03.03.2021 Views

From Frontiero to the Air Force: Citizenship and Equal Protection in U.S. Reproduction Jurisprudence

Olivia Siemens '21

Olivia Siemens '21

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

From ​Frontiero​ to the Air Force: Citizenship and Equal Protection in U.S. Reproduction

Jurisprudence

Olivia Siemens

Abstract

Since the late 20th century, the Supreme Court has upheld female reproductive rights as a

subset of the implied constitutional right to privacy. This essay argues that the Constitution’s

intertwined proceduralist and equal protection standards, established first in ​Frontiero v.

Richardson​ (1973) and guided by the historical context of legal sex discrimination in the United

States, should instead govern the Court’s assessments of women’s reproductive autonomy cases.

Rather than defending ​Roe v. Wade​’s tenuous privacy justifications for a woman’s right to

choose, this essay will emphasize the discriminatory impacts of anti-choice laws and provide an

alternative constitutional remedy for addressing the procedural inequities inherent in such

legislation. This dual process- and equality-oriented approach encourages jurists to recognize the

concrete social, economic, and political constraints that abortion restrictions pose to women’s

equal standing in the American political community. It recognizes that many anti-abortion laws

amount to arbitrary constraints on a woman’s life, liberty, and property interests, thus ensuring

that women remain relegated to a state of permanent second-class citizenship. By clarifying this

inherent link between procedural and substantive sex equality, this approach seeks once and for

all to place men and women on truly equal constitutional footing under the Equal Protection

Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment.

Introduction

In 1973, the United States Supreme Court decided a case that would permanently alter

the landscape of American constitutional law. It laid the foundation for women to assert their

independence from discriminatory and explicitly gendered legislation. It created a legal

framework for the recognition of female bodily autonomy grounded in the Constitution’s due

process guarantees. It offered women the chance to venture beyond the realm of domesticity, to

transcend their culturally prescribed roles as homemakers and caretakers, and to pursue their

1


independent economic, political, and societal ambitions. This case was not ​Roe v. Wade​. It was

Frontiero v. Richardson​.

In 1969, Lieutenant Sharron Frontiero, a 23-year-old Air Force officer, sought and was

denied military spousal benefits for her dependent husband. Had Frontiero been a man, these

spousal benefits would have been granted automatically. Because she was a woman, she was

required to prove that her husband was dependent on her for over one-half of their joint income.

When her application was rejected, Frontiero filed a lawsuit against the federal government,

arguing that her rights under the Fifth Amendment’s Due Process Clause had been violated by

this discriminatory dependency standard. A three-judge panel in the Middle District of Alabama

first sided with the government to uphold the standard on rational review grounds.​ 1​ In an 8–1

decision, the Supreme Court reversed, holding that the government’s dependency standard

exerted an unconstitutional burden on Frontiero’s political and economic liberty.

Writing for the majority, Justice William Brennan argues that the law’s invidious

assumptions about sex differences amounted to discrimination “so unjustifiable as to be violative

of due process.” Operating under the auspices of so-called “romantic paternalism”—a set of

cultural and legal attitudes which had historically justified the arbitrary preference of men over

women—Brennan writes that discriminatory laws had served to “put women not on a pedestal,

but in a cage.” A person’s sex “frequently bears no relation to ability to perform or contribute to

society,” he continues, and as such, “statutory distinctions between the sexes often have the

effect of invidiously relegating the entire class of females to inferior legal status without regard

to the actual capabilities of its individual members.”​ 2

The Court’s ruling in ​Frontiero​ established a novel legal basis for future generations of

jurisprudence aimed at outlawing pervasive sex discrimination. It prohibited the conflation of

gender with inherent ability, and it rejected the premise that an entire classification of persons

might be stereotyped as ineligible for full constitutional standing. Finally, it grounded these

ideals not only in the Fourteenth Amendment’s expanded Equal Protection Clause but also in the

procedural protections required by the original Bill of Rights.

1

“Rational basis review” is the least onerous standard of judicial review. It requires only that a statute or ordinance

serves a “legitimate state interest” and that there be a “rational connection” between the statute’s/ordinance’s

“means and goals.” See: “Rational Basis Test,” Cornell Legal Information Institute,

https://www.law.cornell.edu/wex/rational_basis_test​.

2

​Frontiero v. Richardson​, 411 U.S. 677 (1973).

2


History and Domesticity

While the U.S. Framers may have understood some notion of political equality to be

implicit in the structure of the Constitution, the original document makes no affirmative

overtures to equality. It was not until 1868, nearly a century after the Founding, that

constitutional equality was made an explicit right of citizenship via the ratification of the

Fourteenth Amendment. In the decades immediately thereafter, the Fourteenth Amendment’s

equal protection guarantee was applied inconsistently by the courts and political branches and

was reserved for men alone. For another century, federal and state courts, comprised exclusively

of male judges, often allowed discriminatory laws to stand in the name of protecting women.

Their decisions reflected the same “romantic paternalism” which, as Justice Brennan so aptly

noted, served not to privilege women but instead to exclude them from full participation in

American society.​ 3

For the majority of U.S. history, constitutional mechanisms designed to prohibit arbitrary

constraints on individual liberties have done little to remedy invidious sex discrimination.

Instead, American legal institutions have actively taken part in formalizing sex-based

stereotypes, preventing women from claiming the same rights that male citizens have enjoyed

freely since the Founding. In one such case, ​Bradwell v. The State ​(1873), the Supreme Court

upheld an Illinois state law prohibiting female citizens from obtaining a license to practice law.

The Court plainly rejected Myra Bradwell’s constitutional claim to equal protection under the

Fourth and Fourteenth Amendments for the following reason:

Man is, or should be, woman’s protector and defender. The natural and proper

timidity and delicacy which belongs to the female sex evidently unfits it for many

of the occupations of civil life. The Constitution of the family organization, which

is founded in the divine ordinance as well as in the nature of things, indicates the

domestic sphere as that which properly belongs to the domain and functions of

womanhood. The harmony, not to say identity, of interest and views which

belong, or should belong, to the family institution is repugnant to the idea of a

woman adopting a distinct and independent career from that of her husband.​ 4

Bradwell​ exemplifies precisely how constitutionally-sanctioned sex discrimination worked to

relegate women to a permanently inferior status under the law. Relying on flawed assumptions

about the inherent “timidity and delicacy” of the female sex, the ​Bradwell​ majority categorically

3

Ibid.

4

​Bradwell v. The State​, 83 U.S. 130 (1872).

3


disqualified women from claiming the right to seek gainful employment while simultaneously

reaffirming this same right for men.​ 5​ In reserving a different set of rights for each gender, the

Court in essence created two distinct and unequal classes of citizenship, each entitled to a

different range of constitutional liberties. Section One of the Fourteenth Amendment defines

citizenship and its corresponding rights as follows:

All persons born or naturalized in the United States and subject to the jurisdiction

thereof, are citizens of the United States and of the State wherein they reside. No

State shall make or enforce any law which shall abridge the privileges or

immunities of citizens of the United States; nor shall any State deprive any person

of life, liberty, or property, without due process of law; nor deny to any person

within its jurisdiction the equal protection of the laws.​ 6

In ​Bradwell​, however, the Court explicitly refused to acknowledge that women were entitled,

under either the Privileges and Immunities or the Equal Protection Clause of the Fourteenth

Amendment “to engage in any and every profession, occupation, or employment in civil life.”​ 7

While the decision referred to women as “citizens,” it outright rejected the notion that female

citizenship conferred upon women the same rights as male citizenship did men. Men, the more

“rational” and “civic-minded” sex, could claim full republican citizenship, including the right to

earn a living and contribute to the economic prosperity of the nation. Women, on the other hand,

were deemed “[unfit] for many of the occupations of civil life” and thus confined to a separate

“domestic sphere” of citizenship.​ 8​ The Court’s implication here is self-evident: women enjoyed

only those rights deemed appropriate to the nature and abilities of the female sex. Bound to

respect the whims of political representatives they did not elect—and lacking both procedural

and substantive constitutional remedies—women in the early republic were subject to a

government of men, not of laws.

Republican Citizenship: Representation and Equality

The passage of the Nineteenth Amendment in 1920, which barred states from denying a

person’s right to vote based on her sex, carried with it the prospect that American women might,

for the first time, enjoy the same citizenship stature as their male counterparts. Once granted the

5

Ibid.

6

U.S. Const. amend. XIV, §1.

7

​Bradwell​, 83 U.S. 130.

8

Ibid​.

4


exercise of that which Chief Justice Earl Warren considered “preservative of all rights,” full

republican citizenship finally appeared within the reach of the female sex.​ 9​ Still, questions

remained: After female suffrage was secured, would the Constitution guarantee women equal

standing under American law? Which other rights would women have to secure in order to

achieve something resembling full constitutional liberty? And what might the Constitution have

to say about the connection between representation and equality? John Hart Ely’s proceduralist

theory of constitutional interpretation provides some basic answers. In his book ​Democracy and

Distrust​, Ely conceives of the Court as a mechanism for policing the process of democratic

representation. He argues that the Constitution does not enshrine substantive values or guarantee

equal outcomes but instead attempts to lay out a fair system—one that guarantees that every

citizen is included on equal footing in the democratic process. He writes:

[O]ur Constitution has always been substantially concerned with preserving

liberty. If it weren’t, it would hardly be worth fighting for. The question… is how

that concern has been pursued. The principal answers to that, we have seen, are by

a quite extensive set of procedural protections, and by a still more elaborate

scheme designed to ensure that in the making of substantive choices the decision

process will be open to all on something approaching an equal basis.​ 10

The central idea that Ely captures here is that the Constitution—and by extension, the Court

tasked with interpreting it—preserves individual liberties by ensuring each citizen (a) a fair

decision-making process and (b) an equal opportunity to participate in that process. While access

to the democratic process, he argues, is a person’s primary means of protecting their liberty, Ely

also notes that:

Other provisions, however—centrally but not exclusively the Equal Protection

Clause—reflect a realization that access will not always be sufficient… [The

Constitution] has sought to assure … that the process of individual application

will not be manipulated so as to reintroduce in practice the sort of discrimination

that is impermissible in theory.​ 11

This passage is critical to our understanding of how the Constitution’s procedural protections

square with its apparent substantive concern for equality. With respect to protecting

constitutional liberty, Ely points out, inequality is a procedural issue as much as it is a

9

​Reynolds v. Sims​, 377 U.S. 533 (1964).

10

John Hart Ely, ​Democracy and Distrust: A Theory of Judicial Review​ (Cambridge: Harvard University Press,

1980), 100.

11

Ibid., 100–101.

5


substantive issue. Ely’s conception of a level democratic playing field does not merely permit

but ​requires​ the Constitution to protect against any form of discrimination that leads to

procedural unfairness. Representation alone, Ely recognizes, is often insufficient to guarantee

participational equity in a society where a legislative majority may manipulate the law to

reproduce discriminatory processes.

This is why, in Ely’s view, the ​Carolene Products​ footnote theorizes a higher level of

scrutiny for laws that may uniquely impact the rights of “discrete and insular minorities.”​ 12​ Ely

writes, “[T]hey ask us to focus… on whether the opportunity to participate either in the political

processes by which values are appropriately identified and accommodated, or in the

accommodation those processes have reached, has been unduly constricted.”​ 13​ ​ Ely understands

that substantive inequality in the political process triggers a vicious cycle of procedural inequity.

Discriminatory laws not only diminish the substantive liberties of a given minority group but

also prevent this group from addressing their grievances through normal democratic

channels—virtually guaranteeing perpetual discrimination in subsequent policy outcomes. In

order to protect the participatory interests of all citizens, he posits, the Court may call for such

legislation to withstand “more exacting judicial scrutiny under the general prohibitions of the

Fourteenth Amendment.”​ 14

Sex Equality and the Court

Still, the Supreme Court was slow to apply this exacting scrutiny standard to cases

involving sex classifications.​ ​ Over fifty years passed after the passage of the Nineteenth

Amendment before the Court truly recognized sex discrimination as a minority rights issue.

Finally, beginning in the 1970s, the Court started to see sex discrimination, in many of its forms,

as an unconstitutional violation of the rights and liberties of both men and women. In a series of

12

​United States v. Carolene Products Co​. was a 1938 case that upheld a federal law restricting shipments of certain

milk substitutes under rational basis review. The majority opinion, written by Justice Harlan Stone, contains a

footnote (Footnote 4), which indicates that the Court should apply a higher form of judicial scrutiny to laws that

might disproportionately infringe on the constitutional rights of “discrete and insular minorities.” Stone did not

specify the requirements of this “exacting standard,” but subsequent courts have nevertheless referenced Footnote 4

in their development of both “intermediate” and “strict” scrutiny tests. See: ​United States v. Carolene Products Co.​,

304 U.S. 144 (1938).

13

Ely, ​Democracy​, 77.

14

Ibid., 76.

6


landmark cases throughout this decade, the Burger Court—in spite of its notably conservative

composition—proved receptive to incorporating sex as a suspect criterion entitled to heightened

judicial scrutiny under the Fourteenth Amendment.

In ​Reed v. Reed ​(1971)​, ​the Court ruled for the first time that laws subjecting the two

sexes to different treatment “on the basis of their sex” could be struck down on a rational basis

review under the Equal Protection Clause.​ 15​ In ​Frontiero v. Richardson ​(1973)​, ​Justice Brennan

and three of his colleagues entreated the Court to subject legal sex classifications to a strict

scrutiny standard of review.​ 16​ In applying this standard—the most stringent form of judicial

review—the Court would have required legislatures making policy distinctions on the basis of

sex to demonstrate a “compelling state interest” for the distinction and language “narrowly

tailored” to the legislative purpose.​ 17​ The majority refrained, hoping that the prospective

ratification of the Equal Rights Amendment would instead bring forth a political resolution to the

women’s rights question.​ 18​ Still, three years later, in ​Craig v. Boren ​(1976), the Court agreed to

adopt a new “intermediate standard” for sex classifications, which would require governments to

prove that their sex-based legal distinctions bore a “substantial relationship” to an “important

governmental [objective].”​ 19

Each of these decisions grappled with two primary questions: first, which types of

legislative enactments might trigger heightened scrutiny under the Equal Protection Clause; and

second, the role of the Court in making such determinations in the first place. Since its rulings in

Reed, Frontiero, ​and​ Craig,​ the Court has expanded the use of the Equal Protection Clause to

extend many constitutional protections to American women. As a result, most women in the

United States today likely enjoy a greater degree of personal and political freedom than would

have been possible at any other time in the nation’s history. But even as it has outlawed sex

15

​Reed v. Reed​, 404 U.S. 71 (1971).

16

Strict scrutiny review requires that a law not only serve a “compelling governmental interest” but also be

“narrowly tailored to achieve that interest.” Strict scrutiny is the highest judicial review standard, and it is most often

invoked to evaluate legislative measures that implicate equal protection considerations. See: “Strict scrutiny,”

Cornell Legal Information Institute,

https://www.law.cornell.edu/wex/strict_scrutiny#:~:text=Strict%20scrutiny%20is%20a%20form,sues%20the%20go

vernment%20for%20discrimination​.

17

Corey Brettschneider, ​Civil Rights and Liberties: Cases and Readings in Constitutional Law and American

Democracy​ (New York: Wolters Kluwer Law & Business, 2013), 806–07.

18

​Frontiero v. Richardson​, 411 U.S. 677 (1973) (Powell, J. concurring opinion).

19

​Craig v. Boren​, 429 U.S. 190 (1976).

7


discrimination in commercial hiring practices;​ 20​ ​ struck down mandatory maternity leave

policies;​ 21​ upheld equal pay requirements for male and female workers;​ 22​ and certified the rights

of married and unmarried women alike to obtain access to contraception—all at least partially

under the auspices of the Equal Protection Clause—the Court has failed to apply these same

equal protection criteria to enshrine an equality-based constitutional right to abortion access.​ 23

Rather than acknowledging that abortion restrictions place an unconstitutional burden on the

participatory rights of female (though not male) citizens, the Court has opted to inject an air of

false gender neutrality into its abortion jurisprudence.

Abortion as Privacy

The Supreme Court first recognized a constitutional right to abortion in the 1973 case

Roe v. Wade. ​In a 7–2 decision, the Court struck down a Texas law that outlawed abortion in all

cases, except when it was medically necessary to save a woman’s life. The ​Roe​ majority located

the abortion right under the umbrella of the so-called “right of personal privacy”—a right which,

though never mentioned explicitly in the text of the Constitution, ostensibly emanates from the

First, Fourth, Fifth, Ninth, and Fourteenth Amendments.​ 24​ Justice Harry Blackmun, writing for

the majority, argues:

This right of privacy, whether it be founded in the Fourteenth Amendment’s

concept of personal liberty and restrictions upon state action, as we feel it is, or as

the District Court determined, in the Ninth Amendment’s reservation of rights to

the people, is broad enough to encompass a woman’s decision whether or not to

terminate her pregnancy.​ 25

As a result of its recognition of these “broad enough” rights, the Court prohibited first-trimester

abortion restrictions but reserved the option for states to regulate abortions on a

“narrowly-tailored” basis after the “compelling” point of fetal viability. In effect, the Court

enacted a strict scrutiny standard for post-viability restrictions.​ 26

20

​Phillips v. Martin Marietta Corp.​, 400 U.S. 542 (1971).

21

C​leveland Board of Education v. LaFleur​, 414 U.S. 632 (1974); ​Craig v. Boren​, 429 U.S. 190 (1976).

22

​Corning Glass Works v. Brennan​, 417 U.S. 188 (1974).

23

​Eisenstadt v. Baird​, 405 U.S. 438 (1972).

24

​Roe v. Wade​, 410 U.S. 113 (1973); ​Griswold v. Connecticut​, 381 U.S. 479 (1965).

25

​Roe​, 410 U.S. 113.

26

Ibid.

8


Roe​’s essential holding was reaffirmed in the Court’s 1992 decision in ​Planned

Parenthood of Southeastern Pennsylvania v. Casey​, a case challenging the Pennsylvania

legislature’s updated abortion codes. These restrictive laws required informed consent, a 24-hour

waiting period, parental consent for minors, and spousal consent from married women seeking

abortion care. The ​Casey​ majority, however—in a fractured and profoundly controversial 5–4

decision for the petitioners—altered its established holding prohibiting first-trimester abortion

restrictions. The majority opinion, written by Justice O’Connor, rejected ​Roe​’s trimester

approach to abortion laws, positing instead a distinct “undue burden” standard for all future

abortion-related cases.​ 27​ According to this standard, the Court could strike down only those laws

which placed a “substantial obstacle in the path of a woman seeking an abortion before the fetus

attains viability.” Under the new ​Casey​ framework, the Court upheld most of the Pennsylvania

law, striking down only the spousal consent provision as an “undue burden” on a woman’s right

to choose.​ 28

Roe v. Wade​ and ​Casey v. Planned Parenthood​ are fundamentally flawed decisions, and

not merely because they seem, as Justice White notes in his ​Roe​ dissent, to “simply [fashion] and

[announce] a new constitutional right.”​ 29​ Their most basic inadequacy, rather, lies in the Court’s

failure to see the consequences of abortion restrictions for what they are: legally-sanctioned sex

discrimination that is “so unjustifiable as to be violative of due process.”​ 30

Choice and Citizenship: Liberty and Equality

In a 1973 article first published in the ​Yale Law Review​, Ely—the aforementioned legal

architect of the proceduralist theory of judicial review—denounces the Court’s decision in ​Roe​.

He writes that in artificially discovering a fundamental right to privacy in the Constitution, the

Court had not applied any “express” constitutional prohibition but rather opted to “substitute

their social and economic beliefs for the judgment of legislative bodies.”​ 31​ Focusing on the

27

Notably, O’Connor was the first female associate justice of the Supreme Court.

28

​Planned Parenthood of Southeastern Pa. v. Casey​, 505 U.S. 833 (1992).

29

​Roe v. Wade​, 410 U.S. 113 (1973) (White, J. dissenting opinion).

30

​Frontiero​, 411 U.S. 677.

31

John Hart Ely, “Wages of Crying Wolf: A Comment on Roe v. Wade,” in ​Civil Rights and Liberties: Cases and

Readings in Constitutional Law and American Democracy​, ed. Corey Brettschneider (New York: Wolters Kluwer

Law & Business, 2013), 561.

9


Court’s historical propensity to expand substantive due process rights in order to nullify any

disfavored legislative enactment, he accuses the majority in ​Roe​ of “[setting] itself a question the

Constitution had not made the Court’s business.”​ 32​ While Ely’s underlying argument regarding

the correlation of substantive due process with judicial overreach may be well-founded (see, for

example, ​Lochner v. New York​), this point is simply incorrect.​ 33​ The Constitution does speak to

how the Court should address the abortion question: through the Fourteenth Amendment’s Equal

Protection Clause.

Anti-abortion laws, by their very nature, restrain the liberties of female citizens while

exerting no analogous burden on male citizens. These sex-specific restrictions subject women to

the various social, financial, and political costs of carrying an unwanted pregnancy to term, a

possibility that similarly situated male citizens will never face. Consider, for example, the

prospective life choices available to Alyssa and Henry, two fictional students attending a Texas

university. They enter into a sexual relationship, and Alyssa inadvertently becomes pregnant. But

because the state has passed legislation to successfully limit the availability of abortion care,

Alyssa finds that she will be unable to gain access to a safe and legal abortion procedure. Instead,

her unplanned pregnancy results in a series of social and economic tradeoffs. She may need a

college degree to achieve her desired career goals, but if she cannot afford the cost of both tuition

and childcare, she will be forced to either drop out of school or put her child up for adoption. Her

social network may diminish as her acquaintances distance themselves from the stigma of her

out-of-wedlock pregnancy. Even if she is able to keep the baby, earn her degree, and secure

gainful employment, her future earnings are likely to suffer as a result of the “motherhood

penalty,” a driving factor in the persistent U.S. gender pay gap.​ 34​ Taken alone, the Texas

legislature has placed an obvious—though not obviously unconstitutional—restraint on Alyssa’s

range of life choices. After all, as Ely notes, the state may as a general matter deprive citizens of

their liberty so long as the inhibition has some “rational connection” with a “permissible

governmental goal.”​ 35

32

Ibid., 563.

33

Lochner v. New Yor​k, 198 U.S. 45 (1905).

34

Abigail Hess, “Women’s earnings drop after having a child—but men’s do not,” ​CNBC​, October 16, 2019,

https://www.cnbc.com/2019/10/16/womens-earnings-drop-after-having-a-childbut-mens-do-not.html​.

35

Ely, “Wages,” 560.

10


However, the unconstitutionality of the state’s abortion restriction comes clearly into

view—particularly under Ely’s proceduralist reading of the Constitution—when we observe the

law’s comparative impact (or, more accurately, its lack thereof) on Alyssa’s male counterpart. As

Alyssa’s sexual partner, Henry bears equivalent proximate responsibility for the biological

consequences of their intercourse. But while both parties engaged in exactly the same

pregnancy-inducing sexual behavior, the law holds Alyssa alone responsible for carrying their

unwanted pregnancy to term. Moreover, Alyssa alone must weather the most trying social,

economic, and political burdens of her pregnancy. Henry will likely be able to complete his

degree while maintaining a wide pre-professional network, gainful employment, and few if any,

childcare responsibilities—opportunities that Alyssa does not share. The Court’s decision in

Frontiero​ provides insight into why the Constitution prohibits such invidious forms of sex

discrimination under the Equal Protection Clause. Justice Brennan, again writing for the

majority, argues:

Moreover, since sex, like race and national origin, is an immutable characteristic

determined solely by the accident of birth, the imposition of special disabilities

upon the members of a particular sex because of their sex would seem to violate

“the basic concept of our system that legal burdens should bear some relationship

to individual responsibility.”​ 36

Not only do abortion restrictions implicate a woman’s social and economic opportunities, but

also her political standing in the republic. Abortion restrictions, forms of legal coercion which

indisputably reduce female liberty, certainly impose “special disabilities upon the members of a

particular sex” and also do so “because of their sex.” While Henry may be required to share

partially in the financial burdens associated with childcare (e.g., via child support payments), he

is under no legal obligation to engage in full-time co-parenting alongside Alyssa. Thus, only

Alyssa’s liberty is meaningfully constrained as a result of the abortion prohibition and only as a

consequence of her “immutable sex characteristic.” In restricting the reproductive autonomy of

pregnant women, with no equivalent legal burden for her male partner, abortion restrictions

discriminate against women because they are women. Incidentally, both male and female

reproductive organs are necessary to induce pregnancy; still, no American legislature interested

in reducing the frequency of abortion procedures has ever tested the constitutionality of the

36

​Frontiero​, 411 U.S. 677.

11


preemptive vasectomy. Instead, by placing legal restrictions squarely upon the female partner,

the state exerts a legal burden that bears no relation to a woman’s individual responsibility and

every relation to the accident of her birth.

Much in the same way that sex-based stereotyping promotes invidious discrimination “so

unjustifiable as to be violative of due process,” so too do restrictive abortion laws—a clear form

of sex discrimination—perpetuate inequalities that themselves violate women’s procedural

rights.​ 37​ Ely’s representation-reinforcing method prohibits the government from “unduly

constricting” the participatory rights of minorities based on their minority status.

In theory, laws that restrict access to abortion classify the autonomy of a pregnant woman

as qualitatively different from that of her male sexual partner. In practice, these laws make each

woman’s equal citizenship contingent on her pregnancy status. Just as the Illinois legislature’s

decision to bar women from the legal profession worked to relegate women to the “domestic

sphere” (see ​Bradwell​), contemporary abortion laws—which impose upon women, but not men,

the consequences of unplanned parenthood—function to strip them of the otherwise

presumptively equal citizenship status shared by other members of a democratic republic.​ 38

Justice Ruth Bader Ginsburg argues as much in her dissent in the 2007 ​Gonzales v. Carhart​ case,

in which the Court’s 5–4 conservative majority upheld the federal government’s Partial-Birth

Abortion Act of 2003:

Women, it is now acknowledged, have the talent, capacity, and right ‘to

participate equally in the economic and social life of the Nation.’ Their ability to

realize their full potential, the Court recognized, is intimately connected to ‘their

ability to control their reproductive lives.’ Thus, legal challenges to undue

restrictions on abortion procedures do not seek to vindicate some generalized

notion of privacy; rather, they center on a woman’s autonomy to determine her

life’s course, and thus to enjoy equal citizenship stature.​ 39

Ginsburg’s ​Gonzales​ dissent highlights not only the substantive inequality of abortion

restrictions but also the innate participational stakes of female reproductive autonomy. A

woman must embrace the fact that her “autonomy to determine her life’s course,” as Ginsburg

writes, could be diminished at any moment—during a momentary lapse of judgment, a birth

control defect, or a nonconsensual sexual encounter. While a male citizen may engage in

37

Ibid​.

38

​Bradwell​, 83 U.S. 130.

39

​Gonzales v. Carhart​, 550 U.S. 124 (2007).

12


wanton sexual intercourse with few inhibitions, a woman must always remember that her “equal

citizenship stature” is contingent on the accident of her sex (that is, her pregnancy status).

Abortion restrictions automatically create a distinct and lesser sphere of liberty for female

citizens while allowing male citizens to embrace their full range of constitutional liberties.

Ely nevertheless argues that a constitution should guarantee “legitimate processes, not

legitimate outcomes.”​ 40​ However, in the context of anti-abortion laws, these two prescriptions

cannot be so readily distinguished from one another. The process by which abortion restrictions

reduce women to their immutable pregnancy characteristic and limit their rights accordingly is

an inherently illegitimate one, which has “the effect of invidiously relegating the entire class of

females to inferior legal statuses without regard to [women’s] actual capabilities.”​ 41​ Pregnant

women and unwilling mothers lack equal standing in the American political community; by

presenting a different range of liberty to males and females on the basis of their sex, these laws

undermine the principles of equal citizenship—a form of discrimination “so unjustifiable as to be

violative of due process.”​ 42

To further exemplify this inherent link between procedural and substantive inequality in

the state’s denial of female reproductive autonomy, we need to look no further than​ Struck v.

Secretary of Defense​, a 1972 case brought before the Ninth Circuit but ultimately resolved out of

court. Captain Susan Struck, a nurse in the U.S. Air Force, became pregnant while stationed in

Vietnam on active duty. At the time, the Air Force required pregnant service members to obtain

abortions or else lose their jobs. However, Struck, a devout Roman Catholic, wanted to have her

baby. After being sent back to the United States to obtain an abortion, Struck sought legal

assistance. The ACLU Women’s Rights Project took up her case; after two consecutive losses in

federal court, the U.S. Supreme Court granted Struck a stay of discharge proceedings, allowing

her enough time to give birth and return to her Air Force duties. The Air Force ultimately

40

Ely, ​Democracy​, 42.

41

​Frontiero​, 411 U.S. 677.

42

Ibid.

13


changed its discharge policy, and the Supreme Court did not grant the ACLU’s petition

43​ ​44

certiorari​.​

Justice Lewis F. Powell, Jr., however, voted to hear ​Struck​. His case notes, now a matter

of public record, indicate that at least some members of the judiciary had in fact recognized

reproductive autonomy as an equal protection issue. Far from seeing some abstract violation of

Captain Struck’s privacy, Justice Powell writes that the question at hand was “whether the state

may discriminate against women in terms of required leave when they do not impose the same

requirements on other temporary disabilities.” He concludes that it likely could not, arguing on

the basis of equal protection that “where the sex discrimination touches on some aspect of the

procreative process, a higher standard of scrutiny should be applied. Only women bear children:

the disabilities associated with pregnancy only befall women.”​ 45

Powell is entirely correct. His argument, underscoring the intimate connection between

equality and reproductive autonomy, points out that the government's attempt to interfere in

Struck’s “procreative process” plainly subverted equal protection. The Air Force had forced

pregnant female service members to choose between their children and their employment while

requiring no such tradeoff for prospective male parents. Moreover, the procedural rights enjoyed

by disabled men were not similarly extended to pregnant women; pregnancy, unlike other

temporary “disabilities,” constituted automatic grounds for dismissal. Once again, the

government had denied women the equal protection of the laws based solely on their immutable

sex characteristics—an arbitrary condition of their birth.

The fact that two categories of similarly situated citizens might hold different rights and

privileges based on their innate sex characteristics runs counter to the Fourteenth Amendment’s

equal protection guarantee and Ely’s proceduralist reading of the Constitution. Reproductive

restrictions such as those reviewed in ​Roe​, ​Casey​, ​Gonzales​, and ​Struck​ subject women alone to

state-imposed constraints on their liberty, thus depriving them of their opportunity to participate

fully in the social, economic, and political realms of citizenship. Male citizens, on the other hand,

43

Jan Eric Peterson, “Pick Your Battles,” ​New Yorker,​ October 15, 2018,

https://www.newyorker.com/magazine/2018/10/22/letters-from-the-october-22-2018-issue​.

44

A party seeking to appeal to the Supreme Court from a lower court decision must file a writ of certiorari, which

the justices will review prior to agreeing to hear such an appeal. See: “Certiorari,” Cornell Legal Information

Institute, https://www.law.cornell.edu/wex/certiorari.

45

Lewis F. Powell, Jr., “Struck v. Secretary of Defense,” ​Supreme Court Case Files​, 582, October 13, 1972,

https://scholarlycommons.law.wlu.edu/casefiles/582.

14


will never be subject to an analogous choice; they may embrace this full range of liberty as a

right of citizenship while women may not. Such outcomes are precisely those to which Justice

Brennan refers when he writes of discrimination “so unjustifiable as to be violative of due

process.”​ 46​ When a constitution allows for citizenship classifications to be made based on sex

alone, neither sex enjoys the promise of due process. According to Ely himself, equal protection

was introduced to ensure “that the process of individual application will not be manipulated so as

to reintroduce in practice the sort of discrimination that is impermissible in theory.”​ 47​ Procedure

does not adequately protect classes of citizens whose right to an equal degree of basic liberty is

not respected by law. Locked out of the critical realms of participation, these citizens are

deprived of the opportunity to be recognized as equal stakeholders in the American political

process.

Conclusion

Thus far, U.S. courts have declined to center either procedural or substantive equality in

their reproduction jurisprudence. ​Roe v. Wade​ and its descendants have used privacy, not

equality, as the working constitutional framework for the abortion right. This is a potentially

destructive oversight, for privacy alone does not encompass the vast burdens that abortion

restrictions place on women’s equal citizenship stature. ​Roe​ obscures the intrinsically gendered

terms of the abortion debate, subjecting the fate of female reproductive rights to the Court’s

increasingly limited recognition of the privacy right itself.

Choosing motherhood, or choosing to forgo it, is a decision that women alone can make.

And coerced motherhood, like coerced abortion, amounts to a political consequence of

unspeakable magnitude that women alone must bear. A woman’s right to reap the equal benefits

of republican citizenship—including, but not limited to, her ability to pursue an independent

career, to run for public office, and to be free from excessive government intervention in her

person and property—are inextricable from her right to choose if and when to give birth to a

child. When the government places restrictions on female reproductive autonomy, it makes these

rights contingent on the accident of her sex. It signals that women are less entitled than their

46

​Frontiero​, 411 U.S. 677.

47

Ely, ​Democracy​, 42.

15


male counterparts to this full range of constitutional citizenship benefits. And it ensures that the

same participatory rights, guaranteed to men in America’s economic, political, and social spheres

regardless of their parenthood status ​are denied to all women.

The Equal Protection Clause—designed to confer a full and equal range of citizenship

rights upon all members of the American political community—leaves little room for the

government to erect barriers to women’s reproductive autonomy short of engaging in per se sex

discrimination. Restrictions limiting the range of women’s autonomy, like those targeting the

civil liberties of other suspect classes, should always be subject to strict judicial scrutiny under

the Equal Protection Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment. The constitutional standard for equal

citizenship should require that citizens of both sexes enjoy equal autonomy in determining their

range of life choices.

In the prescient words of the late Justice Ruth Bader Ginsburg: “I ask no favor for my

sex. All I ask of our brethren is that they take their feet off our necks.”​ 48

48

Louise W. Knight, “The 19​ th​ -century powerhouse who inspired RBG,” ​CNN​, September 1, 2018,

https://www.cnn.com/2018/09/01/opinions/ruth-bader-ginsburg-rbg-and-grimke-sisters-louise-knight/index.html​.

16

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!