10.04.2013 Views

BRIBERY IN CLASSICAL ATHENS Kellam ... - Historia Antigua

BRIBERY IN CLASSICAL ATHENS Kellam ... - Historia Antigua

BRIBERY IN CLASSICAL ATHENS Kellam ... - Historia Antigua

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Conover Bribery in Classical Athens Chapter One<br />

for example, by obtaining even just a rough approximation of what the Athenians<br />

considered an ‘abuse’, ‘public’, ‘power’, ‘private’ and ‘gain’, we might begin to<br />

understand which actions did and did not constitute bribery at Athens. From there we<br />

could more accurately differentiate between those actions that were really bribery at<br />

Athens and those that only seem (to us) like bribery but were perfectly licit for the<br />

Athenians, and so forth.<br />

Or so the theory goes. There are immediate, salient problems with taking a<br />

definition like “abuse of public power for private gain”—already laden in specific<br />

normative terms, it seems—and trying to translate it from one normative context to<br />

another. Even within a given set of cultural norms, it is unclear on what grounds<br />

‘abuse’ should be defined. Is it a violation of formal (legal) rules regarding the conduct<br />

of public officials, an action that goes contrary to the public interest, or one that goes<br />

against the public’s conception of what is acceptable? 2 Again, we could simply limit<br />

ourselves to one way of defining ‘abuse’ (or ‘power’ or ‘gain’, for that matter). But<br />

doing so obscures the crucial political work done by, say, limiting our scope to formal<br />

regulations of official conduct while disregarding both public opinion about what the law<br />

should say and the extent to which the law is seen to foster the public interest. This is not<br />

just an issue of asking, when a particular law is thought unjust, whether it should be<br />

2 These three options correspond to a modified version of Arnold Heidenheimer’s (1989) threefold<br />

typology of definitions of corruption. Heidenheimer differentiates between defining ‘abuse’ according to<br />

the norms of public office (i.e. legal norms) or the public interest; alternatively, under a market-based<br />

approach, public officials qua rational (utility maximizing) agents always tend to use public office to<br />

maximize private gain or influence. As Philp (1997: 445) has convincingly shown, however, market-based<br />

approaches always already incorporate legalistic definitions insofar as they presume that proper official<br />

conduct is determined by the law. In place of the market-oriented approach, therefore, I have included<br />

Gibbons’ (1989) definition based on public opinion even though this approach has not gained much<br />

traction; see also Peters and Welch (1978). Legalistic approaches can be found in Leys (1965), Nye<br />

(1967), Scott (1972). Public interest approach: Gronbeck (1978). Market-based model: Banfield (1975),<br />

Rose-Ackerman (1978, 1999), Klitgaard (1988), Goudie and Stasavage (1998), della Porta and Vannuci<br />

(1999), Lambsdorff (2002).<br />

27

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!