12.11.2019 Views

Abstracted Law, Abstracted Art

Brussels Biennial, 2008

Brussels Biennial, 2008

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

<strong>Abstracted</strong> <strong>Law</strong>,<br />

<strong>Abstracted</strong> <strong>Art</strong>:<br />

Clearing the Way for<br />

Global Ideology?<br />

Fernand Keuleneer<br />

A contemporary art biennial is<br />

not an art fair, or at least, so it<br />

claims. Recently, some biennials<br />

have taken this a step further and<br />

seen it as their mission to move<br />

beyond the presentation of art,<br />

and instead to contribute to a<br />

critical artistic reflection on the<br />

social and political environment in<br />

which they take place. To a degree,<br />

this is also true of the new Brussels<br />

Biennial. The Brussels World Fair<br />

of 1958, introducing modernity<br />

into the fabric of the city, lies at<br />

the basis of the reflection that will<br />

characterize this first edition of<br />

the Biennial. As was stated in the<br />

letter requesting this essay: “The<br />

2008 Biennial is situated in a very<br />

different epoch of modernity, in<br />

a time when the possibilities of<br />

modernism are reconsidered in a<br />

climate of globalization and the<br />

ideologies of post-nationalism,<br />

diversity and hybridization.” Quite<br />

a handful of heavily-laden terms in<br />

one sentence! Later in the letter,<br />

the description of current epoch is<br />

appropriately toned down to one<br />

of “intuitive insight,” rather than the<br />

well-considered conclusion of a<br />

rational analysis.<br />

The mission of this contribution<br />

is to describe current transformative<br />

developments in the area<br />

323<br />

of law, as much within the legal<br />

system itself as with regard to the<br />

functions given to it by policymakers<br />

and opinion leaders. The<br />

ultimate aim of this exercise, which<br />

might look a little far-fetched at first<br />

sight, is to speculate on whether<br />

there might be some link or similarity<br />

between those developments<br />

and certain trends in contemporary<br />

art, both on the artistic level and<br />

as regards the uses made of. And<br />

if there is, can a biennial, and more<br />

specifically a contemporary art<br />

biennial in Brussels, or any other<br />

artistic forum or “intuitive insight,”<br />

genuinely and usefully contribute<br />

to a meaningful debate about the<br />

issues raised? I propose to discuss<br />

what I call the risk, to both law and<br />

contemporary art, of fragmentation<br />

by abstraction. (Bear with me,<br />

I readily admit this requires some<br />

clarification).<br />

Western Europeans commonly<br />

consider Brussels to be the capital<br />

of the European Union, if not the<br />

center of Europe. However, prior<br />

even to being the capital of the<br />

European Union, Brussels was, and<br />

still is, the linchpin of Belgium, and<br />

by extension of the wider region,<br />

which the organizers of the Brussels<br />

Biennial sometimes refer to<br />

as the “Eurocore.” Throughout<br />

European history, this region has<br />

been a permeable space, a meeting<br />

ground for purposes of peaceful<br />

exchange as well as confrontation<br />

between cultures and political<br />

forces. The “Eurocore” region is<br />

not only an idea; it has for a very<br />

long time been an unmistakable<br />

geo-political reality. The big question<br />

before us is this: will Europe<br />

and the European Union continue<br />

to emanate from, incorporate and<br />

indeed embody these geographical,<br />

historical, political and cultural<br />

realities? Or will the new European<br />

construction become an abstraction,<br />

i.e. a “new order” decoupled<br />

from and superimposed upon the<br />

fabric of particulars that has come<br />

to constitute, in the course of<br />

history, a complex of connections<br />

understood as a whole?<br />

I would argue that the new<br />

European order is increasingly taking<br />

shape as an abstraction, based<br />

on the notion of the “European<br />

Citizen,” thereby radically hollowing<br />

out the historically evolved<br />

social and political tissue of states,<br />

nations, societies and cultures,<br />

and replacing it with a great deal of<br />

ideology. The new Europe does not<br />

have to follow this direction, but it<br />

looks likely that it will from this point<br />

on. To illustrate this development,<br />

let us consider some of the developments<br />

in the area of the law.<br />

BB08-Catalogue Brussels Biennial 1_DEF+Robijns.indd 323<br />

01.10.2008 12:01:18 Uhr


A legal system can be described<br />

as a fabric of coherent<br />

and enforceable rules and principles<br />

that help to organize state<br />

and society and which govern the<br />

relationships among citizens. Any<br />

legal system is intimately linked with<br />

a political system, which is about<br />

power (including the power to<br />

shape, enforce and change the law)<br />

that is exercised through political<br />

decisions. In a democracy (which<br />

requires communities that are sufficiently<br />

coherent), political decisions<br />

are made by elected representatives,<br />

almost always after debate<br />

and compromise. For the past few<br />

hundreds of years, such communities<br />

have been known as nationstates<br />

and have formed the basis<br />

of democratic politics. A process<br />

of democratic politics instils public<br />

debate, and imperfect as it may be,<br />

the notion of common good.<br />

Both law and politics<br />

ultimately aim to create or maintain<br />

a just society, or at least this is<br />

what they are supposed to aim<br />

for. The currency of politics is the<br />

regulated but undisguised exercise<br />

of power. The classical modus<br />

operandi of the law is different.<br />

Judges used to apply and interpret<br />

the law; they did not legislate,<br />

and for good reason. One of the<br />

most critical political and societal<br />

decisions is to determine whom<br />

we entrust with the final say on key<br />

political issues. In a democracy,<br />

this final say resides with elected<br />

representatives, not with unelected<br />

judges.<br />

There is a current general tendency<br />

whereby supranational and<br />

international courts and judges are<br />

being increasingly entrusted with<br />

taking fundamental political decisions.<br />

This is by no means a merely<br />

technical shift. On the contrary, it<br />

amounts to a creeping and hidden<br />

transformation of the political and<br />

legal system, entrusting the judiciary,<br />

rather than elected bodies,<br />

324<br />

with the final say on societal issues<br />

of basic importance.<br />

The preferred instrument or<br />

technique to achieve and accelerate<br />

this transformation is the<br />

legalization of politics through a<br />

multiplication of rights—thus legal<br />

norms, rather than moral concepts<br />

or policy guidelines. In doing so,<br />

it is relatively easy to translate a<br />

program of political action that<br />

requires a majority vote to be<br />

accepted, into legal norms, to be<br />

ruled upon and enforced by courts.<br />

Particularly powerful and efficient<br />

in this respect are “human rights,”<br />

which are considered to be fundamental<br />

and constitutional rights,<br />

and therefore find their place at<br />

the top and in the core of the legal<br />

system. At the top of the hierarchy,<br />

these rights always prevail over<br />

norms, which are positioned on a<br />

hierarchically inferior rank, such as<br />

legislation that would violate those<br />

fundamental rights. Therefore, the<br />

vaster the scope and domain of<br />

human rights, the less influence<br />

a democratic change of power<br />

by means of elections will have.<br />

So, if essential societal decisions<br />

only require a vote by a handful<br />

of appointed judges and can be<br />

maintained even against a political<br />

majority that might decide otherwise,<br />

why bother to try to convince<br />

the majority of the people, or<br />

wage election campaigns? Whoever<br />

controls the judicial power,<br />

will no longer need to convince<br />

the people: his word will be law.<br />

Through the legalization of politics,<br />

using the proliferation of human<br />

rights as a seemingly innocent and<br />

even laudable instrument, a new<br />

elite imposes itself, and changes<br />

the distribution of power in society.<br />

Here is a first connection with<br />

contemporary art biennials and<br />

their artistic communities: the elevation<br />

of ever more human rights<br />

to the top of the legal hierarchy,<br />

moral and good at first sight as this<br />

may be, is broadly supported by<br />

the artistic community and meets<br />

with little resistance. But making<br />

an abstraction of human rights,<br />

isolating them from their political<br />

and institutional environment (let<br />

alone creating a quasi-religion of<br />

human rights) may have unintended<br />

(or intended?) consequences. An<br />

intuitive or moral decision cannot<br />

replace the hard analysis of what<br />

the effects are in the context of the<br />

political and the legal system, and<br />

certainly should not replace the<br />

eternal political question: “Who<br />

benefits?” In this case, definitely<br />

not democracy as traditionally<br />

understood.<br />

The project for a European<br />

Constitution, copied into the<br />

Treaty of Lisbon, illustrates this<br />

obfuscated process. The Treaty<br />

clears the way for a gouvernement<br />

des juges [a government of<br />

judges.] Which kind of decisions<br />

will be transferred to the final say<br />

of the Union judiciary? Out of the<br />

Treaty’s lucky bag of general principles<br />

of law, classical freedom<br />

rights, political rights, and economic<br />

and social rights pop out:<br />

the principle of “inviolability of<br />

human dignity,” the “right to life,”<br />

“freedom of thought, conscience<br />

and religion,” “freedom of the<br />

arts and sciences,” the “right of<br />

education,” the principle of “nondiscrimination,”<br />

the “rights of the<br />

child,” the “rights of the elderly,”<br />

“workers’ right to information and<br />

consultation within the undertaking,”<br />

the “right of access to placement<br />

services,” the “right to health<br />

care,” the “right to a high level of<br />

consumer protection”… And this<br />

is only a selection. One can barely<br />

think of a domain of public life in<br />

which courts do not obtain the<br />

power to rule that they should have<br />

the final say.<br />

It is far from clear which<br />

types of claims can originate from<br />

this range of fundamental rights,<br />

BB08-Catalogue Brussels Biennial 1_DEF+Robijns.indd 324<br />

01.10.2008 12:01:18 Uhr


and these rights and freedoms,<br />

all on an equal footing, will often<br />

collide with each other. Defining,<br />

streamlining, interpreting and<br />

applying them touches upon the<br />

very essence of the representative<br />

democratic model, which enables<br />

citizens to express strongly diverse<br />

political convictions through elected<br />

representatives, who will then<br />

have to reach an understanding<br />

based upon deliberation. However,<br />

as stated, this model is being buried.<br />

In the new order, courts take<br />

the final decisions, less as a result<br />

of predictable legal reasoning (for<br />

which there is no sound basis,)<br />

than as a function of the preferences<br />

of the court. These decisions<br />

will be increasingly arbitrary, since<br />

they rely on vague and conflicting<br />

principles. As a result—reduced<br />

as it is to a mere instrument in a<br />

less and less ordered struggle for<br />

power—the law itself degenerates.<br />

Some claim that the Treaty<br />

does not extend the powers and<br />

competences of the European<br />

Union and that, at any rate, the<br />

principle of subsidiarity is maintained.<br />

This statement stains the<br />

truth. Whoever succeeds in presenting<br />

an issue over which Europe<br />

has no jurisdiction (yet) as a dispute<br />

pertaining to a “fundamental<br />

right of the Union”which is not that<br />

difficult to accomplish taking into<br />

consideration its extremely wide<br />

scope—succeeds in transforming<br />

the said issue into a matter of European<br />

law. Therefore, this Treaty<br />

facilitates a gigantic transfer of<br />

powers from the member states to<br />

the Union. Admittedly, on Britain’s<br />

initiative, the Treaty provides that<br />

the new fundamental rights do not<br />

extend the powers of the European<br />

Union, that they only apply to the<br />

institutions of the European Union<br />

and that they only bind the member<br />

states when they implement European<br />

law. However, can one really<br />

imagine that the new human rights<br />

325<br />

provisions, one of the key elements<br />

of such a basic document, will only<br />

apply to a limited segment of the<br />

law (i.e. European law) that governs<br />

the lives of citizens? Before long,<br />

the European Courts will decide<br />

otherwise.<br />

This development within the<br />

European Union goes hand in glove<br />

with a broader transformation of<br />

international law and a concomitant<br />

power shift to new supranational<br />

and international institutions and<br />

elites. Again, this is accomplished<br />

through the legalization of politics,<br />

and again, it is to the detriment<br />

of the democratic model as it has<br />

been understood until now.<br />

Classical international law (the<br />

<strong>Law</strong> of Nations) governed the legal<br />

aspect of relations among states.<br />

The international political or legal<br />

system did not have any direct authority<br />

vis-à-vis the individual, who<br />

had to depend on his own state<br />

and its political and legal system<br />

for the protection of his individual<br />

rights.<br />

As the concept “sovereign<br />

state” gradually occupies a much<br />

less central place in the international<br />

order, and may even be threatened<br />

with disappearance if some<br />

lobbies have their way, powerful<br />

advocates are attempting (though<br />

increasingly fiercely resisted by<br />

the new or returning world powers)<br />

to transform international law into<br />

global law. Unlike classical international<br />

law, such a global law would<br />

intervene in a variety of domestic<br />

matters, directly address individuals<br />

and bypass states, thereby<br />

profoundly modifying the balance<br />

between international and national<br />

(domestic) law. Legal globalists are<br />

attempting to structure and shape<br />

a unified “international citizen community”<br />

of individuals, which would<br />

take the place of the “national<br />

community.” Two key instruments<br />

to this end are, once again, the<br />

introduction of human rights and<br />

fundamental rights at the top of the<br />

new international legal system, and<br />

the attribution of an international<br />

law status to non-governmental<br />

organizations (NGOs).<br />

Of course, there is nothing<br />

wrong, as such, with a worldwide<br />

respect for the dignity of man;<br />

quite the contrary, indeed. But this<br />

is not what it is all about. Again,<br />

one should ask which purposes<br />

are served, in this particular legal<br />

context, by the proliferation of human<br />

rights. The answer is that they<br />

do not serve in the first place to<br />

achieve the noble goals that their<br />

promoters pretend to achieve, but<br />

primarily to redistribute power, to<br />

the detriment of states and their<br />

sphere of sovereign autonomy.<br />

This proliferation benefits both the<br />

imperial powers that consider sovereign<br />

states as obstacles to their<br />

conquest, and global agencies and<br />

networks whose legitimacy is often<br />

self-imposed. With such networks<br />

increasingly assuming the tasks<br />

and roles of states, concern with<br />

respect to the lack of democratic<br />

accountability of such mechanism<br />

seems to be more than justified.<br />

Moreover, society will not become<br />

more humane; quite the contrary, in<br />

fact. Since the “international citizen<br />

community” lacks the coherence<br />

of a national community that makes<br />

it acceptable for a minority to<br />

at least provisionally accept the<br />

vote of a majority, the limited and<br />

rules-based competition among<br />

forces and ideas will be replaced<br />

by a generalized permanent and<br />

unordered conflict.<br />

Notwithstanding the sort of<br />

May 68 ring that the prominence<br />

of human rights has to it, a similar<br />

analysis is now also being made<br />

by authors affiliated with the (true)<br />

left, as Ugo Mattei writes in his<br />

essay on the theory of imperial law:<br />

The rhetorical device used in<br />

the process of repressing deviance<br />

has been a genuinely legal<br />

BB08-Catalogue Brussels Biennial 1_DEF+Robijns.indd 325<br />

01.10.2008 12:01:18 Uhr


concept, that of “international<br />

human rights.” Indeed, a doctrine<br />

of limited sovereignty in the interest<br />

of international human rights has<br />

threatened the traditional nature of<br />

international law as a decentralized<br />

system based on territoriality, and<br />

has advocated the need for centralization<br />

in order to make international<br />

law more similar to systems<br />

of national law. The International<br />

Criminal Court is the most advanced<br />

point of this shift. Ad hoc<br />

courts, such as the one presently<br />

used against former Yugoslavian<br />

president Slobodan Milosevic, are<br />

the product of an even more open<br />

use of international law as en ex<br />

post facto legitimating factor of<br />

war. Today we believe that international<br />

law is not natural but positive<br />

law, whose fundamental sources<br />

are treaties and customs. Tomorrow,<br />

we might believe that international<br />

law is a worldwide legal<br />

system grounded in uniformity and<br />

in commonly shared ideals of law<br />

and order…Hence, sovereignty can<br />

be routinely addressed as deviance<br />

from a standard of legality grounded<br />

in U.S.-constructed international<br />

human rights. 1<br />

Michael Hardt and Antonio<br />

Negri, in their seminal Empire point<br />

to the same conclusion: It is in fact<br />

through the extension of internal<br />

constitutional processes that we<br />

enter into a constituent process<br />

of Empire. The transition we are<br />

witnessing today from traditional<br />

international law, which was defined<br />

by contracts and treaties, to<br />

the definition and constitution of a<br />

new sovereign, supranational world<br />

order (and thus to the imperial notion<br />

of right), however incomplete,<br />

gives us a framework in which to<br />

read the totalizing social process<br />

of Empire. 2<br />

The amalgamation of the<br />

national and international spheres<br />

into a global sphere is favored by<br />

groups and lobbies from different<br />

326<br />

philosophical and political angles.<br />

First of all, there are those motivated<br />

by an anti-statist philosophy,<br />

who believe that individuals ought<br />

to be the only subjects of a world<br />

community and its legal order,<br />

and the free associations of civil<br />

society their principal actors. State<br />

and government are considered<br />

oppressive and encroaching on<br />

the domain of freedom. The global<br />

order should be a market order.<br />

Natural rights should be non-negotiable<br />

and enforceable everywhere,<br />

and the legal order of the world<br />

community should provide the instruments<br />

to this effect. This group<br />

is traditionally situated on the<br />

libertarian right, has limited affinity<br />

with international bodies and agencies,<br />

but seems to be very much<br />

in favor of “constitutional litigation”<br />

individualizing the process of<br />

balancing rights through litigation,<br />

rather than through political debate.<br />

Its operating basis is mostly<br />

the United States, but its influence<br />

in Europe is marginally increasing<br />

through a network of think tanks.<br />

Some European free-market liberals/conservatives<br />

would fit into this<br />

category.<br />

A second category is constituted<br />

by those counting on networks<br />

to promote a new social and<br />

political agenda, one of personal<br />

autonomy and multiculturalism,<br />

which is apparently less easily pursued<br />

through majoritarian decisionmaking.<br />

Here one finds organized<br />

attempts to form, through interplay<br />

with international bodies and<br />

NGOs, a new international consensus<br />

on the basis of human rights.<br />

This consensus should serve as the<br />

basis for new norms and principles<br />

of international law, to be imported<br />

into national legal systems. The adherents<br />

of this approach are influential<br />

in the media and use courts<br />

as their favored transmission channel.<br />

Traditionally strong among<br />

the American liberal left, they have<br />

gained influence in Europe. The<br />

EU Charter of Fundamental Rights,<br />

and its incorporation into the Treaty<br />

of Lisbon, came into being under<br />

the influence of this group.<br />

A third current endeavors to<br />

create a new world order based on<br />

the principles of democratic capitalism.<br />

Some in this group find their<br />

inspiration in natural law and moral<br />

theology. They are opposed to the<br />

“new human rights” agenda and<br />

to judicial activism, but still want<br />

the legal system to enhance the<br />

agenda of spreading democratic<br />

capitalism.<br />

Different as the three currents<br />

may be on substantive issues, they<br />

do not seem to be that far apart in<br />

their concept of the proper relationship<br />

of national to international<br />

law. All three see international law<br />

as an instrument that should serve<br />

to usher nations into a global order,<br />

under the supervision of either<br />

the United Nations or the United<br />

States.<br />

Whereas the promotion and<br />

safeguarding of the dignity of man<br />

in a just society ought to be the<br />

ultimate goal and criterion of all<br />

political action, not all rights said to<br />

be fundamental human rights are<br />

perceived as such in all cultures.<br />

Seeking to enhance human dignity<br />

does not translate automatically<br />

into the need to create a global<br />

legal system. Such a system does<br />

not generally achieve the goals that<br />

its promoters, of different political<br />

colors, pretend they seek to<br />

achieve, but serves to redistribute<br />

power to the detriment of autonomous<br />

and sovereign states and<br />

for the benefit of global players,<br />

sometimes of doubtful legitimacy.<br />

The biennial movement is<br />

itself a diverse movement, broad<br />

in scope, but nevertheless known<br />

or perceived to be outspoken in its<br />

criticism of “neo-capitalism,” “neoliberalism”<br />

and the “marketization<br />

of society.” All very well, but does<br />

BB08-Catalogue Brussels Biennial 1_DEF+Robijns.indd 326<br />

01.10.2008 12:01:18 Uhr


it not itself constitute a globetrotting<br />

elite, constantly on the move,<br />

poorly connecting to the social<br />

tissue around its events? To what<br />

extent do the installations shown<br />

carry a message that is meaningful<br />

to a broader public, beyond the<br />

limited circle of curators and their<br />

disciples? If biennials are about art<br />

that is not embedded in a particular<br />

cultural context that makes it<br />

understandable and meaningful<br />

to a community, it abstracts and<br />

de-links art from its natural environment<br />

in the same way as the<br />

normative legal order may become<br />

de-coupled and de-linked from any<br />

particular community. When the<br />

abstract notion of human rights,<br />

with all its contradictions and arbitrariness,<br />

becomes the supreme<br />

legal norm and replaces a system<br />

rooted in the realities of history and<br />

tradition, law cedes to power plays.<br />

Something similar is going on in the<br />

art world. Until recently, the mere<br />

self-expression of the artist was<br />

considered a valued freedom, but<br />

no more than that. Now, self-expression<br />

is increasingly developing<br />

into the ultimate, untouchable and<br />

virtually uncriticizable norm to determine<br />

what constitutes art. “<strong>Art</strong>”<br />

therefore is becoming denuded<br />

from, and thus also unchecked and<br />

uncontained by, communal notions<br />

that are a product of history and<br />

tradition. As a result, the arbitrary<br />

replaces the rich, complex and<br />

evolving ordered reality of art. My<br />

word is or at least ought to be law!<br />

My statement is or at least ought<br />

to be art! This way, pure selfimportance,<br />

often coupled with<br />

a ruthless will to power, come to<br />

determine what law is, or what art<br />

is. Abolishing any obstacle to this<br />

process, in particular neutralizing<br />

resistant mediating structures and<br />

worlds such as law and art (at least<br />

as they were commonly understood<br />

until recently), seems to be a<br />

priority for the adherents of global<br />

327<br />

ideology. To the extent that they<br />

promote this new art and help to<br />

superpose these new art elites, biennials—as<br />

critical as they may be<br />

or pretend to be—might therefore<br />

be highly instrumental for those<br />

who have an interest in accelerating<br />

the process of fragmentation<br />

by abstraction as described in this<br />

essay. As we have argued, power is<br />

the name of the game here.<br />

Neo-liberalism and a globalmarket<br />

society have undoubtedly<br />

many shortcomings (the main failure<br />

of neo-liberalism being the promotion<br />

of capitalism where capital<br />

is replaced by debt—a system that<br />

is arguably the opposite of capitalism.)<br />

However, more immediately<br />

consequential may be the disruption<br />

of a valuable social fabric<br />

through the break-up of common<br />

institutions and their replacement<br />

by mere assertions of individual<br />

rights and claims. Such an institutional<br />

break-up would reinforce<br />

and go in tandem with a cultural<br />

break-up of societies. The cult of<br />

un-ordered diversity, through the<br />

celebration of radical individualism,<br />

the rejection of a heritage manifesting<br />

itself in the ridiculing of popular<br />

culture and values, are clear symptoms<br />

of this, while the concomitant<br />

superposition of new elites is an<br />

inevitable side-effect, if not the<br />

explicitly aimed-for objective.<br />

A biennial cannot escape the<br />

question of where it positions itself<br />

in this universe. As Udo Di Fabio<br />

points out 3 , the critics of capitalism<br />

in fact gave the starting signal for<br />

the globalization of the economy.<br />

Detached and “liberated” as they<br />

were from the bounds of tradition,<br />

and de-legitimizing state, family,<br />

education and educational institutions,<br />

they laid the groundwork<br />

for the single market without any<br />

cultural barriers to entry.<br />

In a society where so much is<br />

fake, where the rhetoric of human<br />

rights is less about the dignity of<br />

man than about the redistribution<br />

of power, where wars are started<br />

on the basis of deception disguised<br />

in human-rights clothing, at<br />

least art should not be fake. A biennial<br />

should in the first place present<br />

genuine and meaningful art, which,<br />

like building a coherent system of<br />

law, requires craft and vision and<br />

never exists by virtue of a mere intention<br />

or concept (like abstracted<br />

human rights.) <strong>Art</strong> always relates<br />

to an actual and living community.<br />

Whether artists like it or not, art,<br />

just like law, is always embedded<br />

in a context of meaning determined<br />

by the complex interaction<br />

of history and tradition, individuals<br />

and nations, nature and culture,<br />

religion and rebellion…This context<br />

of meaning is never explainable<br />

in a fully rational way. It remains<br />

very much intuitive. In that sense,<br />

intuition constitutes an essential<br />

characteristic of art, just as it is an<br />

essential characteristic of law.<br />

The author thanks his law associate<br />

Jelle Flo for his valuable comments<br />

and suggestions.<br />

Notes<br />

1. Ugo Mattei, “A Theory of Imperial<br />

<strong>Law</strong>: A Study on U.S. Hegemony and the Latin<br />

Resistance,” Global Jurist Frontiers, Volume 3,<br />

Issue 2, <strong>Art</strong>icle 1, 2003, pp. 16–17. Available at:<br />

http://www.bepress.com/gj/frontiers/vol3/<br />

iss2/art1<br />

2. Michael Hardt and Antonio Negri,<br />

Empire, Cambridge: Harvard University Press,<br />

2001, 182, pp. 9–10.<br />

3. Udo di Fabio, Die Kultur der Freiheit,<br />

Munich: C.H. Beck Verlag, 2005), p. 40.<br />

BB08-Catalogue Brussels Biennial 1_DEF+Robijns.indd 327<br />

01.10.2008 12:01:18 Uhr

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!