16.01.2013 Views

Proceedings of the 13 ESSLLI Student Session - Multiple Choices ...

Proceedings of the 13 ESSLLI Student Session - Multiple Choices ...

Proceedings of the 13 ESSLLI Student Session - Multiple Choices ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

<strong>Proceedings</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>13</strong> th <strong>ESSLLI</strong> <strong>Student</strong> <strong>Session</strong><br />

Thus, φ answers ψ if φ removes some salient possibilities that ψ introduces. This<br />

notion <strong>of</strong> answerhood should be familiar from a partition <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> questions: in both<br />

cases, answering a question amounts to eliminating some <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> possibilities it introduces.<br />

But an important, unique feature <strong>of</strong> this definition is that an answer doesnt necessarily give<br />

information: it suffices that an answer suggest certain possibilities for <strong>the</strong> questioner to<br />

consider.<br />

We close this section by working through a few examples. We use <strong>the</strong> following notational<br />

conventions: {p} = {i ∈ I | i |= p}, {¬p} = {i ∈ I | i �|= p} etc.<br />

Example 2: A Polar Question.<br />

Recall example (2), and let p and q be <strong>the</strong> propositions ‘Bill is coming to <strong>the</strong> party’ and ‘John<br />

is coming to <strong>the</strong> party’ respectively. Let Γ = {I, ∅}; <strong>the</strong>n ⋄p ∧ ⋄q answers ?p ∧ ?q: Γ[?p ∧<br />

?q] = {I, {p}, {¬p}, {q}, {¬q}, ∅} = Γ 1 . Then: Γ 1 [⋄p ∧ ⋄q] = {I, {p}, {q}, ∅} = Γ 2 , and<br />

since 〈Γ 2 〉 ⊂ 〈Γ 1 〉, ⋄p ∧ ⋄q answers ?p ∧ ?q.<br />

Example 3: A Wh-Question.<br />

Consider <strong>the</strong> question ‘Who is likes to paint?’, and note that ‘Bill might like to paint’ felicitously<br />

answers this question. Let Px be ‘x likes to paint’, and let b be Bill. Let Γ = {I, ∅}.<br />

Then: Γ[?Px] = Γ ∪ {{i | i ≡ j (mod Px)} | j ∈ I }<br />

= Γ ∪ {{i |i(P) = D*}| D* ⊆ D} = Γ 1 . Then<br />

Γ 1 [⋄Pb] = Γ ∪ {{ i | i(P) = D*}[⋄Pb] |D* ⊆ D}<br />

= Γ ∪ {{i | i(b) ∈ i(P) and i(P) = D*}|D* ⊆ D such that i(b) ∈ D*}<br />

Since Γ 1 [⋄Pb] ⊂ Γ 1 , ⋄Pj is an answer to ?Px.<br />

Examples 3 and 4 bring out an important feature <strong>of</strong> this paper’s framework: epistemic<br />

modals behave much like questions. Both questions and epistemic modals draw attention<br />

to certain possibilities without committing <strong>the</strong> speaker to a position on whe<strong>the</strong>r or not<br />

<strong>the</strong>se possibilities are actual. Epistemic modals, however, are stronger than questions:<br />

modals draw attention to fewer possibilities than questions, suggesting that <strong>the</strong> chosen<br />

possibilities are somehow more important than <strong>the</strong> ignored possibilities. The notion <strong>of</strong> a<br />

salient possibility allows us to represent this similarity between questions and epistemic<br />

modals in fully formal way.<br />

Example 4: Raising Issues Without Questions.<br />

Recall (4), and let p and q be ‘Alice and A are going fishing in Leiden tomorrow’ and ‘It’s<br />

illegal to fish in Leiden’ respectively. Let Γ = {I, ∅}. Then<br />

Γ[p][⋄q] = {{p}, {p ∧ q}, ∅}. Here, since no possibility in Γ[p] satisfied q, <strong>the</strong> epistemic<br />

modal acted to add <strong>the</strong> possibility {p ∧ q} to <strong>the</strong> context. Thus, even though no questions<br />

have been asked in this context, B is able to bring A’s attention to some issue by using an<br />

epistemic modal.<br />

Example 5: Infelicitous Answer.<br />

Responding to a polar question ?φ with ⋄φ ∧ ⋄¬φ should not count as answering <strong>the</strong> question:<br />

ra<strong>the</strong>r, responding to a question with ‘maybe, maybe not’ is a deliberate and almost<br />

reticent refusal to answer <strong>the</strong> question. Our semantics allows us to account for this: {I,<br />

∅}[?p][⋄p ∧ ⋄¬p] = {I, {p}, {¬p}, ∅}[⋄p ∧ ⋄¬p]<br />

= {I, {p}, {¬p}, ∅}[⋄p][⋄¬p] = {I, {p}, ∅}[⋄¬p] = {I, {p}, {¬p}, ∅}. Thus,<br />

⋄p ∧ ⋄¬p does not answer ?p. Moreover, ⋄p ∧ ⋄¬p is actually equivalent to ?p in this information<br />

state.<br />

In general, ?φ and ⋄φ ∧ ⋄¬φ are equivalent in any information state that is consistent with<br />

both φ and ¬φ, so polar questions can almost be defined using epistemic modals (if we assume<br />

that polar questions presuppose that both <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir answers are possible, polar questions<br />

can be defined in terms <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> epistemic modality operator).<br />

32

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!