have one fundamental po<strong>in</strong>t ofdeparture <strong>in</strong> common: both of them hold that the observation of all there is to be observed <strong>in</strong>the behaviour of a species must go before the quest for explanation of the s<strong>in</strong>gle items ofbehaviour. This means that both of them treat the behaviour of a species as it mustunconditionally be treated: as an organic system. To Jenn<strong>in</strong>gs we owe the conception of thesystem of actions of a species, and though J. v. Uexküll gave a vitalistic name (Bauplan) to thesame reality, he also approached it with the same <strong>method</strong> as Jenn<strong>in</strong>gs, with the <strong>method</strong> of atruly correlative analysis, proceed<strong>in</strong>g on a broad observational front.If there is one behaviorist or reflexologist of Pavlov's school, or one purposivepsychologist, who also approached the problems of behaviour by the obligatory <strong>method</strong> ofcorrelative analysis, that is, who began by observ<strong>in</strong>g all there is to be observed <strong>in</strong> a species,mak<strong>in</strong>g an <strong>in</strong>ventory of its system of actions before form<strong>in</strong>g a work<strong>in</strong>g hypothesis, then I amvery s<strong>in</strong>cere <strong>in</strong> ask<strong>in</strong>g his forgiveness; I am not a very well-read man and have failed to hearof his existence. But all other professional students of animal behaviour have been guilty ofthe one unpardonable offence aga<strong>in</strong>st the most fundamental law of <strong>in</strong>ductive natural science:they have one and all formed a hypothesis first and proceeded to look for examples to confirmit afterwards. <strong>The</strong> protean multiformity of organic nature and quite particularly of thebehaviour of higher animals is such that a circumspect search for examples can never fail todetect a wealth of evidence for literally any theory, however arbitrarily you chose to <strong>in</strong>ventone. <strong>The</strong> facts <strong>in</strong> themselves may be quite correct, but choice of facts <strong>in</strong> itself is ever afalsification of the <strong>in</strong>ductional basis. And this statistical falsification of the very foundation


K. <strong>Lorenz</strong> <strong>1950</strong> <strong>The</strong> <strong>comparative</strong> <strong>method</strong> <strong>in</strong> study<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>nate behavior patterns 234 of natural science can only be prevented <strong>in</strong> one way: unprejudiced observation of all there isto be observed must go temporarily before the build<strong>in</strong>g up of hypothesis.III. METHODS PECULIAR TO COMPARATIVE ETHOLOGY(1) Observational basis of <strong>in</strong>ductionIt is a fact worthy of very serious contemplation that very nearly all the relevant details of<strong>in</strong>nate behaviour, the ignorance of which so seriously impaired the theories of the two greatschools of behaviour study, mechanism and vitalism, have long been known to and fullyappreciated by bird lovers. H. Eliot Howard, Edmund Selous and many other men who wouldhave been considered mere 'amateurs' by the 'scientific' schools, have been conversant withthese facts, without, however, know<strong>in</strong>g how badly these facts were needed by psychology.Also the professional zoologists whom we consider as the pioneers of <strong>comparative</strong> ethology,such as C. O. Whitman, O. He<strong>in</strong>roth, Julian Huxley and Jan Verwey, at first regarded theirobservational work more as a hobby or at best as a very secondary occupation. Indeed, sitt<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong> a bl<strong>in</strong>d observ<strong>in</strong>g birds, or just star<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>to an aviary with pigeons, or on a pond with acollection of ducks, or <strong>in</strong>to an aquarium, does not, at first sight, appear to be as 'scientific' asthe tremendous experiments of mechanists or the deep philosophical speculations of vitalists.Yet it is very far from be<strong>in</strong>g accidental that just this k<strong>in</strong>d of observation yielded facts whichrema<strong>in</strong>ed unknown to the great schools.<strong>The</strong> development of any <strong>in</strong>ductive natural science proceeds through three<strong>in</strong>dispensable stages: the purely observational record<strong>in</strong>g and describ<strong>in</strong>g of fact, the orderlyarrangement of these facts <strong>in</strong> a system, and f<strong>in</strong>ally the quest for the natural laws prevail<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>the system. <strong>The</strong>se three steps have been termed the idiographic, the systematic and thenomothetic stage by W<strong>in</strong>delband. For rather obvious reasons, which I need not expound here,the relative importance of the strictly observational basis of any natural science is <strong>in</strong> directproportion to the degree <strong>in</strong> which its object bears the character of a whole or system: thegreater the number of constituent parts of a system, the more complicated their <strong>in</strong>teraction, themore necessary it evidently becomes to get an <strong>in</strong>ventory of these parts, before beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g theanalysis of their correlations. Now the system of actions of any animal is at least as much of a'whole' and possesses at least as many particulate constituent parts as its body. <strong>The</strong>refore theonly legitimate manner of proceed<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> the study of the behaviour of any species of liv<strong>in</strong>gorganisms is to beg<strong>in</strong>, quite exactly as H. S. Jenn<strong>in</strong>gs has done, with what I would call amorphology of behaviour, by a thorough observation and description of all the behaviourpatterns at the disposal of the species.


K. <strong>Lorenz</strong> <strong>1950</strong> <strong>The</strong> <strong>comparative</strong> <strong>method</strong> <strong>in</strong> study<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>nate behavior patterns 235 Now this, <strong>in</strong> higher animals, is a tall order. If the morphologist must spend months <strong>in</strong>gett<strong>in</strong>g an approximate survey of the anatomy of a species, the ethologist must spend years todo the same regard<strong>in</strong>g its system of actions. And that is exactly where the 'fancy' of the'amateur' comes <strong>in</strong>. I confidently assert that no man, even if he were endowed with asuperhuman patience, could physically br<strong>in</strong>g himself to stare at fishes, birds or mammals aspersistently as is necessary <strong>in</strong> order to take stock of the behaviour patterns of a species, unlesshis eyes were bound to the object of his observation <strong>in</strong> that spellbound gaze which is notmotivated by any conscious effort to ga<strong>in</strong> knowledge, but by that mysterious charm that thebeauty of liv<strong>in</strong>g creatures works on some of us!(2) <strong>The</strong> keep<strong>in</strong>g of animals as a scientific <strong>method</strong>In many natural sciences, such as botany, zoology, m<strong>in</strong>eralogy and others, scientific activityhas begun with collect<strong>in</strong>g, and I do not doubt that this collect<strong>in</strong>g was, <strong>in</strong> most cases, at firstmotivated much more by 'fancy* for attractive objects than by cognitive purpose. No<strong>comparative</strong> ethologist of my acqua<strong>in</strong>tance has ever denied that his scientific career began <strong>in</strong>the same manner. He<strong>in</strong>roth was ten when he started collect<strong>in</strong>g and keep<strong>in</strong>g ducks and geese; Imyself was still younger when I did the same. Whitman is said to have been addicted topigeon keep<strong>in</strong>g at about the same age. Though hav<strong>in</strong>g done this undoubtedly is not a merit, itnevertheless was the <strong>method</strong>ologically correct th<strong>in</strong>g to do, and I th<strong>in</strong>k I am justified <strong>in</strong>rang<strong>in</strong>g the keep<strong>in</strong>g of animals <strong>in</strong> captivity first among the <strong>method</strong>s peculiar to <strong>comparative</strong>ethology.By 'keep<strong>in</strong>g' an animal I do not mean the mere attempt to keep it alive <strong>in</strong> captivity foras long as possible, but the endeavour to make a given species unfold its whole system ofactions under constant, controllable conditions. Keep<strong>in</strong>g, therefore, always implies theattempt to breed the species <strong>in</strong> question.It is far from me to disparage the advantages of field observation and the merits offield observers. But for the purposes of correlative analysis it is, as I have already stressed, ofthe first importance to get an <strong>in</strong>ventory of the particulate behaviour patterns of a species andto get some notion to what extent these constituents of behaviour patterns are woven <strong>in</strong>to aregulative 'whole'. I have already emphasized (p. 226) the necessity of ascerta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g, at anearly stage of analysis, how far a system of actions is a regulative whole and how far it is amosaic of relatively <strong>in</strong>dependent elements. This question is extremely difficult to decide <strong>in</strong>field work, because <strong>in</strong> the natural surround<strong>in</strong>gs of a species its system of action is apt to seemmuch more adaptive and its several activities much more purposive than they really are. Thus


K. <strong>Lorenz</strong> <strong>1950</strong> <strong>The</strong> <strong>comparative</strong> <strong>method</strong> <strong>in</strong> study<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>nate behavior patterns 236 adaptedness is easily confounded with adaptability. It is only by miscarry<strong>in</strong>g that anybehaviour pattern can show its nature of a particulate element. Now, of course, it is possibleto notice miscarry<strong>in</strong>g behaviour patterns <strong>in</strong> field observation, as H. Eliot Howard hassufficiently proved. But it is quite impossible not to see it <strong>in</strong> observ<strong>in</strong>g animals kept <strong>in</strong>captivity.It is hardly possible to exaggerate the importance of miscarry<strong>in</strong>g behaviour patterns asa source of our knowledge. W. Craig's great discovery that it is the discharge ofconsummatory actions and not the survival value which is the goal of appetitive behaviourwas exclusively due to the observation of behaviour patterns be<strong>in</strong>g executed without atta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>gtheir 'normal' survival value. <strong>The</strong> existence of <strong>in</strong>nate releas<strong>in</strong>g mechanisms would never havebeen discovered and their function would not have been possible to analyse if it had not beenfor the observation of cases, <strong>in</strong> which they were activated 'erroneously' by stimulus situations,<strong>in</strong> which the released activity was thoroughly miscarry<strong>in</strong>g. <strong>The</strong> whole set of phenomenaconnected with the process of accumulation of action-specific energy (such as lower<strong>in</strong>g ofthreshold, explosion activity, etc.) also could only be discovered by observ<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>natebehaviour patterns miscarry<strong>in</strong>g when discharged at an <strong>in</strong>adequate object.It is not only the miscarry<strong>in</strong>g of reactions caused by the absence of normalenvironmental stimulation which makes the observation of animals kept <strong>in</strong> captivity sovaluable. <strong>The</strong> physiology of the central nervous system has ga<strong>in</strong>ed much of its knowledgeabout particulate functions by study<strong>in</strong>g cases <strong>in</strong> which some functions had dropped out,because of pathological processes, or had been experimentally destroyed. Very much the samemanner of proceed<strong>in</strong>g has led <strong>comparative</strong> ethology to analogous results. Very slightdisturbances of the general 'condition' of captive animals are apt to cause surpris<strong>in</strong>gly farreach<strong>in</strong>gdis<strong>in</strong>tegrations of their systems of actions. Endogenous activities lose much of theirnormal <strong>in</strong>tensity or drop out altogether; <strong>in</strong>nate releas<strong>in</strong>g mechanisms lose much of theirselectiveness. <strong>The</strong> general dis<strong>in</strong>tegration of the species' system of actions caused by these twoma<strong>in</strong> processes is essentially reversible. If one starts keep<strong>in</strong>g a new species, with whose needsone is not yet familiar, one automatically gets an opportunity to observe this particular formof dis<strong>in</strong>tegrated behaviour, very often a jumble of unconnected behaviour patterns whosenormal survival value is often very difficult even to guess. Yet this jumble of disconnectedbehaviour patterns is extremely valuable for the purpose of tak<strong>in</strong>g stock of the particulate,genetically fixed 'mosaic stones' of behaviour. When, later on, one learns how to keep thespecies <strong>in</strong> question and when, with the improvement of technique, the animals are got back<strong>in</strong>to the p<strong>in</strong>k of condition, then the jumble of dis<strong>in</strong>tegrated parts is slowly reassembled


K. <strong>Lorenz</strong> <strong>1950</strong> <strong>The</strong> <strong>comparative</strong> <strong>method</strong> <strong>in</strong> study<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>nate behavior patterns 237 <strong>in</strong>to a function<strong>in</strong>g system which fully delivers its normal survival value. I hardly know a more<strong>in</strong>structive object of observation than just this type of dis<strong>in</strong>tegration and reassembl<strong>in</strong>g of thesystem of actions <strong>in</strong> animals kept <strong>in</strong> captivity. It is, <strong>in</strong> fact, an actualized example of analysisand resynthesis of behaviour!If dis<strong>in</strong>tegration is a valuable source of our knowledge about behaviour and, <strong>in</strong>deed,the most valuable fulcrum for its analysis, it must also forever be remembered as a possiblesource of error. I want to give one warn<strong>in</strong>g example of this. <strong>The</strong> red-backed shrike, Laniuscollurio L., has got a very beautifully differentiated endogenous movement for impal<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>sects on thorns. This activity has a taxis component generally direct<strong>in</strong>g it to branches ortwigs, but apparently none that directs it to a thorn. <strong>The</strong> reaction to the thorn was <strong>in</strong>dubitablyacquired by the trial-and-error <strong>method</strong> by the shrikes I observed as early as 1932, and <strong>in</strong> apaper then published I enlarged upon this particular case of <strong>in</strong>nate behaviour patterns<strong>in</strong>terlock<strong>in</strong>g with trial and error and condition<strong>in</strong>g. Now G. Kramer has recently reared redbackedshrikes with a view to study<strong>in</strong>g their migration activities and <strong>in</strong>cidentally observed thedevelopment of their reaction to the thorn. What he saw at first was <strong>in</strong> perfect accord withwhat I had written <strong>in</strong> 1932; the shrikes showed the movement first and got conditioned to thethorn by trial and error. Kramer is a past master <strong>in</strong> rear<strong>in</strong>g birds, and you may rest assured thatthese shrikes were <strong>in</strong> the best of condition. And yet, when he tried still further to improve hisfeed<strong>in</strong>g technique and started breed<strong>in</strong>g silkworms for the young shrikes, the birds thus rearedneeded no condition<strong>in</strong>g to the thorn, but most amaz<strong>in</strong>gly proved to have an <strong>in</strong>nate directivemechanism react<strong>in</strong>g to the specific optical sign stimuli emanat<strong>in</strong>g from a sharp end or thorn.This particular source of error must be kept <strong>in</strong> m<strong>in</strong>d.As a <strong>method</strong> of analysis of animal behaviour, keep<strong>in</strong>g truly deserves the adjective'correlative', because it very strictly compels the <strong>in</strong>vestigator to consider the behaviourpatterns of a species <strong>in</strong> correlation to the environmental conditions to which they are adapted.Aga<strong>in</strong>, it is the observation of miscarry<strong>in</strong>g behaviour patterns, from which the keeper must beable to deduce what particular conditions of the artificial environment of the animal he mustchange, to make those behaviour patterns atta<strong>in</strong> their normal survival value. Just as he woulddeduce from the morphological characters of a mole's forepaws that this species needs earthto dig <strong>in</strong>, so he must, from slight 'h<strong>in</strong>ts' of miscarry<strong>in</strong>g behaviour patterns, be able to deducethe correspond<strong>in</strong>g environmental exigencies of the species. Perhaps the most importantcognitive value of this proceed<strong>in</strong>g lies there<strong>in</strong>, that it forcefully compels the observer to treatthe several behaviour patterns of a species exactly as he would treat organs. <strong>The</strong> observer isvery conv<strong>in</strong>c<strong>in</strong>gly


K. <strong>Lorenz</strong> <strong>1950</strong> <strong>The</strong> <strong>comparative</strong> <strong>method</strong> <strong>in</strong> study<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>nate behavior patterns 238 taught that behaviour patterns are not someth<strong>in</strong>g which animals may do or not do, or do <strong>in</strong>different ways, accord<strong>in</strong>g to the requirements of the occasion, but someth<strong>in</strong>g which animalsof a given species 'have got', exactly <strong>in</strong> the same manner as they 'have got' claws or teeth of adef<strong>in</strong>ite morphological structure.From the recognition of this fact it is only a very short step to the systematiccomparison of the <strong>in</strong>nate behaviour patterns characteristic of allied species. It is, <strong>in</strong>deed, only<strong>in</strong> keep<strong>in</strong>g animals that this comparison obtrudes itself to the observer's notice. <strong>The</strong> discoveryof phyletic homology between <strong>in</strong>nate behaviour patterns was unavoidable, once a scientistconversant with the <strong>method</strong>s of <strong>comparative</strong> morphology got the opportunity to observeclosely a number of species belong<strong>in</strong>g to the same systematic group. It is there that C. Q.Whitman's 'fancy' for pigeons and O. He<strong>in</strong>roth's partiality to Anatides have played a verydecisive part. A man know<strong>in</strong>g the s<strong>in</strong>gle system of actions of every species as they knew itcould not fail to notice that certa<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>nate behaviour patterns were just as characteristic of aspecies, a genus or a family, as any morphological character. As early as 1898, C. O. Whitmanwrote the sentence that marks the birth of <strong>comparative</strong> ethology. 'Inst<strong>in</strong>cts and organs are tobe studied from the common viewpo<strong>in</strong>t of phyletic descent.'(3) 'Comparative anatomy' of behaviourWith the discovery of phyletic homology of behaviour patterns the study of behaviour may besaid to have grown out of the purely idiographic stage of its development and to have reachedthe second systematic stage. This discovery was of the greatest importance <strong>in</strong> several respects.Not only could <strong>in</strong>nate behaviour patterns be used as very valuable and certa<strong>in</strong>ly very welcomenew taxonomic characters <strong>in</strong> ascerta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g the phyletic relations between allied forms, but thespecial form of certa<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>nate behaviour patterns became accessible to a causal explanationbased on the understand<strong>in</strong>g of their phyletic orig<strong>in</strong>. Both of these facts, though certa<strong>in</strong>lyimportant enough <strong>in</strong> themselves, atta<strong>in</strong> an even greater secondary importance by prov<strong>in</strong>g thegreat <strong>in</strong>dependence of the behaviour patterns <strong>in</strong> question, as particulate elements ofbehaviour. Thus not only the well-tried <strong>method</strong> of <strong>comparative</strong> morphology becameapplicable to the study of behaviour, but it also became possible to isolate a very dist<strong>in</strong>ctphysiological process as an <strong>in</strong>dependent constituent of behaviour and to study it separately, <strong>in</strong>a legitimate departure from the otherwise obligatory <strong>method</strong> of correlative analysis on a broadfront. <strong>The</strong>refore, physiological analysis followed closely on the heels of the <strong>comparative</strong> andsystematic study of the elementary process <strong>in</strong> question.Zoological systematics and <strong>comparative</strong> morphology are, by many,


K. <strong>Lorenz</strong> <strong>1950</strong> <strong>The</strong> <strong>comparative</strong> <strong>method</strong> <strong>in</strong> study<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>nate behavior patterns 239 considered tedious and rather mummified branches of research. It is too easy to forget that weowe them the most revolutionary discovery of the last hundred years, the discovery ofevolution. Though I emphatically deny the charge that <strong>comparative</strong> morphology is a spentscience which has already borne all its fruits, I should concede that it certa<strong>in</strong>ly has borne themost important of them. Now there is some danger that the same might be thought, veryprematurely, of <strong>comparative</strong> ethology. In the study of behaviour the phyletic viewpo<strong>in</strong>t hasyielded, as a very valuable result, the possibility of isolat<strong>in</strong>g and study<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> l<strong>in</strong>ear,experimental analysis an important, particulate central nervous function, the endogenousactivity. In consequence of this, a second, nearly as <strong>in</strong>dependent perceptual function, the socalled<strong>in</strong>nate releas<strong>in</strong>g mechanism, has become experimentally accessible. Each of these twofunctions, as a constituent of behaviour, doubtless plays as important a part as the reflex andthe conditioned response, and there is a very great temptation to repeat the error of which wehave reproached behaviourists and reflexologists, by believ<strong>in</strong>g that we have got hold of 'all'the necessary 'elements' to expla<strong>in</strong> 'everyth<strong>in</strong>g', and to plunge <strong>in</strong>to l<strong>in</strong>ear, experimentalanalysis without giv<strong>in</strong>g any further thought to the necessity of further collect<strong>in</strong>g purelyobservational facts. Of course, the fulfill<strong>in</strong>g of this duty will not keep us from eagerlyfollow<strong>in</strong>g up the leads to l<strong>in</strong>ear, experimental analysis which we have discovered. But it iswell that we should keep <strong>in</strong> m<strong>in</strong>d the extreme youth of our branch of science and that weshould cherish no illusions about the breadth of the observational basis of <strong>in</strong>duction that hashitherto been atta<strong>in</strong>ed. A precipitate transition from systematics to nomothesis would beparticularly disastrous to our branch of research, and the longer and the more we lay stress onthe descriptive side of <strong>comparative</strong> ethology, the better it will be <strong>in</strong> the long run.S<strong>in</strong>ce the days of Charles Darw<strong>in</strong> the term '<strong>comparative</strong>' has assumed a very def<strong>in</strong>itemean<strong>in</strong>g. It <strong>in</strong>dicates a certa<strong>in</strong> rather complicated <strong>method</strong> of procedure which, by study<strong>in</strong>g thesimilarities and dissimilarities of homologous characters of allied forms, simultaneouslyobta<strong>in</strong>s <strong>in</strong>dications as to the phyletic relationships of these forms of life and as to thehistorical orig<strong>in</strong> of the homologous characters <strong>in</strong> question. I need not enlarge on the details ofthis <strong>method</strong> which is a commonplace to biologists and physiologists. We all know perfectlywell what we mean by '<strong>comparative</strong>' anatomy, morphology, physiology and so on. But it is allthe more mislead<strong>in</strong>g if psychologists, who evidently are not familiar with what we meanwhen we speak of the <strong>comparative</strong> <strong>method</strong>, apply the same term <strong>in</strong> a very loose sense to allbehaviour studies concerned with different forms of life. I must confess that I strongly resentit, not only from the term<strong>in</strong>ological viewpo<strong>in</strong>t,


K. <strong>Lorenz</strong> <strong>1950</strong> <strong>The</strong> <strong>comparative</strong> <strong>method</strong> <strong>in</strong> study<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>nate behavior patterns 240 but also <strong>in</strong> the <strong>in</strong>terests of the very hard-work<strong>in</strong>g and honest craft of really <strong>comparative</strong><strong>in</strong>vestigators, when an American journal masquerades under the title of '<strong>comparative</strong>'psychology, although, to the best of my knowledge, no really <strong>comparative</strong> paper ever hasbeen published <strong>in</strong> it.Phyletic comparison is slow and pa<strong>in</strong>ful work, even <strong>in</strong> morphology, where thecomparable, homologous characters are immediately and permanently accessible to theanatomist's knife. It is obvious how the difficulties are <strong>in</strong>creased <strong>in</strong> the study of <strong>in</strong>natebehaviour patterns which are not there cont<strong>in</strong>uously, just to be looked at and described, butfor which one must wait <strong>in</strong> patient observation. It is therefore easy to understand that onlyvery few systematic groups of animals have hitherto been thus studied with any appreciabledegree of thoroughness. Historically the first and perhaps still the most thoroughly studiedgroup is the order of pigeons which was <strong>in</strong>vestigated by Whitman. Second are the order ofAnatidae, as studied by He<strong>in</strong>roth, and one family of this order, the Anat<strong>in</strong>ae, more especiallystudied by He<strong>in</strong>roth and by myself. If, as a third group, I add the cichlid fishes, <strong>in</strong>vestigatedby A. Seitz, G. P. Baerends & Baerends van Roon and A. Ste<strong>in</strong>er, whose paper on dwarfcichlids is, however, not yet published, our list is complete. <strong>The</strong>re are some very good paperson lizards which can, to a certa<strong>in</strong> extent, be evaluated <strong>comparative</strong>ly, though wide gaps stillrema<strong>in</strong> between the known species, and there is a <strong>comparative</strong> <strong>in</strong>vestigation on herons by O.Koenig nearly f<strong>in</strong>ished. <strong>The</strong> only paper aim<strong>in</strong>g at giv<strong>in</strong>g even a superficial survey of the<strong>comparative</strong> ethology of a group of mammals, is the paper by O. Antonius on Equidae.Concern<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>vertebrates, O. Plath has used the behaviour patterns of nest build<strong>in</strong>g andprovision<strong>in</strong>g of humble-bees as taxonomic characters, and analogous work was done by A.Petrunkewitch with spiders. <strong>The</strong>re are, of course, hosts of unconnected facts known that mayeventually, when gaps are bridged, become accessible to <strong>comparative</strong> evaluation.<strong>The</strong> immense field of observation which is still wait<strong>in</strong>g to be systematically exploitedneeds whole armies of <strong>in</strong>vestigators. <strong>The</strong>se armies are, however, already <strong>in</strong> existence, at leasttwo of them: the bird-lovers and the fish-fanciers. It is a superlative merit of a book like thatof the Rev. E. A. Armstrong that it calls the amateurs' attention to the important details whichwe need to know. <strong>The</strong>re can never be too many such really scientific and yet generally<strong>in</strong>telligible books on behaviour. I have already expla<strong>in</strong>ed why the bird or fish 'lover' is <strong>in</strong>some respects the ideal observer. <strong>The</strong> task is, to enlist him to help us <strong>in</strong> concerted effort.<strong>The</strong> <strong>method</strong>ologically first task is, without any doubt, the <strong>in</strong>tensive study of all of the<strong>in</strong>nate behaviour patterns of a restricted group of forms. Besides this, it is a legitimate way ofproceed<strong>in</strong>g, extensively to study throughout the


K. <strong>Lorenz</strong> <strong>1950</strong> <strong>The</strong> <strong>comparative</strong> <strong>method</strong> <strong>in</strong> study<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>nate behavior patterns 241 animal k<strong>in</strong>gdom one given homology of behaviour pattern. O. He<strong>in</strong>roth (1930), <strong>in</strong> a paper as<strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g as it is short, has given us a survey of the extension and distribution of someexceed<strong>in</strong>gly widely spread and evidently exceed<strong>in</strong>gly old behaviour patterns of vertebrates,such as yawn<strong>in</strong>g and scratch<strong>in</strong>g the head with the h<strong>in</strong>d leg. Curiously enough, I do not knowof another paper proceed<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> this way, though this way of pursu<strong>in</strong>g a behaviour pattern as ahomologous character throughout a large group is <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g work and gives quick results <strong>in</strong>comparison with other <strong>comparative</strong> <strong>in</strong>vestigations. At present I am collect<strong>in</strong>g notes on thescratch<strong>in</strong>g movements of mammals, particularly of rodents. In this group, and also <strong>in</strong>primates, the areas scratched with the h<strong>in</strong>d leg and with the forepaw respectively are ataxonomic character whose distribution is most <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g.Only <strong>in</strong> two groups (<strong>in</strong> ducks and cichlid fishes) have our <strong>in</strong>tensive studies of thes<strong>in</strong>gle species and our extensive studies of the several behaviour patterns progressed farenough to make possible what <strong>in</strong> <strong>comparative</strong> morphology is quite a commonplace th<strong>in</strong>g, thatis, to represent both l<strong>in</strong>es of <strong>in</strong>vestigation <strong>in</strong> a tabular <strong>in</strong>dex. In one of my papers (1947) Ihave given such an <strong>in</strong>dex concern<strong>in</strong>g a number of behaviour patterns of sixteen species ofducks belong<strong>in</strong>g to different families (Anat<strong>in</strong>ae, Cair<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>ae and Casarc<strong>in</strong>ae). This <strong>method</strong> oflett<strong>in</strong>g, metaphorically speak<strong>in</strong>g, two l<strong>in</strong>es of <strong>in</strong>vestigation cross each other at right angles, isfundamental to every k<strong>in</strong>d of phyletic <strong>in</strong>vestigation of homologous characters. Only this k<strong>in</strong>dof broad survey can give us the possibility of form<strong>in</strong>g a firm op<strong>in</strong>ion about the relative ageand phyletic conservativity of any taxonomic character.In some cases which are particularly favourable to this k<strong>in</strong>d of <strong>in</strong>vestigation, it hasbeen possible to form a quite well-founded op<strong>in</strong>ion concern<strong>in</strong>g the l<strong>in</strong>es along which theevolution of certa<strong>in</strong> behaviour patterns has taken place. Always keep<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> m<strong>in</strong>d that there areno 'primitive' forms of life, and that therefore any l<strong>in</strong>ear taxonomic arrangement of liv<strong>in</strong>ganimals or plants is necessarily sheer nonsense, it is nevertheless possible and legitimate toattribute the quality of relative primitivity to s<strong>in</strong>gle characters. It is a dangerously loose andmislead<strong>in</strong>g expression to call any recent form of life, however many primitive characters itmay possess, a 'primitive' animal. In regard to all the characters of his mouth and teeth, man ismuch more primitive than the Platypus. What alone may be arranged <strong>in</strong> a l<strong>in</strong>ear sequence arethe different forms of actualization which one and the same homologous character shows <strong>in</strong>related forms of life. <strong>The</strong> ramify<strong>in</strong>g 'l<strong>in</strong>e of differentiation' thus obta<strong>in</strong>ed does, very probably,correspond to the actual stages of evolutional development of the character <strong>in</strong> question. Anumber of <strong>in</strong>dubitable sequences of differentiation could be established among <strong>in</strong>natebehaviour patterns.


K. <strong>Lorenz</strong> <strong>1950</strong> <strong>The</strong> <strong>comparative</strong> <strong>method</strong> <strong>in</strong> study<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>nate behavior patterns 242 In all cases where it has been found possible to do this, the <strong>in</strong>nate behaviour pattern <strong>in</strong>question was a 'releas<strong>in</strong>g ceremony'. This is far from be<strong>in</strong>g accidental. <strong>The</strong>re are two papersbe<strong>in</strong>g read here on the subject of social releasers, so I must be very short. A social releaser is adevice — either a property of colour and/or shape, or a special sequence of movements, or,for that matter, of sounds, or a scent — specially differentiated to the function of elicit<strong>in</strong>g aresponse <strong>in</strong> a fellow-member of the species. To every releaser, as an organ for send<strong>in</strong>g outsign stimuli, there corresponds a perceptual correlate, an 'organ' to receive sign stimuli and toactivate the answer<strong>in</strong>g reaction. This we call an <strong>in</strong>nate releas<strong>in</strong>g mechanism (auslösendesSchema). <strong>The</strong> function of social releasers and of answer<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>nate releas<strong>in</strong>g mechanisms isvery much like that of a human signal code, or of that of human word language. Exactly as theseveral forms of the s<strong>in</strong>gle word symbols of our language do not have any direct connexionwith their mean<strong>in</strong>g, but are only fixed by the convention of one particular sign code, so also isthe particular form of any social releaser determ<strong>in</strong>ed by an <strong>in</strong>traspecific 'convention' betweenthe sender and the receiver of sign stimuli. <strong>The</strong> important consequence of this is that we mayexclude from our consideration the possibility of convergent adaptation when compar<strong>in</strong>gsimilarity and dissimilarity of releasers. It is immeasurably improbable that the similarity ofthe words mother, mutter, mater, μήτηρ and мать, <strong>in</strong> English, German, Lat<strong>in</strong>, Greek andRussian, should be due to anyth<strong>in</strong>g else than to their common derivation from a mutual Indo-European 'ancestral form'. If, therefore, the <strong>comparative</strong> philologist is fully justified <strong>in</strong>neglect<strong>in</strong>g any other possibility, then the very same holds true for any resemblance betweenreleas<strong>in</strong>g 'ceremonies' of phyletically allied species. This is why we know more about theorig<strong>in</strong> and the evolution of releas<strong>in</strong>g ceremonies than we do about any other <strong>in</strong>nate behaviourpatterns. This is also why, on the basis of releas<strong>in</strong>g activities used as taxonomic characters, itis, <strong>in</strong> quite a number of cases, possible to ascerta<strong>in</strong> phyletic <strong>in</strong>terrelations of species with acertitude and a wealth of detail, hardly ever atta<strong>in</strong>able on the basis of purely morphologicalcharacters.We know of two phyletically dist<strong>in</strong>ct ways, by which non-social, mechanicallyeffective endogenous activities may develop <strong>in</strong>to social releasers: <strong>in</strong> one case the so-called'<strong>in</strong>tention movement' (Intentionsbewegung, He<strong>in</strong>roth), <strong>in</strong> the other the so-called 'displacementactivities'. Both types of movement are, <strong>in</strong> their primary form, mere by-products of actionspecificexcitation and certa<strong>in</strong>ly devoid of any survival value. <strong>The</strong> <strong>in</strong>tention movement isnoth<strong>in</strong>g but a slight h<strong>in</strong>t of a certa<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>nate behaviour pattern, as will occur whenever actionspecificexcitation only reaches a very low level of <strong>in</strong>tensity. Displacement activities are theresult of a very different physiological


K. <strong>Lorenz</strong> <strong>1950</strong> <strong>The</strong> <strong>comparative</strong> <strong>method</strong> <strong>in</strong> study<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>nate behavior patterns 243 process. If action-specific excitation is at a <strong>comparative</strong>ly high level of <strong>in</strong>tensity and f<strong>in</strong>ds itspath to its normal outlet suddenly blocked — for <strong>in</strong>stance, by activation of an antagonisticdrive or by sudden disappearance of the adequate object — it 'sparks over', as Makk<strong>in</strong>k veryexpressively describes it, <strong>in</strong>to a nervous path not normally its own and f<strong>in</strong>ds its expression <strong>in</strong>behaviour patterns belong<strong>in</strong>g to a quite different action-specific excitation. Makk<strong>in</strong>k,T<strong>in</strong>bergen, Koortlant and E. A. Armstrong have studied displacement activities veryextensively.Intention movements as well as displacement activities are, to an observer wellconversant with the system of actions of a species, very reliable <strong>in</strong>dicators for the present'mood' of an animal, that is, <strong>in</strong> objectivistic term<strong>in</strong>ology, for its present <strong>in</strong>ternal state ofspecific read<strong>in</strong>ess for certa<strong>in</strong> activities. Now <strong>in</strong> very many animals an analogous'understand<strong>in</strong>g' of the <strong>in</strong>tention movements and the displacement activities of a fellowmemberof the species has evidently been developed on the basis of <strong>in</strong>nate releas<strong>in</strong>gmechanisms. (It seems well worth mention<strong>in</strong>g that as yet we do not know of a s<strong>in</strong>gle <strong>in</strong>stance<strong>in</strong> which a similar 'understand<strong>in</strong>g' is brought about by condition<strong>in</strong>g!) In other words, thecharacteristic movements <strong>in</strong> question developed a totally new function as social releasers.From that po<strong>in</strong>t onwards both types of releas<strong>in</strong>g movements underwent an exceed<strong>in</strong>glycharacteristic process of differentiation. <strong>The</strong> primarily important, mechanically effectiveconstituent parts of the movement are lessened <strong>in</strong> strength and amplitude, while all opticallyeffective features of the movement are exaggerated and emphasized <strong>in</strong> a very peculiar andstrik<strong>in</strong>g way. We know to-day of a very great number of examples of this particular process ofevolution; there are all possible gradations between movements, as yet hardly different fromtheir orig<strong>in</strong>al form and behaviour patterns, whose differentiation along the l<strong>in</strong>es describedabove has gone so far as to transform them <strong>in</strong>to grotesque 'ceremonies' or 'dances' whoseactual homology to the primary <strong>in</strong>tention or displacement activity can only be ascerta<strong>in</strong>edthrough a thorough study of <strong>in</strong>termediate forms — if such happen to exist. Releas<strong>in</strong>gceremonies derived by this over-accentuation or 'mimical exaggeration' from <strong>in</strong>tentionmovements were called 'symbolic movements' (Symbolbewegungen) by He<strong>in</strong>roth. In the caseof displacement activities a term<strong>in</strong>ological difference has not yet been made between primarydisplacement and fixed, ritualized, mimically over-accentuated ceremonies.In a very great number of known cases, the differentiation of a homologous releas<strong>in</strong>gbehaviour pattern has, <strong>in</strong> allied species, taken place along divergent l<strong>in</strong>es. Very often differentmorphological devices have been evolved to accentuate the optical effect of a ceremony, thusemphasiz<strong>in</strong>g different parts of one homologous behaviour pattern <strong>in</strong> different species.


K. <strong>Lorenz</strong> <strong>1950</strong> <strong>The</strong> <strong>comparative</strong> <strong>method</strong> <strong>in</strong> study<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>nate behavior patterns 244 In surface-feed<strong>in</strong>g ducks there are a good many <strong>in</strong>stances of this. <strong>The</strong> evolutive processdescribed makes it easily <strong>in</strong>telligible why <strong>in</strong> many <strong>in</strong>stances the behaviour pattern should be— as it evidently is — phyletically very much older and much more conservative than themorphological devices, colour and/or structure, that help to accentuate it. Another notable factis that the sequence of movements, constitut<strong>in</strong>g a releas<strong>in</strong>g ceremony, is, <strong>in</strong> very many cases,much more conservative than its 'mean<strong>in</strong>g', than the <strong>in</strong>nate releas<strong>in</strong>g mechanism activated bythis particular set of sign stimuli <strong>in</strong> a fellow-member of the species. <strong>The</strong> extensive<strong>comparative</strong> study of one dist<strong>in</strong>ct releas<strong>in</strong>g behaviour pattern often leads to amaz<strong>in</strong>gly similarresults, as the <strong>comparative</strong> study of a root word <strong>in</strong> the historical development of language.Just as the mean<strong>in</strong>g of one word symbol may split up <strong>in</strong>to different and even oppositemean<strong>in</strong>gs of its derivatives (for <strong>in</strong>stance, <strong>in</strong> the English and German words knight and Knecht,which have both been derived from a common root describ<strong>in</strong>g an armed follower of a warlord but have assumed the opposite mean<strong>in</strong>gs of a lord <strong>in</strong> English and of a serf <strong>in</strong> German), sodoes, to cite only one <strong>in</strong>stance, the behaviour pattern orig<strong>in</strong>ally express<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>feriority <strong>in</strong>cichlid fishes assume the exactly opposite mean<strong>in</strong>g of a threaten<strong>in</strong>g gesture <strong>in</strong> the 'dwarfcichlids' of the genera Nannacara and Apistogramma. What is more, we know the phyleticdevelopment by which it has done so.A good example of a l<strong>in</strong>e of differentiation of mimetically over-accentuated <strong>in</strong>tentivemovements is offered by the releas<strong>in</strong>g behaviour patterns which, <strong>in</strong> cichlid fishes, elicit anddirect the young fishes' reaction of follow<strong>in</strong>g after their parents. <strong>The</strong>re are two elements <strong>in</strong> thenormal movements of a fish start<strong>in</strong>g to swim which are particularly effective <strong>in</strong> an opticalway and suitable for mimetic over-accentuation. One is the sideway sw<strong>in</strong>g of head and body,the second is the movement of the median f<strong>in</strong>s which, <strong>in</strong> cichlids as <strong>in</strong> most otheracanthopterygians, are furled when the fish starts to swim and re-erected whenever it stops.Both these elements have undergone an <strong>in</strong>dependent and divergent differentiation and also a'splitt<strong>in</strong>g up' of their 'mean<strong>in</strong>g' <strong>in</strong> the course of the evolution of cichlids. In the most widelyspread and doubtlessly most primitive form of the releas<strong>in</strong>g behaviour pattern <strong>in</strong> question, thesw<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>g of the head and the furl<strong>in</strong>g and erect<strong>in</strong>g of median f<strong>in</strong>s are still coupled <strong>in</strong> the sameobligatory way as <strong>in</strong> the orig<strong>in</strong>al movement which has not yet got a releas<strong>in</strong>g function. In thisprimitive form of the releas<strong>in</strong>g and direct<strong>in</strong>g behaviour pattern, it differs from a normalswimm<strong>in</strong>g start only <strong>in</strong> that, after all the grand preparation, the fish does not get farther than 4or 5 cm. and then stops aga<strong>in</strong>. Also <strong>in</strong> this primitive form, as we f<strong>in</strong>d it <strong>in</strong> Aequidens,Hemichromis, Geophagus and most species of the genus Cichlasoma, the directive function ofthe sideways sw<strong>in</strong>g of


K. <strong>Lorenz</strong> <strong>1950</strong> <strong>The</strong> <strong>comparative</strong> <strong>method</strong> <strong>in</strong> study<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>nate behavior patterns 245 the head is very clear. <strong>The</strong> swarm of young 'obediently' turns to the left or to the rightaccord<strong>in</strong>gly, which is especially strik<strong>in</strong>g, when the young are swimm<strong>in</strong>g 10 or more cm. <strong>in</strong>front of the guid<strong>in</strong>g parent. Even <strong>in</strong> some of these species the movement of the median f<strong>in</strong>s isbecom<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>dependent of the body movements, and a quick lower<strong>in</strong>g and rais<strong>in</strong>g of f<strong>in</strong>s canbe observed, especially when the parent fishes are a bit alarmed. <strong>The</strong>re is an <strong>in</strong>dubitablecorrelation between these <strong>in</strong>dependent movements of the median f<strong>in</strong>s and their colour<strong>in</strong>g: thedorsal f<strong>in</strong> is richly beset with 'jewels' <strong>in</strong> species, <strong>in</strong> which the movement is developed. InHemichromis bimaculatus, <strong>in</strong> which the dorsal f<strong>in</strong> is particularly richly adorned, the up-anddownmovement has taken the form of an exceed<strong>in</strong>gly quick twitch<strong>in</strong>g that makes the jewelson the f<strong>in</strong> flicker like a heliograph. Also this movement, <strong>in</strong> its higher <strong>in</strong>tensities, has assumeda specialized mean<strong>in</strong>g; it is used quite particularly when the young are called together andtucked up for the night <strong>in</strong> the nest-hole.In the genus Apistogramma and Nannacara, on the other hand, the sideways sw<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>gof the head has taken an <strong>in</strong>dependent path of differentiation. Without any concomitantmovement of the median f<strong>in</strong>s, the females of these species (which alone lead the brood)twitch their head sideways <strong>in</strong> a lightn<strong>in</strong>g jerk. <strong>The</strong> body and tail are not moved, and thehomology with the orig<strong>in</strong>al form of the movement is only apparent when the fish really startsto swim. <strong>The</strong> brood<strong>in</strong>g females of these species wander about very little, but 'browse' theirflock of youngsters for long <strong>in</strong>tervals <strong>in</strong> one spot, all the time execut<strong>in</strong>g their sidewaysflick<strong>in</strong>g of the head with the regularity and about the same frequency as a mother hen uttersher cluck<strong>in</strong>g call note. In old Nannacara females the flick<strong>in</strong>g movements can be elicited byputt<strong>in</strong>g the fish <strong>in</strong>to a dense swarm of Daphnia. Though the fish will eat s<strong>in</strong>gle Daphnias, itwill refuse to eat them if they are too close together, <strong>in</strong> which case it proceeds to 'brood' them.In all species of Apistogramma the broody female has a bright black and yellow pattern<strong>in</strong>g ofthe head and throat which goes to accentuate the optical effect of the flick<strong>in</strong>g movement.Ste<strong>in</strong>er's experiments to <strong>in</strong>vestigate the releas<strong>in</strong>g and direct<strong>in</strong>g function of these colourpatterns on the young were <strong>in</strong>terrupted by the war.In Herichthys cyanoguttatus (formerly Neetroplus carp<strong>in</strong>tis) a movement doubtlesslyhomologous to the 'call' of the dwarf cichlid females has assumed the function of a warn<strong>in</strong>gsignal to the young. Herichthys resembles the dwarf cichlids <strong>in</strong> a number of ethological traits.<strong>The</strong> female has a particular brood<strong>in</strong>g colour, be<strong>in</strong>g jet black on the throat and along theunderside of its body, and undertakes most of the brood<strong>in</strong>g of eggs and young, while the maletakes only short spells of these functions and is chiefly concerned with defend<strong>in</strong>g the territory.When the fishes are alarmed


K. <strong>Lorenz</strong> <strong>1950</strong> <strong>The</strong> <strong>comparative</strong> <strong>method</strong> <strong>in</strong> study<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>nate behavior patterns 246 by strong stimuli, as very big fish <strong>in</strong> their tank or the experimenter's hand approach<strong>in</strong>g them,the female beg<strong>in</strong>s a furious sideways twitch<strong>in</strong>g movement of head and body. <strong>The</strong> fish rema<strong>in</strong>sabsolutely stationary all the time, and the young, as if drawn by a strong magnet, convergefrom all sides and lie down on the bottom just under their mother, at the same time 'becom<strong>in</strong>gheavy' through contraction of their swimm<strong>in</strong>g bladder, just as they do whenever one of theparents catches them <strong>in</strong> his mouth. <strong>The</strong> releas<strong>in</strong>g and direct<strong>in</strong>g value of the female'smovement is easy to prove; any black object, e.g. a founta<strong>in</strong> pen, twitched sideways betweenthe f<strong>in</strong>gers, will attract the young Herichthys <strong>in</strong> exactly the same way, and if the object isblacker and twitched more furiously than the mother's body, it will even draw the swarmaway from the mother, notwithstand<strong>in</strong>g the male's furious attacks upon the substituted object!<strong>The</strong> warn<strong>in</strong>g movement of the Herichthys female is, <strong>in</strong> a way, farther differentiated from theorig<strong>in</strong>al swimm<strong>in</strong>g-away-movement than is the head flick<strong>in</strong>g of the female Sannacara andApistogramma, because no <strong>in</strong>termediates between it and the orig<strong>in</strong>al behaviour pattern couldbe observed, while frequently enough occurr<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> the latter species.This k<strong>in</strong>d of '<strong>comparative</strong> philology' of releas<strong>in</strong>g behaviour patterns is not only afasc<strong>in</strong>at<strong>in</strong>g study <strong>in</strong> itself, but it may, once we know more about its object, develop a verypractical value. I would stress the fact that the human expression of emotion is largely built upon exactly the same k<strong>in</strong>d of <strong>in</strong>tention movements as Charles Darw<strong>in</strong> knew long ago. In man,<strong>in</strong> whom <strong>in</strong>nate behaviour patterns are, to a great degree, rudimentary, the study of these<strong>in</strong>nate expressions of emotion may become a most valuable clue to the human '<strong>in</strong>st<strong>in</strong>cts'!(a) <strong>The</strong> accumulation of action-specific energy(4) Approach to physiologyC. O. Whitman and O. He<strong>in</strong>roth were phylogenists and not physiologists. <strong>The</strong>ir chief <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>nate behaviour patterns was of a systematic and taxonomic nature. If they had, as wehave reasons to believe, some shrewd suspicions of the physiological s<strong>in</strong>gularity of the <strong>in</strong>natebehaviour patterns which they so accurately described, they never said so <strong>in</strong> so many wordsand they certa<strong>in</strong>ly did not separate them conceptually from other <strong>in</strong>nate behaviour patternswhich are of a reflex nature, as taxes, <strong>in</strong>nate releas<strong>in</strong>g mechanisms and others. But whilesystematically describ<strong>in</strong>g and arrang<strong>in</strong>g what they called '<strong>in</strong>st<strong>in</strong>cts' and 'arteigeneTriebhandlungen' respectively, they did, maybe quite unconsciously, discrim<strong>in</strong>ate a verydist<strong>in</strong>ct type of <strong>in</strong>nate behaviour pattern from all others. On the grounds of what we know today,it is quite obvious why the endogenous behaviour patterns are much


K. <strong>Lorenz</strong> <strong>1950</strong> <strong>The</strong> <strong>comparative</strong> <strong>method</strong> <strong>in</strong> study<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>nate behavior patterns 247 more useful as taxonomic characters than reflex ones. Maybe it was only this that made thepioneers select endogenous activities for their object. But by select<strong>in</strong>g them and group<strong>in</strong>gthem together as someth<strong>in</strong>g dist<strong>in</strong>ct, they brought to light certa<strong>in</strong> strik<strong>in</strong>g characteristicswhich seemed to be clamour<strong>in</strong>g for a causal, physiological explanation. And this is exactlyhow, <strong>in</strong> a healthy <strong>in</strong>ductive science, nomothesis will automatically grow out of systematics.What particularly seemed to demand an explanation was a very unexpected correlationwhich evidently existed between the spontaneity and the <strong>in</strong>variability of the <strong>in</strong>nate behaviourpatterns <strong>in</strong> question. Accord<strong>in</strong>g to the vitalists' op<strong>in</strong>ion, spontaneous activity mustautomatically be considered as purposive, and must, therefore, show adaptive variability <strong>in</strong>the pursuit of its end or goal. Accord<strong>in</strong>g to the mechanists' op<strong>in</strong>ion, any <strong>in</strong>nate and<strong>in</strong>dividually <strong>in</strong>variable behaviour pattern must be considered to be a cha<strong>in</strong> of unconditionedreflexes and must, therefore, be totally devoid of spontaneity. In defiance of both thesedogmas, just those highly differentiated <strong>in</strong>nate sequences of movements that not only wereabsolutely <strong>in</strong>variable <strong>in</strong>dividually, but even <strong>in</strong> phylogeny were rather conservative and slowlychangeable characters, proved to possess a very dist<strong>in</strong>ct and strik<strong>in</strong>g k<strong>in</strong>d of spontaneity.At the level of superficial observation the <strong>in</strong>nate behaviour patterns <strong>in</strong> questionappeared reflex-like <strong>in</strong> that they were set off by a sort of 'trigger-action' <strong>in</strong> a very specificstimulus situation. But on closer <strong>in</strong>spection it became apparent that these activities are, atbottom, to a very high degree <strong>in</strong>dependent from external stimulation. Captive animals,deprived of the normal object or releas<strong>in</strong>g situation of an <strong>in</strong>nate behaviour pattern, will persist<strong>in</strong> discharg<strong>in</strong>g the same sequences of movements at a very <strong>in</strong>adequate substitute object orsituation. <strong>The</strong> longer the normal stimulation is withheld, the less necessary it becomes, <strong>in</strong>order to set off the reaction, to supply all of the stimuli perta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g to it. <strong>The</strong> longer thereaction does not go off, the f<strong>in</strong>er the trigger that releases it seems to become set. In otherwords, the threshold of the stimulation necessary to release this type of <strong>in</strong>nate reaction, is nota constant, but is undergo<strong>in</strong>g a cont<strong>in</strong>uous process of lower<strong>in</strong>g, go<strong>in</strong>g on throughout the timedur<strong>in</strong>g which the reaction is not released. This gradual lower<strong>in</strong>g of threshold does, <strong>in</strong> a goodmany cases, actually reach the theoretically possible limit of zero, that is, the activity <strong>in</strong>question will f<strong>in</strong>ally go off <strong>in</strong> vacuo, with an effect somewhat suggestive of the explosion of aboiler whose safety valve fails to function. This occurrence has been termed 'Leerlaufreaktion'<strong>in</strong> German, vacuum reaction and explosion reaction. I would move the general acceptance ofArmstrong's term 'energy accumulation activity' for reasons discussed later.


K. <strong>Lorenz</strong> <strong>1950</strong> <strong>The</strong> <strong>comparative</strong> <strong>method</strong> <strong>in</strong> study<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>nate behavior patterns 248 <strong>The</strong> consequences of the 'damm<strong>in</strong>g up' of a certa<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>nate activity are, however, notconf<strong>in</strong>ed to the threshold of the mechanism (whatever that mechanism may be) which releasesthe activity. It is not only a facilitation of the releas<strong>in</strong>g process, not only an <strong>in</strong>crease of passiveexcitability that takes place, but, quite on the contrary, an active and peculiar excitation. Anyone of these particular <strong>in</strong>nate behaviour patterns, however small and unimportant it may seem<strong>in</strong> itself, develops <strong>in</strong>to an active source of excitation which <strong>in</strong>fluences the whole of theorganism whenever it f<strong>in</strong>ds its outlet blocked. In this case, the undischarged activity becomesa motive <strong>in</strong> the literal and orig<strong>in</strong>al sense of the word, derivated from movere, 'to move'. In thesimplest and most primitive case the organism shows undirected, 'random' locomotion,k<strong>in</strong>eses as we term it. In more highly differentiated types these k<strong>in</strong>eses are <strong>in</strong>terlaced withtaxes orient<strong>in</strong>g the organism's locomotion <strong>in</strong> space, or even with conditioned responses and allthe most complicated and least analysed forms of animal and human behaviour, which, forlack of a better term, we are wont to describe as '<strong>in</strong>telligent'. Though the activities thuselicited comprise the whole range of behaviour, from its simplest to its most complex form,they have one decisive character <strong>in</strong> common: they are all purposive <strong>in</strong> the sense which E. C.Tolman has given to this term, that is to say, they all tend to br<strong>in</strong>g about, by variablemovements, an <strong>in</strong>variable end or goal, and they go on until this goal is reached or the animalas a whole is exhausted. <strong>The</strong> <strong>in</strong>variable end or goal is represented by the releas<strong>in</strong>g stimulussituation and, therewith, the discharge of the specific behaviour pattern that had been dammedup. <strong>The</strong> purposive behaviour striv<strong>in</strong>g for this discharge was called appetitive behaviour byWallace Craig, the behaviour pattern f<strong>in</strong>ally discharged was termed consummatory action.I want to emphasize what a great wealth of observational evidence is underly<strong>in</strong>g thefacts condensed <strong>in</strong>to the two preced<strong>in</strong>g paragraphs. It took the life's work of at least threeexcellent observers to gather that evidence: Whitman, He<strong>in</strong>roth and Craig. All these facts arestrongly suggestive of a very def<strong>in</strong>ite assumption, and it is em<strong>in</strong>ently characteristic of thesethree men that every one of them has conscientiously recorded those facts while none of themput this assumption <strong>in</strong>to words. This is all the more significant of the value they set onobservation free of any hypothesis, as they must have found it quite hard to avoid descriptiveterms like damm<strong>in</strong>g up, discharg<strong>in</strong>g, etc., which already imply the assumption that some sortof energy, specific to one def<strong>in</strong>ite activity, is stored up while this activity rema<strong>in</strong>s quiescent,and is consumed <strong>in</strong> its discharge.This hypothesis is, roughly speak<strong>in</strong>g, identical with the assumption that the behaviourpatterns <strong>in</strong> question are caused by processes of endogenous


K. <strong>Lorenz</strong> <strong>1950</strong> <strong>The</strong> <strong>comparative</strong> <strong>method</strong> <strong>in</strong> study<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>nate behavior patterns 250 <strong>in</strong>terdependent relational properties. In <strong>in</strong>nate releas<strong>in</strong>g mechanism we do not yet know as<strong>in</strong>gle case <strong>in</strong> which the <strong>in</strong>nate and immediate reaction is elicited by a relational propertycompris<strong>in</strong>g the relation between more than two elements. <strong>The</strong> <strong>in</strong>nate releas<strong>in</strong>g and direct<strong>in</strong>gmechanisms of the gap<strong>in</strong>g activity of young thrushes (Turdus) are a good example. <strong>The</strong>nestl<strong>in</strong>gs will gape at (a) the nearer of two objects, (b) the higher of two objects and (c) thesmaller of two objects, the optimum relation of the smaller to the bigger be<strong>in</strong>g 30%. All threeof these relational properties are characteristic of the normal object of the reaction, theparent's head. Each of them, considered by itself, is a true, if extremely simple, 'Gestalt',show<strong>in</strong>g all of Ehrenfels' 'Gestalt' criteria, most important of all, transposability. Each of theserelational properties represents a key-stimulus sett<strong>in</strong>g of the same <strong>in</strong>nate releas<strong>in</strong>gmechanism, but each of them does so quite <strong>in</strong>dependently from the other. Unlike theimmeasurable number of relational properties <strong>in</strong>extricably woven <strong>in</strong>to the whole of a 'Gestalt'perception, these s<strong>in</strong>gle relational key stimuli act merely as a sum of non-<strong>in</strong>terdependentelements. This process of summation of key stimuli, belong<strong>in</strong>g to one and the same <strong>in</strong>natereleas<strong>in</strong>g mechanism, has been termed 'Reiz-Summen-Phänomen' by A. Seitz, who was thefirst to study it <strong>in</strong>tensively. N. T<strong>in</strong>bergen translated this <strong>in</strong>to English by 'law of heterogeneoussummation'. What I have said about the <strong>in</strong>nate releas<strong>in</strong>g mechanism suffices for theunderstand<strong>in</strong>g of the subsequent section on dual quantification, especially as the subject willprobably be expounded <strong>in</strong> detail <strong>in</strong> the papers that are to be read on social releasers.A few words must be added about the term. <strong>The</strong> mechanisms <strong>in</strong> question were firstdiscovered <strong>in</strong> their function of sett<strong>in</strong>g off endogenous activities; they can, <strong>in</strong>deed, mostadvantageously be studied <strong>in</strong> this particular function, for reasons expla<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong> the nextsection. But evidently the very same type of perceptual organization as the one that receivesthe key stimuli sett<strong>in</strong>g off endogenous activities also plays a part just as important <strong>in</strong> a greatmany quite different functions. <strong>The</strong> perceptual side of taxes may be organized <strong>in</strong> exactly thesame manner, appetitive behaviour may be activated by evidently identical processes and somay specific <strong>in</strong>hibitions. Especially important is the function of <strong>in</strong>nate releas<strong>in</strong>g mechanisms<strong>in</strong> the hierarchical system of moods, as expla<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong> N. T<strong>in</strong>bergen's paper. In his <strong>in</strong>vestigationof the gap<strong>in</strong>g reactions of young thrushes, T<strong>in</strong>bergen dist<strong>in</strong>guished between releas<strong>in</strong>g anddirect<strong>in</strong>g mechanisms, accord<strong>in</strong>g to whether they activate discharge of endogenous activity ora taxis. I th<strong>in</strong>k that this term<strong>in</strong>ological differentiation is not advisable. Of course, it is not veryelegant to talk of an <strong>in</strong>nate mechanism 'releas<strong>in</strong>g' a taxis, or, still worse, a social <strong>in</strong>hibition.But somehow we ought to express <strong>in</strong> our term<strong>in</strong>ology the fundamentally


K. <strong>Lorenz</strong> <strong>1950</strong> <strong>The</strong> <strong>comparative</strong> <strong>method</strong> <strong>in</strong> study<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>nate behavior patterns 251 important fact that it <strong>in</strong>dubitably is the same <strong>in</strong>nate organization of perception that is filter<strong>in</strong>gand select<strong>in</strong>g the key stimuli activat<strong>in</strong>g these very different responses.(5) <strong>The</strong> <strong>method</strong> of dual quantificationA very considerable percentage of all animal activities consists of the typical successive l<strong>in</strong>ksof appetitive behaviour, atta<strong>in</strong>ment of a desired stimulus situation, to which an <strong>in</strong>natereleas<strong>in</strong>g mechanism responds and sets off the discharge of accumulated endogenous action.In the vast majority of cases where we f<strong>in</strong>d an organism respond<strong>in</strong>g specifically and withoutprevious experience to certa<strong>in</strong> stimulus situations, closer <strong>in</strong>vestigation will reveal one or otherof the <strong>in</strong>numerable variations to this theme, always lead<strong>in</strong>g up <strong>in</strong> one way or the other to thef<strong>in</strong>al discharge of consummatory actions. What we can objectively observe is exclusively thisdischarge. But this discharge is dependent upon two absolutely heterogeneous causal factors:(1) the level atta<strong>in</strong>ed by the accumulated action-specific energy at the moment and (2) theeffectiveness of external stimulation. None of these two factors is directly accessible to ourobservation. Absolutely identical reactions can result, <strong>in</strong> one case, from an extremely lowlevel of endogenous accumulation and strong stimulation, and, <strong>in</strong> the other, from a high levelof accumulated action-specific energy and a very weak external stimulation, or even, <strong>in</strong> thecase of explosion activity, from <strong>in</strong>ternal factors alone, external stimulation not tak<strong>in</strong>g any part<strong>in</strong> the activity at all. This has to be taken <strong>in</strong>to very serious consideration <strong>in</strong> the experimentalstudy of perceptual organization. If, after the elim<strong>in</strong>ation of one or more s<strong>in</strong>gle stimuli, theactivity can still be elicited <strong>in</strong> its normal form, this does not <strong>in</strong> any way justify the conclusionthat these stimuli are <strong>in</strong>effective <strong>in</strong> activat<strong>in</strong>g the releas<strong>in</strong>g mechanism perta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g to theactivity <strong>in</strong> question. If Stone's (1923) rats discharged certa<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>nate behaviour patternsapparently normally, although they were deprived of important sensory organs, this is <strong>in</strong> noway astonish<strong>in</strong>g. A mother rat who, <strong>in</strong> spite of the removal of her olfactory bulbs, cont<strong>in</strong>ues tofoster her young, is <strong>in</strong> no other position than an old virg<strong>in</strong> Scotch terrier bitch who, with asufficient lower<strong>in</strong>g of threshold, proceeds to discharge homologous reactions with a cushionfor a substitute object.What is constant is not the effect actually produced by a certa<strong>in</strong> key stimulus at agiven moment, but the relation between this effect and the organism's momentary <strong>in</strong>ternalstate of accumulation of action-specific energy. <strong>The</strong> constancy of this correlation onlybecomes apparent when both the <strong>in</strong>ternal and the external factors are quantitatively<strong>in</strong>vestigated simultaneously. <strong>The</strong> <strong>method</strong> of do<strong>in</strong>g this truly deserves the name of a correlative


K. <strong>Lorenz</strong> <strong>1950</strong> <strong>The</strong> <strong>comparative</strong> <strong>method</strong> <strong>in</strong> study<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>nate behavior patterns 252 analysis. In a dabbl<strong>in</strong>g and uncerta<strong>in</strong> way I sensed the possibility of this <strong>method</strong> as early as1926, when I was experiment<strong>in</strong>g with my first free-fly<strong>in</strong>g tame jackdaw. <strong>The</strong> observations Ithen made are still very vivid <strong>in</strong> my memory, and though it has taken me years to see their realpurport, they are a good and simple illustration of what I am try<strong>in</strong>g to expla<strong>in</strong>. <strong>The</strong> follow<strong>in</strong>greaction of a hand-raised and fully fledged young jackdaw (Coloeus monedula) is elicited by asmall number of s<strong>in</strong>gle stimuli which, though apparently simple, nevertheless imply thenecessity of assum<strong>in</strong>g an <strong>in</strong>nate perceptual organization respond<strong>in</strong>g to relational properties.<strong>The</strong> experimenter who wants to elicit the reaction which the young birds give to the stimuliemanat<strong>in</strong>g from its parents guid<strong>in</strong>g it, must do at least one of three def<strong>in</strong>ite th<strong>in</strong>gs. He musteither more or less quickly move away from the bird, or upwards from its position, or he mustutter a good imitation of the call-note of the species. (A fourth very effective stimulus,perta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g to the same releas<strong>in</strong>g mechanism, is the sudden unfold<strong>in</strong>g of a pair of black w<strong>in</strong>gs,but this is not so easy for the human experimenter to imitate. Its existence is, however,immaterial for our present concern.) When I walked abroad with that young jackdaw, the birdwould, at first, follow me very will<strong>in</strong>gly. It would fly up <strong>in</strong> pursuit even when I walked awayfrom it quite slowly. (Though it was always possible to get away from the bird, withouthav<strong>in</strong>g it follow<strong>in</strong>g after me, by the <strong>method</strong> of lett<strong>in</strong>g the stimulus 'creep <strong>in</strong>', walk<strong>in</strong>g awaywith extreme slowness.) After a time it became necessary for me to walk away abruptly, overaccentuat<strong>in</strong>gmy movements very much <strong>in</strong> the same way as a parent cichlid does with hisswimm<strong>in</strong>g-away movements. After a few more performances I had to add another stimulus,that is, I had either to call, or to crouch low to the ground beside the sitt<strong>in</strong>g bird and jump up<strong>in</strong> start<strong>in</strong>g. At last, I had to do all of these th<strong>in</strong>gs simultaneously and with the utmost <strong>in</strong>tensity,crouch<strong>in</strong>g close to the jackdaw, jump<strong>in</strong>g up suddenly, runn<strong>in</strong>g away as quickly as I could andyell<strong>in</strong>g jackdaw-calls all the time, <strong>in</strong> order to make the bird take to w<strong>in</strong>g at all. In this simpleexperience two important facts are obtrusively apparent: (a) the activity is exhaustible<strong>in</strong>dependently from the general state of exhaustion of the organism as a whole, (b) the stimuliwhich release it are <strong>in</strong>terchangeable and the general releas<strong>in</strong>g effect of a situation isdependent on the sum of the s<strong>in</strong>gle releas<strong>in</strong>g stimuli conta<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong> it. Furthermore, another factmentioned earlier is aga<strong>in</strong> illustrated: <strong>in</strong>ternal and external motivation may add up to exactlyidentical results if the weakness of one is compensated by strength of the other.Whenever we put stimulation <strong>in</strong> front of an organism and register its answer to thisstimulation, we have to deal with an equation conta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g two unknown factors. <strong>The</strong>quantification of each of these factors is, on


K. <strong>Lorenz</strong> <strong>1950</strong> <strong>The</strong> <strong>comparative</strong> <strong>method</strong> <strong>in</strong> study<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>nate behavior patterns 255 what his cichlids were just go<strong>in</strong>g to do. When demonstrat<strong>in</strong>g some experiment on fight<strong>in</strong>g orcourtship activities of his fishes, he always quite unconsciously dropped <strong>in</strong>to the same mannerof speak<strong>in</strong>g as when demonstrat<strong>in</strong>g a film that he knew by heart, forever anticipat<strong>in</strong>g by a fewseconds <strong>in</strong> his explanations what the fishes were do<strong>in</strong>g, call<strong>in</strong>g the attention of the onlookersto the m<strong>in</strong>utest detail of behaviour which he knew would occur <strong>in</strong> the next moment.<strong>The</strong> practical way of proceed<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> experiments of dual quantification is obvious, afterwhat has already been said. Present<strong>in</strong>g the animal with a given stimulus situation andrecord<strong>in</strong>g the <strong>in</strong>tensity of its reaction presents us, as I have expla<strong>in</strong>ed, with an equationconta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g two unknowns: we do not know how much of the <strong>in</strong>tensity recorded is due to<strong>in</strong>ternal accumulation of action-specific energy and how much is due to external stimulation.<strong>The</strong> obvious th<strong>in</strong>g to do, is to let maximal stimulation imp<strong>in</strong>ge upon the organismimmediately after the first experiment, <strong>in</strong> order to see how much specific energy is 'left'. Thisalready gives us a def<strong>in</strong>ite notion about the relative effectiveness of the stimulation supplied<strong>in</strong> the first experiment. What we are do<strong>in</strong>g is best illustrated <strong>in</strong> a hydro-mechanic modelwhich, <strong>in</strong> spite of its extreme crudeness and simplicity is able to symbolize a surpris<strong>in</strong>gwealth of facts really encountered <strong>in</strong> the reactions of animals. In Fig. 1 the tap T supply<strong>in</strong>g aconstant flow of liquid represents the endogenous production of action-specific energy; theliquid accumulated <strong>in</strong> the reservoir R represents the amount of this energy which is at thedisposal of the organism at a given moment, the elevation atta<strong>in</strong>ed by its upper levelcorresponds, at an <strong>in</strong>verse ratio, to the momentary threshold of the reaction. <strong>The</strong> cone-valve Vrepresents the releas<strong>in</strong>g mechanism, the <strong>in</strong>hibitory function of the higher centres be<strong>in</strong>gsymbolized by the spr<strong>in</strong>g S. <strong>The</strong> scale-pan SP which is connected with the valve-shaft by astr<strong>in</strong>g act<strong>in</strong>g over a pulley represents the perceptual sector of the releas<strong>in</strong>g mechanism, theweight applied corresponds to the imp<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>g stimulation. This arrangement is a good symbolof how the <strong>in</strong>ternal accumulation of action-specific energy, and the external stimulation areboth act<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> the same direction, both tend<strong>in</strong>g to open the valve. It can also easily andobviously represent the occurrence of explosion activity. <strong>The</strong> activity itself is represented bythe spout discharged from the jet J. <strong>The</strong> <strong>in</strong>tensity of the reaction is symbolized by the distanceto which the jet spr<strong>in</strong>gs, <strong>in</strong> other words, by the speed of the outflow. This automaticallycorresponds to the proven fact that the consumption of action-specific energy <strong>in</strong> the time unitis <strong>in</strong> direct proportion to the <strong>in</strong>tensity of the reaction. <strong>The</strong> <strong>in</strong>tensity of the reaction can be readon the scale G. To this apparatus we can easily attach a gadget exactly symboliz<strong>in</strong>g the way <strong>in</strong>which a sequence of different movement patterns


K. <strong>Lorenz</strong> <strong>1950</strong> <strong>The</strong> <strong>comparative</strong> <strong>method</strong> <strong>in</strong> study<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>nate behavior patterns 256 belong<strong>in</strong>g to one scale of action-specific excitation is activated. A row of little funnelsattached below the gradation will meet the case where, with the atta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g of a higher level ofexcitation, the activities correspond<strong>in</strong>g to lower levels are discont<strong>in</strong>ued (as, for <strong>in</strong>stance, <strong>in</strong>the tak<strong>in</strong>g-to-w<strong>in</strong>g ceremony of the greylag goose). It is, however, much more usual that theFig. 1movements activated at the lowest levels of action-specific excitation are cont<strong>in</strong>uedunceas<strong>in</strong>gly all the while those correspond<strong>in</strong>g to higher levels are discharged. We cansymbolize this by fix<strong>in</strong>g below the scale G an oblong trough Tr which has an oblique bottomperforated by a number of holes. <strong>The</strong> outflow from these holes then represents the <strong>in</strong>tensityscale of a sequence of different activities, such as f<strong>in</strong>-spread<strong>in</strong>g, gill-membrane expand<strong>in</strong>g,etc. For reasons subsequently to be expounded, we have arranged the scale tray represent<strong>in</strong>gthe receiv<strong>in</strong>g section of the <strong>in</strong>nate


K. <strong>Lorenz</strong> <strong>1950</strong> <strong>The</strong> <strong>comparative</strong> <strong>method</strong> <strong>in</strong> study<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>nate behavior patterns 257 releas<strong>in</strong>g mechanism <strong>in</strong> such a manner as to let some of the ultimate flow<strong>in</strong>g out of liquidimp<strong>in</strong>ge on it <strong>in</strong> a diffuse way.This contraption is, of course, still a very crude simplification of the real processes itis symboliz<strong>in</strong>g, but experience has taught us that even the crudest simplisms often prove avaluable stimulus to <strong>in</strong>vestigation. As an <strong>in</strong>strument for the quantification of external and<strong>in</strong>ternal stimulation this model has already proved to be of some value. Let me expla<strong>in</strong> its use.Suppose we present an organism with a stimulus of unknown effectiveness. All we canimmediately record is, as already expla<strong>in</strong>ed, the <strong>in</strong>tensity of the reaction. In the terms of ourmodel, we do not know what weight we have applied to the pan. In order to ascerta<strong>in</strong> it, wemust try to get some notion of the pressure push<strong>in</strong>g on the valve from the <strong>in</strong>side. <strong>The</strong> simplestway to do this is to open the valve altogether and record the distance which the spoutdelivered by the jet will now atta<strong>in</strong>. In other words, we shall present our animal with thenormal object of the reaction which may be roughly (though not theoretically) identified withits optimal object, and record the <strong>in</strong>tensity of which the reaction is capable at the moment. Outof both data the relative effect of the first stimulus can be roughly calculated, as well as thepressure act<strong>in</strong>g from with<strong>in</strong>. In other words, we have now got two equations with twounknowns.<strong>The</strong>re can be a very great number of variations to the <strong>in</strong>tr<strong>in</strong>sically identical <strong>method</strong> ofcalculation described above. Which of them is the most favourable largely depends on theobject and on the particular questions which are <strong>in</strong> the experimenter's m<strong>in</strong>d at the moment. If,as it is most advisable at the very start of any <strong>in</strong>vestigation, we are <strong>in</strong>terested <strong>in</strong> tak<strong>in</strong>g stockof all the stimuli that activate the <strong>in</strong>nate releas<strong>in</strong>g mechanism, it is a very good way ofproceed<strong>in</strong>g, to 'pump out' the reservoir of action-specific energy gradually. We beg<strong>in</strong> bypresent<strong>in</strong>g a <strong>comparative</strong>ly simple dummy which is reacted to only with little <strong>in</strong>tensity andonly for a short time. When the reaction to this dummy noticeably beg<strong>in</strong>s to flag, we 'improve'upon the dummy by <strong>in</strong>troduc<strong>in</strong>g additional stimuli. In the terms of our hydromechanicalmodel, we are lower<strong>in</strong>g the <strong>in</strong>ternal pressure to such an extent, that the releas<strong>in</strong>g weight xceases to open the valve, while the weight x plus 1 still will do so. We get the threshold of thereaction exactly between the releas<strong>in</strong>g values of the two successive dummies. We maycont<strong>in</strong>ue with this procedure until we arrive at dummies whose releas<strong>in</strong>g value cannot be<strong>in</strong>creased any more. In many cases, the objects thus atta<strong>in</strong>ed by far surpass the releas<strong>in</strong>g effectof the natural object of the reaction <strong>in</strong> question, a fact which <strong>in</strong> itself is a serious blow to thevitalistic belief <strong>in</strong> the <strong>in</strong>fallibility of '<strong>in</strong>st<strong>in</strong>ct'. And not only has the experimentation of humanscientists succeeded <strong>in</strong> discover<strong>in</strong>g such 'supernormal' objects, but the evolutionary adaptationof certa<strong>in</strong>


K. <strong>Lorenz</strong> <strong>1950</strong> <strong>The</strong> <strong>comparative</strong> <strong>method</strong> <strong>in</strong> study<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>nate behavior patterns 258 social parasites to the releas<strong>in</strong>g mechanisms of their hosts has evidently done the very sameth<strong>in</strong>g. <strong>The</strong> cuckoo, for <strong>in</strong>stance, is obviously present<strong>in</strong>g a superlatively strong stimulation tothe <strong>in</strong>nate mechanisms releas<strong>in</strong>g the feed<strong>in</strong>g activities of many small passer<strong>in</strong>es, far excell<strong>in</strong>gthe one emanat<strong>in</strong>g from young of the respective species. He<strong>in</strong>roth, <strong>in</strong> his drastic way, oncesaid that cuckoo feed<strong>in</strong>g may become a real vice <strong>in</strong>dulged <strong>in</strong> by most of the occupants of anaviary. Though meant as a joke, this utterance conta<strong>in</strong>s a very serious truth, because somehuman vices are evidently noth<strong>in</strong>g more than a cont<strong>in</strong>ued search for supernormal stimulation.What is true for the cuckoo very probably is also true of many social parasites of termites andants. All these organisms are a challenge to the ambitious ethological experimenter.If a releas<strong>in</strong>g mechanism conta<strong>in</strong>s the perceptual correlates to a <strong>comparative</strong>ly largenumber of key stimuli, it is possible to construe an immense number of comb<strong>in</strong>ations andpermutations of these stimuli. By this we obta<strong>in</strong> the further possibility of compar<strong>in</strong>g thestimulat<strong>in</strong>g effect of objects whose releas<strong>in</strong>g value is approximately the same, but is broughtabout by a summation of entirely different constituent key stimuli. By patiently construct<strong>in</strong>g agreat number of dummies of approximately equal releas<strong>in</strong>g value, but different elementarystimuli, A. Seitz (1942) was able to show rather conclusively that the releas<strong>in</strong>g value of thes<strong>in</strong>gle constituent stimulus is absolutely constant <strong>in</strong> all possible comb<strong>in</strong>ations. This is what hetermed 'Reiz-Summen-Phänomen' <strong>in</strong> German, and what T<strong>in</strong>bergen translated <strong>in</strong>to English by'Law of heterogeneous summation'. Wolfgang Schmidt (to be published) <strong>in</strong>vestigated thehuman reaction to the visual stimuli of laugh<strong>in</strong>g with exactly the same <strong>method</strong> and obta<strong>in</strong>edstrictly analogous results. <strong>The</strong> effect of heterogenous summation could be demonstrated evenmore clearly <strong>in</strong> this case, because <strong>in</strong> experiment<strong>in</strong>g with humans it is possible to comparedirectly the releas<strong>in</strong>g values of two dummies, by apply<strong>in</strong>g the choice <strong>method</strong>. Inexperiment<strong>in</strong>g with animals, especially with the lower forms, this <strong>method</strong> has a very seriousdrawback: it frequently occurs that the stimuli, activat<strong>in</strong>g an <strong>in</strong>nate releas<strong>in</strong>g mechanism, arenot identical with those that direct it <strong>in</strong> space, and therefore very mislead<strong>in</strong>g results can beobta<strong>in</strong>ed by lett<strong>in</strong>g an organism 'choose' between two dummies. As T<strong>in</strong>bergen has shownconclusively <strong>in</strong> the greyl<strong>in</strong>g butterfly, Satyrus semele, it is quite possible that one object elicitsthe discharge of endogenous activity, while the second is send<strong>in</strong>g out direct<strong>in</strong>g stimulationguid<strong>in</strong>g the organism's reaction to itself.<strong>The</strong>re are endogenous activities which have a rather quick generation of actionspecificenergy, but, speak<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> the terms of our hydromechanical metaphor, a narrowreservoir <strong>in</strong> which to hold it. <strong>The</strong> gap<strong>in</strong>g activity of


K. <strong>Lorenz</strong> <strong>1950</strong> <strong>The</strong> <strong>comparative</strong> <strong>method</strong> <strong>in</strong> study<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>nate behavior patterns 259 young passer<strong>in</strong>es, for <strong>in</strong>stance, 'fills up' from total exhaustion to explosion activity with<strong>in</strong> halfan hour or an hour and, <strong>in</strong> smaller species, is exhausted after a discharge last<strong>in</strong>g only afraction of a m<strong>in</strong>ute. In rear<strong>in</strong>g such birds by hand, it is, <strong>in</strong> very many species, quiteimpossible to feed all of the nestl<strong>in</strong>gs dur<strong>in</strong>g one gap<strong>in</strong>g 'burst'. If there are six nestl<strong>in</strong>gs, nos.4, 5 and 6 will cease to gape, before one has f<strong>in</strong>ished feed<strong>in</strong>g nos. 1, 2 and 3. This also veryclearly shows how the activity is not motivated by a directive 'food <strong>in</strong>st<strong>in</strong>ct' or 'hunger'. Insuch quickly exhaustible activities the enormous <strong>in</strong>constancy of the level of action-specificenergy is a very serious obstacle to the comparison of releas<strong>in</strong>g values of different stimuli.Even the obvious <strong>method</strong> of present<strong>in</strong>g the stimulus suspected to be 'stronger' immediatelyafter the reaction to the weaker stimulus has ceased, does not give reliable results. It is verypossible that a stimulus which is really quite appreciably stronger than the preced<strong>in</strong>g one, failsto elicitate any reaction when thus presented. Here we have to take <strong>in</strong>to consideration aneffect which has been very aptly termed <strong>in</strong>ertia of reaction by A. Seitz. When we suddenlydeprive an animal of the object of its reaction, the activity never breaks off abruptly but nearlyalways cont<strong>in</strong>ues a considerable time <strong>in</strong> vacuo. Doubtless it is a consequence of the samephenomenon that the 'momentum' ga<strong>in</strong>ed by any activity will carry it on for an appreciabletime after the moment when its releas<strong>in</strong>g threshold, ris<strong>in</strong>g cont<strong>in</strong>ually throughout the durationof the discharge, has reached the value correspond<strong>in</strong>g to the external stimulation imp<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>g atthe moment. This is also the reason why an organism that is left cont<strong>in</strong>ually <strong>in</strong> the presence ofa releas<strong>in</strong>g object does not cont<strong>in</strong>ually react to it with a constant <strong>in</strong>tensity, as otherwise wouldbe expected. <strong>The</strong> <strong>in</strong>ertia of a reaction carries the threshold high above the value correspond<strong>in</strong>gto the ever-present stimulat<strong>in</strong>g object. After the reaction has ceased, the gradual lower<strong>in</strong>g ofthe threshold dur<strong>in</strong>g its period of quiescence acts exactly as a correspond<strong>in</strong>gly slow <strong>in</strong>creaseof stimulation would act upon a constant threshold, that is, it results <strong>in</strong> the well-knownphenomenon of 'creep<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>' of stimulation. Because of this, the new burst of activity does notoccur until the threshold is very appreciably below the value correspond<strong>in</strong>g to that of theconstant stimulation. <strong>The</strong> result of this is the usual form of discharge, <strong>in</strong> rhythmicallyrecurr<strong>in</strong>g 'bursts' of activity. <strong>The</strong> heighten<strong>in</strong>g of threshold, caused by <strong>in</strong>ertia of reaction, maybe so considerable that it can supersede a quite substantial difference between the stimulat<strong>in</strong>geffects of two dummies. If we let the animal react to one comb<strong>in</strong>ation of stimuli until activityceases and then fail to elicit any response by the presentation of another set of stimuli, we arenot yet <strong>in</strong> possession of conclusive proof that the second comb<strong>in</strong>ation is not quiteconsiderably stronger than the first. For obvious reasons this


K. <strong>Lorenz</strong> <strong>1950</strong> <strong>The</strong> <strong>comparative</strong> <strong>method</strong> <strong>in</strong> study<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>nate behavior patterns 260 fact is all the more important, the more quickly the activity <strong>in</strong> question is exhaustible.It is probable that the <strong>in</strong>itial <strong>in</strong>ertia of endogenous activities and their propensity tocont<strong>in</strong>ue longer than corresponds to present stimulation, are two entirely differentphenomena, requir<strong>in</strong>g different physiological explanations. <strong>The</strong> way <strong>in</strong> which quiescentactivities respond to stimulation is more suggestive of <strong>in</strong>itial friction. <strong>The</strong>y 'behave' exactly asif the valve releas<strong>in</strong>g their discharge was a bit sticky. Furthermore, there arises the questionwhether there is not a dist<strong>in</strong>ct relationship between creep<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> of stimulation and what wecall habituation. Contrary to these phenomena of an <strong>in</strong>itial resistance to stimulation, thecont<strong>in</strong>uance of activity after cessation of adequate stimulation is easily expla<strong>in</strong>able on theassumption that the activity is self-stimulat<strong>in</strong>g. A strong argument for this assumption lies <strong>in</strong>the fact that this type of <strong>in</strong>ertia of an activity is evidently <strong>in</strong> exact direct proportion to the<strong>in</strong>tensity the discharge has atta<strong>in</strong>ed. If <strong>in</strong> our hydrostatical model we arrange the scale-panreceiv<strong>in</strong>g the weights represent<strong>in</strong>g stimulation <strong>in</strong> such a way as to let part of the outflow ofthe activity imp<strong>in</strong>ge upon it <strong>in</strong> a somewhat diffuse way (Fig. 1), we are able to reproduce avery exact replica of the avalanche-like way <strong>in</strong> which the endogenous activities tend to growafter be<strong>in</strong>g released. Also we can account for the fact that the valve stays open much longerthan corresponds to the added values of <strong>in</strong>ternal pressure and weights on the scale-pan. A veryconsiderable part of all endogenous activities is <strong>in</strong> this way self-exhaust<strong>in</strong>g and selfstimulat<strong>in</strong>gat the same time, a fact which has been stressed by Julian Huxley long ago.(6) Analysis of taxis and k<strong>in</strong>esis constituents of '<strong>in</strong>st<strong>in</strong>ct'As long as the whole of <strong>in</strong>nate behaviour was considered a cha<strong>in</strong> reflex, there was no reasonto make any particular dist<strong>in</strong>ction between the s<strong>in</strong>gle constituent reflexes which are build<strong>in</strong>g itup. <strong>The</strong> discovery of endogenous generation of action-specific energy has considerablychanged this position. I have already shown <strong>in</strong> what way the recognition of the very peculiarphysiological character of these functions forces us to conceive of endogenous activity and ofthe perceptual organization releas<strong>in</strong>g it as of two very dist<strong>in</strong>ct physiological processes which,though they are strictly <strong>in</strong>terdependent constituents of one mutual function, each demand adifferent <strong>method</strong> of analytical approach. In very much the same manner as the discovery ofendogenous activity has <strong>in</strong>fluenced our conception of the releas<strong>in</strong>g mechanism, it alsonecessitates some corrections of our notions about the mechanisms direct<strong>in</strong>g activity <strong>in</strong> space.Correlative analysis is like the solv<strong>in</strong>g of a crossword puzzle, <strong>in</strong> that the correction of oneword which had been put <strong>in</strong> erroneously makes it necessary to revise our notions


K. <strong>Lorenz</strong> <strong>1950</strong> <strong>The</strong> <strong>comparative</strong> <strong>method</strong> <strong>in</strong> study<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>nate behavior patterns 261 about all the parts <strong>in</strong>terlock<strong>in</strong>g with it. I need not say anyth<strong>in</strong>g here about the <strong>in</strong>terdependenceof endogenously automatic activities and taxes as constituents of <strong>in</strong>nate behaviour; a muchbetter authority on the subject will do so.I would, however, say a few words <strong>in</strong> answer to an evidently widely spreadmisconception about our conceptional dist<strong>in</strong>ction of physiologically <strong>in</strong>dependent constituentfunctions. It is <strong>in</strong> the very nature of analysis that it leads to a progressive narrow<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> offormerly wider and more general conceptions. What formerly was very simply conceived ofas 'an <strong>in</strong>st<strong>in</strong>ct' is shown by the advance of analysis to be a very complex mechanism of verydist<strong>in</strong>ct and very different constituents, such as endogenous automatisms, releas<strong>in</strong>gmechanisms, taxes, k<strong>in</strong>eses and, maybe, quite a number of further as yet unrecognizedparticulate functions. For this we have been reproached by many psychologists, all of themmore or less under the <strong>in</strong>fluence of vitalistic and f<strong>in</strong>alistic preconceptions. We were accusedof pull<strong>in</strong>g to pieces what really was a whole, and it has been said of us what Goethe said of acerta<strong>in</strong> type of analytical science: 'Sie haben die Teile <strong>in</strong> der Hand, fehlt, leider, nur dasgeistige Band.' I would emphatically deny this charge. When we dist<strong>in</strong>guish <strong>in</strong>dependent andparticulate constituent functions of <strong>in</strong>nate behaviour, we are just as much justified <strong>in</strong> do<strong>in</strong>gthis as the physiological anatomist is justified <strong>in</strong> dist<strong>in</strong>guish<strong>in</strong>g between the bones, jo<strong>in</strong>ts,muscles and nerves of, let us say, a human arm or leg. <strong>The</strong> conceptional dist<strong>in</strong>ction ofconstituent parts and of their particular qualities does not <strong>in</strong> any way preclude the fullestcognizance of the general mutual <strong>in</strong>terdependence and <strong>in</strong>teraction of these parts. It does not,<strong>in</strong> any way, prevent us from see<strong>in</strong>g the organism as a whole or system. This will seem a verycommonplace th<strong>in</strong>g to say to physiologists, as, <strong>in</strong>deed, it really is. But it is a deeplyregrettable fact that it seems to be exceed<strong>in</strong>gly necessary to say it aga<strong>in</strong> and aga<strong>in</strong> to somepsychologists.(7) <strong>The</strong> hierarchy of moodsDoubtless a quite considerable percentage of all the activities of animals and men arecompounded of the three successive l<strong>in</strong>ks described <strong>in</strong> the classical diagram given by WallaceCraig and further differentiated by T<strong>in</strong>bergen and myself: (1) accumulation of action-specificenergy giv<strong>in</strong>g rise to appetitive behaviour; (2) appetitive behaviour striv<strong>in</strong>g for and atta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>gthe stimulus situation activat<strong>in</strong>g the <strong>in</strong>nate releas<strong>in</strong>g mechanism; (3) sett<strong>in</strong>g off of thereleas<strong>in</strong>g mechanism and discharge of endogenous activity <strong>in</strong> a consummatory action.Doubtless this tripartite organization of behaviour does occur. Pessimists assert thatyesterday's truth is to-day's error. In biological research work it is certa<strong>in</strong>ly more correct tosay that the


K. <strong>Lorenz</strong> <strong>1950</strong> <strong>The</strong> <strong>comparative</strong> <strong>method</strong> <strong>in</strong> study<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>nate behavior patterns 262 truth of yesterday is, not the error, but the special case of to-day. In biological research, an alltoo-cautiousabsta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g from form<strong>in</strong>g a hypothesis would get us nowhere, and we must havethe courage to formulate prelim<strong>in</strong>ary hypotheses, though we are well aware that theseprelim<strong>in</strong>ary formulations are much too simplistic and correspond, at the best, to a particularlysimple special case. In fact, the discovery of a natural law has been, <strong>in</strong> many <strong>in</strong>stances,identical with the discovery of a special case, <strong>in</strong> which it was actualized <strong>in</strong> a particularlysimple manner. We are therefore neither surprised, nor pa<strong>in</strong>ed, that the orig<strong>in</strong>al, tripartitediagram of the organization of <strong>in</strong>nate behaviour has proved a typical example of this k<strong>in</strong>d ofsimplification. That is to say, it meets a good many cases, but is much too simple for mostcases.It was a most decisive step forward <strong>in</strong> our understand<strong>in</strong>g of <strong>in</strong>nate behaviour whenBaerends (1941) po<strong>in</strong>ted out that appetitive behaviour by no means always leads immediatelyto the discharge of consummatory action. In the vast majority of cases, the appetitivebehaviour with which an activity beg<strong>in</strong>s is of a much more generalized nature. <strong>The</strong> releas<strong>in</strong>gsituation atta<strong>in</strong>ed by this first step of appetite and the <strong>in</strong>nate releas<strong>in</strong>g mechanism activated <strong>in</strong>this situation, do not lead to the discharge of the f<strong>in</strong>al consummatory act, but, as the next step,to another form of appetitive behaviour of a dist<strong>in</strong>ct and more specialized form, striv<strong>in</strong>g foranother, also more specialized, releas<strong>in</strong>g situation. A very general 'mood', <strong>in</strong> the sense of aread<strong>in</strong>ess to certa<strong>in</strong> activities, as, for <strong>in</strong>stance, the 'reproductive mood' of a male stickleback,which comprises the several read<strong>in</strong>esses to a very considerable but f<strong>in</strong>ite number ofconsummatory acts, is, step by step, narrowed down to the discharge of one of these. <strong>The</strong>re is,<strong>in</strong> other words, a hierarchical order of wider and narrower read<strong>in</strong>esses or moods. <strong>The</strong> actionspecificappetite and the discharge of the consummatory action are the lowest rung <strong>in</strong> thisladder of superimposed command<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>stances or 'centres'. Baerends has extensively studiedthe 'Hierarchy of moods' <strong>in</strong> the digger wasp, Ammophila campestris, and T<strong>in</strong>bergen <strong>in</strong> thestickleback. As the latter is go<strong>in</strong>g to read a paper on the subject himself, I need not say morehere.From the <strong>method</strong>ological viewpo<strong>in</strong>t, which is the subject of this paper, it must beemphasized that the conception of a hierarchy of '<strong>in</strong>st<strong>in</strong>cts', at which we have arrived, issometh<strong>in</strong>g entirely different from what W. McDougall and other purposive psychologistsconceive of as cha<strong>in</strong> appetites, first and second order drives and the like. <strong>The</strong>se conceptionshave been arrived at from the opposite direction of approach. We have not gone out fromf<strong>in</strong>alistically consider<strong>in</strong>g what the animal ought to do, <strong>in</strong> order to susta<strong>in</strong> itself and its species,but from what it actually does. We have not


K. <strong>Lorenz</strong> <strong>1950</strong> <strong>The</strong> <strong>comparative</strong> <strong>method</strong> <strong>in</strong> study<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>nate behavior patterns 263 started from the hypostatization of a 'reproductive <strong>in</strong>st<strong>in</strong>ct', deduced from the fact thatsticklebacks reproduce their k<strong>in</strong>d, but from the observation and <strong>in</strong>ventory of the lowest rungof the hierarchical ladder of <strong>in</strong>tegration, with the consummatory actions, and worked our way<strong>in</strong>ductively up that ladder <strong>in</strong>stead of deductively down. <strong>The</strong> conceptions of the successivelevels of <strong>in</strong>tegration are therefore determ<strong>in</strong>ed causally and not ideologically. <strong>The</strong>reforeT<strong>in</strong>bergen's and Baerend's conception of hierarchically superimposed 'centres', thoughdeterm<strong>in</strong>ed exclusively from a functional po<strong>in</strong>t of view, may prove a most valuable h<strong>in</strong>t to theexperiment<strong>in</strong>g physiologist as to the number of localizations for which he has to look.(8) <strong>The</strong> psychological aspect of <strong>comparative</strong> ethology<strong>The</strong>re is an amaz<strong>in</strong>gly widely spread prejudice that a given process of behaviour can onlyhave either a physiological or a psychological explanation. In F. Hempelmann's otherwiseadmirable text-book this fundamental error keeps recurr<strong>in</strong>g every few pages. Of course theresimply is no psychological process which does not have its physiological correlate and whichdoes not demand a physiological explanation as well as a psychological one. <strong>The</strong> seriousconsequence of the erroneous 'either-or' lies there<strong>in</strong> that it implies the superfluity ofphysiological explanations <strong>in</strong> all cases where a psychological explanation can be found. Onthe other hand, there are a lot of processes comprised <strong>in</strong> animal behaviour which do not havea psychological explanation. In other words: every psychological process has its physiologicalside, but not every physiological process is correlated to psychological phenomena.Though <strong>comparative</strong> ethology is resolutely and exclusively concerned with anobjectivistic study of behaviour, as long as it is concerned with animals, we do not, by anymeans, shut our eyes to one important fact: just those particular physiological processes thatare the ma<strong>in</strong> object of our <strong>in</strong>vestigations, undoubtedly belong to the k<strong>in</strong>d which does have acorrelated psychological side to it. This is true of all the three most important elementaryprocesses of <strong>in</strong>nate behaviour, of endogenous-automatic activities as well as of <strong>in</strong>natereleas<strong>in</strong>g mechanisms and of taxes.<strong>The</strong>re cannot be the least doubt that the discharge of accumulated action-specificenergy is accompanied by very <strong>in</strong>tense and very specific subjective phenomena. I fully agreewith W. McDougall <strong>in</strong> his fundamental assertion that man has just as many '<strong>in</strong>st<strong>in</strong>cts' as hehas qualitatively dist<strong>in</strong>guishable emotions. Jan Verwey, an <strong>in</strong>dubitably objectivistic student ofanimal behaviour, is evidently of the same op<strong>in</strong>ion when, <strong>in</strong> his famous paper on the greyheron (1930), he writes: 'Where reflexes and <strong>in</strong>st<strong>in</strong>cts can be dist<strong>in</strong>guished from each other atall, there the reflex is function<strong>in</strong>g mechanically, while <strong>in</strong>st<strong>in</strong>ctive activities are accompaniedby subjective phenomena'


K. <strong>Lorenz</strong> <strong>1950</strong> <strong>The</strong> <strong>comparative</strong> <strong>method</strong> <strong>in</strong> study<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>nate behavior patterns 264 (translated from the German). He<strong>in</strong>roth used to answer to anybody's assertion that animalswere reflex mach<strong>in</strong>es by say<strong>in</strong>g jocularly: 'Quite on the contrary, animals are exceed<strong>in</strong>glyemotional people, possess<strong>in</strong>g very little <strong>in</strong>tellect'. <strong>The</strong> same op<strong>in</strong>ion is evidently underly<strong>in</strong>gHe<strong>in</strong>roth's conception and treatment of 'moods' (Stimmungen). Our firm conviction that thereexists a subjective, emotional side to 'moods', as well as to the discharge of action-specificenergy, does not <strong>in</strong> any way imply our mak<strong>in</strong>g illegitimate assertions about the nature andquality of an animal's subjective experiences. <strong>The</strong>se are, and ever will be, <strong>in</strong>accessible to ourknowledge. I would lay great stress upon the fact that He<strong>in</strong>roth's conceptions of 'moods' canone and all be strictly def<strong>in</strong>ed from a purely objectivistic po<strong>in</strong>t of view, as specific <strong>in</strong>ternalstates of read<strong>in</strong>ess to discharge a certa<strong>in</strong> complex of behaviour patterns. Even He<strong>in</strong>roth'sterms are not derived from human subjective phenomena, but from the objective activityitself, as, for <strong>in</strong>stance, 'Flugstimmung', 'Fortpflanzungs-Stimmung' (fly<strong>in</strong>g mood, reproductivemood) and others. We still hold that a real 'psychology' of animals is on pr<strong>in</strong>ciple impossible.But <strong>in</strong> its application to man, the fact that the discharge of certa<strong>in</strong> endogenous activities iscorrelated to certa<strong>in</strong> dist<strong>in</strong>ct emotional phenomena may become of tremendous importance.<strong>The</strong> psychological aspect of <strong>in</strong>nate releas<strong>in</strong>g mechanisms presents some parallels tothat of endogenous activities. We know for a certa<strong>in</strong>ty that the atta<strong>in</strong>ment of the releas<strong>in</strong>gstimulus situation represents the end or goal to which appetitive behaviour is directed. We cangive an exact and purely objective def<strong>in</strong>ition of this k<strong>in</strong>d of directedness or purpose (p. 248).In all human behaviour, which also objectively fits this def<strong>in</strong>ition, we furthermore know forcerta<strong>in</strong> that the organism, as an experienc<strong>in</strong>g subject, is striv<strong>in</strong>g for certa<strong>in</strong> pleasurablesubjective phenomena accompany<strong>in</strong>g as well the perception of the releas<strong>in</strong>g stimulus situationas the discharge of the accumulated endogenous activity. I do not th<strong>in</strong>k that any observerreally familiar with appetitive behaviour <strong>in</strong> higher animals will ever doubt the fact that theanimal as a subject also experiences <strong>in</strong>tense sensual pleasure as the subjective correlate ofatta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g the releas<strong>in</strong>g stimulus situation. W. Craig gives a conv<strong>in</strong>c<strong>in</strong>g description of thebehaviour of a young male dove on atta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g the specific situation elicit<strong>in</strong>g the nest-call<strong>in</strong>gactivity: When 'a ready-made nest is put <strong>in</strong>to his cage, the <strong>in</strong>experienced dove does notrecognize it as a nest, but sooner or later he tries it, as he has tried all other places for nestcall<strong>in</strong>g,and <strong>in</strong> such trial the nest evidently gives him a strong and satisfy<strong>in</strong>g stimulation (theappetitive stimulus) which no other situation has given him. In the nest his attitude becomesextreme; he abandons himself to an orgy of nest-call<strong>in</strong>g (complete consummatory action),turn<strong>in</strong>g now this way and now that <strong>in</strong> the hollow, palpat<strong>in</strong>g the


K. <strong>Lorenz</strong> <strong>1950</strong> <strong>The</strong> <strong>comparative</strong> <strong>method</strong> <strong>in</strong> study<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>nate behavior patterns 265 straw with his feet, w<strong>in</strong>gs, breast, neck and beak, and riot<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> a wealth of new, luxuriousstimuli' (italics m<strong>in</strong>e). Aga<strong>in</strong>, we cannot say anyth<strong>in</strong>g about the specific quality of the animal'ssubjective experiences. But aga<strong>in</strong> the laws we have found <strong>in</strong> animal behaviour f<strong>in</strong>d anenormously important application to the special phenomena of human psychology. We do notgo far wrong if we suspect the existence of an <strong>in</strong>nate releas<strong>in</strong>g mechanism, wherever we can<strong>in</strong>trospectively ascerta<strong>in</strong> a specific quality of sensual pleasure. To give a good example ofthis, and quite a proper one at that: it is a dist<strong>in</strong>ct and <strong>in</strong>dubitably sensuous pleasure to fondlea nice plump, appetiz<strong>in</strong>g human baby. <strong>The</strong> stimulation emanat<strong>in</strong>g from such a baby evenelicits one of the very few motorically <strong>in</strong>nate behaviour patterns of our species, a quitedist<strong>in</strong>ct movement of tak<strong>in</strong>g the <strong>in</strong>fant on one arm, hold<strong>in</strong>g it with the other. In fondl<strong>in</strong>g thebaby, we behave to its 'sweet' stimulation very much like Craig's pigeon does to the nest. By<strong>in</strong>trospection I can ascerta<strong>in</strong> that the pleasure I feel <strong>in</strong> fondl<strong>in</strong>g and pett<strong>in</strong>g the baby iscerta<strong>in</strong>ly qualitatively different from any other k<strong>in</strong>d of sensual pleasure, especially, whateverpsycho-analysts may assert to the contrary, from that of a sexual nature. Indeed, I can assertthat my pleasurable sensations <strong>in</strong> fondl<strong>in</strong>g a sweet human child are of the same quality asthose I experience <strong>in</strong> fondl<strong>in</strong>g a chew-puppy, or a baby lion. <strong>The</strong>re is not even an appreciabledifference of <strong>in</strong>tensity between these reactions; <strong>in</strong>deed, it is questionable whether a young lionis not, <strong>in</strong> some respects, what we call a supernormal object to my reaction. But I wouldseriously warn any psychoanalyst aga<strong>in</strong>st tell<strong>in</strong>g me that I am react<strong>in</strong>g sexually to that lion! Inthis case, the existence of a true <strong>in</strong>nate releas<strong>in</strong>g mechanism <strong>in</strong> man has been clearly proven,the relational properties which the object must possess have been analysed, and the fact thattheir common effect is obey<strong>in</strong>g the law of heterogeneous summation is quite evident. Also,the objective and subjective reactions activated by the mechanism are clearly dist<strong>in</strong>guishable.A normal man — let alone a woman — will f<strong>in</strong>d it exceed<strong>in</strong>gly difficult to leave to its fateeven a puppy, after he or she has enjoyed fondl<strong>in</strong>g and pett<strong>in</strong>g it. A very dist<strong>in</strong>ct 'mood', aread<strong>in</strong>ess to take care of the object <strong>in</strong> a specific manner, is brought about with thepredictability of an unconditioned response. Quite especially a strong <strong>in</strong>hibition to hurt or killthe 'sweet' baby is activated by the <strong>in</strong>nate releas<strong>in</strong>g mechanism <strong>in</strong> question. When, muchaga<strong>in</strong>st my emotional <strong>in</strong>cl<strong>in</strong>ation, I once forced myself for rational reasons to kill a number ofyoung hooded rats who still were <strong>in</strong> a 'sweet' stage of development, I acquired a very slight,but <strong>in</strong>dubitable neurosis; that is to say, I repeatedly dreamt of the occurrence <strong>in</strong> anemotionally super-accentuated way. This particular <strong>in</strong>nate releas<strong>in</strong>g mechanism of our speciesis, for obvious reasons, an exceptionally favourable object for the <strong>method</strong> of approach justdescribed.


K. <strong>Lorenz</strong> <strong>1950</strong> <strong>The</strong> <strong>comparative</strong> <strong>method</strong> <strong>in</strong> study<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>nate behavior patterns 266 But there is no doubt that <strong>in</strong> many more cases <strong>in</strong>trospection, circumspectly applied, can leadto similarly important discoveries.Perhaps an even greater theoretical <strong>in</strong>terest is due to the psychological aspect of taxes.It can be shown irrefutably that it is not possible to draw a sharp dist<strong>in</strong>ction between taxes and<strong>in</strong>sight either from the objectivistic or from the psychological po<strong>in</strong>t of view. Considered fromthe objectivistic viewpo<strong>in</strong>t, taxes, as constituents of appetitive behaviour, are represented <strong>in</strong>all possible gradations of complexity, rang<strong>in</strong>g from simple and clearly analysable direct<strong>in</strong>greflexes to those complex processes of spontaneous solution of spatial problems that we arewont to call '<strong>in</strong>sight'. <strong>The</strong> former merge gradually and imperceptibly <strong>in</strong>to the latter, withoutgiv<strong>in</strong>g us an opportunity to draw a dist<strong>in</strong>ction between both. Neither is it possible to arrive ata clear conceptual dist<strong>in</strong>ction between taxis and <strong>in</strong>sight from the psychological, <strong>in</strong>trospectiveside of the matter. <strong>The</strong> subjective experience of <strong>in</strong>sight which Karl Bühler so veryexpressively has termed the 'Aha-Erlebnis', always characteristically takes place <strong>in</strong> the exactmoment when disorientedness gives way to orientation. But <strong>in</strong> this also there is no essentialdifference between the simplest and the most complicated processes of 'orientation'. <strong>The</strong>specific experience of the 'Aha' crops up <strong>in</strong> the moment when we atta<strong>in</strong> an 'illum<strong>in</strong>ation'concern<strong>in</strong>g some very complicated problem, but it also does <strong>in</strong> the case of a simple and<strong>in</strong>dubitable tropotaxis. When, for <strong>in</strong>stance, our tropotactic orientation to gravity has beenremoved, let us say by narcosis, or, as I have experienced it twice, <strong>in</strong> a vasomotoric collapse,then the reorientation sets <strong>in</strong> aga<strong>in</strong> with what I should metaphorically call an audible click,and this click is accompanied by a superlatively strong and qualitatively dist<strong>in</strong>ct 'Ahaexperience'!In my op<strong>in</strong>ion, every physiological process which can, <strong>in</strong> the manner just described,be approached simultaneously from the objective and from the subjective side is of aparamount theoretical and practical importance. <strong>The</strong> card<strong>in</strong>al problem of psychology, thequestion of the <strong>in</strong>terdependence of body and m<strong>in</strong>d, cannot be <strong>in</strong>ductively approached <strong>in</strong> anyother way than by study<strong>in</strong>g those not too common cases, <strong>in</strong> which the <strong>in</strong>tr<strong>in</strong>sic unit of one ofthese highest life processes can be studied from the objective, physiological side as well, asfrom the subjective, psychological one. To refra<strong>in</strong> from <strong>in</strong>trospection <strong>in</strong> such cases wouldmean renounc<strong>in</strong>g a superlatively valuable source of knowledge for purely dogmatic reasonswhich would be about the worst th<strong>in</strong>g a natural scientist could do. On the other hand, it ishigh time that social and group psychology began to occupy itself with the physiological sideof behaviour and more especially with the <strong>in</strong>nate processes of which I spoke above. It is hightime that the collective human <strong>in</strong>tellect got some control on the necessary outlets for certa<strong>in</strong>endogenously generated


K. <strong>Lorenz</strong> <strong>1950</strong> <strong>The</strong> <strong>comparative</strong> <strong>method</strong> <strong>in</strong> study<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>nate behavior patterns 267 drives, for <strong>in</strong>stance 'aggression', and some knowledge of human <strong>in</strong>nate releas<strong>in</strong>g mechanisms,especially those activat<strong>in</strong>g aggression. Hitherto it is only demagogues who seem to have acerta<strong>in</strong> work<strong>in</strong>g knowledge of these matters and who, by devis<strong>in</strong>g surpris<strong>in</strong>gly simple'dummies', are able to elicit fight<strong>in</strong>g responses <strong>in</strong> human be<strong>in</strong>gs with about the samepredictability as T<strong>in</strong>bergen does <strong>in</strong> sticklebacks.REFERENCESAllen, Arthur A. (1934). Sex rhythm <strong>in</strong> the ruffed grouse (Bonasa umbellus L.) and other birds. Auk,51, 180-99.Antonius, O. (1937-38). Ueber Herdenbildung und Paarungseigentümlichkeiten der E<strong>in</strong>hufer. Z.Tierpsychol. 1, 259; 2, 115.Armstrong, E. A. (1942). Bird Display. Cambridge University Press.Baerends, G. P. (1941). Fortpflanzungsverhalten und Orientierung der Grabwespe Ammophilacampestris. Tijdschr. Ent. 84, 68-275.Baerends, G. P. (<strong>1950</strong>). An <strong>in</strong>troduction to the ethology of cichlid fishes. Behaviour (<strong>in</strong> the Press).Bierens de Haan, J. A. (1940). Die tierischen Inst<strong>in</strong>kte und ihr Umbau durch Erfahrung. Leiden: Brill.Bühler, Karl (1922). Handbuch der Psychologie, I. Teil. Jena.Craig, W. (1918). Appetites and aversions as constituents of <strong>in</strong>st<strong>in</strong>cts. Biol. Bull. Woods Hole, no. 2,pp. 91-107.Darw<strong>in</strong>, C. (1874). Der Ausdruck der Gemütsbewegungen (German translation, Stuttgart).Dewey, John (1918). Human Nature and Conduct. New York: Henry Holt and Co.Eliot, Howard H. (1929). An Introduction to the Study of Bird Behaviour. Cambridge University Press.He<strong>in</strong>roth, O. (1910). Beiträge zur Biologie, <strong>in</strong>sbesonders Psychologie und Ethologie der Anatiden.Verh. V. Int. Ornithol. Kongr.He<strong>in</strong>roth, O. (1930). Ueber bestimmte Bewegungsweisen von Wirbeltieren. S.B. Ges. naturf. Fr. Berl.pp. 333-42.He<strong>in</strong>roth, O. & M. (1924-8). Die Vögel Mitteleuropas. Berl<strong>in</strong>.Holst, E. v. (1935). Alles oder Nichts, Block, Alternans, Bigem<strong>in</strong>i und verwandte Ersche<strong>in</strong>ungen alsEigenschaften des Rückenmarkes. Pflüg. Arch. ges. Physiol. 236, Hefte 4, 5 and 6.Holst, E. v. (1936). Versuche zur relativen Koord<strong>in</strong>ation. Pflüg. Arch.ges. Physiol. 237, Heft 1.Holst, E. v. (1936). Vom Dualismus der motorischen und der automatisch-rhythmischen Funktion imRückenmark und vom Wesen des automatischen Rhythmus. Pflüg. Arch. ges. Physiol. 237, Heft 3.Huxley, J. S. (1914). <strong>The</strong> courtship habits of the great crested grebe (Podiceps cristatus); with anaddition on the theory of sexual selection. Proc. Zool. Soc. Lond.Jenn<strong>in</strong>gs, H. S. Das Verhalten der niederen Organismen (German translation by Mangold 1910).Leipzig.Koehler, Otto (1933). Die Ganzheitsbetrachtung <strong>in</strong> der modernen Biologie. Verh. KönigsbergerGelehrten Gesellschaft.Köhler, Wolfgang (1933). Die physikalische Gestalten <strong>in</strong> Ruhe und stationärem Zustand.Braunschweig.Koortlant, A. (1938). De uitdrukk<strong>in</strong>gsbeweg<strong>in</strong>gen en geluiden von Phalacrocorax s<strong>in</strong>ensis Shaw &Nodder. Ardea.


K. <strong>Lorenz</strong> <strong>1950</strong> <strong>The</strong> <strong>comparative</strong> <strong>method</strong> <strong>in</strong> study<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>nate behavior patterns 268 McDougall, W. (1933). An Outl<strong>in</strong>e of Psychology, 6th ed. London.Makk<strong>in</strong>k, G. F. (1936). An attempt at an ethogramm of the European avocet (Recurvirostra avocettaL.) with ethological and psychological remarks. Ardea, 25, 1-60.Matthaei, R. (1929). Das Gestaltproblem. München.Morgan, C. Lloyd (1909). Inst<strong>in</strong>kt und Erfahrung (German translation by M. Semon). Leipzig andBerl<strong>in</strong>.Petrunkewitch, A. (1926). <strong>The</strong> value of <strong>in</strong>st<strong>in</strong>ct as a taxonomic character <strong>in</strong> spiders. Biol. Bull. WoodsHole, 50, 427-32.Plath, O. (1938). Bumble Bees and <strong>The</strong>ir Ways. Boston.Portielje, A. F. J. (1938). Dieren zien en leeren kennen. Amsterdam.Seitz, A. (1940). Die Paarbildung bei e<strong>in</strong>igen Zichliden. I. Die Paarbildung bei Astatotilapia strigigenaPeffer. Z. Tierpsychol. 4, Heft 1, pp. 40-84.Seitz, A. (1942). Die Paarbildung bei e<strong>in</strong>igen Zichliden. II. Die Paarbildung bei Hemichromisbimaculatus Gill. Z. Tierpsychol. 5, 74-101.Seitz, A. (<strong>1950</strong>). Vergleichende Verhaltensstudien an Buntbarschen (Cichlidae). Z. Tierpsychol. (<strong>in</strong> thePress).Selous, E. (1905). Observations tend<strong>in</strong>g to throw light on the question of sexual selection <strong>in</strong> birds,<strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g a day-to-day diary on the breed<strong>in</strong>g habits of the ruff (Machetes pugnax). Zoologist, fourthseries, 10, no. 114.Stone, C. P. (1922). <strong>The</strong> congenital sexual behaviour of the male alb<strong>in</strong>o rat. J. Comp. Psychol. 2, 95-153.Stone, C. P. (1923). Further study of sensory functions <strong>in</strong> the activation of sexual behaviour <strong>in</strong> theyoung male alb<strong>in</strong>o rat. J. Comp. Psychol. 3, 469-73.Thorpe, W. H. (1948). <strong>The</strong> modern concept of <strong>in</strong>st<strong>in</strong>ct. Bull. Anim. Behav.T<strong>in</strong>bergen, N. (1940). Die Uebersprungbewegung. Z. Tierpsychol. 4, 1-40.T<strong>in</strong>bergen, N. (1942). An objectivistic study on the <strong>in</strong>nate behaviour of animals. Bib. Biotheoretica, 1,39-98.T<strong>in</strong>bergen, N. & Kuenen, D. J. (1939). Ueber die auslösenden und richtungsgebenden Reizsituationender Sperrbewegungen von jungen Drosseln (Turdus m. merula L. und T. e. ericetorum Turton). Z.Tierpsychol. 3, 37-60.T<strong>in</strong>bergen, N., Meeuse, B. J. D., Boerema, L. K. & Variosseau, W. W. (1942). Die Balz desSamtfalters, Eumenis (Satyrus) semele (L.). Z. Tierpsychol. 5, 182-226.Tolman, E. C. (1932). Purposive Behaviour <strong>in</strong> Animals and Men. (Century Psychol. Series.) New Yorkand London.Uexkull, J. v. (1921). Umwelt und Innenwelt der Tiere. Berl<strong>in</strong>.Verwey, J. (1930). Die Paarungsbiologie des Fischreihers. Zool. Jb., Abt. allgem. Zool., 48.Watson, J. B. (1913). Psychology, as the behaviorist views it. Psychol. Rev. 20, 158.Weiss, P. (1937). Further experimental <strong>in</strong>vestigations on the phenomenon of homologous response <strong>in</strong>transplanted amphibian limbs. J. Comp. Neurol. 66, 181-209, 481-535, 537-48; 67, 269-315.Whitman, C. O. (1899). Animal Behaviour. Biol. Lectures of the Mar<strong>in</strong>e Biological Laboratory, WoodsHole, Mass.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!