07.04.2013 Views

volume XV, 2005 - ALL.pdf - San Francisco State University

volume XV, 2005 - ALL.pdf - San Francisco State University

volume XV, 2005 - ALL.pdf - San Francisco State University

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

eex<br />

post<br />

efacto


ex post facto<br />

Journal of the History Students at <strong>San</strong> <strong>Francisco</strong> <strong>State</strong> <strong>University</strong><br />

SPRING <strong>2005</strong> VOLUME XIV


epf<br />

Ex Post Facto is published annually by the students of the Department<br />

of History at <strong>San</strong> <strong>Francisco</strong> <strong>State</strong> <strong>University</strong>, and members of Kappa Phi<br />

Chapter of Phi Alpha Theta, the national history honor society. All views<br />

of fact or opinion are the sole responsibility of the authors and may not<br />

reflect the views of the editorial staff.<br />

Questions or comments may be directed to:<br />

Ex Post Facto<br />

c/o Department of History, <strong>San</strong> <strong>Francisco</strong> <strong>State</strong> <strong>University</strong><br />

1600 Holloway Ave.<br />

<strong>San</strong> <strong>Francisco</strong>, CA 94512<br />

Contact us via email at: epf@sfsu.edu<br />

The journal is also published online at userwww.sfsu.edu/~epf<br />

The Ex Post Facto editorial board wishes to thank the Instructionally<br />

Related Activities Committee at <strong>San</strong> <strong>Francisco</strong> <strong>State</strong> <strong>University</strong> for providing<br />

funding. Ex Post Facto also thanks Christopher Waldrep, Vernon<br />

<strong>San</strong>ders, and Alicia Vosberg, who have all made the process much smoother<br />

than it might have been. Thanks should also go to the professors who<br />

encouraged students to write the high quality papers that are included in<br />

this publication.<br />

Ownership of papers is retained by authors and may be submitted<br />

for publication elsewhere. Authorization has been granted by authors for<br />

use of papers both in the printed publication of Ex Post Facto and the<br />

website.<br />

Copyright © <strong>2005</strong>, <strong>San</strong> <strong>Francisco</strong> <strong>State</strong> <strong>University</strong>.


MANAGING CO-EDITORS<br />

Thomas Dorrance & Andrew Oetzel<br />

Rhiannon Anderson<br />

Sarah Barkin<br />

Michael Caires<br />

Jon Cole<br />

Corry Dodson<br />

Sam Dupont<br />

Patricia Melinkoff<br />

Joyce Mills<br />

staff<br />

EDITORIAL BOARD<br />

LAYOUT<br />

Kevin Bourque<br />

FACULTY ADVISOR<br />

Christopher Waldrep<br />

Michael Mott<br />

Kevin Mummey<br />

Jeremy Pearson<br />

Lindsey Peregoff<br />

Rebecca Shaw<br />

Maryan Soliman<br />

Sarah Stern<br />

Robert Taylor


graduate WORK undergraduate WORK<br />

contents<br />

p. 1. MICHAEL T. CAIRES<br />

Friend to Slavery: Legal Protection of Slavery<br />

by the California Supreme Court<br />

p. 15. HEATHER COOPER<br />

Radical Exclusion: Nazi Euthanasia, 1939-1945<br />

p. 41. DANIEL ELASH<br />

The Persistence of a Muslim Sicily<br />

p. 53. SARAH BARKIN<br />

Little Women & Evil-Looking Men:<br />

Rebecca Buffum Spring & the Politics of Motherhood in Antebellum America<br />

p. 71. MICHAEL MOTT<br />

“From Bush-League Hamlet to Major-League Metropolis:”<br />

Los Angeles, the Dodgers, and Proposition B<br />

p. 95. MARYAN SOLIMAN<br />

American Fourierism: Universalizing Reform<br />

p. 109. LEAH THOMPSON<br />

The Revitalization of Tactical Debate in the Convention of 1843<br />

p. 123. RHIANNON ANDERSON<br />

Chasing Sodomy During the Renaissance:<br />

A Comparative Study of Venice and Florence<br />

p. 139. SAM DUPONT<br />

Kings and Christianity:<br />

The Politics of Religious Conversion in Seventh-Century England<br />

p. 153. BOOK REVIEWS & HISTORIOGRAPHY


Friend to Slavery<br />

L E G A L P RO T E C T I O N O F S L AV E RY<br />

B Y T H E C A L I F O R N I A S U P R E M E C O U RT<br />

E<br />

M I C H A E L T . Caires<br />

undergraduate WINNER: SARAH RUTH PRIZE


eex<br />

post<br />

efacto


he end of war with Mexico increased the size of the United <strong>State</strong>s<br />

in the biggest acquisition of territory since the Louisiana Purchase. Yet,<br />

this victory for Manifest Destiny threatened the delicate balance between<br />

slave and free states in the Union. The new territory unleashed a fury<br />

of sentiment and opinions on the future of slavery in the West. Senators<br />

and representatives from the South threatened secession and northerners<br />

refused to endorse slavery’s westward expansion. Newspapers across the<br />

South and the North denounced each other and some called for violent<br />

action. To avoid secession in this volatile atmosphere, Congress admitted<br />

California as a free state based on the Compromise of 1850. With a series<br />

of concessions between the two factions, including allowing a new stricter<br />

fugitive slave law for the South, Congress hoped that the compromise<br />

could answer the problems posed by slavery. 1<br />

T<br />

Yet, even with the Compromise of 1850, no combination of geography<br />

or law could stop the spread of slavery. On June 15, 1852, the <strong>San</strong><br />

<strong>Francisco</strong> Herald, far from the shores of Virginia or South Carolina, advertised<br />

the sale of a “negro slave” for $300 or $100 if the local abolitionists<br />

would like to free the slave rather than attempt to steal him. 2 While this<br />

article might seem common in a newspaper from any of the slave states at<br />

the time, the California Constitutional Convention of 1849 unanimously<br />

voted to ban slavery in the new constitution. 3 California’s very presence<br />

in the Union was a result of a national compromise in which Congress<br />

admitted California as a free state and wrote a new fugitive slave law to<br />

protect pro-slavery interests. Western slavery created a serious divide in<br />

Congress during the Wilmot Proviso in 1848. Many southerners saw the<br />

West as open to slavery by right of popular sovereignty.<br />

GIOVANNA PABLOMO<br />

3


4<br />

From the first days of the Gold Rush, white southerners brought<br />

along their slaves to California to make their fortunes, and intended to<br />

keep them as slaves as long as they resided in the state. 4 When California<br />

entered the Union as a free state, many southerners brought their slaves<br />

anyway, despite the antislavery constitution. After its passage, many<br />

southerners who moved to California during the Gold Rush wanted<br />

two Californias, a free North and a slave South. They felt that the political<br />

dealings in Washington did not reflect their popular will. The “two<br />

California plan” would maintain the sectional balance and would not violate<br />

the spirit of the compromise back in Washington. 5<br />

Early twentieth-century works on slavery in California focus on reasons<br />

for the failure of slavery to take root by political means. These scholars<br />

paint a picture of a patchwork of cases where judges used more principal<br />

than law to either dismiss or remove accused slaves from the state.Yet, they<br />

avoid explaining effectively the way the state allowed slavery to exist even in<br />

limited ways, rather than as an inconstant policy enforced by local judges.<br />

Other research portrays lawmakers actively using positive law to establish<br />

slavery in California. 6 They argue that the question of slavery in California<br />

remained well embedded in the national debate on slavery and protected by<br />

the southern-born group of lawmakers and the California Supreme Court.<br />

This paper will argue that the Supreme Court of California did much to<br />

protect slavery in California by way of judicial opinions that allowed slave<br />

owners to keep their slaves, despite the anti-slavery constitution.<br />

By the time California joined the Union, a series of cases demonstrated<br />

the importance of the courts in shaping the law of slavery in<br />

America. Before 1850, a few cases drastically changed American law dealing<br />

with slavery and the relationship between free states and slave states.<br />

All of these laws and cases strongly affected the thinking of the California<br />

Supreme Court. For example, the U.S. Constitution promised that “full<br />

faith and credit shall be given in each <strong>State</strong> to public Acts, Records, and<br />

Judicial Proceedings of every other <strong>State</strong>.” 7 This in effect meant that comity,<br />

or the consideration for the laws and acts of other states, required<br />

respect by the other states in the Union. 8 In practice, this meant if a man<br />

owned slaves which the state of Virginia recognized as his property, that<br />

fact demanded recognition in the other states of the Union, including<br />

states where slavery did not exist. This idea would prove vital to many<br />

judges across the nation who would protect slavery in the free states and<br />

territories. Furthermore, this type of argument would find its way into the<br />

opinions of the justices in California, making comity more important than<br />

enforcing the anti-slavery clause in the California constitution.<br />

In addition, the U.S. Constitution also provided for the return of<br />

fugitive slaves who attempted to escape to free states. 9 A fugitive slave law<br />

in 1793 depended on northern state judges and officials to enforce the law<br />

and return the slaves back into bondage. 10 Combined with the cases that<br />

MICHAEL T. CAIRES


went before them, these two ideas helped form the court’s thinking and<br />

influence their decisions to give favoritism to the slave owner rather than<br />

the people who argued for their freedom.<br />

In the era after the Revolution, states like Pennsylvania and New<br />

York that saw many southern officials and businessmen, often let these<br />

men bring their slaves with them to stay for a short period. In this early<br />

period, these states became models of how a free state could interact with<br />

slave states. Even after the North began abolishing slavery, slave owners<br />

still traveled through the North with their slaves. However, with a growing<br />

anti-slavery movement during the 1830s, this changed and northern<br />

judges slowly began to rescind the hospitality given to slave masters and<br />

their property. This meant that free states began entitling freedom to any<br />

slave who came to live in their state past a certain time period. 11 The<br />

Massachusetts Supreme Court completely changed this tradition in 1836<br />

with the case Commonwealth v. Aves. 12 The Court freed a slave girl named<br />

Med, who traveled with her master Mrs. Slater to visit her father Thomas<br />

Aves in Boston. 13 In his opinion, Chief Justice Lemuel Shaw ruled that<br />

comity did not apply here because such a construction would mean that<br />

a slave master could bring a slave to a free state for as long as he pleased,<br />

when it was clear that human property did not exist in Massachusetts. 14<br />

This case radicalized the relations between states on the subject of slavery,<br />

fully breaking the tradition of comity on slavery as it had existed. In the<br />

years after Aves, many northern courts ruled that any slave brought voluntarily<br />

into the state, became free.<br />

These basic themes of fugitive slaves, traveling with slaves, and the<br />

issues of comity among states are at the core of the thinking behind the<br />

opinions and decisions of the California Supreme Court in the years preceding<br />

the Civil War. Their opinions and logic demonstrate that they did<br />

not agree or conform to opinions like Aves but acted in a manner that<br />

showed their loyalty to slave-state citizens and their slave property. Many<br />

states passed personal liberty laws that prevented state officials from helping<br />

slave catchers under the fugitive slave law. In 1842, the U.S. Supreme<br />

Court decided in Prigg v. Pennsylvania, that the federal government could<br />

not force the states to help in the capture of fugitive slaves. This decision<br />

effectively negated the law of 1793 and led to the Compromise of 1850<br />

that used federal officials to enforce the law. All of these voices contributed<br />

to the conception of slavery in California after 1850.<br />

The first real source for a pro-slavery voice in the state came from the<br />

legislature. The pro-slavery politicians in California proved too strong in<br />

Sacramento during the early years of the state to allow for any meaningful<br />

enforcement of the anti-slavery clause of their new constitution. 15 Led<br />

by the southerner Henry A. Crabb, these Californians (mostly from the<br />

South and living in Southern California) not only approved of the new<br />

national slave law, but felt that it did not go far enough in its protection<br />

Friend to Slavery<br />

5


6<br />

of the rights of slaveholders traveling to the state in the years before it<br />

became a state. 16 On April 15, 1852, the state legislature passed a new law<br />

entitled, “Respecting fugitives from labor and slaves brought into this state<br />

prior to her admission into the Union.” 17 This law sounded like its national<br />

counterpart except for the fourth section stating that any slave brought to<br />

California voluntarily before it became a state, and who refused to leave,<br />

became a fugitive slave. Moreover, this legislation provided for state officials<br />

to help in their recapture until 1853 (later extended to 1855). 18 Like<br />

the 1850 federal law, many greatly feared this provision might result in the<br />

arbitrary carrying off of free blacks into slavery. 19<br />

Less than six months after its passage, the Supreme Court of<br />

California would consider the constitutionality of the law in the case In<br />

re Perkins. Yet, pro-slavery men in the state could make their voices heard<br />

in this forum too, and placed pro-slavery men on the bench. The 1849<br />

California constitution, allowed the public to vote for state Supreme Court<br />

justices (one chief justice and two associate judges) for a term of six years,<br />

with the legislature picking the chief justice for a term of two years. 20 Yet,<br />

only white males and former Mexican citizens received the right to vote,<br />

and with the flood of southerners into the state, the pro-slave delegation<br />

became strong in the California legislature. 21 At the time of the Perkins<br />

case, two of the justices on the bench (including Chief Justice Hugh C.<br />

Murray from Missouri) came from slave states and one came from New<br />

York. 22 The backgrounds of the justices could have played a part in their<br />

opinion and sentiments on slavery.<br />

Yet, if the court was proslavery before Perkins, the facts of the case<br />

gave the court the opportunity to indicate their position. Before California<br />

became a state, C.S. Perkins of Mississippi brought his slaves Robert<br />

Perkins, Carter Perkins, and <strong>San</strong>dy Jones to mine for the gold that lured<br />

so many Americans to the state. 23 In 1851, C.S. Perkins went back to<br />

Mississippi, leaving his slaves in the care of Dr. John Hill. In early 1852,<br />

according to the slaves, Hill told them that they were free men, and for<br />

several months, they created a business for themselves and had no connections<br />

with C.S. Perkins. 24 By April 1852, Perkins decided that he wanted<br />

his slaves back and appointed Albert G. Perkins of Sacramento as his<br />

agent to remove Robert, Carter, and <strong>San</strong>dy from the state. 25 On May 31,<br />

1852, A.G. Perkins and another man by the name of Harden Scoles arrested<br />

the slaves and brought them before B.D. Fry, a Sacramento justice<br />

of the peace. 26 In a hearing with no jury or substantial proof, Fry decided<br />

that the three black men were fugitive slaves, and issued a certificate for<br />

their immediate return back to Mississippi. 27 On June 11, 1852, the three<br />

attempted to obtain a writ of habeas corpus before Judge Aldrich of the<br />

Sixth District. Aldrich concurred that the three men were still slaves and<br />

the property of C.S. Perkins. 28 With the approval of a justice of the peace<br />

and a judge, A.G. Perkins and Scoles took the three men to <strong>San</strong> <strong>Francisco</strong><br />

for a steamer bound for Mississippi. At this point, the black communities<br />

MICHAEL T. CAIRES


of Sacramento and <strong>San</strong> <strong>Francisco</strong>, with the help of white sympathizers,<br />

had raised money for a legal defense. 29 They hired the firm of Brown,<br />

Pratt, and Leary who in turn directly petitioned Justice Alex Wells of the<br />

state Supreme Court for a writ of certiorari, which Wells granted on June<br />

14. 30 While it is unclear why the court decided to hear the case, perhaps<br />

the court saw this as a chance to defend the new fugitive slave law and<br />

settle the question of slavery in California.<br />

To this point, Chief Justice Hugh C. Murray demonstrated that he<br />

understood the many political concerns and pressures on the subject of<br />

slavery in the state at that time. Murray saw that this case presented a<br />

chance to end the uproar on the subject. He contended that it was not<br />

the job of the court to determine if the three accused were slaves, as B.D.<br />

Fry had the full power under the act to do this. Rather, the court could<br />

only determine if the act of 1852 conformed to the constitution of the<br />

state. Even that consideration had political reasons: “a desire to settle this<br />

question may induce us to advise in its adjudication.” 31 This sentiment<br />

carried with it the more important point that the court saw itself as the<br />

ultimate arbiter of legal power in the state. While judicial review and the<br />

court’s power of final say on the laws and interpretation of constitutional<br />

questions is common today, this was not always so. Indeed, the court in<br />

their opinion asserted their ultimate power to decide the status of slavery<br />

in the state. 32 Rather than debates in the legislature or the outcries of the<br />

public for or against slavery, the court asserted its position to decide this<br />

question, fundamentally increasing its responsibility in strengthening the<br />

slave owner’s position in the state.<br />

Murray went on to say that the law of 1852 was constitutional<br />

because, unlike in Prigg v. Pennsylvania, where the laws of Pennsylvania<br />

clashed with those of the federal government, California’s law supplemented<br />

and reinforced the fugitive slave law of 1850. 33 Indeed, Murray<br />

followed the dissenting opinion of Chief Justice Taney, who said, “The<br />

language used in the Constitution does not, in my judgment, justify the<br />

construction given to it by the court. It contains no words prohibiting the<br />

several states from passing laws to enforce this right.” 34 Murray was willing<br />

to go further than capturing actual fugitive slaves; California’s location<br />

prevented runaway slaves from reaching its borders. Rather, Murray was<br />

showing the extent of the pro-slavery sentiment that this particular court<br />

possessed. This kind of comity could only mean that respect for the right<br />

of slave owners to bring slaves into California when it became a territory<br />

decided the case.<br />

In respect to the rights of slave owners to bring slaves into a territory,<br />

Murray’s opinion also sounded like the upcoming Taney opinion<br />

in the infamous Dred Scott case. 35 Murray argued that when Mexico<br />

gave up California, it became a territory of the United <strong>State</strong>s. Since the<br />

Constitution recognized slavery as a type of property, no local laws could<br />

Friend to Slavery<br />

7


8<br />

take that away. Murray said, “If the slave holder possessed any authority<br />

to bring slaves here under the Constitution…that right could not be<br />

abridged or controlled.” Justice Anderson agreed and wrote, “The institution<br />

of slavery goes with the extent of the national territory wherever<br />

that is.” 37 To both Murray and Anderson, slavery found protection in the<br />

Constitution of the Union. Therefore, when Perkins brought his three<br />

slaves to the state, this in no way freed them, and enslavement followed<br />

them, meaning that the passage of an anti-slavery constitution could not<br />

end this condition either.<br />

While Murray cited other state and federal cases as the rationale for<br />

this decision, the state had good political reasons for wanting to remove<br />

any blacks they could. Murray argued that it was well within the police<br />

powers of the state to exclude fugitive slaves from its boundaries. As he<br />

stated, “I have no doubt that the section of the Act now under consideration,<br />

was originated for the purpose of securing the rights of the master.”<br />

38 This shows the main intention of the courts: to reinforce the rights<br />

of slave masters at the cost of the black population in the state.<br />

Controlling that population was another clear goal of the court.<br />

The state of Oregon did not even allow blacks to migrate into the state. 39<br />

California now meant to achieve the same effect through the court. In<br />

Perkins, Murray quoted another jurist in reference to slaves who entered<br />

the state as “festering sores upon the body politic.” Of course, Carter,<br />

Robert, and <strong>San</strong>dy making a living in the state were the “festering sores”<br />

that Murray despised. By 1852, the black population in California was<br />

about 2,392. 40 The debates during the constitutional convention of 1849<br />

revealed the deep racist views of the delegates who contemplated banning<br />

all free blacks. If Murray freed slaves like Carter, Robert, and <strong>San</strong>dy, this<br />

would set a dangerous precedent for that state and would only increase the<br />

black population, because more blacks would see California as a friendly<br />

state they could escape to. Therefore, in one move, the court could minimize<br />

the black population in the state with the law of 1852, and show a<br />

committed sense of comity that favored slave states. 41<br />

In effect, the court approved of the law of 1852. The court said that<br />

a master who brought slaves to California could leave those slaves in the<br />

state, and use their labor until the law expired, which, after two renewals in<br />

the legislature, lasted until 1855. 42 This meant a master who brought slaves<br />

into California before 1850 could use his slaves for perhaps five to seven<br />

years before he had to worry about removing them from the state, allowing<br />

for a limited type of slavery in the state for that period. That all slaves<br />

brought after 1850 became free was too much for Murray to concede.<br />

In reference to slaves who entered free states, he argued that a “slave<br />

does not become ipso facto free or that his status is changed; but the master’s<br />

control ceases for some want of positive law.” 43 Justice Anderson also<br />

concurred with this opinion, but he took this idea further than Murray<br />

MICHAEL T. CAIRES


when he argued that the clause in the state constitution banning slavery<br />

was not active until the legislature made laws that enforced it. He argued,<br />

“If it is designed to confer it (freedom to slaves), then it must be by future<br />

legislation.” 44 The Perkins case highlighted how much comity the state favored<br />

for other slave states, suggesting that the state was more than willing<br />

to help capture runaway slaves, return them, and give a more than generous<br />

period for visitors and entrepreneurs to use slave labor rather than let<br />

free blacks make a living in the state. While the law of 1852 did expire, the<br />

question of slavery had not, and the court would again decide the law of<br />

slavery in California in the case Ex Parte Archy. 45<br />

In the wake of Perkins, it is hard to gauge public reaction. Because<br />

of the nature of the law, many accused slaves received little due process,<br />

and the records of their removal are nonexistent. Many of the newspapers<br />

did not cover the removal of accused slaves, with only a few letters of<br />

concerned people serving as the only proof of their removal. 46 What the<br />

newspapers did report were the pleas of slave masters asking the public for<br />

information to find their slaves. In 1854, O.R. Rozier from Arkansas asked<br />

for public help in finding his runaway slave Stephen. He must have felt<br />

that at this time both the public and the law supported his claim to take<br />

Stephen back into slavery. 47 By 1854, pro-slavery men agitated for change<br />

and ex-southerners argued for the division of the state, because southern<br />

Californians demanded slavery. 48 In another fugitive slave case in 1855,<br />

the lawyers for the runaway waited until the Fugitive Slave Law expired<br />

to let the slave stand trial. 49 The judge declared the slave free. With the<br />

expiration of the Fugitive Slave Law, slave owners needed another law<br />

from the legislature or judicial decision that could help maintain their<br />

slave property in California.<br />

Into this situation came a case that allowed the court another chance<br />

to protect slavery. Born in Pike County, Mississippi, Archy Lee was the slave<br />

of Charles Stovall. 50 In 1857, Stovall took Archy on a trip to California<br />

for Stovall’s health, and in October of that year, after a hard journey, they<br />

entered Sacramento. 51 Stovall hired Archy out for close to a month, and<br />

Stovall opened a school for two months in Sacramento. Months later,<br />

Stovall decided to make a return trip home and sent Archy ahead with<br />

an agent to catch a steamer bound for Mississippi. 52 Archy ran away and<br />

Stovall petitioned a justice of the peace for his return. The police arrested<br />

Archy and held him in jail, but would not return him. 53 After two failed<br />

attempts in court to return Archy, Stovall petitioned the state Supreme<br />

Court to hear his case. Justice Burnett, a southerner from Tennessee and<br />

ex-governor of the state, started his opinion by trying to avoid the many<br />

emotional and political outcries heard in public when he quoted another<br />

judge saying the case “should be decided by the law as it is and not as it<br />

ought to be.” 54 Yet, nothing in the Archy case would follow any kind of<br />

law. Rather, it would follow a need by the court to support slavery and the<br />

rights of slave owners.<br />

Friend to Slavery<br />

9


10<br />

In Burnett’s opinion, he argued based on the idea that a traveling<br />

person had a constitutional right to bring slaves with them on a journey.<br />

He argued this based on the recently decided Scott v. <strong>San</strong>dford, which fell in<br />

line with what Anderson and Murray said in Perkins. 55 This right to travel<br />

did not depend on comity. Rather, it was a right vested in the Constitution.<br />

The real question in the case depended on Stovall’s status as a traveler,<br />

visitor, or resident. The key to defining this was the actions Stovall took<br />

while he was in the state. Burnett said, “The traveler must pursue his<br />

journey with no unnecessary delay.” 56 To him, it was clear that Stovall did<br />

stay longer than he needed to, when he started his school and especially<br />

when he hired Archy out. Stovall violated his status as a visitor because<br />

he profited from his slave’s labor while in the state. 57 He quoted an Illinois<br />

case that stated if a person profited from a slave’s labor in a free state while<br />

visiting then “the slave was entitled to (his/her) freedom.” 58 Unlike traveling,<br />

the laws having to do with visiting rested entirely on comity. Since the<br />

law of 1852 did not apply, and the legislature did not make any laws on<br />

the subject, “the courts are under the necessity of determining how far<br />

the rule of comity must apply.” 59 Indeed, by Burnett’s own logic, Archy<br />

must be free. Yet, it is here that Burnett and the Archy case took one of its<br />

strangest turns.<br />

Indeed, Burnett believed that comity was vital to the state and wanted<br />

to welcome slave-owners to the state. Burnett said, “The citizens of the<br />

free states can bring their confidential servants with them-why should not<br />

the citizens of the slave <strong>State</strong>s be allowed the same privilege?” 60 At this<br />

point, Burnett stretched comity so far that a slave master might bring his<br />

slave to that state and put him to work for a short time. Yet, he had to concede<br />

that Stovall’s business in that state and his hiring out of Archy violated<br />

the Constitution. Burnett disagreed with Justice Anderson in Perkins<br />

and said that the anti-slavery clause in the Constitution did not need any<br />

positive law, “when power is withheld, or certain state prohibited, the provision<br />

must, from the very nature of the case, be conclusive.” 61 From all<br />

these facts it would seem Archy would have been free, because Stovall<br />

could not be a visitor or traveler. Yet, Burnett gave Stovall the benefit of<br />

the doubt and ordered Archy back into his custody and back into slavery<br />

based on Stovall’s health and the fact that Stovall perhaps believed that<br />

Anderson’s opinion in Perkins might have meant that he could bring his<br />

slave to the state. 62<br />

In the end, Burnett decided that the state needed a “plain, practical,<br />

and efficient rule; one that all can understand.” 63 Yet, after following a line<br />

of thinking that led to the conclusion that Archy deserved his freedom,<br />

Burnett decided to send him back to slavery. No one in the state could<br />

understand this decision. One newspaper wrote, “It caps the climax of all<br />

human absurdity and lowers the dignity of the Supreme Court.” 64 Even<br />

Chief Justice Terry, a southerner from Mississippi who vigorously defended<br />

slavery and would later fight for the Confederacy could not understand<br />

MICHAEL T. CAIRES


Burnett’s logic, stating, “I concur in the judgment…while I do not entirely<br />

agree with his conclusions from the facts of the case.” 65 Even so, pro-slavery<br />

politicians in the legislature scrambled to pass a new fugitive slave law<br />

to make extending the travel of people like Stovall legal. But this time,<br />

they were not able to pass this law. 66 Slavery in California made no legal<br />

sense in the face of a clear anti-slavery constitution. When Burnett gave<br />

the benefit of the doubt to Stovall, it appeared as if any slave owner could<br />

receive preference in California. The unclear nature of Burnett’s decision<br />

shows how the court favored slave owners over freedom for slaves, even<br />

when all legal reasoning pointed to freedom. Archy eventually did earn<br />

his freedom, but the California Supreme Court had already inflicted too<br />

much damage to conclude that it did not endorse slavery. 67<br />

In California, a very clear anti-slavery clause and a declaration of<br />

rights said, “All people are by nature free and independent.” Yet, this only<br />

applied to the whites in the state. 68 While slavery began when southern<br />

forty-niners brought their slaves to toil in the mines, the rulings of the<br />

Supreme Court of California reinforced, strengthened, and protected<br />

slavery in California when the legislature made no laws to help protect<br />

the black population of the state. Perhaps the court felt pressured by the<br />

need to extend gracious comity to the southern states, but a fear of a large<br />

free black population and general racism also most likely entered into the<br />

court’s reasoning. These cases reveal how politics entered the court and<br />

affected rulings in California. The pro-slavery legislature that passed fugitive<br />

slave laws also won enough support to elect pro-slavery judges. During<br />

the Archy case, when pro-slavery politicians lost power, the judges still on<br />

the bench stood out as an oddity. However, the court became a reminder<br />

of the pro-slavery population still in the state. The opinions of the court<br />

took the shield of comity to protect their rulings. Yet, it is clear, especially<br />

in the Archy case, that the court favored the slave owner to a point that few<br />

states would be willing to go. So far in distance from the other states and<br />

the Union, and geographically removed from the raging battles of the<br />

looming Civil War, the cases in California proved Lincoln right: a house<br />

divided could not stand. Both slave laws and free laws could not exist together<br />

in the same state forever. These decisions attempted to balance the<br />

multiple concerns of its southern slave-holding population, while respecting<br />

an anti-slavery constitution. This, however, could not go on forever.<br />

The nation and California would have to choose a side, for it would have<br />

to “become all one thing, or all the other.” 69<br />

Friend to Slavery<br />

11


12<br />

NOTES<br />

1<br />

Don E. Fehrenbacher, ed., The Impending Crisis: 1846-1861 (New York: Harper & Row<br />

Publishers, 1976), 1-17 and 90-120. For a discussion of Webster and Clay in the slavery debate,<br />

see Eric Foner, Free Soil, Free Labor, Free Men: The Ideology of the Republican Party Before the Civil War<br />

(New York: Oxford <strong>University</strong> Press, 1995), 186-195.<br />

2<br />

<strong>San</strong> <strong>Francisco</strong> Herald, 15 June 1852.<br />

3<br />

J. Ross Browne, The Debates of the Convention of California on the Formation of the <strong>State</strong><br />

(Washington, D. C.: John T. Towers, 1850), 43-44.<br />

4<br />

Rudolph M. Lapp, Blacks in Gold Rush California (New Haven: Yale <strong>University</strong> Press,<br />

1977), 12-49.<br />

5<br />

Paul Finkelman, “The Law of Slavery and Freedom in California 1848-1860,”<br />

California Western Law Review 12 (1981): 442.<br />

6<br />

For the earlier school of thinking, see Clyde A. Duniway, “Slavery in California after<br />

1848,” in Annual Report of the American Historical Association for the Year 1905, Vol. 1 (Washington, D.<br />

C.: Washington Government Printing Office, 1906), 243; and Marion Reynolds, “Instances of<br />

Negro Slavery” (PhD diss., Harvard <strong>University</strong>, 1914). More recent work on Lapp includes Paul<br />

Finkelman, “The Law of Slavery and Freedom in California 1848-1860,” California Western Law<br />

Review 12 (1981): 437-464.<br />

7<br />

U. S. Constitution, Article 4 § 1.<br />

8<br />

Paul Finkelman, An Imperfect Union: Slavery, Federalism, and Comity (Chapel Hill: The<br />

<strong>University</strong> of North Carolina Press, 1981), 4.<br />

9<br />

U. S. Constitution, Article 4 § 2.<br />

10<br />

“Fugitive <strong>State</strong> Law of 1793” in Christopher Waldrep and Lynne Curry, The<br />

Constitution and the Nation: The Civil War and American Constitutionalism, 1830-1890 (New York:<br />

Peter Lang Publishing, Inc., 2003), 43.<br />

11<br />

Finkelman, An Imperfect Union, 104.<br />

12<br />

Commonwealth v. Aves, 35 Mass. 193, 1836.<br />

13<br />

Ibid.<br />

14<br />

Ibid.<br />

15<br />

Lapp, 138<br />

16<br />

Lapp, 138-139.<br />

17<br />

In re Perkins, 2 Cal. 424, 1852.<br />

18<br />

Ibid.<br />

19<br />

Lapp, 140.<br />

20<br />

California Constitution, 1849, Article VI § 3.<br />

21<br />

California Constitution, 1849 Article II § 1, and Lapp, 140.<br />

22<br />

J. Edward Johnson, History of the Supreme Court Justices of California: 1850-1900, vol. 1<br />

(<strong>San</strong> <strong>Francisco</strong>: Bender-Moss Company, 1963), 43-49.<br />

23<br />

Lapp, 143.<br />

24<br />

Robert Perkins, Carter Perkins and <strong>San</strong>dy Jones, “Affadavit,” In re Perkins Case File,<br />

Supreme and Appellate Court Collections (California <strong>State</strong> Archives, Sacramento), and Lapp,<br />

142.<br />

25<br />

C. S. Perkins, “Power of Attorney, <strong>State</strong> of Mississippi,” In re Perkins Case File,<br />

Supreme and Appellate Court Collections (California <strong>State</strong> Archives, Sacramento).<br />

26<br />

In re Perkins, 2 Cal. 424, 1852.<br />

27<br />

B. D. Fry, “Affidavit,” In re Perkins Case File, Supreme and Appellate Court Collections<br />

(California <strong>State</strong> Archives, Sacramento).<br />

28<br />

Judge Lewis Aldrich, “Affidavit,” In re Perkins Case File, Supreme and Appellate Court<br />

Collections (Calfornia <strong>State</strong> Archives, Sacramento).<br />

29<br />

The black population in both Sacramento and <strong>San</strong> <strong>Francisco</strong> Counties was extremely<br />

small. In Sacramento, the black population made up 2.6% of the population and in <strong>San</strong><br />

<strong>Francisco</strong> they made up about 1.28%. California Legislature, Document no. 14 Governor’s Message<br />

and Report of the Secretary of <strong>State</strong> on the Census of 1852, of the <strong>State</strong> of California, Senate 4th Session,<br />

1852, 31, 41.<br />

MICHAEL T. CAIRES


30<br />

Brown Pratt and Leary, “Petition for a writ of Certiorari,” 1852, In re Perkins Case File,<br />

Supreme and Appellate Court Collections (California <strong>State</strong> Archives, Sacramento).<br />

31<br />

In re Perkins, 2 Cal. 424, 1852.<br />

32<br />

Larry D. Kramer, The People Themselves: Popular Constitutionalism and Judicial Review<br />

(Oxford: Oxford <strong>University</strong> Press, 2004).<br />

33<br />

Ibid.<br />

34<br />

Prigg v. Pennsylvania, 41 U. S. 539, 1842.<br />

35<br />

Scott v. <strong>San</strong>dford, 19 Howard 393, 1857; Finkelman, “Slave Law in California,” 455-<br />

456. Also see Donn E. Fehrenbacher, The Dred Scott Case: Its Significance in American Law and<br />

Politics (Oxford: Oxford <strong>University</strong> Press, 1978), 232-235. For a discussion of the thinking of<br />

the Taney Court, Fehrenbacher also says that these issues were debated in many courtrooms<br />

around the nation when the court took the case.<br />

36<br />

In re Perkins, 2 Cal. 424, 1852.<br />

37 Ibid.<br />

38<br />

In re Perkins, 2 Cal. 424, 1852.<br />

39<br />

Oregon Constitution, Bill of Rights, Section 35.<br />

40<br />

California Legislature, Document no. 14 Governor’s Message and Report of the Secretary of <strong>State</strong><br />

on the Census of 1852, of the <strong>State</strong> of California, Senate 4th Session, 1852, 6.<br />

41<br />

J. Ross Browne, 137, and Finkelman, “Slave Law in California,” 455.<br />

42<br />

Finkelman, “Slave Law in California,” 452.<br />

43<br />

In re Perkins, 2 Cal. 424, 1852.<br />

44<br />

Ibid.<br />

45<br />

Ex Parte Archy, 9 Cal. 147.<br />

46<br />

Lapp, 147.<br />

47<br />

Alta California, 27 September 1854.<br />

48<br />

Alta California, 18 December 1854.<br />

49<br />

<strong>San</strong> <strong>Francisco</strong> Herald, 22 April 1855.<br />

50<br />

Sacramento Union, 2 April 1858.<br />

51<br />

Ex Parte Archy, 9 Cal. 147.<br />

52<br />

Ibid.<br />

53<br />

Ibid.<br />

54<br />

Ibid., and Johnson, 62-63.<br />

55<br />

In re Perkins, 2 Cal. 424, 1852, and Scott v. <strong>San</strong>dford, 19 Howard 451, 1857.<br />

56<br />

Ex Parte Archy, 9 Cal. 147.<br />

57<br />

Ibid..<br />

58<br />

Ibid.<br />

59<br />

Ibid.<br />

60<br />

Ibid.<br />

61<br />

Ibid.<br />

62<br />

Ibid.<br />

63<br />

Ibid.<br />

64<br />

Sacramento Union, 18 February 1858.<br />

65<br />

Ex Parte Archy, 9 Cal. 147, and Johnson, 52-61.<br />

66<br />

Sacramento Union, 19 January 1858.<br />

67<br />

Sacramento Union, 15 April 1858.<br />

68<br />

California Constitution, Article 1 § 1.<br />

69<br />

Roy B. Pasler, ed., The Collected Works of Abraham Lincoln, Vol. 2 (New Brunswick, N. J.:<br />

Rutgers <strong>University</strong> Press, 1953), 462.<br />

Friend to Slavery<br />

13


Radical Exclusion<br />

N A Z I E U T H A N A S I A , 1 9 3 9 - 1 9 4 5<br />

X<br />

H E A T H E R Cooper


eex<br />

post<br />

efacto


“The rose that does not bloom will be pulled up and tossed in the fire,<br />

and the gardener will chop down the tree that bears no fruit.”<br />

— Walter Gross, 1933<br />

he history of National Socialist rule in Germany is, in many ways, a<br />

history of atrocities. Hitler and the men and women who supported him<br />

sought to fashion a new ethnic identity based on self-sacrifice, unwavering<br />

allegiance, and the radical exclusion of undesirable groups. In the process,<br />

the Nazi machine systematically annihilated millions of individual lives<br />

considered to be of no, or negative value to the Volk. While much attention<br />

has been duly paid to the destruction of Jewish lives in the Holocaust,<br />

new scholarship has emerged over the last two decades to shed light on<br />

the concurrent program of Nazi euthanasia, which aimed at cleansing the<br />

ethnic body politic from within. In the quest to create a strong and healthy<br />

racial state, it was not only necessary to rid Germany of foreign elements<br />

like Jews and Gypsies, but also to cleanse the Aryan ranks of the unfit<br />

— those mentally or physically handicapped individuals whose existence<br />

threatened the strength and health of the Volk as a whole. As Hitler wrote<br />

in Mein Kampf, “A stronger race [must] drive out the weak” and replace<br />

“the so-called humanity of individuals” with “the humanity of Nature<br />

which destroys the weak to give his place to the strong.” 1 T<br />

In a society that<br />

demanded that the interests of the Volk be placed above the interests of<br />

any individual, destroying those who could neither care for themselves nor<br />

contribute to society became a kind of moral imperative — an act of<br />

devotion for the greater good.<br />

Feminine Witchcraft in Medieval Europe<br />

17


18<br />

The euthanasia program began in the fall of 1939 with a secret decree,<br />

issued on Hitler’s personal stationary, which charged Dr. Karl Brandt<br />

and Phillip Bouhler with recruiting doctors to grant “mercy death[s]” to<br />

handicapped patients who were considered “incurable.” 2 Under the direction<br />

of the administrative headquarters established at Tiergartenstrasse<br />

4 (T4), approximately 5,000 children and 70,000 adults met their deaths<br />

at the hands of physicians and nurses in German killing centers between<br />

1940 and August 1941. 3 Thousands more died during the period of “wild<br />

euthanasia” that followed Hitler’s 1941 halt order, which had put an end<br />

to the gassing of institutionalized patients in special centers, but not to<br />

the starvation diets and lethal injections that could be carried out on an<br />

individual and less public basis in any institution. 4<br />

Viewed within the limited context of other atrocities, like the concentration<br />

camps and Einsatzgruppen sweeps, the euthanasia program<br />

might only be seen as another example of a peculiarly Nazi disregard for<br />

human life. But the devaluation of individual life was not peculiar to the<br />

Nazi power of 1933-1945. It was, rather, an integral facet of a eugenics<br />

and racial science movement, which predated the Nazis by decades, and<br />

gained increasing influence among German psychiatrists and anthropologists<br />

from 1900 on. Furthermore, the tendency to devalue individual<br />

life and create a hierarchy of worth based on one’s ability to contribute<br />

to society grew out of the visceral and intellectual response of many<br />

Europeans to the devastating loss of life suffered in World War I. When<br />

early advocates of euthanasia asked their readers how one could justify<br />

the maintenance of “worthless” lives in institutions while the healthy<br />

died en masse at the front, 5 they posed a question, which had already<br />

crept into the subconscious of many Germans’ minds: Were individual<br />

lives not of relative value in an age in which millions were sacrificed in<br />

the name of a higher cause? When Hitler backdated the euthanasia order<br />

signed on October 1, 1939 to the outbreak of the war in September,<br />

he played on an association between war and sacrifice, which Germans<br />

had accepted for years. 6<br />

What was peculiar to the Nazis was the transformation of thought<br />

into radical action. In the hands of the T4 administration, a pre-existing<br />

inclination toward euthanasia and theoretical discussions of its merits<br />

became a concrete program for the destruction of “life unworthy of life”<br />

on a mass scale. 7 This transformation of theory into practice was made<br />

possible by three principle factors: a government-sponsored bureaucracy<br />

specifically devoted to euthanasia, which compartmentalized tasks and<br />

created an environment of “free-floating responsibility;” 8 the training and<br />

indoctrination of medical staff in the rhetoric of eugenics and racial science<br />

prior to and during their participation in the euthanasia program;<br />

and the natural tendency of the perpetrators to create mechanisms for<br />

distancing themselves from the reality of unpleasant, or difficult tasks.<br />

Through an examination of the above factors, this essay attempts to un-<br />

HEATHER COOPER


derstand how it was possible to justify, commit, and deny responsibility for<br />

the murder of almost 100,000 handicapped children and adults between<br />

1939 and 1945.<br />

Historical interest in racial science and euthanasia in Nazi Germany<br />

has increased over the last two decades, as historians have sought to understand<br />

the origins of Nazi violence and the Final Solution, the racial hierarchy<br />

of the Third Reich, and the psychology of perpetrators in various<br />

programs of radical exclusion. The work of Henry Friedlander, Michael<br />

Burleigh, and Robert Jay Lifton has been particularly valuable in addressing<br />

these topics. Friedlander’s The Origins of Nazi Genocide: From Euthanasia<br />

to the Final Solution argues that euthanasia was one stage along a continuum<br />

of exclusion, which first sought to exclude undesirables from future generations<br />

and then to eradicate them from the present one through systematic<br />

extermination. His work is primarily concerned with examining the<br />

ways in which the T-4 administration and bureaucracy served as a model<br />

for the Final Solution, which followed. Burleigh provides a different context<br />

for the euthanasia program in his books, Ethics and Extermination and<br />

Death and Deliverance, when he considers the ways in which eugenics, racial<br />

science, and changes in psychiatry before 1933 created an environment<br />

that made organized euthanasia possible under the Nazis. 9 Finally, Lifton’s<br />

psychohistorical study in The Nazi Doctors introduces some valuable questions<br />

about the psychological mechanisms employed by perpetrators in<br />

the “medicalized killing” operations of the Third Reich. 10<br />

Most of what we know of the Nazi euthanasia program is from the<br />

testimony and documentation of the post-war trials, which have given a<br />

face to the perpetrators and a shape to the T-4 administration that necessitated<br />

their crimes. All the books mentioned above, and many others not<br />

touched upon here, culled their evidence from similar sources and utilized<br />

a common outline of perpetrators, victims, and administration in their examinations<br />

of euthanasia. What separates them is the context in which that<br />

basic outline has been placed and the questions which each author has<br />

asked of those sources. The research presented in this essay is obviously<br />

considerably more limited than that of Lifton, Burleigh, or Friedlander —<br />

and, yet, it still works with the same basic outline of information relating<br />

to perpetrators, victims, and the T-4 administration. I have attempted to<br />

place the Nazi euthanasia program within the context of an earlier eugenics<br />

and race hygiene movement, which frequently devalued individual life,<br />

in order to establish that an environment conducive to euthanasia was already<br />

forming in Germany prior to the Nazi rise to power. By examining<br />

the T-4 administration and organization, indoctrination and training of<br />

medical staff, and distancing mechanisms of perpetrators, I hope to offer<br />

a tentative and partial answer to two questions central to the historiography<br />

of this topic: How did the Nazis transform theoretical discussions of<br />

the merits of euthanasia into a systematic program for the destruction of<br />

“life unworthy of life?” And how was it possible for the men and women<br />

Radical Exclusion: Nazi Euthanasia, 1939-1945<br />

19


20<br />

responsible for tens of thousands of deaths to deny their responsibility,<br />

justify their actions, and separate themselves from the physical and moral<br />

meaning of what they did?<br />

PRELUDE TO EUTHANASIA:<br />

Eugenics and Psychiatry before 1939<br />

The first steps toward creating a hierarchy of the valued and valueless<br />

in German society were taken in the name of eugenics. Inspired by<br />

Darwin’s theories of natural selection and survival of the fittest, eugenicists<br />

applied those same principles to man and began to see the successes<br />

and failures of their society as biological matters of selection, counter-selection,<br />

and hereditary fitness. At the same time, individuals were reduced<br />

to “aggregates of ‘negative’ or ‘positive’ biological materials” whose value<br />

was determined by their contribution to, or burden on society; such a contribution<br />

was understood both in terms of hereditary traits and capacity<br />

for production and labor. 11<br />

Alfred Ploetz and William Schallmayer were two of the foremost<br />

German eugenicists in the late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries.<br />

Despite their early resistance to notions of scientific racism, the Nazis<br />

would later credit their work with creating the biological foundations of<br />

the Nazi racial state. 12 In 1895 Ploetz published the book, The Efficiency<br />

of our Race and the Protection of the Weak, which argued that genetic health<br />

ensured national efficiency and that welfare and modern medicine were<br />

counter-selective forces that protected inferior genetic elements at the<br />

nation’s expense. He coined the term “racial hygiene” to describe the process<br />

of cleansing and strengthening the national body. 13 Schallmayer was<br />

similarly concerned with collective health and efficiency and argued that<br />

an individual’s primary function was to contribute to the regeneration<br />

of society by producing healthy offspring. He seemed to foreshadow the<br />

Nazi ideal of devotion and self-sacrifice when he wrote that the “law of<br />

nature, the total subservience of the interest of the individual to that of<br />

the species, must also hold true for human development.” 14 Yet neither<br />

Ploetz nor Schallmayer advocated negative eugenics measures like forced<br />

sterilization, or euthanasia. They were, rather, primarily concerned with a<br />

positive eugenics that would encourage genetically compatible marriages<br />

and increase the reproduction of healthy offspring. 15<br />

Other scientists of this period perceived a dire threat to the health<br />

of the nation, which could not be silenced by positive eugenics alone. In a<br />

1904 book entitled The Riddle of Life, zoologist Ernst Haeckel specifically<br />

advocated euthanasia of the handicapped when he wrote:<br />

What profit does humanity derive from the thousands of<br />

cripples who are born each year, from the deaf and dumb,<br />

from cretins, from those with incurable hereditary defects etc.<br />

HEATHER COOPER


who are kept alive artificially and then raised to adulthood?<br />

… How much of this loss and suffering could be obviated, if<br />

one finally decided to liberate the totally incurable from their<br />

indescribable suffering with a dose of morphia. 16<br />

Later advocates of euthanasia would couch their arguments in strikingly<br />

similar terms, emphasizing both the burden on society represented by an<br />

ever-growing population of “cretins” and the “indescribable suffering” that<br />

made their eradication an act of mercy. In an influential treatise published in<br />

1920, Karl Binding and Alfred Hoche considered the merits of euthanasia<br />

for those incurable individuals whose lives were “not only completely worthless<br />

but [were] of negative value.” 17 In language that turned the intended victims<br />

of euthanasia into inhuman agents of degeneration and the would-be<br />

perpetrators into victims and heroes, Binding and Hoche called on Germans<br />

to consider the necessity of relieving themselves and the handicapped of the<br />

burden of nonproductive lives. While they insisted that euthanasia should<br />

only be permitted when the person involved viewed it as a “release,” this<br />

standard was only applicable to individuals with a terminal disease, such as<br />

cancer. 18 In contrast, the incurably insane were said to “have neither the will<br />

to live nor to die” and, therefore, euthanasia could be carried out without<br />

“clash[ing] with any will to live which would have to be broken.” 19<br />

Binding and Hoche’s Permission for the Destruction of Worthless Life did<br />

not meet with immediate approval in all psychiatric circles, but it certainly<br />

provoked discussion. It was, in fact, a very topical subject just two years after<br />

the end of the twentieth century’s most devastating war to date. Germany<br />

suffered unprecedented military and civilian casualties in WWI and these<br />

losses created an environment in which the worth of an individual life had<br />

to be weighed against the hundreds of thousands who were already dying<br />

and the millions who lived on because of their sacrifice. Germany’s psychiatric<br />

institutions felt the ravages of war just as the general population<br />

did. Accounting for normal peacetime mortality rates, Michael Burleigh<br />

estimates that nearly 72,000 patients died in institutions 1914-1918 as a<br />

result of hunger, disease, or neglect. 20 In his 1920 address to the German<br />

Psychiatric Association, chairman Karl Bonhoeffer seemed to suggest that<br />

Binding and Hoche’s call for “a higher morality” which would “cease …<br />

implementing the demands of an exaggerated concept of humanity” was<br />

already being answered: 21<br />

It could almost seem as if we have witnessed a change in the<br />

concept of humanity. I simply mean that we were forced by<br />

the terrible exigencies of war … to get used to watching our<br />

patients die of malnutrition in vast numbers, almost approving<br />

of this, in the knowledge that perhaps the healthy could be<br />

kept alive through these sacrifices. 22<br />

Many of the psychiatrists who were faced with limited resources during<br />

the war believed that they must acknowledge a hierarchy of human value<br />

and be willing to take from the weak in order that the strong might survive.<br />

After the war, the principle of relative worth continued to be applied.<br />

Radical Exclusion: Nazi Euthanasia, 1939-1945<br />

21


22<br />

Armed with a new concept of individual worth, in the 1920s psychiatrists<br />

equated one’s ability to contribute to society with one’s physical<br />

and mental health. Following the example of Hermann Simon, an asylum<br />

director at Gütersloch, occupational therapy became widespread in German<br />

asylums and offered a means for classifying patients according to the<br />

tasks they were capable of performing. 23 Burleigh estimates that by the<br />

end of the 1920s, up to 80 percent of institutionalized patients were doing<br />

some form of work, ranging from basic manual labor and weaving to gardening,<br />

office work, and factory labor. 24 The full significance of productivity<br />

as a measure of worth would be felt after 1939 when productive capacity<br />

became one of the criteria for deciding which patients to include in the<br />

euthanasia program. 25 In the meantime, occupational therapy provided a<br />

free labor pool to institutions for their own maintenance and came close<br />

to realizing racial hygienist Ignaz Kaup’s 1910 vision of a “work colony”<br />

in which worthless lives could “repay the money spent on them.” 26 As state<br />

expenditures on asylums fell, patient labor became critical to make up for<br />

the food and staff shortages, which institutions faced.<br />

But by insisting on productivity as a sign of health and worth, occupational<br />

therapy created an environment in which those who were unable<br />

to work, or to advance beyond the more basic skill sets, were considered<br />

incurable and, therefore, inherently inferior. Such individuals were,<br />

as Binding and Hoche suggested, “not only completely worthless but …<br />

of negative value.” 27 Given the burden that their care placed on society<br />

and the risk that their diseases posed to the nation’s gene pool, incurable<br />

patients were increasingly labeled “degenerates” because of their alleged<br />

role in the degeneration of the Volk. In what amounted to a wave of racial<br />

hysteria, eugenicists feared that a declining birth rate among the healthy<br />

and the uncontrolled reproduction of degenerates would eventually lead<br />

to a society in which inferior elements outnumbered the genetically desirable.<br />

28 The solution to this crisis not only involved government programs<br />

to educate the public about racial hygiene, create genetically compatible<br />

couples, and increase the reproduction of healthy offspring, but also a<br />

compulsory sterilization program to prevent the hereditarily ill from reproducing<br />

additional burdens.<br />

The sterilization program, initiated in July 1933 under the Law for<br />

the Prevention of Offspring with Hereditary Diseases, was responsible for<br />

the sterilization of 200,000-400,000 people. 29 The sterilization program<br />

cannot be adequately treated in this essay, but it is necessary to note certain<br />

consistencies between its organization and that of the euthanasia program<br />

that followed. The Sterilization Law named those diseases which were to<br />

be considered hereditary, including congenital feeblemindedness, schizophrenia,<br />

manic-depression, hereditary epilepsy, hereditary Huntington’s<br />

chorea, hereditary blindness and deafness, severe hereditary physical deformity,<br />

or severe alcoholism. 30 After being reported by health officials<br />

and having their cases heard in Genetic Health Courts, individuals with<br />

HEATHER COOPER


these conditions could be forcibly sterilized under the law. 31 A similar list<br />

of hereditary and, therefore, “incurable” diseases was used to classify and<br />

select patients for the euthanasia program. While euthanasia never operated<br />

publicly in the way that sterilization did, it nonetheless relied on the<br />

decision of medical experts similar to those in the health courts to decide<br />

the fates of patients who were reported by local officials. Both programs<br />

relied on the cooperation of government bureaucracy and medical professionals<br />

in order to exclude the handicapped, first from future generations<br />

and then from the existing one. 32<br />

When one considers the atrocities that followed the outbreak of war<br />

in 1939, one is confronted by events so sweeping and utterly destructive<br />

that they seem to almost stand outside of time. Yet it would be wrong to<br />

consider the horrors of the ghettos, extermination camps, and T-4 killing<br />

centers without acknowledging the historical context which made them<br />

possible. The Nazi euthanasia program was not a random development<br />

driven by the whims of a madman. It was, rather, the final stage in a<br />

decades-long movement toward the devaluation of individual life by the<br />

scientific community. Understanding the development of the eugenics<br />

movement in Germany and the significance of radical changes in psychiatry<br />

prior to 1939 is necessary for any informed understanding of what<br />

followed. Now one must ask, if euthanasia was the next point on a continuum<br />

of radical exclusion, how did the Nazis make that leap possible?<br />

ADMINISTRATING DEATH:<br />

T-4 Operations<br />

The creation of a government-sponsored administration specifically<br />

responsible for euthanasia was a critical development in the process of<br />

transforming theoretical discussions into a concrete program of radical<br />

exclusion and annihilation for the handicapped. By compartmentalizing<br />

tasks and creating an environment of “free-floating responsibility” 33 the T-<br />

4 administration made it possible for men and women to participate in the<br />

destruction of lives deemed “not worth living.” 34 In 1939, the administrative<br />

headquarters for the euthanasia program were established in Berlin<br />

at a seized Jewish property located at Tiergartenstrasse 4. Hitler’s secret<br />

decree had granted authority for overseeing the program to Karl Brandt<br />

and Philip Bouhler, both of whom would delegate various responsibilities<br />

to lower authorities and functionaries once the T-4 organization was established.<br />

The euthanasia program was primarily under the direction of<br />

the Chancellory of the Führer (KdF), but its various tasks were often carried<br />

out in coordination with the Reich Ministry of the Interior (RMdI).<br />

As head of the KdF, Philip Bouhler placed the euthanasia program under<br />

the direction of Victor Brack in Central Office II. Brack assigned<br />

the children’s euthanasia program to Hans Hefelmann and Richard von<br />

Radical Exclusion: Nazi Euthanasia, 1939-1945<br />

23


24<br />

Hegener of Office IIb, while he continued to oversee the general operations<br />

of adult euthanasia himself. 35 From their central headquarters, these<br />

men and the one hundred on-site staff members who supported them<br />

orchestrated the reporting, selection, transport, murder, and death records<br />

of patients chosen for euthanasia. 36 An examination of the process of<br />

selecting, transporting, and killing patients in the children’s and adult euthanasia<br />

programs will reveal the degree to which T-4 compartmentalized<br />

tasks and established hierarchies of shifting responsibility.<br />

The first stage in the euthanasia program was collecting information<br />

about prospective victims and making judgments as to who was capable<br />

of recovery and who was not. In 1939 RMdI issued a decree to state<br />

governments requiring that midwives and doctors report the births of<br />

newborns suspected of having idiocy, mongolism, microcephalie, severe<br />

hydrocephalus, deformities, or paralysis. Doctors were also required to<br />

report all children under the age of 3 with such conditions. 37 In July of<br />

1941, a new order was issued requiring doctors, midwives, and medical<br />

personnel to report all minors, up to the age of 17, who were known to<br />

have crippling handicaps. Even teachers were called on to report students<br />

in their charge who suffered from various hereditary ailments. Doctors<br />

and midwives faced a fine, or month-long imprisonment for failure to report<br />

appropriate cases to the authorities, 38 but received 2RM for each case<br />

they did report. 39<br />

It was Richard von Hegener’s responsibility to review the reports on<br />

children as they came in and choose those cases in which he felt euthanasia<br />

was necessary. Triplicate copies of the selected children’s reports were<br />

made and distributed to the members of the Reich Committee for the<br />

Scientific Processing of Serious Genetic Diseases, which was composed of<br />

three doctors appointed by Karl Brandt. Once the committee discussed<br />

the case and informed Brandt of their approval, his signature sealed the<br />

fate of the child concerned. 40<br />

The adult euthanasia program utilized a similar means of reporting<br />

and selection. On September 21, 1939 Department IV of RMdI issued<br />

a circular to state governments requiring them to report all clinics<br />

and institutions in their jurisdiction in which “mentally ill, epileptics, and<br />

the feeble minded are cared for on a long-term basis.” 41 Philip Bouhler,<br />

Werner Heyde, and Friedrich Nietsche drafted questionnaires to send to<br />

each of the reported institutions in order to collect information on their<br />

patients. 42 These were forwarded to the institutions on October 9, 1939 43<br />

under the auspices of the Reich Committee for the Scientific Registration<br />

of Severe Hereditary Ailments, the T-4 front organization responsible for<br />

data collection. 44 Institutions were not informed of the purpose of the<br />

forms and, early in the program, generally assumed that they were for<br />

statistical purposes only. In most cases, they were given 2-3 weeks to complete<br />

questionnaires on hundreds of patients. When T-4 was not satisfied<br />

HEATHER COOPER


with the speed or accuracy with which institutions completed the forms,<br />

it dispatched a team of experts to do the job themselves. Thus, in some<br />

cases, patients were classified and reported by inexperienced medical personnel<br />

totally unfamiliar with their history. 45 The staff of the Schönbrunn<br />

asylum described a visitation from one of the T-4 teams as the “spreading<br />

of a burial shroud over the asylum.” 46<br />

The questionnaires were single-page forms with fill-in-the-blank<br />

spaces to answer specific questions regarding the condition of each patient.<br />

Most questionnaires required the following information: name and<br />

address of asylum, patient name, birthplace, citizenship and race, diagnosis,<br />

detailed statement of the nature of employment, length of time in asylum,<br />

whether a criminal patient and what offenses if so, address of next<br />

of kin, whether patient was regularly visited, whether patient has relatives,<br />

address of legal guardian, and who was responsible for asylum costs. 47<br />

Institutions were required to report all patients who could not perform<br />

more than basic tasks and were suffering from schizophrenia, epilepsy, senility,<br />

paralysis, feeble-mindedness, encephalitis, or Huntington’s chorea;<br />

in addition, patients who had been continuously confined in institutions<br />

for more than five years, or who had been confined as criminal lunatics<br />

were also reported. 48 Thus the criteria for selection were largely based on<br />

the categories of hereditary diseases established under the sterilization<br />

program of 1933, along with an added emphasis on the patient’s productive<br />

capacity, which was in keeping with the eugenics thought of the<br />

last several decades. By 1941, productive capacity had become an even<br />

more critical factor in selection, as T-4 decided to eliminate all patients<br />

who could not work, “not only those who are mentally dead.” 49 Statistical<br />

analyses of those who were eventually killed reveals that most of the<br />

patients chosen from state hospitals were designated as schizophrenics,<br />

while those from church-affiliated institutions were more often diagnosed<br />

as feeble-minded, or epileptic. 50<br />

Upon completion, the questionnaires were returned to Dr. Herbert<br />

Linden at RMdI. Photostats were made and forwarded to four experts<br />

chosen from among ten to fifteen doctors on an expert medical panel organized<br />

by T-4. 51 These junior experts marked a corner of the form with a<br />

red + sign to signal inclusion in the euthanasia program and a blue – sign<br />

to designate exclusion. 52 Then Drs. Heyde or Nietsche, as chief experts,<br />

reviewed the decisions of the junior experts, made a final judgment regarding<br />

the patient, and informed Dr. Linden so that he might arrange for<br />

the patient’s transfer to a killing center. 53 Junior experts received hundreds<br />

of questionnaires at a time and were paid according to the speed with<br />

which they processed them: 100RMs for 500 forms per month, 200RMs<br />

for up to 2,000, 300 RMs for 3,500, and 400RMs for over 3,500. 54 Dr.<br />

Hermann Pfanmüller, a junior expert and head of the children’s euthanasia<br />

center at Eglfing-Haar, testified that he received at least 159 shipments<br />

of 200-300 questionnaires each before August 1941. 55<br />

Radical Exclusion: Nazi Euthanasia, 1939-1945<br />

25


26<br />

After patients were chosen for euthanasia, they had to be transferred<br />

to facilities designed for that purpose. In the case of the children’s<br />

program, parents were generally consulted and informed that<br />

since all traditional therapies had failed, it was necessary to transfer<br />

their child to a special center where more intensive therapies could<br />

be tried. Parents were told that their children might be “healed” in<br />

the new setting, but also ran the risk of death from complications<br />

of the treatment. 56 Made to feel that no hope existed in the current<br />

setting and a cure might be possible if the risk was taken, many<br />

parents consented. In a twisted manipulation of the truth, doctors<br />

interpreted parents’ permission for intensive therapy as consent for<br />

the murder of their children. 57<br />

Relatives were not consulted for the transfer of adult patients.<br />

Another of T-4’s front organizations, the Charitable Foundation<br />

for the Transport of Patients, Inc., contacted institutions with a list<br />

of patients who were to be moved to an undisclosed location. Most<br />

lists contained the names of 50-100 patients and institutions were<br />

required to prepare their medical records and personal belongings<br />

for the trip. 58 Patients were generally assigned a number at the time<br />

of transfer so that they could be readily identified later; in one case,<br />

numbers were written in ink on their wrists. 59 Patients were often sedated<br />

before the trip in order to calm their fears about where they<br />

were going and make them compliant for the staff who accompanied<br />

them to the killing centers. 60 The surrendering institutions were told<br />

not to inform relatives of the transfer or location of patients. 61 Shortly<br />

after the patient’s death, which usually occurred within hours of arrival<br />

at the killing center, his or her relatives received a notification<br />

of transfer from the receiving institution, which informed them that<br />

no visitation was possible at that time “for reasons connected with the<br />

defence of the Reich.” 62 After waiting a period of 10 days or more,<br />

a second notice was sent informing relatives of the patient’s sudden<br />

death and subsequent cremation. 63<br />

The final stage of the euthanasia program took place in the actual<br />

killing centers and wards designed for the elimination of patients.<br />

Children were generally transferred to special pediatric wards<br />

within existing institutions, where they were observed for a few<br />

months prior to being killed by slow starvation, or overdose. 64 The<br />

method of killing for children was left somewhat to the preference of<br />

the head physician at each center. Dr. Pfanmüller of Eglfing-Haar,<br />

for instance, preferred the more “natural” method of starvation to<br />

rid Germany of its “living burdens.” 65 Other doctors preferred using<br />

progressively high doses of Luminal until a child “lapsed into continual<br />

sleep” and died. 66 In some cases, the parents would be contacted<br />

before the administration of the drug, informed that their child was<br />

gravely ill, and given the opportunity to visit him or her before she<br />

HEATHER COOPER


died. 67 In other cases, they simply received a condolence letter after<br />

the fact, which listed a fictitious cause of death and asked them to<br />

consider that their child’s death had been a release from “great and<br />

incurable suffering.” 68<br />

Adults who were transferred to killing centers during the first phase<br />

of euthanasia went through a very different process than the children who<br />

died in pediatric wards. Six killing centers were established in Germany<br />

by 1941, although only four were in operation at any one time; they were<br />

known by their locations at Brandenburg, Grafeneck, Hartheim, Sonnenstein,<br />

Bernburg, and Hadamar. Patients were generally taken to an<br />

undressing room upon arrival and instructed to undress so that they could<br />

be bathed and deloused prior to being shown to their beds. Their clothes<br />

and belongings were put in a pile, labeled, and numbered so that personal<br />

effects could either be returned to relatives after death, or confiscated by<br />

the Charitable Foundation for Institutional Care. 69 The Charitable Foundation<br />

was another of T-4’s front organizations, which was responsible for<br />

collecting payments for the care of patients up to, and sometimes beyond,<br />

the time of their death. In addition, it occasionally confiscated the more<br />

valuable property of victims for its own use. 70 Patients had to open their<br />

mouths so the staff could see whether they had any gold teeth and those<br />

that did had a four-digit stamp pressed against their chests so the teeth<br />

could be extracted after death.<br />

Patients were then led into an examination room where a doctor<br />

checked to make sure that their medical records were complete and considered<br />

a reasonable cause of death to list on the death certificate for each<br />

of the patients before them. At some sites, doctors marked patients at this<br />

time who were considered of scientific interest so that their bodies could<br />

be set aside for autopsy later. 72 Some patients were also given a small dose<br />

of sedative at this time. 73 They were then led into a separate room where<br />

they were photographed while naked in order to preserve their images for<br />

anthropological research. 74<br />

Following this, patients were led into the gas chamber, which was<br />

disguised as a “shower room” complete with a tiled floor, tiled walls, and<br />

a row of showerheads attached to the ceiling. 75 Anywhere from 20 to 150<br />

patients might be gassed at one time. 76 It was the responsibility of the<br />

physician-in-charge to turn the lever that released gas into the chamber<br />

through an overhead pipe. The advocates of euthanasia considered carbon<br />

monoxide poisoning a humane killing method because it supposedly<br />

allowed the victim to “simply fall asleep under the gas and feel nothing<br />

more.” 77 However, more objective witnesses remembered watching<br />

through the peephole as men and women died, “semi-collapsed, others<br />

with their mouths terribly wide open, their chests heaving.” 78 Patients<br />

were generally unconscious in five minutes and dead in ten. After a few<br />

hours of ventilation, their bodies were dragged from the chamber by stok-<br />

Radical Exclusion: Nazi Euthanasia, 1939-1945<br />

27


28<br />

ers, who extracted gold teeth as needed, cremated two to eight bodies at<br />

a time, and ground down the bones that did not burn with a mill. 79 Approximately<br />

3kg of bonemeal was used to fill each urn to be sent to the<br />

patient’s relatives. 80<br />

Each killing center had its own Special Registry Office in which official<br />

causes of deaths were chosen and recorded. 81 T-4 provided doctors<br />

with a list of sixty-one possible causes of death, their corresponding symptoms,<br />

and the merits and demerits of using it for patients of different<br />

sexes, ages, and conditions. Pneumonia, for example, was listed as “an<br />

ideal cause of death for our action” because the public regarded it as a<br />

sudden and critical illness and it could occur at any age in both sexes. At<br />

Hadamar, the Registry Office used a map and colored pins to plan the<br />

timing of death notifications so that no single area would receive a large<br />

batch of condolence letters at one time. Alternatively, they might send<br />

the information for patients killed at Hadamar to another killing center<br />

so that the death notices could be sent from there; in this way, public<br />

suspicions regarding the nature of Hadamar could be kept at bay. 82 Once<br />

all these details had been arranged, the condolence department in each<br />

center prepared a relatively generic letter for the patient’s relatives notifying<br />

them of his or her death, the fact that the body had already been<br />

cremated, and instructing them as to how to collect the urn. 83<br />

The program of “wild euthanasia,” which followed Hitler’s August<br />

1941 halt order may be seen as distinct from the organized efforts of the<br />

T-4 administration prior to that date. Wild euthanasia continued in the<br />

spirit of T-4, but was based more on the initiative of individual institutions<br />

and medical staff than on a formal program of selection issuing<br />

from Berlin. In 1942, the directors of Bavarian asylums held a conference<br />

at the Ministry of the Interior to discuss the need “for the asylums to do<br />

something themselves” now that gas chambers were unavailable for the<br />

murder of the handicapped. They decided on a method of starvation<br />

using a “special diet” with no fat, meat, bread, or carbohydrates for those<br />

patients who were incapable of work. 84 Many institutions in Germany<br />

introduced a similar program of starvation, which gradually eliminated<br />

patients. In other cases, patients were given medication orally, or by injection,<br />

which caused them to lose consciousness and eventually die. 85 Despite<br />

its less organized nature, the wild euthanasia program still managed<br />

to compartmentalize tasks and shift responsibility. Different nurses within<br />

the same killing ward had responsibility for different tasks, so that the<br />

person who handed out drugs was not the person who administered them,<br />

or the person who disposed of the bodies. 86 Nurses who gave injections<br />

focused on the task before them rather than on its consequences, so that<br />

giving sedatives to children became a matter of calming the “impaired”<br />

and “restless” rather than an act of murder. 87 Furthermore, most nurses<br />

felt that they were relieved of responsibility because they were simply following<br />

the instructions of the doctors they were trained to serve. 88<br />

HEATHER COOPER


It is unsettling to consider how few people were necessary to bring<br />

about the deaths of nearly 100,000 individuals in the five years of euthanasia<br />

operations. As already stated, approximately 100 staff worked at<br />

T-4 headquarters in Berlin. 89 Approximately 60 physicians may have been<br />

involved at some level of selection. Each killing center was manned by one<br />

physician-in-charge and one or two assistant physicians. 90 In addition, killing<br />

centers had a small staff to handle patient transportation, disposal of<br />

bodies, administrative duties, and facility maintenance; Hadamar managed<br />

all this with only 25 workers. 91<br />

Friedlander describes the bureaucratic process of killing carried out<br />

by this relatively small number of men and women as “assembly line mass<br />

murder.” 92 The T-4 administration contributed to the process of mechanized<br />

killing by placing individual perpetrators at one point on the assembly<br />

line and assigning them specific, compartmentalized tasks. Different<br />

departments at T-4 headquarters were responsible for the reporting, selection,<br />

transport, and death notifications of patients. Doctors at institutions<br />

completed questionnaires, junior experts who had neither visited the<br />

institution nor met the patient marked the questionnaires and prepared<br />

them for review by a senior expert. Different staff members greeted the<br />

patients at different steps in the killing process — from the time of transport,<br />

to the undressing room, to the examination room, to the gas chamber,<br />

and finally to the crematoria. The death records for patients killed at<br />

one institution might be completed and processed at another. Those who<br />

autopsied the bodies were not necessarily those who had released the gas<br />

into the chamber and killed them. As other researchers of the Nazi bureaucracy<br />

have noted, the compartmentalization of tasks often created a<br />

tendency in the perpetrators to see only the task before them and operate<br />

with “moral blinders” as to the larger process at work. 93<br />

The compartmentalization of tasks not only made it possible for perpetrators<br />

to deny, or ignore the larger significance of their actions, but also<br />

created an environment of “free-floating responsibility” in which no single<br />

perpetrator felt responsible for the ultimate fate of patients because his or<br />

her actions were only one part of a larger process. 94 On the one hand, this<br />

is an example of the well-known protest of perpetrators that they were “just<br />

following orders.” On the other hand, it was a very real process of disassociation,<br />

which made it possible for individuals’ technical responsibility to<br />

the administration to eclipse any moral responsibility to fellow human beings.<br />

95 A focus on compartmentalized tasks and disassociation from moral<br />

responsibility were two of the principle means by which perpetrators distanced<br />

themselves from the full meaning and significance of their actions.<br />

Radical Exclusion: Nazi Euthanasia, 1939-1945<br />

29


30<br />

MAKING BIOLOGICAL WARRIORS:<br />

Staff Training and Indoctrination<br />

One of the principle questions under consideration by historians of<br />

Nazi euthanasia is how it was possible for doctors and nurses who had sworn<br />

to protect life to willingly participate in a “medicalized killing” operation designed<br />

to eradicate it. 96 While there can be no definitive answer to this question,<br />

a partial explanation may be offered by considering the training and<br />

indoctrination that doctors and nurses went through prior to and during<br />

their participation in the euthanasia program. By teaching the principles of<br />

eugenics and racial hygiene, instilling the values of individual sacrifice and<br />

service to the Volk, and dehumanizing the handicapped, medical education<br />

under the Nazis trained doctors and nurses to be “biological soldier[s]” who<br />

cared for the health of the nation before that of the individual. 97<br />

As already discussed, eugenics and racial hygiene gained growing<br />

influence in German scientific circles from 1900 on. By the 1920s, these<br />

studies were fundamental components of psychiatry, medicine, and anthropology.<br />

By 1932, over forty courses in race hygiene were offered at German<br />

universities. 98 By 1936, race hygiene was considered an obligatory course<br />

for the medical profession in many universities and was incorporated into<br />

the medical exams required of students prior to graduation and actual<br />

practice. 99 Training continued after graduation in various formats. The<br />

1935 Physicians’ Ordinance required that all physicians under the age of<br />

sixty attend a three-week course on recent medical developments in racial<br />

hygiene; by 1936, 5,000 doctors a year were receiving specialized training<br />

in this field. 100 As one of the premier research centers for racial science and<br />

eugenics, the Kaiser Wilhelm Institute for Anthropology had trained over<br />

1,000 doctors in “genetic and racial care” by 1934. 101 The Office of Racial<br />

Politics, headed by Walter Gross, trained medical professors as well as political<br />

educators in the importance of racial hygiene and offered dozens of<br />

medical seminars each year in which young doctors received lectures on<br />

“‘liberating’ the ethnic community from its ‘undesirable’ elements.” 102<br />

Most of the physicians who came to be involved in the euthanasia<br />

program were relatively young 103 and had either gone to medical school<br />

during the 1930s heyday of eugenics education, or practiced medicine<br />

during a time when the medical community embraced concepts of racial<br />

hygiene, degeneracy, and “worthless” lives wholeheartedly. Much of the<br />

medical profession was drawn to the Nazi party, which seemed to place<br />

new importance on their particular knowledge and skills in its creation of<br />

a biological and racial state. By 1942, approximately half of the doctors<br />

in Germany had joined the Nazi party. 104 By 1940, 45 percent of all physicians<br />

had joined the National Socialist Physicians’ League, which was devoted<br />

to the promotion of racial hygiene, racial science, and eugenics. 105<br />

HEATHER COOPER


As medical personnel, nurses were subject to similar efforts of indoctrination.<br />

As early as 1933, nurses were being instructed that their primary<br />

duty was to “secure and promote a genetically sound, valuable race” and<br />

“not to expend an exaggerated effort on the care of genetically or racially<br />

inferior people.” 106 Some psychiatrists suggested that nurses should be<br />

given early experience with incurable patients so that they might understand<br />

the seriousness of the burden represented by their lives and begin<br />

to recognize the negative eugenics measures of the state as a virtue for the<br />

greater good. 107 Furthermore, their roles as obedient servants to doctors<br />

continued to be emphasized, with an added obligation of obedience to the<br />

wishes of the Führer. 108<br />

A fundamental component of the training and indoctrination of<br />

doctors and nurses was the dehumanization of the handicapped. The Office<br />

of Racial Policy made documentary films of the handicapped and<br />

feeble-minded, which were seen by 20 million people a year, including<br />

medical personnel. 109 These films painted an animalistic and degraded<br />

picture of the handicapped with images of “a shaven-headed youth …<br />

eating handfuls of grass” and footage of the handicapped juxtaposed with<br />

that of criminals and the physically deformed. In the traditional language<br />

of racial hygiene, these films referred to the handicapped as “‘beings’,<br />

‘creatures’, ‘existences’, ‘idiots’, ‘life unworthy of life’, [and] ‘travesties of<br />

human form and spirit.’” 110 Trained to see the handicapped as worthless,<br />

bestial, and dangerous, many doctors and nurses were able to deny the<br />

humanity and rights of those whose lives they took.<br />

In some cases, the training and indoctrination of medical staff continued<br />

during their participation in the euthanasia program. Alfons Klein,<br />

supervisor of the Hadamar killing center, recalled that lectures were offered<br />

at the killing center to explain the merits and necessity of the euthanasia<br />

operation. 111 Another participant in the program recalled that in order<br />

“to relieve [their] consciences,” medical staff was given frequent talks<br />

on the economic significance of euthanasia. Such lectures demonstrated<br />

the positive uses to which money could be put if it was not required for the<br />

support of the incurable in institutions. Doctors and nurses were assured<br />

that euthanasia was necessary for the well-being of the nation and that<br />

“the method of elimination was the most humane imaginable.” 112<br />

It seems unlikely that many doctors and nurses would have actively<br />

participated in euthanasia without the training and education in racial<br />

hygiene, which took place prior to and during their involvement in the<br />

program. Medical education under the Nazis not only imbedded the<br />

principles of eugenics and racial hygiene in its students, but created an<br />

environment in which those principles were regarded as the only proper<br />

standard. Doctors and nurses may have sworn an oath to protect life, but<br />

for those who practiced medicine in the 1930s or later, that oath had become<br />

virtually meaningless given the larger context of Nazi medicine.<br />

Radical Exclusion: Nazi Euthanasia, 1939-1945<br />

31


32<br />

Other oaths were also sworn in allegiance to Hitler, or to the goals of the<br />

euthanasia program itself, 113 and these oaths ultimately exercised more<br />

influence on those who took them. In a 1933 lecture, Walter Gross had<br />

called for “a revolutionary professional ethic that mandates medical care<br />

for the Volk and not for the individual.” 114 In this context, destroying the<br />

“gangrenous appendix” 115 of the national body became a new kind of<br />

moral imperative that destroyed the Nazi doctor’s former obligations. In<br />

an utter reversal of values, it was the refusal “to kill valueless life [that] was<br />

considered immoral and evil.” 116<br />

DISTANCING MECHANISMS<br />

In addition to a medical training that prepared them for an environment<br />

in which the lives of the handicapped were devalued, the perpetrators<br />

of euthanasia were served by distancing mechanisms that allowed<br />

them to deny, or ignore the full significance of their actions. Doctors,<br />

nurses, and other T-4 staff separated themselves from the reality of killing<br />

and saw their actions as distinct from, or insignificant in the larger context<br />

of organized mass murder. This process of disassociation took a variety<br />

of forms, including a focus on the compartmentalized nature of tasks, the<br />

use of a language of falsehood and euphemisms, and the conviction that<br />

euthanized patients were spared a more painful fate.<br />

The T-4 administration and its division of labor and responsibility<br />

was, in itself, a distancing mechanism for many of the men and women<br />

who committed and facilitated murder. In post-war testimony, perpetrators<br />

repeatedly seemed incapable of recognizing the connection between<br />

their specific duties and the larger program of murder to which they contributed.<br />

Irmgard Huber, the chief nurse at Hadamar, denied any responsibility<br />

for the euthanization of tubercular Russians and Poles near<br />

the end of the war. As she put it, “I did nothing to the Russians and the<br />

Poles, and I do not feel any guilt. The transport was there already and it<br />

had to be received. It was already standing in front of the door.” 117 In this<br />

case, Huber’s moral responsibility seems to have been superceded by her<br />

“technical responsibility” to the institution of Hadamar. 118 She felt an obligation<br />

to fulfill her assigned task and emphasized that other forces, presumably<br />

larger than herself, had already brought the Russians and Poles<br />

to her door. Likewise, Edith Kloster, a nurse at one of the killing centers,<br />

insisted that she could “find no connection at all between the required<br />

transport of patients into the examination room and any killing that might<br />

take place later.” 119 Pfanmüller, who personally oversaw the murder of<br />

children at Eglfing-Haar and acted as a junior expert for patient selection,<br />

denied responsibility for choosing patients for death — one of his specific<br />

responsibilities — because his opinion was not the final decision in the<br />

case. He insisted that that was done by a “higher echelon” of authority. 120<br />

HEATHER COOPER


In a letter to his wife, Dr. Friedrich Mennecke described the task of selecting<br />

thousands of patients for death at Buchenwald as “purely theoretical<br />

work.” 121 After the war he said, “It was not my duty to shorten the lives<br />

of the insane persons, it was my duty to act as a medical expert.” 122 In<br />

all these cases, a focus on the compartmentalized nature of their tasks<br />

allowed perpetrators to deny responsibility for the final product of the<br />

euthanasia program. Whether they were unable to see, or simply refused<br />

to admit the full significance of their actions is impossible to know.<br />

The language of euphemisms and falsehood employed by the euthanasia<br />

program may also have contributed to disassociation in perpetrators,<br />

as it hid the darker reality of euthanasia beneath a façade of positive programs<br />

and actions. Hence, “murder” became “special treatment,” “therapy,”<br />

or “cleansing.” 123 “Disinfection” might stand in for “murder,” or for the<br />

processing of bones into ash by the stokers who manned the crematoria. 124<br />

The Reich Committee issued orders to kill as orders to “treat” even in secret<br />

documents. 125 The insistence on calling the destruction of handicapped<br />

life anything but that is evident in Dr. Ernst Lüdemann’s irritation when an<br />

asylum director referred to patients who were to be “‘killed,’ as he insisted on<br />

putting it” rather than those who were to be treated or cleansed. 126<br />

One wonders whether the fact that T-4 departments operated under<br />

a set of front organizations that existed in name only may also have<br />

contributed to disassociation. Under this system, the Reich Cooperative<br />

for <strong>State</strong> Hospitals and Nursing Homes, Charitable Foundation for Institutional<br />

Care, Charitable Foundation for the Transport of Patients, Inc.,<br />

Central Accounting Office for <strong>State</strong> Hospitals and Nursing Homes, and<br />

Reich Committee for the Scientific Registration of Severe Hereditary Ailments<br />

stood in for the offices responsible for registering victims, hiring<br />

perpetrators, transporting patients to their deaths, collecting payment for<br />

the care of patients already murdered, and orchestrating the euthanasia<br />

campaign against children. 127 What’s more, the physicians who selected<br />

patients for euthanasia and signed their death certificates used one or<br />

more pseudonyms to disguise their identities on documents relating to the<br />

program. Thus, Ernst Baumhard, the leading physician at Grafeneck and<br />

Hadamar, became Dr. Jäger; Irmfried Erbel, a physician at Brandenburg<br />

and Bernberg, became Dr. Schneider or Dr. Meyer, depending on which<br />

institution he was at; and Klaus Endruweit, of the Sonnenstein killing<br />

center, became Dr. Bader. 128 It seems likely that working in a setting in<br />

which one’s tasks were carried out under a false identity for an organization<br />

with a false name and purpose would have made it possible to distance<br />

oneself from the moral responsibility for such tasks and the truth of<br />

the organization’s goals.<br />

Some perpetrators acknowledged that they were taking life, but<br />

clung to the belief that euthanasia really was a “mercy death” for patients,<br />

especially in wartime. Hannah Arendt suggests that the most powerful<br />

Radical Exclusion: Nazi Euthanasia, 1939-1945<br />

33


34<br />

manipulation of language in the euthanasia program was Hitler’s original<br />

order, which replaced “murder” with the phrase “to grant a mercy death.”<br />

This transformation created an environment in which “the unforgivable<br />

sin was not to kill people but to cause unnecessary pain.” 129 One euthanasia<br />

doctor expressed astonishment at those who had reservations about<br />

granting mercy deaths, but could stand by and watch their patients starve<br />

as rations were cut in wartime:<br />

They refuse to end the suffering of their patients by administering<br />

drugs but they are happy to accept the fact that patients,<br />

who are by then really famished and emaciated, will<br />

one day take the road which could earlier have been made so<br />

much easier for them by a little assistance. 130<br />

Nurses and doctors might be disturbed by the actions they were asked to<br />

carry out, but they saw it as a matter of “releas[ing] unfortunate creatures<br />

from their suffering.” 131 This reasoning went back to some of the earliest<br />

arguments for euthanasia, which had always emphasized the mindless<br />

pain of those suffering from incurable diseases and made it the doctor’s<br />

duty to “release” them. 132<br />

CONCLUSION<br />

In 1932, Julius Moses, a Jewish physician and politician, saw clearly<br />

what the evolution of German medicine was leading to and the radical<br />

transformation of ethics, which Nazism was making possible. One year<br />

before Hitler’s fateful appointment as Chancellor, he issued a warning<br />

to the medical community, which would soon include him in its radical<br />

policy of exclusion:<br />

Everything that was considered until now as the holiest obligations<br />

of medicine — to care for the sick without paying attention<br />

to their race, to deal in the same way with all diseases,<br />

to help ill men everywhere and ease their pain — all this is<br />

viewed by the National-Socialists as sheer sentimental stuff<br />

which should be thrown away. The only matter of importance<br />

in their eyes is leading a war of annihilation against the less<br />

worthy (Minderwertige) — the incurable patients. … If this<br />

line of thought will win the upper hand the German medical<br />

profession will lose its ethical norms […], the physician will<br />

act as a killer, the doctor will become a murderer. 133<br />

Moses would eventually die in Theresienstadt, but not before his awful premonition<br />

had been realized in the organized murder of nearly one hundred<br />

thousand handicapped children and adults.<br />

This paper has attempted to understand the transformation of what was<br />

only an inclination toward euthanasia in 1932 into a concrete program for<br />

the destruction of “worthless lives” after 1939. A partial explanation has been<br />

offered by placing euthanasia in the context of an earlier eugenics and racial<br />

hygiene movement and examining the role played by the T-4 bureaucracy,<br />

training and indoctrination of medical staff, and the creation of distancing<br />

HEATHER COOPER


mechanisms in that radical transformation. Yet somehow questions persist<br />

about the meaning of the Nazi euthanasia program for our world. The Nazi<br />

atrocities and subsequent investigations into the “banality of evil” have led<br />

many to question what separates us from the men and women who orchestrated<br />

death on a mass scale from 1939 to 1945. As Arendt famously wrote,<br />

“The trouble with Eichmann was precisely that so many were like him, and<br />

that the many were neither perverted nor sadistic, that they were, and still are,<br />

terribly and terrifyingly normal.” 134<br />

If it was possible to convince ordinary Germans to cooperate in an unprecedented<br />

campaign of destruction against the helpless, how easily might<br />

the ordinary citizens of other nations have been drawn into a similar enterprise?<br />

Certainly Germany was not alone in its devaluation of individual life<br />

and ostracism of the handicapped. The United <strong>State</strong>s was a model of eugenics<br />

in the first half of the twentieth century; 45,127 people were sterilized in<br />

order to cleanse American society of the unfit between 1907 and 1945. 135<br />

One of the first proposals of euthanasia came from the American scholar,<br />

W. Duncan McKim in 1899, who suggested that euthanasia was a means<br />

of “improving the human race” and providing a “sweet death” to the unfit.<br />

136 In 1935, the French-American Nobel Prize winner Alexis Carrel wrote<br />

that criminals and the handicapped should be “humanely and economically<br />

disposed of in small euthanasia institutions supplied with proper gases.” 137<br />

In 1935, British physicians formed the Voluntary Euthanasia Legalization<br />

Society and submitted bills before the House of Lords for the legalization of<br />

euthanasia for the terminally ill. Just one year before Hitler signed the decree<br />

for euthanasia in Germany, W.G. Lennox spoke at Harvard regarding the<br />

need for physicians to acknowledge “the privilege of death for the congenitally<br />

mindless and for the incurable sick who wish to die.” 138<br />

Clearly, the fear of racial degeneration and the advocacy of radical measures<br />

were not unique to Germany. Yet perhaps it is Germany that must be<br />

credited with making those fears and ideas taboo. It was not until the Nazis<br />

took the radical step of transforming theoretical discussions of euthanasia’s<br />

merits into an actual program of annihilation that other nations recognized<br />

the terrible path they had been wandering for decades. Just as the Holocaust<br />

seemed to make anti-Semitism unthinkable after 1945, the euthanasia program<br />

made eugenics and its hierarchy of human worth into a symbol of the<br />

perversion of truth and science for future generations.<br />

From this distance, it seems almost impossible to imagine a world in<br />

which the government and scientific community could cooperate in the destruction<br />

of tens of thousands of lives. But that is to deny the world in which<br />

T-4 administrators, doctors, and staff lived and worked. The Nazi racial state<br />

created an environment in which the interests of the individual were subservient<br />

to those of the Volk and radical sacrifices were demanded to ensure the<br />

safety and health of the ethnic body politic. Within this context, the bureaucracy<br />

of T-4, the indoctrination of medical staff, and the creation of psychological<br />

distancing mechanisms allowed men and women to justify, commit,<br />

Radical Exclusion: Nazi Euthanasia, 1939-1945<br />

35


36<br />

and deny responsibility for mass murder of the handicapped. The scientific<br />

community in Germany did not heed Julius Moses’ 1932 warning, but the<br />

terrible legacy of that failure continues to stand as a harrowing warning to the<br />

generations that followed.<br />

NOTES<br />

1<br />

Adolf Hitler, Mein Kampf, trans. Ralph Manheim (Boston & New York: Houghton<br />

Mifflin Company, 1971), 132.<br />

2<br />

Document 740, Hitler’s order for euthanasia, signed October 1939, dated September<br />

1, 1939. In Foreign Policy, War and Racial Extermination. Ed. J. Noakes and G. Pridham. Vol 3<br />

of Nazism 1919-1945: A Documentary Reader (Exeter: <strong>University</strong> of Exeter Press, 1997), 1021.<br />

[Hereafter Noakes].<br />

3<br />

Henry Friedlander, The Origins of Nazi Genocide: From Euthanasia to the Final Solution<br />

(Chapel Hill & London: The <strong>University</strong> of North Carolina Press, 1995), 61; 112..<br />

4<br />

Ibid., 151.<br />

5<br />

Document 716, Excerpt from Binding & Hoche’s 1920 book, Permission for the<br />

Destruction of Worthless Life, its Extent and Form. In Noakes, 998.<br />

6<br />

Friedlander, The Origins of Nazi Genocide, 67.<br />

7<br />

Ibid., 14.<br />

8<br />

Zygmunt Bauman, Modernity and the Holocaust (Ithaca, New York: Cornell <strong>University</strong><br />

Press, 1989), 163.<br />

9<br />

Michael Burleigh, Death and Deliverance: ‘Euthanasia’ in Germany c. 1900-1945 (New<br />

York: Cambridge <strong>University</strong> Press, 1994); Michael Burleigh, Ethics and Extermination: Reflections<br />

on Nazi Genocide (Cambridge: Cambridge <strong>University</strong> Press, 1997).<br />

10<br />

Robert Jay Lifton, The Nazi Doctors: Medical Killing and the Psychology of Genocide (New<br />

York: Basic Books, 1986), 15.<br />

11<br />

Michael Burleigh and Wolfgang Wippermann, The Racial <strong>State</strong>: Germany 1933-1945<br />

(Cambridge: Cambridge <strong>University</strong> Press, 1991), 32.<br />

12<br />

Robert Proctor, Racial Hygiene: Medicine Under the Nazis (Cambridge & London:<br />

Harvard <strong>University</strong> Press, 1988), 27-28.<br />

13<br />

Burleigh and Wipperman, The Racial <strong>State</strong>, 32.<br />

14<br />

Sheil Faith Weiss, Race Hygiene and National Efficiency: The Eugenics of Wilhelm Schallmayer<br />

(Berkeley: <strong>University</strong> of California Press, 1987), 79.<br />

15<br />

Ibid., 86-87.<br />

16<br />

Burleigh and Wipperman, The Racial <strong>State</strong>, 30-32.<br />

17<br />

Document 716, Excerpt from Binding & Hoche’s 1920 book, Permission for the<br />

Destruction of Worthless Life, its Extent and Form. In Noakes, 998.<br />

18<br />

Ibid.<br />

19<br />

Document 718, Excerpt from Binding & Hoche’s 1920 book, Permission for the<br />

Destruction of Worthless Life, its Extent and Form. In Noakes, 999.<br />

20<br />

Burleigh, Death and Deliverance, 11.<br />

21<br />

Document 719, Excerpt from Binding & Hoche’s 1920 book, Permission for the<br />

Destruction of Worthless Life, its Extent and Form. In Noakes, 1001.<br />

22<br />

Burleigh, Death and Deliverance, 11.<br />

23<br />

Ibid., 30-33.<br />

24<br />

Burleigh, Ethics and Extermination, 116; Burleigh, Death and Deliverance, 32.<br />

25<br />

Document 730, Questionnaire for euthanasia program issued on October 9, 1939. In<br />

Noakes, 1012.<br />

26<br />

Sheila Faith Weiss, “The Race Hygiene Movement in Germany,” Osiris 2, no. 3<br />

(1987): 210-11.<br />

27<br />

Document 716, Excerpt from Binding & Hoche’s 1920 book, Permission for the<br />

Destruction of Worthless Life, its Extent and Form. In Noakes, 998.<br />

HEATHER COOPER


28 Paul Weindling, Health, Race and German Politics between National Unification and Nazism,<br />

1870-1945 (Cambridge: Cambridge <strong>University</strong> Press, 1989), 338-42.<br />

29 Lifton, 27; Weiss, “The Racial Hygiene Movement in Germany,” 230; Friedlander,<br />

The Origins of Nazi Genocide, 30. According to Lifton, 200,000-300,000 were sterilized; according<br />

to Weiss, as many as 400,000; according to Friedlander, 375,000 or more.<br />

30 Friedlander, The Origins of Nazi Genocide, 26.<br />

31<br />

Robert Proctor, “Nazi Doctors, Racial Medicine, and Human Experimentation,” in<br />

The Nazi Doctors and the Nuremberg Code: Human Rights in Human Experimentation, eds. George J.<br />

Annas and Michael A. Grodin (New York & Oxford: Oxford <strong>University</strong> Press, 1992), 21.<br />

32<br />

Friedlander, The Origins of Nazi Genocide, 26.<br />

33<br />

Bauman, 163.<br />

34<br />

Proctor, “Nazi Doctors, Racial Medicine, and Human Experimentation,” 24.<br />

35<br />

Friedlander, The Origins of Nazi Genocide, 39-40.<br />

36<br />

Peter Delius and Horst Dilling, “The End of the Strecknitz Asylum at Lübeck — a<br />

Contribution to the Social History of Psychiatry During National Socialism,” ed. Andreas Hill,<br />

History of Psychiatry 6, no. 3 (1995): 269.<br />

37<br />

Document 724, Reich Interior Ministry circular issued to state governments, 1939. In<br />

Noakes, 1006-7.<br />

38<br />

Proctor, Racial Hygiene, 188.<br />

39<br />

Burleigh, Death and Deliverance, 99.<br />

40<br />

Götz Aly et. al., Cleansing the Fatherland: Nazi Medicine and Racial Hygiene, trans. Belinda<br />

Cooper (Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins <strong>University</strong> Press, 1994), 189.<br />

41<br />

Noakes, 1011.<br />

42<br />

Affidavit of Victor Brack, Nuremberg Trials Transcript of the Proceedings, United<br />

<strong>State</strong>s of America v. Karl Brandt, et. al. In Medical Experiments on Jewish Inmates of Concentration<br />

Camps, ed. John Mendelsohn. Vol. 9 of The Holocaust (New York: Garland Publishing, Inc.,<br />

1982), 4-5. [Hereafter Mendelsohn, Vol. 9]<br />

43<br />

Noakes, 1011.<br />

44<br />

Friedlander, The Origins of Nazi Genocide, 44.<br />

45<br />

See, for example, Document 734, RMdI to Neuendettelsau Asylum, 2 September<br />

1940 and Document 735, Dr. Rudolf Boeckh, Director of Neuendettelsau Asylum to Reich<br />

Interior Ministry, Nov. 7, 1940. In Noakes, 1015-16.<br />

46<br />

Burleigh, Death and Deliverance, 138.<br />

47<br />

Document 730, Reporting forms for patients, issued October 9, 1939. In Noakes, 1012.<br />

48<br />

Document 731, Instructions for reporting forms. In Noakes, 1013.<br />

49<br />

Document 737, March 10, 1941 meeting to set criteria for patient elimination. In<br />

Noakes, 1017.<br />

50<br />

Weindling, 549.<br />

51<br />

Affidavit of Victor Brack, Nuremberg Trials Transcript of the Proceedings, United<br />

<strong>State</strong>s of America v. Karl Brandt, et al. In Mendelsohn. Vol. 9, 4-5.<br />

52<br />

Friedlander, The Origins of Nazi Genocide, 83.<br />

53<br />

Affidavit of Victor Brack, Nuremberg Trials Transcript of the Proceedings, United<br />

<strong>State</strong>s of America v. Karl Brandt, et al. In Mendelsohn. Vol. 9, 9.<br />

54<br />

Burleigh, Death and Deliverance, 129.<br />

55<br />

Trials of war criminals before the Nuernberg Military Tribunals under Control<br />

Council law no. 10, Nuremberg, October 1946-April 1949, Vol. 1: “Medical Case” (Washington,<br />

DC: USGPO, 1949-1953), 800.<br />

56<br />

Testimony of Viktor Brack, Official Transcript of the American Military Tribunal in<br />

the matter of the USA against Karl Brandt. In Mendelsohn, Vol. 9, 124.<br />

57<br />

Friedlander, The Origins of Nazi Genocide, 60.<br />

58<br />

Document 742, Letter informing institution of patients to be transferred. In<br />

Noakes, 1022-23.<br />

59<br />

Document 743, Description of transfer fro Jestetten asylum. In Noakes, 1023-24.<br />

60<br />

Friedlander, The Origins of Nazi Genocide, 94.<br />

61<br />

Ibid., 85.<br />

62<br />

Document 748, Letter to relatives informing of transfer. In Noakes, 1028.<br />

Radical Exclusion: Nazi Euthanasia, 1939-1945<br />

37


38<br />

63<br />

Friedlander, The Origins of Nazi Genocide, 103-4.<br />

64<br />

Ibid., 57; Aly, 190-91.<br />

65<br />

Document 727, Description of visit to Egelfing-Haar asylum on Feb. 16, 1940. In<br />

Noakes, 1008.<br />

66<br />

Lifton, 55.<br />

67<br />

Testimony of Viktor Brack, Official Transcript of the American Military Tribunal in<br />

the matter of the USA against Karl Brandt. In Mendelsohn, Vol. 9, 125.<br />

68<br />

Document 749, Letter to relatives informing of death. In Noakes, 1028.<br />

69<br />

Document 744, Account of a burner at Hartheim. In Noakes, 1026.<br />

70<br />

Aly, 176-77 and 182-83.<br />

71<br />

Description of a gassing given after war by a participant. In The Nazi Years: A<br />

Documentary History, ed. Joachim Remak (Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall, 1969), 138-39<br />

72<br />

Burleigh, Death and Deliverance, 149.<br />

73<br />

Affidavit of Pauline Kneissler, Nuremberg Trials Transcript of the Proceedings,<br />

United <strong>State</strong>s of America v. Karl Brandt, et. al. In Mendelsohn, Vol. 9, 13.<br />

74<br />

Friedlander, The Origins of Nazi Genocide, 95.<br />

75<br />

See Figure 6.4: Gas chamber of the Bernberg psychiatric hospital. In Burleigh and<br />

Wippermann, The Racial <strong>State</strong>, 151.<br />

76<br />

Friedlander, The Origins of Nazi Genocide, 96.<br />

77<br />

Document 746, Participant recollection. In Noakes, 1026.<br />

78<br />

Friedlander, The Origins of Nazi Genocide, 97; Document 747, Employee witness to gassing.<br />

In Noakes, 1027.<br />

79<br />

Friedlander, The Origins of Nazi Genocide, 97.<br />

80<br />

Document 744, Account of a burner at Hartheim. In Noakes, 1026.<br />

81<br />

Lifton, 75.<br />

82<br />

Burleigh, Death and Deliverance, 150.<br />

83<br />

Document 749, Letter to relatives informing of death. In Noakes, 1028.<br />

84<br />

Burleigh, Death and Deliverance, 240.<br />

85<br />

Burleigh, Death and Deliverance, 246; Bronwyn Rebekah McFarland-Icke, Nurses in Nazi<br />

Germany: Moral Choice in History (Princeton, NJ: Princeton <strong>University</strong> Press, 1999), 214.<br />

86<br />

McFarland-Icke, 238.<br />

87<br />

Lifton, 57.<br />

88<br />

McFarland-Icke, 227-28.<br />

89<br />

Delius and Dilling, 269.<br />

90<br />

Friedlander, The Origins of Nazi Genocide, 300.<br />

91<br />

Burleigh, Death and Deliverance, 147.<br />

92<br />

Friedlander, The Origins of Nazi Genocide, 300.<br />

93<br />

Fred E. Katz, “Implemenation of the Holocaust: The Behavior of Nazi Officials,”<br />

in The “Final Solution:” The Implementation of Mass Murder, Vol. 2, ed. Michael R. Marrus, Vol. 3<br />

of The Nazi Holocaust: Historical Articles on the Destruction of the European Jews (Westport & London:<br />

Meckler, 1989), 355.<br />

94<br />

Bauman, 163.<br />

95<br />

Ibid., 101.<br />

96<br />

Lifton, 15.<br />

97<br />

Ibid., 30.<br />

98<br />

Friedlander, The Origins of Nazi Genocide, 13.<br />

99<br />

Proctor, Racial Hygiene, 79-81.<br />

100<br />

Ibid., 82.<br />

101<br />

Ibid., 42.<br />

102<br />

Claudia Koonz, The Nazi Conscience (Cambridge, MA & London: The Belknap Press<br />

of Harvard <strong>University</strong> Press, 2003), 126.<br />

103<br />

Burleigh, Ethics and Extermination, 124; Friedlander, The Origins of Nazi Genocide, 216.<br />

HEATHER COOPER


104<br />

Robert N. Proctor, “Racial Hygiene: The Collaboration of Medicine and Nazism,”<br />

in Medicine, Ethics, and the Third Reich: Historical and Contemporary Issues, ed. John J. Michalczyk<br />

(Kansas City, MO: Sheed & Ward, 1994), 36-40.<br />

105<br />

Proctor, Racial Hygiene, 65.<br />

106<br />

Susanne Hahn, “Nursing Issues during the Third Reich,” in Medicine, Ethics, and the<br />

Third Reich: Historical and Contemporary Issues, ed. John J. Michalczyk (Kansas City, MO: Sheed &<br />

Ward, 1994), 143-44.<br />

107<br />

McFarland-Icke, 131-32.<br />

108<br />

Burleigh, Ethics and Extermination, 124; 157-59.<br />

109<br />

Koonz, 125.<br />

110<br />

Burleigh, Death and Deliverance, 192-94.<br />

111<br />

Testimony of Alfons Klein, Evidence for the Defense, in Trial of Alfons Klein, Adolf<br />

Wahlmann, Heinrich Ruoff, Karl Willig, Adolf Merkle, Irmgard Huber, and Philipp Blum (The Hadamar<br />

Trial), ed. Earl W. Kintner, Vol. IV of War Crimes Trials (London: William Hodge and Company,<br />

Limited, 1949), 93. [hereafter Hadamar Trial]<br />

112<br />

Document 746, Participant recollection. In Noakes, 1027.<br />

113<br />

Testimony of Alfons Klein, Evidence for the Defense, in Hadamar Trial, 90.<br />

114<br />

Koonz, 112.<br />

115<br />

Lifton, 16.<br />

116<br />

James M. Glass, “Life Unworthy of Life:” Racial Phobia and Mass Murder in Hitler’s Germany<br />

(New York: Basic Books, 1997), 156.<br />

117<br />

Testimony of Irmgard Huber, chief nurse at Hadamar. In Hadamar Trial, 119.<br />

118<br />

Bauman, 101.<br />

119<br />

McFarland-Icke, 238-39.<br />

120<br />

Testimony of Dr. Herman Pfanmueller, taken at Nuremberg, Germany, 1435-1630 5<br />

September 1945. In Mendelsohn, Vol. 9, 28-30.<br />

121<br />

Mennecke to Wife, 26 November 1941, 7:50 pm. In Aly, 254.<br />

122<br />

Friedlander, The Origins of Nazi Genocide, 80.<br />

123<br />

Glass, 61.<br />

124<br />

Friedlander, The Origins of Nazi Genocide, 98.<br />

125<br />

Ibid., 57.<br />

126<br />

Aly, 33-34. Italics added by author.<br />

127<br />

Friedlander, The Origins of Nazi Genocide, 73-74.<br />

128<br />

Table 5.2: The Euthanasia Killing Center Physicians and Their Pseudonyms, in<br />

Friedlander, The Origins of Nazi Genocide, 103.<br />

129<br />

Hannah Arendt, Eichmann in Jerusalem: A Report on the Banality of Evil (New York:<br />

Penguin Books, 1977), 108-109.<br />

130<br />

Benno Müller-Hill, Murderous Science: Elimination by Scientific Selection of Jews, Gypsies, and<br />

Others, Germany 1933-1945, trans. George R. Fraser (Oxford: Oxford <strong>University</strong> Press, 1988), 64.<br />

131<br />

Burleigh, Ethics and Extermination, 122-23.<br />

132<br />

Document 716, Excerpt from Binding & Hoche’s 1920 book, Permission for the<br />

Destruction of Worthless Life, its Extent and Form. In Noakes, 998.<br />

133<br />

Daniel Nadav, “Sterilization, ‘Euthanasia,’ and the Holocaust — The Brutal Chain,”<br />

in Medicine, Ethics, and the Third Reich: Historical and Contemporary Issues, ed. John J. Michalczyk<br />

(Kansas City, MO: Sheed & Ward, 1994), 42.<br />

134<br />

Arendt, 276.<br />

135<br />

Koonz, 105.<br />

136<br />

Enzo Traverso, The Origins of Nazi Violence, trans. Janet Lloyd (New York: The New<br />

Press, 2003), 122.<br />

137<br />

Proctor, “Nazi Doctors, Racial Medicine, and Human Experimentation,” 24.<br />

138<br />

Proctor, Racial Hygiene, 179-80.<br />

Radical Exclusion: Nazi Euthanasia, 1939-1945<br />

39


T H E P E R S I S T E N C E O F A<br />

Muslim Sicily<br />

P\<br />

D A N I E L Elash


eex<br />

post<br />

efacto


Sxxicily has been a contested place for the whole of recorded human<br />

history. Arguably, it continues to be a cultural battleground. This Mediterranean<br />

island plays a critical role as a primary entry point into Europe for<br />

countless immigrants from Africa and elsewhere, and its very existence in<br />

the modern Italian nation causes recurrent debates on autonomy, development,<br />

corruption and racism. The island has both celebrated and suffered<br />

the consequences of millennia of conquest and domination, upheaval<br />

and displacement. Such turbulence produced a unique Sicilian culture, in<br />

which one may still find identifiable strands of Roman, Greek, Muslim,<br />

and Germanic traditions beneath the contemporary Italian mass culture.<br />

These varied cultural roots blended together in a fiercely indigenous expression<br />

that can only roughly fit into a singular cultural category. Part<br />

European and part North African, Sicily’s Catholicism retains Orthodox<br />

features, and its people and places seem in some ways as remarkably Arab<br />

as they are Italian.<br />

Each successive conquest has in its turn suppressed previously-dominant<br />

cultural features in Sicily. For example, when the French and Spanish<br />

seized the Island from the Normans and Muslims, the new conquerors<br />

squelched Muslim culture. Despite the displacement and painful readjustment<br />

to a new orthodoxy, did the Muslims really disappear? Also referred<br />

to as Moors, Saracens, Arabs and Africans, the Muslims of Sicily came<br />

from many different places. However, they can be difficult to isolate from<br />

each other, particularly because they shared a common culture: Islam.<br />

In considering this multiethnic Muslim presence and influence in Sicily,<br />

Islam offers the right blend of specificity and inclusivity. A brief review<br />

of centuries of Sicilian history and a consideration of its contemporary<br />

population and culture reveals abundant evidence for the persistence of a<br />

Muslim Sicily to this day.<br />

Conservation and the California Redwood Lumber Companies<br />

43


44<br />

Muslim Sicilians had forbearers called the Phoenicians — another<br />

Semitic ethnic group originating in the eastern Mediterranean.<br />

Archaeologists have dated Phoenician graves in western Sicily back to<br />

the seventh century BCE. Thucydides maintained that they controlled<br />

the whole island. 1 Early Greek colonists shared the island with Phoenicians<br />

from Carthage who founded cities like Motya, Lilybaeum, and<br />

Ziz (Palermo) that became important Islamic centers in later centuries.<br />

2 The situation changed when the Romans arrived, expelling the<br />

Carthaginians in the series of Punic Wars from 264 to 146 BCE. 3 Yet,<br />

Greek endured as a dominant language and culture through the centuries<br />

of Roman rule. 4 After the fall of Rome in 476 CE, Sicily became<br />

the western frontier of the Byzantine Empire. 5 Muslim armies began<br />

conquering the island in 827 CE, and while they took Palermo as their<br />

capital almost immediately, 6 the entire Island was not under Muslim<br />

rule until the year 902 CE. 7<br />

Muslims plundered Sicily as early as 669 CE. 8 The rapid emergence<br />

of an Islamic empire precipitated a series of crises for the Byzantines,<br />

involving threats to Constantinople itself. 9 Thus, while Byzantium<br />

did fight for its last western possession, Sicily had to fend for itself in<br />

the end. Islamic conquest in Sicily took a century in part because of<br />

the heterogeneous nature of its conquerors, the Aghlabids, in addition<br />

to other troubles in North Africa. 10 Fierce resistance to Islamic rule in<br />

regions of the island also delayed the final consolidation of Muslim rule<br />

in Sicily, particularly in the culturally Greek northeast. 11 Islamicization<br />

was much more thorough in western Sicily, corresponding to the old<br />

Carthaginian sphere of influence. 12 Once established, Muslim administrators<br />

imposed a tax, called the dhimma on non-Muslim monotheistic<br />

communities in exchange for the right to exist. 13 A relatively tolerant act<br />

by the standards of its time, 14 the tax was a common Islamic administrative<br />

procedure. 15<br />

Due to Muslim conquest, Sicily participated directly in the zenith of<br />

Islamic culture that occurred during the Abbasid Caliphate and its immediate<br />

aftermath at the same time that most of the rest of Europe was at a<br />

nadir. Islam, for all of its political upheavals, provided a basis of unity and<br />

stability that stretched from India to Spain, encouraging trade, travel and<br />

academic discourse in its lingua franca, Arabic. Located within this eastwest<br />

path, Sicily received many Muslim contributions in fields ranging<br />

from literature to architecture, agriculture to political science. Muslims<br />

brought the magazine, the cupola, and muslin, 16 as well as tuna fishing and<br />

goats to the Mediterranean island. 17 Scholars suspect Islamic cultural influence<br />

in the origins of dolce stil nuovo, a later Sicilian school of poetry and<br />

the first in an Italian vernacular, as well as in the poetry of Dante. 18 Islam<br />

reinforced pre-existing traditions of scientific inquiry and multicultural<br />

tolerance and created new traditions. 19<br />

DANIEL ELASH


Over time, Muslim political power in Sicily factionalized. The Normans,<br />

responding to a request for military aid from one of the competing<br />

factions, conquered the island in 1060. 20 However, the Norman victory<br />

did not displace the Muslims. The Normans instead retained many Muslim<br />

administrators throughout their nearly 200 year rule on the island. 21<br />

The Normans reversed the dhimma, placing it on Muslim communities for<br />

Christian ends — a situation that horrified Muslim visitors. 22 Norman rulers<br />

at times appeared to be as much Muslim caliphs as Christian kings. 23<br />

This “Christian Caliphate” again suggests an avant-garde multiculturalism,<br />

captured in the awkwardness of the descriptive phrase “Norman-<br />

Arab,” as well as the unease such a phenomenon caused in a Europe on<br />

the verge of Crusades against the Muslim infidel. 24 The Papacy also had<br />

geoterritorial concerns of being surrounded when Sicily was annexed to<br />

the Holy Roman Empire. 25 The crisis came to a head during Frederick II’s<br />

reign, when a series of Popes crushed the ruler and placed another in his<br />

political office, despite his military victory in a Crusade. 26<br />

The French arrived as Papal-sanctioned successors to the Normans<br />

and quickly reduced Sicily to a vassalage of absentee landlords and tax<br />

collectors, as it had been under Rome. 27 The resulting rebellion, called<br />

the Sicilian Vespers, transferred political control of Sicily from the hated<br />

French to the hands-off-Spanish. 28 Sicily nevertheless declined into a<br />

backwater for the next several centuries. The island remained so mired<br />

in poverty and ignorance that Garibaldi’s 19th-century Italian unification<br />

movement came and went without meaningfully altering feudalistic<br />

Sicilian social relations. In fact, even in more recent centuries, Sicily has<br />

remained an officially autonomous region within Italy since World War<br />

II, 29 reflecting an ambivalence that Sicily and Italy feel and sometimes still<br />

express in their relations.<br />

Islam had a profound historical impact on Sicily, for better and<br />

worse. Both good and bad are now buried together underneath intervening<br />

centuries’ worth of experiences. Comparable to archaeological ruins,<br />

these experiences remain present in physical detail, yet without much narrative<br />

integrity in the contemporary culture of Sicily.<br />

People interpret these ruins in order to unearth evidence of Sicily’s<br />

Muslim cultural past. A distinct and measurable Muslim genetic legacy<br />

remains in Sicily, though such studies tend to focus on geographical origins.<br />

It would be a mistake to infer too much specificity about culture from<br />

geographical origins or vice versa as populations migrate naturally over<br />

time. However, genetics can still be a strong indicator of relations between<br />

populations. 30 Recently, geneticists produced several studies specific to Sicily.<br />

One of these studies concludes that the modern Sicilian population is<br />

genetically as closely related to Iran as it is to Northern Italy. 31 Another<br />

noted that “Arab domination seems to have had a very strong genetic<br />

impact” in Sicily, leaving measurable genetic proximities to populations in<br />

The Persistence of a Muslim Sicily<br />

45


46<br />

Egypt and Morocco. 32 A third study found that the populations of Sicily,<br />

Calabria, and Greece are not only geographically clustered, but are also<br />

demarcated from the other European populations examined. 33 The study<br />

attributed these facts to “the impact of people of Mediterranean and<br />

Middle Eastern ancestry on the island.” A fourth study contends that a<br />

Near Eastern genetic contribution to Sicily “appears unquestionable.” 34<br />

Language also provides evidence for the persistence of a Muslim Sicily.<br />

Arabic enriched both the Sicilian dialect and modern Italian. One<br />

may see this in Sicilian proverbs, 35 folk songs, 36 and the names of the<br />

Island’s locales. 37 Italian grammarians acknowledge that the standard Italian<br />

words for orange, lemon, artichoke, eggplant, spinach, sugar, and cotton all<br />

derive from Arabic, which also indicates the origins of those crops. Italian<br />

likewise borrowed its words for customs/duty, warehouse, manufacturing defect,<br />

tariff, arsenal, wharf, and hemp rope, again implying contributions in maritime<br />

trade. Arabic also gave Italian algebra, algorithm, cipher, zero, nadir, and<br />

zenith, as well as chemistry terms like alchemy, elixir, camphor, talc, alkali, and<br />

borax. Arabic supplied Italians with words for chess and checkmate, blue, porter,<br />

and boy — everyday words implying the breadth and depth of linguistic<br />

and cultural contributions. 38 Scholars of Arabic likewise concede that “the<br />

Sicilian dialect of today reveals lexical remnants of the Siculo-Arabic in<br />

a large inventory of Material Cultural terms.” 39 Linguistic impact is also<br />

visible in Arabic surnames which persist in the Sicilian population. 40 Researchers<br />

maintain there is a correlation between surname distribution<br />

and gene distribution. 41<br />

Various architectural treasures further illuminate a Muslim Sicily in<br />

both their visual splendor and their highly public nature. Sicily’s regional<br />

parliament resides in the famous Norman-Arab palace at Palermo. 42 The<br />

building includes its own church, the Capella Palatina, which is similar<br />

to other Muslim-designed structures of the era, such as the <strong>San</strong> Cataldo<br />

church. 43 Inside the Capella Palatina, one finds Islamic cultural elements<br />

woven into the architecture, including Arabic script on door handles and<br />

ceiling decorations, Islamic architectural elements, and elaborate floors<br />

that mimic Arab design motifs. The Capella Palatina once featured striking<br />

examples of Arabic script as highly visible decoration, including the<br />

name of the Norman king Roger II. The abundance of such evidence at<br />

Palermo makes sense, given the city’s former status as the capital of Muslim<br />

Sicily. As the contemporary capital of an autonomous Italian region,<br />

it is perhaps more surprising that the very seat of government is located in<br />

such a high-profile reminder of the island’s Muslim roots.<br />

Other components of current Sicilian culture, and that of Italy more<br />

generally, reaffirm Sicily’s Muslim heritage. One particularly dramatic and<br />

colorful example is the tradition of “i pupi siciliani,” or Sicilian puppetry.<br />

Largely drawn from the Chanson de Roland and other similarly epic poetic<br />

traditions, the repertoire includes the battles between Christians and Mus-<br />

DANIEL ELASH


lims for dominion. 44 The art form is important enough that UNESCO has<br />

declared it a world heritage resource. 45 Francesca Corrao noted the simultaneous<br />

existence in Sicilian, Turkish and Arab cultures, of a series of folk<br />

tales regarding a sacred fool named Giufà/Nasreddin or Hoca/Guha.<br />

According to her, the differences among versions of the tales say as much<br />

about the related Arab and Sicilian cultures as their similarities. 46<br />

Modern Italian schoolbooks tend to downplay Sicily’s relation to Islam.<br />

For example, Garzanti’s Italian junior high history text offers a lone<br />

statement on Muslim rule of Sicily, characterizing the territory as a base for<br />

piracy. 47 The same Italian grammar text that lists the above-cited Arabicderived<br />

Italian words, insists that “unlike the Germanic peoples, [the Arabs]<br />

never fused with the conquered population.” 48<br />

Tourist literature in English tends to showcase Muslim Sicily. Lonely<br />

Planet offers seven paragraphs on Muslim and Norman-Arab rule, totaling<br />

one of its 26 pages of text dedicated to Italian history. 49 At least three major<br />

tourist guides feature Arab sights to see in Palermo. One guide, specific to Sicily,<br />

emphasizes the point with no less than four color photos on the theme. 50<br />

Yet, Sicily deems some tourists unwanted as many illegal immigrants<br />

from Africa reach the island’s borders each year. Because of geographical<br />

proximity, Sicily is the primary entry point for most Africans attempting<br />

to enter the European Union without proper documentation. 51 This has<br />

aggravated already existing tensions in Italy between the North and South,<br />

as well as Italian relations with Europe. Italy’s old, unresolved question of<br />

disparate economic development between the North and South lurks below<br />

the surface of the debate, which has also been aggravated by racism. One<br />

result is xenophobic political movements such as the Lega Nord, one party in<br />

the coalition currently controlling the Italian government. 52 In this context,<br />

it is little wonder that attitudes in the Italian South are ambivalent, at best,<br />

to its own non-European roots, particularly its Muslim heritage. Nevertheless,<br />

the artifacts from a Muslim Sicily remain popular tourist destinations.<br />

Contemporary Muslim communities face difficult racial and xenophobic<br />

attitudes in Italy. Arab.it, an online resource for Italian Muslims,<br />

lists about 158 Islamic Centers and Associations in Italy, nine of those in<br />

Sicily. 53 The current Muslim population in Italy is between 800,000 and<br />

1 million 54 making Islam the country’s second largest religion. However,<br />

there are no official government representatives to or other relations between<br />

the Muslim communities and the Italian government, unlike many<br />

other religious groups in the nation. Lega Nord further exacerbates this situation<br />

through its official hostility to mosque-building in Italy. 55<br />

The existence and persistence of a Muslim Sicily therefore appears<br />

to be an inescapable conclusion. It is apparent through evidence such as<br />

history, population, language, material culture, popular culture, and politics.<br />

Islamic persistence in the face of all obstacles, however, has in turn<br />

The Persistence of a Muslim Sicily<br />

47


48<br />

required painful changes that have somewhat obscured the direct connections.<br />

Thus, we see Arab palaces and Crusader-hero puppet plays side-byside<br />

in contemporary Palermo. Sicily is a land full of Muslim agricultural<br />

gifts and architectural gems, of which it brags to its guests in the same<br />

breath as it proclaims its monolithic Catholicism. If modern problems<br />

like illegal immigration leave Sicilians relatively unmoved, perhaps it is because<br />

the problem is both eternal and theirs alone. The island has always<br />

been a transit point for masses of people headed somewhere else. Dominant<br />

cultures come and go, each leaving behind a series of impressions<br />

that refract like an Arabesque tile design down through the ages, playing<br />

out in the faces, words, and material culture of the Sicilian people they<br />

invariably leave behind. One gets this impression from the way in which<br />

Sicily defends its honor against insults, insisting on its place at the Italian<br />

and European tables while maintaining a sense of distance from both.<br />

Indeed, Sicily insists upon its cultural difference. Beneath that insistence,<br />

beats the heart of a permanently besieged people, quietly and stubbornly<br />

continuing to be who they always have been, whatever the socio-political<br />

order of the day might require. Given its location, Sicily will continue to<br />

be contested for a long time to come, but through it all and come what<br />

may, there will always be a Muslim Sicily, in spirit and in fact. All considered,<br />

how could it be otherwise?<br />

DANIEL ELASH


01<br />

Gerhard Herm, The Phoenicians: The Purple Empire of the Ancient World, trans. Caroline<br />

Hillier (New York: William Morrow and Co., 1975), 138.<br />

02<br />

Striking geoterritorial similarities between Phoenician and Muslim areas can be seen<br />

by comparing the maps found in Herm, Phoenicians, 188 and Ira Lapidus, A History of Islamic<br />

Societies, 2nd ed. (Cambridge, 2002), 303.<br />

03<br />

The Punic Wars are extensively referenced in ancient sources. Two good ancient<br />

sources include Polybius, Rise of the Roman Empire, trans. Ian Scott-Kilvert (London: Penguin<br />

Books 1979) and Livy, Rome and the Meditteranean, Books XXXI-XLV of the History of Rome from its<br />

Foundation, trans. Henry Bettenson (London: Penguin Books, 1976); see also Herm, Phoenicians,<br />

for a narrative of those events, particularly pages 236-263.<br />

04<br />

M. I. Finley, A History of Sicily: Ancient Sicily to the Arab Conquest (New York: Viking<br />

Press, 1968), 165, 178.<br />

05<br />

Byzantine general Belisarius reconquered Sicily from the Ostrogoths in 535 CE; see<br />

Finley, Sicily, 180.<br />

06<br />

Jeremy Johns, Arabic Administration in Norman Sicily: The Royal Diwan (Cambridge,<br />

2002) 24. Michele Amari, Storia dei musulmani di Sicilia, <strong>volume</strong> primo (Catania, 1933), 394-605,<br />

extensively describes the step by step conquest.<br />

07<br />

George Ostrogorsky, History of the Byzantine <strong>State</strong>, rev. ed., trans. Joan Hussey (New<br />

Brunswick: Rutgers <strong>University</strong> Press, 1969) 208, 257.<br />

08<br />

Finley, Sicily, 184. See also Aziz Ahmad, A History of Islamic Sicily (Edinburgh, 1975),<br />

3-4. These raids included the capture of prisoners, according to Alex Metcalfe, Muslims and<br />

Christians in Norman Sicily, Arabic Speakers and the End of Islam (London and New York, 2003), 10.<br />

09<br />

Ostrogorsky, Byzantine, 110-125, includes the history of an abortive attempt to move<br />

the Byzantine capital to Syracuse.<br />

10<br />

Lapidus, Islamic Societies, 302-303; Albert Hourani, A History of the Arab Peoples (New<br />

York, 1991), 38.<br />

11<br />

Metcalfe, Muslims and Christians, 11-12.<br />

12<br />

Ahmad, History, 22.<br />

13<br />

The dhimma, a sort of capitation/tribute tax that allowed non-Muslim individuals<br />

their land and other rights, and communities the right to a certan amount of collective selfrule;<br />

also known as the jizya; comparable to the Ottoman millet system, though different in the<br />

particulars of its implementation. Lapidus, Islamic Societies, 265; Johns, Norman Sicily, 23, 26-27;<br />

Metcalfe, Muslims and Christians, 11, 34-37; Ahmad, History, 22; Hourani, Peoples, 35.<br />

14<br />

For examples, compare Byzantine disputes such as iconoclasm, Ostrogorsky, Byzantine,<br />

160-165, 171-175. For monophysitism Ostrogorsky, Byzantine, 64, 78, 107-109. For the<br />

rise of feudalism due to a lack of circulating currency or security, as well as a discussion of the<br />

continuing effects of the barbarian invasions and western Roman collapse, no so much a sign<br />

of intolerance as of the utter social atomization generally characterized as a “Dark Age” see<br />

George Holmes, Oxford Illustrated History of Italy (Oxford, 1997), 34-36 Garzanti Editorie, Il libro<br />

Garzanti della storia, <strong>volume</strong> primo (Milan, 1980), ch. 31..<br />

15<br />

Hourani, Peoples, 30. In fact, disputes over such taxes and their application to converts<br />

to Islam played a large role in the overthrow of the Umayyad and rise of the Abbasid<br />

Caliphates; Lapidus, Islamic Societies, 51-54..<br />

16<br />

Ahmad, History, 93.<br />

17<br />

Joseph F. Privitera, Beginner’s Sicilian (New York, 2001), 7-8.<br />

18<br />

Ahmad, History, 93-96..<br />

19<br />

See Ahmad, History, which discusses “Intellectual Activity During the Muslim Period.”<br />

Of course such activity was far from unknown to the Greeks — although Byzantium<br />

was moving away from that tradition.<br />

20<br />

Johns, Norman Sicily, 31-33. It’s particularly ironic that this was exactly how the Muslims<br />

came to the island themselves. See also Ahmad, History, 6-7.<br />

21<br />

Ahmad, History, 59, 66-7; Metcalfe, Muslims and Christians, 41-4; Johns, Norman Sicily.<br />

Johns argues that initial convenience was later reinforced by adoption of Fatimid Egyptian<br />

administrative norms as generally the best available.<br />

22<br />

Ahmad, History, 68; Johns, Norman Sicily, 34-39; Metcalfe, Muslims and Christians, 34-36.<br />

The Persistence of a Muslim Sicily<br />

NOTES<br />

49


50<br />

23<br />

Ahmad, History, 63-65; Johns, Norman Sicily. Johns argues for some of the social and<br />

political uses of maintaining such an image aside from administrative function.<br />

24<br />

On a heterogeneous Norman-Arab Sicily, see Clifford Backman, The Worlds of Medieval<br />

Europe (Oxford, 2003), 204-205. See Holmes, Italy, 50 on how this was as opportunistic<br />

as idealistic. Backman speaks of the profusion of issues and their multifarious effects in the<br />

tensions between church and state in Sicily during the reign of Frederick III, in The Decline and<br />

Fall of Medieval Sicily (Cambridge, 1995), particularly 186-7.<br />

25<br />

Holmes, Italy, 52.<br />

26<br />

On Papal intrigue against Norman regime in Sicily, see Backman, Worlds, 270-1 and<br />

293-6. Extensive detail on the terse summation of events presented here may be found in David<br />

Abulafia, Frederick II, A Medieval Emperor (London, 1988), 340-407.<br />

27<br />

Steven Runciman, The Sicilian Vespers (Cambridge, 1958) 124-31.<br />

28<br />

Runciman, Vespers, 277-9.<br />

29<br />

Holmes, Italy, 202-5, for both the nineteenth and twentieth century situation in Sicily.<br />

For an even more concise summation, see Privitera, Sicilian, 5-6.<br />

30<br />

John H. Relethford, Reflections of Our Past: How Human History Is Revealed in Our Genes<br />

(Cambridge: Westview Press, 2003), 101-22, offers an excellent discussion of the science involved<br />

in the genetic studies upon which the following four citations are based, and the use of<br />

such data in considering probable relations between discrete populations.<br />

31<br />

Olga Rickards et. al., “Genetic Structure of the Population of Sicily,” American Journal<br />

of Physical Anthropology 87 (1992): 395-406.<br />

32<br />

C. M. Calò et. al., “Genetic Analysis of a Sicilian Population Using 15 Short Tandem<br />

Repeats,” Human Biology 75 (2003): 163-178.<br />

33<br />

P. Francalacci et. al., “Peopling of Three Mediterranean Islands (Corsica, Sardinia,<br />

and Sicily) Inferred by Y-Chromosome Biallelic Variability,” American Journal of Physical Anthropology<br />

121 (2003): 270-9.<br />

34<br />

G. Vona et. al., “Mitochondrial DNA Sequence Analysis in Sicily,” American Journal of<br />

Human Biology 13 (2001): 576-89.<br />

35<br />

Cristaldi Communications, “The Sicilian Dialect and Language,” Sicilian Culture, 21<br />

(March 2002), http://www.sicilianculture.com/dialect/index.htm; Internet; accessed 23 Oct<br />

2004. See list of proverbs under the link “Famous Sicilian Proverbs.”<br />

36<br />

Alan Lomax, “Cialomi (Tuna Fishermen’s Chants),” Italian Treasury: Sicily, Rounder<br />

Records, Rounder 11661-1808-2. Also, track three notes in the accompanying booklet, by Sergio<br />

Bananzinga et. al.<br />

37<br />

William E. Granara, “Political Legitimacy and Jihad in Muslim Sicily 217/825-<br />

445/1053” (PhD diss., <strong>University</strong> of Pennsylvania, 1986), viii-ix..<br />

38<br />

All specific words from Maurizio Dardano and Pietro Trifone, Grammatica italiana,<br />

terza edizione (Bologna, 1995), 643. While the cited text is in Italian, the vocabulary is presented<br />

here in English for convenience.<br />

39<br />

Dionisius A. Agius, “Focus of Concern in Ibn Makki’s Tatqif Al-Lisan: The Case of<br />

Gender in the Medieval Arabic of Sicily,” in The Arabist: Budapest Studies in Arabic: Proceedings of<br />

the Colloquium on Arabic Grammar, Held in Budapest 1-7 September 1991, ed. Alexander Folor (Budapest:<br />

Eötvös Loránd <strong>University</strong> Chair for Arabic Studies and Csoma De Körös Society Section<br />

of Islamic Studies, 1991), 1.<br />

40<br />

Angela Pavesi et. al., “Brief Communication: Coexistence of Two Distinct Patters in<br />

the Surname Structure of Sicily,” American Journal of Physical Anthropology120 (2003): 195..<br />

41<br />

A. A. Rodriguez-Larralde et. al., “Isonomy and the Genetic Structure of Sicily,” Journal<br />

of Biosocial Science, 26 (1994): 10.<br />

42<br />

Robert Andrews and Jules Brown, The Rough Guide to Sicily, 5th ed. (London: Rough<br />

Guides Ltd., 2002), 75.<br />

43<br />

William Tronzo, The Cultures of His Kingdom: Roger II and the Capella Palatina in Palermo<br />

(Princeton, 1997) extensively discusses the Palazzo dei Normanni as a work of Arab architecture.<br />

For locating <strong>San</strong> Cataldo as another example of Arab-Norman architecture, see the City<br />

of Palermo website at http://www.comune.palermo.it/English/old_city.htm. Palermo also<br />

discusses the relation of Arab architects and Norman building projects at http://www.comune.<br />

palermo.it/English/crossroads.htm.<br />

44<br />

On the origins of Sicilian puppetry as an art form, and its situation in a contemporary<br />

context, see: Rod Jenkins, “Refighting old religious wars in a miniature arena,” New York<br />

Times, 8 December 2001 [website]; available from http://pupisiciliani.com/eng/links/nyt_sicilian_puppets.htm;<br />

Internet; accessed 23 October 2004. On the puppet shows as expression of<br />

ambivalence regarding Sicily’s simultaneous roots in opposing cultures, see the History section<br />

of: Pasqualino Brothers, “History,” Sicilian Puppet Theatre of the Fratelli Pasqualino, 2002 [website];<br />

available from http://www.pupisiciliani.com/eng/index.html; Internet; accessed 23 October<br />

DANIEL ELASH


2004. On the centrality of “Moorish” characters to this art form, and its establishment elsewhere<br />

in Sicily, see: Puppet House Theater, “History of the Sicilian Puppets,” The Puppet House<br />

Theater, 2004 [website]; available from http://www.puppethouse.org/history.htm; Internet; accessed<br />

23 October 2004..<br />

45 UNESCO, “Opera dei Pupi, Sicilian Puppet Theatre,” Proclamation of Masterpieces of<br />

the Oral and Intangible Heritage of Humanity, 18 May 2001 [website]; available from http://www.<br />

unesco.org/bpi/intangible_heritage/italy.htm; Internet; accessed 23 October 2004.<br />

46 Francesca M. Corrao, “The Infraction of the Religious Codes in the Mediterranean<br />

Folk Literature, the Case of the Islamic Guha and the Sicilian Giufa,” in The Arabist: Budapest<br />

Studies in Arabic: Proceedings of the Colloquium on Popular Customs and the Monotheistic Religions in the<br />

Middle East and North Africa, Held in Budapest 19-25th September 1993, ed. Alexander Fodor (Budapest:<br />

Eötvös Loránd <strong>University</strong> Chair for Arabic Studies and Csoma De Körös Society Section<br />

of Islamic Studies, 1994), 283-293.<br />

47 Garzanti, Storia, 14-16. The text does offer a sidebar, entirely dedicated to a Muslim<br />

writer’s description of Palermo as a beautiful place.<br />

48 Maurizio Dardano and Pietro Trifone, Grammatica italiana, terza editzione, 642. The<br />

text goes on to credit the Arabs’ scientific vocabulary to their “Greek and Indo-Iranian cultural<br />

patrimony;” compare this to its handling of Germans as a related set of peoples on page 641,<br />

at times as “disciples of the Romans” and later as having a “highly developed culture.” Also<br />

compare its citing on page 642 of such as the Crusades and monastic orders (among others) as<br />

bases of Italian-French relations, all the more interesting as the Normans are given full credit<br />

for their two centuries in the south in this context. The Greeks, however, are likewise minimized<br />

on page 641, and words of obviously Greek origin are actually credited to French on page 644.<br />

I would thus maintain that there is an obvious propaganda function involved an attempt to<br />

distance Italy from the Mediterranean and draw it closer to Europe.<br />

49 Damien Simonis et. al., Lonely Planet: Italy (Oakland, 2002), 27-9.<br />

50 See also Andrews and Brown, Rough Guide, who give the Muslims three paragraphs<br />

and the Normans ten, for over two of its fourteen pages of history text, 428-432. This would<br />

seem proportionate; however, Penelope A. Carter et. al., Let’s Go Italy 2000 (New York, 2000),<br />

10, merely mention the entire period in a subordinate clause.<br />

51 This relationship is readily apparent in current new coverage, for example see Sopie<br />

Arie, “A Two-Way Thing,” Guardian Unlimited Online, 12 Oct. 2004, http://www.guardian.<br />

co.uk/elsewhere/journalist/story/0,,1325531,00.html; accessed 4 Dec. 2004..<br />

52 For a good general summary of the very complicated, nuanced situation, see Frank<br />

Viviano, “The Fall of Rome,” Mother Jones, Sept./Oct. 1993. Website. http://www.moterhjones.com/news/feature/1993/09/viviano.html;<br />

accessed 4 Dec. 2004. The situation has<br />

changed somewhat as the Lega Nord has come into power in the current coalition government<br />

in Italy, toning down their rhetoric in the process. However, the subtext remains the same. For<br />

a folkloric take on the problem, and the racism involved, see Dr. Joseph Sciorra’s “A History of<br />

the Insulted World,” 1998-2004, a web page discussing the situation as told from the point of<br />

view of Southern Italian rap music: http://www.italianrap.com/intro/south.html, accessed 4<br />

Dec. 2004..<br />

53 ARCO Service. “Centri ed associazioni islamici in Italia,” 1997-2004. http://www.<br />

arab.it/almarkaz.html; accessed 4 Dec. 2004.<br />

54 Sophie Arie, “Anti-Islamic books’ success fuel fears of racisim in Italy,” Guardian Unlimited<br />

Online, 7 Aug. 2004. http://www.guardian.co.uk/international/story/0,,1278177,00.<br />

html; accessed 4 Dec. 2004. The 1 million figure is from Sophie Arie, “Italian MPs Plan Control<br />

of New Mosques,” Guardian Unlimited Online, 25 March 2004. http://www.guardian.<br />

co.uk/international/story/0,,1177462,00.html. As the Guardian’s correspondent in Rome, Ms.<br />

Arie offers a reliable source of information on Italian current events in English.<br />

55 Arie, “Italian MPs Plan Control of New Mosques.”<br />

The Persistence of a Muslim Sicily<br />

51


Little Women &<br />

Evil-looking Men:<br />

R E B E C C A B U F F U M S P R I N G A N D<br />

T H E P O L I T I C S O F M O T H E R H O O D I N<br />

A N T E B E L L U M A M E R I C A<br />

O\<br />

S A R A H Barkin<br />

graduate WINNER: SARAH RUTH PRIZE


eex<br />

post<br />

efacto


n November 1859, roughly a month after John Brown’s unsuccessful<br />

raid on Harpers Ferry, a woman walked through a crowd of “evil-looking”<br />

men and made her way to the steps of the prison where John Brown<br />

was incarcerated. Accompanied by her nineteen-year-old son, Rebecca<br />

Buffum Spring waited in the guardroom for thirty minutes, braving the<br />

“rough talk” of the men in the room and the suffocating heat of the stovewarmed<br />

air before being allowed to visit “Old Man” Brown in his cell. 1<br />

After visiting with the prisoner for some time, Spring and her son were<br />

forced to leave on the order of Sheriff J.W. Campbell. He argued that the<br />

crowd outside was growing dangerous and had threatened violent action<br />

if she remained much longer. In her unpublished autobiography, written<br />

late in her life, Spring described the scene she and her son encountered as<br />

they left the prison:<br />

The great, tall Sheriff, with a scowl on his face, impatiently<br />

opened the door, and hurried out a little woman and a boy,<br />

in the face of a furious mob of the worst looking men I ever<br />

saw. We stood for a moment on the little platform, and looked<br />

down over a sea of thousands of angry eyes, and saw clenched<br />

hands raised, threateningly; and I did not feel afraid. As we<br />

descended the steps they stood aside, giving us only just room<br />

to pass, and soon we were safe in the hotel. 2<br />

I<br />

In the published account of her visit, Spring added this thought: “I,<br />

who dare not pass a cow and who have such a terror of great dogs, was so<br />

uplifted in spirit that I had lost all feeling of fear and walked through the<br />

mob . . . without thinking of the mob at all. I believe I was safer because<br />

I was not afraid. . . . It is good sometimes to get a glimpse of the power<br />

within us.” 3 Much of this inner power derived from her upbringing: as<br />

a Quaker and a passionate anti-slavery activist, Spring was used to confronting<br />

opposition and had experience in standing up for her beliefs. 4<br />

Thus, despite the harrowing experience and her precarious position as a<br />

northern abolitionist woman surrounded by angry southern men, Spring<br />

refused to leave the town and even managed to arrange a second visit before<br />

she returned to her home, a communitarian settlement known as the<br />

Raritan Bay Union in Eagleswood, New Jersey.<br />

55


56<br />

Like other Garrisonian abolitionists, Spring used gendered language<br />

to link the personal with the political. 5 The power she claimed for herself<br />

was strength of soul; by linking it to her uplifted religious spirit, she effectively<br />

emphasized women’s roles as moral superiors. Similarly, like Moses<br />

parting the Red Sea, she made her way through the crowd and arrived<br />

safely at her destination. She was also careful to offset inner power with<br />

descriptions of her outer powerlessness. Yet there is a subversive element<br />

in her portrayal of herself as a “little woman” and her grown son as a<br />

“boy.” She called southern manliness into question when she contrasted<br />

the “great, tall” sheriff and the violent crowd against the image of her<br />

helplessness. She implied that only brutes, or “great dogs” would threaten<br />

violence against a woman and her son; in Spring’s mind these were not<br />

true men but snarling animals.<br />

Such examples of gendered imagery and language do more than illustrate<br />

Spring’s character; they also provide the modern-day historian with an<br />

intriguing glimpse into the gendered world of antebellum America. Previous<br />

historians have attempted to categorize Spring as either a “subtle feminist”<br />

or a conservative abolitionist. 6 But such characterizations are overly<br />

simplistic and ignore the complex nature of Spring’s actions. In an era when<br />

the “Cult of True Womanhood” defined women’s position as confined to<br />

the domestic sphere, Spring’s physical and moral show of support for John<br />

Brown both challenged and underscored traditional definitions of female<br />

roles and illustrated the extent to which Spring recognized and manipulated<br />

her position as a gendered being. Like other women in reform and<br />

benevolent movements, she used her domestic role as wife and mother as<br />

justification to step beyond the private sphere of the home. When Rebecca<br />

Spring visited John Brown’s prison cell, she enacted a performance of gender<br />

in which she used traditional notions of femininity and women’s duties<br />

to justify what was, in essence, a radical political action.<br />

Gender performance as a theoretical concept is not new, but it has<br />

received increasing attention from historians in recent years. In the 1960s,<br />

and more recently in the 1990s, social scientists like Erving Goffman,<br />

Kath Weston, and others applied notions of performance and representation<br />

to identity, race, and gender, thus calling into question categories that<br />

once seemed absolute and natural. 7 Building upon this framework, as well<br />

as the works of French philosophers like Simone de Beauvoir and Michel<br />

Foucault, in 1990 Judith Butler, a critical theorist, published Gender Trouble<br />

in which she argued that gender was neither clear-cut nor biologically<br />

based, but was instead a social construction. Gender does not exist of its<br />

own accord, so much as it is “done,” or performed, by people. Thus, gender<br />

norms are defined by repeated reenactments that, taken as a whole,<br />

are meant to delineate what it is to be feminine or masculine. It is possible<br />

to perform one’s appropriate gender improperly, and such instances<br />

of failure are duly punished, often violently, for transgressions of gender<br />

threaten identity and social order.<br />

SARAH BARKIN


Kathleen Brown is one of the first historians to place gender performance<br />

in a historical context. In her groundbreaking work Good Wives,<br />

Nasty Wenches, and Anxious Patriarchs: Gender, Race, and Power in Colonial Virginia,<br />

she discusses the ways in which eighteenth-century men and women<br />

defined, redefined, and challenged gender norms. Brown persuasively<br />

argues that gender discourse, however instable, served as the basis for colonial<br />

Virginia’s developing social and political structure. The “anxious<br />

patriarchs” defined their political status and identity in contrast to their<br />

“seemingly natural” dependents: slaves and women. 9 In actuality this<br />

social order was anything but natural and thus required repeated performances<br />

to maintain the illusion that it was. Unfortunately for many<br />

white men, their dependents did not always willingly follow the choreographed<br />

steps they had been assigned. Slaves ran away or rebelled and<br />

women refused to obey their fathers and husbands. As Brown convincingly<br />

contends, these failed performances persistently threatened self-serving<br />

definitions of white masculinity, thereby reinforcing Butler’s theory<br />

that gender — and one might add race — is little more than “an identity<br />

tenuously constituted in time, instituted in an exterior space through a<br />

stylized repetition of acts.” 10<br />

Other historians have developed this notion of exterior space to a<br />

greater extent. Walter Johnson’s Soul by Soul: Life Inside the Antebellum Slave<br />

Market is particularly useful for its in-depth analysis of performance’s public<br />

nature, both in its physical and philosophical sense. Presentations of<br />

masculinity, femininity, and dependency only become meaningful if they<br />

make sense to an audience. In examining the letters, narratives, advertisements,<br />

and other declarations of self that were generated or influenced<br />

by the antebellum slave market, Johnson succeeds in demonstrating that<br />

white slaveowners as well as the slaves themselves drew from a “cultural<br />

register of … roles” in an effort to make themselves make sense to others. 11<br />

In the public arena of the marketplace as well as the narrower public of<br />

correspondence, men and women defined their identities in reference to<br />

others. Traders’ manipulations of the bodies of their human cargo, buyers’<br />

public discussions on the finer points of purchase, and slaves’ attempts<br />

to guide the terms of their sales in a manner that would benefit themselves<br />

are all examples of self-performance, of people attempting to construct<br />

their identities in a meaningful way for an audience.<br />

Historians have long grappled with notions of public and private<br />

spheres, particularly inasmuch as they refer to gendered arenas of influence.<br />

For early practitioners of women’s history, the rhetoric of the<br />

“sphere” served as a convenient method for discussing American women’s<br />

historical roles. However, like the category of gender, the trope of separate<br />

spheres is not as well defined or binary as early historians presented<br />

it to be. 12 In 1966, Barbara Welter’s article on the “Cult of True Womanhood”<br />

identified men and manhood with the public, women and “true”<br />

womanhood with the private. 13 More recent works have moved beyond<br />

Little Women and Evil-Looking Men<br />

57


58<br />

this explicit dualism, recognizing that the boundaries between public and<br />

private are more often blurred than distinct. Bruce Dorsey’s ambitious<br />

work, Reforming Men and Women: Gender in the Antebellum City, for example,<br />

tackles the tenuous definitions of public versus private and masculinity<br />

and femininity among reform-minded men and women of Philadelphia.<br />

Like Johnson and Brown, Dorsey draws heavily from the philosopher Jürgen<br />

Habermas’s theory of the public sphere, rooting antebellum gender<br />

norms in the “uncertain gender milieu” of the eighteenth-century republican<br />

rhetoric of civic virtue. 14 In Dorsey’s account, Habermas’s public<br />

sphere was created “out of the private sphere of individual conscience,<br />

before ‘public’ and ‘private’ came to mean a rigid dichotomy between the<br />

political and economic realm of men and the domestic realm of women<br />

in the nineteenth century.” 15 Like the spheres themselves, the definitions<br />

of manhood and womanhood were not firmly delineated, and as a result<br />

gender “entailed a measure of performance.” 16 The division between<br />

public and private, manliness and femininity was not immutable, and it<br />

was possible — although discouraged — for men and women to traverse<br />

the boundary. Dorsey’s treatment of Quaker women’s access to the public<br />

sphere is especially enlightening, noting as he does that many, particularly<br />

single, Quaker women drew upon spiritual authority as well as “appropriating<br />

discourses that employed feminine, rather than masculine, imagery<br />

and language.” 17 As preachers and visionary prophetesses, these women<br />

made their way into the public realm; they traveled on the streets and<br />

entered the markets and prisons that were traditionally bastions of masculine<br />

political power. 18<br />

When Rebecca Spring wrote her memoir near the end of her long<br />

life, she was, in effect, performing a final act of self. In the often-rambling<br />

pages of “A Book of Remembrance” Spring writes more about the people<br />

who moved in and out of her life than she does about herself. A significant<br />

exception is the account of her visit to John Brown in 1859. Like<br />

the men and women in Johnson’s Soul by Soul, Spring’s identity is revealed<br />

through her observations and descriptions of others. Drawing upon her<br />

correspondence and autobiography, and paying particular attention to the<br />

John Brown episode, this study will examine the manner in which Spring<br />

manipulated, challenged, and supported the gender norms of her time in<br />

an effort to construct a meaningful identity for herself. At the same time,<br />

understanding her construction of self also leads to a greater understanding<br />

of the world she lived in and the cultural register of meaning available<br />

to her audience(s).<br />

Rebecca Spring was born in Providence, Rhode Island in 1811, the<br />

fourth daughter of devout Quakers. 19 Her father, Arnold Buffum, would<br />

become the first President of the New England Anti-Slavery Society; he<br />

heavily influenced the activist lives of all of his children, his daughters<br />

especially. As Spring’s older sister Elizabeth Buffum Chace recalled, their<br />

father had a “tender heart, and . . . unshrinking conscience,” and he em-<br />

SARAH BARKIN


aced “without doubt or question, the principles of the Garrisonian antislavery<br />

movement. . . . Thus was I born and baptized into the antislavery<br />

spirit. Our family were [sic] all Abolitionists.” 20<br />

Quakers also believed in educating both girls and boys, and Spring<br />

attended the New England Friends Boarding School with her sisters<br />

and, notably, a young woman who would become a radical abolitionist<br />

and feminist: Abby Kelley. 21 With her sisters and other young women,<br />

Spring participated in a literary society. As Elizabeth described it, the<br />

group was “called ‘The Female Mutual Improvement Society,’” and the<br />

members “agreed to meet one evening a week and read some useful<br />

book, and contribute original compositions of our own.” 22 Often the<br />

“useful” books centered around religious and political themes, encouraging<br />

the society’s members to think, from an early age, beyond the<br />

confines of the home.<br />

Academically minded, Spring proved an apt recipient for her<br />

father’s abiding interest in education. Arnold Buffum was particularly<br />

intrigued by the European educational reforms aimed toward factory<br />

children and he encouraged his daughters to teach in similar institutions.<br />

Spring taught at a coeducational school for mill children in Uxbridge,<br />

as well as the integrated and coeducational Philadelphia Colored<br />

Infant School after her father’s business interests took the family<br />

to Pennsylvania in 1834.<br />

On October 26, 1836, Rebecca Buffum married Marcus Spring, a<br />

wealthy philanthropist who shared her passion for social reform. Lillie<br />

Buffum Chace Wyman, Spring’s niece, remembered Marcus as a “handsome,<br />

lovable man, who had a decidedly artistic endowment.” 23 Their<br />

marriage was a loving, companionate partnership, and although Spring<br />

abandoned the simple dress of the Quakers in favor of the more expensive<br />

clothing her husband’s wealth afforded, they also put their money<br />

to good use by investing in a number of social, cultural, and political<br />

projects. One of their more noteworthy ventures was their investment<br />

in the North American Phalanx, a communitarian experiment based on<br />

the socialist principles of French philosopher and mathematician Charles<br />

Fourier. 24 Although they had never moved to the community, the Springs<br />

ultimately withdrew their financial support and in 1853 they, along with<br />

other Phalanx dissenters, formed their own settlement, The Raritan Bay<br />

Union, on Marcus’s Eagleswood estate in Perth Amboy, New Jersey. 25 Reflecting<br />

Spring’s interest in education, the centerpiece of the Union was<br />

its coeducational school, which claimed the honor of abolitionist Theodore<br />

Weld’s service as principal and Angelina Grimké Weld and her sister<br />

Sarah’s presence as faculty members. Although the Union lasted only a<br />

short time as a communitarian settlement, the school continued to function<br />

for several years, and it drew students from a number of notable<br />

families in New England. 26<br />

Little Women and Evil-Looking Men<br />

59


60<br />

Spring’s Quaker background instilled in her a strong belief in girls’<br />

right to equal education, and in her memoir she credits her father with supporting<br />

his daughters in their political pursuits as well: “[O]ur father was<br />

so fond and proud of his daughters that he thought them worthy to be citizens<br />

of the country they all loved.” 27 She was interested in women’s greater<br />

political equality, and like other Garrisonian abolitionists, she often linked<br />

women’s subjugation with the demeaning and tyrannical qualities of slavery:<br />

“Slavery in our Land of Liberty, was as inconsistent as taxing women,<br />

after declaring ‘Taxation without representation is tyranny.’” 28 Yet her support<br />

for equal rights was not as public in nature as her support for abolition<br />

and educational development, a fact her niece Lillie noted when she wrote,<br />

“Mrs. Spring made at least one speech in favor of woman’s rights, but she<br />

was never exactly a public worker in [woman’s] reform.” 29 Rather, Spring<br />

emphasized women’s important roles as mothers, which she saw as endowing<br />

them with certain obligations toward the rest of society. In this respect<br />

she was like other women in the 19th century who used their positions as<br />

women as justification for stepping into the public realm of reform.<br />

An example of Spring’s integration of motherhood and reform can<br />

be seen in the motion she and Abby Cox put forward at the first Anti-<br />

Slavery Convention for American Women held in New York City in 1837.<br />

The motion read:<br />

RESOLVED, that there is not a class of women to whom the<br />

anti-slavery cause makes so direct and powerful an appeal as<br />

to mothers; and that they are solemnly urged by all the blessings<br />

of their own and their children’s freedom, and by all the<br />

contrasted bitterness of the slave-mother’s condition, to lift up<br />

their hearts to God on behalf of the captive, as often as they<br />

pour them out over their own children in a joy with which ‘no<br />

stranger may intermeddle’; and that they are equally bound to<br />

guard with jealous care the minds of their children from the<br />

ruining influences of the spirit of pro-slavery and prejudice. 30<br />

Spring’s position in regards to women was complex. Like other<br />

Garrisonian abolitionists, she supported, albeit in a muted way, woman’s<br />

rights, yet she also agreed with the notion that one of slavery’s worst sins<br />

was the way in which it “stripped . . . slaves of their manhood and womanhood.”<br />

31 Motherhood was an essential element of True Womanhood; in<br />

separating slave mothers from their children, using them as “breeders,” or<br />

forcing them to work during pregnancy at dangerous risk to the child they<br />

carried, slaveowners — in the abolitionist view — proved themselves enemies<br />

of moral social order. Furthermore, Spring’s support for this motion<br />

indicates her belief that mothers were somehow more attuned to slave<br />

women’s suffering and were therefore in a prime position to act. Indeed<br />

they were obligated to educate their children in the evils of the slave system<br />

and protect them from learning to be prejudiced.<br />

Although Spring’s motion at the anti-slavery convention was unanimously<br />

endorsed, her support and promotion of motherhood was not always<br />

greeted by her friends and acquaintances with as much enthusiasm.<br />

SARAH BARKIN


Her close friend, the Transcendentalist writer Margaret Fuller, teased her<br />

about a letter Spring had written regarding Fuller’s little boy: “Your letter,<br />

my dear Rebecca, was written in your noblest and most womanly spirit.<br />

Thank you for your sympathy about my little boy.” She went on to say,<br />

“Yet in answer to what you say, that it is still better to give the world this<br />

living soul than a part of my life in a book; it is true; and yet of my book I<br />

could know whether it would be of any worth or not, of my child I must<br />

wait to see what his worth will be.” 32 While Fuller loved her son dearly, her<br />

view of motherhood was not as ecstatic as Spring’s; it was tempered by a<br />

wariness that was at odds with Spring’s “womanly spirit.” Unlike Spring,<br />

Fuller did not see motherhood as trumping her career as a writer. If<br />

anything, her written works provided her with a greater sense of security<br />

than parenthood did.<br />

It was partly in the name of motherhood that Spring made the journey<br />

to John Brown’s prison cell in 1859. On hearing that her friend, the<br />

abolitionist Lydia Maria Child, had written to Governor Wise for permission<br />

to attend the prisoner, Spring resolved to accompany her. Although<br />

her husband was initially reluctant to let her go, she responded by saying,<br />

“We have talked against slavery all these years, now somebody has done<br />

something. These men have risked their lives: I must go.” 33 Still averse to<br />

the notion, Marcus returned to his job in the city, but he later sent her a<br />

note stating he thought it was a pity Spring did not accompany Child on<br />

her mission. As Spring recalled in her autobiography: “Taking this for<br />

consent, before Mr. Spring returned home, my young son and I were on<br />

our way South.” 34 Not everyone believed that Marcus’s consent was necessary.<br />

Lillie Wyman wrote, “I am inclined to believe that she really acted<br />

independently of him. I was told at the time that she did not have to consult<br />

him because he chanced to be from home on that important day.” 35<br />

Nevertheless, by including this consultation, real or otherwise, into her<br />

narrative, Spring at least paid lip service to the gender mores of the time.<br />

She may have felt that her visit would be more palatable to her intended<br />

audience if they knew it was sanctioned by a male authority figure. 36<br />

Spring’s son Eddie was nineteen years old when he accompanied his<br />

mother to Virginia, but her emphasis on his presence is telling for a couple<br />

of reasons. First, his company underscored her role as a mother, thus<br />

reinforcing her maternal position and justifying her transgression into the<br />

public sphere. Second, as a grown man, Eddie could effectively serve as a<br />

male chaperone, both providing his mother with physical protection and<br />

reassuring those who might be worried that despite appearances, she was<br />

still under a man’s control.<br />

On reaching Virginia, Spring discovered that Lydia Maria Child had<br />

in fact not gained permission to visit, leaving the Springs to find their<br />

own way. It was not an easy one. Violence was an ever-present threat, but<br />

Spring persevered nonetheless. When asked why she had come, she re-<br />

Little Women and Evil-Looking Men<br />

61


62<br />

called answering: “[W]hen men fight and hurt each other, women should<br />

go and take care of them.” 37 This statement reveals much about her<br />

worldview; for Spring, men were destructive, and it was a woman’s obligation<br />

to nurse them back to health. Such reasoning reinforced nineteenthcentury<br />

definitions of gender, even though she was ultimately performing<br />

a subversive and political act. She did not travel to Virginia to minister to<br />

just anyone, but rather she sought to care for an extremely controversial<br />

political figure: a man who had attacked a United <strong>State</strong>s armory in a raid<br />

that had resulted in the deaths of several people. 38<br />

Spring may have been conscious of her precarious position and thus<br />

repeatedly highlighted the “feminine” aspects of her trip. For instance,<br />

she brought leaves to decorate Brown’s cell, she brought him a fresh pillowcase,<br />

sent bandages for his wounds, and, perhaps most revealing, she<br />

brought along her worsted and began to knit while they spoke, for which<br />

Brown “looked gratified.” 39 In recounting these actions, Spring may have<br />

hoped to call attention to the stereotypically constructive “nature” of<br />

women and deflect interest away from those actions that threatened the<br />

status quo. Even when she asked Brown to relate his motives for the attack<br />

she assured him — and the southerners surrounding the prison — that<br />

she was merely a vessel to convey information: “‘I want to ask you one<br />

question,’ said I, ‘not for myself, but for others.’” 40 As a woman, she had<br />

no interest — indeed what interest could she have in such matters? — in<br />

his answers, but as a messenger, it was a necessity that she ask.<br />

Spring’s observations of Brown also provide insight into her views<br />

on masculinity and violence. As a Quaker, she did not, at least outwardly,<br />

condone his violent actions, and yet, neither did she rebuke him for them.<br />

Rather, she sought to understand why he had undertaken such harsh measures.<br />

After ascertaining that he did not attack the Ferry for personal revenge,<br />

Spring avoided discussing his violent actions altogether. Instead,<br />

she described John Brown with language filled with religious imagery. For<br />

instance, on gaining entrance to the prison a second time, she depicted the<br />

change in Brown’s appearance:<br />

Captain Brown on our second visit, was sitting at a table writing.<br />

He looked well, his hair, washed and brushed, was thrown<br />

up from his forehead; it was soft and white and looked like<br />

a halo about his head. His high white forehead had a glory<br />

about it as he stood looking like an inspired old prophet. 41<br />

In describing him in such a way, Spring implied that there was something<br />

holy, even Biblical in his person. In her mind, the violence of his<br />

mission had an element of Old Testament justice about it. There may<br />

even have been a hint of millenarian hope in her depiction of him as<br />

a prophet, as if his deeds foretold the Second Coming of Christ as well<br />

as the end of slavery. 42 In a letter to Andrew Hunter, the prosecuting attorney<br />

in the cases against several of Brown’s fellow conspirators, Spring<br />

described the spiritual element of Brown’s mission:<br />

SARAH BARKIN


When I entered the prison I expected to see a rough, hard<br />

man, but I found instead the most beautiful Christian graces.<br />

I had asked to be allowed to enter, hoping to bring some holy<br />

light into the valley of the shadow of death, through which<br />

Mr. Brown must shortly pass, -And, behold—the glory of<br />

the Lord shone round about him—and my feeling of pity<br />

changed to veneration. 43<br />

Spring had expected her mission to be one of mercy; she thought<br />

she would be bringing the light of religion to John Brown. In this passage,<br />

however, she indicated that Brown not only did not need her pity, he<br />

deserved her “veneration.” In subsuming her potentially volatile mission<br />

of feminine mercy to the “greater” masculine power of Brown’s religious<br />

strength of purpose, Spring reassured her audience that she knew her<br />

place in the gender hierarchy, and indeed, she depicted that hierarchy as<br />

handed down by God. Furthermore, when Spring imbued Brown with religious<br />

authority she also argued that in his raid against the armory, Brown<br />

merely acted on faith, serving as a martyr for a just cause: “For twenty<br />

years he had believed that he had a divine call to free the slaves; he had<br />

tried, and failed, and the slave power seemed stronger than ever; his little<br />

band of earnest young men were scattered, dead, or in prison, himself<br />

condemned to die on the scaffold, but his faith never left him.” 44<br />

The tacit acceptance of Brown’s violent raid may have raised him to<br />

the level of true manhood in her eyes, but such respect did not extend to<br />

the “evil-looking” southern men surrounding the prison. Brown attacked<br />

armed men at an arsenal in an effort to end what many believed, and<br />

rightfully so, to be the unjust and tyrannical system of slavery. But the<br />

southern men’s violence had no aura of holy calling or virtuous patriotism.<br />

Rather, these men were unmanly in that they took joy in attacking<br />

the defenseless. Not only did they treat slaves brutally, but their behavior<br />

at the prison indicated that they would be willing to commit violent acts<br />

against a “little woman” and a “boy.” They were only able to show their<br />

strength when the odds were in their favor. 45 Spring was outraged when<br />

she discovered that a group of southern men had shot and killed one<br />

of the wounded raiders while he was being treated for his wounds. Her<br />

indignation caused her to leap out of her chair and confront the group<br />

discussing the event: “Who killed him? How cowardly to kill a wounded<br />

man.” 46 In Spring’s eyes, such violence was not only unjustified, it was<br />

a sign of unmanliness, of weakness. True men would not have killed a<br />

wounded prisoner.<br />

Although Spring avoided explicitly mentioning Brown’s violence in<br />

contrast to her emphasis on southern brutality, it nevertheless held true for<br />

her that destructiveness was an inherently male quality. Recall her answer<br />

to the man who questioned her presence: “When men fight and hurt each<br />

other, women should go take care of them.” 47 In Spring’s worldview, when<br />

men sought to destroy life, women were obligated to nurture it, even if<br />

they had to step into the public sphere to do so.<br />

Little Women and Evil-Looking Men<br />

63


64<br />

Spring’s efforts were not limited to the leader of the Harpers Ferry<br />

raid. As Lucretia Mott noted in a letter to her niece Anna Temple Brown,<br />

“I have intended to write direct to Reba. Spring . . . She deserves credit<br />

for remembg. [sic] all the poor prisoners, with such generous exertions.” 48<br />

In particular, Aaron Dwight Stevens became one of the main recipients of<br />

those “generous exertions.” In her correspondence with Stevens, Spring’s<br />

emphasis on motherhood and women’s nurturance took a more extreme<br />

form. She first met Stevens during her visit to John Brown. Aaron was a<br />

young man — he was twenty-nine years old at the time of his execution<br />

in March 1860 — and Spring’s empathy toward him was evident in every<br />

account she provided of his character. In “A Book of Remembrance,”<br />

she described Stevens as “an old crusader in spirit, and yet he was loving<br />

and gentle as a child. He was only dangerous to wrong and oppression.” 49<br />

She determined that the early loss of his mother “when he was quite a<br />

child made him a wanderer in his early life.” 50 Without female influence,<br />

Stevens — in Spring’s estimation — was driven to the overtly dangerous<br />

and rootless life he had led and as a result he faced a similarly violent<br />

death by execution. Throughout her memoir, she emphasized his gentleness,<br />

pointing out his “love of God, of nature, and of good people,” and<br />

his “manly” courage in the face of death. 51 Perhaps most important in<br />

Spring’s mind was Stevens’s appreciation for “true” womanhood. In “A<br />

Book of Remembrance” she reprinted one of his letters to her in which<br />

he stated: “There is no greater joy on earth for me than to see a noble<br />

woman, for in her I see more of God than in anything else.” 52 Once again<br />

“woman” appeared as the spiritual superior, reinforcing nineteenth-century<br />

notions of female morality.<br />

Spring attempted to remedy Stevens’s motherless situation by standing<br />

in as a surrogate in his time of need. She went so far as to address<br />

one of her letters to him as “My dear little boy.” 53 For his part, Stevens<br />

returned the sentiment, “And now my dear Mother, what shall I say? . .<br />

. As you have been a mother, sister, and all to me in this hour of need,<br />

say a few kind words to my father and sister.” He then closed the letter,<br />

“Your son in the bonds of love, truth, friendship and righteousness.” 54 In<br />

their communications with one another, Stevens and Spring enacted the<br />

roles of kinship. Their performances were not only gendered, they were<br />

subversive as well. Unlike gender, kinship was supposed to be immutable;<br />

it was determined by “blood.” In demonstrating that kinship, too, could<br />

be performed, the blurred boundaries of gender as a social construction<br />

appeared even more tenuous in contrast. When Spring emphasized her<br />

maternal nature by bringing her son Eddie with her to the prison, her actions<br />

underscored her position as an actual mother. On the other hand, her<br />

maternal performance with Stevens exposed the fragility of social family<br />

and gender norms; she expanded the notion of motherhood to include<br />

those not related by blood and subsequently used that expanded role to<br />

intercede on Stevens’s behalf. 55<br />

SARAH BARKIN


Though Spring failed to save Stevens from the scaffold, she carried<br />

out one last act of defiance in support of the Harpers Ferry band.<br />

Spring acknowledged the male, destructive power of the state to execute<br />

Stevens for his participation in Brown’s transgression on southern masculinity,<br />

but as his surrogate mother she arranged to reclaim his body<br />

and have him buried at her husband’s Eagleswood estate in “the land of<br />

the free.” Spring’s final endeavor essentially appropriated southern state<br />

power and transformed it in a bold act of both kinship and gender performance.<br />

56 In burying Stevens and Absalom Haslett — another conspirator<br />

— in the North, Spring denied the southerners their complete<br />

revenge; their hope that the executions of the Harpers Ferry crew would<br />

restore their defamed masculinity and honor was only partially — one<br />

might say impotently — satisfied. Moreover, in her mind this recalcitrant<br />

act derived from her view of southern manhood as emasculated;<br />

she believed them to be cowards who preyed violently on the weak, thus<br />

they did not deserve her respect.<br />

A close reading of Spring’s memoir and correspondence reveals the<br />

extent to which gendered mores were understood, challenged, and manipulated<br />

in antebellum America. The cultural register that Spring lived<br />

with and used on a daily basis gave “A Book of Remembrance” its meaning<br />

as a performance of self. Spring justified her radical political actions<br />

with gendered rhetoric emphasizing motherhood, physical frailty (on her<br />

part), and domestic duty. She understood the political implications of her<br />

actions, as well as the threat such deeds might pose to the status quo. In<br />

visiting and supporting John Brown, she definitively stated her alliance<br />

with the anti-slavery political activists in a public arena. The prison was<br />

public not only because it was accessible, but also because it served as<br />

a symbolic representation of the state’s power and masculinity. Spring<br />

recognized the larger political implications of Brown’s — and by implication<br />

her — actions. As she wrote: “The truth is that the raid at Harper’s<br />

ferry [sic] was the beginning of the Civil War, and the Proclamation of<br />

Emancipation finished John Brown’s work.” 57 Thus she also understood<br />

the need to make her part in such actions palatable to her audience.<br />

Spring’s visit to Brown’s prison cell and her correspondence with and<br />

burial of Aaron Stevens had a larger impact as well, perhaps not in an<br />

earthly context but in a more unworldly sense. In a letter to Spring, Lydia<br />

Maria Child remarked on the spiritual effects of Spring’s actions: “It must<br />

always be a source of pleasant recollection to you that you have had the<br />

ability and the will to do so much to console John Brown, and his unfortunate<br />

family and companions. Such deeds become flowers in gardens of<br />

the eternal world.” 58 Like Spring, Child reinforced the notion of woman<br />

as nurturer, as a gardener of ethereal blossoms whose beauty, if not appreciated<br />

in the immediate and secular sense, would come into their own<br />

in the more enduring afterlife.<br />

Little Women and Evil-Looking Men<br />

65


66<br />

As a “little woman” in a world of angry men, Spring carefully negotiated<br />

her way through the “gray area” in which the gendered public and<br />

private spheres overlapped, using and manipulating long-held notions of<br />

femininity to disguise the public and political nature of her actions. In<br />

doing so she exposed the fragile nature of socially constructed roles, sometimes<br />

surprising herself with the audacity of her deeds. In the actions of<br />

this one individual, modern historians are confronted with a compelling<br />

example of the means by which women of the antebellum period transformed<br />

the domestic into the political, the allegedly powerless into the<br />

powerful. And Spring’s audience recognized the dangerous implications<br />

— both physical and intellectual — of her actions. Writing in the early<br />

years of the twentieth century, Lillie Buffum Chace Wyman remarked on<br />

the bravery her aunt displayed in journeying to Brown’s prison cell: “It is<br />

hard now to realize that it was a greatly heroic thing for a woman and a<br />

boy to do . . . but great and heroic it was for Rebecca Buffum Spring and<br />

her lad to go on that errand in the early November of 1859.” 59<br />

SARAH BARKIN


Little Women and Evil-Looking Men<br />

NOTES<br />

1 Rebecca Buffum Spring, “A Book of Remembrance,” Rebecca Spring Papers,<br />

M0541, Department of Special Collections, Stanford <strong>University</strong> Libraries, Stanford, CA: 120.<br />

2 Ibid, 124.<br />

3 Rebecca Buffum Spring, “A Visit to John Brown in 1859,” in Virtuous Lives: Four Quaker<br />

Sisters Remember Family Life, Abolitionism, and Women’s Suffrage, ed. Lucille Salitan and Eve Lewis<br />

Perera (New York: Continuum, 1994), 122-23.<br />

4 In one case in particular, Spring found herself using her religious beliefs as a defense<br />

for her anti-slavery stance. In “A Book of Remembrance” Spring described an altercation on a<br />

steamboat outside of St. Louis, in which she identified herself as an abolitionist to a group of<br />

southern slave owners. After taking refuge in her cabin, she managed to assuage their anger —<br />

and violent intentions — by declaring that abolitionist sentiments were a necessary component<br />

to her Quaker religious beliefs adding the astute observation that “People will tolerate a good<br />

deal of diversity in religious belief.” See Spring, “A Book of Remembrance,” 15-17.<br />

5 Kristin Hoganson, “Garrisonian Abolitionists and the Rhetoric of Gender, 1850-<br />

1860,” American Quarterly 45, no. 4 (Dec. 1993): 558-95.<br />

6 Marie Marmo Mullaney appears intent on proving that Spring was a feminist, no<br />

matter how subtly she expressed it. While most of Mullaney’s arguments are most convincing<br />

when she discusses the contrast between Spring’s conventional femininity and reform interests,<br />

in the end she emphasizes the “feminist” element in Spring’s reform career. See Marie Marmo<br />

Mullaney, “Feminism, Utopianism, and Domesticity: The Career of Rebecca Buffum Spring,<br />

1811-1911,” New Jersey History 104, nos. 3-4 (1989): 1-21. Amy Swerdlow, on the other hand,<br />

underscores Spring’s conservatism. Swerdlow points to a resolution Spring put forward at the<br />

first Anti-Slavery Convention for American Women in 1837, which linked the abolitionist<br />

movement to women’s “traditional” roles as mothers. Like Mullaney, Swerdlow seems intent on<br />

pigeonholing Spring rather than admitting and analyzing her complexity. See Amy Swerdlow,<br />

“Abolition’s Conservative Sisters: The Ladies’ New York City Anti-Slavery Societies, 1834-<br />

1840,” in The Abolitionist Sisterhood: Women’s Political Culture in Antebellum America, ed. Jean Fagan<br />

Yellin and John C. Van Horne (Ithaca, NY: Cornell <strong>University</strong> Press), 31-44.<br />

7 Erving Goffman defines “performance” as “all the activity of an individual which<br />

occurs during a period marked by his continuous presence before a particular set of observers<br />

and which has some influence on the observers.” See Erving Goffman, The Presentation of Self<br />

in Everyday Life (1959; New York: Doubleday, 1972), 22; Kath Weston discusses the ways in<br />

which people — particularly gay men and lesbians — construct their identities in a world<br />

determined to classify them in one category (man) or another (woman). According to Weston,<br />

even identifying someone/oneself as gay or lesbian imposes “a ‘Western’ classification in which<br />

sexual behaviors and desires are understood thoroughly to infuse a self.” See Kath Weston, Long,<br />

Slow Burn: Sexuality and Social Science (New York: Routledge, 1998), 33; and Gender Me, Render Me:<br />

Lesbians Talk Sex, Class, Color, Nations, Studmuffins (New York: Columbia <strong>University</strong> Press, 1996).<br />

8 Judith Butler, Gender Trouble: Feminism and the Subversion of Identity, 10th anniversary<br />

ed. (1990; New York: Routledge, 1999). See especially chapter four in Part Three: “Bodily<br />

Inscriptions, Performative Subversions,” 163-80.<br />

9 Kathleen Brown, Good Wives, Nasty Wenches, and Anxious Patriarchs: Gender, Race, and<br />

Power in Colonial Virginia (Chapel Hill: <strong>University</strong> of North Carolina Press, 1996), 372. It is<br />

ironic that the patriarchs were the true dependents, basing their identities on those who were<br />

considered their social and racial inferiors.<br />

10 Butler, Gender Trouble, 179. Butler’s emphasis.<br />

11 Walter Johnson, Soul by Soul: Life Inside the Antebellum Slave Market (Cambridge, MA:<br />

Harvard <strong>University</strong> Press, 1999), 13.<br />

12 Linda Kerber, “Separate Spheres, Female Worlds, Woman’s Place: The Rhetoric of<br />

Woman’s History,” Journal of American History 75 (June 1988): 9-39. Kerber emphasizes the<br />

need to move beyond the constraints of dualistic rhetoric in favor of a more complex and<br />

reciprocal language of gendered interaction. Paula Baker notes that women’s arguments for<br />

political participation in the antebellum years used their roles and concerns in the private realm<br />

to justify their cross over into the public world of politics. See Paula Baker, “The Domestication<br />

of Politics: Women and American Political Society, 1780-1920,” American Historical Review 89<br />

(June 1984): 620-47.<br />

13 Barbara Welter, “The Cult of True Womanhood: 1820-1860,” American Quarterly18<br />

(Summer 1966): 151-74.<br />

67


68<br />

14<br />

Bruce Dorsey, Reforming Men and Women: Gender in the Antebellum City (Ithaca, NY:<br />

Cornell <strong>University</strong> Press, 2002), 13.<br />

15<br />

Ibid.<br />

16<br />

Ibid., 15.<br />

17<br />

Ibid, 39.<br />

18<br />

Ibid, 40-41. According to Habermas’s definition of the public sphere, prisons were<br />

public not only because they were accessible (mainly to men) but also because they were often<br />

run by state governments and as such were representations, in a physical sense, of the state’s<br />

political power. See Jürgen Habermas, The Structural Transformation of the Public Sphere: An Inquiry<br />

into a Category of Bourgeois Society, trans. Thomas Burger with Frederick Lawrence (Cambridge,<br />

MA: MIT Press, 1989).<br />

19<br />

Unless otherwise stated, the biographical information is drawn from two of Marie<br />

Marmo Mullaney’s essays on Rebecca Spring. See “Rebecca Buffum Spring, 1811-1911,” in<br />

Past and Promise: Lives of New Jersey Women, ed. The Woman’s Project of New Jersey (Metuchen,<br />

NJ: Scarecrow Press, 1990), 84-86; “Feminism, Utopianism, and Domesticity,” (see note 6).<br />

20<br />

Elizabeth Buffum Chace, “My Anti-Slavery Reminiscences,” in Virtuous Lives (see note<br />

4), 95.<br />

21<br />

Dorothy Sterling, Ahead of Her Time: Abby Kelley and the Politics of Antislavery (New York:<br />

W. W. Norton, 1991), 83, 264.<br />

22<br />

Elizabeth Buffum Chace, “Reminiscences of Childhood,” in Virtuous Lives, 36.<br />

23<br />

Lillie Buffum Chace Wyman, American Chivalry (Boston: W. B. Clarke, 1913), 51.<br />

24<br />

George Kirchmann, “Unsettled Utopias: The North American Phalanx and The<br />

Raritan Bay Union,” New Jersey History 97 (Spring 1979), 25-36.<br />

25<br />

There are a number of different accounts relating to the Springs’ involvement in<br />

the Phalanx’s dissolution. A couple of historians point to Rebecca’s insistence on mandatory<br />

religious meetings as one of the primary points of contention. Marie Mullaney argues that<br />

Rebecca mistook the religious pluralism that dominated the Phalanx for irreligion. George<br />

Kirchmann tends to place the blame more squarely on Marcus’s financial influence, but he also<br />

argues that the Springs created “great bitterness and discomfort” when they lobbied for a fixed<br />

liturgy at the Phalanx. See Mullaney,” Rebecca Buffum Spring,” 85; Kirchmann, “Unsettled<br />

Utopias,” 32.<br />

26<br />

Jayme Sokolow, “Culture and Utopia: The Raritan Bay Union.” New Jersey History 94<br />

(Summer-Autumn 1976): 89-100.<br />

27<br />

Spring, “Book of Remembrance,” 88.<br />

28<br />

Ibid., 106-107. It is interesting to note that this is the very excuse Abby Kelley used as<br />

justification for not paying taxes on the farm she and her husband Stephen Foster jointly owned.<br />

Unfortunately, the government did not agree and put their farm up for auction several times.<br />

In 1880, Abby and her husband finally abandoned the protest and paid their tax bill, declaring<br />

that Stephen’s health was too poor to continue. See Sterling, Ahead of Her Time, 367-73.<br />

29<br />

Wyman, American Chivalry, 59<br />

30<br />

Turning the World Upside Down: The Anti-Slavery Convention of American Women Held in New<br />

York City, May 9-12, 1837, 1st ed. with an introduction by Dorothy Sterling (New York: Feminist<br />

Press at the City <strong>University</strong> of New York, 1987), 17. Italics not mine.<br />

31<br />

Hoganson, “Garrisonian Rhetoric,” 575.<br />

32<br />

Margaret Fuller to Marcus and Rebecca Spring, 12 December 1849. In Robert<br />

Hudspeth, ed., The Letters of Margaret Fuller, vol. 5 (Ithaca, NY: Cornell <strong>University</strong> Press, 1983),<br />

294-97.<br />

33<br />

Spring, “Book of Remembrance,” 109-10.<br />

34<br />

Ibid., 110.<br />

35<br />

Wyman, 59.<br />

36<br />

In emphasizing the fact that she obtained his permission through a letter rather than<br />

in person, Rebecca accomplished two goals. She protected herself and her mission with a veil<br />

of male approval, and she protected her husband from carrying too much of the blame should<br />

her actions offend. Thus, Rebecca nominally respected the gender hierarchies of her time,<br />

while she simultaneously subverted them.<br />

37<br />

Spring, 110-11.<br />

38<br />

The Harpers Ferry Armory and Arsenal was established by George Washington<br />

in 1794. Thus it was a symbol of a new nation’s victory and might. In the minds of some<br />

Southerners (and Northerners), John Brown’s assault against such an icon may have represented<br />

an attack against the very core of American democracy. Brown’s attack on Harpers Ferry can<br />

be read in multiple ways. On the one hand he hoped to arm slaves for rebellion against tyranny,<br />

thus echoing revolutionary rhetoric of male virtue. On the other hand, he was defacing<br />

SARAH BARKIN


Southern manhood, symbolically appropriating it not only for himself and his Northern cause,<br />

but also for enslaved — and thus emasculated — black men. For Southerners such an act struck<br />

at the very core of their being. For a more in-depth discussion of American Revolutionary<br />

masculinity and the role it played in the intergenerational battle for male identify, see Dorsey,<br />

Reforming Men and Women.<br />

39<br />

Spring, 120-21.<br />

40<br />

Ibid., 122.<br />

41<br />

Ibid., 125.<br />

42<br />

Robert Abzug discusses in fascinating detail the different cosmological explanations<br />

that motivated antebellum reformers in his work Cosmos Crumbling: American Reform and the<br />

Religious Imagination (New York: Oxford <strong>University</strong> Press, 1994).<br />

43<br />

Rebecca Buffum Spring to Andrew Hunter, 2 January 1860. Reprinted in Spring, “A<br />

Book of Remembrance,” 137.<br />

44<br />

Ibid., 126. Such language also brings to mind Christ’s suffering before his crucifixion.<br />

45<br />

Kristin Hoganson provides an excellent analysis of Garrisonian rhetoric regarding<br />

Southern honor and brutality. See Hoganson, “Garrisonian Rhetoric,” 582-583.<br />

46<br />

Spring, 112.<br />

47<br />

Spring, 110-11.<br />

48<br />

Lucretia Coffin Mott to Anna Temple Brown, 2 January, 1860. In Selected Letters of<br />

Lucretia Coffin Mott, ed. Beverly Wilson Palmer (Chicago: <strong>University</strong> of Illinois Press, 2002), 292.<br />

49<br />

Spring, “A Book of Remembrance,” 164-65. The biographical information is drawn<br />

from “A Book of Remembrance,” 165-75.<br />

50<br />

Spring, 167.<br />

51<br />

Ibid., 166, 169.<br />

52<br />

Aaron Dwight Stevens to Rebecca Buffum Spring, 18 March 1860, Reprinted in<br />

Spring, “A Book of Remembrance,” 162.<br />

53<br />

Rebecca Buffum Spring to Aaron D. Stevens, 13 February 1860. Rebecca Spring Papers,<br />

M0541, Department of Special Collections, Stanford <strong>University</strong> Libraries, Stanford, CA.<br />

54<br />

Aaron D. Stevens to Rebecca Buffum Spring, 13 March 1860. Reprinted in Spring,<br />

“A Book of Remembrance,” 147.<br />

55<br />

In Antigone’s Claim: Kinship Between Life and Death, Judith Butler argues that Antigone’s<br />

act of kinship — burying her brother in defiance of the King’s laws — serves as a “trespass on<br />

the norms of kinship and gender that exposes the precarious character of those norms, their<br />

sudden and disturbing transferability, and their capacity to be reiterated in contexts and in ways<br />

that are not fully to be anticipated.” Rebecca’s performance of kinship can be read in a similar<br />

fashion. See Judith Butler, Antigone’s Claim: Kinship Between Life and Death (New York: Columbia<br />

<strong>University</strong> Press, 2000), 24.<br />

56<br />

Spring’s burial of Stevens and Absalom Haslett, another of the Harpers Ferry crew,<br />

was remarkably similar to Antigone’s defiant burial of her brother. As Butler contends: “Antigone<br />

comes, then, to act in ways that are called manly not only because she acts in defiance of the<br />

law but also because she assumes the voice of the law in committing the act against the law. . . .<br />

Her agency emerges precisely through her refusal to honor his [King Creone’s] command, and<br />

yet the language of refusal assimilates the very terms of sovereignty that she refuses. . . . [S]he<br />

asserts herself through appropriating the voice of the other, the one to whom she is opposed;<br />

thus her autonomy is gained through the appropriation of the authoritative voice of the one<br />

she resists. See Butler, Antigone’s Claim, 11.<br />

57<br />

Spring, 126.<br />

58<br />

Lydia Maria Child to Rebecca Buffum Spring, 19 March 1860, Rebecca Spring<br />

Papers.<br />

59<br />

Wyman, American Chivalry, 60.<br />

Little Women and Evil-Looking Men<br />

69


from Bush-League Hamlet<br />

TO M A J O R - L E AG U E M E T RO P O L I S :<br />

L O S A N G E L E S , T H E D O D G E R S<br />

A N D P R O P O S I T I O N B<br />

S\<br />

M I C H A E L Mott


72<br />

eex<br />

post<br />

efacto


he post-World War II period brought unprecedented and unparalleled<br />

urban growth to Southern California. As a result of a revitalized<br />

economy and the expansion of a vast military-industrial complex, a population<br />

boom stretched the geographic contours of the region, creating<br />

a vast multi-centered metropolis encompassing Ventura County to the<br />

north, <strong>San</strong> Bernardino to the east, and Orange County and <strong>San</strong> Diego<br />

to the south. For the city and county of Los Angeles, as for other regions<br />

of the Far West, this expansive decentralization was not necessarily a new<br />

experience. As Robert Fogelson demonstrates, from its experience as a<br />

Mexican pueblo through the ravages of the Great Depression, the history<br />

of the Los Angeles region encompasses both the emergence of a “populous,<br />

urbanized, and industrialized settlement” and the “rejection of the<br />

metropolis in favor of its suburbs.” Nevertheless, the postwar transformation<br />

solidified the dual processes of expansion and decentralization in<br />

galactic proportions. 1<br />

T<br />

Accompanying this flow of people and economic growth westward<br />

across the nation, the game of baseball was also experiencing an exceptional<br />

geographic transformation. At the end of World War II, the westernmost<br />

major league city was St. Louis, a territorial boundary in place<br />

since the early 1890s. However, with the combination of a postwar boom<br />

in spectator sports and the successes of such minor league teams as the<br />

Pacific Coast League’s Los Angeles Angels, Oakland Oaks, <strong>San</strong> <strong>Francisco</strong><br />

Seals, and <strong>San</strong> Diego Padres, the west coast appeared certain to play a<br />

significant role in any future reconsideration of the major league baseball<br />

map. Moreover, the successful transitions of the Boston Braves to<br />

Milwaukee in 1953 and the Philadelphia Athletics to Kansas City in1955<br />

forced the organized baseball establishment to reconsider the pastime’s<br />

limited geographic scope. 2<br />

73


74<br />

By 1958, both <strong>San</strong> <strong>Francisco</strong> and Los Angeles would play host to<br />

the “national game” as well. However, unlike the comparably smooth<br />

move of the Giants, Los Angeles’ procurement of Walter O’Malley’s<br />

Brooklyn Dodgers initiated a complex interplay involving the city’s<br />

citizenry and politicians in a hotly contested battle over a plot of land<br />

called Chavez Ravine, home to a small but intimate community of<br />

Mexican Americans. After almost a decade of political infighting to define<br />

the proper use of this land, ranging from proposals for public housing<br />

to anticommunist backlashes squashing such purposes, Los Angeles<br />

Mayor Norris Poulson met with Dodger President Walter O’Malley in<br />

1957 to offer a stadium site at the same time that O’Malley was failing<br />

in his own attempts to negotiate a new ballpark with the city of<br />

New York. On October 7, 1957, the city council approved a resolution<br />

calling for the transfer of Chavez Ravine to O’Malley and his Dodger<br />

organization. In an attempt to block this reassignment of more than<br />

300 acres of public land, citizens, as well as local and regional businesspersons,<br />

placed the issue on the ballot in the form of Proposition<br />

B, a referendum to be held on June 3, 1958. Only after voter approval<br />

of the measure and the resolution of subsequent logistical and legal<br />

hurdles, would O’Malley and his Dodgers be able to build their new<br />

home, Dodger Stadium. 3<br />

The present examination attempts to place this “Battle for Chavez<br />

Ravine” within the political, social, and economic context of postwar<br />

Los Angeles. More specifically, by calling into question the contract<br />

between Walter O’Malley’s Dodgers and the City of Los Angeles,<br />

Proposition B reveals the contestation and anxiety over a fragmented<br />

urban landscape. On one side, the proponents of the “Yes on Prop. B”<br />

campaign sought to define a coherent centralized metropolis through<br />

the integration of a disorderly cityscape. They believed the appropriation<br />

of Chavez Ravine for a privately funded baseball stadium would<br />

unify Los Angeles, politically, socially, and economically, allowing the<br />

city to emerge as “major league” in relation to its eastern counterparts.<br />

Refuting the “giveaway” of public property for an explicitly private<br />

purpose, the opponents of the contract with O’Malley’s club advocated<br />

a pattern of urban land use reinforcing the existing balance between<br />

core and periphery. As such, they believed any use of Chavez Ravine,<br />

whether for baseball or other municipal purposes, should lie within<br />

public control for the benefit of both the outlying districts as much as<br />

the downtown center. Thus, the referendum issue evokes many of the<br />

concepts integral to the discipline of urban history, specifically the effects<br />

of popular culture and politics on the struggle for spatial meaning.<br />

More than a reflection of support for their local government’s attempts<br />

at bringing baseball to Los Angeles, the debates by citizens, politicians,<br />

and baseball executives provide a site from which one can examine a<br />

dialogue of the city-building process.<br />

MICHAEL MOTT


In the past thirty years, scholars have approached the “Battle for<br />

Chavez Ravine” and the Dodger referendum issue from a variety of perspectives.<br />

A number of writers have stressed the positive benefits and<br />

negative repercussions associated with the westward move of Walter<br />

O’Malley’s Dodgers. Lee Elihu Lowenfish’s “A Tale of Many Cities,”<br />

examines the Dodger’s move to Los Angeles within a larger context of<br />

the postwar expansion of major league baseball. In doing so, Lowenfish<br />

identifies the effects of this franchise movement on the receiving communities.For<br />

Lowenfish, O’Malley’s rationale behind westward expansion<br />

“showed little intrinsic relationship to the needs or desires of the<br />

would-be new home towns,” except if they constituted opportunities for<br />

profit-making ventures. 4 The relocation of the Dodgers, therefore, involved<br />

little more than the management of narrow self-interest of the<br />

business elite against the greater public interest. Portraying Proposition B<br />

as a “clash of the temporary interests of rich and poor,” he conceptualizes<br />

the issue as a struggle between moneyed interests and community<br />

loyalties. 5 Oftentimes allowing his biases to direct his historical analysis,<br />

Lowenfish identifies these self-serving motivations as providing a negative<br />

model for future franchise relocation.<br />

At the opposite spectrum, Cary Henderson and Neil Sullivan argue<br />

for the positive ramifications associated with the Dodger deal. In his<br />

“Los Angeles and the Dodger War, 1957-1962,” Henderson explores how<br />

baseball as big business served as a source of civic pride and personal<br />

identification for the city. Like Lowenfish, Henderson essentially characterizes<br />

both the referendum and the larger narrative by utilizing the same<br />

dichotomy between business and community interests. Unlike Lowenfish,<br />

however, Henderson finds distinct advantages in the Dodger deal for the<br />

city of Los Angeles. Besides procuring “loyal fans, a fine ballpark, and<br />

handsome profits,” notes the author, Los Angeles’ ultimate compensation<br />

for relinquishing its public property for private purposes was the annual<br />

local tax paid by the team. Despite political, legal, and moral upheaval, the<br />

city “found a workable solution, one that was reasonable and justifiable.” 6<br />

In much the same manner, Neil Sullivan’s The Dodgers Move West attempts<br />

to dispel the common assumption that “the citizens and taxpayers<br />

in Los Angeles were exploited by the ill-advised decisions of their elected<br />

officials.” 7 As a result, Sullivan offers a dispassionate analysis of Walter<br />

O’Malley and the political actors in both New York and Los Angeles.<br />

Oftentimes failing to contextualize the Dodgers’ move within a proper<br />

historical, political, and social backdrop, Sullivan utilizes the same dichotomy<br />

as Henderson of mutually benefiting community and business<br />

interests to show how the Dodger deal “demonstrates the significance of<br />

a proper relationship between a community and its sports teams.” 8 With<br />

a privately funded stadium with limited governmental assistance, Sullivan<br />

notes, the city of Los Angeles was able to reap a plethora of financial benefits,<br />

exemplifying “a model association of community and ballclub.” 9<br />

Los Angeles, the Dodgers, and Proposition B<br />

75


76<br />

However, by focusing solely on the benefits and costs of baseball’s<br />

move to Los Angeles and by oversimplifying the debate surrounding<br />

Proposition B to an acrimonious conflict between the material interests<br />

of business and political leaders, and local and community interests, these<br />

analyses fail to problematize issues lying at the heart of urban historical<br />

discourse. In effect, these authors leave a historiographical gap in assessing<br />

the relationships between the Dodger’s relocation and questions of race<br />

and ethnicity, the contested meanings over urban space and land usage,<br />

and the city’s long tumultuous history with public housing. Partially filling<br />

this void, Thomas Hines’ “Housing, Baseball, and Creeping Socialism”<br />

places the Dodger move and the referendum issue within Los Angeles’ tenyear<br />

struggle over public housing in Chavez Ravine. From the Los Angeles<br />

Housing Authority’s purchase of the land under the National Housing<br />

Act of 1949 and the anticommunist crusades against publicly subsidized<br />

land use in the early 1950s, through O’Malley’s privatization of an area<br />

once inhabited by a bustling Mexican-American community, the author<br />

examines the Dodger’s relocation within a Cold War dialectic concerning<br />

the proper use of city space. Characterizing Proposition B and O’Malley’s<br />

victory as the “final apple pie American resolution,” Hines identifies the<br />

referendum issue as the proper finale to “an era in American history in<br />

which public housing was only one of the casualties.” 10<br />

Focusing more explicitly on the Mexican-American experience of<br />

Los Angeles, Ronald Lopez’s dissertation, “The Battle for Chavez Ravine:<br />

Public Policy and Chicano Community Resistance in Post War Los<br />

Angeles, 1945-1962,” explores the ways in which the story is “archetypal<br />

of the Mexican-American experience of injustice, segregation, and dislocation.”<br />

11 Viewing the sale of Chavez Ravine to O’Malley’s Dodgers within<br />

a “narrative of resistance,” Lopez focuses on the destruction of Chavez<br />

Ravine’s Chicano community, from initial attempts at establishing public<br />

housing on the site through O’Malley’s development of the land. Inspired<br />

by the concepts of “action research” or “advocacy research,” this analysis<br />

equates the Dodger deal and Proposition B with a “symbolic black eye,”<br />

a constant reminder of the city’s “past crimes and past promises” in light<br />

of the virtual displacement and destruction of a community. 12 In the end,<br />

notes Lopez, the move of the Brooklyn Dodgers has the markings of a<br />

conspiracy, a tragic moral drama of a powerless minority community unable<br />

to resist the overwhelming forces of both major league baseball and<br />

the city’s elite power structure.<br />

Also examining resistance to the development of Chavez Ravine,<br />

Don Parson shifts his focus from the issue of race and ethnicity to the politics<br />

of modernism in postwar Los Angeles. Exploring a “modern geography”<br />

characterized by “visionary and large-scale developments,” Parson<br />

depicts a struggle between “older, obsolete, or blighted urban areas” of<br />

Los Angeles and politicians intent on creating a “rational and functional<br />

built environment.” 13 As the author notes, “opponents to the moderniza-<br />

MICHAEL MOTT


tion strategies of…Chavez Ravine were seen as obstructionists to the vision<br />

of modern Los Angeles.” 14 With Proposition B’s victory symbolizing<br />

the failure of channeling popular protest into a formal political structure,<br />

community members opposing the development of Chavez Ravine occupied<br />

the site and implemented a vigorous letter writing campaign in<br />

an attempt to halt the forced eviction of the remaining residents of the<br />

area. Feeling ostracized and excluded by a local political structure, states<br />

Parson, “direct action became the means to combat modernism.” 15<br />

Focusing on the issues of cultural diversity and “whiteness” in postwar<br />

Los Angeles, Eric Avila examines the Dodger’s move to the city, as<br />

well as cinematic representations of Los Angeles, the city’s freeway system,<br />

and Disneyland, to “locate the attempt to resurrect an…ideal of Los<br />

Angeles as a ‘white’ city.” 16 Because of the changing spatial and racial<br />

dynamics of postwar Los Angeles, notes Avila, “the struggle to reinvent<br />

Los Angeles in the image of a sanitized, homogenous ‘white’ city took<br />

on a special imperative.” 17 Popular culture became a means of fulfilling<br />

such a reinvention. In a city and an era in which ethnic diversity seemed<br />

to threaten the hegemony of a “singular, core ‘American’ culture,” notes<br />

Avila, O’Malley’s Dodgers served as an attempt to combat social dislocation<br />

and cultural fragmentation by constructing a site for inclusion, a<br />

spatial reorganization of “whiteness.” 18<br />

This examination of O’Malley’s move to Los Angeles and, more specifically,<br />

the referendum issue of Proposition B, will offer a more explicit<br />

analysis of space in the postwar metropolis. At a time when urban expansion<br />

stretched the geographic boundaries of the Los Angeles region to<br />

unprecedented proportions, Proposition B became more than an issue of<br />

whether the Dodgers should play in Chavez Ravine. On closer examination,<br />

the referendum and the Dodger deal in general becomes a debate<br />

over the function of popular culture in reconfiguring the spatial dimensions<br />

of Los Angeles. For opponents of the city’s contract with the club<br />

and the “giveaway” of public land for private enterprise, this struggle to<br />

define the meaning of urban space hinged on their desire to maintain<br />

and reinforce new patterns of postwar urban growth and expansion, and<br />

resist the domination of their outlying districts by centralized downtown<br />

concerns. While never arguing against baseball in Chavez Ravine, per<br />

se, they sought a deal which would allow for a public use suitable for the<br />

region as a whole, rather than a private purpose for the direct benefit of<br />

the downtown district.<br />

For large portions of the populace, however, Proposition B became<br />

a means of arresting postwar “urban sprawl” through the centralized integration<br />

of a disorderly metropolis, revealing a certain anxiety over a<br />

new urban configuration defined more by decentralized horizontal expansion<br />

than traditional conceptions of proper growth. In this sense, Dodger<br />

Stadium resembles, what John Findlay terms, “a magic kingdom for base-<br />

Los Angeles, the Dodgers, and Proposition B<br />

77


78<br />

ball,” in other words, a miniature version of the ideal virgin city, an “antidote<br />

to the apparent chaos of their…urban milieus.” 19 Faced with what<br />

they considered to be an unmanageable pattern of growth, proponents of<br />

the contract also viewed Dodger Stadium as a way of liberating the western<br />

city from the constricting comparison to its eastern counterpart. As<br />

Jules Tygiel notes, “the acquisition of a major league team marked a sense<br />

of maturity, arrival, and acceptance, an acknowledgment of an elevated<br />

status in a newly emergent American constellation.” 20<br />

Lying less than five miles north of downtown Los Angeles, Chavez<br />

Ravine and the battle over its “proper use” became, what the city’s Mayor<br />

Norris Poulson considered, “one of the hottest issues in my last term as<br />

Mayor…the hottest battle in California since the war with Mexico,” and<br />

what one local newspaper publisher termed, “the biggest story in Los<br />

Angeles since the [Mayor Frank] Shaw recall in the 1930s.” 21 What became<br />

known as Walter O’Malley’s “Golden Gulch,” however, had a rich<br />

history dating back to the city’s Spanish roots as a burgeoning pueblo. A<br />

hilly, tree-filled plot of land shaped in the form of a guitar pick, Chavez<br />

Ravine was originally part of a land grant from King Carlos III of Spain. 22<br />

Arriving in the pueblo from New Mexico in the early 1830s, Julian Chavez,<br />

a laborer and later city councilmember of the American town, laid claim<br />

to the four hundred acre plot until his death in 1879. 23 Leading up to its<br />

re-creation as a ballpark, Chavez Ravine served a multitude of purposes<br />

for a variety of inhabitants. Photographer Don Normack documented<br />

the ravine’s use as “a cattle ranch, a dairy farm, two brickyards, a Jewish<br />

cemetery, [and] a Chinese cemetery.” 24<br />

In the minds of public officials concerned with the contentious area’s<br />

“proper use,” however, Chavez Ravine became more of an abstraction<br />

of public policy than a site for human settlement. Reflecting a depiction<br />

recounted in arguments for the area’s development, sportswriter Robert<br />

Shaplen characterized the “rat, shack, and goat hill” as a “sprawling, unkempt<br />

area that has been used principally for a police academy, an unofficial<br />

city dump and, in its fewer choicer spots, a spooning grounds…” 25<br />

After the red baiting of city public officials temporarily halted a three-year<br />

attempt at developing the site for a series of public housing units in 1952,<br />

newly-elected Mayor Poulson, running on an anti-housing platform,<br />

negotiated a number of complicated compromises with public housing<br />

advocates in early 1953. In effect, Poulson freed the entirety of Chavez<br />

Ravine from the hands of the Los Angeles Housing Authority and the<br />

federal government in exchange for an agreement to use the area for “appropriate<br />

public purposes,” a tag that would haunt the Dodger proceedings<br />

for almost a decade. Unconstrained from such legal chains, the City<br />

of Los Angeles conveniently possessed a large plot of centrally located<br />

land at the same time Dodger President O’Malley had a falling out with<br />

the City of New York over his desire for a privately owned ballpark to<br />

replace the dilapidated Ebbets Field. 26<br />

MICHAEL MOTT


In September 1955, a year before Los Angeles officials even began<br />

their courtship with Dodger President Walter O’Malley, Mayor Poulson,<br />

articulated the parameters of a debate that would eventually drive the<br />

arguments for and against Proposition B: “We’re…decentralized here<br />

in Los Angeles. But we’ve got to support and strengthen the downtown<br />

area. It’s my notion that no city can be a great city without a strong<br />

central core.” 27 The availability of property miles from downtown Los<br />

Angeles and its proximity to three freeways surely enticed O’Malley<br />

into leaving his Brooklyn abode. As the prospects for a successful<br />

resolution to his attempts at staying in or around Brooklyn dimmed,<br />

O’Malley’s purchase of Wrigley Field and the Los Angeles Angels of the<br />

Pacific Coast League in February 1957 sounded the death knell for the<br />

Brooklyn Dodgers. After the New York Giants solidified their move to<br />

<strong>San</strong> <strong>Francisco</strong> in August 1957, National League President Warren Giles<br />

officially announced the shift of the Dodger franchise to Los Angeles on<br />

October 8, providing the city with major-league baseball and provoking,<br />

for Brooklynites, what one historian termed, “arguably the greatest<br />

treachery by an American since Benedict Arnold.” 28<br />

Leading up to this moment, O’Malley had, for months, conversed<br />

with Los Angeles city officials over the possible site of a ballpark. Upon<br />

introducing the prospect of Chavez Ravine, the Dodger President surprised<br />

Mayor Poulson: “…he surprisingly knew all about the area…<br />

Walter could visualize its possibilities. He said he liked its central location.<br />

He has never cared for the outskirts…” 29 Although O’Malley<br />

appeared set on the ravine as the future home of his Dodgers, the deal<br />

was anything but certain. After a flurry of negotiations in mid-1957<br />

with O’Malley, Poulson enlisted the services of L.A. business leader,<br />

Harold McClellan, City Attorney Roger Arnebergh, and Chief City<br />

Administrator Samuel Leask to hammer out an offer to the Dodgers<br />

that would, as the mayor noted, “not get all of us run out of the city.” 30<br />

After several weeks of rancorous debate within the city council, a tento-four<br />

majority approved City Ordinance Number 110, 204 at midnight,<br />

September 7, on live television. With the Dodger contract, the<br />

city would give the team some 300 acres of Chavez Ravine, agreeing<br />

to grade the area at a cost of $2,000,000 and build access roads at<br />

an additional $2,740,000. In return, O’Malley’s Dodgers would turn<br />

over $2,000,000 Wrigley Field, a 15-acre site, to the city and construct<br />

a modern baseball stadium in the ravine to seat no less than 50,000<br />

spectators. Moreover, O’Malley agreed to construct and maintain recreational<br />

facilities within the area to be controlled by the city for twenty<br />

years, after which time the team would gain ownership of the structures.<br />

These sureties proved short-lived. According to Poulson, “Our<br />

team turned up with ten votes. We cheered loudly. The battle, at last,<br />

was won — or so we thought.” 31<br />

Los Angeles, the Dodgers, and Proposition B<br />

79


80<br />

On December 1, 1957, Walter Peterson, the Los Angeles city clerk,<br />

announced that petitioners had collected enough valid signatures to place<br />

the Chavez Ravine contract on the upcoming ballot to challenge the validity<br />

of the agreement, initiating what sports columnist John Lardner<br />

coined, “the biggest war for a ditch since the Suez trouble in ’56.” 32 Two<br />

days after the council’s approval of the Dodger contract, a group of lawyers,<br />

homeowners, and real estate agents, almost all of who resided in<br />

the outlying districts of the city, formed the Citizens’ Committee to Save<br />

Chavez Ravine. Unwilling to accept what committee chairman C.A.<br />

Owen considered to be the exorbitant tax breaks of the downtown baseball<br />

deal, the group decided at this time to collect enough signatures to<br />

place the issue on the upcoming summer ballot. Employing both volunteer<br />

and professional petition circulators at a salary of twenty cents per<br />

signature and retaining the publicity efforts of community newspapers,<br />

the committee’s month-long effort succeeded, despite what one sympathizer<br />

considered, “a virtual black-out of any positive news about it in the<br />

downtown press.” 33 Notwithstanding the lack of press in such newspapers<br />

as the Los Angeles Times, a media outlet whose owner, the Chandler family,<br />

had a financial stake in the success in the downtown project, the committee<br />

transported over 85,000 signatures in mid-November to city hall in<br />

an armored car to protect their work from potential threats by the pro-<br />

O’Malley crowd. 34<br />

The news met with equal parts disdain and surprise from public officials<br />

and Walter O’Malley. “Los Angeles is probably America’s softest<br />

touch for a guy clutching a petition,” noted Mayor Poulson, adding, “A<br />

writer once observed that one putting his mind to it could gather enough<br />

signatures in the city to outlaw orange juice.” 35 The Dodger President reacted<br />

with shock at the placement of the Dodger contract on the upcoming<br />

ballot, stating, “I never anticipated a referendum.” Still unaccustomed to<br />

his new California environs, O’Malley noted, “I was completely unaware<br />

of the thing they called a referendum…Very few places have it. They have<br />

initiatives and referendums out here. Very peculiar. No boss…” 36<br />

Regardless of such apprehension, the voters would determine the<br />

fate of the contract on the June 3rd ballot the upcoming year. Despite<br />

city councilman John Holland’s claim that the Dodgers might reap an<br />

advantage from a “B is for Baseball” campaign, the council established<br />

the baseball referendum measure as Proposition B. The voting guidelines<br />

appeared clear-cut. A “yes” vote would approve the Dodger’s contract<br />

with the city, while a “no” would negate the deal, allowing the city to<br />

renegotiate with the club. The underlying issues, however, were not so<br />

simple. Ultimately, the six-month period leading up to the vote magnified<br />

competing visions of the postwar metropolis, dividing the city over the<br />

“proper use” of Chavez Ravine and the meaning of urban space within<br />

Los Angeles. 37<br />

MICHAEL MOTT


Viewing the Dodgers as a possible cure for an ailing metropolis, the<br />

stance of a Los Angeles reporter best exemplifies both the arguments in<br />

support of the Chavez Ravine contract and Proposition B, and the essence<br />

of the western city’s relationship to the East:<br />

L.A. has no identity. We haven’t got a landmark. In New York,<br />

it’s the skyline…Here every little township attaches itself to<br />

L.A., but it worries over its own school problem and its own<br />

sewer problem. We’re looking for the Dodgers to pull it all together.<br />

Land of the freeways, sprawling Los Angeles has high<br />

hopes that the Dodgers will pull it together. 38<br />

As an outspoken leader of the “Yes on Prop. B” group, Mayor Poulson<br />

offered a similar sense of urgency: “Psychologically, it was a great boost<br />

for Los Angeles and the West. It was that of the ‘old East looking down<br />

its nose at the young West.” Imagining the intangibles of “major-league”<br />

status for his city, Poulson stressed, “We just were not big-leaguers in any<br />

way. Then to think that we could become world champions overnight<br />

made them sit up and listen.” 39<br />

In order for the city to achieve “major-league” status, its citizens<br />

would need to be persuaded of the efficacy of the Dodger contract.<br />

As both sides of the referendum issue began to energize their efforts to<br />

reach out to the public with their respective message, many proponents<br />

of the contract pooled their forces into the creation of the “Taxpayers’<br />

Committee for Yes on Prop. B.,” chaired by popular stage, film, and television<br />

comedian, Joe E. Brown. Stressing the vast influx of tourism, commerce,<br />

and industry that would accompany the Los Angeles Dodgers into<br />

the city, Brown and the Taxpayers’ Committee acted as an umbrella organization<br />

for a large variety of people and groups in support of the city’s<br />

agreement with the ball club. With a published budget of over $140,000,<br />

these highly organized political campaigners advertised their own Dodger<br />

gospel through radio advertisements and roadside billboards. 40<br />

Throughout the months leading up to the ballot measure, the<br />

committee circulated vast amounts of literature throughout the city as<br />

well. Not only was a baseball stadium a proper use of publicly-owned<br />

land, noted one pamphlet, the development of Chavez Ravine would<br />

provide over $300,000 of new tax revenues for the development of<br />

other downtown projects. Moreover, the committee’s press emphasized<br />

the importance of more incidental values. Attracting tourism to the<br />

downtown, the Dodgers “will make Los Angeles more attractive as<br />

an ‘all-year’ resort.” 41 Labeling Chavez Ravine a “civic liability and<br />

largely a hilly wasteland,” Brown’s Taxpayers’ Committee celebrated<br />

the site’s possibilities for becoming “one of the scenic and architectural<br />

wonders of the West.” 42 Joining Disneyland as a significant addition<br />

to the region’s cultural makeup, Dodger Stadium would also bring<br />

“order and cohesion” to a city and a downtown district divided by<br />

local interests. 43 As such, the tourist appeal of “the most modern, mag-<br />

Los Angeles, the Dodgers, and Proposition B<br />

81


82<br />

nificent major league stadium in the world” would shift much-deserved<br />

attention to the central business district. 44 Asked if visitors and passersby<br />

would come downtown to conduct business if the city refused<br />

the Chavez Ravine contract, chairman Brown, during a luncheon<br />

meeting, assuredly replied, “78% of them would not.” 45 Ultimately,<br />

as one self-professed member of the Taxpayers’ Committee wrote to<br />

the city council, anyone failing to recognize the importance of baseball<br />

to downtown Los Angeles “belongs to some hick town and not to this<br />

modern marvel, Los Angeles.” 46<br />

As sports historian Steven Riess has noted, boosters and boosterism<br />

have been hugely significant for the development and growth<br />

of Los Angeles, “a town which has based its ability for survival on<br />

self-promotion even before the days of the hype and glamour of<br />

Hollywood.” 47 Endorsement of the Dodger contract continued this<br />

trend in the city’s history. As Joe E. Brown’s Taxpayers’ Committee<br />

placed the promotion of the Chavez Ravine contract on their shoulders,<br />

several other booster groups began dotting the landscape as well.<br />

Along with the endorsement of the AFL-CIO, Town Hall, the Property<br />

Owners Tax Association of California, and the Los Angeles Realty<br />

Board, a group comprising over 130 attorneys as well as a committee<br />

of doctors worked for approval of Proposition B. Citing the benefits of<br />

downtown baseball on additional tax revenue and business activity, the<br />

Downtown Business Men’s Association gave their unanimous approval<br />

of a contract that would start downtown Los Angeles “on a brilliant<br />

new era of prosperity and unprecedented expansion.” 48 Employing<br />

rhetoric common to the endorsement of a majority of these boosters,<br />

the Los Angeles Chamber of Commerce also urged a “yes” vote on<br />

“B for Baseball” in order to transform the “unsightly wastelands” of<br />

Chavez Ravine into a downtown attraction and a taxpaying asset. 49<br />

Although it is difficult to determine the effectiveness of the boosters’<br />

efforts, combined with the outspoken endorsements of the mayor, portions<br />

of the city council, and the dominating coverage of the downtown<br />

press, the proponents of Proposition B had an ample platform<br />

through which to present their own dream of Los Angeles. This vision<br />

constituted nothing less than the restoration of a downtown district<br />

left barren by the ravages of economic dispersion. 50<br />

With initial polls revealing that seventy percent of the city favored<br />

the Chavez Ravine contract in early 1958, O’Malley and Mayor Poulson<br />

announced their desire to detach themselves from the referendum fight.<br />

Taking the position that the ball club should not interfere with such a community<br />

issue, O’Malley refused to contribute to Joe E. Brown’s Taxpayers’<br />

Committee. As the Dodger president expressed to Sports Illustrated,<br />

“Baseball is a democratic game. I have to recognize what’s happening out<br />

here as a democratic process,” adding, “We’ve got to keep baseball out of<br />

politics and the damn politicians out of baseball.” 51<br />

MICHAEL MOTT


However, with their opposition gathering steam and subsequent polls<br />

disclosing an increasing aversion to the Chavez Ravine contract, Poulson<br />

quickly departed from his neutral stance. Returning from an East Coast<br />

business trip, the mayor spoke to reporters at City Hall, emphasizing<br />

his concern with how the Chavez Ravine opposition was negating the<br />

downtown district’s position in important financial and trade circles in<br />

New York. As Poulson stated, eastern businessmen are “wondering if Los<br />

Angeles is a bush league town or whether we’re major league in character.”<br />

52 Opposition to Proposition B and the Chavez Ravine deal, he noted,<br />

stemmed from the growing fragmentation of the city. As the mayor observed<br />

during a subsequent hearing on the contract, “I am sorry to say<br />

that it is obvious to anyone that a great deal of this is sectional opposition.”<br />

“A few people from outlying communities,” continued Poulson,<br />

“are apparently afraid that this is going to bring some business downtown<br />

that they are not going to participate.” Admonishing what he considered<br />

the self-interest of certain councilmembers, Poulson stated, “I have to represent<br />

all of the city…I can’t afford to represent just one section…We<br />

have to think of the city as a whole.” 53<br />

Poulson later proceeded to employ more underhanded tactics in<br />

May of 1958 with polls revealing even less support for the contract, especially<br />

in the outlying <strong>San</strong> Fernando Valley district. Changing his strategy<br />

of “using carefully reasoned arguments to justify the contract,” the mayor<br />

employed a “scare campaign” to win the support of “low-income people<br />

who didn’t belong to country clubs and social groups.” 54 In effect, he led<br />

these constituents to believe the referendum was unalterably a yes-or-no<br />

vote for baseball, purposefully confusing the central issue of Proposition<br />

B for fear of “being drowned out by cries of ‘Save our land for the people!”<br />

55 In another self-professed tactic to turn the issue on its head, Mayor<br />

Poulson wrote National League President Warren Giles encouraging him<br />

to convince the public that they were actually voting on baseball rather<br />

than the Dodger’s contract with the city. The mayor’s efforts surfaced<br />

when Giles’ words appeared in the Los Angeles Times, stating, “The June<br />

3 referendum…will be an expression by the people of Los Angeles as to<br />

whether they want major league baseball.” 56 If the city voted against the<br />

Chavez Ravine, noted Giles, organized baseball would force the Dodgers<br />

to look elsewhere for a home. 57<br />

With equal partiality and less underhandedness, the Los Angeles Times<br />

played an integral role in shaping the contours of the Proposition B debate<br />

as well. If the tactics and efforts of citizen groups and the mayor<br />

were ineffective in persuading the populace of the contract’s benefits,<br />

perhaps the newspaper’s editorializing could prove more successful. With<br />

a large amount of investment in downtown real estate concerns, the<br />

Chandler family had a vested interest in bringing the Dodgers and the<br />

subsequent flow of downtown business activity to Chavez Ravine. The<br />

newspaper’s proclivity for pro-contract media coverage and paucity of<br />

Los Angeles, the Dodgers, and Proposition B<br />

83


84<br />

opposition coverage demonstrated a clear bias. Moreover, the Times’ editorial<br />

pages defined the deal’s supporters’ concerns about the future of<br />

postwar Los Angeles. Two months before the referendum battle began,<br />

the Times addressed a distinct sense of anxiety about the social, political,<br />

and geographic fragmentation facing the city. As a remedy to sprawl and<br />

disorder, the Times editorialized, “The Dodgers might be expected to bind<br />

the neighborhoods together with a sort of communal glue.” Baseball, the<br />

newspaper added, would prove that “Los Angeles is not just the name of<br />

a large group of neighborhoods without common aims, with nothing to<br />

hold them together but the surrounding mountains.” 58<br />

Reflecting similar themes as the referendum vote approached in<br />

June, an op-ed piece entitled, “A Vote in Favor of Everybody,” asked<br />

the public to transform a “half-centered wilderness in the very center<br />

of the metropolitan area” into “a central meeting place for the whole<br />

metropolitan area.” 59 Positing a less literal reading of the proposition,<br />

the following question signifies the important meaning of space to the<br />

referendum debate:<br />

Do you, a citizen-voter, want Los Angeles to be a great city,<br />

with common interests and the civic unity which gives a great<br />

city character; or are you content to let it continue its degeneration<br />

into a geographical bundle of self-centered sections each<br />

fighting with the others for the lion’s share of the revenues and<br />

improvements that belong to all? 60<br />

As the statement demonstrates, these proponents attempted to equate a<br />

“yes” vote with the idea “that Los Angeles shall be a city, not just an aggregation<br />

of suburbs.” 61 This writer clearly expressed a belief that the<br />

Dodgers could replace a fragmented landscape with a centrally located<br />

cultural hub connecting a collection of communities.<br />

Mimicking the mayor’s argument, the writer also characterized the<br />

“fraudulent” and “spiteful” opposition as a self-interested group of outlying<br />

interests set on channeling sectional resistance “to the general idea of<br />

doing anything for the city as a whole.” 62 Their efforts represented little<br />

more than an attempt to prevent the economic success of the city’s downtown<br />

and the achievement of civic unity. Out of an obligation of civic<br />

honor and as a duty to “restore the communion of citizens in Los Angeles<br />

that has been dissolving so alarmingly,” declared the editorial, a “yes”<br />

for Dodger baseball and the Chavez Ravine embodied the belief in “all<br />

city-enterprise.” 63 In this sense, Proposition B no longer represented just a<br />

vote of support for the Dodger contract. A “yes” for the Dodger contract<br />

was a “yes” for the city and the downtown to reclaim its proper place<br />

in a sea of satellite communities. Revealing the anxiety over an expanding,<br />

decentralized metropolis, the writer incorporated a skewed historical<br />

memory in calling for the same sense of community that had once tapped<br />

the mountains of the Sierra Nevadas for water and built “a great harbor<br />

in the shallow mud flats below <strong>San</strong> Pedro.” 64<br />

MICHAEL MOTT


With less symbolic vigor, another Times editorial earlier in May<br />

framed the proponents’ stance in similar terms. As the editorialist noted,<br />

selfish city officials from West Los Angeles and the Pacific Palisades, areas<br />

already receiving large public funds for police and sewer facilities, objected<br />

to Proposition B because the public enterprise of baseball would<br />

not benefit their parochial constituents. “God help the city,” the Times<br />

writer added, “if that principle is always to be applied.” 65 In these terms,<br />

the opponents’ argument “suggested nothing more than the fact that the<br />

city has become fragmented.” 66 If opposition to any public enterprise is<br />

to be continually based on such fragmentation, the editorialist concluded,<br />

“the city and all its services may very well disintegrate.” 67 Therefore, the<br />

development of Chavez Ravine would refocus civic energy on the downtown<br />

district, with a centrally located stadium providing the cohesion to<br />

create spatial order out of seeming chaos.<br />

Reaction to this latter editorial surfaced rather quickly. In a letter<br />

written to the Times staff, an attorney, Jim Bolger, struck out against<br />

the newspaper, outlining the basic contours of the opposition’s argument<br />

and its own reflections on space and growth within postwar Los<br />

Angeles. Bolger saw the Dodger’s deal as part of a “frustrating campaign<br />

to save the downtown district,” and the Times’ editorial was correct<br />

in highlighting the city’s fragmentation: “Yer durn right it is and<br />

the outlying communities and taxpayers are not one whit predisposed<br />

to save the broken down metropolitan area.” 68 This “decentralization<br />

bonfire” has continued unabated for years, noted Bolger. Reaching a<br />

point of no return, “the congeries of ‘little cities’ inside metropolitan<br />

Los Angeles are not interested in arresting its decline.” 69 Characterizing<br />

the city’s downtown as a passé existence of an outdated geography,<br />

Bolger added, “all the Times’ king’s horses and men can’t put the old<br />

broken down Humpty-Dumpty together again.” 70 For a city whose<br />

patterns of growth never resembled more traditional models of core<br />

and periphery, any efforts at establishing subservience to a central business<br />

district were both senseless and out of tune with current realities.<br />

Unwilling to cast a glance downtown for any sense of identity, he offered<br />

a “resounding ‘NO’ on Prop. B.” 72<br />

Although the dominating presence of the downtown media often<br />

smothered their efforts, opponents to Proposition B and the Chavez<br />

Ravine contract were a hodge-podge conglomeration of disparate interests.<br />

In his memoirs, Mayor Poulson offers a popular representation of<br />

this group. Three entities, noted Poulson, seized upon the issue to further<br />

and protect their own interests. In an effort to expand their circulation and<br />

advertising, community newspapers in Los Angeles and Orange counties<br />

attempted to fight their downtown nemesis by labeling the Dodger deal a<br />

“give away.” At the same time, in reaction to Walter O’Malley’s advocacy<br />

of pay television for broadcasting his club’s games, local television supported<br />

the efforts of the opposition. Finally, Poulson identified <strong>San</strong> Diego<br />

Los Angeles, the Dodgers, and Proposition B<br />

85


86<br />

businessman, John A. Smith, as one of the primary individuals financing<br />

their efforts. Smith, owner of the Pacific Coast League’s <strong>San</strong> Diego<br />

Padres, faced the breaking up of the league if O’Malley experienced any<br />

sort of success in Los Angeles. 72<br />

While these groups most likely played a significant role in supporting<br />

the opposition, this characterization of the opponents to Proposition<br />

B vastly oversimplifies the issues for the tens of thousands challenging<br />

the contract between the Dodgers and the city of Los Angeles, many of<br />

whom attempted to resist the encroachment of their own communities by<br />

the political and economic interests of the central district. As Tim Cohane<br />

of Look magazine suggested, to understand their position, “it is necessary<br />

to remember that Los Angeles has sprawled out so fast in all directions<br />

that many residents of outlying districts…are impatient for streets, sidewalks,<br />

sewers, refuse collection and even schools.” 73<br />

Supported by city councilmen John Holland, Pat McGee, Karl<br />

Rundberg, Earl Baker, and Ed Roybal, the opposition’s position centered<br />

on a core set of issues. Many felt the contract was an illegal “giveaway” of<br />

a huge tract of publicly owned land. As Roybal characterized the Dodger<br />

deal, “The problem here is not a question of baseball, but rather one of<br />

propriety and legality.” 74 Rallying against what they considered a subsidy<br />

to big business, the opposition forces asserted that the city government<br />

could not legally turn publicly owned land over to a private corporation<br />

for the operation of private enterprise. Despite the tax benefits facing the<br />

city, O’Malley’s club remained the primary beneficiary.<br />

Although different groups within the coalition offered contrasting<br />

suggestions for alternative stadium sites and financing, no one single<br />

group desired to keep the Dodgers out of Los Angeles. The coalition<br />

simply wanted the mayor and the city council to obey the “for public<br />

purposes only” stipulation within the city’s title to the ravine. Framing<br />

the question in similar terms, the Citizens’ Committee to Save Chavez<br />

Ravine for the People stated, “The referendum asked for is NOT to stop<br />

the Dodgers from coming to Los Angeles. We welcome the Dodgers!<br />

But not the ‘deal.’ We ask only that the people of L.A. be allowed to<br />

vote on a huge real estate transaction.” 75 If the Dodgers were to play<br />

baseball in Chavez Ravine, argued a majority of the opposition, the<br />

city should still retain possession of the site, allowing the citizens “to<br />

preserve this invaluable community asset in public ownership for the<br />

use of this and future generations.” 76<br />

Buoyed by the grass-roots organizing of the Citizens’ Committee to<br />

Save Chavez Ravine for the People, the opposition to Proposition B also<br />

rallied around a reconsideration of a contract more attuned to and reflective<br />

of the “community interest,” as opposed to the central concerns of<br />

the downtown. The issue was paramount to any implementation of scarce<br />

resources in Los Angeles: how can city officials dump public funds into a<br />

MICHAEL MOTT


private downtown development while neglecting the exploding needs of<br />

the suburbs? As councilman McGee stated during a May hearing on the<br />

Dodger deal, “This city…can’t afford this program financially…There<br />

isn’t one complete street in the <strong>San</strong> Fernando Valley…There are no sewers<br />

out there.” 77 Despite concerns with an ever-expanding metropolitan<br />

region, the city could not reverse the trends of growth by refusing the<br />

needs of its outlying districts and granting concessions to O’Malley’s<br />

downtown corporation. Not only would a centrally located stadium<br />

take important business away from the outskirts, councilmen such as<br />

McGee, along with the Citizens’ Committee, felt their districts needed<br />

vital services more than the city needed big-league baseball. In a direct<br />

response to charges of sectional self-interest, McGee characterized the<br />

city’s contract with the Dodgers as lavishness, stating, “I believe it is the<br />

fundamental obligation of government to provide the necessities before<br />

you provide the luxuries.” 78<br />

Responding also to proponents’ rhetoric of creating unity out of a<br />

disorderly cityscape, opponents of Proposition B, particularly the Citizens’<br />

Committee, espoused their own image of spatial accord within the existing<br />

dynamic of core and periphery. As the city’s population grows and<br />

as its boundaries continue to expand, “the value of the Chavez Ravine<br />

tract,” noted one supporter “will become even greater.” “One of the great<br />

lacks facing American cities in their efforts to bring order out of metropolitan<br />

chaos,” the supporter added, unencumbered land stands as the<br />

answer to such urban problems. The establishment of a municipally controlled<br />

facility such as a zoo, rather than a privately owned ballpark, would<br />

serve the needs of both downtown and the outlying districts in creating<br />

a sense of unity across the metropolis. Once the ravine is sold to private<br />

interests, an opponent added, this opportunity “will be forever lost to the<br />

people.” 79 A large portion of the Citizens’ Committee’s rhetoric reflects<br />

this association of a “proper public use” for Chavez Ravine with the harmony<br />

of the community. Commenting on the scarcity of available land in<br />

and around the city of Los Angeles suitable for communal purposes, they<br />

asked, “Where are you going to put a major Convention Hall? An Opera<br />

House or Civic Auditorium? A World Trade Center, just to mention a few<br />

presently known needs.” 80 If Chavez Ravine was to fall into private hands,<br />

many opponents believed the entire city would miss out on a golden opportunity<br />

for fulfilling a desirable community need.<br />

In their letters to both public officials and the press, the words of concerned<br />

citizens opposing the Chavez Ravine contract also reveal similar<br />

themes. One “plain, blunt Hearst newspaperman” wrote to the publisher<br />

of the Los Angeles Examiner, charging the paper’s promotion of a downtown<br />

ballpark with “setting off an unfortunate civil war” between the downtown<br />

and suburbia. 81 In a letter written to County Supervisor Kenneth<br />

Hahn, one of the architects of the Chavez Ravine contract, Wilma<br />

Merrill wrote, “we are primarily against this deal because it is strictly a<br />

Los Angeles, the Dodgers, and Proposition B<br />

87


88<br />

giveaway of our land and money.” Recognizing what she considered to be<br />

the capitulation of public officials to the interests of downtown business<br />

concerns, she added, “Forget about your newly acquired big business socalled<br />

friends…Walk again among your people.” 82 Lucille Toll’s letter to<br />

Kahn reveals a more conspiratorial tone, asking him, “Before the ‘Artful<br />

Dodgers’ grab the whole county suppose you quit pitching spitballs and<br />

put a clean one over home plate?” 83 The words of Ms. Merrill and Ms.<br />

Toll reveal a certain distrust of their city officials’ appropriation of public<br />

land in the name of the public good.<br />

More significantly, these letters, alongside the entire campaign against<br />

Proposition B, represent the contested use of space in their postwar city.<br />

Accepting decentralization and dispersion as an inevitable, if not positive,<br />

result of urban growth in Los Angeles, the opposition to Proposition B<br />

largely focused on retaining what they considered a proper balance between<br />

core and periphery. For many Angelenos on the fringe of the city<br />

limits, the “giveaway” of centrally located public land for the benefit of a<br />

private corporation was an example of the subjugation of their own interests<br />

to an irrelevant downtown area. If the city was to help in developing<br />

downtown Los Angeles, then the entire community should play a large<br />

role in approving such plans for the future. The upcoming election on<br />

June 3rd could be a medium for helping decide that future.<br />

Leading up to the vote, the Dodgers’ slump on the field during the<br />

opening months of the season did not seem to help the proponents of<br />

Proposition B. Despite impressive attendance records, the Dodgers started<br />

the 1958 season slow at their interim home, the Coliseum, an irregularly<br />

shaped structure reflecting the city’s own spatial disorder. Their poor record<br />

inspired the city council to pass a ten to zero vote of confidence on April 25.<br />

Councilman Ernest E. Debs chose, as well, to blame the opposition forces<br />

for the Dodger’s poor outings, stating, “We claim to welcome this ball club<br />

here. Our kind of welcome has brought shame to a great city. Our kind<br />

of welcome has undermined the morale of this team…” 84 In a less direct<br />

manner, Dodger President O’Malley offered a similar explanation: “I think<br />

after this election on June 3rd when all of this dies down, one way or the<br />

other, I think they will come through and play to their capacity.” 85<br />

Despite their poor play, record-breaking numbers of fans continued<br />

to pour into the Coliseum to watch their home team, easing any fear of<br />

flagging support for the Dodgers. Such popularity did not stop supporters<br />

of Proposition B in making one last public plea, an appeal exemplifying<br />

Los Angeles’ own unique style of Hollywood boosterism. Days before the<br />

vote, on Sunday, June 1, Joe E. Brown’s Taxpayers’ Committee bought<br />

more than five hours of television time on Times-affiliated station KTTV<br />

for an enormously popular Dodgerthon. What Mayor Poulson considered<br />

a turning-point in the referendum battle, the telethon included a<br />

long list of entertainment personalities, such as Jerry Lewis, Laraine Day,<br />

MICHAEL MOTT


Dean Martin, and George Burns, all plugging for major league baseball<br />

as a solution to the city’s major urban problems. Deeming the Chavez<br />

Ravine a “good deal” for both O’Malley and the city, actor Ronald<br />

Reagan castigated the opposition’s argument as, “One of the most dishonest<br />

documents I ever read in my life…Where is a baseball stadium<br />

to go, in the suburbs, away from the freeways?” 86 Moving the broadcast<br />

from the studio to the airport where thousands of supporters welcomed<br />

the Dodgers from their recent road trip, the Dodgerthon reached an estimated<br />

1,800,000 viewers. 87<br />

Unwilling to forego this favorable press coverage, O’Malley stepped<br />

out of the shadows to make his own final push for approval of the Dodger<br />

contract. During a television forum the following day, the Dodger President<br />

directed his concluding remarks to both his opponents in the studio and<br />

the city-wide audience at home, stating, “”I’ve had enough of all this business.<br />

I know the Dodger case will be tried by the fairest jury in the land<br />

and I want to tell you all that I’m willing to abide by the decision…” 88 The<br />

next day, on June 3, the people of Los Angeles cast their vote.<br />

With only a quarter of the precincts reporting, the proponents of<br />

Proposition B took the lead and never lost ground. With 351,683 yes<br />

votes and 325,898 negative ballots, the final tally revealed a rather slim<br />

25,785-vote majority for the Chavez Ravine contract. However, in expressing<br />

his gratitude to the city, O’Malley noted, “I don’t regard the outcome<br />

as close, but rather as a very significant margin…Few Presidents<br />

get elected with a greater majority than the 52% indicated by the latest<br />

count.” 89 For Mayor Poulson, the vote represented a “progressive step”<br />

towards bridging the gaps of a divided community. 90 An examination of<br />

voter response by council districts demonstrates the geographic split of<br />

this division. Four out of the six districts voting against Proposition B were<br />

in the <strong>San</strong> Fernando Valley, revealing the strength of sectional opposition<br />

to the downtown attraction. Moreover, a significant portion of the<br />

city’s more centrally located African-American and Mexican-American<br />

neighborhoods cast their vote in support of Proposition B. Without heavy<br />

support from an African-American community still rallying around an<br />

organization that broke the color line with Jackie Robinson in 1947, historian<br />

Charles Alexander has noted, perhaps O’Malley and his supporters<br />

would never have achieved their triumph, especially considering the apparent<br />

political clout of the city’s suburbs. 91<br />

What one City Hall employee considered, “the courtship of a lunatic<br />

ball club and a lunatic city,” the Dodger saga did not end with the victory<br />

of Proposition B. 92 By November 1959, O’Malley and his Dodgers had to<br />

overcome even more hurdles, including two taxpayers’ suits challenging<br />

the legality of the contract and the forceful eviction of the Arechiga family<br />

and others, the sole remnants of the once burgeoning Chavez Ravine<br />

community. With the ravine physically and legally cleared, work on the<br />

Los Angeles, the Dodgers, and Proposition B<br />

89


90<br />

new Dodger Stadium began in 1959, just weeks after the Dodgers’ 1959<br />

World Series victory. What Jim Murray of the Los Angeles Times described<br />

as “the Taj Mahal, the Parthenon, and Westminster Abbey of baseball,”<br />

Dodger Stadium opened on April 10, 1962 to much fanfare. 93 Designed<br />

by a New York City-based architectural firm, the ballpark stood as a symbol<br />

of California in a postwar age. With minimal obstruction to either<br />

the view of the field or of the mountains rising behind the city, Dodger<br />

Stadium employed tens of thousands of parking spaces to service a largely<br />

mobile clientele, a testament to the city’s all-powerful automobile culture.<br />

More importantly for the city coffers, the first privately funded ball park<br />

since Yankee Stadium’s completion in 1923 served over two million fans<br />

for five years in a row, providing the city of Los Angeles with tax revenue<br />

of almost $10,000,000 in the first twelve years of its existence, a figure<br />

that would consistently grow as the years passed. 94<br />

With, what one columnist considered, “something akin to the intensity<br />

of a revival meeting,” the Proposition B drama amounted to more than a<br />

show of support for major league baseball in Los Angeles. 95 In the context<br />

of a postwar atmosphere of explosive urban growth and decentralization,<br />

Los Angeles played host to competing claims over the meaning of space in<br />

the metropolis. As John Allswang has noted, the notion of a referendum<br />

reflects “that rule by the people must extend beyond representation when<br />

that representation does not, in fact, do the people’s bidding.” 96 In this<br />

sense, opponents to the contract did not believe their mayor and other city<br />

officials were conducting business in a manner appropriate to the existing<br />

city structure. The campaign against Proposition B illustrated a pattern<br />

of urban land use reflecting the existing balance between downtown and<br />

the outlying districts. Rather than handing over centrally located land to<br />

a private corporation capable of strengthening downtown interests to the<br />

detriment of the periphery, opponents believed Chavez Ravine should remain<br />

in public hands for the benefit of the community at large instead of<br />

an ineffectual downtown district.<br />

Anxious over the unbridled expansion of their metropolis, supporters<br />

of the Chavez Ravine contract sought to arrest such growth by focusing the<br />

city on what the Times considered, “one of those centers of attachment that<br />

the metropolitan area of Los Angeles has needed so desperately.” 97 In this<br />

way, the Dodgers could provide a form of communal glue to combat a process<br />

of social dislocation wrought by geographical fragmentation. By reordering<br />

a disorderly and atomistic landscape, supporters hoped to build, what<br />

John Findlay has termed, a “legible city” easier to comprehend. 98 However,<br />

looking at Los Angeles more than forty years later, their goals remain elusive.<br />

Although they were successful in bringing the Los Angeles Dodgers to<br />

downtown Los Angeles, their victory in bringing order to the city is highly<br />

questionable. Despite one writer’s appraisal of Proposition B’s victory as a<br />

“transformation of conflict into union,” Los Angeles continues to reflect a<br />

landscape marked by rampant geographic and social diffusion. 99<br />

MICHAEL MOTT


01<br />

Allen Scott and Edward Soja, The City: Los Angeles and Urban Theory at the End of the<br />

Twentieth Century (Berkeley: <strong>University</strong> of California Press, 1996), 8; Robert M. Fogelson, The<br />

Fragmented Metropolis: Los Angeles, 1850-1930 (Berkeley: <strong>University</strong> of California Press, 1967), 2.<br />

02<br />

Lee Elihu Lowenfish, “A Tale of Many Cities: The Westward Expansion of Major<br />

League Baseball in the 1950’s,” Journal of the West 71 (July 1978): 72-73.<br />

03<br />

Jules Tygiel, Past Time: Baseball as History (New York: Oxford <strong>University</strong> Press, 2000),<br />

179-183; Charles Alexander, Our Game: An American Baseball History (New York: Henry Holt<br />

and Company, 1991), 242-243; Don Normark, Chavez Ravine, 1949: A Los Angeles Story (<strong>San</strong><br />

<strong>Francisco</strong>: Chronicle Books, 1999), 18-21.<br />

04<br />

Ibid., 80.<br />

05<br />

Lowenfish, 79.<br />

06<br />

Cary S. Henderson, “Los Angeles and the Dodger War, 1957-1962,” Southern<br />

California Quarterly 62 (Fall 1980): 286.<br />

07<br />

Neil J. Sullivan, The Dodgers Move West (New York: Oxford <strong>University</strong> Press, 1987), ix.<br />

08<br />

Ibid., x.<br />

09<br />

Ibid.<br />

10<br />

Thomas S. Hines, “Housing, Baseball, and Creeping Socialism: The Battle of Chavez<br />

Ravine, Los Angeles, 1949-1959,” Journal of Urban History 8 (February 1982): 141, 142.<br />

11<br />

Ronald William Lopez II, “The Battle for Chavez Ravine: Public Policy and Chicano<br />

Community Resistance in Post War Los Angeles, 1945-1962” (Ph. D. diss., <strong>University</strong> of<br />

California, Berkeley, 1999), 15.<br />

12<br />

Ibid., 25.<br />

13<br />

Don Parson, “‘This Modern Marvel’: Bunker Hill, Chavez Ravine, and the Politics<br />

of Modernism in Los Angeles,” Southern California Quarterly 75 (Fall-Winter 1993): 333.<br />

14<br />

Ibid., 335.<br />

15<br />

Ibid.<br />

16<br />

Eric Raymond Avila, “Reinventing Los Angeles: Popular Culture in the Age of White<br />

Flight, 1940-1965” (Ph. D. diss., <strong>University</strong> of California, Berkeley, 1997), 20.<br />

17<br />

Ibid.<br />

18<br />

Ibid, 37, 171.<br />

19<br />

John M. Findlay, Magic Lands: Western Cityscapes and American Culture After 1940 (Berkeley:<br />

<strong>University</strong> of California Press, 1992), 5.<br />

20<br />

Tygiel, 167.<br />

21<br />

“The Genealogy and Life Story of Erna and Norris Poulson,” <strong>University</strong> of<br />

California, Los Angeles, Special Collections (UCLASC), Norris Poulson Papers, Box 5, 197,<br />

199; Oran W. Asa, “Chavez Ravine Deal...Biggest Story Since the ‘30s,” El Sereno Star, April 24,<br />

1958, p. 1.<br />

22<br />

Normark, 12, 17.<br />

23<br />

“Chavez Ravine Fact Book,” UCLASC, Edward R. Roybal Papers, Box 6, 8.<br />

24<br />

Normark, 17.<br />

25<br />

Robert Shaplen, “O’Malley and the Angels,” Sports Illustrated, March 24, 1958, p. 67.<br />

26<br />

Hines, 138-140.<br />

27<br />

“Mayor Poulson,” Frontier, September 1955, p. 5.<br />

28<br />

Alexander, 239; Henderson, 265-266; Lowenfish, 79.<br />

29<br />

“The Genealogy and Life Story of Edna and Norris Poulson,” 200.<br />

30<br />

Ibid.<br />

31<br />

Ibid, 204; “Chavez Ravine Fact Book,” 8; Henderson, 271-275; Tim Cohane, “The<br />

West Coast Produces Baseball’s Strangest Story,” Look, August 19, 1958, pp. 54-55.<br />

32<br />

John Lardner, “The War for Chavez,” Newsweek, December 16, 1957, p. 78.<br />

33<br />

“Chavez Ravine Fact Book,” 9.<br />

Los Angeles, the Dodgers, and Proposition B<br />

NOTES<br />

91


92<br />

34<br />

Sullivan, 138; “Chavez Ravine Fact Book,” 8-9; “40, 829 of Names Okd for Vote on<br />

Ball Park,” Los Angeles Times (LAT), December 3, 1957, p.1; California Legislature, Assembly<br />

Interim Committee on Governmental Efficiency and Economy, “Chavez Ravine Volume II,”<br />

(Los Angeles, 1959), 82-88.<br />

35<br />

“The Genealogy and Life Story of Erna and Norris Poulson,” 204.<br />

36<br />

“O’Malley: He Liked the Fight,” LAT, August 10, 1979, sec. 1, p. 32.<br />

37<br />

“Ballot Title Delayed on Dodger Referendum,” LAT, April 9, 1958, sec. 1, p. 2;<br />

“Dodger’s Referendum Given Title B on Ballot,” LAT, April 11, 1958, sec. 1, p. 2.<br />

38<br />

“Who Called that Bum a Smodger,” Sports Illustrated, March 24, 1958, p. 15.<br />

39<br />

“The Genealogy and Life Story of Erna and Norris Poulson,” 198.<br />

40<br />

“Joe E. Brown to Speak on L. A. Baseball,” LAT, April 3, 1958, sec. 3, p. 3; “Chavez<br />

Ravine Fact Book,” 8.<br />

41<br />

“Town Hall: Municipal and County Government Section, Proposed Report on<br />

Dodgers Referendum,” UCLASC, Edward Roybal Papers, Box 6, 11..<br />

42<br />

“Taxpayers’ Committee for Yes on B,” UCLASC, Edward Roybal Papers, Box<br />

6; “Why Taxpayers Support City-Dodger Contract!,” UCLASC, Frederick Francis Houser<br />

Papers, Box 163.<br />

43<br />

“Taxpayers’ Committee for Yes on B,” UCLASC, Edward Roybal Papers, Box 6.<br />

44<br />

Ibid.<br />

45<br />

“Dodgers Will Bring Visitors From Far Away, Joe E. Brown Declares,” LAT, April 4,<br />

1958, sec. 3, p. 22.<br />

46<br />

Letter from Ernest Evans to Edward Roybal, UCLASC, Edward Roybal Papers, Box<br />

6; “Town Hall: Municipal and County Government Section, Proposed Report on Dodgers<br />

Referendum,” 1-14.<br />

47<br />

Steven A. Riess, “Power Without Authority: Los Angeles’ Elites and the Construction<br />

of the Coliseum,” Journal of Sport History 8 (Spring 1981): 50.<br />

48<br />

“Downtown Group Urges ‘Yes’ Vote on Prop. B,” LAT, May 7, 1958, p. 20.<br />

49<br />

“Chamber Cites Benefits of Baseball Stadium,” LAT, May 23, 1958, sec. 1, p. 13.<br />

50<br />

“100 Lawyers to Work for Dodger Measure,” LAT, April 15, 1958, sec. 1, p. 4;<br />

“Doctor Cites Tax Gain in Dodgers ‘Yes’ Vote,” LAT, April 30, 1958, sec. 1, p. 18; “Huge Tax<br />

Gain Seen in Dodgers’ Use of Chavez,” LAT, May 6, 1958, sec. 1, p. 1.<br />

51<br />

Robert Shaplen, “O’Malley and the Angels,” Sports Illustrated, March 24, 1958, p. 62.<br />

52<br />

“City Standing Affected by Dodgers, Says Mayor,” LAT, April 8, 1958, sec. 3, p. 1;<br />

Cohane, 56.<br />

53<br />

California Legislature, Assembly Interim Committee on Governmental Efficiency<br />

and Economy, “Chavez Ravine Volume II,” (Los Angeles, 1959), 137-138.<br />

54<br />

“The Genealogy and Life Story of Erna and Norris Poulson,” 205.<br />

55<br />

Ibid.<br />

56<br />

“L. A. Faces Loss of Dodgers – Giles,” LAT, May 23, 1958, sec. 4, p. 1.<br />

57<br />

“Poll Shows Heavey Vote Favors ‘Yes’ on Prop. B,” LAT, May 8, 1958, p. 28; “The<br />

Genealogy and Life Story of Erna and Norris Poulson,” 204-205.<br />

58<br />

“The Dodgers and This City,” LAT, October 2, 1957, sec. 2, p. 4.<br />

59<br />

“A Vote in Favor of Everybody,” LAT, June 1, 1958, sec. 2, p. 4.<br />

60<br />

Ibid.<br />

61<br />

Ibid.<br />

62<br />

Ibid.<br />

63<br />

Ibid.<br />

64<br />

Ibid.<br />

65<br />

“Prop. B and a Clear Conscience,” LAT, May 18, 1958, sec. 2, p. 4.<br />

66<br />

Ibid.<br />

67<br />

Ibid.<br />

68<br />

Jim Bolger, “The Times Strikes Out,” UCLASC, Edward Roybal Papers, Box 6.<br />

69<br />

Ibid.<br />

70<br />

Ibid.<br />

71<br />

Ibid.<br />

72<br />

“The Genealogy and Life Story of Erna and Norris Poulson,” 203-4.<br />

MICHAEL MOTT


73 Cohane, 55.<br />

74 Edward Roybal, Local Reporter, June 1959, p. 3.<br />

75 Citizens’ Committee to Save Chavez Ravine for the People Fact Sheet, UCLASC,<br />

Edward Roybal Papers, Box 6.<br />

76 “Town Hall: Municipal and County Government Section, Proposed Report on<br />

Dodgers Referendum,” 13.<br />

77 California Legislature, Assembly Interim Committee on Governmental Efficiency<br />

and Economy, “Chavez Ravine Volume II,” (Los Angeles, 1959), 179.<br />

78 Ibid; Cohane, 55.<br />

79 “Town Hall: Municipal and County Government Section, Proposed Report on<br />

Dodgers Referendum,” 5.<br />

80 “Save Chavez Ravine for the Citizens of Los Angeles,” UCLASC, Edward Roybal<br />

Papers, Box 6, 3.<br />

81 Letter to Franklin S. Payne, UCLASC, Edward Roybal Papers, Box 6.<br />

82 Letter from Wilma Merrill to Kenneth Hahn, UCLASC, Edward Roybal Papers,<br />

Box 6.<br />

83<br />

Letter from Lucille Toll to Kenneth Hahn, UCLASC, Edward Roybal Papers, Box 6.<br />

84<br />

“Debs Blame Dodgers’ Slump on Uncertainty of Future in L. A.,” LAT, April 26,<br />

1958, sec. 1, p. 1.<br />

85<br />

California Legislature, Assembly Interim Committee on Governmental Efficiency<br />

and Economy, “Chavez Ravine Volume II” (Los Angeles, 1959), 40-41; Sullivan, 148.<br />

86<br />

“5-Hour Telethon Supports Prop. B,” LAT, June 2, 1958, sec. 1, p. 3.<br />

87<br />

Cohane, 58; “Dodgerthon Telecast Will Promote Team,” LAT, June 1, 1958, sec. 1, p.<br />

1; “Five-hour Dodgerthon Slated on KTTV Today,” LAT, June 1, 1958, sec. 1, p. 2; “Notables<br />

Back Prop. B on TV,” LAT, June 2, 1958, sec. 1, p. 1.<br />

88<br />

“Final Chavez Plea Made by O’Malley,” LAT, June 3, 1958, sec. 1, p. 1.<br />

89<br />

“O’Malley Thanks,” LAT, June 5, 1958, sec. 4, p. 2.<br />

90<br />

“Baseball Vote,” LAT, June 5, 1958, sec. 1, p. 2.<br />

91<br />

“Proposition B,” LAT, July 2, 1958, sec. 3, p. 26; Rodolfo F. Acuna, A Community Under<br />

Siege: A Chronicle of Chicanos East of the Los Angeles River, 1945-1975 (Los Angeles: Chicano Studies<br />

Research Center Publications, 1984), 71-72; Alexander, 242-43.<br />

92<br />

Cohane, 58.<br />

93<br />

Sullivan, 197.<br />

94<br />

Henderson, 281-284; Sullivan, 228; Letter from Lloyd A. Menveg to Norris Poulson,<br />

May 14, 1975, UCLASC, Norris Poulson Papers, Box 5; “Los Angeles Votes to Give Chavez<br />

Ravine Site to Dodgers for New Baseball Stadium,” Architectural Forum, July 1958, p. 13.<br />

95<br />

“Ravine Drama Presents Many Unique Questions,” El Sereno Star, April 24, 1958, p. 4.<br />

96<br />

John M. Allswang, The Initiative and Referendum in California, 1898-1998 (Stanford:<br />

Stanford <strong>University</strong> Press, 2000), 4.<br />

97<br />

Tygiel, 185.<br />

98<br />

Findlay, 284.<br />

99<br />

“Closed Ranks,” Los Angeles Examiner, January 1962, UCLASC, Edward Roybal<br />

Papers, Box 6.<br />

Los Angeles, the Dodgers, and Proposition B<br />

93


American Fourierism<br />

U N I V E R S A L I Z I N G R E F O R M<br />

T\<br />

M A R Y A N Soliman


eex<br />

post<br />

efacto


etween the years 1840 and 1880, a movement of middle-class men<br />

and women attempted to transform America into a cooperative society<br />

modeled on the teachings of French social theorist Charles Fourier.<br />

Best known for establishing communes called Phalanxes, the American<br />

Fourierists, or Associationists, recognized the right to private property but<br />

turned the bourgeois order on its head by proposing to distribute profits<br />

equitably between capitalists and laborers. Associationists envisioned a society<br />

in which work not only satisfied the material wants of humankind<br />

but also enabled each person to reach his or her full creative potential.<br />

To bring about the new social order, Associationists believed they had to<br />

convince America of Association’s advantages. Associationists, therefore,<br />

went to great lengths to clarify their views to the public. During their peak<br />

in the 1840s, they published a weekly periodical, The Harbinger, which<br />

served as the central vehicle for elaborating their views. 1<br />

B<br />

Although a rich documentary record preserves the writings of<br />

Associationists, most scholars have telescoped their ideas. Arthur Bestor’s<br />

ground-breaking Backwoods Utopias and Ronald G. Walters’s synthetic study<br />

American Reformers 1815-1860 made much out of the fact that Associationists<br />

did not oppose private property on principle and sought to unite all classes,<br />

unlike later socialists who advocated that workers struggle against the<br />

capitalist class and put an end to private property. 2 Bestor presented the<br />

Associationists’ trans-class program as proof that secular movements in the<br />

United <strong>State</strong>s, such as Association, shared more in common with American<br />

religious communitarianism than with European socialism. In a more explicit<br />

way than Bestor, Walters treated the Associationists’ trans-class program<br />

as a conservative position, one that placed American Fourierists to<br />

the right of those pietistic societies that opposed private property. Bestor<br />

and Walters ignored how Associationists understood themselves and the<br />

significance they assigned to their trans-class program.<br />

97


98<br />

In his definitive study on American Fourierism, The Utopian Alternative:<br />

Fourierism in Nineteenth-Century America, historian Carl J. Guarneri urged<br />

scholars to discuss Associationists on their own terms. 3 For one, a close<br />

reading of The Harbinger reveals that Associationists did not defend the<br />

way capitalists or private property functioned in their current society,<br />

which indeed would have represented a conservative position, but rather<br />

contemplated the potential role these forces could play in an egalitarian<br />

system. Under the current system, profits lined the pockets of the<br />

capitalists. However, in a new social order, industry would provide for<br />

the needs of everyone, liberating humankind. Moreover, the nuances of<br />

their trans-class program illustrate that they did not have a conservative<br />

approach but one flexible enough to let them side firmly with the noncapitalist<br />

classes on practical matters. Associationists recognized that,<br />

because the current order privileged the capitalist class, reformers would<br />

have to look to other classes for financial and intellectual support as well<br />

as organize actively on the side of the most oppressed classes if they<br />

wished to achieve an ultimate unity. An examination of The Harbinger<br />

in its first year suggests that any characterization of the Associationists’<br />

trans-class position should center on the broader context of Association’s<br />

deep commitment to universalism and to changing the world, rather<br />

than its ostensible conservatism.<br />

The Harbinger adopted Charles Fourier’s theory of human progress.<br />

Fourier divided human history into stages: human beings had lived<br />

through Savagery, Patriarchate, and Barbarism, and currently occupied<br />

a state called Civilization. Each stage had its own distinct social and economic<br />

organization, which Associationists termed Collective Unity. In a<br />

two-part article devoted to human history, Associationists explained, “The<br />

Collective Unities of these Societies have not been, however, true unions,<br />

offering a congenial sphere for the life of man, and the growth and exercise<br />

of his moral and material powers — but mere aggregations of<br />

families confusedly and incoherently brought together.” 4 Associationists<br />

believed Collective Unity should facilitate the moral and material development<br />

of each person. Only in a future society called Harmony would<br />

human beings achieve true Collective Unity or universalism. However, in<br />

bringing humankind one step closer to Harmony, each successive stage<br />

represented progress.<br />

Associationists viewed the development of industry as a prerequisite<br />

to human progress and universalism. In the Savage or lowest<br />

state, “industry, in its various branches of agriculture, manufactures,<br />

[etc.], does not exist; consequently man’s physical wants, and his love<br />

of material comfort and refinement, (without which no high intellectual<br />

development is possible,) cannot be satisfied.” 5 In the following stage,<br />

the Patriarchate, “industry — which is the ground-work of all human<br />

progress — begins to be exercised.” 6 Associationists looked favorably<br />

upon modern industry because they saw in it the potential to satisfy the<br />

MARYAN SOLIMAN


material needs of the entire human race, which would lay the basis for<br />

man to strive toward his creative goals. Their view on the necessity of<br />

modern industry provides a clue as to why they embraced some form of<br />

capitalism, an economic system which they saw as having ushered in the<br />

greatest advances in industry.<br />

While Associationists welcomed the industrial innovations introduced<br />

under Barbarism and Civilization, they condemned these phases<br />

for causing the greatest turmoil and disunity known to humankind. The<br />

Associationists noted, “These two societies being the periods of the initiation<br />

and apprenticeship of Humanity in Industry, are the most miserable<br />

that can exist on the earth during the whole career of mankind.” 7 The<br />

Harbinger reserved its most stinging criticism for Civilization, with its<br />

isolated households and its separation of families, so favorable<br />

to that spirit of individualism and selfishness which draws and<br />

concentrates every thing within itself; its false system of commerce,<br />

furnishing such admirable facilities for trick and fraud<br />

and overreaching; its oppressive modes of industry which enable<br />

those who have capital to take advantage of the laboring<br />

masses, who have none, and to live and grow rich upon the<br />

profits of their toil; its unnatural system of law, which affords<br />

a few an opportunity of fattening upon the moral carrion or<br />

discords of society; its political parties and feuds, where ‘to<br />

the victors belongs the spoils;’ its different sects in religion, the<br />

members of which strive to obtain even heaven isolatedly and<br />

for themselves, leaving those of other sects to sink into perdition<br />

in the world to come with the same indifference that they<br />

leave them to sink into poverty and misery in this. 8<br />

Associationists argued that in the various spheres of life — familial, economic,<br />

governmental, and religious — Civilization organized society<br />

along selfish lines rather than in the spirit of universalism. They viewed<br />

the root of their society’s problems as Civilization, not capitalism.<br />

According to Associationists, Civilization caused capitalism to function<br />

in opposition to the principles of universalism. They complained,<br />

“The present false and unorganized system of Industry is the fundamental<br />

cause of the majority of evils which oppress the working-classes, who<br />

compose three fourths of the population.” 9 Associationists found it particularly<br />

egregious that Civilization marginalized those who produced<br />

all the wealth in society: the laborers. The Harbinger stated, “By its unjust<br />

division of profits, giving the fruit of labor to those who do not produce<br />

it, it presents the monstrous anomaly of the increase of poverty among<br />

the producing classes in proportion to the increases of national wealth.” 10<br />

Under Civilization, the wealth of a few capitalists depended on the misery<br />

of the entire working class. Associationists described the condition of<br />

labor as “monotonous and ill-requited, and it overwhelms with excessive<br />

toil those engaged in it, — debarring them from the advantages of mental<br />

culture.” 11 Associationists argued that Civilization committed one of its<br />

greatest crimes in denying intellectual enrichment to laborers.<br />

American Fourierism<br />

99


100<br />

The Associationists’ dedication to universalism informed their general<br />

approach to social reform. Instead of campaigning solely on behalf<br />

of the most oppressed layer, the laboring class, Associationists sought to<br />

represent all of society, including the capitalists. They wrote, “If we do<br />

not address ourselves to working men exclusively . . . it is because we<br />

know that this reform concerns the whole of humanity, not a part, or<br />

a fraction. We advocate it on universal principles . . . The present organization<br />

of labor is the curse of society; that no class of men can do<br />

justice to their nature in the actual condition of industry.” 12 Because of<br />

the severity of the oppression under Civilization, Associationists argued,<br />

it negatively impacted even the most privileged layers of society. In this<br />

sense, their trans-class program flowed more from a condemnation of the<br />

current order than a conciliation of it. Associationists believed that, in a<br />

well-organized society, capitalists would behave justly.<br />

Facing criticism from all sides, Associationists worked hard to<br />

clarify their position on capitalism to the public. On the one hand,<br />

Associationists had to squash the rumor that they opposed private property.<br />

The Associationists quoted leading Fourierist Parke Godwin who<br />

said, “What man thus derives from his labor, may with peculiar propriety<br />

be said to be his: it is that which, without him, would not have<br />

existed . . . it is his property, his goods, his right to capital.” They directly<br />

followed this quote with a clear statement of their position on private<br />

property: “Here is certainly a refutation of the charge of agrarianism.<br />

Association promises as much security and as complete identity of<br />

Property, as does the present social organization.” 13 On the other hand,<br />

Associationists had to convince social reformers of capitalism’s potential<br />

equitability. Anticipating criticism, they stated, “Some may object<br />

to giving capital any interest. But what is Capital? ... Capital is nothing<br />

but Labor which has been accumulated and rendered permanent, so that<br />

in fact all property is Labor.” 14 In this way, capital simply represented<br />

labor in a different stage.<br />

Fourierists promised that under Association, capitalism would not<br />

conflict with universalism but rather guarantee it. For Associationists, the<br />

only remedy rested “in producing a union between capital and labor,” in<br />

which “the man who labors with the machine must share its profits, as well<br />

as the man who owns it.” 15 Association would maintain the existence of<br />

separate classes but moderate the profits of capitalists. As The Harbinger explained,<br />

“In an Association, employment and compensation are provided<br />

for all who labor, in the very basis of its organization.” 16 Detailing a plan<br />

Associationists found favorable, the paper proclaimed, “A certain portion<br />

of the product, — such as shall be found mathematically just — will be<br />

awarded to those who hold the stock, — that is to those whose labor made<br />

the improvements, and this will be the interest upon their capital.” 17 In<br />

compensating people according to their efforts, capitalism — in their view<br />

— would function in a fairer fashion than collectivized property forms. The<br />

MARYAN SOLIMAN


kind of society they envisioned rested on the modern industry of capitalism<br />

but differed greatly in the distribution of wealth. In a sense, the profitsharing<br />

system they described resembled nothing close to capitalism.<br />

Capitalism under Association would also advance universal goals<br />

by improving the very condition of labor. In responding to a question<br />

about their purpose, they stated, “Let us answer in a few words, — by<br />

the systematic organization of labor, to make it more efficient, productive<br />

and attractive; in this way, to provide for the abundant gratification<br />

of all the intellectual, moral, and physical wants of every member of the<br />

Association.” 18 When Association took hold, society would replace the<br />

monotonous work characterizing Civilization with gratifying labor or<br />

“Attractive Industry.” Capitalism’s technological innovations could potentially<br />

save laborers time and energy which they could devote to their creative<br />

pursuits. If organized in a more harmonious way, capitalism could<br />

end the degradation of labor. Driven by a humanist goal to make life<br />

more fulfilling for all human beings, Associationists set out to transform<br />

their society.<br />

Articles in The Harbinger reveal that Associationists rejected violent<br />

revolution as a means for bringing about social change because it conflicted<br />

with their universal outlook. The introductory notice to The Harbinger<br />

described the Associationist motto as “the elevation of the whole human<br />

race, in mind, morals and manners,” not by “violent outbreaks and revolutionary<br />

agitations, but orderly and progressive reform.” 19 The Harbinger’s<br />

endorsement of progressive reform over revolution indicates both the<br />

Associationists’ rejection of any movement based solely on a single segment<br />

of society and their belief in the universal acceptance of a program<br />

representative of the entire population.<br />

Associationists also believed that God had predestined the triumph of<br />

universalism. In a typical statement from the Associationists, The Harbinger<br />

expressed, “The universal Association of Humanity must some day take<br />

place, for Humanity is a child of God, and as such, must fulfill the Laws<br />

of its Author; and the will and the Law of God are Universal Unity, peace<br />

and harmony, expressed eternally in universal Association.” 20 Their opposition<br />

to violent revolution did not bespeak conservatism as much as<br />

it underlined their total faith and confidence in their universal program.<br />

This did not mean, however, that they left the task of establishing a new<br />

society up to either fate or circumstance.<br />

In an article written in opposition to well-known secular communitarian<br />

Robert Owen, the Associationists explained their belief in human agency.<br />

They wrote, “[Owen] believes all men wholly creatures of circumstance, and<br />

therefore they of themselves can do nothing towards forming their own convictions,<br />

feelings or characters, and are neither rewardable nor punishable.” 21<br />

Associationists, on the other hand, believed “that some are eminently masters<br />

of circumstances, the mass inferior to circumstances, but no one wholly<br />

American Fourierism<br />

101


102<br />

unable to affect his own feelings, opinions, convictions, and character, for<br />

better or worse.” 22 Associationists argued that in eliminating human accountability,<br />

social reformers also erased the human ability to change society.<br />

Rather than wait for history to take its course, Fourier and<br />

Associationists sought to inspire people to reach Harmony sooner rather<br />

than later. In trying to convert others to their cause, Associationists stated,<br />

“Mankind are prepared, society is prepared, to enter upon the epoch of<br />

social unity and harmony, — the true, natural, and organic social condition<br />

of Humanity . . . Let us hasten the advent of this glorious epoch; let<br />

us labor for the great social Reformation which is to usher it in.” 23 For<br />

Associationists, people could enjoy the Harmonious order for a longer<br />

period if the human race skipped the several stages between Civilization<br />

and Harmony. This leap only required people to follow Fourier’s blueprint<br />

for the establishment of model communities or Phalanxes. 24<br />

When Associationists sought to transform this plan into reality, their<br />

equal reliance on all classes disappeared. Associationists searched for<br />

leaders for their movement. They wrote, “The times are more than ripe<br />

for [Harmony], and it is the political ignorance and littleness, the selfishness<br />

and apathy of the leaders of the world only, that prevent it. It wants<br />

new leaders to do the glorious and sacred work. Let them arise and be<br />

about it.” 25 The leaders whom Associationists had in mind came from the<br />

middle class. The Harbinger ran an article explaining the difference in the<br />

circumstances Fourier encountered in France and those that existed in<br />

America. According to the Associationists, Fourier courted the capitalist<br />

class to establish Phalanxes because he had no middle class of real wealth<br />

and intelligence to address. They wrote:<br />

The case is entirely different in our own country. It is not necessary<br />

with us to court the favor of enormous capitalists, who,<br />

with the rarest exceptions, are the last men to approve of novel<br />

movements for the general good . . . We depend on the intelligence,<br />

the sense of justice . . . the practical skill and energy,<br />

and the material resources, which will be consecrated to this<br />

cause, by the great middling classes of American society. 26<br />

Associationists acknowledged that the great profits enjoyed by the top<br />

capitalists made it less likely for them to part with the present order. In<br />

choosing their leaders, Associationists seemed to choose Robert Owen’s<br />

approach of highlighting circumstances over the Associationist belief that<br />

individuals from all classes would readily accept Association.<br />

Associationist work around labor reform illustrates the nuance of<br />

Association’s universal program. While Associationists motivated the<br />

“complete association of all interests and all classes,” in practice they supported<br />

an organization representing only the working class. 27 They explained,<br />

“That the tendency is downwards, to a state of abject vassalage<br />

among the masses . . . is too apparent for denial, whatever may be the<br />

outside show of a temporary prosperity [and] the venal representations of<br />

MARYAN SOLIMAN


parties interested in the triumph of Capital over Labor.” Moreover, they<br />

continued, “The Workingmen must help themselves, or we fear there are<br />

none to help them.” 28 For Associationists, extreme conditions demanded<br />

they set aside their method of organizing on behalf of all classes. The<br />

capitalist class had its parties. Associationists drew the conclusion that if<br />

they wanted to see the working class gain any kind of hearing, they would<br />

have to help organize it. In this way, their universal outlook did not prevent<br />

them from taking a side with the lower classes. In order to achieve<br />

universal ends, Associationists conceded they had to forgo, at least temporarily,<br />

certain universal means.<br />

With similar logic, Associationists called on the government to intervene<br />

on the side of the working class. Reporting on a Fourth of July<br />

function, The Harbinger described an Associationist speaker to have shown<br />

“that the negative basis of our Government, (which only steps in as an<br />

arbiter between individuals, but holds itself aloof from the industrial operations<br />

of the country,) should be changed to a positive basis, which would<br />

secure all the blessings we now enjoy, from political liberty, and at the<br />

same time, give to the laboring classes a guaranty of social independence<br />

and comfort, which now they do not possess.” 29 Because Associationists<br />

believed the working class occupied such lowly ground, government aid<br />

to laborers would not compromise universalism, but rather would level<br />

the playing field.<br />

American Fourierism<br />

103<br />

However, according to Associationists, government in their era had<br />

gone in the opposite direction of universalism, giving in to local and regional<br />

ruling cliques. The Associationists wrote:<br />

The views held upon [the questions of tariff and currency]<br />

are but the reflected images of the conflicting interests which<br />

divide society into contending factions. Politicians represent<br />

merely local and partial interests, and hence they are but the<br />

organs or the instruments to express opinions that coincide<br />

with them. The questions will never be settled on a permanent<br />

basis until the voice of united interests prevails in legislation. 30<br />

Associationists prescribed universalism as the cure to the political issues of<br />

their day, such as tariffs and currency.<br />

Associationists especially condemned government for allowing the<br />

continuation of slavery. They stated with regret, “[Texas Annexation] is<br />

pressed to a speedy consummation with all the warmth of a slave-holding<br />

rapacity . . . [and] we see no possibility of averting this shameless usurpation.<br />

Viewed in some lights, we hold the act of Annexation to be a highhanded<br />

crime, which stamps on the National Escutcheon an indelible<br />

stigma and reproach.” 31 Associationists complained that government had<br />

permitted a handful of slaveholders to turn America into an increasingly<br />

exploitive society. In the Associationist schema, slavery signified an outmoded<br />

remnant of older stages of human history. Discussing the eradication<br />

of slavery, they wrote:


104<br />

That means exist for attaining this end, we must believe, if<br />

we have faith in God and his providence, for Slavery could<br />

only exist upon earth (except during the period of the political<br />

and social infancy of mankind, as exception in human destiny<br />

and under the reign of inverse Providence) in virtue of a<br />

high universal principle, having its origin in the plan of Divine<br />

Government; and who will say that God rules the universe by<br />

despotism and that the worlds are his slaves. 32<br />

Their belief in a universal god helped Associationists continue in the fight<br />

against slavery, despite their government’s efforts not only to delay the<br />

abolition of slavery but to extend it to new territories.<br />

Associationists directed their comments on slavery not to their government,<br />

but to the abolitionist movement of their day — as part of an effort to<br />

win their peers to universalism. As The Harbinger stated, “We believe that the<br />

time has arrived or nearly so for the abolition movement to rise to its universality<br />

and to direct its labors against universal servitude.” 33 Associationists<br />

identified nine varieties of servitude: chattel slavery, serfdom, wage slavery,<br />

domestic servitude, slavery of caste, sale of women, military conscription,<br />

perpetual monastic vows, and indigence. They urged abolitionists to fight<br />

against all forms of servitude, but demanded that the movement oppose<br />

at least the two kinds of slavery most prevalent in America: chattel slavery<br />

in the South and wage slavery in the North. As they stated, “Abolitionists<br />

should also look carefully to the question of an Industrial Reform and the<br />

Organization of Labor; for when they have freed the slaves and elevated<br />

them to the condition of hired laborers, — the serfs of capital and want,<br />

— they cannot leave them there, as they will be obliged to do, unless a better<br />

system of Labor is established than that which now exists.” 34 In other<br />

words, enslaved blacks would go from one form of slavery to another. As<br />

Associationists argued, true emancipation would only come to pass if social<br />

reformers eradicated both chattel and wage slavery.<br />

Associationists paid particular attention to the question of women’s<br />

oppression. The Associationists quoted Fourier’s axiom: “Social progress is in<br />

proportion to the progress of woman towards liberty, and the decline of the social order<br />

in proportion to the diminution of that liberty.” 35 According to Associationists,<br />

under Civilization, women had advanced to a position of half-freedom.<br />

Before marriage, law considered women equal to men, except in politics,<br />

allowing them to own property and control their actions. Once married,<br />

women descended “from free-women into slaves.” Detailing women’s<br />

position under marriage, they wrote, “Many of them do not bear their<br />

own names, but are called by the names of their legal masters; they are<br />

in a state of perpetual minority, and cannot dispose of anything which<br />

belongs to them, not even of the products of their own labor.” 36 As such,<br />

Fourierists viewed women as one of the most oppressed laborers.<br />

Moreover, Associationists argued, social reformers could not resolve<br />

the condition of domestic servants without addressing the larger<br />

issue of the family. Describing the condition of female servants, they<br />

MARYAN SOLIMAN


American Fourierism<br />

105<br />

wrote, “The physical wants of the Servant are generally better supplied<br />

than those of any other class of working women . . . But of the intellectual<br />

and moral advantages of the Servant Girls we have nothing favorable<br />

to say.” 37 The root of the problem, according to the Associationists,<br />

rested in the fact that:<br />

they are of the family, yet apart from it . . . therefore they<br />

are left to live in ignorance and complete isolation from those<br />

whose happiness and peace are so intimately interwoven with<br />

theirs . . . This separation of interests among members of<br />

the same family is the great curse of private life. Suspicion,<br />

treachery, meanness, fraud, oppression, hatred, malice, and<br />

revenge are its inevitable consequences; and under these<br />

malign influences what wonder is it that servants grow to be<br />

what they are generally and unhesitatingly denounced, even<br />

in their very presence — pests and curses? 38<br />

Without tackling the selfish organization of the family, Associationists believed<br />

social reformers could have little hope in curing the severe ailments<br />

of domestic servitude.<br />

Associationist universalism in regards to the family meant unity and<br />

cooperation within families and between families. In the face of harsh<br />

charges regarding their position on the family, Associationists formulated<br />

their criticism by first making clear that they sought to improve upon,<br />

not destroy, the institution. For example, an article entitled “The Family<br />

Sphere” quoted leading American Fourierist Albert Brisbane stating:<br />

Neither does the practical experiment thus far show, what so<br />

many have dreaded, a tendency to the loosening of family ties.<br />

On the contrary, some, at least, of these Associationists think,<br />

that husbands and wives become more relying, more courteous,<br />

less arbitrary and selfish . . . And in regard to children, as<br />

the Association takes somewhat the attitude of critic of their<br />

faults, the parent becomes rather the confidant, and trustful<br />

fosterer of their virtues, and fills the place to which instinct on<br />

both sides prompts, of bosom friend. 39<br />

Associationists struck a balance between criticizing the family and improving<br />

upon it. Their criticisms had to do with the selfishness fostered by<br />

the current structure; their solutions related to the great improvements in<br />

familial relationships promised by a truly cooperative society.<br />

Associationists’ equal treatment of men and women fell apart when<br />

they broached the question of social and moral reform. Associationists<br />

supported both criminal and temperance reforms, but in dealing with<br />

these issues, they always directed social reformers to treat the root of the<br />

problem. They wrote, “The cure of crime, however, will be found to need<br />

first, the negative course of removing the bad influences which lead to<br />

unmanliness; but second and chiefly, the positive course of securing opportunities<br />

for upright action. We must drain off impurities breeding miasma.”<br />

40 Associationists placed social problems in gendered terms, equating<br />

vice with unmanliness. They openly held the position that woman’s<br />

nature prevented her from happily engaging in carnal activity: “Women


106<br />

are far more affectionate, far less animal, than men . . . No women except the<br />

poor creatures whose profession is self abandonment, give themselves up<br />

bodily, where the heart is unmoved . . . But men, by the thousands, like<br />

beasts of prey, absolutely hunt for victims to gratify their merely brutal<br />

instincts.” 41 Associationists, therefore, made great efforts to represent men<br />

as beasts in order to distinguish them from women.<br />

With this gender divide in place, Associationists found it only natural<br />

to assign women the task of social regeneration. As they proclaimed, “In<br />

every city and town let there be in some form or other, varying according<br />

to the population and the degree of social intimacy prevailing, a SENATE<br />

OF WOMEN, who shall practically enact and enforce laws of manners, and<br />

declare who is, and who is not worthy of confidence.” 42 Associationists<br />

may have exercised the same thought process in devising their position on<br />

women as they did their stance on laborers. In this way, they would have<br />

reasoned that, because women occupied such a severely low position in<br />

society, special attention toward them did not violate universalism, but<br />

rather worked to place women on a level playing field with men. However,<br />

unlike with their position on workers, Associationists did not provide such<br />

a rationale for their various stances on women. In fact, the articles in The<br />

Harbinger indicated Associationists simply saw women as fundamentally<br />

different from men on a social and physiological level.<br />

This essay has focused more on the ideas than the practices of<br />

Associationists. Associationists developed a number of Phalanxes and The<br />

Harbinger reported on the progress of each one. The newspaper also gave<br />

advice. For example, as one writer noted:<br />

One successful attempt to embody the principles of Association,<br />

would guarantee the complete triumph of the movement<br />

in the United <strong>State</strong>s . . . A rare combination of fortunate circumstances<br />

must exist, before a new Association can be established,<br />

with any rational hope of prosperity. Abundance<br />

of capital, a favorable location, scientific knowledge, practical<br />

skill are all indispensable; but still more indispensable, are<br />

true-hearted men and women, deeply convinced of the sacredness,<br />

the religiousness of the movement. 43<br />

Associationists did not concern themselves solely with ideas and ideals; they<br />

tried to transform their vision into a reality and they worried about how society<br />

would arrive at Association. Scholars have done well to document life<br />

on the Phalanxes. However, the historical studies on Association have tended<br />

to inflate the Associationists’ pro-capitalist positions to the point of diminishing<br />

the extent to which Fourierists sought to change their society. This<br />

study, in the spirit of historian Carl Guarneri’s work, helps to correct that<br />

distortion by returning to the words and thoughts of the Associationists.<br />

Historians must consult the literature of the Associationists if they hope to<br />

gain a clearer picture of these fascinating men and women.<br />

MARYAN SOLIMAN


American Fourierism<br />

107<br />

01<br />

The Harbinger spanned the years 1845 to 1849. The cover page of the first bound<br />

<strong>volume</strong> reads: “The Harbinger, Devoted to Social and Political Progress. ‘All things, at the present<br />

day, stand provided and prepared, and await the light.’ Vol I. Published by the Brook Farm<br />

Phalanx. New-York: Burgess, Stringer, and Company. Boston: Redding and Company.” New<br />

York became the headquarters for the publication in 1847, after a fire at Brook Farm on March<br />

3, 1846 led to the termination of that phalanx.<br />

02<br />

See Arthur Eugene Bestor, Jr., Backwoods Utopias: The Sectarian and Owenite Phases of<br />

Communitarian Socialism in America, 1663-1829 (Philadelphia: <strong>University</strong> of Pennsylvania Press,<br />

1959) and Ronald G. Walters, American Reformers 1815-1860 (New York: Hill and Wang, 1995).<br />

03<br />

See Carl J. Guarneri, The Utopian Alternative: Fourierism in Nineteenth-Century America<br />

(Ithaca: Cornell <strong>University</strong> Press, 1991).<br />

04<br />

“The Collective Unity, or the Organization of the Township,” The Harbinger, July<br />

12, 1845.<br />

05<br />

Ibid.<br />

06<br />

Ibid.<br />

07<br />

“The Collective Unity, No. II,” The Harbinger, August 16, 1845.<br />

08<br />

“The Collective Unity, or the Organization of the Township,” The Harbinger, July<br />

12, 1845.<br />

09<br />

“What Do the Workingmen Want?” The Harbinger, July 5, 1845.<br />

10<br />

Ibid.<br />

11<br />

Ibid..<br />

12<br />

“The Working Men’s Movement,” The Harbinger, July 12, 1845.<br />

13<br />

“Fourierism,” The Harbinger, October 11, 1845.<br />

14<br />

“Reform Movements Originating Among the Producing Classes,” The Harbinger,<br />

January 24, 1846.<br />

15<br />

“Influence of Machinery,” The Harbinger, June 14, 1845.<br />

16<br />

“Fourierism,” The Harbinger, October 11, 1845.<br />

17<br />

“Reform Movements Originating Among the Producing Classes,” The Harbinger, January<br />

24, 1846.<br />

18<br />

“What Do You Propose?” The Harbinger, June 28, 1845.<br />

19<br />

“Introductory Notice,” The Harbinger, June 14, 1845.<br />

20<br />

“Association,” The Harbinger, January 10, 1846.<br />

21<br />

“Robert Owen at Hopedale,” Practical Christian, reproduced in The Harbinger, December<br />

13, 1845.<br />

22<br />

Ibid.<br />

23<br />

“The Collective Unity, No. II,” The Harbinger, August 16, 1845.<br />

24<br />

Guarneri, The Utopian Alternative, 18.<br />

25<br />

“The Collective Unity, No. II,” The Harbinger, August 16, 1845.<br />

26<br />

“Association in this Country,” The Harbinger, February 28, 1846.<br />

27<br />

“Social Movements in Germany,” The Harbinger, July 19, 1845.<br />

28<br />

“The Workingmen’s Protective Union,” The Harbinger, December 13, 1845.<br />

29<br />

“The Fourth of July at Woburn,” The Harbinger, July 12, 1845.<br />

30<br />

“The President’s Message,” The Harbinger, December 13, 1845.<br />

31<br />

Ibid.<br />

32<br />

“The Question of Slavery,” The Harbinger, June 21, 1845.<br />

33<br />

Ibid.<br />

34<br />

“What Do the Workingmen Want?” The Harbinger, July 5, 1845.<br />

35<br />

“The Women of the Boston Anti-Slavery Fair,” The Harbinger, October 4, 1845.<br />

36 Ibid.<br />

NOTES


108<br />

37<br />

“Labor in New York: Its Circumstances, No. XX: Domestic Servitude,” Tribune, reproduced<br />

in The Harbinger, December 13, 1845.<br />

38<br />

Ibid.<br />

39<br />

“The Family Sphere,” The Harbinger, July 12, 1845.<br />

40<br />

“Moral Reform,” The Harbinger, August 2, 1845.<br />

41<br />

Ibid.<br />

42<br />

Ibid.<br />

43<br />

“Association in the West: The Integral Phalanx,” The Harbinger, July 19, 1845.<br />

MARYAN SOLIMAN


the Revitalization of<br />

T A C T I C A L D E B A T E I N T H E<br />

C O N V E N T I O N O F 1 8 4 3<br />

F\<br />

L E A H Thompson


eex<br />

post<br />

efacto


group of African American activists convened in 1830 to discuss<br />

tactics for calming racial tensions, including the possibility of expatriation.<br />

What began as a single-issue organization, evolved into a forum for multisubject<br />

debate, and established a precedent for annual national meetings.<br />

Twelve National Conventions for free people of color assembled between<br />

1830 and the end of the Civil War. Howard H. Bell’s 1957 article,<br />

“National Negro Conventions of the Middle 1840’s: Moral Suasion vs.<br />

Political Action,” introduced the significance of the convention movement<br />

to historians. Bell argued that the Conventions of the 1840s illustrated a<br />

turn towards independent black voices, absent in the thirties, whose political<br />

action and militant tactics began to compete with moral suasion as the<br />

most expedient method of abolishing slavery. 1 A<br />

Unfortunately historians<br />

have overlooked Bell’s contribution, failing to incorporate the convention<br />

movement in their synthetic works on abolition. This oversight reinforces<br />

the prevailing assumption that militance in the abolition movement began<br />

in the 1850s after the passage of the Fugitive Slave Act. Bell accurately<br />

assessed the effects of the conventions of the 1840s, however, he failed<br />

to account for the longstanding tradition of resistance in the free black<br />

community. The convention movement of the 1840s does not represent a<br />

turn towards militance in the abolition movement; rather the conventions<br />

mark a return to a strong culture of resistance long alive in the black community<br />

of the early republic.<br />

111


112<br />

In the 1970s, two major pieces of antebellum scholarship joined a<br />

growing body of work on the complex reformers of the pre-Civil War era.<br />

Unfortunately for readers, neither Ronald Walters’s American Reformers:<br />

1815-1860 nor James Brewer Stewart’s Holy Warriors: The Abolitionists and<br />

American Slavery presented a full picture of the true scope of the movement<br />

to end slavery. 2 Walters and Stewart, while offering detailed synthetic<br />

works on abolition and reform in general, chose to focus on the role of<br />

white reformers in abolition. Walters wholly overlooked the convention<br />

movement in American Reformers, while Stewart’s Holy Warriors only briefly<br />

mentions the convention movement’s significance in allowing blacks to<br />

lead themselves at a time when discrimination within the overarching<br />

movement ran rampant. The intellectual origins of militancy were limited<br />

to Stewart’s brief recognition of the importance of Garnet’s call for insurrection.<br />

By not fully incorporating Bell’s contribution into their syntheses,<br />

Walters’s and Stewart’s books tell an incomplete tale in which the Fugitive<br />

Slave Act appeared as the sole important precursor to more militant actions<br />

in the 1850s. Both historians took greater interest in investigating<br />

the motives, social status, and tactics of the white reformers who took on<br />

the causes of those they considered less fortunate, rather than exploring<br />

the struggle of blacks in the process of self-liberation. Only later would<br />

historians more fully recognize the rich intellectual discourse occurring on<br />

the topic of militancy.<br />

The first step in this process was the rediscovery and revision of black<br />

revolutionary, David Walker. Peter P. Hinks’s biography of David Walker,<br />

To Awaken My Afflicted Brethren: David Walker and the Problem of Antebellum Slave<br />

Resistance excavated the much ignored intricacies of black political and<br />

intellectual culture and illuminated the effects of this culture on David<br />

Walker. Before Hinks’s addition to the historiography, Walker was often<br />

referenced as the sole example of black militancy before the Fugitive Slave<br />

Act of 1850. Hinks argued, however, that Walker, best known for his 1829,<br />

Appeal to the Colored Citizens of the World, was one of many examples<br />

of a tradition of militancy in early abolition and a product of a rich intellectual<br />

and political culture of resistance.<br />

Contrary to the works of Walters and Stewart, Hinks argued, “the<br />

years 1800-1831 comprised the period of the most active and carefully<br />

planned slave conspiring and rebelling in American history.” 3 Born a free<br />

black in New Hanover County, North Carolina where blacks constituted<br />

a majority of the population, this experience informed Walker’s life long<br />

frustration with the subordination of enslaved blacks in situations where<br />

they outnumbered whites. Despite his commitments to the Methodist community<br />

in his area, economic conditions drove Walker toward Charleston<br />

where he sought a livable wage and opportunity to “clarify the meaning<br />

of his blackness and freedom in a world dominated by slavery.” 4 Hinks<br />

examined how Denmark Vesey’s failed insurrection of 1822 played a role<br />

in Walker’s life in “Vesey’s Charleston.” Hinks posed the likelihood that<br />

LEAH THOMPSON


Walker experienced his first lessons in organizing during the four years<br />

Vesey plotted his rebellion. Hinks showed Vesey’s influence on Walker,<br />

examining their similar beliefs that God was the creator of equal rights.<br />

Hinks wrote, “For both Walker and Vesey, evangelical notions not only<br />

happened to correspond with a theory of natural rights but were in fact<br />

integrally bound together, working always to exalt their ultimate source,<br />

the Christian Deity. Republicanism was divinely ordained.” 5 While intellectual<br />

history has traced the origins of many of Walker’s ideas to earlier<br />

sources, his Appeal continues to be considered revolutionary for its time,<br />

showing the conflict inherent in the alignment of slavery and republicanism<br />

in American society. Peter P. Hinks found, “This was not a problem<br />

that had escaped the attention of white thinkers and orators since the days<br />

of the Revolution, but for an African American to come forward and ridicule<br />

and accuse American pretensions was a bold and, possibly dangerous<br />

action, even in the late 1820s.” 6 Through depicting the short life of David<br />

Walker, Hinks has more fully elucidated a rich African American political<br />

and intellectual culture that combined religion and militant ideas to<br />

formulate a strong belief in republicanism ordained by God. This culture<br />

far predated the 1850s where many historians have oriented the origins of<br />

the abolitionist movement.<br />

With a few notable exceptions, most abolition scholarship has portrayed<br />

anti-slavery activity as truly awakening in 1831. This awakening<br />

has traditionally been attributed to William Lloyd Garrison who in 1831<br />

promised to “lift up the standard of emancipation in the eyes of the nation,<br />

within the sight of Bunker Hill and in the birth place of liberty,”<br />

with the first publication of his newspaper, The Liberator. 7 A new trend<br />

towards “immediatism” was associated with Garrison’s arrival at the forefront<br />

of the movement. Garrison’s immediatism was characterized by his<br />

devout religious belief in Christian perfection and the tactics of moral<br />

suasion. Henry Mayer’s 1998 biography of Garrison, All on Fire: William<br />

Lloyd Garrison and the Abolition of Slavery has added greater contextualization<br />

to Garrison’s life and influences. While most abolitionist texts delineated<br />

a complete disconnect between the work of David Walker and the abolition<br />

movement that Garrison inspired, Mayer and historian Donald M.<br />

Jacobs, in the collection Courage and Conscience: Black and White Abolitionists<br />

in Boston, have begun to show an intellectual and communal connection<br />

between the two figures. Mayer argued that Garrison never fully discounted<br />

David Walker’s ideas “that both appalled and fascinated Garrison.” 8<br />

Moreover, Mayer described Garrison’s relationship with Walker’s ideas,<br />

arguing, “Garrison paid close attention to the ambivalent emotions that<br />

swirled through the Appeal and appreciated Walker’s ‘seasonable warnings’<br />

that an uprising could be averted through white repentance and the abolition<br />

of slavery.” 9 David Walker met an early death in 1830, and therefore<br />

was absent from debates following the insurrection of Nat Turner. For<br />

many moral suasionists, this insurrection embodied the words of David<br />

Revitalization of Tactical Debate in the Convention of 1843<br />

113


114<br />

Walker, and therefore the Appeal’s moderate initial reception was quickly<br />

sidelined by the emerging powers of the abolition movement. While never<br />

condemning Walker, the reality of the insurrection was something the<br />

pacifistic Garrison was unable to condone.<br />

Donald M. Jacobs argued in his article “David Walker and William<br />

Lloyd Garrison: Racial Cooperation and the Shaping of Boston<br />

Abolition,” that while Garrison was a significant character in abolition,<br />

he has been for too long “historically perceived as the leading figure of the<br />

national abolition movement, creating and shaping it in his own image.”<br />

Jacobs’s article showed how Garrison recognized Walker’s preeminence<br />

in the black community of Boston; to garner support in that community,<br />

Garrison had to seriously consider Walkers ideas, which “resulted in the<br />

stance he began to adopt on colonization, racial intermarriage, black<br />

unity, and even the question of the Appeal’s authorship, all in spite of<br />

Walker’s support of blacks’ using any means necessary to gain their freedom.”<br />

10 Jacobs’s pivotal article, showed how even Garrison was a part<br />

of a large community of abolitionists, and a long tradition of resistance<br />

— Garrison’s ideas were not his alone.<br />

Finally, Richard S. Newman’s The Transformation of American Abolitionism:<br />

Fighting Slavery in the Early Republic explored the active abolition movement<br />

present in the early days of the republic. In a chapter titled, “An Appeal to<br />

the Heart: The Black Protest Tradition and the Coming of Immediatism,”<br />

Newman fully investigated the rich tradition of resistance and militancy<br />

present in the black community long before the notion of moral suasion<br />

came to the fore. He opened his chapter with the fiery argument,<br />

William Lloyd Garrison uttered perhaps the most ironic words<br />

in antebellum American history when he proclaimed in 1831,<br />

“I will be heard.” For though the young Massachusetts printer<br />

had only recently announced his fiery abolitionist strategy<br />

of “Immediatism,” black activists had long demanded that<br />

Americans end slavery.” 11<br />

Often denied political rights such as the right to petition, black resistance<br />

cultivated literary activism in the form of the protest pamphlet.<br />

Newman argued literary tactics were a way in which African Americans<br />

legitimated their “claims to universal freedom and equal citizenship.”<br />

12 Richard Allen’s 1800 pamphlet eulogized the death of George<br />

Washington and praised him for releasing his slaves, issuing the challenge:<br />

“May a double portion of Washington’s [emancipatory] spirit rest<br />

on the officers of the government of the United <strong>State</strong>s and the whole of<br />

the American people.” 13 Newman also quoted George Lawrence who<br />

in 1813 asked Americans<br />

‘if [they] are ignorant of their own Declaration,’ which proclaimed<br />

all men naturally free. If not ‘ignorant of it,’ he challenged,<br />

then ‘they must enforce’ the Declaration’s words (by<br />

completely and speedily abolishing slavery), for ‘this government<br />

is founded on principles of liberty and equality.’ 14<br />

LEAH THOMPSON


Recent developments in historiography depict a culture of resistance<br />

within the black community that utilized literary tactics and republican<br />

and religious rhetoric to critique the existence of slavery. This rich community<br />

and culture influenced both David Walker and William Lloyd<br />

Garrison, who would present this long tradition of black immediacy to<br />

white abolitionists in the 1830s.<br />

Excluded from most white antislavery organizations in the early<br />

republic, Newman showed how African American activists found original<br />

methods for combating slavery specific to their experiences. While<br />

Garrisonian abolitionists included black abolitionists to a greater extent in<br />

the 1830s, the initial promise of the “immediatists” faded as progressive<br />

change remained elusive. By the 1840s, many black abolitionists again<br />

sought greater autonomy in a movement overwhelmingly dominated by<br />

the discourse of moral suasion in the 1830s.<br />

Contrary to early abolition historiography highlighting the predominance<br />

of moral suasion tactics until the more militant responses to<br />

the Fugitive Slave Act of 1850, a revival of intellectual debate over the<br />

place of militance in the abolition movement resurfaced during the Negro<br />

Convention of 1843. The roots of this important resurgence lay not solely in<br />

the work of David Walker, but in a vibrant political and intellectual culture<br />

of resistance dating back to the revolutionary era. A community of black<br />

activists came of age during this era, powerfully critiquing slave power and<br />

Northern whites with revolutionary and religious rhetoric. 1850 was not the<br />

origin of militance in the abolition movement, but neither was the convention<br />

movement of the 1840s as Howard Bell argued. Bell served to awaken<br />

historians to the significance of the convention movement. However, this<br />

movement does not signify the origins of black independent power and<br />

militancy, but rather represents the reclamation of a powerful culture of<br />

resistance long present in the history of free blacks in the United <strong>State</strong>s.<br />

Every year from 1830 to 1835 a National Negro Convention convened<br />

in the United <strong>State</strong>s, but Howard Bell wrote, “the national conventions<br />

of the 1830’s were sometimes almost overrun by whites pleading a<br />

particular cause or offering gratuitous advice on a multiplicity of subjects.”<br />

15 Garrison’s brand of “moral suasion,” gave free black abolitionists<br />

hope in the 1830s and early 40s, and the necessity of a separate convention<br />

tapered off. However, by the early 40s, many free blacks rethought<br />

the radical nature of the white “immediatists.” As Garrison aligned his<br />

anti-slavery beliefs with pacifism and women’s rights, free blacks lamented<br />

that the struggle to end slavery no longer stood as the highest priority of<br />

Garrisonians. Many black activists sought freedom to act without the constraints<br />

of a large white-dominated movement. The intellectual debate<br />

of the 1840s reflected this reclamation of black agency within the abolitionist<br />

movement and reawakened sentiments, like that of David Walker,<br />

within the cause of abolition.<br />

Revitalization of Tactical Debate in the Convention of 1843<br />

115


116<br />

The call for the Convention of 1843 did not signal that black activists<br />

abandoned the work of Garrison and his followers, but rather that African<br />

Americans sought to create another organization capable of ensuring that<br />

their separate voice be heard in addition to their voice as part of a coalition<br />

with white activists. This represents an important difference between<br />

abolition of the 1830s and antislavery in the early republic, where blacks<br />

were almost never allowed to participate in the organizations of white<br />

abolitionists and often considered colonization the answer to the problem<br />

of slavery. The Conventions of the 1840s recognized the need for black<br />

activists to serve as part of a larger organization with whites, as well as<br />

ensure, through a separate entity, that issues important to their specific<br />

needs were debated.<br />

Representing the interests of over fifty black activists from seven<br />

states, a call was signed to resume holding an annual National Negro<br />

Convention in 1843. The Call for the Convention stated, “The history of<br />

the present and the past establish the great truth that it is as much impossible<br />

for any people to secure the enjoyment of their inalienable rights<br />

without organization, as it is to reach an end without means.” 16 The recognition<br />

of this need for black organization led the revival of the National<br />

Negro Convention Movement, on hold since 1835. The signers of the Call<br />

believed “since we have ceased to meet together in National Convention,<br />

we have become ignorant of the moral and intellectual strength of our<br />

people.” 17 The convention reinvigorated debate surrounding issues pertinent<br />

to the black community, including education, a free black press, and<br />

tactical methods for abolishing slavery. These issues embodied the overall<br />

theme of the convention; however, the necessity of a separate organization<br />

to ensure abolition remained paramount.<br />

Opening remarks by Buffalo resident Samuel H. Davis set the tone<br />

for the convention, reiterating the Call’s determination to reawaken the<br />

cause of abolition through organization. Davis asked, “What shall we do,”<br />

getting to the heart of the convention as a debate over means. Davis questioned<br />

the effectiveness of petitioning and political parties. He accused<br />

the Christian community of shielding within, “her pontifical robes…the<br />

horrid monster, slavery, with her very bosom — within her most sacred<br />

enclosures.” 18 Questioning the role of white activists in the antislavery<br />

movement, Davis asked, “Shall we then look to the abolitionists, and wait<br />

for them to give us our rights.” 19 The very existence of the convention<br />

answered his question in the negative, as he defined the purpose of the<br />

convention as allowing free black men to once again take on the task of<br />

freeing their enslaved brothers. Davis appreciated the white abolitionists’<br />

“exertions for the cause of truth and humanity,” however Davis argued,<br />

“If we are not willing to rise up and assert our rightful claims, and plead<br />

our own cause, we have no reason to look for success. We ourselves, must<br />

be willing to contend for the rich boon of freedom and equal rights…It is<br />

found only of them that seek.” 20 The exact avenues the free blacks would<br />

LEAH THOMPSON


utilize, however, thematically framed the convention.One man in particular,<br />

Henry Highland Garnet, called the slaves of the United <strong>State</strong>s<br />

to action, challenging the parameters of moral suasion and reviving an<br />

overdue debate.<br />

Representing Troy, New York, Henry Highland Garnet opened his<br />

Address to the Slaves of the United <strong>State</strong>s of America with a criticism of the<br />

National Convention, serving traditionally as a meeting place to “sympathize<br />

with each other and to weep over your [the slaves’] unhappy condition.”<br />

21 Garnet’s call to action sought to change and radicalize the function<br />

of the convention. Echoing Davis’s opening remarks, Garnet urged<br />

the delegates to no longer be “contented in sitting still and mourning over<br />

your sorrows, earnestly hoping that before this day, your sacred liberties<br />

would have been restored.” 22 The Address followed this stylistic pattern<br />

throughout, addressing the slaves all the while assuming black abolitionists<br />

would serve as its main listeners.<br />

Working within a long tradition of utilizing religious morality to critique<br />

slavery, Garnet stated,<br />

The voice of Freedom cried, ‘emancipated your Slaves.’ Humanity<br />

supplicated with tears for the deliverance of the children<br />

of Africa. Wisdom urged her solemn plea. The bleeding<br />

captive plead his innocence, and pointed to Christianity who<br />

stood weeping at the cross. Jehovah frowned upon the nefarious<br />

institution, and thunderbolts, red with vengeance, struggled<br />

to leap forth to blast the guilty wretches who maintained<br />

it. But all was in vain. Slavery had stretched its dark wings of<br />

death over the land. 23<br />

This scathing criticism met with Garnet’s criticism of those who submitted<br />

to slavery stating, “To such degradation it is sinful in the extreme for<br />

you to make voluntary submission.” 4 The institution of slavery required<br />

slaves to locate the highest power in their masters, denying slaves the right<br />

to submit to the true highest authority of God. The Convention minutes<br />

described how Garnet “reviewed the abominable system of slavery…its<br />

deeds of darkness and of death-how it robbed parents of children, and<br />

children of parents, husbands of wives; how it prostituted the daughters<br />

of the slaves; how it murdered the colored man.” 25 After listing the evils<br />

of slavery, Garnet stated the crux of his call to action, “Think how many<br />

tears you have poured out upon the soil which you have cultivated with<br />

unrequited toil, and enriched with your blood; and then go to your lordly<br />

enslavers, and tell them plainly, that you are determined to be free.” 26<br />

After asking their masters for freedom, if not obliged, Garnet called upon<br />

the slaves to perform an act of civil disobedience, demanding freedom<br />

through work stoppage.<br />

While often described as calling for insurrection, Garnet actually<br />

stated, “We do not advise you to attempt a revolution with the sword,<br />

because it would be INEXPEDIENT.” 27 Rather, Garnet believed work<br />

stoppage and subsequent submission to death, effectively responded<br />

Revitalization of Tactical Debate in the Convention of 1843<br />

117


118<br />

to the continuance of slavery. Historian Lewis Perry assessed Garnet’s<br />

rhetoric; “Its call to widespread insubordination, tempered by considerations<br />

of expediency, envisioned something more like mass civil disobedience<br />

than armed insurrection.” 28 Garnet’s evocation of revolutionary<br />

rhetoric, however, led many to assume he had only slightly masked his<br />

true call for insurrection.<br />

The spirit of the Revolutionary War did not solely invigorate white<br />

activists in the United <strong>State</strong>s, and Garnet’s Address reflected the legacy of<br />

revolution in African American slavery critiques. Invoking the rhetoric of<br />

the Revolution to rally his cause, Garnet derived many lines of his speech<br />

from the words of Patrick Henry, with Garnet restating, “In the name of<br />

the merciful God and by all that life is worth, let no longer be a debatable<br />

question, whether it is better to choose LIBERTY or DEATH.” 29 In his own<br />

words, Garnet recalled that colonists once blamed slavery upon England,<br />

and that they would rid themselves of it if they could.” 30 Time<br />

came for revolt, however, and the colonists’ sincerity was tested.<br />

After praising their “glorious document” Garnet asked if<br />

their slaves were emancipated, “No; they rather added new<br />

links to our chains. Were they ignorant of the principles of<br />

Liberty? Certainly they were not. 31<br />

These words call to memory the 1813 words of black activist George<br />

Lawrence who asked if Americans understood their own Declaration.<br />

The Revolutionary War was not the only instance of revolution active<br />

in the historical memory of African Americans in the antebellum era.<br />

Both the Haitian Revolution and failed slave insurrections recalled images<br />

of black power and resistance. Garnet praised the actions of historical<br />

black revolutionaries including Denmark Vesey and Joseph Cinque of<br />

the Amistad in the Address. Predicting a change in public opinion towards<br />

militant action, Garnet wrote of Nathaniel Turner, “his name has been<br />

recorded on the list of infamy, but future generations will number him<br />

among the noble and brave.” 32<br />

The Convention of 1843 represented a return to debate, but it did<br />

not signify a complete break from Garrison and the tactics of moral suasion.<br />

The revolutionary call of Garnet was too militant for many delegates<br />

in attendance. Frederick Douglass’s presence and influence represented<br />

the continued power of Garrison’s brand of immediatism. The convention<br />

minutes from 1843 described an audience moved to tears by Garnet’s<br />

speech, but Frederick Douglass quickly responded in opposition to the<br />

Address and a major debate ensued. Douglass believed a committee needed<br />

to modify Garnet’s Address before the convention voted to ratify or reject<br />

its sentiment. Douglass argued that the Address emphasized too much<br />

physical force, stating he was, “for trying the moral means a little longer.” 33<br />

While he concluded Garnet did not call for insurrection directly, Douglass<br />

believed the Address could incite armed rebellion and he did not want to<br />

give agency to such a violent uprising. After emerging from a committee<br />

LEAH THOMPSON


containing both Garnet and Douglass, the Address contained much of its<br />

original ideas, and those who originally opposed the Address decided not<br />

enough had been altered. The committee presented a resolution and put<br />

it to a vote,<br />

Resolved, That each member of this Convention who is friendly<br />

to the sentiments contained in this address, come forward and<br />

sign it in the name of the ever living God, and that measures<br />

be taken to print 1000 copies for circulation[.]<br />

After much debate, the resolution to accept and distribute received one<br />

more vote of nay than yea.<br />

Reinvigorated debate over Garnet’s ideas and militance in general was<br />

the legacy of the Convention of 1843. The hegemonic power the moral<br />

suasionists held over the abolitionist discourse since 1831 was challenged,<br />

and a more dynamic debate over tactics and the urgency of emancipation<br />

continued through the convention movement and the abolition presses.<br />

Garnet’s speech and those by militant activists before him, illustrated<br />

the historical memory of revolution in their calls to action, however both<br />

activists promoting greater militancy and the continuance of moral suasion<br />

invoked a duty to God in their argument. Garnet believed it was<br />

sinful to not resist enslavement. Moral suasionists utilized religious beliefs<br />

to a different end. A month after the convention, The Liberator published<br />

a critique of the convention. Written by white abolitionist Maria Weston<br />

Chapman, the article represented the feelings of many moral suasionists<br />

in the abolition movement. The author condemned Garnet’s address<br />

hoping it was an utterance prompted by the “stimulus of political meetings,<br />

for which men are afterward sorry,” rather than a morally defunct<br />

profession of great deliberation. Chapman believed Garnet’s speech was<br />

morally debasing and against the true power of God, declaring,<br />

It is a matter of thankfulness whenever the spirit of freedom<br />

and of good, — of love, forgiveness, and inagnanimity prevails,<br />

even in a single heart, over evil; hatred, force, revenge,<br />

and littleness. It did so, in a measure, at this Convention;<br />

— the address to the slaves, of the Reverend H.H. Garnet,<br />

expressing the idea that the time for insurrection had come,<br />

having been rejected. 34<br />

Chapman questioned the necessity of a separate convention, but wrote in<br />

The Liberator that she was thankful Douglass had taken the time to attend,<br />

keeping the bad counsel of Garnet from overpowering the convention.<br />

Chapman wrote,<br />

to the man of color, trust not the counsels that lead you to the<br />

shedding of blood. That man knows nothing of nature, human<br />

or Divine, — of character, — good or evil, who imagines that a<br />

civil and servile war would ultimately promote freedom. 35<br />

A turn towards insurrection or revolutionary ideas represented an evil call<br />

for revenge to Chapman, a different end for the use of religious rhetoric.<br />

Revitalization of Tactical Debate in the Convention of 1843<br />

119


120<br />

Garnet’s Address criticized slaves for their patience, yet Garrison and<br />

other “immediatists” reacted negatively to Garnet’s call to action. E.A.<br />

Marsh reported for The Liberator on Garnet’s speech, describing it as affirming<br />

“that abolitionists, who, by the bye, were very benevolent men,<br />

had done about all that they could do; that non-resistance was ridiculous;<br />

and not to be thought of, even for the present, by the slaves.” 36 After a<br />

long description and misrepresentation of the Address, Marsh critiqued<br />

Garnet who “seemed rather addressing a victorious army, than a gang<br />

of crushed and imbruted slaves, despoiled of all rights and without the<br />

means of successful resistance.” 37 The just nature and effectiveness of rebellion<br />

were just two questions asked of Garnet’s militant call. However,<br />

the ability of white abolitionists to passively await emancipation was the<br />

main critique of moral suasion inherent in Garnet’s Address. The success<br />

of the Convention of 1843 lay not in Garnet’s ability to sway abolitionists<br />

away from moral suasion. Rather, the convention institutionalized an<br />

organization for responding to concerns specific to the African American<br />

community, and reinvigorated the tactical debate on abolition.<br />

The National Convention of 1843 reopened abolition’s tactical<br />

discourse, after an unsatisfying decade of black adherence to the tactics<br />

of moral suasion. The results of this revitalized debate are observed in<br />

the conventions of the later 1840s. During the Convention of 1847, the<br />

term “moral suasion” was removed by vote from the convention’s report<br />

on abolition, favoring the concept of political action. Furthermore, the<br />

Cleveland National Convention of 1848 published Henry H. Garnet’s<br />

controversial Address to the Slaves of the United <strong>State</strong>s of America in a commemorative<br />

book alongside David Walker’s Appeal. Juxtaposed to Garnet’s initial<br />

mixed reception in 1843, this celebration of the works of Garnet and<br />

Walker highlighted an intellectual transition within the black community,<br />

illustrating a return to a rich tradition of resistance and tactical debate.<br />

LEAH THOMPSON


Revitalization of Tactical Debate in the Convention of 1843<br />

121<br />

NOTES<br />

01<br />

Howard H. Bell, “National Negro Conventions of the Middle 1840’s: Moral Suasion<br />

vs. Political Action, Journal of Negro History 42, no. 4 (October 1957): 260.<br />

02<br />

Ronald G. Walters, American Reformers: 1815-1860 (New York: Hill and Wang, 1978)<br />

and James Brewer Stewart, Holy Warriors: The Abolitionists and American Slavery (New York: Hill<br />

and Wang, 1976).<br />

03<br />

Peter P. Hinks, To Awaken My Afflicted Brethren: David Walker and the Problem of Antebellum<br />

Slave Resistance (<strong>University</strong> Park: Pennsylvania <strong>University</strong> Press, 1997), xiv.<br />

04<br />

Ibid., 21.<br />

05<br />

Ibid., 30-31.<br />

06<br />

Ibid., 176.<br />

07<br />

Henry Mayer, All on Fire: William Lloyd Garrison and the Abolition of Slavery (New York: St.<br />

Martin’s Griffin, 1998), 110.<br />

08<br />

Ibid., 83.<br />

09<br />

Ibid., 84.<br />

10<br />

Donald M. Jacobs, “David Walker and Lloyd Garrison: Racial Cooperation and the<br />

Shaping of Boston Abolition,” Courage and Conscience: Black and White Abolitionists in Boston, ed.<br />

Donald M. Jacobs (Bloomington and Indianapolis: Indiana <strong>University</strong> Press, 1993), 15.<br />

11<br />

Richard S. Newman, The Transformation of American Abolitionism: Fighting Slavery in the<br />

Early Republic (Chapel Hill and London: <strong>University</strong> of North Carolina Press, 2002), 86.<br />

12<br />

Ibid., 93.<br />

13<br />

Ibid., 90.<br />

14<br />

Ibid., 93.<br />

15<br />

Howard H. Bell, Minutes of the Proceedings of the National Negro Conventions 1830-1864<br />

(New York: Arno Press and the New York Times, 1969), ii.<br />

16<br />

Ibid., 3.<br />

17<br />

Ibid.<br />

18<br />

Ibid., 6.<br />

19<br />

Ibid., 7.<br />

20<br />

Ibid.<br />

21<br />

William L. Katz, ed., Walker’s Appeal in Four Articles, David Walker. An Address to the Slaves<br />

of the United <strong>State</strong>s of America, Henry Highland Garnet (Salem: Ayer Company, Publishers, Inc.,<br />

1969), 90.<br />

22<br />

Ibid., 90.<br />

23<br />

Ibid., 91.<br />

24<br />

Ibid., 92.<br />

25<br />

Bell, Minutes of the Proceedings of the National Negro Conventions 1830-1864, 13.<br />

26<br />

Katz, 94.<br />

27<br />

Ibid., 96.<br />

28<br />

Lewis Perry, “Black Abolitionists and the Origins of Civil Disobedience,” Moral<br />

Problems in American Life: New Perspectives on Cultural History, eds. Karen Halttunen and Lewis<br />

Perry (Ithaca and London: Cornell <strong>University</strong> Press, 1998), 115.<br />

29<br />

Katz, 95.<br />

30<br />

Ibid., 91.<br />

31<br />

Ibid., 92.<br />

32<br />

Ibid., 96.<br />

33<br />

Bell, Minutes of the Proceedings of the National Negro Conventions 1830-1864, 13.<br />

34<br />

M. W. C., “The Buffalo Convention of Men of Color,” The Liberator, 22 September 1843.<br />

35<br />

Ibid.<br />

36<br />

E. A. Marsh, “The Colored Convention,” The Liberator, 8 September 1843.


122


123<br />

Chasing Sodomy<br />

D U R I N G T H E R E NA I S S A N C E :<br />

A C O M P A R A T I V E S T U D Y<br />

O F V E N I C E A N D F L O R E N C E<br />

A\<br />

R H I A N N O N Anderson


124<br />

eex<br />

post<br />

efacto


…Those sins which are against nature, like those of men of<br />

Sodom, are in all times and places to be detested and punished.<br />

Even if all nations committed such sins, they should all<br />

alike be held guilty by God’s law which did not make men so<br />

that they should use each other thus. The friendship which<br />

should be between God and us is violated when that nature<br />

— whose author He is — is polluted by so perverted a lust. 1<br />

ith these words, St. Augustine expressed the widespread fear held<br />

against sodomy and the belief that it was a heinous crime capable of<br />

calling down the wrath of God. Although this statement was made near<br />

the end of the fourth century, negative attitudes about sodomy continued<br />

throughout the middle ages. Despite the moral condemnation of<br />

same sex eroticism by the church, lay authorities were ambivalent about<br />

punishing the said “sin against nature” until the mid-thirteenth century. 2<br />

During this period, European states first began to prescribe harsh laws<br />

and punishments against sodomy. In 1259, for example, Bologna adopted<br />

the death penalty for sodomy, while in 1277 the German King Rudolf<br />

I of Habsburg sentenced a convicted sodomite to be burned alive. 3 W<br />

By<br />

the second half of the fourteenth century, many Italian communities had<br />

adopted legislation that invoked capital punishment for those found guilty<br />

of sodomy, making it the most serious of all sex crimes. However, it was<br />

during the fifteenth century that the major Italian cities began to take<br />

extraordinary measures in policing and punishing the sexual crime. The<br />

quattrocento marked the beginning of the most extensive and methodical<br />

repression of sodomy by major Italian city-states, demonstrating the deep<br />

concern over this sexual vice.<br />

125


126<br />

Two leading Renaissance cities, Florence and Venice, were at the<br />

forefront of anti-sodomy legislation in Northern Italy. In fact, both established<br />

institutions devoted exclusively to controlling sodomy during<br />

the early quattrocento. 4 Although these cities were equally alarmed about<br />

sodomy, they implemented different approaches in its repression and<br />

punishment. While the typical penalty in Venice was death by burning,<br />

punishments in Florence ranged from corporal punishment to relatively<br />

mild fines. 5 Venice maintained a stable and more severe form of punishment<br />

whereas Florence fluctuated in its treatment of convicted sodomites.<br />

The development of dissimilar methods and penalties by the anti-sodomy<br />

councils of these two dominant Italian city-states during the quattrocento<br />

reflected equally dissimilar attitudes toward the repression of sodomy.<br />

Venice was determined to cleanse the Republic completely from the sin,<br />

thus invoking severe punishments consistently, whereas Florence seemed<br />

to realize the impossibility of fully repressing the sexual behavior, thus<br />

seeking methods of regulating it rather than trying to eradicate the vice.<br />

What makes a comparison between Venice and Florence so attractive<br />

is that they were the two leading powers in Northern Italy during the<br />

Renaissance. Both republics were major power centers and shared the distinction<br />

of preserving their liberty and republican forms of government<br />

longer than most of their Italian counterparts. Their central and burgeoning<br />

commercial and trade activities linked them intimately with the world<br />

market and contributed to their economic success and stability. In addition,<br />

Florence and Venice were renowned cultural centers that essentially gave<br />

birth to Europe’s golden age known as the Renaissance. 6 Consequently,<br />

these quintessential Northern Italian republics left behind a long trail of<br />

surviving evidence regarding their attitudes and actions taken against sodomy.<br />

From literary sources to trial records, the pursuit of sodomy during<br />

the quattrocento was well documented in Venice and Florence. Although<br />

individual studies have been done on each republic, a comparative history<br />

of sodomy in Florence and Venice has yet to surface. Guido Ruggiero has<br />

dealt extensively on the subject of sodomy in Renaissance Venice, arguing<br />

that Venice’s grave concern over the matter of sodomy resulted in the<br />

frequent execution of sodomites. 7 Another scholar, Michael Rocke, has<br />

traced the flexibility and leniency of punishment in the Florentine state,<br />

despite the serious alarm. By comparing these two leading powers we shall<br />

see that they both shared similar concerns regarding sodomy, yet their<br />

regulations and punishments differed.<br />

To begin with, it is important to define what was punished as sodomy<br />

in Renaissance Florence and Venice. Sodomy had a theological definition<br />

and was often referred to as the “unnatural vice.” 8 It was understood as<br />

non-procreative sexual acts, mainly anal intercourse with men or women,<br />

masturbation and even bestiality. Yet, the sexual crimes that were prosecuted<br />

as sodomy in both Florence and Venice included all sexual relations<br />

between male and male, and in some rare cases non-reproductive<br />

RHIANNON ANDERSON


sexual practices committed between male and female. 9 Cases regarding<br />

“unnatural acts” between men and women were widely accepted as a<br />

practical means of contraception and almost all cases were absolved. 10<br />

Ruggiero described the crime of sodomy between males and females as<br />

“seldom punished; if prosecuted, seldom convicted; and if convicted, seldom<br />

punished severely.” 11 In addition, same sex relations between females<br />

went untried and unpunished all together. 12 Thus, the majority of sodomy<br />

cases in Venice and Florence during the quattrocento and cinquecento dealt<br />

specifically with same-sex eroticism between males.<br />

Another component of the definition of sodomy in both Venice<br />

and Florence was the distinction made between the active and the passive<br />

partner. In most cases the passive partner was younger or an adolescent,<br />

while the active was older or an adult. Authorities normally<br />

punished the passive participant with only a light penalty or none at all,<br />

while the active partner suffered dire consequences. According to tradition,<br />

male children under the legal age of fourteen were not culpable<br />

and thus not to be prosecuted for their crimes. In addition, since the<br />

older partner usually took the dominant role, he was viewed as the aggressor<br />

or the initiator of the crime. 13<br />

The seriousness that was placed on the oft-referred to “abominable<br />

vice” had its theological and religious implications. According<br />

to Thomas Aquinas, sodomy was an “unnatural vice” because it was<br />

against reason and “contrary to the natural order of the venereal act<br />

as becoming to the human race.” 14 In other words, “copulation with an<br />

undue sex,” such as male with male, was a sin against nature because<br />

it threatened the natural intent of procreation, undermining society’s<br />

most basic institutions of family and marriage. Furthermore, the sin<br />

of sodomy was perceived as being so grave that it could invoke God’s<br />

wrath, as it did for Sodom and Gomorrah. The enormity of this sin<br />

was evidenced by the fate of these two cities: both were utterly leveled<br />

to the ground and no living thing survived (Genesis 19-23). Thus, sodomy<br />

was perceived as a sin against God and feared for its potential of<br />

destroying the whole of society.<br />

Both Florence and Venice had widespread reputations as centers<br />

for deviant sexual behavior, particularly sodomy. 15 In Germany,<br />

same sex erotic activity was often referred to as “Italian weddings,”<br />

and those involved were called Venedische breute or “Venetian brides”<br />

and Florentzische breutgam or “Florentine grooms.” 16 Not surprisingly,<br />

legends circling Venice envisioned it as a tolerant island republic with<br />

sexual liberties and loose morals. 17 In 1511, the Patriarch announced<br />

that Venice was so full of sodomites that even the prostitutes were<br />

upset about them. Courtesans complained that sodomy was popular to<br />

such a degree that they were losing customers and consequently their<br />

livelihood was threatened. 18 A Venetian diarist, Girolamo Priuli, re-<br />

Chasing Sodomy During the Renaissance<br />

127


128<br />

corded: “…the unnatural vice called sodomy…was openly [practiced]<br />

in Venice without shame; indeed, it had become so habitual that it was<br />

more highly regarded than to with one’s own wife.” 19<br />

Venice’s counterpart also carried the ill repute of being “another<br />

Sodom.” In Dante’s Inferno, written around 1307, four out of the<br />

seven sodomites were identified as Florentines. 20 During the 1420’s,<br />

Bernardino of Siena devoted his efforts against the “abominable vice”<br />

in a series of sermons throughout the city. The influential Franciscan<br />

believed that sodomy was rampant throughout Tuscany, especially in<br />

Florence where he considered it to be so common that it was virtually a<br />

custom. Another contemporary observer described Florence as “excessively<br />

corrupted [by sodomy].” 21<br />

Despite their reputations, sodomy in Venice and Florence was not<br />

as free and unrestrained as imagined. Both cities were religious and committed<br />

to the traditional values of the church. Although the state did not<br />

enact punishments for sodomy until the trecento, sodomy was punished<br />

penitentially. Clergy used manuals of penance, which regulated penalties<br />

to be imposed for various sins, to deal with vices. The church punished<br />

sodomites with heavy penances or excommunication.For example,<br />

a “male who [committed] fornication with a male” typically received<br />

seven to fifteen years penance — less than or equal to the amount of time<br />

for one who committed manslaughter. 22 By the late thirteenth and early<br />

fourteenth centuries, secular legislation and punishment of sodomy had<br />

arrived in Florence and Venice. In 1284, the statutes of the podestà had<br />

made sodomy punishable by exile in Florence, and in 1326 the Venetians<br />

had already begun prosecuting sodomites. 23<br />

From the beginning of state-imposed anti-sodomy laws in Venice<br />

and Florence, the two cities shared a similar desire for eradicating the<br />

“unnatural vice” from their domains. Possibly brought forth by a time of<br />

crisis and social turmoil, both cities moved to impose strict penalties for<br />

sodomy. In 1348, the Black Death ravaged both Venice and Florence,<br />

decimating the population of each place. Giovanni Boccacio, a Florentine<br />

who witnessed the onslaught of the Black Death, documented the terror<br />

and social upheaval in his Decameron. He wrote that many people believed<br />

the plague “was a punishment signifying God’s righteous anger at [their]<br />

iniquitous way of life.” 24 His statement echoed the same sentiments from<br />

the scriptural stories of Sodom and Gomorrah that both church and secular<br />

legislation made extensive use of. Laws that followed the devastation<br />

of the plague stipulated harsher penalties for sodomy. For example, before<br />

the plague, Florence had punished convicted sodomites with castration<br />

or fines; in 1365, the penalty for sodomy was increased so that anyone<br />

convicted of sodomy or aiding it could be put to death by burning. 25 In<br />

another instance, the first surviving record of convicted sodomites burned<br />

alive in Venice was dated from 1348. 26<br />

RHIANNON ANDERSON


However, the stricter laws did not stem the sexually “deviant behavior”<br />

in Venice or Florence, and the quattrocento marked a turning point in<br />

their methods of repressing sodomy. Venice experienced a transition in<br />

prosecution from the Signori di Notte to the Council of Ten. Up until 1407,<br />

the Signori di Notte (Guardians of the Night Watch) were responsible for<br />

dealing with cases of sodomy. The Signori di Notte was a judicial body made<br />

up of six nobles, whose primary duty was to patrol the streets and to preserve<br />

order at night. 27 Other responsibilities included arresting criminals<br />

and investigating murder, robbery, and sodomy cases. Between the years<br />

1348 and 1400, the Guardians of the Night had prosecuted sixteen individuals<br />

for sodomy; their first case resulted in both convicted sodomites<br />

being burned alive. 28 All the surviving records of the Signori di Notte reveal<br />

that there were no cases in which nobles were involved; however, this did<br />

not mean nobles were not participants in the sexual taboo. 29 In fact, the<br />

involvement of a large number of nobles in a sodomy case of 1406 triggered<br />

the move of prosecution from the Signori di Notte to the Council of<br />

Ten in 1407. 30<br />

The Signori di Notte’s reluctance to prosecute nobles combined with the<br />

complexities of the case in 1406 led to the Council of Ten’s takeover of the<br />

prosecution of the crime. In 1406, the Signori di Notte discovered a major<br />

sodomy case that involved seventeen nobles and eighteen populares. The<br />

hesitancy of the Signori di Notte to prosecute the nobles and their apparent<br />

readiness to help certain nobles escape justice instigated the “murmuring”<br />

of the city. 31 This “murmuring” of the popolani was an important force to<br />

be reckoned with, yet the uncertainty of the Signori di Notte to move forth on<br />

the case was based on the fact that it involved members of very important<br />

families. Since the penalty imposed for sodomy was burning alive, it put the<br />

members of the official body in an awkward position. The Signori di Notte<br />

was in fact composed of the nobility, thus the conviction of nobles was<br />

to move against their own kind which was politically dangerous. Thus, if<br />

not handled with caution, the case could potentially disrupt the social and<br />

political stability of Venice. If equal justice was given out for all involved,<br />

the nobility could become divided; however it would not be acceptable to<br />

burn non-nobles while allowing nobles to escape punishment.<br />

Recognizing the complexities and heightened social tension, which<br />

were viewed as harmful to Venice, the Council of Ten took over the case.<br />

They stated: “It is necessary that everything be done to avoid angering<br />

God against us and to preserve justice and our honor and to not diminish<br />

the faith and devotion of our popolani who are murmuring because they see<br />

popolani executed while nobles escape unpunished.” 32 The Council of Ten<br />

was one of the most important councils of the Venetian Republic and was<br />

composed of the doge and his councilors and other magistrates from the<br />

most prestigious families of the city. 33 Their main responsibilities were policing<br />

and punishing serious crimes against the state, such as treason, and<br />

anything else that threatened the stability of Venice. They had unlimited<br />

Chasing Sodomy During the Renaissance<br />

129


130<br />

power in arresting and executing any one who imposed a threat to the security<br />

of the state. The authority of such an eminent council carried extra<br />

weight and was therefore fit to handle the sodomy case of 1406 that had<br />

social and political dangers attached to it.<br />

Although the Council of Ten took over the delicate case in 1407,<br />

it did not take complete jurisdiction over sodomy cases until 1418. The<br />

case of 1407 only marked the beginning of the Ten’s involvement in sodomy<br />

cases, but the majority of cases were still tried by the Signori di Notte.<br />

However, the Signori di Notte was deemed ineffective and inefficient by the<br />

Ten for its inability to eradicate sodomy from Venice. The Council of Ten<br />

declared that “those eager to commit this abominable crime are not afraid<br />

of committing it, rather they commit it lightly, not fearing the authority of<br />

the Signori di Notte.” 34 Dissatisfied with the Signori di Notte’s handling of sodomy<br />

cases, the Council of Ten took complete jurisdiction over the crime<br />

in 1418. In addition to taking total authority over matters of sodomy, the<br />

Ten also established a specialized anti-sodomy committee called the collegium<br />

contra sodomites, or the collegio sodomiti. 35<br />

The significance of the transition in the prosecution of sodomy from<br />

the Signori di Notte to the Council of Ten was manifested in the fact that the<br />

Ten took on a more aggressive role in pursuing the matter, resulting in an<br />

increase of prosecutions among a broader range of classes. For example,<br />

between the years 1401-1500, sixty-six nobles were prosecuted for sodomy<br />

out of two hundred and sixty-six cases, demonstrating a dramatic rise relative<br />

to the number of nobles prosecuted by the Signori di Notte — which was<br />

zero. 36 The Council of Ten committed itself to eradicating sodomy from<br />

Venice “so that not only would no one presume to its practice but no one<br />

would even dare to mention it.” 37 With the establishment of an institution<br />

specifically mandated for sodomy, the Council of Ten also passed legislation<br />

to tighten control on the “unnatural vice.” For instance, in 1420, after<br />

complaints of widespread acts of sodomy on Venetian ships, the Council<br />

of Ten passed a ruling which declared that anyone caught committing<br />

sodomy in a Venetian ship would be punished as if in Venice. 38 Previously,<br />

when Venetian ships sailed outside of Venetian territory, they were also<br />

considered outside the jurisdiction of Venetian law. The Council of Ten<br />

further promised monetary rewards for those who turned in sodomites if<br />

they were convicted.<br />

After passing the regulation regarding Venetian ships in 1420, the<br />

Council of Ten regularly adopted legislation which aided in the policing<br />

and punishing of sodomy. In 1458, the Council of Ten passed another<br />

law that increased public surveillance in an attempt to control sodomy. 39<br />

The legislation stipulated that each year two nobles were elected in each<br />

neighborhood to investigate and search for “signs” of sodomy in their locales.<br />

In addition, “danger zones” were pronounced: places such as apothecary<br />

shops, barber-surgeon shops, schools of music, gymnastics, fencing,<br />

RHIANNON ANDERSON


and singing, were regarded as breeding grounds for the congregation of<br />

sodomites. A ruling in 1477 imposed curfews on hours of operation and<br />

ordered that schools were not allowed to have private teaching rooms.<br />

Secluded public places were also considered “hot spots” during the night,<br />

thus the Council of Ten required more street lamps to be kept lit after<br />

nightfall. By 1467, the Council of Ten had become so aggressive in their<br />

pursuit of sodomy that they passed a regulation that required medical<br />

practitioners to report anyone treated for a “break in the rear parts caused<br />

by a member.” 40<br />

While Venetian authorities sought to eradicate the “vice of sodomy”<br />

from the Republic, Florence pursued a more pragmatic approach in trying<br />

to repress the “devious” sexual behavior. Traditionally, the surveillance<br />

and punishment of sodomy in Florence fell under the jurisdiction<br />

of the city’s three main magistrates until a specialized anti-sodomy institution<br />

was established in 1432. These tribunals included the podestà, the<br />

capitano del popolo, and the esecutore degli ordinamenti di giustizia, whose posts<br />

were held by foreign rectors in an attempt to keep them from forming<br />

alliances with the various factions that vied for control of the commune.<br />

In Florence, the central figure of authority was the podestà whose main<br />

duty was to administer justice. 41 In addition, the podestà and his court were<br />

responsible for investigating sodomy, either by their own initiative or in response<br />

to accusations. The statutes of the podestà of 1325 stipulated harsh<br />

punishments for sodomy, such as castration, flogging, and large fines. 42 By<br />

1365, those convicted of sodomy were subject to death by burning, at the<br />

discretion of the podestà. Although the punishment for sodomy was severe,<br />

the Florentine courts rarely prosecuted the sexual crime, unless there were<br />

other crimes attached. For example, in documented cases of sodomy between<br />

the years 1348-1432, fifty six people convicted for sodomy were also<br />

found guilty of other crimes, such as child abuse, rape, violent attacks, kidnapping,<br />

and theft. 43 For the most part, under the jurisdiction of the three<br />

main tribunals, the sexual taboo committed alone went largely ignored.<br />

At the beginning of the quattrocento, the Florentine government tried<br />

to implement innovative reforms aimed at controlling sodomy. In 1403,<br />

a proposal was passed that granted the Signoria authority to spend whatever<br />

was necessary and to impose any legislation that would help in the<br />

“removal and extirpation of this vice and sodomitical [sic] crime and<br />

for its purging and punishment…from the territory of Florence.” 44 The<br />

law further stipulated that all future officer holders in the Signoria were to<br />

swear an oath “to pursue sodomites and to condemn and punish them.”<br />

However, rather than pursuing sodomites, the Signoria created an institution,<br />

the Officers of Decency, to police female prostitution instead. Once<br />

again, those responsible for policing sodomy ignored it , causing a divide<br />

within the regime. Advocates for harsher controls on sodomy voiced their<br />

opinions in advisory meetings, yet the Florentine government was unwilling<br />

to implement repressive measures. In fact, they did the opposite: in<br />

Chasing Sodomy During the Renaissance<br />

131


132<br />

1415 the government adopted more lenient penalties with the belief that<br />

such harsh punishments, such as death by burning, were an obstacle in the<br />

path of effective control. The statutes of 1415 reduced the punishments<br />

for a first time conviction of sodomy to a fine and forbade exile, mutilation,<br />

or execution — only a second conviction could result in execution. 46<br />

Consequently, the lack of prosecution and lenient penalties for<br />

sodomy resulted in demands for reform throughout Florence from various<br />

government officials, poets, and preachers. Recurring outbreaks of<br />

plague in 1348, 1400, 1417, 1423-24, and 1430 contributed to the heightened<br />

concern over sodomy. One official, Antonio di Niccolò complained,<br />

“how abominable are [these acts] in the sight of God, and how [their<br />

suppression] will redound to the honor and reputation of the Signoria and<br />

the city.” He went on to criticize the Signoria’s handling over the “vice,”<br />

stating that although “there exist laws [against sodomy], they are flawed<br />

in their implementation.” 47<br />

Poets, such as Stefano Finiguerri, and Domenico of Prata also expressed<br />

their disapproval of sodomy in their work. However, the most aggressive<br />

campaign against sodomy arrived in 1424, with the Franciscan<br />

friar Bernardino of Siena. Between 1424 and 1425, Bernardino preached<br />

a number of sermons on the “pestilential ruin” of sodomy. He used the traditional<br />

arsenal of Sodom and Gomorrah and attributed disasters such as<br />

wars, floods, famine, and plague to sodomy. Bernardino also attacked the<br />

Florentine government for allowing sodomites to escape from punishment,<br />

comparing them to other cities, such as Venice, which burned sodomites.<br />

He complained: “They don’t pardon the gentleman or the important citizen<br />

for sodomy, but banish irrevocably even the greatest citizens. Unlike<br />

you Florentines, who before the wound had healed have already lifted the<br />

criminal’s exile.” 48 Furthermore, Bernardino demanded that Florence follow<br />

the same harsh methods of its neighbors or suffer the wrath of God.<br />

Although the Franciscan’s crusade against sodomy drew people’s attention<br />

to the lack of justice doled out for “cursed sodomites,” civic officials did not<br />

implement any new measures to repress the vice immediately.<br />

Agitation for reform during the early quattrocento eventually did result<br />

in the development of a specialized anti-sodomy institution in 1432, the<br />

Uffici di Notte or the Officers of the Night. On April 17, the Florentines<br />

founded the special magistracy, declaring: “[The government] wishes to<br />

root out of its city the abominable vice of sodomy, called in the holy scriptures<br />

the most evil sin, and having decided that if what is written herein is<br />

done, for the most part this will be accomplished.” 49 With these words, the<br />

new institution set out to police sodomy and encouraged the community<br />

to participate. In contrast to Venice, where anonymous accusations were<br />

deemed unacceptable, the Officers of the Night encouraged secret accusations,<br />

placing boxes called tamburi inside churches where people could<br />

leave denunciations. 50 Rewards were offered for informers of convicted<br />

RHIANNON ANDERSON


sodomites and their anonymity was guaranteed. The Officers of the Night<br />

also adopted the use of spies, who were paid one-fourth of the total fine<br />

received from convicted sodomites. With the creation of the specialized<br />

anti-sodomy magistracy and the incentives offered for accusations, the policing<br />

of sodomy was intensified.<br />

Although the surveillance and repression of sodomy increased with<br />

the establishment of the Uffici di Notte, the government reduced the penalties<br />

for it. While the statutes of 1415 had replaced draconian punishments<br />

with a fine of 1,000 lire for those condemned of sodomy, the law<br />

of 1432 further reduced fines to fifty gold florins for the first conviction,<br />

one-hundred gold florins for a second, and two-hundred gold florins<br />

plus exclusion from holding office for two years for a third. Each time<br />

an adult male was found guilty of committing the crime of sodomy, the<br />

penalties steadily increased. For example, if one was convicted a fourth<br />

time, he would be “fined 500 gold florins and perpetually excluded from<br />

all offices,” if found guilty a fifth time would be “led through the customary<br />

public squares to the place of justice and there to be burned so<br />

that he dies.” 51 Another provision in the law of 1432 also allowed for<br />

these penalties to be decreased even further. For instance, if an accused<br />

sodomite confessed to the charge, his fines were reduced to one-half,<br />

while one who confessed before charges were brought against him could<br />

escape punishment altogether. 52<br />

As a result of the imposition of more lenient penalties by the Uffici<br />

di Notte, combined with incentives for denunciations, the number of<br />

convictions for sodomy steadily rose and crossed across different social<br />

classes. Everyone, regardless of status was subject to the punishments of<br />

the Officers of the Night, from vagabonds to patricians. In fact, the first<br />

person convicted by the Officers of the Night was Doffo di Nepo Spini,<br />

a former Gonfalonier of Justice, which was one of the highest positions<br />

in government. He was accused of sodomizing a fourteen year old and<br />

when approached by the authorities, he confessed to committing the<br />

crime. Because of his confession, his fine was reduced to twenty-five florins.<br />

53 Between the years 1432 and 1440, over one hundred males were<br />

convicted of having sexual relations with other men. 54<br />

Although there was an increase in the number of prosecutions during<br />

the early years of the Uffici di Notte, the magistracy quickly realized its<br />

inability to repress sodomy. In 1436, the Officers of the Night suggested<br />

that rather than trying to eradicate sodomy from Florence, a more effective<br />

approach would be to regulate it. In a passage from a trial, a sense of<br />

despair and pragmatism is revealed:<br />

[The Officers of the Night] are watching with unceasing diligence<br />

so that the horrible crime of sodomy might be rooted<br />

out of the city and its territory, and they devote themselves to<br />

nothing else. Yet after all their labors, words, threats, punishments<br />

against many persons, they believe that, in effect, it is<br />

Chasing Sodomy During the Renaissance<br />

133


134<br />

nearly impossible for any good to come about, so corrupt and<br />

stained is the city. Nonetheless, they prudently reason that if<br />

despite every sort of punishment these men are still not restrained,<br />

at least some might control themselves, and perhaps<br />

those defiled by such ignominy will not do so openly…although<br />

their crimes may not be completely prevented, they<br />

may in part be constrained. 55<br />

The Officers of the Night felt that it was impossible to completely rid<br />

Florence from the vice of sodomy regardless of the type of penalties doled<br />

out. Severe punishments of the past did not hinder “unnatural” sexual<br />

behavior between men, nor did the innovative “benevolent” measures<br />

adopted in the early quattrocento. In 1459, another piece of legislation reduced<br />

the fines for sodomy once again: ten florins for first time offenders,<br />

twenty-five florins for a second, and fifty florins for a third offense. 56 The<br />

dramatic decrease in fines resulted in a notably increase in prosecutions of<br />

sodomites, reaching an all time high between the years 1472-1473, where<br />

161 men where convicted of sodomy. 57<br />

Overall, both Venice and Florence experienced an increase of prosecutions<br />

with the development of special anti-sodomy institutions during<br />

the mid-quattrocento. Although they both voiced similar concerns over<br />

the “abominable vice,” they adopted different measures in policing and<br />

punishing convicted sodomites. Venice remained determined to free the<br />

Republic from the “terrible crime” of sodomy, whereas Florence was<br />

pragmatic in its approach, finally coming to the conclusion that it was<br />

impossible to root out the “evil sin.” While the policing of sodomy continued<br />

throughout the cinquecento, it had become apparent to both Venice and<br />

Florence that sexual behavior was something that could not be controlled.<br />

In 1502, the magistracy of the Uffici di Notte was abolished on the grounds<br />

that having a specialized sodomy institution insinuated the unfavorable<br />

reputation of being another Sodom.<br />

Venice, in turn, would soon come to realize that its plan to eradicate<br />

sodomy so completely that “no one would even dare mention it” was<br />

doomed to fail. In the late 1520’s Pietro Aretino had arrived in Venice<br />

after his expulsion from Rome for his erotic and explicit poems he had<br />

written to go along with Giulio Romano’s infamous engravings of sexual<br />

positions. One of these poems, in fact, was about sodomy between a male<br />

and female. 58 Once in Venice, he completed his comedy, “Il Marescalco,”<br />

or “The Master of the Horse,” whose hero, Marescalco, was an openly<br />

practicing sodomite. 59 By the mid-sixteenth century, the punishment for<br />

sodomy in Venice had been reduced from death by burning to time served<br />

on the galleys or a prison sentence.<br />

Furthermore, the quattrocento had marked the beginning of an era of<br />

exhaustive repression of sodomy in both Venice and Florence, a repression<br />

that would last up until the mid-cinquecento. Unlike other Italian citystates,<br />

they both created specialized institutions which dealt solely with the<br />

issue of sodomy. These anti-sodomy establishments reflected the official<br />

RHIANNON ANDERSON


view of unacceptable sexuality in both republics, while offering insight<br />

to society’s perception of “normal” sexual activities. However, the specialized<br />

institutions failed to stem the “sexual crime.” Although the number<br />

of convictions rose with the establishment of the anti-sodomy magistracies,<br />

sodomy itself was likely unaffected. In fact, the harder Venice<br />

and Florence sought to repress sodomy, the more cases they uncovered.<br />

Rather than putting a stop to same sex eroticism between males, they just<br />

discovered more of it going on throughout the city. In trying to control<br />

sexual behavior, both Venice and Florence became disappointed with the<br />

outcome and both eventually adopted policies of toleration.<br />

01 St. Augustine, Confessions, book III, ch. 8.<br />

02 For more on the hostility and the adoption of harsh laws imposed by the state on sodomy,<br />

see James Boswell, Christianity, Social Tolerance, and Homosexuality, 269-332. Also see Michael<br />

Goodrich, “Sodomy in Medieval Secular Law,” Journal of Homosexuality, 1 (1976), 295-302.<br />

03 On the legislation of Bologna, see Blanshei, “Criminal Law and Politics in Medieval<br />

Bologna,” Criminal Justice History: An International Journal, 2 (1981), 13. For a list of sodomy trials<br />

and convictions in early modern Germany and Switzerland, see Puff, Helmut, Sodomy in<br />

Reformation Germany and Switzerland: 1400-1600 (Chicago: <strong>University</strong> of Chicago Press, 2003),<br />

17, 183.<br />

04 In 1418, Venice created a special standing committee called the Collegio Sodomiti.<br />

For more on the creation of this committee, see Patricia H. Labalme, “Sodomy and Venetian<br />

Justice in the Renaissance,” Revue d’histoire du droit, 52 (1985): 217-254. In 1432, Florence established<br />

the special magistracy called the Ufficiali di Notte. “Establishment of a Magistracy to<br />

Extirpate Sodomy, 1432,” in The Society of Renaissance Florence: a Documentary Study, ed. Gene<br />

Brucker (New York: Harper & Row, 1971). For more on the Florentine committee, see Michael<br />

J. Rocke, Forbidden Friendships: Homosexuality and Male Culture in Renaissance Florence (New York:<br />

Oxford <strong>University</strong> Press, 1996), 45-84.<br />

05 On the regulation and punishment of sodomy in Venice see Guido Ruggiero,<br />

Boundaries of Eros: Sex Crime and Sexuality in Renaissance Venice (Oxford <strong>University</strong> Press, 1985),<br />

109-145. For regulation and punishment of sodomy in Florence, see Rocke, Forbidden Friendships,<br />

45-84, 195-226.<br />

06 For more on the history of both republics, see Lauro Martines, Power and Imagination:<br />

City-<strong>State</strong>s in Renaissance Italy (Baltimore: John Hopkins <strong>University</strong> Press, 1988). For a more<br />

concise history on Venice, see Lane, Frederic C., Venice: a Maritime Republic (Baltimore: John<br />

Hopkins <strong>University</strong> Press, 1973). For more on Florence, see Gene Brucker, Florence: the Golden<br />

Age, 1138-1737 (Berkeley: <strong>University</strong> of California Press, 1998).<br />

07 Ruggiero, The Boundaries.<br />

08 In Thomas Aquinas’s Summa Theologia, Aquinas described what he considered to be<br />

the “vice of sodomy.” See Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologia, 2a2ae 154, 11.<br />

09 Although what was punished as sodomy falls under the modern term of homosexual<br />

acts between males, I will use the word “sodomy” or “sodomite” throughout the essay because<br />

that was the terminology used in Florentine and Venetian documents. According to<br />

Jeffrey Weeks, the term “homosexuality” was created in 1869 and notions of sexual identity did<br />

not exist until the late nineteenth century. Weeks, Jeffrey, “Movements of Affirmation: Sexual<br />

Meaning and Homosexual Identities,” Radical History Review, 20 (1979): 164.<br />

10 Ruggiero, Boundaries, 119. Rocke, Forbidden Friendships, 46.<br />

11 Ruggiero, Boundaries, 119. Judith C. Brown, “Lesbian Sexuality in Medieval and<br />

Early Modern Europe,” in Hidden from History: Reclaiming the Gay and Lesbian Past, ed. Martin<br />

Duberman, et al., (New York: New American Library, 1989), 67-75.<br />

12 According to Labalme and Ruggiero, no records of punishment or trials regarding<br />

same sex relations between females have been found. Labalme, 220. Ruggiero, Boundaries, 190.<br />

However, sexual relationships between women did in fact exist. See Judith C. Brown, Immodest<br />

Acts: the Life of a Lesbian Nun in Renaissance Italy (New York: Oxford <strong>University</strong> Press, 1986).<br />

Chasing Sodomy During the Renaissance<br />

135<br />

NOTES


136<br />

13<br />

For a discussion regarding how age played out in the prosecution of sodomy in<br />

Florence, see Rocke’s Forbidden Friendships, 87-111. For more on Venice, see Ruggiero’s Boundaries,<br />

121-124. For the remainder of the paper, I will only be looking at the active adult males convicted<br />

of sodomy and not of passive adolescents. Except for a few rare cases, the passive partner<br />

or adolescent did not receive the same harsh punishments as the adult partner.<br />

14<br />

Aquinas, Summa Theologia, 2a2ae. 154, 11.<br />

15<br />

Although Venice and Florence had reputations for widespread sodomy, this does not<br />

mean that sodomy was non-existent in other European states. In fact, there is much evidence of<br />

sodomy everywhere in addition to records of other states trying to eradicate it. See Puff, Sodomy.<br />

16<br />

During the reformations, reformers such as Martin Luther used these terms when<br />

describing sodomitical relations between men. See Puff, Sodomy, 137, 246n. 86.<br />

17<br />

For more regarding the myth of Venice, see James Grubb, “When Myths Lose Power:<br />

Four Decades of Venetian Historiography,” Journal of Modern History, 58 (1986): 43-94. Also Edward<br />

Muir, Civic Ritual in Renaissance Venice, (New Jersey: Princeton <strong>University</strong> Press, 1981), 13-61.<br />

18<br />

<strong>San</strong>udo, Diarii, 12:84, 1511: “e questa terra è piena di pechati, primo di sodomia, che si fa per<br />

tutto senza rispeto, e le meretrici li ha mandato a dir che non poleno viver, niun va di lhoro, tanto è la sodomie; a<br />

fino vechij si fanno lavorar,” quoted in Labalme, 248.<br />

19<br />

Priuli, Girolamo, “Homosexual Practices Unpunished, 1509,” in David Chambers<br />

and Brian Pullan, eds., Venice: a Documentary History 1450-1630, (Toronto: <strong>University</strong> of Toronto<br />

Press, 2001), 124-5.<br />

20<br />

Dante, Inferno, Cantos <strong>XV</strong>, <strong>XV</strong>I.<br />

21<br />

“Civic Opinion, 1415,” in Brucker, The Society of Renaissance Florence, 201.<br />

22<br />

“The Penitential of Theodore, 668-690,” in Medieval Handbooks of Penance: a Translation<br />

of the Principal libri poenitentiales and Selections from Related Documents, edited by Helena M. Gamer<br />

and John T. McNeill, (New York: Columbia <strong>University</strong> Press, 1965), 185, 187.<br />

23<br />

Rocke, Forbidden Friendships, 21. Ruggiero, Boundaries, 128. These are dates of the earliest<br />

surviving records regarding sodomy in both cities. It is hard to know the exact date of the<br />

first piece of anti-sodomy legislation, yet these dates are in accordance with other anti-sodomy<br />

laws and punishments in neighboring cities, such as Bologna, Switzerland, Germany.<br />

24<br />

Giovanni Boccacio, The Decameron, trans. G. H. McWilliam (Penguin Books: England), 5.<br />

25<br />

A.S.F., Provvisioni, Registri,” 52, 128rv (April 3, 1365), in Michael J. Rocke,<br />

Male Homosexuality and its Regulation in Late Medieval Florence (<strong>State</strong> <strong>University</strong> of New York at<br />

Binghampton, Ph. D. dissertation, 1990), 568-572.<br />

26<br />

A.S.V., Signori di Notte, Processi, Reg. 6, f.4v-5v (1348), case quoted in Ruggiero,<br />

Boundaries, 110-111, 188.<br />

27<br />

For a discussion on the Signori di Notte’s responsibilities see Guido Ruggiero, Violence<br />

in Early Renaissance Venice (New Jersey: Rutgers <strong>University</strong> Press, 1980), 26-33.<br />

28<br />

These figures come from a chart in Ruggiero’s Boundaries, which is based on the records<br />

of the Signori di Notte, 128. The first case in the surviving records of the Signori di Notte<br />

was in 1348, in which both of the convicted sodomites were burned alive; however because it<br />

is the first surviving record, does not necessarily indicate if these were the first victims of harsh<br />

sodomy punishment. For more on the case, see Ruggiero, Boundaries, 110-111, 116..<br />

29<br />

Ruggiero’s chart, “Sodomy Prosecutions in Venice, 1326-1500,” indicates that records<br />

from 1326-1425 are incomplete. Ruggiero, Boundaries, 128.<br />

30<br />

Both Ruggiero and Labalme go into detail about the case of 1406-7. Ruggiero,<br />

Boundaries, 127-134. Labalme, 222-225.<br />

31<br />

The “murmuring” of the people in Venice was a force in which the government<br />

was constantly forced to reckon with. For more on the power of the people’s voice, see Finlay,<br />

Robert, Politics in Renaissance Florence (New Brunswick, 1980), 44-108.<br />

32<br />

A.S.V., Dieci, Miste, Reg. 8, f.134v-135v (1406), quoted in Ruggiero, Boundaries, 128-<br />

9, 194.<br />

33<br />

<strong>San</strong>udo, “A Very Severe Magistracy,” in Chambers & Pullan, 54-57. For more discussion<br />

on the Council of Ten, see Ruggiero, Violence, 6-17, 33-39.<br />

34<br />

A.S.V., Dieci, Miste, Reg. 9, f. 183v-184 (May 11, 1418), quoted in Labalme, 224.<br />

35<br />

A.S.V., Dieci, Miste, Reg. 9, f. 183v-184.<br />

36<br />

Figures from Ruggiero’s chart, “Sodomy Prosecutions in Venice, 1326-1500,” in<br />

Boundaries, 128.<br />

37<br />

A.S.V., Diecci, Miste, Reg. 9, f. 179, April 6, 1418, quoted in Labalme, 224.<br />

38<br />

A.S.V., Diecci, Miste, Reg. 10, f. 29v (1420), in Ruggiero, Boundaries, 134-5, 195.<br />

39<br />

A.S.V., Diecci, Miste, Reg. 15, f. 170r (1458), in Ruggiero, Boundaries, 109, 135, 188.<br />

RHIANNON ANDERSON


40<br />

A.S.V., Diecci, Miste, Reg. 17, f. 81v (1467), in Ruggiero, Boundaries, 117-18, 191.<br />

41<br />

For more discussion on the podestà, see Martines, Lauro, Power and Imagination: City-<br />

<strong>State</strong>s in Renaissance Italy (John Hopkins <strong>University</strong> Press, 1988), 41-44, 54-56, 94.<br />

42<br />

A.S.F., Statut di Podestà, 1325, discussed in Rocke, Forbidden Friendships, 21-22.<br />

43<br />

According to the statistics given in Rocke’s Forbidden Friendships, 23.<br />

44<br />

A.S.F., Provvisioni, Registri 92, 9r-10r (April 24, 1403), quoted in Rocke’s Male<br />

Homosexuality, 60. The Signoria was a nine-member executive body in Florence.<br />

45<br />

A.S.F., Provvisioni 92, 9r-10r (April 24, 1403), quoted in Rocke’s Forbidden Friendships, 31.<br />

46<br />

A.S.F., Statuti 23, 86v; cf. Statuta (1415), 1:321, from Rocke’s Forbidden Friendships, 32.<br />

47<br />

A.S.F., Consulte e Pratiche, 43, fol. 76v, in Brucker’s Society, 201.<br />

48<br />

Bernardino of Siena, (Florence 1424), quoted in Rocke’s Male Homosexuality, 93.<br />

49<br />

A.S.F., Provvisioni, Registri 123, 31v-36v (April 17, 1432), in Rocke’s Male Homosexuality,<br />

589.<br />

50<br />

In 1275, the Major Council passed a law in Venice stipulating that anonymous letters<br />

were not allowed to be used and should be burned. However, many argued that the refusal of<br />

reading anonymous letters was not in Venice’s best interests. Therefore, in 1387, anonymous<br />

accusations could be used, but only after intense screening. For more discussion on anonymous<br />

accusations in Venice, see Ruggiero, Violence, 35. For the Florentine acceptance of secret accusations<br />

by the Officials of the Night, see A.S.F. Provvisioni, 123, fols. 31v-35r (1432), in Brucker’s<br />

Society, 203-204.<br />

51<br />

A.S.F., Provvisioni, 123, fols. 31v-35r (1432), in Brucker’s Society, 203-204. Also see<br />

Rocke’s Male Homosexuality, 113 for the value of a florin. According to Rocke, about four lire<br />

were equivalent to one gold florin in 1432, and around fifty florins was the average salary of a<br />

skilled laborer.<br />

52<br />

A.S.F., Provvisioni, Registri 123, 35r. (April 17, 1432), in Rocke’s Male Homosexuality, 606-12.<br />

53<br />

For more on the case of Doffo di Nepo Spini, see Rocke’s Forbidden Friendships, 56-58.<br />

54<br />

Figure from Rocke’s Forbidden Friendships, 57.<br />

55<br />

Guidice 79 (2), 44rv (Jan. 13, 1435-6), in Rocke’s Male Homosexuality, 138.<br />

56<br />

A.S.F., Provvisioni, Registri 150, 119v-120v (October 23, 1459), in Rocke’s Male<br />

Homosexuality, 646-650.<br />

57<br />

This figure comes from a chart regarding the number of convictions for sodomy by<br />

the Officers of the Night, 1432-1502, found in Rocke’s Forbidden Friendships, 199.<br />

58<br />

Aretino, Pietro, “Sonnet 10,” in Lawner Lynn ed. and trans., I Modi: The Sixteen<br />

Pleasures; An Erotic Album of the Italian Renaissance (Illinois: Northwestern <strong>University</strong> Press), 78-79.<br />

59<br />

Aretino, Pietro, “Il Marescalo,” in Five Comedies from the Italian Renaissance, ed. Laura<br />

Giannetti and Guido Ruggiero, 117-204 (Baltimore: John Hopkins Press, 2003).<br />

Chasing Sodomy During the Renaissance<br />

137


138


139<br />

Kings & Christianity<br />

T H E P O L I T I C S O F<br />

R E L I G I O U S C O N V E R S I O N<br />

IN SEVENTH-CENTURY ENGLAND<br />

C\<br />

S A M Dupont


140<br />

eex<br />

post<br />

efacto


om the withdrawal of the Roman legions from Britain in 410 A.D.<br />

until the later half of the 6th century, waves of pagan Angles, Saxons, and<br />

Jutes invaded Britain. The monk Gildas, writing around 540, described the<br />

invasions in gruesome detail, “All the major towns were laid low. Church<br />

leaders, priests, and people alike … with a purple crust of congealed blood,<br />

looked as though they had been mixed up in some dreadful wine press.” 1<br />

The native Romano-British population was destroyed, pushed west, or<br />

assimilated into Anglo-Saxon society. Christianity disappeared from lowland<br />

Britain. 2 About 596 A.D., the monk Augustine was sent to Kent by<br />

Pope Gregory I to convert the heathens. Augustine soon persuaded king<br />

Æthelbert to accept the new faith. 3 F<br />

Other Anglo-Saxon kings followed and<br />

by the end of the seventh century, all of Anglo-Saxon England had accepted<br />

Roman Christianity. This paper examines the process of the conversion<br />

of the Anglo-Saxons to Roman Christianity from the arrival of Augustine<br />

at Kent in 596 through the Synod of Whitby in 664 and argues that the<br />

ultimate success of the English conversion to Roman Christianity was due<br />

primarily to the political benefits it offered the Anglo-Saxon kings. It shows<br />

that the conversion of kings was the decisive factor in the conversion of<br />

whole peoples, that kings did not convert for spiritual reasons, and that<br />

they did so for a variety of political reasons.<br />

141


142<br />

The king played a pivotal role in mass conversions. The Germanic<br />

king was more than mere war leader. He was a sacred ruler whose combined<br />

religious and political functions were considered indissoluble. 4 The<br />

king was nothing less than the conduit that connected his people and the<br />

gods. His ties to the gods were based on his nobilitas — his descent from<br />

the god Woden — while his ties to his people and the loyalty derived<br />

from them came primarily from his virtu — his wealth, his success in war,<br />

and the material benefits and protection he gave his people. 5 The epic<br />

poem Beowulf provides an excellent example of the cultural basis of these<br />

lordship ties. Though told in a heroic setting, it nonetheless portrayed on<br />

a grand stage what people felt to be reality. 6 “Beow’s name was known<br />

through the north,” relates the storyteller, “… giving freely … so that afterwards<br />

… when fighting starts [sic] steadfast companions will [sic] stand<br />

beside him and hold the line.” 7 It was the king’s responsibility to procure<br />

divine favor by sacrificing for victory, peace, and good harvests, and<br />

his failure to do so offered sufficient justification for his people to replace<br />

him. 8 By maintaining his virtu, he thus ensured his people’s loyalty. It is in<br />

this context that the conversions of entire peoples — such as when “ten<br />

thousand of the king’s subjects were baptized” with King Æthelberht of<br />

Kent or when “King Edwin [of Northumbria], [converted] with all the<br />

nobles … and a vast number of the common people” — must be placed. 9<br />

Similarly, when Christian kings apostatized (or when they were succeeded<br />

by pagan kings), their people apostatized too. This occurred in 616, when<br />

Sæberht, king of the East Saxons, died and was succeeded by his three<br />

heathen sons. It also occurred when Sigehere, a later East Saxon king,<br />

apostatized “together with his part of the nation,” after the great plague<br />

of 664. 10 Still more evidence of the king’s decisive role in religious matters<br />

can be found in the dearth of Anglo-Saxon martyrs in the seventh<br />

century, which can be attributed to the royal protection of missionaries as<br />

well as popular acceptance of royal authority. 11 Thus, in religious matters,<br />

the people followed the king’s example.<br />

Having determined that the king’s role was of critical importance in<br />

the conversion of the mass population, the next issue at hand is the question<br />

of whether kings converted to gain spiritual or political benefits. 12<br />

The English monks who provide our primary sources for royal conversions<br />

assert that spiritual factors were paramount. For example, the monk<br />

Bede claims that King Æthelberht converted because he was “attracted<br />

by the pure life of the saints.” 13 The anonymous monk who wrote the Life<br />

of Gregory the Great recounts that King Edwin’s conversion was revealed to<br />

him beforehand in a vision from God Himself. 14 In the Life of St. Wilfrid,<br />

Eddius Stephanus relates that spiritual considerations moved Oswy, king<br />

of Northumbria, to accept Roman rather than Irish Christianity. “Tell<br />

me,” commanded the great king to the synod attendees at Whitby, “which<br />

is greater in the kingdom of Heaven, [the Celtic monk] Columba or the<br />

apostle Peter?” 15 There is good reason, however, to doubt all of these ac-<br />

SAM DUPONT


counts. A brief study of Germanic pagan religious practices suggests that<br />

Anglo-Saxon kings, at least during the first two or three generations after<br />

Augustine’s mission, lacked a sufficient understanding of the Christian<br />

worldview to undergo true conversion, defined by the recognition that<br />

personal Christian salvation is the ultimate objective in life and which is<br />

“characterized by profound personal changes in values, beliefs, identity,<br />

and behavior.” In fact, they underwent only adhesion, “the mere public<br />

compliance with ritual and legislation without much faith.” 16<br />

If the attainment of personal salvation composes the essence of true<br />

spiritual Christian conversion, then it makes sense to begin its analysis by<br />

examining pre-existing pagan beliefs in an afterlife. Bede asserted that<br />

the heathen priests of King Edwin were uncertain of the existence of life<br />

after death. “In this life man appears but for a moment,” states one high<br />

priest named Coifi, “what follows … we know not at all.” 17 However, Bede<br />

was writing from a Christian point of view, and his intent in the Historia<br />

Ecclesiastica was to promote Christianity and the salvation it offered. His<br />

story is primarily a didactic tool. 18 On the contrary, Anglo-Saxon religion<br />

asserted that warriors who died in battle joined the gods in Valhalla,<br />

where they feasted while awaiting Ragnarok, the final war against the<br />

giants that signaled the end of the world. 19 The existence of weapons,<br />

money, furnishings, and other goods in pagan gravesites verifies the belief<br />

in an Anglo-Saxon afterlife. 20<br />

The Christian worldview was so foreign to seventh-century Anglo-<br />

Saxon pagans that they were slow to comprehend the differences in their<br />

respective conceptions of the afterlife. Whereas the Anglo-Saxon worldview<br />

was marked by loyalty to lord and kin, glory in battle, the “ringgiving”<br />

of a lord to his retainers, and the communal nature of legal<br />

obligation, the Christian worldview advocated loyalty to God and His<br />

laws, and the practicing of humility and charity to the poor. Added to<br />

the problems of translating between worldviews was the more mundane<br />

one of translating between the Anglo-Saxon and Latin languages. A case<br />

in point occurred when English clerics of Ælfred the Great translated<br />

the Historia Ecclesiastica into English in the late ninth century. In doing so,<br />

they translated fides (‘faith’) as geleafa (‘permission’ or ‘license’). 21 Due to<br />

these factors, Anglo-Saxon kings had an especially difficult time coming<br />

to terms with Christian concepts of individual sin, guilt, and the means to<br />

facilitate access to Heaven. 22 For example, the Northumbrian king Oswy,<br />

a lifelong Christian, caused the murder of another Christian king, Oswine<br />

of Deira, in order to solidify his power. 23 Seemingly, he felt neither guilt<br />

nor risk to his soul from this entirely ruthless political act. From the context<br />

of his pagan worldview, failure to be virtuous in the Christian sense<br />

had no impact upon entering the afterlife. It is thus fair to say that seventh<br />

century Anglo-Saxon kings, lacking the cultural tools to truly understand<br />

Christian dogma or its consequences, were, in general, unable to experience<br />

true spiritual conversion in the Christian sense.<br />

Kings and Christianity<br />

143


144<br />

Conversely, the polytheistic nature of pagan religion made the<br />

addition of a new god into its pantheon a trivial matter, as witnessed<br />

by the ready willingness of “ten thousand” Kentings to accept baptism<br />

with Æthelberht on Christmas day in 597. 24 Even more telling are the<br />

many apostasies of kings and people alike in the seventh century, including<br />

those of the previously mentioned East Saxons after the death<br />

of King Sæberht following the plague of 664 as well as that of the<br />

Northumbrians following King Edwin’s death in battle. 25 The act of<br />

baptism did not necessarily equate to the complete understanding and<br />

acceptance of all — or even any — of the precepts of the Christian<br />

Church. The Christian god was simply another god from whom benefits<br />

might be received. Rædwald, king of the East Anglians, was so ambivalent<br />

towards Christian monotheism that even after his baptism, he “in<br />

the same temple … had one altar for the Christian sacrifice and another<br />

small altar on which to offer victims to devils.” 26<br />

Pope Gregory was well aware of the difficulties inherent in gaining<br />

true converts in Anglo-Saxon England. He therefore set Augustine’s mission<br />

on a strategy of quick adhesion, followed by slow but true conversion,<br />

as shown in a letter to Abbot Mellitus:<br />

I have decided that the idol temples should by no means be<br />

destroyed, but only the idols in them. When these people see<br />

that their shrines are not destroyed they will … be more ready<br />

to come to the places they are familiar with, but now … worshipping<br />

the true God. Do not let them sacrifice animals to<br />

the devil, but let them slaughter animals for their own food to<br />

the praise of God. 27<br />

Via this plan, pagan feasts were transformed into Christian ones.<br />

Certain pagan spring ceremonies of the field, for example, ultimately became<br />

Easter, Rogationtide, and Whitsunday. 28 The process of true conversion<br />

took so long that paganism was not outlawed in Kent until 640, and<br />

in the last Kentish law code of the seventh century, pagan practices were<br />

still common enough that the king found it appropriate to forbid men to<br />

make offerings to devils. 29<br />

The result, then, of the acceptance of baptism by kings who had<br />

been raised in an Anglo-Saxon pagan culture was that they were generally<br />

willing to superficially convert, but were extremely slow to convert in<br />

a true spiritual sense. Yet they did convert — meaning only that they accepted<br />

baptism and offered some support to Christian missionaries. Since<br />

they generally did not convert for any perceived spiritual benefit, it is left<br />

to determine what kind of benefits they did seek.<br />

In fact kings converted for a number of reasons, all designed to increase<br />

their temporal power. These can be separated into two general<br />

categories. The first of these were the very real benefits kings expected<br />

from God in exchange for their own devotion. A sense of this expectation<br />

is conveyed in the words of Coifi, a pagan high priest of King Edwin,<br />

SAM DUPONT


“None has devoted himself more earnestly than I have to the worship of<br />

our gods, but nevertheless there are many who … are more successful in<br />

their undertakings. If the gods had any power they would have helped me<br />

more readily.” 30 This concept of reciprocity was especially important for a<br />

king, due to his role as intermediary between the gods and his people. In<br />

return for the aid of God, kings offered promises of conversion, of giving<br />

a daughter to a religious institution, or of founding churches or monasteries.<br />

The Anglo-Saxon Chronicle provides one example:<br />

Then the king [Edwin] promised Paulinus to give his daughter<br />

[Eanfled] to God, if he by his prayers would obtain from<br />

God that he might overthrow his enemy who had sent the<br />

assassin there. And he went into Wessex with levies and slew<br />

five kings there and killed a great number of the people. ...<br />

And within a twelve-month the king was baptized at Easter<br />

with all his nobility. 31<br />

Thirty years later, another Northumbrian king made a similar promise:<br />

[Oswy] vowed that if he gained the victory [over Penda] he<br />

would dedicate his daughter to the Lord as a holy virgin and<br />

give twelve small estates to build monasteries. 32<br />

Offering a daughter to God should not be viewed only as the Christian adaptation<br />

of pagan sacrifice, but also as the fulfillment of a marriage alliance<br />

between the king and God, thus carrying explicit political overtones. 33<br />

Early convert kings such as Æthelberht looked across the English<br />

Channel for models of successful relationships between kings and<br />

God. There, the Merovingian royal dynasty had become the dominant<br />

rulers in Christendom. The Christian god had apparently served<br />

them well. 34 In England, several kings won decisive victories that could<br />

be attributed to the aid of God and which established them as overkings.<br />

35 Edwin’s victory over the West Saxons in 626 established him as<br />

the hegemonic English power of his day. 36 The same occurred when<br />

his successor, Oswald and his army, “small in numbers but strengthened<br />

by their faith in Christ,” defeated the British king Cædwalla,<br />

who had been ravaging the Northumbrian countryside. 37 Similarly,<br />

Oswald’s Christian successor Oswy established his overkingship after<br />

an unlikely victory over the pagan king Penda in 655. 38 The Church<br />

was quick to remind kings of their own obligations to God after such<br />

victories. For example, Bishop Paulinus’ letter reminded Edwin, who<br />

had defeated his pagan predecessor Aethelfrith: “First you have escaped<br />

with God’s help from the hands of the foes you feared; secondly<br />

you have acquired by his gift the kingdom you desired; now,<br />

in the third place, remember your own promise [to convert].” 39 Pope<br />

Honorius’ letter to Edwin was more ominous: “You know that you<br />

are a king, only on condition that you have faith in your King and<br />

Creator.” 40 However, the Christian god did not always bring victory<br />

in battle. King Penda, the pagan king of Mercia, killed a number of<br />

Christian kings in battle in the mid seventh century. Sometimes the<br />

Christian god also failed to bring happiness and health to a king’s<br />

Kings and Christianity<br />

145


146<br />

people. The plague of 664 was one such failure and compelled King<br />

Sigehere to apostatize. 41 Thus the aid of the Christian god provides<br />

one, but not necessarily the most potent, political reason to convert.<br />

The second category of reasons for a king to convert was of a<br />

more earthly sort. These benefits accrued via interactions between<br />

kings, overkings, the nobility, and the Church. One such benefit was<br />

the forming of official ties with the “great chief of the new religion<br />

in far-off Rome” and the prestige that came with it. 42 Such ties meant<br />

that the converted king entered into “the family of Catholic kings of<br />

whom the Emperor was the father.” 43 There was no greater diplomatic<br />

recognition a Western European king could acquire in the seventh century.<br />

Additionally, prestige formed a major component in the virtu of<br />

any Anglo-Saxon king. The Church thus possessed a valuable tool with<br />

which to persuade kings to convert. A letter from Pope Gregory to the<br />

newly converted Æthelberht in 601 was delivered in glorifying metaphorical<br />

language:<br />

It was thus that Constantine, the most religious emperor, converted<br />

the Roman <strong>State</strong> from the false worship of idols and<br />

subjected it and himself to Almighty God, together with the<br />

nations under his rule. So it came about that he transcended<br />

in renown the reputation of former princes and surpassed his<br />

predecessors as much in fame as he did in good works. 44<br />

Pope Vitalian used similarly exalting language in a letter to King Oswy, after<br />

the latter chose Roman Christianity, rather than its Irish counterpart,<br />

to be the recognized and practiced Christian rite in Northumbria:<br />

To the most excellent lord, our son Oswy, king of the Saxons,<br />

Bishop Vitalian, servant of the servants of God. We have received<br />

your Highness’ welcome letter. As we read it we recognized<br />

your most sincere devotion and fervent desire for the life<br />

everlasting. We know that, by God’s protecting hand, you have<br />

been converted to the true and apostolic faith. 45<br />

Note that Vitalian refers to Oswy not as king of the Northumbrians but as<br />

king of the Saxons. He is thus recognizing Oswy’s claim to the overkingship<br />

of England, a valuable benefit indeed. 46<br />

As important as prestige and recognition were, the Church nonetheless<br />

had even more to offer. After Æthelberht’s conversion in 597,<br />

Gregory sent him “sacred vessels, altar cloths and church ornaments,<br />

vestments for priests and clerks, relics of the holy apostles and martyrs,<br />

and very many manuscripts.” 47 These gifts brought further prestige,<br />

material wealth, and something new to Anglo-Saxon England literacy.<br />

48 The Latin that the early missionaries brought to England allowed<br />

kings to create their own law codes, such as the one established by<br />

Æthelberht “in the Roman manner.” These codes aided kings in the<br />

centralization of authority over their subjects. 49 Literacy also helped<br />

kings to create more efficient bureaucracies and to conduct more effective<br />

diplomacy.<br />

SAM DUPONT


Christianity also offered kings new ceremonial methods to centralize<br />

their power within their kingdoms. Mass baptisms, such as those accompanying<br />

the conversions of Æthelberht and Edwin, were one way to<br />

accomplish this. The founding of a church or the chairing of a synod,<br />

such as the one chaired by Oswy at Whitby in 664, were two other ways.<br />

All of them offered kings the opportunity to emphasize their own status. 50<br />

The hierarchical nature of Church organization, with the king at the top,<br />

followed by bishops, clergy, and the laity, also offered a route to centralized<br />

royal authority. The decentralized nature of pagan religious institutions<br />

offered no such benefit. 51<br />

Yet another form of political benefit that conversion offered kings<br />

manifested itself out of the courses of fortune and human agency that<br />

occur within the world of royal diplomacy; for example, a shift in power<br />

between two neighboring kingdoms, the potential disloyalty of a king’s<br />

nobility, or the grabbing of power by a king’s ambitious son. Such events<br />

were common in the seventh century, each of them shifted the existing political<br />

power structure, thus threatening certain kings while aiding others,<br />

and they all compelled a political response. Conversion, or the postponement<br />

of it, often offered the surest means to minimize or eliminate these<br />

threats. The timing of a king’s conversion was often as important as the<br />

conversion itself.<br />

The first conversion in England took place in Kent on Christmas<br />

597, when King Æthelberht (r. 580s– 616) accepted baptism. 52 According<br />

to Bede, “Æthelberht … was a very powerful monarch.” 53 Indeed, the<br />

kings of Wessex, East Anglia, and the Hwicce all acknowledged his overkingship.<br />

The twin pillars of his imperium were two dynastic alliances, the<br />

first with his nephew Sæberht, king of the East Saxons. 54 The second was<br />

with Frankish Neustria across the English Channel, via his marriage to<br />

the already converted Frankish princess Bertha. She was accompanied to<br />

Kent by a bishop named Luidhard, who was likely meant to act as the<br />

force behind a Neustrian mission there. 55 Neustria, which had long been<br />

ruled by the capable king Chilperic, was now waning in power. At the<br />

same time, the power of Austrasia, Neustria’s eastern neighbor and chief<br />

rival, was waxing. This shift in power between the two Frankish neighbors<br />

effectively diminished Æthelberht’s capacity to acquire luxury goods<br />

from the continent, crucial items that an overking needed to attract the<br />

best warriors. 56 It also meant that newly dominant Austrasia might cause<br />

trouble for Kent, upon which the former had almost certainly been making<br />

hegemonic claims since the mid sixth century. 57 Bishop Luidhard’s<br />

death in 595 effectively meant the end of the Neustrian mission and offered<br />

an opportunity to Pope Gregory to launch a Roman mission to<br />

Kent and to the Austrasian court to co-opt a Neustrian ally. 58 Numerous<br />

letters from Pope Gregory to the Austrasian court during this time suggest<br />

strong cooperation between the two powers in preparing Augustine’s<br />

mission. 59 His arrival in Kent in 597 offered Æthelberht an opportunity<br />

Kings and Christianity<br />

147


148<br />

to cut his ties to weak Neustria, to establish a benevolent relationship<br />

with Austrasia, and to create new ties to Rome. 60 His fear of political<br />

dependence on Neustria made him willing to accept Roman Christianity<br />

in 597, but not Frankish Christianity under bishop Luidhard earlier. 61<br />

Æthelberht’s conversion strengthened his authority, and his imperium lasted<br />

until his death in 616.<br />

The baptism of Edwin of Northumbria (r. 616-33) provides another<br />

example of how conversions took place within a political context. Edwin<br />

became king of Northumbria when he, with the help of the overking<br />

Rædwald of East Anglia, defeated and killed King Æthelfrith at the river<br />

Idle in 616 and usurped his throne, causing Æthelfrith’s son Eanfrith to<br />

flee into exile. 62 Edwin’s hold on power was initially tenuous, owing to<br />

the possibility of an attack by Eanfrith, and to the potential disloyalty of<br />

the Northumbrian nobility, who had previously benefited from the patronage<br />

of Æthelfrith. 63 On the other hand, Edwin was protected by his<br />

alliance with Rædwald, but the latter died in 624/5, and his weaker son<br />

could not provide the same protection as his father. This placed Edwin<br />

in a very precarious situation. To secure his position from both internal<br />

and external threats, Edwin needed a strong ally. He found one in the<br />

recently converted Eadbald of Kent (son of Æthelberht). In 625, their alliance<br />

was sealed by Edwin’s marriage to Æthelburh, a Christian Kentish<br />

princess. Eadbald, bishop Paulinus (who had accompanied Æthelburh to<br />

York), and Pope Boniface V all called for Edwin to convert. 64 He had<br />

reason to accept the friendship of Rome and seemingly little reason to<br />

refuse, but he nonetheless hesitated. Even the promise he made to God<br />

before his victory over Cwichhelm of Wessex in 625 failed to convince<br />

him to be baptized. The cause of Edwin’s reluctance may be owed to the<br />

Northumbrian nobility, whose loyalty was still not assured. In 628, Bede<br />

reports that Edwin called a council among his “chief men and … councilors”<br />

to see if they would accept conversion. 65 Their acceptance allowed<br />

Edwin to convert with the knowledge that his political power was secure.<br />

He ruled as an overking until 633, when he was killed in battle by the<br />

Mercian king Penda at Hatfield Chase. 66<br />

The Council of Whitby in 664 provides a unique example of the<br />

way conversions were determined by political factors, in that it was not<br />

a conversion from paganism. In this council King Oswy of Northumbria<br />

(641-70) had to decide on the accepted Christian rite within his kingdom,<br />

either the Irish one he had grown up with or the Roman rite that his<br />

wife Eanflæd practiced. According to Bede, both rites, which had different<br />

methods for computing the date of Easter, were tolerated in Oswy’s court<br />

so long as the holy bishop Aidan, who was a strong advocate of the Irish<br />

rite, lived. After his death, the growing religious tension erupted, causing<br />

Oswy and his son Alhfrith, who ruled the subkingdom of Deira for<br />

his father, to call a church council to settle the debate. 67 However, Bede’s<br />

account in this matter rests on fallacious logic, for Aidan died at least thir-<br />

SAM DUPONT


teen years before the council. 68 Further, in the intervening years, Irish and<br />

Roman dates for Easter differed less often than they normally did, and<br />

possibly not at all in 665. 69 Thus the Council of Whitby could not have<br />

been called due to religious tension.<br />

On the contrary, Alhfrith’s rivalry with his father Oswy was the primary<br />

cause. Alhfrith, who had accepted Roman Christianity years before,<br />

had been the likely heir to the throne during the 650s. But by 664, his<br />

position as heir apparent was deteriorating in favor of his half-brother<br />

Ecgfrith, who was by then nineteen years old. The reasons this occurred<br />

were twofold. First, Ecgfrith was the son of the ruling queen and second,<br />

Ecgfrith was married to a princess of East Anglia, a Northumbrian ally,<br />

while Alhfrith was brother-in-law to Wulfhere of Mercia, Oswy’s powerful<br />

enemy. 70 By calling the council, Alhfrith purposely put his father in a<br />

difficult position. If the latter chose Irish Christianity, he would alienate<br />

his Roman Christian allies in Kent and Wessex at a time when he needed<br />

their aid against Wulfhere. If he chose Roman Christianity he would have<br />

to replace his Ionan bishop Colman with a Roman replacement who was<br />

likely to favor Alhfrith and his kingly aspirations. 71 A further factor was<br />

the recent death of the archbishop of Canterbury. As an overking who<br />

was under intense pressure from Wulfhere and Alhfrith, Oswy needed to<br />

solidify his authority by asserting his right to name the new English primate.<br />

At the same time, he also had to be sure the Pope would recognize<br />

his choice, and to be assured of that, he needed to accept the Roman rite.<br />

He decided in favor of Rome. In doing so, he gained papal recognition of<br />

his overkingship and of his choice for archbishop, solidified the support of<br />

Kent and Wessex, and undermined Alhfrith’s position as the defender of<br />

the Roman rite. 72 He gained all this in exchange for his bishop Colman.<br />

Shortly after 664, in a last ditch attempt at the throne, Alhfrith rebelled. 73<br />

The fact that Bede says nothing further about him suggests he met an ignominious<br />

defeat. Oswy, meanwhile, ruled until his natural death in 670.<br />

By the reign of Ælfred the Great (r. 871-99), Roman Christianity,<br />

in all its religious and cultural dimensions, had imbedded itself within<br />

English society. From the peasantry, to the nobility, to the king himself, true<br />

Christian spiritual devotion was everywhere. While many old Germanic<br />

cultural elements remained from two and a half centuries earlier, including<br />

some semblance here and there of the old pagan religion, Christianity<br />

had nonetheless become the dominant religious culture. The transition<br />

from paganism to true spiritual Christianity in England took time. In the<br />

years after Augustine arrived in Kent, Christianity was an almost wholly<br />

new and misunderstood religion. The worldview it promoted had little in<br />

common with its Germanic counterpart. The forces of Christianity, especially<br />

the Papacy, knew this and formed their conversion strategy around<br />

Germanic elements that were familiar to the Anglo-Saxons. Knowing that<br />

the preaching of Christian salvation alone would be largely ineffective,<br />

they used every political means at their disposal to convince kings, and<br />

Kings and Christianity<br />

149


150<br />

thereby the people, to merely accept baptism. For many years, Christian<br />

religious practices remained covered in a pagan veneer. But the strategy<br />

worked. In exchange for perceived material aid from the Christian god,<br />

in exchange for gifts such as literacy from the Roman Church and its<br />

Catholic kings, and in exchange for benevolence, recognition, and prestige,<br />

the Anglo-Saxon kings all ultimately converted. A Christian England<br />

was born.<br />

NOTES<br />

01<br />

Gildas, De Excidio Britonum, trans. and ed. by Michael Winterbottom (London &<br />

Chichester: Phillimore & Co Ltd., 1978), 24.<br />

02<br />

Henry Mayr-Harting, The Coming of Christianity to Anglo-Saxon England (<strong>University</strong> Park:<br />

The Pennsylvania <strong>State</strong> <strong>University</strong> Press, 1991), 32; D. J. V. Fischer, The Anglo-Saxon Age (New<br />

York: Barnes & Noble Books, 1973), 49.<br />

03<br />

Bede, Historia Ecclesiastica Gentis Anglorum, ed. by Judith McClure and Roger Collins<br />

(Oxford & New York: Oxford <strong>University</strong> Press, 1994), I.23; G.N. Garmonsway (trans.), The<br />

Anglo-Saxon Chronicle, Ā manuscript, year 595 (London: J.M. Dent Ltd, 1972), p. 20. The Anglo-<br />

Saxon Chronicle was originally compiled sometime between 855 and 891 A.D. from as many as<br />

eight older sources, three of which contain information from the 7th century or earlier. These<br />

include (i) a chronological summary appended by Bede to his Ecclesiastical History in the 730s<br />

which contains historical information from Rome, Constantinople, and England up to Bede’s<br />

own time, (ii) lists of Northumbrian and Mercian kings along with their respective genealogies,<br />

and (iii) a series of West Saxon annals written in Latin that cover a time span from the<br />

Anglo-Saxon invasion period to the middle of the eighth century, some of which were based on<br />

oral tradition (especially for periods before the arrival of Christianity and literacy), and which<br />

provide genealogies for every West Saxon king down to Ine (688). Much of the information<br />

contained in (i) Bede’s Chronicle can be verified by other Roman sources that were brought to<br />

England by Benedict Biscop and others. They offer evidence that Bede made an honest effort<br />

to record events accurately, albeit from a Christian point of view. The antiquity of (iii) the West<br />

Saxon annals is indicated by archaic linguistic usages that were no longer used in the 9th century.<br />

The fact that they were originally written in the 7th century and therefore contemporary<br />

with events described, suggests that they too were reasonably accurate. A further method by<br />

which the chronological precision of the Chronicle can be judged is by calculating the actual<br />

dates of recorded solar and lunar eclipses. On this count, too, the Chronicle holds up well to<br />

scrutiny. The Chronicles do sometimes record an event as occurring either a year earlier or later<br />

than it actually did. This is due to the fact that different chroniclers used different days to mark<br />

the beginning of a new year. These included 25 March (the Feast of the Annunciation, both<br />

preceding and following our 1 January), 1 September (Greek Indiction day) or 24 September<br />

(Caesarian Indiction day), and 25 December. This caveat notwithstanding, the Anglo-Saxon<br />

chronicles should be judged to provide a relatively convincing record of the chronology of 7th<br />

century England. Wherever possible, however, citations of this work have been verified by Bede<br />

or other sources. See G.N. Garmonsway (ed. and trans.), The Anglo-Saxon Chronicle, p. xxiv-xlii.<br />

04<br />

William A. Chaney, The Cult of Kingship in Anglo-Saxon England (Berkeley and Los<br />

Angeles: <strong>University</strong> of California Press, 1970), 11.<br />

05<br />

Mayr-Harting, The Coming of Christianity, 18.<br />

06<br />

Fischer, The Anglo-Saxon Age, 65.<br />

07<br />

Seamus Heaney (trans.), Beowulf (New York & London: W. W. Norton & Company,<br />

2000), ll. 19-25.<br />

08<br />

N. J. Higham, The Convert Kings: Power and Religious Affiliation in Early Anglo-Saxon England<br />

(Manchester & New York: Manchester <strong>University</strong> Press, 1997), 39-40; Chaney, Cult of Kingship, 12.<br />

09<br />

Pope Gregory the Great, Epistles, viii, 29, cited in Chaney, Cult of Kingship, 158; Bede,<br />

Historia Ecclesiastica, II.14.<br />

10<br />

Bede, Historia Ecclesiastica, II.5, III.30.<br />

11<br />

Higham, The Convert Kings, p. 29.<br />

12<br />

For purposes of this paper, a political benefit is defined as one that specifically enhances<br />

the military, economic, or diplomatic power of kings. A spiritual benefit is defined as the<br />

attainment of personal salvation or the salvation of mass peoples after death.<br />

SAM DUPONT


13<br />

Bede, Historia Ecclesiastica, I.26.<br />

14<br />

Bertram Colgrave (trans.), The Earliest Life of Gregory the Great (Lawrence: The<br />

<strong>University</strong> of Kansas Press, 1968), ch. 16.<br />

15<br />

Eddius Stephanus, Vita <strong>San</strong>cti Wilfridi, trans. J. F. Webb in The Age of Bede (London:<br />

Penguin Books, 1998), ch. 10.<br />

16<br />

Higham, The Convert Kings, 14.<br />

17<br />

Bede, Historia Ecclesiastica, II.13.<br />

18<br />

It is true that the Anglo-Saxon Chronicle was itself partially based on Bede’s own writing,<br />

but it was based on several others as well. As J. M. Wallace-Hadrill has pointed out, “[Bede]<br />

was phenomenally ‘factual’ for a man who lived in a world of invention that could perpetrate<br />

straight-forward forgery with the best of intentions.” He had access to an unusual number of<br />

texts from the monastic libraries of Wearmouth and Jarrow. These included numerous tomes<br />

brought to England from Rome by Benedict Biscop in the previous generation, but also included<br />

more recently arrived texts such as the Liber Pontificalis to record events up to 716. But<br />

since Christianity and literacy went hand in hand, paganism was relatively unfamiliar to Bede<br />

and thus far less well described. Additionally, it is important to keep in mind that Bede was<br />

not writing a general history of England, but an ecclesiastical one. He wrote with the intent<br />

of showing evidence of God’s providence at work as well as to promote unity of discipline<br />

and doctrine within the Church. Therefore, one should always keep in mind several of Bede’s<br />

personal biases that become evident when reading the Historia. First, he wrote from a devoutly<br />

Christian and catholic point of view. He tends to skim over or even leave out events of a purely<br />

pagan nature. For example, he makes no mention of King Ceorl of Mercia, a contemporary<br />

of Æthelberht and a ruler with nearly as much power. Likewise, Bede uses stories of pagans,<br />

such as the pagan high priest of Edwin called Coifi, to display the superiority of Christianity<br />

over paganism. Furthermore, being a Northumbrian, he tends to emphasize his homeland<br />

over other locales and is careful to gloss over the rivalry between its two royal dynasties, the<br />

Bernician and the Deiran. One should feel reasonably comfortable accepting the accuracy of<br />

the majority of the Historia, but ought to be skeptical when Bede describes elements of paganism<br />

with which he was not very familiar and which he might have distrusted.<br />

19<br />

Mayr-Harting, The Coming of Christianity, 25.<br />

20<br />

Ibid., 23.<br />

21<br />

Higham, The Convert Kings, 17.<br />

22<br />

Ibid., 34-35.<br />

23<br />

Colgrave, Life of Gregory the Great, 7; Bede, Historia Ecclesiastica, III.14; the Anglo-Saxon<br />

Chronicle, Ā manuscript, year 651, 28.<br />

24<br />

Chaney, Cult of Kingship, 158.<br />

25<br />

Bede, Historia Ecclesiastica, III.1, III.30.<br />

26<br />

Ibid., II.15.<br />

27<br />

Ibid., I.30.<br />

28<br />

Chaney, Cult of Kingship, 57.<br />

29<br />

Ibid., 43.<br />

30<br />

Bede, Historia Ecclesiastica, II.13.<br />

31<br />

The Anglo-Saxon Chronicle, E manuscript, year 626, 25; Bede, Historia Ecclesiastica, II.9.<br />

32<br />

Bede, Historia Ecclesiastica, III.24.<br />

33<br />

Higham, The Convert Kings, 36.<br />

34<br />

Ian Wood, “The Mission of Augustine of Canterbury to the English,” Speculum, Vol.<br />

69, no. 1 (Jan. 1994): 11, Mayr-Harting, The Coming of Christianity, 63.<br />

35<br />

Bede named seven imperium-wielding kings who ruled over all the English provinces<br />

south of the river Humber; see Bede, Historia Ecclesiastica, II.5. The Anglo-Saxon Chronicle<br />

called them bretwaldas; see the Anglo-Saxon Chronicle, Ā manuscript, year 827 with citation, p.<br />

60. However, Steven Fanning has soundly argued that the bretwalda, as an official office or<br />

title, never existed; see Steven Fanning, “Bede, Imperium, and the Bretwaldas,” Speculum, Vol.<br />

66, No. 1 (Jan., 1991): 24. Further, N. J. Higham has shown that several of the bretwaldas did<br />

not, in fact, rule over all provinces south of the Humber (notably Æthelberht) and that several<br />

kings not named by Bede exerted imperium-like rule themselves (Æthelfrith of Northumbria<br />

and Ceorl of Mercia stand out); see N. J. Higham, An English Empire (Manchester & New York:<br />

Manchester <strong>University</strong> Press, 1995), 48, 51, 56. In order to avoid the confusion surrounding<br />

such terminology, I’ve chosen to use the term ‘overking’ throughout to denote any king who<br />

exerted his rule over other English peoples.<br />

36<br />

Bede, Historia Ecclesiastica, II.9.<br />

37 Ibid., III.1.<br />

Kings and Christianity<br />

151


152<br />

38<br />

Ibid; The Anglo-Saxon Chronicle, E manuscript, year 654, 29..<br />

39<br />

Bede, Historia Ecclesiastica, II.12.<br />

40<br />

Ibid., II.17.<br />

41<br />

Ibid., III.30.<br />

42<br />

Chaney, Cult of Kingship, 169-70.<br />

43<br />

J. M. Wallace-Hadrill, Early Germanic Kingship in England and on the Continent (Oxford:<br />

Clarendon Press, 1971), 32.<br />

44<br />

Bede, Historia Ecclesiastica, I.32.<br />

45<br />

Ibid., III.29. Emphasis mine.<br />

46<br />

Richard Abels, “The Council of Whitby: A Study in Early Anglo-Saxon Politics,” The<br />

Journal of British Studies, Vol. 23, no. 1 (Autumn, 1983): 15.<br />

47<br />

Bede, Historia Ecclesiastica, I.29.<br />

48<br />

The almost total dearth of texts from pre-Augustine England offers ample evidence<br />

of the absence of literacy up until that time.<br />

49<br />

Bede, Historia Ecclesiastica, II.5.<br />

50<br />

Higham, The Convert Kings, 41.<br />

51<br />

Fischer, The Anglo-Saxon Age, 63.<br />

52<br />

Higham, The Convert Kings, 58.<br />

53<br />

Bede, Historia Ecclesiastica, I.25.<br />

54<br />

Ibid., II.3; Higham, An English Empire, 193.<br />

55<br />

Higham, The Convert Kings, 73, 88. The fact that a bishop, rather than a priest, traveled<br />

with Bertha as her confessor suggests that her companion was more than a mere confessor.<br />

56<br />

Mayr-Harting, The Coming of Christianity, 18-19.<br />

57<br />

Abels, “The Council of Whitby,” 8.<br />

58<br />

Higham, The Convert Kings, 75; Abels, “The Council of Whitby,” 9. Evidence suggests,<br />

but fails to prove, Luidhard’s death in 596.<br />

59<br />

Ibid., 72.<br />

60<br />

Ibid., 86.<br />

61<br />

Mayr-Harting, The Coming of Christianity, 63.<br />

62<br />

The Anglo-Saxon Chronicle, E manuscript, year 617, 24.<br />

63<br />

Higham, An English Empire, 199.<br />

64<br />

Mayr-Harting, The Coming of Christianity, 66.<br />

65<br />

Bede, Historia Ecclesiastica, II.13.<br />

66<br />

Ibid., II.20; The Anglo-Saxon Chronicle, E manuscript, year 633, 25.<br />

67<br />

Bede, Historia Ecclesiastica, III.25.<br />

68<br />

Ibid., III.14; The Anglo-Saxon Chronicle, Ā manuscript, year 651, 28.<br />

69<br />

The system of epacts used to determine the Irish Easter cycle is still a matter of conjecture.<br />

B. MacCarthy has reconstructed an Easter cycle based on the Supputatio Romana epacts,<br />

in which Easter of 664 would have occurred a week earlier than the Roman Easter, a situation<br />

that would have occurred in fourteen of the twenty-two years in which Oswy and Eanflæd had<br />

been married. D. J. O’Connell has argued that the Alexandrian epacts would have been used by<br />

the end of the sixth century. Using this system, the two dates of Easter would have occurred on<br />

the same date in nineteen of the twenty-two year previous to Whitby, including 665. See Abels,<br />

“The Council of Whitby,” 4.<br />

70<br />

Abels, “The Council of Whitby,” 7.<br />

71<br />

Ibid., 10.<br />

72<br />

Ibid., 20.<br />

73<br />

Bede, Historia Ecclesiastica, III.25.<br />

SAM DUPONT


Reviews and<br />

H I S T O R I O G R A P H Y<br />

T\<br />

Robert O. Paxton’s<br />

The Anatomy of Fascism<br />

reviewed by Ramajana Hidi Demirovi<br />

History Becomes a Social Science:<br />

O\<br />

New Perspectives in History<br />

by Peter S. Gray


eex<br />

post<br />

efacto


Robert O. Paxton’s<br />

The Anatomy of Fascism (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 2004)<br />

RAMAJANA HIDI DEMIROVI<br />

The collapse of democracy and the<br />

abandonment of liberalism was the<br />

major theme for American historians<br />

of modern Europe after World War<br />

Two. In the decades that followed,<br />

many historians sought to develop the<br />

typology of totalitarianism as a category<br />

for historical understanding. 1 Carl J.<br />

Friedrich’s and Zbigniew Brzezinski’s<br />

attempt to devise a six point criteria<br />

which could be applied equally to<br />

Nazi Germany and Soviet Russia was<br />

followed with other, less taxonomical<br />

approaches. Hannah Arendt approached<br />

the study of totalitarianism<br />

from a standpoint of a political philosopher,<br />

producing work that continues<br />

to influence researchers across different<br />

fields. The study of totalitarianism<br />

further transformed into the study of<br />

fascism. However, as these transformations<br />

took place, two constants become<br />

apparent. Historians and other social<br />

scientists have begun to use the epithet<br />

fascist in many ways that do not conform<br />

to any guidelines. Secondly, the<br />

focus on ideology and leaders remains<br />

present in many works.<br />

Aware of these two components,<br />

Robert O. Paxton in his study The<br />

Anatomy of Fascism attempts to transform<br />

the debate on fascism. As the<br />

author claims, his objective is to pro-<br />

vide a fresh look at fascism rescuing<br />

the concept for meaningful use and<br />

accounting more for its attractiveness,<br />

its complex historical path, and its ultimate<br />

horror. 2 The purpose of the book<br />

thus has two main components. The<br />

first deals directly with the definition of<br />

a fascist movement and the use of that<br />

definition. Paxton redefines fascism as<br />

a form of political behavior marked<br />

by obsessive preoccupation with community<br />

decline, humiliation, or victimhood<br />

and by compensatory cults of<br />

unity, energy, and purity. Further, this<br />

behavior takes place in a mass-based<br />

party of committed nationalist militants,<br />

working in uneasy but effective<br />

collaboration with traditional elites,<br />

abandoning democratic liberties and<br />

pursuing, with redemptive violence<br />

and without ethical or legal restraints,<br />

goals of internal cleansing and external<br />

expansion. 3 Second, Paxton examines<br />

the role of individuals, or ordinary<br />

men and women in the formation and<br />

consolidation of fascist regimes, by exploring,<br />

“… the interaction between<br />

Leader and Nation, and between Party<br />

and civil society.” 4 The author looks<br />

at, as he calls them, fascist “actions”<br />

instead of an ideology in order to<br />

explain and redefine the meaning of<br />

155


156<br />

the term fascist, since as the author<br />

believes “…what fascists did tells us at<br />

least as much as what they said.”<br />

The Anatomy of Fascism is divided into<br />

eight chapters. Paxton gives his arguments<br />

for writing the book, his thesis and<br />

a layout of the book in the introduction.<br />

The author spends the first five chapters<br />

examining the creation of various<br />

fascist movements, their rooting in the<br />

political system, their seizure of power,<br />

the exercise of power, and its long duration,<br />

during which, Paxton claims, a fascist<br />

regime chooses either radicalization<br />

or entropy. Thus, Paxton separates five<br />

stages in order to compare several fascist<br />

movements and regimes at equivalent<br />

degrees of development.In turn, as the<br />

author claims, these five stages help the<br />

reader to see that fascism was a succession<br />

of processes and choices. In chapter<br />

seven, Paxton turns to cases that have<br />

appeared and have been branded as<br />

fascist movements in Eastern Europe in<br />

the recent times. While Paxton spends<br />

little time describing and analyzing a<br />

large number of cases, his conclusion<br />

supports his idea that the epithet fascist<br />

given to some of these regimes in fact<br />

has little grounding in what he regards<br />

to be the fascist movement. In the last<br />

few pages of the book, the author offers<br />

a Bibliographical essay in which he presents<br />

and briefly describes various works<br />

on totalitarianism and fascism that<br />

have appeared since the end of World<br />

War Two. The Bibliographical essay is<br />

divided into nine categories of books<br />

based on their theme and purpose.<br />

Thus, the reader can find extensive lists<br />

of works whose primary concern is the<br />

interpretation of fascism or the lives of<br />

its main leaders. Paxton uses many of<br />

the works listed in the Bibliographical<br />

essay in his own study. These secondary<br />

sources are further supplemented with<br />

a long list of primary sources which<br />

Paxton collected throughout his career,<br />

while researching and writing on Italian<br />

and German fascist regimes as well as<br />

in his previous work involving the Vichy<br />

regime. However, he has also obtained<br />

and used archival documents that deal<br />

with some lesser known fascist movements<br />

that appeared in Europe before<br />

World War Two.<br />

BOOK REVIEWS<br />

Paxton examines various political<br />

movements, parties and their<br />

leaders that he describes as fascist.<br />

Furthermore, Paxton examines various<br />

types of regimes in order to distinguish<br />

between these regimes and fascist<br />

regimes that appeared in the period<br />

between two world wars. Therefore,<br />

his work can be regarded as the work<br />

of a political historian attempting to<br />

disentangle the story of the fascist<br />

movement’s creation, while focusing<br />

more on participants’ “actions” rather<br />

than ideologies.<br />

Paxton’s work certainly adds to the<br />

study of fascist regimes which in itself<br />

has a long tradition. While not quite<br />

focusing on the role of the individual<br />

in various fascist movements as promised<br />

in the introduction, Paxton does<br />

set standards that can be used for the<br />

purpose of determining whether any<br />

movement that shows signs of fascism<br />

is in fact a fascist movement. Moreover,<br />

the study itself is a comparative study<br />

of different fascist movements that<br />

appeared in the interwar period<br />

throughout Europe. Thus, the author<br />

does not attempt to give us an essence<br />

of fascism. Rather, Paxton compares<br />

fascist movements in order to derive<br />

common characteristics. The fascist<br />

movements’ characteristics which<br />

the author derives are the result of<br />

historical research and analysis at its<br />

best. Furthermore, Paxton’s standards<br />

will certainly help in clarifying many<br />

misconceptions present in the study<br />

of fascist movements and the use of<br />

the term fascist. Whether or not these<br />

standards will hold depends upon<br />

further research, sparked by Robert<br />

Paxton’s research and his findings.<br />

NOTES<br />

1<br />

Volker Berghahn and Charles Maier,<br />

“Modern Europe in American Historical Writing,”<br />

in Imagined Histories: American Historians Interpret the<br />

Past, ed. Anthony Molho and Gordon S. Wood<br />

(Princeton: Princeton <strong>University</strong> Press, 1998), 403.<br />

2<br />

Robert O. Paxton, The Anatomy of Fascism<br />

(New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 2004), 8-9.<br />

3<br />

Ibid., 218.<br />

4<br />

Ibid., 9.<br />

5<br />

Ibid., 10.


History Becomes a Social Science:<br />

New Perspectives in History<br />

PETER S. GRAY<br />

In an essay in the American Historical<br />

Review in 1948, Thomas Cochran argued<br />

that the previous “fifty years of<br />

rapid growth in the social sciences<br />

have had surprisingly little effect on<br />

the general content and synthesis<br />

of American History.” 1 While referring<br />

specifically to American history,<br />

Cochran noted that this applied to<br />

American historians of Europe as well<br />

(historians of the rest of the world did<br />

not merit a mention). By contrast, the<br />

following fifty years of American historiography<br />

have seen a revolution in<br />

the use of the social sciences. One can<br />

even say that by the beginning of the<br />

twenty-first century, history was at last<br />

becoming a social science. Historians,<br />

in integrating the social sciences into<br />

their analyses, have not adopted a<br />

single social science theory or relied<br />

on a single social science discipline.<br />

Instead, there has been an eclectic<br />

use of varying theories and concepts<br />

adapted from the other social sciences.<br />

This has led to a variety of approaches<br />

from quantitative economic works to<br />

meaning-oriented cultural anthropological<br />

works. Whatever the disciplinary<br />

source of a particular historical<br />

work’s theoretical or conceptual basis,<br />

historians have refashioned what<br />

history is, moving from narratives of<br />

political events to the socio-cultural<br />

processes underlying these events.<br />

By turning to the social sciences for<br />

theoretical inspiration, historians have<br />

also opened up new fields of historical<br />

investigation. While the creation of<br />

the new histories of gender and race<br />

was certainly inspired by changes in<br />

modern society and politics, the very<br />

conceptualization of such fields would<br />

have been impossible without the social<br />

sciences. Further, the absorption<br />

of social science thinking into history<br />

has led to historians formulating problems<br />

on a world scale as economic,<br />

social, and cultural processes are seen<br />

as transcending political boundaries.<br />

This has led to the new field of world<br />

history. In what follows, several recent<br />

historical works that are representative<br />

of this integration of the social<br />

sciences into historical writing will be<br />

discussed in the context of this shift in<br />

historical knowledge.<br />

The modern social sciences were<br />

essentially a creation of the late nineteenth<br />

century, when the separate<br />

disciplines of the social sciences were<br />

created, though they have their origins<br />

in the Enlightenment. The way<br />

of doing history that was formulated<br />

at that time was different than what<br />

157


158<br />

constitutes history today, and it is this<br />

kind of history that Peter Burke calls<br />

the “Rankean” or “old” history. While<br />

it would be unfair to say that historians<br />

in the nineteenth century were<br />

unaware of social theory, professional<br />

history writing at the time — the ‘old’<br />

history — was primarily about politics<br />

and thus concerned with the nationstate<br />

and relations between nationstates.<br />

The histories of nation-states<br />

were mainly written as narratives of<br />

events and primarily concerned with<br />

individuals in the elite. Events were<br />

explained in terms of those important<br />

individuals formulating intentions and<br />

acting on them. These histories were<br />

based on analyses of written documents,<br />

usually official documents produced<br />

by the governments being studied<br />

and preserved in their archives.<br />

Historians writing the “old” history<br />

put a high premium on absolute objectivity<br />

— that the results of their investigations<br />

did not have bias as they<br />

were disinterested investigations based<br />

on documentary evidence. Finally, history<br />

was created as its own discipline,<br />

separate from the other social sciences,<br />

with its own object of study and methods.<br />

It did not borrow from the other<br />

social sciences. 2<br />

Before World War II, there were<br />

challenges to this “old” history by<br />

professionals (for example, the members<br />

of the Annales school, starting<br />

in the 1920s) and non-professionals<br />

(for example, Marxists) but it was not<br />

until after World War II that the writing<br />

of history really began to take on<br />

the social sciences. Almost everything<br />

in history writing changed. First, the<br />

object of historical study was broadened<br />

to include virtually any human<br />

activity. If it was human or related to<br />

humanity, it had a past and thus could<br />

be studied historically (as long as there<br />

was surviving evidence). The most<br />

important new object of study was<br />

society. Instead of studying important<br />

individuals, historians began studying<br />

social collectivities, especially the lives<br />

of common people — what is now<br />

commonly called “history from below.”<br />

This led to a focus on analyzing<br />

economic, social, and cultural struc-<br />

BOOK REVIEWS<br />

tures rather than narrating events, as<br />

well as to explanation by structural<br />

causes rather than individual intention.<br />

This shift also called for new<br />

forms of evidence, and not just written<br />

evidence outside of the archives:<br />

oral testimony, visual representations,<br />

statistical data, etc. Historians became<br />

more concerned with the subjective<br />

aspect of history writing and, while<br />

not giving up on objectivity (with a<br />

few contentious exceptions), began to<br />

account for the historian’s subjectivity<br />

in historical writing. Finally, all this<br />

meant that history became an interdisciplinary<br />

project, as it borrowed theories<br />

and methods from the other social<br />

sciences and even the humanities. 3<br />

This transition from the “old” history<br />

to the “new” history took place<br />

primarily after the Second World<br />

War. Before that, there were attempts<br />

to make history social scientific, especially<br />

in France. The Annales school,<br />

founded around a journal in 1929,<br />

was created by French historians who<br />

sought to turn history towards the<br />

study of society by integrating theories<br />

and methods from economics, sociology,<br />

and demography. Later, they<br />

added a quasi-anthropology through<br />

their theory of mentalités. However,<br />

the work of the Annales school was<br />

not widely disseminated outside of<br />

France at first and it was not until the<br />

late 1960s that their approach had<br />

any impact on American historians.<br />

Fernand Braudel’s major work on the<br />

Mediterranean, originally published in<br />

France in 1949, was not translated into<br />

English until 1972. In fact, there was<br />

some hostility to the Annales approach,<br />

especially in Britain, and in the United<br />

<strong>State</strong>s it has been usually only used<br />

by historians writing on non-United<br />

<strong>State</strong>s topics like Europe.<br />

This is not because American historians<br />

have been hostile to integrating<br />

the social sciences into their work.<br />

In 1948, in the article referred at<br />

the beginning of this essay, Thomas<br />

Cochran lamented the absence of social<br />

scientific theories, methods, and<br />

results in American historical works.<br />

He called for a new synthesis, one that<br />

brought the social sciences to bear on


subject matters where their use was<br />

appropriate. Cochran argued that the<br />

“old” history was inadequate in dealing<br />

with the types of problems found<br />

in modern societies, by which he<br />

meant industrial societies. He argued<br />

that the traditional emphasis on narratives<br />

of presidential acts — what<br />

he called the “Presidential Synthesis”<br />

— was unable to account for changes<br />

in society. The “old” history relied on<br />

narrative which was “often valid when<br />

applied to the actions of a single individual<br />

but [is not] usually suited to<br />

the analysis of mass phenomena.” 4<br />

Instead, social phenomena were more<br />

effectively explained in terms of structures.<br />

Cochran argued that “while the<br />

historical analysis itself must...be concerned<br />

with concrete physical, political,<br />

or social changes or events, these<br />

should be assigned place and importance<br />

on the basis of their estimated<br />

relation to underlying social forces.” 5<br />

This strategy of moving from the intentions<br />

of individual actors to causal<br />

structures was an important development<br />

in historiography. Though it has<br />

its problems, as will be seen, it represents<br />

a fundamental break with the<br />

“old” history.<br />

Integrating the social sciences into<br />

history required the formulation of a<br />

new epistemology, one that took into<br />

account traditional historical concerns<br />

and developments in philosophy and<br />

the social sciences. Michael Shermer<br />

and Alex Grobman’s Denying History<br />

provides a schematic outline of this<br />

development. Their purpose is to refute<br />

the Holocaust Deniers by showing<br />

that the Deniers, who claim to be doing<br />

legitimate historical work, are not<br />

really doing history at all but rather<br />

are motivated by ideology. To do this,<br />

Shermer and Grobman discuss what<br />

they consider history actually to be<br />

and outline three stages of epistemological<br />

development in historiography:<br />

historical objectivism, historical<br />

relativism, and historical science. In<br />

the nineteenth century, historians adhered<br />

to an objectivist epistemological<br />

paradigm which held that historical<br />

events happened independently of<br />

documentary evidence for them and<br />

interpretations of them and that these<br />

events were recorded in the documentary<br />

record in an accurate and unbiased<br />

way. Further, the historian was<br />

an objective, disinterested investigator<br />

of these documents and the product<br />

of the investigation was an objective<br />

account of what happened. Shermer<br />

and Grobman point out that this epistemological<br />

paradigm did not allow<br />

for the historian’s subjectivity and thus<br />

for bias and interest. Around the turn<br />

of the twentieth century, a new epistemological<br />

paradigm arose in historiography<br />

based on the popular relativistic<br />

philosophies of the day. This paradigm,<br />

historical relativism, holds that<br />

history is a subjective creation which<br />

historians make out of the evidence<br />

available to them: “History exists in<br />

the minds of historians.” 6 In this view,<br />

what really happened in the past is<br />

ultimately inaccessible. The problem<br />

with this epistemology is that historians,<br />

in order to do history (and not<br />

fiction), have to assume at some point<br />

that they can know something about<br />

the past. It follows that neither of these<br />

paradigms turned out to be satisfactory,<br />

as historical objectivism rules out<br />

the subjectivity of historians and historical<br />

relativism rules out any certain<br />

knowledge about the past. In the last<br />

few decades, historians have developed<br />

a newer epistemological paradigm out<br />

of the American pragmatic movement<br />

in philosophy which Shermer and<br />

Grobman call historical science (others<br />

call it “pragmatic hermeneutics”).<br />

This epistemological paradigm holds<br />

that history is both subjective and objective;<br />

history exists inside and outside<br />

the historian’s mind. Historians both<br />

discover elements of a really extant<br />

past and describe that past through<br />

their subjectivity. Historians do have<br />

biases but these can be ameliorated<br />

by various methods and, more importantly,<br />

by the convergence of evidence<br />

in the documentary record. In this<br />

new paradigm, the past has its own<br />

existence upon which historians work<br />

based upon the available evidence and<br />

their own subjectivity. Historical accounts<br />

are always subject to revision<br />

as new evidence is discovered or new<br />

AND HISTORIOGRAPHY<br />

159


160<br />

and better interpretations of existing<br />

evidence are offered. While Shermer<br />

and Grobman’s historical science is<br />

the dominant view among historians<br />

today, it has had its challengers, most<br />

recently among poststructuralist postmodernists<br />

who advocate a return to a<br />

kind of historical relativism.<br />

Shermer and Grobman do not take<br />

this subject far enough.Alan Megill<br />

expands on their notion of “historical<br />

science” (Megill does not call it that)<br />

and argues that the writing of history<br />

embodies four interrelated aspects —<br />

explanation, description or “recounting,”<br />

interpretation, and justification. 7<br />

Social scientists and historians using<br />

the social sciences previously have favored<br />

explanation over description,<br />

interpretation and justification.They<br />

have been concerned with explaining<br />

surface events by underlying causes.<br />

This is essentially what Cochran calls<br />

for in his article when he argues for<br />

placing events within the context of<br />

underlying social forces. In its most extreme<br />

form these explanations take the<br />

form of a covering-law model where<br />

universal laws are hypothesized and<br />

conclusions are deduced from these<br />

laws. Historians have rarely followed<br />

this rigid form, correctly recognizing<br />

that history does not normally<br />

conform to this type of explanation.<br />

Instead, Megill argues that an historical<br />

investigation begins with what he<br />

calls “recounting” — a kind of descriptive<br />

narrative — upon which explanations<br />

arise. Both recounting and<br />

explanation presuppose interpretation<br />

and justification. Megill discusses two<br />

types of interpretation. The first, or<br />

pre-Heideggarian, characteristic of<br />

historical objectivism, holds that texts<br />

are interpreted by an objective observer<br />

relating the part to the whole<br />

and the whole to the part. The second,<br />

or post-Heideggarian, holds that the<br />

interpretation of texts occurs not only<br />

within the text but between the text<br />

and the perspective of the interpreter.<br />

Here, the perspective in the text and<br />

the perspective of the interpreter meet<br />

— there is a “fusion of horizons,” to<br />

use Gadamer’s term. While Megill follows<br />

Heidegger, he does not argue that<br />

BOOK REVIEWS<br />

all interpretations are of equal validity,<br />

a conclusion draw by some vulgar followers<br />

of Heidegger. Interpretations<br />

must be justified in that evidence of<br />

various kinds has to be provided by the<br />

interpreter in support of the interpretation<br />

offered.<br />

Megill’s article shows some influence<br />

from a recent development in<br />

historiography — poststructuralist<br />

postmodernism. The adoption of<br />

this view by certain historians in the<br />

last three decades was perhaps a reaction<br />

to the increasing use of the<br />

social sciences in history since 1945.<br />

This view has its origins in the writings<br />

of Friedrich Nietzsche and Martin<br />

Heidegger, both of whom were profoundly<br />

influential on Michel Foucault<br />

and Jacques Derrida, the “gurus” of<br />

the poststructuralist postmodernist<br />

historians. The Nietzsche connection<br />

is important here because it links these<br />

recent developments with one of the<br />

figures who was indirectly responsible<br />

for the development of what Shermer<br />

and Grobman call historical relativism<br />

around the turn of the twentieth<br />

century. These relativistic Nietzschean<br />

views returned with a vengeance in<br />

the 1960s, particularly in France, and<br />

in the next two decades became influential<br />

in American universities as the<br />

left turned away from Marxism.<br />

There are two important elements<br />

to this approach. The first is the assumption<br />

that, ultimately, the only<br />

thing real is language and language<br />

thus constitutes consciousness. In a<br />

strategy similar to Hegel’s dismissal of<br />

Kant’s “thing-in-itself,” poststructuralist<br />

postmodernists argued that since<br />

everything we know is known through<br />

language it is impossible to know anything<br />

outside of language (and even<br />

if there is anything outside language).<br />

Thus, everything we take for granted<br />

as real is actually an effect of language<br />

and the ultimate ontological status of<br />

anything non-linguistic is unknowable.<br />

Sometimes poststructuralist postmodernists<br />

seem to assume that there is<br />

something beyond language as when<br />

Foucault talks about the body and<br />

seems to be indicating that it really has


a corporeal existence. Unfortunately,<br />

among his followers, such as sense is<br />

often lost and even denied and thus<br />

everything becomes language.<br />

A consequence of this view is that<br />

some poststructuralist postmodernist<br />

historians have abandoned the social<br />

sciences for techniques derived from<br />

literary studies. Thus, primary sources<br />

are seen not so much as repositories of<br />

evidence about what may have been in<br />

the text but rather as texts to be analyzed<br />

in literary terms. In doing this,<br />

the interpreter leaves behind the manifest<br />

content of the text in favor of “interpretation,”<br />

of discerning multiple<br />

interpretations of the text that have<br />

equal value but no necessary relation<br />

to the past. For example, the Magna<br />

Charta could be read the way a literary<br />

scholar might read Joseph Conrad’s<br />

The Secret Sharer. In some readings of<br />

Conrad’s novella, the “secret sharer”<br />

is a figment of the narrator’s imagination;<br />

in other readings, the “secret<br />

sharer” is real. Both are equally valid<br />

interpretations of the novella in terms<br />

of literary theory. For historians, such<br />

divergent readings of the Magna Charta<br />

would be incoherent.<br />

The epistemological assumption<br />

about language of the poststructuralist<br />

postmodernists leads to one important<br />

conclusion. Since all there is<br />

is language, there can be no truth (at<br />

least as it is commonly understood)<br />

and that there are only truth claims or<br />

“effects.” In other words, someone can<br />

make a claim about something being<br />

true but in reality there is nothing outside<br />

of language to validate the truth<br />

of that statement. Foucault spoke of<br />

various and differing truth regimes and<br />

the transition from one to another (or<br />

what he calls the “rupture”), but when<br />

challenged about what that meant for<br />

the truth status of his own position,<br />

he failed to give an adequate answer.<br />

In these truth regimes, what makes a<br />

statement “true” is the ability of the<br />

individual or individuals to get others<br />

to accept it as true either by consent or<br />

coercion. Even within language itself,<br />

there can be no guarantee of truth.<br />

The point of Derrida’s deconstructive<br />

strategy is to show the radical instability<br />

of texts, i.e., that texts, when carefully<br />

analyzed, always contradict themselves<br />

and always reveal meanings that were<br />

unintended by the author. In fact, these<br />

thinkers question the very existence of<br />

an author of a text. Instead, they argue<br />

that there are only discourses which<br />

speak through a subject.<br />

These ideas filtered into historical<br />

writing starting in the 1970s and<br />

until the mid-1990s they were considered<br />

by some to be the cutting edge<br />

in historical technique, though this<br />

was hardly accepted by all historians.<br />

Their influence has ebbed since the<br />

mid-1990s but they have left a positive<br />

trace despite the many real inherent<br />

problems in these views. Historians<br />

are now more aware and more concerned<br />

with language and its multiple<br />

connotations. Historians no longer<br />

take it for granted that language is essentially<br />

transparent to its object (to be<br />

fair, not all historians used to do this,<br />

but many seemed to operate under<br />

this assumption). Another legacy of<br />

poststructuralist postmodernism is the<br />

adoption of the idea of discourse. This<br />

term has many definitions and is often<br />

used as if everyone knows what exactly<br />

it means. The way current historians<br />

use it seems to be that a discourse is<br />

an institutionally, socially, or culturally<br />

produced set of categories, definition,<br />

statements, and theories about some<br />

aspect of reality. In any given society,<br />

there are multiple discourses which<br />

often contradict each other but when<br />

taken together constitute what that<br />

society considers to be reality. These<br />

discourses are internalized by individuals<br />

of society as they grow up in<br />

that society and they powerfully shape<br />

the way people see their world. What<br />

separates the current historian’s use<br />

of the term discourse from the poststructuralist<br />

postmodernist’s is that<br />

the current historian does not reduce<br />

reality to these discourses but rather<br />

sees them as produced by an actually<br />

existing non-linguistic reality (even if<br />

knowledge of that reality presupposes<br />

language). It is also important to note<br />

that the current usage of the term discourse<br />

by historians has shifted from a<br />

AND HISTORIOGRAPHY<br />

161


162<br />

term of literary analysis to essentially<br />

a term of social analysis. Discourse,<br />

like language, is social, and to talk of<br />

discourses is to talk about a social phenomenon.<br />

Shorn of its more literary<br />

connotations, discourse is a useful term<br />

for social analysis. Indeed, it seems to<br />

have replaced ideology as the preferred<br />

term for internalized social and<br />

cultural beliefs (this is primarily due to<br />

a general turn away from Marxism in<br />

the last two decades).<br />

Several recent historical works illustrate<br />

this integration of the social<br />

sciences into the writing of history.<br />

In fact, the integration of the social<br />

sciences has now reached probably<br />

the last holdout of the “old” history<br />

— diplomatic history. Diplomatic<br />

history is “old” history par excellance.<br />

Concerned with the relations between<br />

states, it relies mainly on the intentions<br />

and actions of elite individuals for its<br />

narratives. While nations, societies,<br />

and economies exist in diplomatic narratives,<br />

they are mainly assumptions<br />

and are never really analyzed. For<br />

example, in nineteenth-century diplomatic<br />

history, the fact that Germany’s<br />

rise as an industrial power led to its<br />

becoming a force to be reckoned with<br />

in the international arena is taken for<br />

granted. Diplomatic historians never<br />

go much beyond the mere statement<br />

of the fact. All the economic, social,<br />

and cultural developments that other<br />

historians analyze in depth are merely<br />

assumed by the diplomatic historian<br />

as if everyone knew what terms like<br />

the nation-state, nationalism, industrialization,<br />

and so on meant. In fact,<br />

historians are constantly debating the<br />

meaning of these terms and how these<br />

aspects of social reality work themselves<br />

out in history.<br />

Michael Connelly’s A Diplomatic<br />

Revolution 8 has two aims: first, to look<br />

at the Algerian revolution from an international<br />

prospective and second, to<br />

reconceptualize traditional diplomatic<br />

history by integrating into it the social<br />

sciences. While the work argues that<br />

the Algerian revolution was won in the<br />

diplomatic sphere, it puts this diplomacy<br />

in a social scientific context heavily<br />

BOOK REVIEWS<br />

influenced by the Annales school. The<br />

Annales school arose in France in the<br />

1920’s and the Annalistes specifically<br />

wanted to make history more social<br />

scientific by integrating the most recent<br />

developments in economics,<br />

sociology, demography, and anthropology.<br />

The Annales school tended to<br />

downplay political events, arguing that<br />

long-term economic and social structures<br />

and conjunctures (trends) were<br />

more important causally than political<br />

events. In fact politics was determined<br />

by these economic and social structures<br />

and conjunctions. Even though<br />

Cochran shows no knowledge of the<br />

Annales school, he was essentially making<br />

the same general argument that<br />

they did. While later the Annalistes became<br />

associated with attempting total<br />

history (not to be confused with world<br />

history) as in the works of Fernand<br />

Braudel, many Annalistes worked on<br />

smaller subjects and Connelly’s book<br />

is an example of this. Connelly argues<br />

that long-term demographic trends in<br />

Algeria combined with the failure of<br />

French attempts modernized Algerian<br />

economy and society (attempts which<br />

were mainly aimed at the French<br />

colonists there rather then the indigenous<br />

population) ultimately led to a<br />

situation where many Algerians saw<br />

a revolt for independence as the only<br />

solution to their situation.<br />

Even Connelly’s diplomatic history<br />

has a warrant from the Annales school.<br />

Nineteenth-century history writing<br />

was overwhelmingly national in orientation,<br />

but Braudel, in his work on<br />

the Mediterranean, encouraged a regional<br />

(and in later writings, a global)<br />

approach. While nations certainly had<br />

their importance (at least within a<br />

world view that took them seriously),<br />

economic and social structures and<br />

conjunctures were not limited by arbitrary<br />

national boarders. Connelly<br />

situates the Algerian revolution internationally<br />

because while ostensibly<br />

an internal problem for the French,<br />

the revolt had international ramifications<br />

during the Cold War, especially<br />

because of the concerns of the United<br />

<strong>State</strong>s over military bases in the region<br />

to counter a perceived Soviet threat.


Additionally, the Algerian revolutionaries<br />

realized early on that the international<br />

struggle was decisive — in order<br />

to gain independence, the Algerians<br />

had to drive a wedge between France<br />

and the United <strong>State</strong>s over the Algeria.<br />

For the United <strong>State</strong>s, the stakes were<br />

geostrategic but also related to the<br />

long-term structures and conjunctures<br />

on a world scale. The Algerian revolution<br />

was one of several struggles for independence<br />

at the time that all reflected<br />

the end of the social and economic<br />

structures created by the European<br />

Imperial powers in the previous four<br />

centuries. A new world social and economic<br />

system was coming into being<br />

and the United <strong>State</strong>s was desperate to<br />

control its creation and ultimate form.<br />

Not all histories that utilize the<br />

social sciences are as ambitious as<br />

Connelly’s and instead of attempting<br />

an Annales school total history,<br />

they restrict themselves to adopting<br />

specific theories that seem to fit the<br />

subject being studied. One such book<br />

is William Harris’s Restraining Rage. 9<br />

This book focuses on the discourse of<br />

anger control in the ancient Greco-<br />

Roman world. It is a work of classics<br />

and so the hallmarks of the classics<br />

approach to writing history are everywhere.<br />

This approach is rooted in the<br />

“old” history discussed above in that<br />

it emphasizes textual analysis. A great<br />

deal of Restraining Rage is devoted to<br />

analyzing the meanings of the Greco-<br />

Roman words relating to anger and<br />

to explicating the Greco-Roman texts<br />

on anger and anger control. Even so,<br />

Harris wants to explain why a discourse<br />

of anger control developed<br />

in the Greco-Roman world and here<br />

he relies on a sociological theory of<br />

Norbert Elias. Elias argued that the<br />

development of civilized society or<br />

civil society in the West starting at<br />

the end of the Middle Ages occurred<br />

due to a rise in emotional self-control.<br />

Individuals restrained their aggression<br />

not only out of self-interest but<br />

also because individuals internalized<br />

doctrines of restraint propagated by<br />

educated elites. Harris argues that<br />

this process can be seen at work in the<br />

ancient Greco-Roman world in the<br />

163<br />

discourse of anger control and thus<br />

transposes Elias’s theory to the results<br />

of his discussion of the Greco-Roman<br />

discourse of anger control. Harris’s<br />

theoretical strategy is different than<br />

that of Connelly (and the Annales<br />

school). He takes one specific theory<br />

designed to explain a specific development<br />

in one time and place and<br />

then transposes it to another time and<br />

place. This is an eclectic strategy that<br />

is common in modern historical writing.<br />

Historians usually do not have the<br />

time to master even one of the other<br />

social science disciplines (let alone all<br />

of them) and so they often fish around<br />

for theories and concepts which seem<br />

useful for what they are investigating.<br />

Other social sciences come into<br />

play in Harris’s work, notably psychology<br />

and anthropology. When Harris<br />

discusses anger, he does not define it as<br />

much as offer various understandings<br />

of it from the Greco-Roman world<br />

and, for comparative purposes, modern<br />

psychological theories. This is essentially<br />

an anthropological approach<br />

in that anger control is seen as the<br />

different rules that different cultures<br />

construct regarding the appropriate<br />

and inappropriate expression of anger.<br />

There is no “essence” to anger here,<br />

except perhaps that something like it is<br />

found in all cultures, but only cultural<br />

beliefs and roles.<br />

Anthropology is a seemingly endless<br />

source of ideas for historians.<br />

James Brooks’s Captives and Cousins 10<br />

brings together anthropology with<br />

another new type of history writing<br />

derived from the social sciences,<br />

Microhistory. Indeed, Microhistory is<br />

heavily influenced by anthropology. It<br />

seeks to reduce the scale of historical<br />

investigation while not losing sight of<br />

the interconnections between the local<br />

and the global. As Giovanni Levi<br />

writes, Microhistory “is essentially<br />

based on the reduction of the scale<br />

of observation, [it is] a microscopic<br />

analysis and an intensive study of the<br />

documentary materials.” 11 This makes<br />

Microhistory similar to an anthropologist’s<br />

intensive study of a small community<br />

except instead of living in that<br />

AND HISTORIOGRAPHY


164<br />

community for an extended period<br />

of time and intensely observing how<br />

that community operates, the historian<br />

intensively studies the surviving<br />

documentary evidence. Microhistories<br />

tend to be influenced by the ideas<br />

of Clifford Geertz and his notion of<br />

“thick description.” In this approach,<br />

the observer does not try to impose a<br />

law-like theory on his observations (as<br />

in Megill’s understanding of explanation)<br />

but rather tries to fit signifying<br />

signs into an intelligible structure.<br />

Here, the historian is concerned with<br />

meaning. This approach is related to<br />

poststructuralist postmodernism but<br />

Microhistorians never leave the basics<br />

of historical method for literary analysis.<br />

The concern here is like that of<br />

most anthropologists, i.e. with cultural<br />

meanings rooted in economic and social<br />

structures.<br />

Brooks takes as his subject the interactions<br />

of the different cultures in<br />

the Southwest borderlands of North<br />

America and the distinctive system<br />

of slavery and kinship that developed<br />

there. In a nod to “thick description,”<br />

Brooks begins his book with a description<br />

of a ritual common in the<br />

Southwest borderlands that combines<br />

a Christmas ritual with symbolic bridestealing.<br />

This leads to a discussion of<br />

the slave system in the region. This<br />

slave system grew out of the exercise<br />

of power between Native American<br />

and Euramerican inhabitants there.<br />

To protect and preserve their power<br />

within their families and communities<br />

men from these cultures negotiated interdependency<br />

and maintained power<br />

by acknowledging the exchangeability<br />

of their women and children. It is<br />

commonplace in the anthropological<br />

literature (so much so that Brooks does<br />

not feel obligated to cite a particular<br />

theoretical tradition in anthropology<br />

in support of it) that cultures establish<br />

links with each other through the exchange<br />

of women either willingly or<br />

by force. In the Southwestern borderlands,<br />

the method was force and the<br />

captured women and children were<br />

enslaved. At the same time that they<br />

were enslaved, these women and children<br />

were integrated into the captur-<br />

BOOK REVIEWS<br />

ing culture, primarily through intermarriage.<br />

The new members of the<br />

community brought their original culture<br />

with them and over time elements<br />

of these cultures were integrated into<br />

the capturing culture.<br />

Anthropology is not the only way to<br />

approach culture. European Marxists<br />

have developed analyses of culture out<br />

of Marx’s works as well as traditional<br />

European Kulturkitik. The work of cultural<br />

Marxists builds off of Marx’s<br />

incomplete oeuvre as Marx made<br />

only passing comments about culture.<br />

Instead, Marx was concerned with the<br />

structure of capitalist society, particularly<br />

its economy. Marx argued that<br />

societies were structured by classes<br />

and marked by class struggle. In the<br />

most abstract sense, societies consist<br />

of the direct producers of the society’s<br />

wealth (whether in agricultural or industrial<br />

societies) and a class who appropriates<br />

the results of the labor of<br />

the direct producers. 12 Each society<br />

has its own structure which has its own<br />

specific historical development. Marx<br />

argued that the specific way a society<br />

structures this basic relationship conditions<br />

almost everything else in that<br />

society. This is not an economic determinism.<br />

What he was talking about<br />

were social relationships that structure<br />

how people provide for their needs and<br />

how these fundamental relationships<br />

are refracted throughout the society.<br />

Cultural Marxists of the twentieth<br />

century have been less concerned with<br />

the structure of modern capitalist societies<br />

— there are (or were) plenty of<br />

Marxists working on that — and have<br />

been more concerned with how the<br />

above basic abstract idea works itself<br />

out in other areas of human life, especially<br />

culture. Many of the aspects of<br />

these theories are esoteric and arcane<br />

but historians working in this tradition<br />

have put some of it to good use. An<br />

example of this is Timothy Burke’s<br />

Lifebuoy Men, Lux Women. 13 Burke<br />

analyzes the development of a commodity<br />

culture in modern Zimbabwe<br />

beginning in the late nineteenth century.<br />

The central theory here is Marx’s<br />

notion of commodity fetishism as de-


veloped in the twentieth century by<br />

cultural Marxists out of a chapter in<br />

Marx’s Capital. 14 In a capitalist society<br />

or a society impacted by capitalism,<br />

commodities assume an independent<br />

life from their production and use and<br />

relations between things accompany,<br />

control, or displace the actual state of<br />

relations between people. In a capitalist<br />

society or one under capitalist domination,<br />

the relation that is displaced in<br />

individuals’ consciousness is the class<br />

relation. Commodity fetishism is more<br />

than the meanings invested in goods, it<br />

is also the accumulated power of commodities<br />

to actually constitute, organize,<br />

to contain within themselves the<br />

forms of consciousness through which<br />

capitalism manufactures its subjects.<br />

In this process, the properties ascribed<br />

to commodities become “natural”<br />

properties with no history. In effect,<br />

capitalism becomes the natural state<br />

of affairs — while things were different<br />

back then, in effect they were always<br />

the same. Burke borrows Gramsci’s<br />

understanding of “common sense”<br />

to exemplify this point. For Gramsci,<br />

“common sense” is a manufactured<br />

artifact consisting of dicta lodged in<br />

the public memory of a given society<br />

that everyone “knows” to be true,<br />

dicta that act to reproduce relations of<br />

domination as “natural” occurrences,<br />

thus serving the interests of the ruling<br />

class. This does not happen without<br />

resistance and these meanings are negotiated,<br />

though one side in the negotiations<br />

has a preponderance of power<br />

in the definition of “common sense.”<br />

Another new perspective in history<br />

is that of gender. Gender as an object<br />

of study has grown out of women’s<br />

history. Women’s history itself is a recent<br />

creation, coming out of the long<br />

struggle for women’s emancipation but<br />

not really becoming a part of the historical<br />

profession until the 1960s with<br />

the arrival of the “Second Wave” of<br />

feminism. At that time, women historians<br />

put women’s history on the agenda<br />

in the historical profession. This led to<br />

numerous debates over professionalism<br />

and politics, and history and ideology,<br />

all of which were more than tainted by<br />

the male historians’ desire to control<br />

the writing of women’s history, though<br />

there were some principles at stake. By<br />

the 1990s, women’s history had become<br />

gender history. This was because<br />

practitioners of women’s history realized<br />

that in order to integrate women<br />

into history they needed to reconceptualize<br />

sexual “difference and how its<br />

construction defined relations between<br />

individuals and groups.” 15 Women<br />

were not strictly separable from men<br />

in analysis as both existed (and exist)<br />

in relation to each other. Thus, gender<br />

as a social category arose to capture<br />

the social and cultural relationships<br />

between men and women. Joan Scott<br />

has offered a definition of gender as<br />

a category: “gender is a constitutive<br />

element of social relationships based<br />

on perceived differences between the<br />

sexes, and gender is a primary way of<br />

signifying relationships of power.” 16<br />

As such gender involves four interrelated<br />

elements: (1) culturally available<br />

symbols that evoke multiple (and often<br />

contradictory) representations, (2) normative<br />

concepts that set forth interpretations<br />

of the meanings of symbols or<br />

that attempt to limit and contain their<br />

metaphoric possibilities, (3) economic<br />

and political aspects beyond kinship,<br />

and (4) subjective identity. 17<br />

Mary Renda’s Taking Haiti 18 is an<br />

example of this new gender history.<br />

It is not a work of women’s history<br />

but rather about the construction of a<br />

particular kind of masculinity. Renda<br />

argues that the American occupation<br />

of Haiti contributed to the creation of<br />

a new masculine imperial culture in<br />

the United <strong>State</strong>s in the early twentieth<br />

century. The American occupation<br />

of Haiti called forth a new discourse<br />

based on paternalism which contributed<br />

to a new masculine imperial culture<br />

in the United <strong>State</strong>s. Paternalism was<br />

“an assertion of authority, superiority,<br />

and control expressed in the metaphor<br />

of a father’s relationship with his children.”<br />

19 This discourse was internalized<br />

by many Americans, not only the<br />

United <strong>State</strong>s Marines who occupied<br />

Haiti but also in the United <strong>State</strong>s as<br />

it filtered into popular culture through<br />

works of literature and travel writings<br />

(some of these writings were meant to<br />

AND HISTORIOGRAPHY<br />

165


166<br />

subvert the discourse, e.g. the writings<br />

of Zora Neale Hurston). Its function<br />

was to justify and facilitate the occupation<br />

of Haiti and, more broadly,<br />

any less-developed country which the<br />

United <strong>State</strong>s’ government chose to<br />

occupy. Paternalism itself is a specifically<br />

gendered concept in that it is the<br />

masculine father that is in control.<br />

The Haitians were an “inferior” children<br />

who needed the authority of the<br />

United <strong>State</strong>s as a “father” in order to<br />

have any chance of becoming a developed<br />

nation — an “adult.”<br />

In Taking Haiti, race also plays a<br />

role as Renda never forgets that the<br />

Haitians were seen as a different and<br />

“inferior” race by the Americans. Race<br />

is another category which transcends<br />

any particular social science discipline<br />

and is a central new perspective in<br />

historiography. Like gender, recent<br />

attention in race is a result of political<br />

events — Nazi racial ideology and<br />

its corollary the Holocaust, the Civil<br />

Rights movement in the United <strong>State</strong>s,<br />

and the national liberation movements<br />

that occurred throughout the world after<br />

1945. While now biologists usually<br />

agree that race as a biological concept<br />

has no reality, historically it has been a<br />

powerful concept that has been used<br />

to explain many things but usually<br />

why one “race” should be subordinate<br />

to another. As such, race is a discourse<br />

— a powerful one — a set of beliefs<br />

about how to classify human beings<br />

and to rank-order them in their level<br />

of “civilization” or “development” by<br />

their apparent physical characteristics.<br />

Ada Ferrer’s Insurgent Cuba 20 analyzes<br />

the discourse of race in Cuba<br />

during the Cuban revolution from<br />

1868-1896. Ferrer’s main concern<br />

is with how both sides in the conflict<br />

attempted to shape the discourse of<br />

race to achieve their goals. The rebels<br />

developed a conception of a raceless<br />

nationality in opposition to the racebased<br />

discourse of the Spanish regime.<br />

Their goal in doing this was to<br />

overcome differences among Cubans<br />

in order to bring them together and<br />

overthrow Spanish colonial rule and<br />

establish an independent Cuba. Ferrer<br />

argues that this new discourse was<br />

BOOK REVIEWS<br />

crucial to the ultimate success of the<br />

revolution. This new conception of<br />

a raceless nation was revolutionary<br />

in its own right. For European and<br />

Americans in the nineteenth century,<br />

as well as for many who lived under<br />

their rule, race and racial hierarchies<br />

were a fact of nature supported by the<br />

best science. One thinks of Gramsci’s<br />

notion of “common sense” here. For<br />

the Cuban revolutionaries to claim<br />

that there were no races in Cuba but<br />

only Cubans was to attack directly a<br />

central pillar of Spanish rule there.<br />

For the Spanish rulers, race was linked<br />

to nationality and they believed that<br />

only certain races were equipped to<br />

rule themselves. Since most Cubans<br />

were black Africans, there could be no<br />

Cuban nation because black Africans<br />

were incapable of self-rule. Thus,<br />

Cuba had to remain a Spanish colony<br />

not because Spain needed Cuba for<br />

economic or political reasons but because<br />

the Spanish thought that it was<br />

best for the Cubans. Unfortunately,<br />

as Ferrer points out, the discourse of<br />

race proved to be very strong among<br />

the revolutionaries who had formulated<br />

the discourse of a raceless nation.<br />

Some black Cubans in the rebel movement<br />

towards the end of the rebellion<br />

used the discourse of a raceless nation<br />

against their fellow insurgents and accused<br />

them of being, in effect, racists<br />

who discriminated against Cuban revolutionaries<br />

of African ancestry. This<br />

shows the power and persistence of<br />

discourses even among those who are<br />

consciously trying to overcome them.<br />

The books dealt with so far here<br />

have had modest goals. They generally<br />

take a small subject and try<br />

to analyze it thoroughly. Only A<br />

Diplomatic Revolution had a truly ambitious<br />

goal but even there the author<br />

stepped back from his ambitious integrative<br />

goals and ultimately came up<br />

with a more human sized book. The<br />

final book discussed here stands out<br />

for its theoretical ambition as well as<br />

its scope as it is a work of world history.<br />

When history became a discipline<br />

in the late nineteenth century,<br />

the European powers ruled most of<br />

the world through various formal and


informal means. Europeans wrote histories<br />

of the countries they controlled,<br />

not all of which were designed to support<br />

that rule (though some were), but<br />

these historians never really thought<br />

about the overarching processes at<br />

work around the globe. This is a little<br />

surprising given that there was an imperial<br />

system and a world market by<br />

the end of the century, but it is less<br />

surprising when it is remembered<br />

that historians at the time did not really<br />

think in terms of social processes.<br />

Instead, they thought in terms of narratives<br />

of political events, nations, and<br />

international relations. After 1945, as<br />

historians turned towards the social<br />

sciences historians began thinking in<br />

terms of macro-processes involving<br />

the whole world. Economics, sociology,<br />

and even culture led historians to<br />

think not only beyond politics but also<br />

beyond national borders to socio-cultural<br />

processes transcending nationstates.<br />

It can be said that Marxists had<br />

a role in this in that their discussions<br />

of imperialism always saw imperialism<br />

as a worldwide system (whatever the<br />

merits of their specific theses).<br />

Mike Davis’s Late Victorian Holocausts<br />

21 exemplifies this new world history<br />

because it treats its subject in a<br />

world scale by analyzing an aspect of<br />

the world imperial system of the late<br />

nineteenth century. Further, it integrates<br />

the social sciences with history<br />

from a Marxist point of view while also<br />

seeking to integrate the natural sciences,<br />

specifically climatology, within its<br />

narrative. Davis argues that the severe<br />

droughts that occurred in various parts<br />

of the globe in the late nineteenth century<br />

— India, China, and Brazil are<br />

the main examples — were the result<br />

not only of natural factors but also of<br />

social and historical factors. One element<br />

was the El Niño phenomenon<br />

which, while unknown at the time, has<br />

subsequently been discovered and analyzed<br />

(though it is not yet completely<br />

understood). In itself, the El Niño phenomenon<br />

had probably caused some<br />

hardship in the centuries before the<br />

late nineteenth century but the societies<br />

affected by it had developed methods<br />

with which to cope. What was dif-<br />

ferent in the late nineteenth century<br />

was that these societies were under the<br />

control, either formally or informally,<br />

of the European imperial powers and<br />

had recently been integrated into the<br />

new world capitalist economy which<br />

was, naturally, controlled by Europe.<br />

At its crudest level, this meant that food<br />

surpluses which previously would have<br />

been distributed by the central governments<br />

of these countries within these<br />

countries to alleviate famine were instead<br />

sold on the world market where<br />

they went to those who would pay the<br />

most for them.Thus, countries suffering<br />

extreme famine in some regions<br />

exported surpluses from other regions<br />

to Europe because Europeans offered<br />

the highest price for those commodities.<br />

This was justified in terms of an<br />

ideology of free markets and free trade<br />

which was seen by the Europeans as<br />

the “natural” way the world worked<br />

and would ultimately benefit all involved<br />

(Gramsci’s “common sense”<br />

again?). They maintained this position<br />

(their heirs still maintain this position)<br />

despite all evidence to the contrary. In<br />

the course of roughly 30-40 years of<br />

on-again, off-again famine, millions<br />

died in these countries.<br />

The most important conclusion that<br />

Davis draws from this is that what we<br />

have come to call the Third World was<br />

essentially created at this time. Famine<br />

not only meant a massive loss of life<br />

but also a massive loss of productive<br />

capital as peasants consumed the livestock<br />

they normally would have used<br />

productively in order to survive the<br />

famine. Peasants also sold land they<br />

owned or gave up their leases on lands<br />

they tilled in order to gain some means<br />

by which to buy food and survive. All<br />

of these taken together represented<br />

a massive dispossession of peasant<br />

wealth. Those who survived had much<br />

less than they had before and found<br />

that wealth was now even more heavily<br />

concentrated in fewer hands. While<br />

Davis does not draw the parallel, it is<br />

strikingly similar (in effect if not cause)<br />

to the dispossession of the peasantry<br />

in Europe in the early modern era.<br />

Unlike Europe, however, the countries<br />

Davis discusses had been integrated<br />

AND HISTORIOGRAPHY<br />

167


168<br />

into a world economy designed to<br />

favor Europe (and later the United<br />

<strong>State</strong>s) and thus could not follow the<br />

European development path (let alone<br />

the path the United <strong>State</strong>s followed).<br />

In Davis’s view, the famine of the late<br />

nineteenth century created the structural<br />

imbalance in the world economy<br />

that we have today. The world outside<br />

of Europe was not always poor and<br />

underdeveloped; it was made that way<br />

by European imperial domination.<br />

In the Cochran article referred to<br />

previously, he argued that traditional<br />

narrative and social scientific explanation<br />

were essentially incompatible.<br />

Several decades later, Bernard Bailyn<br />

argued that the integration of the social<br />

sciences into history had created<br />

several narrative challenges for historians.<br />

He argued that:<br />

there are...at least three general<br />

trends in motion, three lines<br />

of development generated by<br />

the force of scholarship itself,<br />

which in varying ways will enrich,<br />

but also complicate, any<br />

comprehensive narratives that<br />

are written: the fusion of latent<br />

and manifest events, the depiction<br />

of large-scale spheres and<br />

systems organized as peripheries<br />

and cores, and the description<br />

of internal states of mind<br />

and their relation to external<br />

circumstances and events. 22<br />

Unlike Cochran, who seemed to call<br />

for the abandonment of narrative,<br />

Bailyn sees the new social scientific<br />

history as a challenge for historians.<br />

While not an explicit response to<br />

Bailyn’s article, Paul Cohen’s History<br />

in Three Keys 23 deals with the narrative<br />

problems laid out by Bailyn. Cohen’s<br />

purpose is to discuss the writing of history<br />

itself through the example of the<br />

Boxer rebellion in China in 1900. He<br />

argues that there are at least three ways<br />

an historian can write the history of an<br />

event: as a narrative of events, as the<br />

lived experience of the participants in<br />

that event, and as the past constructed<br />

by what he terms mythologizers. The<br />

major portion of the book is taken<br />

up by looking at the Boxer Rebellion<br />

through each of these approaches.<br />

BOOK REVIEWS<br />

Cohen’s first approach, the narrative<br />

of events, is the usual strategy taken by<br />

historians. Here, the historian tells the<br />

story of what happened by explaining<br />

its causes and putting it within a broad<br />

context. What troubles Cohen is that<br />

this is a construction of the historian<br />

who knows how the event came about,<br />

how it developed, and how it ended<br />

because it has already occurred in the<br />

past. Further, the historian has a broad<br />

sense of the context within which the<br />

event took place. This gives the historian<br />

a different perspective on the event<br />

from those who actually participated<br />

in it. They did not know all that went<br />

into the initiation of the event, what<br />

caused it to develop as it did, and they<br />

had no idea of its outcome. Neither<br />

were they usually conscious of the<br />

wider context.<br />

None of this is meant to deny the<br />

value of the historian’s account as<br />

there is more to an event than what<br />

the participants are conscious of.<br />

Nevertheless, the historian’s account<br />

downplays the lived experience of<br />

the participants. This leads Cohen to<br />

propose that historians need histories<br />

of people’s lived experiences of events<br />

which takes into account their limited<br />

knowledge of what was happening and<br />

the undecidedness of the outcome. In<br />

Cohen’s own account of the lived experience<br />

of the Boxer Rebellion, he<br />

relies heavily on anthropology, showing<br />

that even in a book about narrative<br />

strategies, the social sciences are still<br />

central to the historian’s work.<br />

For Cohen, there is a third type<br />

of narrative that historians can write.<br />

This is the narrative of the narratives<br />

of the event as written by later writers<br />

(historians are not included in this category).<br />

While these writers often believe<br />

that what they write is true, as do their<br />

readers, they process the event through<br />

a predetermined agenda influenced by<br />

their current circumstances designed<br />

to score political points. Cohen calls<br />

this kind of writing mythology and its<br />

writers mythologizers. What Cohen<br />

argues is that the historian can write<br />

an account of these mythologies by<br />

recounting how and why they develop.


What is important is that these mythological<br />

accounts can be very powerful<br />

and persuasive in the societies in which<br />

they are formulated. This alone makes<br />

them worthy of study.<br />

At the beginning of this essay it<br />

was suggested that history in the early<br />

twentieth century was finally becoming<br />

a social science. The brief survey of<br />

eight recent works of history that followed<br />

more than show this to be an accurate<br />

statement. The books addressed<br />

a wide variety of topics covering the<br />

globe and while they focused more on<br />

the last few centuries, the ancient world<br />

was not excluded. They are eclectic in<br />

the social scientific theories and methods<br />

that they use, which was pointed<br />

out as one of the characteristics of the<br />

new history at the beginning. What is<br />

clear is that history can no longer be<br />

written without the social sciences.<br />

While still a discipline unto itself, history<br />

is at the same time inseparable<br />

from the other social sciences.<br />

NOTES<br />

1<br />

Thomas Cochran, “The ‘Presidential Synthesis’<br />

in American History,” American Historical<br />

Review 53:4 (July 1948), 748.<br />

2<br />

Peter Burke, “Overture. The New History:<br />

Its Past and Future” in Peter Burke (ed.), New<br />

Perspectives on Historical Writing, 2nd ed. (<strong>University</strong><br />

Park, PA: The Pennsylvania <strong>State</strong> <strong>University</strong> Press,<br />

2001), 2-6.<br />

3<br />

Ibid.<br />

4<br />

Cochran, 751.<br />

5<br />

Ibid., 788.<br />

6 .<br />

Michael Shermer and Alex Grobman, Denying<br />

History (Berkeley: <strong>University</strong> of California Press,<br />

2000), 20.<br />

7<br />

Alan Megill, “Recounting the Past: ‘Description,’<br />

Explanation, and Narrative in Historiography,”<br />

American Historical Review 94:3 (June 1989),<br />

627-53.<br />

8<br />

Michael Connelly, A Diplomatic Revolution<br />

(Oxford: Oxford <strong>University</strong> Press, 2002).<br />

9<br />

William V. Harris, Restraining Rage (Cambridge:<br />

Harvard <strong>University</strong> Press, 2001).<br />

10<br />

James F. Brooks, Captives and Cousins (Chapel<br />

Hill: <strong>University</strong> of North Carolina Press, 2002).<br />

11<br />

Giovanni Levi, “On Microhistory” in Peter<br />

Burke (ed.), loc. cit., 99.<br />

12<br />

Karl Marx, Capital vol. I, trans. Ben Fowkes<br />

(New York: Penguin Books, 1976).<br />

13<br />

Timothy Burke, Lifebuoy Men, Lux Women<br />

(Durham: Duke <strong>University</strong> Press, 1996).<br />

169<br />

14<br />

Marx, 163-77.<br />

15<br />

Joan Scott, “Women’s History” in Peter<br />

Burke (ed.), loc. cit., 56.<br />

16<br />

Joan Scott, “Gender: A Useful Category of<br />

Historical Analysis,” American Historical Review 914:5<br />

(December 1986), 1067.<br />

17<br />

Ibid., 1067-68.<br />

18<br />

Mary A. Renda, Taking Haiti (Chapel Hill:<br />

<strong>University</strong> of North Carolina Press, 2001).<br />

19<br />

Ibid., 15.<br />

20<br />

Ada Ferrer, Insurgent Cuba (Chapel Hill:<br />

<strong>University</strong> of North Carolina Press, 1999).<br />

21<br />

Mike Davis, Late Victorian Holocausts (New<br />

York: Verso, 2001).<br />

22 .<br />

Bernard Bailyn, “The Challenges of<br />

Modern Historiography,” American Historical Review<br />

87:1 (February 1982), 22.<br />

23<br />

Paul A. Cohen, History in Three Keys (New<br />

York: Columbia <strong>University</strong> Press, 1997).<br />

AND HISTORIOGRAPHY

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!