07.12.2012 Views

Distinctive Features - Speech Resource Pages - Macquarie University

Distinctive Features - Speech Resource Pages - Macquarie University

Distinctive Features - Speech Resource Pages - Macquarie University

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

8. Possible Objections to <strong>Distinctive</strong> <strong>Features</strong><br />

<strong>Distinctive</strong> features are based on binary features. This was a choice made early<br />

in their development and is based on Trubetzkoy's privative (binary) distinctions.<br />

The choice was made because it simplified the writing of phonological rules. You<br />

should note, however, that Trubetzkoy also allowed for gradual distinctions. This<br />

type of feature has been taken up by phoneticians (e.g. Ladefoged, 1971, used a<br />

single feature for height with up to four levels for the same feature). It also<br />

seems desirable to represent consonant place of articulation as an "equipollent"<br />

(see Trubetzkoy, above) continuum of independent features only one of which<br />

may be selected for a simple articulation (e.g. alveolar for /d/). For complex<br />

articulations, two or more such features might be selected (e.g. labial plus velar<br />

for /w/).<br />

The nature of some of the features (e.g. distributed) seem quite arbitrary and<br />

motivated by the need to disambiguate unseparated vowel or consonant pairs.<br />

Sometimes these feature choices are not supported by phonetic research and<br />

their sole strength is their usefulness in the writing of rules.<br />

The motivation to develop a system that optimises the expression of rules begs<br />

the question - what justifies the belief that humans use rules of this kind? If we<br />

can't prove that humans use phonological rules (particularly rules of the kind<br />

used in this kind of phonology) then we can't use the need to write simpler rules<br />

as a justification for binary features.<br />

Another problem is the way in which distinctive features are related to the<br />

articulatory or acoustic properties of a sound. Initially it seemed that a feature<br />

should be described in terms of acoustic and/or articulatory correlates. The idea<br />

was that such properties were only physical correlates of an internal cognitive<br />

entity (i.e. distinctive features exist only in the brain). Further, acoustic<br />

correlates were dropped from many descriptions of distinctive features (e.g.<br />

Chomsky and Halle, 1968). The notion of distinctive feature became increasingly<br />

abstract as their description moved away from Jakobson's idea that the features<br />

should be clearly defined in terms of their physiological and acoustic correlates.<br />

Moving away from such externally measurable correlates might be argued to be<br />

justified on the grounds that physical and mental reality are not identical, but<br />

doing so also moves away from the possibility of hypothesis falsifiability, the<br />

basis of modern science. "Falsifiability (or refutability or testability) is the logical<br />

possibility that an assertion can be shown false by an observation or a physical<br />

experiment" (Wikipedia).<br />

The above issues bring us to the question of psychological reality. Do human<br />

brains use distinctive features, or more generally features of any kind, in the<br />

specification (and production and perception) of phonemes? If we do, then do we<br />

use the features that have been described above (or similar sets of features)?<br />

Sometimes phonological proof has resembled the strategies of formal logic<br />

whereby proof may consist of providing a logically internally consistent system of<br />

rules and features. Do human brains use rules in normal speech cognition?

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!