03.12.2012 Views

Sartre's second century

Sartre's second century

Sartre's second century

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

<strong>Sartre's</strong> Second Century<br />

Edited by<br />

Benedict O'Donohoe and Roy Elveton<br />

CAMBRIDGE<br />

SCHOLARS<br />

PUBLISHING


<strong>Sartre's</strong> Second Century, Edited by Benedict O'Donohoe and Roy Elveton<br />

This book first published 2009<br />

Cambridge Scholars Publishing<br />

12 Back Chapman Street, Newcastle upon Tyne, NE6 2XX, UK<br />

British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data<br />

A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library<br />

Copyright © 2009 by Benedict O'Donohoe and Roy Elveton and contributors<br />

All rights for this book reserved. No part of this book may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system,<br />

or transmitted, in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or<br />

otherwise, without the prior permission of the copyright owner.<br />

ISBN (10): 1-4438-0161-5, ISBN (13): 978-1-4438-0161-4


To<br />

Heather<br />

and to<br />

Kevin and Solveig


TABLE OF CONTENTS<br />

INTRODUCTION ix<br />

ROY ELVETON AND BENEDICT O'DONOHOE<br />

CHAPTER ONE 1<br />

SARTRE: A BIOGRAPHICAL SKETCH<br />

DAVID DRAKE<br />

CHAPTER Two 17<br />

AUTOBIOGRAPHY, ONTOLOGY AND RESPONSIBILITY<br />

ROY ELVETON<br />

CHAPTER THREE 35<br />

LITERATURE AND PHILOSOPHY IN SARTRE'S EARLY WRITINGS<br />

ALAIN FLAJOLIET<br />

CHAPTER FOUR 46<br />

TEMPORALITY AND THE DEATH OF LUCIENNE IN NAUSEA<br />

CAM CLAYTON<br />

CHAPTER FIVE 56<br />

SARTRE AND NIETZSCHE: BROTHERS IN ARMS<br />

CHRISTINE DAIGLE<br />

CHAPTER SIX 73<br />

1945 - 2005: EXISTENTIALISM AND HUMANISM SIXTY YEARS ON<br />

DEBORAH EVANS<br />

CHAPTER SEVEN 86<br />

SARTRE, INTENTIONALITY AND PRAXIS<br />

ROY ELVETON<br />

CHAPTER EIGHT 104<br />

THE NEW SARTRE: A POSTMODERN PROGENITOR?<br />

NICHOLAS FARRELL FOX


viii Table of Contents<br />

CHAPTER NINE 123<br />

A SURREPTITIOUS ROMANTIC? READING SARTRE WITH VICTOR HUGO<br />

BRADLEY STEPHENS<br />

CHAPTER TEN 142<br />

HIDDEN WORDPLAY IN THE WORKS OF JEAN-PAUL SARTRE<br />

PETER ROYLE<br />

CHAPTER ELEVEN 155<br />

DESTABILIZING IDENTITIES AND DISTINCTIONS:<br />

THE LITERARY-PHILOSOPHICAL EXPERIENCE OF HOPE NOW<br />

IANRHOAD<br />

CHAPTER TWELVE 173<br />

CONTEMPORARY PERSPECTIVES:<br />

SARTRE, CLOONEY, MCCARTHY, MURAKAMI<br />

BENEDICT O'DONOHOE<br />

CHAPTER THIRTEEN 191<br />

SARTRE'S IMPACT ON THE WRITINGS AND MOVIES OF OSHIMA NAGISA<br />

SIMONEMULLER<br />

CHAPTER FOURTEEN 202<br />

SARTRE'S LEGACY IN AN ERA OF OBSCURANTISM<br />

WILLIE THOMPSON<br />

CONTRIBUTORS 215


INTRODUCTION<br />

ROY ELVETON AND BENEDICT O'DONOHOE<br />

It is reasonable to claim—as does Bernard-Henri Levy, for example, in<br />

the title of his landmark study, Le Siecle de Sartre (2000)—that the<br />

twentieth <strong>century</strong> was "<strong>Sartre's</strong> <strong>century</strong>". But what might be <strong>Sartre's</strong><br />

legacy to the twenty-first?<br />

<strong>Sartre's</strong> life encompassed two world wars, together with the Cold War<br />

that dominated the latter half of the twentieth <strong>century</strong>. As a political<br />

activist and prolific political commentator, Sartre was both immersed in,<br />

and an engaged reporter of, the significant events of his <strong>century</strong>. Being and<br />

Nothingness, a philosophical best-seller, confirmed the 1950s as the<br />

"existentialist" age—and the age of anxiety—and sounded themes that<br />

reverberated in much literature, poetry, film and philosophy. Sartre the<br />

phenomenologist extended the relevance of continental European<br />

philosophers such as Edmund Husserl and Martin Heidegger. Sartre the<br />

Marxist philosopher, initially siding with Stalin's Russia, voiced his<br />

support for the proletariat and the victims of colonialism, and effectively<br />

aligned his public stances with important themes of western democracies,<br />

such as the fight against racism and the centrality of individual freedom.<br />

Although philosophical culture in the later twentieth <strong>century</strong> tended to<br />

celebrate the work of Heidegger and Wittgenstein above that of Sartre, a<br />

good deal of <strong>Sartre's</strong> philosophical contributions have become standards<br />

of philosophical culture: "bad faith", "authenticity", "the look", the themes<br />

of consciousness and intentionality, to name only a few.<br />

A <strong>second</strong> dimension of <strong>Sartre's</strong> enduring significance is his reliance<br />

upon the resources of literature—in the forms of drama and the novel,<br />

biography and autobiography—and, together with the requirements of<br />

ontological analysis, the study of history and historical events, and<br />

engaged political commentary. The pathways leading to his exploration of<br />

freedom are as diverse as is the richness of their content. The novel and<br />

the theatre offer vehicles for communicating the metaphysical depths of<br />

human experience that <strong>Sartre's</strong> ontology, historical analysis and dialectical<br />

methodology may supplement, but not replace. Is there an educated<br />

westerner who cannot quote: "Hell is other people"? <strong>Sartre's</strong> work is


X Introduction<br />

unique in embracing such a diversity of genres. The sheer variety of those<br />

methods will surely continue to encourage a unique breadth of readership.<br />

A third reason for the likely vigour of <strong>Sartre's</strong> "<strong>second</strong> <strong>century</strong>" is the<br />

fact that the great creativity of his later years has only recently been made<br />

available. Though unfinished, his Notebooks for an Ethics, for example,<br />

can be read as, at least, a sketch of the study of ethics promised in the<br />

concluding chapter of Being and Nothingness. Likewise, though<br />

unfinished, the Critique of Dialectical Reason appears to signal a<br />

considerable shift in his ontology of human consciousness, the "for-itself'.<br />

Taken together, Notebook and Critique can prompt a serious re-reading of<br />

Being and Nothingness, no doubt <strong>Sartre's</strong> most famous work. Great works<br />

of literature and philosophy invite continued study and reinterpretation, in<br />

the light of repeated close readings and the products of subsequent writers<br />

and thinkers. The last <strong>century</strong> had only just begun the careful study of<br />

these late manuscripts. <strong>Sartre's</strong> "<strong>second</strong> <strong>century</strong>" offers the possibility for<br />

a substantial re-reading of his entire oeuvre.<br />

The centenary of <strong>Sartre's</strong> birth in 2005 was the primary occasion for<br />

many of the essays collected in the present volume. Hosted by the UK or<br />

North American Sartre Societies, contributors participating in <strong>Sartre's</strong><br />

centennial celebrations were asked to address the central themes and<br />

overall development of his life and thought. It was to be expected, then,<br />

that there would be a retrospective dimension to these contributions.<br />

However, it quickly became apparent that attempts to view Sartre in a<br />

synoptic and retrospective light also provided a basis for assessing aspects<br />

of his work that are important here and now, and would probably remain<br />

so for the new <strong>century</strong>.<br />

Thus, the following essays reflect the richness of <strong>Sartre's</strong> vision of the<br />

human condition, the diversity of the means he employed in grappling<br />

with it, and the lengthy trajectory of his enquiry, in a variety of wider<br />

cultural perspectives. Is Sartre a humanist? How persuasively can he be<br />

read as a romantic, a nihilist, an existentialist, a phenomenologist, a postmodernist?<br />

Are there significant cultural traditions that Sartre effectively<br />

advances by whole-heartedly embracing them or by substantially<br />

modifying them, or even by fusing or transcending them? How is it<br />

possible to bring him into fruitful dialogue not only with a living Japanese<br />

novelist, but also with contemporary movie-makers in Tokyo and<br />

Hollywood? What was his life, what was his death? What is his legacy in<br />

an "era of obscurantism"? Given the multi-layered quality of that legacy,<br />

such questions are less a matter of historical labels than of measuring the<br />

plurality of themes, motifs, approaches and genres that make up <strong>Sartre's</strong><br />

unique bequest.


<strong>Sartre's</strong> Second Century XI<br />

It is difficult to imagine that <strong>Sartre's</strong> preoccupation with the question<br />

of human freedom would not remain crucial for the continued influence of<br />

that bequest. His treatment of this central theme is complex and nuanced.<br />

Nausea and The Flies present human freedom as unsettling and disruptive.<br />

Being and Nothingness couples his ontological account of freedom with<br />

distinctive phenomenological descriptions of freedom in its embodiment,<br />

temporality and intersubjectivity. Notebooks for an Ethics relates freedom<br />

to ethical, social and political themes. The unfinished Critique of<br />

Dialectical Reason fuses the freedom of the for-itself with the objective<br />

structures of society and material existence. The biographies of Genet and<br />

Flaubert offer detailed accounts of historically situated freedoms. These<br />

diverse approaches to the fundamental question of individual human<br />

liberty comprise a multi-facetedness of vision, an acuity of perception, and<br />

an elegance of expression that will guarantee its continued relevance for<br />

the generations of the twenty-first <strong>century</strong>.<br />

No less so, we assert, will <strong>Sartre's</strong> salient translations of his theoretical<br />

stances into the practical sphere of political writing and action: for, if the<br />

obverse face of the coin is freedom, its reverse is responsibility. Where<br />

(alas!) is there a playwright of genius capable of stigmatising torture in<br />

Guantanamo Bay, or anywhere else, as Sartre denounced French<br />

brutalities in Algeria with the allegorical Condemned ofAltonal Where is<br />

the committed global intellectual capable of denouncing illegal wars and<br />

their concomitant crimes in Iraq and Afghanistan—"the world's richest<br />

nations bombing the world's poorest"—with the eloquence of Sartre,<br />

chairing the Russell Tribunal on American genocide in Vietnam? Where is<br />

the unsurpassed polemicist capable of writing a fitting sequel to <strong>Sartre's</strong><br />

"Elections, piege a cons" ("Elections, idiot-traps"), critiquing the<br />

grotesque distortions of supposedly democratic systems that gave the<br />

world Tony Blair and George W. Bush? If Sartre could write his<br />

devastating "Preface" to Frantz Fanon's Wretched of the Earth,<br />

spectacularly exposing the murderous colonialising mindset, in 1961,<br />

why—almost fifty years later—can we not find a worthy successor to<br />

decry the hegemonic western institutions that continue to hold poor<br />

African nations in thrall? And if Sartre, sometimes called "the first thirdworldist",<br />

could write (as early as 1970!) a coruscating piece entitled "Le<br />

tiers monde commence en banlieue" ("The Third World starts in the<br />

suburbs"), why, nearly forty years on, is that still true—not only in France,


Xll Introduction<br />

but throughout western Europe and in the US—and who will say so?<br />

"There is somebody missing here: it's Sartre." 1<br />

It is incumbent upon those of us who read and discuss Sartre to keep<br />

asking such questions, to make his voice ceaselessly heard, in absentia:<br />

there is never a good time for not asking difficult questions, and the<br />

irrepressibly contestatory (and incorrigibly self-contestatory) discourse of<br />

the pugnacious little polymath, Sartre, was never more needed than now.<br />

Whilst predominantly American and British forces enter their sixth year of<br />

illegal occupation of countries in the Middle East; whilst the "free market"<br />

of western capitalism—allegedly, irreversibly triumphant over Eastern<br />

Bloc communism only twenty years ago—finds itself (at the time of<br />

writing) apparently in complete meltdown; whilst some partially medieval<br />

regimes—China (murdering up to 8,000 of its own citizens annually for<br />

petty offences), or India (with its handful of super-rich and tens of millions<br />

of super-poor), or Saudi Arabia (still forbidding women to go out alone,<br />

much less vote)—continue to earn the fawning respect of post-<br />

Enlightenment western democracies, where is Sartre? Vivant (alive), as he<br />

himself wrote in his touching tribute to the lately deceased Andre Gide, for<br />

example. 2<br />

In the absence of any comparable colossus, however, the onus is on us<br />

(as the word suggests) to keep asking awkward questions. Not merely to<br />

turn political satire into harmless TV comedy (like Jon Stewart in the US<br />

or Rory Bremner in the UK), nor even to campaign earnestly, if not always<br />

effectually (like the brilliant and admirable journalists, John Pilger in the<br />

UK or Michael Moore in the US), but at least to keep interrogating—like<br />

Voltaire, like Hugo, like Zola—the mindless cliches of a smug bourgeois,<br />

or first-world, elitism. What is a "terrorist"? And what an "extremist"?<br />

And what a "fundamentalist"? And what an "asylum-seeker"? And what<br />

an "immigrant"? And what a "refugee"? Are we really "all middle-class<br />

now"? Who cares, and what would it matter? We need a Sartre to question<br />

the unthinking shibboleths of a self-deceiving western quietism, of a<br />

consumerist capitalism radically "in bad faith", and to do so by way of<br />

every available medium. For want of any obvious successor—Bernard-<br />

Henri L£vy is manifestly more photogenic than Sartre, but markedly less<br />

subversive—Sartre himself must continue to speak to the present age, and<br />

he still has plenty to say that we would do well to heed.<br />

"II y a quelqu'un qui manque ici: c'est Sartre" (Sartre, Les Mots, Paris:<br />

Gallimard, 1964,93).<br />

2 The time of writing being October-November 2008, it is with relief and optimism<br />

that we welcome a shaft of light suddenly penetrating this gathering gloom,<br />

namely the election to the US Presidency of Senator Barack Obama.


<strong>Sartre's</strong> Second Century xm<br />

We venture to hope, therefore, that the present collection—bringing<br />

together essays by promising postgraduates, young academics in their<br />

prime, established and emeritus professors as well as formally retired<br />

scholars from the UK, USA, Canada and continental Europe, and covering<br />

many aspects of <strong>Sartre's</strong> astoundingly multi-dimensional work—will play<br />

some small part in making <strong>Sartre's</strong> indispensable voice heard in this, his<br />

"<strong>second</strong> <strong>century</strong>".


CHAPTER ONE<br />

SARTRE: A BIOGRAPHICAL SKETCH<br />

DAVID DRAKE<br />

Paris, Saturday 19 April 1980. An estimated 50,000 people are lining<br />

the streets of the capital to pay their final respects as the funeral cortege of<br />

the most important French intellectual of the twentieth <strong>century</strong> wends its<br />

way to Montparnasse cemetery. Jean-Paul Sartre eclipsed all his fellowintellectuals<br />

not only in terms of the fame and notoriety he enjoyed, but<br />

also in the sheer volume and variety of his ceuvre. For example, Albert<br />

Camus, like Sartre, was a novelist and a playwright but a lightweight as far<br />

as philosophy was concerned; Maurice Merleau-Ponty was a serious<br />

philosopher but, unlike Sartre had no literary aspirations. Nor did<br />

Raymond Aron, the self-styled spectateur engage (committed spectator)<br />

whom Sartre had known during his student days, make any claims as a<br />

literary figure. He, like Sartre, penned articles on contemporary politics,<br />

but his sober liberal writings were the antithesis of <strong>Sartre's</strong> polemical<br />

prose. How and why did Jean-Paul Charles Aymard Sartre, born in Paris<br />

on 21 June 1905, become one of the most famous Frenchmen of modern<br />

times? This is the question that this mini-biography will attempt to<br />

answer. 1<br />

Following the death of Jean-Paul's father, a mere fifteen months after<br />

<strong>Sartre's</strong> birth, Jean-Paul and his mother were obliged to move in with her<br />

parents, first in the Paris suburb of Meudon and later in a flat near the<br />

Sorbonne University. Jean-Paul was a rather sickly child and, around the<br />

age of three or four, an infantile infection caused him to lose most of the<br />

use of his right eye. "Poulou", as Sartre was known within the family, had<br />

a very isolated early childhood: he only attended school very intermittently<br />

and until the age of ten remained alone with an old man (his maternal<br />

grandfather) and two women (his maternal grandmother and his mother).<br />

He was largely educated at home by his grandfather, a former teacher who<br />

1 This chapter was contributed by the author at the invitation of the editors.


2 Chapter One<br />

had come out of retirement in order to fund his newly-expanded<br />

household. For his part, Sartre would later claim that he had taught himself<br />

to read and write on his own and was soon writing stories inspired by the<br />

tales of derring-do that he loved reading.<br />

In his autobiography Les Mots {Words), Sartre asserts that this passion<br />

for writing that he discovered at an early age provided him with a<br />

justification for his existence. In October 1915, he enrolled at the Lycee<br />

Henri IV, and by the end of the year was deemed to be excellent from<br />

every point of view. In April 1917, <strong>Sartre's</strong> mother remarried, this time to<br />

Joseph Mancy, a factory manager. Sartre was mortified: another had<br />

appropriated his mother, who had been more like a sister to him. A month<br />

later, M. et Mme Mancy—with Sartre in tow—moved to La Rochelle,<br />

where Mancy took up a new post as head of a shipyard and Sartre started<br />

attending the local boys' lycee. He would later describe the next three or<br />

four years as the worst years of his life. He had been snatched away from<br />

new-found school-friends in Paris, including Paul Nizan, who shared his<br />

passion for writing. He disliked and continued to be jealous of his<br />

stepfather. Mancy, for his part, was hostile to <strong>Sartre's</strong> literary aspirations<br />

and attempted to steer him towards science and maths. Furthermore, Sartre<br />

found it difficult to adjust to his new school, where the perception of him<br />

as a precocious Parisian led to him being subjected to much bullying. His<br />

unhappiness led him to abandon his efforts at writing and, in 1920,<br />

although his school results were quite satisfactory, his mother and Mancy<br />

decided to send him back to school in Paris, where he would be away from<br />

"bad influences".<br />

Sartre was now reunited with Nizan and the two became inseparable.<br />

While they pursued their <strong>second</strong>ary school studies, they discussed<br />

literature endlessly and, importantly, they wrote. In 1924, both Nizan and<br />

Sartre passed the competitive entry examination to the prestigious Ecole<br />

Normale Superieure (ENS) that, Sartre later observed, marked the<br />

beginning of his independence and the start of four years of happiness. At<br />

the ENS, although he decided to specialise in philosophy, he read as<br />

widely as he did voluminously, devouring contemporary literature,<br />

philosophy, psychoanalysis, psychology, sociology, in an attempt, as he<br />

expressed it, to become the man who knows most. His reputation as a<br />

diligent worker with a frighteningly powerful intellect co-existed with that<br />

of an anti-authoritarian rebel renowned for his pranks against symbols of<br />

authority and convention. However, while his friends turned towards<br />

political commitment—Raymond Aron towards the socialists of the<br />

Section frangaise de VInternationale ouvriere (French Section of the<br />

Workers' International, or SFIO), and Nizan towards the French Communist


Sartre: A Biographical Sketch 3<br />

Party (PCF)—Sartre displayed no such inclination. He remained a rebel<br />

but, for the moment, a rebel without a cause.<br />

In 1928, to the astonishment of his fellow-students, Sartre failed the<br />

final exam (UAgregatiori) because, he later said, he had tried to be too<br />

original. The following July, while revising for the re-sit, he met Simone<br />

de Beauvoir, known to her friends as le Castor? and who was to become<br />

his life-long companion. Soon after the publication of the exam results—<br />

in which Sartre came first and Beauvoir was placed <strong>second</strong>—Beauvoir<br />

accepted <strong>Sartre's</strong> terms for their relationship. They would not get married,<br />

nor would their relationship be monogamous: theirs would be "a necessary<br />

love", but they would also experience "contingent loves".<br />

After completing his military service, Sartre took up a post as a<br />

philosophy teacher at the lycee in the port of Le Havre, while Beauvoir<br />

was appointed to a girls' school in Marseille, hundreds of miles away.<br />

Since the Agregation was the highest teaching qualification, working in a<br />

lycee was the logical progression from the ENS. And yet Sartre had mixed<br />

feelings about the prospect. On the one hand, it was not too onerous, a<br />

secure job that offered a reasonable salary and long holidays which would<br />

allow plenty of time for writing and travelling. On the other hand, as a<br />

teacher, he would be expected to be an authority figure who enforced rules<br />

and regulations and set an example to his pupils. Furthermore, by now<br />

Sartre had extended the deep antipathy he felt for his stepfather to the class<br />

of which he was a typical representative, namely the bourgeoisie. Sartre<br />

tried to square the circle of his new situation by living in a somewhat rundown<br />

hotel near the station and refusing to conform to the role of teacher<br />

as it was conventionally defined. Not only did he give a talk at the end-ofyear<br />

prize-giving ceremony on the cinema, which was definitely not<br />

considered a "proper" topic, but he also adopted a very relaxed manner<br />

with his pupils in school, and went drinking and playing cards—and even<br />

visited a brothel with them—outside class. It was shortly after his arrival<br />

in Le Havre that he began his work on what he called his "factum on<br />

contingency". The book, which was both literary and philosophical (and<br />

would become La Nausee), was set in Bouville ("Mudtown"), a French<br />

provincial port that drew on both La Rochelle and Le Havre.<br />

Sartre spent the academic year 1933-34 in Berlin while Raymond Aron<br />

replaced him at Le Havre. Aron had talked to Sartre about the German<br />

philosopher Edmund Husserl and phenomenology. Sartre was keen to find<br />

out more about Husserl's notion of intentionality that posited that<br />

2 A punning conceit: "castor" means "beaver" (cf. "Beauvoir") in Latin, and<br />

beavers are notoriously industrious, as was Simone de Beauvoir.


4 Chapter One<br />

consciousness is always conscious of something. In Berlin, <strong>Sartre's</strong> main<br />

intellectual activities involved engaging with Husserl's writings and<br />

working on his novel on contingency. While he found himself in<br />

agreement with much of Husserl, Sartre concluded that the ego was not<br />

located within consciousness, as Husserl contended, but was itself an<br />

object of consciousness. When he was not writing and researching, Sartre<br />

spent much time hanging around in the bars and cabarets of the capital,<br />

apparently little concerned by the political drama unfolding around him,<br />

following Hitler's seizure of power the previous January.<br />

In the autumn of 1934, Sartre returned to Le Havre in time for the new<br />

academic year. Despite the fact that Beauvoir was now teaching in Rouen,<br />

only an hour away, Sartre was soon plunged into depression. He disliked<br />

being a teacher and saw himself as a balding, portly, failed writer. This<br />

sentiment was reinforced when, in 1936, Gallimard rejected his novel on<br />

contingency. In the course of the same year, Sartre and Beauvoir formed<br />

an intense three-way relationship with Olga Kosakiewicz, a former pupil<br />

of Beauvoir's, upon whom Sartre became fixated. Beauvoir later published<br />

a fictionalised account of this episode entitled UInvitee (She Came to<br />

Stay). Sartre supported the Republican cause in the Spanish Civil War,<br />

which had just begun, and welcomed the victory of the Popular Front in<br />

France, although he had abstained from voting. But despite his sympathy<br />

for leftwing or progressive causes, Sartre continued to abstain from<br />

political activity.<br />

By 1937, Beauvoir had secured a teaching job in Paris while Sartre<br />

was now teaching in the well-heeled western suburb of Neuilly. Both were<br />

living (in separate rooms) in a hotel in the 14 th arrondissement of Paris,<br />

and <strong>Sartre's</strong> future as a writer was now looking more promising. In 1936<br />

his book entitled L'Imagination appeared, and the following year saw the<br />

publication of his critique of Husserl, La Transcendance de Vego (The<br />

Transcendence of the Ego), and of a short story, "Le Mur" ("The Wall"),<br />

which appeared in France's most prestigious literary review, La Nouvelle<br />

Revue frangaise (NRF). Other short stories appeared in 1938 and were<br />

subsequently published in a single collection as Le Mur. In 1938,<br />

Gallimard finally published <strong>Sartre's</strong> work on contingency, whose title had<br />

been changed from <strong>Sartre's</strong> Melancholia to Gallimard's La Nausee<br />

(Nausea). Nausea is the record of Antoine Roquentin's attempts to<br />

understand the nature of a deep sense of unease that he periodically<br />

experiences. After considering and discarding various hypotheses,<br />

Roquentin understands, in a blinding insight, that everything in the world,<br />

including himself, is contingent, that is to say exists without any a priori<br />

reason: it just is.


Sartre: A Biographical Sketch 5<br />

By the end of the 1930s, Sartre was beginning to establish himself on<br />

the Paris literary scene. La Nausee had been well received, as had Le Mur,<br />

and he was contributing book reviews on a regular basis to the NRF,<br />

including a highly critical one on Francois Mauriac, which provoked an<br />

outcry. 3 However, in September 1939 <strong>Sartre's</strong> life, like that of millions of<br />

other French people, was thrown into disarray by the declaration of war.<br />

Sartre was one of the five million Frenchmen mobilised in the first ten<br />

days of September. Suddenly, the anti-conformist, anti-authoritarian,<br />

passionately independent budding writer was thrust into the world of rules,<br />

regulations and uniforms. To begin with he had a pretty easy time of it.<br />

Throughout the "Phoney War" (from September 1939 to May 1940) he<br />

was assigned to a meteorological unit operating in the east of France<br />

where his duties were far from onerous, leaving plenty of time for reading,<br />

thinking and writing. He continued with his novel L'Age de raison (The<br />

Age of Reason) that he had begun in the autumn of 1938. He kept<br />

notebooks, published posthumously as Carnets de la drole de guerre (War<br />

Diaries), in which he recorded his thoughts about his daily life and his life<br />

hitherto, as well as his thoughts about ethics and the philosophy of<br />

existence, which were informed by his reading of Kierkegaard, Heidegger<br />

and Hegel. He also wrote daily to his mother as well as to Beauvoir and<br />

other friends. In all, it is estimated that he wrote over a million words<br />

during this period.<br />

This somewhat tranquil and largely uneventful existence was shattered<br />

by the German offensive of May 1940. On 23 May, Paul Nizan was killed<br />

near Dunkirk. Almost a month later, on his thirty-fifth birthday (21 June),<br />

Sartre was captured and incarcerated in a POW camp near Trier where,<br />

despite his uncompromising atheism, he made friends with a number of<br />

priests. He later stated that he had found in the camp a "form of collective<br />

existence" that he had not known since his time at the ENS, and that on the<br />

whole he was happy there. At Christmas 1940, Sartre wrote, directed and<br />

performed in an allegorical "nativity" play, Bariona, which he hoped<br />

would act as an antidote to the pervasive spirit of defeatism and<br />

resignation. In mid-March 1941, he managed to wangle his release from<br />

the camp and made his way back to Paris, where he expressed his intention<br />

to form a resistance group. This he duly did by gathering together a<br />

number of friends, including Simone de Beauvoir, and joining forces with<br />

Maurice Merleau-Ponty's embryonic resistance group, Sous la botte<br />

(Under the Jackboot), to create Socialisme et Liberte (Socialism and<br />

Freedom).<br />

3 Sartre, "M. Francois Mauriac et la libertd".


6<br />

Chapter One<br />

In the summer of 1941, Sartre and Beauvoir cycled to the south of<br />

France where they attempted unsuccessfully to persuade Andre Gide,<br />

Andre Malraux and Daniel Mayer (who had replaced Leon Blum as leader<br />

of the SFIO) to join their resistance group. In the autumn, Sartre took up a<br />

teaching post at the Lycee Condorcet in Paris, and at the same time he and<br />

Merleau-Ponty decided to dissolve Socialisme et Liberte. They had failed<br />

to break out of their isolation and the risks were out of all proportion to the<br />

effectiveness of the group which was, to say the least, very limited.<br />

With the end of Socialisme et Liberte, Sartre returned to writing with a<br />

vengeance. He began he Sursis (The Reprieve), the sequel to L'Age de<br />

raison, and at the same time was writing a dense treatise that fleshed out<br />

many of the philosophical ideas he had developed during the Phoney War.<br />

It was finally published in April 1943 under the title L'hre et le neant<br />

(Being and Nothingness), but made very little impact at the time. Early in<br />

1943, Sartre accepted the invitation from Jean Paulhan, former editor of<br />

the NRF, to join the Comite national des ecrivains (National Writers'<br />

Committee, or CNE), a PCF-sponsored, broad-front writers' resistance<br />

organisation. He had already contributed articles to resistance publications,<br />

including a review of Camus's Vttranger (The Outsider), and now began<br />

writing for the CNE's clandestine publication, Les Lettres frangaises. In<br />

June, <strong>Sartre's</strong> play, Les Mouches (The Flies), based on the Greek myth of<br />

Orestes and Electra, with Olga Kosakiewicz in the role of the latter, began<br />

a short run in Paris. Sartre was convinced that he had fooled the German<br />

censors and had succeeded in presenting a resistance play in occupied<br />

Paris. While it is true that the play argued for a rejection of passivity and<br />

bad faith, and embraced the notion of taking responsibility for one's<br />

actions, it remains debatable whether the audiences understood it as a<br />

resistance play per se. The following year saw the staging of what is<br />

probably <strong>Sartre's</strong> most famous play, Huis clos, known in English as In<br />

Camera, or No Exit, and containing the celebrated, if misunderstood line:<br />

"Hell is other people." The play, in which two women and a man are<br />

condemned to live for eternity within the same enclosed space, is a<br />

dramatisation of sections ofL'&re et le neant that explore the difficulty of<br />

establishing authentic interpersonal relations. In August 1944, Paris was<br />

liberated and an account of these historic days appeared under <strong>Sartre's</strong><br />

name in the newspaper Combat, with which Camus had been closely<br />

associated. Summing up his role during the war long after the event, Sartre<br />

stated that he was a writer who resisted and not a resistant who wrote. 4<br />

Sartre, (Euvres romanesques, lviii.


Sartre: A Biographical Sketch 7<br />

The war, Sartre later remarked, had divided his life in two. His<br />

experiences as a soldier and as a POW had taught him that he was,<br />

whether he liked it or not, a social being, and that he could no longer stand<br />

apart from society and his historical context. It was this desire to engage<br />

with his times that had led him to write Bariona and Les Mouches, and to<br />

try to form a resistance group.<br />

In the wake of the Liberation, <strong>Sartre's</strong> public persona underwent a<br />

dramatic transformation. Whereas before the war he was becoming known<br />

in Parisian literary circles as a writer, in the autumn of 1945 he was frontpage<br />

news, leading him to observe that it was not pleasant to be treated as<br />

a public monument in one's own lifetime. September saw the<br />

simultaneous publication of his novels, L'Age de raison and Le Sursis, and<br />

the following month the first issue of Les Temps modernes, a review<br />

launched by Sartre, Beauvoir and Merleau-Ponty, appeared. <strong>Sartre's</strong><br />

preface, in which he argued that the writer was inevitably implicated in his<br />

times, either by his words or by his silences, provoked uproar in the<br />

literary world. These publications underpinned what Beauvoir called "the<br />

existentialist offensive" of the autumn of 1945.<br />

In post-Liberation Paris, <strong>Sartre's</strong> name was inextricably linked to the<br />

term "existentialism". Such was the popularity of existentialism, and so<br />

widespread was the misunderstanding of what it meant, that in October<br />

Sartre felt obliged to give a public lecture to set the record straight. 5<br />

Briefly put, <strong>Sartre's</strong> atheistic "philosophy of existence" posited that<br />

existence preceded essence, that is to say we exist but we are not "fixed".<br />

We embark on a continual process of becoming through the choices we<br />

make. At the core of this philosophy lies the notion of freedom: we are<br />

free and we alone are responsible for the choices we make. To pretend<br />

otherwise is to fall into "bad faith".<br />

"Freedom" after the dark years of Nazi occupation caught the spirit of<br />

the times, especially when coupled with responsibility. An "existential"<br />

perspective allowed people to take responsibility for what they had (or had<br />

not) done during the Occupation and also gave them a philosophical and<br />

moral basis on which to re-invent themselves. "Existentialism" was also<br />

used to refer to a fashionable "anything goes" life-style particularly<br />

adopted by middle-class youth, whose habitat was the caves (cellars) of St<br />

Germain-des-Pre's. In this context, the popular press carried lurid stories of<br />

<strong>Sartre's</strong> allegedly sordid, bohemian existence that inevitably dwelt on his<br />

"immoral relationship" with Simone de Beauvoir.<br />

5 Later published as UExistentialisme est un humanisme.


8 Chapter One<br />

Sartre had hoped to express his political commitment through working<br />

closely with the PCF, as he had done at the end of the war in the CNE.<br />

However, this was not to be. While he was sympathetic to the Party's aims<br />

and recognised that it had the support of the bulk of the working class with<br />

whom he sympathised, he rejected its espousal of historical and dialectical<br />

materialism and objected to many of its political methods. The Party, for<br />

its part, launched unremitting attacks on <strong>Sartre's</strong> novels, plays and<br />

philosophy, as well as his petit-bourgeois background, and his politics.<br />

The main reason for the ferocity of the attacks, which lasted throughout<br />

the 1940s, was that the PCF was threatened by the popularity of <strong>Sartre's</strong><br />

ideas, especially among young people whom the Party was keen to recruit.<br />

In the <strong>second</strong> half of the 1940s, Sartre continued to provoke scandal<br />

and upset amongst both individuals and groups across the political<br />

spectrum. In November 1946, he presented as a double-bill Morts sans<br />

sepulture (usually translated as Men Without Shadows)? and La Putain<br />

respectueuse (The Respectful Prostitute). 1 The first, set during the<br />

Occupation, provoked a walk-out by Raymond Aron and his wife on the<br />

opening night because of the violence of scenes depicting the torture of<br />

resistants; the <strong>second</strong>, an attack on racism in the USA, led to charges of<br />

anti-Americanism. A year later, Sartre caused uproar again when a radio<br />

programme, presented by the team of Les Temps modernes, compared de<br />

Gaulle with Hitler; and in April 1948 his play, Les Mains sales (Dirty<br />

Hands)? inspired in part by the assassination of Leon Trotsky, brought<br />

forth yet more bile from the PCF who condemned it as an anti-Communist<br />

work. In the same year, the Vatican placed <strong>Sartre's</strong> works on the infamous<br />

Index Librorum Prohibitorum (Index of forbidden books). By now the<br />

Cold War was an undisputed fact of life, and political differences were<br />

taking their toll on <strong>Sartre's</strong> friendships. In 1947, he broke with Aron and a<br />

more recent acquaintance, Arthur Koestler, a former Communist now<br />

turned rabid anti-communist. Relations with Camus, another former<br />

Communist who objected to <strong>Sartre's</strong> refusal to condemn the USSR, were<br />

also somewhat strained.<br />

Sartre had visited the USA immediately after the war and, although<br />

there were aspects of the USA that he liked, he was opposed to American<br />

foreign policy. At the same time, despite a degree of sympathy for the<br />

USSR, he was of the opinion that "the politics of Stalinist communism<br />

6<br />

Although the French literally means "dead persons without tombs", or "unburied<br />

dead".<br />

7<br />

Frequently mistranslated as The Respectable Prostitute.<br />

8<br />

Originally mistranslated in the US as Red Gloves and in the UK as Crime<br />

passionnel.


Sartre: A Biographical Sketch 9<br />

were incompatible with the honest practice of being a professional<br />

writer". 9 Early in 1948, Sartre joined the Rassemblement democratique<br />

revolutionnaire (RDR), a newly formed revolutionary socialist movement<br />

which rejected both Soviet-style communism and American-style<br />

capitalism. The group failed, both in its attempt to form a mass<br />

organisation and to maintain a "democratic, revolutionary socialist"<br />

middle way. After the organisation lurched to the right, Sartre resigned in<br />

October 1949.<br />

In the <strong>second</strong> half of the decade, Sartre expressed an interest in the<br />

Jewish question. In 1946, he had published Reflexions sur la question juive<br />

(Reflections on the Jewish Question), and in February 1948 he appeared as<br />

a witness for a former pupil accused of storing arms for the terrorist group<br />

Stern, who were fighting the British in Palestine. The following month,<br />

Sartre declared his support for the creation of the state of Israel.<br />

At Les Temps modernes it was Merleau-Ponty who was de facto the<br />

political editor. Initially on good terms with the PCF and more<br />

sympathetic to Marxism than was Sartre, Merleau-Ponty was becoming<br />

increasingly disillusioned with the USSR. In January 1950, an article<br />

written by Merleau-Ponty, and signed by him and Sartre, appeared in Les<br />

Temps modernes denouncing the Soviet camps. That summer, the outbreak<br />

of the Korean War was the tipping point for Merleau-Ponty, who viewed<br />

the crossing of the 38 th parallel by Soviet-backed North Korean troops as<br />

incontrovertible evidence that the USSR was as bellicose and expansionist<br />

as the USA. He declared that he would refuse to comment, and urged that<br />

Les Temps modernes do the same. Sartre, for his part, remained sceptical<br />

but unsettled by Merleau-Ponty's stance. <strong>Sartre's</strong> political uncertainty<br />

reflected his inability to resolve the contradiction between the intellectual<br />

and the man of action, a dilemma articulated by Goetz, the hero of <strong>Sartre's</strong><br />

play, Le Diable et le bon Dieu (The Devil and the Good Lord), which<br />

opened in June 1951.<br />

The growing polarisation of the Cold War, <strong>Sartre's</strong> sympathy for the<br />

working class, who continued to support the PCF, and the Party's desire to<br />

broaden its support among the French intelligentsia were creating the<br />

conditions for a rapprochement between Sartre and the Communists. It<br />

came in 1952, when Sartre accepted an offer from leading members of the<br />

Party to join its campaign to free Henri Martin, a sailor imprisoned for five<br />

years for his opposition to French military involvement in Indochina.<br />

Sartre secured an interview with Vincent Auriol, the French president, and<br />

9 "[L]a politique du communisme stalinien est incompatible avec l'exercice<br />

honnete du metier littdraire: [...]" ("Qu'est-ce que la littfrature?", 280, my<br />

translation).


10 Chapter One<br />

undertook to write a book about the affair. In the summer, while he was in<br />

Italy, Sartre learned of a massive anti-Communist crackdown in Paris<br />

following violent demonstrations against Ridgway, an American general,<br />

accused (wrongly) of sanctioning the use of chemical weapons in Korea.<br />

Seething with rage and suspecting that the French ruling elite were<br />

preparing a coup d'etat, Sartre returned to Paris where he wrote furiously<br />

day and night to produce Les Communistes et la paix (The Communists<br />

and Peace), which marked the beginning of a four-year period as a fellowtraveller.<br />

In the summer of 1952, Les Temps modernes published <strong>Sartre's</strong><br />

acerbic response to a letter by Albert Camus, written after Les Temps<br />

modernes had published a scathing review of Camus's book, VHomme<br />

revoke (The Rebel), The two men never spoke again.<br />

Between 1952 and 1956, <strong>Sartre's</strong> literary output was far lower than in<br />

previous years. He wrote two plays. Kean, based on the life of the English<br />

Shakespearean actor, Edmund Kean (and first performed in November<br />

1953), and Nekrassov, a biting satire on the bourgeois popular press (first<br />

performed in June 1955). He also produced a lengthy biographical essay<br />

on the playwright Jean Genet. But most of his energy was being expended<br />

supporting the Communist-backed peace movement and encouraging<br />

contacts between writers from the East and West. In 1952, he attended the<br />

international peace conference in Vienna, an event to which he attached<br />

the same importance as the victory of the Popular Front and the<br />

Liberation. In 1954, he made the first of a number of visits to the USSR,<br />

and in 1955 he and Beauvoir visited China where Sartre met Chairman<br />

Mao Zedong. In November 1956, as a result of the Soviet invasion of<br />

Hungary and the PCF's enthusiastic endorsement of it, Sartre distanced<br />

himself from the French Communists and also resigned from the Franco-<br />

Soviet Friendship Society, of which he had been elected Vice-President in<br />

1954.<br />

For Sartre, the next few years were dominated by his engagement with<br />

the theory and practice of Marxism and his increasingly radical opposition<br />

to French involvement in Algeria. In relation to Marxism, Sartre was<br />

attempting to understand what the Soviet intervention in Hungary revealed<br />

about the USSR, and concluded that it could only escape its state of<br />

ossification by a comprehensive process of de-Stalinisation. Sartre had<br />

earlier expressed his sympathy for Tito's Yugoslavia and now supported<br />

the beginnings of liberalisation in Poland which he visited in January<br />

1957. He was also starting to explore the compatibility between Marxism<br />

and existentialism that resulted in an article "Questions de me*thode"<br />

("Search for a Method") which appeared in Les Temps modernes in<br />

September and October 1957. By now, Sartre, fuelled by amphetamine-


Sartre: A Biographical Sketch 11<br />

based drugs, was frenetically working on a substantial philosophical<br />

treatise in which he attempted to extricate Marxism from the impasse in<br />

which it was locked, to develop it and adapt it to contemporary conditions.<br />

It was published in 1960 as Critique de la raison dialectique (Critique of<br />

Dialectical Reason).<br />

January 1956, the month in which Sartre made his first speech on<br />

events in Algeria, coincided with the appointment of Guy Mollet as Prime<br />

Minister. Mollet soon secured "special powers" and doubled the number<br />

of French soldiers serving in Algeria. As the independence movement<br />

headed by the Front de Liberation Rationale (FLN) gathered momentum,<br />

disturbing accounts of the use of torture by the French army began to<br />

circulate. Sartre initially attacked the oppression, super-exploitation and<br />

violence to which the colonized peoples of Algeria were subjected and<br />

which condemned them to a life of misery and ignorance, but he was soon<br />

denouncing the use of torture by the French army as well.<br />

In May 1958, with France threatened by an army coup, de Gaulle<br />

returned to power, an event that prompted a resurgence of <strong>Sartre's</strong><br />

antipathy to le General, whom he now suspected of intending to establish<br />

a dictatorship. The massive endorsement, by referendum, of de Gaulle and<br />

a new Constitution in September only served to increase <strong>Sartre's</strong> sense of<br />

foreboding and his despair with his fellow-citizens, whom he was soon<br />

lambasting for their indifference over Algeria where the war continued. In<br />

September 1959, he staged a new play, Les Sequestres d*Altona (The<br />

Condemned of Altona), which explored notions of torture, guilt and<br />

national responsibility. Although the play was set in post-Nazi Germany, it<br />

clearly resonated with events in Algeria.<br />

In February and March 1960, Sartre and Beauvoir visited Cuba for a<br />

month where they met Fidel Castro and Che Guevara, and announced their<br />

enthusiastic support for the Cuban revolution. In May, Sartre went to<br />

Yugoslavia where Tito received him. Back in France, he was soon<br />

expressing his support for conscripts who refused to serve in Algeria, and<br />

asserting his solidarity with a clandestine FLN support network headed by<br />

a former colleague at Les Temps modernes, Francis Jeanson. Not only did<br />

Sartre march and continue to protest against French policy in Algeria, but<br />

he was also now explicitly supporting the use of unrestrained violence by<br />

the FLN against Europeans in Algeria, as his notorious preface to Frantz<br />

Fanon's book, Les Damnes de la terre (The Wretched of the Earth), clearly<br />

illustrated. 10 <strong>Sartre's</strong> vigorous opposition to French policy in Algeria had<br />

already led to an anti-Sartre backlash when, in October 1960, pro-French<br />

See Sartre, "PreTace".


12 Chapter One<br />

Algeria demonstrators took to the streets chanting "Fusillez Sartre!"<br />

("Shoot Sartre!"). In July 1961, <strong>Sartre's</strong> Paris flat was bombed by rightwing<br />

ultras, and was bombed again the following January.<br />

After the declaration of Algerian independence in June 1962, Sartre<br />

again turned his attention towards the USSR, which he visited nine times<br />

over the next four years. His official motivation was to resume his role as<br />

a builder of bridges between writers in the East and West (which he had<br />

relinquished in 1956) and to support "progressive oppositionists" among<br />

the Soviet intellectuals. But another reason for his visits was that he had<br />

formed an amorous relationship with his guide and interpreter, Lena<br />

Zonina. In the early 1960s, Sartre returned to an earlier project, namely<br />

revisiting his childhood in order to understand the source of his obsession<br />

with writing and being a writer. The resulting account of his life, up to the<br />

time of his mother's remarriage, was published as Les Mots {Words) in Les<br />

Temps modernes in 1963 and in book form, dedicated to "Madame Z"<br />

(Lena Zonina), a year later. In the same year, Sartre was awarded the<br />

Nobel Prize for Literature, which he declined as he thought this distinction<br />

would turn him into a "literary monument" and limit his freedom to speak<br />

out on political issues.<br />

From the mid-1960s, Sartre demonstrated his opposition to American<br />

involvement in Vietnam. In 1965, he turned down an invitation to speak at<br />

Cornell University and the following July accepted Bertrand Russell's<br />

invitation to join the "tribunal" that Russell was establishing to investigate<br />

American war crimes: in May 1967, Sartre became its executive president.<br />

The Middle East, with its seemingly intractable question of Arab-Israeli<br />

relations, was another area of renewed interest for Sartre at this time. He<br />

had been an unconditional supporter of Israel's right to exist since the end<br />

of World War n, but by the mid-1960s he had become more sensitive to<br />

the plight of the Palestinians. In 1967 he travelled to Egypt with Beauvoir<br />

and their friend (and her lover), Claude Lanzmann, where they were joined<br />

by one of <strong>Sartre's</strong> former mistresses, Arlette El Kai'm, whom he had<br />

legally adopted as his daughter in 1965.<br />

<strong>Sartre's</strong> international reputation as a philosopher, as a writer, and as<br />

the very personification of "the committed intellectual", was at its zenith.<br />

In France, existentialism was no longer fashionable and Sartre was being<br />

eclipsed by a new generation of structuralist and post-structuralist<br />

philosophers that included Michel Foucault and Jacques Derrida. Sartre<br />

was now perceived as something of an elder statesman on the intellectual<br />

stage but—like many elder statesmen—he seemed to have lost much of his<br />

relevance and his ability to inspire.


Sartre: A Biographical Sketch 13<br />

However, when the revolt by students and workers erupted in May<br />

1968, Sartre was quick to reach for his pen and sign petitions to support<br />

the students, to castigate the French system of university education, to<br />

denounce the repressive actions of the riot police, and to urge unity<br />

between workers and students. After the revolt fizzled out in June, Sartre<br />

turned on the PCF, whom he accused of objectively siding with de Gaulle<br />

and of opposing student-worker unity—in short, of betraying the "May<br />

revolution". In the summer, Sartre also broke definitively with the USSR,<br />

following its invasion of Czechoslovakia to crush the "Prague Spring"<br />

programme of reform initiated a few months earlier by Alexander Dubcek.<br />

The "events" of May-June 1968 had revealed the existence of a<br />

vibrant revolutionary potential within French society, but also led Sartre to<br />

reconsider the persona of the committed intellectual that he had epitomised<br />

hitherto. He now concluded that it was not enough for the intellectual<br />

simply to support those in struggle against oppression, the intellectual had<br />

to be an integrated part of the struggle. This was a far cry from his view<br />

of the intellectual that he had outlined in a series of talks in Japan in 1965,<br />

when he presented the intellectual as living in a kind of no man's land<br />

viewed with suspicion by the working class, as a traitor by the ruling class,<br />

and as a would-be fugitive from his own class which he never quite<br />

manages to escape. 11<br />

Sartre soon had the opportunity to put into practice his notion of what<br />

he called the "revolutionary intellectual" or "new intellectual". In April<br />

1970, leaders of the Gauche proletarienne (Proletarian Left), a Maoist<br />

group, asked Sartre to take legal responsibility for the group's newspaper<br />

La Cause du peuple {The People's Cause). Although Sartre had his<br />

political differences with the Maoists, he approved of their spontaneous<br />

approach to revolutionary politics, their refusal to respect "bourgeois"<br />

legality, and their willingness to embark on "symbolically violent actions",<br />

as when they openly stole food from an up-market store and distributed it<br />

among the down-at-heel inhabitants of the suburbs. He admired the<br />

militants who had "de-intellectualised" themselves by abandoning their<br />

studies and going to work in factories. Sartre was on very friendly terms<br />

with the Maoist leadership, especially Benny L£vy (alias, Pierre Victor),<br />

with whom he would discuss politics and philosophy for hours on end.<br />

Also, unlike his experience as a Communist fellow traveller when the<br />

Party discouraged any contact between workers and intellectuals, <strong>Sartre's</strong><br />

involvement with the Maoists led to exchanges with workers, in particular<br />

with Renault car workers and with miners from the Pas de Calais.<br />

11 See Sartre, "Plaidoyer", 426.


14<br />

Chapter One<br />

Despite his age and frail health, Sartre engaged in actions with the<br />

Maoists. He sold La Cause du peuple on the streets at a time when<br />

possession of a single copy could mean a fine or even a prison sentence.<br />

He addressed the workers outside the Renault car plant, and on another<br />

occasion even tried to hold a meeting inside the factory. He took part in an<br />

illegal occupation of the Sacre Coeur basilica to protest at police brutality.<br />

<strong>Sartre's</strong> Maoist period was the most politically radical of his life. It<br />

also coincided with one of his most ambitious literary projects, namely his<br />

multi-volume study of the nineteenth-<strong>century</strong> novelist, Gustave Flaubert.<br />

Sartre had read Flaubert as a child, returning to him again during his time<br />

at the ENS, and again during the Occupation. In the 1950s, he wrote about<br />

1,000 pages of an existentialist analysis of the author of Madame Bovary<br />

before abandoning it. In 1971, the first two volumes of U Idiot de la<br />

famille {The Family Idiot: Gustave Flaubert 1821-1857) were published,<br />

followed by a third in 1972, making a total of over 3,000 pages. Two more<br />

volumes were promised, but in June 1973 disaster struck when Sartre lost<br />

the use of his "good" eye, rendering him almost blind. He realised that he,<br />

who had written for up to ten hours a day for fifty years, would never write<br />

again. Undeterred, he began work with Benny Levy on a political history<br />

of the twentieth <strong>century</strong> for television, but opposition from the political<br />

establishment resulted in the project being aborted. Now Sartre turned to<br />

collaborative writing with Levy, who had been his secretary since 1973<br />

and with whom he had formed a close relationship. Some thought Levy's<br />

challenging engagement with <strong>Sartre's</strong> views had a rejuvenating effect on<br />

him. Others, especially <strong>Sartre's</strong> old friends—and in particular Simone de<br />

Beauvoir—who were marginalised by Levy's forceful presence,<br />

considered L6\y to be an interloper, taking advantage of a frail old man<br />

and forcing Sartre to accept Levy's views as his own. Despite his<br />

infirmity, Sartre travelled to Germany in December 1974 to visit Andreas<br />

Baader, co-founder of the Red Army Fraction, in prison; and in April 1975<br />

he went to Portugal to see what life was like after the overthrow of the<br />

fascist regime. In June 1979 there was a rapprochement of sorts with<br />

Raymond Aron, when both went to the Palais de l'Elysee, trying to secure<br />

assistance for the Vietnamese boat people from the then-President, Valery<br />

Giscard d'Estaing.<br />

Ldvy continued to play a prominent role in <strong>Sartre's</strong> life and, in 1979,<br />

organised a meeting of Arab and Israeli intellectuals in Paris, but it was<br />

not a success, and Sartre played a minor part. In March 1980, Le Nouvel<br />

Observateur's intention to publish three dialogues between Levy and<br />

Sartre confirmed the worst fears of <strong>Sartre's</strong> entourage, for it appeared to<br />

them that Levy had pressured Sartre into denying some of the


Sartre: A Biographical Sketch 15<br />

philosophical notions he had held most dear. Was it a case of an old man<br />

taking the line of least resistance, or of a philosopher doing once again<br />

what he had always done, namely to think against himself? In any event,<br />

Sartre rejected attempts by Beauvoir and others to prevent publication, and<br />

personally telephoned the editor of the weekly magazine to insist that the<br />

articles appear. On 20 March, while the dispute was still raging, Sartre was<br />

rushed to hospital and died three weeks later, on 15 April.<br />

Despite a large exhibition at the Bibliotheque Nationale in 2005 to<br />

mark the centenary of <strong>Sartre's</strong> birth, the celebration of the man and his<br />

works in his native country was more muted than in the rest of the world,<br />

where Sartre is still (as it were) alive and well. <strong>Sartre's</strong> reputation rests on<br />

the staggering breadth of his oeuvre for—as a leading North American<br />

Sartre scholar, Ronald Aronson, has observed—it is possible to study<br />

Sartre in relation to topics as diverse as Marxism, colonialism, the<br />

developing world, violence, racism, art, music, fiction, the theatre and the<br />

cinema. 12<br />

Whereas Sartre remains one of the most studied of all French thinkers<br />

or literary figures, his relevance and significance are not restricted to the<br />

relatively closed world of academia. <strong>Sartre's</strong> philosophy of freedom is a<br />

practical philosophy, as he himself demonstrated. His willingness to<br />

question himself, to think against himself, to explore the tensions between<br />

the man he had been, the man he was, and the man he wanted to become,<br />

underpins the dynamic nature of his life. His philosophy, both at a<br />

personal level and at a broader level, is an optimistic and generous one.<br />

From 1945 until his death, he marched (until he was too frail), wrote,<br />

proclaimed and agitated to oppose all forms of oppression and<br />

exploitation, in particular racism, colonialism and imperialism. He was<br />

convinced that the world could be a different and better place, although,<br />

true to his anti-determinist philosophy, he never assumed that it<br />

necessarily would be.<br />

Works Cited<br />

Aronson, Ronald. "Meanwhile: Jean-Paul Sartre at 100: Still Troubling Us<br />

Today", International Herald Tribune, 22 June 2005.<br />

Sartre, Jean-Paul. "M. Francois Mauriac et la liberte", La Nouvelle Revue<br />

frangaise, no. 305, February 1939, 212-32; and in Situations, /. Paris:<br />

Gallimard, 1947.<br />

See Aronson, "Meanwhile".


16 Chapter One<br />

—. (Euvres romanesques, (eds Michel Contat and Michel Rybalka). Paris:<br />

Gallimard, 1981.<br />

—. UExistentialisme est un humanisme. Paris: Nagel, 1946.<br />

—. "Qu'est-ce que la literature?", in Situations, II. Paris: Gallimard, 1948.<br />

—. "Preface", in Frantz Fanon, Les Damnes de la terre. Paris: Maspero,<br />

1961.<br />

—. "Plaidoyer pour les intellectuels", in Situations, VIII. Paris: Gallimard,<br />

1972.


CHAPTER TWO<br />

AUTOBIOGRAPHY, ONTOLOGY<br />

AND RESPONSIBILITY<br />

ROY ELVETON<br />

The following reflections explore the relationship between ontological<br />

structures and structures of individual responsibility. 1 By the former, I<br />

mean the kind of self-conscious, reflective concern with essential<br />

structures of human experience exemplified in the phenomenological<br />

philosophies of Heidegger and Sartre. By the latter, I mean the situated<br />

historical reality of the philosopher and the thinker's response to and<br />

acknowledgment of this situation.<br />

The question of an individual thinker's responsibility for political<br />

actions has recently focused intensively on Heidegger's relations with the<br />

Nazi party. For example, it is a question central to the relationship between<br />

Paul Celan, perhaps the most important European poet of the post-war<br />

years, and Martin Heidegger. Recall the celebrated conversation between<br />

Celan and Heidegger that occurred in Heidegger's Black Forest cabin on<br />

25 July 1967, the aftermath of which has added to the continuing dismay<br />

felt by many regarding Heidegger's relationship to the Third Reich. Celan,<br />

fully expecting a public acknowledgment by Heidegger of his affiliation<br />

with the Nazis during the 1930s, was so greatly disturbed by the absence of<br />

any such confession that the two men remained thereafter estranged until<br />

Celan's death by suicide in 1970.<br />

While <strong>Sartre's</strong> stances on many social and political issues have also<br />

been questioned and debated—notably his support of Stalinism—his own<br />

candour has tended to defuse the question of responsibility in his case, just<br />

as Heidegger's lack of candour has fueled the ongoing discussion of his<br />

political actions and commitments.<br />

1 A draft of this chapter was presented on 21 October 2006 to the 13 th Annual<br />

Conference of the UK Sartre Society at the Institut Fran^ais, London.


18 Chapter Two<br />

It will be useful to distinguish between the strictly autobiographical<br />

question of individual responsibility and what I will term the "ontoautobiographical"<br />

question of individual responsibility. The former<br />

represents questions regarding how individuals may or may not have<br />

decided to act and what responsibilities they may or may not have chosen<br />

to accept. Whether or not Heidegger failed to publicly acknowledge his<br />

Nazi past is an autobiographical question. However, whether Heidegger's<br />

own thought succeeds in accommodating the question of the thinker's<br />

individual responsibility is a further question, a question I will call an<br />

"onto-autobiographical" one. Another way of phrasing this distinction is<br />

by calling attention to what might be termed an individual's "categorical"<br />

choices, choices in which ontological structures are directly at stake, such<br />

as choices for freedom, or choices for communal, historical aims. An<br />

underlying assumption here is that the relationship between ontological<br />

reflection and individual action can be an important measure of a<br />

philosophical position's coherence. Concerns of this kind clearly play an<br />

important role, for example, in Kierkegaard's critical stance toward<br />

Hegel's speculative idealism. Since both Sartre and Heidegger accept the<br />

historically embedded nature of their ontological reflections, it is<br />

reasonable to ask how thought and action might be correlated in their<br />

philosophical reflections and how these accounts might in turn be<br />

correlated with more autobiographical expressions.<br />

Sartre<br />

The case of Sartre is particularly significant in this connection. <strong>Sartre's</strong><br />

account of individual freedom shows a marked evolution from Being and<br />

Nothingness to the later Critique of Dialectical Reason and The Family<br />

Idiot, an evolution that reveals the increasing importance for Sartre of a<br />

viable account of "embedded" freedom. The later Sartre also pays explicit<br />

attention to the historical embeddedness of his own philosophical analyses.<br />

The result is <strong>Sartre's</strong> recognition of both the self-referential nature of his<br />

ontology and a self-critical development of a positive account of<br />

individual responsibility. Taken together, these elements provide a useful<br />

framework within which onto-autobiographical questions may be<br />

addressed.<br />

Being and Nothingness offers a rather uneasy alliance between the<br />

individual and the individual's situation. In the important Part Four of<br />

Being and Nothingness, Sartre addresses two dimensions of human<br />

freedom: its situated nature and the for-itself s responsibility. Chapter 2 of<br />

this section, "Freedom and Facticity: The Situation", expresses <strong>Sartre's</strong>


Autobiography, Ontology and Responsibility 19<br />

central claim: "There can be a free for-itself only as engaged in a resisting<br />

world. Outside of this engagement, the notions of freedom, of<br />

determinism, of necessity lose all meaning." 2 The world within which the<br />

for-itself exercises its freedom is a world of affordances and resistances,<br />

both of which are measured in terms of the projects the for-itself has<br />

adopted. The rock in front of me is an obstacle if I wish to reach the other<br />

side, but it is an affordance if I intend to climb it. However, my projects do<br />

not entirely create the situation that provides the opportunity for my<br />

choice. The resisting world contains an irreducible "particular datum" 3<br />

which freedom does not choose, for the freedom of the for-itself is not a<br />

freedom to choose its existence, but is constrained to exercise its free<br />

projects within the context of a given situation:<br />

But what is this relationship to the given? Are we to understand by this that<br />

the given (the in-itself) conditions freedom? Let us look more closely. The<br />

given does not cause freedom (since it can only produce the given). Nor is<br />

it the reason of freedom (since all "reason" comes into the world through<br />

freedom). Neither is it the necessary condition of freedom since we are on<br />

the level of pure contingency. Neither is it an indispensable matter upon<br />

which freedom must exercise itself, for this would be to suppose that<br />

freedom exists ready-made as an Aristotelian form or as a Stoic Pneuma<br />

and that it looks for a matter to work in. The given in no way enters into<br />

the constitution of freedom since freedom is interiorized as the internal<br />

negation of the given. It is simply the pure contingency which freedom<br />

exerts by denying the given while making itself a choice. 4<br />

Sartre identifies the implications of this view of situated freedom for<br />

human temporality. He notes that "the past (is) the essence which the foritself<br />

was." 5 He adds that as a "nihilating withdrawal", the for-itself is a<br />

nihilation of the given present and the past "essence". More significantly,<br />

both nihilations form a "single reality". 6 However, the precise nature of<br />

this "single reality" is unclear. Perhaps these nihilations are "single"<br />

because they are nihilations resulting from one and the same spontaneous<br />

act of the for-itself. In this case, their unity appears to be simply an<br />

external one, consisting solely in the unconditioned spontaneity of the for-<br />

2<br />

Sartre, Being and Nothingness, 483.<br />

3<br />

Ibid., 487.<br />

4<br />

Ibid.,486f.<br />

5<br />

Ibid., 487.<br />

6<br />

Ibid. We shall see below that the Sartre of the War Diaries offers a dissenting<br />

analysis of this "single reality" of the negation of the present and the negation of<br />

the past.


20 Chapter Two<br />

itself. On the other hand, perhaps these nihilations are identical. However,<br />

there appears to be a distinctive connection between the past and present<br />

that makes my current situation an inheritance from my past actions and<br />

that reunites me in the present with my past. Is my past in fact identically<br />

"external" to me in the same way as the "particular datum" of the present<br />

given elements of my worldly situation? Such a "bridging", as it were,<br />

between the past and the present would appear to constitute at least a<br />

necessary condition for a relationship of responsibility with respect to the<br />

for-itself s past actions. But since, as Sartre notes, nothing, including the<br />

past as a critical dimension of my situation, enters into the constitution of<br />

my freedom, there is a sense in which the situated for-itself indeed remains<br />

a "pure contingency" whose ontological core remains untouched by both<br />

its history and its present situation. Nevertheless, the Sartrean formula: "I<br />

am my past in the mode of not being it", appears to be an<br />

oversimplification. To recognise my past action as something for which I<br />

am now responsible would appear to entail a more substantial connection<br />

than the Sartrean formula allows. Surely <strong>Sartre's</strong> claim regarding the<br />

ontological status of the past is dictated by the need for the for-itself to<br />

remain untouched by a single trace of the in-itself. However, the<br />

possibility that a connection between my past and my present is at work<br />

above and beyond my simply spontaneous and simultaneous nihilation of<br />

them both (in the sense of their apparent "singleness" discussed above)<br />

entails just such an ontological condition (at least within the confines of<br />

the ontology outlined in Being and Nothingness). We shall see below that<br />

an additional text of <strong>Sartre's</strong> outlines just such a condition.<br />

We need not turn to <strong>Sartre's</strong> later works to discover sketches of such a<br />

connection. Even as early as the War Diaries we find an important series<br />

of reflections on the nature of situated, historical, temporal consciousness.<br />

In several passages <strong>Sartre's</strong> comments strongly suggest that the<br />

corresponding discussions in Being and Nothingness sketch an inadequate<br />

account of the situated for-itself.<br />

Sartre begins by noting that, while accepting Heidegger's account of<br />

Dasein's projective nature in Being and Time, Heidegger's account is open<br />

to a severe criticism. To claim, as Heidegger does, that Dasein "is" its<br />

possibilities, is simply to create a new and useless form of immanence. 7<br />

Rather than considering my possibilities as being contained within me as<br />

(to employ <strong>Sartre's</strong> phrase) an Aristotelian form, "my possibilities" must<br />

be thought of as belonging to my power to "escape myself." In addition to<br />

their transcendent status, Sartre also stresses that my possibilities are<br />

7 Sartre, War Diaries, 39.


Autobiography, Ontology and Responsibility 21<br />

marked by temporality in a way that is only glossed over by this new form<br />

of immanence:<br />

All immanence is a dream state. Even the Heideggerian immanence, since<br />

being rediscovers itself as possibilities beyond the world. And I am well<br />

aware that there is time between the projecting being and the projected<br />

possibilities. But as this time is read backwards, it loses its separating<br />

virtue and ceases to be anything but the substance of Dasein's unity with<br />

itself. 8<br />

It may be noted in defence of Heidegger that Being and Time is<br />

concerned primarily with Dasein's transcendental structures. As a result,<br />

Sartre may be confusing structure with process. To say that Dasein's<br />

possibilities are structurally contained in Dasein may not be to deny the<br />

reality of the "there is time" but only serves to maintain the unity of lived<br />

temporality at the level of ontological analysis. However, <strong>Sartre's</strong> own<br />

analysis of "situation" in Being and Nothingness is subject to a criticism<br />

parallel to that which he directs against Heidegger. To say that the<br />

nihilation that results in the fact that "I am my past in the mode of not<br />

being it" is singly conjoined with my negation of the present situation as it<br />

is given to me, is to suggest incorrectly that my relation to my past is a<br />

relationship of the same kind to something that is transcendent to me in the<br />

sense in which the present given is transcendent to me. Yet my very<br />

temporality ("there is time") would imply that my past is related to me in a<br />

manner that is distinct from my relationship to my present. The<br />

"immanence" of the nihilating nature of the for-itself abstracts from this<br />

important difference.<br />

<strong>Sartre's</strong> comments on Heidegger are followed later in the War Diaries<br />

by an important discussion of the relationship between temporality and the<br />

for-itself in which alternatives to the ontology of Being and Time are<br />

proposed. Time, Sartre notes, is of a different nature than the in-itself. It is<br />

also of a different nature than the for-itself. The passage in which these<br />

claims occur deserves extended citation:<br />

In La Nausee, I assert that the past is not; and earlier I tried to reduce<br />

memory to a true fiction. In my lectures I used to exaggerate the share of<br />

reconstruction in remembrance, because reconstruction operates in the<br />

present. This incomprehension perfectly matched my lack of solidarity<br />

with myself, which led me to judge my dead past insolently from the<br />

vantage-point of my present. The difficulties of a theory of memory,<br />

combined with the influence of Husserl, decided me to endow the past with<br />

Ibid.


22 Chapter Two<br />

a certain kind of existence [...]. I tried in La Psyche to derive time<br />

dialectically from freedom. For me, it was a bold gesture. But all that<br />

wasn't yet ripe. And, behold, I now glimpse a theory of time! I feel<br />

intimidated before expounding it, I feel like a kid.<br />

Let me first observe that time is not originally of the same nature as the<br />

in-itself [...]. If I consider it from one point of view, it is; and if I consider<br />

it from another point of view, it is not: the future is not yet, and the past is<br />

no longer, the present vanishes into an infinitesimal point, time is now but<br />

a dream.<br />

I see clearly, too, that time is not—as contemporary theories would<br />

have us believe—of the same nature as the for-itself. I'm not in time, that's<br />

for sure. But I'm not my own time either, in the way that Heidegger means.<br />

Otherwise there would be a temporal translucidity coinciding with the<br />

translucidity of consciousness; consciousness would be time, inasmuch as<br />

it would be consciousness of time. 9<br />

One important consequence of this analysis is that, while the<br />

temporality of the for-itself is defined in Being and Nothingness as not<br />

being its past and not being its future, Sartre here understands that the foritself<br />

is a being which, if not in time, is perhaps of time. 10 It is possible that<br />

Sartre understands being "in time" in the same manner in which Being and<br />

Nothingness understands "being in a situation". For Sartre, to be in a<br />

situation is to confront possibilities. 11 Since my situation is defined by my<br />

projects and since my projects are transparent to me by virtue of my freely<br />

projecting them, my situation is defined by the translucidity possessed by<br />

the spontaneous upsurge and transparency of my freedom. Consequently,<br />

being in time would carry the connotation of the self-transparency of<br />

freedom. In contrast, to say that I am of time is to say that there is a<br />

"thickness" or "substantiality" to time that cannot be foreshortened or<br />

alleviated by the consciousness I have of it. <strong>Sartre's</strong> following gloss<br />

suggests the reasonableness of such an interpretation:<br />

I escape in time from my own motives; in time from my essence, since it is<br />

what has been [...]. Yet it obviously is not the same thing, since I am my<br />

own nothingness while I am not my own time. If you prefer, there is no<br />

difference between nihilation and temporalisation, except that the for-itself<br />

9 Ibid., 209.<br />

10 The expression "of time" is not <strong>Sartre's</strong>, but is employed here in order to<br />

reference aspects of the theory of time Sartre may have "glimpsed."<br />

11 <strong>Sartre's</strong> expression for this concept in the War Diaries is "exigencies" {War<br />

Diaries, 39).


Autobiography, Ontology and Responsibility 23<br />

nihilates itself but is temporalised. And yet, though existentially distinct,<br />

nihilation and temporalisation are given in one and the same movement. 12<br />

Having offered a different account from the analysis presented in<br />

Being and Nothingness, the claim that the for-itself is of time amounts to a<br />

reassessment of the "pure contingency" that informs <strong>Sartre's</strong> Being and<br />

Nothingness analysis of situated consciousness. It will require the lengthy<br />

volumes of the Critique and the biography of Flaubert to fully articulate<br />

this alternative view. As a foretaste of these later works, the War Diaries<br />

advance a unique interpretation of the past.<br />

<strong>Sartre's</strong> Being and Nothingness account of the past claims that "the<br />

meaning of my past is strictly dependent upon on my present project." 13 It<br />

is precisely this view that the lengthy passage from the War Diaries,<br />

quoted above, rejects. The meaning of the past is not just what I take it to<br />

be from the standpoint of the present, for my past, too, as we have just<br />

seen, as an integral part of my temporality, betrays a movement of<br />

temporalisation that is not identical with the nihilating movement that<br />

makes my past "what I am in the mode of not being it". The past,<br />

according to the War Diaries, is not annihilated, but persists with the<br />

ontologically hybrid character of a dimension of the in-itself within the<br />

for-itself.<br />

To be sure, the for-itself cannot be understood apart from that toward<br />

which it bears a nihilating relationship. It is dependent upon that which it<br />

escapes:<br />

It is dependent on the in-itself, by virtue of the very fact that it exists as<br />

escaping from it. From another point of view, however, this dependence is<br />

nevertheless total independence, since the for-itself is constituted with<br />

respect to extension as that which is not extension. It makes itself<br />

unextendedness; it is its own non-extension. All this we have already<br />

explained. But the in-itself recaptures the for-itself as a by-effect, by virtue<br />

of the fact that it is of a certain in-itself that the for-itself is nihilation. In a<br />

word, the for-itself (which is nihilation of the in-itself and nothing other<br />

than this nihilation), inasmuch as it is for-itself, appears in the unity of the<br />

in-itself as a certain existent belonging to the totality through a phenomenon<br />

of synthetic connection. 14<br />

When applied to the past, this manner of analysis allows Sartre to<br />

distinguish between the present being of the for-itself, which is "a not<br />

12 War Diaries, 210.<br />

13 Being and Nothingness, 498.<br />

14 War Diaries, 2U.


24 Chapter Two<br />

being what it is", from the matter of the past, for which a different<br />

dialectical relationship holds: "I can escape the past only by not being<br />

what / am [...] the former for-itself undergoes an essential modification<br />

[...]. It is not annihilated, but it is recovered by the in-itself [...]. So the past<br />

has over consciousness all the superiority of substantiality and solidity—of<br />

opacity too—which the in-itself confers upon it." 15 In <strong>Sartre's</strong> view, none<br />

of this compromises the freedom of the for-itself, for the for-itself is not<br />

identical with its past. On the other hand, its special "nihilating"<br />

relationship to its past shows that it is the self in the form of "what I was"<br />

that is now synthetically bound to the free and present for-itself. To the<br />

extent that we are time, Sartre argues, "we are something in another mode<br />

than the for-itself'. 16 And to the extent that we are something in another<br />

mode than the for-itself, we bear a relationship to our past that combines<br />

that translucent consciousness of our freedom with a penumbral shadow of<br />

the in-itself nature of our past that can play the role of a condition for the<br />

possibility of a responsibility for our past. Our past belongs to our freedom<br />

in a way that differentiates past actions from present transcendent givens.<br />

"Time", Sartre claims, "is the opaque limit of consciousness." Moreover,<br />

as an "indiscernible opacity", time eludes the transparency of<br />

consciousness, for if the for-itself is transparent to itself by virtue of its<br />

nothingness, "to the extent that we are time, we are something in another<br />

mode than that of the for-itself." 17<br />

Since we can now speak of a "structural", if not "substantial", bond<br />

between my present and my past, an element of continuity between my<br />

past actions and my present situation can serve as basis for the ontology of<br />

responsibility. The recognition of a distinctive ontological complicity<br />

between what I am and what I have been enables Sartre to state: "/ have<br />

become a situation for myself. In this way, / am in my character and my<br />

work. Beginning from a situation that is not-me in relation to me, I have<br />

transformed itself into me." 18<br />

It is outside the scope of the present discussion to go beyond the<br />

suggestion that these notebook entries prefigure the enhanced dialectic of<br />

the for-itself and in-itself that is distinctive of the opening pages of the<br />

Critique of Dialectical Reason. It is also outside the scope of this<br />

discussion to document how <strong>Sartre's</strong> reflections on temporality and the<br />

for-itself might have served as an ontological prolegomena to the later<br />

Notebook entries concerning the life of William II. At this point it will<br />

15 Ibid., 213.<br />

16 Ibid., 209.<br />

17 Ibid.<br />

18 Sartre, Notebooks, 121.


Autobiography, Ontology and Responsibility 25<br />

suffice to note <strong>Sartre's</strong> discussion of William II and its contrast to a<br />

"classical historian's" account of William II as reacting to external<br />

circumstances (his character being "moulded by the action of various<br />

forces" 19 ). In contrast, Sartre attempts to understand this historical figure<br />

in terms of William II's self-understanding and responsibility:<br />

So it seems to me that William IPs original freedom is called royalty.<br />

Moreover, freedom reigns again in the manner of being-to-reign. I see that<br />

William, initially, wants to be a "great" king [...]. One might want to be a<br />

great king in order to excuse oneself for being a king. One may want to use<br />

royalty in order to be great. But William merely considers greatness as the<br />

individualisation of royalty. He wants to be great in order to be that<br />

particular king; in order to be more deeply, more individually king; in<br />

order to appropriate more firmly to himself the title of king [...]. He is the<br />

reign. And this he establishes in his being: his pre-ontological selfunderstanding<br />

coincides with the pro-ject of himself towards coronation.<br />

For, in the very constitution of his being as a being-to-reign, the Crown<br />

Prince remains free to assume his facticity. [...] Behold how he's wholly<br />

and deeply responsible in his being for what the historian first gave us as<br />

an external and contingent fact. The reign is not an outside for William II.<br />

Neither is it an inner and privileged representation. The reign is him. 20<br />

The focus on temporality, the past and responsibility intensifies as <strong>Sartre's</strong><br />

thought develops and provides an important framework for assessing his<br />

own candour with respect to his richly active and varied public political<br />

life. In principle, <strong>Sartre's</strong> ontology of responsibility is sufficiently rich so<br />

as to be able to accommodate his political life and choices. Before turning<br />

our attention to the contrast between <strong>Sartre's</strong> conception of history and<br />

responsibility and Heidegger's emphasis upon history and das Volk, let us<br />

briefly examine the political biographies of the two.<br />

Politics and History<br />

Like Heidegger's, <strong>Sartre's</strong> political life contains moments of controversy,<br />

including his endorsement of Russian Communism. However,<br />

whereas, at least for a period of time, Heidegger's endorsement of Nazism<br />

appeared to be unequivocal, <strong>Sartre's</strong> relationship to Stalinist Russia is in<br />

fact quite complex. Our purpose here is not to justify <strong>Sartre's</strong> political life<br />

and condemn Heidegger's, but to reflect upon Sartre as an example of an<br />

ontological thinker who affirmed both the necessity of individual<br />

Ibid., 304<br />

Ibid., 305.


26 Chapter Two<br />

responsibility and the reality of historical and cultural forces, and who<br />

sought to combine both in his ontology of dialectical freedom. <strong>Sartre's</strong><br />

later work offers a view of human choice, history and the human condition<br />

that rejects human oppression in every form. It is <strong>Sartre's</strong> insistence upon<br />

the reality and necessity of responsible action in the face of human<br />

oppression that calls for emphasis.<br />

Prior to 1939, Sartre considered himself more apolitical than political.<br />

A self-described "anarchist", Sartre became an avid reader of Trotsky's<br />

works. The French Communist Party and its support of the Stalinist<br />

regime represented the political left in pre-and post-war France. Sartre<br />

steadfastly declined to join this party and appeared to be on a constant<br />

search for political and social alternatives further to the political left. As<br />

Ian Birchall stresses, Trotsky's conception of a "permanent revolution"<br />

appealed to the young Sartre far more than the engineered society of<br />

Stalin's Russia. 21<br />

Both Sartre and Heidegger shared a profound dislike for the<br />

bourgeoisie. Whereas Heidegger saw Germany as caught between Russian<br />

communism and American materialism, Sartre recognized the important<br />

difference between Stalinism and Marxism and viewed the distinct forms<br />

of the oppression of the working class in both Russia and America, and the<br />

racism of the latter, as unacceptable denials of human freedom. <strong>Sartre's</strong><br />

historical-political vision was also more encompassing than Heidegger's.<br />

Sartre tended to see the need for a revolutionary politics not only in the<br />

history of the French Revolution, but in the American and Russian<br />

Revolutions as well. Heidegger's increasing concern with the destiny of<br />

the Volk was decidedly Germanic. <strong>Sartre's</strong> views were closer to the<br />

universalism explicit in Marx's view of a communist revolution, whereas<br />

Heidegger's alliance with the Third Reich, at least initially, appeared to<br />

betray a strong nationalism.<br />

One of the more important early influences upon Sartre was his<br />

friendship with Colette Audry. 22 Audry was an anti-communist leftist, one<br />

of the first to write publicly about Heidegger's identification with the Nazi<br />

Party. She wrote an article in 1934, entitled "A Philosophy of German<br />

Fascism", published in a French political weekly, L'Ecole emancipee. 23<br />

Audry writes that Heidegger's philosophy "constitutes a translation into<br />

21 See Birchall, Sartre Against Stalinism. The above brief account of <strong>Sartre's</strong><br />

political commitments is heavily indebted to Birchairs insightful narrative and<br />

detailed scholarship.<br />

22 The details of her friendship with Sartre and Simone de Beauvoir can be found<br />

in Birchall.<br />

23 Birchall, 19.


Autobiography, Ontology and Responsibility 27<br />

philosophical language of the state of mind of the German people since the<br />

war [...] all he did was to follow, as a philosopher, a path parallel to that of<br />

the petty bourgeois masses." Our reference below to Heidegger's<br />

relationship to the "war-ideology" prevalent in the 1920s and 1930s<br />

confirms how insightful this early analysis was. It also points out just how<br />

much the product of his age Heidegger in fact was. Audry also calls<br />

attention to the close connection between Heidegger's notion of historical<br />

destiny and the Nazi Party's doctrine of Germany's national destiny.<br />

Finally, in the concluding paragraphs of her article she chides the Marxists<br />

for restricting their analyses to political and economic factors, leaving the<br />

opponents of Marx, such as Heidegger, free rein to engage in a "monopoly<br />

of intellectual audacity in everything that goes beyond the scope of the<br />

purely economic and political". 24 <strong>Sartre's</strong> writings after Being and<br />

Nothingness (a work heavily influenced by his reading of Heidegger in the<br />

early 1940s) extend Marx's view of the dialectics of the historicaleconomic<br />

world to include the analysis of culture, not as a derivative<br />

superstructure, but as a domain interwoven with the material conditions of<br />

human existence and as a legitimate dimension of human freedom.<br />

<strong>Sartre's</strong> rejection of fascism brought him closer to the communism<br />

Heidegger found totally unacceptable. Between the years 1952 and 1956,<br />

Sartre formed a loose rapprochement with the French Communist Party<br />

(PCF) and defended Stalin's Russia as providing the sole possibility for a<br />

truly revolutionary social order. It was understood that the French<br />

Communist Party was under Moscow's control. Given this context,<br />

<strong>Sartre's</strong> urging individuals to join the party was tantamount to publicly<br />

endorsing Stalinist policies and Stalin's notorious work camps. Sartre<br />

visited Russia for the first time in 1954.<br />

By 1957, Sartre had publicly withdrawn from his loose alliance with<br />

the PCF. The crushing of the Hungarian Revolt in 1957 now saw Sartre<br />

condemning Russian communism. His political writings argued that<br />

Stalin's Russia had become a class society, with a class of exploited<br />

labourers on the one hand and a political dictatorship that called itself<br />

socialist, while clearly oppressing the Soviet worker, on the other. <strong>Sartre's</strong><br />

political Marxism is complemented by his "critique of dialectical reason".<br />

His form of dialectical analysis rejects the existence of an external point of<br />

view from which knowledge of history is to be attained: "A materialist<br />

dialectic will be meaningless if it cannot establish, within human history,<br />

the primacy of material conditions as they are discovered by the praxis of<br />

particular men and as they impose themselves on it. In short, if there is to<br />

Ibid., 21.


28 Chapter Two<br />

be any such thing as dialectical materialism, it must be a historical<br />

materialism, that is to say, a materialism from within [...]." 25 Sartre, in<br />

clearly situating his own ontological and political reflections within their<br />

historical context, argues that, far from excluding a systematic access to<br />

his age, such reflections are the sole means capable of addressing the<br />

meaning of our "social universe".<br />

Heidegger<br />

Being and Time's conceptions of being-in-the-world, care, temporality,<br />

conscience and historicity, suggest a robust conception of situated<br />

existence. As we shall see, however, Heidegger's appeal to "historicity"<br />

serves more to obscure the notion of individual responsibility than to<br />

clarify it.<br />

Perhaps it is possible to derive an ontological account of individual<br />

responsibility on the basis of Being and Time's passages on authenticity,<br />

care and the call of conscience. However, Heidegger's elaboration of a<br />

properly understood, historically situated Dasein occurs primarily in the<br />

discussion of temporality and history in the last sections of Being and<br />

Time. Dasein's "thrownness" largely involves possibilities that "circulate"<br />

in the everyday world of inauthenticity. In this context, "resoluteness"<br />

entails that Dasein disclose to itself authentic possibilities of its "heritage":<br />

"A resolute coming back to thrownness involves handing oneself over to<br />

traditional possibilities, although not necessarily as traditional ones." 26<br />

Central to this account is an emphasis upon the future. Dasein's<br />

"authentic" situation is one in which the heritage of the past ("traditional<br />

possibilities") reveals its "power": "Only factically authentic historicity, as<br />

resolute fate, can disclose the history that has-been-there in such a way<br />

that in retrieve the 'power' of the possible breaks into factual existence,<br />

that is, comes toward it in its futurality." 27<br />

James Phillips has recently argued that this definition of authentic<br />

historicity represents the initial development of Heidegger's notion of das<br />

Volk. 2B Phillips's line of reasoning is as follows: Heidegger does not<br />

preach a radical individualism in Being and Time; authenticity is achieved<br />

through a shared, communal "destiny," not through anarchic individual<br />

choice. Phillips argues that Heidegger's notion of Destiny defines the role<br />

Sartre, Critique of Dialectical Reason, /, 33.<br />

26<br />

Heidegger, Being and Time, 351.<br />

27<br />

Ibid., 360.<br />

28<br />

James Phillips, Heidegger's Volk: Between National Socialism and Poetry.


Autobiography, Ontology and Responsibility 29<br />

of das Volk: "The Volk that it designates knows neither unity or disunity,<br />

because in the transcendence of its historicising, it has always already<br />

reached beyond the isolation of individual subjects, as well as the isolation<br />

of an individual ethnic group." 29 When Heidegger claims that: "Authentic<br />

Being-one's-Self does not rest upon an exceptional condition of the<br />

subject, a condition that has been detached from the 'they'; it is rather an<br />

existentiell modification of the 'they'—of the 'they' as an essential<br />

existential 9 , 30 this modification of the "they" is interpreted by Phillips as<br />

referring to "destiny". The significance of Phillips's discussion resides in<br />

his attempt to identify destiny's defining characteristics, arguing that<br />

Heidegger's notions of destiny and Volk are both inconsistent with the<br />

language of the Nazi Party and ineluctably associated with it.<br />

For Phillips, the core of Heidegger's notions of destiny and das Volk is<br />

"decision". 31 Yet, in Phillips's analysis, ultimately nothing definite is in<br />

place for "decision" to act upon. The core of Destiny becomes an<br />

emphasis upon the pure uncertainty of the future and the "impenetrable<br />

idiocy of time". 32 Phillips has outlined the growing centrality of das Volk<br />

in Heidegger's writings and has pointed out its historical, futural/temporal<br />

nature. In the following discussion, I shall be less concerned to agree or<br />

disagree with Phillips's interpretation than I shall be to offer a complementary<br />

path to understanding Heidegger's post-1930s view of history in<br />

contrast to <strong>Sartre's</strong>.<br />

The opening sections of Being and Time celebrate the pragmatically<br />

oriented involvement of Dasein with the "world" understood as the totality<br />

of instrumental complexes. Dasein is what it does. Dasein 1 s ultimate aim<br />

in this, Heidegger tells us, is Dasein itself. Being and Time's account of<br />

the "world" is the world of work and pragmatic instrumentality.<br />

As early as the Basic Problems of Philosophy, written one year after<br />

Being and Time, we see an important modification of this somewhat<br />

earlier analysis of Dasein's relationship to the world. In Basic Problems,<br />

worldly things are no longer viewed exclusively in terms of their<br />

instrumentality, but are also to be understood in what I will term their<br />

"embodied presence". Things carry a specific ontological weight as things<br />

above and beyond their pure instrumentality. Heidegger writes: "The<br />

characters of thingness [...] were fixed for the first time in Greek ontology<br />

and later faded out and became formalized. [... the Greek meaning of] to<br />

pro-duce, place-here [...] means at the same time to bring into a narrower<br />

Heidegger's Volk, 13.<br />

30 Being and Time, 168.<br />

31 Heidegger's Volk, 199.<br />

32 Ibid., 204.


30 Chapter Two<br />

or wider circuit of the accessible, here [...] so that the produced being<br />

stands-for-itself on its own account and remains able to be found there and<br />

to lie-before as something established stably for itself" 33<br />

Heidegger will use a variety of strategies in his attempt to recall the<br />

genuine meaning of this originally Greek conception of thingness,<br />

acknowledging that things in their essential being are also expressive of<br />

cultural and spiritual values above and beyond, but frequently<br />

incorporating, their use-value. This shift allows us to understand the<br />

importance of the 1935 essay, The Origin of the Work of Art. Even though<br />

it is a produced artefact, the work of art has a "thingly" nature that<br />

transcends its source in human productivity. In fact, Heidegger focuses<br />

less upon the work of art as the product of human labour in emphasizing<br />

the fact that "great" works of art are less the product of individual artists<br />

than they are the "product" of an historical era. Major works of art, such as<br />

the Greek temple, are central points of cultural illumination in which the<br />

light of disclosure (Being) struggles with the concealing darkness of the<br />

earth in order to establish the presence of things. The voice of Being is<br />

announced in great works of art, an announcement that celebrates human<br />

doing as a response to the historical disclosedness of a world and not as<br />

the inspired behaviour of a single individual within the confines of a<br />

purely pragmatic intervention in the world.<br />

Let us term this a shift from a work-centered to a "cultural" view of the<br />

products of human labour. It is this shift that dominates Heidegger's<br />

central argument in the important The Question of Technology. Heidegger<br />

understands technology to be a global, all-encompassing framework<br />

defining the modern world. Technology is defined as a "setting upon", a<br />

"standing reserve", an "ordering". By "standing reserve", Heidegger<br />

means "nothing less than the way in which everything presences that is<br />

wrought upon by the challenging revealing. Whatever stands by in the<br />

sense of standing-reserve no longer stands over and against us as an<br />

object." 34 Heidegger continues: "Yet an airliner that stands on the runway<br />

is surely an object. Certainly. We can represent the machine so. But then it<br />

conceals itself at to what and how it is. Revealed, it stands on the taxi strip<br />

only as standing-reserve, inasmuch as it is ordered to ensure the possibility<br />

of transportation." 35<br />

Technology is the transformation of thing-hood, the object standing<br />

before us in its accessibility on its own terms, into the instrumentality of<br />

worldly Dasein. The opposite of technology is poesis. The Question of<br />

Basic Problems of Phenomenology, 108.<br />

34 Heidegger, The Question of Technology, 17.<br />

35 Ibid.


Autobiography, Ontology and Responsibility 31<br />

Technology gives us several examples of "poetic objects". Two are of<br />

particular significance.<br />

Poetic objects reveal essentia. For Heidegger, the essence of something<br />

is the way in which it develops, its optimal "flowering". As examples of<br />

such development Heidegger cites "the 'essence of a house' and the<br />

'essence of a state'." These are not empty universals, but refer to "the<br />

ways in which house and state hold sway, administer themselves, develop<br />

and decay—the way in which they 'essence' [Weseri]. [...] It means the<br />

city hall in as much as there the life of the community gathers and village<br />

existence is constantly in play, i.e., comes to presence." 36 The emphasis<br />

upon village life and community reflects Heidegger's preoccupation with<br />

the Volk, in contradistinction to the urban anonymity that he critiqued in<br />

Being and Time, and relates to the importance of history in Being and<br />

Time's concluding sections. In the final paragraphs of The Question of<br />

Technology, Heidegger argues that art for the Classical Greeks was not<br />

just one aspect of cultural life among others, but was understood as<br />

something that embraced all revealing of the presence of things, from<br />

sacred objects to public life.<br />

Twenty years earlier, The Origin of the Work of Art displayed a similar<br />

concern with an all-embracing "aesthetic" culture. More specifically, it is<br />

"great" works of art that are the central concern. The work of art<br />

announces a "world". What is a world?<br />

World is the ever-nonobjective to which we are subject as long as the paths<br />

of birth and death, blessings and curse keep us transported into Being.<br />

Wherever those decisions of our history that relate to our essential being<br />

are made, are taken up and abandoned by us, go unrecognized and are<br />

rediscovered by new inquiry, there the world worlds. 37<br />

Poetry, art, architecture and language are the means whereby the world is<br />

disclosed. The substances of such expressions and artefacts are "the<br />

concepts of a historical people's essence, i.e., of its belonging to world<br />

history, are preformed for that people." 38 The world is the disclosure of a<br />

people's historical destiny, the end toward which they are summoned and<br />

subjected.<br />

Heidegger's The Question of Technology suggests that this folkhistorical<br />

dimension has disappeared from the modern, technological<br />

36<br />

Ibid., 30.<br />

37<br />

Martin Heidegger, 'The Origin of the Work of Art", in David Krell (ed.), Basic<br />

Writings, 170.<br />

38<br />

Ibid., 185.


32 Chapter Two<br />

world. Heidegger's identification with the Nazi Party appears to have<br />

been, at least partially, related to the aspects of his writings just discussed,<br />

beginning with Being and Time (1927) and including The Origin of the<br />

Work of Art (1935) and the important The Question Concerning<br />

Technology (1954). There is little doubt that Heidegger's alliance with the<br />

Third Reich was undertaken in part to struggle against this loss of a world<br />

in which the presence of things and the village life of the community<br />

"flowered". For Heidegger, the Third Reich seems to have represented<br />

precisely that "authentic historicity as resolute fate" mentioned in Being<br />

and Time. As noted above, a people's authentic being-with is defined as its<br />

comprehension of the importance of decision and the futural dimension<br />

of human historical time. To rejoin Phillips's analysis, rather than<br />

misunderstand themselves as a nation-state community, Heidegger's Volk<br />

experiences the decisiveness of historical existence as a form of openness<br />

to the future that precludes being identified with the empirical features of<br />

national, geographic or political characteristics. The Volk is not the nation<br />

state, but a consciousness of the non-repeatability of historical time. On<br />

Phillips's reading, Heidegger is mistaken in identifying the crisis of<br />

Germany as a sign of the decisiveness of the true Volk. National Socialism<br />

turns out to define the German people in categories that are the opposite of<br />

Heidegger's Volk. Although Heidegger was clearly tempted by National<br />

Socialism, the rootlessness of the Volk's radical openness to temporality<br />

and the future clashes with the biologism and nationalism of the Third<br />

Reich. 39<br />

A striking consequence emerges from the confluence of Heidegger's<br />

critique of the world of technology and his reflections on the nature of das<br />

Volk. The Question of Technology suggests that the modern world limits<br />

"being" to use, thereby distancing itself from the possibility of a<br />

potentially new form of poetic disclosure. As is well known, such a<br />

possibility was just what Heidegger seemed to identify with the<br />

"metaphysical" heritage of the German people. Modernity, however,<br />

seems to preclude such a possibility by being identified with the<br />

perspective of technology. At the same time, the true nature of das Volk<br />

appears to be increasingly vacuous, for as a "radical openness to the<br />

future" it appears to collapse into the tautology that the future is simply<br />

what must be awaited. As a consequence, Heidegger's later thought moves<br />

a significant distance from his earlier call for Dasein to exist authentically<br />

by resolutely taking over its heritage. The characterless nature of das Volk<br />

3 A differing view of Heidegger's conception of das Volk and its relationship to<br />

National Socialism can be found in Domenico Losurdo's Heidegger and the<br />

Ideology of War: Community, Death and the West, Chapters 2 and 3.


Autobiography, Ontology and Responsibility 33<br />

would appear to entirely dissolve the earlier concept of "heritage", and the<br />

world of modern technology would appear to forestall the possibility of an<br />

enriching experience from the side of any inherited "aesthetic culture".<br />

Conclusion<br />

What role might remain for individual responsibility on the<br />

Heideggerian account, and what ontological structures serve to support<br />

such a role? Within the framework of Heidegger's construal of history and<br />

technology, there appears to be no role for individual responsibility. The<br />

past world of the Greeks is no longer available to us. The present world of<br />

technology, disclosing things as pure tools, is a world from which we are<br />

encouraged to turn away and simply await our "future". The later<br />

Heidegger may believe that it is our "responsibility" to wait for a new<br />

disclosure of Being. But it is difficult to align such a responsibility with<br />

individual action. On Heidegger's account, the ontological conditions<br />

upon which an historical epoch rests are beyond the reach of individual<br />

actions. 40 It is no surprise that the later Heidegger writes explicitly that the<br />

concept of Volk is not to be defined in nationalist terms. The rootless and<br />

anti-nationalist nature of the Volk's radical openness to temporality<br />

appears to represent a notion of community in terms of which individual<br />

agency simply fails to pass the test of ontological relevance.<br />

At this point, the contrast with <strong>Sartre's</strong> thought is striking. For Sartre,<br />

the for-itself involves dimensions of history and intersubjectivity that are<br />

insurmountable and represent an irreducible call for individual responsibility:<br />

"Furthermore, it must be understood that there is no such thing as<br />

man; there are people, wholly defined by their society and by the historical<br />

movement which carries them along; if we do not wish that the dialectic<br />

become a divine law again, a metaphysical fate, it must proceed from<br />

individuals and not from some kind of supra-individual ensemble." 41<br />

Given this context, it is tempting to interpret Heidegger's silence<br />

regarding his personal affiliation with the Third Reich as directly<br />

reflecting just this absence of any ontology of responsibility. In rejecting<br />

the incipient nationalism inherent in Being and Time's early conception of<br />

authenticity, Heidegger's ontology of historical action, in marked contrast<br />

to Sartre, closes off all access to historically significant and responsible<br />

action on the part of the thinker. When correlated with his view of history,<br />

Heidegger's public silence is understandable, for only a people can act<br />

David Kolb, The Critique of Pure Modernity: Hegel, Heidegger and After, 230.<br />

41 Sartre, Critique of Dialectical Reason, 7, 36.


34 Chapter Two<br />

responsibly on the world-stage of history. However, if his ontology of<br />

history is as vacuous as it appears to be, his silence has no excuse.<br />

Situated thinking necessarily confronts responsibilities and its history.<br />

It is perhaps overly dismissive of the suggestiveness of Heidegger's later<br />

thought to view it as simply a strategy to nullify individual historical<br />

responsibility and accountability. Yet the substantive correlation between<br />

responsibility and ontology that can be discovered in <strong>Sartre's</strong> thought and<br />

life appears to have been destroyed in the case of Heidegger. Paul Celan's<br />

anguished dismay over Heidegger's public silence not only raises the<br />

question of individual responsibility, but provokes direct reflection upon<br />

the onto-autobiographical dimension of the thinker as well.<br />

Works Cited<br />

Birchall, Ian. Sartre Against Stalinism. New York: Berghahn Books, 2004.<br />

Heidegger, Martin. The Basic Problems of Phenomenology. Indiana:<br />

Indiana University Press, 1982.<br />

—. Being and Time. Albany, NY: State University of New York Press,<br />

1996.<br />

—. The Question Concerning Technology and Other Essays. New York:<br />

Harper & Row, 1977.<br />

Kolb, David. The Critique of Pure Modernity: Hegel Heidegger and<br />

After. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1986.<br />

Krell, David. Martin Heidegger: Basic Writings. London: Routledge, 1993.<br />

Losurdo, Domenico. Heidegger and the Ideology of War: Community,<br />

Death and the West. Amherst, N.Y.: Humanity Books, 2001.<br />

Phillips, James. Heidegger's Volk: Between National Socialism and<br />

Poetry. Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2005.<br />

Sartre, Jean-Paul. Being and Nothingness. New York: Philosophical<br />

Library, 1956.<br />

—. Critique of Dialectical Reason, I. London: Verso, 2004.<br />

—. Notebooks for an Ethics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1992.<br />

—. War Diaries. London: Verso, 1984.


CHAPTER THREE<br />

LITERATURE AND PHILOSOPHY<br />

IN SARTRE'S EARLY WRITINGS<br />

ALAIN FLAJOLIET<br />

It has often been remarked that the philosophical analysis developed in<br />

VEtre et le neant {Being and Nothingness) can be related to <strong>Sartre's</strong><br />

literature. 1 As a consequence, <strong>Sartre's</strong> early writings have often been<br />

criticised from two points of view. The philosophical works, it is said, are<br />

not sufficiently rigorous, and the novels, short stories, plays, are nothing<br />

but problem literature, too philosophical to arouse curiosity. <strong>Sartre's</strong><br />

phenomenological works are not taken seriously, especially in France (the<br />

situation is quite different with Merleau-Ponty's phenomenology). The<br />

aim of this chapter is to critique this commonly-held opinion. Being and<br />

Nothingness, according to the rules of ontological phenomenology, is a<br />

strictly philosophical work. But the phenomenological field comes under<br />

the influence of a metaphysics that, for its part, is contained in literary<br />

works like La Nausee (Nausea), Le Mur (The Wall), and Une Defaite (A<br />

Defeat)? From a historical point of view, <strong>Sartre's</strong> project of metaphysical<br />

literature is prior to the philosophical works and becomes more and more<br />

precise as Sartre studies philosophy at the Ecole Normale Superieure. 3<br />

This literary project does not disappear when Sartre writes his first<br />

philosophical works, La Transcendance de VEgo (The Transcendence of<br />

the Ego) and "Une idee fondamentale de la ph£nom£nologie de Husserl:<br />

l'intentionnalit£" ("A Fundamental Idea of Husserlian Phenomenology:<br />

1 See G. Prince, Metaphysique et technique dans Vceuvre romanesque de Sartre,<br />

2 We shall not address the influence of the metaphysical psychology contained in<br />

<strong>Sartre's</strong> diploma dissertation: "L'Image dans la vie psychologique: role et nature"<br />

('The Image in the psychological life: role and nature"). For Une Defaite, see<br />

Merits dejeunesse.<br />

3 See Sartre, Carnets de la drole de guerre, Simone de Beauvoir, La Ceremonie<br />

des adieux, and Alexandre Astruc and Michel Contat, Sartre; unfilm.


36 Chapter Three<br />

Intentionality"). In Berlin (1933-34), Sartre writes these two articles and<br />

La Nausee simultaneously. The writing of the novel influences the articles<br />

in a way that we shall examine here. 4<br />

The Project of Metaphysical Literature<br />

As far as <strong>Sartre's</strong> early writings are concerned, we shall consider<br />

Nausea and the Ecrits de jeunesse (Juvenilia). His autobiography, Les<br />

Mots (The Words), is also important for understanding the earliest origins<br />

of the project of metaphysical literature. The latter is a highly original<br />

literary project, involving the creation of fictions, using every means of<br />

inventive metaphors and complex plots. But it is also a philosophical<br />

project, because the writer aims at revealing metaphysical truths. In her<br />

Memoires d*une jeunefille rangee, Simone de Beauvoir portrays Sartre in<br />

1929 as follows:<br />

He liked Stendhal as much as Spinoza and did not want to separate<br />

philosophy from literature; in his mind, contingency was not an abstract<br />

idea, but a real feature of the world: 5 it was necessary to use all means of<br />

art to make one's heart sensitive to the secret weakness he saw in man and<br />

in all things. 6<br />

It should be emphasised that, in <strong>Sartre's</strong> literary works, the metaphysical<br />

experiences are never conceptually explicated: literature comes first. In<br />

1974, Sartre, conversing with Beauvoir about his studies at the Ecole<br />

Normale Superieure, said:<br />

At that time, I did not want to write books of philosophy. I did not want to<br />

write the equivalent of Critique de la raison dialectique or of L'hre et le<br />

niant. No, I wanted to express in my novel the philosophy I believed, the<br />

truths I would discover. 7<br />

Why are the truths revealed by literature "metaphysical" truths?<br />

First, these truths appear in the "Conclusion" to Being and Nothingness,<br />

where they are called "metaphysical implications" ("apergus<br />

An earlier draft of this chapter was given as a paper at the Centenary Conference<br />

of the UK Sartre Society at the Institut Francais, London, in March 2005.<br />

5 Let us note that "contingency" is a fundamental concept of metaphysics.<br />

6 Simone de Beauvoir, Memoires d'une jeune fille rangee (Memoirs of a Dutiful<br />

Daughter), 479. [Translations are by the author unless stated otherwise.—Eds].<br />

7 Simone de Beauvoir, La Ceremonie des adieux (The Farewell Ceremony), 203.


Literature and Philosophy in <strong>Sartre's</strong> Early Writings 37<br />

me'taphysiques"). One example of such an implication is the problem of<br />

the origin of consciousness:<br />

Ontology teaches us two things: 1) if the in-itself were to found itself, it<br />

could attempt to do so only by making itself consciousness [...];<br />

consciousness is in fact a project of founding itself; that is, of attaining to<br />

the dignity of the in-itself-for-itself or in-itself-as-a-self-cause. 9<br />

Therefore, phenomenological ontology can affirm nothing categorically<br />

about the "upsurge of the for-itself\ 10 As far as this problem is concerned,<br />

it has the form of what Sartre calls a metaphysical hypothesis. Ontology,<br />

writes Sartre, "will limit itself to declaring that everything takes place as if<br />

the in-itself gave itself the modification of the for-itself. It is up to<br />

metaphysics to form the hypotheses which will allow us to conceive this<br />

process [...]." n<br />

Secondly, these truths belong to a philosophical tradition referred to by<br />

Heidegger as the "onto-theological" tradition. Ever since Baumgarten,<br />

metaphysics has been understood as the "science which contains the<br />

primary principles of human knowledge", 12 and has been divided into a<br />

metaphysica specialis (the science of God, soul and world), and a<br />

metaphysica generalis (the science of being qua being).<br />

In <strong>Sartre's</strong> early writings, metaphysical truths do not form a welldefined<br />

philosophical system that might pre-exist a literary work. Sartre is<br />

not in possession of a set of rigorously demonstrated statements about<br />

God, the soul, or being qua being. There is indeed a philosophical system<br />

in his early writings, but it is not a metaphysical one. It is the<br />

transcendental phenomenology sketched in Berlin in 1933-34 in The<br />

Transcendence of the Ego and "A Fundamental Idea of Husserlian<br />

Phenomenology: Intentionality". <strong>Sartre's</strong> metaphysics is composed of<br />

uncertain and evolving convictions that can be expressed only by storytelling<br />

and not by conceptualisation. If we try to summarize briefly the<br />

very complex subject of these metaphysical convictions, we can identify<br />

four experiences.<br />

Sartre, Being and Nothingness, 637.<br />

9<br />

Ibid., 641.<br />

10<br />

Ibid<br />

11<br />

Ibid., 640.<br />

12<br />

"Metaphysica est scientia prima cognitionis humanae principia continens"<br />

(Baumgarten, Metaphysica, 1739, § 1).


38 Chapter Three<br />

The first metaphysical experience is the experience of life as "brute<br />

existence" , n an experience that corresponds with the radical upsurge and<br />

appearance of the for-itself: "The for-itself corresponds [...] to an expanding<br />

de-structuring of the in-itself, and the in-itself is nihilated and absorbed in<br />

its attempt to find itself." 14<br />

In Nausea, Roquentin repeatedly experiences the horrible coming to<br />

life of inert things that begin to swarm and bud, especially when he<br />

encounters flesh as the reluctant and gloomy birth of consciousness.<br />

Looking at his face in a mirror, he says:<br />

What I see is well below the monkey, on the fringe of the vegetable world,<br />

at the level of jellyfish. It is alive, I can't say it isn't; [...] I see a slight<br />

tremor, I see the insipid flesh blossoming and palpitating with abandon.<br />

The eyes especially are horrible when seen so close. They are glassy, soft,<br />

blind, red-rimmed, they look like fish scales. 15<br />

When Roquentin's book on Rollebon's life proves to be a failure,<br />

Roquentin is overwhelmed by a violent seizure of nausea in which he<br />

sinks into the repulsive living matter of things.<br />

The <strong>second</strong> metaphysical experience is that of the desire of human<br />

reality to be God, that is, ens causa suL When Sartre describes the foritself<br />

as a "lack" ("manque") 16 in Being and Nothingness, he remarks:<br />

"Human reality is a perpetual surpassing towards a coincidence with itself<br />

which is never given." 17<br />

In Les Mots, a narration of the birth of <strong>Sartre's</strong> vocation as a writer,<br />

this metaphysical experience is, as Paul Ricoeur would say, "put into<br />

play". 18 At the end of the book, Charles Schweitzer's grandson throws<br />

himself into writing in order to stifle and hide his feeling of deep anguish<br />

in front of an absolute freedom he understands as the radically gratuitous<br />

nature of all of his choices: 19 "One writes for one's neighbours or for God.<br />

I decided to write for God with the purpose of saving my neighbours." 20<br />

Upset by his discovery of writing, the young Sartre glimpses the<br />

possible eternalisation of his life through literature. He begins to scribble<br />

Being and Nothingness, 509.<br />

14<br />

Ibid., 108.<br />

15<br />

Sartre, Nausea, 17.<br />

16<br />

Being and Nothingness, 110.<br />

17<br />

Ibid., 113.<br />

18<br />

See P. Ricoeur, Temps et recit, I.<br />

19<br />

Being and Nothingness, 501.<br />

20<br />

The Words, 180.


Literature and Philosophy in <strong>Sartre's</strong> Early Writings 39<br />

fantastic tales, adventure novels inspired by Jules Verne, Michel Ze*vaco,<br />

and, finally, mystical fictions. The latter are written under the influences of<br />

Charles's humanistic religion, readings such as Charles Perrault's<br />

Griselidis and Edmond Rostand's Chantecler, and a Platonic idealism<br />

shaped by his grandfather's library. The child's mysticism is a key to<br />

understanding most of <strong>Sartre's</strong> early writings where the topic of salvation<br />

through art occurs repeatedly.<br />

Une Defaite, an unpublished novel written in 1927 and inspired by the<br />

relationships between Richard Wagner, Nietzsche and Cosima Wagner,<br />

relates the troubled situation which binds Fr£d6ric, an ambitious young<br />

student, Organte, an ageing musician unable to create, and Cosima, the<br />

bright and beautiful wife of Organte. Frederic's life is a pitiful failure<br />

whose advances are spurned by Cosima. Organte stifles him and prevents<br />

him from writing. However, Fr&ie'ric finally manages to finish his inspired<br />

Empedocle, and all the hardships are thereby redeemed. The novel<br />

concludes with the lines:<br />

We can leave [FrddeYic] on this defeat, on this fruitful defeat. He is<br />

humiliated and distressed. He will have doubts about himself for a long<br />

time, he will realise the loss of his strength. He is alone. [...] but it will<br />

soon be time for his victories. 21<br />

The third metaphysical experience is intimately connected to the<br />

<strong>second</strong>. It is the intuition of absolute freedom. In Being and Nothingness<br />

Sartre asserts that "man is wholly free". 22 He adds: "We shall never<br />

apprehend ourselves except as a choice in the making. But freedom is<br />

simply the fact that this choice is always unconditioned." 23 Sartre does not<br />

hesitate to retreat, apparently, from the theory of the "facticity" and<br />

"finitude" of the for-itself given in the <strong>second</strong> part of Being and<br />

Nothingness. He now writes: "Freedom is total and infinite, which does<br />

not mean that it has no limits but that it never encounters them." 24<br />

Let us now return to The Words at the moment when, as a child, Sartre<br />

dreams about his "false birth":<br />

When I examine my life from the age of six to nine, I am struck by the<br />

continuity of my spiritual exercises. Their content often changed, but the<br />

program remained unvaried. I had made a false entrance; I withdrew<br />

21 Sartre, Merits dejeunesse, 286.<br />

22 Being and Nothingness, 464.<br />

23 Ibid., 501.<br />

24 Ibid., 552, my emphasis.


40 Chapter Three<br />

behind a screen and began my birth over again at the right moment, the<br />

very minute that the universe silently called for me. 25<br />

At this point we encounter a phantasy of self-recreation, in which Sartre<br />

expresses his metaphysical intuition of the creatio ex nihilo that Descartes<br />

attributed to God, and that Sartre attributes to human consciousness. In<br />

The Words, self-recreation ex nihilo, that is to say, absolute freedom, is<br />

experienced by the child as a deep anguish:<br />

I lived in a state of uneasiness: at the very moment when their ceremonies<br />

convinced me that nothing exists without a reason and that everyone, from<br />

the highest to the lowest, has his place marked out for him in the universe,<br />

my own reason for being slipped away; I would suddenly discover that I<br />

did not really count, and I felt ashamed of my unwonted presence in that<br />

well ordered world [...]. A father would have weighted me with a certain<br />

stable obstinacy. Making his moods my principles, his ignorance my<br />

knowledge, his disappointments my pride, his quirks my law, he would<br />

have inhabited me. That respectable tenant would have given me selfrespect,<br />

and on that respect I would have based my right to live. My<br />

begetter would have determined my future. 26<br />

But Jean-Baptiste Sartre was dead a long time ago and the child was<br />

compelled to grow up with a feeling of total gratuitousness, without any<br />

paternal law to interiorise.<br />

The fourth metaphysical experience is that of the contingency of every<br />

real entity—real thing or human reality. In Being and Nothingness Sartre<br />

claims that "Being-in-itself can neither be derived from the possible, nor<br />

reduced to the necessary. [...] This is what we call the contingency of<br />

being-in-itself." 27 In the famous scene of the public garden in Nausea,<br />

Roquentin stops in contemplation before the black, gnarled root of the<br />

tree, and experiences the unintelligible fact that this root lies in front of<br />

him at this place and at this time, without any reason why it appears<br />

precisely at this time, at this place, with its specific qualities and to him,<br />

Roquentin. This concrete intuition of contingency underlies the entire<br />

narrative of Jesus la Chouettet professeur de province (Jesus the Owl, A<br />

Provincial Schoolmaster), a novel partly published in 1923. 28 In this book,<br />

25 The Words, 113.<br />

26 Ibid., 86-87.<br />

27 Being and Nothingness, 22.<br />

28 The title contains an ironic and untranslatable play on words because, in popular<br />

speech, "chouette" can also refer to an ugly and cantankerous old woman, or to<br />

anything that is "neat, smart, chic", etc.


Literature and Philosophy in <strong>Sartre's</strong> Early Writings 41<br />

Sartre describes a small provincial town as a symbol of hell on earth:<br />

everywhere manners mask violence, cowardice, cynicism, cruelty, and<br />

cupidity.<br />

The Influence of Metaphysics on the Early<br />

Phenomenological Works<br />

Written in Berlin, The Transcendence of the Ego and "A Fundamental<br />

Idea of Husserlian Phenomenology: Intentionality" are two proper<br />

philosophical works using the rigorous Husserlian method of<br />

transcendental reduction. The challenge is to display a transcendental<br />

phenomenology inspired by Husserl, but simultaneously criticising<br />

HusserPs Logical Investigations, the first volume of Ideas and the<br />

Cartesian Meditations, But the way Sartre works in Berlin is very<br />

interesting.<br />

In the film made in 1972 by Alexandre Astruc and Michel Contat, 29<br />

Sartre explains that when he was in Berlin he worked at his philosophical<br />

works in the morning and that in the afternoon he settled down to his<br />

literary task, that is to say, he tried to rewrite his "pamphlet about<br />

contingency", which was to be published later in 1938 under the title,<br />

Nausea. <strong>Sartre's</strong> schedule is significant. It would be misleading to claim<br />

that he mixes his two activities. For him, the ways of writing philosophy<br />

and literature are essentially different, as he clearly explained in 1975:<br />

In philosophy, every sentence should have only one meaning. [...] In<br />

literature, which in some way always has to do with what has been<br />

experienced [vecu], nothing that I say is totally expressed by what I say.<br />

The same reality can be expressed in a practically infinite number of<br />

ways. 30<br />

This is the main reason why there is a sharp contrast between the<br />

philosophical and the literary manuscripts: all of the philosophical<br />

manuscripts are written in one go; on the other hand, the literary<br />

manuscripts are scratched out, erased and rewritten many times.<br />

Nevertheless, the fact remains that there is a connection between<br />

philosophy and literature in the early works of Sartre, especially in the<br />

works of the mid-1930s. For example, in the "pamphlet on contingency",<br />

Roquentin's adventures express two metaphysical convictions that are not<br />

assumed as such by the phenomenologist because they are in principle<br />

Sartre, unfilm, 44.<br />

Sartre, "Self-Portrait at Seventy", 7-8.


42 Chapter Three<br />

"reduced" or "excluded" ("bracketed", Husserl would say), but which<br />

nevertheless influence the phenomenological analysis: the convictions that<br />

all real existence is contingent and that consciousness is an absolute<br />

spontaneity.<br />

Let us begin with contingency. If we turn to Nausea, we see a clear<br />

sequence of significant events in Roquentin's life, each one linked to the<br />

other. We find the heart-breaking discovery that "there are no<br />

adventures" 31 —nothing in real life begins and ends like a hero's adventure<br />

in a novel. The famous visit to the museum in Bouville follows. Here,<br />

Roquentin becomes aware that the quiet happiness of the bourgeois is<br />

nothing but cowardice and nastiness. A few days later, meeting Dr Roge at<br />

the restaurant Chez Camille, Roquentin mocks him as a "professionnel de<br />

l'experience" ("an experience professional")—the truth is that it is a<br />

complete illusion to think that any life improves by experience: to live is<br />

to decline in an irresistible decay. Further on in the novel we witness the<br />

death of the project of writing the scholarly book on Rollebon. Finally, we<br />

have the lunch with the Autodidact, a repulsive caricature of genuine<br />

culture, the embodiment of disgusting humanism:<br />

The Self-Taught Man's face is close to mine. He smiles foolishly, all the<br />

while close to my face, like a nightmare. [...] People. You must love<br />

people. Men are admirable. I want to vomit—and suddenly, there it is: the<br />

Nausea. 32<br />

This crisis introduces the episode of the public garden, the discovery of the<br />

contingency of the tree's root and, more generally, the discovery of the<br />

contingency of all things existing in the world.<br />

Finally, we encounter the definite death of the love for Anny ("we<br />

have nothing more to say" 33 ) and the conclusion that in every real life<br />

everybody loses the game. 34 In this entire sequence of events, the<br />

metaphysical experience of contingency is expressed in a plot and fixed in<br />

metaphors. As a consequence, the phenomenological article on intentionality<br />

rejects the most idealistic implications of Husserl*s phenomenology.<br />

Indeed, intentionality itself is considered by Sartre to be a "burst" ("un<br />

dclatement") of consciousness in the midst of the world and not the<br />

"constitution" of the world within the "transcendental Ego", as Husserl<br />

repeatedly insists in Ideas and in the Cartesian Meditations. Let us read a<br />

31 Sartre, Nausea, 150.<br />

32 Ibid., 122.<br />

33 Ibid., 153.<br />

34 Ibid., 157.


Literature and Philosophy in <strong>Sartre's</strong> Early Writings 43<br />

few lines of <strong>Sartre's</strong> article that try to describe the intentionality of<br />

consciousness with the assistance of the image of a "bursting out"<br />

("eclatement"). To have consciousness of things, Sartre says,<br />

[...] is to "explode towards", to uproot oneself from the moist intimacy of<br />

one's visceral being in order to flee over there, beyond oneself, towards<br />

what is not oneself, out there, near the tree and yet outside it, for it escapes<br />

me and repels me as something in which I can no more dissolve myself<br />

than it can dilute itself in me: outside of it, outside of me. 35<br />

Sartre thinks—incorrectly, but that is not the point here—that his reinterpretation<br />

of Husserlian intentionality as a "bursting out of<br />

consciousness" is closer to the interpretation in Being and Time of<br />

"Dasein" as "being-in-the world" and "transcendence". If we ask why<br />

Sartre, forsaking Husserl's transcendental idealism, moves to a kind of<br />

realism in which transcendent things always overflow consciousness, the<br />

answer is to be found in his metaphysical literature. If, for example, we<br />

return to the episode of the public garden in La Nausee, we see that the<br />

sickness of nausea experienced by Roquentin discloses the raw,<br />

indeterminate being of the repulsive black root as something quite beyond<br />

all thought. Expressed as an episode in a novel, the metaphysical truth<br />

does not give rise to a philosophical and conceptual account, but rather<br />

forms a conviction that influences the arguments of the article on<br />

Husserl's theory of intentionality.<br />

Let us now consider the matter of the spontaneity of consciousness. In<br />

The Transcendence of the Ego, Sartre significantly alters Husserl's<br />

conception of transcendental consciousness. He states that this<br />

consciousness is not a reflective Ego, but an anonymous, non-reflective<br />

consciousness that he terms "spontaneity" ("spontandite"), a term rarely<br />

used by Husserl in Ideas because it is clearly reminiscent of the<br />

metaphysical concept of causa suL Sartre asserts that the transcendental<br />

pre-reflective consciousness is "absolute": "This transcendental sphere is a<br />

sphere of absolute existence, that is to say of pure spontaneities which are<br />

"Connaitre, c'est 's'eclater vers\ s'arracher a la moite intimity gastrique pour<br />

filer, la-bas, par-dela soi, vers ce qui n'est pas soi, la-bas, pres de l'arbre et<br />

cependant hors de lui, car il m'£chappe et me repousse et je ne peux pas plus me<br />

perdre en lui qu'il ne se peut diluer en moi: hors de lui, hors de moi" (Sartre, "Une<br />

ide*e fondamentale de la phe'nome'nologie de Husserl: rintentionnalite'", 30—<br />

translation by author and editors).


44 Chapter Three<br />

never objects and which themselves determine to exist." According to<br />

Sartre, consciousness lives its spontaneity in anguish and terror. The day<br />

after the meeting with Dr Rogd, Roquentin writes in his diary: "I must not<br />

be afraid." 37 Dense fog is hanging over Bouville, the familiar objects<br />

disappear, at the Cafe Mably a frosty darkness welcomes Roquentin, who<br />

suddenly falls into a panic. The owner could be dead:<br />

A real panic took hold of me. I didn't know where I was going. I ran along<br />

the docks, turned into the deserted streets [...]. The houses watched my<br />

flight with their mournful eyes. I repeated with anguish: Where shall I go?<br />

Where shall I go? Anything can happen. 38<br />

Within the context of the novel, "anything can happen" suggests a<br />

possible sex crime, and can be interpreted in two ways. On the one hand, if<br />

I am an absolute freedom, I can choose or refuse to commit the crime, a<br />

situation of anguish. On the other hand, this crime may be so fascinating<br />

that I am condemned to commit it, which terrifies me.<br />

Conclusion<br />

Thus, <strong>Sartre's</strong> literary works, such as Nausea—and we could add Er<br />

VArmenien {Er the Armenian) with its reminder of the Platonic myth about<br />

the original choice of existence—can be considered the source of the<br />

fundamental metaphysical concept of "spontaneity". Spontaneity is a way<br />

of living one's life for a consciousness that does not feel the weight of<br />

circumstances, family, social class, language, and moral rules. For<br />

example, in The Words Sartre writes: "The days of happiness originated in<br />

me; I drew them from the nothingness of my own abilities in order to bring<br />

to others the books they loved." 39<br />

In theory, Being and Nothingness is entirely written in accordance with<br />

the rules of ontological phenomenology. But, as we have seen,<br />

metaphysics is not totally absent from the book. In his conclusion, Sartre<br />

explains that phenomenological investigation leads to the metaphysical<br />

question of the origin of the for-itself: why and how does the for-itself<br />

emerge from the in-itself? At this point, ontological phenomenology offers<br />

"Cette sphere transcendentale est une sphere d'existence absolue, c'est-a-dire de<br />

spontaneous pures, qui ne sont jamais objets et qui se d&erminent elles-m§mes a<br />

exister" (Sartre, La Transcendance de VEgo, 11—editor's translation).<br />

37<br />

Sartre, Nausea, 70.<br />

38<br />

Ibid., 78.<br />

39<br />

Sartre, The Words, 146.


Literature and Philosophy in <strong>Sartre's</strong> Early Writings 45<br />

two suggestions. First: every process of self-foundation breaks the identity<br />

of the in-itself. Second: the for-itself really is the failure of the project of<br />

self-foundation. The significant point is that ontological phenomenology<br />

cannot answer the "metaphysical question". In fact, only literature can<br />

face the metaphysical problem of the origin of the for-itself not with the<br />

help of concepts and arguments, but by means of metaphors and plots. A<br />

detailed analysis of Nausea and of all the texts published in Merits de<br />

jeunesse would confirm this assertion.<br />

If it is literature that truly faces the metaphysical problem of the origin<br />

of the for-itself, literature is also the key for understanding all of the<br />

passages in Being and Nothingness in which ontological phenomenology<br />

approaches metaphysics in sketching its theories of facticity, freedom, the<br />

body, and being-for-others.<br />

Works Cited<br />

Astruc, Alexandre and Michel Contat. Sartre, un film. Paris: Gallimard,<br />

1977.<br />

Baumgarten, A. G. Metaphysica. Halle, 1739.<br />

Beauvoir, Simone de. La Ceremonie des adieux. Paris: Gallimard, coll.<br />

Folio, 1981.<br />

—. Memoires d'unejeunefille rangee. Paris: Gallimard, coll. Folio, 1958.<br />

Contat, Michel. "Self-Portrait at Seventy", in Life/Situations (trans. Paul<br />

Auster and Lydia Davis). New York: Pantheon, 1977.<br />

Prince, Gerald. Metaphysique et technique dans Vozuvre romanesque de<br />

Sartre. Geneve: Droz, 1968.<br />

Ricceur, Paul. Temps et recit, I. Paris: Seuil, 1983.<br />

Sartre, Jean-Paul. Being and Nothingness (trans. H. E. Barnes). New York:<br />

Philosophical Library, 1956.<br />

—. Carnets de la drole de guerre. Paris: Gallimard, 1995.<br />

—. Nausea (trans. Lloyd Alexander). New York: New Directions, 1964.<br />

—. (Euvres romanesques. Paris: Gallimard, Bibliotheque de la Plelade,<br />

1981.<br />

—. "Une idee fondamentale de la phenom£nologie de Husserl: l'intentionnalite",<br />

in Situations, I. Paris: Gallimard, 1947,29-32.<br />

—. The Words. New York: George Braziller, 1964.<br />

—. Une Defaite, in Ecrits de jeunesse. Paris: Gallimard, 1990.<br />

—. ErVArmenien, in Merits de jeunesse. Paris: Gallimard, 1990.<br />

—. La Transcendance de VEgo. Paris: Librairie philosophique J. Vrin,<br />

1972.


CHAPTER FOUR<br />

TEMPORALITY AND THE DEATH<br />

OF LUCIENNE IN NAUSEA<br />

CAM CLAYTON<br />

<strong>Sartre's</strong> celebrated novel, Nausea (1938), is usually interpreted by way<br />

of the themes of contingency, absurdity, nausea, and freedom. There has<br />

been little attention given to the role of temporality and the temporal<br />

structure of consciousness in understanding and explaining the strange<br />

malaise of <strong>Sartre's</strong> protagonist, Antoine Roquentin. It is by way of <strong>Sartre's</strong><br />

conception of temporality, as presented in Being and Nothingness (1943),<br />

that I propose to interpret Nausea in this chapter. 1<br />

There is one scene in particular in Nausea that commentators have<br />

struggled to explain and therefore often ignore. Roquentin is at the library<br />

doing historical research for a biography on which he is working. His<br />

journal entry describes the difficulty he is having making sense of, and<br />

giving order to, the past. Sartre thereby signals that temporality and man's<br />

relationship to the past is the theme of this section of the book. Roquentin<br />

is struggling to understand whether and, if so, how the past can continue to<br />

exist through him and through his writing. He asks: "How can I, who have<br />

not the strength to hold to my own past, hope to save the past of someone<br />

else?" 2 Only two days after declaring that this work "represents the only<br />

justification for my existence", 3 Roquentin gives it up declaring that "the<br />

past did not exist". 4<br />

The journal entry then takes a strange turn when Roquentin reads about<br />

the rape and murder of a little girl named Lucienne. This news triggers a<br />

1 A previous draft of this chapter was given as a paper at the 15 th Biennial<br />

Conference of the North American Sartre Society at Fordham University,<br />

Manhattan, New York City, 27-29 October 2006.<br />

2 Nausea, 95.<br />

3 Ibid., 70.<br />

4 Ibid., 96.


Temporality and the Death of Lucienne in Nausea 47<br />

sort of panic attack in which Roquentin becomes sexually aroused, admits<br />

to a desire for rape, and gives details of the rape from the point of view of<br />

the rapist. There is no previous mention of Lucienne in the book, and the<br />

reader is left to wonder how and why Roquentin's anxiety about the past<br />

and about existence would be catalysed by this news into such a sexualised<br />

episode of panic and self-doubt. The scene seems to represent a thematic<br />

break from the discussion of temporality leading up to it. But it is by<br />

examining the journal entry as a whole in the context of the theme of<br />

temporality that I think we can find an explanation for Roquentin's strange<br />

reaction. I shall argue that Roquentin's reaction to the news of Lucienne's<br />

rape and murder is a demonstration of the temporal structure of<br />

consciousness. By examining this section of Nausea in parallel with<br />

<strong>Sartre's</strong> discussion of temporality in Being and Nothingness, we shall see<br />

that the desire for rape that Roquentin admits to, and the details of the<br />

rape, are all fragments of his own past. This hypothesis will suggest, in<br />

other words, that Roquentin raped and murdered little Lucienne.<br />

In trying to make sense of time and the past, Sartre has Roquentin<br />

formulate two conceptions of time that Sartre will later specifically argue<br />

against in the section on temporality in Being and Nothingness. First, let<br />

us quote Roquentin:<br />

The past did not exist. Not at all. Not in things, not even in my thoughts. It<br />

is true that I had realised a long time ago that mine had escaped me. But<br />

until then I believed that it had simply gone out of my range. For me the<br />

past was only a pensioning off: it was another way of existing, a state of<br />

vacation and inaction; each event, when it had played its part, put itself<br />

politely into a box and became an honorary event [...]. Now I knew: things<br />

are entirely what they appear to be—and behind them [...] there is<br />

nothing. 5<br />

Originally, Roquentin thinks that the past exists, though in a state<br />

disconnected from the present and unable to affect the present. However,<br />

his estrangement from his own past, and his inability to resuscitate the past<br />

by way of his historical research, lead him to conclude that the past does<br />

not exist and that he is "forsaken in the present". 6 On the one hand we<br />

have the idea that the past exists, but ineffectually isolated from the<br />

present, and on the other hand we have the idea that the past does not exist<br />

at all.<br />

5 Ibid., 96.<br />

6 Ibid., 95.


48 Chapter Four<br />

Sartre makes the argument, in Being and Nothingness, that both of<br />

these conceptions of the past are inadequate for the task of explaining the<br />

temporality of consciousness, because they strand consciousness in an<br />

instantaneous present. Sartre writes:<br />

[...] if we begin by isolating man on the instantaneous island of his<br />

present, and if all his modes of being as soon as they appear are destined<br />

by nature to a perpetual present, we have radically removed all methods of<br />

understanding his original relation to the past. We shall not succeed in<br />

constituting the dimension "past" out of elements borrowed exclusively<br />

from the present [.. .]. 7<br />

Sartre is arguing that understanding our existence only in terms of the<br />

present cannot explain the original relationship that we have to our past.<br />

Sartre is not arguing that the past does, in fact, exist in and of itself.<br />

Rather, he is arguing that we cannot understand man's original ontological<br />

connectedness to his past if we understand his modes of being, or his<br />

modes of consciousness, non-temporally in the instantaneous present.<br />

Similarly, Sartre challenges the notion, as expressed by Roquentin, that<br />

"each event puts itself politely into a box and becomes an honorary event".<br />

In this case the past would exist but impotently disconnected from the<br />

present. For Sartre, this conception is no better than a non-existent past:<br />

Popular consciousness has so much trouble in refusing a real existence to<br />

the past that alongside the thesis just discussed [that the past does not exist]<br />

it admits another conception equally imprecise, according to which the past<br />

would have a kind of honorary existence. Being past for an event would<br />

mean simply being retired, losing its efficacy without losing its being. 8<br />

Note that Sartre uses here the same metaphor that he had Roquentin make<br />

use of. In Nausea, the past is "pensioned off to become an "honorary<br />

evenf, while in Being and Nothingness the past is "retired" to become a<br />

kind of "honorary existence". In both books, the same conceptions of time<br />

are described, in the same order, and using the same formulations. It<br />

would seem that, in Nausea and in Being and Nothingness, <strong>Sartre's</strong><br />

understanding and usage of these conceptions of time remained constant.<br />

It would be surprising if Sartre had Roquentin express these erroneous<br />

notions without repudiating them in some manner. And, in fact, what I am<br />

suggesting here is that the strange scene of the news of Lucienne's death is<br />

the repudiation of Roquentin's musings on the nature of time. In Being<br />

7 Being and Nothingness, 161.<br />

8 Ibid., 161.


Temporality and the Death of Lucienne in Nausea 49<br />

and Nothingness, Sartre repudiates these conceptions of the past by<br />

describing the temporal structure of consciousness, and by describing the<br />

past as an integral aspect of this structure. In Nausea, the repudiation of<br />

these conceptions takes a different form. Rather than describing the<br />

temporality of consciousness directly, Sartre has Roquentin illustrate this<br />

temporality by way of his stream-of-consciousness reaction to the news of<br />

Lucienne's murder.<br />

Upon hearing of the fate of Lucienne, Roquentin admits to having a<br />

desire to rape. He describes how this desire comes upon him: "A soft<br />

criminal desire to rape catches me from behind." 9 Note how Sartre has<br />

Roquentin emphasise this formulation of being taken "from behind":<br />

[...] existence takes my thoughts from behind and gently expands from<br />

behind; someone takes me from behind, they force me to think from<br />

behind, therefore to be something, behind me [...] he runs, he runs like a<br />

ferret, "from behind" from behind from behind [...]. 10<br />

Sartre has Roquentin repeat the phrase "from behind" a total of thirteen<br />

times in the space of a page and a half. Why does Sartre place such<br />

emphasis on this formulation?<br />

The reason can be found in <strong>Sartre's</strong> discussion of temporality in Being<br />

and Nothingness. This formulation plays a very specific role in <strong>Sartre's</strong><br />

phenomenology of temporality. I give below three examples from Being<br />

and Nothingness in which Sartre describes the past as an unavoidable<br />

obligation that catches one "from behind":<br />

[...] the past is precisely and only that ontological structure which obliges<br />

me to be what I am from behind. 11<br />

The past is given as a for-itself become in-itself [...]. It has become what it<br />

was—behind me. 12<br />

[...] the Past is an ontological law of the For-itself; that is, everything<br />

which can be a For-itself must be back there behind itself [.. .]. 13<br />

Sartre uses this imagery of being claimed "from behind" to describe our<br />

relation to the past. The past is an ontological structure of consciousness<br />

9<br />

Nausea, 101.<br />

10<br />

Ibid., 102.<br />

11<br />

Being and Nothingness, 172.<br />

12<br />

Ibid., 174.<br />

13<br />

Ibid., 175.


50 Chapter Four<br />

which reveals itself as that which one is obliged to be "from behind". The<br />

specific and repeated use of this phrase signals that the past—this<br />

"ontological law of the For-itself'—is operative in Roquentin's desire for<br />

rape and in his visions of rape. With this in mind, consider again<br />

Roquentin's strange reaction to the news of Lucienne's rape and murder:<br />

"A soft criminal desire to rape catches me from behind." 14 Roquentin does<br />

not choose this desire as a mode of consciousness. Rather, this desire is the<br />

past catching him unaware and claiming him as the facticity of his<br />

existence.<br />

Sartre gives another indication that the rape is from Roquentin's own<br />

past. Sartre emphasises the flight of Roquentin in this section several<br />

times. Let us cite several lines in the account of Roquentin's reaction:<br />

The criminal has fled [...].<br />

I flee. The criminal has fled [...].<br />

[...] I walk, I flee [...].<br />

He runs to flee [...]. 15<br />

Roquentin then literally "flees" by running through the streets of Bouville,<br />

and later flees Bouville altogether. From what is he "fleeing"? The answer<br />

again can be found by reading this scene from Nausea in parallel with<br />

<strong>Sartre's</strong> discussion of temporality. Consider these two examples from<br />

Being and Nothingness, illustrating <strong>Sartre's</strong> use of the imagery of flight to<br />

describe our relationship to the past:<br />

My past is past in the world, belonging to the totality of past being, which I<br />

am, which I flee. 16<br />

The present is a perpetual flight in the face of being [...]. As For-itself it<br />

has its being outside of it, before and behind. Behind, it was its past; and<br />

before, it will be its future. It is a flight outside of co-present and from the<br />

being which it was toward the being which it will be.<br />

Instead of beginning with the three temporal phases of past, present, and<br />

future, and then situating consciousness within the flow of time, Sartre<br />

begins with consciousness and describes how these three temporal modes<br />

arise as an aspect of the nihilating activity of consciousness. Consciousness<br />

temporalises itself. As the For-itself flees itself and its embodied situation,<br />

lA Nausea, 101.<br />

15 Ibid., 102.<br />

16 Being and Nothingness, 285.<br />

17 Ibid., 179.


Temporality and the Death of Lucienne in Nausea 51<br />

it constitutes this situation as the past. The past is revealed to<br />

consciousness in this nihilating flight as the facticity of one's existence.<br />

The past obligates him to exist and to exist within this particular, yet<br />

contingent, reality. The past is not ineffectually "pensioned off and<br />

Roquentin is not isolated on the instantaneous island of his present.<br />

It is important to note that the obligation made by one's past is made<br />

on a pre-reflective level. Earlier in Nausea, Roquentin claims that he is<br />

unable to distinguish imagination from memory:<br />

I can search the past in vain, I can only find these scraps of images and I<br />

am not sure what they represent, whether they are memories or just<br />

fiction. 18<br />

Although he is unable to distinguish memory from fiction on a reflective<br />

level, Roquentin's reaction demonstrates how the past is distinguished<br />

from imaginative fiction at a pre-reflective level. This distinction is not<br />

made by an effort of cognition or reflective examination alone. Rather, the<br />

past invokes an obligation in a way that our imagination cannot. The past<br />

lays a primordial, pre-reflective claim upon who we are. Even while<br />

Roquentin is unable to distinguish memory from imagination reflectively,<br />

the past is making its claim pre-reflectively. The past is distinguished from<br />

imagination as that which is constituted in the nihilating flight of<br />

consciousness.<br />

But how is it possible for Roquentin to describe the pre-reflective<br />

obligation that his past has upon him without being able fully to integrate<br />

this past as memory? What accounts for the unity of the past as memory?<br />

Sartre tells us in Being and Nothingness: "In order for us to 'have' a past,<br />

it is necessary that we maintain it in existence by our very project toward<br />

the future." 19 In order for a past experience to be retained in memory, it is<br />

necessary that it somehow fits, and is accounted for, in the projection of<br />

the self into the future. Past experience is ordered and made sense of, at<br />

least tangentially, by one's projects. Even half-forgotten incidents and<br />

ambiguous experiences are organised as far as possible into the many<br />

overlapping projects that make up a self:<br />

A living past, a half-dead past, survivals, ambiguities, discrepancies: the<br />

ensemble of these layers of pastness is organised by the unity of my<br />

project. It is by means of this project that there is installed the complex<br />

18 Nausea, 32.<br />

19 Being and Nothingness, 639.


52 Chapter Four<br />

system of references which causes any fragment of my past to enter into an<br />

hierarchical, plurivalent organization, as in a work of art [...]. 20<br />

When one is unable to maintain the past as part of a project toward the<br />

future, it becomes lost to the "hierarchical, plurivalent organization" that<br />

informs our memory and our sense of self. However, we should not<br />

understand this as simply an experience or event that is lost to the past by<br />

an otherwise well integrated self that stands apart from the past. This<br />

"complex system of references" that synthesises the past is the self. One<br />

cannot object by saying, for example, that "/ would not forget an<br />

experience like thatY\ because this hypothetical "I" that does remember<br />

would be a wholly different "I" from the "I" that does not remember. The<br />

forgetting or remembering indicates a different "system of references"<br />

constituting a different "I". There is no "I" that stands separate from the<br />

integration of one's past. The "I"—or the ego, psyche, or self—is this<br />

integration. Roquentin's journal documents a growing inability to unify<br />

his past and himself into any sort of context or project. Roquentin has<br />

divested himself of any grounds upon which to justify his existence and<br />

recollect fragments of his past. Without this recollecting synthesis,<br />

Roquentin's ability to integrate his past breaks down and, to the same<br />

extent, his psyche, or ego, disintegrates. Roquentin's journal illustrates<br />

how this disconnection from the past is accompanied by a disconnection<br />

from a sense of agency, of freedom, and of self.<br />

However, Sartre recognises that a memory may stay with us despite<br />

this lack of integration. It may be carried with us via the body:<br />

This is nonetheless a real characteristic of the psyche—not that the psyche<br />

is united to a body but that under its melodic organization the body is its<br />

substance and its perpetual condition of possibility [...]. It is this, finally,<br />

which motivates and to some degree justifies psychological theories like<br />

that of the unconscious, problems like that of the preservation of<br />

memories. 21<br />

Thus, Sartre recognises that the preservation of memory relies on the body<br />

as that which keeps the past available for a synthesising recollection as<br />

memory. The past is the body in that it is only through the body that the<br />

preservation of memory is possible: "[...] the body as facticity is the past<br />

[...]. Birth, the past, contingency, the necessity of a point of view [...]—<br />

20 Ibid., 641-42.<br />

21 Ibid., 444.


Temporality and the Death of Lucienne in Nausea 53<br />

such is the body, such it is for me. In his discussion of the body, Sartre<br />

describes how pain, for example, when not directly apprehended,<br />

"disappears in the ground of corporeality". 23 Similarly, one's past<br />

disappears into the ground of corporeality until apprehended in memory.<br />

In this way, even though a past experience may not be integrated into the<br />

psyche as memory, the experience can stay with the body as a sort of<br />

somatic memory. The body, as "substance" and as "perpetual condition of<br />

possibility", allows for its preservation. This explains how it would be<br />

possible for the past to maintain a hold upon Roquentin without his being<br />

able to recognise and affirm this past as his own. The rape of Lucienne has<br />

stayed with Roquentin's body. The news of Lucienne's death triggers a<br />

somatic or pre-reflective recognition "from behind" that Roquentin<br />

attempts to recover as memory. His psyche, however, is unable to provide<br />

the synthesis or "melodic organisation" that would make sense of this<br />

fragment from his past. Without this synthesis, Roquentin remains<br />

alienated from his past—he remains unable to make sense of these images<br />

of violence from his past.<br />

An encounter earlier in the book gives us a clue as to why Roquentin<br />

might have murdered Lucienne. Roquentin comes across a man staring<br />

lecherously at a little girl. Roquentin describes the scene:<br />

It would have been enough to cough or open the gate. But in my turn I was<br />

fascinated by the little girl's face [...] they were riveted one to the other by<br />

the obscure power of their desires, they made a pair together. 24<br />

The scene is interrupted when the man notices Roquentin. Roquentin is not<br />

concerned for the safety of the little girl. Instead, he is drawn to the<br />

"obscure power of their desires". Sartre tells us in Being and Nothingess<br />

that "the unique goal of desire" is the "reciprocity of incarnation". 25 In the<br />

apparently reciprocating look of the little girl, the "unique goal" of the<br />

man's desire seemed to have been achieved. Rather than objectifying the<br />

man, the little girl's look seemed to complete the man's self-justifying<br />

project. This early example of "The Look" 26 shows the apparent<br />

redemptory power of possessing the look of the Other, and we can imagine<br />

that Roquentin may have been inspired by this scene in his own pursuit of<br />

self-justification. We know, however, that any attempt by Roquentin to<br />

22 Ibid., 431.<br />

23 Ibid., 440.<br />

24 Nausea, 79.<br />

25 Being and Nothingness, 517.<br />

26 Ibid., 340.


54 Chapter Four<br />

possess the look of the Other would have ultimately failed. In his<br />

discussion of "Concrete Relations with Others", 27 Sartre describes a sort of<br />

logical progression as the failure of desire leads to sadism and then to the<br />

ultimate despairing strategy of hate. We can imagine how Roquentin, fully<br />

absorbed in a project of objectification and desire, and moved solely by<br />

the doomed logic of these strategies of objectification, might have ended<br />

up raping and murdering Lucienne.<br />

The book that Roquentin decides to write at the end of Nausea can be<br />

seen as an attempt to remove himself from this spiral of failure by<br />

providing a unifying project for his ego and his past. This book project<br />

would be the "melodic organisation" for a re-integration of his past.<br />

Roquentin says of this book:<br />

[...] a time would come when the book would be written, when it would be<br />

behind me and I think that a little of its clarity might fall over my past.<br />

Then, perhaps, because of it, I could remember my life without<br />

repugnance. 2<br />

Roquentin hopes to relieve himself of the sense of alienation from who he<br />

is, and from who he was: "And I might succeed—in the past, nothing but<br />

the past—in accepting myself." 29 By the end of Nausea, therefore,<br />

Roquentin has come to recognise the unshakeable hold that his past has<br />

upon him, as well as the necessity of giving sense to this past. Roquentin<br />

recognises that he is not isolated or forsaken in the present and that his<br />

existence will seem meaningless to the extent that his past—and therefore<br />

his sense of self—is not unified and justified by a synthesising project.<br />

When Roquentin considers what kind of book to write, he muses:<br />

It would have to be a book [...]. I don't quite know which kind—but you<br />

would have to guess, behind the printed words, behind the pages, at<br />

something which would not exist [...]. 30<br />

Perhaps Nausea is that book. And perhaps behind its printed words,<br />

behind its pages, is a past that does not exist in and of itself but which<br />

catches and lays claim to the author with a rigour that cannot be avoided.<br />

That past is the rape and murder of "little Lucienne".<br />

27 Ibid., 471.<br />

28 Nausea, 178.<br />

29 Ibid.<br />

30 Ibid.


Temporality and the Death of Lucienne in Nausea 55<br />

Works Cited<br />

Sartre, Jean Paul. Being and Nothingness (trans. Hazel E. Barnes). New<br />

York: Washington Square Press, 1966.<br />

—. Nausea (trans. Lloyd Alexander). New York: New Directions, 1964.


CHAPTER FIVE<br />

SARTRE AND NIETZSCHE: BROTHERS IN ARMS<br />

CHRISTINE DAIGLE<br />

Nietzsche and Sartre have been two major figures for the twentieth<br />

<strong>century</strong>. Both stand at the centre of the existentialist movement, one as a<br />

precursor, and the other as its main proponent. Interestingly, the deep<br />

connections found between <strong>Sartre's</strong> and Nietzsche's thought have been<br />

little investigated. It is only recently that works have begun to appear on<br />

this "Nietzschean connection". 1 This chapter will investigate what I<br />

consider to be the crux of the connection: the reconstructive ethical<br />

programme that both propose as a solution to nihilism. 2<br />

Indeed, as I see it, there is a necessary connection between nihilism,<br />

the search for meaning, and ethics. If one is a nihilist and consequently<br />

rejects traditional worldviews, as Nietzsche and Sartre do, then one must<br />

tackle the problem concerning the meaning of existence, i.e. one must<br />

establish a new worldview. Following this rejection, ethics is reconsidered<br />

and new ethical proposals are presented in order to guide the human being<br />

in a post-nihilistic world. In this chapter, I will explain how both Sartre<br />

and Nietzsche share the same kind of nihilism that hinges on an atheistic<br />

worldview. Although there certainly is a difference in their nihilistic<br />

attitudes, I will argue that this divergence ought not to be mistaken for a<br />

divergence in their nihilism. Nietzsche's and <strong>Sartre's</strong> nihilism, regardless<br />

of how it is manifested, will nonetheless result in the same essential<br />

problems. Both thinkers have to deal with the loss of meaning that<br />

accompanies the disappearance of a metaphysical Christian worldview.<br />

1 See my Le Nihilisme est-il un humcmisme? Etude sur Nietzsche et Sartre. For<br />

specific analysis in English of the question of meaning and its articulation with the<br />

problem of nihilism, see my "Sartre and Nietzsche". For a study of the Nietzschean<br />

influence on <strong>Sartre's</strong> literature, see Louette, Sartre contra Nietzsche. One may also<br />

consult the article by Debra Bergoffen, "Nietzsche's Existential Signatures".<br />

2 An earlier draft of this chapter was given as a paper at the Centenary Conference<br />

of the UK Sartre Society at the Institut Frangais, London, in March 2005.


Sartre and Nietzsche: Brothers in Arms 57<br />

Their immanent thinking forces them to look within the human realm<br />

alone for that meaning of life. They both find it in the notion of human<br />

creation. Both claim that although there is no intrinsic meaning to the<br />

world nor to the human's existence, the human being can still infuse<br />

meaning in his own life and in the world. This shedding of meaning, to<br />

both thinkers, is a crucial component of post-nihilistic human existence.<br />

Consequently, this will lead Nietzsche and Sartre to build an ethics that<br />

rests on the reconstruction of human values. Throughout this chapter I will<br />

demonstrate how close Nietzsche and Sartre in fact are, and how, because<br />

of this, they can be considered to be fighting the same battle: the<br />

establishment of a new morality based upon their new answer to the quest<br />

for meaning. I will show that both have similar manners of grounding their<br />

ethics in ontology.<br />

The ''unaware Nietzschean"<br />

Before getting to the crux of the argument, a few things need to be said<br />

about the reception of Nietzsche in <strong>Sartre's</strong> thought. Nietzsche is an<br />

ambiguous figure for Sartre and in fact, Sartre may have misunderstood a<br />

lot of what Nietzsche had to say. Owing to his misunderstanding of<br />

Nietzsche, I call Sartre an "unaware Nietzschean". I believe that Nietzsche<br />

was not only very present in <strong>Sartre's</strong> intellectual universe, but that he<br />

could possibly have influenced his thinking, despite the fact that he<br />

misunderstood his philosophy.<br />

There are many references to Nietzsche in <strong>Sartre's</strong> works. However, it<br />

is not clear that Sartre had a comprehensive understanding of Nietzsche's<br />

writings. For one thing, he uses only a small number of direct quotations<br />

from Nietzsche and some of the quotations that he does in fact use are<br />

taken from Charles Andler's biography on Nietzsche instead of from<br />

Nietzsche himself. 3 It is very likely that he gathered most of his<br />

information from reading this particular biography as well as that of<br />

Daniel Haldvy. It is also speculated that he may have read a selection of<br />

aphorisms published by Jean Bolle in 1934, or even the selection of<br />

aphorisms published as La Volonte de puissance by Genevieve Bianquis in<br />

the late 1930s—however, the latter is doubtful. 4 In his Ecrits dejeunesse<br />

3 This is the biography of Nietzsche in six volumes by Charles Andler. Contat and<br />

Rybalka think that Sartre had read at least volume 2. See their commentary in<br />

Sartre, Merits dejeunesse.<br />

4 Not only is this doubtful, but given the nature of the text and the many editions<br />

that The Will to Power has gone through, it is not clear what picture of Nietzsche<br />

Sartre could have derived from such a reading. The collection of aphorisms that


58 Chapter Five<br />

(Juvenilia), Sartre explicitly claims to have read Nietzsche, though he is<br />

not very specific with regard to which texts he has in fact read. 5<br />

Furthermore, it is possible that Sartre could have learned about Nietzsche<br />

through his earlier education, especially by having to write a paper on him<br />

in a class he took with Brunschvicg. 6 Annie Cohen-Solal explains that at<br />

the moment of writing his early novel, Une Defaite (A Defeat), Sartre did<br />

re-read Nietzsche, specifically Ecce Homo. 1<br />

Nietzsche is an ambiguous figure for Sartre: he says that he is more a<br />

poet than a philosopher; the form of his thought is better than the thought<br />

itself. 8 He loathes Nietzsche's vitalism and his notion of the will to power<br />

(which he accordingly misunderstands as being the brute desire to exert<br />

power over others). Sartre furthermore rejects the Nietzschean notion of<br />

eternal recurrence, which he exposes in Saint Genet, by showing that he<br />

understands the notion in a literal fashion—a reading now rejected by<br />

most, if not all, Nietzschean scholars. His interpretation of Nietszche's<br />

"Overman" also reveals his misunderstanding of Nietzsche, as he presents<br />

this creature as the fruit of a natural evolution in which only the strongest<br />

survive. The one thing that he admires in Nietzsche is the atheism that<br />

leads to "terrestrial thought". It is to Nietzsche's nihilism that he refers<br />

approvingly in the opening pages of Being and Nothingness. In fact,<br />

Nietzsche is the first philosopher mentioned by name in the treatise. I<br />

would like to contend that this is no small thing. 9 The person of Nietzsche<br />

and his life must have interested him immensely since he did write Une<br />

Defaite, a novel on the famous Tribschen triangle (Nietzsche, Richard and<br />

bears the title "The Will to Power" is constituted of notes published posthumously.<br />

I am in agreement with Mazzino Montinari who contests the use of the text and<br />

claims that despite its many avatars The Will to Power as a work by Nietzsche does<br />

not exist. See his "La Volonte depuissance" n'existepas.<br />

5 See Sartre, fccrits dejeunesse, 471.<br />

6 When questioned about his education in an interview by Rybalka, Pucciani and<br />

Gruenheck, Sartre stated that the lycee and the Sorbonne were determining of his<br />

knowledge in philosophy. He was also asked whether he was influenced by<br />

Nietzsche, to which he answered: "I remember giving a seminar paper on him in<br />

Brunschvicg's class, in my third year at the ficole Normale. He interested me, like<br />

many others; but he never stood for anything particular in my eyes" (Rybalka,<br />

Pucciani, Gruenheck, 9).<br />

7 See Cohen-Solal, Sartre, 146.<br />

8 This he says in his "Carnet Midy", a little notebook he had found in the subway<br />

and filled with notes of all kinds (Merits dejeunesse). See my previous works for a<br />

listing of Sartrean statements on Nietzsche and their sources.<br />

9 He says: "[...] but if we once get away from what Nietzsche called 'the illusion of<br />

worlds-behind-the-scene' [...]" (Sartre, Being and Nothingness, 2).


Sartre and Nietzsche: Brothers in Arms 59<br />

Cosima Wagner). Something in Nietzsche's philosophy must have also<br />

been attractive, at least to the young Sartre, as he included several<br />

Nietzschean ideas^h morality in this other early novel, Er VArmenien (Er<br />

-the^Armeniari).vrurther proof of <strong>Sartre's</strong> continued interest in things<br />

Nietzschean can be found in the fact that he wrote a text which Contat and<br />

Rybalka describe as follows:<br />

One of the most mysterious texts by Sartre and one that it seems no-one<br />

has read (it is not yet found and might be lost) is a long study on Nietzsche<br />

that he began in the period of the Notebooks for an Ethics (1947-1948) and<br />

which, according to Sartre, was a part of his ethical research. 10<br />

Although it is not clear whether <strong>Sartre's</strong> interest in Nietzsche stemmed<br />

from a recognised affinity or from a spirit of opposition—seeing himself<br />

as an opponent of Nietzsche—I would like to make the claim that Sartre is<br />

in fact much closer to Nietzsche than he would like to admit. True enough,<br />

if there has been a Nietzschean influence on his thought, this influence can<br />

be seen as slowly disappearing as <strong>Sartre's</strong> preoccupations become<br />

increasingly political. However, I am not concerned with the later<br />

developments of <strong>Sartre's</strong> philosophy, preferring instead to concentrate on<br />

his earlier existentialist philosophy.<br />

Two Nihilists<br />

<strong>Sartre's</strong> and Nietzsche's common point of departure is nihilism. As I<br />

have indicated, the initial reference to Nietzsche in Being and Nothingness<br />

is indeed a reference to his nihilism. In fact, Nietzsche and Sartre hold the<br />

same kind of nihilism even if this nihilism is expressed differently in both<br />

thinkers. As I like to put it, we are dealing with a "militant nihilism" in<br />

Nietzsche and a "passive nihilism" in Sartre. Indeed, Nietzsche is waging<br />

My own translation of: "L'un des textes les plus myste*rieux de Sartre et que nul<br />

ne semble avoir encore lu (il n'est pas localise' a l'heure actuelle, et peut-£tre est-il<br />

perdu) est une longue dtude sur Nietzsche entreprise a l'epoque des Cahiers pour<br />

une morale (1947-1948) et qui, selon ce que Sartre nous en a dit, faisait partie de<br />

sa recherche dthique" (Sartre, Merits de Jeunesse, 194, footnote). Perhaps this is the<br />

analysis of the ethics of the will to power that Sartre had promised in Appendix I<br />

of the Notebooks. But, contrary to what Contat and Rybalka assert, it seems that at<br />

least Simone de Beauvoir read it, as we can gather from this part of their<br />

discussion: "S. de B.—'Then after Being and Nothingness, you began writing a<br />

work on ethics [...]. That was the book in which you wrote an important, long, and<br />

very fine study of Nietzsche.' J.-P. S.—'That formed part of it.'" (Simone de<br />

Beauvoir, Adieux. A Farewell to Sartre, 180).


60 Chapter Five<br />

a war against the metaphysical-religious tradition of Christianity whereas<br />

Sartre is merely the consenting heir to this kind of nihilism. He no longer<br />

needs to fight since the predominant worldview of Nietzsche's time has<br />

already crumbled. All he needs to do is nod approvingly.<br />

Nietzsche's own nihilism comes as a reaction to the nihilism he finds<br />

already active within the metaphysical-religious tradition. This accounts<br />

for the severity of his nihilism. He diagnoses one form of nihilism,<br />

proposing a stronger one as a remedy. The nihilism he diagnoses is that of<br />

the Christian and rationalistic worldview that negates both the human life<br />

and the human being itself through the weight it places on transcendence.<br />

The immanent life of the individual is here seen as devalued in favour of a<br />

supposed "after-life". In other words, the human is seen as striving for an<br />

illusory beyond. Further, the traditional anthropological position is<br />

nihilistic in that it values only the rational aspects of the human being. In<br />

The Antichrist, Nietzsche explains: "If one shifts the centre of gravity of<br />

life out of life into the 'Beyond'—into nothingness—one has deprived life<br />

as such of its centre of gravity." 11 Of course, Nietzsche's critique of<br />

Christianity is intimately tied up with his critique of the philosophical<br />

tradition upon which it is based. After all, "Christianity is Platonism for<br />

'the people'." 12 For him, they both present an ethics of "impossible<br />

virtue". 13 Much of this is also shared by Sartre, but again, he presents his<br />

own criticism in a much more moderate form. His statements are so mild<br />

in comparison to Nietzsche's that we may say that in Sartre we find a<br />

"subdued Nietzsche".<br />

As a remedy to the nihilism he diagnoses, Nietzsche proposes atheism.<br />

Atheism is the first step of his own nihilism. Since God is responsible for<br />

holding the whole system of values together, rejecting God means<br />

destroying the entire system. This, Nietzsche undertakes as a task in order<br />

to clear the ground for the reconstruction of values he has in view.<br />

However, as any close examination of the Madman's announcement of the<br />

death of God would reveal, this liberation from the yoke of an alienating<br />

worldview will first be experienced by humans as abandonment. God is<br />

dead, we killed Him. The madman asks:<br />

Who gave us the sponge to wipe away the entire horizon? What were we<br />

doing when we unchained this earth from its sun? Whither is it moving<br />

now? Whither are we moving? Away from all suns? Are we not plunging<br />

11 Nietzsche, Twilight of the Idols/The Antichrist, §43,165.<br />

12 Nietzsche, Beyond Good and Evil, Preface, 2.<br />

13 Nietzsche, Daybreak, §87, 88.


Sartre and Nietzsche: Brothers in Arms 61<br />

continually? Backward, sideward, forward, in all directions? Is there still<br />

any up or down? Are we not straying as through an infinite nothing? 14<br />

The immediate result is thus a loss of meaning for the human being. It<br />

hence becomes necessary to tackle the question of meaning in hopes of<br />

ultimately establishing new meanings as a replacement.<br />

Sartre agrees with all this. He also considers the death of God as a<br />

genuine liberation for human beings, as expressed in such plays as The<br />

Flies (Les Mouches, 1943) and The Devil and the Good Lord (Le Diable et<br />

le bon Dieu, 1951). As he explains though, this liberation is also a<br />

condemnation as we are entirely responsible for what we make of<br />

ourselves. We are condemned to be free, i.e. to be responsible for<br />

ourselves and for our lives. Sartre has said that the death of God is the<br />

equivalent to the death of all transcendence but with it comes "the opening<br />

of the infinite", 15 that is, the infinite of human possibilities. As he puts it in<br />

his Notebooks for an Ethics, "In this way, man finds himself the heir of the<br />

mission of the dead God: to draw Being from its perpetual collapse into<br />

the absolute indistinctness of night. An infinite mission." 16 Thus, nihilism<br />

brings us to the loss of meaning, a meaning that the human being will have<br />

to create in the wake of God's death and the absence of any transcendent.<br />

Two Optimists<br />

Immediately following nihilism, the human must deal with the<br />

question of the meaning of existence. One must find an answer to the<br />

question of whether life has any meaning and, if the answer is positive,<br />

one must also determine what exactly that meaning is. The rejection of the<br />

traditional worldview means a loss of a meaning-provider and consequently<br />

of meaning itself. One must replace God by providing life with a<br />

new meaning. And it is only through this that one can hope to erect a new<br />

ethics entirely. Interestingly, Nietzsche and Sartre are both optimists in<br />

relation to this quest for meaning. They believe that there is a meaning to<br />

human existence and that we can uncover what that meaning is, since the<br />

human being is the sole meaning-provider.<br />

Their dealings with the problem are in each case very similar. Both<br />

begin by stating that the world does not have intrinsic meaning. 17<br />

14 Nietzsche, The Gay Science, §125,181.<br />

15 Sartre, Notebooks for an Ethics, 34.<br />

16 Ibid., 494.<br />

17 Their theoretical bases for claiming this are different. I have given the details of<br />

this in my previous works (see note 1).


62 Chapter Five<br />

However, they both agree that despite this a priori lack of meaning, the<br />

human being is in a position to create his own meaning. Actually, both see<br />

the human being as an intentional consciousness that sheds meaning on the<br />

world as soon as it grasps it. The human being is thus fundamentally<br />

creative in that she literally makes the world her own.<br />

Interestingly, the first answer given to the problem of meaning in both<br />

thinkers' writings is an aesthetic answer. Both provide us with an aesthetic<br />

justification of life: Nietzsche in The Birth of Tragedy and Sartre in<br />

Nausea. In The Birth of Tragedy, the initial identification of creation as<br />

artistic creation is immediately broadened by Nietzsche into an aesthetic<br />

creation, that is, the creation of both oneself and one's world. However, in<br />

<strong>Sartre's</strong> case, it takes some time before the notion of artistic creation<br />

indicated as the solution to the problem in Nausea is broadened. In fact, it<br />

is only through the development of a number of texts published in the<br />

early 1940s, and through the writings later collected for his Notebooks for<br />

an Ethics, that such a solution fully emerges.<br />

Nietzsche presents an interesting angle on his answer to the question of<br />

the meaning of life in Thus Spoke Zarathustra, namely an angle that is<br />

particularly relevant to his ethical proposals. He says that life is<br />

meaningful only as an expression of the will to power, i.e. as the constant<br />

overcoming and re-creating of oneself. Life can only be meaningful if it is<br />

dynamic and creative. When the individual sets out to become an<br />

Overman, she is on the path of creation and is thusly justified. The human<br />

ought to embody the affirmative and creative ideal of the Overman. I will<br />

address this in more detail in a coming section.<br />

<strong>Sartre's</strong> handling of the problem is similar to that of Nietzsche's,<br />

although in his case the artistic justification persists somewhat longer. In<br />

Nausea, Roquentin finds meaning in his decision to become an artist. 18 He<br />

understands that the creative artistic act is the only act that can redeem<br />

human existence and give it a justification. Otherwise, an individual is<br />

purely contingent in an absurd world. In his Notebooks, Sartre revisits the<br />

problem of the meaning of life and now addresses it in terms of the human<br />

being as project. The human's coming to the world is both a creative and<br />

an interpretive event. By his uttering "il y a", "there is", the human sheds a<br />

layer of meaning on the in-itself, making it a human world. Sartre explains<br />

that "it is not in contemplation that Being will be unveiled as having a<br />

meaning: it is in effort so that man has a meaning, that is, in action [...]. To<br />

True enough, the ending of Nausea does not give the reader a clear indication<br />

that Roquentin will take up that newly-found project. Nevertheless, his decision, as<br />

well as the rationale he comes up with to adopt this artistic stance, is revealing of<br />

<strong>Sartre's</strong> position at this point regarding the question of meaning.


Sartre and Nietzsche: Brothers in Arms 63<br />

act is to posit that Being has a meaning." This is posited as the human<br />

being's duty. Further, Sartre adds the dimension of the Other: I create<br />

meaning for myself and interpret the world in which I act; however, only<br />

through the intervention of the Other can I make my presence in the world<br />

necessary.<br />

Although Sartre is very close to Nietzsche in his dealings with the<br />

question of the meaning of life, this is one aspect that distinguishes him. In<br />

Nietzsche, there is no appeal to the Other. Both however agree that life can<br />

be made meaningful through the creative act of the human being.<br />

Questions of Ethics 1: The Ideal Type<br />

The nihilism of Nietzsche and Sartre opens up the way to a humanistic<br />

ethics. Their ethics are humanistic insofar as they both focus on the<br />

individual and her flourishing. Such ethical developments would have<br />

been impossible under the yoke of an alienating worldview such as that of<br />

the metaphysical-religious tradition. Now that they both have rejected it<br />

and proposed the human as meaning-provider, they are free to adopt a<br />

humanistic stance. 20<br />

Nietzsche's ethics is to be found in three key concepts: the will to<br />

power, the eternal return, and the Overman. Nietzsche conceives of the<br />

human being as a creature that embodies the will to power. Wille zur<br />

Macht is a surpassing or overcoming principle that can be interpreted as a<br />

driving force that pushes beings forwards toward growth. Nietzsche<br />

defines "power" as the feeling of growth. Human beings are motivated by<br />

the will to power just as the whole world is driven by the will to power.<br />

The human being and life are the will to power. This view of the human<br />

being rests at the base of Nietzsche's ethical concept of the Overman. In<br />

Schopenhauer as Educator, Nietzsche says that "We are responsible to<br />

ourselves for our own existence; consequently we want to be the true<br />

helmsman of this existence and refuse to allow our existence to resemble a<br />

Sartre, Notebooks for an Ethics, 486.<br />

20 By "Humanism" here I understand a theory or philosophical viewpoint that<br />

focuses on the human being, its potential and flourishing and has faith in such. I<br />

understand that both Nietzsche and Sartre are critical of humanism as it was<br />

expressed in certain philosophies. However, if they are critical of certain<br />

philosophical viewpoints that claim to be humanist it is, most of the time, because<br />

they consider that these fail in providing the human with a worldview that leaves<br />

room for the human's free development. In that sense, their humanism is more<br />

demanding and requires that no restraints be imposed on the human being (be they<br />

religious or moral).


64 Chapter Five<br />

mindless act of chance." In Thus Spoke Zarathustra, the Overman is this<br />

figure who is successful in being his own master, the true helmsman of his<br />

own existence. He is an over-man, that is, more than a human being. 22<br />

This Ubermensch is thus a human being who is both human and more than<br />

human. She is the human being who has overcome the fragmentation we<br />

find in the metaphysical-religious tradition. She is a reunited being, a<br />

human being who has decided to fully live what she is. She is a human<br />

being who knows that life is will to power, of which she is a particular<br />

instance. She wishes to incarnate and materialize this will to power in<br />

herself. By doing so, she saves herself from alienation and re-affirms her<br />

whole being. Further, she accepts the hypothesis of the eternal return. She<br />

is ready to suppose that her actions, her decisions, and her entire life will<br />

eternally return, repeating every single moment in the exact same way.<br />

The change that occurs between man and the Overman is enormous. This<br />

is why we cannot speak of an elevation to the status of Overman, but must<br />

speak instead of a transfiguration. Even the highest type of man that we<br />

find in Nietzsche is much lower than the Overman. In fact, as Nietzsche<br />

has it, the higher men would call the Overman a devil! 23<br />

The figure of the Overman must be understood in terms of a moral<br />

ideal. It is meant as an emulative figure that illustrates human potential.<br />

Only a human being who would decide on being her own creator, i.e. an<br />

individual who would fully embody the will to power that she is, could<br />

possibly become such an Overman. One may ask whether or not this ideal<br />

type, the Overman, is a state that can be reached by striving human beings.<br />

However, I do not think this is the case. Nietzsche leaves the question<br />

open as to whether there will ever actually be Overmen. When he<br />

announces the coming of superior men, he is not in fact announcing the<br />

coming of the Overman (as these are very distinct figures in his<br />

philosophy). 24 1 think it is more fruitful to think of the Overman as a nonfixed<br />

state of being, or as a state of constant becoming. Indeed, as an<br />

Overman would accept and conceive of life and herself as instances of the<br />

will to power, she would be in this state of becoming. As an embodied will<br />

to power, she would be seeking to grow beyond and to overcome herself,<br />

thus we would find her only in a constant state of flux, a state of perpetual<br />

21 Nietzsche, Untimely Meditations, 128.<br />

22 We must bear in mind that the German term is gender neutral. "Ubermensch"<br />

literally means "over-human being". Had Nietzsche wanted to restrict this<br />

possibility to men, he could have used the term "Ubermann", but he never did.<br />

See Nietzsche, Thus Spoke Zarathustra, "Of Manly Prudence".<br />

24 See the multiple warnings against so-called "higher men" in Thus Spoke<br />

Zarathustra.


Sartre and Nietzsche: Brothers in Arms 65<br />

becoming. This is the meaning of the "over" of "Overman". Furthermore,<br />

the individual must aim at this constant state of becoming in order to live<br />

in accordance with what she really is, i.e. a will to power. This is the key<br />

to the Nietzchean formula found in The Gay Science: ''What Saith thy<br />

Conscience!—Thou shalt become what thou art." 25 In order to achieve<br />

this, the notions that concern the creation of oneself and the creation of<br />

values must come into play.<br />

It is imperative that the individual be her own creator if she is to be on<br />

the path to the Overman. Nietzsche advocates a morality of self-mastery<br />

where the individual makes her own rules. The meaning of the "master<br />

morality" is to be found therein. It has often been misunderstood to refer to<br />

a morality of powerful masters who would keep weaker individuals under<br />

their yoke (as Sartre understood it). However, what Nietzsche has in mind<br />

is in fact quite different. Following the death of God, the individual who is<br />

left only to herself would consequently face an ethical void. No values are<br />

left to stand after nihilism has come to fruition. Nietzsche insists that it<br />

would be a mistake for the individual to proceed by finding another<br />

transcendent being or realm on which to ground her values: the past<br />

experience of Christian morality indicates that any such re-adoption is<br />

likely to result only in the re-alienation of the individual. Instead, the postnihilistic<br />

individual must rely on herself as the ground for values. Only an<br />

ethics that regards the human being as an embodied will to power can<br />

allow for the complete flourishing of the human being.<br />

These descriptions of the human being as becoming or overcoming<br />

itself towards the Overman will sound familiar to Sartreans, who are used<br />

to dealing with the human being as a project in <strong>Sartre's</strong> works. In fact, the<br />

notion of overcoming seems to be appropriate when the time comes to talk<br />

about the for-itself in the world. If Nietzschean ethics revolves around the<br />

notions of the will to power, the eternal return, and the Overman, that of<br />

Sartre revolves around the notions of freedom and authenticity.<br />

In Being and Nothingness, Sartre describes the for-itself and all of its<br />

structures. Therein he explains how the for-itself constantly strives to be<br />

an in-itself. Of course, so long as we are living beings, this project will<br />

always necessarily fail. Only in death can one achieve this. However, this<br />

does not prevent the for-itself from constantly striving towards this<br />

impossible goal; Sartre himself regards the for-itself as a "futile passion".<br />

At a more fundamental ontological level, one can say that the<br />

intentionality of consciousness has made it so that the for-itself is always a<br />

projection of itself, i.e. a projecting of itself in the world that also lets<br />

Nietzsche, Gay Science, 270.


66 Chapter Five<br />

oneself be affected by its being-in-the-world. The for-itself is a potential<br />

being that must aim toward a possible that it will never attain. Again, this<br />

is very close to the Nietzschean descriptions of overcoming. The Overman<br />

is not a fixed goal but it is a constant striving.<br />

Let us recall what the human being as project is striving towards. In the<br />

Notebooks, Sartre says that the individual strives for authenticity by<br />

aiming to be the creator of being and holding her own freedom as the<br />

foundation of herself and the world. By an act of will, freedom makes its<br />

aims essential to its own project. The authentic being is the one who<br />

knows that she is the creator of herself, of the world, and of values. It is<br />

the being that also accepts the responsibility that ensues. The authentic<br />

person gives meaning and value to her life in accepting and affirming<br />

herself as the free creator of a meaningful world. She is a contingent and<br />

free creator. Here we come full circle, since it seems that authenticity is<br />

simply the affirmation of one's own way of being. However, the for-itself<br />

is necessarily a creative being. Authenticity requires that one recognises<br />

and accepts this creative endeavour. Again, we are very close to Nietzsche.<br />

The Overman is the person who recognises and accepts that her being is<br />

the manifestation of the will to power and its dynamic of overcoming.<br />

In both cases then, we are dealing with an ethics that is humanistic in<br />

that it favours the flourishing of the individual above all else. The<br />

individual must strive to be what she is, by embodying the will to power<br />

for one, or freedom for the other. Both ethics thus have as an aim to<br />

actualise the true being of the human rather than some sort of<br />

transcendental ideal. It is in each case an immanent, humanistic ethics.<br />

Questions of Ethics 2: Ethical Rules<br />

Both thinkers have proposed certain rules in order to help the human<br />

being attain either Overman-status or authenticity. In Nietzsche, we are<br />

dealing with vitalism and the eternal return, whereas in Sartre, we are<br />

talking in terms of freedom.<br />

The vitalism of Nietzsche's philosophy is founded upon the will to<br />

power: life is good in itself as will to power. As something that is<br />

intrinsically good, life itself can serve as an ethical standard. Life as will to<br />

power then, is that standard by which the value of everything will be<br />

determined. Nietzsche explains this:<br />

What is good?— All that heightens the feeling of power, the will to power,<br />

power itself in man.<br />

What is bad?— All that proceeds from weakness.


Sartre and Nietzsche: Brothers in Arms 67<br />

What is happiness?— The feeling that power increases — that a resistance<br />

is overcome.<br />

Not contentment, but more power; not peace at all, but war, not virtue, but<br />

proficiency (virtue in the Renaissance style, virtu, virtue free of moralic<br />

acid). 26<br />

Given the passage above, we can formulate the fundamental moral<br />

principle of Nietzsche's ethics as: All that affirms, creates and promotes<br />

life as will to power is good. Individuals must make use of this criterion in<br />

choosing their values. Individuals should pursue the goods that are<br />

conducive to the promotion of life as will to power. In doing this,<br />

individuals will also be promoting their own being as will to power. This,<br />

for Nietzsche, is the way of authenticity and human flourishing. Because,<br />

ultimately, this is Nietzsche's fundamental concern, we can here say that<br />

his ethics of the Overman is truly a humanistic ethics.<br />

Before turning our attention towards <strong>Sartre's</strong> own ethical proposals, it<br />

is necessary to look into the role played by the eternal return in<br />

Nietzsche's ethical realm. It is important to state immediately that this<br />

notion is not meant as an ontological description of how the world actually<br />

is or how it evolves. That is, Nietzsche is not advocating a cyclical theory<br />

of time and the universe. When he advances the eternal return, it is as a<br />

thought experiment that individuals can use as a guide for their actions,<br />

similar in function to a "categorical imperative". 27 We must then<br />

understand the eternal return as an ethical hypothesis. In the section of the<br />

Gay Science entitled "The Greatest Weight" (or "The Heaviest Burden" as<br />

it has also been translated), the eternal return is presented in the<br />

conditional formulation of "what if...?" This hypothesis is used to validate<br />

every choice. The text has it that one is followed by a demon that unveils<br />

the "truth" of the eternal return of the same. The question is then: How<br />

would you act, knowing that your deed will eternally return? How would<br />

you react to such an announcement? 28 Hence, the key to practical<br />

deliberation lies in asking oneself whether the deed that one is about to<br />

commit is something that one wishes to see eternally return. Individuals<br />

26 Nietzsche, The Antichrist, §2, 125-26.<br />

27 It should be noted that every attempt to "prove" the eternal return is to be found<br />

only in the unpublished part of his work. In the published material, the eternal<br />

return is always formulated in the conditional mode. This, of course, would make it<br />

a "hypothetical imperative" in Kantian terms and not a "categorical" one as I state<br />

above. When I refer to the eternal return as something akin to Kant's categorical<br />

imperative, I mean that it can serve the same role: when faced with a decision, one<br />

can take the formula and weigh options according to it.<br />

28 Nietzsche, The Gay Science, §341, 273-74.


68 Chapter Five<br />

must choose now as if even this choice was to recur indefinitely. Only a<br />

choice or a deed that contributes to human flourishing is a choice or deed<br />

that one will wish to see eternally recur.<br />

Will to power and eternal return are articulated together as ethical<br />

guidelines. A choice is good if it promotes life as will to power. It is also<br />

good if one wants it to recur eternally which, consequently, will be the<br />

case only if the choice serves to promote life as will to power. The goal<br />

being to realise oneself as embodied will to power, that is, to lead a<br />

flourishing human life as involving both the constant overcoming of<br />

oneself and the creation of oneself, the will to power and eternal return can<br />

assist us in making the right choices, which are, according to Nietzsche,<br />

life-promoting choices.<br />

If we were to formulate a Sartrean fundamental moral principle it<br />

would read like this: All that affirms, respects and promotes freedom is<br />

good; all that negates and destroys it is bad. Human beings must make<br />

their choices in view of the promotion of their own freedom, since they<br />

can strive towards authenticity only by promoting themselves as the free<br />

beings that they truly are. In the Sartrean scheme, there is no room for a<br />

device like the eternal return. In fact, he was very critical of it in his Saint<br />

Genet. 29 His reasons for being so critical, however, are misplaced. He<br />

understands the eternal return as a nihilistic attitude. He also takes<br />

Nietzsche to mean it literally, that is, as a cyclical theory of time or<br />

ontological model of the universe. Accordingly, his reading of the notion<br />

of the eternal return is basically ill-founded. That being said, this does not<br />

mean that Sartre would have adopted such an ethical device, had he read<br />

Nietzsche properly. Nonetheless, the ethical rule that he does propose is<br />

very close to that of Nietzsche. In fact, it can be read as being essentially<br />

the same if one looks closely at the relationship between the will to power<br />

and freedom.<br />

Nietzsche conceives of freedom as "something one has and does not<br />

have, something one wants, something one conquers 99 . 30 This formula<br />

from Twilight of the Idols is reminiscent of <strong>Sartre's</strong> description of the foritself<br />

as freedom and as the being that is what he is not and is not what he<br />

is. 31 For Nietzsche, freedom is something within the human being 32 that<br />

See Sartre, Saint Genet Actor and Martyr, 346-50.<br />

30<br />

Nietzsche, Twilight of the Idols/The Anti-Christ, §38,103.<br />

31<br />

See Being and Nothingness for numerous instances of this formula describing<br />

the for-itself.<br />

32<br />

Could it be that there lies the ultimate difference between the two? Freedom is<br />

something one has for Nietzsche whereas freedom is something one is in Sartre.<br />

The very being of the human being is freedom in Sartrean philosophy. For


Sartre and Nietzsche: Brothers in Arms 69<br />

one must assume and actualise, something that one must will, just like in<br />

Sartre. Peter Caws's description of Sartrean freedom reveals how close<br />

this concept is to that of the will to power. He says: "What Sartre calls<br />

'original freedom' is, therefore, nothing other than the presuppositionless<br />

and undetermined upsurge of the for-itself in every moment of my life", 33<br />

just like the Nietzschean will to power.<br />

For some time I have conceived of the fundamental divergence<br />

between Nietzsche and Sartre in the following terms: in the end, will to<br />

power and freedom can be conceived of as referring to the same<br />

fundamental human drive. What differs from Nietzsche to Sartre is that<br />

Nietzsche says that this will to power is also active in the world outside of<br />

human beings, while Sartre speaks of freedom only in relation to the<br />

human being. For example, Zarathustra exclaims that wherever he finds<br />

life, he finds will to power at work. 34 This has been interpreted to mean<br />

that human beings, animals, plants, and even the world itself as a living<br />

and evolving organism, are all expressions of the will to power. The will<br />

to power would thus be a force at play beyond the human being,<br />

something that Sartrean freedom is not.<br />

However, this divergence might not withstand scrutiny. If one<br />

interprets Nietzsche as a proto-phenomenologist, we could find the same<br />

ontological setting as that which we find in Being and Nothingness, i.e. a<br />

phenomenological ontology that revolves around the notion of an<br />

intentional consciousness. 35 Simply and very briefly put, it could be that,<br />

when Nietzsche claims that "This world is the will to power—and nothing<br />

besides", 36 —he could be referring to the same thing as the circuit of<br />

selfness that Sartre describes in Being and Nothingness, Nietzsche talks<br />

about being itself as being irrelevant for humans; what really matters is the<br />

world as it exists for us. In this case, the world is necessarily the world of<br />

Nietzsche, the being of the human being is will to power. Is will to power<br />

freedom? As I will argue now, the answer is yes.<br />

33 Caws, Sartre, 115.<br />

34 Nietzsche, Thus Spoke Zarathustra, 137.<br />

35 Granted, it is difficult to equate Sartrean consciousness with Nietzschean<br />

consciousness, but I do not think the task is impossible. As a suggestive<br />

experiment, compare the multi-layered, labyrinthine self described by Nietzsche in<br />

different texts (particularly Daybreak and The Gay Science), with the complex<br />

consciousness described by Sartre in the Transcendence of the Ego.<br />

36 Nietzsche, The Will to Power, §1067, 550. This is the most famous utterance of<br />

this idea. However, it stems from the Nachlass. Its corresponding published<br />

aphorism states it somewhat differently: "The world viewed from inside, the world<br />

defined and determined according to its 'intelligible character'—it would be 'will<br />

to power' and nothing else" (Nietzsche, Beyond Good and Evil, §36,48).


70 Chapter Five<br />

the will to power. Since human beings are fundamentally an embodiment<br />

of will to power and since they make the world in accordance with<br />

themselves, the world is necessarily a world of will to power. If this is the<br />

case, we would be dealing with the same ontological setting in both<br />

Nietzsche's and <strong>Sartre's</strong> philosophy. Hence, what I had previously<br />

identified as a fundamental divergence would vanish, revealing that they<br />

are in fact much closer than I had initially thought. Whatever the case may<br />

be, even if the divergence were to persist, one would still have to<br />

recognize that their ethical proposals are very much akin.<br />

Conclusion: Brothers in Arms<br />

I have shown that the philosophies of Nietzsche and Sartre stand very<br />

close together in the realm of ethics. They both share the same nihilism<br />

and both propose the same solution to it, namely a solution that is<br />

elaborated through a positive and optimistic answer to the question of the<br />

meaning of existence. The ethics founded upon their respective ontologies<br />

present an ideal of authenticity that, in each case, urges the human being to<br />

strive towards self-actualisation. This is the meaning shared between the<br />

Nietzschean Overman and <strong>Sartre's</strong> notion of authenticity. My claim is that<br />

the Overman is essentially a Sartrean authentic person and vice versa.<br />

One is still left to question whether or not there remains any<br />

divergence between the two (especially now that I contend that the<br />

divergence pertaining to the will to power as worldly phenomenon does<br />

not hold). However, I think there is still a divergence, particularly in the<br />

ethical realm. Nietzsche's ethics is humanistic, but, perhaps above all, it<br />

remains individualistic. There is little opening to the Other in his ethical<br />

philosophising and when Nietzsche does address relationships among<br />

humans, he slips into a messy political talk that is difficult to reconcile<br />

with his ethical views. 37 In contrast, Sartre explicitly presents an opening<br />

to the Other. It could be a failed one, as some have argued, but at least<br />

there is the attempt along with the recognition that one cannot be ethical<br />

without the Other. 38<br />

I have discussed this tension in my "Nietzsche: Virtue Ethics... Virtue Politics?"<br />

In this article, I argue that Nietzsche's ethics is akin to virtue ethics. I then discuss<br />

how the aristocratic politics clashes with an ethics that favours the flourishing of<br />

all and conclude that in order to be coherent, Nietzsche must stand for a "virtue<br />

politics", i.e. a politics that would favour the flourishing of all in the group.<br />

More often than not, commentators take the failed opening to the Other as the<br />

backbone of their argument for the abandonment of the Notebooks for an Ethics.<br />

Some have argued that <strong>Sartre's</strong> opening is successful only when he seriously


Sartre and Nietzsche: Brothers in Arms 71<br />

That being said, I have shown that in the ethical realm, Nietzsche and<br />

Sartre are really fighting the same battle despite the fact that they express<br />

their ethical views differently. They want to liberate the human being from<br />

the yoke of an alienating worldview in order for her to be capable of<br />

ethical growth in her striving towards Sartrean authenticity and<br />

Nietzschean overcoming. Theirs is thus truly a humanistic ethics.<br />

Works Cited<br />

Beauvoir, Simone de. Adieux. A Farewell to Sartre (trans. Patrick<br />

O'Brian). New York: Random House, 1984.<br />

Bergoffen, Debra. "Nietzsche's Existential Signatures", International<br />

Studies in Philosophy, 34, no. 3 (2002), 83-93.<br />

Caws, Peter. Sartre. Boston: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1979.<br />

Cohen-Solal, Annie. Sartre 1905-1980. Paris: Gallimard, 1999.<br />

Daigle, Christine. Le Nihilisme est-il un humanisme? Etude sur Nietzsche<br />

et Sartre. Sainte-Foy: Presses de l'Universite Laval, 2005.<br />

—. "Nietzsche: Virtue Ethics...Virtue Politics?" Journal of Nietzsche<br />

Studies, 32 (2006), 1-21.<br />

—. "Sartre and Nietzsche", Sartre Studies International, 10, no. 2 (2004),<br />

195-210.<br />

—. "The Ambiguous Ethics of Beauvoir", in Existentialist Thinkers and<br />

Ethics (ed. Christine Daigle), 120-41. Montreal: McGill / Queen's<br />

University Press, 2006.<br />

Louette, J.-F. Sartre contra Nietzsche ("Les Mouches", "Huis Clos", u Les<br />

Mots"). Grenoble: Presses Universitaires de Grenoble, 1996.<br />

Montinari, Mazzion. "La Volonte de puissance" n f existe pas (ed. P.<br />

DTorio). Paris: Editions de l'Eclat, 1996.<br />

Nietzsche, Friedrich. Beyond Good and Evil (trans. W. Kaufmann). New<br />

York: Vintage Books, 1966.<br />

tackles Marxism in his Marxistic treatise, Critique of Dialectical Reason. For my<br />

part, I remain sceptical of the Sartrean success. As I have said earlier, I am<br />

concerned with <strong>Sartre's</strong> existentialist philosophy. The conflictual relationships he<br />

has so strongly delineated in Being and Nothingness defeat in advance any attempt<br />

to resolve the said conflicts. It is also not true that Simone de Beauvoir is<br />

successful in that matter. If she is indeed successful in elaborating an ethics in<br />

Ethics of Ambiguity, it is because she does not develop it on the basis of the<br />

Sartrean ontology as has been claimed, but rather upon her own understanding of<br />

human reality as ambiguous and upon her own understanding of interpersonal<br />

relationships. She sees these as potentially conflictual, but not irremediably so. A<br />

way out of conflict is possible. See my "The Ambiguous Ethics of Beauvoir".


72 Chapter Five<br />

—. Daybreak (trans. R. J. Hollingdale). Cambridge: Cambridge University<br />

Press, 1997.<br />

—. The Gay Science (trans. W. Kaufmann). New York: Vintage Books,<br />

1974.<br />

—. Thus Spoke Zarathustra (trans. R. J. Hollingdale). New York: Penguin<br />

Books, 1969.<br />

—. The Will to Power (trans. W. Kaufmann and R. J. Hollingdale). New<br />

York: Vintage Books, 1968.<br />

—. Twilight of the Idols/The Antichrist (trans. R. J. Hollingdale). New<br />

York: Penguin Books, 1968.<br />

—. Untimely Meditations (trans. R. J. Hollingdale). Cambridge: Cambridge<br />

University Press, 1983.<br />

Rybalka, Michel, Oreste F. Pucciani and Susan Gruenheck. "An Interview<br />

with Jean-Paul Sartre on May 12 and 19, 1975", in The Philosophy of<br />

Jean-Paul Sartre (ed. Paul Arthur Schilpp). La Salle (Illinois): Open<br />

Court, 1981.<br />

Sartre, Jean-Paul. Being and Nothingness (trans. H. E. Barnes). New York:<br />

Philosophical Library, 1956.<br />

—. Merits de jeunesse (eds Michel Contat and Michel Rybalka). Paris:<br />

Gallimard, 1990.<br />

—. Notebooks for an Ethics (trans. D. Pellauer). Chicago: Chicago<br />

University Press, 1992.<br />

—. Saint Genet Actor and Martyr (trans. B. Frechtman). New York:<br />

George Braziller, 1963.


CHAPTER SIX<br />

1945-2005:<br />

EXISTENTIALISM AND HUMANISM<br />

SIXTY YEARS ON<br />

DEBORAH EVANS<br />

In his seminal work, Le Siecle de Sartre (Sartre, Philosopher of the<br />

Twentieth Century) published in 2000, Bernard-Henri L6vy states that<br />

Sartre "is not a humanist". In this opinion he is joined by the Communist<br />

Jean Kanapa, one of <strong>Sartre's</strong> former pupils, who wrote a work in 1947<br />

entitled VExistentialisme n'est pas un humanisme (Existentialism is not a<br />

Humanism). So the question I want to address is this: is Sartrean philosophy<br />

a humanist philosophy and what, specifically, should we understand<br />

by <strong>Sartre's</strong> use of the term "humanist"? What relevance does his humanism<br />

have for us today? 1<br />

In <strong>Sartre's</strong> La Nausee (Nausea, 1938), Antoine Roquentin laments of<br />

the humanist: "Alas, I've known so many!" He attacks the radical humanist,<br />

the so-called "left-wing" humanist, the implicit humanism of the<br />

communist writer, the Catholic humanist, the humanist philosopher, the<br />

"joyful humanist" and even (foreshadowing later attacks on <strong>Sartre's</strong> own<br />

philosophy) the "sombre humanist". Sartre also appears to parody a certain<br />

type of humanism, which takes man as an end in himself, through the<br />

character of the self-taught man, the Autodidact. Antoine Roquentin, the<br />

protagonist who wants to avoid being labelled at all costs, finally<br />

1 A draft of this chapter was given at the special conference of the UK Sartre<br />

Society, commemorating <strong>Sartre's</strong> centenary, at the Institut Frangais, London, in<br />

March 2005.<br />

2 "H&as, j'en ai tant connu!" (Sartre, La Nausee, 165). All translations from<br />

French are my own.


74 Chapter Six<br />

declares in these well-known words: "I'm not stupid enough to call myself<br />

an 'anti-humanist'. I'm not a humanist, that's all."<br />

However, Sartre is more than Roquentin. The Second World War<br />

proved a decisive catalyst in the development of the thinking of the young<br />

philosopher. <strong>Sartre's</strong> experiences of capture, internment, and finally<br />

liberation left an indelible mark on the evolution of his thought, marking a<br />

rite of passage from youth to maturity. In a letter to Simone de Beauvoir,<br />

dated 4 September 1939, Sartre writes: "[W]e heard that war had been<br />

declared and it's as if a wall was erected behind me to cut me off from my<br />

past life." In October 1945, he gave a lecture at the Club Maintenant in<br />

Paris entitled "L'Existentialisme est un humanisme" ("Existentialism is a<br />

Humanism"). This relatively short expose of existential thought was<br />

destined to change forever the course of twentieth-<strong>century</strong> philosophy. The<br />

lecture had two main aims. One was to popularise certain aspects of<br />

existential philosophy contained in <strong>Sartre's</strong> recently published magnum<br />

opus: Uiltre et le neant (Being and Nothingness, 1943). However, the<br />

lecture was simultaneously an attempt by Sartre to stave off numerous<br />

potentially damaging allegations made against existentialism, specifically<br />

as a humanist philosophy. To be an existentialist, Sartre claimed, had<br />

become such an abused term that it had come to signify nothing at all.<br />

Sartrean existentialism was not short of its critics. Pope Pius XII<br />

condemned its "terrifying nihilism" and censured <strong>Sartre's</strong> work by placing<br />

it on the Index Librorum Prohibitorum (Index of forbidden books) in<br />

1948, where he joined such illustrious names as Nietzsche, Sterne,<br />

Voltaire, Defoe and Balzac. But existentialism was no less pilloried by<br />

secular critics who charged it with being a philosophy of isolation,<br />

pessimism, despair, anarchy, vulgarity, baseness, and even ugliness. Not<br />

least, existentialism was charged with amorality because Sartre, restating<br />

the position of Dostoyevsky, affirmed the humanistic starting-point of<br />

existentialism: "If God did not exist, everything would be permitted." 5 If<br />

there are no universal values, no God whose commandments we must<br />

obey, we can all behave exactly as we like. We cannot judge the actions of<br />

others since all actions are equally valid. In this scenario, how can Sartre,<br />

seizing on the opportunity to popularise existential philosophy and to<br />

3 "[J]e ne commettrai pas la sottise de me dire 'anti-humaniste'. Je ne suis pas<br />

humaniste, voila tout" (ibid., 167).<br />

4 "[0]n a appris la declaration de guerre et c'&ait comme si un mur se dressait<br />

derriere moi pour me couper de ma vie passee" (Sartre, Lettres au Castor, I, 278-<br />

79).<br />

5 "Si Dieu n'existait pas, tout serait permis" (Sartre, L'Existentialisme est un<br />

humanisme, 36).


1945-2005: Existentialism and Humanism Sixty Years On 75<br />

sketch some of its ethical implications, avoid the twin pitfalls of anarchy<br />

and social amorality, implied in Dostoyevsky's statement?<br />

A further problem area of <strong>Sartre's</strong> thought, in both L'Etre et le neant<br />

and L'Existentialisme est un humanisme, concerns his alleged startingpoint<br />

of the Cartesian cogito. The maitrise (dominion) of the "I think" as<br />

the isolated presence of a pure subjectivity was considered by both<br />

Communist and Christian critics alike to preclude any form of concrete<br />

action in, or social solidarity with, the outside world. The existentialist was<br />

considered to live in a Kierkegaardian world of "inwardness of thought".<br />

To certain Communist critics, singled out for particular attention by Sartre,<br />

existentialism appeared nothing more than an abstract bourgeois ideology.<br />

How could such a misunderstanding have arisen? <strong>Sartre's</strong> reply to the<br />

various charges of anarchy, amorality, pessimistic nihilism and despair is<br />

definitive. He does not set out to prove the non-existence of God, but<br />

merely affirms that, even if God did exist, nothing would be changed. We<br />

are delaisses (abandoned), "thrown" into the world. But far from<br />

engendering a humanistic philosophy of despair and pessimism, this very<br />

abandonment is the source of metaphysical optimism since human beings<br />

now become the source of all values and meanings. To illustrate this point,<br />

Sartre cites the example of the student who asks his advice as to whether<br />

he should stay with his dependent mother or abandon his mother and go<br />

off to war. Of course, Sartre cannot give a ready-made answer to this<br />

moral problem; there is no a priori moral stance which can justify either<br />

course of action: "[Y]ou are free, [so] choose, that is to say, invent." 6 In<br />

this sense, existential philosophy is a direct correlate of a metaphysical<br />

humanism which seeks in the human subject an absolute foundation for all<br />

knowledge and values. But in this knowledge and in these values lies<br />

anguish. We are alone, without excuse. There is no justification for our<br />

existence. None whatsoever. As Sartre famously puts it, "man is condemned<br />

to be free". 7 More than this, however, we are precisely the sum<br />

total of our freely-chosen actions in any given situation. A coward "is"<br />

not—if we wish, we can even place that "is" in Husserlian parentheses, by<br />

literally "suspending" its meaning—because each coward is nothing more<br />

than a coward by virtue of their own particular actions: each is responsible<br />

for his or her own cowardice. In other words, we "create" ourselves. There<br />

is no a priori determinism, no in-built "character"; we are never the<br />

hapless victims of our own passions. In a word we are not only free, we<br />

incarnate freedom itself, we are freedom, and it is this non-essentialist<br />

concept of freedom that Levy prizes above all as <strong>Sartre's</strong> legacy to the<br />

"[V]ous etes libre, choisissez, c'est-a-dire inventez" (ibid., 47).<br />

7 "[L]'homme est condamne' a §tre libre" (ibid., 37).


76 Chapter Six<br />

twentieth <strong>century</strong>. However, perhaps a non-essentialist view of the human<br />

being is not totally incompatible with a certain humanist tradition which<br />

places "Man", as a generic category, at the centre of philosophic enquiry.<br />

As Sartre famously remarked: "[W]e are in a world where there are only<br />

men." 8<br />

What would Nietzsche have made of <strong>Sartre's</strong> conception of freedom?<br />

In Beyond Good and Evil, he states:<br />

For the desire for "freedom of will" in that metaphysical superlative sense<br />

which is unfortunately still dominant in the minds of the half-educated, the<br />

desire to bear the whole and sole responsibility for one's actions, and to<br />

absolve God, world, ancestors, chance, society from responsibility for<br />

them, is nothing less than the desire to be that causa sui and with more<br />

than Munchhausen temerity, to pull oneself into existence out of the<br />

swamp of nothingness by one's own hair. 9<br />

The charge of the isolated subjectivity of the existentialist was to prove<br />

difficult to refute. The alleged Cartesian origin of <strong>Sartre's</strong> thought,<br />

beginning with the pure subjectivity of the "I think", has provoked over<br />

the course of the last half <strong>century</strong> a vast amount of critical attention,<br />

particularly from Anglo-Saxon commentators. In this context I think it<br />

would be helpful to maintain the distinction which Sartre maintains<br />

throughout his lecture between, on the one hand, Cartesian philosophy<br />

and, on the other, the philosophy of Descartes. Cartesian philosophy is<br />

concerned with the rationalistic analysis of the structures of individual<br />

human thought or consciousness, as is L'Etre et le neant, As Sartre<br />

remarks in this work: "[T]he only possible starting-point was the Cartesian<br />

cogito" 10 He takes up this theme again, this time with a humanist<br />

emphasis, in L'Existentialisme est un humanisme:<br />

Our starting-point is in fact the subjectivity of the individual [...] because<br />

we want a doctrine based on truth, [...]. There can be no other truth at the<br />

outset than this: / think therefore I am, this is the absolute truth of<br />

consciousness attaining itself. [...] this theory is the only one which gives a<br />

dignity to man, the only one which does not make him into an object. 11<br />

"[N]ous sommes sur un plan ou il y a seulement des hommes" (ibid., 36).<br />

9<br />

Nietzsche, Beyond Good and Evil, 51<br />

10<br />

"[L]e seul depart possible gtait le cogito cartesien" (Sartre, Ufctre et le neant,<br />

290).<br />

11<br />

"Notre point de depart est en effet la subjectivity de Tindividu, [...] parce que<br />

nous voulons une doctrine basee sur la ve*ritd, [...]. II ne peut pas y avoir de v&ite'<br />

autre, au point de depart, que celle-ci: je pense done je suis, e'est la la ve'rite'


1945-2005: Existentialism and Humanism Sixty Years On 77<br />

However, Sartre is never content merely to follow. As Nik Farrell Fox<br />

states in his excellent book, The New Sartre, "<strong>Sartre's</strong> attachment to the<br />

Cartesian cogito in his early work is never a complete or exhaustive<br />

one". 12 The later Sartre tries to distance himself from an overtly Cartesian<br />

emphasis on his early work, and his comments made during the 1960s<br />

seemed to resonate with the times when he said it was never his intention<br />

to reiterate Cartesianism. But what exactly do we understand by this term<br />

"Cartesianism", specifically from a humanistic perspective? Sartre avoids<br />

the substantiality of the subject by creating the pre-reflective cogito as the<br />

foundation to its Cartesian counterpart. As he puts it very succinctly in<br />

VEtre et le neant: "[T]here is a pre-reflective cogito which is the<br />

condition of the Cartesian cogito." 13<br />

First described in La Transcendance de VEgo {The Transcendence of<br />

the Ego, 1936), the pre-reflective cogito challenges some fundamental<br />

assumptions made by Descartes. For Sartre, Descartes assumes the<br />

subjective, isolated presence of the cogito which exists at a specific<br />

moment in time: the instant or now. And it is this aspect of the Cartesian<br />

cogito which Sartre is, of course, anxious to challenge. He does this in two<br />

main ways. Firstly, in order to get outside this problem of instantaneity,<br />

the pour-soi (for-itself) is constructed as a non-material, temporal being. It<br />

is itself this process of temporalisation by which the past and present<br />

ecstasies are continually transcended towards an "open" future. Secondly,<br />

to refute the charge of subjectivity, while at the same time distancing<br />

himself somewhat from his erstwhile mentor, Husserl, the ego is made<br />

transcendent to consciousness. It does not "inhabit" the pour-soi. Then, in<br />

a further radical move for phenomenology, the Sartrean cogito is called<br />

into question by the presence of the Other. The existence of the Other is as<br />

certain as our own existence, and a condition of it. In this way, the charge<br />

of subjective "isolation" implied in the Cartesian cogito is counterbalanced<br />

by Sartre with Hegel's intuition of the Other. In other words, it is<br />

counterbalanced by the ontological significance of alterity. Only the Other<br />

has power to confer value to my own subjectivity. I may consider myself<br />

to be good, bad, cunning, out-going, generous, etc., but I cannot confer<br />

these values on myself outside of the presence of others.<br />

absolue de la conscience s'atteignant elle-m§me. [...] cette thdorie est la seule a<br />

donner une dignitd a rhomme, c'est la seule qui n'en fasse pas un objet" (Sartre,<br />

VExistentialisme est un humanisme, 63-64, 65).<br />

12 Farrell Fox, The New Sartre, 14.<br />

13 "[I]l y a un cogito prgrgflexif qui est la condition du cogito carte'sien" (Sartre,<br />

L'fore et le neant, 19).


78 Chapter Six<br />

Nevertheless, Simone de Beauvoir was clearly unhappy with critics'<br />

understanding of Ufctre et le neant, particularly in connection with<br />

<strong>Sartre's</strong> use of the term "useless passion" to describe the pour-soi: the<br />

knowingly futile attempt of self-consciousness to become its own<br />

foundation. One of the principal aims of her 1947 essay, Pour une Morale<br />

de Vambiguite (The Ethics of Ambiguity), is precisely to re-examine the<br />

term "useful", opening it up to the fundamental ambiguity of existential<br />

meaning: "[A]t the level of description where Being and Nothingness is<br />

situated, the word useful has not yet been given any meaning [...]. In the<br />

original abandonment where man rises up, nothing is useful, nothing is<br />

useless." 14 In a parallel trajectory to <strong>Sartre's</strong> lecture, then, the aim of<br />

Beauvoir's essay was to give a lively defence of certain allegations made<br />

against existentialism, in particular that it was a philosophy of the absurd,<br />

that it gave rise to a "sterile anguish" and an "empty subjectivity". These<br />

charges are, in Beauvoir's typically brusque manner, publicly rebuffed.<br />

Although <strong>Sartre's</strong> relationship to the Cartesian tradition has long been<br />

the object of much critical scrutiny, it is <strong>Sartre's</strong> relationship to Heidegger<br />

which, over the course of the last sixty years or so, has arguably caused the<br />

most controversy. Sartre places himself squarely in the tradition of<br />

atheistic existentialist thinkers, and further implicates Heidegger in his<br />

"humanist" project. Levy rightly asserts that "Sartre is not a French<br />

Heidegger". 15 However, <strong>Sartre's</strong> relationship to Heidegger is fundamentally<br />

problematic. It begins with his implicit acceptance of Henri Corbin's<br />

translation of Dasein (meaning literally "There-being") as "human<br />

reality". Jacques Derrida famously denounced "human reality" as a<br />

"monstrous translation" of Dasein in his essay "Les Fins de l'homme"<br />

("The Ends of Man"), and a symptom of a false anthropological reading of<br />

Heidegger's Being and Time. 16 Heidegger would, of course, refute any<br />

suggestion that the ontology contained in his Sein und Zeit (Being and<br />

Time) is humanistic: his well-known "Letter on Humanism", published in<br />

1947, was his reply to <strong>Sartre's</strong> UExistentialisme est un humanisme: "[...]<br />

—isms", writes Heidegger, "have for a long time now been suspect". 17<br />

Non-metaphysical, non subject-based, post-structuralist theorists throughout<br />

the 1960s and 70s—Barthes, Foucault and Derrida, amongst others—<br />

have taken this aspect of Heidegger's thought through to its logical<br />

14 "[A]u niveau de description ou se situe Ufctre et le Neant, le mot utile n'a pas<br />

encore regu de sens [...]. Dans le delaissement originel ou l'homme surgit, rien<br />

n'est utile, rien n'est inutile" (Beauvoir, Pour une Morale de Vambiguite, 17).<br />

15 "Sartre n'est pas le Heidegger frangais" (B.-H. Le\y, Le Siecle de Sartre, 171).<br />

16 Derrida, "Les Fins de rhomme", in Marges de la philosophic 131-64.<br />

17 Heidegger, Basic Writings, 219.


1945-2005: Existentialism and Humanism Sixty Years On 79<br />

conclusion: literally the "de-struction" of the subject, or what we could<br />

call, in Derridean terms, the "dis-placement" of the subject.<br />

Heidegger in particular criticises what he perceives to be <strong>Sartre's</strong><br />

philosophical starting-point, Cartesian subjectivity, for failing to address<br />

adequately the question of Being. He writes: "Da-sein ist je meines" ("D


80 Chapter Six<br />

Sartre a philosopher of freedom rather than a humanist, in the sense that<br />

man is not taken as an end in himself.<br />

However, as always when reading philosophy, Sartre reads Heidegger<br />

with the eye of a literary writer as much as with the eye of a philosopher.<br />

The neat formula—"existence precedes essence"—immediately provides<br />

him with a basis for a phenomenological ethics: "If, in fact, existence<br />

precedes essence [...] man is free, man is freedom." 19 Sartre seizes on the<br />

opportunity to oppose a long line of literary and philosophical figures such<br />

as Diderot, Voltaire and Kant, who argue that "essence precedes<br />

existence" since, according to these thinkers, we all possess a universal<br />

human nature. Sartre inverts the term, and we need to remember here that<br />

this idea of a human nature does not just refer to a type of nineteenth<strong>century</strong><br />

cultural tombstone. Today for example, Noam Chomsky advocates<br />

that scientific knowledge, without reference to a type of "human nature",<br />

would be impossible. 20 However, for Sartre, the attraction of turning<br />

several hundred years of philosophical enquiry on its head must have been<br />

enormous. And then, what could be more readily comprehensible to the<br />

general public than to associate the notion of the "authentic" and "inauthentic",<br />

taken from Heidegger, with both "existence" and "essence"?<br />

The "inauthentic", on this reading, would be associated with an<br />

"essentialist" reading of human subjectivity, whilst the "authentic" would<br />

be a correlate of that raw, nauseating experience of human existence,<br />

tinged with anguish, describing that fundamental existential state of<br />

"being-in-question" found in La Nausee, Les Chemins de la Liberte<br />

{Roads to Freedom, 1945), and in certain sections of L'&re et le neant.<br />

Authentic existence is based on freedom of choice, responsibility, the<br />

perpetual transcendence of consciousness in the project of being, the<br />

perpetual mise-en-question (bringing into question, or interrogation) of our<br />

being. Inauthentic existence is based on a denial of choice, responsibility<br />

and human freedom. It is rooted in stagnation and immanence and conveys<br />

all the characteristics of the en-soi (in-itself). Like the salauds (bastards)<br />

of La Nausee, the mauvaisefoi (bad faith) of inauthentic existence means<br />

openly embracing the formula "essence precedes existence".<br />

For Sartre, on the contrary, we are "not" what we are: we "make<br />

ourselves" to be. An understanding of the concept of the continual<br />

"becoming" of consciousness, that is, the time of authentic existence, is<br />

"Si, en effet, Fexistence precede l'essence [...] rhomme est libre, l'homme est<br />

liberty" (Sartre, L'Existentialisme est un humanisme, 36-37).<br />

20 Noam Chomsky in a personal e-mail to the author dated 9 March 2005. Human<br />

nature, for Chomsky, is our unique biological endowment which distinguishes us<br />

from other mammals.


1945-2005: Existentialism and Humanism Sixty Years On 81<br />

crucial to an understanding of <strong>Sartre's</strong> humanistic project. This "becoming<br />

time" of existence finds an echo in the work of three major philosophers:<br />

Kierkegaard, Bergson and Hegel, yet only one of the three, Hegel, is an<br />

acknowledged source in L'fctre et le neant. Although Sartre begins to<br />

incorporate certain aspects of Hegelian dialectical temporality into the<br />

structures of the pour-soi, a fuller exploration is found in the dialectic of<br />

Les Chemins de la liberte, in the Critique de la raison dialectique, I (The<br />

Critique of Dialectical Reason, I, 1960) and in the posthumously<br />

published, Cahiers pour une morale (Notebooks for an Ethics, 1983).<br />

However, for Sartre at this largely individualistic stage, as for Kierkegaard<br />

in his Concluding Unscientific Postscript, "subjective thinking invests<br />

everything in the process of becoming". Bergson gives a similar view in<br />

L'Evolution creatrice (Creative Evolution, 1907). In particular, Bergson's<br />

insistence on the future as a possibility of being was to become a crucial<br />

concept in <strong>Sartre's</strong> re-appropriation of Heidegger.<br />

For Sartre, Man "is" what he makes himself in the pro-jection of<br />

himself towards the sum of possibilities that he is. In this way he is no<br />

longer bounded by finitude and death. Heidegger, on the contrary,<br />

emphasises both our "freedom-towards-death" (Freiheit-zum-Tode) and<br />

our "Being-towards-death" (Sein-zum-Tode). 21 The "authentic future"<br />

given through "resolute anticipation" is a "coming-towards". That is, "Zukunft"<br />

(the future) is interpreted as "zukommen auf': a coming-towards or<br />

coming-up-to. This is an inverse relation to the temporalisation of the<br />

pour-soi. However, Heidegger also states that Dasein is always "ahead of<br />

itself ("sich vorweg") and Corbin—with characteristic artistic licence—<br />

interestingly translates this aspect of Dasein as Man's being "un §tre des<br />

lointains": a being who is distant, far-away or remote. Sartre uncritically<br />

takes on board this translation, perhaps again as it appeals to him by<br />

appearing to reinforce his idea of an always "open future". In<br />

L Existentialisme est un humanisme, he goes one step further and refers to<br />

the "virgin" future which awaits man and which he "makes". 22 For Sartre,<br />

it is the perpetual "becoming time" of the present (as neant) which gives<br />

the future its possibility of being. Arguably, it is only an "always open"<br />

future that can provide Sartre with an absolute basis for a philosophy of<br />

freedom, at the time so desperately needed by so many people under the<br />

21 "Being-towards-death" may be understood existentially as both inauthentic<br />

(waiting for, dwelling on), and authentic in the sense of anticipating death as our<br />

"ownmost possibility of being". In being "free-for-death", Dasein is thrown back<br />

on itself, experiencing the authentic finitude of existence (see Heidegger, Being<br />

and Time, 290-311,435).<br />

22 See Sartre, L'Existentialisme est un humanisme, 39.


82 Chapter Six<br />

German occupation. Metaphysics and political history embrace one<br />

another—that is to say, a metaphysics shaped, at least in part, by political<br />

forces. If, for <strong>Sartre's</strong> generation, the idea of the future is confused, that is<br />

because the war has taught them that it is unpredictable. The future carries<br />

within it a perpetual "lack" of being, or what Valery termed "un creux<br />

toujours futur" ("an always future hollow").<br />

<strong>Sartre's</strong> approach to the question of human freedom in his lecture is<br />

later mirrored in his biographical writing, and we shall now briefly<br />

compare the "authentic" future with <strong>Sartre's</strong> brilliant depiction of its<br />

antithesis in his study of Baudelaire (1947). The poete maudit, "cursed"<br />

by an "original choice", decides in a particular situation what he will be<br />

and who he is: "Feeling of solitude, from my childhood. In spite of<br />

family—and in the midst of friends, especially—the feeling of an eternally<br />

solitary destiny." 23 Although these lines may strike us with their quasiautobiographical<br />

tone for Sartre, nevertheless, Baudelaire's action is of<br />

course, for Sartre, a supreme act of bad faith because the poet has decided<br />

on his own destiny: not only to live in isolation from others, but also to see<br />

himself as an "Other", to look on himself through the eyes of a stranger. In<br />

other words, Baudelaire's future has become cut off from the project of<br />

human transcendence. Later, the scenario is repeated in <strong>Sartre's</strong> study of<br />

Jean Genet, the man whose "original choice" is to label himself a "thief.<br />

However, Sartre emphasises that the original choice of one man never<br />

affects just one individual. The morality of existentialism is that in<br />

choosing for himself, man chooses for the whole human race. In this<br />

context, Simone de Beauvoir cites Dostoyevsky as the preface to her<br />

<strong>second</strong> novel, Le Sang des autres {The Blood of Others, 1945): "Each one<br />

of us is responsible for everything and to every human being." 24<br />

Arguably, this epigraph could equally well apply to recent events in<br />

Iraq, where clearly the original choices and actions of individual men have<br />

had worldwide media coverage and global repercussions. In choosing to<br />

go to war, for whatever the reason, President Bush and Prime Minister<br />

Blair have chosen for the whole of humanity, and a new generation is<br />

discovering the meaning of <strong>Sartre's</strong> humanistic emphasis on the<br />

interrelated existential terms of "anguish", "despair" and "abandonment".<br />

These terms underlie the relevance of existential humanism today, because<br />

we shall always live in a "human" universe. We could modify <strong>Sartre's</strong><br />

"Sentiment de solitude, des mon enfance. Malgre* la famille—et au milieu des<br />

camarades, surtout—sentiment de destine*e dternellement solitaire" (Sartre,<br />

Baudelaire, 19).<br />

24 "Chacun est responsable de tout devant tous" (epigraph to Simone de Beauvoir's<br />

Le Sang des autres).


1945-2005: Existentialism and Humanism Sixty Years On 83<br />

comments in UExistentialisme est un humanisme to read: "We are still in a<br />

world where there are only men."<br />

What of philosophy today? Edward Said wrote, shortly before his<br />

death in September 2003, that there is "always something radically<br />

incomplete, insufficient, provisional, disputable and arguable about<br />

humanistic knowledge that gives the whole idea of humanism a tragic flaw<br />

that is constitutive to it and cannot be removed." 25 With Said, it could be<br />

argued that the word "humanist" has, over the course of the last half<strong>century</strong><br />

become so over-used that it has literally become ab-used. The<br />

metaphysical horizon of "Humanism" indicates the semantic chain:<br />

"humanity", the "humane", the human, the being and "name" of "Man"<br />

(homme, homo), "Man" as the truth of being, "Man" as disclosing the truth<br />

of being. Although, for Sartre, the subject is continually called into<br />

question, perpetually deferred and fissured, the philosopher's interest, the<br />

writer's interest, is still this incomplete but totally human subject who, as a<br />

presence in the world, bears witness to the world. Even in Questions de<br />

Methode {Search for a Method), when Sartre affirms that he does not like<br />

to speak of existentialism—which he describes in quite scathing terms as<br />

"this idealistic protest against idealism" 26 —his overriding concern is still<br />

to examine the nature of existence in a human universe. Rejecting an<br />

idealistic humanism, what attracts Sartre to Marxism is precisely an<br />

examination of "the reality of Marxism, the heavy presence, on my<br />

horizon, of the working masses, the enormous and sombre body which<br />

lived Marxism". 27 Sartre never lost sight of the "human" in humanism.<br />

What of politics, today? The future as a possibility of being still holds<br />

a profound moral and ethical value as a source of human freedom. The<br />

terrorist attacks of the new millennium, the invasions of Afghanistan and<br />

Iraq mean that we have all recently felt the pressure of history just as<br />

surely—albeit less intensely—as did Sartre when he wrote UEtre et le<br />

neant, or later when he wrote about the Soviet labour camps, the Soviet<br />

suppression of the Hungarian uprising, or the Algerian war: "We are<br />

alone, without excuse." We ourselves and our leaders are "condemned to<br />

be free", alone, unjustified: we are never free not to choose; to choose not<br />

to act may, in certain situations, carry even greater weight than the choice<br />

to act Both Bush and Blair have focused on the need to "liberate" Iraq and<br />

Said, Humanism and Democratic Criticism, 12.<br />

26 "[C]ette protestation ide*aliste contre riddalisme" (Sartre, Critique de la raison<br />

dialectique, I, 26).<br />

27 "[L]a realite du marxisme, la lourde presence, a mon horizon, des masses<br />

ouvrieres, corps enorme et sombre qui vivait le marxisme" (<strong>Sartre's</strong> emphases,<br />

ibid., 28).


84 Chapter Six<br />

Afghanistan. Both need to remember the history lesson that Sartre has<br />

taught us, that liberty is a process and not a commodity.<br />

"The freedom genie is out of the bottle in the Middle East", ran a<br />

headline in a US newspaper in March 2005. Certainly, we are living in<br />

historic times: the prospect of women being given the vote in Saudi<br />

Arabia, the prospect of Syria's withdrawal from a part of Lebanon, the<br />

prospect of free elections in Egypt, and—perhaps most surprisingly—we<br />

witnessed a large turnout in the first post-invasion elections to be held in<br />

Iraq. Each of those Iraqi voters had been faced with perhaps the ultimate<br />

existential situation-limite (extreme situation). Their original choice to<br />

vote must have been accompanied by fear and anguish in the ever-present<br />

threat of death. From an existential perspective, hope for their future—<br />

which is also hope for our future—lies in a commitment to furthering the<br />

cause of human freedom: a freedom expressed not just through the ballot<br />

box, but in re-affirming each and every individual's right to freedom of<br />

speech and social justice. Will the Iraqi voters of today experience history<br />

as alienation, or as the affirmation of individual choice? In exercising our<br />

freedom of choice, we need to remember, with Sartre, that there is no<br />

freedom without responsibility, and that our freedom engages the whole of<br />

humanity in the future course of world politics.<br />

Works Cited<br />

Beauvoir, Simone de. Le Sang des autres. Paris: Gallimard, 1945.<br />

—. Pour une Morale de Vambiguite. Paris: Gallimard, 1947.<br />

Bergson, Henri. UEvolution creatrice. Paris: PUF, 1962.<br />

Derrida, Jacques. Marges de la philosophic Paris: Editions de Minuit,<br />

1972.<br />

Farrell Fox, Nicholas. The New Sartre. London: Continuum, 2003.<br />

Heidegger, Martin. Basic Writings (ed. David Farrell Krell). London:<br />

Routledge, 2000.<br />

Kanapa, Jean. UExistentialisme n'est pas un humanisme. Paris: Editions<br />

sociales, 1947.<br />

Kierkegaard, Soren. Concluding Unscientific Postscript. New York:<br />

Princeton University Press, 1941.<br />

Levy, Bernard-Henri. Le Siecle de Sartre. Paris: Grasset, 2000.<br />

Nietzsche, Friedrich. Beyond Good and Evil. London: Penguin, 1990.<br />

Said, Edward. Humanism and Democratic Criticism. New York:<br />

Columbia University Press, 2004.<br />

Sartre, Jean-Paul. Baudelaire. Paris: Gallimard, 1947.<br />

—. Critique de la raison dialectique, I. Paris: Gallimard, 1960.


1945-2005: Existentialism and Humanism Sixty Years On 85<br />

—. La Nausee. Paris: Gallimard, 1938.<br />

—. La Transcendance de VEgo. Paris: Vrin, 1992.<br />

—. L'£tre et le neant. Paris: Gallimard, 1943 (Collection 'TEL', 1995).<br />

—. Lettres au Castor, I. Paris: Gallimard, 1983.<br />

—. L'Existentialisme est un humanisme. Paris: Nagel, 1964.


CHAPTER SEVEN<br />

SARTRE, INTENTIONALITY AND PRAXIS 1<br />

ROY ELVETON<br />

In January, 1939, one year after the death of Edmund Husserl, Sartre<br />

published a very brief essay entitled "Husserl's Central Idea". 2 In the<br />

space of a few paragraphs, Sartre rejects the epistemology of Descartes<br />

and the neo-Kantians and their view of consciousness's relationship to the<br />

world. Consciousness is not related to the world by virtue of a series of<br />

mental representations and acts of mental syntheses that combine such<br />

representations to provide us with our knowledge of the external world.<br />

Husserl's intentional theory of consciousness provides the only acceptable<br />

alternative: "Consciousness and the world are immediately given together:<br />

the world, essentially external to consciousness, is essentially related to<br />

it." 3 The only appropriate image for intentionality and our knowing<br />

relationship to the world is that of an "explosion": "to know is to 'explode'<br />

toward" an object in the world, an object "beyond oneself, over there [...]<br />

towards that which is not oneself [...] out of oneself'. 4<br />

<strong>Sartre's</strong> account captures an important aspect of Husserl's theory of<br />

intentionality by insisting upon the essential nature of intentionality:<br />

consciousness is always a consciousness of an object, be it a real object, an<br />

imagined object, a memory or an emotion.<br />

While the ontological realism of <strong>Sartre's</strong> account of the nature of<br />

consciousness's intentional relationship to the world (the being-in-itself of<br />

transcendent objects is not created or constituted by consciousness)<br />

A draft of this chapter was presented to the special conference of the UK Sartre<br />

Society at the Institut Frangais, London, commemorating the centenary of <strong>Sartre's</strong><br />

birth, 18-19 March 2005.<br />

2 Sartre," Une id6e fondamentale de la phdnom£nologie de Husserl: rintentionnalit£ ".<br />

3 "La conscience et le monde sont donnas d'un meme coup: ext^rieur par essence h<br />

la conscience, le monde est, par essence, relatif h elle" ("Une Id£e fondamentale de<br />

Husserl", 32). All translations from French are my own.<br />

4 Ibid.


Sartre, Intentionality and Praxis 87<br />

deviates from the form of idealism Husserl adopts in his Ideas, /, and<br />

Cartesian Meditations, <strong>Sartre's</strong> reading of intentionality is not at all<br />

foreign in spirit to the early group of phenomenologists in Munich<br />

influenced by Husserl. Rejecting Husserl's idealism, philosophers such as<br />

Adolph Reinach, advocated a form of phenomenology closer in spirit to<br />

Husserl's pre-transcendental writings, and pursued a radically descriptive<br />

approach to the study of consciousness. It is in a similar spirit that Sartre<br />

writes the 1936 essay, La Transcendance de L'Ego: Equisse d*une<br />

description phenomenologique? In mistranslating the essay's title<br />

(properly, "outline of a descriptive phenomenology"), the English<br />

translation prefers the glory of the term "existentialism" to the clear<br />

indebtedness Sartre wished to maintain in the original title with respect to<br />

his Husserlian roots. Husserl's mistake, and the error leading to his form<br />

of phenomenology as a transcendental idealism, is the failure to<br />

understand that the very exercise of Husserl's transcendental reflection<br />

reifies, and thus distorts, the intentional nature of experience rather than<br />

disclosing it. In <strong>Sartre's</strong> view, Husserlian idealism involves a relationship<br />

between two consciousnesses: the reflecting consciousness and the<br />

consciousness reflected upon. However, for Sartre, reflecting consciousness<br />

is incapable of adequately grasping the consciousness reflected upon<br />

because it has the latter as its object. The consciousness reflected upon<br />

[...] must not be posited as an object of a reflection. On the contrary, I must<br />

direct my attention to the revived objects, but without losing sight of the<br />

unreflected consciousness, by joining in a sort of conspiracy with it and by<br />

drawing up an inventory of its content in a non-positional manner. 6<br />

It is clear that there is a fundamental difference between Husserl and<br />

Sartre on the question of the identity of the reflecting and reflected-upon<br />

consciousnesses. For Husserl, transcendent objects are constituted by the<br />

transcendental ego by means of complex acts of synthesis, beginning with<br />

the kinesthetic dimensions of my perceptual experience as an embodied<br />

consciousness and advancing to the eidetic structures that make my<br />

experience an experience of a tree and not of a table. Phenomenological<br />

analysis thus discloses the anonymous acts of a spontaneously constitutive<br />

consciousness and remains equally responsive to the world just as it is<br />

experienced. For Sartre, however, consciousness is, one might say, a pure<br />

spontaneity that does not "act" anonymously in Husserl's sense. I am an<br />

5 Sartre, The Transcendence of the Ego: An Existentialist Theory of Consciousness<br />

6 Transcendence, 46.


88 Chapter Seven<br />

unreflected consciousness of "Peter-having-to-be-helped." 7 The correct<br />

phenomenological description of this event cannot be arrived at by<br />

postulating a prior "unreflected pitying consciousness" 8 that would<br />

provide an anonymous unreflected-upon content of my awareness of Peter.<br />

Only the detailed description of Peter as the object of my intentional<br />

experience can succeed in offering a genuine phenomenological insight<br />

into the nature of intentional consciousness.<br />

This perspective appears to have already informed <strong>Sartre's</strong> earlier<br />

celebrated passages in Nausea concerning the radically superfluous nature<br />

of the world of the in-itself. On such occasions, we are overwhelmed by<br />

the in-itself and its obscene givenness. The experience of nausea signals<br />

the indescribability of the in-itself in its purity. If not directly describable,<br />

such experiences can nevertheless be approached as a kind of thoughtexperiment.<br />

Imagine that things refuse to play the conceptual roles we<br />

have assigned to them. Imagine not the harmonious flow of experience in<br />

which our attention is directed first to this object and then to another, but<br />

the very inability of our attending to gain traction in the face of the initself.<br />

What we might be left with is a sense of the radically contingent<br />

character of things in the world:<br />

This moment was extraordinary. I was there, motionless and icy, plunged<br />

in a horrible ecstasy. But something fresh had just appeared in the very<br />

heart of this ecstasy; I understood the Nausea, I possessed it. To tell the<br />

truth, I did not formulate the discoveries to myself. But I think that it<br />

would be easy for me to put them in words now. The essential thing is<br />

contingency. I mean that one cannot define existence as necessity. To exist<br />

is simply to be there; those who exist let themselves be encountered. 9<br />

How distant are these elaborations of being-in-itself from <strong>Sartre's</strong><br />

Husserlian roots? Since synthetic unities of experience are the defining<br />

characteristics of the stream of consciousness for Husserl, it would appear<br />

that Sartre has transformed Husserlian descriptive phenomenology into its<br />

radical opposite. Perhaps Sartre entertained such a transformation of<br />

phenomenology with profound delight. We need only recall the opening<br />

pages of Being and Nothingness where Sartre painstakingly dissects<br />

Husserl's idealism and its identification of transcendent objects with<br />

syntheses performed by the transcendental ego in order to replace it by his<br />

own phenomenological ontology.<br />

7 Ibid., 56.<br />

8 Ibid., 57.<br />

9 Sartre, Nausea, 131.


Sartre, Intentionality and Praxis 89<br />

Husserl's own version of transcendental idealism does not preclude the<br />

affirmation of an important contingency in our experience of the world of<br />

transcendent objects. Nevertheless, it is the de facto harmony of<br />

experience that represents the central focus of Husserlian phenomenology<br />

and that serves to justify the rigorous and "scientific" study of<br />

consciousness that is the distinctive feature of his transcendental<br />

philosophy.<br />

Additional episodes in Nausea concern the failure of language.<br />

Roquentin murmurs, "It's a seat":<br />

But the word stays on my lips; it refuses to go and put itself on the thing<br />

[...]. Things are divorced from their names. They are there, grotesque,<br />

headstrong, gigantic and it seems ridiculous to call them seats or say<br />

anything at all about them: I am in the midst of things, nameless things.<br />

Alone, without words, defenceless [...]. 10<br />

Such an account has affinities with the collapse of language that is<br />

depicted in Hugo von Hoffmansthal's "The Letter of Lord Chandos". 11<br />

While the early Sartre argues that Husserl's preoccupation with the eidetic<br />

structures of experience—structures that prefigure the essential and<br />

harmonious structures of experience—remains at a distance from an<br />

important stratum of intentional experience, we will note below a later,<br />

important revision made by Sartre regarding the role of language in<br />

consciousness's intentional life. Roquentin's paralysing "Chandos"<br />

experience will give way to an authentically intersubjective experience of<br />

language.<br />

Dialectical Phenomenology<br />

The radical givenness of the in-itself persists as a major theme of<br />

<strong>Sartre's</strong> reflections throughout his writings. Yet, whereas for the early<br />

Sartre consciousness literally exhausted itself in its intentional relation to<br />

the givenness of things, in Being and Nothingness the relationship between<br />

the in-itself and the for-itself becomes more complex. We might even say<br />

that, in its details, the intentional ontology of Being and Nothingness<br />

betrays significant duress and contortion.<br />

We are told in Being and Nothingness that the for-itself is the negation<br />

of the objects of consciousness's awareness. Yet Being and Nothingness<br />

addresses several dimensions of experience in which consciousness's<br />

10 Nausea, 125.<br />

11 Hugo von Hofmannsthal, Selected Prose, 133f.


90 Chapter Seven<br />

intentional object has the capacity to modify the very substance of<br />

consciousness itself. This result hardly appears to be compatible with the<br />

nature of the for-itself as being the negation of its objects, for different<br />

kinds of beings "in-themselves" have the power to define the for-itself<br />

differentially.<br />

Hegel's shadow looms heavily over the play of <strong>Sartre's</strong> dialectical<br />

phenomenology. At whatever level we engage the Hegelian system, we<br />

encounter a complicity between the in-itself and the for-itself that answers<br />

to the fact that neither can be understood apart from the other: their<br />

apparent dialectical independence is to be superseded by their dialectical<br />

resolution. However, for Sartre, the genuinely dialectical irreducibility of<br />

the in-itself to the for-itself requires a dialectical relationship that is<br />

endless and strictly irresolvable. In the process, Husserl's "fundamental<br />

idea" undergoes a complex reworking.<br />

The for-itself cannot exist without the in-itself, but neither can it be<br />

synthetically conjoined with it. This, of course, yields an endless alteration<br />

of dialectical scenarios. Let us consider, for example, the dialectic of the<br />

for-itself and the other. In <strong>Sartre's</strong> account of "the look", the other<br />

objectifies me. Initially, my world is given as centered about me: it is my<br />

field of consciousness and I constitute its centre. The arrival of the "other"<br />

disintegrates the unity of this perceptual field. I now surrender my<br />

perceptual centre of gravity to the other. I become an object perceived<br />

within the other's perceptual field. As a result, my own being escapes me.<br />

Imprisoned within the look of the other, my projects of existence are<br />

arrested, my freedom is lost and the original orientation of my being as a<br />

being-for-itself becomes dis-oriented and dis-placed.<br />

There is reason to ask why this is so. Surely my being as something<br />

for-itself intentionally directs me toward the objects of my experience?<br />

Indeed, as Nausea suggests, I can surrender myself to the "other" in a sort<br />

of total abandon and still not lose myself in the other. For what I am is just<br />

this transcending toward the other. However, Being and Nothingness adds<br />

a critically new element to this dialectical structure. The otherness of the<br />

other should be revealed to me as a new dimension of the in-itselfness of<br />

what is given to me as "other" (for example, its intersubjective nature).<br />

And so it is. The "look" reveals to me the givenness of another<br />

consciousness within the world. Yet <strong>Sartre's</strong> dialectic of the self and other<br />

cannot rest with this givenness. Just as the other's freedom constitutes not<br />

only a threat but a successful suppression of my own, so, in turn, I must be<br />

able to imprison the other in my "look".<br />

Modifications of the being of two consciousnesses emerge that echo<br />

the life-and-death struggle in Hegel's Phenomenology. However, more


Sartre, Intentionality and Praxis 91<br />

significantly, they dramatically exceed the relationship of self and other<br />

outlined in <strong>Sartre's</strong> initial delineation of Husserl's idea of intentionality. If,<br />

originally, my intentional being consisted solely in my (negative) relation<br />

to the object of my awareness, now this relationship is itself understood as<br />

being within the power of the object of which I am aware because my<br />

being is subject to an essential modification by the other.<br />

A reasonable inference from this experience of the other's look is that<br />

the ontology of intentionality conceals aspects that extend beyond my<br />

intentional relationship to transcendent objects that I am not. Despite the<br />

language of the ontological phenomenology of Being and Nothingness, the<br />

nothingness that is the for-itself has "being" just in the sense that it is<br />

subject to essential modifications. The "purity" of the for-itself (the purity<br />

of its not-being what it is) is a misleading abstraction.<br />

<strong>Sartre's</strong> own language betrays this dilemma. In the experience of the<br />

look of the other, "I am suddenly affected in my being (which means that)<br />

essential modifications appear in my structure—reflections which I can<br />

apprehend and fix conceptually by means of the reflective cogito" 12 One<br />

of these "essential" modifications is revealed in the experience of shame.<br />

If the other looks at me, imprisoning me into a shameful situation, then I<br />

also experience my identity with my shameful situation: "I am this<br />

(shamed) being. I do not for an instant think of denying it; my shame is a<br />

confession." 13 <strong>Sartre's</strong> text is quite clear on this point. There is something<br />

of the in-itself in my very being: "Behold, now I am somebody". 14<br />

What I "am" in the face of another for-itself involves at least two<br />

important and corollary dimensions. First, since what I "am" is my beingseen<br />

by the other, I can only be "seen" because I am an embodied<br />

consciousness (just as the other is only able to look at me by virtue of the<br />

other's embodiment). Hence, part of what I am in the look of the other is<br />

"my body". Second, the other not only sees my body, but sees my body as<br />

situated. In my freedom, my situation is a Gestalt within which I freely<br />

project myself toward my possibilities. Under the other's look, however,<br />

this Gestalt of freedom becomes the alienation of my possibilities: "A<br />

given synthesis is there of which I am the essential structure, and this<br />

structure at once possesses both ecstatic cohesion and the character of the<br />

in-itself." 15 The "ecstatic cohesion" is the result of the other's seeing my<br />

purpose within the context of my situation (I caught you spying on Pierre),<br />

12 Sartre, Being and Nothingness, 260.<br />

13 Ibid., 261.<br />

14 Ibid., 263.<br />

15 Ibid., 266.


92 Chapter Seven<br />

and the character of the in-itself refers to the death of my projects when<br />

they are simply defined by the situation as perceived by the other.<br />

As we shall see, <strong>Sartre's</strong> later Critique of Dialectical Reason witnesses<br />

to an effort to remove the abstractness of this account of the self and other.<br />

Something will have to be added to the pre-reflective spontaneity of beingfor-itself<br />

in order to make it possible for the for-itself to become mutually<br />

engaged by and with the other and not simply juxtaposed in opposition.<br />

Finally, a further comparison with Husserl sheds useful light on this<br />

feature of Being and Nothingness. In addition to the thoughts of Hegel and<br />

Heidegger on the nature of the other, Sartre criticises Husserl's account of<br />

the other as presented in Husserl's Cartesian Meditations. For Sartre, the<br />

Husserl of the "Fifth" of the Cartesian Meditations and its "deduction" of<br />

the existence of the Other, based as it is on Husserl's reliance upon the<br />

infamous phenomenological reduction, relates only to the subject's<br />

"knowledge" of the Other. 16 Sartre acknowledges that for Husserl the<br />

Other is always "with" me and is immediately given within the very<br />

structure of my perception of the world. 17 But this basis is insufficient to<br />

account for the Other-as-a-look, for this phenomenon cannot be "derived"<br />

from me, "for it is neither a knowledge nor a projection of my being nor a<br />

form of unification nor a category". 18 However, Husserl's account of<br />

intersubjectivity and the "otherness" of the Other is more complex than<br />

Sartre allows. Merleau-Ponty, acquainted, as Sartre was not, with<br />

Husserl's more sustained reflections on a phenomenological account of the<br />

other (for example, the analysis of the other in Ideas II) will later elaborate<br />

in detail a more positive account of intersubjectivity in the spirit of<br />

Husserl. 19 It must suffice here to note that for Husserl the horizon of the<br />

Other's alterity can only be unfolded as a possibility with the horizon of<br />

co-subjectivity. This is the realm of empathy, in which the other and his<br />

primordial being is originally given to me. 20 It would appear that, apart<br />

from a more detailed explication of all of the various dimensions of<br />

intersubjectivity itself, <strong>Sartre's</strong> attempt in Being and Nothingness to base<br />

his account of the Other upon the single dimension of the Other-as-look<br />

strains his ontological phenomenology. As we shall see, his later works<br />

Being and Nothingness, 233.<br />

17 Ibid., 272.<br />

18 Ibid.<br />

19 For a recent discussion critical of <strong>Sartre's</strong> account of the nature of alterity from<br />

the perspectives of Husserl and Merleau-Ponty, see Dan Zahavi, Self-Awareness<br />

and Alterity: A Phenomenological Investigation, Chapter 9.<br />

20 Husserl, Ziir Phanomenologie der Intersubjectivitdt.


Sartre, Intentionality and Praxis 93<br />

abandon the abstract ontology of Being and Nothingness for the sake of<br />

just such an enriched perspective.<br />

While Sartre has little to say about the historicity of being-for-itself in<br />

Being and Nothingness, a theme that will become central in The Critique<br />

of Dialectical Reason, he does have a great deal to say about time.<br />

Following Heidegger, Sartre defines time "ecstatically" as the for-itself s<br />

relationship to the past, present and future. The past is the mode of beingfor-itself<br />

as a "no longer having to be the past that I was". The future is the<br />

mode of being-for-itself as "what I have to be insofar as I cannot be it". 21<br />

Thus, both the past and the future are viewed as belonging to the province<br />

of being-in-itself. As instances of the in-itself, they are subject to the<br />

negative relation that defines the for-itself in relation to the in-itself. What,<br />

then, is the present? The present is the presence of the for-itself to<br />

something in the mode of being its own "witness" to the coexistence of<br />

itself and being-in-itself. 22 It is also the present that turns my past into the<br />

past. But even if I am now not my past, it is still my past that has been<br />

transformed in this way, just as it was revealed to have been my situation<br />

that is transcended and negated by the other. Time allows me to become<br />

the other to myself. Given the modifications of my being brought about by<br />

temporality, I appear to be involved with a substantive self-modification<br />

(of my present into my past) that represents something no less significant<br />

than the modification of my being brought about by the other. Similar<br />

considerations apply to my dialectical relationship to my future.<br />

As in the case of <strong>Sartre's</strong> analysis of intersubjectivity, we must ask<br />

whether temporality also points to a dimension of human experience that<br />

reveals something essential about the very nature of being-for-itself<br />

beyond "pure nothingness". The analysis of temporality as a mode in<br />

which the for-itself simply transforms the dimensions of past and future<br />

into surrogates of being-in-itself appears to overlook the radical<br />

temporality constituting the stream of consciousness so emphatically noted<br />

by Husserl. Perhaps by declining to follow Heidegger, whose Being and<br />

Time privileges the future over the past and the present, <strong>Sartre's</strong> emphasis<br />

upon the centrality of the present suggests a leveling down of the temporal<br />

flow in our experience of the world. The insight that consciousness is<br />

essentially temporal, as both Husserl and Heidegger claim, encompasses a<br />

dynamic that a pure nothingness, as the negation of being-in-itself, may be<br />

incapable of recognising.<br />

21 Being and Nothingness, 125.<br />

22 Ibid., 121.


94 Chapter Seven<br />

Praxis and History<br />

Early interpretations of Heidegger's Being and Time closely associated<br />

this work with the "existentialist" writings of Sartre. Heidegger's<br />

"authentic" Dasein was understood as another version of <strong>Sartre's</strong> account<br />

of the free projection of the for-itself into the future. That Sartre endorsed<br />

Heidegger's formula—that the "essence" of Dasein is its "existence"—<br />

made it indeed appear as if Sartre and Heidegger were pursuing a shared<br />

programme, an impression strengthened by <strong>Sartre's</strong> own high regard for<br />

the Heidegger of Being and Time.<br />

<strong>Sartre's</strong> later turn to Marx's philosophy would appear to constitute a<br />

repudiation of this earlier existentialist affiliation with Heidegger's work.<br />

However, the Sartre of The Critique of Dialectical Reason is much closer<br />

to the Heidegger of Being and Time than one might first imagine. As we<br />

shall see, the Sartre of The Critique is involved with themes that now<br />

occupy an increasingly central position in current philosophical<br />

discussions. It is not the "existentialist" Heidegger that preoccupies our<br />

attention today. Rather it is the Heidegger whose analyses of the structures<br />

of social, institutional and pragmatic agency now make it possible for us to<br />

begin to grapple with the profound importance of <strong>Sartre's</strong> later Marxinspired<br />

"existentialism".<br />

In Search for a Method, Sartre announces a new interpretation of the<br />

relationship between being-in-itself and being-for-itself:<br />

I cannot describe here the true dialectic of the subjective and the objective.<br />

One would have to demonstrate the joint necessity of the 'internalisation of<br />

the external' and 'the externalisation of the internal.' Praxis, indeed, is a<br />

passage from objective to objective through internalisation. The project, as<br />

the subjective surpassing of objectivity toward objectivity, and stretched<br />

between the objective conditions of the environment and the objective<br />

structure of the field of possibles, represents in itself the moving unity of<br />

subjectivity and objectivity, those cardinal components of activity [...] the<br />

subjective contains within itself the objective, which it denies and which it<br />

surpasses toward a new objectivity; and this new objectivity by virtue of<br />

objectification externalises the internality of the project as an objectified<br />

subjectivity. 23<br />

Human agency as the externalisation of an objectified subject is clearly<br />

adopted from the Marx of the Economic and Philosophic Manuscripts. It<br />

is also a dramatically different formula from that expressing the human<br />

subject understood as a nihilating transcendence of being-in-itself. We<br />

Sartre, Search for a Method, 91 f.


Sartre, Intentionality and Praxis 95<br />

must now grasp the human subject in its historically determined situation<br />

as a radically embedded spontaneity that accomplishes the rebirth of its<br />

inherited world in its own self-projection, an embedded spontaneity whose<br />

"objectification" must be understood as its substantial "truth": "[T]he<br />

objectified subjective must be considered as the only truth of the<br />

subjective." 24<br />

It is clearly beyond the scope of this chapter to treat <strong>Sartre's</strong> various<br />

nuanced treatments of the "objectified subjective", spanning, as they do,<br />

recently published manuscripts as well as major late works such as Search<br />

for a Method (1960), The Critique of Dialectical Reason (1960) and the<br />

multi-volume work on Flaubert, The Family Idiot. However, an insightful<br />

and compelling path into <strong>Sartre's</strong> later thought is provided by an example<br />

that Sartre himself offered in 1966, an example that responds to our<br />

culture's almost obsessive preoccupation with language:<br />

There was a time when thought was defined independently of language, as<br />

something intangible and ineffable that pre-exists expression. Today<br />

people fall into the opposite error. They would have us believe that thought<br />

is only language, as if language itself were not spoken.<br />

In reality, there are two levels. On the first level, language presents<br />

itself, in effect, as an autonomous system, which reflects social unification.<br />

Language is an element of the 'practico-inert', a sonorous substance<br />

unified by a set of practices. The linguist takes this totality of relations as<br />

an object of study, and he has a right to do this because it is already<br />

constituted. This is the stage of structure, in which the totality appears as a<br />

thing without man [...]. But this thing without man is at the same time<br />

matter worked by man, bearing the trace of man [...]. If you admit the<br />

existence of such a system, you must also admit that language exists only<br />

as spoken, in other words in act. Each element of the system refers to a<br />

whole, but this whole is dead if nobody takes it up for his own purposes,<br />

makes it work. 25<br />

Peter Caws writes that "the (concept of the) practico-inert strikes me as<br />

one of the most useful additions to the conceptual repertoire of social<br />

philosophy in the last <strong>century</strong>". 26 This may well be true. For the moment, I<br />

will suggest that <strong>Sartre's</strong> various comments on spoken language, today<br />

largely unappreciated, yield valuable illustrations of the meaning and<br />

significance of the "practico-inert".<br />

Ibid., 98.<br />

Sartre, L'Arc, no. 30,88-89, cited in Peter Caws, "Sartrean Structuralism?", 299.<br />

Caws, 309.


96 Chapter Seven<br />

The hegemony of Chomsky's linguistic theory and its emphasis upon<br />

the formal aspects of the grammar of natural languages stops short, in<br />

Chomsky's own words, before the mystery of the creative use of language.<br />

Even before Chomsky, the writings of Frege, Russell and the early<br />

Wittgenstein focused upon language as a formal-logical system. However,<br />

we are beginning to see the collapse of the dominance of the formal<br />

analysis of the written over the dynamics of spoken language. Although<br />

writing with specific reference to Saussure and Chomsky, Pierre Bourdieu,<br />

hardly one of <strong>Sartre's</strong> most ardent defenders, surreptitiously restates<br />

<strong>Sartre's</strong> insight into the importance of spoken language:<br />

To posit, as Saussure does, that the true medium of communication is not<br />

speech, a datum immediately considered in its observable materiality, but<br />

language, a system of objective relations that makes possible both the<br />

production and decoding of discourse, is to perform a complete reversal of<br />

appearances by subordinating the very substance of communication, which<br />

presents itself as the most visible and real aspect, to a pure construct of<br />

which there is no sense experience. [...] It would be no doubt worthwhile<br />

to try to set out the whole set of theoretical postulates implied in adopting<br />

this viewpoint, such as the primacy of logic and structure, apprehended<br />

synchronically, over individual and collective history (that is, the learning<br />

of the language and, as Marx might have said, "the historical movement<br />

that gave birth to it") [...]. 27<br />

Sartre would certainly not only agree that language is a material object,<br />

but that it also has a history and that speech has its historical<br />

embeddedness. As dimensions of the practico-inert, language and culture<br />

clearly pre-exist the speaking individual. By infusing this pre-existent<br />

universe with the individual's own purposive action and spontaneity, the<br />

Sartrean subject achieves an objectification that, no sooner than it is<br />

achieved, reintroduces the subject into the material flow of human<br />

purpose, action and intersubjectivity. The subject inhabits language<br />

without being exhausted by it. If there is a transcendence of language, it is<br />

not the adoption of the "impartial spectator" view of language rejected by<br />

Bourdieu, but the subject's existing in the "further" and future of the world<br />

of others and practical tasks (the horizon of the future). <strong>Sartre's</strong> discursive<br />

task is to maintain a perilous balance between the dynamics of the<br />

subject's transcendence and the world of the ready-made that makes up the<br />

individual's historical embodiment. The notion of the practico-inert<br />

signifies a unity of the subject and the subject's world that can never be<br />

collapsed into an inert totality or identity:<br />

27 Pierre Bourdieu, The Logic of Practice, 30f.


Sartre, Intentionality and Praxis 97<br />

Words are matter. They carry the projects of the Other into me and they<br />

carry my projects into the Other. Language might well be studied along the<br />

same lines as money: as a circulating, inert materiality, which unifies<br />

dispersal. [...] There can be no doubt that in one sense language is an inert<br />

materiality. But this materiality is also a constantly developing organic<br />

totalisation [...] it is obvious that a person's every word must depend, in its<br />

present meaning, on its references to the total system of interiority and that<br />

it must be the object of an incommunicable comprehension. But this<br />

incommunicability—in so far as it exists—can have meaning only in terms<br />

of a more fundamental communication, that is to say, when based on<br />

mutual recognition and on a permanent project to communicate [...]. Every<br />

word is in fact unique, external to everyone; it lives outside, as a public<br />

institution; and speaking does not consist in inserting a vocable into a brain<br />

through an ear, but in using sounds to direct the interlocutors's attention to<br />

this vocable as public exterior property. [...] To speak is to modify each<br />

vocable by all the others against the common background of the word;<br />

language contains every word and every word is to be understood in terms<br />

of language as a whole; it contains the whole of language and reaffirms it<br />

[...] language as the practical relation of one man to another is praxis, and<br />

praxis is always language [...]. Languages are the product of History; as<br />

such they have all the exteriority and unity of separation. 28<br />

How distant is this from the Sartre of the Transcendence of the Ego and its<br />

radicalisation of Husserlian intentionality? What remains is the dialectical<br />

relationship of the inseparable moments of an indissoluble relationship.<br />

What has changed is the introduction of a third medium that now embeds<br />

the for-itself/in-itself opposition. This medium makes me available to the<br />

other in the form of the omnipresence and priority of an intersubjective<br />

community. It is by virtue of an intersubjective praxis that we in the<br />

present inhabit together our future and redeem our past.<br />

Thomas Flynn, partly quoting Sartre, emphasises a most important<br />

feature of the Sartre of the Critique:<br />

When two or more for-itselfs enter into relationship, Sartre argues, there is<br />

a reciprocity that is an existential modification of each. Exhibiting the<br />

kinds of thinking that will remain through the Critique, Sartre urges that<br />

such reciprocity [...] presumes a prior unity. [... Sartre asks, is there not]<br />

"an existence proper to the reciprocal existentialist modification, an<br />

existence that would pose itself in terms neither of the for-itself nor of the<br />

for-others" (CDR, 252). The answer, he implies, lies in that special in-itself<br />

of the for-others, which he will soon call the "event" (363). This would be<br />

the locus of historical facticity. [...] Consider a conversation between two<br />

Sartre, Critique of Dialectical Reason, I, 98.


98 Chapter Seven<br />

people. Besides the respective fact that each happens to be talking, there is<br />

the mutuality that we call the conversation itself that exists beyond the<br />

being-for-itself of each participant, though not independent of the individuals<br />

involved. 29<br />

Sartre alludes to two aspects of language that are of increasing interest to<br />

current research. Spoken language, involving the speakers' co-presence<br />

and interaction,<br />

defines a property that can be called situatedness—the closeness language<br />

has to the immediate physical and social situation in which it is produced<br />

and received. The nature of conversational language and conversational<br />

consciousness is dependent on their situatedness. 30<br />

In addition to this dimension of situatedness or historical facticity, situated<br />

discourse is framed by structures of intersubjectivity. At this point,<br />

<strong>Sartre's</strong> thought in the Critique comes closer to Husserl's reflections on<br />

the encompassing structures of intersubjectivity in consciousness's<br />

experience of the world:<br />

The most important factor to be stressed is that community is not a mere<br />

collection of individuals and that communal existence and common<br />

achievements are not simply collections of individual lives and individual<br />

achievements. On the contrary, all individual existence and individual life<br />

is thoroughly informed by a unity of existence, grounded, to be sure, in<br />

individual lives, but a unity penetrating and transcending the private<br />

worlds of individuals [...]. 31<br />

Although Husserl goes on to make reference to "forms of life, work and<br />

cultural configurations" and their corresponding "norms", his analyses are<br />

composed of largely incomplete and programmatic texts. I have elsewhere<br />

referred to these and other aspects of Husserl's views on intersubjectivity<br />

and the relevance of perceptual, embodied experience to the understanding<br />

of language as "envoiced subjectivity". 32<br />

We may usefully engage <strong>Sartre's</strong> suggestion that language illustrates<br />

important aspects of the practico-inert by considering specific aspects of<br />

the envoiced subject. Envoiced subjectivity incorporates Husserl's account<br />

29 Thomas Flynn, "Sartre and the Poetics of History", 216f.<br />

30 Wallace Chafe, Discourse, Consciousness and Time: The Flow and<br />

Displacement of Conscious Experience in Speaking and Writing, 44f.<br />

31 Husserl, Aufsatze und Vortrage, 48.<br />

32 See Elveton, 'Tolerance, Envoiced Subjecivity and the Lifeworld."


Sartre, Intentionality and Praxis 99<br />

of the structures of the embodied, experiencing and perceiving subject<br />

given in his analysis of the "lifeworld". Primary among these structures<br />

are those involving kinesthetic processes, an implicit awareness of the<br />

world-horizon and, as noted above, the communalisation of experience.<br />

The first of these features refers to the fact that even perceptual<br />

experience is a matter of an embodied "I can" and "I move" that forms the<br />

core of what Husserl terms the "living body". Communicative speech<br />

represents what might be the most distinctive accomplishment of the living<br />

body, encompassing not only its gestural expressivity, but also the full<br />

range of the rhythm and sonority of spoken and sung language. The<br />

substance of speech is both its meaning and its necessary material<br />

embodiment. When Sartre thinks of the practico-inert as a materiality in<br />

which words as matter "carry the projects of the Other into me", he is<br />

clearly thinking of the embodied materiality of speech.<br />

Husserl's account of the world-horizon primarily refers to the fact that<br />

our perceptual experience of the world occurs against the background of<br />

an open-ended horizon within which individual experiences form a stream<br />

of future-directed, presumptive, and, for the most part, harmoniously<br />

conjoined perceptions. Communicative, situated discourse is fully<br />

immersed in this stream of experience in at least two respects. First,<br />

envoiced subjects are embedded in conversational time. Spoken discourse<br />

has both a material and a temporal thickness that is situated within an<br />

awareness of the more encompassing unfolding of the temporality of the<br />

world-horizon. Second, discourse carries its own presumptive horizon and<br />

is borne by presumptions that are both pragmatically and culturally shaped<br />

and which implicitly, and often overtly, directly structure the flow of<br />

conversation. The horizonality of discourse is formed by both its historical<br />

situation and its temporal dynamic.<br />

Finally, the communalisation of experience represents Husserl's understanding<br />

of the inseparability of perception and intersubjectivity. To<br />

perceive is to perceive a world that is also experienced by others. As the<br />

two immediately previous Sartre quotations show, this is an irreducibly<br />

central feature of the practico-inert. While Husserl's manuscripts propose<br />

a complex interplay of a variety of different forms that the intersubjective<br />

unity of existence may assume, <strong>Sartre's</strong> attempts in the Critique and The<br />

Family Idiot to understand intersubjectivity as a "unity" that is always<br />

partial, "in play" and never completed, extends this aspect of Husserl's<br />

treatment of the lifeworld in an enriched manner.<br />

However, it is not only the materiality of language that exemplifies the<br />

nature of the practico-inert. Speech and language are, as Sartre noted<br />

above, the products of history. As such, Sartre argues, they have a certain


100 Chapter Seven<br />

"exteriority". To say that human agency finds itself embedded in this form<br />

of exteriority is not only to say that human agency is suspended in its<br />

historical situation, but that a certain kind of exteriority is in fact<br />

constitutive of the historical subject itself. Many of the obscurities and<br />

difficulties of <strong>Sartre's</strong> later philosophical language can perhaps be traced<br />

back to the effort needed to reconcile the "interiority" of the for-itself s<br />

freedom and the "exteriority" of language and history. Regardless of the<br />

assessment that might be offered regarding the success or failure of<br />

<strong>Sartre's</strong> efforts, it is important to emphasise that issues strongly analogous<br />

to <strong>Sartre's</strong> are being increasingly emphasised in much current philosophy<br />

of mind and language, and in a range of related disciplines broadly<br />

devoted to the study of human cognition in recognising that the mind is<br />

more "extended", "external" and "institutional" than much philosophy,<br />

psychology and anthropology had taken it to be—indeed, more central<br />

than the Sartre of Being and Nothingness was able to allow.<br />

Here we briefly note examples of this emphasis. In analytical<br />

philosophy, the thought of the later Wittgenstein has been said to move in<br />

this direction, as is most recently argued in the work of Meredith<br />

Williams. 33 The understanding of mind and language as social, public and<br />

institutional presented in Williams's work contributes a non-Sartrean<br />

vocabulary to the issue of materiality and exteriority in <strong>Sartre's</strong> sense of<br />

the practico-inert.<br />

Foucault has also exercised a strong influence on analytical thought.<br />

Ian Hacking's recent Historical Ontology, explicitly indebted to Foucault,<br />

is an additional important contribution to understanding the role of history<br />

for language and the "publicness" of the human mind. 34<br />

Recent trends in continental-inspired thought, driven in part by a<br />

renewed interest in Hegelian and neo-Hegelian accounts of mind and truth<br />

as "communal", as reflected in the recent work of Michael Forster and<br />

Terry Pinkard, 35 also provide a non-Sartrean vocabulary focusing on issues<br />

analogous to those raised in <strong>Sartre's</strong> later philosophy. Finally, similar<br />

themes are reflected in the work of Robert Brandom and its concern with<br />

institutional-cognitive structures, 36 and in Robert Brandom's and John<br />

Haugeland's neo-pragmatic interpretation of the work of Heidegger, 37<br />

Meredith Williams, Wittgenstein, Mind and Meaning: Toward a Social<br />

Conception of Mind.<br />

34 Ian Hacking, Historical Ontology.<br />

35 Michael Forster, Hegel's Idea of a Phenomenology of Spirit; Terry Pinkard,<br />

Hegel's Phenomenology: The Sociality of Reason.<br />

36 Robert Brandom, Making it Explicit.<br />

37 John Haugeland, "Dasein's Disclosedness".


Sartre, Intentionality and Praxis 101<br />

which develops a reading of Being and Time, not as an existentialist<br />

treatise, but as an important statement of an institutional-social theory of<br />

mind and language.<br />

Conclusion<br />

Over the course of <strong>Sartre's</strong> long and prolific career, we have seen an<br />

increasing complexity appear in his treatment of intentionality, Husserl's<br />

"fundamental idea". The interplay between human praxis and world<br />

becomes inspired by detailed descriptions of historical events and<br />

individuals, such as Gustave Flaubert and Jean Genet. <strong>Sartre's</strong> ontology of<br />

praxis becomes overlaid by attempts to do full justice to the particularity<br />

of individual freedom and the details of the individual's "exterior" and<br />

historical situation.<br />

It was Chomsky who wrote that a central goal of the study of language<br />

"is to determine the meaning of a word [...] in a 'shared public' language,<br />

a notion that remains to be formulated in some coherent terms". 38 It is<br />

arguably just such a project Sartre may be said to have undertaken. We are<br />

perhaps only beginning to understand the importance of <strong>Sartre's</strong><br />

contribution to such an endeavour. Perhaps his most important legacy in<br />

this regard is the claim that language as public can only be understood<br />

within the context of a more encompassing view of human action, history<br />

and spontaneity. Although Sartre has reinterpreted Hegel's dictum that<br />

true history is the history of freedom in Marxist terms, <strong>Sartre's</strong> conception<br />

of freedom and praxis signals his continuing legacy as a philosopher of<br />

freedom. "Possibility", Sartre states, "lies at the very heart of the particular<br />

action, (it is) the presence of the future as that which is lacking and that<br />

which, by its very absence, reveals reality." 39 But since it is an embedded<br />

freedom that is at stake, a freedom embedded within the public world of<br />

the practico-inert, perhaps at this point it is Nietzsche who deserves the<br />

last word:<br />

What does commonness really mean? Words are acoustic signs for<br />

concepts; concepts, however, are more or less precise figurative signs for<br />

frequently recurring and simultaneous sensations, for groups of sensations.<br />

Using the same words is not enough to ensure mutual understanding: we<br />

must also use the same words for the same category of inner experiences;<br />

ultimately, we must have the same experiences in common [...] when<br />

people have lived together for a long time under similar conditions of<br />

Noam Chomsky, New Horizons, 148.<br />

Sartre, Search for a Method, 94.


102 Chapter Seven<br />

climate, soil, danger, necessity, work, then something comes into being as<br />

a result, something that "goes without saying" [...]. 40<br />

Works Cited<br />

Bourdieu, Pierre. The Logic of Practice (trans. Richard Nice). Stanford:<br />

Stanford University Press, 1990.<br />

Brandom, Robert. Making it Explicit. Boston: Harvard University Press,<br />

1994.<br />

Caws, Peter. "Sartrean Structuralism?", in The Cambridge Companion to<br />

Sartre (ed. Christina Howells). Cambridge: Cambridge University<br />

Press, 1992<br />

Chafe, Wallace. Discourse, Consciousness and Time: The Flow and<br />

Displacement of Conscious Experience in Speaking and Writing.<br />

Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1994.<br />

Chomsky, Noam. New Horizons in the Study of Language and Mind.<br />

Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000.<br />

Elveton, Roy. "Tolerance, Envoiced Subjectivity and the Lifeworld", in<br />

Interpretando la experiencia de la tolerancia / Interpreting the<br />

Experience of Tolerance, II (ed. Rosemary Rizo-Patron de Lerner).<br />

Lima: Pontifica Universidad Catolica del Peru, 2006.<br />

Flynn, Thomas. "Sartre and the Poetics of History", in The Cambridge<br />

Companion to Sartre (ed. Christina Howells). Cambridge: Cambridge<br />

University Press, 1992.<br />

Forster, Michael. Hegel's Idea of a Phenomenology of Spirit. Chicago:<br />

University of Chicago Press, 1998.<br />

Hacking, Ian. Historical Ontology. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University<br />

Press, 2002.<br />

Haugeland, John. "Dasein's Disclosedness", in Heidegger: A Critical<br />

Reader (ed. H. L. Dreyfus and H. Hall). Oxford: Blackwell Publishers,<br />

1992.<br />

Hofmannsthal, Hugo von. Selected Prose. New York: Pantheon Books,<br />

1952.<br />

Husserl, Edmund. Aufsatze und Vortrage (1922-1937). Dordrecht: Kluwer<br />

Academic Publishers, 1989.<br />

—. Ideen zu einer reinen Phanomenologie und phanomenologischen<br />

Philosophic. Zweites Buck The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1952.<br />

—. Zur Phanomenologie der Intersubjectivitat: Dritter Teil (1929-1935).<br />

The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1973.<br />

Nietzsche, Beyond Good and Evil, 163.


Sartre, Intentionality and Praxis 103<br />

Nietzsche, Friedrich. Beyond Good and Evil (trans. Marion Faber).<br />

Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1998.<br />

Pinkard, Terry. HegeVs Phenomenology: The Sociality of Reason.<br />

Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press, 1994.<br />

Sartre, Jean-Paul. "Jean-Paul Sartre repond", UArc, no. 30, "Sartre<br />

Aujourd'hui", 1966, 87-96.<br />

—. Being and Nothingness (trans. H. E. Barnes). New York: Philosophical<br />

Library, 1956.<br />

—. Critique of Dialectical Reason, /(trans. Alan Sheridan-Smith). London:<br />

Verso, 2004.<br />

—. Nausea (trans. Lloyd Alexander). New York: New Directions, 1967.<br />

—. The Family Idiot: Gustave Flaubert (1821-1857), I (trans. Carol<br />

Cosman). Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1981.<br />

—. Search for a Method. New York: Knopf, 1963.<br />

—. The Transcendence of the Ego: An Existentialist Theory of<br />

Consciousness (trans. Forrest Williams and Robert Kirkpatrick). New<br />

York: The Noonday Press, 1957.<br />

—. "Une id£e fondamentale de la phenome'nologie de Husserl:<br />

Fintentionnalite", in Situations, I. Paris: Gallimard, 1947.<br />

Williams, Meredith. Wittgenstein, Mind and Meaning: Towards a Social<br />

Conception of Mind. New York: Routledge, 1999.<br />

Zahavi, Dan. Self-Awareness and Alterity: A Phenomenological<br />

Investigation. Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1999.


CHAPTER EIGHT<br />

THE NEW SARTRE:<br />

A POSTMODERN PROGENITOR?<br />

NICHOLAS FARRELL FOX<br />

"[...] for every thought one must expect a strange tomorrow." 1<br />

In the eyes of many, Sartre was the foremost intellectual of the<br />

twentieth <strong>century</strong>, a master thinker of freedom whose diverse literary<br />

talents earned him notoriety as a philosopher, playwright, novelist and<br />

polemicist. And yet, he is often seen as a philosopher of a world that has<br />

passed, a child and relic of modernity whose voice rang out amidst the<br />

alienations and horrors of the twentieth <strong>century</strong>, but which is now scarcely<br />

detectable in the soundwaves of our contemporary postmodern condition.<br />

After all, history has it that the Sartrean corpse was laid to rest not only in<br />

the cemetery at Montparnasse, upon the event of his death in April 1980,<br />

but also twenty years or so earlier when a (post)structuralist revolt—<br />

organised by Foucault, Derrida and others—overthrew the monarchical<br />

Sartrean regime and buried its humanist entrails in the ground. 2 So, what<br />

relevance, it might be asked, does <strong>Sartre's</strong> work hold for postmodernism? 3<br />

Sartre and the (Post)structuralists<br />

In some respects, it is not altogether surprising that standard interpretations<br />

have cited Sartrean existentialism as the principal target for the<br />

(post)structuralist revolution of the 1960s and 1970s. An initial sense of<br />

hostility between Sartre and the (post)structuralists found expression in a<br />

1 Baudrillard, Forget Foucault, 99.<br />

2 "(Post)structuralism" is used here to denote both structuralist and poststructuralist<br />

theory, whereas "poststructuralism" refers only to poststructuralist theory.<br />

3 An earlier draft of this chapter was given as a paper at the Centenary Conference<br />

of the UK Sartre Society at the Institut Fran^ais, London, in March 2005.


The New Sartre: A Postmodern Progenitor? 105<br />

series of polemical exchanges that took place in the 1960s between Sartre<br />

and L6vi-Strauss, Foucault and others. They criticised Sartre for relying on<br />

a humanist and idealist theory of the subject, while Sartre criticised<br />

(post)structuralism in turn for dissolving human freedom by holding<br />

history hostage to the play of impersonal forces. As Foucault describes it,<br />

the (post)structuralist attack on Sartre arose "from a dissatisfaction with<br />

the phenomenological theory of the subject" and "involved different<br />

escapades, subterfuges, breakthroughs [...] in the direction of linguistics,<br />

psychoanalysis or Nietzsche". 4 It was a matter, as he states elsewhere, "of<br />

calling this theme of the subject into question once again, that great<br />

fundamental postulate which French philosophy, from Descartes until our<br />

own time, had never abandoned". 5<br />

This polemic between Sartre and Foucault perhaps reached its greatest<br />

point of intensity in 1966 when, in an article in La Quinzaine litteraire,<br />

Foucault identified <strong>Sartre's</strong> philosophy with a bygone era, cursorily<br />

dismissing Sartre and Merleau-Ponty as "courageous and generous men"<br />

who were animated by a spirit that had passed from the intellectual scene.<br />

In response, Sartre acknowledged the importance of Foucault's Les Mots<br />

et les choses {Words and Things), but criticised him for avoiding the<br />

question of history (i.e. how one episteme is supplanted by another),<br />

arguing that Foucault effectively "replace[s] movies with a magic lantern,<br />

movement with a sequence of immobile images". 6<br />

Since <strong>Sartre's</strong> death in 1980, however, interpretations of his work have<br />

begun to probe the underbelly of this standard account. In recent years the<br />

phenomenon of "the new Sartre" has been gradually emerging out of the<br />

ashes of his philosophical oeuvre, pointing to a fundamental reappraisal of<br />

<strong>Sartre's</strong> work in its relation to poststructuralism and, in a wider sense, to<br />

postmodernism. In Christina Howells's words, this idea of "the new<br />

Sartre" presents him as:<br />

[...] a figure whose diversity was far from being mastered, who could not,<br />

without distortion or impoverishment, be identified with the "classical<br />

existentialism" of the 1940s, and whose relationship to Structuralism and<br />

Post-Structuralism, as well as to psychoanalysis, Marxism, and literary<br />

theory, was far more complex than ha[s] generally been supposed. 7<br />

4 InRaulet, Telos, 55,199.<br />

5 Foucault, Remarks on Marx, 56.<br />

6 Quoted in Poster, Foucault, Marxism and History, 5<br />

7 Howells, "Introduction", in The Cambridge Companion to Sartre, 1.


106 Chapter Eight<br />

In this respect, traditional accounts of post-war intellectual history in<br />

France can be said to have pitted Sartre as a theoretical adversary against<br />

poststructuralists such as Foucault, Lacan, Deleuze and Derrida, far too<br />

readily. Moreover, standard interpretations of <strong>Sartre's</strong> work can be seen to<br />

rely too heavily on certain themes, or on particular passages in his "classic<br />

existentialist" works of the 1940s, to the serious neglect of other elements<br />

in his work of this period and, indeed, in the wider trajectory of his work<br />

as a whole. Howells makes the further claim that since <strong>Sartre's</strong> two main<br />

works of philosophy, Being and Nothingness and The Critique of<br />

Dialectical Reason, /, predate the main wave of poststructuralist texts in<br />

the 1960s, 1970s and 1980s, they can be seen, in effect, to prefigure many<br />

key poststructuralist themes, such as:<br />

[...] the decentred subject, the rejection of a metaphysics of presence, the<br />

critique of bourgeois humanism and individualism, the concept of the<br />

reader as producer of the text's multiple meanings, the recognition of<br />

language and thought structures as masters rather than mastered in most<br />

acts of discourse and thinking, [and] a materialist philosophy of history as<br />

detotalised and fragmented. 8<br />

These themes, she argues, are not "the inventions of Lacan, Foucault,<br />

Ldvi-Strauss and Derrida", but can "be found in <strong>Sartre's</strong> later works" and<br />

are "present from the outset" even in his early work, which dates from The<br />

Transcendence of the Ego (1936). 9 Taken together, they serve to contradict<br />

the simple identification of Sartre with the usual image of a classic<br />

intellectual steeped in a Cartesian tradition of modern philosophy which is,<br />

by implication, a form of philosophy diametrically opposed to the<br />

postmodernising strategies of the poststructuralists.<br />

Until now, Sartre has been a marginal and mainly absent figure in<br />

discussions of postmodernism, which have tended to focus upon critiques<br />

of modernism put forward by the French poststructuralists, notably Michel<br />

Foucault, Gilles Deleuze, Felix Guattari, Jean-Francois Lyotard, Jacques<br />

Derrida and Jean Baudrillard. When Sartre is included, it is usually as no<br />

more than the target for these critiques. In contrast to this, I would suggest<br />

that it is time to bring him into the heart of the postmodern debate, and to<br />

trace the strands of opposition and convergence between <strong>Sartre's</strong> work and<br />

postmodernist theory. In so doing, we see the image of "the new Sartre"<br />

gradually emerge—one that recasts his popular image from that of an<br />

archetypal and classic modernist thinker, to that of a thinker who has a<br />

8 Ibid., 2.<br />

9 Ibid.


The New Sartre: A Postmodern Progenitor? 107<br />

complex and multifaceted relationship with the postmodern ethos. This<br />

will, I hope, highlight the contemporary relevance and value of <strong>Sartre's</strong><br />

work by helping to cut through the mist of our present postmodern<br />

condition. Much of this value derives from the way in which <strong>Sartre's</strong> work<br />

occupies a transitional space between modernist and postmodernist<br />

categories, integrating elements of each into a constellated and synthetic<br />

whole. Sometimes this has the effect of catapulting the Sartrean system<br />

into contradiction and antinomy, but for the most part it serves to form it<br />

as a window through which we are better placed to view, and to reflect<br />

upon, the inadequacies and revelations of postmodernist theory, and its<br />

trenchant critique of modernity.<br />

In this respect, one can cite Roland Barthes who has located the special<br />

value of <strong>Sartre's</strong> work in its "divided" or "transitional" nature. 10 In an<br />

interview in 1976 with Jacques Chancel, Barthes put forward the view that<br />

Sartre can be seen as the exemplary intellectual of his period because he<br />

was situated at the crossroads of two cultures—at the point of division<br />

between the disintegration of the old and the birth of the new. This was<br />

evident in the way that Sartre managed to straddle both pre-war and postwar<br />

ideological and political currents in France, thus marking him out,<br />

according to Barthes, as a uniquely important transitional figure.<br />

Following Barthes's observation, I suggest that <strong>Sartre's</strong> philosophy can be<br />

situated in a transitional space that straddles the divide and creates a<br />

sometimes uneasy tension between a postmodern sense of despair,<br />

plurality, fragmentation and indeterminacy, and a modernist longing for<br />

comprehension, meaning, constructivism and totality.<br />

Sartre and Postmodernism<br />

In recent years, the idea of postmodernism has dominated academic<br />

dialogue in the humanities and the social sciences. Although the term<br />

"postmodernism" has long been in use, in one form or another, to describe<br />

developments in literary theory, architecture and art, which attack the<br />

dominant modernist paradigm, it has become associated more recently<br />

with theories of cultural, political, economic and philosophical change,<br />

taking its inspiration from critiques of modernist theory found in the work<br />

of the French poststructuralists. In general terms, it is the radical<br />

questioning, or "unmasking", of modern assumptions and modes of<br />

understanding that, as Ihab Hassan points out, can be said to define the<br />

postmodern movement:<br />

See Chancel, "Radioscopie: Roland Barthes", 255.


108 Chapter Eight<br />

It is an antinomian moment that assumes a vast unmasking of the Western<br />

mind—what Michel Foucault might call the postmodern episteme. I say<br />

"unmasking", though other terms are now de rigueur. for instance,<br />

deconstruction, decentering, disappearance, demystification, discontinuity,<br />

differance, dispersion, etc. Such terms express an ontological rejection of<br />

the traditional full subject, the Cogito of Western philosophy. They<br />

express, too, an epistemological obsession with fragments, and a<br />

corresponding commitment to minorities in politics, sex and language. To<br />

think well, to feel well, to act well, to read well according to the episteme<br />

of unmasking, is to refuse the tyranny of wholes: totalization in human<br />

endeavor is potentially totalitarian. 11<br />

In The Dismemberment of Orpheus, Hassan constructs an interesting<br />

and authoritative shorthand list that enables us to contrast clearly the main<br />

differences between modernism and postmodernism. Below is an abridged<br />

version of this: 12<br />

Modernism Postmodernism<br />

Purpose Play<br />

Presence Absence<br />

Transcendence Immanence<br />

Centring Dispersal<br />

Synthesis Antithesis<br />

Art object/Finished work Process/Happening<br />

Design Chance<br />

Hierarchy Anarchy<br />

Distance Participation<br />

If we apply this list to <strong>Sartre's</strong> work, his postmodernist markings come<br />

readily into view. In <strong>Sartre's</strong> early philosophy, transcendence is a<br />

dominant motif that finds expression in an idealist theory of freedom.<br />

Although Sartre never abandons his notion of the possibility of "going<br />

beyond existing circumstances", the concept of immanence assumes a far<br />

greater prominence in his post-war philosophy, culminating in an<br />

encumbered subject which, like the decentred subject theorised by the<br />

French poststructuralists, is shot through with social, historical, linguistic<br />

and semiotic codes. Even in his early philosophy, the Sartrean subject is<br />

marked by the features of dispersal and absence—consciousness is, Sartre<br />

insists, "diasporic", "non-identical", and has "its being outside it, before it<br />

11 Hassan, The Postmodern Turn, 37.<br />

12 See Hassan, The Dismemberment of Orpheus, Chapter 1.


The New Sartre: A Postmodern Progenitor? 109<br />

and behind". Purpose and play both appear as important themes at<br />

different times in <strong>Sartre's</strong> philosophy, the former being most evident in the<br />

Critique, where he adopts a praxis-based model of agency, and the latter in<br />

his earlier existentialist texts where he assumes a more aestheticist leaning.<br />

Despite the strong Marxist colouration of <strong>Sartre's</strong> social philosophy in<br />

the Critique, the concepts of process and antithesis capture well the<br />

essence and features of the Sartrean dialectic. The concept of totalisation<br />

that looms large in <strong>Sartre's</strong> dialectic involves synthesis insofar as it<br />

consists in drawing disparate elements into a meaningful totality but is<br />

always, as William McBride notes, a "process word" denoting activity,<br />

performance and happening, and so does not refer to a rigorously<br />

completed or definable entity. 14 Similarly, in contrast to the Hegelian<br />

dialectic, the Sartrean dialectic invokes no ultimate synthesis of its<br />

constituent parts (pour-soi and ensoi, "for-itself" and "in-itself f ) that<br />

proceeds towards a state of perfected human consciousness or the "end of<br />

history". <strong>Sartre's</strong> theory of history conceives the historical process in<br />

terms of contingency, chance, negation and circularity, criticising linear<br />

accounts that give history a progressivist telos or intrinsic pattern of<br />

design. 15<br />

The political logic of <strong>Sartre's</strong> work also displays a discernibly<br />

postmodern ethos insofar as it is premised on the eradication of hierarchy<br />

and distance. This blossoms into a form of political activism that drew him<br />

towards political Marxism in the 1940s and 1950s, but eventually drove<br />

him away following May 1968. <strong>Sartre's</strong> archetype of the group-in-fusion<br />

can be seen alongside Deleuze's and Guattari's idea of the subject group<br />

as guiding theoretical models for a new form of political practice that<br />

emerged out of the student revolts of 1968. Unlike the hierarchical,<br />

authoritarian structures of modern political practice, this involves fluid,<br />

egalitarian, anarchic, reciprocal and participatory forms of political<br />

organisation. Although Sartre did not explicitly adopt the dialogue of<br />

"micropolitics" advocated by Foucault, Lyotard and others, his political<br />

project, both before and after the war, is generally consistent with it,<br />

moving beyond the traditional focus of Marxist theory to uncover and<br />

contest wider sources of power and domination in the social field: these<br />

extend beyond the productive order and serve to "jeopardise the exploited<br />

classes to the extent that they intrude into each individual from without<br />

13 Sartre, Being and Nothingness, 182,713,179.<br />

14 McBride, "Existential Marxism and Postmodernism", 332.<br />

15 See, for instance, Critique, 33-35.


110 Chapter Eight<br />

and impose themselves in the memory as ramparts against any coming to<br />

awareness". 16<br />

These similarities that span across the broad theoretical range of the<br />

subject, social theory, history and politics, clearly mark a determinate and<br />

significant postmodern element in <strong>Sartre's</strong> thinking that is present from the<br />

outset in the 1930s and intensifies as his work evolves. They point<br />

unequivocally to a "new", postmodern Sartre, and to an urgent need to<br />

reposition his traditional place among the standard-bearers of modern<br />

philosophy.<br />

In the trajectory of <strong>Sartre's</strong> work from the 1930s to the 1970s, the<br />

modern and postmodern elements of his thought can at times intensify or<br />

recede according to a particular text or to a specific emphasis within a<br />

single text. The Critique, for instance, contains both modern and<br />

postmodern themes, utilising, developing, clarifying and reinvigorating<br />

Marxist theory as it simultaneously probes its weaknesses and calls into<br />

question its basic methods. Similarly, although Being and Nothingness<br />

reproduces features of a Cartesian framework, there are other significant<br />

elements in this work that move beyond this framework and connect with<br />

later postmodernist themes—in particular, <strong>Sartre's</strong> critique, as Foucault<br />

noted, of "the idea of the self as something which is given to us". 17<br />

Changing intensities and emphases can also be found in postmodernists<br />

like Foucault, Deleuze and Guattari, whose work incorporates a mixture of<br />

postmodern and modern elements. In the passage from Foucault's<br />

archaeology to genealogy, for example, his focus changes significantly<br />

from showing how the subject is fundamentally constructed, to a form of<br />

analysis that seeks to draw out the political consequences of subjectification<br />

in order to help form resistances to subjectifying practices. In the transition<br />

from genealogy to ethics, Foucault replaces subjectivity in the confined<br />

body with the constitution of subjectivity in the self-consciousness of<br />

desire, and switches, in this sense, from impersonal explanations of why<br />

people act as they do to the reflective practices whereby individuals train<br />

themselves. In this later ethical period, Foucault even returns to Kant (a<br />

previous target of his critique of modernity in Les Mots et les choses) as a<br />

critical means of identifying "that thread that may connect us with the<br />

Enlightenment". 18 This can be seen too in the case of Lyotard, who begins<br />

in the 1960s with a radical anti-modernist Nietzscheanism, but ends up in<br />

the 1980s echoing the mantra of Kant's critical Enlightenment project. 19<br />

Sartre, U Idiot de lafamille, III, 47 (my translation).<br />

17 Foucault, "How we Behave", 64.<br />

18 In Rabinow, The Foucault Reader, 42.<br />

19 See, for instance, Lyotard, "Rewriting Modernity", in Substance, 1987.


The New Sartre: A Postmodern Progenitor? Ill<br />

To clarify the complexity of this modern / postmodern constellation in<br />

the work of the French poststructuralists, it is useful to employ the<br />

distinction between affirmative and sceptical forms of postmodernism, in<br />

order to contrast those who reconfigure, rework and transform modernist<br />

categories such as the subject, freedom and reason, with those who tend to<br />

dissolve them as sceptics do. It is the way in which the more extreme,<br />

sceptical forms of postmodernism dissolve completely these modernist<br />

categories that has prompted some affirmatives, like Guattari, to distance<br />

themselves from postmodern discourse. Despite agreeing with postmodernism<br />

in general that a "certain idea of progress and of modernity has<br />

gone bankrupt", in his essay "The Postmodern Dead End" (1986), 20 for<br />

instance, Guattari identifies the popular discourse of postmodernism as a<br />

cynical and reactionary fad which engenders an ethics of non-commitment<br />

that paralyses affirmative political action when social repression and<br />

ecological crises are escalating. In the 1980s, both Lyotard and Foucault<br />

similarly distanced themselves from some of the fashionable bons mots of<br />

the postmodern discourse.<br />

In spite of these "constellated similarities" between Sartrean and some<br />

forms of affirmative postmodern theory, there is nonetheless a greater<br />

intensity and gravity towards the modern in <strong>Sartre's</strong> work than in the work<br />

of Foucault, Deleuze and other poststructuralists. In the area of the subject,<br />

Sartre maintains a consistent attachment to some forth of humanism and<br />

freedom that contrasts with the anti-humanist dialogue sometimes taken up<br />

by the French poststructuralists, even though he prefigures many of the<br />

themes of the "decentred subject" which they later adopt. In this respect,<br />

<strong>Sartre's</strong> assiduous efforts to probe the complex dimensions of (subjective)<br />

freedom and his endeavour to resurrect a theory of autonomy in the face of<br />

its progressive alienation through "bad faith" {Being and Nothingness), or<br />

through the determining force of the "practico-inert" {Critique of<br />

Dialectical Reason), contrast favourably with the extreme anti-humanism<br />

of the 1960s, in which Foucault and others were proclaiming the "death of<br />

the subject" and the eclipse of meaningful agency.<br />

Without doubt, the humanist insignia of <strong>Sartre's</strong> work is something<br />

that generally sits uncomfortably with the postmodern outlook. According<br />

to Derrida, for instance, by making "man'' into a supreme value or<br />

measure, "humanism" is essentially a form of exclusion and racism since it<br />

excludes women, children and animals and defines "humanity" according<br />

to specific cultural norms. 21 This critique of humanism links up with Levi-<br />

20 Guattari, "The Postmodern Dead End", 40.<br />

21 See Derrida, Of Spirit: Heidegger and the Question, 62, 70.


112 Chapter Eight<br />

Strauss's criticisms of Sartre in The Savage Mind, where <strong>Sartre's</strong> Critique<br />

is seen as ethnocentric since, as Levi-Strauss observes, it excludes from<br />

the "properly human" all previous, supposedly "ahistorical", societies of<br />

"repetition". 22<br />

Although Sartre is consistently vitriolic towards forms of humanism<br />

associated with bourgeois individualism, there is nonetheless a discernible<br />

anthropocentric bias in his work that places him much closer to the<br />

modernist paradigm. This is evident most of all in the way he consistently<br />

distinguishes the human realm from the rest of nature in his work,<br />

valorising the former as pour-soi, active and transformational, and<br />

associating the latter with the brute, inert, en-soi qualities of matter. As<br />

Boundas points out, this demonstrates a noticeable difference between "the<br />

Sartrean prose of the is and is not" and "the poststructuralist, minoritarian<br />

discourse of the and'? 3 Indeed, <strong>Sartre's</strong> Cartesian theorisation of nature<br />

clearly estranges him from the postmodern quest to re-enchant nature and<br />

to resurrect it from the denuding, utilitarian and analytical logic of modern<br />

science.<br />

This is, however, at least partially offset by other elements in his<br />

work—in particular, his notion of dialectical reason—which inveigh<br />

against the analytical reason of modern science and move beyond a<br />

simplified Cartesianism. Although Sartre clearly elevates the human above<br />

the non-human throughout his work, he does reject forms of humanism<br />

that serve to exclude and subordinate, arguing in the Critique (in tones<br />

redolent of Derrida) that "humanism is the obverse of racism: it is a<br />

practice of exclusion". 24 Thus, in the third volume of U Idiot de lafamille<br />

(The Family Idiot), he is quick to dismiss abstract notions of "humanity":<br />

Humanity is not and corresponds diachronically to no concept; what exists<br />

is an infinite series whose principle is recurrence, defined precisely by<br />

these terms: man is the son of man. For this reason history is perpetually<br />

finished, that is to say composed of broken-off sequences each of which is<br />

the divergent continuation (not mechanically but dialectically) of the<br />

preceding one and also its transcendence toward the same and different<br />

ends (which assumes that it is at once distorted and conserved). 25<br />

The complex constellation of modern and postmodern themes in<br />

<strong>Sartre's</strong> work can also be seen in the area of social theory and historical<br />

See Levi-Strauss, The Savage Mind, 324-57.<br />

Boundas, "Foreclosure of the Other", 339-40.<br />

Sartre, Critique of Dialectical Reason, I, 702.<br />

Sartre, VIdiot de lafamille, III, 346-47 (my translation).


The New Sartre: A Postmodern Progenitor? 113<br />

explanation. Central to <strong>Sartre's</strong> socio-historical theory is the concept of<br />

totalisation which, at the outset, does not square readily with the<br />

postmodern preference for detotalisation. As a synthesising activity that<br />

draws together disparate elements into a meaningful whole, <strong>Sartre's</strong><br />

concept of totalisation contrasts with postmodernist attempts to fragment,<br />

splinter and pluralise the social field. Sartre does at times emphasise the<br />

poly valence of meanings and the detotalised nature of all alleged totalities,<br />

but his intention elsewhere is to give history a single, unitary meaning. 26<br />

Whether one ascribes greater emphasis to the element of detotalisation in<br />

<strong>Sartre's</strong> work, or fixes instead on his attempts to unify history and provide<br />

a single meaning, it is clear that his socio-historical outlook incorporates<br />

both these elements that intensify and recede as his emphasis changes.<br />

Sartre, however, is not the only one who equivocates between totalisation<br />

and detotalisation in this way, for it is possible to glimpse a similar<br />

equivocation in Foucault and other poststructuralists, who utilise totalising<br />

methods and concepts as they simultaneously prohibit and condemn<br />

them. 27<br />

This complex blend of the modern and the postmodern can also be<br />

found in <strong>Sartre's</strong> political outlook, which gravitates towards the<br />

postmodern search for new forms of politicisation and political practice,<br />

while retaining key modernist notions such as the categories of need,<br />

political freedom, commitment and agency. Sartre shows none of the<br />

suspicion that postmodernists like Baudrillard exhibit towards the category<br />

of need, making it the starting-point of his investigation in the Critique'.<br />

"Everything is to be explained through need; need is the first totalising<br />

relation between the material man, and the material ensemble of which he<br />

is a part." 28 The difficulty with <strong>Sartre's</strong> account of need in the Critique, I<br />

have argued, is not so much the way he invokes it as a central point of<br />

departure, but the way in which he tends to equate need with material need<br />

alone, thus reproducing standard Marxist interpretations (reflected, above<br />

all, in his consistent emphasis on the necessity of material abundance as a<br />

prerequisite for the possibility of a communist society, and his consequent<br />

preoccupation with eradicating scarcity). In spite of this, however, Sartre<br />

does begin to probe the dynamic of solidarity through the category of<br />

need, which creates a shared human condition, and so goes some way<br />

See Sartre, Search for a Method, 90, and Critique of Dialectical Reason, II, 20.<br />

27 Habermas refers to this as a "performative contradiction" in Foucault's work.<br />

See The Philosophical Discourse of Modernity, Chapter 1.<br />

28 Sartre, Critique of Dialectical Reason, I, 80.


114 Chapter Eight<br />

towards constructing an account of intersubjectivity that is largely absent<br />

from the postmodernist narrative. 29<br />

In the years that followed the Critique up to his death, Sartre<br />

developed this idea of need further, integrating it centrally into the<br />

framework of a "Third Ethics" which he outlined in dialogue with Benny<br />

L£vy in the 1970s, and which he had initially proposed in The Rome<br />

Lecture given at the Gramsci Institute in May, 1964. In The Rome Lecture,<br />

Sartre states that "[t]he root of morality is in need". Radical, unalienated<br />

needs, he argues, are those that humans possess, as members of the human<br />

species, and belong to "nude man" irrespective of class, system or culture.<br />

They constitute a form of "human reality" which is "common to men" and<br />

allow us to define humanity as "belonging to a species". 30 In his sketch of<br />

a "Third Ethics", Sartre insists that, in contrast to his previous ethics, this<br />

one is "une morale du NOUS" ("a morality of the WE"). 31 Although he<br />

had previously theorised intersubjectivity and communality in the Critique<br />

and in Cahiers pour une morale (Notebooks for an Ethics), he had insisted<br />

that union between individuals is fragile, ephemeral, and purely practical,<br />

and not constituted in any other, deeper way. In an interview with Michel<br />

Sicard shortly before his death, however, Sartre moves beyond this<br />

position and posits the existence of an internal ontological bond between<br />

human beings:<br />

[O]ntologically, consciousnesses are not isolated, there are planes where<br />

they enter into one another—planes common to two or to n consciousnesses.<br />

[... humans'] perceptions or their thought are in relation one with<br />

others, not only by exposure to the other, but because there are<br />

penetrations between consciousnesses. 32<br />

Although <strong>Sartre's</strong> communally-based "Third Ethics" remains a<br />

provisional sketch rather than a fully elaborated model, it is indicative of a<br />

progressive trajectory in his work towards a more positive account of<br />

sociality and intersubjectivity in which "one must try to learn that one can<br />

only seek one's being, one's life, in living for others". 33 This movement<br />

towards intersubjectivity in <strong>Sartre's</strong> later work reveals him as a<br />

philosopher of change, who is able to leave behind previous categorial<br />

29 See Farrell Fox, The New Sartre, 42-53.<br />

30 Sartre, The Rome Lecture, 100, 88 (my translation).<br />

31 Sartre, "Entretien [avec Michel Sicard]", Obliques, 15.<br />

32 Ibid, (my translation).<br />

33 Sartre, "Man muss fur sich selbst und fur die anderen leben", 1221-22 (my<br />

translation).


The New Sartre: A Postmodern Progenitor? 115<br />

assumptions by turning his critical vision towards complexity and<br />

constellation rather than stasis and univocity.<br />

Another significant respect in which <strong>Sartre's</strong> political outlook contrasts<br />

with the postmodernist view is his search for a primary political agent<br />

which, as Pontalis has noted, changes as <strong>Sartre's</strong> political trajectory<br />

evolves. In his early political period this agent is the individual, in his<br />

middle phase the Communist Party (PCF), and in his later period, the<br />

youth. This clashes directly with the postmodern project to pluralise<br />

political agency (or to dissolve it altogether, as in the case of Baudrillard)<br />

in order to prevent the imposition of the viewpoint of a single hegemonic<br />

group. Postmodernists decentre the importance of the proletariat as a<br />

primary political agent, favouring instead a kind of patchwork alliance<br />

between different and disparate discourses, knowledges and groups. By<br />

contrast, in Anti-Semite and Jew, Sartre argues for the prime historical<br />

importance and status of the proletariat, arguing that it is not merely one<br />

oppressed group among several, but a "universal class" which holds the<br />

key to the liquidation of oppression:<br />

The reason why the revolutionary adopts the standpoint of the proletariat is<br />

first of all because this is his own class, then because it is oppressed,<br />

because it is by far the most numerous, so that its fate tends to merge with<br />

that of humanity, and finally because the consequences of its victory<br />

necessarily entail the suppression of classes. 34<br />

Sartre steadily distances himself from this Marxist viewpoint as his<br />

work evolves, turning instead, in his final political period, to the youth and<br />

to student groups as a prime focus for progressive political change.<br />

However, although the object of his focus changes as his work evolves, his<br />

political project consistently inclines towards unity embodied in his idea of<br />

a prime political agent—an idea that postmodernist political thinking<br />

rejects (following Lyotard) as terroristic and exclusionary.<br />

This tension between <strong>Sartre's</strong> universalising and unifying political<br />

aims and the postmodern preference for multiplicity, difference,<br />

fragmentation and plurality can be seen in part in the changing role of the<br />

intellectual following 1968 in France, which led Sartre to question and<br />

revise his own status as a classic intellectual. This came most notably into<br />

focus in 1969 when, addressing a meeting of student groups at the<br />

Mutualite, he was given the instruction "Sartre, sois bref—"Sartre, be<br />

brief'. 35 This small incident was representative of a wider shift in the role<br />

34 Sartre, Anti-Semite and Jew, 72.<br />

35 For a description of this incident see Cohen-Solal, Sartre: A Life, 780-81.


116 Chapter Eight<br />

and aims of the intellectual that followed 1968. In Foucault's view, this<br />

involved a shift away from the "general" (modern) intellectual, who<br />

speaks on behalf of all oppressed groups, towards the (postmodern)<br />

"specific" intellectual, who acts as an advisor within a particular group or<br />

form of struggle. In opposition to the unifying aims of the general or<br />

classic intellectual, the specific intellectual, Foucault argues, helps to<br />

ensure the autonomy of local struggles by recovering "subjugated" and<br />

"disqualified" knowledges from the hegemony of positivistic sciences,<br />

hierarchical political parties, and master-narratives. While it is clear that<br />

<strong>Sartre's</strong> abiding search for a totalising consciousness and primary political<br />

agent would seem to contravene the pluralist discourse of the specific<br />

intellectual that Foucault and other postmodernists advocate, it is also the<br />

case that 1968 precipitated a change in <strong>Sartre's</strong> outlook. The events of<br />

1968 made him realise the limitations of his privileged classic intellectual<br />

status, and changed his view of the intellectual's role which, he now<br />

argued in line with Foucault, must be to serve the masses:<br />

Today I have finally understood that the intellectual [...] must resolve his<br />

own problem—or, if you like, negate his intellectual moment in order to<br />

achieve a new popular status. 36<br />

Sartre Old and New<br />

In the course of this essay, I have endeavoured to sketch a picture in<br />

which two Sartres can be seen to emerge alongside each other: the Old<br />

Sartre—assertive and totalistic, Cartesian and classic, modernist and<br />

Marxist, an optimist and grand-thinker—and a New postmodern Sartre<br />

who is changing and plural, aestheticised and splintered, aporetic and<br />

anarchistic, a pessimist and arch-deconstructionist. Like two pugilists in a<br />

boxing-ring (an image central to <strong>Sartre's</strong> investigation in the <strong>second</strong><br />

volume of the Critique), they shadow one another, join together, clash,<br />

contend and struggle for primacy within individual texts and in his work<br />

taken as a whole. However, there is no clear resolution or victorious endpoint<br />

to this fight but an ongoing agonism of differences and emphases<br />

that rise and fall as <strong>Sartre's</strong> critical perspective shifts.<br />

In standard interpretations of Sartre, only the face of the Old classical<br />

Sartre is recognised—that is, the humanist Sartre resolutely opposed to the<br />

postmodern trickeries of the French poststructuralists. This view still bears<br />

a strong influence and is evident, for instance, in Andrew Dobson's book,<br />

Sartre, Between Existentialism and Marxism, 227.


The New Sartre: A Postmodern Progenitor? 117<br />

Jean-Paul Sartre and the Politics of Reason, where Sartre is presented as a<br />

Master Constructionist impelled by an Enlightenment animus that is<br />

distinctly anti-postmodern. Against this view, I would argue that there are<br />

strong postmodern elements in <strong>Sartre's</strong> work that span the broad<br />

theoretical range, from his analysis of the subject through his theory of<br />

history to his understanding of political life, making him, to use Frederic<br />

Jameson's phrase, a "hidden origin" of important theoretical manoeuvres in<br />

postmodernist theory. 37<br />

In general terms, I present Sartre as a schizophrenic thinker whose<br />

critical consciousness is split between the modern and the postmodern.<br />

Indeed, I think that much of the originality and dynamism of his work lies<br />

precisely in this tense relationship between modern and postmodern<br />

elements. <strong>Sartre's</strong> relation to modernism is not straightforward but<br />

complex, vacillating between a project to overturn, break open and move<br />

beyond modernist modes of understanding and an underlying impetus to<br />

hold on to certain modernist ideas and categories. This tension is reflected<br />

in the final years of his life, which he divided between a political activism<br />

that struggled desperately to overthrow the social conditions of capitalist<br />

modernity and a classic, academic study of the bourgeois Flaubert that was<br />

far removed from this activist impulse. Thus, although Sartre was unable<br />

to transcend fully his starting-points, he was able, as Ronald Aronson has<br />

pointed out, to think—and live—them to their limits, while immersing<br />

himself in our world and its most powerful cross-currents. 38<br />

Undoubtedly, there are several respects in which Sartre was unable to<br />

transcend the limitations imposed on him by the philosophical, social,<br />

historical and political situation of his time. On a theoretical level, this<br />

manifests itself in his inability to get beyond some of the theoretical<br />

limitations of the (modernist) outlook he inherited from Descartes, Husserl<br />

and Marx. On a political level, this came into view in the early 1950s,<br />

where <strong>Sartre's</strong> allegiance to the PCF was strongly influenced by the<br />

ideological polarities of the Cold War environment. In this sense, although<br />

Sartre stretched the parameters of modernism to their limits, articulating<br />

new perspectives that prefigured many important themes taken up later by<br />

postmodernists like Foucault, Guattari and Derrida, in other respects he<br />

was unable to progress fully beyond these limits, reproducing some of the<br />

basic assumptions which form the modernist outlook and the classical<br />

French tradition of which he was a part.<br />

37 Frederic Jameson, "The Sartrean Origin", 19.<br />

38 Aronson, Jean-Paul Sartre: Philosophy in the World, 353.


118 Chapter Eight<br />

Despite these limitations, it is worthwhile in overall terms to<br />

emphasise the positive value of <strong>Sartre's</strong> work in understanding and<br />

navigating our contemporary postmodern situation. Like postmodernists<br />

such as Foucault, Deleuze, Derrida, Guattari, Lyotard and Baudrillard,<br />

Sartre offers a trenchant critique of the condition of modernity and a deep,<br />

searching scepticism towards the project of the Enlightenment. More<br />

importantly, however, his work acts as a kind of critical searchlight that<br />

shines through the cracks and exposes the fragile foundations of both<br />

modern and postmodern excesses. Thus, there are clearly aspects of<br />

postmodernism that are anathema to <strong>Sartre's</strong> theoretical sensibilities.<br />

Beneath the elements of change and evolution in his philosophical<br />

outlook, there is a deep and consistent attachment to the idea of human<br />

freedom and of transforming the world to bring this about. In the 1960s,<br />

this brought Sartre into conflict with (post)structuralists like Foucault,<br />

Derrida and Althusser who were intent at the time on consigning the figure<br />

of "Man" to the dustbin of history. In the late 1960s and the 1970s,<br />

Foucault and others severed their links with structuralism and moved on to<br />

the (Sartrean) project of resurrecting the subject and articulating a vision<br />

of freedom, relinquishing their hostility and adopting a more positive<br />

attitude towards the value of <strong>Sartre's</strong> work. In an interview in 1968 for<br />

instance, Foucault pays homage to <strong>Sartre's</strong> contribution to intellectual<br />

thought in France and views his own work as "minor" in relation to the<br />

"immensity" of <strong>Sartre's</strong>:<br />

I think the immense work and political action of Sartre defines an era. [...]<br />

I would never accept a comparison—even for the sake of a contrast—of<br />

the minor work of historical and methodological spadework that I do with<br />

a body of work like his. 39<br />

In an article devoted to Sartre, entitled "II a 6t6 mon maitre",<br />

published in a special 1964 issue of the periodical, Arts, Deleuze also<br />

expresses his admiration for "the private thinker [who] introduced new<br />

themes, a new style, a new polemic and a new way of raising problems as<br />

well as a hatred for all modes of 'representation'". 40 He reiterates this<br />

tribute in a series of interviews with Claire Parnet, published as Dialogues<br />

in 1977, where he speaks enthusiastically of his respect for Sartre:<br />

Foucault, in La Quinzaine litteraire, no. 46 (1968), 20, cited in Poster, Foucault,<br />

Marxism and History, 5.<br />

40 Deleuze, "II a 6l€ mon maitre", 1208-09 (my translation).


The New Sartre: A Postmodern Progenitor? 119<br />

Fortunately there was Sartre. Sartre was our Outside, he was really the<br />

breath of fresh air from the backyard [...]. And Sartre has never stopped<br />

being that, not a model, a method or an example, but a little fresh air—a<br />

gust of air even when he had just been to the Cafe* Flore—an intellectual<br />

who singularly changed the situation of the intellectual. 41<br />

Similarly, despite his previous criticisms of Sartre in the 1960s and<br />

1970s, in the lead article for the commemorative fiftieth anniversary issue<br />

of Les Temps modernes, Derrida expresses the "boundless gratitude" and<br />

acknowledges the "immense debt" he and others owe to Sartre. He<br />

confesses that in previous years he "wouldn't have dared" admit his<br />

affection for Sartre and Les Temps modernes, but that he is now moved to<br />

"do justice" to them and recognise the value of <strong>Sartre's</strong> philosophical<br />

ceuvre. 42 Even Baudrillard, the arch-sceptic of postmodernity, acknowledges<br />

the enormity of <strong>Sartre's</strong> influence on post-war French intellectual<br />

life and how the "theory of commitment through Sartre in the 1960s [...]<br />

had been more or less the point of departure for intellectuals". 43<br />

Since his death in 1980, however, commitment has seemingly died<br />

with Sartre. The postmodern condition presented by Baudrillard and others<br />

is one in which apathy, nihilism, melancholy and withdrawal are seen as<br />

appropriate responses to a prevailing situation characterised by meaninglessness,<br />

simulation, hyperconformity and the absence of grand-narratives<br />

that claim a better future for human society. In contrast with Baudrillard's<br />

asemic political vision, that celebrates the death of meaning and the futility<br />

of political action and engagement, <strong>Sartre's</strong> political itinerary is an<br />

evolving story of progressive radicalisation, a ceaseless journey to explore<br />

the radical possibilities and complex dimensions of freedom, with a view<br />

to making the world a less alienating and oppressive home. Shortly before<br />

his death, in the course of interviews with Benny Le\y (published in<br />

March 1980 as VEspoir maintenant [Hope Now]), Sartre identifies hope<br />

as a means of overcoming the malaise of apathy and despair that<br />

characterises the postmodern world of the late twentieth <strong>century</strong>:<br />

What with the third world war that can break out at any day, and the<br />

wretched mess our planet has become, despair has come back to tempt me<br />

with the idea that there is no end to it all, that there is no goal, that there<br />

are only small, individual objectives that we fight for. We make small<br />

revolutions, but there's no human end, there's nothing of concern to human<br />

beings, there's only disorder [...]. In any event, the world seems ugly, evil,<br />

41 Deleuze, Dialogues, 12.<br />

42 Derrida, "II courait mort", 44,40 (my translations).<br />

43 In Gane, Baudrillard: Critical and Fatal Theory, 17.


120 Chapter Eight<br />

and hopeless. Such is the calm despair of an old man who will die in that<br />

despair. But the point is, I'm resisting, and I know I shall die in hope. But<br />

this hope must be grounded. We must try to explain why the world of<br />

today, which is horrible, is only one moment in a long historical<br />

development, that hope has always been one of the dominant forces of<br />

revolutions and insurrections, and how I still feel that hope is my<br />

conception of the future. 44<br />

Whether the future conforms to <strong>Sartre's</strong> hope-full conception remains<br />

to be seen, marked as it is, of course, by the feature of contingency that<br />

Sartre theorised so effectively throughout his work. In any case, his critical<br />

spirit, philosophical guile and gift of dialectical understanding provide us<br />

with the inspiration and the means to recover a sense of the authentically<br />

human in an increasingly inhuman and cybernetic postmodern world. In<br />

the context of Deleuze's remark, in Negotiations, that "[a] thought's logic<br />

is like a wind blowing on us, a series of gusts and jolts", <strong>Sartre's</strong><br />

thinking can be likened to a gust of freedom which blows away<br />

constricting webs that bind and entrap. This shines through in the focus of<br />

his work, which grapples constantly with the problematic of freedom, as<br />

well as in his personal life, where his activism and struggle against<br />

oppression thrust him into the forefront of ideological and political<br />

controversy in post-war France. Somewhat diminutive and corpulent,<br />

physically enfeebled and almost blind in his later years, Sartre stood<br />

defiantly as a resolute defender of the marginalised and downtrodden<br />

against the strong arm of the Goliath capitalist state. This made him an<br />

object of vitriolic hatred for the French state, which threatened on<br />

numerous occasions to imprison him; for pro-colonial groupings on the<br />

Right, who threatened and ultimately attempted to kill him; and even for<br />

those on the Left, such as the orthodox guardians of the Communist faith,<br />

who demonised and excommunicated him as a heretic. Through all this,<br />

Sartre continued, in his own inimitable way, to articulate and to refine his<br />

telling discourse of freedom. It remains to be seen how this will be taken<br />

up and articulated by others in the postmodern configuration of the<br />

twenty-first <strong>century</strong>.<br />

Works Cited<br />

Aronson, Ronald. Jean-Paul Sartre: Philosophy in the World. London:<br />

New Left Books, 1980.<br />

44 Sartre, Hope Now: The 1980 Interviews, 109-10.<br />

45 Deleuze, Negotiations, 1972-1990, 94.


The New Sartre: A Postmodern Progenitor? 121<br />

Baudrillard, Jean. Forget Foucault. New York: Semiotext(e), 1987.<br />

Boundas, Constantin. "Foreclosure of the Other: From Sartre to Deleuze",<br />

in W. McBride (ed.), <strong>Sartre's</strong> French Contemporaries and Enduring<br />

Influences. New York: Garland Publishing, 1997.<br />

Chancel, Jacques. "Radioscopie: Roland Barthes", in Radioscopie, vol. 4,<br />

1976,255-56.<br />

Cohen-Solal, Annie. Sartre: A Life. London: Heinemann, 1987.<br />

Deleuze, Gilles. "II a ete mon maitre", Arts, November 1964,1207-27.<br />

—. Dialogues (trans. H. Tomlinson and B. Habbersam). London: Athlone<br />

Press, 1987.<br />

—. Negotiations, 1972-1990 (trans. M. Joughin). New York: Columbia<br />

University Press, 1995.<br />

Derrida, Jacques. Of Spirit: Heidegger and the Question (trans. G.<br />

Bennington and R. Bowlby). Chicago: University of Chicago Press,<br />

1989.<br />

—. "'II courait mort: Salut, salut.' Notes pour un courrier aux Temps<br />

modernes", in Les Temps modernes, no. 587, 1996, 61-74.<br />

Dobson, Andrew. Jean-Paul Sartre and the Politics of Reason: A Theory<br />

of History. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993.<br />

Farrell Fox, Nicholas. The New Sartre: Explorations in Postmodernism.<br />

London: Continuum, 2003.<br />

Foucault, Michel. Remarks on Marx: Conversations with Duccio<br />

Trombadori (trans. R. Goldstein and J. Cascaito). New York:<br />

Semiotext(e), 1991.<br />

—. Les Mots et les choses. Paris: Gallimard, 1966.<br />

—. "How we Behave", Vanity Fair, November 1983.<br />

Gane, Michael. Baudrillard: Critical and Fatal Theory. London:<br />

Routledge, 1991.<br />

Guattari, Felix. "The Postmodern Dead End", Flash Art, no. 128, 1986,<br />

40-41.<br />

Habermas, Jurgen. The Philosophical Discourse of Modernity. Cambridge,<br />

MA: MIT Press, 1987.<br />

Hassan, Ihab. The Dismemberment of Orpheus: Toward a Postmodern<br />

Literature. New York: Oxford University Press, 1982.<br />

—. The Postmodern Turn. Columbus: Ohio State University Press, 1987.<br />

Howells, Christina. "Introduction", in The Cambridge Companion to<br />

Sartre (ed. C. Howells). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,<br />

1992.<br />

Jameson, Frederic. "The Sartrean Origin", Sartre Studies International,<br />

vol. 1, no. 1-2, Berghahn, 1995,1-20.


122 Chapter Eight<br />

Levi-Strauss, Claude. The Savage Mind. London: Weidenfeld and<br />

Nicolson, 1966.<br />

Lyotard, Jean-Francois. "Rewriting Modernity", Substance, no. 54,1987.<br />

McBride, William. "Existential Marxism and Postmodernism at our Fin de<br />

Siecle", in W. McBride (ed.), <strong>Sartre's</strong> French Contemporaries and<br />

Enduring Influences. New York: Garland Publishing, 1997.<br />

Poster, Mark. Foucault, Marxism and History: Mode of Production versus<br />

Mode of Information. Cambridge: Polity Press, 1984.<br />

Rabinow, Paul (ed.). The Foucault Reader. New York: Pantheon, 1984.<br />

Raulet, Gerard. "Structuralism and Post-Structuralism: An Interview with<br />

Michel Foucault" (trans. J. Harding), Telos, no. 55, Spring 1983, 195-<br />

211.<br />

Sartre, Jean-Paul. Being and Nothingness: An Essay in Phenomenological<br />

Ontology (trans. H. E. Barnes). London: Philosophical Library, 1956.<br />

—. The Rome Lecture (at the Gramsci Institute), 1964: available at the<br />

Bibliotheque Nationale, Paris.<br />

—. Anti-Semite and Jew (trans. G. Becker). New York: Schocken Books,<br />

1965.<br />

—. Between Existentialism and Marxism (trans. J. Mathews). New York:<br />

Pantheon, 1974.<br />

—. VIdiotde lafamilley III. Paris: Gallimard, 1974.<br />

—. The Critique of Dialectical Reason, I: Theory of Practical Ensembles<br />

(trans. A. Sheridan-Smith). London: New Left Books, 1976.<br />

—. The Critique of Dialectical Reason, II: The Intelligibility of History<br />

(trans. A. Sheridan-Smith). London: Verso, 1985.<br />

—. Cahiers pour une morale. Paris: Gallimard, 1983.<br />

—. "J.-P. Sartre et M. Sicard: Entretien", in Obliques, no. 18-19, 1979, 9-<br />

29.<br />

—. "Man muss fur sich selbst und fur die anderen leben", Merkur,<br />

December 1979.<br />

—. Hope Now: The 1980 Interviews (trans. Adrian van den Hoven).<br />

Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1996.


CHAPTER NINE<br />

A SURREPTITIOUS ROMANTIC?<br />

READING SARTRE WITH VICTOR HUGO<br />

BRADLEY STEPHENS<br />

"A seismographic and prophetic Sartre, the man of the <strong>century</strong>, organ<br />

blasts a la Hugo, podiums, voice of the oriflamme and grand<br />

commitments." 1 Bernard-Henri Levy's picture of Sartre in relation to<br />

Victor Hugo flags a connection between these two cultural icons that is<br />

widely acknowledged. The two become automatically linked as<br />

practitioners of the traditional moral-political stance of French engagement<br />

(commitment). Sartre indeed is held to be the most recent—maybe even<br />

the last—member of a prestigious lineage comprising Voltaire, Hugo and<br />

Zola. They are the tireless men of letters, the ecrivains engages, those<br />

French writers who committed themselves to the Revolution's principles<br />

of liberty, equality, and fraternity. Hugo and Sartre, in particular, have<br />

come to be seen as the foremost representatives of this tradition in their<br />

respective times, with each of their energetic lives almost perfectly<br />

spanning the nineteenth and twentieth centuries, centuries which came to<br />

be known as theirs. 2<br />

The historical similarities between the two are stark. Born in 1802,<br />

Hugo would strike a chord with his time by demanding that art free not<br />

only content, but also form, from the regimen of Classicism. Campaigning<br />

for French Romanticism, he privileged the boundless human imagination<br />

rather than a reasoned intellect. Only then could the artist truly become a<br />

part of the <strong>century</strong>'s quest for democracy, liberating both his world and his<br />

work from constraint. Preferring exile to empire, he was the conscience of<br />

a nation, ensuring that Emperor Louis-Napoleon would forever be known<br />

as "Napoleon le Petit". He defied social convention, amassing one wife,<br />

1 L6vy, Sartre, 32.<br />

2 An earlier draft of this chapter was given as a paper at the Centenary Conference<br />

of the UK Sartre Society at the Institut Fran^ais, London, in March 2005.


124 Chapter Nine<br />

one long-term mistress, and countless sexual encounters that amazingly<br />

escalated in number the older he got. He became an inspiration to Dickens,<br />

Tolstoy, Van Gogh and Tennyson, to name but a handful, and some two<br />

million people descended upon Paris for his funeral in 1885, itself a State<br />

event attended by dignitaries and drunks alike. Death did little to slow<br />

down Hugo's ascent to superstardom as the "Elvis or Madonna" of his<br />

day. 3 His enduring universal appeal is perhaps best indicated by the<br />

unprecedented popularity of the stage version of Les Miserables, which<br />

became the first Western musical to be granted performance in communist<br />

China in June 2002.<br />

Such impressive credentials are not unfamiliar to Sartre. From 1945<br />

onwards, he graced the pages of Vogue, Time, even Playboy, becoming so<br />

internationally recognised that Charles de Gaulle famously refused to<br />

place him under arrest. Revealing the indeterminate and Godless nature of<br />

existence, Sartrean Existentialism articulated not only the despair of an<br />

entire generation forced to live in the age of the atomic bomb, but also its<br />

hope that human creativity could be used more positively to remake a<br />

better world. Criss-crossing the world, he met with Castro, drank with<br />

Cocteau, and dined with Chaplin, refusing to conform to any social status<br />

quo. Long before the summer of love sizzled in 1967, he made no secret of<br />

his virtual open marriage with Simone de Beauvoir, nor of his affairs. 4 At<br />

least 50,000 people followed his coffin in 1980, with the Left Bank today<br />

remaining the breeding ground for aspiring intellectuals. His willingness to<br />

philosophise every corner of modern living, from politics to jazz, has since<br />

helped thinkers broaden both their subject matter and their audience,<br />

"opening-out" rather than "dumbing-down".<br />

Faced with such immense cultural standing, it is hardly surprising that<br />

references thus far to Hugo within Sartre studies have been more anecdotal<br />

than analytical. The brightness of their respective stars seems to blind the<br />

critical eye and prevent scholars from looking any closer. These giants are<br />

frequently linked only by their place in history and their will to speak out,<br />

without questioning whether their thinking or writing could be connected<br />

in a more substantial way. What has arguably hindered any attempt to<br />

pursue this matter is the unease and even resentment that many writers and<br />

academics have displayed towards Hugo since his death. Andre Gide's<br />

notorious "Helas!" ("Alas!"), when confirming Hugo as his choice of the<br />

greatest French poet of the nineteenth <strong>century</strong>, 5 reflects a discomfort<br />

3<br />

Grossman, "From Classic to Pop Icon".<br />

4<br />

Both <strong>Sartre's</strong> and Hugo's galanterie is notorious: see Rowley, Tete-a-Tete, and<br />

Decker, Hugo.<br />

5<br />

Replying to a survey in L'Ermitage, February 1902,109.


Reading Sartre with Victor Hugo 125<br />

widely felt in a new age when Romantic sensibility was no longer in<br />

vogue, given the growing anguish of the modern period. That literary<br />

successors to Hugo have felt the need to eclipse him also owes some debt<br />

to an anxiety usually associated with childhood, whereby youth seeks to<br />

remove the father figure and determine a new identity. As Flaubert attested<br />

in 1859, "it is hopeless to write after such a man [...] this colossal poet". 6<br />

Sartre himself was the victim of such an "Oedipal reaction" from a<br />

younger generation of thinkers in the 1960s eager to make their own mark,<br />

although Hugo's fate has been more protracted. Hugo's "Romantic taste<br />

for grandiose visions and myth-making", along with his glorification, led<br />

to his imprisonment "in the display case of an anthology", trapped in the<br />

caricature of an impractical dreamer. 7<br />

In my discussion here, I want to cut through the cultural agendas and<br />

suggest that a consideration of Hugo alongside Sartre can go beyond<br />

biographical detail. Starting with Iris Murdoch's portrait of Sartre in 1953<br />

as a "Romantic Rationalist", I will show that connecting Sartre to the<br />

Romantic movement yields a fresh but telling reading that complements<br />

current criticism in studies of both Sartre and indeed Hugo. Furthermore, I<br />

will refer to overlooked comments made by Sartre himself that not only<br />

nominate Hugo as a specific interlocutor, but also suggest the nature that<br />

their dialogue should take. <strong>Sartre's</strong> reflections imply that the "High Priest"<br />

of French Romanticism and the "Pope" of Existentialism are singing from<br />

the same hymn sheet, albeit in different tones. I will compare and contrast<br />

both men's philosophies, relating their strategies of being to the wider<br />

issue of engagement that each has become synonymous with, and which<br />

has become integral to French cultural identity. Hugo may not often be<br />

thought of in philosophical terms, but his relevance as a thinker of the<br />

human condition will become apparent nonetheless. 8 Within the confines<br />

of the present chapter, I do not of course intend to provide an exhaustive<br />

6 "[I]l est d&espdrant d'e'crire apres un pareil homme [...] ce colossal poete"<br />

(Correspondence, 376). All translations from French are my own.<br />

7 Brombert, Victor Hugo, 3-5.<br />

8 Hugo certainly fits into the nineteenth-<strong>century</strong> tradition of French spiritualist<br />

philosophy after Francois Maine de Biran, who had argued against the "reductions<br />

of mental life to the flow of passing sense impressions" practised by Condillac and<br />

the Ideologues (see Gary Gutting, French Philosophy, 3-25). Hugo's own thoughts<br />

focus however on artists and writers rather than strictly philosophers, demonstrating<br />

his more Romantic tastes. Nonetheless, for Charles Renouvier, the<br />

neocritical philosopher who exerted a tremendous influence on William James and<br />

many of the Dreyfusards, Hugo was arguably one of the most insightful French<br />

thinkers of the period: see his 1900 study Victor Hugo, le philosophe, as well as<br />

Maurel, Victor Hugo, philosophe.


126<br />

Chapter Nine<br />

reading of the connection between Sartre and Hugo. Rather, I will mark<br />

the parameters of what is an original and exciting area in which future<br />

studies of Sartre might develop. 9<br />

The "New" Sartre<br />

Since <strong>Sartre's</strong> death over 25 years ago, the image of an almost<br />

schizophrenic thinker has increasingly come into focus: a "new" Sartre, as<br />

Christina Howells put it, in constant yet productive tension with his own<br />

positions. 10 "[His] diversity was far from being mastered" by the coy<br />

stereotype of an outdated thinker that had been successfully circulated by<br />

the Structuralists. 11 The most comprehensive look at this "new" Sartre is<br />

offered by Nik Farrell Fox, whose thorough study reads <strong>Sartre's</strong> work as a<br />

site of "complexity and constellation rather than stasis and univocity". 12<br />

Farrell Fox picks up on Roland Barthes's image of Sartre straddling a<br />

cultural crossroads between pre-war and post-war trends, reiterated in<br />

Levy's presentation of "un double Sartre". Levy likewise sees an earlier,<br />

rebellious Sartre, full of moral sensitivity and literary output, who reckons<br />

with a later, almost totalitarian Sartre, loaded with political conviction. 13<br />

Farrell Fox is however careful to insist that this divide is less an<br />

historical rupture than a philosophical necessity that can be traced back to<br />

the outset of <strong>Sartre's</strong> thinking. 14 He asks us to accept a "transitional"<br />

Sartre who refuses to enclose a meaningless existence within the human<br />

desire for meaning, but who craves understanding nevertheless. This<br />

Sartre slides between a postmodern awareness of disintegration and a<br />

modernist longing for constructivism. On repeated occasions, Howells<br />

9<br />

In his entry in Noudelmann and Philippe (eds), Dictionnaire Sartre, Bruno<br />

Cldment suggests that there are many justifications for a tandem study of Sartre<br />

and Hugo (226). I explored in particular the philosophical and literary similarities<br />

between the two in my doctoral thesis, which I am currently preparing for a book<br />

publication entitled Sartre, Hugo, and the Liability of Liberty.<br />

The Cambridge Companion to Sartre, 1.<br />

11<br />

See L£vi-Strauss, La Pensee sauvage, and "L'homme, est-il mort?: un entretien<br />

avec Michel Foucault", Arts et Loisirs, 38,15 June 1966, for the best examples.<br />

12<br />

Farrell Fox, New Sartre, 157.<br />

13<br />

Sartre, 460.<br />

14<br />

Here Farrell Fox echoes Jacques Derrida's tribute for the fiftieth anniversary of<br />

Les Temps modernes. Derrida found an affinity with <strong>Sartre's</strong> own internal conflict<br />

as a thinker caught between the humanism of his desire to make sense of the world<br />

through writing, and the anti-humanism of existential man's nausea at existence—<br />

both of which are in operation before his political adventures post-1945: see "II<br />

courait mort", 32.


Reading Sartre with Victor Hugo 127<br />

herself has emphasised that <strong>Sartre's</strong> sometimes uneven thinking cannot<br />

and should not be assimilated into a kind of Hegelian synthesis. Instead,<br />

his emphasis is on "maintaining in tension the dual poles of a dialectic of<br />

paradox". This tenacity "necessarily led him to reject the one-sided nature<br />

of the so-called 'death of the Subject', even though he welcomed the antiindividualism<br />

of the Structuralist endeavour in so far as it was conceived<br />

as an antidote to bourgeois humanism." 15<br />

This ongoing effort to expose and explore the plurality inherent in<br />

<strong>Sartre's</strong> thinking is seemingly anticipated by Iris Murdoch in 1953.<br />

Writing just before the onslaught of postmodernism, the English moral<br />

philosopher uses different poles in which to figure <strong>Sartre's</strong> duality.<br />

<strong>Sartre's</strong> emphasis on analytical understanding is countered in her eyes by<br />

his exuberant imagination, bringing tangible fact and emotive feeling into<br />

a turbulent interaction: the "Romantic Rationalist". She makes her point<br />

by citing a familiar dilemma of Sartrean philosophy: if man is a nonessential<br />

and therefore free being, what fundamental purpose could he ever<br />

have? Sartre may have ardently attended both to the notion of individual<br />

liberty and to its everyday practice, but he could not square one with the<br />

other into an integrated ethical framework of social conduct. For Murdoch,<br />

the devil is in the detail. Existence may precede essence for Sartre, but this<br />

binary sequence crucially depends on both. Doing and becoming are the<br />

key focus as the actions which bring us into existence, but they carry with<br />

them an element of being that cannot be fully erased. Sartre throws the<br />

individual into a to-and-fro, or va-et-vient as he puts it, always yearning<br />

for an absolute state of being and yet encountering an indeterminism<br />

which thwarts that desire.<br />

<strong>Sartre's</strong> metaphysical distinction between being and nothingness had in<br />

fact foregrounded a paradoxical duality in his philosophy. To summarise:<br />

"Consciousness is rupture, it is able to spring out of unreflective thing-like<br />

conditions—but it is also projet, it aspires towards a wholeness which<br />

forever haunts its partial state." 16 Human consciousness is insubstantial:<br />

self-reflexive being-for-itself, rather than self-present and in-itself. It<br />

ruptures us out of the material "thing-ness" of the world, but we are thus<br />

left trying to shape in the emptiness of that consciousness a world we can<br />

call our own. Sartre in turn finds himself exercising a balancing act<br />

between the conscious mind and the physical world, whereby each weighs<br />

upon the other back and forth in a fraught equilibrium. Under <strong>Sartre's</strong><br />

supervision of this existential "see-saw", conscious being and objective<br />

15 Howells, Sartre, the Necessity of Freedom, 115.<br />

16 Murdoch, Romantic Rationalist, 92.


128 Chapter Nine<br />

being can never be released from the to-and-fro movement, or flight<br />

toward being, that distinguishes man from thing and lends him his<br />

freedom:<br />

The being of human reality is originally not a substance but a lived relation<br />

[...]. We should not say that man is at all: he is what he is not and he is not<br />

what he is; he is the annihilation of the contingent In-itself in so far as the<br />

self of this annihilation is its flight ahead toward the In-itself as selfcause.<br />

17<br />

"[T]he Sartrean subject is not just a thinking, rationalising consciousness<br />

which gives meaning to things, but is also engaged—an actor immersed in<br />

the world of things. In this sense it incorporates both freedom and<br />

necessity, transcendence and facticity." 18 It is in praxis, as Sartre says, by<br />

getting involved in the world to change or confirm a course of action, that<br />

man "situates" his freedom as if he could pin himself down into pure<br />

being. But his indeterminism will still prise him loose from the situations<br />

he enters into. Man cannot escape his "facticity": the simple fact that he<br />

has to be something in his world. But nor can he escape the contingency of<br />

that same world: he is not free not to be free, as it were, and has to choose<br />

as well as interpret roles to play. Man is neither complete being nor<br />

absolute nothingness, but an unstable hybrid of the two. His freedom<br />

emancipates him from any determinate state, then compels him to try and<br />

retrieve such solidity, only to repeat this to-and-fro thereafter, forever<br />

"beyond what I am, about to come to myself'. 19<br />

Using this paradox, Murdoch notes that Sartre figures man as striving<br />

for, but crucially never attaining, an impossible reconciliation of<br />

opposites: a being in-itself-for-itself. <strong>Sartre's</strong> insistence that human consciousness<br />

situates its freedom risks aggrandising the human condition by<br />

positing an essential mode of being just beyond our reach. He had found<br />

his taste for concrete or actual human experience uneasily diluted by the<br />

idealism associated with Romantic writing. This cocktail is necessarily<br />

volatile, since in experiencing himself as a lack of being, "we lose<br />

ourselves in vain. Man is a useless passion": 20 without direction, yet<br />

"[L']§tre de la rgalitd humaine est originellement non une substance mais un<br />

rapport v£cu [...]. L'homme n'est point: il est ce qu'il n'est pas et n'est pas ce<br />

qu'il est, il est la ne'antisation de l'En-soi contingent en tant que le soi de cette<br />

ndantisation est sa fuite en avant vers l'En-soi cause de soi" (L'fore et le neant,<br />

664).<br />

18 Farrell Fox, The New Sartre, 35.<br />

19 "[P]ar dela ce que je suis, a venir a moi-m§me" (L'fore et le neant, 242).<br />

20 "[N]ous nous perdons en vain: l'homme est une passion inutile" (ibid., 708).


Reading Sartre with Victor Hugo 129<br />

driving towards purpose. "The general impression of <strong>Sartre's</strong> work is<br />

certainly that of a powerful but abstract model of a hopeless dilemma,<br />

coloured by a surreptitious romanticism which embraces the hopelessness."<br />

21<br />

The Surreptitious Romantic<br />

Murdoch's reference is an intriguing one. It allows us to look at Sartre<br />

from an angle that highlights rather than obscures idealist humanism,<br />

without overlooking existential indeterminism. She gestures to a<br />

worldview that is structurally similar to Existentialism. Romanticism's<br />

different emphasis can help us examine <strong>Sartre's</strong> idealist leanings more<br />

closely so as to confirm such aspirations to be themselves anguished, not<br />

forthright. Romanticism identifies the same discrepancy between the<br />

transcendent and the material that is found in Existentialist thought. The<br />

Romantic temperament was not only stirred by the harshness of everyday<br />

life but also enticed by the escapes offered through the imagination. The<br />

vital difference between the two mindsets is one of perspective, not effect.<br />

Whereas Existentialism reaches for a totality of being, Romanticism sees<br />

existence as part of an infinity of being, often a divine entity, whose<br />

endless creativity is at the heart of nature. Touching on nuances already<br />

broached by Emmanuel Ldvinas, totality implies a recuperation of<br />

fragmented parts into one fixed whole, whereas infinity multiplies that<br />

fragmentation into an incomprehensible and interminable whole. Rather<br />

than start with man's alienation and his yearning to integrate with his<br />

world, the Romantic senses an intangible harmony, whose eternal essence<br />

is intuited in a temporal world of matter and substance. The result is<br />

similarly tense. Much like the blank page allowed the writer to give free<br />

rein to his imaginative powers, so could the physical world become a work<br />

of art to be crafted by man and claimed as his own. But that claim is never<br />

sovereign, for nature's unending creation shapes an ever-changing<br />

existence of which man is but one element.<br />

This incompletion is no coincidence. Since both modes of thinking<br />

thrive on human freedom and self-determination, they must each prise<br />

open the kind of dialectic that Murdoch marks. In order to safeguard<br />

existence as a dynamic rather than static condition, Sartrean alienation<br />

cannot entirely do away with the notion of a fully unified mode of being<br />

for us to pursue. Conversely, the Romantic vision of a supreme or<br />

supernatural order is complicated by malaise and uncertainty in the here-<br />

Murdoch, Romantic Rationalist, 111.


130 Chapter Nine<br />

and-now, so that the imagination remains key. It would be unfair to say<br />

that the French Romantics were naive in any way. They were neither<br />

theologians with a blind faith in a mystical being, nor pedantic<br />

philosophers bogged down in actual fact. Rebecca Comay makes an<br />

especially crucial observation in this context:<br />

From the time of Fichte and Schlegel, the fractured subject is said to<br />

"resist" its own inevitable dispersal by generating the "necessary illusion"<br />

of a self-coincident self. Unity is therefore postulated, but as a fiction<br />

which knows itself as a fiction: such a simultaneous positing and<br />

undermining of belief indeed constitutes the essence of Romantic irony. 22<br />

This Romantic irony seemingly mirrors the Existentialist paradox of being.<br />

Both underpin yet undermine an impossible desire to integrate with and<br />

thereby know our world completely. To recall Chateaubriand: "My soul,<br />

which no passion had yet satiated, searched for something that could pin it<br />

down. But I realised that I was striving for more than I would find." 23<br />

This connection is prised open further by Sartre himself when<br />

discussing the nineteenth-<strong>century</strong> literary scene in his study of Flaubert.<br />

Sartre dispels any idea of Romanticism as a simple optimism that could<br />

will our estranged world into some divine fantasy. Romanticism is rather<br />

an immense friction between man's hopes for a harmonious world and his<br />

anguish at the ruinous reality he occupies: "[These poets], unsure of<br />

themselves and victims of an agnosticism to which they are not resigned,<br />

replace the idea of a supreme Being with the sorrow of having lost Him as<br />

the inspiration for their poems." 24 They may cling to a notion of God, but<br />

their own emphasis on man's isolation exposes that deity as a speculative<br />

and logically inconceivable presence. They are drawn towards an ideal of<br />

perfection that lies beyond the indeterminism to which mankind has been<br />

exiled. This pure state, or essence, can only be imagined and fleeting,<br />

never realised or fixed in place, lest man's creative freedom be neutered.<br />

As such, to align Hugo's faith in an absolute Being with <strong>Sartre's</strong> alienated<br />

world, in which "totality escapes us" and man must "always draw near,<br />

never arrive", is not as rash as it might at first appear.<br />

22 "Benjamin", 138.<br />

23 "Mon &me, qu'aucune passion n'avait encore usde, cherchait un objet qui put<br />

l'attacher; mais je m'apergus que je donnais plus que je ne recevais" {Rene, 154-<br />

55).<br />

24 "[Ces poetes] incertains, victimes d'un agnosticisme auquel ils ne se rdsignent<br />

pas, remplacent l'Etre supreme, a la source de leurs poemes, par la douleur de<br />

l'avoir perdu" (L'Idiotde lafamille, //, 1960).


Reading Sartre with Victor Hugo 131<br />

This undertaking becomes considerably smoother by acknowledging<br />

that the citations here come not from Sartre but from Hugo himself,<br />

immediately hinting at the latter's own perturbations. 25 More fascinating<br />

still, Sartre uncannily talks of Hugo in the same discordant tone as the<br />

"new" Sartreans speak of Sartre. His attraction towards Hugo is clearly<br />

hesitant, no doubt informed by that Flaubertian apprehension towards<br />

Hugo's stature, but it is also undeniable, commendable even, for the<br />

critical balance that it puts in place vis-a-vis the Hugolian stereotype.<br />

During an interview in 1975, Michel Contat reminds Sartre that he had<br />

once admitted to an admiration for Hugo. Nearly three decades earlier,<br />

Sartre had indeed praised Hugo for his cultivation of writing as a form of<br />

commitment. In <strong>Sartre's</strong> eyes, Hugo was equally committed to the<br />

ideological liberties that appealed to the bourgeois sensibility as he was to<br />

the material liberties that the proletariat was clamouring for. In other<br />

words, Hugo did not allow the intuitive world of his imagination to<br />

overtake the immediate world of his reality. His determination to address<br />

the key principle of freedom from both an aesthetic and a social<br />

perspective connected his work to a mass audience: "He was one of the<br />

only, perhaps the only, one of our writers who was truly popular." 26<br />

<strong>Sartre's</strong> knee-jerk reaction to Contat's reminder is to tone down his<br />

admiration:<br />

Oh, only a little. I can't give you any precise feeling toward Victor Hugo.<br />

There are many things to reproach him for, and others which are really<br />

quite wonderful. My feelings are confused and jumbled, so I would get out<br />

of this by saying that I admired him. But in truth, I don't admire him any<br />

more than I do anyone else. 27<br />

But Sartre quickly reinstates his attraction nevertheless, concluding that<br />

these sentiments are more a question of esteem than admiration.<br />

Sartre had in part elucidated this esteem in his account of Flaubert's<br />

literary background in L'Idiot de la famille. In the <strong>second</strong> volume, and<br />

more particularly in the third, Sartre touches upon a philosophical tension<br />

"Le total echappe [...] approcher toujours, n'arriver jamais" (Le Droit et la loi><br />

41,42).<br />

26 "C'est un des seuls, peut-6tre le seul de nos ecrivains qui soit vraiment<br />

populaire" ("Qu'est-ce que la literature?", 126).<br />

"Oh, bien peu. Je ne peux pas vous dormer de sentiment exact pour Victor Hugo.<br />

II y a beaucoup de choses a bl&mer en lui, et d'autres qui sont vraiment tres belles.<br />

C'est confus et m§le\ alors je m'en tirerais en disant que je l'admirais. Mais, en<br />

ventd, je ne 1'admire pas plus qu'un autre" ("Autoportrait a soixante-dix ans",<br />

195).


132<br />

Chapter Nine<br />

in Hugo surprisingly similar to his own, although his focus on Flaubert<br />

keeps him from reflecting in more detail on this similarity. Flaubert's<br />

grand crocodile represents for Sartre a sort of chameleon, able to flicker<br />

between "enlightened order" and "a tumultuous and inexplicable<br />

disorder": 28<br />

Hugo, optimism incarnate, the vatic poet, recognised by God as the only<br />

worthy interlocutor, the courageous defender of the Communards [...], this<br />

bard of the poor, [...] this astonishing man, half priest and half anarchist,<br />

incontestable sovereign of the <strong>century</strong>. 29<br />

Here he identifies two Hugos, contradictory and yet cohabiting, both of<br />

whom are strikingly similar to the "new", double Sartre of uniformity and<br />

multiplicity. Even though Hugo thrives off divine inspiration, he still<br />

believes himself imperfect since he is human after all, subject to alienation<br />

and loss. God speaks, but what Hugo hears are whispers from an uncertain<br />

space that lies beyond this world, outside of all reason. We are thus<br />

brothers with an absent father. Whilst mortal, man must find his own way,<br />

exercising his creativity to make something of this existence: "He has no<br />

cause to die to this world: on the contrary, he must live in it and engage<br />

with it." 30 Hugo resolves to make sense of a senseless world in the<br />

immediate absence of God, exercising the human inventiveness which<br />

foregrounds Sartrean self-determination, as well its lack of fixity.<br />

<strong>Sartre's</strong> observations actually anticipate a strand of nineteenth-<strong>century</strong><br />

studies that has promoted the idea of Hugo as a distinctly complex figure.<br />

These readings bear considerable resemblance to those found in Sartre<br />

scholarship, emphasising dialectic, not unity. Alongside Hugo's "longing<br />

for order", Victor Brombert notes the "surprisingly modern nature of his<br />

fiction-making, which undermines and decentres the subject". 31 Kathryn<br />

Grossman likewise describes his "fundamental playfulness, an element all<br />

too ignored in Hugo", whereby "opposites mix rather than confuse". 32 To<br />

"La lumiere d'ordre", and "un desordre tumultueux et inexplicable" {L*Idiot, III,<br />

123).<br />

29 "Hugo, Foptimisme incarnd, le poete-'vates', reconnu par Dieu comme seul<br />

interlocuteur valable, le ddfenseur courageux des Communards [...], ce chantre des<br />

pauvres, [...] cet homme dtonnant, moide* pretre et moide* anar, incontestable<br />

souverain du siecle" (ibid., 383).<br />

30 "[I]l n'a pas besoin de mourir au monde: il faut qu'il y vive au contraire et qu'il<br />

s'y engage" (L'Idiot, II, 1968).<br />

31 Hugo, 1-5.<br />

32 The Early Novels, 16,197.


Reading Sartre with Victor Hugo 133<br />

these voices I myself have added Walter Benjamin's favourable appraisals,<br />

which have mostly fallen off the critical radar:<br />

Hugo reflected the superficial views of the day as well as a blind faith in<br />

the future, but he also had a profound vision of the life that was forming in<br />

the womb of nature and of the people. Hugo never succeeded in fashioning<br />

a bridge between the two. He saw no need for such a bridge. 33<br />

Benjamin outlines how Hugo never denied the lure of our fantasy for a<br />

total sense of being, rather the possibility of its realisation. As a poet, he<br />

acknowledged both the imaginary and the real, but refused to assimilate<br />

the two into some mythic truth that could pretend to validate our existence.<br />

The "Rules" of Engagement<br />

Like Sartre, Hugo believes that the human condition moves between<br />

both the immediate and the transcendent as part of an existence<br />

characterised by its elasticity. Reading their thinking alongside each<br />

other's, we see that the notion of totalisation which earned Sartre so much<br />

Structuralist criticism cannot be neatly dismissed as naive idealism. The<br />

concept of an essential mode of being as elusive is vital. To forward the<br />

idea of man as a free yet responsible being, <strong>Sartre's</strong> philosophy has to<br />

point to the metaphysical quicksand on which it treads. We must not<br />

overlook how, within their differing points of origin, Sartre and Hugo<br />

therefore construct the makings of both an imaginary release from<br />

alienation, and an immediate apprehension of its material reality. Elements<br />

of both bad faith and acute self-awareness abound, as man forever tries to<br />

fit with his world like the missing piece of a puzzle. This ambiguity is<br />

evident in the ways in which both men's thinking inevitably sits atop the<br />

flipside that the other represents. The Romantic ideal of man and world in<br />

unison, and the existential reality of alienation, prove themselves two<br />

poles within a similar philosophical structure of human being that<br />

necessarily attract as much as they repel. Pivotally, <strong>Sartre's</strong> and Hugo's<br />

different choices of precedence do not prevent either from crossing paths<br />

in this double-bind and making strikingly similar demands of engagement<br />

on their fellow man. It is to these demands, in light of the duality which<br />

attracted Sartre to Hugo, that I now wish to turn in the closing section of<br />

this chapter.<br />

Benjamin, Charles Baudelaire, 65. See my article "Reading Walter Benjamin's<br />

Concept of the Ruin in Victor Hugo's Notre-Dame de Paris", French Studies, LXI,<br />

2, April 2007,155-66.


134 Chapter Nine<br />

Indeed, s*engager (to commit oneself, or to be committed) is for both<br />

men an exercise of freedom that occurs at the most basic levels of<br />

existence, revealing our actions—and our inactions—to be a matter of<br />

human choice, not natural design. Their characteristic intellectual<br />

commitment to freedom and integrity emerges out of their ever-shifting<br />

mindsets, requiring alternation as much as uniformity. Once again, we can<br />

make reference to the arguably crude concept of a see-saw of being,<br />

comparing <strong>Sartre's</strong> "to-and-fro" of existence with Hugo's "flux and<br />

reflux" of experience. 34 For Sartre, the world is a space of Tetre et le<br />

neant", whereas for Hugo it is a meeting of "le Nil et l'Ens". 35 These<br />

reversed orders in the presentation of "being and nothingness" highlight<br />

the differences at work. Sartre begins with material reality, and the<br />

anguish we feel in experiencing our existence as a lack: "We do not<br />

simply apprehend the fact that the possibilities we project are perpetually<br />

eroded away by our freedom to come; in addition, we apprehend our<br />

choice, that is to say ourselves, as unjustifiable" 3 ^ And so our reality is a<br />

"perpetual surpassing toward a coincidence with itself which is never<br />

given", 37 and which signals our coming into existence. Consciousness is<br />

quite simply an appeal for being that goes unanswered. Like the donkey<br />

being led by the carrot, "We run toward ourselves and we are, due to this<br />

fact, the being which cannot be reunited with itself'. 38 Responsibility for<br />

our world therefore lies squarely with us: "Responsible for everything,<br />

indeed, except for my very responsibility, since I am not the foundation of<br />

my being." 39<br />

In the Proses philosophiques des annees 1860-65—an expansive but<br />

abandoned preface to Les Miserables—Hugo would anticipate this view of<br />

man as autonomous but not absolute, albeit in a less analytical and more<br />

poetic way. The for-itself and the in-itself can be observed in what he calls<br />

34 These terms are prevalent in <strong>Sartre's</strong> Vttre et le neant and Hugo's William<br />

Shakespeare (1864), although variations can be found across their work.<br />

35 From the Proses philosophiques in (Euvres completes: Critique, 709.<br />

36 "Nous ne saisissons pas simplement le fait que les possibles que nous projetons<br />

sont perpe'tuellement ronges par notre liberte* a venir, nous apprghendons en outre<br />

notre choix, c'est-a-dire nous-mSmes, comme injustifiable" (L'fore et le neant,<br />

542).<br />

37 "[...] un depassement perp&uel vers une coincidence avec soi qui n'est jamais<br />

donneV' (ibid., 132).<br />

38 "Nous courons vers nous-mdmes et nous sommes, de ce fait, l'etre qui ne peut<br />

pas se rejoindre" (ibid., 250).<br />

"Responsable de tout, en effet, sauf de ma responsabilite' meme car je ne suis pas<br />

le fondement de mon etre" (ibid., 641).


Reading Sartre with Victor Hugo 135<br />

"this necessary and indisputable meeting of ideas with matter",<br />

elsewhere termed la vision of human imagination and la vue afforded by<br />

reality. All nature is an exchange between these twin faculties of insight<br />

and sight, perception and picture, which will forever be "necessarily<br />

unequal". 41 Thus, no ambition realises itself fully in this world: "This<br />

flame which is in me, which warms me and which enlightens me and<br />

which sets me alight, and which thinks and hopes and loves" can ignite<br />

"my material self of flesh and emptiness", but not consume it. 42<br />

Nonetheless, "what is missing from us attracts us", hence: "We are at once<br />

points of arrival and points of departure. Every being is a centre of the<br />

world." 43 The sovereignty of the individual that is so crucial to Sartrean<br />

freedom is likewise affirmed by Hugo as man's endlessly imaginative<br />

productivity, for which he alone is responsible: "Freedom implies<br />

responsibility. [...] Responsibility starts with choice. To choose is to act:<br />

to choose is to react." 44 Similarly, Hugo pre-echoes <strong>Sartre's</strong> accent on<br />

"doing" over "being". But whereas Sartre argues that there is no essential<br />

human reality accessible to us in our contingent world, Hugo sees that<br />

ideal of being as remaining hidden within that same supposed contingency.<br />

Such wholeness is the trace of the divine for Hugo, an anchor of<br />

being from which we have been cut loose. As a result, <strong>Sartre's</strong> initial<br />

portrait of man is untouched by bad faith in any essential meaning to our<br />

lives, whilst Hugo's is on the contrary laden with it.<br />

However, in order for man to enter into the to-and-fro of subjectivity<br />

and objectivity that they mark as the free human condition, both Sartre and<br />

Hugo will have to slide over to and through the other's position. The<br />

Sartrean course will have to smuggle a clandestine amount of bad faith<br />

along for the ride, since for the for-itself to come into existence, it is<br />

condemned to seek an impossible fulfilment of being. In this respect,<br />

<strong>Sartre's</strong> ethical investment in a Judaic spirituality that based its fraternity<br />

on religious as much as social values, as expressed in his controversial<br />

"Cette rencontre n£cessaire et incontestable de l'idee et de la matiere" (Proses<br />

philosophiques, 493).<br />

41 "Ndcessairement inegal" (ibid., 680).<br />

42 "Cette flamme qui est en moi, qui me chauffe et qui m'eclaire et qui me brGle, et<br />

qui pense et qui espere et qui aime [...] mon moi matenel de la viande et du n6ant"<br />

(ibid., 527).<br />

43 "Nous sommes en meme temps points d'arrivee et points de depart. Tout &re est<br />

un centre du monde" (ibid., 685).<br />

44 "Libertd implique responsabilitd. [...] La responsabilite' commence au choix.<br />

Choisir, c'est agir; choisir, c'est r£pondre" (ibid., 512).


136 Chapter Nine<br />

1980 interviews, 45 is not as shocking as various members of the so-called<br />

"Sartre family" have tried to make out. He had explained to Beauvoir<br />

herself six years earlier that, even though the idea of a sovereign creator<br />

contradicted many of his other notions, "it is in there, as a vague<br />

presence". 46 Hugo's portrait of himself in his poem Les Mages, hearing the<br />

audible but faint footsteps of a being in the beyond, surely casts the<br />

shadow of the new Romantic across <strong>Sartre's</strong> work here. But Hugo's<br />

trajectory conversely has to acknowledge the impossibility of harmony, so<br />

as not to confuse his individual being with that of the world entire; to do<br />

so would lay claim to an incorporation that only God can provide once the<br />

mortal coil is done with. The notion of a supreme form of being that is but<br />

an echo or spectre admonishes as much as advocates the idea of an essence<br />

to human life, since this totalisation is "the clarity we do not see": "God<br />

the incomprehensible, the evidently invisible", who gives no guarantee of<br />

his existence and leaves the responsibility for our choices to us. 47 This<br />

being so, and in light of his own deep mistrust of the dogmas of<br />

institutionalised religion, Hugo has before him a perpetual vision of a<br />

better world that is just that: an ever-receding horizon of closure "across<br />

the shadows of this life". 48<br />

Consequently, Sartre encounters a "bad faith", whilst Hugo must<br />

discount it, only for each position to pass once more through its original<br />

point of departure. To borrow <strong>Sartre's</strong> terminology: "There must be a<br />

duality at the heart of freedom. And this duality is precisely what we call<br />

detotalised totality." 49 Hugo articulates this duality best in his beloved<br />

definition of himself as the poet-philosopher, itself a potential forerunner<br />

to Murdoch's Romantic Rationalist: "He must leave, but he must come<br />

back. He must have wings to soar endlessly above, but he must have feet<br />

to tread the earth, and after seeing him ascend, we must see him wander.<br />

He must return to being a man after transcending that state." 50 On the one<br />

hand, consciousness is intentionality: a flight toward being suffering from<br />

See UEspoir maintenant.<br />

46 "[...] elle est la, vague" (in Beauvoir, La Ceremonie des adieux, 616).<br />

47 "[...] la clartd qu'on ne voit pas"; "[...] Dieu 1'incomprehensible, l'invisible<br />

Evident" (Proses philosophiques, 527, 529).<br />

48 "[...] a travers les tdnebres de cette vie" (Le Droit et la hi, 232).<br />

49 "II faut une duality au coeur de la liberty. Et cette duality est precisdment ce que<br />

nous nommons totality d&otalisee" (Cahiers pour une morale, I, 345).<br />

50 "Qu'il parte, mais qu'il revienne. Qu'il ait des ailes pour l'infini, mais qu'il ait<br />

des pieds pour la terre, et qu'apres Favoir vu voler, on le voie marcher. Qu'il rentre<br />

dans rhomme apres en §tre sorti" (William Shakespeare, in (Euvres completes:<br />

Critique, 402).


Reading Sartre with Victor Hugo 137<br />

a thirst for the absolute that is as undeniable as it is unquenchable. When<br />

looking back on his search for an ethics, Sartre indeed points out: "It's<br />

what I wanted myself. Naturally you can't have it all, but you must want it<br />

all." 51 Equally, both Hugo and Sartre recognise that this suffering is the<br />

unavoidable consequence of being separated from any absolute. Hugo<br />

explains: "Anguish, we deeply believe, is the law of the world, until the<br />

new divine order. To suffer is the foundation of human life, itself<br />

mysterious." 52<br />

It is this interaction of man and world that enables both Sartre and<br />

Hugo to call for the individual to engage with such duality, rather than<br />

retreat from its dilemmas or claim to have mastered them. For both, liberty<br />

implies a kind of liability that can stall our endeavours as easily as enable<br />

them. Freedom is pointless without purpose, the aims of which could<br />

however lock the individual in a fixity that would be contrary to his<br />

indeterminism. Sartre thus responds to this burden by arguing: "Nothing<br />

remains for the for-itself other than to re-enter the circle and allow itself to<br />

be indefinitely tossed from one to the other of the two fundamental<br />

attitudes". 53 Meanwhile, Hugo reminds us that "classification and negation<br />

are hand in hand. Neither 'Yes' nor 'No' should be used too much.<br />

Idolatry is the centripetal force; nihilism is the centrifugal force." 54 With<br />

regard to this demanding approach, Henri Pena-Ruiz's and Jean-Paul<br />

Scot's placing of Hugo between materialism and romanticism in "a double<br />

sentiment of proximity and estrangement" is of special note. They see<br />

Hugo embracing a philosophy of freedom in action, in other words "in<br />

situation, as Sartre would say, with the insertion of all action into the<br />

profundity of a personal history which itself succeeds a social history." 55<br />

The validity of such a claim should now be clear, particularly as Sartre<br />

51 "C'est ce que j'ai voulu moi-m§me. Naturellement on n'arrive pas a tout, mais il<br />

faut vouloir tout" ("Autoportrait", 186).<br />

52 "La douleur, nous le croyons profonde'ment, est la loi terrestre, jusqu'a nouvel<br />

ordre divin. Souffrir est le fond de rhomme, fond inconnu" (Proses<br />

philosophiques, 552-58).<br />

"II ne reste plus au pour-soi qu'a rentrer dans le cercle et a se laisser<br />

indeTiniment ballotter de Tune a l'autre des deux attitudes fondamentales" (L'£tre<br />

et le neanu 484).<br />

54 "Classification et negation, c'est deux. II ne faut ni trop de Oui ni trop de Non.<br />

L'idolatrie est la force centripete; le nihilisme est la force centrifuge" (Proses<br />

philosophiques, 699).<br />

"Un double sentiment de proximity et d'&rangetd [...] en situation, comme dirait<br />

Sartre, avec Inscription de toute action dans la profondeur d'une histoire<br />

personnelle qui elle-meme relaie une histoire sociale" (Un Po&te en politique, 395,<br />

403).


138 Chapter Nine<br />

uses the concept of situated freedom as the direct basis for the to-and-fro<br />

of existence that both he and Hugo confront: "And so we begin to catch a<br />

glimpse of the paradox of freedom: there is freedom only in a situation,<br />

and there is a situation only through freedom." 56 Therein also lies an<br />

opportunity to take up Ronald Santoni's exciting suggestion that there is a<br />

difference between living in bad faith and acting in it:<br />

[B]oth Sartre and Sartrean scholarship would read and fare better if a<br />

distinction were drawn more sharply between the original bad faith of the<br />

human being's original pre-reflective project or "natural attitude" of<br />

attaining self-coincidence or in-itself-for-itself [...], and the bad faith of<br />

more specific "acts", "choices", "behaviours" and "ways of living". 57<br />

Whilst the former could be construed as a total loss of (or indeed total<br />

immersion in) consciousness, the latter is a more reflective gesture: a kind<br />

of "knowing" bad faith that does not eliminate the possibility of a return of<br />

self-awareness, and would be aptly suited to propel Sartre and Hugo on<br />

their existential see-saw. Sartre hints at such a conception when comparing<br />

bad faith to a dreamlike state: "You put yourself in bad faith as you would<br />

lull yourself to sleep, and you are in bad faith as you would be asleep in a<br />

dream." 58 Sticking with this analogy of sleep, it is possible to split that<br />

dreamlike state. If we take pre-reflective bad faith to be akin to a dream,<br />

then reflective bad faith could be seen as a daydream. The latter occurs at<br />

specific intervals, puncturing our conscious state as opposed to suspending<br />

it. As such, consciousness is compromised but not overwhelmed by this<br />

deception, in the same way as a daydream subdues our self-awareness<br />

without sending us into deep sleep. Such a metaphor in fact corresponds<br />

exactly to how Hugo figures the problematic of living an existence that<br />

absurdly tries to stabilise our turbulent condition, of believing in an<br />

essence to our lives that we know is, according to reason, ridiculous:<br />

"Each morning, everyone picks up their bundle of daydreams and leaves<br />

for a faraway California. [...] All of us follow a path." 59<br />

The dialogue that I have set up here amplifies critical discourses on the<br />

identity of the French "engaged writer" as a necessarily oppositional one<br />

"Ainsi commengons-nous a entrevoir le paradoxe de la libertd: il n'y a de liberty<br />

qu'en situation et il n'y a de situation que par la liberte"' (L'&tre et le neant, 569-<br />

70).<br />

57 Santoni, Bad Faith, 183.<br />

58 "On se met de mauvaise foi comme on s'endort et on est de mauvaise foi comme<br />

on reve" (L'fitre et le neant, 109).<br />

59 "Tous les matins chacun fait son paquet de reveries et part pour la Californie des<br />

songes. [...] Tous suivent une piste" (Proses philosophiques, 663).


Reading Sartre with Victor Hugo 139<br />

whose gestures are more involving than simplistic political activism.<br />

<strong>Sartre's</strong> and Hugo's philosophies figure and refigure visionary imagination<br />

and rational thought onto one another in a dialectic that must remain<br />

engaged with itself if freedom is to survive. They tackle the crisis of how<br />

to live in a modern age in which man is, as Marx famously argued, both<br />

producer and product of his world. They stress engagement (commitment)<br />

as the pursuit of a meaningful and unconditional way of life, but never its<br />

firm attainment—a mode of being that is always constructed, never done<br />

with. Their massive ceuvres of novels, plays, essays, and political<br />

commentaries were not merely self-indulgent exercises of their creative<br />

imaginations, nor militant crusades of social action, but a richly tense<br />

interaction of the two. To be engaged is to accept a necessary contradiction,<br />

and to be caught between independence from ideological agendas<br />

and involvement in those same domains. Steve Fuller reminds us:<br />

The intellectual, like the superhero, lives in a dualistic universe. [...] For<br />

intellectuals and superheroes, social structures are disposable sites for the<br />

ongoing struggle between Good and Evil: what embodies Good one week<br />

may embody Evil the next. The heroic intellectual never gives up on the<br />

chase. 60<br />

A paternal or vertical system of thinking that demands a hierarchy of<br />

meaning is turned on its side by the fraternal impulse for both Sartre and<br />

Hugo. Here again we have the analogy of the see-saw, whereby any rigidly<br />

categorical thinking has to be pushed aside in favour of a more circular<br />

mindset that respects the slippage between subject and object. To cite<br />

Sartre: "The truth always remains to be discovered, because it is<br />

immeasurable; which is not to say that you don't obtain truths in the plural<br />

sense." 61 Hence Hugo's succinct aim: "Authority transfigured into<br />

freedom." 62 As a result, the Sartre-Hugo dialogue begins to reaffirm the<br />

modern French cultural tradition—and, importantly, Sartrean ethics—as a<br />

site not of resolution or resignation, but of revolution, in the strictest<br />

sense: of a continued engagement with a contingent world.<br />

60 The Intellectual 36-37.<br />

61 "La ventd reste toujours a trouver, parce qu'elle est infinie. Ce qui ne veut pas<br />

dire qu'on n'obtienne pas des venteV ("Autoportrait", 148).<br />

62 "L'autorite' transfigure en liberte"' (Le Droit et la hi, 399).


140 Chapter Nine<br />

Works Cited<br />

Beauvoir, Simone de. La Ceremonie des adieux, suivi de Entretiens avec<br />

Jean-Paul Sartre, aout-septembre 1974. Paris: Gallimard, 1981.<br />

Benjamin, Walter. Charles Baudelaire: A Lyric Poet in the Era of High<br />

Capitalism (trans. Harry Zohn). London: NLB, 1973.<br />

Brombert, Victor. Victor Hugo and the Visionary Novel. Harvard<br />

University Press, 1984.<br />

Chateaubriand, Frangois-Rene' de. Rene (1802). Paris: Gallimard, 1971.<br />

Comay, Rebecca. "Benjamin and the Ambiguities of Romanticism", in<br />

The Cambridge Companion to Walter Benjamin (ed. David S. Ferris).<br />

Cambridge University Press, 2004,134-51.<br />

Decker, Michel de. Hugo: Victor pour ces Dames. Paris: Belfond, 2002.<br />

Derrida, Jacques. "II courait mort: Salut, salut", Les Temps modernes, 587,<br />

Spring 1996,7-54.<br />

Farrell Fox, Nicholas. The New Sartre: Explorations in Postmodernism.<br />

London: Continuum, 2003.<br />

Flaubert, Gustave. Correspondance. Paris: Gallimard, 1975.<br />

Fuller, Steve. The Intellectual: The Positive Power of Negative Thinking.<br />

Cambridge: Icon, 2005.<br />

Grossman, Kathryn. The Early Novels of Victor Hugo: Towards a Poetics<br />

of Harmony. Geneva: Librairie Droz SA, 1986.<br />

—. "From Classic to Pop Icon: Popularising Hugo", The French Review,<br />

vol. 74, no. 3, February 2001,482-95.<br />

Gutting, Gary. French Philosophy in the Twentieth Century. Cambridge<br />

University Press, 2001.<br />

Howells, Christina. Sartre, the Necessity of Freedom. Cambridge<br />

University Press, 1988.<br />

—. "Introduction", in The Cambridge Companion to Sartre. Cambridge<br />

University Press, 1992.<br />

Hugo, Victor. GEuvres completes: Critique (ed. Jean-Pierre Reynaud).<br />

Paris: Laffont, 1985.<br />

—. Le Droit et la hi et autres textes citoyens. Paris: Editions 10/18, 2002.<br />

L£vi-Strauss, Claude. La Pensee sauvage. Paris: Plon, 1962.<br />

Le\y, Bernard-Henri. Sartre, the Philosopher of the Twentieth Century<br />

(trans. Andrew Brown). Cambridge: Polity Press, 2003.<br />

Maurel, Jean. Victor Hugo, philosophe. Paris: P.U.F., 1985.<br />

Murdoch, Iris. Sartre: Romantic Rationalist (1953). London: Vintage,<br />

1999.<br />

Noudelmann, Francois and Gilles Philippe (eds). Dictionnaire Sartre.<br />

Paris: Honord Champion, 2004.


Reading Sartre with Victor Hugo 141<br />

Pena-Ruiz, Henri and Jean-Paul Scot. Un Poete en politique: les combats<br />

de Victor Hugo. Paris: Flammarion, 2002.<br />

Rowley, Hazel. Tete-a-Tete: The Lives and Loves of Simone de Beauvoir<br />

and Jean-Paul Sartre. New York: Harper Collins, 2005.<br />

Santoni, Ronald. Bad Faith, Good Faith, and Authenticity in Sartre*s<br />

Early Philosophy. Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 1995.<br />

Sartre, Jean-Paul. U&tre et le neant. Paris: Gallimard, 1943.<br />

—. "Qu'est-ce que la litterature?", in Situations, II. Paris: Gallimard, 1948.<br />

—. Uldiotde lafamille, MIL Paris: Gallimard, 1971-72.<br />

—. "Autoportrait a soixante-dix ans", in Situations, X. Paris: Gallimard,<br />

1976.<br />

—. Cahiers pour une morale, /-//. Paris: Gallimard, 1983.<br />

—. (avec Benny Levy), VEspoir maintenant: les entretiens de 1980.<br />

Lagrasse: Verdier, 1991.


CHAPTER TEN<br />

HIDDEN WORDPLAY IN THE WORKS<br />

OF JEAN-PAUL SARTRE<br />

PETER ROYLE<br />

Le Mur {The Wall) is a collection of five short stories, the first four of<br />

which point to what Sartre calls "limit-situations" {"situations-limites"):<br />

death, madness and the impossibility of being another person while<br />

remaining oneself, the impossibility for a human being of becoming<br />

inhuman or transcending the human condition, and the necessity of having<br />

a body. 1 But in the longest of these stories, "L'Enfance d'un chef ("The<br />

Childhood of a Leader"), there is no limit-situation (although there have<br />

been various attempts to conjure one up): there is instead a hidden play on<br />

words. Each limit-situation may be seen as constituting a wall. But where<br />

is the wall in "L'Enfance d'un chef? Is it not the arbitrary wall that<br />

Lucien Fleurier, the budding community leader, erects around himself by<br />

means of his antisemitic views, in order to protect himself and make<br />

himself feared? Also the wall against which he and his racist comrades of<br />

the brasserie Polder (an example of wordplay 2 ) corner and beat up a<br />

"m&eque" ("wog") to try to prevent their country from being swamped by<br />

foreigners? At the same time there are several allusions to their maturity:<br />

Lemordant [...] was mature; but he didn't appear to have acquired this<br />

maturity, like Lucien, through multiple painful experiences: he was an<br />

adult by birth. 3<br />

An earlier draft of this chapter was given as a paper at the Centenary Conference<br />

of the UK Sartre Society at the Institut Frangais, London, in March 2005.<br />

2 "Polder" is a Dutch word adopted by both French and English, meaning a piece<br />

of low-lying land protected by dykes from submersion by the sea.<br />

3 "Lemordant [...] dtait mur; mais il ne paraissait pas avoir acquis, comme Lucien,<br />

cette maturity h travers de multiples et pdnibles experiences: c'&ait un adulte de


Hidden Wordplay in the Works of Jean-Paul Sartre 143<br />

They were adults and several of them wore beards.<br />

He highly appreciated this odd mixture of obstinate earnestness and<br />

turbulence which gave this mature look to the youngest of them and this<br />

impish appearance to the oldest.<br />

At the beginning of the story there is a wall beyond which the infant<br />

Lucien is not allowed to venture; but now he is mature he can go where he<br />

likes and do what he likes; and on maturing he has elected to turn himself<br />

into a wall. The wall in "L'Enfance d'un chef is not only un mur: it is,<br />

ironically, un mur.<br />

Is this play on words deliberate? Naturally one cannot be sure, but<br />

there are grounds for believing it is. There is, for example, a passage in Le<br />

Sursis {The Reprieve), the <strong>second</strong> volume of Les Chemins de la liberte<br />

{The Roads to Freedom), where the verb murir (to mature) is closely<br />

associated with "two high walls" ("deux hauts murs"):<br />

Years and years of future peace had settled on things in advance and had<br />

matured them, gilded them; to take one's watch, a door handle, a woman's<br />

hand was to take peace in one's hands. The postwar years were a<br />

beginning. The beginning of peace [...]. 'Time and peace were the same<br />

thing. Now this future is here, at my feet, dead. It was a false future, an<br />

imposture." He beheld these twenty years he had lived becalmed, bathed in<br />

sunlight, a flat sea, and he saw them now as they had been: a finite number<br />

of days squeezed between two high walls without hope, a period with a<br />

label, with a beginning and an end, which would appear in the history<br />

books as the Interwar Years. 6<br />

naissance" (Sartre, "L'Enfance d'un chef, in Le Mur, 366). All translations from<br />

the French are my own.<br />

4 "[Cl'&aient des adultes et plusieurs portaient la barbe" (ibid., 374).<br />

5 "II goutait vivement ce melange original de gravity tdtue et de turbulence qui<br />

donnait aux plus jeunes cet air mur et aux plus age's cette allure de diablotins"<br />

(ibid., 375).<br />

6 "Des annees et des annees de paix future s'dtaient de'posees par avance sur les<br />

choses et les avaient muries, dordes; prendre sa montre, la poignee d'une porte, une<br />

main de femme, c'e'tait prendre la paix entre ses mains. L'apres-guerre £tait un<br />

commencement. Le commencement de la paix [...]. 'Le temps, la paix, c'e'tait la<br />

m§me chose. A present cet avenir est la, a mes pieds, mort. C'6tait un faux avenir,<br />

une imposture.' II regardait ces vingt annees qu'il avait vecues Stales, ensoleillees,<br />

une plaine marine et il les voyait a present comme elles avaient 6t&. un nombre fini<br />

de journees comprimees entre deux hauts murs sans espoir, une peYiode<br />

cataloguee, avec un de'but et une fin, qui figurerait dans les manuels d'histoire sous<br />

le nom d'Entre-deux-guerres" {Le Sursis, in (Euvres romanesques, 807).


144 Chapter Ten<br />

And what is L'Age de raison {The Age of Reason), the title of the first<br />

volume of this same unfinished tetralogy, if not a virtual synonym of l'age<br />

murl And is this title not meant to apply, ironically, both to Mathieu<br />

Delarue, the main character, and the age itself? Puns are not rare in<br />

<strong>Sartre's</strong> work: Walter Redfern points out, as Sartre himself explains in Les<br />

Mots {Words), that he had been, like Flaubert, his "enemy brother",<br />

addicted to punning from early childhood. 7 But whereas a postmodernist<br />

like Derrida will flaunt his puns, Sartre on the whole prefers to keep his<br />

hidden. Thus, instead of calling his novel VAge mur, which would, it is<br />

true, have lost perhaps somewhat in irony, he calls it VAge de raison. It is<br />

true also that L'Age mur would have been awkwardly reminiscent of Le<br />

Mur, and would have risked drawing attention to its hidden wordplay.<br />

Let us look at some of <strong>Sartre's</strong> proper names. There are some,<br />

certainly, which contain plays on words which are immediately obvious:<br />

Frantz, for example, in Les Sequestres d'Altona {The Condemned of<br />

Altona), symbolises France, as the author has confirmed; Genet becomes<br />

Saint Genet, comedien et martyr because he bears the name of the patron<br />

saint of martyred actors; Sartre bestows on Simone de Beauvoir the<br />

nickname le Castor not only because she is industrious, but also because<br />

her name resembles the English word "beaver"; Bouville, the name of a<br />

real place not far from Le Havre, which is where La Nausee {Nausea) is in<br />

fact situated, becomes the fictional scene of the novel because of its name,<br />

with its evocation of mud {boue, in French, plus ville, town), and the<br />

distaste that the port of Le Havre arouses in the hero, Roquentin. 8 But<br />

there are also other linguistic games that, while not hidden, are less<br />

obvious. The three "inseparables" of Huis clos {In Camera or No Exit),<br />

Garcin, Ines, and Estelle, have names that interlock {GarcInEstelle). The<br />

role of Goetz, in Le Diable et le bon Dieu {The Devil and the Good Lord),<br />

is no doubt based on the actions of the historical Gotz, who had inspired<br />

daydreams in the infant Sartre. 9 But could not Sartre have chosen this<br />

name partly because Gbtze in German, a language he knew, means "idol"<br />

and thus "diabolical god"? Other proper names involving wordplay are the<br />

7 See Redfern, "Applying the Tourniquet".<br />

8 Roquentin's name may also involve a play on words. Various theories have been<br />

advanced about its meaning, but it appears to me to have affinities with rouquin<br />

(redhead or ginger nut), which is what Roquentin is proud to be. Whereas the word<br />

marron, as we shall see, has sinister overtones for Sartre, roux and roussi, which<br />

are used to describe any number of "red" things (houses, wood, light, cats, bushes,<br />

mountains, plains, smells, moustaches, cities, wine, onions, and so forth), generally<br />

have a positive sense.<br />

9 See Sartre, Les Mots, 126.


Hidden Wordplay in the Works of Jean-Paul Sartre 145<br />

aforementioned Delarue (literally, "of the street"), <strong>Sartre's</strong> quasi-<br />

Doppelgdnger in Les Chemins de la liberte (Sartre often said he was and<br />

wished to be "n'importe qui", "anyone at all"); Latex, a minor character in<br />

Les Chemins de la liberte, who is encountered appropriating a little girl's<br />

rubber ball; Achille—this is ironic, as Monsieur Achille, in La Nausee, is<br />

an obvious lacked a coward; and Schalom—another irony, as this Jewish<br />

character of Le Sursis, whose name means "peace", is, unlike most of<br />

those surrounding him and for good reasons, in favour of war with<br />

Germany during the Munich crisis of 1938. Sereno, the surname of Daniel,<br />

the tormented homosexual of Les Chemins de la liberte, who is anything<br />

but "serene", provides yet another irony; and Lemordant (literally, "the<br />

biter", or "the biting one") who, as we have seen, is one of Lucien's<br />

"biting", more aggressive friends in "L'Enfance d'un chef," has a bitingly<br />

appropriate name.<br />

A more cryptic example is to be found in the name of the character<br />

Schneider, whose real name turns out to be Vicarios. It will be observed<br />

that Schneider is German for "tailor", and, lo and behold, Sartre is "tailor"<br />

in old French. So, should we infer that Schneider/Vicarios—we naturally<br />

think of "vicarious" in English—is to be identified with Sartre himself? It<br />

is more subtle than this. As Michel Contat points out, 11 what happens to<br />

Vicarios in Les Chemins de la liberte is essentially what happened in real<br />

life to <strong>Sartre's</strong> friend Nizan, who left the Communist party on the occasion<br />

of the Soviet-German pact, and was unjustly denounced by his former<br />

comrades as a police agent. Schneider/Vicarios is the incarnation of the<br />

political uncertainties of both Sartre and Nizan, with whom Sartre had une<br />

drole d'amitie (a peculiar friendship), and for whose rehabilitation he<br />

worked after Nizan's death in the war. Finally, before we leave the subject<br />

of proper names, let us note that there are a number of (no doubt) tonguein-cheek<br />

references to the Swiss, and that <strong>Sartre's</strong> mother and her family<br />

were Schweitzers. 12<br />

In Les Mouches (The Flies), a title reminiscent of such plays as The<br />

Wasps, The Birds, and The Frogs by Aristophanes, we have a triple play<br />

on words, two that are obvious—les mouches mordent (flies bite), les<br />

Cf. Sartre, L'Existentialisme est un hwnanisme, 84.<br />

11 CEuvres romanesques, 2107.<br />

12 E.g.: "Tout le monde n'a pas la chance d'etre Suisse" ["It's not everyone who<br />

has the good luck to be Swiss"] (Le Sursis, 1033); "Tu es sur que ta montre<br />

marche?' Le sergent sourit et regarde sa montre avec complaisance. 'C'est une<br />

montre suisse,' dit-il simplement" ["'You're sure your watch is going?'" The<br />

sergeant smiled and looked at his watch complacently. 'It's a Swiss watch' was all<br />

he said"] (La Mort dans Vame, 1415).


146 Chapter Ten<br />

remords (remorse), les morts (the dead)—and one that is, for necessary<br />

reasons, semi-submerged. An older meaning of the word mouche is "spy",<br />

"informer", corresponding to the modern mouchard, and insofar as the<br />

play can be taken as an allegory of the German occupation of France,<br />

supported as it was by deplorable numbers of citizens ready and<br />

sometimes eager to denounce their neighbours, that is what the flies—<br />

loyal to Egisthe but able to be called off by Jupiter—represent.<br />

In Les Mots, Sartre tells us that as a child he believed words to be the<br />

quintessence of things, "la quintessence des choses", 13 and "having<br />

discovered the world through language, for a long time I took language to<br />

be the world". 14 He also tells us of a sinister chestnut tree, un marronnier,<br />

about which he had read in the newspaper Le Matin; 15 and his work bears<br />

witness to what appears to have been a protracted obsession with chestnut<br />

trees. The most famous reference is, of course, to be found in the passage<br />

in La Nausee where Roquentin sits hypnotised before a chestnut root; and<br />

it is here, precisely, that he comes to the understanding that reality lies<br />

beneath words, that words are, in a sense, impostors, and that we are<br />

simply deceived by them. Now, one of the French words for "impostor",<br />

which also designates the victim of an imposture as well as a clout or a<br />

thump, is marron (chestnut), as in un medecin marron (an unqualified or<br />

fake doctor), tu es marron (you've been had or duped), and recevoir un<br />

marron (to get thumped). And the word marron evokes other words such<br />

as marrant, of which Sartre seems particularly fond, and one of the senses<br />

of which is "odd" or "peculiar". In La Mort dans Vdme {Iron in the Soul),<br />

the situation of Mathieu and his soldier colleagues during the French<br />

defeat in June 1940 is described by them as "marrant"; but it is also false<br />

as in many ways it appears and is (at least at that stage of the fighting)<br />

unreal. In any case, they are totally depressed, "Us en ont marre", and,<br />

perhaps surprisingly, they all roar with hysterical laughter: "Us se<br />

marrent". 16 Mathieu then begins to carve his name in a chestnut tree, only<br />

to discover, like Lucien in "The Childhood of a Leader"—who proclaims<br />

for that reason that the chestnut tree he hates and insults is en bois (made<br />

of wood)—that the tree is resistant to words. So far, it would seem that the<br />

13 Les Mots, 121.<br />

14 "Pour avoir ddcouvert le monde h travers le langage, je pris longtemps le<br />

langage pour le monde" (ibid., 154).<br />

15 Ibid., 128.<br />

16 Incidentally, marre comes from the Spanish word for "sea", mar, and en avoir<br />

marre (to be thoroughly fed-up) means, etymologically, to be sea-sick, i.e. avoir la<br />

nausee.


Hidden Wordplay in the Works of Jean-Paul Sartre 147<br />

phonemic sequence "m-vowel-r"—marre, mort / mord, mur / mur—<br />

exerted a certain fascination on Sartre. 17<br />

There are in <strong>Sartre's</strong> work several word clusters that could be seen as<br />

based on puns: for example, rond, gris, colloquial terms for "tipsy", and<br />

the proper names Ramon Gris and Steinbock. The latter—a German name<br />

meaning "ibex"—which can be broken down into Stein and Bock, both<br />

redolent of beer, is allocated by Sartre to an Irishman! Both these names,<br />

occurring in the first, eponymous story of Le Mur, might well be intended<br />

to evoke the intoxication with death expressed in the Spanish civil war<br />

slogan, /Viva la muerte! (Long live death!). But there is one such cluster<br />

that stands right at the heart of <strong>Sartre's</strong> conception of humankind, and the<br />

pun at its centre lies fairly deeply buried.<br />

It is well known that Sartre had a horror of crustaceans, and in<br />

particular crabs, which figure abundantly in his work. For example:<br />

It wasn't the miserable look of this fellow that scared us, nor the tumour he<br />

had on his neck which rubbed against the edge of his detachable collar: but<br />

we sensed that his head was full of crab or crayfish thoughts. And that<br />

terrorized us [...]. 18<br />

Suddenly I lost my human appearance and they saw a crab escaping<br />

backwards from this room that was so human. 19<br />

But the most flagrant instance of this fixation is to be found in Les<br />

Sequestres d'Altona where, in the unhinged mind of Frantz, the men of the<br />

thirtieth <strong>century</strong> have become "crabs", "decapods" sitting in judgment<br />

over the men of our generation. The crustaceans which in La Nausee are<br />

presented as the antithesis of humankind are now themselves men. But,<br />

truth to tell, they always have been, and the fact that Roquentin sees<br />

himself at certain moments as a crab shows to what an extent Sartre, while<br />

distancing himself from them, is prepared to acknowledge his kinship with<br />

them. This obsession with crabs, crayfish, and lobsters, by which he felt<br />

Lucien is not the only character to be compared to un mur, a wall (see for<br />

example, Le Sursis, 904, "vous Stes un mur"; and 948, "comme si j'&ais un mur").<br />

Also, one of the three prisoners awaiting execution in Le Mur is Mirbal (mur-balle,<br />

"wall-bullet": death by firing squad?).<br />

18 "Ce n'est pas l'air miserable de ce type qui nous faisait peur, ni la tumeur qu'il<br />

avait au cou et qui frottait contre le bord de son faux col: mais nous sentions qu'il<br />

formait dans sa tSte des pensdes de crabe ou de langouste. Et ga nous terrorisait<br />

[...]" (La Nausee, 14).<br />

19 "Tout d'un coup, j'ai perdu mon apparence d'homme et ils ont vu un crabe qui<br />

s'£chappait h reculons de cette salle si humaine" (ibid., 146).


148 Chapter Ten<br />

himself persecuted, has been explained as an effect of <strong>Sartre's</strong> short-lived<br />

experimentation with mescaline. But it is clear also, as different doctors<br />

affirmed—so Simone de Beauvoir tells us in La Force de Vage {The<br />

Prime of Life)—that it comes from further afield. In Les Mots, Sartre<br />

recounts the following anecdote:<br />

I nearly fainted one day in the train to Limoges as I leafed through the<br />

Hachette almanac: I had happened upon a hair-raising engraving: a quayside<br />

in the moonlight, a long, rough claw coming out of the water and<br />

seizing a drunkard, dragging him down to the bottom of the dock [...]. I<br />

was scared of water, scared of crabs and trees. Scared above all of books: I<br />

cursed the torturers who peopled their stories with these atrocious images.<br />

Nevertheless I imitated them [...]. What then fell from my pen—octopus<br />

with flaming eyes, twenty-ton shellfish, giant talking spider-crab—was<br />

myself, a child monster, it was my dissatisfaction with life, my fear of<br />

death, my insipidity and my perversity [...].<br />

If mescaline did indeed induce hallucinations in the adult Sartre, why,<br />

we may ask, the ones which find expression in his work? The answer is<br />

easy: they go back to his glossolatrous (language-worshipping) childhood.<br />

So would it be unreasonable to suggest that his fixation on crustaceans<br />

springs from the fact that the word for lobster, homard, not to write<br />

hommard, could be taken to mean, with a little imagination, homme<br />

primitif (primitive man) or homme degenere (degenerate man)? Naturally,<br />

just as Flaubert refrains from spelling "Hommet" the name of his stupid<br />

humanist Monsieur Homais, which would point too obviously to the way<br />

we are meant to think of him, Sartre resists the temptation openly to call<br />

human beings homards, a term which would be manifestly pejorative, like<br />

roublard (crafty devil), froussard (coward), vantard (braggart), pleurard<br />

(whiner) and, indeed, mouchard (sneak), not to speak of a host of other<br />

words ending in -ard. So he uses instead the term crabe.<br />

It is in Les Sequestres d'Altona, as I have intimated, that the<br />

resemblance between human beings and crabs is best elucidated. Frantz<br />

"Je pensai m'£vanouir un jour, dans le train de Limoges, en feuilletant<br />

Talmanach Hachette: j'&ais tomb£ sur une gravure a faire dresser les cheveux: un<br />

quai sous la lune, une longue pince rugueuse sortait de l'eau, accrochait un<br />

ivrogne, Tentrainait au fond du bassin [...]. .Feus peur de l'eau, peur des crabes et<br />

des arbres. Peur des livres surtout: je maudis les bourreaux qui peuplaient leurs<br />

rdcits de ces figures atroces. Pourtant je les imitai [...]. Ce qui venait alors sous ma<br />

plume—pieuvre aux yeux de feu, crustac£ de vingt tonnes, araignde g£ante et qui<br />

parlait—c'dtait moi-meme, monstre enfantin, c'&ait mon ennui de vivre, ma peur<br />

de mourir, ma fadeur et ma perversity" (ibid., 129-30).


Hidden Wordplay in the Works of Jean-Paul Sartre 149<br />

von Gerlach, who has tortured Russian prisoners during the Second World<br />

War and who feels intolerably guilty in consequence, sequesters himself in<br />

an upstairs room of the large family house in Altona, which is a suburb of<br />

Hamburg. He is still there, although officially dead, in 1959. His sister<br />

Leni, with whom he has an incestuous relationship, brings him food. His<br />

remorse has driven him completely mad. He believes himself to be<br />

persecuted, as a man who embodies the entire twentieth <strong>century</strong>, by a<br />

Tribunal of Crabs sitting in the thirtieth. The crabs are decapods who<br />

"understand nothing", and he is a man who regards himself as a crab. But<br />

as he says to his sister, he is defending his <strong>century</strong> before magistrates<br />

whom he has not the pleasure of knowing. But who exactly are these<br />

magistrates? When Johanna, his sister-in-law, who manages to violate his<br />

solitude, speaks to him of crabs, he replies:<br />

What Crabs? Are you mad? What Crabs? Ah! Yes. Well, yes... The Crabs<br />

are men. What, you say? Where did I get that idea from? [...] Real men,<br />

fine and good, on all the balconies of the centuries. As for me, I was<br />

crawling in the courtyard; I thought I could hear them: "Brother, what's<br />

that I see?" That was me... Me the Crab... Well, I said no: my time will<br />

not be judged by men. What will they be, after all? The sons of our sons.<br />

Do we allow brats to condemn their grandfathers? I turned the tables on<br />

them; I yelled: "Here is man; after me the flood; after the flood, Crabs,<br />

you\" Unmasked, all of them! The balconies were swarming with arthropods.<br />

21<br />

The Tribunal of Crustaceans consists then, after all, of men. Naturally<br />

Frantz is in bad faith; and it is clear that he knows very well that it is he<br />

himself who is judging himself when he says: "The defendant bears<br />

witness for himself... I am Man, Johanna; I am every man and the whole<br />

of Man, I am the Century, like absolutely anyone." 22 Judge and defendant,<br />

he is also witness for the defence. So why does he not find himself guilty<br />

21 "Quels Crabes? fites-vous folle? Quels Crabes? Ah! oui. Eh bien, oui... Les<br />

Crabes sont des hommes. Hein, quoi? Oil ai-je 6t6 chercher cela? [...] De vrais<br />

hommes, bons et beaux, h tous les balcons des si&cles. Moi, je rampais dans la<br />

cour; je croyais les entendre: 'Fr&re, qu'est-ce que c'est que ga?' Qa, c'&ait moi...<br />

Moi le Crabe... Eh bien, j'ai dit non: des hommes ne jugeront pas mon temps. Que<br />

seront-ils, apr£s tout? Les fils de nos fils. Est-ce qu'on permet aux marmots de<br />

condamner leurs grands-pfcres? J'ai retournd la situation; j'ai crte: 'Void l'homme;<br />

apr&s moi, le deluge; apr&s le deluge, les Crabes, vousV D6masqu£s, tous! les<br />

balcons grouillaient d'arthropodes" {Les Sequestres d'Altona, in Theatre, 838-39).<br />

22 "L'accusd tdmoigne pour lui-meme... Je suis l'Homme, Johanna; je suis tout<br />

homme et tout l'Homme, je suis le Sfecle comme n'importe qui" (ibid., 839).


150 Chapter Ten<br />

and put it all behind him? Because he is or pretends to be convinced that<br />

Germany is still in ruins, and that it would have been better for the whole<br />

of humanity if his country had won the war; and perhaps, he thinks, if he<br />

had been even more cruel and ruthless than he was, his country would<br />

have been victorious. Are then the Crabs hard men judging soft ones, or<br />

soft men condemning brutes? Dur (hard) and mou (soft) are adjectives that<br />

constantly recur throughout <strong>Sartre's</strong> work, and it is to be observed that<br />

crustaceans are hard on the outside and soft within. And are these<br />

particular so-called crustaceans more advanced than we or, on the<br />

contrary, are they homards, degenerate men?<br />

For Sartre, who describes his anti-humanist humanism as an optimistic<br />

hardness, "une durete optimiste", 23 and whose judgments are often hard,<br />

the answer to these questions is clear: the Crabs reflect Frantz, and Frantz,<br />

like Lucien the anti-Semite in "L'Enfance d'un chef, is a soft man who<br />

has tried to fashion an independent personality by making himself hard.<br />

He is a mou who has become dur, just as Lucien (with compliments to Dr<br />

Spooner) is a doux (sweet, gentle) who becomes mur (mature). It is the<br />

hard Frantz who condemns the soft one, and the soft one who judges the<br />

brute. There is, too, a hidden play on words that lies at the heart of the<br />

drama, and that possibly even inspired it: Frantz eats oysters; the<br />

crustacean is eating himself, eating himself, that is, in a metaphorical sense<br />

of the verb "to eat", manger, i.e. to torture, that is quite common in Sartre.<br />

// se met a la question: he is questioning himself, i.e., in the traditional<br />

euphemism, torturing himself—and that shortly after the publication of La<br />

Question, the book in which Henri Alleg denounces France's use of torture<br />

in the Algerian war, apropos of which Sartre wrote his controversial article<br />

"UneVictoire". 24<br />

But not all men are homards, and not all homards are brutes. There are<br />

men of whom Sartre naturally approves, and who aspire to be des hommes<br />

parmi les hommes, free men among equals. Furthermore, there is another<br />

play on words to which, when considering the nature of his humanism, we<br />

must pay attention. In their notes on La Nausee, Michel Contat and Michel<br />

Rybalka write that, whereas the in-itself, the en-soi, is conceived in terms<br />

of "black", noir, and "matter", mati&re, and the for-itself, the pour-soi, in<br />

terms of "white", blanc, and "light", lumiere, human reality, la realite<br />

humaine, often equated with the Heideggerian Dasein, is described in<br />

L'Existentialisme est un humanisme, 58.<br />

24 [First published in L'Express, 6 March 1958 (seized by the authorities as a<br />

consequence), subsequently published as a postface to Alleg's book and collected<br />

in Situations, V—Eds.]


Hidden Wordplay in the Works of Jean-Paul Sartre 151<br />

terms of "grey", gris, and "shadow", ombre. But just as a person can, for<br />

Sartre, not only encounter a wall but can actually become one, so can one<br />

not only be in shadow but also be a shadow. Examples of this abound in<br />

<strong>Sartre's</strong> work:<br />

A couple of shadows got up, slipped between the tables and made off.<br />

Mathieu remained alone outside the cafe. 26<br />

A man alone, forgotten, eaten by shadow, in the face of this perishable<br />

eternity [...]. There had once been a gentle, timorous man who loved and<br />

walked about in Paris. The man was dead. 27<br />

All human lives melted into the shadow. 28<br />

Shadows came and went in the white light of a cafe [...]. This to-ing and<br />

fro-ing of the shadows continued [...]. Some shadows stopped and he saw<br />

men coming towards him. 29<br />

These passages are taken from Le Sursis and relate to the effect on the<br />

French people of the Munich crisis in 1938. The following passage comes<br />

from La Mort dans Vame, where Mathieu and his soldier colleagues await<br />

their fate in the face of a German advance, about which they have been<br />

kept in ignorance. They are wondering whether further resistance is<br />

possible:<br />

Everything is asking us our opinion. Everything. A great interrogation<br />

surrounds us: it's a farce. We are asked the question as if we were men;<br />

they want to make us believe that we are still men. But no. No. No. What a<br />

farce, this shadow of a question put by a shadow of war to semblances of<br />

men. 30<br />

See (Euvres romanesques, 1676.<br />

26 "Un couple d'ombres se leva, glissa entre les tables et s'en fut. Mathieu restait<br />

seul a la terrasse" {Le Sursis, 1046).<br />

27 "Un homme tout seul, oublte, mangg par 1'ombre en face de cette gternife<br />

p&issable [...]. II y avait eu un homme tendre et timord qui aimait Paris et qui s'y<br />

promenait. L'homme dtait mort" (ibid.).<br />

"[T]outes les vies humaines se fondirent dans l'ombre" (ibid., 1047).<br />

29 "[D]es ombres passaient et repassaient dans la lumifcre blanche d'un cafe [...].<br />

[C]e va-et-vient des ombres continua [...]. Quelques ombres s'arr§t£rent et il vit<br />

des hommes qui venaient vers lui" (ibid., 1061).<br />

30 "Tout nous demande notre avis. Tout. Une grande interrogation nous cerne: c'est<br />

une farce. On nous pose la question comme a des hommes; on veut nous faire<br />

croire que nous sommes encore des hommes. Mais non. Non. Non. Quelle farce,


152 Chapter Ten<br />

Is it not clear that shadows (and Sartre naturally avoids the word here<br />

to describe these semblances of men) are men who have been dehumanized<br />

and rendered ludicrous? Shadow may well be the element of all human<br />

reality, but it is also the reality of those particular human beings<br />

transformed into something else, possibly lobsters or crabs, by themselves<br />

or others. In the same way as we have salauds (bastards) and laches<br />

(cowards), Dr Rog6 and Monsieur Achille, so we have guilty homards,<br />

and homards who are soft but hardly guilty at all. And it is difficult to<br />

avoid the suspicion that the New York scene with which La Mort dans<br />

Vame begins—in which the Spanish fighter Gomez encounters the<br />

indifference of the American population to a defeated Spanish republican<br />

cause fought in the name of "man", and in which, having uttered the mild<br />

expletive hombre! (man!), he complains of the extreme heat and lack of<br />

ombre (shade)—is inspired at some level by a play on words. If true, it<br />

would mean that, for him at least, "shadow" relates to a humanist, as<br />

opposed to idealist, conception of man, akin to that of Hoederer in Les<br />

Mains sales (Dirty Hands), and not to its travesty.<br />

Other marine creatures that figure in <strong>Sartre's</strong> work are shrimps<br />

(crevettes) and jellyfish (meduses). The word meduse is one of the<br />

contemptuous terms by which Lucien denotes Jews and foreigners, the socalled<br />

meteques (wogs). There is nothing softer, it will be conceded, than a<br />

jellyfish, but Medusa is also the name of the Gorgon who turns to stone all<br />

those who look at her. In "The Childhood of a Leader", this metaphor is<br />

highly ironic: Sartre often compares the look of the Other to the look of<br />

Medusa; but Lucien does not need to be petrified: he has petrified himself<br />

by choosing for himself the stupid hardness of stone. Besides the apparent<br />

metaphor, we have, it seems, a play on words and a hidden metaphor one<br />

of whose terms, Medusa, is endowed with lethal qualities which are the<br />

opposite of the inoffensive and contemptible attributes to which Lucien<br />

gives the name. Whereas Medusa turns people to stone, here we have a<br />

"stone" who reduces them to meduses, a guilty homard and creatures of<br />

the sea that are not necessarily guilty of anything at all.<br />

As for crevette, this is a word used by Daniel, the so-called archangel<br />

and would-be homosexual seducer, to describe one of his young boyfriends,<br />

3129 as well as by Lucien of his erstwhile friend Berliac, who has<br />

been seduced by the homosexual writer Bergere. 32 It is a word which<br />

could well be the feminine diminutive of crabe\ and indeed one of the<br />

cette ombre de question posde par une ombre de guerre & des apparences<br />

d'homines" (La Mort dans Vame, 1183).<br />

31 See L'Age de raison, 556.<br />

32 See "L'Enfance d'un chef \ in he Mur, 359.


Hidden Wordplay in the Works of Jean-Paul Sartre 153<br />

German words for "shrimp" is Krabbe. There is here, in Lucien's rejection<br />

of Berliac's crustaceousness, a direct link between words, the words he<br />

has used, and crustaceans: "He had spoken forcefully but the words rolled<br />

out of him like empty shells." 33 As he grows older, Lucien—like the little<br />

Poulou himself—is gradually cured of his inordinate love of language; but<br />

unlike Sartre, and in terms which seem to foreshadow those used by<br />

Daniel after his decision not to kill his beloved cats, he fails to commit<br />

himself to any worthwhile human goal<br />

Regarding Daniel's cats—which clearly represent a homosexual self of<br />

which he would like to be rid, and which he ends by reluctantly letting out<br />

of the basket in which he has planned to drown them—one may well ask<br />

whether this whole richly revealing episode (showing as it does Daniel's<br />

hesitations about coming out of a closet in which he has been stifling), was<br />

not inspired by the German equivalent—Sartre never learnt English<br />

properly—of the English expression "to let the cat out of the bag", die<br />

Katze aus dem Sack lassen.<br />

Be that as it may, various questions remain. Is Sartre conscious of his<br />

plays on words? And if he is not, can one even use the term? After all,<br />

some of them are fairly commonplace, and some are built into the<br />

language itself: thus, consciousness and reflection are very frequently<br />

compared with a mirror, as in Sartre, and biting and remorse have obvious<br />

affinities. And could there be unconscious puns of a subjective nature?<br />

This is what he writes on the subject of Lacanian psychology:<br />

Lacan says that the unconscious is structured like a language. I would<br />

rather say that the language that expresses the unconscious has the<br />

structure of a dream. In other words, understanding of the unconscious, in<br />

the majority of cases, never finds its clear expression. 34<br />

Whether Sartre is fully aware of his more cryptic wordplay or not, we are<br />

therefore, I believe, justified in claiming, in conformity with his own<br />

ideas, that it has its source in a hidden trope. Either it is a case of hide-andseek,<br />

prompted perhaps by the literary craftsman's desire to keep hidden at<br />

least some of the nuts and bolts of his work—but as children playing this<br />

game (to which there are frequent references in <strong>Sartre's</strong> work) very well<br />

"II avait parld avec force mais les mots roul&rent hors de lui comme des<br />

coquilles vides" (ibid., 361).<br />

34 "Lacan dit que l'inconscient est structure comme un langage. Je dirais plutdt que<br />

le langage qui exprime l'inconscient a la structure d'un r§ve. Autrement dit, la<br />

comprehension de l'inconscient, dans la plupart des cas, ne trouve jamais son<br />

expression claire" ("Sartre par Sartre", in Situations, IX, 111).


154 Chapter Ten<br />

understand, there would be no fun in hiding so effectively that seekers<br />

would have no chance at all of finding them—or it is the unconscious<br />

game that Freud claims criminals who leave behind incriminating clues<br />

often play with the police. It would be invidious to claim that Sartre, of all<br />

people, was unconscious of what he was doing; but there could indeed be a<br />

psychological reason for these pun burials. Being well on the way to<br />

curing himself of the illusion that words were the quintessence of things,<br />

Sartre had nevertheless to acknowledge that literature, his chosen<br />

vocation, was words, and that his inspiration often came from fortuitous<br />

homonymic collisions. Of this inspiration, while not yet repudiating it<br />

entirely, he might well—like Schiller, who deplored the musical origin of<br />

his own writing, and unlike the punning Derridas of this world—have felt<br />

just a little ashamed.<br />

Works Cited<br />

Beauvoir, Simone de. La Force de Vage. Paris: Gallimard, 1981.<br />

Redfern, Walter. "Applying the Tourniquet: Sartre and Punning", French<br />

Studies, vol. XXXIX, no. 3, July 1985, 298-304.<br />

Sartre, Jean-Paul. L'Existentialisme est un humanisme. Paris: Nagel, 1965.<br />

—. LesMots. Paris: Gallimard, 1964.<br />

—. Les Mouches, Huis clos, he Diable et le bon Dieu, Les Sequestres<br />

d'Altona, in Theatre. Paris: Gallimard, 1962.<br />

—. Le Mur ("Le Mur", "La Chambre", "Erostrate", "Intimite",<br />

"L'Enfance d'un chef"), La Nausee, Les Chemins de la liberte<br />

(L'Age de raison, Le Sursis, La Mort dans Uame, Une drole d'amitie),<br />

in (Euvres romanesques (edition &ablie par Michel Contat et Michel<br />

Rybalka). Paris: Gallimard, Bibliotheque de la Pl&ade, 1981.<br />

—. Saint Genet, comedien et martyr. Paris: Gallimard, 1952.<br />

—. Situations, V: Colonialisme et neo-colonialisme. Paris: Gallimard,<br />

1964.<br />

—. Situations, IX: Melanges. Paris: Gallimard, 1972.


CHAPTER ELEVEN<br />

DESTABILISING IDENTITIES<br />

AND DISTINCTIONS:<br />

THE LITERARY-PHILOSOPHICAL EXPERIENCE<br />

OF HOPE NOW<br />

IAN RHOAD<br />

The title of this chapter might seem strange at first glance. 1 Why bring<br />

up the notion of a "literary experience" with regard to Hope Now! After<br />

all, the text in question is not one of <strong>Sartre's</strong> novels or plays. Hope Now is<br />

a set of interviews between Sartre and his secretary, Benny Levy, that<br />

purports an undeniably philosophical aim: to sketch out an ethics for the<br />

political left. Published a month before he died, Hope Now was <strong>Sartre's</strong><br />

last attempt to make good, at least partially, on the promise he had made at<br />

the end of Being and Nothingness: to put forth an ethics. As such, it<br />

engages with a project—a specifically philosophical project—that Sartre<br />

had kept with him for almost four decades. Thus, it might be thought that I<br />

am doing Sartre a disservice by subordinating his philosophy to his<br />

literature. That is not my intention.<br />

The aim of this essay is simply to appreciate the unique project of<br />

Hope Now and to argue that the way it has been studied has not taken into<br />

account a certain literary element therein. This literary element is not<br />

something imposed on the text from the outside, but rather inherent in the<br />

text itself, and can be identified by using <strong>Sartre's</strong> own criteria (not my<br />

own) for separating his philosophy and his literature. Far from privileging<br />

<strong>Sartre's</strong> literature over his philosophy, then, my aim is to show that the<br />

1 1 am indebted to Craig Vasey, Professor of Philosophy at the University of Mary<br />

Washington, Virginia, for challenging me to develop many of the ideas I present in<br />

this essay; all conclusions are of course my own. A previous draft was given as a<br />

paper at the 15 th Biennial Conference of the North American Sartre Society at<br />

Fordham University, Manhattan, New York City, 27-29 October 2006.


156 Chapter Eleven<br />

very distinction between the two categories is provocatively deconstructed<br />

in Hope Now. Thought of in this way, Hope Now occupies an especially<br />

interesting position in <strong>Sartre's</strong> ceuvre—not simply because it was his final<br />

publication, but because it points to an explicit convergence of his<br />

philosophical and literary ambitions, which he had for so long insisted<br />

were distinct.<br />

It is, of course, difficult to discuss Hope Now without letting the<br />

controversy surrounding the text obstruct our analysis. After forty years in<br />

the public eye, Jean-Paul Sartre appeared to reinvent himself just before<br />

his death in 1980. In a set of interviews between Sartre and Levy,<br />

published in Le Nouvel Observateur only weeks before <strong>Sartre's</strong> death,<br />

Sartre came curiously close to embracing a Jewish messianic attitude and<br />

he shockingly dismissed many of his earlier ideas. In the aftermath of the<br />

publication, an outraged Simone de Beauvoir accused Benny Levy of<br />

manipulating the aged Sartre while others chided her in turn for betraying<br />

<strong>Sartre's</strong> final wishes. The stakes of the debate were high because the<br />

legacy of a great philosopher was in question. It is understandable,<br />

therefore, that the controversy has dominated most discussion of the text.<br />

However, since it has now been more than a quarter of a <strong>century</strong> since the<br />

controversy first erupted, I am going to ask that the reader of this chapter<br />

momentarily look past the intrigue for the sake of doing justice to the text<br />

itself. To borrow a phrase from Husserl, I suggest that we "bracket off the<br />

question of <strong>Sartre's</strong> possible conversion to Judaism or his manipulation at<br />

the hands of Benny Levy. 2 To be sure, that does not mean the murkiness<br />

will disappear entirely. We should not approach the text as if it were<br />

written by Sartre in his prime, for it was indeed published shortly before<br />

he died. Sartre was blind, debilitated, and in many ways dependent on<br />

L6vy when it was composed. Our knowledge of that should and inevitably<br />

does condition our experience of it, but let us treat it as one determining<br />

factor of the work and not as the be-all and end-all of the discussion.<br />

Proceeding in this manner, I shall argue two basic points. First, I will<br />

show that <strong>Sartre's</strong> distinction between imaging and signifying<br />

consciousnesses is key for understanding how he separated his<br />

philosophical works from his literary endeavours. Then, I will show how<br />

this distinction ultimately fails when we apply it to Hope Now. <strong>Sartre's</strong><br />

Accordingly, I have not included a discussion of the controversy in the present<br />

essay. For a comprehensive account, see Ronald Aronson, "<strong>Sartre's</strong> Last Words".<br />

Aronson's introduction to the interviews remains the most exhaustive treatment of<br />

the subject to date. For readers interested in a more biographical account of the<br />

Sartre-Levy friendship, a good place to start is Annie Cohen-Solal's Sartre: A Life.


The Literary-Philosophical Experience of Hope Now 157<br />

final project was something altogether different, regardless of the exact<br />

motivations for its publication.<br />

Our point of entry is a passage from The Imaginary, written in the mid-<br />

1930s by a young, unknown Sartre who was just beginning to find his<br />

philosophical voice. In this passage, Sartre tells us what it is like to<br />

observe an impersonator on a stage:<br />

On the stage of a music hall, Franconay is "doing some imitations"; I<br />

recognise the artist she is imitating: it is Maurice Chevalier. I assess the<br />

imitation: "It is really him", or else: "It is lacking". What is going on in my<br />

consciousness? 3<br />

Seventy years later, we might describe the experience of reading Hope<br />

Now in a similar way. With the interviews compiled in book-form and<br />

accompanied by Ronald Aronson's introduction and Benny Levy's essays,<br />

any reader of Hope Now is put in the presence of the controversy the<br />

moment he or she opens the book. Aware of the complexity of the<br />

situation, we ask ourselves: is that really Sartre talking about the Messiah?<br />

We try to situate his new ideas so they fit within his earlier philosophy. In<br />

the same way that Sartre tries to reconcile the "essence" of Maurice<br />

Chevalier and the physical attributes of the impersonator, we too look for a<br />

way to smooth over the tension that exists between the "essence" of<br />

Sartre—his true self that we claim to know—and this peculiar<br />

manifestation of it. Once again, the appropriate phenomenological<br />

question is: what is going on in my consciousness? <strong>Sartre's</strong> answer in The<br />

Imaginary is revealingly similar to our own experience:<br />

It quite often happens that the synthesis is not entirely made: the face and<br />

the body of the imitator do not lose all their individuality; yet the<br />

expressive nature "Maurice Chevalier" nevertheless appears on that face,<br />

on that female body. A hybrid state follows, neither fully perception nor<br />

fully image, which should be described for itself. These states without<br />

equilibrium and that do not endure are evidently, for the spectator, what is<br />

most pleasant in the imitation. 4<br />

Similar hybrid states without equilibrium, which Sartre calls<br />

"metastable", 5 are brought about in Hope Now. <strong>Sartre's</strong> initials appear on<br />

3<br />

Sartre, The Imaginary, 25.<br />

4<br />

Ibid., 29.<br />

5<br />

The term "metastable" is used by Sartre in Being and Nothingness. However, as<br />

Robert Cumming has shown, we can retroactively apply the term to the "states<br />

without equilibrium" that Sartre described a few years prior in The Imaginary. See


158 Chapter Eleven<br />

the page in bold, laying claim to subsequent words and ideas. The<br />

expressive nature of "Jean-Paul Sartre" appears in this way much as<br />

"Maurice Chevalier" appears on the face and body of the female<br />

impersonator. Levy's comments are likewise claimed by his name,<br />

although for most readers he is an unfamiliar character, shrouded in<br />

mystery and controversy. Thus, we create a fictitious identity for Levy<br />

which takes ownership over the words that follow his initials. But while<br />

this takes place, the content of the Sartre-Levy discussion contradicts the<br />

gesture of its supposedly straightforward form. We watch as Sartre, a<br />

lifelong atheist, adopts a younger man's religious vocabulary in order to<br />

think with him. Sartre petitions us, the reader, to understand the<br />

importance of their collaboration. Unlike a traditional interview where two<br />

individuals exchange ideas back and forth, Hope Now is an effort to create<br />

"plural thoughts". We witness an experiment in a way of thinking and<br />

doing philosophy. Still, this experiment takes place on a page that visually<br />

maintains the traditional interview format, and thus a white space<br />

continues to separate the initials of the interlocutors, as if to say: "We may<br />

be thinking together, but each of us deserves our own voice." The political<br />

and ethical analogies here are numerous, and Sartre delights in using them<br />

to full effect.<br />

The result is a unique literary and philosophical experience that<br />

destabilises the traditional concept of the interview. These metastable<br />

states without equilibrium are the subject of my investigation. After all,<br />

our experience of Hope Now is obviously not reducible to that of an<br />

impersonation. Let us, then, attempt to grasp the text in all its uniqueness<br />

and see whether it brings us any new insights. Before doing this, however,<br />

we need to dive more deeply into <strong>Sartre's</strong> own thoughts on the difference<br />

between philosophy and literature.<br />

<strong>Sartre's</strong> Distinction between Literature and Philosophy<br />

In the course of an interview given in May 1975, Sartre stated that he<br />

had never had a stylistic ambition for philosophy, defining style as "first of<br />

all, economy [...] making sentences in which several meanings co-exist<br />

and in which the words are taken as allusions, as objects rather than as<br />

concepts." 6 He says unequivocally: "In philosophy a word must signify a<br />

Cumming's excellent article, "Role-Playing: <strong>Sartre's</strong> transformation of Husserl's<br />

phenomenology".<br />

"An interview with Jean-Paul Sartre", with Michael Rybalka, et al. I first<br />

encountered this quotation in Jonathan Webber, "Notes on the Translation". For<br />

his part, Webber uses the passage to justify the consistency with which he


The Literary-Philosophical Experience of Hope Now 159<br />

concept and that one only.' The important point here is not that style is<br />

necessarily completely absent in a philosophical text, but that style is not<br />

the goal, the ambition, of the work itself. A work of philosophy is meant to<br />

clarify concepts, not indulge in a play on words. As a result, the<br />

experience of a philosophical work is different from that of a literary<br />

work. In The Imaginary, Sartre discussed the issue in terms of the types of<br />

consciousnesses produced when we read philosophy versus those<br />

produced when we read literature. He argued that reading an academic text<br />

produces a signifying consciousness, whereas reading a work of literature<br />

involves an imaging consciousness.<br />

In both signifying and imaging consciousnesses, an absent object is<br />

aimed at through another object. However, in imaging consciousness the<br />

intermediary object fulfils consciousness in place of the object that is<br />

being aimed at, thus functioning as what Sartre calls an "analogon". 8 In<br />

The Imaginary, Sartre tells us that when we read a formal report about<br />

property owners in Paris, we are given the absent object "building", but<br />

not in the same way as a novel gives it to us when a character is described<br />

as running down a flight of stairs. It is not the content of our knowledge<br />

that changes—in each case we are given "building"—but the way in which<br />

it is known that distinguishes our experiences. In the case of the novel,<br />

"building" is given to us in the manner of an entire plot inside an entire<br />

world, which Sartre describes as "irreal":<br />

If we are reading a scholarly work, we produce a consciousness in which<br />

the intention adheres to the sign at every instant. Our thought, our<br />

knowledge slip into the words and we become conscious of it on the<br />

words, as an objective property of the words. Naturally these objective<br />

properties do not remain separated but fuse from one word to another, one<br />

phrase to another, one page to another: hardly have we opened a book and<br />

we are faced with an objective sphere of signification [...]. But if the book<br />

is a novel, everything changes: the sphere of objective signification<br />

becomes an irreal world. To read a novel is to take a general attitude of<br />

translates certain distinct terms into English. For my part, the source text—the<br />

interview itself—was well worth a look, as it was conducted only a few years prior<br />

to <strong>Sartre's</strong> discussions with Benny L£vy, and in it Sartre reaffirms his conception<br />

of the imagination that he laid out in The Imaginary. Sartre remarks: "It seems to<br />

me that if I had to write on the imaginary, I would write what I wrote previously"<br />

(14). For my own purposes, therefore, it is extremely useful since it justifies<br />

approaching Hope Now through a discussion of The Imaginary, which had been<br />

written some forty years earlier.<br />

7 Ibid., 11.<br />

8 Sartre, The Imaginary, 83.


160 Chapter Eleven<br />

consciousness: this attitude largely resembles that of a spectator who, in<br />

the theatre, sees the curtain rising. It is preparing to discover a whole<br />

world, which is not that of perception, but neither is that of mental images.<br />

To be present at a play is to apprehend the characters on the actors, the<br />

forest of As You Like It on the cardboard trees. To read is to realise contact<br />

with the irreal world on the signs. 9<br />

We can extract from this passage that it is the experience of a text,<br />

determined by the type of consciousness involved, which decides a text's<br />

character as dramatic or academic. It is possible, therefore, that a person<br />

could have dramatic experiences throughout the course of reading an<br />

academic text if his or her consciousness approached the words as things<br />

inside a world. It is up to the author to try and elicit his or her desired<br />

response in the reader. Thus, I propose that the primary way to<br />

differentiate Sartre*s literary endeavours from his academic projects is to<br />

look for stylistic techniques that appear to aim at putting us in the<br />

presence of a world.<br />

Before showing how this differentiation ultimately fails when applied<br />

to Hope Now, there are three nuances regarding this distinction worth<br />

addressing. These nuances will allow us to see why <strong>Sartre's</strong> strict<br />

distinction between philosophy and literature, although ultimately<br />

untenable, is useful for understanding our everyday experiences of<br />

different types of texts. Also, from a purely biographical perspective, these<br />

observations can help us to understand something of <strong>Sartre's</strong> own literary<br />

objectives and methodology. They are, first, how the presence of an irreal<br />

world in <strong>Sartre's</strong> literature assigns to the reader the role of judge; next, the<br />

felt duration established in all literary works; and, third, the desirable<br />

ambiguity and ineffability that are possible in and through literature.<br />

First, let us consider the role of the reader. In the presence of one of<br />

<strong>Sartre's</strong> imaginary worlds, the reader engages with the given work<br />

differently from when he or she reads one of <strong>Sartre's</strong> philosophical essays.<br />

Presented with characters inside a plot, the reader makes qualitative<br />

judgments about specific actions and events that take place. 10 Obviously,<br />

we can make judgments when we read academic works: a person can read<br />

a philosophical treatise on capital punishment and formulate a passionate<br />

stance on the idea. However, if that same person sees the issue worked out<br />

9 Ibid., 64.<br />

10 James Edie has shown how <strong>Sartre's</strong> theatrical works, in particular, encourage the<br />

audience to adopt the position of judge: "In <strong>Sartre's</strong> own plays, especially the<br />

important ones [...] the action is frequently ambiguous and can only be judged by<br />

those who stand outside the agon itself, namely the audience, us" (Edie, 436).


The Literary-Philosophical Experience of Hope Now 161<br />

on a stage with characters and plotlines, they will take it in as a lived<br />

reality. When watching a play, we do not just judge the idea: we judge the<br />

particular. In most cases it is up to us to formulate the idea from the<br />

particular rather than the other way around.<br />

At this point, one might raise the objection that the same could be said<br />

about news reports or essays on particular events. A Sartrean response, I<br />

believe, would remark, first, that these are not hard and fast distinctions,<br />

some blurring is to be expected; and, <strong>second</strong>ly, that our experiences of<br />

those other types of writing for the most part lack a certain temporal<br />

quality that is characteristic of literary experiences—which brings us to<br />

our <strong>second</strong> point: the felt duration of literary works. It is not until we read<br />

<strong>Sartre's</strong> literature that we see his phenomenological insights take place in<br />

time. Consider, for example, his play Dirty Hands (Les Mains sales,<br />

1948). We watch the character Hugo slip into the identity of a communist<br />

and become objectified throughout the course of the play. Now, in<br />

Notebooks for an Ethics (Cahiers pour une morale, 1983), which Sartre<br />

was working on at roughly the same time as he wrote Dirty Hands, we<br />

find an abundance of passages in which he describes just such a<br />

conversion phenomenologically. But the difference is that in Dirty Hands,<br />

Hugo's conversion is not put forth as a simple event to be held in front of<br />

consciousness, but rather as an entire mode of being and becoming that we<br />

see, feel, and judge in time. Moreover, the felt duration of a literary work<br />

establishes a relationship between the author and reader. In a set of<br />

interviews with Simone de Beauvoir from 1974, later published as part of<br />

Beauvoir's Adieux, Sartre described this relationship:<br />

It is a question of aligning words that have a certain tension of their own<br />

and that by this tension will bring into being the tension of the book, which<br />

is a duration to which one commits oneself. When you begin a book you<br />

enter into that duration. You cause your own duration to be determined in<br />

such a manner that it now has a certain beginning, which is the beginning<br />

of the book, and which will have an end. There exists therefore a certain<br />

relation between the reader and a duration that is his own and that at the<br />

same time is not his own, a relation that lasts from the moment he begins<br />

the book until he finishes it. This supposes a complex relation between the<br />

x l<br />

author and the reader [...].<br />

Sartre goes on to explain that the relationship between the author and<br />

reader is one in which the author has to maintain this sense of duration in<br />

the reader. Writing literature—at least, if it is to be any good—thus<br />

Sartre, in Simone de Beauvoir, Adieux, 211.


162 Chapter Eleven<br />

involves an obligation on the part of the writer. We will return to the<br />

notion of obligation and, in particular, the importance of "beginnings and<br />

ends" in shaping relationships (both between authors and readers and<br />

between people in general) in our analysis of Hope Now.<br />

Putting the reader in the presence of a temporal world discloses a truth<br />

of its own. Writing, Sartre explained to Beauvoir in that same set of<br />

interviews, "was an activity that produced a reality, not exactly the book,<br />

but something beyond the book. The book belonged to the imaginary, but<br />

beyond the book there was truth." 12 The use of "something" in this<br />

quotation is significant because it shows that Sartre was not clear about the<br />

exact nature of the truth found in literature. Earlier in their discussion,<br />

Beauvoir picks up on this uncertainty and asks him: "You group words<br />

and then all of a sudden, by some unknown magic, these words disclose<br />

the world?" Sartre responds by saying: "Yes that's how it was. Some<br />

unknown magic indeed, because I had no idea. It was faith in language." 13<br />

We now see perhaps the most important reason behind <strong>Sartre's</strong><br />

adamant separation of philosophy and literature, and it also brings us to<br />

the third nuance I set out to discuss: the desirable ambiguity and<br />

ineffability of literature. Surely, <strong>Sartre's</strong> approach to philosophy was<br />

descriptive, but as a philosopher he always attempted to put forth a clear<br />

argument. It is evident from his comments to Beauvoir, in Adieux and<br />

elsewhere, that Sartre did not want his readers to come away from one of<br />

his philosophical works unsure of the nature of the truth suggested. In<br />

other words, we are not supposed to read The Imaginary and conclude:<br />

"Sartre is telling us something about the imaginary." It was, of course, in<br />

his literary works that Sartre was able to take the time to play with<br />

ambiguity and ineffable truths to his heart's content.<br />

To conclude this first section, we have seen that the primary way to<br />

distinguish <strong>Sartre's</strong> literary endeavours from his purely philosophical<br />

projects is to look for a style that puts us in the presence of a world. Sartre<br />

himself made this distinction many times over, often discussing the<br />

difference in terms of signifying and imaging consciousnesses. However,<br />

since this distinction is more or less subjective—the genre of a given text<br />

is not strictly determined by a set of formal properties inside the text but<br />

by how it is experienced when read—I have tried to identify a set of<br />

experiential qualities that take place when we find ourselves confronted<br />

with a literary world, namely: the role of the reader; the felt duration of the<br />

literary work; and the desired ambiguity and ineffability that are possible<br />

12 Ibid., 216, my italics.<br />

13 Ibid., 140.


The Literary-Philosophical Experience of Hope Now 163<br />

through literature. This set should not be taken as exhaustive, for it is<br />

possible, and indeed likely, that there are many other nuances worth<br />

discussing. However, these are three that, in my view, are especially useful<br />

for analysing Hope Now. Let us therefore turn to the text itself.<br />

Hope Now: Destabilising the Distinction<br />

If we accept the basic guidelines I have proposed, then the first way to<br />

decide whether Hope Now is a literary or a philosophical work, by <strong>Sartre's</strong><br />

own standards, is this: to determine whether it is a philosophical argument<br />

that uses literary techniques for the sake of clarification or, conversely, it<br />

is a presentation of a world that we are meant to experience and from<br />

which we can then extract philosophical ideas. The first thing we can say<br />

on this matter is that Sartre and L£vy are clearly attempting to build an<br />

argument. Sartre tells L£vy: "I would like our discussion here both to<br />

sketch out an ethics and to find a true guiding principle for the left." 14 We<br />

see Sartre relying on his philosophical vocabulary, using such phrases as:<br />

"try to clarify", "we have to define", and "develop your idea further".<br />

Furthermore, the method he employs to identify the "true guiding<br />

principle" is reminiscent of the eidetic analysis he had used for much of<br />

his previous philosophical work. He focuses on various instances of<br />

human solidarity in order to extract the essence of the experience of<br />

solidarity itself, so that he can then construct ethical formulations.<br />

Together with L£vy, Sartre compares and contrasts his ideas with those of<br />

Kant, Marx, Plato, and, of course, famously with Judaism.<br />

But it is impossible to ignore that Sartre offers Hope Now to the reader<br />

as a demonstration. 15 Sartre brings up the nature of his project with Ldvy<br />

directly after he puts forth his new opinion that consciousness is at every<br />

moment conditioned by the other. He describes his collaboration with<br />

Levy as "a thought created by two people" filled with "plural thoughts we<br />

have formed together, which constantly yield me something new." 16<br />

Moreover, he shows an explicit desire to have the reader understand the<br />

true nature of their collaboration:<br />

[A]s always when you are not alone with me, you stay a little in the<br />

background, so that, in spite of everything, what one sees in this exchange<br />

is an old man who has taken a very intelligent guy to work with him but<br />

who nevertheless remains the essential figure. But that isn't what happens<br />

14 Hope Now, 61.<br />

15 See Aronson, "<strong>Sartre's</strong> Last Words", 12-13.<br />

16 Hope Now, 73-74.


164 Chapter Eleven<br />

between us. And it isn't what I want. We're two men—the difference in<br />

our ages matters little—who know the history of philosophy and the<br />

history of my own thought well and who are jointly working on ethics, an<br />

ethics that will, furthermore, often be in contradiction with certain ideas<br />

that I have had. That's not the problem. But the problem is that one doesn't<br />

sense in our discussion your true importance in what we're doing. 17<br />

We see here that the form of the interviews is crucially important. Because<br />

of the form of Hope Now, the ethics Sartre hopes to sketch out is fulfilled<br />

for the reader through an analogon. Sartre and Levy could easily have<br />

presented their ideas as a co-authored essay, but they kept it in interview<br />

form, ensuring that the reader would observe them shape ideas together.<br />

But neither is Hope Now a simple transcript of a conversation. Sartre<br />

carefully edited the dialogue and gave it a very specific title. It was<br />

published in a particular form, and, as we see above, Sartre wants us to<br />

understand what is happening. As with a literary work, all of this takes<br />

place over time, which gives Hope Now a "felt" duration. Sartre and L6\y<br />

thus create the inherent tension of literature—the tension we heard Sartre<br />

describe to Beauvoir in Adieux, as helping to constitute a certain duration<br />

for the reader that is both the reader's and not the reader's at the same<br />

time 18 —while they sketch out ideas on how solidarity is possible inside<br />

the more general tension of human coexistence.<br />

At this point, I should clarify that when I claim that the text serves as<br />

an analagon, or that our experience of the interviews is literary, I am not<br />

suggesting that we consistently produce mental images when we read<br />

Hope Now, We are not actually projecting images of Levy and Sartre<br />

talking back and forth throughout the course of the book. But neither is<br />

this the case when we read novels. Sartre tells us in The Imaginary that<br />

reading is actually characterised by a "poverty of images". 19 It is only<br />

when there is a break in the reading that we look back and imagine the<br />

hero of the plot. Otherwise, we are engrossed in the act of reading. But<br />

that does not mean that imaging consciousness is not at work. As readers,<br />

we are still presented with an irreal world and that is why, according to<br />

Sartre, we can become emotionally involved in the plot. 20 I would argue<br />

that something similar happens with Hope Now. It presents a world to<br />

us—indeed we feel something of the content through the text—but it is<br />

only when we stop and think about what we have read that the images<br />

17 Ibid., 74.<br />

18 See Sartre, in Simone de Beauvoir, Adiewc, 211.<br />

19 The Imaginary, 63.


The Literary-Philosophical Experience of Hope Now 165<br />

become explicit. With that said, we must now look at the content of the<br />

text. What is it exactly that, if I am right, we are supposed to be feeling<br />

and comprehending in a literary way?<br />

The central conclusion Sartre and Levy reach is that a leftist ethics<br />

aims at a transhistorical ideal of man and is thus more fundamental than<br />

politics. This conclusion will become clearer if we explain the basic terms<br />

involved: ethics, man, and the left.<br />

Ethics is specifically defined by Sartre in the fourth section of the<br />

interviews: "By 'ethics' I mean that every consciousness, no matter whose,<br />

has a dimension that I didn't study in my philosophical works and that few<br />

people have studied, for that matter: the dimension of obligation." 21 Each<br />

consciousness, Sartre explains, is dependent on all other consciousnesses<br />

and thus has an inner constraint of obligation to every other consciousness.<br />

The ethical conscience is a product of "the self considering itself as self<br />

for the other". 22 This obligation, Sartre explains, does not come and go, for<br />

we are "constantly in the presence of the other, even when we are going to<br />

bed or falling asleep [...] my response, which isn't only my own response<br />

but is also a response that has been conditioned by others from the<br />

moment of my birth, is of an ethical nature." 23<br />

Man refers to the ideal unification of all consciousnesses that would<br />

allow every consciousness to exist together ethically. According to<br />

<strong>Sartre's</strong> definition, this entails a community in which each self can truly be<br />

for the other: "[0]ur goal is to arrive at a genuinely constituent body in<br />

which each person would be a human being and collectivities would be<br />

equally human." 24 This goal, as an ideal, is aimed at throughout history but<br />

is transhistorical. Sartre states: "It appears in history but doesn't belong to<br />

history." 25<br />

The left is a reference to the hopeful effort of the masses to realise the<br />

ideal of man. It is, in other words, the appearance of the transhistorical<br />

ideal in history in the form of social movements. The individual goals of<br />

these social movements are connected by a common radical intention,<br />

which is necessarily hopeful. As historical circumstances change, the left<br />

must adapt in order to continue operating as the hopeful vehicle by which<br />

the ideal will be realised.<br />

Obviously, the term "left" has a political connotation. It is not<br />

surprising, therefore, that Ronald Aronson, in his introduction to Hope<br />

21 Hope Now, 69.<br />

22 Ibid., 71.<br />

23 Ibid., 71.<br />

24 Ibid., 67.<br />

25 Ibid., 82.


166 Chapter Eleven<br />

Now, describes <strong>Sartre's</strong> hope as "above all a political hope". While I do<br />

not disagree with Aronson's statement, we do need to clarify what the<br />

term "political" means in this context. 27 Indeed, a more commonplace<br />

understanding of the term "political" will lead to a misunderstanding of<br />

the text's overriding message. In Hope Now, Sartre tells us that he<br />

considers democracy to be more than a form of government. He says to<br />

L£vy: "[F]or me, and I believe for you, too, democracy seems to be not<br />

only a form of government, or a way of granting power, but a life, a way<br />

of life. One lives democratically, and in my view human beings should<br />

live in that way and in no other." 28 Thus, we might say that <strong>Sartre's</strong> hope<br />

is political only insofar as it demands through politics the realisation of a<br />

pre-political existential desire for society.<br />

Following this line of thought, the realisation of ethical life does not<br />

need a traditional political vehicle. Instead, ethics has more to do with the<br />

kind of thing Levy and Sartre are attempting: thinking together. Sartre<br />

describes humanism as "the act of thinking about the relationship of man<br />

to man in terms of the principles that prevail today", 29 and later says about<br />

ethics:<br />

We non-Jews are searching for an ethics, too. The question is to find the<br />

ultimate end, the moment when ethics will be simply and truly the way in<br />

which humans live in relations to each other. The rules-and-prescriptions<br />

aspect of ethics that prevails today will probably no longer exist—as has<br />

often been said, for that matter. Ethics will have to do with the way in<br />

which men form their thoughts, their feelings [...]. 30<br />

My intention here is not to dive into a thorough discussion of the exact<br />

ethics proposed in Hope Now, but rather to point out the importance of the<br />

act of thinking in whatever that ethics might be. <strong>Sartre's</strong> attempt to think<br />

with Levy should not be seen as an interesting footnote, but should frame<br />

the way we understand the text as a whole. The Sartre-Ldvy project is an<br />

example, then, of the transhistorical ideal of man appearing in history in<br />

the sense that they are internalising the ideal through their way of beingwith-one-another.<br />

In his recent book on Sartre, Bernard-Henri Levy (no relation of Benny<br />

L6vy) argues that the real importance of the Sartre-Levy interviews is that<br />

"<strong>Sartre's</strong> Last Words", 29.<br />

To be sure, Aronson makes this clarification in his introduction as well.<br />

Hope Now, 83.<br />

Ibid., 68.<br />

Ibid., 106-107.


The Literary-Philosophical Experience of Hope Now 167<br />

they show that, at the end of his life, Sartre was beginning to think again<br />

like a young man. 31 While his emphasis on the act of thinking is a<br />

constructive move away from traditional critiques of Hope Now, I cannot<br />

follow Bernard-Henri Levy to his conclusion that "this last Sartre was a<br />

Levinassian". 32 1 cannot make this move because the very structure of such<br />

a statement is incompatible with my opinion of what is taking place. If,<br />

when studying an academic work, we agree to use a person's ideas as<br />

representative of his or her identity (for example, we might say: "Sartre is<br />

a Marxist in The Critique of Dialectical Reason"), then the very form of<br />

Hope Now prohibits us of from describing Sartre as anything; we must say<br />

that They are something, "They", here, being understood as the textual<br />

voice of the collaboration between Sartre and L£vy. Thus, if Sartre had<br />

conducted another investigation of this type with somebody else, even<br />

during the same period of his life, then the identity of the They might have<br />

been something quite different. What is important is not the identity of<br />

Sartre himself, but his effort to shape thoughts with another person and<br />

draw ethical conclusions from the process. Much like a jazz ensemble<br />

where a lead saxophonist plays notes that only sound pleasant in relation<br />

to the backing music played by musicians with different ideas, <strong>Sartre's</strong><br />

statements take on religious overtones because he is trying to think with<br />

Levy and not against him. 33 To extend this music analogy a bit further, we<br />

might say that Sartre and L£vy have decided to play in a common key.<br />

They improvise off one another, but like a jazz group they do so with the<br />

hope that the whole will be greater than the sum of its parts and that a They<br />

will become manifest before the audience. Thought of in this way, Hope<br />

Now is simultaneously a testament to, and an attack upon, the notion of<br />

authorship. In Derridean terms, we might say that the text deconstructs<br />

itself The question then becomes: should we therefore throw out <strong>Sartre's</strong><br />

distinction between literature and philosophy altogether? For my part, I<br />

find <strong>Sartre's</strong> adamant separation of philosophy and literature highly<br />

problematic, and indeed one aim of this essay has been to show that Hope<br />

31 Sartre, 498-502.<br />

32 Ibid., 495.<br />

33 1 am using jazz as an example very deliberately. Thomas Larson has suggested<br />

five guidelines for defining jazz: 1) Improvisation, 2) Rhythm, 3) Dissonance, 4)<br />

Jazz Interpretation, and 5) Interaction. With the exception of point 4, which is<br />

necessarily specific to jazz, I think we find all of these elements in one form of<br />

another in Hope Now. For those who think analogically, a close attention to the<br />

presence of these almost musical elements in Hope Now can yield some very<br />

interesting observations and comparisons, (see Larson, History and Tradition of<br />

Jazz, 3).


168 Chapter Eleven<br />

Now destabilises his distinction. Notwithstanding, <strong>Sartre's</strong> work on the<br />

imaginary, particularly his thoughts on the types of consciousness<br />

involved in reading different kinds of texts, remains quite helpful. <strong>Sartre's</strong><br />

philosophy provides a way of accounting for our immediate experiences of<br />

pre-deconstructed texts. Our experience watching a play or reading a<br />

novel is certainly not the same as our experience reading a philosophical<br />

treatise or, for that matter, skimming over the back of a cereal box. I<br />

contend that there is no inconsistency in appreciating these differences or<br />

in constructing basic categories such as "philosophy" and "literature" that<br />

correspond to our immediate experiences while, nonetheless, also holding<br />

that these very categories ultimately fail, in the final analysis, on account<br />

of their internal auto-deconstructive logic<br />

For people who are familiar with <strong>Sartre's</strong> general philosophical<br />

positions, many of his statements in Hope Now will come as a surprise.<br />

But surprise is only a bad thing if our goal is to ascertain the "true Sartre".<br />

If we start off knowing full well that such a project is doomed to fail and<br />

that only a metastable They can be found in the text, then the element of<br />

surprise becomes extremely useful. These moments of surprise break up<br />

the flow of reading and, as in the case of a novel, allow the latent images<br />

of the text to rise to the surface. Furthermore, one of the lessons of Hope<br />

Now may be that ethical collaboration is necessarily disconcerting, and so<br />

it is exactly the disconcerting parts of the text that we should examine. We<br />

should ask questions such as: what surprising vocabulary do they use and<br />

how does it stretch our normal understanding of <strong>Sartre's</strong> philosophy?<br />

What do Sartrean ideas look like in Jewish clothing and vice-versa? How<br />

far will the two interlocutors go in order to think with one another?<br />

These are literary considerations. We must recognise that there is a<br />

stylistic ambition to Hope Now. In this work of philosophy, a word does<br />

not mean one thing only. How, then, do we reconcile Hope Now's overt<br />

stylistic ambition with <strong>Sartre's</strong> emphatic assertion, only a few years prior,<br />

that he had never had a stylistic conception of philosophy? 34 We could<br />

submit that Sartre simply failed to meet his own requirements, but we<br />

could also, more interestingly, hypothesise that something in his final<br />

years (perhaps his blindness, his inability to do philosophy alone, etc.) led<br />

him to conceive of philosophical inquiry in a fundamentally different way.<br />

Sartre suggests as much at one point in the dialogue by telling Levy that he<br />

could only have considered their collaboration in his old age. 35<br />

See notes 6 and 7, above.<br />

Hope Now, 73.


The Literary-Philosophical Experience of Hope Now 169<br />

Age is, in fact, important. For not only is Sartre dialoguing with L£vy,<br />

but in a sense he is dialoguing with himself, thirty years prior, through<br />

L6vy. In his blindness and old age Sartre cannot read or recall the details<br />

of everything he wrote earlier in his career, and he remarks to L6vy: "[I]t<br />

is important that you remind me from time to time of what I said in 1945<br />

or 1950, and that you confront me with what there may be in my present<br />

ideas that contradicts or reasserts my past ideas." 36 His conversation with<br />

his past work, however, is not an attempt at consistency. Sartre makes it<br />

clear that he is not concerned about contradicting himself. In fact, Hope<br />

Now is an explicit risking of identity on <strong>Sartre's</strong> part for the sake of<br />

continuing philosophy and thinking new thoughts. Indeed, throughout the<br />

course of Hope Now, Sartre makes a number of criticisms about his past<br />

work but perhaps none more appropriate for our purposes, than when he<br />

says of Being and Nothingness: "I hadn't determined what I am trying to<br />

determine today: the dependence of each individual on all other<br />

individuals." 37<br />

Whichever conclusion one draws concerning <strong>Sartre's</strong> intentions, I hope<br />

to have made this much evident: there is, by <strong>Sartre's</strong> own standards, a<br />

literary element to Hope Now and our approach to the text should take it<br />

into account. In appreciating this literary element we need not lose sight of<br />

the philosophical argument put forth by Sartre and Ldvy. Ideally, we<br />

should be able to follow both the literary and philosophical aspects of<br />

Hope Now and let each inform the other. Of course, the way in which a<br />

reader engages with a literary-philosophical hybrid is quite individual and<br />

any attempt to draw up guidelines for reading Hope Now is well beyond<br />

the scope of this chapter. Nevertheless, before concluding, I propose to<br />

give an example of how one might approach the interviews in a way that<br />

reopens them and attends to their literary character.<br />

The final four sections of the interviews are in many ways the most<br />

controversial. In these sections, Sartre surprisingly discusses the idea of a<br />

common mother and Messiah that can unite all humanity. Neither one of<br />

these ideas—the mother or the Messiah—is supposed to be taken literally.<br />

In reference to the mother, he says that she "can just as well be a totemic<br />

bird", 38 and about the Messiah he remarks: "[I]t's not the Name that has<br />

36 Ibid., 74.<br />

37 Ibid., 72.<br />

38 Ibid., 89. To be clear, Sartre does seem to have an interest in "the mother" over<br />

and beyond pure symbolism. In my view, however, this has more to do with the<br />

actual physical dependence and connection between a mother and her child as a<br />

sort of condition of possibility for the filial / fraternal feeling and obligation that


170 Chapter Eleven<br />

any meaning for me. Bracketing off the debate over whether or not<br />

Sartre experienced a personal conversion to Judaism, in Hope Now the<br />

mother and the Messiah represent a common beginning and a common<br />

end. They are symbols used to elucidate the notion of fraternity, which<br />

Sartre defines in section nine: "We call the relationship of a man to his<br />

neighbour fraternal because they feel they are of the same origin. They<br />

have a common origin and, in the future, a common end—that's what<br />

constitutes their fraternity." 40<br />

Before using such religious terminology, Sartre and Levy had<br />

discussed how fraternity informs their understanding of politics, ethics,<br />

and their own project of creating plural thoughts. But when Sartre begins<br />

to speak in terms of the mother and the Messiah, he employs a literary<br />

technique that pushes the notion of fraternity to a level that we can all<br />

grasp. The final four sections are the literary climax, the point at which<br />

Sartre really starts to work within Levy's vocabulary. Here, we are no<br />

longer talking about "the left", or about ethics as an abstract philosophical<br />

enterprise: our subject is the fate of all humanity. Still more interesting is<br />

that this macro-approach brings about a very particular realisation of the<br />

subject at hand, for it makes manifest the notion of fraternity in the context<br />

of the flow of the book. Starting in section one at a common beginning,<br />

discussing <strong>Sartre's</strong> philosophy, which they both know well, and using<br />

traditional Sartrean terminology (for-itself, consciousness, anguish, etc.),<br />

and then ending the interviews with a discussion of Judaism—another<br />

common interest, but this time in Levy's vocabulary—Sartre and Levy are<br />

bound by a common beginning and a common end. Furthermore, the two<br />

figures begin to take on characteristics of one another throughout this<br />

process. Still, neither character loses his individuality entirely as a white<br />

space continues to separate their initials. Sartre plays in Levy's vocabulary<br />

and vice versa, and in doing so they challenge the reader to question her /<br />

his prior conception of who "Sartre" really is, but the loaded name of the<br />

great twentieth-<strong>century</strong> philosopher never for a moment disappears from<br />

the page. Instead, what emerges between the book covers, over and above<br />

the individual names of the interlocutors, is a metastable but intriguing<br />

They. While the They is divided and works within multiple vocabularies, it<br />

is unified by a single theme from start to finish: hope. As Aronson<br />

obtain in every consciousness from birth (consider <strong>Sartre's</strong> earlier statements as<br />

referenced by note 23, above).<br />

39 Ibid., 105.<br />

40 Ibid., 90.


The Literary-Philosophical Experience of Hope Now 171<br />

observes in his introduction, the interviews open and end with discussions<br />

of hope. 41<br />

Consequently, when we read Hope Now these two philosophers appear<br />

to us as persons inside a world—a world, moreover, that emerges from the<br />

tension between the very words on the page (in all their varying<br />

vocabularies), as well as between the metastable identities of the interlocutors,<br />

with whom we share a particular duration from beginning to end.<br />

As a result, we become part of the discussion as well. The They comes to<br />

include the reader. It is we who decide whether Sartre is a Jew or an<br />

atheist, a traditional Marxist or a disenchanted Maoist. Like the waiter in<br />

Being and Nothingness, we are still playing and taking the specific<br />

identities of the characters in our imaginary world a little too seriously. 42<br />

But in the ebb and flow of this play, we experience that truthful<br />

"something" that exists beyond the work itself, and which is given to us as<br />

a particular so that we can, once again, play the role of the judge.<br />

In the quarter-<strong>century</strong> since its publication, the two most common<br />

verdicts handed down on Hope Now have been either to dismiss its<br />

contents as an unsalvageable mess, or to celebrate it as a clear turn in<br />

<strong>Sartre's</strong> thought towards Judaism or mysticism. Even Aronson, who tries<br />

to find a middle ground in his introduction to the text, ultimately treats the<br />

tensions in Hope Now as obstacles that we must overcome as readers. My<br />

approach is the opposite. The confusion that Hope Now induces in us—<br />

much like the kind that an impersonator of Chevalier once did for Sartre—<br />

is ultimately what is most enjoyable about it. The most fruitful approach<br />

we can take towards <strong>Sartre's</strong> last words is not to lament their peculiarity,<br />

or to regret the friendship that produced them, but to consider them the<br />

product of yet another way of discussing philosophical ideas and<br />

disclosing ineffable, ambiguous, literary truths.<br />

Perhaps the most appropriate way to end this chapter is by once again<br />

immersing ourselves in Benny Levy's vocabulary, for our own purposes.<br />

Indeed, one way to summarise the project of Hope Now is to borrow<br />

Levy's thoughts on a different but related issue: the future of radical<br />

politics. In section seven of the interviews, L6vy says to Sartre: "To be<br />

radical, then, would be to pursue in a radical way the bringing together of<br />

scattered intentions to the point where they achieve an adequate unity." To<br />

this, Sartre answers: "Yes, insofar as it is possible." 43<br />

41 Aronson, "<strong>Sartre's</strong> Last Words", 29.<br />

42 See Sartre, Being and Nothingness, 101-102.<br />

43 Hope Now, 81.


172 Chapter Eleven<br />

Works Cited<br />

Aronson, Ronald. "<strong>Sartre's</strong> Last Words", in Jean-Paul Sartre and Benny<br />

L6\y, Hope Now: The 1980 Interviews, 3-40. Chicago: University of<br />

Chicago Press, 1996.<br />

Beauvoir, Simone de. Adieux: A Farewell to Sartre (trans. Patrick<br />

O'Brian). New York: Pantheon Books, 1984.<br />

Cohen-Solal, Annie. Sartre: A Life. New York: Pantheon Books, 1987.<br />

Cumming, Robert D. "Role-playing: <strong>Sartre's</strong> transformation of Husserl's<br />

phenomenology", in Christina Howells (ed.), The Cambridge Companion<br />

to Sartre, 39-66. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,<br />

1992.<br />

Edie, James M. "The philosophical framework of <strong>Sartre's</strong> theory of the<br />

theatre", Man and World, vol. 27, no. 4, October 1994,415-44.<br />

Larson, Thomas. History and Tradition of Jazz. Dubuque: Kendall / Hunt<br />

Publishing Company, 2002.<br />

Ldvy, Bernard-Henri. Sartre: The Philosopher of the Twentieth Century<br />

(trans. Andrew Brown). Cambridge: Polity Press, 2003.<br />

Rybalka, Michel, Oreste F. Pucciani and Susan Gruenheck. "An interview<br />

with Jean-Paul Sartre" (trans. Susan Gruenheck), in Paul Arthur<br />

Schilpp (ed.), The Philosophy of Jean-Paul Sartre, 1-51. La Salle:<br />

Open Court, The Library of Living Philosophers, 1981.<br />

Sartre, Jean-Paul. Being and Nothingness (trans. Hazel E. Barnes). New<br />

York: Washington Square Press, 1984.<br />

—. The Imaginary (trans. Jonathan Webber). New York: Routledge, 2004.<br />

—. (with Benny Levy). Hope Now: The 1980 Interviews (trans. Adrian<br />

Van den Hoven). Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1996.<br />

Webber, Jonathan. "Notes on the Translation", in Jean-Paul Sartre, The<br />

Imaginary. New York: Routledge, 2004.


CHAPTER TWELVE<br />

CONTEMPORARY PERSPECTIVES:<br />

SARTRE, CLOONEY, MCCARTHY, MURAKAMI<br />

BENEDICT O'DONOHOE<br />

One of the most remarkable features of <strong>Sartre's</strong> work, in all genres, is<br />

its uncanny knack of updating itself as time passes. This might be because<br />

history tends to repeat itself, so that there are few really new situations<br />

under the sun, and—since <strong>Sartre's</strong> project as a writer was unapologetically<br />

comprehensive and totalising—therefore few situations to which Sartre<br />

had not, at some time or other and in one guise or other, turned his incisive<br />

attention. This no doubt explains why scholars engaged with his work tend<br />

to sustain their interest over many years, frequently whole lifetimes,<br />

without diverging much or flagging in their enthusiasm. This Sartrean<br />

phenomenon of intuitive prescience coupled with universalist ambition is<br />

particularly well brought out by the intellectual historian and philosopher,<br />

Tom Flynn, in his centennial essay on Sartre and Foucault, and by the<br />

philosopher and political scientist, Bill McBride, in his chapter on Sartre at<br />

the "twilight of liberal democracy" in the same volume. 1 Sartre is a writer<br />

for our times, and this is no less true in his theatre and fiction than in his<br />

philosophy and political essays, as I propose to show. Thus, the first part<br />

of this chapter is devoted to an unfinished play of <strong>Sartre's</strong>, whose belated<br />

publication happily coincided with a significant American cinema release<br />

in 2005, while the <strong>second</strong> part examines the contemporary legacy of<br />

<strong>Sartre's</strong> most famous novel, La Nausee {Nausea, 1938), for Japan's most<br />

fashionable novelist.<br />

1 See Thomas R. Flynn and William L. McBride in Leak and Van den Hoven (eds),<br />

Sartre Today.


174 Chapter Twelve<br />

La Part dufeu and Good Night, and Good Luck 2<br />

The Pleiade edition of <strong>Sartre's</strong> Theatre complet, published in his<br />

centenary year 2005, includes substantial fragments of a hitherto unknown<br />

and incomplete play, which the editors have titled La Part du feu (The<br />

Devil's Portion)? In this project, Sartre set out to dramatise the true story<br />

of the crisis of conscience suffered by his protagonist, Abraham Feller, a<br />

UN official caught up in the destructive machinations of the communist<br />

witch-hunter, Senator Joseph McCarthy. Set in 1952—the year in which<br />

McCarthy's influence was at its height and Abraham Feller eventually<br />

took his own life—<strong>Sartre's</strong> play proposed to explore the personal anguish<br />

of this private individual enmeshed in a highly public debacle on the<br />

American political scene.<br />

That exploration was to take the form of Feller recounting his<br />

experiences and concomitant anxieties to a psychotherapist, their dialogue<br />

being interspersed with narrative-developing flashbacks. These interludes<br />

refer in particular to Feller's relationship with his son, who has fallen<br />

under the spell of McCarthy, who is also Feller's brother-in-law and,<br />

therefore, the boy's sinister "Uncle Joe". It becomes clear that Feller's<br />

anguish is at least as much affective and psychological as it is ethical or<br />

political. Seemingly unable to reconcile himself either with his teenage<br />

son or with the moral compromises he had latterly made in his diplomatic<br />

career, Feller would finally commit suicide (as he apparently did, in fact,<br />

along with other victims of McCarthyite persecution). Of the several<br />

striking things about La Part dufeu, I want to consider two in particular:<br />

first, its topicality in the recent period of renaissance for political cinema<br />

in the US; next, its continuity with Sartrean theatrical themes and<br />

techniques.<br />

Drafted and abandoned in 1954, La Part du feu is set in the fervid<br />

atmosphere created by the communist witch-hunt of Senator McCarthy's<br />

chairmanship of the House UnAmerican Activities Committee (HUAC).<br />

This dark and embarrassing episode in American post-war domestic<br />

politics was most famously satirised by Arthur Miller in his allegory of<br />

Puritanical New England, The Crucible, from January 1953. And this<br />

tragic satire on the literal witch-hunting purgations of supposed evil spirits<br />

was, as it happens, adapted by Sartre in 1955 for the French movie screen<br />

as Les Sorcieres de Salem (The Witches ofSalem)—hitherto, the only hard<br />

2 An earlier draft of this section was given as an invited paper at the 15 th Biennial<br />

Conference of the North American Sartre Society at Fordham University,<br />

Manhattan, New York City, 27-29 October 2006.<br />

3 In Sartre, Theatre complet, 1183-1214.


Contemporary Perspectives 175<br />

evidence we had of <strong>Sartre's</strong> artistic commitment to an exposure of this<br />

deplorable political scandal. According to Michel Contat's "Notice" in the<br />

Pleiade volume, however, it was Miller's earlier drama, Death of a<br />

Salesman (1949), that made the greater impact upon Sartre. 4 In Miller's<br />

classic piece, the eponymous salesman, Willy Loman, having been made<br />

redundant late in life, kills himself in order both to salvage some selfrespect<br />

and to provide some future security (by way of life insurance) for<br />

his wife and sons. At first glance, then, there is solid evidence for a<br />

powerful Milleresque influence upon Sartre, even if the context, the<br />

dynamics and the motivation of the fictional Loman's suicide are rather<br />

different from those of the historical character Abraham Feller, <strong>Sartre's</strong><br />

doomed hero in La Part dufeu.<br />

Reflecting upon these fragments of dialogue and sketches for possible<br />

scenes, it seemed to me that George Clooney's 2005 picture, Good Night,<br />

and Good Luck, fortuitously provides some interesting points of comparison<br />

with <strong>Sartre's</strong> rediscovered and unfinished play. Most obviously, of<br />

course, both are set amidst the hysterical anti-communism of the early-<br />

1950s, and both focus upon (initially reticent) antagonists of McCarthy,<br />

each of whose encounters with him would prove literally life-changing.<br />

Clooney's hero, the eminent broadcast journalist Edward R. Murrow, was<br />

to be canonised as the patron saint of American patriotism when he<br />

exposed McCarthy's mendacity in his current affairs programme, See It<br />

Now, in March 1954, thereby precipitating the Junior Senator's downfall.<br />

By contrast, <strong>Sartre's</strong> hero, the equally real-life Abraham Feller—legal<br />

counsel and chief policy adviser to the Secretary General of the United<br />

Nations, Trygve Lie, and McCarthy's brother-in-law—was driven to<br />

suicide.<br />

Clooney's excellent film is surely one of the best in its genre since<br />

Oliver Stone's JFK (1992), or even Alan J. Pakula's All the President's<br />

Men (1976). I will not dwell here on the numerous merits of Good Night,<br />

and Good Luck, but I want to consider two key aspects of its success by<br />

way of a contrastive prelude to my consideration of <strong>Sartre's</strong> failure with<br />

La Part dufeu. The first such element is the medium itself. By shooting a<br />

movie, Clooney can take full advantage of all the facilities he needs in<br />

order to recreate the location and the ambience of a national TV studio at<br />

the beginning of the medium's heyday. This recreation is ingeniously<br />

enhanced by Clooney's decision to shoot the whole thing in black and<br />

white. This technique both provides a sympathetic context for the clips of<br />

authentic archive footage, and subtly introduces a distancing effect that<br />

4 See ibid., 1573-79.


176 Chapter Twelve<br />

subliminally reminds us that we are witnessing historical events—a<br />

message reinforced by the clever framing of the main action within the<br />

bookends, so to speak, of Murrow's famous retirement address to the<br />

American Broadcasting Association, couched naturally in his own words.<br />

The <strong>second</strong> of these key aspects is the intensity of Clooney's thematic<br />

focus. Setting his action almost entirely in the studio or its offices—there<br />

are no exterior shots at all—Clooney zooms in on the relationship between<br />

Fred Friendly and Ed Murrow, on the one hand, and the growing<br />

animosity between Murrow and McCarthy, on the other. This nexus<br />

achieves a symmetry and balance that create a compelling tension up to<br />

the cathartic moment when Murrow becomes McCarthy's nemesis—a<br />

moment of triumph marred only by the psychological disintegration of<br />

Murrow's colleague and friend, Don Hollenbeck, who takes his own life<br />

around the time of McCarthy's impeachment (this suicide providing<br />

another tangential parallel with <strong>Sartre's</strong> play). For good measure, the<br />

casting, the direction and the photography of Clooney's picture are all<br />

brilliant, while the paranoid struggle against universal communist<br />

infiltration naturally finds contemporary resonances with the equally<br />

wrong-headed "global war on terror". But if Clooney found such success<br />

with this subject in 2005, half-a-<strong>century</strong> after the events, why did Sartre<br />

strive and fail to accomplish his comparable project just two years after the<br />

central historical action in question, namely the suicide of Abraham<br />

Feller?<br />

First, let us consider the medium. Sartre, like Clooney, might have<br />

been more comfortable in the cinema than the theatre, a medium of which<br />

he had some experience thanks to his post-war contract with Pathe. In<br />

order to let Feller tell his story and explore his angst, Sartre sets the action<br />

in a psychiatrist's consulting room—an inherently static or (worse)<br />

sedentary environment—from which the actor would move to other parts<br />

of the set in order to re-enact scenes he is narrating on the couch. This<br />

flashback technique is essentially cinematic and was used by Sartre to<br />

good effect in the film Les Jeux sontfaits (The Chips Are Down, 1947), as<br />

it would be again in his last original play, Les Sequestres d'Altona (The<br />

Condemned ofAltona, I960). 5 Yet, even in the few fragments we have of<br />

La Part du feu, this device is clearly not working: if anything, the effect<br />

would be comic as the analysand climbs off the couch and wanders away<br />

from the consulting space to engage in conversations with his son or his<br />

colleagues at the UN. Moreover, this potentially useful narrative conceit<br />

See my edition of his scenario, Les Jeux sont faits, and my chapter on Les<br />

Sequestres d'Altona in <strong>Sartre's</strong> Theatre: Acts for Life.


Contemporary Perspectives 177<br />

has the consequence of dispersing widely a focus that needs to home in<br />

intensely on the moral agony of the central figure, for that surely is the<br />

very stuff of the drama, the inner mental conflict that will lead Abraham<br />

Feller to self-destruction.<br />

For the same reason, the topicality of <strong>Sartre's</strong> enterprise is problematic.<br />

Whereas Clooney is assisted by historical perspective in creating a period<br />

piece—at one level, even a costume drama—most of whose protagonists<br />

have themselves passed into history, Sartre is conversely impeded by the<br />

temporal immediacy of his subject and subjects. For example, he planned<br />

dialogues featuring Trygve Lie and Joe McCarthy, scenes unlikely to carry<br />

conviction if only because both men were still alive and neither was prone<br />

to express himself in French. Moreover, Feller himself had died less than<br />

two years prior, and in bizarre, not to say suspicious, circumstances. An<br />

anonymous article in Time magazine—"Death of an Idealist"—described<br />

how his wife had tried to restrain him physically from leaping out of a<br />

twelve-storey window, but to no avail. Feller's depression was, it seems,<br />

too deep and overwhelming and, according to the Time report, chiefly<br />

attributable to the recent intense scrutiny of UN personnel by a Federal<br />

Grand Jury and the McCarran sub-committee:<br />

Feller, under no suspicion himself, was the UN's legal adviser on the<br />

subject. The hearings uncovered seventeen among the 200 Americans on<br />

the UN staff who refused to say whether or not they have engaged in<br />

subversive activities. [Former UN Secretary General Trygve] Lie angrily<br />

charged that Abe Feller's suicide had been brought on by the extra strain of<br />

defending Americans at [the] UN against "indiscriminate smears and<br />

exaggerated charges". 6<br />

Inspired by Marcel P6ju's article on the subject in Les Temps<br />

modernes, 1 Sartre was evidently approaching a veritable minefield of<br />

contention and controversy, a subject rich in themes that recur elsewhere<br />

in his plays and scenarios, namely: the role of the intellectual and his<br />

relations with institutions, the state, politics and history; the social and<br />

political status of the Jew; the individual's place in, and fidelity or<br />

treachery towards, the group; the functions and validity of professional<br />

psychoanalysis; family relationships, especially those between father and<br />

son; tribal and class struggles for political power and dominion; the<br />

Time, 24 November 1952. Lie had resigned as Secretary General on 10<br />

November 1952. Feller killed himself—if that is indeed what happened—three<br />

days later, on 13 November.<br />

7 See Pdju, Les Temps modernes.


178<br />

Chapter Twelve<br />

existential torment of the individual's tussle with his own moral<br />

conscience; the merits or otherwise of suicide as an authentic action—and<br />

so on. With such a cornucopia of dramatic material before him, why then<br />

did Sartre abandon La Part dufeul<br />

Considering this question, Michel Contat first dismisses possible<br />

"external" causes—such as the difficulties of staging the play, the<br />

potential problems of litigation, or the risk of displeasing the audience of<br />

the Theatre Antoine with a political theme—and proffers instead the<br />

following three "internal obstacles". 8 First, the antipathy of the hero:<br />

"Sartre chooses to write his play against compassion. [... Feller's] death<br />

does not touch us [...]: his existence was worthless." 9 Second, <strong>Sartre's</strong><br />

inability to find a suitable satirical tone: "One might even think that the<br />

play was abandoned for want of finding that new satirical style that Sartre<br />

was looking for." 10 Third, the unforeseen alteration of current circumstances:<br />

[Sartre] had here all the elements of a contemporary political drama, of a<br />

committed and even militant play. But the political world situation<br />

changed. In November 1954, the threat of a nuclear conflict receded; Stalin<br />

died [...]. All at once, the play became less urgent. 11<br />

While not dissenting from any of this expert opinion, I want to consider a<br />

fourth and possibly decisive "internal obstacle" to <strong>Sartre's</strong> completion of<br />

La Part dufeu, namely what I shall call "thematic overload".<br />

As Contat rightly observes, P6ju's article presented Sartre with "all the<br />

ingredients of an existential and political drama", to which the playwright<br />

then proposed to add "his own psychological interpretation [and] the<br />

symbolic representative of the witch-hunt", McCarthy himself. 12 My<br />

present hypothesis is simply that all of this was just too rich a mix. To<br />

8 See Sartre, Theatre complet, 1577.<br />

9 "Sartre choisit d'dcrire sa pi&ce contre la compassion. [...] sa mort ne nous<br />

touche pas [...]: son existence &ait sans valeur" (ibid., 1578). All translations from<br />

French are my own.<br />

10 "On peut mSme penser que la pi&ce a €t€ abandonee faute d'avoir trouvd ce<br />

style satirique nouveau que Sartre cherchait" (ibid.).<br />

11 "[Sartre] a \k tous les 61dments d'un drame politique contemporain, d'une pifcce<br />

engagde, et m§me militante. Mais la situation mondiale politique a change. En<br />

novembre 1954, la menace d'un conflit nucteaire s'&oigne; Staline est mort [...].<br />

Du coup, la pi&ce devient moins urgente" (ibid.).<br />

12 "[...] tous les ingredients d'un drame existentiel et politique [...] sa propre<br />

interpretation psychologique [et] le repr£sentant symbolique de la chasse aux<br />

sorcifcres [...]" (ibid.).


Contemporary Perspectives 179<br />

extend Contat's culinary metaphor, I suggest that Sartre must have realised<br />

that he was over-egging the pudding, and that it would be much too heavy<br />

in its texture and complex in its flavours ever to be consumed, even if he<br />

managed to get it baked! To support this contention, I propose to analyse<br />

only the first 'Tableau" of the published text, amounting to just ten pages<br />

in the Pleiade volume, with a view to identifying each new topos as it<br />

appears.<br />

As he did in Les Mains sales (Dirty Hands, 1948), Sartre establishes<br />

the historical time and place by means of a radio announcement: "Two<br />

American aircraft shot down by Mig fighters." 13 These are the first words<br />

spoken, setting the scene for the initial repartee between Feller and the<br />

psychiatrist:<br />

FELLER—I want to think out loud in front of you. [...] Should I lie down<br />

here?<br />

PSYCHIATRIST—If you like.<br />

FELLER—Why?<br />

PSYCHIATRIST—It's the custom.<br />

FELLER—Perfect. Let's not ignore custom. That's what makes the world<br />

go round, wouldn't you say? (He lies down.) 14<br />

Within moments, therefore, we already have the Cold War and<br />

psychoanalysis introduced as themes, the latter couched in a bantering and<br />

facetious tone such as Sartre would perfect in his next play, Nekrassov<br />

(1955), but which tends to elude him here, as Contat rightly points out.<br />

Feller's demand: "I want to know what my life is worth", 15 raises the<br />

central existential issue of the play: there is an ethical question at the heart<br />

of this psychological crisis. And his ensuing abrupt self-introduction<br />

ushers in a whole new cast of themes: family, money, class and, in<br />

particular, political opinion and allegiance: "[I am] against the communists.<br />

But I think the communists have the right to speak." 16<br />

Feller's next significant speech includes the first instances of the<br />

flashback technique. However, the intended interruption is so brief that it<br />

13 "Deux avions amdricains abattus par des Migs" (ibid., 1183).<br />

14 "FELLER—Je veux penser h haute voix devant vous. [...] II faut que je me<br />

couche m? / LE PSYCHIATRE—Si vous voulez. / FELLER—Pourquoi? / LE<br />

PSYCHIATRE—C'est l'habitude. / FELLER—Parfait. Ne renongons pas aux<br />

habitudes. C'est elles qui font marcher le monde, n'est-ce pas? (7/ se couche.) 99<br />

(ibid., 1183-84).<br />

15 "Je veux savoir ce que vaut ma vie" (ibid., 1184).<br />

16 "[Je suis] contre les communistes. Mais je pense que les communistes ont le<br />

droit de parler" (ibid., 1184).


180<br />

Chapter Twelve<br />

is hard to imagine the actor's mobilisation (from couch to office, and back<br />

to couch) as anything other than farcical. This is an impression that sits<br />

uneasily alongside Feller's statement that—despite his material comfort<br />

and professional commitment and satisfaction—he is "afraid", and wants<br />

the doctor to help him find out why. Nor does it chime with the gravity of<br />

the themes next introduced, themes familiar from one earlier and one later<br />

play:<br />

I am being put on trial, in the shadows. One day I shall be judged. [...] I<br />

want to defend myself, to recover my life from their hands. [...] Who can<br />

judge my life if God doesn't exist? Others? 17<br />

Trial, persecution, self-defence, judgment at the hands of others: these are<br />

very recognisable Sartrean preoccupations, not only from Huis clos {In<br />

Camera, or No Exit, 1944) but also from Les Sequestres d'Altona, and it is<br />

true to say that they suffuse the whole of <strong>Sartre's</strong> drama.<br />

Then, almost in the same breath, Feller envisages the prospect of<br />

nuclear annihilation:<br />

War means the death of mankind. You know it does. The hydrogen bomb<br />

will swallow up the earth's atmosphere. Will turn it in to a moon. Doesn't<br />

it bother you to think of dying without mankind surviving? It terrifies me.<br />

Mind you, there'd be an advantage: nobody would judge me. But it's like<br />

dying twice. [...] Man is wicked. Mad and wicked. 18<br />

Here there are resonant, almost verbatim pre-echoes of <strong>Sartre's</strong> last two<br />

plays, Les Sequestres d'Altona and Les Troyennes {The Trojan Women,<br />

1965): visions of Armageddon, the extinction of the species, the positive<br />

need for judgment by one's peers, alongside the dread of it; preverberations<br />

of Frantz von Gerlach's apologias and condemnations, and of<br />

the dire prognostications of Euripides's Greek chorus.<br />

And so the litany of familiar themes continues. In his very next<br />

speech—and we are on only the third page of dialogue—Feller discloses<br />

his affinity with Goetz von Berlichingen, hero of Le Diable et le bon Dieu<br />

"[0]n me fait mon proems, dans 1'ombre. Un jour je serai jug£. [...] Je veux me<br />

ddfendre, leur arracher ma vie des mains. [...] Qui peut juger ma vie si Dieu<br />

n'existe pas? Les autres?" (ibid., 1185).<br />

18 "La guerre, e'est la mort de l'homme. Vous le savez. La bombe k l'hydrogfcne<br />

bouffera T atmosphere de la terre. En fera une lune. £a ne vous dit rien de mourir<br />

sans que les hommes survivent? Moi $a me fait horreur. II y aurait int£r§t pourtant:<br />

personne ne me jugerait. Mais e'est deux fois mourir. [...] L'homme est mdchant.<br />

Fou et m£chant" (ibid.).


Contemporary Perspectives 181<br />

(The Devil and the Good Lord, 1951), and indeed with Sartre himself,<br />

when he evinces this ambition: "I'd like to be nobody special". 19<br />

"N'importe qui", no-one in particular, that elusive identity of the authentic<br />

existentialist hero, modest yet responsible, to which Sartre aspires in the<br />

last lines of his autobiography, Les Mots (Words, 1964):<br />

If I put impossible Salvation back in the props cupboard, what remains? A<br />

whole man, made up of all men and who is worth any one of them and<br />

whom any one of them is worth. 20<br />

Also like Goetz and Sartre, Feller apparently has one mistress while<br />

wanting another, a predicament familiar to Sartrean protagonists throughout<br />

his fiction and theatre, as well as to the writer himself. The next snatch<br />

of dialogue, in which Feller's maid tells him they have had a visit from the<br />

police, both prefigures the Keystone Cops scenes of <strong>Sartre's</strong> next play,<br />

Nekrassov (1956)—which are such a distinctive element in the comic<br />

impact of that political farce—and establishes the fact that Feller himself<br />

is possibly under suspicion in the all-embracing climate of fear that his<br />

obsessive brother-in-law, Joe McCarthy, has created.<br />

Another dimension of that climate is introduced by the visit of Mr<br />

Goldschmitt, the high school teacher of Feller's fifteen-year-old son.<br />

Goldschmitt tells us that the boy has fallen under the right-wing spell of<br />

Uncle Joe, and has demonstrated in the streets demanding the death<br />

sentence for the supposed traitors, Julius and Ethel Rosenberg. Here,<br />

Sartre is opening up not one but two new thematic portals. First, implicit<br />

in Goldschmitt's concern for the boy's political aberrations is a question<br />

about the child's loyalty to his own Jewishness. The predominantly<br />

Catholic McCarthyite machine was scarcely less anti-Semitic than it was<br />

anti-communist. Yet, here is Goldschmitt's pupil and Feller's son baying<br />

for the blood of the Jewish Bolcheviks, Julius and Ethel Rosenberg!<br />

Clearly, as the tutor tells Feller, he "must talk to the boy", father to son:<br />

GOLDSCHMITT—I want you to speak to him.<br />

FELLER, sadly.—Speak to him? Could you speak to him?<br />

GOLDSCHMITT—Me, no. But he loves you.<br />

FELLER—You think he loves me?<br />

GOLDSCHMITT—In his way, yes.<br />

FELLER—OK. I'll speak to him. 21<br />

"Je voudrais §tre n'importe qui" (ibid.).<br />

20 "Si je range 1'impossible Salut au magasin des accessoires, que reste-t-il? Tout<br />

un homme, fait de tous les hommes et qui les vaut tous et que vaut n'importe qui"<br />

(Sartre, Les Mots, 213).


182 Chapter Twelve<br />

This topos of the father / son relationship is central in <strong>Sartre's</strong> work and<br />

life, and it is naturally a rich vein of psychological investigation. Consider<br />

not only Les Mots, of course, but think also of Hugo's obsession with, and<br />

continuous revolt against, his father in Les Mains sales; or Bariona's<br />

protest against paternity (in Bariona, 1940), or Mathieu's phobia of fatherhood<br />

in L'Age de raison {The Age of Reason, 1945); or, again, Oreste's<br />

determination to avenge his father by assassinating his stepfather in Les<br />

Mouches (The Flies, 1943). Above all, compare the pivotal part played by<br />

the father / son dynamics in Les Sequestres d'Altona, where it is gradually<br />

revealed to be not only the motor of Frantz's psychosis, but also the<br />

motivation of old von Gerlach's manipulation of the family towards a<br />

situation in which, eventually, he will both be reunited with his favourite<br />

son and preserve the macabre status quo beyond his own death. Clearly,<br />

these extant fragments of La Part dufeu adumbrate the subtle exploration<br />

of the filial / paternal theme that characterises the later play.<br />

The case of Feller and son is especially complicated. The anonymous<br />

boy is McCarthy's nephew, so his mother was, like her brother, an Irish<br />

Catholic. This being so, the boy is not strictly speaking Jewish since, in<br />

orthodox Judaic tradition, Jewishness (however construed) is transmitted<br />

by the maternal line. 22 This might explain why he is apparently unashamed<br />

to denounce the Rosenbergs as "communists. And Jews". 23 By way of<br />

aggravation, Sartre has Feller tell the psychiatrist that his late wife<br />

(McCarthy's sister) was frigid, uncommunicative, and possibly "in love<br />

with her brother". 24 So we have echoes again here of Les Mains sales and<br />

Hugo's dispassionate, pseudo-sibling marriage to Jessica, and pre-echoes<br />

of the phantasm of incest acted out by Frantz and Leni in Altona, and<br />

mused upon by Sartre in Les Mots.<br />

As if this pot-pourri of pungent themes and this cauldron of highlycharged<br />

emotions were not yet a sufficiently explosive concoction, Sartre<br />

supplements it with Feller's sense of alienation from his colleagues. A<br />

well-intentioned leading figure who nevertheless becomes a focus of<br />

21 "GOLDSCHMITT—Je veux que tu lui paries. / FELLER, tristement—Lui<br />

parler? Tu pourrais lui parler, toi? / GOLDSCHMITT—Moi, non. Mais il t'aime. /<br />

FELLER—Tu crois qu'il m'aime? / GOLDSCHMITT—A sa manifcre, oui. /<br />

FELLER—ficoute. Je vais lui parler" (Theatre complet, 1187).<br />

22 However, "according to the Reform movement, a person whose father is a Jew is<br />

also a Jew" (http://www.jewfaq.org/cgi-bin/search.cgi?Keywords=mother). For an<br />

opinion as to whether Jewishness should be construed as a religious affiliation or a<br />

racial one, or both or neither, see http://www.jewfaq.org/judaism.htm.<br />

23 "[D]es communistes. Et des juifs" (Theatre complet, 1188).<br />

24 "[A]moureuse de son frfcre" (ibid., 1190).


Contemporary Perspectives 183<br />

mistrust—compare Bariona, Oreste, Garcin, Pierre, Canoris or Hoederer—<br />

Feller is suddenly feared and shunned by his subordinates. He retains the<br />

trust and respect of his boss, Trygve Lie, but he in turn makes too many<br />

enemies and resigns just three days before Feller's suicide. The two events<br />

were surely affectively, if not quite causally, connected, in much the same<br />

way as Don Hollenbeck's suicide in Good Night, and Good Luck is<br />

precipitated, in part, by Murrow's refusal to take up the cudgels against<br />

Hollenbeck's persecutors in the press. This is a sub-plot that is rightly<br />

relegated to the background by Clooney, whereas a whole plethora of subplots<br />

would, it seems, have been crowding into the foreground of <strong>Sartre's</strong><br />

play, La Part dufeu.<br />

In short, I suggest that the incompleteness of <strong>Sartre's</strong> hitherto unknown<br />

theatrical project is a case of "death by thematic overload". There is<br />

further evidence of this syndrome, but we have seen, from an overview of<br />

the first "Tableau" alone, that the sheer burden of the subject matter causes<br />

the project to collapse under its own weight. From the outset, Sartre<br />

introduced a host of potentially central themes in rapid succession, surely<br />

too many to deal with in the course of Feller's psychoanalysis, the<br />

trajectory of which would inevitably lead to his despairing suicide as the<br />

dramatic climax and resolution. In a sense, the play takes its own life<br />

before Feller gets a chance to take his, and Sartre was no doubt wise to redirect<br />

his critical energies on this subject into his adaptation of Miller's<br />

play for the big screen.<br />

Sartrean Sources? Haruki Murakami's<br />

"Nausea 1979" 2S<br />

Browsing through Tobias Hill's review of Haruki Murakami's<br />

collection of short stories, Blind Willow, Sleeping Woman, published in the<br />

UK in 2006,1 was struck by one title in particular: "Nausea 1979". Why<br />

not just "Nausea", I wondered, why the qualifying date? No doubt the<br />

author was conscious of a precedent, a certain Nausea circa 1939 (actually<br />

1938, to be precise). When I read that the story concerned the diary of a<br />

young man with a passion for jazz, but afflicted by recurrent and<br />

unexplained bouts of nausea, my curiosity was piqued. Could it be that<br />

Japan's most fashionable contemporary writer—hailed by The Times, for<br />

example, as a "post-modern Kafka, a literary David Lynch", 26 and author,<br />

An earlier draft of this section was given as a paper at the 13 Conference of the<br />

UK Sartre Society at the Institut Fran^ais, London, 21 October 2006.<br />

26 See blurb on jacket front of Murakami, Blind Willow, Sleeping Woman.


184 Chapter Twelve<br />

indeed, of Kafka on the Shore, inter alia—was paying homage to, or at<br />

least acknowledging a debt to, Jean-Paul Sartre? Having once established,<br />

that the Japanese word for "nausea"—"6to"—was indeed the same in<br />

Murakami's title as it is in <strong>Sartre's</strong> title when translated into Japanese, 27 1<br />

felt sure that this was a question worth considering.<br />

At first sight, there are startling differences: <strong>Sartre's</strong> Nausea is a fulllength<br />

novel, while Murakami's is a ten-page novella. <strong>Sartre's</strong> protagonist,<br />

Antoine Roquentin, is also the narrator of the book, which supposedly<br />

consists of entries from his personal diary; Murakami's narrator is himself,<br />

whilst his protagonist is his interlocutor. Chiefly perhaps, Roquentin's<br />

nausea reflects a psychological and emotional response to the external<br />

world, an essentially metaphysical condition which manifests itself as a<br />

physical revulsion but which stops short of vomiting. By contrast,<br />

Murakami's anonymous hero is afflicted by repeated bouts of actual<br />

vomiting over a forty-day period, each one accompanied by anonymous<br />

phone calls in which the caller speaks the hero's name (which we readers,<br />

perversely, never learn). Finally, Roquentin has, at best, a desultory and<br />

perfunctory interest in the opposite sex, whereas Murakami's protagonist<br />

is virtually obsessed with seducing the wives and girlfriends of his male<br />

acquaintances.<br />

Taken together, these distinctions might lead one to suspect that<br />

Murakami's title is a mere coincidence, and the date suffix, "1979", of no<br />

real significance. However, given the extent of <strong>Sartre's</strong> fame, and even<br />

popularity, in Japan, this seems improbable and indeed, on closer scrutiny,<br />

parallels begin to emerge. 28 Antoine Roquentin is a writer, an academic<br />

historian who develops, over time, the aspiration to write a novel.<br />

Murakami's anonymous character is an artist and illustrator, but also a<br />

meticulous diarist, and therefore also a writer. Moreover, we are told that<br />

he became friends with the author, Murakami himself, when he illustrated<br />

one of his short stories—which is, in one sense, what he is about to do<br />

again. Equally, Roquentin, insofar as he was <strong>Sartre's</strong> alter ego, as we shall<br />

see, "illustrated" <strong>Sartre's</strong> story of his own experience of contingency while<br />

a philosophy teacher at the Lycee in Le Havre. Or again, while Roquentin<br />

was haunted by a certain jazz song, Some of these Days, which becomes<br />

both the theme tune and the panacea of his melancholia, Murakami's<br />

Thanks are due to my colleague Simone Muller for this reassurance.<br />

28 In 1966, when he and Beauvoir visited Japan for a month, "Sartre had more<br />

readers in Japan than in any other country" (Rowley, 293; see also Asabuki). Forty<br />

years on, there is a thriving Sartre Society in Japan, the acts of whose international<br />

colloquium for <strong>Sartre's</strong> centenary (2005)—Sartre, penseur pour le XXIe siecle?<br />

[Sartre, a Thinker for the 21 st Century?]—were published in Tokyo in 2007.


Contemporary Perspectives 185<br />

character is a collector of "jazz from the 50s and early 60s", a mutual<br />

interest shared with his creator and interlocutor. Moreover, their respective<br />

experiences of "nausea", while different, mirror each other: Roquentin's is<br />

a sensation of sickness without vomiting, whereas his Japanese<br />

counterpart's involves real vomiting without the sensation of sickness.<br />

Furthermore, Murakami's diarist reveals that his nausea lasts exactly forty<br />

days—from 4 June to 14 July 1979—a period embracing almost at its midpoint<br />

<strong>Sartre's</strong> birthday (21 June), as it happens, and concluding on Bastille<br />

Day. Roquentin's diary, although less punctilious, covers a comparable<br />

period from "early January 1932" 30 to approximately 18 February<br />

(reckoned from the first dated page of "Monday 25 January 1932", 31 plus<br />

twenty-four days, by my calculation). This period embraces the start of<br />

Lent, indicated by the record of "Mardi gras", 32 a penitential phase in the<br />

Christian calendar of forty days' fast and abstinence, commemorating<br />

Jesus's exile in the desert—an association of which Murakami can hardly<br />

have been unaware when he chose his hero's precise quarantine.<br />

It remains to be seen, however, whether these structural resemblances<br />

are more than merely superficial and coincidental. What significance, if<br />

any, should we attach to the hypothetical time lapse in La Nausee, for<br />

example? Is there, in fact, any more to this transcultural intertextuality<br />

than meets the eye? I suspect there is, chiefly because Murakami appears<br />

to have embedded, within a very small space, a number of other more<br />

subtle and cryptic clues. For instance, like Roquentin—"Maybe, after all,<br />

it was a brief bout of madness" 33 —Murakami's sick man fears for his<br />

sanity: "When you start having thoughts like this, it's the first sign of<br />

schizophrenia, you know". 34 Also, he shares with <strong>Sartre's</strong> Antoine a<br />

profoundly solitary life:<br />

The calls came only when I was alone. Same with the vomiting. So then I<br />

began to wonder: how come I'm alone so much? In fact, I probably<br />

average a little over twenty-three hours a day alone. 35<br />

Another notable "Antoine" spent abundant time in solitude, namely Saint<br />

Anthony, whose eremitical isolation and diabolical trials had been<br />

29<br />

Murakami, "Nausea 1979", in Blind Willow, Sleeping Woman, 143-53 (144).<br />

30<br />

"[...] vers le commencement de Janvier 1932" (Sartre, La Nausee, 3).<br />

31<br />

Ibid., 8.<br />

32<br />

Ibid., 72.<br />

33<br />

"Peut-etre bien, apr£s tout, que c'dtait une petite crise de folie" (ibid., 6).<br />

34<br />

Murakami, "Nausea 1979", 149.


186 Chapter Twelve<br />

imaginatively recreated by Gustave Flaubert in his La Tentation de Saint<br />

Antoine (1874). The archetypal nineteenth-<strong>century</strong> novelist was a life-long<br />

preoccupation for Sartre—culminating in his monumental three-volume<br />

critique of Flaubert, UIdiot de lafamille (1971-72)—a fact surely not lost<br />

on Murakami, who amuses himself elsewhere in this collection with an<br />

oblique and facetious allusion to Flaubert's masterpiece, Madame Bovary<br />

(1857):<br />

She gets married a virgin. And once she's somebody's wife she has an<br />

affair. Sounds like some classic French novel. Minus any fancy-dress ball<br />

or maids running around. 36<br />

However that may be, there is less tenuous and tangential evidence of<br />

an affinity between Sartre and Murakami, whether conscious or unwitting,<br />

to be found in a single sentence just a few lines from the end of the latter's<br />

disturbing little tale. The author is warning his nameless protagonist to<br />

beware that his bizarre and unexplained malaise might just as inexplicably<br />

return: "Next time it might not end in forty days. Things that start for no<br />

reason end for no reason. And the opposite can be true." 37 That almost<br />

poetically balanced phrase—"Things that start for no reason end for no<br />

reason"—chimes conspicuously with one of Roquentin's most arresting<br />

formulations: "Every existent starts life for no reason, persists out of<br />

weakness and dies by accident." 38 Admittedly, Murakami might not have<br />

had this very sentence of <strong>Sartre's</strong> novel in mind, nor is he saying exactly<br />

the same thing. Nevertheless, Roquentin's ontological observation about<br />

generic existence is here transposed to the more dynamic plane of a<br />

personalised narrative history, and it is clear that Murakami is applying the<br />

same principle as Sartre—namely that of contingency—even if he does not<br />

use the term itself.<br />

Such evidence of Murakami's affiliation with Sartre is strengthened by<br />

the hypothesis that the author himself advances for his character's<br />

condition, namely that his forty-day torment of vomiting and anonymous<br />

phonecalls might in fact be psychosomatic manifestations of repressed<br />

guilt for his promiscuous and treacherous seductions:<br />

Murakami, "A Folklore for My Generation: A Prehistory of Late-Stage<br />

Capitalism", in Blind Willow, Sleeping Woman, 74.<br />

37 "Nausea 1979", 152.<br />

38 'Tout existant nait sans raison, se prolonge par faiblesse et meurt par rencontre"<br />

(Sartre, La Nausee, 158).


Contemporary Perspectives 187<br />

"So, what you're telling me, Mr Murakami, is that my own guilt<br />

feelings—feelings of which I myself was unaware—could have taken on<br />

the form of nausea or made me hear things that were not there?"<br />

"No, Vm not saying that", I corrected him. "You are." 39<br />

Two things are worthy of note. First, Murakami's man speculates (in<br />

classic Freudian fashion) that his physical dysfunction might be<br />

symptomatic of his repressed and unconscious moral inner world. Contrast<br />

this with Roquentin's nausea as symptomatic of his newly conscious<br />

apprehension of the contingency of the external world. The former's gaze<br />

is directed inwards to psychological and affective structures, the latter's<br />

outwards to real material phenomena. It is as if Murakami has adopted<br />

<strong>Sartre's</strong> concept of "nausea", then literally (and appositely, given the<br />

physical effect of nausea) turned it inside-out.<br />

Second, Murakami's rejoinder—"No, Vm not saying that [...] You are"<br />

(and the emphases are his own)—is a disingenuous authorial sleight-ofhand<br />

inviting the inference that he and his unnamed "friend" are, in effect,<br />

one and the same person: symbiotic, indivisible alter egos. This<br />

impression is reinforced by the fact that the unknown caller's last<br />

telephonic intervention is unique: "His final call was different. First he<br />

said my name. That was nothing new. But then he added, 'Do you know<br />

my name?'". 40 The implication that the recipient ought to be able to guess<br />

the identity of his caller—who might be nothing more nor less than a voice<br />

inside his own head—is underpinned by the last line of the novella:<br />

"Fortunately, neither he nor I have been visited by nausea or phone calls<br />

so far." 41 The implied degree of identification between the nameless<br />

character and his named creator is reminiscent of <strong>Sartre's</strong> explicit<br />

reappropriation of Antoine Roquentin in Les Mots: "/ was Roquentin [...];<br />

at the same time, I was me [...]". 42 Is it fanciful to suggest that Murakami's<br />

nauseated artist stands in the same relationship to him as <strong>Sartre's</strong> sick-atheart<br />

historian does to him? Are they both phantsamatic, empirical victims<br />

of their creators' bipolar selves, the avatars of different nightmares<br />

exteriorised in the relatively secure, cathartic and ultimately salutary<br />

process of fictional projection?<br />

For the time being, at least, such questions must be left hanging in the<br />

air. But it is worth remarking that, elsewhere in this collection of short<br />

39 "Nausea 1979", 152.<br />

40 Ibid., 151.<br />

41 Ibid., 153.<br />

42 "J'etais Roquentin [...]; en meme temps j'&ais moi [...]" {Les Mots, 210,<br />

<strong>Sartre's</strong> emphases).


188 Chapter Twelve<br />

stories, there are further hints that Murakami, if not quite consciously<br />

drawing upon "Sartrean sources", shares with his existentialist forebear a<br />

number of preoccupations that bespeak similar perspectives and<br />

interrogations. Let us consider a few examples. First, the anonymous firstperson<br />

narrator of "The Mirror" 43 has a problem recognising himself in it:<br />

My reflection in the mirror wasn't me. It looked exactly like me on the<br />

outside, but it definitely was not me. No, that's not it. It was me, of course,<br />

but another me. Another me that should never have been. 44<br />

This disconcerting inability to comprehend one's own image as, in fact,<br />

just that is powerfully reminiscent of the scene in which Roquentin suffers<br />

the same frightening and sickening experience:<br />

On the wall there is a white hole, the mirror. It's a trap. I know I'm going<br />

to let myself get caught. That's it. The grey thing has just appeared in the<br />

mirror. [...] it's the reflection of my face. [...] I understand nothing about<br />

this face. Other people's have a meaning. Not mine. 45<br />

For Murakami, this anomaly leads his narrator to banish mirrors from his<br />

house and to conclude that "the most frightening thing in the world is our<br />

own self', 46 a conclusion reached also by <strong>Sartre's</strong> trio of damned<br />

characters in Huis clos, from whose hellish confines mirrors are equally<br />

banished, so that they must rely entirely and agonisingly on each other's<br />

gaze for their sense of self.<br />

Next, we find the concept of the "wall" used by Murakami as a<br />

metaphor of containment, limitation and frustration—"I'm going to be<br />

surrounded by this thick wall for ever, never allowed to venture outside.<br />

The rest of my insipid, pointless life" 47 —much as it is by Sartre in his<br />

prize-winning collection of short stories, Le Mur (The Wall). 4 * Or again,<br />

Murakami touches upon the contingency of human existence in another<br />

place, telling us that a poor aunt's "existence is her reason. Just like us.<br />

43<br />

In Blind Willow, Sleeping Woman, 55-59.<br />

44<br />

Ibid., 58.<br />

45<br />

"Au mur, il y a un trou blanc, la glace. C'est un pi&ge. Je sais que je vais m'y<br />

laisser prendre. £a y est. La chose grise vient d'apparaitre dans la glace. [...] c'est<br />

le reflet de mon visage. [...] je n'y comprends rien, a ce visage. Ceux des autres<br />

ont un sens. Pas le mien" (La Nausee, 22).<br />

46<br />

'The Mirror", 59.<br />

47<br />

"A Folklore for My Generation", 71.<br />

48<br />

In (Euvres romanesques, 211-388; published in 1939 and awarded the Prix du<br />

Roman Populiste in 1940.


Contemporary Perspectives 189<br />

We exist here and now, without any particular reason or cause" —words<br />

that might be taken verbatim from any one of Roquentin's perorations on<br />

the subject, or indeed from UExistentialisme est un humanisme<br />

(Existentialism is a Humanism, 1946). Finally (but not exhaustively),<br />

Murakami evokes what we might call the "nauseous worldview" in a story<br />

whose very title—"Crabs"—resonates with Sartrean obsessions about<br />

crustaceans and all the menacing underworld of the submarine biosphere:<br />

"The world felt out of kilter. He could hear as it creaked through this new<br />

orbit. Something had happened, he thought, and the world had changed." 50<br />

Compare this with Roquentin's anxiety at the outset of his journal, the<br />

document that will be both the record of his anguish and the vehicle of his<br />

enquiry into it: "It's an abstract change that settles on nothing. Is it I that<br />

have changed? If not me, then it's this room, this town, this nature; I have<br />

to choose." 51<br />

It goes without saying that Sartre had no monopoly of reflection upon<br />

appearance, image and reality; upon individual limitations and our sense<br />

of futility; or upon existential contingency and the unnameable vertigo<br />

entailed by our apprehension of it. Nor does it follow that any<br />

contemporary writer who alludes to or meditates upon such things is either<br />

deliberately paying tribute to Sartre or inadvertently disclosing his<br />

influence. Nevertheless, initially intrigued by Haruki Murakami's<br />

provocative plagiarism of one of the best-known titles in twentieth-<strong>century</strong><br />

world literature, I contend that there is sufficient prima facie evidence in<br />

Blind Willow, Sleeping Woman to justify further investigation into the<br />

Sartrean influence that the author tacitly avows. This claim is yet another<br />

indicator, therefore, that <strong>Sartre's</strong> thought and work remain sufficiently<br />

vibrant and dynamic to be brought into dialogue with early twenty-first<strong>century</strong><br />

artists in different genres—here, the cinema of George Clooney or<br />

the prose fiction of Haruki Murakami—with mutual illumination and<br />

profit.<br />

49 "A Toor Aunt' Story", in Blind Willow, Sleeping Woman, 125-42 (136).<br />

50 "Crabs", in ibid., 209-14 (213).<br />

51 "C'est un changement abstrait qui ne se pose sur rien. Est-ce moi qui ai changd?<br />

Si ce n'est pas moi, alors c'est cette chambre, cette ville, cette nature; il faut<br />

choisir" (La Nausee, 9).


190 Chapter Twelve<br />

Works Cited<br />

Anon. "Death of an Idealist", Time, 24 November 1952, accessed<br />

28/08/2006 @<br />

www.time.com/time/magazine/printout/0,8816,817355,00.html.<br />

Asabuki Tomiko. Vingt-huit Jours au Japon avec Jean-Paul Sartre et<br />

Simone de Beauvoir (trans. Claude Peronny and Tanaka Chiharu).<br />

Paris: Langues et Mondes / L'Asiatheque, 1996.<br />

Flynn, Thomas R. "Introduction: Sartre at One Hundred—a Man of the<br />

Nineteenth Century Addressing the Twenty-First?", in Leak and van<br />

den Hoven (eds), Sartre Today: A Centenary Celebration, 1-14.<br />

Hill, Tobias. "A Hole in the Middle of the Pacific: Haruki Murakami's<br />

latest collection of short stories, Blind Willow, Sleeping Woman, is a<br />

delight." The Guardian Review, Saturday 8 July 2006.<br />

Leak, Andrew and Adrian van den Hoven (eds). Sartre Today: A<br />

Centenary Celebration. Oxford: Berghahn Books, 2005. (Also<br />

published as Sartre Studies International, vol. 11, no. 1/2, 2005.)<br />

McBride, William L. "Sartre at the Twilight of Liberal Democracy as We<br />

Have Known It", in Leak and van den Hoven (eds), Sartre Today: A<br />

Centenary Celebration, 311-18.<br />

Murakami Haruki. "Nausea 1979", in Blind Willow, Sleeping Woman<br />

(trans. Philip Gabriel and Jay Rubin). London: Harvill Seeker, 2006.<br />

O'Donohoe, Benedict. <strong>Sartre's</strong> Theatre: Acts for Life. Bern: Peter Lang,<br />

Modern French Identities, 34,2005.<br />

Pdju, Marcel. "Abraham Feller, ou 'son propre bourreau'" ["Abraham<br />

Feller, or 'his own executioner'"], Les Temps modernes, March 1953.<br />

Rowley, Hazel. Tete-a-tete: The Lives and Loves of Simone de Beauvoir<br />

and Jean-Paul Sartre. London: Vintage Books, 2007.<br />

Sartre, Jean-Paul. Les Mots. Paris: Gallimard, 1964.<br />

—. La Nausee (1938), in (Euvres romanesques (Edition &ablie par Michel<br />

Contat et Michel Rybalka), 1-210. Paris: Gallimard, Bibliotheque de la<br />

Pleiade, 1981.<br />

—. Les Jeux sont faits (ed. B. P. O'Donohoe). London: Routledge,<br />

Twentieth Century French Texts, 1990.<br />

—. La Part dufeu, in Theatre complet (edition publiee sous la direction de<br />

Michel Contat), 1183-1214. Paris: Gallimard, Bibliotheque de la<br />

Pleiade, 2005.


CHAPTER THIRTEEN<br />

EXISTENTIALIST IMPACT<br />

ON THE WRITINGS AND MOVIES<br />

OF OSHIMA NAGISA<br />

SIMONEMULLER<br />

Introduction<br />

Existentialism had an enormous impact on post-war Japanese<br />

intellectual history. The works of existentialist philosophers such as<br />

Martin Heidegger, Karl Jaspers and Albert Camus were analysed in great<br />

detail in Japan. It was, however, Jean-Paul Sartre who was most closely<br />

associated with existentialism. Sartre had an extraordinarily strong effect<br />

on Japanese post-war literature and philosophy, as well as Japanese art and<br />

politics. Sartre himself had a life-long fascination for Japan. In 1966 he<br />

visited the country on a month-long lecture tour with Simone de Beauvoir.<br />

His impact on Japanese post-war literature was high: the works of many<br />

important Japanese authors of that time—among others Abe K6bo (1924-<br />

1993) and the Nobel prize laureate 6e KenzaburS (born 1935)—are<br />

strongly influenced by <strong>Sartre's</strong> philosophy of existence.<br />

<strong>Sartre's</strong> existentialism had a great impact on Japanese movie directors<br />

as well. Particularly Oshima Nagisa (born 1932), a leading figure of the<br />

Japanese New Wave Cinema, known in the West for his controversial film<br />

Ai no korrida (The Empire of the Senses, 1976) was strongly influenced by<br />

<strong>Sartre's</strong> philosophy. Like many Japanese post-war intellectuals, Oshima<br />

was attracted to <strong>Sartre's</strong> idea of the engaged intellectual. Moreover, many<br />

of the things Oshima wrote and filmed, remind one of the phenomenological<br />

analyses of Sartrean existentialism. In his theoretical writings<br />

Oshima often quoted Sartre and his philosophy.<br />

The extent of <strong>Sartre's</strong> impact on Oshima Nagisa becomes evident in<br />

the following quotation from an interview on his film Koshikei (Death by<br />

Hanging, 1968), in which Oshima called Sartre his favourite author and


192<br />

Chapter Thirteen<br />

explicitly declared that Sartre was the main reason why he had become a<br />

movie director:<br />

"Which author do you admire?"<br />

Asked this question, my heart beat faster.<br />

"Jean-Paul Sartre."<br />

Answering, I felt how my eyes filled with tears. Hadn't I made movies<br />

for ten years just to say this single phrase? All the efforts to become a<br />

director, to make movies, weren't they just done for this instant? I<br />

remembered the end of the first chapter of Troubled Sleep [La Mort dans<br />

Vame\, the third part of The Roads to Freedom [Les Chemins de la liberte]:<br />

"He approached the balustrade and started shooting, standing upright.<br />

This was an enormous act of vengeance, each shot taking revenge on his<br />

former scruples. One shot for Lola whom I didn't dare to rob, one shot for<br />

Marcelle whom I should have broken up with, one shot for Odette whom I<br />

didn't want to fuck. This one for the books I didn't dare to write, that one<br />

for the travels I denied myself, this other one for all the people I wanted to<br />

hate and tried to understand. He fired and laws blew apart in mid-air: thou<br />

shalt love thy neighbour as thyself, bang, right into that idiot's face; thou<br />

shalt not kill, bang, at that bastard opposite."<br />

Yes! My movies as well were single revenges against past hesitations.<br />

Yes! I shoot! I continue to shoot! Bang, bang, bang. 2<br />

As Mathieu fired upon his missed opportunities in an act of revenge, so<br />

Oshima used his movies to express his unrealised wishes and dreams:<br />

I can't recall who said that cinema is the visualisation of wishes and<br />

desires. For me, cinema is the visualisation of the wishes and desires of the<br />

movie director. 3<br />

In this chapter, I will investigate how <strong>Sartre's</strong> philosophy is expressed<br />

in Oshima Nagisa's theoretical writings and in his movies. I will examine<br />

parallels of <strong>Sartre's</strong> and Oshima's conceptions of engagement, freedom,<br />

1 "II s'approcha du parapet et se mit a tirer debout. C'e'tait une enorme revanche;<br />

chaque coup de feu le vengeait d'un ancien scrupule. Un coup sur Lola que je n'ai<br />

pas os6 voler, un coup sur Marcelle que j'aurais du plaquer, un coup sur Odette<br />

que je n'ai pas voulu baiser. Celui-ci pour les livres que je n'ai pas ose* ecrire,<br />

celui-la pour les voyages que je me suis refuses, cet autre sur tous les types, en<br />

bloc, que j'avais envie de d&ester et que j'ai essays' de comprendre. II tirait, les<br />

lois volaient en l'air, tu aimeras ton prochain comme toi-meme, pan dans cette<br />

gueule de con, tu ne tueras point, pan sur le faux jeton d'en face" (Sartre, Les<br />

Chemins de la liberte, III: La Mort dans Vame, 193). All translations are my own.<br />

2 Hasegawa (2001), 26-27.<br />

3 Oshima (1988), 181.


Existentialist Impact on 6shima Nagisa 193<br />

shame and sexuality. And I intend to show how Oshima incorporated his<br />

theoretical ideas into his movies by focussing on films such as Ai to kibd<br />

no machi (A Town of Love and Hope, 1959), Koshikei {Death by Hanging,<br />

1968), and Hakuchu no torima (Violence at Noon, 1966). 4<br />

Oshima Nagisa: an engaged movie director<br />

Just as Sartre was an engaged writer, so Oshima Nagisa can be called<br />

an engaged movie director. Like the French philosopher, Oshima was<br />

politically active and regularly discussed his opinions on political and<br />

cultural matters before a broad public. Also like Sartre, Oshima considered<br />

that everybody is responsible for the world and has the duty to get<br />

involved in its affairs, and he thought about the potential to change the<br />

present situation and to transcend the historic conditions of human society.<br />

In an essay on Nihon no yoru to kiri (Night and Fog in Japan, 1960), a<br />

film about the Japanese student movements triggered by the renewal of the<br />

US-Japan Security Treaty in 1960, Oshima wrote as follows:<br />

All people are responsible. Those who created this situation must change<br />

it. You, who could be the real power behind these changes, but who<br />

nevertheless persist with the given situation, as if paralysed and walled in;<br />

you, who stood up a single time and who are so depressed by this single<br />

failure that you are now waiting for a change from outside; you, who allow<br />

this situation to continue, even though you believe that you are changing<br />

it—this means you all! It is you whom I want to unmask together with your<br />

failures, your corruption and your weaknesses. 5<br />

Oshima Nagisa made movies that appealed to the audience in order to<br />

change social and political conditions. Thus Oshima "used cinema as a<br />

tool, a weapon in a cultural struggle". 6 As Sartre wanted to captivate his<br />

readers, so Oshima wanted to fascinate his spectators. According to him,<br />

this is only possible if the subjectivity of the film technician is set free:<br />

The new cinema, above all, has to be a personal and subjective-active<br />

cinema of the author. A dialogue between the author and his spectators can<br />

only be established if the aeuvre is the subjective-active expression of the<br />

author and has, in form of a tension with reality, a critical function. [...]<br />

The expression of free subjectivity implies also that different methods are<br />

4 An earlier draft of this chapter was given as a paper at the 13 th Conference of the<br />

UK Sartre Society at the Institut Fran?ais, London, 21 October 2006.<br />

5 6shima(1988), 127.<br />

6 Desser, 3.


194 Chapter Thirteen<br />

used to make each film. Otherwise, movies would merely be a moribund<br />

schema, and there would no longer be any dialogue between author and<br />

viewer. Subjectivity can be kept only through permanent self-negation. 7<br />

In Oshima's postulation of the committed movie director, in his emphasis<br />

upon the subjectivity of the author, in his claim for a permanent dialectical<br />

exchange between author, spectator, oeuvre and reality, and in his demand<br />

for a constant self-negation in the process of movie making, we find again<br />

<strong>Sartre's</strong> literary theories as he expounded them in "Qu'est-ce que la<br />

litterature?" ("What is Literature?", 1947). For comparison, consider this<br />

extract from <strong>Sartre's</strong> essay:<br />

[T]he author chooses to disclose the world, especially the human to other<br />

humans, in order that they—in the light of the object thus exposed—<br />

shoulder their whole responsibility. [...] Likewise it is the function of the<br />

author to act such that nobody can ignore the world and call himself<br />

innocent in it. 8<br />

Oshima Nagisa criticises Japanese politics and society from different<br />

perspectives. But the central theme of his movies, which he uses to express<br />

his criticism, is oppression. 9 By exploring oppression, Oshima treats<br />

political matters such as the Vietnam War, student protests and the death<br />

penalty, as well as social matters such as poverty and racial discrimination.<br />

In other words, the leitmotiv of Oshima's movies is the question: how can<br />

human beings be really free and subjective? The struggle against<br />

oppression was one of <strong>Sartre's</strong> central concerns as well:<br />

If our wishes could be fulfilled, the author [...] would be read by the<br />

oppressed as well as by the oppressor, would bear witness to the oppressed<br />

against the oppressor, would reproach the oppressor with his own<br />

reflection from inside, would become aware, with the oppressor and for<br />

him, of the oppression and contribute to a constructive and revolutionary<br />

ideology. 10<br />

7 6shima(1988),34.<br />

8 "[L]'6crivain a choisi de ddvoiler le monde et singuli&rement l'homme aux autres<br />

hommes pour que ceux-ci prennent en face de l'objet ainsi mis a nu leur entfere<br />

responsabilitd. [...] Pareillement la fonction de Tdcrivain est de faire en sorte que<br />

nul ne puisse ignorer le monde et que nul ne s'en puisse dire innocent" ("Qu'est-ce<br />

que la literature?", 74).<br />

9 See Sat6,376.<br />

10 Ibid., 141.


Existentialist Impact on 6shima Nagisa 195<br />

In order to express oppression and the revolt against it, Oshima's<br />

protagonists are often criminals. They are people with a repressed, deeply<br />

rooted psychological aberration that manifests itself in incomprehensible,<br />

often destructive, behaviour. Criminals are by definition combatants<br />

against the system, thus fighting against political, social or personal<br />

oppression. But not only his protagonists fight against the system:<br />

Oshima's films themselves are an opposition to the Japanese system.<br />

Oshima himself calls the fact that he makes movies a "crime". 11 Thus,<br />

Oshima Nagisa can be called a highly political and critical film director.<br />

Even in movies that at first glance do not seem to have any political<br />

content, one can detect hidden political allegories.<br />

Oshima Nagisa is not only comparable to Sartre by virtue of being an<br />

engaged artist. His films obviously show existentialist traits, which derive<br />

directly from influences of <strong>Sartre's</strong> writings—especially themes such as<br />

shame, guilt, freedom or sexuality show parallels to <strong>Sartre's</strong> theories,<br />

elaborated in u£tre et le neant {Being and Nothingness, 1943). I will now<br />

investigate some of these traits through an analysis of some of Oshima's<br />

films.<br />

Ai to kibo no machi (A Town of Love and Hope, 1959):<br />

Self-definition by the others<br />

A <strong>second</strong> characteristic of Oshima's movies, which is revealed<br />

especially in his films of the late 1960s, leads us back to Sartre,<br />

specifically to <strong>Sartre's</strong> psychology of existence: the investigation of the<br />

human psyche, and the analysis of human behaviour. Oshima describes<br />

people who become revolutionaries against the system, not in the name of<br />

an organisation, but simply for the realisation of their will: people who<br />

resist, but who at the same time take responsibility for their resistance.<br />

Already in Oshima's first film, Ai to kibo no machi, influences of<br />

Sartre can be traced. The film is the story about a small boy whose poverty<br />

makes him sell the same pigeon again and again to different people, since<br />

the pigeon always escapes from the new owner and flies back to the boy.<br />

The child is not consciously committing a crime. He becomes aware of his<br />

crime only through the judgement of the adults, who call him a thief, thus<br />

constituting his self-perception as a thief. If one wants to apply <strong>Sartre's</strong><br />

philosophy, then one may say that "the stealing that the boy did<br />

unconsciously was discovered by adults who now blame him for being a<br />

11 Ibid., 380.


196 Chapter Thirteen<br />

thief. As a consequence, the boy becomes a conscious thief." 12 One is<br />

reminded of the scene in <strong>Sartre's</strong> Saint Genet, comedien et martyr (Saint<br />

Genet, Actor and Martyr, 1952), when Genet is caught while stealing, and<br />

his being called a thief by the others henceforth becomes his Urwahl<br />

(fundamental choice) to be a thief. <strong>Sartre's</strong> existential-psychoanalytical<br />

critique of Jean Genet was translated into Japanese in 1958, one year<br />

before the release of Ai to kibo no machi, and it is very likely that Oshima<br />

was inspired by it in producing his film.<br />

The small boy in Oshima's movie gains the consciousness of being a<br />

thief but he resists being defined by others: that is to say, he declines to<br />

adopt their moral judgment regarding his actions. Thus, this newly gained<br />

self-perception does not lead him to give up selling the pigeon. Rather, he<br />

takes responsibility for his actions, and in so doing he opposes society. 13<br />

The movie Ai to kibo no machi therefore has a critical function: it serves as<br />

a harsh and unsentimental realist document on the disparity of social class<br />

and the inescapability of poverty. 14<br />

Koshikei (Death by Hanging, 1968):<br />

The question of guilt and identity<br />

The topic of guilt and shame recurs in another of Oshima's films,<br />

namely Koshikei. The film was inspired by the notorious, real-life<br />

execution of a convicted murderer, Ri Chin'u, who had killed two Japanese<br />

schoolgirls in 1958 and subsequently courted publicity for his crimes<br />

through the newspapers and the police. The premise of Koshikei is that a<br />

man, sentenced to death, is rendered amnesiac through a failed hanging<br />

and thus made unconscious of his crime. He cannot be hanged again since,<br />

according to Japanese law, a man who has no memory cannot be legally<br />

punished. This creates a situation in which the embarrassed officials must<br />

reawaken the convicted man's conscious knowledge of his identity, and<br />

thus of his past and his guilt. 15 In this context, one recalls Kafka's novel<br />

Der Prozess (The Trial, 1925). 16 Moreover, in Oshima's movie, Ri Chin'u<br />

is called, in Kafkaesque manner, merely by his initial, R.<br />

12 Ibid., 33.<br />

13 Ibid., 335.<br />

14 See http://www.filref.com/directors/dirpages/oshima.html.<br />

15 See Turim, 65.<br />

16 See ibid., 64.


Existentialist Impact on 6shima Nagisa 197<br />

The movie as a whole clearly displays certain Brechtian devices, for<br />

instance distanciation, strategically readjusted to cinematic form. 17 But<br />

there are also features that lead us again to <strong>Sartre's</strong> theories. In Sartrean<br />

fashion, Oshima analyses the circumstances which led to R's crime, and at<br />

the same time he criticises Japanese society and the death penalty. R is a<br />

Korean living in Japan. He is intelligent but, in order to escape<br />

discrimination by the Japanese, he pretends to be Japanese. We might say<br />

that he is in a state of "bad faith". R begins to escape into a world of<br />

fantasy, which, in the end, he can no longer distinguish from reality.<br />

Oshima describes R as a person who, being under extreme pressure,<br />

develops an extreme imagination, which leads him to crime. He is finally<br />

executed, but he shows no signs of remorse and denies the right of the<br />

Japanese to execute him. The law defines the protagonist as a criminal but<br />

the protagonist opposes that judgement, just as the protagonist of Ai to<br />

kibo no machi does not consider himself a criminal, but a justified<br />

malefactor. The film can thus be interpreted as a criticism of Japanese<br />

society that discriminates against the Koreans. This theme of criminals<br />

who reject definition as criminals by others must be considered in the<br />

context of the 1960s. These artists belonged to a generation who wanted to<br />

form their own opinions and were hostile to being told what to think. They<br />

represented an opposition to a ruling £lite that says: because you are not<br />

right you must criticise yourselves. 18 This was the newly gained freedom<br />

of the post-war generation, which was expressed in the movies of the<br />

1950s as well, but especially in those of the 1960s.<br />

Oshima himself explained his frequent depiction of "righteous<br />

criminals" in his films by the tendency of the Japanese to see themselves<br />

as victims:<br />

I do not want to negate in any way the sympathy for the victims. But if<br />

people develop such a victim-complex, and if this is taken up as a theme<br />

again and again, then I must decidedly oppose it. I have perfect sympathy<br />

for victims, but I distance myself from the victim complex. Out of these<br />

considerations, I tried to make movies. I wanted to develop characters that<br />

do not nourish the victim complex. Characters that are not victims but<br />

offenders. 19<br />

Parallels between <strong>Sartre's</strong> existentialism and the case of Li Chin'u are also<br />

stressed by the Sartre specialist Suzuki Michihiko. In a discussion with<br />

17 See ibid., 62.<br />

18 See Sat6,38.<br />

19 Seehttp://www.3sat.de/3sat.php?http://www.3sat.de/ard/50268/index.html.


198 Chapter Thirteen<br />

another specialist of Sartre, Takeuchi YoshirS on the occasion of <strong>Sartre's</strong><br />

visit to Japan in 1966, Suzuki points out that Li's murder was the action of<br />

a man who finds himself in a situation in which the only way to regain<br />

freedom is an escape into imagination. Suzuki thus interprets Li's case in<br />

the manner of existentialist psychology as an interplay of historical<br />

conditioning and personal freedom, which stands in connection with the<br />

history between Korea and Japan and with the discriminated situation of<br />

the Koreans in Japan. Thus, Li's murder may be seen as addressed to<br />

Japan as a whole. If the case of Li had become literature and not reality,<br />

Suzuki claims, it would have become Genet. 20<br />

Hakuchu no torima (Violence at noon, 1966):<br />

The feeling of shame<br />

How fantasies can lead to committing a crime is shown again in<br />

another film by Oshima Nagisa, made in 1966. The story of Hakuchu no<br />

torima is based on a novel by the famous Japanese author Takeda Taijun<br />

(1912-1976), whose writings were influenced by Sartre. The story is about<br />

a poor serial killer who strangles women to death and rapes them. He does<br />

not feel guilty since he does not see his victims as humans but as things.<br />

The protagonist in the film says:<br />

A dead person is not a human being. It is not a woman either. It is merely a<br />

thing, an object. It doesn't mean anything, if one plays with it, or cuts it<br />

into pieces. 21<br />

Oshima describes his protagonist as a person with a high degree of shame.<br />

Because of this shame he is not able to perform sexually with women in a<br />

normal way. In order not to feel shame, he puts his victims into a state in<br />

which they cannot see him. The feeling of shame emerges from being seen<br />

by others. Thus, Oshima describes exactly the feeling of shame as Sartre<br />

defined it in VP.tre et le neant.<br />

In an article about his film, Oshima emphasises that the core topic of<br />

Hakuchu no torima is shame. He also stresses that the feeling of shame is<br />

an essentially masculine feeling:<br />

In general, it is assumed that shame is a characteristic of women. I cannot<br />

share that opinion. On the contrary—I believe that shame is rather a man's<br />

business. It is a feeling that is innate to men, that essentially belongs to<br />

20 See Suzuki, 77.<br />

21 Sat6, 247.


Existentialist Impact on 6shima Nagisa 199<br />

them; it can only very rarely be found in women. I would even claim that<br />

women basically do not even know what shame is. 22<br />

According to Oshima, men are shamefaced because they always have to<br />

become a subject in sexual intercourse, they always have to play the active<br />

part in sexual relations. They have to "perform" sexually while being<br />

"seen". Thus arises the wish to transform the partner into an object:<br />

It is safe to say that there are men who can only have sexual intercourse<br />

with a bought body—a body that they have transformed into a "thing" by<br />

the act of buying—who are freed from their shame and repression only<br />

under this condition. It is possible to call such men "wimpy creatures" in a<br />

time of total sexual liberation—but if we unveil the traditional prejudices,<br />

we will find out that every man who has feelings of shame knows the<br />

desire of this kind of sexual relations. Are there any men at all who are free<br />

of this desire? 23<br />

Shame is the fear of being defined by others whilst, at the same time,<br />

rejecting that definition. Thus, here again, we can read the movie as an<br />

allegory of social criticism. Society is constructed such that it makes<br />

people constantly feel ashamed. Everybody appears to be equal but in<br />

reality society is conceived as a stratification of classes. If people bear<br />

their shame and try to gain freedom only in their hearts, then they become<br />

fantasists, dreaming criminals.<br />

Conclusion<br />

Oshima Nagisa offers strong parallels with Sartre, both insofar as he<br />

was a politically engaged movie director, and insofar as he displays<br />

distinctively Sartrean existentialist traits in his movies. Oshima's films<br />

express the individual's reaction to his oppression by society. He describes<br />

highly sensitive people who are unable to adapt themselves to Japanese<br />

society, and who—in dealing with well adapted people—place themselves<br />

in the position of a superego. 24 One is forcefully reminded of the<br />

protagonists of <strong>Sartre's</strong> existential biographies, namely Baudelaire, Genet<br />

and Flaubert.<br />

Oshima's essays and films are documents of the political culture of the<br />

Japanese post-war period. They are witnesses of the far-reaching changes<br />

22 Oshima (1988), 71.<br />

23 Ibid., 75.<br />

24 See Sato, 381.


200 Chapter Thirteen<br />

in the way of life of a nation that almost paradigmatically represents the<br />

process of modernisation. Oshima never devoted himself to the illusion of<br />

a lost paradise of tradition. He advocated the new, the radical revolution,<br />

and is therefore often compared to Jean-Luc Godard. 25 Oshima himself did<br />

not consider himself to have much in common with Godard, though.<br />

Asked about the subjects he shares with the French movie director,<br />

Oshima answered in lapidary style: "One is politics and the other is<br />

cinema." 26<br />

By dealing with the subject of oppression, Oshima wanted to<br />

investigate how freedom and subjectivity can be preserved in a world that<br />

tries to restrain the freedom of people. In 1965, Oshima wrote an article<br />

with the title "The Path of Freedom"—obviously an allusion to <strong>Sartre's</strong><br />

novelistic trilogy, Les Chemins de la liberte {The Roads to Freedom,<br />

1945-47). In it he stresses, like Sartre, that freedom can only be gained<br />

through acceptance of contingency:<br />

If I was asked: which way did you go? I would answer: the way of<br />

freedom. [...] I believe one must realize that there is neither freedom nor<br />

joy in this world before one discovers the way to freedom, the way of joy<br />

for oneself. Only if we know that there is no freedom, can we be free: this<br />

staggering conclusion is the heavy burden that I have to carry with me day<br />

by day. [...] In this moment, I intend to shoot movies constantly. I believe<br />

that I am ready for it and that it is a good thing. It will be my way to<br />

freedom. 27<br />

Works Cited<br />

Desser, David. Eros plus Massacre: An Introduction to the Japanese New<br />

Wave Cinema. Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1988.<br />

Hasegawa Hiroshi. Dojidaijin Sarutoru [Sartre, a Contemporary], Tokyo:<br />

Kddansha, 200L<br />

Higuchi Naofumi. Oshima Nagisa no subete [All about Oshima Nagisa].<br />

Tokyd: Kinema junpdsha, 2002.<br />

Mellen, Joan. Voices from the Japanese Cinema. New York: Liveright,<br />

1975.<br />

6shima Nagisa. Sengo eiga—hakai to sozo [Post-war Cinema—<br />

Destruction and Creation]. T6ky6: San'ichi shobd, 1963.<br />

25 See 6shima (1988), "Preface" by Gertrud Koch, 9.<br />

26 Mellen, 261.<br />

27 Oshima (1988), 67.


Existentialist Impact on 6shima Nagisa 201<br />

—. Koshikei. Oshima Nagisa sakuhinshu [Death by Hanging. Collected<br />

Works of Oshima Nagisa], T6ky6: Shiseidd, 1968.<br />

—. Oshima Nagisa hydronshu: kaitai to funshutsu [Collected Reviews of<br />

Oshima Nagisa—Dismantling and Spouting]. T6ky6: H6ka shoten,<br />

1970.<br />

—. Taikenteki sengo eiga ron [Essays on Experienced Post-war Film<br />

Portraits]. T6kyo: Asahi shinbunsha. (Asahi sensho 38), 1975.<br />

—. Sekai no eiga sakka 6: Oshima Nagisa [Movie Writers of the World 6:<br />

Oshima Nagisa]. T6ky6: Kinema junpdsha, 1978.<br />

—. Die Ahnung der Freiheit [The Idea of Freedom] (trans. Grete<br />

Osterwald and Uta Goridis). T6ky6: Fischer, 1988.<br />

—. 7960. Tokyo: Nihon tosho senta. (Ningen no kiroku 137), 2001.<br />

—. 1968. Tokyd: Seidosha, 2004.<br />

Sartre, Jean-Paul. Les Chemins de la liberte, /-///. Paris: Gallimard, 1945-<br />

47.<br />

—. Ufctre et le neant: Essai d*ontologie phenomenologique. Paris:<br />

Gallimard, 1943.<br />

—. "Qu'est-ce que la literature?", in Situations, II. Paris: Gallimard,<br />

1948,55-330.<br />

Sato Tadao. Oshima Nagisa no sekai [The World of Oshima Nagisa].<br />

Tokyd: Asahi bunko, 1987.<br />

Suzuki Michihiko, et al. "Sarutoru no shisd to nihon" ["<strong>Sartre's</strong> Thought<br />

and Japan"], Gendai no me, 10, 1966, 64-77.<br />

Tanaka Chiseko. Filmmakers, 9: Oshima Nagisa. T6ky6: Kinema<br />

junpdsha, 1999.<br />

Turim, Maureen. The Films of Oshima Nagisa. Images of a Japanese<br />

Iconoclast. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1998.


CHAPTER FOURTEEN<br />

SARTRE'S LEGACY IN AN ERA<br />

OF OBSCURANTISM<br />

WILLIE THOMPSON<br />

Introduction<br />

This chapter sets out to suggest why we should regard <strong>Sartre's</strong> work<br />

and political example as continuing to be highly pertinent at the start of the<br />

twenty-first <strong>century</strong>, as well as in the likely circumstances of the decades<br />

to follow. 1<br />

John Gerassi described Sartre as "the hated conscience of his<br />

<strong>century</strong>", 2 and with good reason. He certainly made himself hated for the<br />

positions he adopted on a great range of social and political issues, and<br />

during his active years he disdained to conceal his own hatred of the<br />

bourgeoisie. In consequence of his intellectual superstardom, his standpoints<br />

counted for something; in France, certainly, during the Algerian<br />

War, his outspoken opinions provoked assassination attempts by the OAS 3<br />

and compelled him to go into hiding. Apart from being a philosopher of<br />

the first rank, he was also a major novelist, biographer and autobiographer,<br />

playwright and essayist as well as a political activist—and all this in<br />

addition to the perpetual fascination that his highly unconventional<br />

personal life exercised upon his contemporaries (and it continues to do so<br />

1 A previous draft of this chapter was given as a paper at the UK Sartre Society's<br />

Centenary Conference, Institut Fran^ais, London, 19-20 March 2005.<br />

2 Gerassi, Hated Conscience,<br />

3 Organisation de I'Armee Secrete, a supposedly clandestine grouping of serving<br />

and retired French military officers and men, pledged to keeping Algeria French,<br />

and therefore bitterly opposed to <strong>Sartre's</strong> de-colonising libertarianism.


<strong>Sartre's</strong> Legacy in an Era of Obscurantism 203<br />

down to the present day). Indeed, in his or her own time, no thinker of the<br />

twentieth <strong>century</strong> had such global impact and influence. 4<br />

However, despite the very extensive academic territory of Sartre<br />

studies, the more general consensus would appear to be that his<br />

philosophical approach has been entirely superseded, while there is no<br />

doubt at all that the political causes he represented are in total eclipse.<br />

With the collapse of any significant left-wing presence throughout the<br />

world, an entire cliff of social and political experience has fallen into the<br />

sea. Marxism, "the only humanistic philosophy committed to realising<br />

itself in the world" 5 to which Sartre himself was committed, 6 and which,<br />

for a number of years and in a variety of guises, dominated the intellectual<br />

landscape in both East and West during the <strong>second</strong> half of the <strong>century</strong>, is<br />

generally treated now as totally discredited, at least in its political<br />

manifestations.<br />

The vacuum created by the disintegration of the Marxist universe has<br />

provided room for the flourishing and proliferation of all manner of<br />

obscurantist superstitions, which certainly have always been around,<br />

surviving in the cultural undergrowth, but during most of the twentieth<br />

<strong>century</strong> held in check by the prevailing climate of rationalist discourse,<br />

Marxist or otherwise, which monopolised intellectual respectability. Such<br />

phenomena include varieties of fundamentalist religion, occasionally<br />

staging well-publicised displays; and popular superstitions which never<br />

died out anywhere in the world, whether in the scientifically committed<br />

West—where, among other instances, populist newspapers continue to<br />

carry their astrology columns—or even in the formally atheist former<br />

Eastern Bloc where they revived and blossomed speedily enough after<br />

1989.<br />

What room then remains for <strong>Sartre's</strong> legacy? My argument is that<br />

<strong>Sartre's</strong> Marxism 7 does in fact provide a viable and intellectually credible<br />

alternative to the versions which have so spectacularly fallen apart, but<br />

that is by no means all: his pre-Marxist philosophy is important as well.<br />

<strong>Sartre's</strong> positions are uncompromisingly rationalist and throughout his life<br />

(except possibly in his final years, with weakening mental powers), he<br />

4 Though the jury may still be out on whether Simone de Beauvoir might not<br />

equally, or better, deserve that accolade.<br />

5 Aronson, Sartre*s Second Critique, 7.<br />

6 Towards the end of his life he denied that he was any longer a Marxist, but by<br />

that time his powers were failing significantly.<br />

7 The somewhat fuzzy category in which <strong>Sartre's</strong> Marxism is generally placed is<br />

that of "Western Marxism", developed mostly, but by no means entirely, by<br />

thinkers unattached to the Marxist political movements.


204 Chapter Fourteen<br />

held unwaveringly to that standpoint. Moreover, there existed a consistency<br />

in his thinking as it developed from the 1930s to the early 1970s,<br />

which as a corpus constitutes an effective counter to contemporary<br />

irrationality and obscurantism.<br />

Obscurantism now<br />

First, however, it is worth listing some of the more salient examples,<br />

both new and revived, of the obscurantisms that afflict contemporary<br />

culture, foregoing here the exploration of the tensions, contradictions and<br />

socio-cultural antagonisms which exist within each of these categories.<br />

Mainstream religion, particularly in its fundamentalist versions, and<br />

especially in the evangelical Protestantism of the United States, is the most<br />

immediately evident instance of the phenomenon: a determined, coordinated<br />

attack against secularist rationalism is being mounted both in the<br />

USA itself and abroad, with far-reaching social and cultural consequences.<br />

It is entrenched at the centre of the state possessing the most overwhelming<br />

military, economic and cultural power on the globe, afflicted for two terms<br />

(2001-09) with a President who imagined that he was spoken to directly by<br />

God, and whose predecessor in the 1980s (Ronald Reagan) consulted<br />

astrologers. Beyond the borders of the USA, the concurrent upsurge of<br />

faith-driven politics in Latin America, Eastern Europe, India and Africa—<br />

not to speak of the Middle East—is a reality unprecedented since the time<br />

of the Enlightenment. Some of the more trivial but symptomatic<br />

consequences include the decision in the 1990s by the UK vehiclelicensing<br />

agency to exclude the number 666 from registration plates, and<br />

the refusal by house-builders to use the number 13. At the time of <strong>Sartre's</strong><br />

centenary, the example most in the news was the determined effort being<br />

made on both sides of the Atlantic to reinstate, as part of the school<br />

curriculum, Biblical accounts of the origins and development of life.<br />

Divine creationism in these instances conceals itself under the cloak of<br />

"intelligent design"—a concept which provided some amusing jokes at<br />

George W. Bush's expense, but which is otherwise intellectually vacuous.<br />

The emergence of New Age mystification and marginal religious cults<br />

as a cultural phenomenon in the West goes back to the 1960s, but began to<br />

thrive spectacularly from the 1980s onwards. Although wholly incoherent<br />

and resembling nothing so much as a supermarket shelf of faith options,<br />

their orientation in general terms is a re-enchantment of the material world<br />

(a tendency present in some sections of the otherwise entirely commendable<br />

environmental movement). In this they find common ground<br />

with versions of mainstream religion, particularly, in the Christian context,


<strong>Sartre's</strong> Legacy in an Era of Obscurantism 205<br />

Roman Catholicism, and elsewhere especially the Hindu culture, notably<br />

its fundamentalist versions. New Ageism also parallels, much more<br />

seriously, faith-driven versions of identity politics that repudiate rational<br />

secular interpretations of the world in the name of ancient traditions, or<br />

even of newly invented ones, such as those of Afrocentrism.<br />

Religious belief has been and is a frequent marker of "identity<br />

politics", though the latter also has much broader dimensions and is not<br />

always necessarily obscurantist in character. Nationalism, originating in<br />

reaction to the obscurantisms of dynastic traditionalism, is after all a form<br />

of identity politics, but is not in any sense incompatible with a universalist,<br />

scientifically orientated cultural outlook; 8 and there are, of course,<br />

innumerable forms of harmless cultural self-identification. However, the<br />

proclivities towards irrationalist forms of ethnic nationalism became all<br />

too evident during the twentieth <strong>century</strong>, producing not merely<br />

exterminatory fantasies but exterminatory projects. In the late twentieth<br />

<strong>century</strong>, forms of identity politics, ethnically based and otherwise, have<br />

combined readily with explicit and virulent versions of obscurantist<br />

religion or even unapologetic superstition, demanding "respect" on the<br />

basis of particular and peculiar versions of their own "truth". Sartre would<br />

certainly have had no time for the notion that it is proper to "respect"<br />

fantasies, no matter how bizarre and preposterous, because to call them<br />

into question might "offend" their adherents. He would certainly have<br />

agreed with the phrase from Marx that Edward Thompson was fond of<br />

quoting: "To leave error unrefiited is intellectual immorality."<br />

The collation of literary and ideological concepts termed<br />

"postmodernism", though it could not be regarded as a superstition in the<br />

strong sense, nevertheless fits well into the definition of obscurantism,<br />

above all in the repudiation, explicit or implicit, of rationalism (or even<br />

rationality) that is characteristic of the tendencies identified by this term. It<br />

has served as the basis for the denunciation of reason on the grounds that it<br />

is oppressive, male, Western, imperialist, or whatever. Although efforts<br />

have been made to detect affinities between <strong>Sartre's</strong> writings and the<br />

postmodern trend, 9 they carry little conviction. <strong>Sartre's</strong> positions are<br />

always rationalist through and through, no less in his Marxist than in his<br />

phenomenological phase.<br />

A major theme of postmodernist endeavour has been to attack, or even<br />

try to pervert, the scientific tradition. 10 What is known as the "strong<br />

Tom Nairn distinguishes in this context between ethnic nationalism and civic<br />

nationalism: see his "Breakwaters of 2000: From Ethnic to Civic Nationalism".<br />

9 See, for example, Dominik La Carpa, A Preface to Sartre, 1979.<br />

10 See Alan Sokal and Jean Bricmont, Intellectual Impostures, 1998.


206 Chapter Fourteen<br />

programme" in the sociology of science, associated particularly with a<br />

group at Edinburgh University, claims no less than that all scientific<br />

knowledge rests on nothing more than conventional agreement among<br />

scientific practitioners and has no other basis in reality. It must certainly<br />

be acknowledged that Sartre had a regrettable blind spot in regard to<br />

science as usually conceived—possibly due to an aversion generated by<br />

his stepfather's authoritarian efforts to teach him science and mathematics.<br />

In her memoirs, Simone de Beauvoir notes that he would pursue such a<br />

line of thought to the extent sometimes of being, and knowing he was<br />

being, silly. On one occasion he argued for the non-existence of microbes<br />

and other entities invisible to the naked eye. 11 She explains his attitude<br />

regarding science as being due to its necessary abstractions and general<br />

laws, contradicting his project of philosophically grasping living reality<br />

with "more imagination than logic". 12 On the face of things, this might<br />

indeed appear to resonate with postmodern ideas. Later, however, she<br />

insists that if he repudiated scientific rationalism, that was on behalf of a<br />

more dialectical and humanly conceived version. 13<br />

In a dialectical reversal which Sartre would have appreciated, an<br />

ideology supposedly resting on the strictest of rational principles has<br />

turned into one of the mainstays of contemporary obscurantism. A recently<br />

published volume, Contesting Fundamentalisms, quite properly includes<br />

economic neo-liberalism in the fundamentalist catalogue, and this—while<br />

claiming to be based on impeccable scientific principles (though also<br />

embraced by the religious Right)—may well be regarded as the most<br />

rampant and hegemonic obscurantism of them all; certainly, it has the<br />

worst and most devastating practical consequences.<br />

Bad Faith<br />

The importance of the entire range of <strong>Sartre's</strong> work and its pertinence<br />

to the twenty-first <strong>century</strong> is most significant, I would argue, in relation to<br />

these developments. It was a philosophy of and for the twentieth <strong>century</strong>,<br />

driven by contemporary concerns, as Sartre himself would have been the<br />

first to insist, yet its underlying themes have a permanent relevance. He<br />

wrote the Critique of Dialectical Reason to try—single-handedly!—to<br />

rescue Marxism from the sclerosis that had overtaken it at the hands of the<br />

official Communist movement and the Trotskyist sects. But the concepts<br />

11 See Simone de Beauvoir, Prime of Life, 42.<br />

12 Ibid., 31.<br />

13 Ibid., 131. The Critique makes this perfectly plain.


<strong>Sartre's</strong> Legacy in an Era of Obscurantism 207<br />

developed there have a permanent relevance wherever socio-political<br />

interaction occurs, while those of the pre-war and war-time years—<br />

organised around the en-soi (in-itself) and the pour-soi (for-itself), even if<br />

impossible to validate scientifically or sociologically—are, with their<br />

emphasis on choice and decision without metaphysical props or excuses, a<br />

suitable model for the understanding of subjectivity, of seeing it from the<br />

inside, so to speak, as well as a meaningful guide to living. 14<br />

However they also have significance for the theme of this paper: the<br />

notions of bad faith and essentialism. All versions of obscurantism are no<br />

less varieties of bad faith. The first principle of obscurantism—if one may<br />

so put it—is a closed mind, an imperviousness to evidence, a procedure in<br />

bad faith for the indefinite multiplication of subordinate hypotheses, so as<br />

to manufacture reasons for dismissing and ignoring manifest realities. Or,<br />

as Lewis Carroll expresses it somewhere, believing fifty impossible things<br />

before breakfast. In other words, obscurantism is a means of throwing<br />

responsibility for individualised judgment onto the essentialised properties<br />

of things and relationships, whether essentialised by the pronouncement of<br />

external sources or simply by tradition. 15<br />

If the obscurantism is of a superstitious sort—whether mainstream or<br />

exotic—then a further level of bad faith is involved. In this, the<br />

responsibility for choice and decision has been alienated to an imaginary<br />

supernatural entity, regardless of whether that is conceived as a personal<br />

deity or an indifferent supernatural mechanism such as karma or its less<br />

intellectualised equivalents. The individual adherents conceive themselves<br />

the objects of imagined forces which they may hope to influence but<br />

cannot control, and whose commandments or oracles they cannot contradict<br />

but have to follow or suffer the consequences.<br />

Being and Nothingness famously ends with a declaration disclaiming<br />

the significance of its theory, at least as elaborated there, for social or<br />

political commitment. Nevertheless, there may be a degree of disingenuousness<br />

here (after all it was published under the Occupation). In any<br />

consideration of bad faith and authenticity, it is perfectly clear from<br />

<strong>Sartre's</strong> pre-war and war-time writings that the book's conclusion does not<br />

reflect his own attitude and that the principal targets for <strong>Sartre's</strong> contempt<br />

are individuals convinced of their own rectitude and entitlement to their<br />

14 See O'Donohoe, "Why Sartre Matters". There is a problem, nonetheless, in<br />

relating this approach to the mentally incompetent, as Simone de Beauvoir hints in<br />

relation to the insane murderers she mentions in Prime of Life, 131.<br />

15 For example, according to the early Victorian poet, Arthur Hugh Clough, in<br />

"The Latest Decalogue": "Thou shalt not covet, but tradition Approves all forms of<br />

competition."


208 Chapter Fourteen<br />

superior place and status in the world. This was certainly intended to apply<br />

to the bourgeoisie—and a fortiori to the fascists—of that particular time,<br />

and would equally fit the apostles of global corporatism in the present. If<br />

we are all in some degree prone to bad faith, such people are sure to be<br />

particularly severely addicted, and if bad faith is to be deplored they are to<br />

be especially condemned. To be sure, Brunet, the Communist militant in<br />

The Roads to Freedom (of which the first volume appeared in 1945) is<br />

also mired in dogmatic bad faith and yet is a relatively sympathetic<br />

character; however, his project is to destroy the existing social universe,<br />

not to assert his rightful place within it. Even setting aside the questions of<br />

ethics and commitment, if found to be convincing and taken seriously,<br />

<strong>Sartre's</strong> analysis of the cogito, consciousness, choice and responsibility,<br />

leaves no room for any of the obscurantist fantasies noted above.<br />

Political Legacy<br />

Even those most appreciative of <strong>Sartre's</strong> life and writings are<br />

constrained to admit the fallibility of some of his political judgments. His<br />

commitment to political engagement, which he assumed in the mid-1940s,<br />

was sometimes expressed in dubious fashion, for example, his degree of<br />

identification with the Soviet bloc and the French Communist Party in the<br />

early 1950s, and his embrace of the French Maoists in the late 1960s and<br />

early 1970s. Nevertheless, even when he was wrong, Sartre was, as the<br />

phrase has it, "right to be wrong". If he chose highly contentious allies<br />

with politically disreputable connections, he did so from the position that<br />

it was necessary to decide between the available alternatives as they<br />

actually existed, rather than to paralyse one's action on the pretext that an<br />

imaginary perfection was not to be had. <strong>Sartre's</strong> primary and fundamental<br />

commitment was to a project of emancipation: it is the thread that runs<br />

through all his work from the early 1930s to the early 1970s.<br />

From the mid-1940s, he correctly identified the principal threat to an<br />

emancipatory programme as capitalism, and in particular American<br />

capitalism and the imperial ambitions it generated in the US state system<br />

(though never failing to appreciate the cultural attainments of American<br />

society). In the context of the early twenty-first <strong>century</strong>, that insight<br />

appears particularly prescient and well-founded, the more so when the<br />

imperial project's ideological wrapping takes the form of market fundamentalism<br />

and the kind of parliamentarianism that Sartre despised. No less<br />

relevant is his intransigent denunciation of colonialism, a condemnation<br />

which he expressed both in writing and in action, putting himself on the<br />

line in both respects during the Algerian War. Once again, the relevance is


<strong>Sartre's</strong> Legacy in an Era of Obscurantism 209<br />

not purely historical at a time when not only is imperial expansion a<br />

present reality, but also the virtues of empire past and present are once<br />

more being expounded in print and the broadcast media. 16<br />

Marxism and the Dialectic<br />

<strong>Sartre's</strong> reaction to the developments of the 1950s was the project of<br />

reformulating Marxism, which became The Critique of Dialectical<br />

Reason, the first volume published in 1960, the <strong>second</strong> volume remaining<br />

unfinished and mostly unpublished during his lifetime. Certainly, the<br />

circumstances of its composition were not encouraging, nor was the mode:<br />

much was written when Sartre was maintaining his work-rate with wild<br />

excesses of stimulant drugs, 17 not to speak of alcohol and tobacco. In the<br />

words of Ronald Aronson, the text proved to be "awe inspiring and<br />

chaotic, penetrating and sloppy to the point of incoherence" (although<br />

much of it is also written with perfect clarity).<br />

Does it matter? Marxism has been declared, on seemingly irrefutable<br />

evidence, to be dead and buried, and no significant movement of the<br />

present any longer claims to be inspired by it. 19 Aronson has a perceptive<br />

insight, although his own volume was published as long ago as 1987:<br />

"<strong>Sartre's</strong> failure opened the door for the current wave of post-Marxism."<br />

This was even before the Soviet bloc fell, the direction of Chinese<br />

development became fully apparent, and the political parties which<br />

continued to use the "Communist" title or pretend to its inheritance<br />

declared their allegiance to global markets and capitalist success. "Post-<br />

Marxism" can of course mean many different things; it need not of<br />

necessity be obscurantist, but the general discredit into which Marxism has<br />

fallen has meant that, where previously it would have been grasped as an<br />

explanation for oppression and a guide to action in resisting it, now all<br />

manner of obscurantisms have come forward to present themselves as the<br />

only effective explanation or alternative in an intolerable present.<br />

For example, by the historian Niall Ferguson in Empire: How Britain Made the<br />

Modern World. A group in the USA is republishing the works of the nineteenth<strong>century</strong><br />

author for boys, G. A. Henty, who wrote novels applauding imperialism.<br />

Their objective is to enthuse American youth along similar lines.<br />

17 The trade name was Corydrane. Sartre outrageously exceeded the stated dosage.<br />

18 Aranson, Second Critique, 235.<br />

19 The "Communist" Party which continues to enjoy support in Russia is a<br />

nationalist formation with no relation even to the Stalinist version, let alone<br />

anything nearer to Marx or Lenin. The Chinese regime, though still claiming<br />

communist credentials, has abandoned all communist tenets.


210 Chapter Fourteen<br />

Although the exposition of <strong>Sartre's</strong> argument in the Critique may<br />

frequently appear confused, its essential outlines are clear enough. Perry<br />

Anderson summarises them as follows:<br />

The struggle against scarcity generated the division of labour and so the<br />

struggle between classes: therewith man himself became the negation of<br />

man. Violence, incessant oppression and exploitation of all recorded<br />

societies, is thus internalised scarcity. The harsh domination of the natural<br />

world over men and the divided antagonism of their efforts to transform it<br />

to assure their lives typically give rise to serial collectivities—inhuman<br />

ensembles of which each member is alien to each other and himself, and in<br />

which the ends of all are confiscated in the total outcome of their actions.<br />

Such series have always been the predominant form of social coexistence<br />

in every mode of production to date. 20<br />

By contrast, what Sartre terms a "fused group" is typified by a<br />

revolutionary movement in the immediate hour of its victory, when what<br />

up to that point have been serialised ensembles become a genuine<br />

collective united in a common emancipatory endeavour. This state of<br />

affairs is of necessity temporary and ephemeral: following the brief<br />

interval of exaltation, circumstances—embodied in the collapse of<br />

productive and distributive mechanisms, armed counter-revolution, foreign<br />

aggression and similar emergencies—soon compel, if the revolution is to<br />

survive, the establishment of institutionalised leadership, coercive<br />

measures, bureaucracy; the quondam fused group is before long returned<br />

to seriality and the cycle recommences, albeit of course in transformed<br />

circumstances, not as simple repetition—an important point. It is easy<br />

enough to discern equivalent processes at work in circumstances less<br />

dramatic than those of revolutionary success and degeneration.<br />

This account obviously oversimplifies, not only omitting important<br />

elements of <strong>Sartre's</strong> conceptual apparatus, but also failing to mention the<br />

specific examples he calls upon to sustain his case, most importantly the<br />

French and Russian revolutions. The title of his text is not accidental—this<br />

is a dialectical approach—and <strong>Sartre's</strong> method is defined as progressiveregressive<br />

in its understanding, from the individual to the collective and<br />

back form the collective to the individual, "the objective movement of<br />

history through the historical individual and the mark made by the<br />

individual on the historical movement". 21 Thus he sets out to rescue<br />

Marxism from the reductionist and mechanistic understanding which<br />

Anderson, Considerations, 86-87.<br />

21 Sartre, in Situations, VII, quoted in Ian Birchall, Sartre against Stalinism, 180.


<strong>Sartre's</strong> Legacy in an Era of Obscurantism 211<br />

plagued its institutional forms throughout most of its history. His aim is to<br />

strengthen Marxist analyses with the insights of existentialism, once and<br />

for all to dispose of its mechanistic variants.<br />

The aim of the Critique is to re-evaluate and strengthen some of the<br />

basic Marxian concepts and to utilise them as tools for understanding the<br />

manner in which the history of the communist movement and the USSR<br />

worked out, but it also provides clues and anticipatory insights as to why<br />

the Marxist intellectual universe imploded near the end of the <strong>century</strong>.<br />

<strong>Sartre's</strong> developed thoughts on this would have been most illuminating<br />

had he lived long enough and remained well enough to express them.<br />

What relevance does this have to contemporary affairs? The Critique<br />

has in the past tended to be dismissed as an over-ambitious failure (even<br />

from positions sympathetic to Sartre). However, as time has passed, its<br />

merits have become more apparent; particularly in the light of the "new<br />

world order" of the post-1989 era, it deserves a positive re-evaluation. The<br />

analyses of individual/collective relationships that it elaborates hold<br />

suggestive clues towards understanding the potentialities existing in the<br />

current balance of forces within political and social relations today.<br />

It is a perceptive remark on Perry Anderson's part that the Western<br />

Marxist tradition—which can be dated from the aftermath of the First<br />

World War and in which he positions Sartre (although others, e.g. Ronald<br />

Aronson, dispute this)—has been distinguished by an outlook of historical<br />

pessimism, in contrast to the optimism of Marxism's founders and<br />

adherents (at different times) in both the Second and the Third Internationals.<br />

This he attributes, on the one hand, to the conviction held by its<br />

adherents of certain victory for the global working class in the decades<br />

before 1914, and following the Bolshevik Revolution; and, on the other, to<br />

the reality of defeat and capitalist ascendancy, in one form or another,<br />

during most of the twentieth <strong>century</strong>.<br />

By the twenty-first <strong>century</strong>, the triumph of global corporatism appears<br />

to be complete, not only materially but ideologically as well. Francis<br />

Fukuyama's notorious phrase regarding "the end of history" might be<br />

deemed absurd at one level (and even included in the table of<br />

obscurantisms) yet, in the narrower sense that global corporatism and its<br />

attendant ideologies now no longer have any convincing competitors, he<br />

might be judged to have had a point. This is not to say that there is not<br />

plenty of anger and opposition directed at the global marketisation of<br />

goods, services and labour (and the baleful consequences which follow),<br />

but that, as yet, there is no convincing alternative to it—as its apologists


212 Chapter Fourteen<br />

never fail to remind us. I would argue that if any such alternative ever<br />

emerges, <strong>Sartre's</strong> work is likely to be intrinsic to its theoretical foundation.<br />

However, for the moment we have sought to consider his philosophy in<br />

relation to the infestation of contemporary obscurantisms. It surely<br />

provides an invaluable basis for understanding "how mumbo-jumbo<br />

conquered the world", to cite the title of Francis Wheen's recent volume, 23<br />

as a prelude to this quotation from Aronson:<br />

Whatever struggles may now occur, however fierce they may become, they<br />

will take place within "the framework of retotalized retotalization." This is<br />

the key to understanding the relationship between groups and masses in<br />

history. But it is ignored by positivist historians [emphasis added] who see<br />

only active forces acting on the passive masses—as if a physical force is<br />

engaged in some "natural" process. <strong>Sartre's</strong> theme of "retotalization" on<br />

the contrary allows us to grasp the intelligibility of this otherwise puzzling<br />

phenomenon: "the action of action on action". The totalizing action of the<br />

leaders (the totalization of directed retotalizations) depends on the action of<br />

the led (retotalized totalizations) for its success. 24<br />

Aronson is also the author of The Dialectics of Disaster: A Preface to<br />

Hope. It was published over twenty years ago, when the menace of nuclear<br />

war was still regarded as the most threatening planetary issue. Possibly it<br />

would now be appropriate to reverse the terms of the title, and write<br />

instead on the theme of: "The dialectic of hope: a preface to disaster"—<br />

something which Sartre would have been admirably equipped to do. The<br />

loss of the transcendent hope represented by socialism in its different<br />

varieties (or its pale welfare equivalent in the USA), of the presumption<br />

that a different order of things was possible from that of the commodification<br />

of human relationships with the market as supreme arbiter, has<br />

opened the door to the entry, on a mass scale, of ancient prejudices into the<br />

public consciousness as ersatz substitutes. However, not in their ancient<br />

form, 25 but subject to the dialectic of modernity, which is liable, if<br />

anything, to render them not less obscurantist but, on the contrary, even<br />

more so.<br />

It is indicative that the anti-globalisation movements, whatever their merits,<br />

concentrate on negative critique and do not propose an alternative economic order<br />

that will stand up to scrutiny.<br />

23<br />

Wheen does not in fact explain how, but rather confines himself to describing<br />

the species of mumbo-jumbo.<br />

24<br />

Aronson, Second Critique, 136.<br />

25<br />

See for example Ernest Gellner, Postmodernism, Reason and Religion, 1992.


<strong>Sartre's</strong> Legacy in an Era of Obscurantism 213<br />

The threatened environmental catastrophe, the overriding issue of the<br />

present, could most usefully, with appropriate modifications, be subjected<br />

to the kind of analysis that Sartre carried out on Soviet society in the<br />

unfinished <strong>second</strong> volume of the Critique: "[T]he anti-social forces of the<br />

practico-inert impose a negative unity of self-destruction on the society, by<br />

usurping the unifying power of the praxis which produced them." 26 Indeed<br />

it could almost be possible to imagine fancifully that the Critique might<br />

have been written with this crisis specifically in mind. Consider, for<br />

example, the following, as summarised by Aronson (Sartre was in this<br />

instance discussing problems of industrialisation in the USSR):<br />

For an example of "necessity" revealing praxis as its underside, Sartre<br />

takes the inert synthetic relationship set up between two cities when<br />

industrial expansion requires that their communications be improved [...].<br />

If there is now a scarcity of transport between A and B, this situation<br />

demands new investment of resources. But even this choice will only solve<br />

the problem by posing new ones elsewhere, while retaining the original<br />

practico-inert demands engendered by the original praxis. Necessity then is<br />

"the temporary alienation of this praxis in its own practical field" by<br />

creating new relations between elements of the field. 27<br />

Conclusion<br />

Obscurantist tendencies have always maintained an underground<br />

survival, even in the most rationalist of cultures. The novelty of present<br />

times is that they have flooded to the surface and, to change the metaphor,<br />

are militantly on the march around the globe, and more worryingly still,<br />

they have started to be taken seriously in areas of intellectual discourse. 28<br />

What might be termed the positivist opposition to their penetration,<br />

represented by writers like Francis Wheen or Richard Dawkins, is<br />

handicapped by the lack of an effective philosophical foundation and an<br />

adequate understanding of what has generated them; in other words, they<br />

lack a dialectical comprehension of the processes at work. 29 The strength<br />

of <strong>Sartre's</strong> approach is that it can supply just that: it is capable of totalising<br />

the field under consideration. <strong>Sartre's</strong> philosophy and other writings, and<br />

their engagement with the circumstances and dilemmas of his time, hold<br />

Quoted in Aronson, Second Critique, 115.<br />

27 Ibid., 126.<br />

28 For example, in 2005, The Times Higher Education Supplement (as it then was)<br />

conducted a seemingly serious discussion on the theme of "Intelligent Design".<br />

29 Demonstrated in the dreadful final section of Wheen's otherwise admirable<br />

volume.


214 Chapter Fourteen<br />

numerous lessons for our present one. Overall, they provide an understanding<br />

of human relationships much more valid than the alternatives,<br />

based as those are on the variety of mysticisms currently on offer, or on<br />

the rationalist perspectives which lack his dialectical insights.<br />

Works Cited<br />

Anderson, Perry. Considerations on Western Marxism. London: Verso,<br />

1979.<br />

Aronson, Ronald. The Dialectics of Disaster: A Preface to Hope. London:<br />

Verso, 1983.<br />

—. Sartre*s Second Critique. Chicago: Chicago University Press, 1987.<br />

Beauvoir, Simone de. The Prime of Life (trans. Peter Green).<br />

Harmondsworth: Penguin, 2003.<br />

Birchall, Ian. Sartre Against Stalinism. New York and Oxford: Berghahn,<br />

2004.<br />

Clough, Arthur Hugh. "The Latest Decalogue", in Victorian Poetry (ed. E.<br />

K. Brown), 384. New York: The Ronald Press, 1942.<br />

Ferguson, Niall. Empire: How Britain Made the Modern World.<br />

Harmondsworth: Penguin, 2003.<br />

Gellner, Ernest. Postmodernism, Reason and Religion. London:<br />

Routledge, 1992.<br />

Gerassi, John. Jean-Paul Sartre: Hated Conscience of his Century.<br />

Chicago: Chicago University Press, 1989.<br />

La Carpa, Dominik. A Preface to Sartre. London: Methuen, 1979.<br />

Nairn, Tom. "Breakwaters of 2000: From Ethnic to Civic Nationalism",<br />

New Left Review, 214, November / December 1995, 91-103.<br />

O'Donohoe, Benedict. "Why Sartre Matters", Philosophy Now, November<br />

/December 2005, 7-10.<br />

Sartre, Jean-Paul. Being and Nothingness (trans. Hazel Barnes). London:<br />

Methuen, 1969.<br />

—. Critique of Dialectical Reason, I (trans. Alan Sheridan-Smith).<br />

London: Verso, 2004.<br />

Schick, Carol, JoAnn Jaffe and Alisa M. Watkinson (eds). Contesting<br />

Fundamentalisms. Winnipeg: Fernwood, 2004.<br />

Sokal, Alan, and Jean Bricmont. Intellectual Impostures. London: Profile,<br />

1998.<br />

Wheen, Francis. How Mumbo-Jumbo Conquered the World: A Short<br />

History of Modern Delusions. London: Fourth Estate, 2004.


CONTRIBUTORS<br />

CAM CLAYTON<br />

Cam Clayton wrote the paper included in this collection as a Masters<br />

student in philosophy at Brock University, St Catharines, Ontario. He is<br />

now a doctoral candidate in philosophy at the University of Guelph, also<br />

in Ontario.<br />

CHRISTINE D AIGLE<br />

Christine Daigle is the Director of the Centre for Women's Studies and<br />

Associate Professor of Philosophy at Brock University, St Catharines,<br />

Ontario. She is also President of the North American Sartre Society. She is<br />

the author of Le Nihilisme, est-il un humanisme? ttude sur Nietzsche et<br />

Sartre (Presses de l'Universit£ Laval, 2005), and editor of Existentialist<br />

Thinkers and Ethics (McGill/Queen's University Press, 2006). She has coedited<br />

with Jacob Golomb the volume Beauvoir and Sartre: The Riddle of<br />

Influence (Indiana University Press, 2008), and has authored a book on<br />

Sartre forthcoming in the Routledge Critical Thinkers Series (2009). She<br />

has published articles in Sartre Studies International and the Journal of<br />

Nietzsche Studies. Her research focuses on the works of Friedrich<br />

Nietzsche, Jean-Paul Sartre and Simone de Beauvoir, and examines the<br />

phenomenological, ethical and political import of their respective<br />

philosophies.<br />

DAVID DRAKE<br />

David Drake is Maitre de conferences associe at the Institut d'Etudes<br />

europ^ennes, University Paris VIII. He is a former Secretary and<br />

President of the UK Sartre Society and is currently an Executive Editor<br />

of Sartre Studies International. He has given conference papers on<br />

Sartre in the UK, France, North America and China, and has published<br />

on Sartre both in the UK and in France. He is the author of a biography<br />

of Sartre—published in English by Haus in 2005, then in Spanish in<br />

2006—and has also published widely on French intellectuals and<br />

politics, notably: French Intellectuals and Politics from the Dreyfus<br />

Affair to the Occupation (Palgrave/Macmillan, 2005), and Intellectuals<br />

and Politics in Post-War France (Palgrave/Macmillan, 2002). He is a


216 Contributors<br />

member of the Editorial Boards of Modern and Contemporary France and<br />

of the Journal of War and Culture Studies.<br />

ROYELVETON<br />

Roy Elveton is Maxine H. and Winston R. Wallin Professor of Philosophy<br />

and Cognitive Studies at Carleton College, Minnesota. He has published<br />

The Phenomenology ofHusserl (Noesis Press, 2000) and numerous papers<br />

on Husserl, phenomenology, phenomenology of language, Nietzsche and<br />

cognitive science, and has edited Educating for Participatory Democracy:<br />

Paradoxes in Globalizing Logic (Hampton Press, 2006).<br />

DEBORAH EVANS<br />

Deborah Evans is an independent scholar who has published articles on<br />

Sartre in Sartre Studies International, and on Beauvoir in Simone de<br />

Beauvoir Studies. She has also contributed an essay ("Sartre and Beauvoir<br />

on Hegel's Master-Slave Dialectic and the Question of the 'Look'") to the<br />

collective volume, Beauvoir and Sartre: The Riddle of Influence (eds<br />

Christine Daigle and Joseph Golomb), forthcoming with Indiana<br />

University Press. She is currently working on a monograph for Cambridge<br />

Scholars Publishing entitled: Sartre and Beauvoir: Public Images, Private<br />

Lives. Her research interests include Sartre, Beauvoir, Hegel, Heidegger,<br />

Derrida and contemporary philosophy.<br />

NICHOLAS FARRELL FOX<br />

Nik Farrell Fox is an independent academic and writer who has taught<br />

philosophy at the University of Bristol. In addition to a series of articles on<br />

the subjects of music, philosophy and existentialism, he is currently<br />

writing a book, The Fragmentation of Music in the Postmodern Age. His<br />

first book, The New Sartre: Explorations in Postmodernism, was<br />

published in 2003 by Continuum.<br />

ALAIN FLAJOLIET<br />

Alain Flajoliet studied phenomenology in the mid-1970s under Jean-<br />

Toussaint Desanti and Paul Ricceur, and took his doctorate in 2000 with a<br />

thesis on <strong>Sartre's</strong> first philosophy. He works on the relations between<br />

anthropology, phenomenology and metaphysics. He has published a book,<br />

La Premiere Philosophic de Sartre (Champion, 2008), as well as many<br />

articles and papers on Sartre, Merleau-Ponty, Husserl and Heidegger. He<br />

is currently a Board member of the Groupe d y etudes sartriennes and of the<br />

French School of Daseinsanalyse. He is also a member of the Editorial<br />

Advisory Board of the journal ttudes sartriennes.


<strong>Sartre's</strong> Second Century 217<br />

SlMONE MULLER<br />

Simone Muller is a Senior Lecturer and Research Fellow in Japanese<br />

Studies at Zurich University, Switzerland. She focuses on Japanese<br />

literature and history of ideas, and her publications include articles on<br />

classical Japanese dream poetry and modern literary issues, such as the<br />

writings of Serizawa Kqjird and Miyamoto Yuriko. She is currently<br />

working on a postdoctoral thesis on the impact of Sartrean existentialism<br />

on post-war Japanese literature and intellectual thought. Reflecting that<br />

research, she has presented papers at various international conferences,<br />

including those of the French, the UK, and the North American Sartre<br />

Societies. Among her publications on Sartre are studies of his concept of<br />

freedom in the writings of Noma Hiroshi, and of the influence of his<br />

universalism in post-war Japan. Simone's latest article, considering the<br />

impact of existentialism on the writings of Shiina Rinzo and 6e<br />

Kenzaburo, is published in the German periodical Bochumer Jahrbuch zur<br />

Ostasienforschung (Fall 2008).<br />

BENEDICT O'DONOHOE<br />

Ben O'Donohoe took his first degree in French and his doctorate at<br />

Magdalen College, Oxford, and is now Head of Modern Languages at the<br />

University of Sussex. He has published Sartre*s Theatre: Acts for Life<br />

(Peter Lang, 2005) and a critical edition of <strong>Sartre's</strong> screenplay, Les Jeux<br />

sontfaits (Routledge, 1990), plus a score of articles or chapters in the UK,<br />

France, Canada, Japan, the USA and Australia. He has also given<br />

numerous papers, notably around <strong>Sartre's</strong> centenary celebration in 2005,<br />

to conferences in San Francisco, New York, Tokyo, Toronto, Bath,<br />

Bristol, London, Leeds, Dublin and Paris. He is currently President of the<br />

UK Sartre Society and UK-side Reviews Editor of the journal Sartre<br />

Studies International<br />

IANRHOAD<br />

Ian Rhoad is a doctoral student in the Department of Philosophy at the<br />

New School for Social Research in New York City, and Adjunct Instructor<br />

of Philosophy at St Johns University. He has presented numerous papers at<br />

academic conferences, most recently a paper entitled "The Politics of<br />

Spectacle" at the Graduate Student Philosophy Conference at Emory<br />

University. His current research focuses on twentieth-<strong>century</strong> French<br />

thought and the idea of democracy.


218 Contributors<br />

PETER ROYLE<br />

Peter Royle is a Professor Emeritus at Trent University, Peterborough,<br />

Ontario. He has published numerous articles on Sartre as well as three<br />

books: UEnfer et la liberte: le theatre de Sartre (Presses de l'Universite<br />

Laval, 1973); The Sartre-Camus Controversy: A Literary and Philosophical<br />

Critique (University of Ottawa Press, 1982); L'Homme et le neant chez<br />

Jean-Paul Sartre (Laval, 2005). He organized a major conference of the<br />

North American Sartre Society at Trent University in May 1993, and has<br />

given papers on guilt and responsibility, and on the Sartrean conception of<br />

space, at annual conferences of the Groupe d*etudes sartriennes in Paris.<br />

He has also given many other papers at conferences in Canada, the USA,<br />

the UK, Ireland, and South Africa.<br />

BRADLEY STEPHENS<br />

Bradley Stephens is Lecturer in French at the University of Bristol, UK.<br />

He is a member of the Executive Committees of both the UK Sartre<br />

Society and BIRTHA (Bristol Institute for Research in The Humanities<br />

and Arts). His research focuses on literary cultures of engagement in the<br />

nineteenth and twentieth centuries, and he has published various articles<br />

and book contributions in this field, including work on Sartre, Victor<br />

Hugo, Walter Benjamin, Charles Renouvier, and John Steinbeck. He is<br />

also the co-editor of Transmissions: Essays in French Literature, Thought<br />

and Cinema (Peter Lang, 2007), and is currently preparing another book<br />

that explores previously overlooked connections between Sartre and Hugo.<br />

WILLIE THOMPSON<br />

Willie Thompson was formerly Professor of Contemporary History at<br />

Glasgow Caledonian University, Scotland. He is currently retired and lives<br />

in Sunderland.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!