24.12.2012 Views

Towards a Framework for Global Citizenship Education - Institute of ...

Towards a Framework for Global Citizenship Education - Institute of ...

Towards a Framework for Global Citizenship Education - Institute of ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Abstract<br />

<strong>Towards</strong> a <strong>Framework</strong> <strong>for</strong> <strong>Global</strong> <strong>Citizenship</strong> <strong>Education</strong><br />

Laura Johnson<br />

PhD Student, <strong>Institute</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Education</strong>, University <strong>of</strong> London<br />

The promotion <strong>of</strong> „<strong>Global</strong> <strong>Citizenship</strong>‟ (GC) has emerged as a common feature <strong>of</strong> school<br />

curricular re<strong>for</strong>m around the world, reflecting a shift away from conceptions <strong>of</strong> citizenship<br />

based wholly on the national. <strong>Global</strong> <strong>Citizenship</strong> <strong>Education</strong> (GCE) is there<strong>for</strong>e a<br />

broadening field, manifested in both academic and policy contexts. As an international<br />

phenomenon, it is subject to a wide range <strong>of</strong> interpretations, mirroring the diverse<br />

ideological and politico-philosophical frameworks from which the policies and programmes<br />

promoting the concept derive. For teachers <strong>of</strong> GCE, policy makers and academics, there<br />

is sufficient ambiguity in this field to cause confusion and misunderstanding. This paper<br />

describes an ongoing research project aiming to develop an analytical framework through<br />

which GCE policies, programmes and philosophies can be distinguished, explored and<br />

deconstructed in context. Through a critical review <strong>of</strong> the literature, the study establishes<br />

a set <strong>of</strong> systematic categories and classifications <strong>for</strong> this complex field from which an<br />

analytical framework can be constructed. This typology provides the groundwork <strong>for</strong> the<br />

development <strong>of</strong> a powerful and effective analytical tool through which the field <strong>of</strong> GCE may<br />

be better understood and applied in both theory and practice.<br />

Introduction<br />

„<strong>Global</strong> citizenship‟ is a term used increasingly in educational contexts around the world,<br />

permeating curriculum policy in a fashion similar to constructs such as „lifelong learning‟.<br />

As an international phenomenon, it is subject to a wide range <strong>of</strong> interpretations, mirroring<br />

Laura Johnson 1


the diverse ideological and politico-philosophical frameworks from which the policies and<br />

programmes promoting the concept derive. The term „global citizenship education‟ is also<br />

entwined with a large number <strong>of</strong> overlapping educational arenas including development<br />

education, education <strong>for</strong> cosmopolitan citizenship, peace education and human rights<br />

education. Consequently, the term is <strong>of</strong>ten used with a sense <strong>of</strong> ambiguity <strong>for</strong> its meaning,<br />

which can potentially cause disjunctures between intention and practice <strong>for</strong> teachers <strong>of</strong><br />

GCE, policy makers and academics. This paper aims to deconstruct the concept <strong>of</strong> „global<br />

citizenship‟ according to its academic interpretations. Through a critical review <strong>of</strong> the<br />

literature, I establish a set <strong>of</strong> systematic categories and classifications <strong>for</strong> this complex<br />

field from which an analytical framework <strong>for</strong> global citizenship education can be<br />

constructed.<br />

The initial typology developed within this paper is constructed through an inductive<br />

analysis <strong>of</strong> academic literature, focusing principally on texts relating to global citizenship<br />

but also to some literature specifically within the educational field. The analysis loosely<br />

follows McCracken‟s (1988) „five stages <strong>of</strong> analysis‟, converting the stages into an iterative<br />

process through which observations and relationships in academic texts are explored and<br />

combined into themes and categories which will ultimately <strong>for</strong>m the analytical framework.<br />

The following sections summarise and illustrate the categories identified within this<br />

typology <strong>for</strong> global citizenship.<br />

Conflicting and converging <strong>for</strong>ms <strong>of</strong> cosmopolitan global citizenship<br />

The term „cosmopolitanism‟ has seen a recent resurgence in popularity, due to its<br />

appropriation by scholars such as Nussbaum (1996), Appiah (2006) and, in the education<br />

field, Osler and Starkey (2008). Often couched within a framework <strong>of</strong> human rights,<br />

Laura Johnson 2


cosmopolitanism is regarded by a number <strong>of</strong> critical post-development and post-colonial<br />

scholars as a neo-imperial <strong>for</strong>m <strong>of</strong> global citizenship since its universalist perspective (the<br />

notion that all human beings share the same fundamental values) is rooted within a set <strong>of</strong><br />

institutions and practices that are said to be West-centric (Arneil, 2007; Tully, 2008).<br />

However, as Humes (2008, p. 43) acknowledges, there are significant pragmatic<br />

advantages to the cosmopolitan position:<br />

“Some writers deplore the trend towards what they describe as a globally<br />

connected political and bureaucratic elite which determines priorities <strong>for</strong> the rest<br />

<strong>of</strong> the world. Others take a more positive view <strong>of</strong> political globalisation and see<br />

it (potentially at least) as bringing some <strong>of</strong> the benefits <strong>of</strong> advanced<br />

democracies to nations which are ruled by undemocratic systems <strong>of</strong><br />

government. One thinks, <strong>for</strong> example, <strong>of</strong> the United Nations Convention on the<br />

Rights <strong>of</strong> the Child. The spread <strong>of</strong> awareness <strong>of</strong> the principles enshrined in<br />

such documents, it is argued, puts pressure on oppressive regimes and gives<br />

hope to those who suffer from various <strong>for</strong>ms <strong>of</strong> political persecution.”<br />

(Humes, 2008, p. 43)<br />

The word „cosmopolitanism‟ itself derives from Ancient Greek ideas <strong>of</strong> universality, where<br />

the „cosmos‟ (universe / world) is one‟s „city‟ (living place / community). Peters, Blee and<br />

Britton (2008) identify three „types‟ <strong>of</strong> cosmopolitan global citizenship: moral, political and<br />

economic. While these three categories are useful, they omit a notable conception <strong>of</strong><br />

cosmopolitan global citizenship described by Waks (2008, p. 204) as ‘aesthetic-cultural<br />

cosmopolitanism’, which, he suggests, represents “a kind <strong>of</strong> multi-national sophistication”.<br />

Within a range <strong>of</strong> the literature under scrutiny, these four categories <strong>of</strong> cosmopolitanism<br />

demonstrate elements <strong>of</strong> convergence and all overlap to some extent, but there are also<br />

Laura Johnson 3


significant areas <strong>of</strong> conflict between each. The following sections summarise these areas<br />

<strong>of</strong> convergence and conflict.<br />

Political cosmopolitan global citizenship<br />

Three main styles <strong>of</strong> thinking pervade political cosmopolitan global citizenship. The first is<br />

what one might term a „radical‟ conception <strong>of</strong> political-institutional global citizenship, in<br />

which the idea <strong>of</strong> a „world state‟ is conceived which does away with current nation-state<br />

boundaries and transfers sovereignty to a democratic world polity with legislative,<br />

executive and judicial powers, including a “monopoly on the legitimate use <strong>of</strong> organized<br />

violence” (Wendt, 1999, p. 202). This idea is advocated by some scholars as a utopian<br />

but currently impossible ideal (<strong>for</strong> example, Carter, 2001; Dewey, 1918/1982; Heater,<br />

2002; Shaw, 2000; Singer, 2004), and by a small minority even as a real possibility (<strong>for</strong><br />

example, Wendt, 2003). The dream <strong>of</strong> a world government abolishing nation-state<br />

sovereignty and instituting a <strong>for</strong>mal status <strong>for</strong> all human beings <strong>of</strong> „world citizenship‟ is<br />

criticised by many intellectuals as being unfeasible, undesirable and unnecessary (Lu,<br />

2008).<br />

The second <strong>for</strong>m <strong>of</strong> political cosmopolitan global citizenship rejects the idea <strong>of</strong> a world<br />

state and is thus characterised as a weaker, less radical <strong>for</strong>m <strong>of</strong> global governance<br />

involving democratisation and strengthening <strong>of</strong> current international institutions such as the<br />

United Nations, World Trade Organisation and World Bank into a “well-ordered world<br />

society” (Pogge, 1989, p. 216). This is <strong>of</strong>ten referred to as a <strong>for</strong>m <strong>of</strong> „cosmopolitan<br />

democracy‟, as advocated by Held (1995, 2004), McGrew (1997), Dower (2000, 2003),<br />

Linklater (1998) and Archibugi (2008) among others. However, Tully (2008, p. 23), from a<br />

post-colonial critical perspective, considers this <strong>for</strong>m <strong>of</strong> global citizenship to be an<br />

Laura Johnson 4


extension <strong>of</strong> „Western imperialism‟; and Roman (2004, p. 245) similarly describes<br />

proponents <strong>of</strong> such a conception as “democratic civilizers” engaged in a <strong>for</strong>m <strong>of</strong> “neo-<br />

colonial humanism.” Conversely, proponents <strong>of</strong> cosmopolitan democracy argue that, with<br />

the democratisation <strong>of</strong> the institutions <strong>of</strong> global governance, problems <strong>of</strong> Western power<br />

and dominance will recede and new <strong>for</strong>ms <strong>of</strong> co-operation and global social justice will<br />

emerge (Held, 2004).<br />

The final <strong>for</strong>m <strong>of</strong> political cosmopolitan global citizenship can be termed ‘anarcho-<br />

cosmopolitanism’ (Gabay, 2008). This rests on the argument that a truly „cosmopolitan‟<br />

ethic cannot be adequately embedded within either a world state or within a nation-state<br />

system, and there<strong>for</strong>e that an anarchistic or libertarian socialist society is the best political<br />

system in which to “develop a cosmopolitan ethic that seeks to overcome selfish self-<br />

interest” (Gabay, 2008, p. 198). This mirrors the growth in what is known as ‘global civil<br />

society’, to the extent that the spread across the world <strong>of</strong> not-<strong>for</strong>-pr<strong>of</strong>it and voluntary<br />

networks and organisations with little regard <strong>for</strong> nation-state boundaries could be regarded<br />

as a <strong>for</strong>m <strong>of</strong> anarcho-cosmopolitanism, at least where their aims align with cosmopolitan<br />

values and ideas (see also Herzog, 2004).<br />

Moral cosmopolitan global citizenship<br />

Theories <strong>of</strong> moral cosmopolitanism can be regarded as the foundation <strong>for</strong> dominant<br />

conceptions <strong>of</strong> global citizenship, as they are so pervasive within both academic and policy<br />

discourses. The roots <strong>of</strong> moral cosmopolitanism are commonly located with the Stoics <strong>of</strong><br />

Ancient Greece, and also in the ideas <strong>of</strong> Kant, who “defended and popularised the idea<br />

that human beings belong to a single moral community” (Peters, et al., 2008, p. 3). The<br />

idea <strong>of</strong> a global or world ethic is necessarily universal, in that the moral values expressed<br />

Laura Johnson 5


would need to be accepted by all in order to be truly effective. However, the extent to<br />

which a global ethic owed to all <strong>of</strong> humanity supersedes more local moral, or „special‟<br />

obligations (<strong>for</strong> example, to one‟s family or fellow national citizens), or whether this should<br />

be an issue at all, is controversial. Waks identifies two <strong>for</strong>ms <strong>of</strong> moral cosmopolitan: the<br />

“strong cosmopolitans” such as Nussbaum (1996), Dower (1998), MacIntyre (1981) and<br />

Singer (2004), who argue that special obligations are morally arbitrary and that patriotism,<br />

<strong>for</strong> example, is an unacceptable moral position; and the “new cosmopolitans” such as<br />

Appiah (2006) and Beck (2006) who advocate a <strong>for</strong>m <strong>of</strong> global moral ethics drawn from “a<br />

synthesis <strong>of</strong> liberal universalism and communitarianism” (Waks, 2008, p. 209) in which<br />

special obligations are “ineluctable elements <strong>of</strong> moral life” (Waks, 2008, p. 210) according<br />

to the contexts within which personal narratives are <strong>for</strong>med and „otherness‟ is recognised.<br />

Papastephanou (2008, p. 179) also subscribes to this pragmatic conception, in which she<br />

claims that “particularity is not the opposite <strong>of</strong> universality, as is usually theorised, but<br />

rather a subset <strong>of</strong> it”: <strong>for</strong> example, patriotism, as a moral „particularity‟, can easily co-exist<br />

with ideas <strong>of</strong> a global ethic.<br />

Moral cosmopolitanism is most visibly and famously expressed in the <strong>for</strong>m <strong>of</strong> universal<br />

human rights such as those expressed in the United Nations Universal Declaration <strong>of</strong><br />

Human Rights. Many proponents <strong>of</strong> human rights argue <strong>for</strong> a universal, or “strong<br />

cosmopolitan”, understanding <strong>of</strong> human rights (<strong>for</strong> example, Abdi & Shultz, 2008),<br />

although they are also to an extent compatible with the more communitarian ideas <strong>of</strong> the<br />

„new cosmopolitans‟, since they can be reinterpreted and embedded within local, national<br />

and regional contexts. In contrast, some scholars maintain that human rights do not go far<br />

enough towards a universal global ethic, in that they cannot provide a sufficiently sturdy<br />

foundation on which a system <strong>of</strong> global justice can be built: <strong>for</strong> example, because <strong>of</strong> the<br />

fragile and uncertain „legal personality‟ <strong>of</strong> the United Nations (Navari, 2000) and the lack <strong>of</strong><br />

Laura Johnson 6


emphasis on the limitations <strong>of</strong> natural resources that require interdependence and<br />

sustainable living (and particularly reductions in Western consumption) in order <strong>for</strong> global<br />

social justice to be possible.<br />

Economic cosmopolitan global citizenship<br />

Pogge (2002) argues that the cosmopolitanism position in general encompasses three<br />

elements: individualism, universality and generality. While the presence <strong>of</strong> the latter two<br />

elements in the economic sphere seem uncontroversial, their combination with<br />

individualism ties economic cosmopolitan global citizenship to divisive theories <strong>of</strong><br />

neoliberalism and capitalism, and what Faulks (2000, p. 11) describes as “thin citizenship”.<br />

Richardson (2008, p. 128) depicts this “global imaginary” as one which “is founded on<br />

individualism and neo-liberal economic ideas that suggest that despite superficial<br />

differences individuals have the same fundamental wants and needs, and by serving their<br />

own self-interest, ultimately the interests <strong>of</strong> the planet are also served.” Tied to notions <strong>of</strong><br />

competition, the free market and human capital, neo-liberalism is demonised in a great<br />

number <strong>of</strong> moral cosmopolitan, political cosmopolitan and educational texts <strong>for</strong> its<br />

disregard <strong>for</strong> moral and political cosmopolitan principles, in favour <strong>of</strong> economic growth,<br />

consumption and elitism (<strong>for</strong> example, Bauman, 1998; Falk, 1993; Isin & Wood, 1999;<br />

Roman, 2004; Schattle, 2008a; Szelényi & Rhoads, 2007).<br />

It is inaccurate to state that economic cosmopolitan global citizenship, or „neoliberal‟ /<br />

„corporate‟ global citizenship as it is <strong>of</strong>ten labelled, is entirely blind to moral values and<br />

detached from other, more „humane‟, elements <strong>of</strong> cosmopolitanism. As Schattle (2008b)<br />

identifies, moves towards „corporate social responsibility‟ such as the United Nations<br />

Laura Johnson 7


<strong>Global</strong> Compact in 2000, are increasingly pervasive. Nevertheless, the donations and<br />

philanthropic activities <strong>of</strong> rich multinational corporations are generally regarded with<br />

scepticism: <strong>for</strong> example, they are <strong>of</strong>ten considered a „smokescreen‟ to distract the public<br />

from individualistic and/or corrupt pr<strong>of</strong>it-making schemes destroying communities and the<br />

environment (Tully, 2008). Manifestations <strong>of</strong> corporate social responsibility may also be<br />

perceived (positively or negatively) as ef<strong>for</strong>ts by businesspeople to atone <strong>for</strong> their wealth<br />

and com<strong>for</strong>table lifestyles. The extent to which a neoliberal, consumerist, capitalist society<br />

can co-exist with genuine ef<strong>for</strong>ts to make the world a better place is there<strong>for</strong>e ambiguous.<br />

Aesthetic-cultural cosmopolitan global citizenship<br />

The final <strong>for</strong>m <strong>of</strong> cosmopolitan global citizenship identified in this analysis <strong>of</strong> academic<br />

literature is its aesthetic-cultural <strong>for</strong>m, which is described by Waks (2008) as follows:<br />

“To be cosmopolitan in this sense is to be open to those from other places, take<br />

an interest in their cultural practices, learn about these practices through<br />

reading, travel, and personal contact, and even to shape a personal identity as<br />

a cosmopolitan through such experiences.”<br />

(Waks, 2008, p. 204)<br />

Conceptions <strong>of</strong> aesthetic-cultural cosmopolitan global citizenship can also refer to the<br />

pervasive cultural globalisation <strong>of</strong> media and languages: <strong>for</strong> example the global spread <strong>of</strong><br />

MTV and the internet giving people across the world common cultural expressions, as well<br />

as the increasing international dominance <strong>of</strong> the English language (Crystal, 2003; Phan,<br />

2008).<br />

Laura Johnson 8


De Ruyter and Spiecker (2008) propose a more specific conception <strong>of</strong> aesthetic-cultural<br />

cosmopolitan global citizenship. Four main elements contribute to their conception; first,<br />

the idea that the notions <strong>of</strong> „citizen‟ and „world citizen‟ correspond directly to notions <strong>of</strong><br />

„minimal‟ and „maximal‟ citizenship. Rather than the socio-political definitions <strong>of</strong> „minimal‟<br />

and „maximal‟ citizenship constructed by scholars such as McLaughlin (1992), themselves<br />

based on Galston‟s (1989) characterisations <strong>of</strong> the „autarchic‟ and „autonomous‟ citizen,<br />

De Ruyter and Spiecker (2008) construct a socio-cultural definition:<br />

“Being a citizen in the minimal sense means that a person is able to speak and<br />

read the dominant language, has the disposition to abide by the law and has<br />

moral, political and social knowledge… Being a citizen in the maximal sense<br />

[differs] from minimal citizenship in the level <strong>of</strong> the aspects mentioned, [and]<br />

also in a qualitative respect: a citizen in the maximal sense is someone who is<br />

culturally competent too.”<br />

(De Ruyter & Spiecker, 2008, p. 353)<br />

This idea <strong>of</strong> cultural competence is the second element <strong>of</strong> this cosmopolitan conception,<br />

referring to “a culturally and intellectually well-developed person” who “actively plays a<br />

modest part in the cultural flourishing <strong>of</strong> the society” (De Ruyter & Spiecker, 2008, pp. 354,<br />

355). This notion has class-based and potentially elitist implications, as reflected in the<br />

following: “Some citizens do not have any desire to become world citizens and do not need<br />

to, because their scope is relatively limited” (De Ruyter & Spiecker, 2008, p. 360).<br />

However, it remains a cosmopolitan perspective because the authors suggest that “all<br />

citizens have a right to develop into a world citizen” (De Ruyter & Spiecker, 2008, p. 360).<br />

Laura Johnson 9


The third element relates more clearly to moral conceptions <strong>of</strong> cosmopolitanism: De<br />

Ruyter and Spiecker (2008, p. 358) posit that world citizens must also evaluate cultural<br />

practices “from an ethical perspective”. They use this element to critique economic<br />

globalisation (or perhaps neoliberal / economic cosmopolitanism) in their claim that “world<br />

citizens would not be able to live in countries – unless as an activist – in which human lives<br />

are being threatened” (De Ruyter & Spiecker, 2008, p. 359). Un<strong>for</strong>tunately they do not<br />

elaborate on the definition <strong>of</strong> „threatened‟, <strong>for</strong>, as Falk, Kim and Mendlovitz (1991, p. 346)<br />

note, “There are many skeletons in virtually every global actor‟s closet”, and there<strong>for</strong>e it<br />

would be difficult to justify living anywhere on a broad interpretation <strong>of</strong> this ethical position.<br />

Finally, to be a world citizen within this conception one must live in what De Ruyter and<br />

Spiecker (2008, p. 359) call a “genre-rich society”, which others might term a “multicultural<br />

society”. It is not enough, according to the authors, simply to reside within such a society:<br />

one must actively access a wider variety <strong>of</strong> cultures. The authors claim that “citizens in<br />

liberal democracies” are taught to “respect the rights <strong>of</strong> others and evaluate the political,<br />

social and moral qualities <strong>of</strong> societies” (De Ruyter & Spiecker, 2008, p. 360), which are<br />

identified as the necessary ingredients to complete their conception <strong>of</strong> world citizenship.<br />

The foundations <strong>for</strong> this conception, they argue, arise from the work <strong>of</strong> J. S. Mill,<br />

particularly in his support <strong>for</strong> education in cultural aesthetics (Mill, 1867). However, the<br />

four elements <strong>of</strong> cultural-aesthetic cosmopolitanism as described here reveal tendencies<br />

towards a Nietzschean perspective, aiming to develop <strong>for</strong>ms <strong>of</strong> cultural „übermensch‟<br />

(„superman‟ or „beyond-man‟) (Nietzsche, 1883/1961).<br />

Despite the links to moral cosmopolitan ideas, aesthetic-cultural cosmopolitan global<br />

citizenship can start to resemble the more negatively perceived aspects <strong>of</strong> economic<br />

cosmopolitanism: <strong>for</strong> example, Roman (2004, p. 240) employs Bauman‟s (1998) „tourist‟ /<br />

„vagabond‟ terminology to critique those “intellectual tourists” and “voyeurs” who enjoy the<br />

Laura Johnson 10


fruits <strong>of</strong> unlimited travel and reify stereotypes and notions <strong>of</strong> cultural „otherness‟, whilst so<br />

many are “trapped in states <strong>of</strong> class, racialized and gendered immobility” (Roman, 2004, p.<br />

242): the notion <strong>of</strong> the „vagabond‟, which resonates with De Ruyter and Spiecker‟s (2008)<br />

description <strong>of</strong> those with „limited scope‟. De Ruyter and Spiecker (2008) contend that their<br />

conception <strong>of</strong> global citizenship relies not upon international mobility but on access to a<br />

liberal multicultural society. However, as Roman (2004, p. 241) claims, “Intellectual<br />

tourism is not always confined to actual physical and geographical travel”, and yet it can<br />

still mask a hegemonic system <strong>of</strong> social disenfranchisement, class rivalry and cultural<br />

elitism that counteracts the ef<strong>for</strong>ts <strong>of</strong> moral and political cosmopolitans as well as post-<br />

colonial actors.<br />

Critical, Positional and Holistic <strong>for</strong>ms <strong>of</strong> <strong>Global</strong> <strong>Citizenship</strong><br />

Critical (post-colonial) <strong>Global</strong> <strong>Citizenship</strong><br />

Once the political, moral, economic and aesthetic-cultural cosmopolitan <strong>for</strong>ms <strong>of</strong> global<br />

citizenship have been explored and classified, four alternative perspectives remain, which<br />

cover a range <strong>of</strong> areas based on more relativist or holistic (anti-individualistic) ideologies.<br />

The first, critical (post-colonial) global citizenship, is <strong>of</strong>ten posed in direct opposition to<br />

cosmopolitan <strong>for</strong>ms <strong>of</strong> global citizenship. Tully (2008), <strong>for</strong> example, uses intensely<br />

negative and violent imagery to describe cosmopolitan, or „modern‟ types <strong>of</strong> global<br />

citizenship:<br />

“From the perspective <strong>of</strong> the non-Western civilisations and <strong>of</strong> diverse<br />

citizenship, the two cosmopolitan rights appear as the Trojan horse <strong>of</strong> Western<br />

imperialism (Anghie, 2005)”<br />

Laura Johnson 11


(Tully, 2008, p. 23)<br />

He thus presents a powerful case <strong>for</strong> the second type <strong>of</strong> global citizenship („diverse‟),<br />

referring to an idealised world that “is reciprocally sustained by the civic freedom <strong>of</strong> its<br />

citizens” (Tully, 2008, p. 29). The roots <strong>of</strong> this conception lie within theories <strong>of</strong> post-<br />

development (Escobar, 1995; Rahnema & Bawtree, 1997) and post-colonialism (Said,<br />

1978; Spivak, 1988), and thus what Tully names „diverse‟ global citizenship is more aptly<br />

renamed ‘critical (post-colonial) global citizenship’. Roman (2004, p. 249) puts <strong>for</strong>ward a<br />

similar conception <strong>of</strong> post-colonial global citizenship which he calls “relational genealogy”.<br />

This has its philosophical roots in the post-structuralist critiques <strong>of</strong> Derrida and Foucault;<br />

the historicism / historical materialism <strong>of</strong> Hegel, Marx and Gramsci; and the „Frankfurt<br />

School‟ <strong>of</strong> critical theory, which also inspired Freire‟s (1970, p. 40) influential notion <strong>of</strong><br />

educational „praxis‟ (a synergistic process <strong>of</strong> reflection and action through which the<br />

people would become “involved in the organized struggle <strong>for</strong> their liberation”), identified by<br />

Tully as central to the expression <strong>of</strong> his „diverse‟ global citizenship.<br />

Critical (post-colonialist) conceptions <strong>of</strong> global citizenship tend to promote a <strong>for</strong>m <strong>of</strong><br />

„counter-hegemony‟, emphasising the deconstruction <strong>of</strong> oppressive global structures, and<br />

are also connected to “a politics <strong>of</strong> social trans<strong>for</strong>mation” (Dei, 2008, p. 479). While they<br />

generally take a relativist stance, potentially aligned with postmodern perspectives, a<br />

number <strong>of</strong> theorists in this area express explicit support <strong>for</strong> human rights (generally a<br />

universalist, cosmopolitan standpoint): <strong>for</strong> example, Abdi and Shultz (2008) in their book<br />

„Educating <strong>for</strong> Human Rights and <strong>Global</strong> <strong>Citizenship</strong>‟ explore post-colonial ideas within a<br />

clear framework <strong>of</strong> human rights. This illustrates the potential <strong>for</strong> associations between<br />

certain conceptions <strong>of</strong> critical (post-colonial) global citizenship and <strong>for</strong>ms <strong>of</strong> moral and<br />

political cosmopolitan global citizenship, which present a clear contrast to radical post-<br />

Laura Johnson 12


colonial scholars taking a more localised and moral relativist stance (<strong>for</strong> example,<br />

Andreotti, 2006a; Arneil, 2007; Roman, 2004; Tully, 2008).<br />

Positional <strong>Global</strong> <strong>Citizenship</strong><br />

I term the next category <strong>of</strong> global citizenship ‘positional’ global citizenship since, while it<br />

has significant overlaps with Tully‟s (2008) „diverse‟ and other <strong>for</strong>ms <strong>of</strong> critical (post-<br />

colonial) global citizenship (particularly the less radical <strong>for</strong>ms), it is not necessarily drawn<br />

from post-colonial or post-development foundations: this type <strong>of</strong> global citizenship arises<br />

from a range <strong>of</strong> social discourses or „positions‟. This type constructs interconnections<br />

between capitalist, institutional, cosmopolitan universalism and rooted, localised, grass-<br />

roots post-colonial relativism: founded along similar lines to Habermas‟s (1984)<br />

„communicative rationality‟. It is also similar to „anarcho-cosmopolitanism‟, in that its<br />

manifestation is generally through civil society organisations. However, with positional<br />

global citizenship there is not necessarily a universalist timbre within the ideologies or aims<br />

<strong>of</strong> the organisations: <strong>for</strong> example, „Freemasonry‟ traditionally excludes women; and the<br />

„Universal Negro Improvement Association and African Communities League‟ works<br />

towards “the general uplift <strong>of</strong> the people <strong>of</strong> African ancestry <strong>of</strong> the world”. These two<br />

examples are undeniably members <strong>of</strong> a global civil society which, since they are<br />

constructed on the basis <strong>of</strong> a particular position (<strong>for</strong> example, Isin and Wood‟s (1999)<br />

„urban citizenship‟), or sociological discourse such as gender, ethnicity, sexuality, disability<br />

and class, can be labelled „positional‟ global citizenship.<br />

The ideological basis <strong>of</strong> this conception lies within areas such as feminism,<br />

multiculturalism and theories <strong>of</strong> „reflexive positionality‟ (Rose, 1997). Banks (2008), <strong>for</strong><br />

Laura Johnson 13


example, outlines a <strong>for</strong>m <strong>of</strong> education based on „multicultural citizenship‟ (Kymlicka, 1995)<br />

that acknowledges the importance <strong>of</strong> liberal cosmopolitan thinking (<strong>for</strong> example, through<br />

human rights) but argues that citizens must develop “a delicate balance <strong>of</strong> cultural,<br />

national, and global identifications” (Banks, 2008, p. 322). While it could be argued that<br />

critical (post-colonial) global citizenship is simply a more radical subset <strong>of</strong> positional global<br />

citizenship, there appear to be certain ideological and practical differences which justify the<br />

division <strong>of</strong> these concepts into separate categories. Positional global citizenship contains<br />

a range <strong>of</strong> ideas that align with critical, poststructuralist and postcolonial works (<strong>for</strong><br />

example, Spivak‟s (1990) concept <strong>of</strong> „strategic essentialism‟ and Isin and Wood‟s (1999)<br />

„diasporic and aboriginal citizenship‟), but proponents <strong>of</strong> the <strong>for</strong>mer are likely to take a<br />

more pragmatic approach to global citizenship, exploring shifting identities and working<br />

within institutional (and perhaps national) boundaries, <strong>of</strong>ten towards goals such as poverty<br />

reduction and social justice. Similar ideas in existing typologies <strong>of</strong> global citizenship are<br />

Schattle‟s (2008a, p. 74) “liberal multiculturalism”, Szelényi and Rhoads‟s (2007, p. 31)<br />

“globally in<strong>for</strong>med nationalism / regionalism” and Falk‟s (1993, p. 46) “regional political<br />

consciousness”.<br />

Similarities can also be observed between „positional global citizenship‟ and the<br />

descriptions above <strong>of</strong> „the new cosmopolitanism‟ (<strong>for</strong> example, as manifested in Cogan<br />

and Derricott‟s (1998 & 2000) idea <strong>of</strong> ‟multidimensional citizenship‟). Although there are<br />

clearly significant overlaps between these two conceptions <strong>of</strong> global citizenship, the<br />

„positional‟ <strong>for</strong>ms remain sufficiently relativist to make a „cosmopolitan‟ label inappropriate;<br />

and can also include individuals and organisations who, rather than working towards<br />

„moral cosmopolitan‟ goals such as human rights, aim towards more secretive, partisan,<br />

nihilistic, narcissistic or even violent objectives.<br />

Laura Johnson 14


Environmental <strong>Global</strong> <strong>Citizenship</strong><br />

Concern <strong>for</strong> the environment, or „sustainable development‟, is <strong>of</strong>ten identified as a distinct<br />

theme aligning with global citizenship, particularly in educational contexts (<strong>for</strong> example,<br />

see Isin & Wood, 1999; Richardson, 2008; Schattle, 2008a); but as a conception <strong>of</strong><br />

„environmental global citizenship‟ it is less common. This is partly because<br />

environmentalism derives to a certain extent from the non-human elements <strong>of</strong> biology,<br />

ecology, geography and even aesthetics (<strong>for</strong> example, nature photography), which tend to<br />

reflect the science-arts-humanities academic split in their separation from the humanistic<br />

social concepts <strong>of</strong> politics, economics and culture. It is also possibly due to the conceptual<br />

complexity <strong>of</strong> applying a citizenship approach to human relationships with a non-sentient<br />

object (from a non-spiritual perspective); as raised by Jelin (2000, p. 60), “does nature<br />

have rights?” If this is considered to be the case (<strong>for</strong> example, in the case <strong>of</strong> animal rights,<br />

by Regan & Singer, 1976), the rights-responsibilities framework is reversed: from a focus<br />

on human rights to a focus on human responsibilities. The „Gaia hypothesis‟ (Lovelock &<br />

Margulis, 1974), which portrays the earth as a homeostatic living organism, has also<br />

added to the ecocentric idea <strong>of</strong> the earth or nature as a being needing protection on an<br />

intrinsic level.<br />

These perspectives are regarded by Ferry (1995), from his anthropocentric position, as<br />

dangerous to democracy: if nature is regarded as a legal subject, with no „larger entity‟ to<br />

distribute justice, turning to rational logic could result in the such totalitarian arguments as<br />

killing <strong>of</strong>f a large proportion <strong>of</strong> the human population in order to restore earth‟s natural<br />

balance (Aiken & Regan, 1984; Ferry, 1995). Žižek also challenges the notion that the<br />

earth is a fragile and good „Mother Nature‟ needing protection from humans (Else, 2010;<br />

Žižek, 2010); and Ward (2009) puts <strong>for</strong>ward a similar critique in his „Medea Hypothesis‟,<br />

Laura Johnson 15


arguing that the earth is ultimately self-destructive without the „assistance‟ <strong>of</strong> humans.<br />

While such viewpoints are fairly extreme, the anthropocentric position is certainly at<br />

present more visible in mainstream environmental movements (such as the United Nations<br />

Environment Programme: UNEP) than the ecocentric. Justification <strong>for</strong> environmentalism<br />

tends to focus first on the rights <strong>of</strong> living human beings across the world to enjoy clean air;<br />

fresh water and uncontaminated food; and second on the rights <strong>of</strong> future generations to<br />

enjoy the same: reflecting the „sustainability‟ element in „sustainable development‟ (Jelin,<br />

2000). With regard to some locations such as the Brazilian Rain<strong>for</strong>ests, the group rights <strong>of</strong><br />

indigenous peoples to their natural habitat and culture are <strong>of</strong>ten included within<br />

environmental conservation ef<strong>for</strong>ts (<strong>for</strong> example, UNESCO & UNEP, 2002), revealing links<br />

to critical (post-colonial) global citizenship and aesthetic-cultural cosmopolitan global<br />

citizenship as outlined above. Dobson (2006, p. 176) uses the term “ecological politics” to<br />

describe issues arising from our “metabolistic relationship with our non-human natural<br />

environment”, describing his credo as “thick cosmopolitanism” (Dobson, 2006, p. 165).<br />

While this links directly to moral cosmopolitan perspectives, it is also drawn upon heavily<br />

by Andreotti (2006a) in her postcolonial conception <strong>of</strong> global citizenship.<br />

Manifestations <strong>of</strong> environmental global citizenship tend to lie either within the realms <strong>of</strong><br />

government (local, national and international); within global civil society; or within the<br />

corporate world. The activities <strong>of</strong> these agents may fall within the scope <strong>of</strong> moral<br />

cosmopolitan approaches, in which concepts such as sustainable development, global<br />

justice and human rights take precedence: <strong>for</strong> example, in United Nations Millennium<br />

Development Goal Seven, „Ensure Environmental Sustainability”. Environmental global<br />

citizenship can also overlap significantly with anarcho-cosmopolitanism or positional global<br />

citizenship: Greenpeace in particular has an anarchic reputation and tends to disregard<br />

nation-state and private boundaries in favour <strong>of</strong> direct action (Associated Press, 2009;<br />

Laura Johnson 16


Hooper, 2009; McCurry, 2010; Press Association, 2010); while organisations such as<br />

WWF have been accused <strong>of</strong> „selling out‟ by working in partnership with corporate actors<br />

such as Coca-Cola (PR Watch, 2007): a more „positional‟ stance on the basis <strong>of</strong> the above<br />

description. However, despite the multiplicity <strong>of</strong> convergences between environmentalism<br />

and other <strong>for</strong>ms <strong>of</strong> global citizenship, there is a distinctly holistic conception that justifies a<br />

separate categorisation as „environmental global citizenship‟. Such a conception tends to<br />

prioritise above all an “ecological awareness <strong>of</strong> the fundamental interrelatedness <strong>of</strong> all<br />

aspects <strong>of</strong> the Earth”, from either an anthropocentric or an ecocentric position,<br />

emphasising “a sense <strong>of</strong> connectedness, empathy, and an appreciation <strong>for</strong> diversity and<br />

difference” (Richardson, 2008, p. 128): i.e. what Richardson terms “The Ecological<br />

Imaginary” (Richardson, 2008, p. 122).<br />

Spiritual <strong>Global</strong> <strong>Citizenship</strong><br />

The final type <strong>of</strong> global citizenship to <strong>for</strong>m a distinct category <strong>for</strong> the purposes <strong>of</strong> this<br />

analytical framework is what might be termed „religious‟, „faith-based‟ or „spiritual‟ global<br />

citizenship. Ideas relating to intangible phenomena such as „love‟ and „caring‟ can be<br />

found also in many conceptions <strong>of</strong> moral global citizenship; and conceptions <strong>of</strong> spiritual<br />

global citizenship may share aspects with cultural cosmopolitan global citizenship (such as<br />

the need <strong>for</strong> students to understand religious and cultural symbolism). Significant<br />

intersections are also found with positional global citizenship: a large number <strong>of</strong> global civil<br />

society organisations have roots in one or more <strong>of</strong> the major world religions; and<br />

conversely many <strong>of</strong> the world religions not only work with intergovernmental organisations<br />

such as the United Nations but also promote <strong>for</strong>ms <strong>of</strong> political cosmopolitan global<br />

citizenship themselves (<strong>for</strong> example, the promotion <strong>of</strong> the ideal <strong>of</strong> World Government by<br />

the Bahá‟í Faith); although Warburg (1999) argues that these <strong>for</strong>ms are ultimately<br />

Laura Johnson 17


conservative rather than liberal-democratic since they oppose a secular model <strong>for</strong> the ideal<br />

world-state in favour <strong>of</strong> a religious / spiritual / theocratic system <strong>of</strong> governance.<br />

The idea <strong>of</strong> spiritual global citizenship, like the environmental conception, goes further than<br />

the moral, cultural, positional and political <strong>for</strong>ms in that it generally promotes a sort <strong>of</strong><br />

holism in which “deeper” notions <strong>of</strong> the self and society connect and combine with “the<br />

energies <strong>of</strong> metaphysical commitment” to <strong>for</strong>mulate an understanding <strong>of</strong> the world or<br />

universe beyond the rational, empiricist Enlightenment model: a <strong>for</strong>m <strong>of</strong> “transcendence”<br />

(Conroy & Davis, 2008, p. 200). This can be found not only within religious teachings and<br />

faith-based meditations but also within certain <strong>for</strong>ms <strong>of</strong> humanism; not so much anti-<br />

religious secular humanism but instead those humanistic writings that emphasise affective<br />

elements that transcend rational philosophy and that cannot be measured empirically: <strong>for</strong><br />

example, „love <strong>for</strong> humanity‟, correlated by Dei (2008, p. 486) with „African and indigenous<br />

humanism‟; „spiritual happiness‟ and „spiritual awakening‟ (Noddings, 2003, pp. 173, 200);<br />

spiritual interpretations <strong>of</strong> „ubuntu‟ (Battle, 1997); and the type <strong>of</strong> global citizenship<br />

described by Danesh (1997, p. 81) and Golmohamad (2004, p. 140) as a combination<br />

between deep maturity, empathy and unselfish altruism, leading towards an „integrative<br />

attitude‟.<br />

Faith-based holistic manifestations <strong>of</strong> global citizenship also abound. Many world religions<br />

promote maxims such as the „Golden Rule‟ („treat others as you would like them to treat<br />

you‟); emphasise humility, empathy and charity towards all humanity; and focus on the<br />

pursuit <strong>of</strong> global social justice. However, religion and faith can also be seen as<br />

problematic, <strong>for</strong> example in the small minority <strong>of</strong> cases where fundamentalism,<br />

sectarianism and extreme close-mindedness arise. In such cases, McKinney (2008)<br />

argues that programmes <strong>of</strong> global citizenship education such as Oxfam‟s (1997)<br />

Laura Johnson 18


curriculum can be adapted and used to try to reduce sectarianism and promote religious<br />

co-operation, although, as Bryan and Vavrus (2005) note, it is unwise to regard any <strong>for</strong>m<br />

<strong>of</strong> education as a panacea to deeper social problems. Nevertheless, as Golmohamad<br />

(2008, p. 532) observes, global citizenship as it is conceived within spiritual contexts has<br />

the potential to cultivate the „good‟ in humanity, including: “openness to new encounters…<br />

mutual appreciation and respect <strong>for</strong> differences… [and] unity in diversity”, finally working<br />

towards “the betterment <strong>of</strong> the whole society.”<br />

Conclusions<br />

Within this paper, I have identified eight principal categories <strong>of</strong> global citizenship that can<br />

<strong>for</strong>m the basis <strong>of</strong> a framework <strong>for</strong> global citizenship. A summary diagram outlining these<br />

eight types is below at Table 1.<br />

Table 1: Categories <strong>of</strong> <strong>Global</strong> <strong>Citizenship</strong> Identified from Prevailing Literature<br />

Categories Conceptual Types and Manifestations Related to theories by:<br />

Political<br />

Cosmopolitan<br />

<strong>Global</strong> <strong>Citizenship</strong><br />

Moral Cosmopolitan<br />

<strong>Global</strong> <strong>Citizenship</strong><br />

Economic<br />

Cosmopolitan<br />

<strong>Global</strong> <strong>Citizenship</strong><br />

Cultural-aesthetic<br />

Cosmopolitan<br />

<strong>Global</strong> <strong>Citizenship</strong><br />

Critical (postcolonial)<br />

<strong>Global</strong><br />

<strong>Citizenship</strong><br />

World-state / institutional<br />

cosmopolitanism<br />

Cosmopolitan democracy<br />

Anarcho-cosmopolitanism<br />

„Strong‟ cosmopolitanism<br />

Human Rights-based<br />

„New‟ cosmopolitanism<br />

Competitive / egocentric<br />

Corporate Social Responsibility /<br />

Philanthropic<br />

Identification with globalised <strong>for</strong>ms <strong>of</strong><br />

media and languages („MTV / Internet<br />

generation‟)<br />

Identification with / awareness <strong>of</strong><br />

cultures and individuals<br />

Evaluation <strong>of</strong> cultural genres<br />

Post-development / post-colonial<br />

Post-Marxist<br />

Kant; Rawls; Held;<br />

McGrew; Linklater;<br />

Carter; Archibugi<br />

Stoics; Kant;<br />

Nussbaum; Sen; Singer;<br />

Appiah<br />

Smith; Quesnay; Hayek;<br />

Friedman<br />

Nietzsche (übermensch)<br />

Escobar; Said; Gramsci;<br />

Marx; Frankfurt School;<br />

Critical Pedagogy (e.g.<br />

Laura Johnson 19


Categories Conceptual Types and Manifestations Related to theories by:<br />

Freire)<br />

Positional <strong>Global</strong> Sociological discourse-based (e.g. Habermas<br />

<strong>Citizenship</strong><br />

feminism; race theory)<br />

(communicative<br />

Pragmatic and relationship-based:<br />

global civil society<br />

rationality)<br />

Environmental Ecocentric<br />

Dobson; Lovelock;<br />

<strong>Global</strong> <strong>Citizenship</strong> Anthropocentric<br />

enviro-scientific<br />

research<br />

Spiritual <strong>Global</strong> Spiritual / humanist<br />

Noddings; Danesh;<br />

<strong>Citizenship</strong><br />

Faith-based<br />

religious texts<br />

The categories outlined above and summarised within Table 1 contain a wide range <strong>of</strong><br />

philosophical standpoints, from relativism to universalism; from individualism to holism.<br />

They are fluid classifications rather than set in stone: many conceptions <strong>of</strong> global<br />

citizenship may traverse categories and combine a variety <strong>of</strong> different elements from each;<br />

and alternative categorisations may arise on reference to further scholarship and where<br />

new developments are constructed in theory and practice. Many overlaps have been<br />

identified between this and prevailing typologies <strong>of</strong> global citizenship: <strong>for</strong> example, by Falk<br />

(1993), Isin and Wood (1999), Roman (2004), Andreotti (2006b), Szelényi and Rhoads<br />

(2007), Arneil (2007), Richardson (2008), Schattle (2008a) and Shukla (2009).<br />

While the typology explicated within this paper enables a more ordered analysis <strong>of</strong> global<br />

citizenship programmes and policies, what is missing from these eight ideological<br />

categorisations is a sense <strong>of</strong> how they each connect between ideas and manifestations <strong>of</strong><br />

„global citizenship‟; between thought, identity and action; and between past, present and<br />

future. „<strong>Citizenship</strong>‟ itself can be seen as a set <strong>of</strong> rights (Marshall, 1950), a set <strong>of</strong> attributes<br />

(Cogan, 1998 & 2000), as a „status, feeling or practice‟ (Audrey Osler & Starkey, 2005) or<br />

as „a category, a tie, a role or an identity‟ (Tilly, 1996). However, even these helpful<br />

classifications are too narrow to expose the ontological depths <strong>of</strong> global citizenship: <strong>for</strong><br />

example, in identifying the sociological discourses at the root <strong>of</strong> conceptions <strong>of</strong> positional<br />

Laura Johnson 20


global citizenship and how these might give rise to specific organisations and actions. The<br />

next stage <strong>of</strong> this research is thus to construct an analytical framework <strong>for</strong> global<br />

citizenship that contains spaces <strong>for</strong> such elements, drawing upon existing frameworks and<br />

literature in the field. This will then be expanded into an analytical framework <strong>for</strong> global<br />

citizenship education, which will subsequently be used to analyse real-life manifestations<br />

<strong>of</strong> global citizenship, using two case study programmes <strong>for</strong> global citizenship education:<br />

specifically the Model United Nations and the Commonwealth Youth Summits. By<br />

exploring, deconstructing and re-categorising different conceptions <strong>of</strong> global citizenship<br />

education and analysing and comparing their manifestations in practice, this research<br />

provides a step towards a more coherent understanding <strong>of</strong> the phenomenon <strong>of</strong> „global<br />

citizenship education‟ <strong>for</strong> academics, policy-makers and practitioners.<br />

Laura Johnson 21


References<br />

Abdi, A. A., & Shultz, L. (2008). Educating <strong>for</strong> Human Rights and <strong>Global</strong> <strong>Citizenship</strong>. Albany, NY: State<br />

University <strong>of</strong> New York Press.<br />

Aiken, W., & Regan, T. (1984). Earthbound: new introductory essays in environmental ethics. New York:<br />

Random House.<br />

Andreotti, V. (2006a). A Postcolonial Reading <strong>of</strong> Contemporary Discourses Related to the <strong>Global</strong> Dimension<br />

in <strong>Education</strong> in England. Unpublished PhD, University <strong>of</strong> Nottingham.<br />

Andreotti, V. (2006b). S<strong>of</strong>t versus critical global citizenship education. Development <strong>Education</strong>, Policy and<br />

Practice, 3(1). Retrieved from http://www.osdemethodology.org.uk/texts/s<strong>of</strong>tcriticalvan.pdf<br />

Anghie, A. (2005). Imperialism, sovereignty and the making <strong>of</strong> international law. Cambridge: Cambridge<br />

University Press.<br />

Appiah, K. A. (2006). Cosmopolitanism: Ethics in a world <strong>of</strong> strangers. New York: W. W. Norton.<br />

Archibugi, D. (2008). The <strong>Global</strong> Commonwealth <strong>of</strong> Citizens: Toward Cosmopolitan Democracy. Princeton,<br />

NJ: Princeton University Press.<br />

Arneil, B. (2007). <strong>Global</strong> <strong>Citizenship</strong> and Empire. <strong>Citizenship</strong> Studies, 11(3), 301-328.<br />

Associated Press (2009). Greenpeace dumps rocks in sea to stop trawling. The Guardian, (10th August<br />

2009). Retrieved from http://www.guardian.co.uk/environment/2009/aug/10/greenpeace-fishingprotest<br />

Banks, J. A. (2008). <strong>Citizenship</strong> <strong>Education</strong> and Diversity: Implications <strong>for</strong> Teacher <strong>Education</strong>. In M. Peters, A.<br />

Britton & H. Blee (Eds.), <strong>Global</strong> citizenship education: philosophy, theory and pedagogy (pp. 317-<br />

331). Rotterdam: Sense.<br />

Battle, M. (1997). Reconciliation: the Ubuntu theology <strong>of</strong> Desmond Tutu. Cleveland, Ohio: Pilgrim Press.<br />

Bauman, Z. (1998). <strong>Global</strong>ization: The Human Consequences. Cambridge: Polity Press.<br />

Beck, U. (2006). The Cosmopolitan Vision (C. Cronin, Trans.). Cambridge: Polity Press.<br />

Bryan, A., & Vavrus, F. (2005). The promise and peril <strong>of</strong> education: the teaching <strong>of</strong> in/tolerance in an era <strong>of</strong><br />

globalisation. <strong>Global</strong>isation, Societies and <strong>Education</strong>, 3(2), 183-202.<br />

Carter, A. (2001). The political theory <strong>of</strong> global citizenship. London: Routledge.<br />

Cogan, J. J. (1998 & 2000). <strong>Citizenship</strong> <strong>Education</strong> <strong>for</strong> the 21st Century: Setting the Context. In J. J. Cogan &<br />

R. Derricott (Eds.), <strong>Citizenship</strong> <strong>for</strong> the 21st century: an international perspective on education (pp. 1-<br />

21). London: Kogan Page.<br />

Cogan, J. J., & Derricott, R. (1998 & 2000). <strong>Citizenship</strong> <strong>for</strong> the 21st century: an international perspective on<br />

education. London: Kogan Page.<br />

Conroy, J. C., & Davis, R. A. (2008). <strong>Citizenship</strong>, <strong>Education</strong> and the Claims <strong>of</strong> Religious Literacy. In M. Peters,<br />

A. Britton & H. Blee (Eds.), <strong>Global</strong> citizenship education: philosophy, theory and pedagogy (pp. 187-<br />

202). Rotterdam: Sense.<br />

Crystal, D. (2003). English as a global language (2nd ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.<br />

Danesh, H. B. (1997). The Psychology <strong>of</strong> Spirituality: From Divided Self to Integrated Self. Victoria, B.C.:<br />

Paradigm.<br />

De Ruyter, D. J., & Spiecker, B. (2008). The World Citizen Travels with a Different View. In M. Peters, A.<br />

Britton & H. Blee (Eds.), <strong>Global</strong> citizenship education: philosophy, theory and pedagogy (pp. 351-<br />

363). Rotterdam: Sense.<br />

Dei, G. (2008). Anti-Racism <strong>Education</strong> <strong>for</strong> <strong>Global</strong> <strong>Citizenship</strong>. In M. Peters, A. Britton & H. Blee (Eds.), <strong>Global</strong><br />

citizenship education: philosophy, theory and pedagogy (pp. 477-490). Rotterdam: Sense.<br />

Dewey, J. (1918/1982). What are we fighting <strong>for</strong>? In J. A. Boydston (Ed.), John Dewey: The middle works,<br />

1899-1924, Volume 11 (1918-1919). Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press.<br />

Dobson, A. (2006). Thick Cosmopolitanism. Political Studies, 54(1), 165-184.<br />

Dower, N. (1998). World ethics: the new agenda. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.<br />

Dower, N. (2000). The Idea <strong>of</strong> <strong>Global</strong> <strong>Citizenship</strong>: A Sympathetic Assessment. <strong>Global</strong> Society, 14(4), 553-567.<br />

Dower, N. (2003). An introduction to global citizenship. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.<br />

Else, L. (2010). Slavoj Žižek: Wake up and smell the apocalypse New Scientist, 2775(30 August 2010).<br />

Retrieved from http://www.newscientist.com/article/mg20727751.100-slavoj-zizek-wake-up-andsmell-the-apocalypse.html?page=1<br />

Laura Johnson 22


Escobar, A. (1995). Encountering Development: The Making and Unmaking <strong>of</strong> the Third World. Princeton:<br />

Princeton University Press.<br />

Falk, R. A. (1993). The Making <strong>of</strong> <strong>Global</strong> <strong>Citizenship</strong>. In J. Brecher, J. B. Childs & J. Cutler (Eds.), <strong>Global</strong><br />

visions: beyond the new world order (pp. 39-50). Boston: South End Press.<br />

Falk, R. A., Kim, S. S., & Mendlovitz, S. H. (1991). The United Nations and a just world order. Boulder:<br />

Westview Press.<br />

Faulks, K. (2000). <strong>Citizenship</strong>. London: Routledge.<br />

Ferry, L. (1995). The new ecological order (C. Volk, Trans.). Chicago, Ill.; London: University <strong>of</strong> Chicago Press.<br />

Freire, P. (1970). Pedagogy <strong>of</strong> the oppressed. New York: Continuum Publishing Company.<br />

Gabay, C. (2008). Anarcho-cosmopolitanism: The Universalisation <strong>of</strong> the Equal Exchange. <strong>Global</strong> Society,<br />

22(2), 197-216.<br />

Galston, W. (1989). Civic education in the liberal state. In N. L. Rosenblum (Ed.), Liberalism and the Moral<br />

Life. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.<br />

Golmohamad, M. (2004). World <strong>Citizenship</strong>, Identity and the Notion <strong>of</strong> an Integrated Self. Studies in<br />

Philosophy and <strong>Education</strong>, 23, 131-148.<br />

Golmohamad, M. (2008). <strong>Global</strong> <strong>Citizenship</strong>: From Theory to Practice, Unlocking Hearts and Minds. In M.<br />

Peters, A. Britton & H. Blee (Eds.), <strong>Global</strong> citizenship education: philosophy, theory and pedagogy<br />

(pp. 519-533). Rotterdam: Sense.<br />

Habermas, J. (1984). The theory <strong>of</strong> communicative action. Vol.1, Reason and the rationalization <strong>of</strong> society.<br />

London: Heinemann <strong>Education</strong>.<br />

Heater, D. (2002). World citizenship: cosmopolitan thinking and its opponents. London: Continuum.<br />

Held, D. (1995). Democracy and the global order: from the modern state to cosmopolitan governance.<br />

Cambridge: Polity.<br />

Held, D. (2004). <strong>Global</strong> covenant: the social democratic alternative to the Washington consensus.<br />

Cambridge: Polity.<br />

Herzog, A. (2004). Political itineraries and anarchic cosmopolitanism in the thought <strong>of</strong> Hannah Arendt.<br />

Inquiry, 47(1), 20-41.<br />

Hooper, J. (2009). Greenpeace activists hijack Italian power stations. The Guardian, (8th July 2009).<br />

Retrieved from http://www.guardian.co.uk/environment/2009/jul/08/greenpeace-g8-protest-coalitaly<br />

Humes, W. (2008). The Discourse <strong>of</strong> <strong>Global</strong> <strong>Citizenship</strong>. In M. A. Peters, A. Britton & H. Blee (Eds.), <strong>Global</strong><br />

citizenship education: philosophy, theory and pedagogy (pp. 41-52). Rotterdam: Sense.<br />

Isin, E. F., & Wood, P. K. (1999). <strong>Citizenship</strong> and identity. London: Sage.<br />

Jelin, E. (2000). <strong>Towards</strong> a <strong>Global</strong> Environmental <strong>Citizenship</strong>? <strong>Citizenship</strong> Studies, 4(1), 47-63.<br />

Kymlicka, W. (1995). Multicultural citizenship: a liberal theory <strong>of</strong> minority rights. Ox<strong>for</strong>d: Ox<strong>for</strong>d University<br />

Press.<br />

Linklater, A. (1998). The trans<strong>for</strong>mation <strong>of</strong> political community: ethical foundations <strong>of</strong> the post-Westphalian<br />

era. Ox<strong>for</strong>d: Polity.<br />

Lovelock, J. E., & Margulis, L. (1974). Atmospheric homeostasis by and <strong>for</strong> the biosphere: the gaia<br />

hypothesis. Tellus, 26(1), 2–10.<br />

Lu, C. (Ed.) (2008) The Stan<strong>for</strong>d Encyclopedia <strong>of</strong> Philosophy (Fall 2008 ed.).<br />

MacIntyre, A. (1981). After virtue: a study in moral theory. London: Duckworth.<br />

Marshall, T. H. (1950). <strong>Citizenship</strong> and social class, and other essays. Cambridge: Cambridge University<br />

Press.<br />

McCracken, G. (1988). The long interview. Newbury Park, Calif. ; London: Sage Publications.<br />

McCurry, J. (2010). Anti-whaling activists face trial in Japan. The Guardian, (14th February 2010). Retrieved<br />

from http://www.guardian.co.uk/world/2010/feb/14/sato-suzuki-trial-japan-whaling<br />

McGrew, A. G. (1997). The trans<strong>for</strong>mation <strong>of</strong> democracy?: globalization and territorial democracy.<br />

Cambridge: Polity, in association with the Open University.<br />

McKinney, S. J. (2008). Immigrants and Religious Conflict: Insider Accounts <strong>of</strong> Italian, Lithuanian and Polish<br />

Catholics in Scotland. In M. Peters, A. Britton & H. Blee (Eds.), <strong>Global</strong> citizenship education:<br />

philosophy, theory and pedagogy (pp. 333-349). Rotterdam: Sense.<br />

Laura Johnson 23


McLaughlin, T. H. (1992). <strong>Citizenship</strong>, Diversity and <strong>Education</strong>: a philosophical perspective. Journal <strong>of</strong> Moral<br />

<strong>Education</strong>, 21(3), 235-250.<br />

Mill, J. S. (1867). Inaugural Address delivered to the University <strong>of</strong> St. Andrew's, Feb. 1st, 1867. London:<br />

Longmans, Green, Reader and Dyer.<br />

Navari, C. (2000). Internationalism and the state in the twentieth century. New York: Routledge.<br />

Nietzsche, F. W. (1883/1961). Thus spoke Zarathustra (R. J. Hollingdale, Trans.). Harmondsworth: Penguin<br />

Books.<br />

Noddings, N. (2003). Happiness and education. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.<br />

Nussbaum, M. C. (1996). Patriotism and cosmopolitanism. In M. C. Nussbaum & J. Cohen (Eds.), For love <strong>of</strong><br />

country: debating the limits <strong>of</strong> patriotism (pp. 2-17). Boston: Beacon Press.<br />

Osler, A., & Starkey, H. (2005). Changing citizenship: democracy and inclusion in education. Maidenhead:<br />

Open University Press.<br />

Osler, A., & Starkey, H. (2008). <strong>Education</strong> <strong>for</strong> Cosmopolitan <strong>Citizenship</strong>. In V. Georgi (Ed.), The making <strong>of</strong><br />

citizens in Europe: new perspectives on citizenship education. Berlin: Bundeszentrale für politische<br />

Bildung (BPB) (German Federal Agency <strong>for</strong> Civic <strong>Education</strong>).<br />

Oxfam (1997). A curriculum <strong>for</strong> global citizenship. Ox<strong>for</strong>d: Oxfam Development <strong>Education</strong> Programme.<br />

Papastephanou, M. (2008). Cosmopolitanism: With or Without Patriotism? In M. Peters, A. Britton & H.<br />

Blee (Eds.), <strong>Global</strong> citizenship education: philosophy, theory and pedagogy (pp. 169-185).<br />

Rotterdam: Sense.<br />

Peters, M. A., Blee, H., & Britton, A. (2008). Introduction: Many Faces <strong>of</strong> <strong>Global</strong> Civil Society: Possible<br />

Futures <strong>for</strong> <strong>Global</strong> <strong>Citizenship</strong>. In M. A. Peters, A. Britton & H. Blee (Eds.), <strong>Global</strong> citizenship<br />

education: philosophy, theory and pedagogy (pp. 1-13). Rotterdam: Sense.<br />

Phan, L. H. (2008). Teaching English as an international language: identity, resistance and negotiation.<br />

Clevedon: Multilingual Matters.<br />

Pogge, T. W. M. (1989). Realizing Rawls. Ithaca; London: Cornell University Press.<br />

Pogge, T. W. M. (2002). World poverty and human rights. Cambridge: Polity Press.<br />

PR Watch (2007). WWF Greenwashes Coca-Cola. Center <strong>for</strong> Media and Democracy: PR Watch, (5th June<br />

2007). Retrieved from http://www.prwatch.org/node/6123<br />

Press Association (2010). Greenpeace activists scale BP's London headquarters in oil protest. The Guardian,<br />

(20th May 2010). Retrieved from<br />

http://www.guardian.co.uk/environment/2010/may/20/greenpeace-activists-scale-bp-buildingro<strong>of</strong><br />

Rahnema, M., & Bawtree, V. (Eds.). (1997). The post-development reader. London: Zed Books.<br />

Regan, T., & Singer, P. (1976). Animal rights and human obligations. Englewood Cliffs; London: Prentice-<br />

Hall.<br />

Richardson, G. (2008). Conflicting Imaginaries: <strong>Global</strong> <strong>Citizenship</strong> <strong>Education</strong> in Canada as a Site <strong>of</strong><br />

Contestation. In M. Peters, A. Britton & H. Blee (Eds.), <strong>Global</strong> citizenship education: philosophy,<br />

theory and pedagogy (pp. 115-131). Rotterdam: Sense.<br />

Roman, L. G. (2004). States <strong>of</strong> Insecurity: Cold War memory, “global citizenship” and its discontents.<br />

Discourse: Studies in the Cultural Politics <strong>of</strong> <strong>Education</strong>, 25(2), 231-259.<br />

Rose, G. (1997). Situating knowledges: positionality, reflexivities and other tactics. Progress in Human<br />

Geography, 21(3), 305-320.<br />

Said, E. W. (1978). Orientalism. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.<br />

Schattle, H. (2008a). <strong>Education</strong> <strong>for</strong> global citizenship: Illustrations <strong>of</strong> ideological pluralism and adaptation.<br />

Journal <strong>of</strong> Political Ideologies, 13(1), 73-94.<br />

Schattle, H. (2008b). The Practices <strong>of</strong> <strong>Global</strong> <strong>Citizenship</strong>. Maryland, USA: Rowman & Littlefield.<br />

Shaw, M. (2000). Theory <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Global</strong> State: <strong>Global</strong>ity as Unfinished Revolution Cambridge: Cambridge<br />

University Press.<br />

Shukla, N. (2009). Power, discourse, and learning global citizenship: A case study <strong>of</strong> international NGOs and<br />

a grassroots movement in the Narmada Valley, India. <strong>Education</strong>, <strong>Citizenship</strong> and Social Justice, 4(1),<br />

133-147.<br />

Singer, P. (2004). One world: the ethics <strong>of</strong> globalization (2nd ed.). New Haven, Conn.; London: Yale<br />

University Press.<br />

Laura Johnson 24


Spivak, G. C. (1988). Can the Subaltern Speak? In C. Nelson & L. Grossberg (Eds.), Marxism and the<br />

interpretation <strong>of</strong> culture (pp. 271-313). Urbana: University <strong>of</strong> Illinois Press.<br />

Spivak, G. C., & Harasym, S. (1990). The postcolonial critic: interviews, strategies, dialogues. New York;<br />

London: Routledge.<br />

Szelényi, K., & Rhoads, R. A. (2007). <strong>Citizenship</strong> in a global context: The perspectives <strong>of</strong> international<br />

graduate students in the United States. Comparative <strong>Education</strong> Review, 51(1), 25-47.<br />

Tilly, C. (1996). <strong>Citizenship</strong>, Identity and Social History. In C. Tilly (Ed.), <strong>Citizenship</strong>, Identity and Social<br />

History (pp. 1-17). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.<br />

Tully, J. (2008). Two Meanings <strong>of</strong> <strong>Global</strong> <strong>Citizenship</strong>: Modern and Diverse. In M. A. Peters, A. Britton & H.<br />

Blee (Eds.), <strong>Global</strong> citizenship education: philosophy, theory and pedagogy (pp. 15-40). Rotterdam:<br />

Sense.<br />

UNESCO, United Nations <strong>Education</strong>al, Scientific and Cultural Organization, & UNEP, United Nations<br />

Environment Programme (2002). Cultural Diversity and Biodiversity <strong>for</strong> Sustainable Development.<br />

Paper presented at the jointly convened UNESCO and UNEP high-level Roundtable held on 3<br />

September 2002 during the World Summit on Sustainable Development, Johannesburg.<br />

Waks, L. J. (2008). Cosmopolitanism and <strong>Citizenship</strong> <strong>Education</strong>. In M. Peters, A. Britton & H. Blee (Eds.),<br />

<strong>Global</strong> citizenship education: philosophy, theory and pedagogy (pp. 203-219). Rotterdam: Sense.<br />

Warburg, M. (1999). Baha'i: A Religious Approach to <strong>Global</strong>ization. Social Compass, 46(1), 47-56.<br />

Ward, P. (2009). The Medea Hypothesis: Is Life on Earth Ultimately Self-Destructive? . Princeton: Princeton<br />

University Press.<br />

Wendt, A. (1999). Social Theory <strong>of</strong> International Politics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.<br />

Wendt, A. (2003). Why a World State Is Inevitable. European Journal <strong>of</strong> International Relations, 9(4), 491-<br />

542.<br />

Žižek, S. (2010). Living in the end times. London: Verso.<br />

Laura Johnson 25

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!